The Routledge Handbook of Planning Theory 1138905011, 9781138905016

The Routledge Handbook of Planning Theory presents key contemporary themes in planning theory through the views of some

740 33 2MB

English Pages 362 [375] Year 2017

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Table of contents :
The Routledge Handbook of Planning Theory- Front Cover
The Routledge Handbook of Planning Theory
Title Page
Copyright Page
Contents
Notes on Contributors
Chapter 1: Planning Theory: An Introduction
Aims of This Book
The Changing Landscape of Planning Theory
Theories of Planning Practice
Theories of Planning Meaning
Theories of Planning Framework
References
PART I: Contemporary Planning Practices
Chapter 2: Spatial Planning: The Promised Land or Rolled-Out Neoliberalism?
Introduction
Place Matters: The Ascendance of Spatial Planning
Theoretical Contexts of Spatial Planning and Their Critiques
Neoliberalisation of Spatial Planning
Conclusion
References
Chapter 3: Strategic Planning: Ontological and Epistemological Challenges
Introduction
Strategic Spatial Planning: History, Logic, Aims, Critique
Potential Critical Features Explaining the Strategic Nature of Planning
What Next?
Notes
References
Chapter 4: Growth Management Theory: From the Garden City to Smart Growth
A Brief History of Growth Management
Approaches to Managing Growth
Smart Growth as a Paradigm
Challenges to Smart Growth
The Future of Growth Management
References
Chapter 5: Planning in the Anthropocene
Introduction: Framing the Conundrum
The Question of Urban ‘Land’: A Biophysical Systems Perspective
Cities as ‘Dissipative Structures’
Are Cities Ecosystems?
The Eco-footprints of Cities: What Really Constitutes ‘Urban’ Land?
Evidence-based Planning for the Anthropocene
Growth or Development? The Need for New Economic Theory
Economics For the Anthropocene
Epilogue: Is H. Sapiens Fatally Flawed?
Notes
References
PART II: How Meaning/Values Are Constructed in Planning
Chapter 6: The Public Interest
Introduction: The Fall from Grace of the Idea of the Public Interest
What Kind of Inexistence? First View, Divergentism
What Kind of Inexistence? Second View, Dialogical Proceduralism
What Kind of Inexistence? Third View, (Classical) Liberalism
What Kind of Inexistence? Fourth View, Value-Pluralism
Rethinking the Public Interest: First Point, Acceptable (and Unacceptable) Criticisms
Rethinking the Public Interest: Second Point, Viable (Nomocratic) Universalism
Final Remarks: The Ineliminability of the Concept of the Public Interest
References
Chapter 7: Rethinking Scholarship on Planning Ethics
Introduction
Conceptualising Planning’s Dominant Focus on Normative Ethics
Turning Our ‘Gaze’ to Southern Epistemologies of Ethical Actions
Conclusion
References
Chapter 8: Communicative Planning
Core Ideas and Progress of Communicative Planning
Communicative Planning and Citizen Participation
The Planner Role
Legitimizing Communicative Planning
Debates and Critique
Concluding Remarks
References
Chapter 9: Neoliberal Planning
Pioneering
Normalizing
Established Tools and Policies
Crisis and Its Aftermath
Past the Political?
What next?
References
Chapter 10: Neo-Pragmatist Planning Theory
Introduction
Pragmatism and Planning Theory
Postmodern Critique
Pragmatism Unbound
Cosmopolitan Pragmatism
Conclusion
Note
References
Chapter 11: Urban Planning and Social Justice
Giving Priority to Justice
The Role of Planning
The Process/Outcome Debate
The Potential for Reform under Capitalism
Diversity and Justice
Environmentalism and Equity
What Can Be Done?
Notes
References
Chapter 12: The Grassroots of Planning: Poor People’s Movements,
Political Society, and the Question of Rights
A Theory of the City
Urban Citizens
Poor People’s Movements
From Waste to Human
Beyond Neoliberalization
References
Chapter 13: The Dilemmas of Diversity: Gender, Race and Ethnicity
in Planning Theory
Introduction
Gender Theory
Gender and Planning Theory
Race and Ethnicity
Race, Ethnicity and Planning Theory
Critiques and Dilemmas
Conclusion
References
Chapter 14: Postcolonial Consequences and New Meanings
Introduction
Postcolonial Theorizing: A Short Overview and Some Qualifications
Seeing from Elsewhere: The Ethico-Political Commitment of Postcolonial Theorizing
Identity and Difference in Postcolonial Theorizing
Representation, Resistance and the Politics of Recognition
Planning and the Production of Colonial Space
The Challenge: Decolonizing Planning Theory?
References
Chapter 15: Postpolitics and Planning
Diagnosing the “Postpolitical Condition”
The Postpolitics of Planning
Some Criticisms
Potentials for Further Development
Concluding Discussion
Notes
References
Chapter 16: ‘Cultural Work’ and the Remaking of Planning’s ‘Apparatus of Truth’
Raiding Foucault’s Toolbox
Planning’s Foucault and His Discontents
From Discursive Formations to the Problematic Apparatus of Planning
Efficiency Effects? Understanding the Disciplinary Micro-Politics of Planning Reform
Exploring the Contribution of ‘Cultural Work’
Conclusion
Notes
References
Chapter 17: Countering ‘The Dark Side’ of Planning: Power, Governmentality, Counter-Conduct
Introduction
Planning and Foucault
Foucault and the ‘Dark Side of Planning’
The Subject and Power
Counter-Conducts
Conflict, Counter-Conducts, Subjectification
Planning’s Counter-Conducts: Developments and Openings
Conclusion
References
Chapter 18: Co-Evolutionary Planning Theory: Evolutionary Governance
Theory and Its Relatives
Introduction
Co-Evolution in Social Theory
Co-Evolution in Planning Theory
Co-Evolution in Evolutionary Governance Theory (EGT)
Governance Configurations: Formal and Informal Institutions
Governance Configurations: Power/Knowledge
Object and Subject Formation
Path, Inter and Goal Dependencies
Final Thoughts
References
PART III: Networks, Flows, Relationships and Institutions
Chapter 19: The Governance of Planning: Flexibly Networked, Yet Institutionally Grounded
Introduction: Governance as an Analytical Concept in Planning Theories
From Government to Governance
The Path Dependence of Governance Practices
The Legitimacy of Governance Networks?
Neoliberal Governance in Planning Theory
Governance in Practice: Soft and Hard Planning
Concluding Remarks
References
Chapter 20: New Institutionalism and Planning Theory
Core Concepts in NI
The Three Major Branches
HI and Planning Theory
Acknowledgments
References
Chapter 21: Conflict and Agonism
Introduction
Critical Planning Theory – Now
The Agon of Agonism
Conflict, Consensus, Hegemony, Politics – ‘The Ineradicable Antagonism’ and the ‘War of Position’
War of Position, Hegemony, Agonism – and Planning
Critical Paths Using Mouffe
Dissensus, the Inadmissible, Politics – and Planning
Conflict and Agonism as an Inadmissible – and Planning
Outlook – Agonism and Futures?
Acknowledgements
Notes
References
Chapter 22: Insurgent Practices and Decolonization of Future(s)
Insurgent Planning: An Ontological Break with Liberal Inclusive Planning
A Theoretical Elaboration: Invited and Invented Spaces of Action and Misconceptions about Them
Imagination and the Urgency in Decolonizing the Future
Conclusion: The Way Forward
Notes
References
Chapter 23: Hegemonic Planning and Marginalizing People
Introduction
Theories on the Planning of Oppression and Marginalization
Three Cases of Oppression and Marginalization
Planning, Oppression, and Marginalization: The Dearth of Theory
Theorizing Hegemonic Planning: Outlining a Future Theoretical Direction
References
Chapter 24: Actor-Network Theory
Introduction
Origins and Applications
Key Concepts and Dynamics
Modes of Researching and Arguing
Critiques and Responses
Future Directions
References
Chapter 25: Spatial Planning and the Complexity of Turbulent, Open Environments: About Purposeful Interventions in a World of Non-Linear Change
About Planning, a Biased Mindset and the Idea of Change
Time, Non-Linearity and the Complexity Sciences
Settlements as Non-Linear Dynamic Systems
Framing Dynamics
Bifurcations and Transitions
Complexity and the Planning Debate
Synopsis
References
Chapter 26: Assemblage Thinking in Planning Theory
Introduction
What Is Assemblage Theory?
What Does Assemblage Theory Do for Planning Theory (and What Does It Not Do)?
Content Theories as Actualizations of Assemblage Theory
Conclusion
Notes
References
Chapter 27: Lines of Becoming
Introduction
On Expecting a Non-essentialist Unexpected
How Is Becoming? What Does Becoming Do?
Becomings-minor
Becoming-Woman
Becoming-Animal
Pragmatics
Emergent Law: Becoming-Law?
Strategic Spatial Planning: Planning for Not Having a Plan?
On Revolutionary-Becoming
In Conclusion
Acknowledgements
References
Index
Recommend Papers

The Routledge Handbook of Planning Theory
 1138905011, 9781138905016

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF PLANNING THEORY

The Routledge Handbook of Planning Theory presents key contemporary themes in planning theory through the views of some of the most innovative thinkers in planning. They introduce and explore their own specialized areas of planning theory, to conceptualize their contemporary positions and to speculate how these positions are likely to evolve and change as new challenges emerge. In a changing and often unpredictable globalized world, planning theory is core to understanding how planning and its practices both function and evolve. As illustrated in this book, planning and its many roles have changed profoundly over the recent decades; so have the theories, both critical and explanatory, about its practices, values and knowledges. In the context of these changes, and to contribute to the development of planning research, this handbook identifies and introduces the cutting edge, and the new emerging trajectories, of contemporary planning theory. The aim is to provide the reader with key insights into not just contemporary planning thought, but potential future directions of both planning theory and planning as a whole. This book is written for an international readership, and includes planning theories that address, or have emerged from, both the global North and parts of the world beyond. Michael Gunder FNZPI is an Associate Professor at the School of Architecture and Planning, University of Auckland, New Zealand. From 2011–2015, he was Managing Editor of Planning Theory and remains an editor. His research draws on poststructuralism to analyse the ideological dimensions of built environment public policies and related narratives. Ali Madanipour is Professor of Urban Design and a founding member of the Global Urban Research Unit at the School of Architecture, Planning and Landscape, Newcastle University, UK. His four-volume edited collection, Planning Theory, was published in 2015 in Routledge’s Critical Concepts in Built Environment series. Vanessa Watson is Professor of Planning in the School of Architecture, Planning and Geomatics at the University of Cape Town, South Africa, holding a PhD from the University of Witwatersrand, and is a University Fellow. She is a founder and on the Board of the African Centre for Cities at UCT.

‘From Habermas and Lefebvre to Rancière and Mouffe this handbook captures the zeitgeist of planning theory with contributions from some of the most innovative thinkers in their fields.’ Professor Phil Allmendinger, Head of the School of the Humanities and Social Sciences, University of Cambridge, Fellow of Clare College

THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF PLANNING THEORY

Edited by Michael Gunder, Ali Madanipour and Vanessa Watson

First published 2018 by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 and by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business  2018 Taylor & Francis The right of Michael Gunder, Ali Madanipour and Vanessa Watson to be identified as the authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual chapters, has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Gunder, Michael, editor. | Madanipour, Ali, editor. | Watson, Vanessa, editor. Title: The Routledge handbook of planning theory / edited by Michael Gunder, Ali Madanipour and Vanessa Watson. Description: New York, NY : Routledge, 2018. Identifiers: LCCN 2017011547 | ISBN 9781138905016 (hardback) Subjects: LCSH: City planning. | Regional planning. | Land use—Planning. Classification: LCC HT166 .R696 2018 | DDC 307.1/216—dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2017011547 ISBN: 978–1–138–90501–6 (hbk) ISBN: 978–1–315–69607–2 (ebk) Typeset in Bembo Std by Swales & Willis Ltd, Exeter, Devon

CONTENTS

Notes on Contributors

viii

  1 Planning Theory: An Introduction Michael Gunder, Ali Madanipour and Vanessa Watson

1

PART I

Contemporary Planning Practices

13

  2 Spatial Planning: The Promised Land or Rolled-Out Neoliberalism? Simin Davoudi

15

  3 Strategic Planning: Ontological and Epistemological Challenges Louis Albrechts

28

  4 Growth Management Theory: From the Garden City to Smart Growth Jill L. Grant

41

  5 Planning in the Anthropocene William E. Rees

53

PART II

How Meaning/Values Are Constructed in Planning

67

  6 The Public Interest Stefano Moroni

69

  7 Rethinking Scholarship on Planning Ethics Tanja Winkler

81

v

Contents

  8 Communicative Planning Tore Sager

93

  9 Neoliberal Planning Guy Baeten

105

10 Neo-Pragmatist Planning Theory Charles Hoch

118

11 Urban Planning and Social Justice Susan S. Fainstein

130

12 The Grassroots of Planning: Poor People’s Movements, Political Society, and the Question of Rights Ananya Roy

143

13 The Dilemmas of Diversity: Gender, Race and Ethnicity in Planning Theory Suzanne Speak and Ashok Kumar

155

14 Postcolonial Consequences and New Meanings Libby Porter

167

15 Postpolitics and Planning Jonathan Metzger

180

16 ‘Cultural Work’ and the Remaking of Planning’s ‘Apparatus of Truth’ Andy Inch

194

17 Countering ‘The Dark Side’ of Planning: Power, Governmentality, Counter-Conduct Margo Huxley

207

18 Co-Evolutionary Planning Theory: Evolutionary Governance Theory and Its Relatives Kristof Van Assche, Raoul Beunen and Martijn Duineveld

221

PART III

Networks, Flows, Relationships and Institutions

235

19 The Governance of Planning: Flexibly Networked, Yet Institutionally Grounded Raine Mäntysalo and Pia Bäcklund

237

vi

Contents

20 New Institutionalism and Planning Theory André Sorensen

250

21 Conflict and Agonism John Pløger

264

22 Insurgent Practices and Decolonization of Future(s) Faranak Miraftab

276

23 Hegemonic Planning and Marginalizing People Yosef Jabareen

289

24 Actor-Network Theory Yvonne Rydin

302

25 Spatial Planning and the Complexity of Turbulent, Open Environments: About Purposeful Interventions in a World of Non-Linear Change Gert de Roo

314

26 Assemblage Thinking in Planning Theory Joris Van Wezemael

326

27 Lines of Becoming Jean Hillier

337

Index 351

vii

CONTRIBUTORS

Louis Albrechts is a Professor Emeritus at Leuven University, Belgium, and founder and editor of European Planning Studies. Current research and writings focus on the practice and nature of strategic spatial planning, diversity and creativity in planning, co-production in planning and bridging the gap between planning and implementation. Pia Bäcklund is a senior researcher at the University of Tampere, Finland. Her research interests concern the limits and role of participation, connections between democracy and planning theories and especially the knowledge base of planning practices and public administration in general. Guy Baeten is Professor of Urban Studies at Malmö University, Sweden. He has previously worked at the universities of Lund, Oxford, Leuven and Strathclyde. Guy Baeten is interested in urban development projects and urban sustainability. He is the principal investigator of the Strong Research Environment CRUSH – Critical Urban Sustainability Hub. Raoul Beunen is Assistant Professor of Environmental Governance at the Open University, the Netherlands. His research explores the potentials and limits of environmental policy and planning in the perspective of adaptive governance and sustainability. It focuses on the processes that drive evolution and innovation in governance. Simin Davoudi MRTPI, FAcSS, FRSA is Director of GURU (Global Urban Research Unit) at Newcastle University and past President of AESOP (Association of European Schools of Planning). Her recent books include: The Resilience Machine (2017, Routledge), Justice and Fairness in the City (2016, Policy Press), Reconsidering Localism (2015, Routledge). Gert de Roo is Professor of Spatial Planning. He heads the Department of Spatial Planning & Environment, at the University of Groningen. He was President of AESOP. De Roo is the editor of A Planner’s Encounter with Complexity (2016, Routledge) and Complexity and Planning (2012, Routledge), and author of numerous articles on complexity and planning.

viii

Contributors

Martijn Duineveld works at the Cultural Geography group at Wageningen University. He focuses on urban governance, planning and design. He is especially interested in the dynamics of power and places, inspired and influenced by Michel Foucault and Niklas Luhmann. Susan S. Fainstein is a Senior Research Fellow in the Harvard University Graduate School of Design. She received the Distinguished Educator Award and the Davidoff Book Award for The Just City, both from the Association of Collegiate Schools of Planning. She focuses on planning theory, urban redevelopment, and comparative policy. Jill L. Grant FCIP LPP is Professor of Planning at Dalhousie University. She has authored dozens of articles, chapters, reports, and five books, including Seeking Talent for Creative Cities (2014, University of Toronto Press) and Planning the Good Community: New urbanism in theory and practice (2006, Routledge). Michael Gunder FNZPI is an Associate Professor at the School of Architecture and Planning, University of Auckland. From 2011–2015, he was Managing Editor of Planning Theory and remains an editor. His research draws on poststructuralism to analyse the ideological dimensions of built environment public policies and related narratives. Jean Hillier is Emeritus Professor of Sustainability and Urban Planning at RMIT University, Melbourne. Her main research concern is with poststructural theory. Books include Deleuze and Guattari for Planners (InPlanning e-book in conversation with Gareth Abrahams, 2013) and the Ashgate Research Companion to Planning Theory (2010) edited with Patsy Healey. Charles Hoch has taught urban planning at the University of Illinois at Chicago since 1981. He studies how professional planners and others make spatial plans and the kind of work plans do. He has taught courses on the history, theory, organization and practice of planning using pragmatist ideas. Margo Huxley has worked in local and metropolitan planning departments in Melbourne, and held posts at various Australian and UK Universities. Drawing on and developing the works of Foucault, she researches in the fields of cultural, historical and postcolonial urban geography and planning, and planning theory. Andy Inch is a Research Fellow at the Instituto de Ciências Sociais, Universidade de Lisboa, Portugal. From 2010–2016 he was a Lecturer in Urban Studies and Planning at the University of Sheffield, UK. His research interests include the politics of planning, planning cultures and relationships between citizens and the state. Yosef Jabareen focuses on the nexus between planning theory and practices in two realms: sustainability and climate change, as well as justice and urban rights. His book The Risk City (2015, Springer) presents a new theory regarding contemporary city plans around the world and the evolving risk and uncertainties. Ashok Kumar is Professor of Physical Planning in the School of Planning and Architecture, New Delhi. His research interests include Politics of Inclusive City Planning, Collaborative

ix

Contributors

Planning, Capabilities and Spatial Justice. He is a member of the Indian Institute of Town Planners and edits the ITPI Journal. Ali Madanipour is Professor of Urban Design and a founding member of the Global Urban Research Unit at the School of Architecture, Planning and Landscape, Newcastle University, UK. His four-volume edited collection, Planning Theory, was published in 2015 in Routledge’s Critical Concepts in Built Environment series. Raine Mäntysalo (D.Sc., architect) is Professor of Strategic Urban Planning at Aalto University, Department of Built Environment, Finland. He is also Adjunct Professor at University of Oulu, Finland, specializing in planning theory and communicative planning. His research interests concern strategies, trading zones, democracy and power in spatial and land use planning. Jonathan Metzger is an Associate Professor of Urban and Regional Studies at the KTH Royal Institute of Technology in Stockholm, Sweden. Most of his work concerns decision-making processes relating to complex environmental issues – often with a focus on urban and regional planning, policy and politics. Faranak Miraftab is Professor of Urban and Regional Planning at the University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign, USA. Her work, empirically based in cities of Latin America, Africa, the Middle East and North America, concerns the global and local development processes involved in the formation of the city and citizens’ struggles to access dignified livelihood. Stefano Moroni is Professor in Planning at the Polytechnic University of Milan (Italy). He teaches ‘Land use ethics and the law’ and ‘Planning theories and practices’, and works mainly on planning theory and applied ethics. He is a member of the editorial board of Planning Theory. John Pløger, Professor of Urban Planning at the University of Agder, Norway, conducts research on planning theory and practice and urban studies. In 2015 he published The Ephemeral City (Danish) and The Vital City (with Jonny Aspen, School of Architecture, Oslo) (Norwegian), and is currently writing a series of articles on ‘the presence city’. Libby Porter is Vice Chancellor’s Principal Research Fellow at the Centre for Urban Research, RMIT University. Her work concerns the processes and politics of displacement and dispossession as a consequence of urban planning and development. Her current activities are focused on the possibilities of decolonizing urban geography and planning. William E. Rees, Professor Emeritus, University of British Columbia, is a human ecologist, ecological economist and former Director of UBC’s School of Community and Regional Planning. He researches the biophysical prerequisites for sustainability and cognitive/behavioural barriers to progress. His work as the originator/co-developer of ecological footprint analysis is globally recognized. Ananya Roy is Professor of Urban Planning and Social Welfare and inaugural Director of The Institute on Inequality and Democracy at the Luskin School of Public Affairs, UCLA. Her latest book, Encountering Poverty: Thinking and Acting in an Unequal World, was published in 2016 by the University of California Press.

x

Contributors

Yvonne Rydin is Professor of Planning, Environment and Public Policy at University College London’s Bartlett School of Planning. She specializes in urban planning, governance and sustainability. A collection on ANT and planning studies Actor Networks of Planning (co-edited with Laura Tate) was published by Routledge in 2016. Tore Sager is Professor Emeritus at NTNU, Norway, where he teaches strategic planning. His latest book is Reviving Critical Planning Theory (2013, Routledge). Recent research concerns transport policy packages and neoliberal urban planning policies. Besides, Sager studies activist planning as resistance to neoliberalism, and the activist planning of intentional communities. André Sorensen is Professor of Urban Geography at the University of Toronto. His research examines planning, property and temporal processes in urbanization and urban governance from an institutionalist perspective. His paper ‘Taking Path Dependence Seriously’ published in Planning Perspectives won the Association of European Schools of Planning Best Paper Award in 2016. Suzanne Speak is Senior Lecturer in International Spatial Planning at Newcastle University, England. Her research explores issues of urban poverty, homelessness, housing and informal settlements in the Global South. She works particularly in India and South Africa, seeking to understand how contemporary urban policy impacts on the poor. Kristof Van Assche is Professor in Planning, Governance & Development at the University of Alberta. He is interested in evolution and innovation in governance, with focus areas in spatial planning and design, development and environmental policy. He has worked in many parts of the world, as researcher, teacher and consultant. Joris Van Wezemael is an Associate Professor at the Department of Architecture, ETH Zürich. His research focus is the sustainable transformation of urban landscapes in a strongly networked world. He teaches at the Department of Architecture (ETH Zürich) and at the Centre for Urban and Real Estate Management (UZH). Vanessa Watson is Professor of Planning in the School of Architecture, Planning and Geomatics at the University of Cape Town (South Africa), holding a PhD from the University of Witwatersrand, and is a University Fellow. She is a founder and on the Board of the African Centre for Cities at UCT. Tanja Winkler is based at the School of Architecture, Planning and Geomatics at the University of Cape Town, South Africa. Her research interests include community-led planning initiatives, critically assessing ‘the voice of the poor’ in public decision-making processes, exploring the values of meta ethics for situated planning actions, and planning education through engaged scholarship.

xi

1 PLANNING THEORY An Introduction Michael Gunder, Ali Madanipour and Vanessa Watson

Aims of This Book In a changing and globalizing world, planning theory is core to understanding how planning and its practices both function and evolve. As illustrated in this book, planning and its many roles have changed profoundly over the recent decades; so have the theories, both critical and explanatory, about its practices, values and knowledges. In the context of these changes, and to contribute to the development of planning education and research, this handbook seeks to identify and introduce the cutting edge, and the new emerging trajectories, of contemporary planning theory. This will provide the reader with key insights into not just contemporary planning thought, but potential future directions of both planning theory and planning as a whole. This handbook’s objective is to present the most important themes of planning theory through the views of some of the most innovative thinkers in planning thought. We have invited them to write new chapters for this book, in which they introduce and explore their own specialized areas of planning theory, to conceptualize their contemporary positions and to speculate how these positions are likely to evolve and change as new challenges emerge. Further, given that this book speaks to an international readership, we have sought to include planning theories that address, or have emerged from, parts of the world beyond the global North. We have also encouraged authors, where possible, to consider how their particular theoretical and practical focus has manifested itself differently in various contexts around the world. We do not claim comprehensive coverage in this respect and we recognize that our choice of theorists who write and publish in the English language inevitably limits the scope of our endeavour. This introductory chapter briefly maps out the contemporary evolution of planning theory. It documents the profound change that planning and the theories of planning have undergone over the last third of a century so as to lay the foundations for the following chapters that comprise contemporary planning theory. Commencing with the public loss of traditional confidence in instrumental rationality, technical authority and positivistic predication from which planning historically advanced a progressive future, the introduction documents the emergence of new strands of both critical and explanatory theoretical understanding and resultant planning practices that arose in place of planning’s earlier modernist rationality. After this introductory chapter, the book will comprise three specific sections. The first section provides theoretical understandings and critical observations pertaining to the contemporary state 1

M. Gunder, A. Madanipour and V. Watson

of planning’s diverse practices. The second section draws on multiple intellectual perspectives to consider how meanings and values are constructed in planning. The final section theorizes the contemporary and emerging structures and functions that underlie planning. It considers the networks, flows, relationships and institutions that constitute the planning frame and the inherent consequences that these frameworks produce. In aggregate, the book provides the reader with a clear view of the current established state, as well as the latest exploratory perimeters, of knowledge in planning theory.

The Changing Landscape of Planning Theory As Nietzsche famously put it, philosophies are narratives told from a perspective. They are the products of particular times and places, rather than timeless truths valid for everywhere. Planning theories, therefore, need to be contextualized and localized, as they are narratives developed in the context of particular circumstances and in response to certain concerns. To map out the current state of planning theory, therefore, these theories need to be located in the context of their historical evolution, and in reference to the changing conditions of the societies in which they emerge. They reflect the structural challenges of our time, which are driven by social, economic, political, cultural and technological change, with direct implications for society and environment (Madanipour 2015a, 2015b). As the instrument of managing change in the built and natural environments, planning clearly reflects the changing relationship between the institutions of power and the society and environment. The recent history of planning theory in the Western countries parallels the rise and fall of the welfare state, which advocated an increased level of intervention by the democratic state in managing the economy and society. At the peak of the welfare state, during the three decades after the Second World War, planning enjoyed its highest level of popularity and activity, which was supported by theories for its legitimacy, rationality and efficiency. As the welfare state declined, however, planning came under attack and its rationale and its performance in the previous period were severely criticized. Since then, the last three decades have witnessed a period of increased restrictions on the idea and the activities of planning, and a proliferation of theories that are critical of this decline, searching for ways of revitalizing planning in new forms. Outside the Western context, with a wide range of completely different experiences in the relationship between the state and society, the history of planning played out in a number of different ways. In the socialist countries, planning was an integral part of the state, and planning theories were at the heart of the state’s ideology. The collapse of the Soviet system, which was symbolized by the fall of the Berlin Wall in 1989, heralded a radical divorce from the idea of planning in Eastern European countries. Where the socialist political structure was entwined with market economics, as in China, which experienced perhaps the largest wave of urbanization in human history, planning combined an ideology of the state with a framework for capitalist modernization. In the colonized countries around the world, planning had been an instrument of colonial power to control the colonized society. The process of decolonization after the Second World War transformed the nature of the state, which now faced the challenges of institutional renewal, rapid urbanization and modernization. Where the country had not been directly colonized, meanwhile, planning had become a vehicle of the local elites to foster modernization and Westernization, which now faced severe criticisms for their failure to pay sufficient attention to the local context. The test for planning theory in these post-socialist, postcolonial, and post-modernist contexts has been articulating new forms of relationship between the transformed state and society, and 2

Planning Theory: An Introduction

developing ideas that would respond to local specificities rather than an uncritical transmission of ideas from the Western context. With the intensification of globalization and urbanization, and with the scale of problems such as climate change, some of the challenges for planning and its theories are also becoming increasing global. While the strength and capacities of local institutions to address these problems vary widely, a significant range of problems are increasingly shared across countries and continents. In this changing landscape of planning and its theories, the post-war planning of the Keynesian welfare state has profoundly transformed into planning for the contemporary entrepreneurial neoliberal state, with considerable spatial, temporal and institutional implications (Madanipour 2010). In this transformation, the primary bases of public planning – its instrumental rationality, claims to representing the public interest, to objective scientific knowledge, democratic legitimacy, comprehensive coverage of problems and long-term future orientation – have all been questioned. In the new atmosphere, in which market considerations and modes of practice have taken priority, the character of planning theory and practice has largely changed, and the ‘legitimacy of the profession and public trust in its institutions have both been challenged’ (Laurian 2009: 369). Planning has come under numerous challenges as an outcome of a range of often inter-related issues. These include: the loss of faith in predictive certainty and positivistic science in a world increasingly understood to be dynamically non-linear in its complex multiplicity of flows and behaviours (de Roo 2015); the loss of ‘notions of exclusivity of knowledge’; the ‘displacement of the power of the bureau-professions by managerial[ism]’; the ‘de-professionalising tendencies of government through the imposition of performance management techniques’; and, also, ‘increasing specialisations within the domains of practice’ (Vigar 2012: 363). With its roots in the European Enlightenment, planning emerged in the early 20th century as ‘a technique for guiding social progress’ for territorial management that sought societal improvement (Friedmann 1987: 53). The explicit term ‘planning theory’ can be first attributed to the University of Chicago’s Program of Education and Research in Planning in the late 1940s (Hillier and Healey 2008: 3). Planning theory has since evolved as the theorization and contextualization of spatial management practices, often with an ethical or critical dimension, as well as a means for introducing alternative knowledge perspectives from other fields into the wider planning discipline (Friedmann 2008). Planning initially arose largely from an architectural and engineering background. At least in the United States, planning emerged after the Second World War, in alignment with Keynesian economic theory, as a social science discipline of public policy. This was largely attributable to planning’s successful pre-war deployment as a tool of Federal government regional economic development policy during the Great Depression and its subsequent war-time accomplishments in national logistics and related public management (Friedmann 1987). Andreas Faludi (1973: 1) summarized this social science planning perspective as being ‘the application of scientific method – however crude – to policy-making’. Central to this scientific method of policy planning was the application of rational choice, where the best, i.e. most efficient, means were identified within known constraints to achieve a desired goal or end state, often called instrumental rationality (Banfield 1959; Davidoff and Reiner 1962). These long-term goals/objectives and the efficient means to achieve them were then incorporated into comprehensive master plans for future settlement development reflecting the achievement of an ‘overall public interest’ (Altshuler 1965: 186). Arising from mounting dissatisfaction with Western governments and their social policy failures, the limitations of this approach, however, were pointed out by questioning the notion of public interest; planning’s ability to set and achieve long-term, comprehensive goals; the impact of its prescriptions on people’s lives; and its ability to address major problems in changing societies (Jacobs 1961; Lindblom 1959; Rittel 3

M. Gunder, A. Madanipour and V. Watson

and Webber 1973). A series of critical and alternative theories began to emerge from the 1960s onwards: political economy, social diversity, environmentalism, post-positivism, pragmatism and poststructuralism, all vying to offer a clearer understanding of what planning was and what it could become. The political economy critique drew attention to the substantive components of planning and sought to shape a new form of urbanism founded on social justice (Castells 1977; Harvey 1985, 2009; Lefebvre 1991, 1996). It appealed for a new approach to planning ethics (Marcuse 1976), where ‘the consequences for the lower classes of solutions proposed by monopoly capital’ were minimized (Fainstein and Fainstein 1979: 399). In parallel, planning was urged to pay attention to the reality of social diversity, where the issues of difference in gender, age, race and ethnic groups were often absent from the planning agenda (Ritzdorf 1992; Sandercock and Forsyth 1992; Young 1992). It was argued as well that planning could have a potentially adverse impact on minorities, or even on suppressed majorities, in any nation state (Yiftachel 1998). The environmental crisis, meanwhile, was found to be a major omission of traditional planning, as the serious consequences of development on the natural world had often been ignored. The emerging themes of sustainable development, smart growth and new urbanism signified this new awareness (Beatley 1989; Campbell 1996; Hebbert 2003). The critics of technocratic planning advocated the transformation of planning through public participation, displacing instrumental rationality with communicative rationality, avoiding conflict and aiming at the creation of social consensus. Inspired by the work of the German philosopher Jürgen Habermas, by the American pragmatist tradition, and by the linguistic turn in social analysis, new calls were made for communication and collaboration to become the basis of planning theory and practice (Forester 1989, 2013; Habermas 1984, 1987; Healey 1992, 1997; Innes 1995, 1996; Sager 1994). By the 1990s, in many parts of the world, communicative and collaborative theories had occupied the centre stage in planning. As the liberal theory of incremental planning had argued before (Lindblom 1959), this pragmatist trend questioned the value of abstract theories and gave priority to practice and interaction (Hoch 1988). In parallel, the post-positivist critics of planning theories refuted the claims of rational planning to scientific knowledge. Following the philosopher Karl Popper, they argued that planning theory should produce empirically testable theory that is open to refutability (Scott and Roweis 1977). As a critique of the pragmatist call for collaborative planning, and of the political economy’s emphasis on the distribution of resources, a poststructuralist trend analysed planning in alternative ways. A key inspiration was the French philosopher Michel Foucault (1980, 2002) and his analysis of power and knowledge. The normative idealism of liberal planning came under attack, found to be an instrument of state power, an expression of ‘governmentality’, masking the real differences and conflicts by turning arguments into knowledge and enforcing it through seeking consensus (Flyvbjerg 1992; Flyvbjerg and Richardson 2002; Gunder and Mouat 2002; Huxley 2002; Pløger 2004; Richardson 1996). Another inspiration was the French psychoanalyst Jacques Lacan (2006 [1966]), whose work was used to question the Habermas-inspired search for ideal speech and consensus, as well as to explore the role of desire and fantasy in planning policy formation (Gunder 2003; Gunder and Hillier 2009; Hillier 2003). As a consequence of the supremacy of public choice, free-market economics and the rise and global acceptance of a dominant and extensive neoliberal ideology that undermines the role of public institutions, faith in the efficiency and legitimacy of public planning has degraded to being, at best, a poor alternative to market-based solutions. In this context, the planner’s role has been restricted to that of a ‘designer of efficient and democratically acceptable market institutions’ (Sager 2009: 66). Indeed, within our contemporary neoliberal world, rather than the traditional welfare state promoting its role of pastoral care for its Foucauldian obedient and 4

Planning Theory: An Introduction

docile masses while promising a ‘better’ future for all, a new imaginary has emerged of the state enabling the market to facilitate socially competitive and mobile individualism. The ‘symbolic prohibitive norms’ of the prior welfare state have been ‘increasingly replaced with imaginary ideals’ constituting individual success (Žižek 1998: 480; emphasis in original). Now the neoliberal subject is driven by an ideologically imposed injunction to no longer simply ‘obey’, but rather to ultimately ‘enjoy’ in his/her consumption. This contemporary world is no longer one of government, but rather one of governance, and the ideological task of planning is no longer one of control so as to guide balanced development for a collective interest, but rather to ensure the success of a polity by guaranteeing the correct environment for the competitively achieved market-derived enjoyment for its inhabitants (Gunder 2010, 2016).

Theories of Planning Practice The 26 chapters of the book are structured in three parts: theories of planning practices, planning meanings and planning frameworks. The first part of the book, on theories of planning practice, explores how planning is currently done. In four chapters, it investigates the theories of spatial planning, strategic planning, smart growth and environmental planning. Over the last two decades spatial planning has emerged as the dominant planning paradigm in much of Europe and has been implemented in many other parts of the globe. While it has numerous formal definitions, it is generally concerned with giving spatial governance expression to the economic, social, ecological and cultural dimensions of a geographically defined polity. In Chapter 2, Simin Davoudi argues that the revival of spatial planning in the 2000s was a belated response to the growing realization that place matters, coinciding with and informed by relational concepts of space and communicative and normative aspects of spatial planning processes. Certain interpretations of spatial planning and its theoretical underpinnings, however, have led to its alignment with neoliberal policies and practices. Strategic planning acts as a coordinating mechanism to frame actions between diverse organizations and authorities in the achievement of desired shared societal outcomes, often of a territorial nature at the metropolitan or larger spatial level. While strategic planning often functions as a mechanism to produce aligned policy consensus, this often occurs as an artefact of global competition. In Chapter 3, Louis Albrechts critically explores the competitive tension that underlays this set of planning practices. The chapter focuses first on the roots of strategic planning, its aims, logic and some critiques, followed by an exploration of the dimensions that would explain the strategic nature of planning. Albrechts argues for revisiting strategic planning, which requires an in-depth reflection on key concepts (envisioning, becoming, legitimacy), on the path dependency of resources and on space-time geographies. Growth management might be considered the overarching aim of the planning function at the urban and regional governance levels in many parts of the world today. Urban planning’s core mission is linked to managing the location, amount and character of growth. Growth management includes strategies for preventing sprawl and attempting to encourage and accommodate steady and efficient development in appropriate locations. In Chapter 4, Jill L. Grant presents a brief history of growth management theories, paying special attention to smart growth, which has dominated North American urban planning approaches in recent years. Advocates of smart growth adopted many strategies from new urbanism and the language of sustainable development to generate a persuasive paradigm to rally diverse interests in support of growth. As smart growth became increasingly popular, however, it faced increasing critiques about its assumptions, implementation failures, and inappropriateness for cities in developing countries or for Western regions experiencing decline. 5

M. Gunder, A. Madanipour and V. Watson

The loss of ecological biodiversity and climate change, with the resultant need to minimize the human ecological footprint in the face of continued demographic and economic growth are, for many, the greatest challenges facing the planet. William Rees in Chapter 5 asks how urban and regional planners might address humanity’s cumulating ecological predicament. He argues that the biophysical foundations of planning, particularly pertaining to urban ecosystems, are seriously underdeveloped; the prevailing neoliberal framing of economic planning is dangerously misguided; resolving the ecological crisis requires reasserting the common good and the public interest over selfish individualism and corporate privilege; and the ‘disjointed incrementalism’ characterizing typical development planning is woefully inadequate for the Anthropocene. Contrary to popular wisdom, he argues, some developing countries have an advantage over advanced high-income countries in addressing the threat if they can organize to use it.

Theories of Planning Meaning Part II is concentrated on how meanings and values are constructed in planning. Its 13 chapters explore the themes of public interest, planning ethics, communicative planning, neoliberal planning, neo-pragmatism, social justice, right to the city, gender and race, postcolonial planning, post-political planning, discursive formations, governmentality and co-evolutionary planning. Stefano Moroni broadly interrogates the concept of the public interest in Chapter 6, considering if the concept actually exists so as to map out different positions for and against it in the literature. This questioning is deployed to prepare means for rehabilitating the concept of the public interest. Moroni contends that while we may delete this concept from public debate, in so doing we will simply have to develop a new concept to take its place. Moroni articulates a reconstruction of the concept that calls for a nomocracy predicated public interest that is ‘ends independent’ and serves as a meta-criterion for institutional design in the decision-making process. His main conclusion is that it is important to reconstruct the concept of public interest in ways that prove useful and relevant for today’s urban environments, with all their inherent complexity and diversity of values perspective. The positivist claims about value-free knowledge and action were rejected to show the value-laden nature of all planning ideas and practices. Values, therefore, became a subject of intense interest in planning theory, to the extent that some planning theorists consider ethical considerations to be the defining feature of planning theory. In Chapter 7, Tanja Winkler explores how engagements with meta-ethical questions might offer scholars alternative bases for theorizing and operating at the interface of knowledge and action in situated contexts. In order to begin to understand why scholarships on planning ethics are rooted, almost exclusively, within normative ethical frameworks, the chapter first sets out critically to analyse (via a discourse analysis) some of planning’s dominant epistemologies of ethical actions. This is followed by briefly turning to the potential relevance of meta-ethics in Southern contexts. In Chapter 8, Tore Sager overviews the participatory and dialogical democratic practice called communicative planning. He documents the rise of communicative planning during the 1980s and how it advances on the practice of citizen participation. Sager then considers the planner’s role as a facilitator, rather than just a technocratic expert, when undertaking communicative planning processes, although this role in itself requires a skilled voice. The chapter then considers the importance of legitimacy when undertaking communicative planning. Sager then considers the debates and criticisms of communicative planning, especially how it has been argued that this form of consensual planning has been captured as a powerful tool of neoliberal hegemony. Sager defends communicative planning from these assertions, 6

Planning Theory: An Introduction

arguing for the need of meta-consensus rather than outright consensus when a polity agrees to a plan. The author concludes the chapter with a consideration of communicative planning from a global perspective. In Chapter 9, Guy Baeten considers the historical rise of neoliberal planning and its eventual spread around the globe. He documents the shift of urban management to one of urban entrepreneurialism and planning’s inevitable conformity with this new market-orientated ethos. The chapter overviews planning’s new neoliberal practices from city marketing, through the formulation of competitive cities attracting the creative classes for economic development, through governance and private-public partnerships, as well as entrepreneurial public urban development projects. Baeten is optimistic of planning’s continued role under neoliberalism, but cautions that under this dominant ideology planning might have to pull back from its traditional roles of promoting equity, social justice and sustainability under the post-political conditions of neoliberalism. That is, until new utopian values can displace those of neoliberalism and its inherent consumptive enjoyment in the popular imaginary. Charles Hoch, in Chapter 10, interrogates neo-pragmatism and planning and its use by planning theorists over the last 30 or so years. Pragmatist theorists consider the relevance of social knowledge for arising situations so as to deal with the complexity of contemporary issues and problems. Hoch considers the pragmatic theories of John Forester on power, Tom Harper and Stan Stein on resolving facts and values, Hilda Blanco’s deployment of abductive reasoning to address complex issues and resolve plausible possible actions in response to them, as well as Patsy Healey on relational pragmatism. The chapter considers poststructural critiques of pragmatism and calls for an unbounded and cosmopolitan pragmatism that binds together knowledge and action through social learning for democratic inquiry. The procedural nature of much post-war planning theory has been questioned on the basis that it does not engage with what planning aims to achieve, i.e. the substantive issues about the social and environmental consequences of planning. The quest for equality and justice, therefore, occupies a primary place for critical planning theorists, who reject the idea that good procedures necessarily lead to desirable outcomes. In Chapter 11, Susan S. Fainstein investigates the use of spatial justice as the foremost criterion by which to develop approaches to urban and regional growth and decline. She acknowledges that planning for spatial justice cannot overcome economic inequality but argues that it can help to improve the quality of life of lower-income populations. In this chapter Fainstein uses the case of Singapore to show how planning can increase equity, because of the way the state is able to protect certain economic groups from market pressure through mechanisms that include intervention in the built environment. Drawing largely on the writings of Henri Lefebvre, the language of rights and the ‘right to the city’ has found its way into planning theory. With widely varying definitions of the concept and more or less radical explanations of what ‘right to the city’ might mean, the concept has been used in planning theory to promote positions that are both spatially and socially more equitable. In Chapter 12, Ananya Roy voices concerns with ‘right to the city’ positions and suggests that, instead, postcolonial and poststructuralist theory offers new understandings of the relationship between the urban and the political. She takes Castells as a starting point rather than Lefebvre as this allows her to emphasize the importance of a theory of the state, which for Castells is also a theory of the city, for an analytics of planning and politics. Much of traditional planning theory was criticized as having been written by elite males, disregarding the needs and demands of people who were different from them by gender, age, race and culture. How has planning theory addressed this quest for diversity? In Chapter 13, Suzanne Speak and Ashok Kumar explore the achievements and frustrations of planning theorists 7

M. Gunder, A. Madanipour and V. Watson

who have raised these issues for a generation but with little impact and with still limited clarity on how to respond to diversity. Taking just three aspects of social diversity – gender, race and ethnicity – they consider the state of current planning theorization and practice, focusing on these issues in global South contexts. However, they also note the growing trend toward rightwing politics and social tensions in Europe and the USA which will undoubtedly pose major challenges for planning theory and practice. Libby Porter engages the postcolonial consequences of planning in Chapter 14. She contends that planning is a Western, or Northern, concept concerned with the imagination of the future and the use and control of land. As a consequence, it is central to the production of colonial space and the alienation of land from colonized peoples. Accordingly, postcolonial planning theorizing provides a critical perspective from which to deconstruct the contemporary situation and provide understanding about planning’s role in the normalization of that alienation. Porter also contends that postcolonial theorizing can act as a praxis of struggle as the colonized ‘speak back’ to their oppressors. In Chapter 15, Jonathan Metzger considers the current debates on post-political planning, where planning procedures are deployed to at best ‘window-dress’ democratically deeply deficient governance processes. Drawing on the political philosophy of Mouffe, Žižek and Rancière, Metzger considers the suppression of the political by mere managerial apparatus that defines what is sensible, hence in Žižek’s conceptualization foreclosing the political in the symbolic order. The chapter considers a range of ways that planning practices have been deployed to foreclose political contestation. Critiques of the post-political concept are also explored, including how an acceptance of the concept facilitates its very intent of neutering the political. Metzger also proposes directions for further researching the concept, via further defining and specifying the post-political, and especially contesting its actual existence as a state of oppression. In Chapter 16, Andy Inch draws on the work of Foucault which explored the ways social practices are shaped by ‘regimes of truth’ that powerfully circumscribe what can and cannot be said, done and considered truthful at different times. Using the example of planning in Scotland, Inch explores how neoliberal and managerial agendas are transforming the discipline and practice of planning. He suggests that examining the micro-practices (the ‘cultural work’) through which change is negotiated renders visible some of the subtle reworkings and transformations that this can prompt. Margo Huxley continues the exploration of Foucault in Chapter 17 from the perspective of power and governmentality and especially counter-conduct, for it addresses the ‘dark side’ of planning. After exploring the deployment of Foucault in planning theory, Huxley considers Foucault’s engagement with how culture produces its subjects through governmentality via the power shaping the ‘conduct of conducts’ and resultant subjectification. Huxley then considers counter-conduct: the right to question and contest. She then proposes how theory can study counter-conduct in relation to planning, in a manner that should consider all applications of power as potentially dangerous and consequently in need of continued questioning. In Chapter 18, Kristof Van Assche, Raoul Beunen and Martijn Duineveld analyse the origins and the potential of co-evolutionary perspectives in planning theory and they particularly engage with their own conception of evolutionary governance theory (EGT). EGT is a theory predicated on poststructuralism, institutional economics and social systems theory. The authors develop a co-evolutionary understanding of society into a co-evolutionary theory of governance, administration and planning. They contend that this is a theory of organization, steering, and planned change. EGT is partly rooted in planning research and aims to delineate planning and its possibilities in different governance paths. Planning within this perspective is understood 8

Planning Theory: An Introduction

as a political activity that can and does take many forms that change over time, in evolutions that alter both the structures and elements of planning systems.

Theories of Planning Framework Part III investigates the networks, flows, relationships and institutions that are involved in planning. In eight chapters, it analyses the theories of governance, new institutionalism, agonism, insurgency, conflict, actor networks, complexity, assemblage and becoming. As the state withdrew from some activities, to be replaced by market forces, the traditional role of the government in planning went through considerable transformation. The multiplication of non-state actors, however, often created fragmented governance. To be effective, therefore, public policy and planning needed to overcome this fragmentation through the formation of collective action. The relations of governance, therefore, became a subject of theoretical scrutiny and empirical research. In Chapter 19, Raine Mäntysalo and Pia Bäcklund analyse the role that planning has played as part of the relations of place-based governance. They first take a broad look at how the change from government to governance has taken and is taking place, utilizing especially discussions within administrative studies. They then focus on the uses of governance as an analytical concept, and conclude that it would be fruitfully employed in the planning theoretical discourse. In the last few decades a number of disciplines in the social sciences have been marked by the development of an ‘institutional turn’ in intellectual thought, and this has influenced strands of planning theory as well. Theorists have seen ‘institutions’ as both generative and constitutive reflecting a suspicion of any form of binary separation, especially that between structure and agency. Theorists in this field have attempted to develop analytical frameworks to help understand contemporary forms of governance as well as trying to identify the transformative potential embedded within dynamic, multi-layered and fragmented governance environments. In Chapter 20, André Sorensen introduces the core concepts and major areas of agreement and disagreement between the main new forms of institutionalism, analyses its three strands of rational choice, sociological and historical institutionalism and how these have been incorporated into planning theory, and suggests an institutionalist approach to planning theory. The critics of consensual planning theory argue that the reality of social relations in diverse and unequal societies is based on the conflict of interest between different groups. Rather than harmony and consensus, which could suppress some voices, the differences of interest have to be recognized and integrated into planning from the beginning. Inspired by thinkers such as Michel Foucault and Chantal Mouffe, agonism has become a new keyword in planning theory. In Chapter 21, John Pløger examines agonism and whether it can offer a future alternative for planning theory. The chapter explores how planning praxis can work with conflict as agonistic conflict; what challenges this gives planning, which is positioned within and relying on political legitimacy, consensus processes, and political decisions. A key question is: how can planning praxis acknowledge contestation and inadmissible difference as key forces of a multiverse democracy; a democracy of many interpretations? In Chapter 22, Faranak Miraftab defines the ways in which the concept of insurgency has been imported into planning theory, starting as a notion of radical planning for the 21st century that acknowledges the socio-cultural as well as economic dimensions of globalization and the culturally diverse landscapes these produce. While earlier ideas of insurgent planning were seen as a response to globalization in which new forms of progressive, bottom-up, planning began to emerge, in more recent times the term has been used to describe how a very wide range of social actors can shape planning intervention through counter-hegemonic or 9

M. Gunder, A. Madanipour and V. Watson

transgressive actions. The chapter argues for acknowledging the value of insurgent planning not as a set of blueprints for action but as a conceptual and normative construct to guide planning theory and practice. Conflict and violence over land and resources pose a growing challenge for planning theory and practice. In these contexts ethno-nationalistic states use space and (ethnocratic) planning as a tool of political repression against ethnically marginalized castes, races, religions or cultures. In Chapter 23, Yosef Jabareen argues that planning cannot always be regarded as ‘a good thing’ and that it can also have a ‘dark side’ which can have highly negative consequences. In this chapter Jabareen aims to theorize the role of planning as an instrument of marginalization and domination, drawing on examples from various parts of the world and on Lacanian, Žižekian, Laclauian concepts of fantasy, lack, and desire. Yvonne Rydin begins Chapter 24 with the history of Actor-Network Theory (ANT) as initially a social constructionist contribution to scientific studies. Rydin then outlines ANT’s relational ontology and considers the metaphor of the network. She then explores the work involved in bringing elements into association with each other in a network; the stages of translation; the radical symmetry of the social and the material; and other key ANT concepts. Following a brief discussion of ANT’s distinctive mode of research and argumentation, Rydin considers criticisms posed around issues of ANT’s structure, inequality, power and change, together with possible responses to these criticisms. The chapter concludes with some possible trajectories for planning research around materiality and developing a normative ANT planning approach. With the growth of the information and communication technology, and with the deepening of the environmental crisis, systems theory has returned to the agenda of planning theory. By envisaging society and environment as complex systems, the emergence of new phenomena is analysed and explained through the way these systems adapt in a dynamic and non-linear way to their environment. In Chapter 25, Gert de Roo explores how complexity theory has been applied to the understanding of planning’s traditional ‘wicked problems’ and the resultant notions of agency, interaction, feedback, and contextual specificity under conditions of uncertainty and non-linearity. The concepts of non-linearity, complexity and uncertainty, which represent the complexity sciences, processes of discontinuous change and evolutionary pathways through time, are explored. The chapter argues for the relevance of a non-linear, transformative and dynamic understanding to the planning debate. Manuel Delanda drew on the philosophical understandings of Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari to develop assemblage theory. Planning theorists have drawn on assemblage theory to demonstrate how a collection of diverse elements may come together in a relationship of exteriority that constitutes a temporary selective coding and territorialization of elements so as to stabilize the distinctiveness and function of an assemblage into a particular identity, such as a city or neighbourhood, or even that of a more ethereal spatial concept such as a positive or negative ‘sense of place’. As such, Chapter 26 by Joris Van Wezemael demonstrates that assemblage theory has considerable potential in providing understanding in both planning theory and practice. He argues that it can help to deal with the critique of collaborative approaches toward rationalist planning, and help to fix shortfalls identified in collaborative planning approaches. He acknowledges, however, that the contribution of this perspective to normative foundations of planning has yet to be developed. Jean Hillier’s Chapter 27 engages with Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of ‘becoming’ and contends that this concept positively resonates in a world marked by uncertainty. Following a brief discussion of uncertainties and essentialisms in planning, Hillier introduces ‘becoming’ as a transition-affecting encounter between elements. She then considers specific becomings: 10

Planning Theory: An Introduction

becoming-minor, becoming-woman and becoming-animal. Hillier explores the potentialities of a DeleuzoGuattarian-inspired pragmatics regarding emergent forms of law and strategic spatial planning before engaging a discussion of critical ‘revolutionary-becoming’. Hillier completes the chapter with the assertion that by undermining the essentialist identities and fixed terms of majoritarian planning cultures, becomings offer us ways to think and act differently in dynamic worlds.

References Altshuler, A. (1965) The Goals of Comprehensive Planning, Journal of the American Institute of Planners, 31(3): 186–197. Banfield, E. (1959) Ends and Means in Planning, International Social Science Journal, 11(3): 361–368. Beatley, T. (1989) Environmental Ethics and Planning Theory, Journal of Planning Literature, 4(1): 1–32. Campbell, S. (1996) Green Cities, Growing Cities, Just Cities? Urban Planning and the Contradictions of Sustainable Development, Journal of the American Planning Association, 62(3): 296–312. Castells, M. (1977) The Urban Question: A Marxist Approach, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Davidoff, P. and Reiner, T. (1962) A Choice Theory of Planning, Journal of the American Institute of Planners, 28(2): 103–115. De Roo, G. (2015) Going for Plan B – Conditioning Adaptive Planning: About Urban Planning and Institutional Design in a Non-linear, Complex World, in R. Geyer and P. Cairney (eds) Handbook on Complexity and Public Policy, Cheltenham (UK): Edward Elgar Publishing, 349–368. Fainstein, N. and Fainstein, S. (1979) New Debates in Urban Planning: The Impact of Marxist Theory within the United States, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 3(1–4): 381–403. Faludi, A. (1973) What is Planning Theory? in A. Faludi (ed.) A Reader in Planning Theory, Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1–10. Flyvbjerg, B. (1992) Aristotle, Foucault and Progressive Phronesis: Outline of an Applied Ethics for Sustainable Development, Planning Theory, 7/8: 65–83. Flyvbjerg, B. and Richardson, T. (2002) Planning and Foucault: In Search of the Dark Side of Planning Theory, in P. Allmendinger and M. Tewdwr-Jones (eds) Planning Futures: New Directions for Planning Theory, London: Routledge, 44–62. Forester, J. (1989) Planning in the Face of Power, Berkeley: University of California Press. Forester, J. (2013) On the Theory and Practice of Critical Pragmatism: Deliberative Practice and Creative Negotiations, Planning Theory, 12(1): 5–22. Foucault, M. (1980) The Eye of Power, in Colin Gordon (ed.) Power/Knowledge, Harlow: Pearson Education Limited, 146–165. Foucault, M. (2002) The Order of Things, London: Routledge. Friedmann, J. (1987) Planning in the Public Domain: From Knowledge to Action, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Friedmann, J. (2008) The Uses of Planning Theory: A Bibliographic Essay, Journal of Planning Education and Research, 28(2): 247–257. Gunder, M. (2003) Passionate Planning for the Other’s Desire: An Agonistic Response to the Dark Side of Planning, Progress in Planning, 60(3): 236–319. Gunder, M. (2010) Planning as the Ideology of (Neo-Liberal) Space, Planning Theory, 9(4): 298–314. Gunder, M. (2016) Planning’s ‘Failure’ to Ensure Efficient Market Delivery: A Lacanian Deconstruction of this Neoliberal Scapegoating Fantasy, European Planning Studies, 21(1): 21–38. Gunder, M. and Hillier, J. (2009) Planning in Ten Words or Less: A Lacanian Entanglement with Spatial Planning, Farnham: Ashgate. Gunder, M. and Mouat, C. (2002) ‘Symbolic Violence and Victimisation in Planning Processes: A Reconnoitre of the New Zealand Resource Management Act’, Planning Theory, 1(2): 125–146. Habermas, J. (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 1, Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1987) The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 2, Cambridge: Polity Press. Harvey, D. (1985) On Planning the Ideology of Planning, in D. Harvey The Urbanization of Capitalism, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 165–184. Harvey, D. (2009 [1973]) Social Justice and the City, London: The University of Georgia Press. Healey, P. (1992) Planning through Debate: The Communicative Turn in Planning Theory, Town Planning Review, 63(2): 143–162.

11

M. Gunder, A. Madanipour and V. Watson Healey, P. (1997) Collaborative Planning, London: MacMillan. Hebbert, M. (2003) New Urbanism: The Movement in Context, Built Environment, 29(3): 193–209. Hillier, J. (2003) Agon’ising Over Consensus: Why Habermasian Ideals Cannot Be ‘Real’, Planning Review, 2(1): 37–59. Hillier, J. and Healey, P. (2008) Foundations of the Planning Enterprise: Critical Essays in Planning Theory: Volume 1, Aldershot: Ashgate. Hoch, C. (1988) A Pragmatic Inquiry, Society, 26(1): 27–35. Huxley, M. (2002) Governmentality, Gender, Planning: A Foucauldian Perspective, in P. Allmendinger and M. Tewdwr-Jones (eds) Planning Futures: New Directions for Planning Theory, London: Routledge, 136–153. Innes, J. (1995) Planning Theory’s Emerging Paradigm: Communicative Action and Interactive Practice, Journal of Planning Education and Research, 14(3): 183–189. Innes, J. (1996) Planning through Consensus Building: A New View of the Comprehensive Planning Ideal, Journal of the American Planning Association, 62(4): 460–472. Jacobs, J. (1961) The Death and Life of Great American Cities, New York: Random House. Lacan, J. (2006 [1966]) Écrits, London: Norton. Laurian, L. (2009) Trust in Planning: Theoretical and Practical Considerations for Participatory and Deliberative Planning, Planning Theory & Practice, 10(3): 369–391. Lefevbre, H. (1991 [1974]) The Production of Space, Oxford: Blackwell. Lefevbre, H. (1996) Writings on Cities, Oxford: Blackwell. Lindblom, C. (1959) The Science of ‘Muddling Through’, Public Administration Review, 19(2): 79–88. Madanipour, A. (2010) Connectivity and Contingency in Planning, Planning Theory, 9(4): 351–368. Madanipour, A. (ed.) (2015a) Planning Theory, 4 volumes, Critical Concepts in Built Environment Series, London: Routledge. Madanipour, A. (2015b) Introduction, in A. Madanipour (ed.) Planning Theory, Volume 1: Planning with Creativity, Critical Concepts in Built Environment Series, London: Routledge, 1–25. Marcuse, P. (1976) Professional Ethics and Beyond: Values in Planning, Journal of the American Institute of Planners, 42(3): 264–274. Pløger, J. (2004) Strife: Urban Planning and Agonism, Planning Theory, 3(1): 71–92. Richardson, T. (1996) Foucauldian Discourse: Power and Truth in Urban and Regional Policy Making, European Planning Studies, 4(3): 279–292. Rittel, H. and Webber, M. (1973) Dilemmas in a General Theory of Planning, Policy Sciences, 4(2): 155–169. Ritzdorf, M. (1992) Feminist Thoughts on the Theory and Practice of Planning, Planning Theory, 7/8:13–19. Sager, T. (1994) Communicative Planning Theory, Aldershot: Ashgate. Sager, T. (2009) Planner’s Role: Torn between Dialogical Ideals and Neo-liberal Realities, European Planning Studies, 17(1): 65–84. Sandercock, L. and Forsyth, A. (1992) A Gender Agenda: New Directions for Planning Theory, Journal of the American Planning Association, 58(1): 49–59. Scott, A. and Roweis, S. (1977) Urban Planning in Theory and Practice, Environment and Planning: A, 9(10): 1097–1119. Vigar, G. (2012) Planning and Professionalism: Knowledge, Judgement and Expertise in English Planning, Planning Theory, 11(4): 361–378. Yiftachel, O. (1998) Planning and Social Control: Exploring the Dark Side, Journal of Planning Literature, 12(4): 395–406. Young, I.M. (1992) Concrete Imagination and Piecemeal Transformation, Planning Theory, 7/8: 59–62. Žižek, S. (1998) Cyberspace, or, How to Traverse the Fantasy in the Age of the Retreat of the Big Other, Public Culture, 10(3): 483–513.

12

PART I

Contemporary Planning Practices

2 SPATIAL PLANNING The Promised Land or Rolled-Out Neoliberalism? Simin Davoudi

Introduction The new millennium marked the revival of strategic spatial planning in many parts of the world (Albrechts et al., 2003, Sartorio, 2005; Healey, 2007; Davoudi and Strange, 2009; Friedmann, 2004; Watson, 2002; Gunder, 2010). In defining what spatial planning is and promoting its virtues, commentators often contrast it with traditional land use planning, master planning, and/or project-based planning. They argue that spatial planning is a long range and strategic approach to place-based integration of sectoral policies. Some suggest that the revival of spatial planning marks a paradigm shift, while others argue that it has introduced a slippery concept. For the former the spatial planning approach is ‘the Promised Land’, while for the latter it is a ‘mirage’ (Cullingworth et al., 2015: 4). Concerns are also raised about having ‘too little or too much’ of spatial planning and ‘the dangers of spatial planning’ particularly when ‘the question of space and spatial organisation is treated separately from other considerations, or when it assumes primacy over these’ (Parr 2005: 120). The terminology itself has been subject to debate, too, and seen as an example of ‘Euro-English’, referring variously to l’amenagement du territoire, Raumordnung, pianificazione territoriale, and urban and regional planning (Salet and Faludi, 2000). In this chapter I would argue that first, the revival of spatial planning in the 2000s was a belated response to the growing realisation that place matters. Second, it coincided with and was informed by two sets of theoretical developments. One is relational space and deals with the object of spatial planning and its substantive focus. The other is communicative action and deals with the normative aspects of spatial planning processes. In practice, while the latter has influenced the discourses of spatial planning, at least at a rhetorical level, the former has been hardy taken up. Third, I would argue that certain interpretations of spatial planning and its theoretical underpinnings have led to its alignment with neoliberal policies and practices.

Place Matters: The Ascendance of Spatial Planning The latter part of the 20th century saw a renewed interest in the critical role played by places and localities in the understanding of social, economic, environmental and cultural relations and in policy decisions. However, as I have argued elsewhere (Davoudi and Strange, 2009), this realisation was interpreted differently by different disciplines. Economic geographers considered 15

Simin Davoudi

the turn to spatiality as the outcome of transition from the Fordist mass production to the post-Fordist flexible specialisation whereby place adds (or takes away) value to new cycles and patterns of productions and consumptions. They argued that place-quality could be an asset for pinning down footloose globalised capital. For political scientists, the trend epitomised the transition from the universal Keynesian welfare states to the competitive Hayekian neoliberal states in which places and territories become key sites of localised service delivery and political contestations. For cultural analysts, the turn to spatiality was a sign of transformation from modernism to post-modernism and the growing diversity of lifestyles and identities. Here, place-quality becomes an important component of the quality of everyday life. Ecologists put the emphasis on the significance of locales in responding to global environmental crises and adapting to climate change. A parallel debate highlighted: the profound restructuring of the state; the move from government to governance; and the emergence of multi-level and networked governance. In this perspective, place is seen as a site for integrating fragmented policy sectors and governance networks and as an organising device for institutional coordination (Nadin, 2007). All these highlighted how the shifts in social, political, environmental and institutional contexts were challenging the traditional sector-based policy making and implementation, and calling for place-based policy formulation. Similar ideas about ‘the defence of locale, of their meaning, of their uses’ were stressed by scholars such as Manuel Castells who considered the role of planning as being the making of ‘new spaces, meaningful places with connecting capabilities’ (Cuthbert, 1996: 8). By the 2000s, the call on planning to become ‘more spatial’ had become pervasive. In response to the disillusionments with land use, master and project-based planning, it was argued that the traditional ways of preparing plans were being replaced with proactive place making (Healey et al., 1997). In Europe, an important mobilising force was the processes that culminated in the publication of the European Spatial Development Perspective in 1999 (Faludi, 2007). In the UK, the growing attention to spatiality was reflected in and reinforced by the Royal Town Planning Institute’s change of corporate identity to: ‘making of place and mediation of space’ and the redefinition of its ‘basic discipline’ as ‘spatial planning’ (RTPI, 2004: 1). Thus, by the end of the 20th century spatial planning became à la mode (Parr, 2005). However, the extent to which its ideals and progressive intents managed to change planning practices is questionable. Indeed, in many parts of the world (including some countries in Europe) master planning remained the dominant mode (UN-Habitat, 2009; Watson, 2002; Cerreta et al., 2010). For example, Hajer and Zonneveld (2000: 350) argue that in the Netherlands ‘the old idea of “survey, analysis, plan” still looms large in the style of planning’. Others caution that attempts to find evidence that match spatial planning ideals can result in ‘shifting our gaze too far from current realities of planning practice’ (Newman, 2008: 1372). More importantly, there is a growing concern that spatial planning has become the carrier of neoliberal values, a point to which I will return.

Theoretical Contexts of Spatial Planning and Their Critiques Two sets of theoretical developments provided the intellectual contexts of spatial planning. One was planning scholars’ belated engagement with the substantive theories of planning and particularly the theorisation of absolute and relational space. The other was their long established interest in procedural theories of planning. I will discuss these in turn but, before that, it is important not to conflate the theories about space and place (i.e. the substantive question of what) with the theories about planning processes (i.e. the procedural question of how). Also, the critique of these theories should not be confused with the criticisms of the 16

Spatial Planning

interpretation and implementation of spatial planning in practice, while acknowledging that aspects of these theories have unintentionally helped the appropriation of spatial planning into neoliberal practices.

Relational Space and Place-Bundles A significant theoretical contribution to the spatial turn in planning came from a relational conceptualisation of space and place which, although new to planners and geographers, has a history that goes back to modernity and its origin in the Enlightenment project (Agnew, 2005). In the 17th century a radically new worldview emerged that was premised on Cartesian duality and its attempt to split the concerns about why the world exists from how it works. The latter became the domain of scientific endeavours that started with discovering the physical world and expanded into exploring the social world in the 18th century. Indeed, one of the hallmarks of modernity is its focus on conceptualising space with the help of foundational contributions from philosophy, physics and geometry and by intellectual giants such as Descartes, Newton, Spinoza, Leibniz, Kant, Minkowski and Einstein. Geometry and the work of Euclid, in particular, played a defining role in the conception of space as absolute. The absolute space enjoyed a long uninterrupted currency and was seen as a leading example of how a priori intellectual intuition can be the main source of scientific knowledge; an idea that was strongly supported by Emanuel Kant. Space, defined by the Euclidean dimensions of ‘height, depth, size and proximity’ (Murdoch, 2006: 12), was seen as the container of the objects. The longstanding influence of Euclid’s geometry was due to its incorporation into Newtonian physics (Scruton, 1996: 361). Newton portrayed space as an infinite container in which objects could be positioned at any point. As Agnew (2005: 83) put it, ‘in the Newtonian view, space is absolute in the sense that it is an entity in itself, independent of whatever objects and events occupy it, containing these objects and events, and having separate powers from them’. In the 19th and 20th centuries, Euclid’s geometry was challenged on a number of grounds by scholars such as Riemann, Minkowski and Lobachewski, but it was not until Einstein’s spacetime theory that space was firmly conceptualised as interdependent with objects and events, and that space is not an abstract entity out there but is socially and culturally produced. As Harvey (1996: 53; original emphasis) suggests: Space and time are neither absolute nor external to processes but are contingent and contained within them. There are multiple spaces and times (and space-times) implicated in different physical, biological and social processes. The latter all produce – to use Lefebvre’s (1974) terminology – their own forms of space and time. Processes do not operate in but actively construct space and time and in so doing define distinctive scales for their development. What gave the relational space a new salience in the 1970s was the work of Henri Lefebvre who rejected the structuralist readings of absolute or abstract space and argued that every society and every mode of production produces its own space. He advocated a multi-dimensional space (which he called ‘trialectic’) consisting of: conceived spaces of cartographers, planners and property speculators, perceived spaces of artists’ and writers’ imaginations, and lived spaces of everyday life (Lefebvre, 1974 [1991]). However, it took nearly 20 years for Lefebvre’s pioneering ideas about relational space to be translated into English and, hence, influence the work of geographers such as David Harvey and Ed Soja. This partly explains why the legacy of Euclid and the Newtonian view of spatiality remained the dominant spatial imaginary in planning well into 17

Simin Davoudi

the second half of the 20th century (Davoudi, 2012). Indeed, Friedmann (1993: 482) cautioned that ‘the conventional concept of planning is so deeply linked to the Euclidian mode that it is tempting to argue that if traditional model has to go, then the very idea of planning must be abandoned’. As mentioned above, geometry played a critical role in the debate about space. A prominent critic of Euclid was Minkowski and his theory of n-dimensional (as opposed to three dimensional) geometries. His work was a source of inspiration for Einstein’s theory of relativity which is often considered as the foundation for the relational view of space. However, the idea that space is relative, and not absolute, has a longer history and played a major role in the development of Leibnitz’s philosophy. He suggested that ‘spatial properties are relational, and the position of any object is to be given in terms of its relation to any other objects’ (Scruton, 1996: 362). This implies that space does not exist independent of objects and events but is constructed from the relations between them. Harvey’s above suggestion that space is not a container but made of processes and substances is, in some ways, a reflection on Leibniz philosophy. Furthermore, in rejecting the structuralist understanding of space, Harvey also asserts that space is not made by underlying structures but by diverse social, economic, cultural and physical processes which, themselves, are ‘made by the relations established between entities of various kinds’ (quoted in Murdoch, 2006: 19). One of the important differences between the Newtonian absolute space and the Leibnitzian relational space is their conceptualisation of place. For the former, space and place are either synonymous or binaries. For the latter, their relationship is dialectical. They represent ‘simultaneity of multiple trajectories’ (Massey, 2005: 61). The relational perspective underpinned the postmodern consciousness of the LA School of geography and particularly the works of Michael Dear and Ed Soja who rejected the absolute nature of space and place and their binary oppositions and instead promoted notions of ‘fluidity, reflexivity, contingency, connectivity, multiplicity and polyvocality’ (Davoudi and Strange, 2009: 37). Doreen Massey, a significant contributor to the rise of relational thinking, suggests that, ‘instead of thinking of places as areas with boundaries around them, they can be imagined as articulated moments in networks of social relations and understanding’ (Massey, 1993: 66). This way of knowing places affirms that people live not ‘in a framework of geometric relationships but a world of meaning’ (Hubbard et al., 2004: 7). Places are both real and imagined assemblages of material, events, discourses and practices. Space and place are socially and culturally produced and their production is infused with power and politics. Although sense of place and affective experience of being here and now play a significant role in framing and making places, affective experiences are themselves iteratively created through social and political processes (Martin, 2003). Relational places are ‘bundles of space-time trajectories’ that individuals bring together through systemic, cognitive and emotional processes (Massey, 2005: 119). These individually made and multi-scalar ‘place-bundles are socially negotiated, constantly changing and contingent’ (Pierce et  al., 2011: 58). Harvey’s description of place making and its ephemeral character is apt. The process of place formation becomes a process of carving out ‘permanences’ from the flow of processes (that are) creating spaces. But the ‘permanences’ – no matter how solid they may seem – are not eternal; they are always subject to time as ‘perpetual perishing’. (Harvey, 1996: 261) Drawing on a number of case studies, Pierce et  al. (2011: 67) affirm Harvey’s temporary permanences by suggesting that, ‘all places are relational, and are always produced through 18

Spatial Planning

networked politics’. It is this inherently political nature of place formation that, at best, overlooked and at worst ostracised, certain interpretation and implementation of spatial planning and, hence, formed the basis of its criticisms, as discussed later.

Critiques of Relational Spatiality Embracing relational space in practice even after the revival of spatial planning has not been easy. The difficulties are evident from a number of empirical studies. For example, a study of six spatial strategies produced in the British Isles after the revival of spatial planning shows that ‘new ideas about relational geography have rarely erased the previous paradigms’ (Davoudi, 2009: 241). It reveals the difficulties of translating relational space into planning practices whose spatial imaginary is still dominated by fixities and certainties of absolute space and bounded place. It concludes that ‘planners’ conceptual interpretations of the socio-spatial processes have remained surprisingly similar to the ones formed in the mid-twentieth century by a positivist view of the world’ (Davoudi, 2009: 243). Jensen and Richardson (2003) draw similar conclusions in their analysis of the European Spatial Development Perspectives (ESDP). Furthermore, a study of regional plans and interviews with planners in Finland also confirms the mismatch between absolute and relational space in everyday planning practices. It demonstrates that ‘despite the current emphasis on networks, flows and connectivity, planning occurs in many respects in a “regional world” that is perpetually characterized by a sort of boundedness and a certain degree of fixity’ (Paasi and Zimmerbauer, 2016: 90). It shows that ‘while borders may be porous or even fuzzy in certain cartographic representations as well as in planning rhetoric, they are often less porous in planning practice that is embedded in statutory contexts’ (ibid.). There are multiple reasons for the persistence of absolute and bounded spatial imaginaries in planning practices. Some commentators blame planners’ limited engagement with theorisation of space and place. Others blame the difficulties of disentangling the absolute from the relational space in planners’ imaginaries. Regarding the former, although social theorists, sociologists and cultural geographers have engaged with spatial theories since the middle of the 20th century, planning scholars have been slow and missed a number of opportunities to do so. One historical opportunity came about in the 1920s when Patrick Geddes offered to the utopian idealism of the time an underpinning of social philosophy and a sociological, rather than merely physical, reading of the city. Another was the introduction of systems theory which led to the so called ‘paradigm shift’ in planning in the 1970s. The shift had two dimensions: one was the positivist view of space and place and the other was the perception of planning (and policy making in general) as a rational process. While the former is about the object of spatial planning and relates to the ‘substantive’ planning theory, the latter relates to ‘procedural’ planning theory and is about the processes of spatial planning and the role of planners in it. Although the rational planning process attracted considerable criticisms from planning theorists (discussed below), the positivist view of spatiality crept almost uncritically into planning thoughts and practices. This led to decades of theoretical disengagement with spatial theories and a disjunction in the development of planning thoughts and practices in which ‘a predominantly positivist planning content stands alongside an emerging poststructuralist planning process’ (Davoudi, 2009: 242). A more recent example of a missed opportunity in the UK was when ‘critical thinking about space and place as the basis for action or intervention’ (RTPI, 2004: 1) was misinterpreted as reintroducing physical design into planning rather than a conceptual engagement with relational space. Therefore, the intellectual and practical challenges of embedding relational space into spatial planning practices have not been fully developed. 19

Simin Davoudi

The second line of reasoning for the limited uptake of relational space in daily spatial planning practices highlights the necessary entanglement of relational and bounded (territorial) space. While the boundedness is temporary, contingent and always becoming, it nevertheless produces powerful spatial imaginaries and shapes the ways in which relations are understood and acted upon. Cochrane and Ward (2012: 7), therefore, argue that, Policy making has to be understood as both relational and territorial; as both in motion and simultaneously fixed, or embedded in place. The conventional distinction that is often made between the two misses the extent to which each necessarily defines and is defined by the other. A similar argument is put forward by Passie and Zimmerbauer (2016: 90) who suggest that: Despite the new planning lexis accentuating fluidity, fuzziness, and connectivity, neither the networks of governance nor the planning itself are able to escape the penumbra of the politico-administrative units. […] Relational and territorial should therefore be viewed not as entirely commensurable categories, but as sometimes, but not always, mutual and intertwining, contextual, dynamic, and contested dimensions in planning practices.

Communicative and Collaborative Planning The second theoretical contribution to the spatial turn in planning came from the communicative conceptualisation of planning processes. Procedural planning theories have a long history dating back to the introduction of systems theory into planning in the 1970s and its subsequent criticisms. Systems theory introduced scientism to the understanding of not only space and place, but also policy making itself (Taylor, 1998). It conceives of planning as a rational process of decision making in which technical experts follow a cycle of logical steps to reach an optimal rational decision. The critics of rational instrumentalism were quick to highlight the mismatch between how decisions ought to be made and the disjointed, incremental and partial processes that characterise how decisions are actually made in practice (Lindblom, 1959). They argue that the ‘messy’ world of planning does not match the neatly defined and sequential steps of comprehensive rational planning in which planners are portrayed as value-neutral and objective experts (Davoudi, 2006). In the 1990s, a new wave of criticisms of rational planning emerged which, although it was inspired by multiple sources of philosophical inspirations, shared a common affinity to Jürgen Habermas’ communicative action. Planning theorists drew on Habermasian deliberative democracy and pragmatist tradition to develop the communicative/collaborative planning theory (CPT) which by the 2000s dominated planning literature and discourses. At the heart of CPT is Habermas’ deliberative democratic response to an age old question: how to reconcile competing agendas, contrasting interests, conflictual objectives and aspirations of different factions of the governed and the governing in liberal democracies (Horowitz, 2013). Habermas’ response is to establish a system of governance whose aim is to achieve consensus, not through trade-offs and compromises but through convergence of preferences toward a socially optimal decision. Such convergence would be achieved through argumentation and opinion/will formation in the public domain. To make such deliberation and consensus possible he advocates ‘communicative action’ defined as: ‘freedom of access, equal rights to participate, truthfulness on the part of participants, absence of coercion in adopting positions, and so on’ (Habermas, 1993: 31). This ‘ideal speech situation’ would arguably enable participants to work together ‘in a cooperative search for truth, where nothing coerces anyone except the force of 20

Spatial Planning

the better argument’ (Habermas, 1990: 198). In this rational argumentation process ‘ear, voice and respect’ are guaranteed for all participants (Dryzek, 1990) who themselves are not ‘primarily oriented to their own individual successes’. Instead they ‘pursue their individual goals under the condition that they can harmonize their plans of action on the basis of common situation definitions’ (Habermas, 1984: 286). The consensus achieved in this way has ‘a rational’ basis because the ‘reflexive’ participants are able to ‘overcome their, at first, subjectively based views in favour of a rationally motivated agreement’ (Habermas, 1987: 315). By minimising what Habermas (1984) calls ‘communicative distortions’ (such as acts of manipulation or misinformation), the power of ‘better argument’ prevails and participants are able to ‘make sense together’ (Forester, 1989: 119), create a ‘shared language’ (Healey, 1997), act in a ‘shared-power-world’ (Bryson and Crosby, 1992) and reach consensus. Drawing on these ideas, CPT has criticised the instrumental rationality of modernist planning in which reasoning is based on scientific, empiricist knowledge. Instead, it has promoted communicative rationality in which reasoning is generated reflexively through intersubjective argumentation and deliberation. The normative aim is to democratise spatial planning processes by empowering the discourses communities and values that are excluded from the decision making over a particular place. The role of a communicative planner is that of a broker, a mediator, or a ‘critical friend’ who enables the process of consensus building. Planners are seen as ‘arbiters of normative standards and guardians of value’ (McGuirk, 2001: 198). Their ultimate aim is to remove power and conflict so that consensual ‘ways of thinking, ways of valuing and ways of acting’ (Healey, 1997: 29) can be created. The influence of CPT in defining spatial planning is evident in the writings of both its proponents and critics for whom the essence of spatial planning is its participatory processes. For example, with regard to the former, Albrechts (2006: 1152) argues that, ‘strategic spatial planning is [. . .] a set of concepts, procedures, and tools’ for achieving ‘desirable outcomes’. It is ‘as much about processes, institutional design, and mobilization as about the development of substantive theories’. The emphasis on process is also evident from a study of Italian strategic spatial plans. Sartorio (2005: 36) concludes that the plans refer ‘primarily to the process and that somehow the spatial dimension [. . .] has disappeared’. Similarly, the critics of CPT suggest that, ‘the failure to find evidence [of spatial planning] in practice is the outcome of the normative direction of the work [referring to CPT] and weaknesses in the theoretical underpinnings of this approach’ (Newman, 2008: 1372).

Critiques of Communicative Planning Critiques of CPT have been diverse, focusing on its: theoretical grounding (Huxley, 2000); idealistic perspective (Tewdwr-Jones and Allmendinger, 1998; Gunder, 2003); normative prescriptions (Fraser, 1990); separation of rationality, knowledge and power (Flyvbjerg, 1998; Pløger, 2004); attempts to reason away powers, interests and inequalities (McGuirk, 2001; FoxRogers and Murphy, 2014); presupposed consensus which risks becoming ‘an instrument of discipline and a rather unbearable group pressure’ (Foucault, 1986: 247); portrayal of planners as ‘people of good-will [. . .] blessed with unusual reflexivity and insight into the constraints on their own and other people’s understandings and actions’ (Huxley, 2000: 376); and confinement of communicative action domain to opinion formation in everyday life which is assumed to be outside the system and the state (ibid.). Despite their diversity, these criticisms share an emphasis on theoretical and practical impossibilities of creating an ideal speech situation in which communicative rationality prevails and consensus emerges. Adding to these is a more radical critique of Habermas’ communicative action by scholars such as Chantal Mouffe and those drawing on Jacques Lacan. They question 21

Simin Davoudi

not just the possibility of consensus building, but also its desirability. Mouffe challenges the powerblind model of deliberative democracy and argues that the idea of ‘dissolving’ power relations ‘through a rational debate’ is not only illusive, it can also ‘endanger democratic institutions’ (Mouffe, 2000: 17). This means that the problem with communicative action is not just that it cannot be delivered but that it is harmful to liberal democracy if it is pursued. Because ‘every consensus exists as a temporary result of a provisional hegemony, as a stabilization of power’, and ‘it always entails some form of exclusion’ (ibid.). Referring to the contested nature of politics and the political, Mouffe (2005: 73) questions the ideal of a consensus-based politics and argues that ‘there is no consensus without exclusion, no we without a they, and no politics is possible without the drawing of a frontier’. She, therefore, advocates a form of ‘agonistic pluralism’ which keeps the democratic contestation alive and acknowledges ‘the dimension of undecidedability and the ineradicability of antagonism, which are constitutive of the political’. In this way, democratic citizenship can be envisioned by putting ‘the emphasis on the type of practices not the forms of argumentation’ (Mouffe, 2000: 21; original emphasis). Thus, a consensus-oriented democracy risks becoming radically undemocratic because the search for consensus risks the evacuation of the political, de-politicisation of particulars, elimination of genuine political space for disagreement and contestation, renouncement or displacement of social conflicts, and foreclosure of ‘proper political framing’ (Swyngedouw, 2010: 2019). To avoid this, critics argue for the creation of agonistic arenas (Hillier, 2003), for ‘radical politicisation of planning’, and for ‘a reorientation of planning theory from normative to a political basis’ (McGuirk, 2001: 214). It is worth stressing that although CPT has been influential in defining spatial planning, the two are not the same. Some recent critiques of spatial planning tend to conflate it with CPT (e.g. Allmendinger and Haughton, 2012). This not only ignores the contribution of spatial theories to the revival of spatial planning, it also perpetuates the over-emphasis on procedural aspects of planning and undermines its substantive aspects. Although, like relational space, communicative planning uses the poststructuralist language of fluidity, difference and place specificities, it should not be confused with spatial theories because the former is essentially a normative prescription about how to do planning, while the latter is a substantive theory about the object of planning, i.e., space and place. As Huxley and Yiftachel (2000: 334) suggest: The communicative planning field […] shares […] a tendency to see planning as a mainly procedural field of activity […]. There is the same sense of searching for the right decision-rules be they rational-comprehensive or rational-communicative, universal or local. In fact, the two theories are so far apart that Harvey was surprised to see that CPT has taken its inspiration from Habermas because, ‘Habermas has, in short, no conception of how spatiotemporalities and “places” are produced and how that process is integral to the process of communicative action and of valuation’ (Harvey, 1996: 354).

Neoliberalisation of Spatial Planning The saying goes that the road to hell is paved with good intentions. Planning theorists should therefore not ignore critique suggesting that their well-intentioned reforms are being transformed and perverted by economic-political forces only to end up making society less rather than more democratic. (Sager, 2005: 7) 22

Spatial Planning

The history of planning is not short of examples of ‘the high-sounding ideals of planning theory’ being ‘translated to grubby practices on the ground’ (Harvey, 1985: 184). Spatial planning ideals appear to have followed such a destiny. There is growing evidence from different places (Cerreta et al., 2010; Allmendinger and Haughton, 2012; Murray and Neill, 2011; Olesen and Richardson, 2012; Van den Broeck, 2008; Waterhout et al., 2013) that shows how the progressive ideas that underpinned the revival of spatial planning have been ‘hijacked and misused to promote neoliberal models of spatial development’ (Olesen, 2014: 289). In attempts to understand why and how spatial planning has become a carrier of neoliberal agendas, commentators have drawn on the above mentioned critiques of its theoretical contexts and particularly that of CPT. It is argued that neoliberalisation of spatial planning is manifested in (a) the shift in the purposes and values of planning, and (b) the de-politicisation of the planning processes, with the latter enabling the former. In many western countries spatial planning was a constitutive part of the post-war welfare state and its social democratic ideals. It was born out of the belief in governments’ right and duty to intervene in and regulate the free markets and use redistributive measures to seek efficiency, equity and socio-spatial cohesion. The purpose of planning was, therefore, to regulate the land and property markets, counteract their negative social and environmental impacts, and improve the quality of places and people’s lives. These social democratic intentions, however, were undermined by the formulaic routines, bureaucratic procedures and the shoehorning of diverse identities into universal prescriptions. In the midst of a widespread disillusionment with these overpowering tendencies, the revival of spatial planning was celebrated from across the political spectrum. However, the motivations for change and the prescriptions for the way forward differed considerably. Those drawing on relational spatiality and communicative planning were advocating a more creative, imaginative, transformative and democratic planning, while those with neoliberal mentalities were seeking further market freedom and toothless planning systems. For them, the purpose of planning is not to regulate the market and correct its failures and its excessive socio-spatial injustices but to enable it, to pave the way for it, and to become the delivery mechanism for pro-market strategies. Despite their radically different motivations, it appears that the progressive critiques of land use regulatory planning have been unintentionally aligned with neoliberal strategies and unwittingly provided the intellectual grounding for their regressive agendas. As mentioned above, neoliberalisation of spatial planning has been rolled out in many countries, albeit in different forms and with different intensity and speed. For example, in Nordic countries a ‘hybrid between traditional welfare state spatial planning ideas and growth-oriented neoliberal strategic planning approaches’ is emerging (Olesen, 2014: 289; Ahlqvist and Moisio, 2014; Andersen and Pløger, 2007; Galland, 2012; Mäntysalo and Saglie, 2010). However, perhaps nowhere was the alignment between the progressive and regressive agendas as pronounced as in the UK. Here, the collaborative planning’s emphasis on consensus mapped conveniently onto government’s ‘joined-up’ approach to policy and ‘Third Way’ approach to politics. The former echoed the definition of spatial planning as an integrative activity, yet one whose purpose was to enable and deliver market growth. The latter promoted a form of politics that, like communicative action, aimed at achieving consensus among traditionally opposite political perspectives by bringing them under a ‘big tent’ in the centre. Such alignments were probably helped by the fact that the structuration theory of Anthony Giddens, a key intellectual advocate of the Third Way politics, provided an influential input into some accounts of CPT (e.g. Healey, 2007). CPT’s emphasis on consensus, interpreted as a search for win-win solutions to contested planning problems, seemed to have unintentionally legitimised the de-politicisation of the planning processes. Therefore, ‘carefully stage-managed processes with subtly but clearly defined parameters 23

Simin Davoudi

of what is open to debate’ (Allmendinger and Haughton, 2012) have been pursued in the name of consensus building. Similarly, the ideals of relational space and its representation in the form of ‘fuzzy maps’ (Davoudi and Strange, 2009: 38) have been misused to ‘blur or camouflage the spatial politics [. . .] and depoliticise strategic spatial planning’ (Olesen, 2014: 297).

Conclusion The early 2000s witnessed the revival of spatial planning which was triggered by a growing recognition of the significance of place in understanding economic dynamics, environmental sustainability, social justice, and governance practices and processes. This was informed by two theoretical perspectives: one related to the object of planning and the other to the planning process. The former promoted a move from the understanding of space and place as absolute, bounded, fixed and neutral containers of people and activities, toward a relational, fluid, contingent and socially constructed spatiality infused with power relations. The latter advocated a move from instrumental to communicative rationality and from exclusive to inclusive planning processes aimed at consensus seeking through deliberative democratic dialogues. Both the theoretical underpinnings and the implementation of spatial planning in practice have been subject to criticisms. At the theoretical level, in line with a long established trend in planning theory of focusing predominantly on planning processes, CPT has attracted more critiques than relational space. The first wave of critiques focused on the practical impossibility of undistorted communicative rationality and informed consensus formation. The second wave has drawn on post-political literature to stress the undesirability of consensus seeking and communicative action. Both have raised concerns about the perceived role of planners as ‘super human’, well-intentioned mediators and facilitators of deliberations. As regards relational space, Nyseth (2012: 41) summed up the key arguments by suggesting that, ‘Too much fluidity, or fluidity going “wild”, would mean not only losing control, but also, in a sense, giving up the ambition of steering, which would certainly give other forces more room to maneuver’. At the level of practice, the ideals of spatial planning have not lived up to their expectation, and their implementations are increasingly distanced from the good intentions of their theoretical underpinnings. Planners find it difficult to translate the relational space into the administrative, legal confines of planning practice. The ‘fuzziness’ of relational space has become a mechanism for de-politicisation of competing and conflictual territorial claims. Similarly, the desire for collaboration and win-win solution has tended to circumscribe debate and depoliticise the politics of place making. The role of planning has changed from the regulator of the market to its facilitator. It is more about delivering economic growth and competitiveness than ameliorating social and environmental injustices. In many ways the consensus seeking collaboration appears to have worked against the idea of relational space as being socially produced through the inherently political processes that planners are part of. Finally, in criticising spatial planning practices, we should be careful not to ‘throw the baby out with the bathwater’. The term ‘spatial’ provided planners a way of breaking free from the theoretical rigidities of using bounded geographical units and binary concepts such as ‘urban’ and ‘rural’ or ‘local’ and ‘global’. The focus on spatiality has triggered debates about the production of space and politics of place making. So, there is nothing wrong with ‘spatial planning’ per se. Spatiality matters, and planning as a specifically spatial practice is deeply embroiled in the politics of place making. Similarly, communicative action has provided an opportunity to challenge the idea of planning as an instrumentally rational process of decision making and advocated inclusive and democratic processes, even though its emphasis on consensus has been used to foreclose political debates. Therefore, the critique of spatial planning should further 24

Spatial Planning

focus on its misuses which (a) portray it as a process that disciplines the adversaries toward a consensus and shrink the political space, and (b) attempt to replace its social democratic values and purposes with a neoliberal agenda of facilitating market transactions. It is this co-option of spatial planning into the dominating neoliberal agendas of economic boosterism, and the stripping away of planning’s welfare values that should be the focus of critique.

References Agnew, J. (2005) Space: Place. In P. Cloke and R. Johnson (eds) Spaces of Geographical Thought, London: Sage. Ahlqvist, T. and Moisio, S. (2014) Neoliberalisation in a Nordic state: From cartel polity towards a corporate policy in Finland. New Political Economy, 19(1): 21–55. Albrechts, L. (2006) Shifts in strategic spatial planning? Some evidence from Europe and Australia, Environment and Planning A, 38(6): 1149–1170. Albrechts, L., Healey, P. and Kunzmann, K. (2003) Strategic spatial planning and regional governance in Europe. Journal of the American Planning Association, 69(2): 113–129. Allmendinger, P. and Haughton, G. (2012) Post-political spatial planning in England: A crisis of consensus? Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers, 37: 89–103. Andersen, J. and Pløger, J. (2007) The dualism of urban governance in Denmark. European Planning Studies, 15(10): 1349–1367. Bryson, J. and Crosby, B. (1992) Leadership for the Common Good: Tackling Public Problems in a Shared-Power World, San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass. Cerreta, M., Concilio, G. and Monno, V. (eds) (2010) Making Strategies in Spatial Planning: Knowledge and Values, Dordrecht: Springer Science + Business Media B.V. Cochrane, A. and Ward, K. (2012) Guest editorial: Researching the geographies of policy mobility: Confronting the methodological challenges. Environment and Planning A, 44: 5–12. Cullingworth, B., Nadin, V., Hart, T., Davoudi, S., et al. (2015) Town and Country Planning in the UK, 15th Edition, London: Routledge. Cuthbert, A. (1996) An interview with Manuel Castells. Cities, 13(1): 3–11. Davoudi, S. (2006) Evidence-based planning: rhetoric and reality. DISP, 165(2): 14–25. Davoudi, S. (2009) Asymmetric development in spatial planning: Positivist content and poststructuralist processes? In S. Davoudi and I. Strange (eds) Conceptions of Space and Place in Strategic Spatial Planning, London: Routledge, 207–243. Davoudi, S. (2012) The legacy of positivism and the emergence of interpretive tradition in spatial planning. Regional Studies, 46(4): 429–441. Davoudi, S. and Strange, I. (2009) Space and place in the twentieth century planning: An analytical framework and an historical review. In S. Davoudi and I. Strange (eds) Conceptions of Space and Place in Strategic Spatial Planning, London: Routledge, 7–42. Dryzek, J. (1990) Deliberative Democracy: Politics, policy and political science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Faludi, A. (ed.) (2007) Territorial Cohesion and European Model of Society, Cambridge, MA: The Lincoln Institute for Land Policy. Flyvbjerg, B. (1998) Rationality and Power: Democracy in Practice, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Forester, J. (1989) Planning in the Public Domain, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Foucault, M. (1986) The Foucault Reader. Edited by P. Rabinow, Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin. Fox-Rogers, L. and Murphy, E. (2014) Informal strategies of power in the local planning system. Planning Theory, 13(3): 244–268. Fraser, N. (1990) Rethinking the public sphere: A contribution to the critique of actually existing democracy. Social Text, 25/26: 56–80. Friedmann, J. (1993) Toward a non-Euclidean mode of planning. Journal of the American Planning Association, 59(4): 482–485. Friedmann, J. (2004) Strategic planning and the longer range. Planning Theory and Practice, 5(1): 49–67. Galland, D. (2012) Is regional planning dead or just coping? The transformation of a state socio-spatial project into growth-oriented strategies. Environment and Planning C: Government and Policy, 30(3): 536–552. Gunder, M. (2003) Passionate planning for the other’s desire: An agonistic response to the dark side of planning. Progress in Planning, 60(3): 235–319.

25

Simin Davoudi Gunder, M. (2010) Planning as the ideology of (neoliberal) space. Planning Theory, 9(4): 298–314. Habermas, J. (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol.1 Reason and the Rationalisation of Society, Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1987) The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Habermas, J. (1990) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Habermas, J. (1993) Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hajer, M. and Zonneveld, W. (2000) Spatial planning in the network society: Rethinking the principles of planning in the Netherlands. European Planning Studies, 8(3): 337–355. Harvey, D. (1985) The Urbanisation of Capital, London: Blackwell. Harvey, D. (1996) Justice, Nature and Geography of Difference, Oxford: Blackwell. Healey, P. (1997) Collaborative Planning: Shaping Places in Fragmented Societies, London: Macmillan. Healey, P. (2007) Urban Complexity and Spatial Strategies: Towards a Relational Planning for Our Times, London: Routledge. Hillier, J. (2003) Agon’izing over consensus: Why Habermasian ideals cannot be ‘real’. Planning Theory, 2(1): 37–59. Horowitz, L.S. (2013) Toward empathic agonism: Conflicting vulnerabilities in urban wetland governance. Environment and Planning A, 45: 2344–2361. Hubbard, P., Kitchin, R. and Valentine, G. (2004) Editors’ introduction. In P. Hubbard, R. Kitchin, and G. Valentine (eds) Key Thinkers on Space and Place, London: Sage, 1–15. Huxley, M. (2000) The limits to communicative planning. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 19: 369–377. Huxley, M. and Yiftachel, O. (2000) New paradigm or old myopia? Unsettling the communicative turn in planning theory. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 19: 333–342. Jensen, O.B. and Richardson, T. (2003) Being on the map: The new iconographies of power over European space. International Planning Studies, 8(1): 9–34. Lefebvre, H. (1974 [1991]) The Production of Space, Oxford: Blackwell (translated from the original 1974 edition by N. Donaldson-Smith). Lindblom, C.E. (1959) The science of ‘muddling through’. Public Administration Review, 19: 79–88. Mäntysalo, R. and Saglie, I.L. (2010) Private influence preceding public involvement: Strategies for legitimizing preliminary partnership arrangements in urban housing planning in Norway and Finland. Planning Theory & Practice, 11(3): 317–338. Martin, D. (2003) Place-framing as place-making: Constituting a neighborhood for organizing and activism. Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 93: 730–750. Massey, D. (1993) Power-geometries and a progressive sense of place. In J. Bird et al. (eds) Mapping the Futures, Routledge: London, 59–69. Massey, D. (2005) For Space, London: Sage. McGuirk, P.M. (2001) Situating communicative planning theory: Context, power, and knowledge. Environment and Planning A, 33: 195–217. Mouffe, C. (2000) Deliberative Democracy or Agonistic Pluralism, Political Science Series 72, Institute for Advanced Studies, Vienna. Mouffe, C. (2005) On the Political, London: Routledge. Murdoch, J. (2006) Post-structuralist Geography, London: Sage. Murray, M.R. and Neill, W.J.V. (2011) Strategic spatial planning in Berlin-Brandenburg: A requiem for balanced development? Planning Practice & Research, 26(1): 107–121. Nadin, W. (2007) The emergence of the spatial planning approach in England. Planning Practice and Research, 22(1): 43–62. Newman, P. (2008) Strategic spatial planning: Collective action and moments of opportunity. European Planning Studies, 16(10): 1371–1383. Nyseth, T. (2012) Fluid planning: A meaningless concept or a rational response to uncertainty in urban planning? In J. Burian (ed.) Advances in Spatial Planning, Rijeka: InTech, 27–46. Olesen, K. (2014) The neoliberalisation of strategic spatial planning. Planning Theory, 13(3): 289–303. Olesen, K. and Richardson, T. (2012) Strategic spatial planning in transition: Contested rationalities and spatial logics in 21st century Danish spatial planning. European Planning Studies, 20(10): 1689–1706. Paasi, A. and Zimmerbauer, K. (2016) Penumbral borders and planning paradoxes: Relational thinking and the question of borders in spatial planning. Environment and Planning A, 48(1): 75–93. Parr, J. (2005) Spatial planning: Too little or too much? Scienze Regionali, 4(2): 113–129.

26

Spatial Planning Pierce, J., Martin, D. and Murphy, J.T. (2011) Relational place-making: The networked politics of place. Transaction of the Institute of British Geographers, NS 36, 54–70. Pløger, J. (2004) Strife: Urban planning and agonism. Planning Theory, 3(1): 71–92. RTPI (The Royal Town Planning Institute) (2004) Policy Statement on Initial Planning Education, London: RTPI. Sager, T. (2005) Communicative planners as naïve mandarins of the neo-liberal state? European Journal of Spatial Development, December 2005. Available at: www.nordregio.se/en/European-Journal-ofSpatial-Development/Debate/ (accessed 20/3/2016). Salet, W. and Faludi, A. (eds) (2000) The Revival of Strategic Spatial Planning, Amsterdam: Koninklijke, Nedelands Akademie van wetenschappen. Sartorio, F.S. (2005) Strategic spatial planning. disP; The Planning Review, 41: 162, 26–40. Scruton, R. (1996) Modern Philosophy: An Introduction and Survey, London: Mandarin. Swyngedouw, E. (2010) Apocalypse forever? Post-political pluralism and the spectre of climate change. Theory, Culture and Society, 27: 213–232. Taylor, N. (1998) Urban Planning Theory since 1945, London: Sage. Tewdwr-Jones, M. and Allmendinger, P. (1998) Deconstructing communicative rationality: A critique of Habermasian collaborative planning. Environment and Planning A, 30: 1975–1989. UN-Habitat (2009) The UN-Habitat Global Report On Human Settlements 2009: Planning Sustainable Cities, London: Earthscan. Van den Broeck, P. (2008) The changing position of strategic spatial planning in Flanders: A socio-political and instrument-based perspective. International Planning Studies, 13(3): 261–283. Waterhout, B., Othengrafen, F. and Sykes, O. (2013) Neo-liberalization processes and spatial planning in France, Germany, and the Netherlands: An exploration. Planning Research & Practice, 28(1): 141–159. Watson, V. (2002) Change and Continuity in Spatial Planning, London: Routledge.

27

3 STRATEGIC PLANNING Ontological and Epistemological Challenges Louis Albrechts

Introduction In a surprising number of countries, planning systems have changed little from the traditional models of the 1970s, and even where the nature of plans have changed, the basic principles of the regulatory system tend to remain. This is cause for serious concern given the nature and scale of problems and challenges that places all over the world are now facing: problems involving poverty, persistent inequality, environmental issues (global warming, flooding), the right to mobility and so on. Secchi and Viganó (2011) frame the current condition of cities all over the world as raising new urban questions in connection with globalizing markets and financial systems. They argue that new principles, concepts and theories are required that can act as guides for finding reliable solutions for complex problems. Statutory planning instruments, such as master plans and land-use plans, seem to be ineffective because their focus is often on maintaining the existing social order rather than challenging and transforming it. They are designed for situations of stability, certainty and reasonable clarity of problems to be addressed, traits that are lacking in contemporary cities. In this way, they fail to capture the dynamics and tensions of relations coexisting in particular places (Albrechts and Balducci, 2013). Traditional spatial planning becomes less focused on the visionary and imagining the impossible, and more concerned with pragmatic negotiations around the immediate in a context of the seeming inevitability of market-based forms of political rationality (Haughton et al., 2013: 232). Some urban transformation narratives become hegemonic because they are in line with wider discourses such as the rise of neoliberalism. The rollout of neoliberal policy privileges urban and regional competitiveness, mainly through the subordination of social policy to economic policy, allows for more elitist forms of partnerships and networks (Jessop, 2000; Allmendinger and Haughton, 2009: 618) and limits the scope for genuinely innovative development. City governments are lured to adopt an entrepreneurial style of planning in order to enhance competitiveness. As a result, planning faces major ontological and epistemological challenges. These may include the scope of planning, approaches, use of skills, resources, knowledge base and the involvement of a wider range of actors. It is therefore argued that spatial planning is in desperate need of a critical debate that questions the political and economic processes of which existing planning approaches are an integral part (see Sager, 2013: xviii), as well as a need for fresh ideas and approaches (see Allmendinger and Haughton, 2010: 328). Within the architectural/urbanism 28

Strategic Planning

discipline an approach to land-use regulation emerged through a new generation of strategic (mainly urban) projects – especially for the revival of rundown parts of cities and regions – such as the French ‘Projet de ville’ (see Secchi, 1986). In addition to traditional sectoral and technical knowledge, design operations provide a specific and original body of knowledge (see Viganó, 2010). In this approach urban design, as an instrument to analyze and to read places, uses images and representations to reveal qualities of existing spaces and places and their possible futures. The influential Barcelona model provides a link between an urban design component involving small-scale interventions to upgrade neighborhoods and improve the image of the city, and a strategic planning component. In the 1990s, strategic approaches, frameworks, and perspectives for cities, city-regions, and regions became fashionable in Europe, Australia and, mainly through the impact of the Barcelona model and UN-Habitat, in Latin-America and Africa (see Borja and Castells, 1997; Healey et  al., 1997; Albrechts, 1999; Salet and Faludi, 2000; Borja, 2000; Tibaijuka, 2005, UN-Habitat, 2009; Gonzáles, 2011). This chapter focuses first on the roots of strategic planning, its aims, logic and some critiques. In a second part I focus on four dimensions that aim to explain the strategic nature of planning. I hereby rely on theoretical literature (Healey, 1997a, 2009; Gonzáles, 2011; Balducci et al., 2011; Haughton et al., 2013; Albrechts, 2013, 2015), a dissection of planning processes all over the world (Albrechts et al., 2017) and my experience in practice.

Strategic Spatial Planning: History, Logic, Aims, Critique Patsy Healey, together with other authors (see Albrechts, 2001, 2004; Balducci et al., 2011), has gradually developed a definition. She defines strategic planning as: ‘a social process through which a range of people in diverse institutional relations and positions come together to design plan-making processes and develop contents and strategies for the management of spatial change’ (Healey, 1997a: 5). For Healey (1997a) strategic planning provides an opportunity for building new ideas and building processes that can carry them forward. Strategic planning is looked upon as ‘self-conscious collective efforts to re-imagine a city, urban region or wider territory and to translate the result into priorities for area investment, conservation measures, strategic infrastructure investments and principles of land use regulation’ (see Healey, 2000: 46). Interpreted in this way, strategic planning deploys one of its most interesting potentials, its capacity to produce action frameworks and interpretative images capable of mobilizing people to action and, in some cases, of constructing a new governance culture (Albrechts et al., 2003). Just as in planning, generally speaking, there are different traditions of strategic spatial planning and as these different traditions/origins leave a mark on the way strategic planning is applied I reflect briefly on its history, logic, aims and critiques formulated.

History The word strategy has its roots within a military context (see Sun Tzu, 1994 [500bc]). The focus is on accurate understanding of the real situation, realistic goals, focused orientation of available strength and persistence of the action. In the early 1980s, the state and local governments in the US were called upon to use the strategic planning approach developed in the corporate world (Kaufman and Jacobs, 1987). Bryson (1995) stresses the need to gather the key (internal and external) stakeholders (preferably key decision makers). Moreover, he stresses the importance of external trends and forces, and the active involvement of senior level managers, to construct 29

Louis Albrechts

a longer term vision. In the 1960s and 1970s strategic spatial planning in a number of Western countries evolved toward a system of comprehensive planning at different administrative levels. In the 1980s a retreat from strategic planning can be witnessed, fueled not only by the neoconservative disdain for planning, but also by postmodernist skepticism, both of which tend to view progress as something which, if it happens, cannot be planned (Healey, 1997a). Instead, the focus of urban and regional planning practices was on projects (Secchi, 1986), especially for the revival of rundown parts of cities and regions, and on land-use regulations. Gradually a definition of strategic planning developed that is clearly different from the military and the corporate stance. In the 1990s a growing literature and an increasing number of practices seem to suggest that strategic spatial planning could provide an answer to the shortcomings of statutory planning (Healey, 1997a, 1997b, 2006, 2007; Albrechts, 2004, 2013, 2015; Tibaijuka, 2005; UN-Habitat, 2009; Albrechts and Balducci, 2013; Balducci et al., 2011). It is not surprising that these ideas and practices started to travel. The Barcelona model (see Borja and Castells, 1997; Borja, 2000; Gonzáles, 2011) became very influential. Strategic planning in Barcelona1 has been limited to creating an environment of civic debate in which the economic actors, public entities, social and labor organizations, and professional and academic sectors are equal. It has served to promote or legitimize public and mixed projects and programs, contribute to their coherence, and reflect on the future (Borja, 2000). In 2005, in four volumes (quick guide, manual, toolkit and action guide) UN-Habitat promotes local economic development through strategic planning. Here the strategic approach implies careful consideration of the various trade-offs and making difficult choices. It demands harnessing and mobilizing the local human, social, financial and natural capital towards the common vision, goals and objectives that the community aspires to achieve. This is possible only when various actors join forces to make a difference in quality of life in their cities, towns and settlements. (Tibaijuka, 2005: iii) In a 2009 publication, UN-Habitat stresses that strategic spatial planning also has a crucial institutional dimension. … Coordination and integration of policy ideas of line-function departments is essential (because planning is not just about the functional use of land), and the plan itself cannot achieve this coordination. New institutional relationships must evolve to do this. (UN-Habitat, 2009: 61) With support from UN-Habitat and the African Network of Urban Management Institutions, strategic plans based on the Millennium Development Goals were drawn up. ‘Integrating the MDGs within planning made it possible to rectify certain major shortcomings encountered in master planning’. The approach made available a strategic spatial framework with time horizons and indicators of objectives. It gave an understanding of the realities and trends in the implementation of the MDGs at the urban level. The approach made it possible to acquire information to identify the actions to take ‘in order to improve living conditions and access to basic social services at the urban level. It made available indicators for monitoring the strategic plan and, thus, strengthened public accountability’ (UN-Habitat, 2009: 61–62). As a result of a reawakening of ‘the political’ based on equality (see Swyngedouw, 2014 in line with Rancière), a demand for transformative practices leads to a call for a more radical strategic planning (Albrechts, 2013, 2015). It is based on dealing with structural issues, co-production 30

Strategic Planning

as a political strategy2 and in this way as a base for democratic engagement, working with conflicts and legitimacy.

Logic, Aims and Critiques The motivations for using strategic spatial planning in practice vary. However, the objectives – as demonstrated in its history – have typically been: to construct a challenging, coherent and coordinated vision and to frame an integrated long-term spatial logic (for land-use regulation, for resource protection, for sustainable development, for spatial quality, sustainability, equity, etc.). It aims to enhance action-orientation beyond the idea of planning as control and to promote a more open multi-level type of governance. Despite a certain popularity of strategic spatial planning, one cannot be blind to the critique articulated on strategic planning (Metzger, 2012). The critiques focus on very different registers of the strategic spatial planning approach (Albrechts, 2015). Some of the criticisms are related to the ontology and epistemology of strategic planning. Questions are raised on how and to what extent the shift from a Euclidean concept of stable entities toward a non-Euclidean concept of many space-time geographies is reflected in strategic spatial planning? How are the different types of knowledge (tacit/experiential knowledge of local communities versus traditional scientific knowledge) relevant for a more relational approach to strategic planning reflected in strategic plans and actions based on these plans? Economic, political and ideological critiques draw a link between the rise of strategic spatial planning and the strengthened neoliberal political climate (see Leal de Oliveira (2000a) on strategic planning in Rio de Janeiro; see also the interesting exchange (2000a) between Borja and Fabricio Leal de Oliveira, and Carlos B. Vainer in Progressive Planning Magazine (both available on Planners Network (www.plannersnetwork.org/)). In this respect questions are raised whether strategic spatial planning practices are able to resist the hegemonic discourses of neoliberalism (see Olesen, 2011). Some attack the militaristic and corporate terminology of strategic planning (see Leal de Oliveira, 2000a). Other critics argue that the results of strategic planning, in terms of improvement of the quality of places, have been modest. They ask whether actually existing practices of strategic spatial planning really follow their normative groundings and they point at its weakness in theoretical underpinnings (Newman, 2008; Monno, 2010). Monno (2010) and Moulaert (2011) question the conditions under which visions would materialize, the lack of concern about the path dependency of the resources, a too sequential view of the relationships between visioning, action, structure, institutions and discourse. Concern is raised about the legitimation of strategic spatial planning, the role of expertise and knowledge, and how to introduce transformative practices (see Albrechts, 2010). Most strategic planning processes react against perceived shortcomings of statutory planning. Statutory planning is blamed for the lack of political, economic and environmental consideration; the rigidity of planning methods; its incapability to deal with uncertainty and tackle flexibility; its view of space as a container that holds objects inside with distinctive physical and administrative boundaries; and the fact that statutory plans serve only (mainly) as binding documents to obtain building permits (see different chapters in Albrechts et al., 2017). So in other words ‘statutory plans serve the purpose of both generating a conception of a place and the locales within it and of defining the legal and spatial parameters within which rights to develop sites and properties are developed’ (see Vigar et al., 2005: 1408). The shifts from control to framing, from an extended present to becoming, from comprehensive to selective, from masterplans and land-use plans to probes of the future, strategies, projects and distributive justice, from places as containers toward many space-time geographies, all constitute not only epistemological challenges but also fundamental ontological issues. 31

Louis Albrechts

Potential Critical Features Explaining the Strategic Nature of Planning The theory and practices of strategic planning demonstrate that strategic planning involves content and process, statics and dynamics, constraints and aspiration, the cognitive and the collective. It involves the planned and the learned, the socioeconomic and the political, the public and the private. It has a focus on the vision and the action, the local and the global, legitimacy and a revised democratic tradition, values and facts, selectivity and integrativity, equality and power, long term and short term. In the next paragraphs these elements are defined according to a set of inherent features that are considered essential to the identity and functioning of strategic planning (see Healey, 2009; Albrechts and Balducci, 2013; Albrechts et al., 2017). They belong to four relevant dimensions: content- and context-related, visioning embedded in becoming, relational nature, and legitimacy.

Context- and Content-Related Political and Institutional Context Strategic spatial planning needs a contextual understanding of power and material interests, of (leading) discourses and the constraints of a more-of-the-same attitude (see also proposition 4 by Huxley and Yiftachel, 2000: 339). The context forms the setting of the strategic planning process but also takes form and undergoes changes in the process (see Dyrberg, 1997). For some (Olesen and Richardson, 2012: 1690; UN-Habitat, 2009) strategic planning needs a specific political and institutional context and is sensitive to specific intellectual traditions. The capacity of a strategic spatial planning system to deliver the desired outcomes is dependent not only on the legalpolitical system itself, but also on the conditions underlying it. These conditions affect the ability of planning systems to implement the chosen strategies. New ideas and concepts need to be able to travel into different contexts to change and to be changed by the dominant culture. Strategic planning does not do any work on its own. It needs change agents, what Kingdon (2003) has described as ‘policy entrepreneurs’ (a champion in the terminology of Bryson, 1995) to take the approach and deploy it. The influence is not direct, but works through multiple processes in which relevant actors can see an opportunity to use strategic planning to push forward a policy change (see Sorensen, 2010: 133). Actors interpret strategic planning differently and will adopt those aspects of the approach that best fit their own situation. This might be a choice for elements that promise to solve some problems and can be implemented or reinterpreted within the frameworks of existing planning tools (see Healey and Upton, 2010). Practices illustrate that dominant models are sometimes reimagined as smoke screens behind which agendas of privatization are implemented. For Leal de Oliveira (2000b) and Vainer (2000) the Barcelona model has opened up in Rio de Janeiro a door for more corporate-friendly strategic planning techniques and mega urban projects (see also Gonzáles, 2011: 1412). Such projects have become a key component of a neoliberal shift from distributive policies, welfare considerations and direct service provision toward more market-oriented and market-dependent approaches aimed at pursuing economic promotion and competitive restructuring (see Swyngedouw et al., 2002: 572). A challenge in contemporary governance – and by extension in strategic planning – consists in the dialectic between movements that seek democratization, collective decision-making and empowerment of citizens on the one hand and the established institutions and structures that seek to reabsorb such demands into a distributive framework on the other (see Young, 1990: 90). The question concerning who is to be considered an actor in a particular context or situation is not only an epistemological challenge, but also a fundamentally ontological issue (Metzger, 32

Strategic Planning

2012: 782). One can find a very wide variety of actors in strategic planning practices (Vainer, 2000; Albrechts, 2006; Albrechts et al., 2017): city, regional, and national governments, sector departments, agencies, banks, universities, chambers of commerce, trade unions, associations of entrepreneurs, cultural organizations, civic associations, consumer organizations. The search of strategic planning for new scales of policy articulation and new policy concepts is also linked to attempts to widen the range of actors involved in policy processes, with new alliances, actor partnerships and consultative processes (Albrechts et al., 2001, 2003; Healey et al., 1997).

Content One of the most important manifestations of legal and spiritual life is the fact that whoever has true power is able to determine the content of concepts and words (Schmitt, 1988: 202). With regard to crucial political (and by extension strategic planning) concepts it depends on who interprets, defines and uses them. Who concretely defines the visions, the strategies, the actions? Who defines what spatial quality, what equity, what accountability, what legitimacy are? As a transformative process strategic planning produces visions or frames of reference, the justification for coherent actions, and the means for implementation that shape and frame what a place is and what it might become (Albrechts, 2001, 2004). Visions and concrete actions must accept the full complexity of a place while focusing on local assets and networks in a global context, social justice, spatial quality, and a fair distribution of the joys and burdens. Where statutory planning ends up – as a result of its legal status – in a closed system, the political potential of strategic planning lies in its dimension to broaden the scope of the possible and imagine the impossible. This implies the development of relational more-than-human perspectives as a way to broaden the concepts used (see Metzger, 2014).

Selectivity Strategic spatial planning defines issues and shapes actions as a result. Much of the process, which is inherently political in nature, lies in making tough decisions about what is most important for the purpose of producing fair, structural responses to problems, challenges, aspirations, and potential. Thus, strategic planning involves choice, valuation, judgment, and decisions that relate to envisioned agreed-upon ends and to the selection of the most appropriate means, not in a purely instrumental sense, for coping with and implementing such ends. In strategic planning, the overall picture that inspires choices is not given by a comprehensive analysis, but rather by synthetic long-term visions.

Output Strategic spatial planning, both in the short and the long term, focuses on results and implementation by framing decisions, actions and projects. It incorporates monitoring, evaluation, feedback, adjustment and revision. Where traditional spatial plans are judged in terms of conformance, strategic spatial plans are judged in terms of performance (Mastop and Faludi, 1997). The focus on becoming produces quite a different picture from traditional planning in terms of: •• •• ••

Products: strategic plans/policies, frames, strategies versus master plans or land-use plans. Type of planning: providing frameworks and justification for specific actions (a geography of the unknown; see Albrechts, 2006) versus technical or legal regulation. Type of governance: government-led versus government-led but co-productive forms of governance. 33

Louis Albrechts

In some places, the process of ‘discourse structuralization’ and its subsequent ‘institutionalization’ becomes perhaps more important than the plan as such (Hajer, 1995; Albrechts, 1999). In this way, new discourses can become institutionalized, i.e., embedded in the norms, attitudes and practices, thus providing a basis for structural change.

Strategic Planning Is Action- or Project-Oriented Traditional spatial planning is concerned with the production of plans as a reaction to problems and challenges or just to something a place wants to achieve. Strategic spatial planning relates to action and implementation. This is seen as the pattern of purposes, policy statements, plans, programs, actions (short, medium and long term), decisions and resource allocation that define what a policy is in practice, what it does and why it does it – from the point of view of the various affected publics (Bryson and Crosby, 1992: 296). This stresses the need to find effective connections between political authorities and implementation actors (planning officers, individual citizens, community organizations, private corporations, developers and public departments) (Hillier, 2002). Most actors will not go on the long march unless they see compelling evidence, within a reasonable period of time, that the process is producing acceptable results. Therefore, short-term results are needed to build the credibility needed to sustain efforts over the long haul and needed to help test visions against concrete conditions (Kotter, 1996). But, a strategic planning process should not maximize short-term results at the expense of the future. It means that strategic planning implies a move from episodic to continuous change (Kotter, 2008: 17).

Visioning Embedded in Becoming Envisioning Envisioning is a process that creates desired futures and then moves back to what is as it wants to present ideas and concepts that are solid, workable, and of testable value. It works as well as possible with uncertainty, and it enables actors to open up the spectrum of possibilities. Visions must symbolize some good, some qualities, and some virtues (diversity, sustainability, equity, spatial quality, inclusiveness, accountability) that the present lacks. Speaking of sustainability, spatial quality, virtues, and values is a way of describing the type of place citizens want to live in, or think they should live in. To get to these ideas, it needs both the solidity of the analysis and the creativity of the design of alternative futures. Since envisioning is also the journey and not just the destination, and as visions are so central to transformation and so all invasive, it cannot be confined to a single actor or institution in the process. The values and images of what a society wants to achieve are not generated in isolation, but rather are socially constructed and are given meaning and validated by the traditions of belief and practice. They are reviewed, reconstructed, and invented through collective experience (see Foucault, 1980: 11; Hillier, 1999).

Becoming Becoming emphasizes actions, movements, relationships, conflicts, process, evolvement and emergence (see Chia, 1995: 601). It expresses very well the dynamic nature of the strategic spatial planning process. Becoming produces, in a non-linear way, visions and frames of reference. A frame is the way people see an issue, a problem, a situation, a challenge, an opportunity or a practice (see Healey, 2004: 46). Strategic planning becomes the activity whereby (taking structural 34

Strategic Planning

constraints into account) that which might become is imposed on that which is, and it is imposed for the purpose of changing what is into what it might become. Becoming privileges change over persistence and novelty over continuity (Chia, 2002: 866).

Relational in Nature It is impossible to understand material places and social nodes such as ‘the city’, ‘the cityregion’ and ‘the region’ in terms of a one-dimensional hierarchy of scales (Healey, 2007: 267). Therefore, strategic spatial planning focuses on place-specific qualities and assets (social, cultural, and intellectual, including physical and social qualities of the urban or regional tissue) in a global context. If planners, politicians and citizens reflect upon the city in which they live their lives, they will be able to discover layers of stakes (Healey, 1997b: 69, 91–92) that consist of existing but perhaps unconscious interests in the fate of their city. Hence a plea for strategies that treat the territory of the urban not just as a container in which things happen, but as a complex mixture of nodes and networks, places and flows, in which multiple relations, activities and values co-exist, interact, combine, conflict, oppress and generate creative synergy (Healey, 2007: 1). This implies that the objects that society engages with are not things, but are rather an interconnecting set of shifting relations in which action is undertaken not only based on the identification and use of material assets, but also on an awareness of divergent understandings, – say, different professional codes or local norms – (Chia and Holt, 2006: 649). The term spatial brings into focus the where of things, whether static or dynamic; the creation and management of special places and sites; the interrelations between different activities and networks in an area; and significant intersections and nodes in an area that are physically co-located (Healey, 2004: 46). Places become both the text and context of new debates about fundamental socio-spatial relations, about ‘thinking without frontiers’ (Friedmann, 2011: 69). They provide new kinds of practices and narratives about belonging to and being involved in the construction of a place and in society at large (see also Holston, 1995; Yiftachel, 2006; Watson, 2011). The focus on the spatial relations of territories allows for a more effective way of integrating different agendas (economic, environmental, cultural, social, and policy agendas). As these agendas have a variable reach, they also carry a potential for a rescaling of issue agendas down from the global, continental, national or regional level, and up from the municipal level.

Legitimacy As (mainly) non-statutory processes, questions are raised on the legitimacy of strategic planning processes (see Mazza, 2013: 40). Legitimacy is not only a procedural problem (who decides) but also a substantive problem (the link between strategic planning and statutory planning). For Mazza (2011, 2013) and Mäntysalo (2013) the possible detachment of strategic spatial planning from the statutory planning system into a parallel informal system would pose a serious legitimacy problem. So, instead of detaching strategic planning from statutory planning Mäntysalo (2013: 51) identifies strategic planning not only as planning distinct from statutory planning but also as a planning framing the statutory-strategic planning relationship itself. In line with Friedmann (2004: 56) he argues that, as a consequence, the object of strategic planning should not be on the production of plans themselves (not even strategic ones) but on the production of insights of prospective change and in encouraging public debates on them. It is a way of probing the future in order to make more intelligent and informed decisions in the present (Friedmann, 2004: 56). The strategic probing of future uncertainties frames the fixing of certainties in the present. 35

Louis Albrechts

The non-statutory character of most strategic planning experiences seems, for some, to act as a structural antidote against marked standardization (see Sartorio, 2005; see also Hillier (2013) for strategic planning in Australia at a metropolitan scale which often tends to be a set of longrange blueprints for investment). For others the end product might consist of a critical analysis of the main processes and structural constraints shaping our places. This can inform realistic, dynamic, integrated, and indicative long-term visions (frames), plans for short-term and longterm actions, a budget, and flexible strategies for implementation. It constitutes a commitment or (partial) (dis)agreement between the key actors. More radical strategic planning enters into conflict with political regimes and has to look for cracks in the system to realize its objectives. It can be looked upon as an attack on the legitimacy of political institutions as it reverses and upsets the relationship between the state and its citizens. It is clear that the representative government articulates merely political and not all values. If we accept that representative democracy is not a single completed thing but that it is capable of becoming in a new context and in relation to new issues at hand then we may conclude that a more radical strategic planning does not reject representative democracy but complements it. It adds to the fullness of concrete human content, to the genuineness of community links (see Žižek, 1992: 163 about the very notion of democracy). The narrative of radical strategic planning is a narrative of emancipation. It fulfills a legitimating function. It legitimates social and political institutions and practices, forms of legislation, ethics, modes of thought and symbols. It grounds this legitimacy not in an original founding act but in a future to be brought about, that is, an idea to realize. This idea (of equity, fairness, social justice) has legitimating value because it is universal (see Lyotard, 1992: 50). So, apart from legitimacy stemming from a representative mandate, in radical strategic planning legitimacy might come from its performance as a creative and innovative force and its capacity to deliver positive outcomes and actually gain benefits. Besides the obvious ‘physical’ space needed to implement projects, strategies and policies, radical strategic planning has a focus on social space. In social space socially innovative relations are both catalysts and outcome of struggle between claims over physical space (Mitlin, 2008; Roy, 2009; Moulaert, 2011: 84; Van Dyck, 2011).

What Next? The four dimensions mentioned earlier cover the major challenges for strategic planning theory as well as for strategic planning practices. They also provide some ingredients for revisiting strategic planning. The critiques mentioned earlier make it clear that if strategic planning wants to play a role in tackling the challenges the revisit will take strategic planning beyond its traditional boundaries of theory, profession, planning laws and regulations. Underlying is the need to change the perspective of strategic planning and move away from the trend to depoliticize strategic planning by translating (potential) political issues into questions of technical knowledge, skills and expertise (see Swyngedouw, 2014). It implies that strategic spatial planning – at least for the protagonists of a more radical strategic planning – is not just a contingent response to wider forces but an active force in enabling change (see Sager, 2013) according to specific terms (equity, social justice) (Moulaert, 2011: 82). Revisiting strategic planning requires an in-depth reflection on key concepts (envisioning, becoming, legitimacy), on the path dependency of resources and on space-time geographies. With the focus on non-linear temporalities a link can be drawn to Bergson’s concepts of duration (durée) and virtuality. Duration, as the unified flow of time or becoming, and virtuality provide strategic planning processes with a way of seeing the future as bound up with the continual elaboration of the new, the openness of things (see Grosz, 1999: 28). This challenges 36

Strategic Planning

the combination of knowledge (traditional scientific, tacit/experiential knowledge of local communities) with the creativity of the design of alternative (even impossible) futures. It raises uncertainties for those involved in the process. How to combine providing certainty for developers, citizens with probing futures? How to combine flexibility with robustness? New space-time geographies (a geography of the unknown; Albrechts, 2006) stress the need for rescaling issue agendas down from the global, city-region, region and up from the municipal/neighborhood scale. Every situation in which strategic planning is carried out needs some understanding of the contextual factors (political, institutional, legal), some grasp of who key actors are, size and power of strategic and statutory planning agencies, and what networks are in play and how this relates to local social, economic, political and power dynamics (see also Healey, 2010: 14). The call for constructing a new governance culture through a more collective decision-making and empowerment of citizens – co-production – (see Mitlin, 2008; Roy, 2009; Watson, 2014) challenge the established institutions and structures and aims for a shift in power relations.

Notes 1 Barcelona’s mentoring role for Latin American cities has been particularly developed through the CIDEU (Centro Iberoamericano de Desarrollo Estratégico Urbano) network founded and headquartered in 1993 in Barcelona and covering more than 80 Ibero-American cities. Its original objective was to diffuse the model and methodology of the Barcelona Metropolitan Strategic Plan to any interested Latin American City (Ajuntament de Barcelona, 2004: 44). It was inspired by a developmentalist discourse to intervene in poorer countries to counteract a lack of urban strategic planning culture to channel the fast urbanization process (March Pujol, 2003: 61). 2 Mitlin (2008) uses the cases of the Orangi Pilot Project (Pakistan), SDI (Slum Dwellers International), FEGIP, a federation of local residents’ associations in Brazil and the Shack Dwellers Federation of Namibia to illustrate the use of co-production as a political strategy of grassroots movements.

References Ajuntament de Barcelona. 2004. Barcelona en el mundo 1995–2004. Ajuntament de Barcelona (cited in Gonzáles 2010). Albrechts, L. 1999. Planners as catalysts and initiators of change: The New Structure Plan for Flanders. European Planning Studies, 7(5), 36–46. Albrechts, L. 2001. From traditional land use planning to strategic spatial planning: the case of Flanders. In L. Albrechts, J. Alden and A. Da Rosa Pires (Eds), The Changing Institutional Landscape of Planning. Aldershot: Ashgate, 83–108. Albrechts, L. 2004. Strategic (spatial) planning reexamined. Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design, 31: 743–758. Albrechts, L. 2006. Shifts in strategic spatial planning? Some evidence from Europe and Australia. Environment and Planning A, 38: 1149–1170. Albrechts, L. 2010. More of the same is not enough! How could strategic spatial planning be instrumental in dealing with the challenges ahead? Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design, 37(6): 1115–1127. Albrechts, L. 2013. Reframing strategic spatial planning by using a coproduction perspective. Planning Theory, 12(1): 46–63. Albrechts, L. 2015. Ingredients for a more radical strategic spatial planning. Environment and Planning B, 42(3): 510–525. Albrechts, L., Alden, J. and Da Rosa Pires, A. (Eds) 2001. The Changing Institutional Landscape of Planning. Aldershot: Ashgate. Albrechts, L., Healey, P. and Kunzmann, K. 2003. Strategic spatial planning and regional governance in Europe. Journal of the American Planning Association, 69: 113–129. Albrechts, L. and Balducci, A. 2013. Practicing strategic planning: In search of critical features to explain the strategic character of plans. DisP: The Planning Review, 49(3): 16–27. Albrechts, L., Balducci, A. and Hillier, J. (Eds) 2017. Situated Practices in Strategic Planning. London: Routledge.

37

Louis Albrechts Allmendinger, P. and Haughton, G. 2009. Soft spaces, fuzzy boundaries, and metagovernance: The new spatial planning in the Thames Gateway. Environment and Planning A, 41(3): 617–633. Allmendinger, P. and Haughton, G. 2010. The future of spatial planning: Why less may be more. Town and Country Planning, July/Aug.: 326–328. Balducci, A., Fedeli, V. and Pasqui, G. (Eds) 2011. Strategic Planning for Contemporary Urban Regions: City of Cities: A Project for Milan. Farnham: Ashgate. Borja, J. 2000. Shedding light on the shades of strategic planning. Progressive Planning Magazine November 18. Borja, J. and Castells, M. 1997. Local and Global. London: Earthscan. Bryson, J. 1995. Strategic Planning for Public and Nonprofit Organizations. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass. Bryson, J. and Crosby, B. 1992. Leadership for the Common Good. Tackling Public Problems in a Shared-power World. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass. Chia, R. 1995. From modern to postmodern organizational analysis. Organization Studies, 16(4): 579–604. Chia, R. 2002. Time, duration and simultaneity: Rethinking process and change in organizational analysis. Organization Studies, 22: 863–868. Chia, R. and Holt, R. 2006. Strategy as practical coping: A Heideggerian perspective. Organization Studies, 27: 635–655. Dyrberg, T.B. 1997. The Circular Structure of Power. London: Verso. Foucault, M. 1980. The History of Sexuality. New York: Vintage. Friedmann, J. 2004. Strategic spatial planning and the longer range. Planning Theory & Practice, 5(1): 49–67. Friedmann, J. 2011. Insurgencies: Essays in Planning Theory. London and New York: Routledge. Gonzáles, S. 2011. Bilbao and Barcelona ‘in motion’: How urban regeneration ‘models’ travel and mutate in the global flows of policy tourism. Urban Studies, 48(7): 1397–1418. Grosz, E. 1999. Thinking the new: Of futures yet unthought. In E. Grosz (Ed.), Becomings: Explorations in Time, Memory, and Futures. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 15–28. Hajer, M. 1995. The Politics of Environmental Discourse. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Haughton, G., Allmendinger, P. and Oosterlynck, S. 2013. Spaces of neoliberal experimentation: Soft spaces, postpolitics, and neoliberal governmentality. Environment and Planning A, 45(1): 217–234. Healey, P. 1997a. The revival of strategic spatial planning in Europe. In P. Healey, A. Khakee, A. Motte and B. Needham (Eds), Making Strategic Spatial Plans. London: UCL Press, 3–19. Healey, P. 1997b. Collaborative Planning: Shaping Places in Fragmented Societies. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Healey, P. 2000. Planning in relational time and space: Responding to new urban realities. In G. Bridge and S. Watson (Eds), A Companion to the City. Oxford: Blackwell, 517–530. Healey, P. 2004. The treatment of space and place in the new strategic spatial planning in Europe. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 28: 45–67. Healey, P. 2006. Relational complexity and the imaginative power of strategic spatial planning. European Planning Studies, 14(4): 525–546. Healey, P. 2007. Urban Complexity and Spatial Strategies: Towards a Relational Planning for Our Times. London: Routledge. Healey, P. 2009. In search of the ‘strategic’ in spatial strategy making. Planning Theory and Practice, 10(4): 439–457. Healey, P. 2010. Making Better Places: The Planning Project for the Twenty-First Century. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Healey, P., Khakee, A., Motte, A. and Needham, B. 1997. Making Strategic Spatial Plans. Innovation in Europe. London: UCL Press. Healey, P. and Upton, R. 2010. Crossing Borders: International Exchange and Planning Practices. Abingdon: Routledge, 1–25. Hillier, J. 1999. What values? Whose values? Ethics, Place and Environment, 2: 179–199. Hillier, J. 2002. Shadows of Power. London: Routledge. Hillier, J. 2013. On relationality and uncertainty. disP, 49(3): 32–39. Holston, J. 1995. Spaces of insurgent citizenship. Planning Theory, 13: 35–51. Huxley, M. and Yiftachel, O. 2000. New paradigm or old myopia? Unsettling the communicative turn in planning theory. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 19: 331–342. Jessop, B. 2000. The crisis of national spatio-temporal fix and the ecological dominance of globalizing. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 24: 323–360.

38

Strategic Planning Kaufman, J.L. and Jacobs, H.M. 1987. A public planning perspective on strategic planning. Journal of the American Planning Association, 53: 21–31. Kingdon, J.W. 2003. Agendas, Alternatives and Public Policies. New York: Longman. Kotter, P. 1996. Leading Change. Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Press. Kotter, P. 2008. A Sense of Urgency. Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Press. Leal de Oliveira, F. 2000a. Strategic planning and urban competition. Planners Network, September/ October 143: 11–13. Leal de Oliveira, F. 2000b. Strategic planning and urban competition: the agenda of multilateral agencies in Brazil. Progressive Planning, September/October (http://www.plannersnetwork.org/publications/ 2000_143/oliveira.html). Google Scholar Lyotard, J.F. 1992. The Postmodern Explained. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Mäntysalo, R. 2013. Coping with the paradox of strategic spatial planning. disP, 49(3): 51–52. March Pujol, J.A. 2003. Iberoamérica: el rol del CIDEU en la construcción del nuevo mapa de ciudades en el siglo XXI. In CIDEU (Ed.), 10 años de planificación estratégica en Iberoamérica. Barcelona: CIDEU, 61–65 (cited in Gonzáles 2011). Mastop, H. and Faludi, A. 1997. Evaluation of strategic plans: The performance principle. Environment and Planning B, 24(6): 815–822. Mazza, L. 2011. Personal communication by e-mail, August 24. Mazza, L. 2013. If strategic ‘planning is everything maybe it’s nothing’. disP, 49(3): 40–42. Metzger, J. 2012. Placing the stakes: The enactment of territorial stakeholders in planning processes. Environment and Planning A, 45(4): 781–796. Metzger, J. 2014. The moose are protesting: The more-than human politics of transport infrastructure development. In J. Metzger, P. Allmendinger and S. Oosterlynck (Eds), Planning Against the Political. New York: Routledge, 191–213. Mitlin, D. 2008. With and beyond the state: Coproduction as a route to political influence, power and transformation for grassroots organizations. Environment and Urbanization, 20(2): 339–360. Monno, V. 2010. When strategy meets democracy: Exploring the limits of the ‘possible’ and the value of the ‘impossible’. In M. Cerreta, G. Concilio and V. Monno (Eds), Making Strategies in Spatial Planning: Knowledge and Values. Dordrecht: Springer, 161–183. Moulaert, F. 2011. When solidarity boosts strategic planning. In S. Oosterlynck, J. Van den Broeck, L. Albrechts, F. Moulaert and A. Verhetsel (Eds), Strategic Spatial Projects: Catalysts for Change. London: Routledge (RTPI Library Series), 79–84. Newman, P. 2008. Strategic spatial planning: Collective action and moments of opportunity. European Planning Studies, 16(10): 1371–1383. Olesen, K. 2011. Strategic Spatial Planning in Transition: Case Study of Denmark. PhD, Department of Development and Planning, Aalborg University. Olesen, K. and Richardson, T. 2012. Strategic spatial planning in transition: Contested rationalities and spatial logics in 21st century Danish spatial planning. European Planning Studies, 20(10): 1689–1706. Roy, A. 2009. Civic governmentality: The politics of inclusion in Beirut and Mumbai. Antipode, 41(1): 159–179. Sager, T. 2013. Reviving Critical Planning Theory. New York and London: Routledge. Salet, W. and Faludi, A. (Eds) 2000. Revival of Strategic Planning. Amsterdam: Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences. Sartorio, F. 2005. Strategic spatial planning: A Historical review of approaches, its recent revival, and an overview of the state of the art in Italy. disP, 162: 26–40. Schmitt, C. 1988. Völkerrechtliche Formen des modernen Imperialismus: Positionen und Begriffe. Berlin: Duncker & Humbolt. Secchi, B. 1986. Una nuova forma di piano [A new form of play]. Urbanistica, 82: 6–13. Secchi, B. and Viganó, P. 2011. La ville poreuse: Un projet pour le Grand Paris et la métropole del’après-Kyoto. Geneva: Edition MetisPresses. Sorensen, A. 2010. Urban sustainability and compact cities ideas in Japan: The diffusion, transformation and deployment of planning concepts. In P. Healey and R. Upton (Eds), Crossing Borders: International Exchange and Planning Practices. Abingdon: Routledge, 117–140. Sun Tzu, 1994 [500bc]. The Art of War. Translated by R. Sawyer. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Swyngedouw, E. 2014. Where is the political? Insurgent mobilisations and the incipient ‘return of the political’. Space and Polity, 18(2): 122–136.

39

Louis Albrechts Swyngedouw, E., Moulaert, F. and Rodriguez, A. 2002. Neoliberal urbanization in Europe: Large-scale urban development projects and the New Urban Policy. Antipode, 34(3): 542–577. Tibaijuka, A.K. 2005. Foreword in Promoting Local Economic Development through Strategic Planning, Volume 3: Toolkit. Nairobi: UN-Habitat, iii–iv. UN-Habitat. 2005. Promoting Local Economic Development through Strategic Planning. The Local Economic Development series. Nairobi. UN-Habitat. 2009. Global Report on Human Settlements 2009: Planning Sustainable Cities. London: Earthscan. Vainer, C. 2000. Light and shadow in the strategies of consultants on strategies. Progressive Planning Magazine, September 18. Van Dyck, B. 2011. Voicing spatial claims to mobilize resources for socially innovative brownfield transformation projects. In S. Oosterlynck, J. Van den Broeck, L. Albrechts, F. Moulaert and A. Verhetsel (Eds), Strategic Spatial Projects: Catalysts for Change. London: Routledge, 26–51. Viganó, P. 2010. A territorial project. In N. Meijsmans (Ed.), Designing for a Region. Amsterdam: SUN. Vigar, G., Graham, S. and Healey, P. 2005. In search of the city in spatial strategies: Past legacies, future imaginings. Urban Studies, 42(8): 1391–1410. Watson, V. 2011. Planning and conflict – moving on. Paper, WPSC Perth. Watson, V. 2014. Co-production and collaboration in planning the difference. Planning Theory and Practice, 15(1): 62–76. Yiftachel, O. 2006. Re-engaging planning theory? Towards ‘south-eastern’ perspectives. Planning Theory, 5(3): 211–222. Young, I. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Žižek, S. 1992. Looking Awry: An Introduction to Jacques Lacan through Popular Culture. Cambridge: MIT Press (paperback edition).

40

4 GROWTH MANAGEMENT THEORY From the Garden City to Smart Growth Jill L. Grant

Growth is a central theme in city planning. But growth creates both opportunities and concerns. Political and business interests typically crave growth as a sign of local success and potential prosperity. Residents might resent growth because of concerns about congestion, loss of open space, and rapid change in urban environments. The proponents and opponents of growth equally seek solutions to problems of gridlock, escalating housing costs, and the quality of urban development. Governments often want growth, but need to manage the externalities it generates. Planners sell planning with the promise of offering tools to shape the amount, character, and location of growth. In practice, growth might have a logic of its own: challenging to achieve and difficult to manage. This chapter briefly surveys the theoretical foundations of growth management in planning. We begin with an historical review of planning ideas about controlling growth before examining the philosophies behind growth management approaches. We then discuss the rise of smart growth as the dominant contemporary approach to managing growth and consider critiques of and challenges to that paradigm. In the final section we briefly discuss the future of growth management.

A Brief History of Growth Management As long as people have been building cities, authorities have sought to manage growth. The walls of ancient cities served not only to protect residents from external threats but contained the areas governors could control (Morris 1994). Outside the orderly growth bounded by walls in ancient Chang’an (China), for instance, sprawling suburbs reflected the inability of ancient planners to prevent growth (Wright 1967). During the 6th and 5th centuries bce, the Greeks established new towns to accommodate growing populations from the city-states: they planned colonial towns for an ideal community of 5,000 to 10,000 residents (Owens 1991). The Romans, who saw urban life as the epitome of civilisation, systematically planned walled cities to assimilate territories, but efforts to manage growth often encountered local challenges, with some places failing to thrive and others over-spilling their bounds (Owens 1991). Fearing threats

41

Jill L. Grant

from plague in the late 16th century, Queen Elizabeth proclaimed a greenbelt around London (England) to try to prevent growth and protect residents from plague: it failed to contain the city (Nelson and Dawkins 2004). Across time and continents, history reflects repeated, sometimes futile, efforts to shape urban growth. By the late 19th century rapid growth in industrial cities in many nations contributed to intense concerns about crowding, disease, and inefficiencies (Creese 1966). High rates of immigration to North America from Europe in the late 19th and early 20th centuries, when the economy was shifting from agricultural to industrial, fuelled rapid growth in many cities (Rae 2003). In the early years of the 20th century, modern town planning came of age as a tool of technological control to promote health. It was linked with civic “boosterism” and the city beautiful movement advocating urban beautification and competitive urban expansion. The desperate search for growth led many North American cities and companies into over-committing resources for people who would never arrive. Rae (2003) described a city beautiful plan for New Haven, Connecticut, which projected the city would grow from its 1910 population of 108,000 to 1 million by the year 2000: instead, New Haven had 123,626 people by then. A similar plan for Winnipeg, Manitoba, Canada—with a population of 136,000 in 1911—expected 4.5 million by 1984: in 1986, the city had just over 590,000 people (R. Turner 2015). As suburban railway lines experienced bankruptcies and real estate booms went bust in the 1910s, governments recognised the need to plan more effectively and realistically for growth (Creese 1966; Ward 1998). Ebenezer Howard (1902) developed one of the most influential theories about how to plan desired growth. Designed to prevent the sprawl of the largest cities, such as London, the garden city offered a model of planned satellite cities of 30,000 residents, linked to a larger city by multi-modal transportation systems, and surrounded by a protected greenbelt of agricultural land (Creese 1966; Howard 1902). Rather than leaving development to builders motivated primarily by desire for economic gain, garden city advocates argued that the state had an obligation to regulate and plan orderly growth with appropriate urban amenities. Garden city theory influenced community development in many parts of the world in the early decades of the 20th century (Creese 1966), the 1938 UK Green Belt Act (Nelson and Dawkins 2004), German planning for occupied Poland during the Second World War (Fehl 1992), and regional plans for major cities such as London, Copenhagen, and Paris in the years after the war (Ward 1992). With the economic boom following the end of the Second World War, and the increasing influence of welfare state policies in Western countries, local governments turned to planning for tools to control where and how growth occurred. In a climate of optimism and faith in modern science, anything seemed possible. Planning for growth became central to comprehensive land-use planning. Planners treated growth as inevitable, desirable, and amenable to direction through the technical exercise of assessing capacities, identifying appropriate locations, and applying regulations (Goodman and Freund 1968; Hall 1975). New town development in nations such as the United Kingdom and Sweden provided opportunities to test garden city theory (Ward 1992). In North America, planning strategies and highway expansion programs generally sought to point commercial growth to city centres and residential growth to the periphery, although cities such as Toronto tried nodal growth policies (Filion 2007). In the developing world, planners experimented with strategies to encourage economic growth and to accommodate rapid urbanisation. During the 1950s and 1960s North American planners elaborated theories about using urban renewal as a strategy to excise run-down neighbourhoods to permit “healthy growth”. As the American Institute of Planners (1950: 53) explained: 42

Growth Management Theory

The spread of blight from the outmoded and run-down central areas of cities, with its wake of excessive crime and fire rates and falling real estate values, must be stopped. New and healthy growth must be encouraged if our cities and their citizens are to have a wholesome future. Mid-century planners focussed on replacing blight—mixed uses in congested, low-income, central neighbourhoods—with spacious, segregated land-use patterns. Rather than letting cities change in undesirable ways, planners advocated regional planning while applying zoning and other regulations to shape new growth. In the process, however, they helped generate sprawl: a widespread pattern of unwanted and fragmented growth (Bruegmann 2005). Some governments began responding to concerns about the nature, rate, location, and impacts of growth in the 1960s and 1970s. In the first wave of US growth management, for instance, Hawaii adopted state land-use planning in 1961 to address natural constraints and protect agricultural lands (Weitz 1999). The 1965 plan for Paris envisioned transportation corridors from the centre connecting suburban new towns of 300,000 residents to accommodate population growth. The Toronto-centred region report in 1970 proposed to control growth, design transportation corridors, and reduce infrastructure costs, but a change in provincial government undermined efforts to mandate regional planning activities (Filion 2003). Managing the character of growth became a popular topic of discussion in the 1970s as the externalities of modernist-inspired growth raised concerns about loss of farmland, commuting congestion, and loss of older neighbourhoods (Ohm 2000). Sprawl—“shorthand for poorly planned growth that consumes precious open space and mars the landscape with ugly development” (Tregoning et al. 2002: 341)—dominated planners’ concerns in North America. Several US states and cities adopted policies in this period to try to reduce sprawl and manage growth (Dierwechter 2008; Nelson and Dawkins 2004). Even in the UK, with its highly centralised planning system and legacy of new town planning, sprawl appeared in some regions (Phelps 2012). The Club of Rome report, The Limits to Growth, stimulated scholarly debate about the perils of unlimited growth (Meadows et al. 1972) but did not slow urban expansion. In the developing world, rapid urbanisation drew attention to the need to plan for affordable housing and adequate access to urban services (J. Turner 1972). From the 1970s on, managing growth became an increasingly important planning concern.

Approaches to Managing Growth Before detailing the approaches to managing urban growth that influence planning theory, we first briefly consider the philosophies behind dealing with growth. We might conceive of those philosophies as arranged along a continuum: on one end, the aim of promoting growth; on the other end, the goal of limiting growth or accepting decline (Table 4.1). In the early years of modern town planning the aim of promoting growth dominated. Political leaders since the Progressive Era (1890–1920) have sought growth in government revenues to provide enhanced services and amenities. City beautiful era plans forecast ballooning populations and sought major investments in urban centres as leaders sought to boost their city at the expense of others. Molotch (1976) argued that a “growth machine” alliance of business, real estate, construction, and political interests continually pushes for urban growth. Capitalist societies justify state intervention because authorities expect that comprehensive planning can generate growth and wealth (Scott and Roweis 1977). In the contemporary period, strategies such as enterprise zones still seek to stimulate growth in contexts where growth is slow or decline in progress. Recent arguments about “making room” for growth in the rapidly growing 43

Jill L. Grant Table 4.1  Planning philosophies of growth with examples of strategies Approach

Promote growth

Manage growth

Belief

Growth is desirable and should be facilitated City beautiful Civic boosterism Comprehensive planning “Making room”

Growth is good and can be shaped

Planning idea

Tools and strategies

Enterprise zones

Control growth

Growth can be good only if controlled Garden city Regional development Sustainable planning development Comprehensive planning City-region New urbanism planning New regionalism Smart growth New towns Developers pay for Growth or infrastructure service Nodes and corridors boundaries Incentives Regulations Codes and deregulation

Limit growth Growth is problematic

Eco-cities Shrinking cities Smart decline

Greenbelts Building permit caps Development moratoria Decommissioning neighbourhoods

cities of developing countries suggest accommodating expansion rather than trying to contain it (Angel 2011). Although powerful forces in local politics promote growth, the negative effects of growth have sometimes stimulated a contrary-minded approach aiming to severely limit growth in particular areas or for certain periods. For instance, in some areas, concern about conserving farmland from urban development led to greenbelt legislation prohibiting development on designated lands. The UK adopted greenbelts in the 1930s to contain growth and protect countryside. South Korea created greenbelts around cities such as Seoul in the early 1970s (Bengston and Youn 2006). Around the same time, the Canadian province of British Columbia established an agricultural land reserve around Vancouver, while in 2005 Ontario protected a greenbelt around Toronto. Many other cities—including Berlin, Barcelona, and Bangkok— adopted greenbelts (Bengston and Youn 2006). Some communities reacted to perceptions of crowding, gridlock, congestion, pollution, and sprawl with new strategies. For instance, in an effort to slow growth, in 1972 Petaluma (California) applied an annual cap on building permits for five years: the tactic slowed growth, but drove housing costs higher (Dierwechter 2008). As downtowns began to feel the effects of suburban shopping centres in the 1970s, the Canadian province of Nova Scotia set a five-year moratorium on new shopping centre development. Of the varying strategies to limit growth, greenbelts have had the greatest staying power, although critics suggest they simply push development farther from the urban centre and increase housing prices. With such wide faith in the potential—and perceived inevitability—of growth, efforts to limit it have proven relatively rare. Mainstream planning rhetoric has not generally promoted a limiting growth strategy, although the eco-cities movement adopted some of its principles (Joss et al. 2013). In recent years, recognition that many cities are decreasing in population has given rise to a movement to plan to accommodate shrinking cities and smart decline with strategies such as withdrawing from some neighbourhoods (Beckman 2010; Hollander and Nemeth 2011). Managing and controlling growth are closely related in their shared interest in shaping development. Those who use the language of managing growth suggest that growth by its nature is positive, while those who favour controlling growth see growth as inclined to produce negative effects. Thus the strategies employed by planners differ between approaches. 44

Growth Management Theory

Trying to control growth in order to reduce its externalities and enhance its benefits implies that the state takes a strong role in shaping land uses. The garden city model, which reflected this approach, was implemented through building new towns in Europe during the post-war period: government master planning and investment provided powerful tools to shape the pace, location, and nature of growth. In the 1970s the state of Oregon required local governments to plan by establishing boundaries to contain future growth and conserve farmland (Nelson and Dawkins 2004). Communities often adopt planning and environmental regulations to control the location of particular land uses or the density of development. The publication of the Brundtland report (WCED 1987) popularised a new theory of growth during the 1990s and 2000s: sustainable development approaches gave priority to protecting the environment and promoting social equity along with ensuring economic growth. Several Canadian provinces have amalgamated city-regions in recent decades (Sancton 2001): they thereby facilitated regional planning by giving municipalities the tools to better control where growth would be encouraged or restricted. Those who seek to manage growth identify its benefits and suggest that planning or design can create conditions to promote good growth. For instance, international development planning and regional economic development strategies in the 1960s and 1970s tried to stimulate growth and direct it to targeted areas by providing infrastructure and other incentives. Comprehensive planning efforts in US states such as Florida sought to address the need for growth management (Dierwechter 2008; Chapin et al. 2007). North American approaches to growth management generally favoured finding ways to work with land development markets to achieve desired planning outcomes. During the 1980s many North American cities began requiring developers to cover the costs of infrastructure to reduce public expenditures (Dierwechter 2008; Krueger and Gibbs 2008). The rise of neoliberalism, with governments urged to roll-back regulations said to restrict markets, influenced planning approaches (Peck and Tickell 2002). Advocates of new urbanism argued that the market would provide attractive developments if planners would remove red tape (Duany et al. 2000). Planners suggested that targeted investments in transportation networks would provide opportunities for node and corridor development (Filion 2003, 2007). Political scientists promoted “new regionalism” through which local governments would voluntarily collaborate to coordinate regional growth (Frisken and Norris 2001; Sancton 2001). During the 1990s and 2000s the idea of smart growth emerged in North America, and gradually spread in influence. Smart growth advocated government incentives and alternative regulatory regimes to shape growth in desired ways, but it also adopted some strategies used to control or limit growth.

Smart Growth as a Paradigm As a theory of growth management, smart growth appeared as an antidote to efforts to limit or control growth. Concerns about the externalities of growth generated development moratoria during the 1970s and later sustainable development approaches that advocated moderating consumption and controlling growth to reduce environmental impacts (Beatley 2000; Wackernagel and Rees 1995). In response, political leaders in Maryland began to develop an alternative paradigm in the 1990s to imagine an “unabashedly pro-growth” approach with positive outcomes (Frece 2004: 113). With inspired rhetorical framing, Maryland governor Parris Glendening and his staff branded the approach smart growth. As Beatley and Collins (2000: 292) noted, “The smart growth tag neatly creates a rhetorical advantage by contrasting it with what can only be considered ‘dumb’ growth. The use of the word smart is simply smart.” Krueger and Gibbs (2008: 1263) suggested that “Smart growth is sometimes referred to as a uniquely ‘American’ 45

Jill L. Grant Table 4.2  What is smart growth? “[S]mart growth refers to the use of financial and other incentives, and public investment decisions, to encourage less-sprawling land use patterns and more compact urban form.” (Beatley and Collins 2000: 289) “Advocates [of smart growth] share many of the same goals of earlier anti-sprawl efforts fought under the banner of sustainability—with a key difference. Their language and methods are more pragmatic and inclusive. . . . they wrap the discussion around basic quality of life issues”. (Tregoning et al. 2002: 341) “Smart Growth . . . supports choice and opportunity by promoting efficient and sustainable land development, incorporates redevelopment patterns that optimize prior infrastructure investments, and consumes less land . . . Supporting the right of Americans to choose where and how they live, work, and play enables economic freedom for all Americans.” (American Planning Association 2012: online)

variant of sustainable development . . . a market-based approach that promotes the tripartite concerns of sustainability.” As the definitions in Table 4.2 illustrate, smart growth promises growth that will reduce sprawl while protecting choice and quality of life. Smart growth adopted many principles and practices from new urbanism, including commitment to compact form, higher densities, mixed uses, walkable communities, and transportation alternatives. Like the growth management theories that preceded it, smart growth builds on particular assumptions. It presumes that it is possible to predict long-term growth: indeed, population forecasts often become growth targets that plans aim to achieve. Smart growth theory treats the market as rational, holding that supply of desired commodities such as attractive neighbourhoods and housing choices will respond to opportunity and demand (Duany and Talen 2001; Krueger and Gibbs 2008). Planners expect that by influencing development options they can achieve aims such as reduced automobile use, mixed land uses, affordable housing, or downtown revitalisation. Smart growth promised economic growth without sacrificing environmental values, social equity, or urban quality of life. Its principal strategies to achieve desired outcomes were financial incentives, regulatory lightness, and ramping planning up to a regional scale (Dierwechter 2008): the perfect theory for an era dominated by neoliberal discourse (Krueger and Gibbs 2008). Smart growth offered a hybrid ideology with something for everyone (Dierwechter 2008): professional associations as diverse as the American Planning Association, US Conference of Mayors, American Farmland Trust, National Home Builders, and the Sierra Club saw smart growth as a way of acknowledging that growth is inevitable (and good), while generating practices to shape development in desired ways (Beatley and Collins 2000; Knaap and Talen 2005). Smart growth rapidly penetrated planning discourse and became the dominant theory of growth management in North America, and in some cases beyond. By the 2000s, smart growth theory and practice had travelled widely. Along with new urbanism—and with Richard Florida’s (2002) creative cities theory—smart growth was part of a cluster of “archetypical ‘mobile’ urban policies” being applied to justify streamlined development processes and large-scale master planning, even in remote areas such as the Scottish Highlands (MacLeod 2013: 2198). The government of Ontario in Canada began organising in 2002 to promote smart growth as provincial policy. Having forced the amalgamation of the City of Toronto with neighbouring communities in the late 1990s, in the mid-2000s the province adopted greenbelt legislation to protect environmentally sensitive and agriculturally important lands from development. It also required municipalities within an area identified as the Greater Golden Horseshoe to develop growth plans with density targets to accommodate a mix of jobs and residents within already developed areas (Filion 2007; Ontario 2005, 2006). In nations such as Canada and Scotland, where higher order governments can give local government powerful 46

Growth Management Theory

tools and mandates to enforce compliance, smart growth approaches might move beyond managing growth toward controlling it. Paradoxically, the state might employ its power to force local governments to use smart growth strategies in political contexts where neoliberalism remains pervasive. The state’s efforts to contain growth and protect some areas from development works effectively with planning regimes that implement “regulatory lightness” to create opportunities for capital gain in the guise of efficient service provision, environmental protection, or social equity. Even when the stars align, however, the product of applying smart growth policies might not be what planners expect. As Kushner (2000: 230) opined, “Opponents of Smart Growth and those who are skeptical should not fear; Dumb Growth still rules.”

Challenges to Smart Growth Downs (2005) suggested that we talk about smart growth more than we do it. In practice, smart growth has encountered many challenges that similarly faced new urbanism and sustainable development (Filion and McSpurren 2007; Grant 2009). Some of its assumptions have proven naive (Downs 2004). Its users interpreted it in varying ways to promote divergent priorities and interests (Filion 2003; Hawkins 2014). Three interrelated categories of challenges—economic, political, and social—make smart growth theory hard to implement even in areas that are growing. Economics and market factors play important roles influencing development dynamics. Smart growth theory assumes that reducing regulatory red tape will induce opportunities to reduce development costs. Several practices frustrate that. First, in many nations the development industry has been consolidating (Coiacetto 2009). While that facilitates large-scale master-planned developments that might include smart growth features, it also empowers industry to control the pace (and hence price) at which housing is released and to reproduce conventional practices they believe the market supports (McGuirk and Dowling 2009). Second, corporate decision making involves complex calculations about risk and potential rewards. Many companies continue development strategies they view as tried and true, delaying innovation (Farris 2001). For instance, efforts to increase mixed use and to integrate commercial uses with residential have encountered significant resistance (Grant and Perrott 2011). Rather than being associated with more walkable communities and transit use, higher densities might, perversely, contribute to demand for more privatised, disconnected, and even gated developments where automobile use dominates (Grant and Curran 2007). In rapidly growing larger cities, market pressures and effective public transportation systems work synergistically to provide a context within which smart growth measures can thrive; in smaller and more remote communities, however, limited demand and ready access to inexpensive land on the urban periphery challenge the potential for change. Successful smart growth initiatives also require government or private sector investment, transportation infrastructure, and a wide range of housing options; such funds are infrequently available at the time and in the amount needed. Political will and the scale of governance play roles in the fate of smart growth initiatives. Smart growth redistributes the costs and benefits of development in ways that create winners and losers: hence, conflict. To work effectively smart growth requires some shift in power and authority from the local to regional level: it requires a different scale of planning and action in a context where political will and fiscal capacity might not always be supportive or sufficient (Filion and McSpurren 2007). Moreover, smart growth demands long-term comprehensive planning (Nelson and Dawkins 2004): such vision exceeds short-term political mandates. State and provincial governments and their leaders play critical roles (Downs 2005), but reliance on political champions leaves initiatives vulnerable when regimes change. Smart growth has provided theory to justify new regionalism in some cities—collaboration to cooperate in elements 47

Jill L. Grant

of regional planning and infrastructure delivery (Scott 2007)—but achieving the overall aims of smart growth remains a significant challenge. In regions where cities and towns are coping with decline, smart growth might seem politically naive. Social behaviour and cultural values influence efforts to achieve smart growth. High levels of immigration and rural-to-urban migration leading to growth of the largest metropoles—such as London, Vancouver or New York—favour increasing densities and mixed uses in urban cores. In smaller cities or slower growth areas, however, cultural expectations contribute to resistance to smart growth policies, especially around increased densities, mixed uses, and mixed housing types (Brewer and Grant 2015; Song 2005). Declining household size means fewer people live in more units, so that increased dwelling unit density might not produce desired population densities. To be effective, smart growth requires amenities and services, such as local retail and schools, and efficient transit systems connecting residents to places of work. The transportation issue is a chicken-and-egg problem: we need transit to support density, and density to support transit. As Filion (2003) noted, it is hard to get both simultaneously. When transit systems are not effective, planners cannot wean people from their cars, especially as the location of jobs becomes more dispersed in many cities. In projects developed to date, evidence is mixed about the relationship between patterns of growth and resulting transportation effects (Handy 2005; Jun 2008). Even if people live in smart neighbourhoods, they might still shop in suburban big-box stores (Pollan 1999), and take cars to work for the convenience offered. In sum, people do not necessarily respond in the way that theory predicts or desires. In some cases, the success of smart growth initiatives disadvantages particular social groups: for instance, urban containment boundaries might increase the costs of housing (Nelson and Dawkins 2004); less affluent and racialized populations might be displaced as central neighbourhoods grow in popularity among the professional classes (Hyra 2015). The Smart Growth Network (2015: online) argued that “Integrating single- and multi-family structures in new housing developments can support a more diverse population and allow more equitable distribution of households of all income levels.” In practice, however, the aim to include affordable housing by implementing smart growth policies has often been thwarted by escalating land values and inadequate government investment in social housing (Downs 2004). Smart growth might be achieving the American Planning Association’s (2012: online) aspiration of “Reversal in the centralization of poverty in communities both urban and rural” but it has not necessarily contributed to more equitable outcomes: instead, poverty has increasingly suburbanised (Vicino 2008). Indeed, the urban revitalisation associated with smart growth and new urbanism initiatives plays a significant role in driving gentrification and displacement (Kushner 2002; Quastel 2009). Experience suggests that smart growth theory’s faith that eliminating regulatory barriers would reduce housing costs and increase choice was fundamentally misplaced. Ramirez de la Cruz (2009: 220) argued that “Smart growth regulations involve redistributing the benefits and costs associated with land development and urban growth . . . Smart growth practices have substantial redistributive effects for various interest groups in the community, particularly for the welfare of developers, environmentalists, and homeowners.” Smart growth has done less to benefit disadvantaged residents and communities. Faith in the benefits of growth can blind authorities to the risks of increasing densities or redeveloping former industrial sites. Angel (2011) has challenged the wisdom of applying smart growth ideas in the developing world: he argues that growth boundaries and greater densities are inappropriate options in cities that are doubling in population at such a rapid rate and are already extremely dense. Sun (2011) noted that some places will never be smart for growth, no matter the strategies used. Coastal areas threatened by flooding, landfilled sites in seismically active zones, wetlands, desert environments, and such cannot be rendered safe or appropriate 48

Growth Management Theory

for development by applying smart growth strategies. Some regions where smart growth intensification policies have been followed for several years—such as parts of coastal North America—have become increasingly vulnerable to potential disasters. Globally linked cities of densely populated neighbourhoods can also face risks of communicable diseases, as the 2002 SARS and 2014 Ebola epidemics demonstrated. “‘Smart Growth in dumb places’—those that are particularly disaster prone—is the antithesis of true sustainability” (Sun 2011: 103). Survival of the smart growth paradigm will require greater attention to longer term risks and locally appropriate development options.

The Future of Growth Management Slogans such as “smart growth”, like “sustainable development” before it, have a limited halflife: utility could be decaying already. The popularity of smart growth as an approach to growth management reflected its ability to bridge interests and agendas as criticisms of growth reached fever pitch. Dierwechter (2008: 4) suggested that “we should see the smart growth paradigm for urban growth management, in particular, as an ongoing territorial struggle – as a still open project of geopolitical agency that concomitantly reflects both progressive and regressive tendencies pulsing within society as a whole.” As the tensions inherent in growth management practices become increasingly evident, and as critics continue to point to flawed assumptions and failures to achieve formidable ambitions, smart growth will at some point yield to new approaches. Managing growth remains a central concern of local governments and integral to the daily activities of many planners. Growth theories and approaches to growth management have always reflected the times, and the changing needs of capital. During the optimistic Progressive Era, local business and political leaders had ambitious aspirations for growth, but generally lacked the means to implement them. The moral codes implicit in the garden city paradigm reflected Victorian values of order and domesticity, as they reshaped suburban landscapes in the 20th century. The transformational objectives of the modernist period supported wholesale change in neighbourhood form and function. The growth control and growth management theories of the later 20th century illuminated concerns about the nature and pace of urban change, and the increasingly important role that real estate development played in the economy. As a core planning paradigm in the late 20th and early 21st century, smart growth responded to the reality that growth might not be universal and, when it occurs, might not be universally beneficial. “Making room” for urban expansion in cities in the developing world responds to pressures to accommodate growth on the fringe (Angel 2011). Smart decline approaches promote positive futures for cities without growth. Challenges for cities over the next decades will likely shape the direction of growth management theories and practices in future. As theories of growth direct planning decisions and policies they have long-term implications for urban development: hence, smart growth policies that have shaped urban form and function in recent years will influence urban life for generations. What factors might affect the nature of growth management theories and planning practices in the years to come? First, we can expect that economic conditions will remain significant in influencing where and how growth occurs, and consequently our ideas about how to manage change. Cities in China and in parts of the developing world have exploded in population while Western nations have experienced considerable de-industrialisation, and in some cases urban decline, over the last several decades. Globalisation is likely to continue to generate upheavals in the location of employment opportunities and in the conditions that attract people to particular cities and particular neighbourhoods. As earlier paradigms of growth management reveal their inadequacies, we can expect planners to develop new theories about how to achieve desirable growth to improve conditions for populations and for urban development interests. With the 49

Jill L. Grant

extent of consolidation that has occurred in the development industry over recent decades, we can expect that large master-planned communities will remain an important feature of urban growth, with increasing inequities between those who can afford to live in well planned communities and those who cannot. At the same time, however, we will continue to need improved theories and strategies to help cities and regions decline gracefully (Hollander and Nemeth 2011). Second, environmental change will generate new threats to which planning will need to respond. For instance, some governments are currently ramping up research activities to consider how threats associated with climate change might alter many of the assumptions that have driven planning for growth in the past (Dedekorkut et al. 2010). Growth management approaches will need a more comprehensive view of the range of threats and hazards that cities might face as they grow (or decline). Third, political instability might present new challenges to planners trying to manage growth. Recent decades in Eastern Europe have illustrated the way that political change can destabilise and reorient growth patterns. Chronic instability in parts of the Middle East and North Africa are stimulating massive population movements that might influence patterns of growth in Europe and beyond. Immigration seems likely to become an increasingly important, and potentially contentious, issue for those planning for growth. In nations such as Canada and the US, which traditionally relied on immigration for growth, the political climate might be less welcoming than it once was. Japan faces a future of planning for decline in the absence of significant changes to its resistance to immigration. Changing cultural values and conditions around the world will generate new concerns that will demand innovative approaches to managing growth and the externalities it creates.

References American Institute of Planners. (1950) “Criteria Used in Delimiting Redevelopment Areas: A Symposium,” Journal of the American Institute of Planners 16, 3, 109–21. American Planning Association. (2012) Policy Guide on Smart Growth (adopted 15 April 2002, updated 14 April 2012). www.planning.org/policy/guides/adopted/smartgrowth.htm (accessed 5 July 2015). Angel, S., with J. Parent, D. L. Civco, and Blei, A. M. (2011) Making Room for a Planet of Cities, Cambridge, MA: Lincoln Institute of Land Policy. Beatley, T. (2000) Green Urbanism: Learning from European Cities, Washington, DC: Island Press. Beatley, T. and Collins, R. (2000). “Smart Growth and Beyond: Transitioning to a Sustainable Society,” Virginia Environmental Law Journal 19, 287–322. Beckman, B. (2010) “The Wholesale Decommissioning of Vacant Urban Neighborhoods: Smart Decline, Public-Purpose Takings, and the Legality of Shrinking Cities,” Cleveland State Law Review 58, 387–461. Bengston, D. N. and Youn, Y.-C. (2006) “Urban Containment Policies and the Protection of Natural Areas: The Case of Seoul’s Greenbelt,” Ecology and Society 11, 1, Art. 3. www.ecologyandsociety.org/ vol11/iss1/art3/ (accessed 5 July 2015). Brewer, K. and Grant, J. L. (2015) “Seeking Density and Mix in the Suburbs: Challenges for Mid-Sized Cities,” Planning Theory and Practice 16, 2, 151–68. Bruegmann, R. (2005) Sprawl: A Compact History, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Chapin, T. S., Connerly, C. E., and Higgins, H. T. (eds) (2007) Growth Management in Florida: Planning for Paradise, Aldershot: Ashgate. Coiacetto, E. (2009) “Industry Structure in Real Estate Development: Is City Building Competitive?” Urban Policy and Research 27, 2, 117–35. Creese, W. (1966) Search for Environment: The Garden City Before and After, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Dedekorkut, A., Mustelin, J., Howes, M., and Byrne, J. (2010) “Tempering Growth: Planning for the Challenges of Climate Change and Growth Management in SEQ,” Australian Planner 47, 3, 203–15. Dierwechter, Y. (2008) Urban Growth Management and Its Discontents: Promises, Practices, and Geopolitics in U.S. City-Regions, New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.

50

Growth Management Theory Downs, A. (ed.) (2004) Growth Management and Affordable Housing: Do They Conflict? Washington, DC: The Brookings Institution. Downs, A. (2005) “Smart Growth: Why We Discuss It More than We Do It,” Journal of the American Planning Association 71, 4, 367–80. Duany, A. and Talen, E. (2001) “Making the Good Easy: The Smart Code Alternative,” Fordham Urban Law Journal 29, 1445–68. Duany, A., Plater-Zyberk, E. and Speck, J. (2000) Suburban Nation: The Rise of Sprawl and the Decline of the American Dream, New York: North Point Press. Farris, J. T. (2001) “The Barriers to Using Urban Infill Development to Achieve Smart Growth,” Housing Policy Debate 12, 1, 1–39. Fehl, G. (1992) “The Nazi Garden City,” in S. Ward (ed.) The Garden City: Past, Present and Future (pp. 88–107), London: Routledge E&FN Spon. Filion, P. (2003) “Towards Smart Growth? The Difficult Implementation of Alternatives to Urban Dispersion,” Canadian Journal of Urban Research 12, 1 (Supplement), 48–70. Filion, P. (2007) The Urban Growth Centres Strategy in the Greater Golden Horseshoe: Lessons from Downtowns, Nodes, and Corridors, Toronto: Neptis Foundation. Filion, P. and McSpurren, K. 2007. “Smart Growth and Development Reality: The Difficult Co-ordination of Land Use and Transport Objectives,” Urban Studies 44, 3, 501–23. Florida, R. (2002) The Rise of the Creative Class, and How It’s Transforming Work, Leisure, Community, and Everyday Life, New York: Basic Books. Frece, J. (2004) “Twenty Lessons from Maryland’s Smart Growth Initiative,” Vermont Journal of Environmental Law 6 (2004–2005), 106–32. Frisken, F. and Norris, D. F. (2001) “Regionalism Reconsidered,” Journal of Urban Affairs 23, 5, 467–78. Goodman, W. and Freund, E. (eds) (1968) The Practice of Local Government Planning, Washington, DC: International City Managers’ Association. Grant, J. (2009) “Theory and Practice in Planning the Suburbs: Challenges to Implementing New Urbanism, Smart Growth, and Sustainability Principles,” Planning Theory and Practice 10, 1, 11–33. Grant, J. and Curran, A. (2007) “Privatized Suburbia: The Planning Implications of Private Roads,” Environment and Planning B 34, 740–54. Grant, J. and Perrott, K. (2011) “Where is the Café? The Challenge of Making Retail Uses Viable in Mixed-Use Suburban Developments,” Urban Studies 48, 1, 177–95. Hall, P. (1975) Urban and Regional Planning, London: Penguin. Handy, S. (2005) “Smart Growth and the Transportation-Land Use Connection: What Does the Research Tell Us?” International Regional Science Review 28, 2, 146–67. Hawkins, C. (2014) “Competing Interests and the Political Market for Smart Growth Policy,” Urban Studies 51, 12, 2503–22. Hollander, J. B. and Nemeth, J. (2011) “The Bounds of Smart Decline: A Foundational Theory for Planning Shrinking Cities,” Housing Policy Debate 21, 3, 349–67. Howard, E. (1902) Garden Cities of To-Morrow, Eastbourne, UK: Attic Books (reprinted illustrated edition, 1985). Hyra, D. (2015) “The Back-to-the-City Movement: Neighbourhood Redevelopment and Processes of Political and Cultural Displacement,” Urban Studies 52, 10, 1753–73. Joss, S., Cowley, R., and Tomozeiu, D. (2013) “Towards the ‘Ubiquitous Eco-City’: An Analysis of the Internationalisation of Eco-City Policy and Practice,” Urban Research and Practice 6, 1, 54–74. Jun, M. J. (2008) “Are Portland’s Smart Growth Policies Related to Reduced Automobile Dependence?” Journal of Planning Education and Research 28, 100–7. Knaap, G.-J. and Talen, E. (2005) “New Urbanism and Smart Growth: A Few Words from the Academy,” International Regional Science Review 28, 2, 107–18. Krueger, R. and Gibbs, D. (2008) “‘Third Wave’ Sustainability? Smart Growth and Regional Development in the USA,” Regional Studies 42, 9, 1263–74. Kushner, J. A. (2000) “Smart Growth: Urban Growth Management and Land-Use Regulation Law in America,” The Urban Lawyer 32, 2, 211–38. Kushner, J. A. (2002) “Smart Growth, New Urbanism and Diversity:” Progressive Planning Movements in America and their Impact on Poor and Minority Ethnic Populations,” UCLA Journal of Environmental Law and Policy 21, 45–74. MacLeod, G. (2013) “New Urbanism/Smart Growth in the Scottish Highlands: Mobile Policies and Postpolitics in Local Development Planning,” Urban Studies 50, 11, 2196–221.

51

Jill L. Grant McGuirk, P. and Dowling, R. (2009) “Master-Planned Residential Developments: Beyond Iconic Spaces of Neoliberalism?” Asia Pacific Viewpoint 50, 2, 120–34. Meadows, D. H., Meadows D. L., Randers, J., and Behrens, W. W. (1972) The Limits to Growth, New York: Universe Books. Molotch, H. (1976) “The City as a Growth Machine: Toward a Political Economy of Place,” American Journal of Sociology 82, 2, 309–32. Morris, A. E. J. (1994) The History of Urban Form before the Industrial Revolutions (third edition), London: Longman Technical and Scientific. Nelson, A. C. and Dawkins, C. J. (2004) Urban Containment in the United States: History, Models, and Techniques for Regional and Metropolitan Growth Management, Planning Advisory Service Report 520, Chicago: American Planning Association. Ohm, B. W. (2000) “Reforming Land Planning Legislation at the Dawn of the 21st Century: The Emerging Influence of Smart Growth and Livable Communities,” The Urban Lawyer 32, 2, 181–210. Ontario, Government of. (2005) Places to Grow Act. www.placestogrow.ca/index.php?option=com_ content&task=view&id=4&Itemid=9 (accessed 5 July 2015). Ontario, Government of. (2006) Growth Plan for the Greater Golden Horseshoe. www.placestogrow.ca/index. php?option=com_content&task=view&id=9&Itemid=14 (accessed 5 July 2015). Owens, E. J. (1991) The City in the Greek and Roman World, London: Routledge. Peck, J. and Tickell, A. (2002) “Neoliberalizing Space,” Antipode 34, 3, 380–404. Phelps, N. A. (2012) An Anatomy of Sprawl: Planning and Politics in Britain, London: Routledge. Pollan, M. (1999) “The Way We Live Now: Land of the Free Market,” The New York Times Magazine, 11 July. http://michaelpollan.com/articles-archive/the-way-we-live-now-land-of-the-free-market/ (accessed 5 July 2015). Quastel, N. (2009) “Political Ecologies of Gentrification,” Urban Geography 30, 7, 694–725. Rae, D. (2003) City: Urbanism and Its End, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Ramirez de la Cruz, E. E. (2009) “Local Political Institutions and Smart Growth: An Empirical Study of the Politics of Compact Development,” Urban Affairs Review 45, 2, 218–46. Sancton, A. (2001) “Canadian Cities and the New Regionalism,” Journal of Urban Affairs 23, 5, 543–55. Scott, A. J. and Roweis, S. (1977) “Urban Planning in Theory and Practice: A Reappraisal,” Environment and Planning A 9, 1097–119. Scott, J. W. (2007) “Smart Growth as Urban Reform: A Pragmatic ‘Recoding’ of the New Regionalism,” Urban Studies 44, 1, 15–35. Smart Growth Network. (2015) “Smart Growth Principles,” http://smartgrowth.org/smart-growthprinciples/ (accessed 5 July 2015). Song, Y. (2005) “Smart Growth and Urban Development Pattern: A Comparative Study,” International Regional Science Review 28, 2, 239–65. Sun, L. G. (2011) “Smart Growth in Dumb Places: Sustainability, Disaster, and the Future of the American City,” Social Science Research Network, pp. 101–45. http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers. cfm?abstract_id=1918386 (accessed 5 July 2015). Tregoning, H., Agyeman, J., and Shenot, C. (2002) “Sprawl, Smart Growth and Sustainability,” Local Environment 7, 4, 341–7. Turner, J. (1972) Freedom to Build: Dweller Control of the Housing Process, New York: Macmillan. Turner, R. (2015) “City Beautiful: How Architecture Shaped Winnipeg’s DNA,” Winnipeg Free Press online. www.winnipegfreepress.com/city-beautiful/City-Beautiful---Part-1-Great-Expectations-273837201. html (accessed 5 July 2015). Vicino, T. J. (2008) “The Quest to Confront Suburban Decline: Political Realities and Lessons,” Urban Affairs Review, 43, 4, 553–81. Wackernagel, M. and Rees, W. (1995) Our Ecological Footprint: Reducing Human Impact on the Earth, Gabriola Island, BC: New Society Publishers. Ward, S. V. (1992) The Garden City: Past, Present and Future, London: Routledge. Ward, S. V. (1998) Selling Places: The Marketing and Promotion of Towns and Cities 1850–2000, London: Routledge. WCED. (1987) Our Common Future, Report of the Brundtland Commission, World Commission on the Environment and Development, New York: Oxford University Press. Weitz, J. (1999) “From Quiet Revolution to Smart Growth: State Growth Management Programs, 1960 to 1999,” Journal of Planning Literature 14, 2, 266–337. Wright, A. (1967) “Changan,” in A. Toynbee (ed.) Cities of Destiny (pp. 138–49), London: Thames and Hudson.

52

5 PLANNING IN THE ANTHROPOCENE William E. Rees

Introduction: Framing the Conundrum Plan (verb): To think about and arrange the parts or details of (something) before it happens or is made. (Merriam Webster) High intelligence, including the ability to reason logically and act upon available evidence, is a uniquely human attribute. So are the capacity to plan ahead and the plethora of social mechanisms for cooperation. Assiduously applied, these qualities should enable the global community to engineer an economically secure and ecologically stable future for the entire human family. But where is the evidence we are exercising our unique intellectual gifts? The cumulative effect of human activities (including meticulously planned activities) is eroding the biophysical structure and life-support functions of the ecosphere—greenhouse gases (GHGs) are accumulating and driving climate change; fishers are emptying the seas; industrial society is polluting and acidifying the oceans; overexploitation and bad management degrade landscapes and erode soils; accelerating biodiversity losses herald the ‘sixth extinction’, etc., etc. In short, people’s demands on nature are breaching critical ‘planetary boundaries’ (Rockström et  al. 2009); the human enterprise is in a state of ‘overshoot’ (Wackernagel et al. 2002, WWF 2014). The cumulative effect might well end hopes for sustainable global civilization. Indeed, some authorities argue that global societal collapse is a real possibility with many precedents, albeit on a sub-global scale (Tainter 1988, Diamond 2005). As Tainter (1995) observes, “what is perhaps most intriguing in the evolution of human societies is the regularity with which the pattern of increasing complexity is interrupted by collapse.” If industrial civilization does indeed succumb, we can hardly claim not to have been warned—the 1972 Club of Rome report on Limits to Growth (LTG) projected the collapse of global society before the mid-21st century under the combined weight of resource shortages, excess population (demand), insufficient capital and pollution (Meadows et al. 1972). This unprecedented modeling study was summarily dismissed—particularly by economists—as failing to take human ingenuity and technological progress into account.1 However, subsequent independent analyses of forty years of actual data since LTG’s publication indicate “that the world is closely tracking [the study’s] BAU scenario” (Turner 2014, Hall and Day 2009). Moreover, various unrelated 53

William E. Rees

studies underscore the LTG message that global civilization is on track to implode (Motesharrei et al. 2014, Barnosky et al. 2012, Barnosky 2014). Whatever the eventual outcome, H. sapiens has become the major geophysical force affecting the evolution of the ecosphere. Welcome to the Anthropocene (Steffen et al. 2007, Crutzen 2002). Assuming that our best scientific evidence is correct (is there any reason not to?) this chapter asks how urban and regional planners might address humanity’s cumulating ecological predicament. What are some of the biophysical and economic principles that should help shape urban land-use, resource and developmental planning theory in the 21st century? My starting premises in addressing this question are that: (1) the biophysical foundations of planning, particularly pertaining to urban ecosystems, are seriously underdeveloped; (2) the prevailing neoliberal framing of economic planning is dangerously misguided; (3) resolving the ecological crisis requires reasserting the common good and the public interest over selfish individualism and corporate privilege; (4) the ‘disjointed incrementalism’ characterizing typical development planning is woefully inadequate for the Anthropocene. It is worth noting that, contrary to popular wisdom, some developing countries actually have an advantage over advanced high-income countries in addressing the threat if they can organize to use it.

The Question of Urban ‘Land’: A Biophysical Systems Perspective The optimal use of ‘land’ has always been central to urban planning. In recent decades, however, ‘optimality’ has increasingly been interpreted in light of neoliberal economic theory. Modern society treats urban land as a tradable, mainly private, commodity and reduces optimality to efficient trade-offs among competing economic land uses. In this framing, land is valued as little more than a lifeless substrate for buildings, roads and engineered infrastructure. There is no appreciation of land-as-living system, of soil as the well-spring of terrestrial life. Nor is the city as a whole much better animated in the modern mind. Typical definitions describe the city as ‘a large permanent settlement’ or ‘a major centre of commerce and culture’ dominated by elements of the ‘built environment’; cities are political entities as well as ‘hotbeds of artistic, cultural and political activity’; Jane Jacobs famously described them, as the ‘engines of national economic growth.’ Cities are, of course, all these things but even in the aggregate this conception is inadequate for navigating the Anthropocene. Just what would happen to such an entity (think ‘London’ or ‘New York’) if it were sealed in an impermeable glass bell-jar whose outer diameter encompassed the city’s entire built-up area? Clearly, the city’s economy and social life would quickly wind down and die with its human inhabitants as they simultaneously starved and suffocated (Wackernagel and Rees 1996, Richardson and Moskal 2016). What is missing is any appreciation of the city as a complex, highly dependent living system.2 Cities are dynamic biophysical entities that must exchange with the larger ecosphere to survive and whose very existence is ultimately subject to the rule of thermodynamic and related biophysical laws (Rees 2012).

Cities as ‘Dissipative Structures’ [Thermodynamics] … holds the supreme position among the laws of nature … If your theory is found to be against the Second Law of Thermodynamics, I can give you no hope; there is nothing for it but to collapse in deepest humiliation. (Eddington 1929) We ignore the laws of thermodynamics at our peril. The Second Law states that any spontaneous change in an isolated system—a system that can exchange neither energy nor material with 54

Planning in the Anthropocene

its environment—increases the ‘entropy’ or randomness of that system. Concentrations disperse, energy dissipates and gradients dissolve. Over time, the system reaches ‘thermodynamic equilibrium’, a state of maximum entropy in which nothing further can happen. Contrast this situation with the familiar world. We all know of systems that are obviously not sliding inexorably toward equilibrium. The ecosphere, for example, is a highly ordered selforganizing system of mind-boggling complexity, multi-layered structure and steep gradients as represented by millions of distinct species, differentiated matter, and accumulated biomass. Over geological time the ecosphere has been moving ever further from disorderly equilibrium. Indeed, self-maintenance in a far-from-equilibrium state might well be the hallmark of life. As Prigogine (1997) asserts, “distance from equilibrium becomes an essential parameter in describing nature, much like temperature [is] in [standard] equilibrium thermodynamics”. All systems experience the same entropic forces that afflict isolated systems—there are no documented exemptions from the Second Law. (Have you ever known a rusted-out automobile to restore itself spontaneously to showroom condition?) So how do living systems avoid continuous decay? The paradox dissolves with recognition that living systems are open systems that freely exchange energy and matter with their environments. They also exist in overlapping nested hierarchies in which each component system is contained by another one level higher up (think ‘individual, population, community, ecosystem, ecosphere, Earth, solar system . . .’). Each subsystem in the hierarchy grows and develops by extracting usable energy/matter (negentropy) from its host system and using it to produce its own structure/function. It also exports degraded energy and material wastes (entropy) back into its host (see Kay and Regier 2000). The main point is that living systems generate local organization and maintain themselves far from equilibrium at the expense of increasing global entropy, most immediately the entropy of their host system (Schneider and Kay 1994, 1995). They are called ‘dissipative structures’ because they selfproduce by consuming/dissipating available concentrations of energy/matter (Prigogine 1997). So, where do cities fit in? Cities, like the ecosphere, are self-organizing far-from-equilibrium dissipative structures but with an important difference. The ecosphere evolves and maintains itself by ‘feeding’ on an extra-terrestrial source of available energy (the sun) and using it to recycle matter; the degraded energy dissipates off the planet as low-grade heat, increasing the entropy of the universe. By contrast, today’s cities can grow and maintain themselves only by ‘feeding’ on the rest of the ecosphere and ejecting low-grade heat and matter (pollution) back into it.3 In short, the local order represented by the burgeoning city is acquired at the expense of a much greater potential increase in the disorder of the ecosphere.4 We now have a sufficient biophysical explanation for humanity’s apparent ecological dysfunction: (1) as a wholly dependent subsystem, the increasingly urban human enterprise is thermodynamically positioned to consume/dissipate the ecosphere from within (Rees 1999); and (2) propelled by the perpetual growth ethic, aggregate human demand already exceeds the ecosphere’s regenerative capacity (WWF 2014). Wealthy urbanites might experience a world of unprecedented luxury and convenience, but the price is a parallel world of degraded landscapes, declining biodiversity, and climate change. Urban humanity has become dangerously parasitic on its planetary host. High-income cities are now as much the engines of global ecological decay as of national economic growth. The question is how might planners re-configure cities to become true regenerative ecosystems?

Are Cities Ecosystems? There is a long-standing interest in cities as ecosystems (e.g., Berkowitz et  al. 2002, Register 2006). However, despite numerous eco-city innovations and physical developments in various 55

William E. Rees

countries around the world (Joss et  al. 2015) no modern city comes close to achieving true human ecosystem status (Rees 1997, 2012). A functionally complete ecosystem is a self-sustaining community of producer organisms (green plants), macro-consumers (mostly humans and other animals), and micro-consumers (bacteria and fungi) existing in complementary relationships with each other and non-living components of a shared ‘environment’. In ‘Second Law’ terms, ecosystems are complex, self-organizing, far-from-equilibrium dissipative structures that assimilate high-quality solar energy (through photosynthesis) and recycle essential inorganic chemicals (water, carbon dioxide, nitrates, phosphates and a few trace minerals) to produce and maintain themselves. As matters stand, cities are nearly devoid of essential ecosystem components, particularly producer and micro-consumer organisms. We might perceive cities as productive ‘economic engines’ but, in strictly biophysical terms they are nodes of intense consumption only. This structural deficiency has important consequences. For example, separating food production from consumption and decomposition fosters soil degradation by inhibiting the economic maintenance of organic matter and the recycling of phosphorus, nitrogen, and other nutrients contained in household and human wastes. These are typically washed out to sea (i.e., ‘dissipated’) where they contribute to the emergence of anoxic marine dead zones and other forms of pollution. In effect, contemporary urbanization transforms what were once local, integrated, cyclically self-sustaining human production systems into global, transport-reliant, horizontally disintegrated, resource-depleting, unidirectional throughput systems (Rees 1992, 2012).5 Society consequently becomes dependent on artificial fertilizers which, in turn, deplete essential feed-stocks (e.g., phosphate rock and natural gas). Far from ‘decoupling’ people from nature (a common assumption of urban geographers and economists) modern cities could hardly be better configured to accelerate the entropic degradation of supporting ecosystems.

The Eco-footprints of Cities: What Really Constitutes ‘Urban’ Land? Which, somewhat circuitously, brings us back to urban land. The UK National Ecosystem Assessment (UK 2011) classifies 6.8% of the UK as urban. But urban land is not necessarily built upon—the classification includes parks, sports fields, private gardens, water courses and other forms of urban green space. In England, fully 78.6% of urban land is ‘natural’—the actual ‘built environment’ constitutes only 2.3% of the landscape in England and less than 1% elsewhere in the UK. Bottom line? The UK-NEA gives the impression that we can consider roughly 98–99% of the UK to be ‘natural’, unoccupied. This undercuts “the great myth of urban Britain” (BBC 2012) and might delude some to believe the country is relatively empty with plenty of room for growth. Contrast this perspective with that viewed through an ecological lens. The first question of urban ecology should be: ‘how large an area of productive ecosystems, both inside and outside the city’s built-up or political area, does its population functionally “appropriate” to support itself?’ The answer is revealed by ecological footprint analysis (EFA), a quantitative method that can estimate any population’s demand for ‘biocapacity’ (Rees 1992, 2013; Wackernagel and Rees 1996). The ecological footprint (EF) of any specified population is: The area of land and water ecosystems required, on a continuous basis, to produce the bio-resources that the population consumes and to assimilate the carbon wastes that the population produces, wherever on Earth the relevant land/water is located. (Rees 2013) In 2010, the UK’s EF was 4.4 gha per capita, more than half of which was carbon sink. In short, it took at least 4.4 hectares (10.9 acres) of ecosystems of average productivity scattered all over 56

Planning in the Anthropocene

the planet to produce food and fibre for, and to assimilate the carbon emissions of, the typical UK citizen (WWF 2014).6 (Significantly, the UK diet demands 0.8 gha/capita of cropland compared to a domestic supply of only 0.4 gha/capita which explains the trade deficit in food.) Assuming per capita consumption has not increased significantly, the UK’s 2015 population of 64 million had an EF of about 282 × 106 gha. Compare this to a domestic biocapacity of 82.8 × 106 gha (~ 1.3 gha per capita) and a total actual land base of 24.3 × 106 ha. The UK ecofootprint is 3.4 times greater than the nation’s biocapacity and 11.6 times the actual area of the country!7 Far from being 98% undeveloped the UK, like the world at large, is in a state of ecological overshoot. Demand for biocapacity greatly exceeds domestic supply.8 Now consider UK cities and ‘urban’ land. In 2015 Greater London had a population of over 8.1 million; assuming its inhabitants are typical UK residents, their collective eco-footprint is 36 × 106 gha. That is, London’s EF is 227 times larger than the city’s political area of 158,300 ha and 1.9 times the entire UK land base. London alone, with just 12% of the UK population, appropriates the equivalent of 43% of the nation’s biocapacity (and we have yet to consider other UK cities). And London is no exception—independent studies of various modern cities have found that urban EFs are typically hundreds to a thousand times larger than the city’s geographic area (Folke et al. 1997, Warren-Rhodes and Koenig 2001, BFF 2002, Moore and Rees 3013, Richardson and Moskal 2016). These observations are more than mere curiosities—remember, London’s eco-footprint represents the city’s true human ecosystem, the area, mostly outside the city, that London must ‘feed’ upon to maintain its human population and built infrastructure in their current stable, highly ordered far-from-equilibrium state. By extrapolation to include other cities, the UK’s entire productive land base, and twice as much again outside the country, constitute the nation’s functional urban ecosystem. If the UK were cut off from extra-territorial sources and global waste sinks, it could not support itself at anything approaching current material standards. Even assuming the inter-convertibility of domestic ecosystem types (e.g., agricultural to forest land, etc.) UK residents would have to reduce energy/material consumption by at least 70% to survive on domestic biocapacity. Such results are typical of high-income countries and cities.

Evidence-based Planning for the Anthropocene City planners have traditionally focused on land within city limits. This was relatively risk-free in ecologically stable times when human demand on nature was manageable, resources abundant and trade unimpeded—but circumstances have changed. The world is in overshoot; population and per capita consumption are increasing; global competition for Earth’s shrinking biocapacity is intensifying (as exemplified by the accelerating phenomenon of ‘land grabbing’ [Gardner 2015]); and sea level rise, mass migrations, resource shortages, energy insecurity and attendant geopolitical tension threaten the relationships between cities and their distant hinterlands even as cities become humanity’s major habitat. Clearly planners must begin to acknowledge in practical terms that arable land, forested land and other ecosystems are a more important functional component of urban ecosystems than are the lifeless roads, parkades and building lots that currently command professional attention. Planning for the Anthropocene should strive to re-conceive cities—or better, urban regions—as self-renewing, regenerative human ecosystems. Residents’ demand for food, fibre and energy should be supplied as much as possible by ‘domestic’ (i.e., intra-regional) production systems driven by photosynthesis and renewable energy technologies. Regional materials and waste management systems must be redesigned to facilitate the intra-regional recycling of essential nutrients and otherwise limit the dissipation of important resources. In short, we must create 57

William E. Rees

urban-centred eco-regions that are potentially self-sustaining—the successful design and execution of this ideal would be the highest form of bio-mimicry. If we could begin again in full knowledge of overshoot, climate change, etc., we might fashion human settlements from the ground up as self-governing bioregional city-states. Lessurbanized developing countries (mostly in Africa and Asia), particularly those with ‘surplus’ biocapacity, actually have a planning advantage here since they are starting with a relatively clean slate. By contrast, fully urbanized countries must cope with historic settlement patterns and governance systems that evolved with no reference whatever to global constraints. The best we might do is to ‘retrofit’ existing towns and cities in ways that reflect emerging biophysical and geopolitical realities. In either case, the major goal should be to reduce dependence on uncertain external sources and to enhance regional self-reliance. Implemented on a planned schedule over several years, the following policies/objectives are consistent with re-configuring present settlement patterns into more functionally self-contained human ecosystems that serve the broader public interest: •• •• •• •• ••

••

•• ••

••

Create a national system of bioregions centred on existing cities with boundaries based on ecologically meaningful land forms and biophysical features (e.g., watersheds, heights of land). Strive to contain, within the eco-region surrounding the urban core, an area equivalent to each city’s currently globally dispersed supportive hinterland; i.e., internalize their de facto ‘eco-footprints’. Re-localize government and economy; devolve sufficient governance and taxation powers to the new urban bioregions to enable effective management of their internal resource- and ecosystems. Organize the regional economy and commerce to sustain the population as much as possible on domestic bio-resources and ecosystems, thus reducing reliance on trade goods. Re-engineer urban utilities to convert cities from resource-depleting throughput systems into self-sustaining circular-flows ecosystems. E.g., collect, treat and recycle animal and domestic wastes onto the bio-region’s farm and forest lands whence it came, thus maintaining soil quality, reducing the need for artificial fertilizers, and eliminating ground and surface water pollution. End all non-essential green-field development. Restore depleted soils, degraded landscapes, wooded areas and other wildlife habitats to promote biodiversity, enhance regional production, increase carbon sink capacity, and mitigate climate change. (Human use has already dissipated half the world’s topsoil but soil still contains several times as much carbon as the atmosphere.) Build up rather than out. Densify existing built-upon land in ways that spatially reintegrate work-places with living-space and recreation areas. Utilize the economies of scale and agglomeration economies that confer a substantial ‘sustainability multiplier’ on well-designed high-density settlements (e.g., reduced per capita demand for occupied space and transportation; greater potential for recycling, reuse and remanufacturing, electricity co-generation and district heating/cooling; expanded opportunities for co-housing, tool-sharing and other activities that reduce material demand) (Rees 2003). Recognize that governance of regional ecosystems and landscapes for the common good will sometimes require stinting customary private property rights. Importantly, citizens who realize that their security depends on maintaining the integrity of local ecosystems have an incentive to support such measures. 58

Planning in the Anthropocene

••

••

•• ••

Create multiply redundant energy/water/food sources and related redundant infrastructure that are not fossil fuel dependent. In particular, sustainable cities should buffer water and food supplies from short-term climate vagaries (e.g., crop failures, drought, flooding) by engineering substantial storage capacity and maintaining reliable trading relationships. Implement economic and social planning policies that facilitate reducing residents’ ecological footprints toward a globally equitable 1.6 hectares per capita (Moore and Rees 2013). This would achieve ‘quasi-sustainability’,9 is technologically possible, and if skillfully implemented could actually improve individual and community well-being. Develop national/regional population policies consistent with regional and global carrying capacity. This will usually mean planned population reductions—overshoot is the product of too many people over-consuming finite resources. Developing countries in particular should prohibit the alienation of seemingly ‘underutilized’ lands to foreign interests. There are no true surplus ecosystems on Earth. International ‘land grabbing’ (see Gardner 2015) compromises prospects for local self-sufficiency, creates unsustainable dependencies, and increases geopolitical tension.

Note that the need to become more self-reliant is not an argument against trade. It is obviously unrealistic to expect retrofitted bioregions to come close to self-sufficiency, certainly not in manufactured goods and even in food and other renewables in the short and medium terms. Cities in the UK and other densely populated countries have long since exceeded the carrying capacities of their regional environs—i.e., they are overpopulated relative to their (partially depleted) resource bases. At best, then, our new urban bioregions will remain partially import-dependent as they rehabilitate regional ecosystems, adapt their consumption habits and implement long-term population policies in the transition toward maximum self-reliance. To facilitate the transition, senior governments will have to renegotiate terms of global trade to ensure the long-term conservation of vital natural capital—soils, biodiversity, etc.—upon which everyone depends. (Current WTO rules rationalize natural capital depletion to accelerate economic growth.) However, given the uncertainties confronting even managed exchange, an early priority goal of urban bioregions should be independence from imports of vital food and fibre resources. A reasonable guiding principle during the transition might be trade if necessary but not necessarily trade.

Growth or Development? The Need for New Economic Theory Something strange happened to economics about a century ago. In moving from classical to neo-classical economics—the dominant academic school today—economists expunged land (or natural resources) [from their theorizing]. (Wolf 2010) As noted, planning is excessively influenced by neoliberal economics, a mechanistic analytic framework that is divorced from biophysical reality and therefore anathema to sustainability. Its core model, the ‘circular flow of exchange value’, sees value in goods and services flowing from firms to households in exchange for spending by households (national product) and a countercurrent represented by factors of production (labour, knowledge, finance capital), flowing from households to firms in exchange for wages, rents, dividend, etc. (national income). There is no reference in this or derivative models to the energy and material resources required from nature to generate the money flows that the model does represent. To understand the economic process as a circular flow while ignoring unidirectional energy and material throughput 59

William E. Rees

is to think of a living body in terms of the circulatory system with no reference to the digestive tract. One might as well ask biology students to accept that “an organism can metabolize its own excreta” (Daly 1991). Abstraction from reality is increased by economists’ belief in the near-perfect substitutability of factors of production. Classical economics considered land, labour and capital to be three essential factors of production. However, finance capital and knowledge (human capital) are now perceived as the drivers of economic growth in advanced countries, so neoliberal economists downplay the role of traditional labour and have eliminated ‘land’ (a surrogate for nature and life-support functions) from their production functions altogether. The notion that knowledge/ human ingenuity (e.g., more efficient and novel technologies) can substitute for nature dispels residual concerns for resource scarcity and clears the way for continued economic growth.10 In theory, if we gradually reduce the energy and material intensity of the economy (lower energy/ material consumption per unit GDP) then the economy is effectively ‘decoupling’ from the material world and growth has reduced impact. Reality paints a different picture. Global material consumption has doubled in the past 35 years (a period of unprecedented efficiency gains), has accelerated since 2000 and there is scant sign of even relative decoupling (Giljum et al. 2014). Indeed, most claims of absolute and relative decoupling can be traced to poor analytic methods and accounting errors (Wiedmann et al. 2013). From a land-use planning perspective, perhaps the most interesting finding is that, with each doubling of income, the per capita land and marine areal footprints of nations increase by a third (Weinzettel et al. 2013). Again, material growth requires the appropriation and depletion of ecosystems.

Economics For the Anthropocene Fortunately, an alternative economic paradigm has emerged in recent decades (Martinez-Alier 1987, Daly and Farley 2010). Ecological economists have advanced a vision of the economy that addresses the most egregious misconceptions of the neoliberal model and maps much better to biophysical reality. For example: •• ••

••

••

••

Ecological economics replaces analytic mechanics with core concepts from ecology, complex systems theory, and far-from-equilibrium thermodynamics. While neoliberal models treat the economy as a separate, open, growing system lacking any important connectedness to an inanimate ‘environment’,11 ecological economists depict the economy as an open but fully contained, wholly dependent subsystem of the living, materially closed, non-growing ecosphere. Neoliberal models generally assume that change in key variables will be smooth and predictable and therefore reversible; ecological economics recognize that complex social, biophysical (and even economic) systems under stress often behave discontinuously. Key variables change unpredictably and can cross irreversible tipping points. Mainstream economics ignores the Second Law and sees no other insurmountable barriers to continued growth. By contrast, ecological economics recognizes that material growth necessitates the irreversible consumption and dissipation of available energy/matter, that beyond a certain point entropic disorder threatens global life-support systems, and that these facts impose strict limits on the safe scale of economic activity. In fact, contraction might be necessary for sustainability. Mainstream economic logic favours globalization, competition, specialization, selfish individualism, corporate values and free trade as stimulants to growth; ecological economics 60

Planning in the Anthropocene

••

•• ••

argues for locality, cooperation, economic diversity, community, the common good and managed trade as the foundation for resilient development. Neoliberal theory assumes that manufactured (and even finance) capital can substitute for natural capital. Ecological economics sees man-made and natural capital as complements (more sawmills are no substitute for denuded forests). Indeed, natural capital is required to produce manufactured capital. This, in turn, suggests a so-called strong ‘constant capital stocks criterion’ for sustainability:12 Each generation should inherit from the previous generation at least an equivalent (and adequate) per capita stock of both manufactured and natural capital in separate accounts (i.e., no substitution). While neoliberal economics promotes quantitative growth (getting bigger) through enhanced efficiency, ecological economics emphasizes qualitative development (getting better), including measures that ensure greater social equity.

More on this final point: in various countries today, including the US and the UK, rising GDP/ capita is accompanied by de-development—greater economic insecurity, deteriorating environments, eroding public services, a growing income gap (implicated in declining population health) and falling real incomes for low-income earners (Wilkinson and Pickett 2010, King 2014) all leading to disenchantment with politicians and government. Growth is failing to satisfy either of its ostensible objectives—continuous poverty reduction and enhancing general wellbeing—even as it simultaneously depletes/destabilizes supportive ecosystems.

Contraction toward a ‘Steady-State’ The astute planner will realize that if the benefits of growth are falling and the costs rising, the former will eventually converge with the latter. Indeed, an economy will have achieved its optimal scale at the point where the (diminishing) marginal benefits of material growth just equal the (rising) marginal costs—including the (currently unaccounted) costs of depleted natural capital, capital substitution and pollution. At this point the total net benefits of economic growth to date (total benefits minus total costs) is at a maximum and further growth actually makes us “poorer than richer” (Daly 1999). If intelligence and logic were the principal determinants of economic policy, the primary goal of development planners would be to ensure that growth slows and stops as we approach optimal scale. Regrettably, we do not have satisfactory methods to monetize various social and ecological costs, so reliable benefit/cost estimates of optimal scale remain an elusive goal. We can, however, reach a first approximation in biophysical terms. Ecological economics recognizes the thermodynamic imperative of limiting the material scale (energy and material throughput) of the economic process to something less than regenerative/assimilative capacity of supporting ecosystems. It follows that one goal of contemporary economic planning should be the transition from a growth-based, increasingly unequal society to a dynamic, more equitable steady-state society, operating within the regenerative means of nature (Daly 1991, 1992).13 (Growth-based, capitalism will not survive.) While ‘no growth’ is foreign to the modern mind, there should be nothing to fear about the steady-state. The normal human body is a steady-state system. Indeed, the ecosphere as a whole is in approximate steady-state, limited by the constant solar flux and the geographically variable availability of water and nutrients. It should be obvious on these grounds alone that the economic subsystem, rapidly becoming the dominant subsystem of the ecosphere, must conform to the operational dynamics of the ecosphere if it is to survive—and the operational dynamics of the ecosphere exemplify the steady-state. 61

William E. Rees

The steady-state is not to be confused with a static state. The economy need not cease developing, it must merely stop growing. Long after one stops growing one continues developing— acquiring more knowledge, greater professional and practical expertise, better social skills, status in the community, etc., etc. With sound planning and good management society at large could hover indefinitely near a materially optimal scale even as the well-being of the citizenry improves. In short, there are no limits on the capacity of human ingenuity to better quality of life, only on the quantity of throughput available to do it. The economy too should continue evolving as technological advances enable new firms and whole industrial sectors to both develop and grow as their thermodynamic equivalents in obsolete or ‘sunset’ industries wither and die off. It should be apparent that a steady-state economy functioning on available biocapacity is an appropriate economic model for our proposed system of increasingly self-reliant bioregional city-states.

Discussion: Do We Have Viable Options? Readers might protest that the spatial reorganization and planned economic contraction of society as proposed here is radically unrealistic: “Whatever the ethical merits of the case, the proposition of no growth has absolutely no chance to succeed” (Porter 2015). Others will argue that rapid transformation is unnecessary because gradually, incrementally, society is already taking tentative steps in the right direction. In any event, only small changes are politically feasible because they can be implemented using existing political mechanisms without upsetting too many establishment apple carts or losing public support. Perhaps, but history and social science suggest that making major cultural shifts incrementally typically takes decades and we no longer have decades—how long has the climate debate gone on even as GHGs and mean global temperatures reach yet another record in 2015? By the time significant movement is evident we will likely have missed important targets (e.g., hope is fading that we can avoid two Celsius degrees warming, which is increasingly looking like disaster [Hansen et al. 2013]) or passed irreversible tipping points, the consequences of which (for human civilization, at least) will play out over centuries. In these circumstances, transformational surgery must be performed as quickly as possible without jeopardizing the patient. At a minimum, rich countries should accept their responsibility to shrink their material economies toward a globally viable steady-state. Prudent analysts increasingly recognize that “appropriate policies and frameworks have to be implemented, leading to reduced resource use and absolute reductions (dematerialisation) particularly in industrialised economies, in order to enable a more balanced allocation of material resources across the globe” (Giljum et  al. 2014). Global equity requires that North Americans reduce their ecological footprints by over 75% from seven global average hectares (gha) per capita to a ‘fair Earth-share’ of 1.6 gha (e.g., Moore and Rees 2013); European throughput would typically fall by 60–70%. The emergent ‘de-growth’ movement is also inspired to create just such an ecologically stable, economically secure, more nearly equal world (Kerschner 2010, Gheorghică 2012, Rees 2015). Bottom line: material contraction at the top is necessary to make room for needed consumption growth in the developing world (Rees 2008, Victor 2008). Unreasonable demands? Impossible goals? Not necessarily—the world actually has the technology to enable a 75–80% reduction in energy and material consumption (von Weizsäcker et al. 2009) while improving quality of life in both rich and poor countries. Remember, too, that people in wealthy countries were actually happier on average with less than half of today’s average per capita income (Lane 2001). Programme implementation on the scale of urban-centred 62

Planning in the Anthropocene

bioregions would break the problem into manageable bits each of which would constitute an experiment from which the others could learn. And, if we are successful in creating a world of more self-reliant sustainable regions, the aggregate effect will be global sustainability. The most plausible alternatives to ‘steady-state with redistribution’ are the growth-oriented status quo or some technologically engineered variant. But if our best science is correct, the increasingly likely outcome of these alternatives is a dystopic chaos of climate change, ecosystemic collapse, resource wars and geopolitical upheaval. This dismal outcome underscores that it is actually in everyone’s long-term interest to give up on continuous material growth and learn to share the Earth’s existing bounty. For what might be the first time in human history, individual and national self-interest has converged with humanity’s collective interests (Rees 2008).

Epilogue: Is H. Sapiens Fatally Flawed? It is often said that the ecologically necessary is not politically feasible. On the other hand, the politically feasible might well be ecologically meaningless (and is often not implemented anyway). Which raises the possibility that humanity’s (un)sustainability conundrum is one of those problems that is simply not solvable. Many behavioural barriers stand in the way (Rees 2010)—like all species, H. sapiens has a natural predisposition to expand to fill all accessible habitat and use all available resources; individual humans have a natural tendency to prefer the here and now over the future and distant places (formalized by economists as ‘social discounting’); customary behaviours and beliefs (e.g., paradigms and ideologies) acquire synaptic circuits in the brain that are difficult to override; we are tribal, hierarchical and belligerent and both individuals and tribes at the top of the economic pyramid will do everything within their considerable power to avoid relinquishing their privileged positions. (Power politics and short-term self-interest generally trump evidencebased analysis and long-term collective interest.) Finally, humans evolved in small groups and ranged over relatively small areas. Our brains are adapted to coping on that scale—no one can wrap his/her mind around the world that is unfolding, let alone determine how it unfolds. (Do we really have a handle on climate change? Who is in control of the global economy or geopolitics? Who predicted ISIS?) Indeed, the history of societal collapses suggests that the inability of a stressed-out society to cope with some new macro-problem and implode (Tainter 1988) might well be an inevitable repeating pattern which, for the first time, is now unfolding inexorably on the global scale (Diamond 2005)—hardly an uplifting prognosis. But planning is by nature an optimistic profession—it is about building a better world. We have the data; we know what must be done; we can break the problem into manageable spatial components as proposed herein. The profession’s overriding challenge now is to help elevate H. sapiens’ unique capacities for high intelligence and forward planning to positions of prominence in the policy arena. If we succeed in rising above reptilian instinct, raw emotion and ideological intransigence it is theoretically possible that we can break the cycle of societal collapse. Does any other discipline have a greater challenge than that of enabling H. sapiens to realize its full and uniquely human potential?

Notes 1 Mainstream condemnation of LTG continued for decades, much of it based on error, misinterpretation, and untruths such as the oft-repeated claim that the model predicted resource depletion and global collapse before the end of the 20th century (Bardi 2011). Evidently, many critics had not actually read the LTG report, preferring to regurgitate the errors of earlier ideologically compatible (e.g., growthoriented techno-optimistic) commentators.

63

William E. Rees 2 This perceptual gap reflects modern humanity’s socially constructed sense of ‘exceptionalism’, the general belief that, because of technology, modern humans are no longer part of, or dependent on, nature. 3 A city’s resource consumption and waste production reflect both bio-metabolism and industrial metabolism. 4 This need not be problematic as long as the regenerative capacity of the ecosphere exceeds the dissipative output of the human enterprise (with a generous allowance for the thousands of other consumer species with whom we share the planet). 5 In effect, ‘the city’ is the human analogue of a livestock feedlot (Rees 2003). In both cases, the ecosystems that produce the primary residents’ food/fibre and recycle their wastes might be thousands of kilometres distant. 6 To facilitate international comparisons, EF data are generally converted to their equivalents in hectares of global average productivity (gha). Significantly, there are only about twelve billion hectares of land and water ecosystems on Earth adequately productive for human use (WWF 2014); this is 1.6 gha per person in 2015. The UK eco-footprint is 2.8 times larger than the share of biocapacity each citizen would receive if ecosystems were allocated on an equal basis. 7 Domestic biocapacity can exceed domestic territory because UK landtypes are more productive than average. For example, if UK farmland is three times as productive as world average farmland, one domestic hectare is the equivalent of three global average hectares (see Note 6). 8 These results are conservative because we err on the side of caution in the case of data discrepancies and we assume that productive lands are being used sustainably which is often not the case. For full details of current methods and implications see Rees (2012) and follow the links at www.footprintnetwork.org/ 9 A settlement is quasi-sustainable if current per capita energy and material throughput could be extended to the entire world population without compromising the integrity of the ecosphere. This would constitute ‘one planet living’ (Moore and Rees 2013) and in 2015 an average eco-footprint of 1.6 gha. 10 See the Ecomodernists’ Manifesto. Available at www.ecomodernism.org/ 11 Even environmental economists merely try to ‘internalize’ nature through market or shadow pricing. This treats ‘the environment’ as a sector of the economy. 12 A weak version, preferred by environmental economists, calls for a constant aggregate per capita monetary value of manufactured and natural capital, i.e., society can liquidate natural assets provided it generates an equivalent value of manufactured or finance capital (implies perfect substitution). 13 Remarkably, more than a century and a half ago when GDP/capita was a small fraction of today’s, John Stuart Mill also reasoned that society would reach a “stationary state” of sufficiency in which virtually everyone would be able to enjoy “sufficient leisure . . . to cultivate freely the graces of life.” Mill was at heart a planner and hoped that people would reach this state of grace deliberately “before necessity compels them to it” (Mill 1848). (He would be disappointed that, in the 21st century, nature is indeed compelling us to it.)

References Bardi, U. (2011) The Limits to Growth Revisited, New York: Springer. Barnosky, A.D. (2014) Dodging Extinction, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Barnosky, A.D. et al. (2012) Approaching a state shift in Earth’s biosphere. Nature 486: 52–58. doi:10.1038/ nature11018. BBC (2012) Mark Easton, The Great Myth of Urban Britain. BBC News online, available at www.bbc.com/ news/uk-18623096 (accessed 4 November 2015). Berkowitz, A., C.H. Nilon and K.S. Hollweg, eds. (2002) Understanding Urban Ecosystems: A New Frontier for Science and Education, New York: Springer-Verlag. BFF (2002) City Limits: A Resource Flow and Ecological Footprint Analysis of Greater London, London: Best Foot Forward, Ltd. for the Chartered Institution of Wastes Management (Environmental Body). Available at www.citylimitslondon.com/downloads/Complete%20report.pdf (accessed 3 November 2015). Crutzen, P.J. (2002) Geology of mankind: the Anthropocene. Nature 415: 23. Daly, H.E. (1991) Steady-State Economics (2nd edn), Washington: Island Press. Daly, H.E. (1992) Steady-state economics: concepts, questions, policies. Gaia 6: 333–338. Daly, H.E. (1999). Uneconomic growth in theory and in fact, The First Annual Feasta Lecture, Trinity College, Dublin (26 April 1999). Available at www.feasta.org/documents/feastareview/daly.htm (accessed 20 November 2015). Daly, H.E. and J. Farley (2010) Ecological Economics: Principles and Applications, Washington, DC: Island Press.

64

Planning in the Anthropocene Diamond, J. (2005) Collapse: How Societies Choose to Fail or Succeed, Viking (US)/Allen Lane (UK). Eddington, A.S. (1929) The Nature of the Physical World, New York: Macmillan Company ([re]Published by Kessinger Publishing, 2005). Folke, C., A.-M. Jansson, J. Larsson, and R. Costanza (1997) Ecosystem appropriation by cities. Ambio 26: 167–172. Gardner, G. (2015) Mounting losses of agricultural resources. Chapter 5 in State of the World 2015: Confronting Hidden Threats to Sustainability, Washington: World Resources Institute. Gheorghică, A.E. (2012) The Emergence of La Décroissanse. CES Working Papers, IV (1), Iași, Romania: Centre for European Studies, Alexandru Ioan Cuza University. Giljum, S., M. Dittrich, M. Lieber, and S. Lutter (2014) Global patterns of material flows and their socioeconomic and environmental implications: A MFA study on all countries world-wide from 1980 to 2009. Resources 3: 319–339, doi:10.3390/resources3010319 resources ISSN 2079–9276. Hall, C.A.S. and J.W. Day (2009) Revisiting the limits to growth after peak oil. American Scientist 97: 230–237. Hansen, J., P. Kharecha, M. Sato, V. Masson-Delmotte, F. Ackerman, and D.J. Beerling et  al. (2013) Assessing ‘dangerous climate change’: required reduction of carbon emissions to protect young people, future generations and nature. PLoS ONE 8(12): e81648. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0081648. Joss, S., R. Cowley, M. de Jong, B. Müller, B.-S. Park, W. Rees, M. Roseland, and Y. Rydin (2015) Tomorrow’s City Today: Prospects for Standardizing Sustainable Urban Development, London: University of New Westminster. Kay, J. and H. Regier (2000) Uncertainty, complexity, and ecological integrity. Chapter 8 in P. Crabbé et al. (eds), Implementing Ecological Integrity: Restoring Regional and Global Environment and Human Health (NATO Science Series IV: Earth and Environmental Sciences 1: 121–156), Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Kerschner, C. (2010) Economic de-growth vs. steady-state economy. Journal of Cleaner Production 18: 544–551. King, A. (2014) Welfare Spending: Trends, Prospects and Risks, London: Office of Budget Responsibility. Lane, R.E. 2001. The Loss of Happiness in Market Democracies, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Martinez-Alier, J. (with Klaus Schlupmann) (1987) Ecological Economics: Energy, Environment, and Society, Oxford: Basil-Blackwell. Meadows, D.H., D.L. Meadows, J. Randers, and W.W. Behrens III (1972) Limits to Growth, New York: New American Library. Mill, J.S. (1848) Principles of Political Economy With Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy (7th edn [1909] W.J. Ashley, ed.), London: Longmans Green and Co. Available at: www.econlib.org/library/ Mill/mlP.html (accessed 15 September 2015). Moore, J. and W.E. Rees (2013) Getting to one planet living. Chapter 4 in State of the World 2013: Is Sustainability Still Possible? Washington, DC: World Resources Institute. Motesharrei, S., J. Rivas, and E. Kalnay (2014) Human and nature dynamics (HANDY): Modeling inequality and use of resources in the collapse or sustainability of societies. Ecological Economics 101: 90–102. Porter, E. (2015) Imagining a World Without Growth, New York Times online. Available at www.nytimes. com/2015/12/02/business/economy/imagining-a-world-without-growth.html?emc=eta1&_r=0 (accessed 13 April 2017). Prigogine, I. (1997) The End of Certainty: Time, Chaos and the New Laws of Nature. New York: The Free Press. Rees, W.E. (1992) Ecological footprints and appropriated carrying capacity: what urban economics leaves out, Environment and Urbanization 4(2): 121–130. Rees, W.E. (1997) Is ‘sustainable city’ an oxymoron? Local Environment 2: 303–310. Rees, W.E. (1999) Consuming the earth: the biophysics of sustainability, Ecological Economics 29: 23–27. Rees, W.E. (2003) Understanding urban ecosystems: an ecological economics perspective. In A.R. Berkowitz, C.H. Nilon, and K.S. Holweg (eds), Understanding Urban Ecosystems: A New Frontier for Science and Education, pp. 115–136. New York: Springer-Verlag. Rees, W.E. (2008) Human nature, eco-footprints and environmental injustice, Local Environment, the International Journal of Justice and Sustainability 13(8): 685–701. Rees, W.E. (2010) What’s blocking sustainability? Human nature, cognition and denial. Sustainability: Science, Practice & Policy 6(2): 13–25. Available at www.gci.org.uk/Documents/BlockingSustainability (Final0910).pdf (accessed 13 April 2017). Rees, W.E. (2012) Cities as dissipative structures: global change and the vulnerability of urban civilization. In M.P. Weinstein and R.E. Turner (eds), Sustainability Science: The Emerging Paradigm and the Urban Environment, pp. 247–273. New York: Springer.

65

William E. Rees Rees, W.E. (2013) Ecological footprint, concept of. In S.A. Levin (ed.), Encyclopedia of Biodiversity, 2nd edn, Volume 2, pp. 701–713. Waltham, MA: Academic Press. Rees, W.E. (2015) Avoiding collapse: an agenda for degrowth and relocalisation. Chapter 10 in S. Davoudi and A. Madanipour (eds), Reconsidering Localism, London: Routledge (RTPI Library Series). Register, R. (2006) Ecocities: Rebuilding Cities in Balance with Nature (rev. edn), Gabriola Island, BC: New Society Publishers. Richardson, J.J. and L.M. Moskal (2016) Urban food crop production capacity and competition with the urban forest. Urban Forestry & Urban Greening 15: 58–64. Summary available at www.science20.com/ print/163422 (accessed 17 January 2016). Rockström, J. et al. (2009) A safe operating space for humanity. Nature 461: 472–475 (24 September 2009) doi:10.1038/461472a. Schneider, E.D. and J.J. Kay (1994) Complexity and thermodynamics: toward a new ecology. Futures 26: 626–647. Schneider, E.D. and J.J. Kay (1995) Order from disorder: the thermodynamics of complexity in biology. In M.P. Murphy and L.A.J. O’Neill (eds), What is Life? The Next Fifty Years pp. 161–172. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Steffen, W., P.J. Crutzen, and J.R. McNeill (2007) The Anthropocene: are humans now overwhelming the great forces of nature? Ambio 36(8): 614–621. Tainter, J.A. (1995) Sustainability of complex societies. Futures 27: 397–407. Tainter, J.A. (1988) The Collapse of Complex Societies, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Turner, G. (2014) Is Global Collapse Imminent? MSSI Research Paper No. 4, Melbourne: Melbourne Sustainable Society Institute, The University of Melbourne. UK (2011) UK National Ecosystem Assessment: Synthesis of the Key Findings. Cambridge: UNEP-WCMC. Victor, P.A. (2008) Managing without Growth: Slower by Design, Not Disaster. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. von Weizsäcker, E., K. Hargroves, M. Smith, C. Desha, and P. Stasinopoulos (2009) Factor 5: Transforming the Global Economy through 80% Increase in Resource Productivity, London, UK/Droemer, Germany: Earthscan. Wackernagel, M. and W.E. Rees (1996) Our Ecological Footprint: Reducing Human Impact on the Earth, Gabriola, BC: New Society Publishers. Wackernagel, M., N.B. Schulz, D. Deumling, A.C. Linares, M. Jenkins, V. Kapos, et al. (2002) Tracking the ecological overshoot of the human economy, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 99: 9266–9271. Warren-Rhodes, K. and A. Koenig (2001) Ecosystem appropriation by Hong Kong and its implications for sustainable development. Ecological Economics 39: 347–359. Weinzettel, J., E.G. Hertwich, G.P. Peters, K. Steen-Olsen and A. Galli (2013) Affluence drives the global displacement of land use. Global Environmental Change 23(2): 433–438, doi:10.1016/j.gloenvcha. 2012.12.010 Wiedmann, T.O., H. Schandl, M. Lenzen, D. Moran, S. Suh, J. West, and K. Kanemoto (2013) The material footprint of nations, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 112: 6271–6276, doi: 10.1073/pnas.1220362110. Wilkinson, R. and K. Pickett (2010) The Spirit Level: Why Equality Is Better for Everyone, London: Penguin Books. Wolf, M. (2010) Why were resources expunged from economics? Wolfexchange, London: Financial Times. Available at http://blogs.ft.com/martin-wolf-exchange/2010/07/12/why-were-resources-expungedfrom-neo-classical-economics/ (accessed 30 October 1015). WWF (2014) Living Planet Report 2014, Gland, Switzerland: Worldwide Fund for Nature.

66

PART II

How Meaning/Values Are Constructed in Planning

6 THE PUBLIC INTEREST Stefano Moroni

Introduction: The Fall from Grace of the Idea of the Public Interest Planning has traditionally considered the public interest as its principal criterion of justification. The notion of the public interest has traditionally provided the raison d’être for planning. This was true, in particular, of comprehensive technocratic planning. As Altshuler (1965: 186) wrote, the traditional master plan approach is based on the assumption “that the comprehensive planners understand the overall public interest”. In other words: “The existence of such a public interest was taken for granted during the heyday of comprehensive planning . . ., and the ability of planners . . . to identify this public interest and justify their proposals in its name, was rarely questioned” (Alexander 1992: 129). This traditional view, which for long dominated planning theory and practice, can be termed the rationalistic conception of the public interest. The situation is completely different today. The concept of the public interest has come under severe attack. It is in fact, today, a commonplace in the planning literature to say that the public interest does not exist. In other words, it has become fashionable “to dismiss the concept of ‘the public interest’ as devoid of content. Its use as a counter of public debate is said to be fraudulent, since there is no such thing as a public interest” (Barry 1990: 207). But the statement “the public interest does not exist” can be interpreted in four different ways (usually not clearly demarcated in the debate) that correspond to four quite different arguments on the ‘inexistence’ of the public interest: first, the public interest does not exist as a fact; second, the public interest does not exist as an a priori criterion; third, the public interest does not exist as an extra-individual value; fourth, the public interest does not exist as an always overriding substantive value (Table 6.1). For each of these four views, I shall ask four questions (further developing some ideas anticipated in Moroni 2004 and 2006): first, what is the presupposed argument and what kind of argument is it? Second, who proposes the argument? Third, against whom (and against what idea of the public interest) is the argument proposed? Fourth, what idea of pluralism is accepted? Answering these questions will allow me not only to present a (new) map of the various positions on the public interest (Table 6.2), but also to suggest a number of conceptual distinctions that will be useful for the subsequent attempt to reconstruct the concept. I use here the term “public interest” in a very broad sense that roughly coincides with expressions like “public good” or “common good”. The expression “common good” is the oldest one 69

Stefano Moroni Table 6.1  Four different arguments on the inexistence of the public interest Main idea

Kind of argument

Perspective

The public interest does not exist as a fact The public interest does not exist as an a priori criterion The public interest does not exist as an extraindividual value The public interest does not exist as an always overriding substantive value

Empirical Ethical Ethical

Divergentism Dialogical proceduralism Classical liberalism

Meta-ethical

Value pluralism

(dating back to Greek and Roman thought), while “public interest” has been introduced more recently (in an attempt to render the concept more consistent with the secularization of political science). However, both concepts convey the same idea: that the state should not pursue private and sectional interests or needs, but rather the interests and needs of all citizens.

What Kind of Inexistence? First View, Divergentism The central idea of this view is that the public interest does not exist as a fact. Let us consider four crucial questions in this regard. First question: What is the main argument and what kind of argument is it? In this case, the idea is that the public interest does not exist as a fact because, in our contemporary fragmented societies and cities, there is no possible factual overlap among the multiple varied individual and group interests. The interests of individuals and groups in our societies are today too divergent to exhibit any significant area in common. It is therefore impossible for public action to operate simultaneously to everyone’s advantage. This is, fundamentally, an empirical argument. In other words, it has something to say about our social and urban world as it is. Second question: Who proposes the argument? This argument is usually advanced by those planning theorists and political scientists who want to evidence the marked distributive effects of political decisions in a society that de facto comprises multiple factions and groups with different interests. In the planning literature, this is a position held by Simmie (1974), who argues that in social circumstances characterized by divergence among the goals and desires of the various individuals and groups as regards access to the scarce resources available, the public interest is a totally inadequate criterion for planning intervention. As he writes: “There is no such thing as THE public interest. Rather there are a number of different and competing interests” (Simmie 1974: 125). A similar view is propounded by Gans (1973: 10): In a pluralistic society, it is difficult to identify communal goals because they generally turn out to be shared by … only a part of the population. For example, open space is usually thought to be in the public interest, but it does not necessarily benefit those too far away to use it, those who do not wish to use it, or those who want scarce resources applied to a more urgent need, such us housing. Third question: Against whom (and against what idea of the public interest) is the argument directed? This argument is directed against the rationalistic conception of the public interest; that is, the idea that all individuals and groups have, in fact, interests in common, even if they are usually not aware of this fact. It is therefore an argument against those (i.e. orthodox technocratic planners) who believe that the role of the planner is to uncover this factual area of common interests and to show it to the individuals and groups. 70

The Public Interest

Fourth question: What idea of pluralism is presupposed? Pluralism (of interests, desires, aims) is, here, merely a fact. More precisely, it is a peculiarity of our contemporary societies that we must recognize as fundamental if we wish to furnish a viable empirical description of them. Today cities represent the clearest example of this irreconcilability of the interests of the various individuals and groups.

What Kind of Inexistence? Second View, Dialogical Proceduralism First question: What is the main argument and what kind of argument is it? In this case the idea is that the public interest does not exist as an a priori criterion. It is maintained that anyone who claims that it is possible to define what the public interest is in abstract terms and in advance ignores the fundamental interactive and dialogical process through which meaningful criteria are actively constructed. This is an ethical argument. Second question: Who proposes the argument? This argument is advanced by planning theorists who stress the centrality of communicative practices. On this view, a good planning process can be understood as one of joint sense-making in practical collective conversation (Forester 1989). This approach focuses on removing barriers of various types – structural, organizational, and political – which may distort dialogue. While the public interest cannot be defined a priori, it can therefore emerge a posteriori in a process of undistorted collective communication. The purpose of intercommunicative planning is to help planners begin and proceed in mutually agreeable ways based on an effort at interdiscursive understanding. … We may be able to agree on what to do next, on how to start out, and then travel along for a while. We cannot know where this will take us. (Healey 1993: 244) As a consequence, the public interest is identified ex post facto through open dialogical processes. As Healey (1997: 296–297) writes: “The ‘public interest’ has to reflect the diversity of our interests and be established discursively.” Compare with Innes and Booher (2015: 205): “Although participants do not come into the process looking for the public interest, as they accommodate diverse interests, the proposals come closer to something that can be viewed as in the common good.” Third question: Against whom (and against what idea of the public interest) is the argument directed? This argument, too, is mainly directed against the rationalistic conception of the public interest. According to communicative planning theory, planners must not limit their action to set ends and look for the means with which to achieve them; rather, they should use their abilities to generate a platform that encourages inter-communication. Planners are not mere problem-solvers; rather, they are (and must be) organizers of public attention. As Healey (1996: 230) writes in an influential paper: The spatial planning tradition emphasized planning’s role in spatial ordering, supported by rationalist methodologies of technical analysis and evaluation designed to achieve “public interest” goals … . The approach outlined in this paper presents strategic spatial planning as a process of facilitating community collaboration in the construction of strategic discourse, in strategic consensus-building. Fourth question: What idea of pluralism is presupposed? Pluralism is here again mainly a fact. The focus is not simply on different interests but also on different ways to formulate problems. As Forester (1989: 57) observes: “In a pluralist world the decision-making setting becomes more 71

Stefano Moroni

complex . . . . Definition of problems in a pluralist environment are multiple. Different interest groups have different senses and valuations of the problems at hand.”

What Kind of Inexistence? Third View, (Classical) Liberalism The central idea of this view is that the public interest does not exist as an extra-individual value. First question: What is the crucial argument and what kind of argument is it? In this case, the main idea is that the public interest does not exist as an extra-individual or supra-individual value because we must reject any value of this kind. The assumption here is that individuals are the only appropriate moral entity to which public choices must refer. In short, only individuals should be taken into account when public decisions are taken. In this perspective, the individual is an end in him/herself; the only source of legitimate moral claims. As a consequence, there are no legitimate distinct moral claims deriving from cultures, structures, communities, groups, etc. (Kukathas and Pettit 1990) We can call this conception “moral (or deontic, or normative) individualism” to distinguish it clearly from other forms of individualism. It is therefore essential to stress what moral individualism is not: first, it is not a meta-ethical subjectivistic claim regarding the nature of the value (in particular, it is not the claim that the only source of value is subjective sensation and that there are no sources of value independent of the real and subjective experiences of individuals); second, it is not an ontological claim regarding the non-existence of entities other than individuals (in particular, it is not the claim that there are no collective entities – collective entities may exist, but they do not have a moral status in themselves); third, it is not a methodological claim regarding the way in which we ought to describe society (in particular, it is not the claim that we ought to explain society by conceiving individuals as monads independent of social relations and prior to them); fourth, it is not an empirical claim regarding a specific individual psychology (in particular, it is not the claim that individuals have to be viewed as selfish agents). This argument against a certain idea of the public interest (i.e. an argument that is focused on the idea of moral individualism) is patently an ethical argument. In other words, it does not concern so much the social reality as it is, as the best way to evaluate that reality, and intervene in it. Second question: Who proposes the argument? This argument is advanced, in particular, by liberal thought. A clear example can be found in Nozick (1974). After having suggested an idea of rights as side constraints expressing the individuals’ reciprocal inviolability, Nozick (1974: 32) asks: “But why may not one violate persons for the greater social good?” Here is his reply: There is no social entity with a good that undergoes some sacrifice for its own good. There are only individual people, different individual people, with their own individual lives. Using one of these people for the benefit of others, uses him and benefits the others. Nothing more. What happens is that something is done to him for the sake of others. Talk of on overall social good covers this up. (Ibid.: 32–33) The term “liberalism” is used here to denote a family of normative political theories which have some fundamental ideas in common: first, the above-mentioned idea of moral individualism; second, the idea that we have to draw a sharp distinction between the good (which personally concerns each individual separately) and the right (which regards all individuals); third, the idea of the desirability of a plurality of conceptions of the good (i.e. the idea that we neither need nor want a society in which people share a similar idea of the good life); fourth, the idea of the centrality of certain basic rights and liberties (i.e. the idea that we have to recognize and 72

The Public Interest

defend certain individual rights or liberties in order to protect ourselves from others and from the state itself). The various contemporary liberal perspectives in this sense can be located on a continuum that ranges from the libertarian-liberal (e.g. Nozick 1974) to the egalitarian-liberal (e.g. Rawls 1971). There are few examples in the planning literature of the libertarian-liberal outlook (e.g. Sorensen and Day 1981). Examples of egalitarian-liberal perspectives are more common (e.g. Stein and Harper 2005). Third question: Against whom (and against what idea of the public interest) is the argument directed? The liberal criticism of the idea of the public interest or the common good as an extraindividual or supra-individual value is levelled first of all against those holistic conceptions that disregard moral individualism. A first example is provided by the holistic transcendental conceptions of the public interest; that is, those conceptions focused on some overall idea such as “the spirit of history”, “the spirit of progress”, or “the essence of the state”. Transcendental conceptions of this kind have had a considerable impact on planning (see Taylor 1994: 106–109). Other examples are the holistic communitarian conceptions of the public interest: that is, those conceptions focused on the community as the prime ethical subject and, consequently, on a common conception and standard of the good life. By “communitarianism” here I do not mean any generic claim in favour of collective or communal life, but rather a strong ethical commitment to community as the only decisive source of value (MacIntyre 1981). Conceptions of the public interest or the common good rooted in communitarian perspectives of this kind have also had a strong impact and are still widely accepted – explicitly or implicitly – in planning theory and practice. (For a critical appraisal of various ideas of community in planning theory and practice – and a warning against the risks of a “strong community” perspective – see Ganapati 2008). The liberal argument is also an argument against aggregationist conceptions of the public interest such as utilitarianism; that is, those normative perspectives based on an aggregative criterion of choice focused on the notion of utility. As is well known, the utilitarian philosophy strongly influenced planning theory and practice (with particular reference to the interpretation of the public interest, see Taylor 1994: 103–106; Campbell and Marshall 2002: 174–176). Utilitarians usually start with an apparently individualistic claim: “Real individual preferences (desires, interests, aims) are what really matter for us.” But their particular principle of collective choice, the maximization of total utility as a sum of individual utilities (interpreted as the satisfaction of individual preferences), is incongruous with the initial individualist stance. In the utilitarian aggregative criterion of public decision-making, the separateness of persons becomes lost in an impersonal global calculus (Rawls 1971: 27; Lukes 1973: 48). The utilitarian aggregative procedure takes account of utility measures and not of individuals. To sum up, utilitarianism seems open to criticism not because it is too individualistic (as many planning theorists believe), but because it is not individualistic enough. Before concluding, it is essential to specify that liberal theorists do not focus specifically on the “rationalistic” conception of the public interest. However, they reject it implicitly, considering rationalistic conceptions to be irrelevant a priori. It is also essential to underscore that what we have said does not imply that liberal thinkers reject any idea of the public interest. A liberal conception of the state simply presupposes a particular idea or version of the public interest. There is a public interest present in liberal conceptions of the state as well, since the intervention of a liberal state aims at safeguarding certain (individual) rights of the members of society (Kymlicka 1990: 206; Freeden 1991: 97). In conclusion, despite the prevailing narratives, no liberal thinker has ever considered self-interest as an alternative to the public interest (Holmes 1989: 252). Fourth question: What idea of pluralism is presupposed? For liberal perspectives the idea of pluralism that is centrally relevant is the idea of the “pluralism of conceptions of the good”. 73

Stefano Moroni

The plurality of the conceptions of the good is here not simply a fact, but a desirable situation. In this perspective, each individual must be free to pursue the conception of the good life that he or she likes, once some guarantees for all are provided (through certain universal individual rights). Classic liberals have nothing to say about the individual’s conceptions of the good and about the possible forms of self-realization. Crucial for liberalism, in fact, is the idea of the state’s neutrality regarding the good itself. A legitimate state is, therefore, a state whose principles do not presuppose any comprehensive conception of the good life (Rawls 1993). Each individual can obviously believe that his or her particular idea of the good life is the best one and that he or she has sound reasons for this conviction, but these reasons cannot become public reasons.

What Kind of Inexistence? Fourth View, Value-Pluralism The core idea of this view is that the public interest does not exist as an always overriding substantive value. First question: What is the argument, and what kind of argument is it? In this perspective, the conviction is that the public interest does not exist as a substantive value since it is impossible to contend that any substantive value is better than others. A strong value-pluralism is the only acceptable option. The interests and goals of individuals and groups are, in this perspective, morally equivalent and strictly incommensurable. The argument is therefore primarily metaethical. That is to say, it concerns whether or not it is actually possible to argue rationally in the field of ethics. Second question: Who proposes the argument? Value-pluralism can assume a quite different meaning in two different perspectives: first, we have non-sceptical value-pluralism; second, sceptical value-pluralism. In the first case, i.e. in the case of non-sceptical value-pluralism, the fundamental idea (Kekes 1993; Gray 2000) is that we can at least identify and defend societal arrangements that can allow pluralism to flourish in peace. Kekes (1993) and Gray (2000) argue that no particular value always overrides any other. Hence moral dilemmas cannot be completely eliminated from ethical experience. But this does imply, according to Kekes and Gray, radical scepticism. Kekes (1993) believes that plural values unavoidably conflict with each other. The state that accepts value-pluralism has, therefore, no overriding commitment to any specific value and must be hospitable to the flourishing of the widest possible array of values. But this does not mean that the state has nothing to do apart from encourage pluralism; it might sometimes become an advocate of particular conflict-resolutions. Along similar lines, Gray (2000) suggests the idea of modus vivendi as the focus of a viable political perspective for value-pluralistic societies. The idea of modus vivendi recognizes the ineliminable plurality of values: not simply the diversity of desires, but the unavoidable diversity of ways of life. In this view, “harmony” is not the preferable starting point for political doctrines: “It is better to begin by understanding why conflict – in the city as in the soul – cannot be avoided” (Gray 2000: 5). In this view, institutions do not reflect any common or universal value; they are simply devices enabling individuals and groups with different ideas of the good to coexist. In short: “The ethical theory underpinning modus vivendi is value-pluralism” (Gray 2000: 6). In planning theory, a similar idea of (non-sceptical) value-pluralism is implicit in Davidoff (1965). Here planners are considered to be advocates of the various groups according to their own personal values: “The planner as advocate would plead for his own and his client’s view of the good society” (ibid.: 333). In other words, advocate planning is “the exercise of the planning function on behalf of specified individuals and groups, rather than on behalf of a broadly defined public” (Davidoff et al. 1970: 12). 74

The Public Interest

Turning to the second case – i.e. the case of sceptical value-pluralism – we can observe that the central idea is that the public interest does not exist, since it is impossible to justify any kind of public choice in any reasonable fashion. It is also asserted that it is difficult to imagine, specify and defend any societal arrangement as preferable to any single other arrangement. Value-pluralism here coincides with total scepticism. A large group of sceptics have advanced an argument of this kind. A recent version of this form of sceptical value-pluralism is connected with the postmodern incommensurability thesis, according to which values, aims and lifestyles are so intrinsically varied and diverse that we lack any common ethical language and standard. An example of this kind of scepticism in the planning literature was anticipated by Rittel and Webber (1973) in a noted article on the impossibility of a general theory of planning (I do not mean to say that Rittel and Webber always sustained a similar form of scepticism; simply that this kind of scepticism can be found in their well-known 1973 article). Rittel and Webber (1973: 168) write: In a situation in which a plurality of individuals is pursuing a diversity of goals, how is the larger society to deal with its wicked problems? … Surely a unitary conception of a unitary “public welfare” is an anachronistic one. We do not even have a theory that tells us how to find out what might be considered a societally best state. Third question: Against whom (and against what idea of the public interest or the common good) is the argument proposed? In this view (i.e. in both the perspective of non-sceptical value-pluralism and that of sceptical value-pluralism, albeit in partially different vein in the two approaches) the argument is against any outlook other than value-pluralism. It is, therefore, an argument against every use of the idea of the public interest to identify certain values as always overriding other values. Fourth question: What idea of pluralism is presupposed? It is essential to maintain the distinction between the idea of pluralism accepted here – value-pluralism – and the idea of pluralism – pluralism of the conceptions of the good – accepted by classic liberals. Kekes (1993: 199) himself writes: Pluralism is committed to the view that there is no particular value that, in conflicts with other value, always take justifiable precedence over them. By contrast, … liberalism … must be committed to holding that in cases of conflict the particular values liberals favour do take justifiable precedence over other values. Observe, moreover, that the idea of pluralism presupposed here is also partially different from that discussed in the first case above (i.e. divergentism). At issue is not whether value-pluralism is a simple fact accentuated by the complexity of contemporary cities and societies and the contradictions inherent in the capitalist system, but whether it is a fundamental condition of human existence. As Gray (2000: 10–11) notes: “Value pluralism is . . . not an interpretation of pluralism in late modern societies. If it is true, it is a truth about human nature, not the contemporary condition.”

Rethinking the Public Interest: First Point, Acceptable (and Unacceptable) Criticisms Having clarified a number of preliminary issues, I now put forward some considerations crucial for formulating a viable idea of the public interest. First of all, not all the versions of the idea that the public interest does not exist seem acceptable. The divergentist perspective – the public interest does not exist as a fact – is plausible but trivial. Presenting it as one of the fundamental discoveries of planning theory and political science 75

Stefano Moroni

in the second part of the twentieth century is an exaggeration. Moreover, if this idea is taken in absolute terms, there is a risk of rendering it simply untrue. It is, in fact, evident that any group of individuals will always share some common interests: we can find common interests even among enemies (Barry 1990: 195). The crucial point is that the interests that are actually in common cannot necessarily help to resolve fundamental conflicts. In any event, accepting this first view implies the (agreeable) rejection of the rationalistic conception of the public interest (and only that). The dialogical proceduralist perspective – the public interest does not exist as an a priori criterion – appropriately directs attention to the usefulness of real interaction and debate; but if this point is taken to the extreme, such a position becomes open to criticism. First, as Alexander (2002: 234) writes: “A dialogical concept of the public interest may be useful as a kind of default legitimation for planning but it fails to provide the substantive content planners need if the public interest is to have any value as an evaluative criterion for plans or planners’ decisions.” Second, the desirability of dialogue cannot be justified dialogically: in other words, some (albeit minimal/thin) idea of the public interest must precede any process. Not every value can be redeveloped ad hoc in each interchange; some of them have to transcend particularity (Fainstein 2005: 126). In short, some sort of meta-consensus (Dryzek and Niemeyer 2006) is an inevitable presupposition. The value-pluralist perspective – which argues that the public interest does not exist as an always overriding substantive value – can be rejected. More precisely: non-sceptical value-pluralism seems simply incoherent; sceptical value-pluralism is, on the contrary, coherent but susceptible to criticism. Non-sceptical value-pluralism (as in Kekes 1993 and Gray 2002) is self-defeating (Tate 2010). The idea that there must be some kind of state – protecting and favouring value-pluralism – rather than no state (Gray 2000) entails accepting certain substantive values rather than others. The same problem arises when we argue (Kekes 1993) that the state has a crucial role to play in conflict-resolution. Strictly speaking, value-pluralism entails nothing at all about what we ought to do (Talisse 2015). Gray (2000: 135) himself seems to admit this when, irreparably damaging his theory, he writes: “Yet value-pluralism does not strictly entail modus vivendi. As a matter of logic, value-pluralism cannot entail any political project.” In short, non-sceptical value-pluralism seeks to reconcile two incompatible elements: on the one hand, total pluralism of values; on the other, some sort of idea of a preferable institutional arrangement and public action. A similar kind of incongruence can be found also in certain current planning approaches. Sceptical value-pluralism is, on the contrary, coherent – or at least can be made such – but can be criticized on different grounds. It is impossible to discuss this issue extensively here (see the arguments by Trainor 2008). I simply stress that incommensurability seems not to be absolute (individuals belonging to different cultures, traditions and groups have strong differences but when they meet they can learn, exchange and change; moreover, to coexist in peace and with reciprocal advantage, they do not need to overlap or converge on everything, but only on very circumscribed “framework-issues”), and axiological reasoning seems not totally impossible (in particular, it can take many intermediate forms between “foundational absolutism” and “total relativism”; as regards planning, see Harper and Stein 1995). The classic liberal perspective – the public interest does not exist as an extra-individual value – can not only be accepted but seems to me particularly relevant. Accepting it implies rejecting not just holistic conceptions of the public interest, such as the transcendental and communitarian, but also the aggregationist conceptions of the public interest, such as the utilitarian one. This happens for reasons that seem appropriate, and that do not deny the relevance of other ideas of public interest. In particular, it is important to stress here that, according to a liberal view, we 76

The Public Interest

can accept conceptions-of-the-good-pluralism as crucial to planning issues without necessarily having to embrace a more radical – and not totally convincing – blanket value-pluralism. Liberalism and value-pluralism are usually thought to be intrinsically linked. The widely accepted idea seems to be that value-pluralism is a fundamental component of liberalism. But this is untrue. This mistaken overlap between liberalism and (value-)pluralism has emerged because pluralism has usually not been clearly demarcated from a different idea that is the core of liberal thought: the idea of reasonable disagreement (Larmore 1996). Reasonable disagreement is the recognition of the inevitable disagreement concerning what can constitute a good life; the recognition that reasonable individuals tend to disagree about the nature of self-realization. But this does not mean that there exists no value at all that overrides others; it merely means that the state cannot impose any comprehensive conception of the good life on all individuals (Rawls 1993). The state must limit itself to safeguarding the right of each individual to pursue the concept of the good life that he or she prefers without seriously harming others. Liberalism is, therefore, not value-neutral.

Rethinking the Public Interest: Second Point, Viable (Nomocratic) Universalism As stressed, liberal criticisms of certain ideas of the public interest seem particularly convincing. Having concluded the pars destruens of the argument, I shall now try to develop a more positive pars construens, which I see as a development and reformulation of the classic liberal paradigm toward what can be termed “nomocracy” (Moroni 2010). (As already evidenced, classical liberalism is against certain ideas of the public interest, not against every idea of it.) Drawing on (and mixing) insights from Buchanan (1977), Hayek (1982) and Cordato (2007), one could say that it is in the public interest to improve in the long term the chances of unknown individuals of pursuing their equally unknown and continuously changing purposes in a complex social environment that is open-ended. This view is still based on moral individualism, but in a quite particular sense. Here, the public interest is not the real interest of any one specific person but the potential interest of anyone at all in the long run. As was already clear to Lewis (1832: 233): “Public, as opposed to private, is that which has no immediate relation to any specified person or persons, but may . . . concern any member or members of the community, without distinction.” In assessing whether something is in the public interest the point is, therefore, if it is in the interest (advantage, benefit . . .) of potentially everybody, but not literally everybody (Taylor 1994: 97). The public interest is something that is in the interest of each individual regardless of his or her membership in any specific sectional interest group: it is the interest of any individual taken at random (ibid.: 95). For instance, there might be no single road or other kinds of infrastructure in a region to whose building cost it would be strictly in everyone’s interest to contribute directly; but it might still be in everyone’s interest to contribute to the costs of an institutional and political setting in which roads and infrastructures will be built (Barry 1990: 197). In this sense the public interest is something that concerns an indefinite number of non-assignable individuals (ibid.: 192). A public rule or policy ought not to be the decision to grant X to B, but to grant X to everyone in suchand-such conditions (ibid.: 197). Note how an idea of the public interest of this kind becomes almost a matter of course if we want to take also future generations into account. And note how it presupposes intrinsic unpredictability and continuous change as peculiar and unavoidable features of complex systems – like contemporary urban realms (Moroni 2015). The suggested definition of the public interest avoids, in fact, any interpersonal comparison of contingent utilities and instead focuses on settings 77

Stefano Moroni

that can help and encourage everyone to discover and use the information and tools concerning the appropriateness of means to (centrally unknowable and not fixed once-and-for-all) individual ends. The above conception of the public interest is “ends-independent” in the sense that it does not depend on single given ends, but aims at promoting a situation where everyone can adaptively pursue the various ends he/she perceives from time to time as most valuable (Cordato 2007). Observe that if the criterion of the public interest is formulated thus, it is primarily a metacriterion for institutional design which can be progressively enriched and specified through successive decision-making stages. As I see the issue, this approach to the public interest requires the granting to each individual of certain basic negative rights (i.e. the right for everyone to freely pursue their idea of the good life – using the knowledge, capacities, resources and assets at their disposal as they wish – without being harmed by others, or harming others; for instance, the right to own, use, manage, transform private spaces without producing – or being affected by – negative externalities), and some positive rights (for instance, the availability for all of certain public spaces and services, such as basic urban infrastructures) (Moroni and Chiodelli 2014). What is crucial, according to the approach suggested, is that these rights and entitlements have to be granted and made effective through much less decision-making discretionality than happens today and a more radical application of the principle of equality of treatment (also at the local level). The simplicity and stability of landuse and building rules are also crucial. The focus of attention will, therefore, be on certain stable patterns of social relations and public provisions, rather than on contingently introduced and frequently revised specific material distributions and physical configurations (Moroni 2010). All of this is in accord with the necessary reaffirmation of a radical (both procedural and substantive) version of the classic ideal of the rule of law (Moroni 2007). As was already clear to Harrington (1771: 241): “The public interest (which is no other than common Right and Justice) may be called the Empire of Laws and not of Men.” In this perspective, planners neither create nor uncover the public interest but contribute to specifying and operationalizing the above-mentioned higher-level criterion. According to this view, communicative and dialogical methods do not entail a new global perspective; rather, they only provide (together with other methods) useful assistance – for example, in particular circumstances at local level – within a more general, stable and different framework.

Final Remarks: The Ineliminability of the Concept of the Public Interest A first conclusion of the foregoing discussion concerns the diverse positions taken on the issue of the public interest. As a partial alternative to more traditional typologies of conceptions of the public interest, it is now possible to compile a somewhat different one (Table 6.2). The second conclusion is that it is not easy to refute the concept of the public interest. We are obviously free to abandon the term “public interest” if we do not like it; but if we do so, we will simply have to deal with the same problem under some other label: determining justifiable public intervention in the face of diversity is crucial for any political order (Flathman 1966: 13). In short, I believe (as do, in the field of planning theory, Friedman 1973; Klosterman 1980; Howe 1992; Campbell and Marshall 2000 and 2002; Taylor 1994; Alexander 2002; Chettiparamb 2016) that one of the main tasks of planning and political theory is to rethink the public interest. To do this – and independently from accepting or otherwise the particular proposal above on how to reformulate a substantive idea of the public interest – we need to revise many current ideas too often taken for granted. In particular, we need: to sharply distinguish arguments at different levels of discourse (empirical, ethical, meta-ethical); to rediscover the real meaning and 78

The Public Interest Table 6.2  Views on the public interest Views on the public interest Rationalistic views Holistic views

Technocratic perspectives Transcendental perspectives Communitarianism Utilitarianism Communicative/dialogical perspectives Classical liberalism Nomocracy Divergentism Value-pluralism (sceptical and non-sceptical)

Aggregationist views Procedural views Individualistic (deontic) views Abolitionistic views

relevance of (moral) individualism; to reconsider the real limits of orthodox approaches such as utilitarianism; to admit that no preferred institutional schema can be derived from value-pluralism; to recognize that value-pluralism and classical liberalism are not connected; to recognize that a different kind of pluralism – pluralism of the conception of the good – is the really crucial one.

References Alexander, E.R. (1992) Approaches to Planning, Philadelphia, PA: Gordon and Breach. Alexander, E.R. (2002) “The Public Interest in Planning”, Planning Theory 1(3): 226–49. Altshuler, A. (1965) “The Goals of Comprehensive Planning”, AIP Journal 31(3): 186–97. Barry, B. (1990) Political Argument, New York: Harvester. Buchanan, J. (1977) Freedom in Constitutional Contract, College Station: Texas A & M University Press. Campbell, H. and Marshall, R. (2000) “Moral Obligations, Planning, and the Public Interest”, Environment and Planning B 27: 297–312. Campbell, H. and Marshall, R. (2002) “Utilitarianism’s Bad Breath? A Re-Evaluation of the Public Interest Justification for Planning”, Planning Theory 1(2): 163–87. Chettiparamb, A. (2016) “Articulating ‘Public Interest’ through Complexity Theory”, Environment and Planning C 34(7): 1284–1305. Cordato, R.E. (2007) Efficiency and Externalities in an Open-Universe, Auburn, AL: The Ludwig von Mises Institute. Davidoff, P. (1965) “Advocacy and Pluralism in Planning”, AIP Journal 31(4): 331–8. Davidoff, P., Davidoff, L. and Gold, N.N. (1970) “Suburban Action: Advocate Planning for an Open Society”, AIP Journal 36(1): 12–21. Dryzek, J.S. and Niemeyer, S. (2006) “Reconciling Pluralism and Consensus as Political Ideals”, American Journal of Political Science 50(3): 634–49. Fainstein, S. (2005) “Planning Theory and the City”, Journal of Planning Education and Research 25: 121–30. Flathman, R.B. (1966) The Public Interest, New York: Wiley. Forester, J. (1989) Planning in the Face of Power, Berkeley: California University Press. Freeden, M. (1991) Rights, Milton Keynes: Open University Press. Friedmann, J. (1973) “The Public Interest and Community Participation”, AIP Journal 39(1): 2–7. Ganapati, S. (2008) “Critical Appraisal of Three Ideas for Community Development in the United States”, JPER 27: 382–99. Gans, H.J. (1973) “Commentary”, AIP Journal 39(1): 10–12. Gray, J. (2000) Two Faces of Liberalism, Cambridge: Polity Press. Harper, T.L. and Stein, S.M. (1995) “Out of the Postmodern Abyss: Preserving the Rationale for Liberal Planning”, JPER 14: 233–44. Harrington, J. (1771) The Oceana and Its Other Works, London: Becket and Cadell. Hayek, F.A. (1982) Law, Legislation and Liberty, London: Routledge.

79

Stefano Moroni Healey, P. (1993) “Planning through Debate: The Communicative Turn in Planning Theory”, in F. Fischer and J. Forester (eds), The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning, London: Duke University Press, 233–53. Healey, P. (1996) “The Communicative Turn in Planning Theory and Its Implications for Spatial Strategy Formation”, Environment and Planning B 23: 217–34. Healey, P. (1997). Collaborative Planning, London: McMillan. Holmes, S. (1989) “The Permanent Structure of Antiliberal Thought”, in N.L. Rosenblum (ed.), Liberalism and the Moral Life, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 227–53. Howe, E. (1992) “Professional Roles and the Public Interest in Planning”, Journal of Planning Literature 6(3): 230–48. Innes, J.E. and Booher, D.E. (2015) “A Turning Point for Planning Theory? Overcoming Dividing Discourses”, Planning Theory 14(2): 195–213. Kekes, J. (1993) The Morality of Pluralism, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Klosterman, R.E. (1980) “A Public Interest Criterion”, APA Journal 46(3): 323–33. Kukathas, C. and Pettit, P. (1990) Rawls: A Theory of Justice and Its Critics, Cambridge: Polity Press. Kymlicka, W. (1990) Contemporary Political Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Larmore, C. (1996) The Morals of Modernity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lewis, G.C. (1832) Remarks on the Use and Abuse of Some Political Terms, London: B. Fellowes. Lukes, S. (1973) Individualism, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. MacIntyre, A. (1981) After Virtue, Notre Dame, IL: Notre Dame University Press. Moroni, S. (2004) “Towards a Reconstruction of the Public Interest Criterion”, Planning Theory 3(2): 151–71. Moroni, S. (2006) “Planning, Evaluation and the Public Interest”, in E.R. Alexander (ed.), Evaluation in Planning, Aldershot: Ashgate, 55–71. Moroni, S. (2007) “Planning, Liberty and the Rule of Law”, Planning Theory 6(2): 146–63. Moroni, S. (2010) “Rethinking the Theory and Practice of Land-Use Regulation: Towards Nomocracy”, Planning Theory 9(2): 137–55. Moroni, S. (2015) “Complexity and the Inherent Limits of Explanation and Prediction: Urban Codes for Self-Organizing Cities”, Planning Theory 14(3): 248–67. Moroni, S. and Chiodelli, F. (2014) “Public Spaces, Private Spaces, and the Right to the City”, International Journal of E-Planning Research, 3(1): 51–65. Nozick, R. (1974) Anarchy, State and Utopia, New York: Basic Books. Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (1993) Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press. Rittel, H.W.J. and Webber, M.M. (1973) “Dilemmas in a General Theory of Planning”, Policy Sciences 4(2): 155–69. Simmie, J. (1974) Citizens in Conflict, London: Hutchinson. Sorensen, A.D. and Day, R.A. (1981) “Libertarian Planning”, Town Planning Review 52(4): 390–402. Stein, S.M. and Harper, T.L. (2005) “Rawls’s ‘Justice as Fairness’: A Moral Basis for Contemporary Planning Theory”, Planning Theory 4(2): 147–72. Talisse, R.B. (2015) “Value Pluralism”, Administration & Society 47(9): 1064–76. Tate, J.W. (2010) “A Sententious Divide: Erasing the Two faces of Liberalism”, Philosophy and Social Criticism 36(8): 953–80. Taylor, N. (1994) “Environmental Issues and the Public Interest”, in H. Thomas (ed.), Values and Planning, Aldershot: Avebury, 87–115. Trainor, B.T. (2008) “Politics as the Quest for Unity”, Philosophy and Social Criticism 34(8): 905–24.

80

7 RETHINKING SCHOLARSHIP ON PLANNING ETHICS Tanja Winkler

Introduction Many scholars accept that planners operate at the interface of knowledge and action (Friedmann, 1987; cf. also Campbell, 2012a; Fainstein, 2010; Flyvbjerg, 2001; Healey, 1997; Porter, 2010; Sandercock, 2003; Yiftachel, 2006). Many equally accept that operating at this interface necessitates not only an awareness of how we know (epistemology), but also an awareness of our value-based judgements (or ethical principles), since ethical principles guide discursive and material actions, and vice-versa. Stated differently, epistemological standpoints and accompanying actions shape—and are shaped by—ethical principles. This suggests articulating knowledge, actions and ethical principles as recursively interlinked conditions, rather than as separate preconditions that occur before each other in some linear, causal chain of events (Davoudi, 2015). Planning might, therefore, be conceptualised as an epistemology of ethical actions. Furthermore, epistemologies of ethical actions undergo periodic shifts in accordance with everchanging philosophical understandings of ‘the world’. Thus, during one moment in history, operating at the interface of knowledge and action was shaped by positivist standpoints, whereas contemporary ways of knowing and doing reject positivist claims about value-free knowledge. Many scholars now argue in favour of the value-laden nature of planning ideas and practices. Many also argue in favour of developing context-specific knowledge for situated actions. And for those of us who argue along these lines, our epistemological standpoints embrace concerns for embodied, historically grounded and embedded knowledge(s) and actions. Planners might then be identified as “situated agents [who] work across different epistemological frames [that] shape not only [our] socio-political ways of knowing and doing, but also [our different] ways of understanding the objects and purpose of [our planning] activities” (Davoudi, 2015: 325). Yet, while contemporary planning theories draw on poststructural, postcolonial, subaltern or feminist scholarships that value subjective and situated epistemologies of action, work on planning ethics tends to retain a focus on normative ethical theories alone. To be sure, Stein and Harper (2005: 148) claim that “contemporary planning theories rest [squarely] on normative ethical theories”. And by extension, it can be argued that planning’s different epistemologies of ethical actions equally rest on normative frames of reference. This resting stems from the fact that planning, as an applied discipline, is oriented toward future courses of action, and, as such, “it tends to be normative” (Madanipour, 2015: 2). But a focus on normative (or first-order) 81

Tanja Winkler

ethical theories alone effectively forecloses further explorations of the nature and meaning of adopted ethical values regardless of ever-changing epistemological understandings of situated contexts, and regardless of the fact that scholars refer to the significance of ‘situational ethics’ in their work (cf. Flyvbjerg, 2001). First-order ethical principles also tend to be objective in nature, because they hone in on what planners should do in accordance with established social rules (Campbell 2012a, 2012b). Should or ought ethical questions, in turn, assume that planners are sufficiently knowledgeable to endorse some ethical judgements while rejecting others, and that planners instinctively know what the nature and meaning of adopted valuebased judgements entail. Argued differently, within first-order ethical frameworks “the [ethical] matter is already decided in advance, and the capacity for reflexive questioning of [value-based] frames is thereby surrendered” (Fraser, 2009: 291). The field of normative ethical theories thus negates opportunities to critically reflect on taken-for-granted ethical discourses, social rules and ‘Master Signifiers’ (cf. Gunder 2004 and Gunder and Hillier 2009 for critiques of planning’s ‘Master Signifiers’). Such observations then beg the question: Why is the scholarship on planning ethics rooted, almost exclusively, within normative ethical frameworks despite ever-evolving epistemologies of action in situated contexts? This is not to suggest that the idea of planning needs be conceptualised as something other than a normative project. The normativity of planning per se is NOT in question. Rather, the aim of this question is to create a space that might allow planners to reflect on their ethical frames of reference in the first place. To this end, I turn to Nancy Fraser (2009: 284) who asks: “What sort of theorizing can both open up a space for entertaining novel claims and also provide for the provisional closure needed to vet and redress them?” In response, Fraser proposes that theorising suited to contemporary moments in history “must engage the meta-level” if we hope to entertain the possibility that our normative ethical “framings might, in themselves, be in dispute” (ibid.). While Fraser’s (2009: 284) project concerns justice in a post-Westphalian world, her argument that our “first-order framings are in dispute” resonates with the concerns put forward in this chapter. And if we hope to ‘see’ this dispute, we need to question the taken-for-granted assumptions of planning ethics by engaging with meta ethical (or second-order) theories. Alternative ways of theorising planning might then rest not only with how we know and act in ‘the world’, but also with how we theorise ethics from first- and second-order ethical standpoints. Arguably, it is difficult, if not impossible, to answer (first-order) normative ethical questions (that concern an ethics of knowing to what end) before engaging with (second-order) meta ethical questions that include, for example: •• •• ••

What are the nature and meaning of an ethical planning judgement in a situated context? How do planners know if their interpretation of an ethical value is ‘better’ (or ‘worse’) than the interpretations made by others? How does the subjective understanding of a ‘better’ (or ‘worse’) planning intervention vary from person to person, context to context, or culture to culture?

Meta ethics is the branch of moral philosophy that pays attention to the study of moral concepts, discourses, languages and thoughts. Whereas the field of normative ethical theories focuses on “what is moral” and “what we ought to do”, meta ethics focuses on “what morality itself is” (Jacobs, 2002: viii). In contrast to the field of normative ethics—that presupposes that some ethical judgements are ‘better’ than others—meta ethical theories allow us to consider subjective and intersubjective interpretations of value-based statements, attitudes and judgements from situated standpoints by asking questions about our moral judgements without attempting to discover what the ‘right’ (or ‘wrong’) course of action is (Foucault, 1984; Garner and Rosen, 1967; 82

Rethinking Scholarship on Planning Ethics

Mackie, 1977). Although less intuitively familiar, meta ethical questions are purposefully crafted to examine how we come to know our own interpretations of ethical values, as well as the interpretations made by others, in the first instance. They enable reflexivity by critically assessing how moral discourses, languages and thoughts shape decision-making processes and planning interventions. At issue here are precisely those value-based frames that are, in themselves, in dispute, but that are often taken for granted in normative ethical questions (Fraser, 2009). In the absence of grappling with meta ethical questions, planners might have no other way of assessing and justifying their value-based claims. The aim of this chapter is to explore how engagements with meta ethical questions might offer scholars alternative bases for theorising and operating at the interface of knowledge and action in situated contexts. It also aims to demonstrate how such engagements might be of particular interest to scholars who are calling for Southern theories. To these ends, this chapter is structured in two sections. In order to begin to understand why scholarships on planning ethics are rooted, almost exclusively, within normative ethical frameworks, the first section sets out to critically analyse (via a discourse analysis) some of planning’s dominant epistemologies of ethical actions. The second section briefly turns to the potential relevance of meta ethics in Southern contexts, before drawing to a conclusion.

Conceptualising Planning’s Dominant Focus on Normative Ethics Epistemology and ethics are usually considered as two distinct philosophical domains. However, when epistemology appeals to the character traits of an epistemic agent as a condition for knowledge production, it might then be argued that ethical commitments function as productive components of epistemic processes (Code, 2007; van Fraassen, 2007). Contemporary planning theories are replete with appeals such as ‘collaborative’, ‘just’, ‘respectful’, or even ‘ordinary’ character traits, and these character traits contribute to the theoretical conceptualisations of Healey’s (1997) collaborative planning, Fainstein’s (2010) Just City, Sandercock’s (2003) intercultural planning, or Robinson’s (2006) Ordinary City (to name a few theories that explicitly draw on value-laden epistemologies of ethical actions). Our ethical choices inform our acquisition of knowledge, and vice-versa (Code, 2007; van Fraassen, 2007). And seeing ourselves as epistemically responsible agents implies that planners’ ethical choices carry a degree of responsibility, since we might be held accountable for the choices we make and the actions we take. Indeed, planning is an archetypical example of Aristotle’s “practical discipline” which concerns the doing of something not separate from the agent [and her] actions and choices. Knowledge of social and spatial processes becomes, at once, a condition for and a consequence of planning. That is why Aristotle’s discussion about action (praxis) is closely linked to the discussion about planners’ ethical values. (Davoudi, 2015: 321, 323) Furthermore, adopted epistemologies and accompanying value-based choices are “situated in time and space and specific to a particular context” (Davoudi, 2015: 323). Such assertions invoke a Foucauldian understanding of ‘situational ethics’ in the sense that epistemologies and values are not only contextually grounded but are also provisional, since human actions—which are closely linked to adopted epistemologies and accompanying values—are “made through ongoing internal and external processes” (Foucault, 1990: 9). And because actions are “made, they can be unmade, as long as we know how they were made” (ibid.). The idea that actions are ‘made’ through ongoing internal and external processes also draws our attention to the fact 83

Tanja Winkler

that epistemologies of ethical actions are both self-constructed (through subjective interpretations) and socially constructed (through intersubjective interpretations). Foucault talks about ethics in relation to “an aesthetics of existence,” that is, the relationship you have to yourself when you act. [Whereas] Aristotle is mainly talking about ethics in relation to social and political praxis, that is, the relationship you have to society when you act. (Flyvbjerg, 2001: 55) Persons and objects, groups and institutions, are therefore not merely given, but are instead open to subjective and intersubjective interpretations that concern both the self and society (Beauregard, 2012). And since individuals and groups hold different world views—that are subjectively and intersubjectively constructed—Foucault (1984: 37) argues that “the search for a form of morality acceptable by everyone, in the sense that everyone would have to submit to it, seems catastrophic to me”. These kinds of arguments then suggest the need for some engagement with the nature and meaning of the ethical choices we adopt when we hope to plan. Such engagements also allow us to question, rethink, and, if necessary, challenge first-order ethical framings that are in dispute (Fraser, 2009). However, because the study of meta ethics explicitly desists from establishing how we ought to plan, scholars of planning ethics tend to dismiss meta ethics as irrelevant to planning theory and practice (cf. Campbell, 2006, 2012a, 2012b; Campbell and Marshall, 1999; Harper and Stein, 1992; Hendler, 1996, 2001; Lo Piccolo and Thomas, 2009; Stein and Harper, 2005; Thomas, 1991; Thomas and Healey, 1991; Wachs, 1985). Thus, for some, further explorations of the nature and meaning of planning values are deemed superfluous, because first-order framings remain uncontested. Argued differently, because the normative idea of planning rests squarely upon “a search for a better future” (Healey, 2012: 199), it is assumed that planners instinctively know what the nature and the meaning of this ‘better’ future entails. This might be argued even if scholars hint at meta ethical concerns when suggesting that it is “the nature of ‘better’ that requires engagement with ethics” (Campbell, 2012b: 393, my emphasis), or when suggesting that the normative idea of planning “demands consideration of what ‘better’ could and should mean” (Healey, 2012: 199, my emphasis). But instead of delving deeper into what this nature means, and how we might know if something is ‘better’ (or not), scholars tend to turn only to first-order ethical theories for answers to their considerations. By way of an example of this tendency, Campbell (2012b: 393, my emphasis) proposes that: [There] is no need for a perfect definition of justice or equality [in order] to take actions which will reduce injustices and inequalities. [That] such actions will fall short is no revelation. The revelation lies in the ability to envisage better actions, which will deliver better outcomes. While planners might not require perfect definitions of justice or equality in order to act, Winkler and Duminy (2016), nevertheless, suggest that since subjective and intersubjective interpretations of ethical values vary from person to person, from culture to culture, and from one context to another (including from one neighbourhood to another neighbourhood within the same city), we need to engage with the nature and meaning of the planning values we adopt when we hope to act. Arguably, in the absence of such engagements our planning actions might “lead to unintended consequences” (Davoudi, 2015: 324). We therefore cannot assume that all participants or recipients of a planning intervention subscribe to the same interpretations 84

Rethinking Scholarship on Planning Ethics

and understandings of ethical values such as ‘justice’ or ‘equality’, for example (cf. Winkler and Duminy 2016 for an example of residents’ and planners’ conflicting interpretations of ‘justice’ or ‘equality’ that led to unintended consequences). But, how can I be sure that contemporary epistemologies of ethical actions preclude, for the most part, meta ethical considerations? Without presenting a lengthy discussion on planning’s philosophical roots, it is worth noting that it was only once an explicit epistemological break from unitary and universal methods was called for in the late 1950s, that a greater engagement with planning ethics began to surface (cf. Marcuse, 1976). Until then, planners seldom felt compelled to justify their work from an ethical standpoint, since planning actions that were based on unitary scientific methods (whether from posteriori or priori standpoints) were deemed to be sufficient justifications for what should take place (cf. Freestone, 2000; Friedmann, 1987). Ethical concerns, therefore, remained subsumed within matters of procedural correctness and professional integrity. With the rise of hermeneutic approaches to knowledge production in the social sciences—that coincided with a recognition of the political nature of planning (cf. Davidoff, 1965; Freestone, 2000; Friedmann, 1987; Klosterman, 1978; Madanipour, 2015)—planning scholars sought to challenge the then assumed value-neutral stance of the profession by arguing that the social world “can only be understood from within, rather than from without” (Davoudi, 2015: 319). Still, one might ask, as Davoudi does, from within what? To this she responds: Either “from within the mind of each individual planner (subjective meaning), [or] from within the social rules which render [a] planner’s action with meaning (objective meaning)”. And for Davoudi (2015: 319): Subjective meanings are concepts “we think about”, while objective meanings are concepts “we think with”. Although difficult to untangle from each other, the separation is analytically [and philosophically] useful as it highlights the distinction between what a planning action means to others and what a planner means by it. It might then be argued that if a planner interprets (or thinks about) ‘the world’ from within her subjective mind in order to understand the meaning of her actions, so too do recipients of a planning action interpret (or think about) ‘their world’ and what a planning action means to them from within their subjective minds. Thus, different and even conflicting interpretations of these meanings can arise. This might be argued regardless of the socially constructed nature of establishing value-based meanings, as “it [seems] impossible to secure one’s own [values entirely] independently of the [values held by] others” (Aristotle, cited in Flyvbjerg, 2001: 59). This can also be argued regardless of the social rules that render planning actions with objective meanings, since we all “interpret the world through specific forms of language and thought that are situated in specific social and political contexts” (Davoudi, 2015: 319). Nonetheless, while the manifold interpretations of subjective and intersubjective ethical meanings were briefly celebrated during the first decades of the twentieth century—as moral philosophy was no longer solely embroiled in (first-order) normative ethical concerns—the study of (second-order) meta ethics declined after the influential publication of John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice in 1971 (Bridge, 2000; Jacobs, 2002). The Rawlsian idea that self-interested and rational individuals emerge from behind ‘a veil of ignorance’ to live in a risk-adverse society became the moral basis for “a rejuvenated conception of normative ethics from a universalist, impartial and liberal-individualist perspective” (Bridge, 2000: 520; cf. Rawls, 1971). For the scholarship on planning ethics in particular, the idea that social rules render planning actions with objective meaning thus grew in prominence, even if Rawls’ (2001) later assertions recant universal ethical positions. Rawlsian philosophy—with its dominant focus on normative ethics—remains a key influence on the scholarship of planning ethics (Howe, 1990). Explicitly stated: “Rawls’ normative 85

Tanja Winkler

ethical theory provides a firm moral basis for much of contemporary planning theory” (Stein and Harper, 2005: 148). Accordingly, scholars maintain that our ethical choices “must be deemed good (or bad) in order for good and bad to have meaning” (Flyvbjerg, 2001: 57, my emphasis). But instead of critically reflecting on subjective and intersubjective meanings of ‘good’ and ‘bad’, or on the nature of ‘good’ and ‘bad’ in situated contexts, scholars of planning ethics assume that “debates in planning theory need to be understood [only] as debates about underlying normative ethical theories” (Harper and Stein, 1992: 105), because “determining what constitutes ‘the good’ or whose interest this good serves are highly normative questions” (Davoudi, 2015: 326; cf. Campbell, 2006, 2012a, 2012b). Let us explore this assumption a little further by demonstrating how three different planning theories—that are grounded in different epistemologies of action—retain a focus on normative ethical theories and the social rules we think with (Davoudi, 2015), irrespective of the fact that all three embrace the idea that planning is a value-laden discipline. Habermas’ (1984, 1987a, 1987b, 1990) theory of communicative action acknowledges, in the first instance, the existence of stakeholders’ subjective and competing ethics. However, in order to proceed from this initial meta ethical acknowledgement, and in order to arrive at an ethics of action, Habermas’ (1990: 120) procedural discourse ethics necessitates the production of “normatively right statements based on good reasons”. For Habermas (1990: 120), these “normatively right statements [are the] agreed upon social rules [that allow us] to reach consensus on generalizable maxims”. And by necessitating a consensus on social rules and generalisable maxims, Habermasian discourses unquestioningly shift their focus from subjective ethical values to “a universal ethics of action” (Bridge, 2000: 519), since, according to Habermas, an ethical norm is “universal when all affected stakeholders [of a communicative process] accept the consequences of an ethical norm” (Bridge, 2000: 523). As such, all participants of a communicative process presumably can, and will, accept the consequences of agreed upon social rules and ethical norms, because these rules and norms are based on the concepts we think with and not the concepts we think about (Davoudi, 2015). In other words, “Habermas is a universalistic, top-down moralist [in that] the rules for correct [ethical] process are normatively given in advance” (Flyvbjerg, 2001: 91). We might then conclude that our normative framings are not in dispute, and that these framings cannot be unmade, since ‘correct’ ethical matters are already decided in advance. Such conclusions, however, ignore Fraser’s (2009) and Foucault’s (1984, 1990) invaluable insights. In the same way that Habermasian procedural discourse ethics moves from recognising subjective values to a position of ‘generalisable’ ethical norms, communicative and collaborative planning theories move from intersubjectivities to a position of consensus based on normatively ‘correct’ ethical processes that are established in advance. Communicative and collaborative theorists thus begin their arguments with a recognition of discursive spaces that are intersubjectively constructed, before shifting their focus to the search for agreed upon communicative actions in a ‘scaled-up’ public realm. Here, in this scaled-up public realm, members of a group no longer orientate their actions toward subjective and intersubjective concerns. Rather, actions are oriented toward a “unifying, consensus-building force in which participants overcome their subjectively biased views in favor of a rationally motivated agreement” (Habermas, 1987b: 315). Habermasian procedural discourse ethics combines elements of intersubjectivity and abstract universal ethics for the ultimate purpose of establishing consensual communicative actions, while the nature of ‘consensual actions’ remains subsumed within a normative understanding of ethical theories that renders communicative actions with objective meanings alone. Flyvbjerg (2001), in contrast to communicative and collaborative theorists, draws on an Aristotelian conceptualisation of phronesis and a Foucauldian understanding of situational ethics 86

Rethinking Scholarship on Planning Ethics

that rejects universal rules. Yet, and somewhat surprisingly, Flyvbjerg’s moral point of departure remains firmly grounded in normative ethical theories. Accordingly, Flyvbjerg (2001: 130) begins his phronetic inquiry by focusing only on the following three normative ethical questions: “Where are we going? Is it desirable? What should be done?” But this focus relegates meta ethical concerns to a realm of mere intellectual curiosity, which is demonstrated via Flyvbjerg’s (2001: 98) acknowledgement that “Foucault is a declared opponent of Kant’s question, ‘what ought I to do?’ or Lenin’s ‘what is to be done?’” Thus, instead of grappling with Foucault’s rejection of Kant’s and Lenin’s normative ethical questions, “phronesis concerns the analysis of values that are good or bad” despite the possibility that different members of a “reference group” might hold different understandings of ‘good’ and ‘bad’ (Flyvbjerg, 2001: 57). To be clear, phronetic research is based on subjective and intersubjective “interpretations [that are] open for testing in relation to other interpretations” (Flyvbjerg, 2001: 130). However, “every interpretation must be built upon claims of validity, [because] one interpretation is not as good as another. [Rather,] the key point is the establishment of a better interpretation” (Flyvbjerg, 2001: 130, 131, original emphasis). Phronetic research, therefore, seeks to ensure that value-based choices are “not based on idiosyncratic morality or personal preferences, but instead on a common view among a specific reference group” (Flyvbjerg, 2001: 130). It is then assumed that all members of a reference group hold a ‘common view’ regarding the value-based choices needed when aiming to establish: What is desirable? And how should we achieve these desires? It is also assumed that all members intuitively know what the meaning of a better interpretation encompasses, because “phronesis is what permits one to chase away false opinions and make good decisions” that are informed by predetermined validity claims (Flyvbjerg, 2001: 110, my emphasis). Other planning scholars, in turn, focus on how “various subjectivities coalesce in ways that undermine and disrupt ways of knowing [and doing in situated contexts]” (Derickson, 2015: 653; cf. Porter, 2010). Contained within these scholarships are more nuanced understandings of the manifold, and often non-discursive, ways in which lived experiences of difference, marginalisation and subalterneity are produced through competing subjectivities. Such understandings are central to multicultural and intercultural planning theories, among other contemporary scholarships that are grounded in postcolonial, subaltern and feminist epistemologies. Sandercock (1998: 30), accordingly, calls for a more “inclusive democracy [of] heterogeneous publics”. And the accompanying ethical values for the fulfilment of heterogeneous publics might be understood from a Levinian conceptualisation of intersubjectivities that is founded on a moral agent’s unconditional responsibility toward others. Here we find an ethics of care and respect. However, ethical responsibilities toward others require “a move from proximity to infinity” (Bridge, 2000: 526), where proximity is based on intersubjective and situational ethics, whereas infinity is based on “a higher realm of ethical conduct” that is shaped by agreed upon social rules (Lash, 1996: 102). Hence, in the same way that Habermas is able to move from the subjective to the universal, or Flyvbjerg is able to move from situational ethics to common validity claims, Levinas is able to move from the intersubjective to the infinite. And in all three epistemologies of ethical action, value-based judgements involve, by-and-large, normative ethical concerns that emphasise the ethical concepts we think with. Regardless then of scholars’ critiques of the tendency in planning to derive ethical principles from “a universal set of deontological values” (Watson, 2006: 46), concerns pertaining to planning values remain, for the most part, normative ethical concerns that are shaped by the social rules ‘we think with’. This is not to suggest that these concepts and rules are irrelevant. Rather, if scholars based in Africa (or elsewhere) are asked to seek “new moral philosophical sources to inform [their] thinking” (ibid.), perhaps a starting point for such a search is from a meta ethical position before arriving at normative judgements. Such a starting point might be of particular 87

Tanja Winkler

interest to scholars who are calling for alternative ways of theorising ‘the African urban’ (or the global South-East), since reflecting on first- and second-order ethical questions allows us to shift our attention from merely explaining social events as being different in different contexts, to “understanding what the social world means for the people who live in it” (Davoudi, 2015: 320, my emphasis). Let us now briefly turn our ‘gaze’ to the relevance of meta ethics for Southern scholarships. In so doing, the aim is not to argue for a totalising narrative. Rather, the aim is to encourage an ongoing search for authentic specificities by embedding local knowledge(s), actions and value-based claims within everyday subjectivities and intersubjectivities.

Turning Our ‘Gaze’ to Southern Epistemologies of Ethical Actions For many Southern scholars, the problem with planning theory stems from the geopolitical dominance of knowledge production within capital-centric settings (Appiah, 2006; Connell, 2007; Kemete, 2010; Parnell et al., 2009; Pieterse, 2010; Robinson, 2006; Roy, 2008; 2011; Watson, 2009; Yiftachel, 2006). And for them, a useful starting point to provincialise mainstream theories—including those with a more critical bent—involves grappling with how we might come to know Southern urbanities. Being able to identify and name Southern urbanities as something different—all be they ‘ordinary’ (Robinson, 2006) and intrinsically linked to global economies (Roy, 2008)—also allows them to question contemporary planning values. In fact, Parnell, Pieterse and Watson (2009: 235, my emphasis) argue in favour of “making the values of planning contextually relevant to our location in Africa”. However, they go on to suggest that “there is scope for the reaffirmation of the fundamental values that underpin planning” (Parnell et al., 2009: 235, my emphasis). But whether ‘contextually relevant’ values are necessarily the same as, or compatible with, planning’s ‘fundamental values’, is an issue that remains undisputed. Rather, for Parnell et al. (2009), concerns pertaining to planning values are normative ethical concerns. Accordingly, their focus is aimed at how we should plan in order to improve urban conditions in Africa; and from their standpoint, we should plan by ensuring ‘greater equity’ and ‘socio-spatial justice’: “Planners do not alter the fundamental relations of society, but they may be able to stimulate particular growth paths, mitigate disasters, [and] identify how to redistribute resources to ensure greater equity and socio-spatial justice” (Parnell et al., 2009: 235, my emphasis). Yet, what precisely is the nature and meaning of ‘greater equity’ and ‘socio-spatial justice’ in a situated context? How might we know if our planning-based interpretations of ‘equity’ and ‘justice’ are ‘better’ than the interpretations made by residents with whom we hope to plan? What are residents’ subjective and intersubjective understandings of values such as ‘equity’ and ‘justice’, and how might these understandings differ from a planner’s interpretation of ‘equity’ and ‘justice’? These are the types of questions that remain unanswered despite the fact that answers to these meta ethical questions have very real consequences for planning in Southern (and other) contexts. To clarify, by posing these kinds of questions I am not questioning the concepts of ‘equity’ or ‘justice’ per se. Rather, second-order ethical questions allow us to explore how subjective and intersubjective interpretations of ethical values such as ‘equity’ or ‘justice’, for example, shape planning outcomes in situated contexts. Engaging with meta ethical questions then becomes relevant if we hope to understand how and why ethical meanings differ in practice, and if we hope to explain how competing understandings of values are in themselves embroiled in power relations that shape planning outcomes. From this perspective, keeping concepts such as ‘equity’ and ‘justice’ (or any other planning value) as relatively undefined normative principles serves only to obscure unequal power relations, while negating opportunities to justify the validity of our normative ethical claims and social rules in the first place. But regardless of the potentials that might arise from 88

Rethinking Scholarship on Planning Ethics

meta ethical inquiries, ongoing quests for Southern theories remain rooted in desires for alternative epistemologies alone: “[W]e need to understand the various epistemological dimensions of the overall knowledge project that has to simultaneously provincialize western-centred urban theories while addressing the imperative to purpose” (Pieterse, 2012: 26, my emphasis). Western-centred epistemologies are identified as necessitating provincialisation, while similar assertions are not asked of normative planning ethics. However, if impartial and universal rationalities are rejected as epistemological bases for Southern scholarships, why then do we continue to frame Southern (or other) epistemologies of ethical actions within planning values that are assumed to be known and shared from the outset? One answer to this question—as gleaned from Davoudi’s (2015) argument—is that we have not yet begun the project of untangling the subjective meanings ‘we think about’ from the objective meanings ‘we think with’. Our normative social rules are presumed to be ‘agreed upon’, ‘shared’, ‘common’ and ‘given’ in advance, even if contemporary theories draw on poststructural, postcolonial, subaltern and feminist scholarships that value subjective and situated epistemologies of action. But by neglecting the project of untangling subjective meanings from taken-for-granted social rules, we equally neglect what our planning interventions might mean to others, and what the consequences of different meanings might be for the residents who live and work in the spaces we plan (even if we aim to plan with them). Of equal concern, by neglecting second-order ethical questions we relinquish the opportunity to question, reflect on and unmake our ethical framings that are in dispute.

Conclusion It is argued that epistemological standpoints and accompanying actions shape—and are shaped by—ethical principles, and that epistemologies of ethical actions undergo periodic shifts in accordance with ever-changing philosophical understandings of ‘the world’. Thus, contemporary ways of knowing and doing are, on the whole, grounded in poststructural, postcolonial, subaltern or feminist scholarships that value subjective and situated knowledge. Yet regardless of an assertion that knowledge, actions and values are recursively interlinked, and that epistemologies of action are subject to ongoing transformations, our objectively defined social rules and moral points of departure seem to be static, because these rules and morals are assumed to be known, shared and given in advance. Furthermore, and despite an acceptance of planning’s value-laden nature, scholarships on planning ethics continue to focus, almost entirely, on normative ethical theories that hone in on first-order ethical questions such as: How should we plan, what ought to be done, and what is done (for the purpose of launching ‘better’ outcomes)? And answers to these types of questions presuppose that planners are sufficiently knowledgeable to endorse some ethical judgements while rejecting others, and that planners intuitively know what the nature and meaning of a ‘better’ outcome should entail. For these reasons, when scholars acknowledge that planners “may not [always] know what to do when it comes to moral choices about what course of action to take” (Davoudi, 2015: 321), they tend only to turn to a normative ethics of knowing to what end. While this purposeful knowing is indispensable if we hope to act, a focus on normative ethics alone precludes the possibility that the nature and meaning of our planning values might be understood and experienced as something different by the recipients of our actions. So while “people [tend to] know what they do; [and while] they frequently know why they do what they do; what they don’t know is what what they do does [to others]” (Foucault, 1982, here cited from Davoudi, 2015: 327). Foucault’s somewhat convoluted assertion therefore remains intact, because scholarships on planning ethics have not yet begun to untangle the value-based meanings ‘we think about’ from the objective meanings and the social rules ‘we think with’. 89

Tanja Winkler

Foucault explicitly defines his ethics as a type of “thinking differently” (Foucault, 1990: 9). Alternative ways of theorising planning might then rest not only with how we know and act in ‘the world’, but also with how we might ‘think differently’ about planning ethics by engaging with normative and meta ethical concerns. Meta ethical concerns allow us to consider the specific nature and histories of ethical principles, and how we come to know our own and other value-based judgements before deciding on how we should plan or what the ‘better’ judgement is. “Because [these concerns are] pitched to the meta-level, [they also] permit us to entertain the possibility that first-order questions have been unjustly framed” (Fraser, 2009: 294), and that taken-for-granted framings can be unmade (Foucault, 1990). Moreover, if “planning cultures worldwide exist only in the plural” (Friedmann, 2005: 184), then meta ethics becomes relevant to scholarships that purposefully seek to embed local knowledge(s), actions and value-based claims within everyday subjectivities and intersubjectivities. “The trick [however] is to resist the reactionary and ultimately futile temptation to cling to assumptions that are no longer appropriate to our post-Westphalian world” (Fraser, 2009: 295). For this reason, meta ethical theories explicitly desist from establishing criteria for making ethical judgements about situated contexts. Establishing such criteria would be a distinctly normative project: one that aims to develop some authoritative model by which other things are judged. So while meta ethical questions cannot assist us in deciding which ethical principles are ‘right’ or ‘wrong’, ‘better’ or ‘worse’, or how we should plan, such questions can assist us in our different understandings of how planners arrive at moral judgements in the first place; how we employ ethical principles in practice; what our planning interventions might mean to others; and what the consequences of different meanings might be. Meta ethical engagements unsettle our own presuppositions. And in so doing, they empower us to critically reflect on our value-based frames of reference by deliberately prompting us to rethink our scholarships on planning ethics.

References Appiah, K. (2006). Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers. London: Allen Lane. Beauregard, R. (2012). Planning with things. Journal of Planning Education and Research. 32(2): 182–190. Bridge, G. (2000). Rationality, ethics, and space: On situated universalism and the self-interested acknowledgement of ‘difference’. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space. 18: 519–535. Campbell, H. (2006). Just planning: The art of situated ethical judgements. Journal of Planning Education and Research. 26(1): 92–106. Campbell, H. (2012a). Planning to change the world: Between knowledge and action lies synthesis. Journal of Planning Education and Research. 32(2): 135–146. Campbell, H. (2012b). Planning ethics and rediscovering the idea of planning. Planning Theory. 11(4): 379–399. Campbell, H. & Marshall, R. (1999). Ethical frameworks and planning theory. International Journal of Urban & Regional Research. 23(3): 464–478. Code, L. (2007). Ethics in Epistemology. Workshop sponsored by CEPTES, 3TU Centre for Ethics and Technology. University of Twente, the Netherlands, 29 May. Connell, R. (2007). Southern Theory: Social Science and the Global Dynamics of Knowledge. Cambridge: Polity Press. Davidoff, P. (1965). Advocacy and pluralism in planning. Journal of the American Institute of Planners. 31: 596–615. Davoudi, S. (2015). Planning as practice of knowing. Planning Theory. 14(3): 316–331. Derickson, K. (2015). Urban geography I: Locating urban theory in the ‘urban age’. Progress in Human Geography. 39(5): 647–657. Fainstein, S. (2010). The Just City. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Flyvbjerg, B. (2001). Making Social Science Matter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Foucault, M. (1982). The subject and power. In H. Dreyfus & P. Rabinow (Eds) Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics. Chicago: Chicago University Press: 208–226.

90

Rethinking Scholarship on Planning Ethics Foucault, M. (1984). Le Retour de la morale. Les Nouvelles. 2937, June: 36–41. Foucault, M. (1990). The Use of Pleasure: The History of Sexuality. Volume II. New York: Vintage Books. Fraser, N. (2009). Who counts? Dilemmas of justice in a post-Westphalian world. Antipode. 41(1): 281–297. Freestone, R. (2000). Learning from planning’s histories. In R. Freestone (Ed.) Urban Planning in a Changing World. London: Routledge: 1–15. Friedmann, J. (1987). Planning in the Public Domain. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Friedmann, J. (2005). Globalization and the emerging culture of planning. Progress in Planning. 64: 183–234. Garner, R. & Rosen, B. (1967). Moral Philosophy: A Systematic Introduction to Normative Ethics and Metaethics. New York: Macmillan. Gunder, M. (2004). Shaping the planner’s ego-ideal: A Lacanian interpretation of planning education. Journal of Planning Education and Research. 23(3): 299–311. Gunder, M. & Hillier, J. (2009). Planning in Ten Words or Less: A Lacanian Entanglement with Spatial Planning. Farnham: Ashgate. Habermas, J. (1984). The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 1: Reason and the Rationalisation of Society. Translated by T. McCarthy. London: Heinemann. Habermas, J. (1987a). The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 2: A Critique of Functionalist Reason. Translated by T. McCarthy. Cambridge: Polity Press. Habermas, J. (1987b). The Philosophical Discourse of Morality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Habermas, J. (1990). Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Translated by C. Lenhardt. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Harper, T. & Stein, S. (1992). The centrality of normative ethical theory to contemporary planning theory. Journal of Planning Education and Research. 11(2): 105–116. Healey, P. (1997). Collaborative Planning: Shaping Places in Fragmented Societies. London: Macmillan. Healey, P. (2012). The universal and the contingent: Some reflections on the transnational flow of planning ideas and practices. Planning Theory. 11(2): 188–207. Hendler, S. (1996). On the use of models in planning ethics. In S. Mandelbaum, L. Mazza & R. Burchell (Eds) Explorations in Planning Theory. New Brunswick: The Center for Urban Policy Research, Rutgers University: 400–413. Hendler, S. (2001). Planning ethics. In N. Smelser & P. Baltes (Eds) International Encyclopaedia of the Behavioural and Social Sciences. Oxford: Elsevier: 11474–11479. Howe, E. (1990). Normative ethics in planning. Journal of Planning Literature. 5(2): 123–150. Jacobs, J. (2002). Dimensions of Moral Theory: An Introduction to Metaethics and Moral Psychology. Oxford: Blackwell. Kemete, A. (2010). Defending illicit livelihoods: Youth resistance in Harare’s contested spaces. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research. 34(1): 55–75. Klosterman, R.E. (1978). Foundations for normative planning. In M. Wachs (Ed.) (1985). Ethics in Planning. New Brunswick: The Center for Urban Policy Research, Rutgers University. Lash, S. (1996). Postmodern ethics: The missing ground. Theory, Culture and Society. 13: 91–104. Lo Piccolo, F. & Thomas, H. (Eds) (2009). Ethics and Planning Research Survey. Burlington, VT: Ashgate. Mackie, J.L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. New York: Penguin Books. Madanipour, A. (Ed.) (2015). Planning Theory: Critical Concepts in Built Environment. Volume 1. Planning with Creativity. London, New York: Routledge. Marcuse, P. (1976). Professional ethics and beyond: Values in planning. Journal of the American Planning Association. 42(3): 264–274. Parnell, S., Pieterse, E. & Watson, V. (2009). Planning for cities in the global South: An African research agenda for sustainable human settlement. Progress in Planning. 72: 233–248. Pieterse, E. (2010). Cityness and African urban development. Urban Forum. 21(3): 205–219. Pieterse, E. (2012). High wire acts: Knowledge imperatives of southern urbanism. Symposium paper. Emergent cities: Conflicting claims and the politics of informality. University of Uppsala, Sweden. 9–10 March. Porter, L. (2010). Unlearning the Colonial Cultures of Planning. Farnham: Ashgate. Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Robinson, J. (2006). Ordinary Cities: Between Modernity and Development. London: Routledge. Roy, A. (2008). Post liberalism: On the ethico-politics of planning. Planning Theory. 7(1): 92–102. Roy, A. (2011). Slumdog cities: Rethinking subaltern urbanism. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research. 35(2): 223–238. Sandercock, L. (Ed.) (1998). Making the Invisible Visible: A Multicultural Planning History. Berkeley: University of California Press.

91

Tanja Winkler Sandercock, L. (2003). Cosmopolis II: Mongrel Cities in the 21st Century. London: Continuum. Stein, S. & Harper, T. (2005). Rawls’ justice and fairness: A moral basis for contemporary planning theory. Planning Theory. 4(2): 147–172. Thomas, H. (Ed.) (1991). Values in Planning. Avebury: Ashgate. Thomas, H. & Healey, P. (1991). Dilemmas of Planning Practice: Ethics, Legitimacy and the Validation of Knowledge. Aldershot: Avebury Technical. van Fraassen, B. (2007). Ethics in epistemology. Workshop sponsored by CEPTES, 3TU Centre for Ethics and Technology. University of Twente, the Netherlands, 29 May. Wachs, M. (Ed.) (1985). Ethics in Planning. New Brunswick: The Center for Urban Policy Research, Rutgers University. Watson, V. (2006). Deep difference: Diversity, planning and ethics. Planning Theory. 5(1): 31–50. Watson, V. (2009). Seeing from the South: Refocusing urban planning on the globe’s central urban issues. Urban Studies. 46(11): 2259–2275. Winkler, T. & Duminy, J. (2016). Planning to change the world? Questioning the normative ethics of planning theories. Planning Theory. 15(2): 111–129. Yiftachel, O. (2006). Re-engaging planning theory? Towards ‘South-Eastern’ perspectives. Planning Theory. 5(3): 211–222.

92

8 COMMUNICATIVE PLANNING Tore Sager

Core Ideas and Progress of Communicative Planning Communicative planning (CP) is seen here as a participatory and dialogical endeavour involving a broad range of stakeholders and affected groups in socially oriented and fairness-seeking developments of land, infrastructure, or public services. It is guided by a process exploring the potential for cooperative ways of settling planning disputes and designed to approach the principles of discourse ethics, demanding processes to be open, undistorted, truth-seeking, and directed at mutual understanding. The process of CP is open in the sense of being inclusive and transparent; the public can gain knowledge of what is going on. Development efforts are socially oriented when they aim to further the interests of large segments of society rather than the interests of a few stakeholders only. Fairness-seeking development aims to improve the living conditions of deprived groups, and its planned results observe the rights of all groups. CP aims to advance deliberative democracy by exploring the potential for broad workable agreement on planning matters, in any case making deliberation inclusive and thorough before a planning issue is politically settled. This mode of planning also helps democracy produce fair outcomes by striving to reduce the influence of systematically biased power relations on the dialogically determined recommendations. It is assumed that a change toward more participative approaches will help to develop social capital and community cohesion, improve service delivery to meet local needs, restore information flows and accountability, and give voice to those most directly affected by public policy. Excellent overviews of CP are offered by Allmendinger (2009: 197–223) and Healey (2012). The present chapter gives more attention to the difference from ordinary citizen participation, the planner role, legitimation, and the critique of CP for facilitating neo-liberalism. All strands of CP research have in common a revision and expansion of what used to count as rational decisions (Sager 1994: 3–25). Instrumental rationality is insufficient in the kind of planning where the ulterior end is embedded in the participatory process itself. Dialogue, close ego-confirming relationships, and the experience of being able to make a difference, are important to the development of mature personalities. These activities have intrinsic value independent of any goal-oriented strategy. ‘Communicative rationality’ (Habermas 1998: 220–22, 300) requires arguments in dialogue to be comprehensible, factually true, sincere, and appropriate within the normative context of public planning. This rationality established Communicative Planning 93

Tore Sager

Theory (CPT) as a bulwark against the relativism of post-modernism (Harper and Stein 2006). It provided a platform for critiquing and building alternatives to plans with a narrow economic focus, and planning processes designed to be the fastest road to implementation of ready-made decisions. Communicative rationality depends on the use of language oriented toward mutual understanding and sets CP apart from earlier modes of planning. Synoptic (rationalistic) planning and disjointed incrementalism are built on instrumental rationality in full-blown or modified versions (Innes 1995: 184). The most important forerunner of CP is John Friedmann’s transactive planning, in which dialogue and mutual learning are key concepts (Friedmann 1973). Processed knowledge justifies the expert status of the planner. Personal knowledge reflects the undisguised subjective interpretations of the lay person, resting on an informed and detailed picture of the local conditions. The planner expands the frame of local lay people’s assessment of the plan; lay people supply nuances and particulars to the planner’s outline of local consequences. The necessary exchange of experience requires – according to Friedmann – a more personal, face-to-face relationship between experts and lay people, namely, the transactive style. Friedmann launched dialogue and transactive planning against the backcloth of what he called ‘the cracked melting pot: rising cultural pluralism’ (Friedmann 1973: 90–93). The sentiment of instability lingers on in Innes and Booher’s (2010: 3) advocacy for CP in the US context marked by rapid transformation, a ‘new tribalism’, and an accompanying loss of identity and shared values. The inception of CPT came with John Forester’s PhD dissertation in 1977, outlining a critical theory of planning. Critical CPT assesses how organizational and institutional contexts affect the contingencies, the fragility, and the vulnerable precariousness of people’s speaking and deliberating together in preparation for collective action (Forester 1993: x, 4). Mangled communication patterns are an important aspect of the contexts in which planning takes place. These patterns are shaped by power and ideology. In CPT, the critique of ideology turns into the critique of systematically distorted communicative structuring of citizens’ attention; that is, the taken-forgranted power relations encroaching on efforts to make sense together in autonomous dialogue (Forester 1993: 62). Critical CPT aims to scrutinize and reform planning and decision processes in order to advance fairness by empowering local publics. In planning practice, communication is political. Even if the power of planners is limited, they can influence the communication between the parties involved in the process. Planners do this, for example, by shaping attention and questioning the information, statements, and arguments of the parties, thereby revealing misinformation, authoritarian pressure, and power games. Forester developed this strategy into a critical tool in articles from the early 1980s. Jürgen Habermas’ critical theory of communication was a main inspiration (Habermas 1998). Other influences are mentioned in Forester’s own accounts of the early development of CP (Forester 2013). The arguments for CP were brought together in the seminal book Planning in the Face of Power (Forester 1989). It spelled out the strategy for achieving fairness in planning processes by approaching dialogue and identifying and counteracting manipulation, threats, concealment, self-serving argumentation, and other forms of communicative distortions. Main works by other authors have later elaborated on the theory and tried to advance the practice of CP (Harper and Stein 2006, Healey 2006, Innes and Booher 2010, Sager 1994, 2013). Healey and Innes searched for new forms of governance, such as consensus building, alternative dispute resolution, and various kinds of partnership and collaboration, while Forester explored the techniques and opportunities of mediation. CP theorists have attended to a wide range of communicative practices, such as listening, storytelling, rhetoric, mediation, and use of metaphors. A rich literature links CP to descriptions of the argumentative and interactive aspects of a planner’s day and to a variety of planning tasks. 94

Communicative Planning

Communicative Planning and Citizen Participation When CPT appeared in academic journals, citizen participation had been a hot topic among planning scholars for one and a half decades or more (Levine 1960). An important difference between typical citizen participation and critical CP is illustrated by the concepts ‘invited space’ and ‘invented space’ (Miraftab 2004). Citizen participation is about inviting groups and individuals from civil society into the official planning process and creating arenas – invited space – for expression of opinion and information exchange between professional planners and affected lay people. CP entails citizen participation, but acknowledges the need that some protest groups and social movements have for standing outside the official planning process. Communicative planners meet these actors in invented spaces external to the planning framework of the authorities. Communication in these arenas can come closer to discussion on an equal footing and bring a wider set of interests into the planning dialogue. Citizen participation takes place within a framework encouraging public input, but ending public involvement well before implementation and even before the decisive discussions. The intention in CP is, in contrast, that the dialogue among stakeholders, planners, and public should include all affected actors, making joint recommendations hard to ignore when the politicians finally decide. The desired shift is from a planner–citizen information exchange under citizen participation, to a wider dialogue, solution-seeking, and decision-oriented deliberation in CP. It has been questioned whether CP, in practice, adds much to earlier planning processes with procedures for public involvement. Similar to the assessment of regular, government-initiated citizen participation, available case studies are by no means in agreement on the potential and the success so far of CP. Margerum (2002) belongs to the creed concluding in a balanced or largely positive tone, while Bedford et  al. (2002) are among the many sceptical researchers. They conclude that experience with CP has been discouraging, or that real gains have still to be proved. CP theorists were keen to study what was going on in participative processes and to make improvements. The aim was not only to expand participation in numbers or to ascend one rung on the ladder from tokenism to codetermination. Rather, the idea was that a dialogical process would enhance mutual understanding, trust, and cooperation, thereby opening up possibilities for planning problem solutions that were not viable in conditions of misunderstanding, mutual suspicion, and clogged communication channels (Innes and Booher 2010). Aspirations were not limited to procedural progress, although this is often assumed by critics (Fainstein 2014: 7). The critique that communicative planners take little interest in the content of the plans is understandable, however, as the transformation from procedural values to substantive realities reflecting them, is severely understudied in CPT. Other aspects of theory building preoccupied the CP theorists. First, they wondered what institutional designs facilitate the communicative mode of planning (van Dijk et al. 2011). How to put up protective institutional fences around the planning process, so that power outside is less easily converted to domination inside? The planner must have institutional backing for preventing the powerful in market-oriented urban development from trampling on the rights and interests of other parties around the table in the official planning process. Second, several theorists studied how to include marginalized groups and make their voices heard (Sandercock 1998). Advocacy planners tried to achieve this by speaking for the deprived and translating their viewpoints and arguments to technical-economic jargon familiar to bureaucrats. In contrast, communicative planners let communities in need of planning assistance speak for themselves, but direct attention to their problems and proposals, and question critically the attitudes and procedures making it difficult for the disadvantaged to get their message through. 95

Tore Sager

Third, CP theorists prepare for diffusion of the dialogical approach to democratic problem solving beyond the single planning process. The aims of CP fit well with the idea of deliberative democracy (Gutman and Thompson 2004). Neither requires that consensus decisions replace voting. Any actor has the right to stand up for his or her own interest in a liberal democracy. However, just as in deliberative democracy in general, CP explores the potential for working agreement emerging from a process that is reasonably free from communicative distortions (Mansbridge et al. 2010). Fourth, from the start, there was an epistemological side to CPT, which was virtually absent in the already established literature on citizen participation. One strand of CP research took a phenomenological and ethnographic approach (Forester 1992, Sandercock and Attili 2010). Even more important, much North American research linked up with the philosophy of pragmatism (Harper and Stein 2006, Hoch 2007, Verma 1998), as shown in Healey’s (2009) excellent overview. Pragmatic CP research has partly dealt with rational inquiry and the consequences of communicative action. The differences between the approaches of main proponents – such as John Forester, Patsy Healey, and Judith Innes – were particularly clear in the 1980s and 90s. Forester was developing the basis of CP as a critical theory, while Innes – in addition to theoretical works – demonstrated the potential of CP and consensus building by drawing attention to successful cases (Innes and Booher 1999). Healey’s approach was somewhat in between, more formed by institutionalist thinking than Innes, and with a stronger leaning toward place-making and spatial planning than Forester (Healey 2012: 344). Some of the differences are reflected in the terms chosen by the researchers to characterize their versions of CP. Forester denotes his version ‘critical pragmatism’, while Healey and Innes settled for ‘collaborative planning’. Harper and Stein (2006) gave the name ‘dialogical planning’ to their variety of CP, which owes as much to John Rawls and American pragmatists, as to Habermas.

The Planner Role It is not obvious how communicative planners can use the technical-economic knowledge acquired in their academic education, which traditionally gave planners expert status (Fainstein 2014: 7). Wide-ranging impact assessments and network governance bring an increasing number of actors into planning processes. Accordingly, the ideal has changed from expert planning with a public involvement supplement, to participatory planning with a technical-economic expert supplement. An illustration of the change from expert planning to CP can take the typical textbook presentation of synoptic planning as the starting point. Its often-listed phases are problem formulation, goal setting, option seeking, forecasting and impact assessment, evaluation, and implementation. The conspicuous feature of this list of tasks is the falsely assumed self-sufficiency of the expert planner. Everything having to do with interaction between actors in the planning process is invisible. This includes collecting and giving information, facilitation, mediation, negotiating land acquisition, conflict solving, citizen participation, consensus building, coordination with other public agencies, eliciting people’s preferences, and building political support. Masking these interactive tasks makes it difficult to plan and even to understand planning. Nearly everything regarded as essential in CP is relegated to the shadows in rationalistic expert planning. ‘CPT introduced practical heuristics alien to the model, such as listening, inclusion, dialogue, and deliberation among diverse stakeholders’ (Innes and Booher 2015: 197). Impact assessment and the other listed tasks of synoptic planning are not ignored in CP. However, the knowledge and preferences of local communities, interest groups, and stakeholders have

96

Communicative Planning

become more important inputs in the techniques applied to carry out the tasks, and in the process leading up to decisions. It is the role of communicative planners to make stakeholders and affected groups collaborate with each other in a creative process, generating opportunities that offer each participating group more than it could achieve for itself through alternative procedures. Throgmorton (2000) describes the communicative planner’s role as that of being a skilledvoice-in-the-flow of persuasive argumentation. The planners must work both on process and substance. It is part of their role to advance fair plans to the advantage of deprived groups, as well as to design an inclusive process based on open exchange of sincere and honest arguments. As pointed out by Allmendinger (2001: 134), the central coordinating role of the planner is played down in CPT. He regards this as a necessary consequence of the planner’s engagement with local stakeholders in an unbarred search for local consensus. This engagement also leads him to question: ‘[H]ow can you have a profession (whose raison d’être is the application of expert knowledge) if you argue that there is no such thing as expert knowledge, only different opinions to be brought together?’ (Allmendinger 2009: 220–21). The trade-off between catering for local interests and meeting the need for expertise of society at large warrants further discussion in CP.

Legitimizing Communicative Planning Sustainable systems for collective action – such as CP – need legitimacy. Legitimation is about the justification of power. In a democracy, public planning must be legitimate in order to build and retain the authority required to implement plans. Solid anchoring of this authority in democratic institutions is of paramount importance to planners who are trying to restrain particularistic interests that rely on force, and fight for solutions serving the great majority. This section concentrates on legitimizing features that are closely associated with the main attractions of CP, that is, its epistemological, empowering, and relation-building potentials. Public planning is legitimate only when planners can invoke sources of authority beyond and above themselves. A decision is justified if made by the right legitimate authority, and if the procedural rules of this authority were observed. What is worth doing together, according to CP theorists, is what the parties come to agree on in a dialogical process. With the demanding requirements to be fulfilled by a communicative process to make it dialogical in the sense adopted by most CP theorists, it might not be unreasonable to define the consensual outcome of dialogue as being in the public interest. After all, everyone concerned should take part, freely and equally, in the cooperative search for truth, where nothing coerces anyone except the force of a valid argument. In ideal conditions, then, the public interest can be discovered discursively through participatory practice. The remainder of this section draws attention to three ways in which CP can favourably affect knowledge, power, and action, respectively (Sager 2013: 3–33). The argument is that CP is a legitimate way of defining what is in the interest of the citizenry for the following reasons: •• •• ••

The dialogue aimed for engages many people representing all interests affected by the planning, thus increasing the likelihood that decisions are right and fair. One interest group cannot for paternalistic reasons set aside the stated preferences of another group. Social capital networks established by CP generate relational goods, such as social approval, confirmation of identity, and community attachment.

97

Tore Sager

Knowledge: The Advantage of Many Minds The Condorcet jury theorem states that majorities are more likely than any single individual to select the better of two alternatives when there is uncertainty about which of the two better serves the purpose. More accurately, the theorem states that, if each individual is more likely than not to make the better choice between some pair of alternatives, and each individual votes independently and sincerely, then the probability of the majority being correct increases as the number of individuals increases, toward a limiting value of 1 (List and Goodin 2001). The Condorcet jury theorem has been generalized in several respects and offers a strong argument for democratic practices such as CP. The exchange of arguments in inclusive debate free from repression educates the interlocutors and makes it more likely that each of them identifies the best alternative.

Power: Anti-Paternalism In a paternalistic power relationship, the subordinate is regarded as incapable of recognizing and defending his or her own interests, and the paternalist therefore defines and manages these interests on behalf of the less competent individual. Paternalism can be defined as the interference of an individual or a collective actor with another person, against the other’s will, claiming that the person interfered with will be better off or protected from harm (Dworkin 1983: 1). Much paternalism in planning springs from the belief that identifying the public interest requires special knowledge, and that those who have attained this knowledge – the planners – are thereby entitled to make policy on behalf of those who have not. This belief is a challenge to CP in particular, as the credence questions the ability of ordinary citizens to make rational choices concerning public goods. Intrinsic to all paternalistic power relations is the problem that subordinates’ attempts to articulate their own interests conflict with the paternalist’s conviction, and will be repressed. In denying the subordinates all independent means of expressing and defending their interests, there is nothing to stop paternalism with a benevolent intent from degenerating into exercise of power in the interest merely of the powerful. CPT takes a stance against paternalism and fights it by advising that all affected parties come to the table and take part in deliberative decision-making.

Action: Producing Relational Goods Public goods are not only produced through market transactions, contracts, and physical construction, but also through the building of interpersonal relations. Relational goods are public goods that are simultaneously produced and consumed in relationships between people who are not anonymous to each other. Examples of relational goods are social approval, friendship, confirmation of identity, emotional support (encouragement and comfort), solidarity, and a sense of belonging. Relational goods can only be produced by people acting together. Such goods emerging from communicative action are anti-rival, in that a person benefits both as her own and others’ consumption increases. CP produces relational goods in addition to physical goods. Dialogue is conducive to empathy, which in turn promotes pro-social behaviour. A spiral of dialogical rewards is at work, as relational goods, in turn, motivate more CP. The spiral goes like this: CP → interpersonal encounters → social capital networks → relational goods → deeper and more extensive participation. The encounters of CP generate networks of social relations in which social capital 98

Communicative Planning

is embedded. Dialogue is the most efficient vehicle for creating the positive communicative externalities that are inherent in relational goods (Rader Olsson 2009). Planners’ transformation of knowledge into action is mediated by power. CP can improve practice in relation to each of these key words and enhance the legitimacy of governance. CP aims for (1) right decisions through the mechanism of the Condorcet jury theorem, (2) reduced misuse of power by encouraging anti-paternalism, and (3) a stronger motive for participatory collective action by producing relational goods. None of these legitimizing features requires that everyone agrees on the planning matter under discussion.

Debates and Critique CPT sparked off some new planning debates and revived other discussions that were ongoing in the social sciences both inside and outside planning. This section deals with four controversial themes that are partially connected: 1 2 3 4

how to link procedural and substantive qualities; how to conceptualize power and deal with it in planning processes; how to handle social conflicts of interest: consensus seeking or agonism; how to avoid urban public planning becoming biased toward satisfying capital interests, in particular neo-liberalism.

Planning theory is criticized for focusing too narrowly on how to design a democratic process and make it work well. This has come at the expense of theorizing about substance, scrutinizing criteria for what is a good plan. The communicative turn, centring on the interaction between actors in the planning process, intensified this critique (Fainstein and Fainstein 2013: 40–42). Mees (2003) builds on the process-substance gap to blame CP theorists for bringing forward a risky mode of planning. The participatory and communicative part of the planning process is often manipulated or contracted to a minimum level, even if the planners’ engagement with the public was originally advertised as a central characteristic of the process. The problem, according to Mees, is that when this happens, there is nothing left in the ruins of the CP effort that can defend broader social interests. In alternative modes of planning – even in the despised rationalistic expert planning – one has professional recommendations about the substance of the plan to lean on, if workable agreement from deliberation is missing. Mees fears that, in a manipulated and curtailed communicative process, there will be nothing to counteract opportunistic political proposals and profit-maximizing market solutions. CP is seen as risky, as it leaves no defence of non-partisan interests if deliberation fails. An equally salient problem is how to prevent CP being used intentionally – or especially unintentionally – to justify policies that support the predominant economic-political ideology of the time. This question is considered here, directly after the question of risk, as the two problems have the same solution. A standard Marxist critique of spatial planning is that it makes the capitalist markets run smoothly and thus enhances the perpetual accumulation of capital (Scott and Roweis 1977). Fainstein and Fainstein (2013) restate this critique, specifically targeting CP. They contend that CPT flourishes due to neo-liberals’ wish to gain legitimacy through locally agreed development projects, and their need for establishing social institutions that match and advance urban land markets and the continuing flow of investment. A planning regime with a minimum of predefined restrictions and guidelines, and ample possibilities to strike deals at the community level, seems to fit with neo-liberalist preferences. This is because critics assume that developers gain the upper hand in local negotiations. If this is so, communicative planners 99

Tore Sager

facilitate market processes and make development plans the products of individual deals between private firms and the public sector (Fainstein and Fainstein 2013: 41). The values of CPT and neo-liberalism differ greatly. Individualism, entrepreneurialism, accountability, prosperity, merit reward, and freedom of choice are among the neo-liberal values. CPT values are, for example, empathy, empowerment, equality of moral worth, fairness, honesty, inclusiveness, responsiveness, and self-government. The value differences are the foundation of the strategy for addressing the charge that CPT facilitates the progress of neo-liberal urban development. The strategy is to bring process qualities and outcome qualities closer together. It must be made evident that what is required from the plan (the outcome) is grounded in substantive principles that explicitly point back to the procedural values. Given the profound differences between the value sets, it is unlikely that urban plans complying with a set of substantive principles that mirror the process values of CPT, will also serve the purposes of neo-liberals. The proposals below make no claim to be exhaustive, but taken together, the listed principles are associated with all the procedural communicative values mentioned above. •• •• •• •• •• •• ••

The plan should accommodate diverse lifestyles and not hinder licit groups from living in accordance with their self-chosen identity. For example, cultural minorities should find places in the city that are fit for their rituals and ways of socializing (empathy). The plan should respect what is culturally essential to affected groups, such as their heritage and their conception of that which is sacred (equality of moral worth). The plan should hold something for each affected group, if not in the main physical manifestation of its purpose, then in the form of compensation. Especially, the situation of underprivileged groups should not be aggravated (fairness). The plan should correspond to the information and the planner intentions conveyed to the participating parties throughout the planning process. The plan should not give reason to suspect previously hidden agendas (honesty). The plan should make it easier, especially for disadvantaged groups, to take part in public life, to work, and to access basic public and private services (empowerment, inclusiveness). The plan, even when designed contrary to the wishes of a particular group, should include elements signalling to this group that it has been listened to. At least some details of the plan should be fashioned to accommodate the needs of protesting groups (responsiveness). Widely accepted solutions negotiated in the communication process (especially consensus proposals) should be incorporated in the final plan, possibly with modifications catering for the interests of people who might not be part of a local consensus; for example, tax payers in general and future generations (self-government).

The substantive principles above help to solve two problems. First, it seems unreasonable to blame CP for lubricating neo-liberal urban development to a greater extent than other modes of planning when holding on to these principles. They are attached to values differing greatly from those of neo-liberalism. Second, they bridge the gap between process and product and make CP less risky by providing guidelines for the content of the plan even when the communication and participation process does not live up to expectations. Over the years, the liveliest and most consequential debate concerning CP has been about power. The question of how to conceptualize power led to deep disagreement on ‘how to deal with it in planning’. Even this innocuous phrase may point to a reductionist view of power as suppressive, that is, as use of force that has to be counteracted. It suggests a reading of power as ‘power over’ instead of emphasizing the productive aspect expressed as ‘power to’. The critics associated Habermas and CP theorists with the reductionist view of power (Huxley 2000: 372). 100

Communicative Planning

It was largely ignored that Habermas (1977) endorsed Hannah Arendt’s notion of ‘communicative power’. This is an enabling collective capacity, which Booher and Innes (2002) linked to CP under the label of network power. The debate on power in CP was very much a Habermas versus Foucault discussion, reaching its peak in the planning academy in the latter half of the 1990s. Foucault did not see power as a ‘massive . . . condition of domination, a binary structure with “dominators” on the one side and “dominated” on the other, but rather a multiform production of relations of domination’ (Foucault 1980: 142). Power always generates resistance, as Foucault sees it, and it must therefore be analysed as something that circulates, rather than a phenomenon present only at particular localities. Productive power involves the capacity to engage in conflict to protect one’s own values and interests, while a conception of communicative action that presupposes consensus comes close to being an instrument for discipline and rather unbearable group pressure, according to Huxley (2000). Foucault’s followers in the planning academy regard communicative planners’ attempts to build consensus as a repressive normalizing practice in planning governance. There is, however, scant empirical support for claiming that mapping the potential for a working agreement on the next few steps in a planning process is likely to result in restrictive conformity. Besides, some notions of consensus are less demanding than perfect agreement at the substantive level. They require instead a common understanding or a shared symbolic space. Theories of social choice and democratic deliberation analyse harmonization of preferences and judgements characterized by overlapping consensus, single-peakedness, meta-consensus, and inter-subjective rationality (Niemeyer and Dryzek 2007). These concepts are consistent with sound deliberative procedure, but have been largely ignored both by CP theorists and their critics. Theorists with a bent for Foucault combined the conceptual critique of power in CPT with the equally widespread critique contending that Habermasians have no credible strategy for counteracting repressive exertion of power, for example, by private developers acting to maximize profit at the expense of broader community interests. The critique for serving neoliberalism gains credibility if communicative planners invite people affected by proposed urban developments to join in consensus-building deliberation without having an effective strategy for how to help them stand up to real estate interests and resourceful investors. This is the objection most often voiced against CPT (Flyvbjerg and Richardson 2002). The problem is how to hold back those trying to influence the planned solution by leaning on their power base instead of persuading by arguments that sound reasonable to the wider public. For all its good intentions of counteracting such behaviour by fighting communicative distortions through critical questioning and by decreasing the political transaction cost of fair-playing actors and groups that stand to lose from the project (Sager 2013: 34–65), critics are not convinced that such measures are effective. One reason is that planners need strong institutional backing in order to follow up with sanctions when threats, manipulations, and other communicative distortions are disclosed. The establishment of such a solid platform for exercising a critical function is at odds with the neo-liberal wish to push planners into an entrepreneurial role. According to the critics, the consensual approach to planning cannot succeed as an emancipatory and empowering project. This view is much inspired by Foucault’s (1980) thinking about power and Mouffe’s (1999) theory of agonistic pluralism. Critics see consensus as shallow due to language games and different community life forms causing participants hailing from different social groups to talk at cross-purposes. Agreement would be the product of power politics or clever rhetoric rather than acknowledgement of common interests. Another main argument of Mouffe’s (1999: 755) is that ‘(p)olitics aims at the creation of unity in a context of conflict and diversity; it is always concerned with the creation of an “us” by the determination of a 101

Tore Sager

“them”’. She sees it as impossible in these circumstances to eradicate communicative distortions and make planning inclusive. Meaning can emerge only by advancing one point of view at the expense and exclusion of other viewpoints, rendering any discourse authoritarian – or so the critics say. Most CP theorists seem unmoved by this argument, as they see the distortion-less situation as an evaluative ideal, not as a realistic destination of politics and planning in practice. Moreover, CPT does not mystify the other by treating her as always violated by being necessarily misunderstood. Mouffe’s argument comes close to giving the peaceful outcome of any real-life discussion an authoritarian stamp, not only the debates and deliberations of CP. Mouffe (1999: 755) stresses the importance of distinguishing between two types of political relations: one of antagonism between enemies, and one of agonism between adversaries … An adversary is a legitimate enemy, an enemy with whom we have in common a shared adhesion to the ethico-political principles of democracy. Equality, liberty, and respect for one another’s beliefs (reciprocity) are among these principles. Deliberative democrats point out that Mouffe cannot explain the transformation from hostile, destructive relations to agonism without a notion of consensus among ‘friendly enemies’ subscribing to the ethico-political principles (Bond 2011). The need is surely for a meta-consensus rather than full agreement on the substance of plans. The recourse to ‘conflictual consensus’ in Mouffe’s theory of agonistic democracy nevertheless raises the question of how deep-seated the contrast between agonistic planning and critical CP is, especially when it comes to practice.

Concluding Remarks Neither conflict nor deliberation can be allowed to delay decisions about plans forever. Lengthy planning processes add costs, delay benefits, and can be a democratic problem. Voting without preceding attempts at alleviating conflict is not intrinsically more democratic than deliberation exploring the potential for negotiated agreement. Minorities can end up being ill-treated both with an agonistic and a communicative approach to planning. Empirical results do not yet indicate which approach best caters for the interests of the weakest parties. It even remains to be seen whether there is a significant difference between the outcomes of CP and agonistic planning in practice. Every social theory can be criticized from some relevant perspective. No form of governance or procedure for reaching a recommendation or a collective decision is without a weak spot. This is certainly so also for CP. Academia has a predilection for reductionist speculation purporting to disclose the ‘real’ function of a theory, usually miles apart from the intention of its originators: Is the dialogical face-to-face kind of planning an attempt to spread the ‘ideology of intimacy’ in the public realm? Increased emphasis on the communication of personal knowledge might be conceived as a danger to public culture, because it contributes to the denial and depreciation of impersonal life. Alternatively, is CPT an attempt at resurrecting the dignity of public planners in the wake of public choice theorists’ attack? Economists in this field were a heavy influence on neo-liberal thinking. They insisted that all actors – public as well as private – should be treated as self-regarding utility maximizers, thus ending public planners’ charade of being benign altruists. Or is CP just a Third Way political technology facilitating the interweaving of social democracy and neo-liberalism? Consumer sovereignty, consultation, user assessment, and client information fit well both with neo-liberalism and CP, and might make neo-liberal policies appear more edible to social democrats. Despite such dismal and reductionist 102

Communicative Planning

complaints that it ‘is nothing but this or that’, CP is still a conspicuous part of the planning theory discourse. A simple Google search reveals that authors link CP firmly to topical themes, such as e-democracy, use of social media, resilience, sustainability, multicultural cities, creativity, partnership, and neo-liberalism. The main ideas of CPT have for many years been crossing national borders (Tag-Eldeen 2015). The increased interest among Chinese planners is a noteworthy trend. Yingjie et  al. (2013) identify emerging elements of CP in China, and discussions of CP are appearing in Chinese language in that country’s rapidly growing planning literature (Wang et al. 2012). This indicates that the central idea of CP, that dialogue among contending parties in the process of preparing for collective decision can benefit a broad range of interests, has relevance under very different political regimes. The widespread acclaim for awarding the Nobel Peace Prize for 2015 to the Tunisian National Dialogue Quartet is a further indication. ‘The Quartet paved the way for a peaceful dialogue between the citizens, the political parties and the authorities and helped to find consensus-based solutions to a wide range of challenges across political and religious divides’ (Norwegian Nobel Committee 2015). Embedded in this is an invitation to see dialogue and the search for consensus on how to move forward, as much more than a potential cooptation technique.

References Allmendinger, P. (2001): Planning in Postmodern Times. London: Routledge. Allmendinger, P. (2009): Planning Theory (Second Edition). London: Palgrave Macmillan. Bedford, T., J. Clark and H. Harrison (2002): ‘Limits to new public participation practices in local land use planning’, Town Planning Review 73(3): 311–31. Bond, S. (2011): ‘Negotiating a “democratic ethos”: moving beyond the agonistic-communicative divide’, Planning Theory 10(2): 161–86. Booher, D.E. and J.E. Innes (2002): ‘Network power in collaborative planning’, Journal of Planning Education and Research 21(3): 221–36. Dworkin, G. (1983): ‘Paternalism: some second thoughts’, pp. 105–111 in R. Sartorius (Ed.): Paternalism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Fainstein, N. and S.S. Fainstein (2013): ‘Restoring just outcomes to planning concerns’, pp.  32–53 in N. Carmon and S.S. Fainstein (Eds): Policy, Planning, and People: Promoting Justice in Urban Development. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Fainstein, S.S. (2014): ‘The just city’, International Journal of Urban Sciences 18(1): 1–18. Flyvbjerg, B. and T. Richardson (2002): ‘Planning and Foucault: in search of the dark side of planning theory’, pp. 44–62 in P. Allmendinger and M. Tewdwr-Jones (Eds): Planning Futures: New Directions for Planning Theory. London: Routledge. Forester, J. (1989): Planning in the Face of Power. Berkeley: University of California Press. Forester, J. (1992): ‘Critical ethnography: on fieldwork in a Habermasian way’, pp. 46–65 in M. Alvesson and H. Wilmott (Eds): Critical Management Studies. London: Sage. Forester, J. (1993): Critical Theory, Public Policy, and Planning Practice: Toward a Critical Pragmatism. Albany: State University of New York Press. Forester, J. (2013): ‘On the theory and practice of critical pragmatism: deliberative practice and creative negotiations’, Planning Theory 12(1): 5–22. Foucault, M. (1980): Power/Knowledge. Brighton: Harvester Press. Friedmann, J. (1973): Retracking America: A Theory of Transactive Planning. Garden City, New York: Anchor Press/Doubleday. Gutman, A. and D. Thompson (2004): Why Deliberative Democracy? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Habermas, J. (1977): ‘Hannah Arendt’s communications concept of power’, Social Research 44(1): 3–24. Habermas, J. (1998): On the Pragmatics of Communication (Editor: Maeve Cooke). Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Harper, T.L. and S.M. Stein (2006): Dialogical Planning in a Fragmented Society. New Brunswick: CUPR Press, Rutgers.

103

Tore Sager Healey, P. (2006): Collaborative Planning: Shaping Places in Fragmented Societies (Second Edition). Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan. Healey, P. (2009): ‘The pragmatic tradition in planning thought’, Journal of Planning Education and Research 28(3): 277–92. Healey, P. (2012): ‘Communicative planning: practices, concepts and rhetorics’, pp. 333–58 in B. Sanyal, L. Vale and C.D. Rosan (Eds): Planning Ideas that Matter: Livability, Territoriality, Governance, and Reflective Practice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hoch, C.J. (2007): ‘Pragmatic communicative action theory’, Journal of Planning Education and Research 26(3): 272–83. Huxley, M. (2000): ‘The limits to communicative planning’, Journal of Planning Education and Research 19(4): 369–77. Innes, J.E. (1995): ‘Planning theory’s emerging paradigm: communicative action and interactive practice’, Journal of Planning Education and Research 14(3): 183–89. Innes, J.E. and D.E. Booher (1999): ‘Consensus building as role playing and bricolage: toward a theory of collaborative planning’, Journal of the American Planning Association 65(1): 9–26. Innes, J.E. and D.E. Booher (2010): Planning with Complexity: An Introduction to Collaborative Rationality for Public Policy. London: Routledge. Innes, J.E. and D.E. Booher (2015): ‘A turning point for planning theory? Overcoming dividing discourses’, Planning Theory 14(2): 195–213. Levine, A. (1960): ‘Citizen participation’, Journal of the American Institute of Planners 26(3): 195–200. List, C. and R.E. Goodin (2001): ‘Epistemic democracy: generalizing the Condorcet jury theorem’, Journal of Political Philosophy 9(3): 277–306. Mansbridge, J., J. Bohman, S. Chambers, D. Estlund, A. Føllesdal, A. Fung, et al. (2010): ‘The place of selfinterest and the role of power in deliberative democracy’, Journal of Political Philosophy 18(1): 64–100. Margerum, R.D. (2002): ‘Evaluating collaborative planning: implications from an empirical analysis of growth management’, Journal of the American Planning Association 68(2): 179–93. Mees, P. (2003): ‘Paterson’s curse: the attempt to revive metropolitan planning in Melbourne’, Urban Policy and Research 21(3): 287–99. Miraftab, F. (2004): ‘Invited and invented spaces of participation: neoliberal citizenship and feminists’ expanded notion of politics’, Wagadu 1(Spring): 1–7. Mouffe, C. (1999): ‘Deliberative democracy or agonistic pluralism’, Social Research 66(3): 745–58. Niemeyer, S. and J.S. Dryzek (2007): ‘The ends of deliberation: meta-consensus and inter-subjective rationality as ideal outcomes’, Swiss Political Science Review 13(4): 497–526. Norwegian Nobel Committee (2015): Announcement of the Nobel Peace Prize for 2015. www.nobelprize. org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/2015/press.html?utm_source=twitter&utm_medium=social&utm_ campaign=twitter_tweet (accessed 19.04.2017). Rader Olsson, A. (2009): ‘Relational rewards and communicative planning: understanding actor motivation’, Planning Theory 8(3): 263–81. Sager, T. (1994): Communicative Planning Theory. Aldershot: Avebury. Sager, T. (2013): Reviving Critical Planning Theory. London: Routledge. Sandercock, L. (1998): Making the Invisible Visible. Berkeley: University of California Press. Sandercock, L. and G. Attili (2010): ‘Digital ethnography as planning praxis: an experiment with film as social research’, Planning Theory and Practice 11(1): 23–45. Scott, A.J. and S.T. Roweis (1977): ‘Urban planning in theory and practice: a reappraisal’, Environment and Planning A 9(10): 1097–1119. Tag-Eldeen, Z.N. (2015): ‘Collaborative planning crossing borders: practice in the context of Egypt’, pp. 407–22 in J. Hillier and J. Metzger (Eds): Connections: Exploring Contemporary Planning Theory and Practice with Patsy Healey. Farnham, England: Ashgate. Throgmorton, J.A. (2000): ‘On the virtues of skillful meandering: acting as a skilled-voice-in-the-flow of persuasive argumentation’, Journal of the American Planning Association 66(4): 367–79. Van Dijk, T., N. Aarts and A. de Wit (2011): ‘Frames to the planning game’, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 35(5): 969–87. Verma, N. (1998): Similarities, Connections and Systems. New York: Lexington. Wang, F., Q. Chen, Y. Xu and Y. Liu (2012): ‘Communicative planning theory: introduction, criticism and inspiration’, Urban Planning International Issue 2012–06 (in Chinese). Yingjie, H., G. de Roo and L. Bin (2013): ‘“Communicative turn” in Chinese spatial planning? Exploring possibilities in Chinese contexts’, Cities 35(1): 42–50.

104

9 NEOLIBERAL PLANNING Guy Baeten

One could provocatively wonder whether neoliberal planning actually exists, since neither planning practitioners nor planning theorists commonly mobilize the term neoliberalism to capture the contemporary planning condition (Baeten, 2012a). At the same time, leading authors agree that neoliberalism remains a ‘keyword for the understanding of regulatory reforms of our time’ (Brenner et al., 2010), which would certainly include (the dismantling of) planning regulations. Neoliberal planning can be understood “as a restructuring of the relationship between private capital owners and the state, which rationalises and promotes a growth-first approach to urban development” (Sager, 2011). It is not a neatly defined set of policies, but rather a ‘restructuring ethos’ based on a strong belief in the virtues of the market and the limited possibilities of state intervention (Peet and Watts, 2004). For Springer (2010), neoliberalism simultaneously exists as a hegemonic ideology promoting the superiority of market solutions, as a policy that effectively increases the power of private actors in planning, and as governmentality: an ‘assemblage of rationalities, strategies, technologies, and techniques’ that allows neoliberal principles to rule in planning practices without major contestation. For Harvey (2005), neoliberalism is ultimately ‘the restoration of class power’ after the position of the financial and economic elites in the western world was threatened by socialism and high levels of state interference in the 1970s – an interpretation that gains credibility when observing the ‘birth’ of neoliberal planning in Chile and Britain during the late 1970s and early 1980s. The neoliberalization of planning implies a partial retreat by planning as a public institution from its conventional core, namely the improvement of the built and natural environment through some sort of concerted effort. This ‘retreat’ should not be read as a mere withdrawal but a complex reworking of relations between state and market in which the state does not simply ‘lose power’ but gains a more proactive role in the introduction of market principles in planning through local, national and international regulatory reforms (Eraydın 2012), alongside the reinforcement of the repressive role of the state. Further, neoliberal planning, both as idea and practice, does not constitute a clear break from a previous regime of planning, but will always be a hybrid between existing planning regimes and subsequent gradual neoliberal transformations (Baeten, 2012b). As Peck and Theodore (2010: 170) have pointed out, “mobile policies rarely travel as complete ‘packages,’ they move in bits and pieces – as selective discourses, inchoate ideas, and synthesized models – and they therefore ‘arrive’ not as replicas but as policies alreadyin-transformation”. Brenner and Theodore (2005: 102) suggest that neoliberal practices are 105

Guy Baeten

always “articulated through contextually specific strategies” and hence should be studied at the local level to lay bare their spatio-temporal particularities. We will take the merger of neoliberal ideas with spatial political-economic circumstances as a leading thread to reconstruct the spatiotemporal development trajectory of neoliberal planning.

Pioneering Neoliberal thought actually has multiple beginnings in various places – a phase that Peck (2008) has called ‘proto-neoliberalism’. The cradle of neoliberalism as we know it is usually traced back to the first meeting of the Mont Pelerin Society in 1947, where Friedrich Hayek, Milton Friedman and more than 30 other prominent liberal thinkers gathered to discuss how to renew and re-energize the liberal tradition in a world ruled by Keynesianism and socialism, and recently threatened by the rise of fascism and Nazism. The Society has had regular meetings ever since and established an expansive global ‘neoliberal thought collective’ over the years in close cooperation with conservative think tanks (Mirowski and Plehwe, 2009). However, it was not until the military coup by General Pinochet in 1973 that these thinkers were offered an opportunity to turn their liberal principles into a practical foundation for the organization of a national economy – and of planning. Economics students from the Catholic University of Chile had been trained for decades at the University of Chicago, where Hayek and Friedman were teaching, and at some other prominent US universities. These ‘Chicago Boys’ had prepared a blueprint (called El Ladrillo or ‘The Stone’ because of its size) for the liberalization of markets in, then socialist, Chile, and Pinochet, in search of liberal economic policies, appointed many of these US-trained economists to key posts at government institutions and universities. One close ally of Pinochet, former naval officer Roberto Kelly, was put in charge of the National Planning Office which implemented the National Urban Development Policy in 1979. The plan was highly programmatic and in line with the liberal economic principles outlined in El Ladrillo (Valdes, 1995). It did not regard land as a scarce resource in itself: land was scarce because of planning restrictions that forced the city to grow ‘vertically’ through the construction of high-rise buildings. Without planning restrictions, the city would grow ‘naturally’ or ‘horizontally’ as the vast majority of people would prefer a house with a garden. According to the plan, rescinding the artificial limitation of land supply would also result in lower land prices. To let ‘the market’ do its work, the plan lifted restrictions and the metropolitan area of Santiago expanded from 36,000 hectares to 100,000 hectares, almost tripling the potential land market instantly. This resulted in unprecedented urban sprawl and, following speculation, increasing land and housing prices. Meanwhile, illegal settlements or campamentos were systematically removed and some 150,000 families were forcibly displaced to peripheral settlements without acceptable facilities, resulting in sharp segregation (Kusnetzoff, 1987). While the 1979 plan for Santiago can be regarded as the first ever neoliberal plan, and it established the basic features of neoliberal planning that remain constitutive today: an unbridled belief in the natural superiority of the market to allocate land in the most efficient way; a principled distrust in state planning per se as it distorts the market; the mobilization of the state to dismantle its own planning functions; the outsourcing of planning functions to the private sector; and the reinforcement of the authoritarian state to fulfil repressive functions (such as forced displacement) that private actors cannot achieve. Shortly after the Chilean experiments with neoliberal planning, neoliberal planning’s most iconic form, the Urban Development Project, and its most iconic form of organization, the public-private partnership (PPP), would materialize in Britain in the early 1980s where the newly appointed Prime Minister Margaret Thatcher had inherited a crisis-ridden economy accompanied by serious social unrest, strikes, and riots in decaying inner cities. In the aftermath of the 106

Neoliberal Planning

particularly violent 1981 riots in Toxteth, Liverpool, the then Minister for the Environment Michael Heseltine was sent on a mission to Liverpool and reported back to the prime minister under the apt title “It took a riot” (The National Archives, 2011). He proposed to abolish the (left-leaning) county councils and to place urban regeneration under central government control. He suggested cooperating with the private sector “to a far greater degree than hitherto”, including the 30 banks, pension funds and insurance companies he had visited during his mission. Urban Development Corporations (UDCs), first in Liverpool and London and later throughout the country, put into praxis the call for economic regeneration to solve the innercity problems. A focus on economic regeneration to solve other problems was already present in Labour’s 1977 White Paper ‘Policy for the Inner Cities’ (Edwards, 1984), and soon became the cornerstone of British urban policies through the 1988 ‘Action for Cities’ policy document (Deakin and Edwards, 1993). UDCs were given extensive powers, including land acquisition and the abolition of local planning regulations and procedures. Just like in Santiago a few years earlier, the British state would, in an authoritarian manner, partly dismantle its own planning infrastructure and transfer it to private companies. Barnekov and Rich (1977) demonstrate in an American context how PPPs in the field of inner-city regeneration emerge in the spirit of so-called ‘urban privatism’, independent of Chicago-style neoliberal theorizing. Their research was based on case studies of ‘development committees’ bringing together political and corporate leaders in American cities in the 1960s after local corporate leaders started to show a strong interest in urban redevelopment due to the emergence of inner-city decline in the USA in those days. In an attempt to restore favourable conditions for capital accumulation in the aftermath of the Fordist crisis, the Reagan administration continued to implement the policies initiated by the Carter administration, including serious cut-backs in federal budgets such as income-maintenance and rent support which hit the urban poor disproportionately. Florida and Jonas (1991) describe Reagan’s implicit urban policy as a set of experiments in political-economic “destructuring” based on selective elimination or redirection of the income-maintenance and social programs of Great Society, the re-routing of federal spending from Democratic constituencies in the older cities to Republican strongholds, a transfer of administrative responsibility from the federal government to states and localities, and an overall reduction of the social wage. Strongly influenced by neo-conservative thinkers such as Charles Murray (1984), the Reagan administration was convinced that the (urban) poor were disencouraged to support themselves due to benefit dependency. Florida and Jonas (1991) insist that the increase of (mainly black urban) poverty was no accidental by-product of these austerity measures but an explicit goal: reducing benefits of various kinds would get the poor ‘back on their feet’. The penalization of the poor and consistent social austerity policies have remained a key feature of neoliberalism ever since.

Normalizing Since the foundations for neoliberal planning were laid through these pioneering urban policy reforms in Chile, the United States and Great Britain, neoliberal planning practices have been spread across the globe, first in the developed world, and by now largely across the globe (see, for example, Lees et  al., 2015). Neoliberalization is a slow incremental process that mutates over time and space. Peck and Tickell (2002) call the first phase of neoliberal policies ‘roll-back 107

Guy Baeten

neoliberalism’ – the neoliberalism of Thatcher and Reagan in the 1980s which sought to roll back the state and its influence over labour markets, ownership of the means of production, welfare provision, financial markets, land use planning, and so on. It was built upon a diagnosis of the 1970s’ economic crisis as a crisis of overregulation and unnecessary interference of the state in matters economic. Paradoxically, the retreat of the state required a strong state to push through reforms that restored the power of the market. Jenkins (2006) calls Thatcher a ‘true apostle of the dictatorship of the bourgeoisie’, or in her own words: “I believe in a strong state, strong to break the power of socialism” (p. 106). The social fall-out of rolling back the state – increasing poverty, rising segregation and income polarization between rich and poor, growing social exclusion, long-term unemployment – gradually forced neoliberal governments to rethink the neoliberal project. The 1990s saw the introduction of ‘roll-out neoliberalism’ – the ‘Third Way’ of Blair and Clinton that reinvigorated the interference of the state, not in economic matters, but in social and penal matters specifically dealing with the “aggressive reregulation, disciplining, and containment of those marginalized or dispossessed by the neoliberalization of the 1980s” (p. 389). As in the pioneering Chilean experiments, the state under neoliberalism once more showed its Janus face: on the one hand it seeks to withdraw from the ‘overregulation’ of capital and labour, and on the other hand it assumes a proactive role in the management, suppression and punishment of the poor (see Wacquant, 2008 and 2009, for a detailed analysis). The rolling-out of neoliberalism into urban planning was famously abstracted by Harvey (1989) as a transition from urban managerialism to urban entrepreneurialism. Managerial cities were primarily focused on the local provision of services, facilities and benefits to the urban population, while entrepreneurial cities in an age of heightened interurban competition more than ever before had to concentrate on the attraction of investment and employment. Cities can achieve this, first, through exploiting and promoting production advantages, which can be natural resources, location, but also tax incentives and the attraction of skilled labour forces – today known as the creative classes. Second, the city can compete for increased consumption through the promotion of tourism, the physical upgrading of the urban environment (for example, spectacular architecture and the removal of unwanted sights and bodies), consumer attractions such as sports stadia and shopping centres and the organization of mega-events. Third, cities can concentrate on the attraction of command and control functions in finance and information industries which necessitates heavy investments in prime transport and communication infrastructures in order to prepare the city to become an informational city or a post-industrial city with service exports as an economic basis. Finally, cities continue to compete for large government contracts in the military industries and other research-intensive industries. By now, cities across the globe have deployed these strategies to various degrees and in various combinations, and it is remarkable how ‘normal’ and ubiquitous these policies appear in contemporary urban settings. Indeed, Keil (2009) has suggested that the twin processes of roll-back and roll-out neoliberalism have recently been complemented by a new form of neoliberalization: roll-with-it neoliberalization. It means “the normalization of neoliberal practices and mindsets, the . . . acceptance of the ‘conduct of conduct’ of neoliberalism, a manner . . . ‘of inciting the subjects to conduct themselves after the model of the enterprise and the general norm of competition’” (p. 232). Roll-with-it is self-referential since it does not refer to something that has to be annihilated (like roll-back had to bring down the overregulating state). It exists by itself, without strong counterdiscourses about alternatives: it is the way things are. Planners today, after all, simply do not refer to their planning ideas and practices as ‘neoliberal’ or ‘third way’ (Jackson, 2009), rendering contemporary planning’s ideological foundations largely invisible. It is important to keep in mind that these forms of neoliberalism exist side by 108

Neoliberal Planning

side and do not simply supersede each other. Moreover, the relation between these different forms of neoliberalisms takes on different forms in different places (for a refined account of ‘roll-back’ and ‘roll-out’ in an English planning context, for example, see Allmendinger and Haughton, 2013).

Established Tools and Policies Planners now have a set of neoliberal tools and policies at their disposal that goes largely uncontested and is applied worldwide to different degrees and in different forms. Tore Sager (2011), based on an extensive literature survey, has named 14 such typical neoliberal planning policies and tools that have somehow gained a ‘natural’ status in the planners’ toolkit. We will highlight some of the most prominent of these: city marketing, attraction of the creative class, Urban Development Projects and PPPs. City marketing, while in itself older than neoliberalism, especially started drawing the attention of researchers when Glasgow surprisingly won the title of European Cultural Capital in 1990 and managed to fundamentally change its image from a clapped-out industrial town to a hip and cool cultural centre of North Britain through systematic marketing efforts. Paddison (1993), Boyle and Hughes (1994) and Kearns and Philo (1993), among others, were astounded by its impact but also by the blatant way in which the history of Glasgow was reimagined and rewritten to fit the new economic exigencies. They already pointed at the obvious danger and injustice of writing away certain neighbourhoods, places, buildings, historical events, memories and individuals, while underscoring others, in an attempt to commodify a place ready for consumption. In spite of these critiques, city branding has become a global neoliberal planning tool which paradoxically has led to more uniformity, not diversity, among cities since the promotion of signature architecture, mega-events and fine dining have become universal templates that are no longer able to strategically position cities vis-à-vis other equally aggressive urban centres (Lui, 2008). Closely related to city marketing is neoliberal planning’s arguably most prominent contemporary paradigm: the idea that successful urban economies are dependent on the attraction of the creative class. Florida’s (2002a) claims are bold and simple: it is the creative class that generates employment and those cities that manage to attract them will be prosperous: “Places have replaced companies as the key organising units in our economy” (p. 30). Now it is ‘cool’ cities with cutting-edge music and art scenes, tolerant gay neighbourhoods, and other ‘soft’ features that will prosper best in an age of competition for creative people: “Cities without gays and rock bands are losing the economic development race” (Florida, 2002b). Florida’s prescriptions for planning flourishing urban economies have been proven wrong over and over again: it is prosperous places with available employment that attract talented people, not the other way around (Peck, 2005; Hansen and Niedomysl, 2009; Scott, 2006); most creative people live ordinary lives that are not distinguishable from other people (Lang and Danielsen, 2005); cities that do attract large numbers of creative people, such as Berlin or New Orleans, have not witnessed positive economic outcomes (Malanga, 2004); and creative class policies paradoxically exclude the low-income segments of the creative class (NION, 2010). Yet, cities across the globe continue to take inspiration from Florida’s ideas. Their immeasurable appeal lies not in their accuracy, sophistication or academic superiority but in their indirect message that cities do have their fate in their own hands – a message that appeals not least to planners in rustbelt cities in the absence of any credible alternative. Urban Development Projects (UDPs), as pioneered in the London Docklands (Brownill, 1990), by now belong to the most common planning templates to establish or radically renew city 109

Guy Baeten

districts, which often comprise a mix of housing, offices, signature architecture, shopping malls, transport facilities, exhibition halls and cultural centres. An extensive survey by Swyngedouw et al. (2002) of 13 UDPs in Europe reveal some characteristics that most UDPs to a greater or lesser extent share. First, large-scale UDPs are used as a “vehicle to establish exceptionality measures in planning and policy procedures” (p. 547). A specific part of the city, often qualified as deprived and in need of regeneration, is carved out and subjected to exceptional planning procedures that (partly) sideline conventional municipal planning authorities. Existing democratic participation mechanisms are abolished or applied in a formulaic manner, hence creating a democratic deficit. Second, these ‘stand-alone’ projects are either not at all, or poorly, integrated in the planning of the rest of the city. As a consequence, both their integration in and socioeconomic impact on the rest of the city remain ambiguous. Third, UDPs often contribute to a further polarization in the city through the establishment of new real estate dynamics that attract high-income groups to specific places in the city while simultaneously stimulating (forced) displacement of low-income groups to impoverished parts of the city. They have also been criticized for pushing social problems such as poverty and unemployment further afield and for failing to connect to local communities. This is partly because the financing of regeneration projects often comes from land sales for property development which means that other regeneration objectives are put in the shadow of land sales and property investment (Raco, 2005). This created a democratic deficit in planning since the control of major development projects was effectively handed over to non-elected, appointed committees (Imrie and Thomas, 1999). UDCs have proven successful as far as the sheer level of construction of offices, transport networks and housing is concerned (Imrie and Thomas, 1999). They also demonstrated in physical, concrete terms the limitations and weaknesses of the existing planning system and possibilities of these new ways of planning governance (Cochrane, 1999). In spite of their obvious shortcomings, UDPs as planning vehicles have been used to implement large-scale projects that vary from waterfront development (Desfor et al., 2012), to Olympic Games sites (Poynter and MacRury, 2009), to railway station neighbourhoods (Peters, 2009). Like city marking, PPPs precede neoliberal forms of planning but have come to be regarded as one of its prime manifestations. As mentioned, PPPs can be traced back to the 1960s when corporate leaders started to cooperate with city officials to tackle American inner-city decline. PPP remains a notoriously vague concept: they appear in several different forms and under different acronyms. However, what they have in common, according to Hildyard (2014: 6), is that “they provide private companies with contract-based rights to flows of public money or to monopoly income streams from services on which the public rely”. These ‘flows of public money’ can take the form of (1) cash subsidies: the government agrees to provide a cash subsidy for a project; (2) payment guarantees: the government agrees to fulfil the obligation of being the purchaser; (3) or revenue guarantees: the government sets a minimum variable income for the private partner and makes up for loss. Proponents claim that PPPs are beneficial because private ownership brings competition and thus lower prices; the private sector brings disciplines to public projects; PPPs bring improved efficiency and lower costs, thus, better value for money: the public sector does not have the resources and PPPs lower the costs by bringing in private finance; PPPs spur economies that will trickle down to low-income groups and PPPs are therefore an instrument to enhance welfare. The critics, on the other hand, claim that the improved efficiency, lower costs and poverty reduction arguments are not valid since infrastructure does not automatically lead to improvements for low-income groups and does not necessarily reduce costs (Stephenson, 1991). Miraftab (2004) points at the false promise of PPPs as a win-win situation (the public sector secures private investment while pursuing the betterment of local living and working conditions) 110

Neoliberal Planning

since PPPs most often act as a ‘Trojan horse’ for further privatization of formerly public services which in the end do not benefit deprived groups and neighbourhoods. Ultimately, PPPs “are less about financing development than about developing finance” (Hildyard, 2014: 10).

Crisis and Its Aftermath By the 2000s, it had become difficult not to be overawed by the seemingly global hegemony of neoliberal thinking. Prominent scholars such as Perry Anderson (2000: 7) stated that “Neoliberalism as a set of principles rules undivided across the globe”, and Edward Said (2000) claimed that “Neoliberalism has swallowed up the world in its clutches”. The 2008 financial crisis would change that. In its immediate aftermath, Peck (2010) believed neoliberalism had reached a zombie-like state, dead but alive, and Smith (2008) compared the condition of neoliberalism with a dead rattlesnake that can still strike in its nerve-driven afterlife, while the journal Development Dialogue (2009) was quick to introduce and discuss the term postneoliberalism. However, as it rapidly became clear after massive state interventions to keep the financial institutions (and hence neoliberalism) afloat, these early ‘hopeful’ positions had to be revised in the light of the ‘strange non-death of neoliberalism’. It is necessary to start from acceptance that political and economic elites will do everything that they can to maintain neoliberalism in general and the finance-driven form of it in particular. They have benefited so much from the inequalities of wealth and power that the system has produced, compared with the experience of strongly redistributive taxation, strong trade unions and government regulation during the social-democratic era. … They will cling to this model tenaciously. (Crouch, 2011: 119) Both Berry (2014) and Peck (2012) have recently demonstrated how the recovery of post-crisis neoliberalism goes hand in hand with a new round of roll-back neoliberalism through sustained ‘austerity urbanism’. While the literature on understanding the reasons behind and nature of the financial crisis is vast, the impact of the financial crisis on planning remains underresearched. Holgersen (2014, 2015) has looked at the response of the city of Malmö, Sweden, to the breakdown of construction activities in 2008–9. The municipal government reacted by offering municipality-owned land at bargain prices to private construction companies since building activities had to continue at any cost. More than anything, the 2008 crisis has demonstrated an absence of credible alternatives to existing neoliberal planning and regeneration practices. But it also illustrates both the resilience of neoliberal planning and the successful restoration of ‘business-as-usual’ planning; that is, pre-crisis neoliberal planning. Meanwhile, urban regeneration, or more specifically green regeneration, is put at the very core of the way out of crisis by some of the most prominent international institutions. The World Bank (2013) claims that “Cities can become global engines of green growth”, the United National Environmental Program (2011) believes that “Cities can and should play a leading role in greening economies”, and the OECD (2013) is convinced that “Urban policies are crucial for achieving national environmental and green growth goals”. If the urban green economy or the production of eco-cities (Joss, 2009) will become the future cornerstone of economic growth as these very powerful organizations seek to promote, then we are entering a new variation of neoliberalism in which urban (green) planning will play a paramount role. The biggest contemporary challenge for future planning, then, is certainly not its very survival: there will be more (privatized) planning than ever before to meet the call for green 111

Guy Baeten

planetary urbanization, alongside the continuing neoliberal desire for the annihilation of space through spectacular transport infrastructures, for the overhaul of city centres to attract tourists, investment and the creative class, and for the marketing of places in an imagined geo-Darwinian globalized world. Paradoxically, then, in times when planning is met with considerable disregard (see, for example, Gleeson and Low, 2000) and even acts as the very ‘scapegoat fantasy’ for neoliberalism’s failures (Gunder, 2016), planning has a bright future under neoliberal conditions. The expansion of neoliberalism, in blatant contrast with its own discourse, necessitates an ever stronger state, not just to bail out financial institutions when needed but also to pro-actively and relentlessly (re)shape neoliberalism’s spaces, places, cities, flows and bodies. Planning, whether practised in architect consultant firms or in the town hall, plays a pivotal role in the formation and continuation of neoliberalism. In the process, it rewards the planner with the aphrodisiac of winning planning proposal competitions, competing on a global scale, pushing through and implementing spectacular development schemes, or bandying about rapidly increasing visitor numbers. A new neoliberal planning subjectivity has downgraded customary concern that once steered planning theory and practice: “What has happened to planning’s traditional concerns about fairness, equity, and social justice which no longer seem to be burning planning questions when they should be more than ever before perhaps”, wonders Gunder (2006).

Past the Political? This cooptation of planning practice by neoliberal interests, alongside the realization that neoliberalism had successfully survived yet another financial crisis, has most recently triggered a debate around the (post-)political nature of contemporary planning. Purcell (2009) argues that communicative or collaborative planning is an excellent vehicle for neoliberals to maintain hegemony while ensuring political stability: What the neoliberal project requires are decision-making practices that are widely accepted as “democratic”. But that do not (or cannot) fundamentally challenge existing relations of power. Communicative planning … is just such a decision-making practice. … communicative action reinforces existing power relations rather than transforms them. (p. 141) Bengs (2005) insists that communicative planning’s prime role is to lubricate the neoliberal project, and Sager (2005) ponders whether communicative planners are the naive mandarins of the neoliberal state. Grange (2016, 2014, 2012) laments the planning community’s fear of conflict and antagonism. She wants to make planners aware again to what extent their practice is driven by consensual neoliberal ideology and she stresses the need for ‘fearless speech’ if planning wants to take up a more transformative role in society. For Gunder (2010), planning has become the ideology of neoliberal space. Influenced by the notion of the post-political, Allmendinger and Haughton (2012) have analysed recent reforms in planning law and discern a reinvigorated effort in English planning to force consensus and displace dissent to other arenas (such as the Court): “What we are witnessing appears to be a new moment in the post-political management of dissent and the continuing selective displacement of the handling of controversial issues to alternative modes and scales of planning” (p. 101). Baeten (2009) reconstructs the history of planning and community on the South Bank in London from the resistance against office development in the 1970s and 1980s, to the introduction of partnership planning under 112

Neoliberal Planning

New Labour in the 1990s, to recent regime changes in which dissent and conflict have been virtually eliminated through the successful cooptation of all stakeholders, whether originally antagonistic or not. While it is undoubtedly true that consensus and the suppression of dissent are all-pervading features of contemporary planning, we should cast doubt over the perception that, lately, planning has somehow entered a new stage that some would label ‘post-political’. When going back to the original writings of Rancière, Badiou, Žižek and Swyngedouw, among others, it becomes clear that these authors understand the post-political condition as ‘normal’, as the way things usually are. ‘Political’ moments, not the least for Rancière (1998), are rare events. The general understanding of politics – a set of procedures that organizes collectivities and powers, distributes places and roles for people, and legitimizes that order, should, according to Rancière (1998), not be understood as ‘politics’ proper but rather as what he labels ‘the police’. It is primarily an order of bodies that defines the allocation of ways of doing, ways of being, and ways of saying and sees that those bodies are assigned … to a particular place and task; it is an order of the visible and the sayable that sees that a particular activity is visible and another is not, that this speech is understood as discourse and another as noise. (p. 29) The police order ultimately determines the distinction between those who have a name and those who have not, those who can speak and will be listened to and those who will not be, in short those who have a part and those who have not. Politics, then, is not about managing and sustaining this order through negotiation and consensus (Dikeç, 2002). Politics is the opposite of ‘the police’. Politics arise when the police order is broken, when bodies are shifted away from the places assigned to them. An important implication of this is that politics do not automatically occur simply because power relationships are at work. Power relationships might exist between groups and result in conflict but not necessarily in politics as the police order might be left untouched. Seen through this lens, urban planning is not necessarily political simply because power relationships between different stakeholders with conflicting interests exist and are dealt with at the negotiation table. Planning politics, following Rancière’s thinking, would only occur when someone leaves their negotiation role and puts forward a claim that threatens the existing police order, existing plans, or existing negotiation procedures that underlie and reproduce existing inequalities in urban neighbourhoods. The post-political condition of planning, in which communicative or collaborative or other fashionable planning regimes seek some form of consensus around land allocation within the given parameters of an economic regime (for example capitalism), is then the ‘common’ state of planning. In line with the post-political literature, political planning would rarely erupt, and the support of economic hierarchies would be a banal condition of planning, before, during and probably after the neoliberal age. As Allmendinger and Haughton (2012: 94) remind us: Planning tends to adapt very quickly to reflect the dominant ideology and priorities of the age. This is not too surprising, perhaps: planning is, after all, the main mechanism through which the state seeks to manage land use changes. As governments change and societal concerns and priorities alter, so planning adapts and evolves through what Reade (1987) termed a shifting consensus. Such shifts in the purpose of planning and the accompanying tools have been criticised as being superficial, masking an enduring, more market-supportive function. 113

Guy Baeten

After all, according to Harvey (1978: 231), “The commitment of the ideology of harmony within the capitalist social order remains the still point upon which the gyrations of planning ideology turn”.

What next? Planning theory has a notorious normative current, and planning theorists on the left are inclined to overload planners with demands that they ought to stand up against existing power configurations, or that they should fearlessly speak out against blatant spatial injustices. They can’t. Neither do politicians, academics or activists as long as the left has no overriding alternative vision of society at hand that could possibly compete with the eloquent and smooth neoliberal mythologies (see Merrifield, 1993; Smith, 2008). This, of course, has pervasive impacts on the nature and content of much of contemporary planning. But we have to remember that neoliberal thinking, certainly in its early days when Keynesianism was hegemonic, was a marginalized intellectual stream. For decades, Hayek, Friedman and others were rowing upstream until the Fordist/Keynesian regime came to a grinding halt in the late 1960s and early 1970s and politicians started looking for economic policies beyond Keynesianism. Until then, neoliberal thinkers were frustrated, and jealous of the success of the socialist body of thought. In ‘The Intellectuals and Socialism’, Friedrich Hayek (1949: 384) laments the absence of an appealing liberal programme that could withstand the attraction of socialism: [W]e must be able to offer a new liberal program which appeals to the imagination. We must make the building of a free society once more an intellectual adventure, a deed of courage. What we lack is a liberal Utopia … a truly liberal radicalism which does not spare the susceptibilities of the mighty (including the trade unions), which is not too severely practical, and which does not confine itself to what appears today as politically possible. We need intellectual leaders who are willing to work for an ideal, however small may be the prospects of its early realization. They must be men who are willing to stick to principles and to fight for their full realization, however remote. The practical compromises they must leave to the politicians … The main lesson which the true liberal must learn from the success of the socialists is that it was their courage to be Utopian which gained them the support of the intellectuals and therefore an influence on public opinion which is daily making possible what only recently seemed utterly remote … if we can regain that belief in the power of ideas which was the mark of liberalism at its best, the battle is not lost. The intellectual revival of liberalism is already underway in many parts of the world. Will it be in time? The contemporary frustration on the left is strikingly similar: one only has to replace ‘liberal’ with ‘socialist’ and vice versa in the quote above. Planning will not pursue fairness, equity and justice if planning cannot draw ideas from a broader alternative utopia that has sufficient legitimacy like neoliberal ideas have just now. In the absence of such a utopia, we cannot impose normative world-changing fantasies on the planning community. If planners are forced to ‘mindlessly’ implement profit-maximizing land-use decisions while unable to tackle their potential detrimental environmental and social fall-out, then any form of ‘sustainable’ planning becomes impossible under neoliberal conditions. The challenge lies in how to continue to pursue the integration of economic, environmental and social issues in land-use decisions when economic concerns are prioritized while social and environmental concerns are coopted to fit into the profit-maximizing agenda. Growth, then, 114

Neoliberal Planning

becomes a goal in itself that overrules other concerns, something that stands in contrast with the conventional balance-seeking spirit that typically pervades planning (Baeten, 2012b).

References Allmendinger, Ph., and G. Haughton (2012), Post-Political Spatial Planning in England: A Crisis in Consensus?, Transactions of the British Institute of Geographers, Vol. 37, No. 1, pp. 89–103 Allmendinger, Ph., and G. Haughton (2013), The Evolution and Trajectories of English Spatial Governance: ‘Neoliberal’ Episodes, Planning, Planning, Practice and Research, Vol. 28, No. 1, pp. 6–26 Anderson, P. (2000), Renewals, New Left Review, No. 1, Jan.–Feb. 2000 Baeten, G. (2009), Regeneration of the South Bank: Reworking the Community and the Emergence of Post-Political Regeneration, in R. Imrie, M. Raco and L. Lees (eds), Regenerating London, London: Routledge, pp. 237–253 Baeten, G. (2012a), Neoliberalism: Does It Really Exist? in T. Tașan-Kok and G. Baeten (eds), Contradictions of Neoliberal Planning, Berlin: Springer, pp. 205–212 Baeten, G. (2012b), Normalising Neoliberal Planning: The Case of Malmö, Sweden, in T. Tașan-Kok and G. Baeten (eds), Contradictions of Neoliberal Planning, Berlin: Springer, pp. 21–42 Barnekov, T., and D. Rich (1977), Privatism and Urban Development: An Analysis of the Organised Influence of Local Business Elites, Urban Affairs Quarterly, Vol. 12, No. 4, pp. 431–444 Bengs, C. (2005), Planning Theory for the Naïve? European Journal of Spatial Development, www.nordregio. se/Global/EJSD/Debate/debate050718.pdf (accessed 21 April 2016) Berry, M. (2014), ‘Neoliberalism and the City: Or the Failure of Market Fundamentalism’, Housing, Theory and Society, Vol. 31, No. 1, pp. 1–18 Boyle, M., and G. Hughes (1994), The Politics of Urban Entrepreneurialism in Glasgow, Geoforum, Vol. 25, no. 4, pp. 453–470 Brenner, N., J. Peck, and N. Theodore (2010), After Neoliberalization? Globalisations, Vol. 7, No. 3, pp. 327–245 Brenner, N., and N. Theodore (2005), ‘Neoliberalism’ and the Urban Condition, City, Vol. 9, No. 1, pp. 101–107 Brownill, S. (1990), Developing London’s Docklands: Another Great Planning Disaster? London: Sage Cochrane, A. (1999), Just Another Failed Experiment? The Legacy of the Urban Development Corporations, in R. Imrie and H. Thomas (eds), British Urban Policy: An Evaluation of the Urban Development Corporations, London: Sage, pp. 243–258 Crouch, D. (2011), The Strange non-Death of Neoliberalism, Cambridge: Polity Deakin, N., and J. Edwards (1993), The Enterprise Culture and the Inner City, London: Routledge Desfor, G., J. Laidley, Q. Stevens, and D. Schubert (eds) (2012), Transforming Urban Waterfronts: Fixity and Flow, London: Routledge Development Dialogue (2009), Postneoliberalism: A Beginning Debate (theme issue), No. 51 Dikeç, M. (2002), Police, Politics and the Right to the City, GeoJournal, Vol. 58, No. 2, pp. 91–98 Edwards, J. (1984), UK Inner Cities: Problem Construction and Policy Response, Cities, Vol. 1, No. 6, pp. 592–604 Eraydın, I. (2012), Contradictions in the Neoliberal Policy Instruments: What Is the Stance of the State? in G. Baeten and T. Tașan-Kok, Contradictions of Neoliberal Planning, Berlin: Springer, pp. 61–77 Florida, R. (2002a), The Rise of the Creative Class, New York: Basic Books Florida, R. (2002b), The Rise of the Creative Class: Why Cities without Gays and Rock Bands are Losing the Economic Development Race, Washington Monthly, May Florida, R., and A. Jonas (1991), U.S. Urban Policy: The Postwar State and Capitalist Regulation, Antipode, Vol. 23, No. 4, pp. 349–384 Gleeson, B., and N. Low (2000), Revaluing Planning: Rolling Back Neoliberalism in Australia, Progress in Planning, Vol. 53, No. 2, pp. 83–164 Grange, K. (2012), Shaping Acting Space: In Search of a New Political Awareness among Local Authority Planners, Planning Theory, Vol. 11, No. 1, pp. 1–19 Grange, K. (2014), In Search of Radical Democracy: The Ideological Character of Current Political Advocacies for Culture Change in Planning, Environment and Planning A, Vol. 46, pp. 2670–2685 Grange, K. (2016), Planners – A Silenced Profession? The Politicisation of Planning and the Need for Fearless Speech, Planning Theory, Vol. 15, No. 1, pp. 1–21

115

Guy Baeten Gunder, M. (2006), Sustainability: Planning’s Saving Grace or Road to Perdition? Journal of Planning Education and Research, Vol. 26, No. 2, pp. 208–221 Gunder, M. (2010), Planning as the Ideology of (Neoliberal) Space, Planning Theory, Vol. 9, No. 4, pp. 298–314 Gunder, M. (2016), Planning’s ‘Failure’ to Ensure Efficient Market Delivery: A Lacanian Deconstruction of this Neoliberal Scapegoating Fantasy, European Planning Studies, Vol. 24, No. 1, pp. 21–38 Hansen, H. K., and T. Niedomysl (2009), Migration of the Creative Class: Evidence from Sweden, Journal of Economic Geography, Vol. 9, No. 2, pp. 191–206 Harvey, D. (1978), On Planning the Ideology of Planning, in R. Burchell and G. Sternlieb (eds), Planning Theory in the 1980s, New Brunswick: CUPR, pp. 213–233 Harvey, D. (1989), From Managerialism to Entrepreneurialism: The Transformation in Urban Governance in Late Capitalism, Geografiska Annaler B, Vol. 71, No. 1, pp. 3–17 Harvey, D. (2005), A Brief History of Neoliberalism, Oxford: Oxford University Press Hayek, F. von ([1949] 1960), The Intellectuals and Socialism, in G. B. de Huszar (ed.), The Intellectuals: A Controversial Portrait, Glencoe: The Free Press, pp. 371–384 Hildyard, N. (2014), Public-Private Partnerships, Financial Extraction and the Growing Wealth Gap: Exploring the Connections, Presentation at Manchester Business School, 31 July 2014 Holgersen, S. (2014), Urban Responses to the Economic Crisis: Confirmation of Urban Policies as Crisis Management in Malmö, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, Vol. 38, No. 1, pp. 285–301 Holgersen, S. (2015), Crisis and the Post-Industrial City. Or: Is Malmö Building Yesterday’s City Tomorrow, Again? Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale Geografie, Vol. 106, No. 3, pp. 231–245 Imrie, R., and H. Thomas (1999) Assessing Urban Policy and the Urban Development Corporations, in R. Imrie and H. Thomas (eds), British Urban Policy: An Evaluation of the Urban Development Corporations, London: Sage, pp. 3–39 Jackson, J. (2009), Neo-liberal or Third Way? What Planners from Glasgow, Melbourne and Toronto Say, Urban Policy and Research, Vol. 27, No. 4, pp. 397–417 Jenkins, S. (2006), Thatcher & Sons: A Revolution in Three Acts, London: Penguin Joss, S. (2009), Eco-cities: A Global Survey 2009, in C. A. Brebbia, S. Hernandez and E. Tiezzi (eds), The Sustainable City VI: Urban Regeneration and Sustainability, Southampton: WITPress, pp. 239–250 Kearns, G., and C. Philo (1993) Selling Places: The City as Cultural Capital, Past and Present, Oxford: Pergamon Press Keil, R. (2009), The Urban Politics of Roll-with-it Neoliberalization, City, Vol. 13, Nos. 2–3, pp. 231–245 Kusnetzoff, F. (1987), Urban and Housing Policies under Chile’s Military Dictatorship 1973–1985, Latin American Perspectives, Vol. 14, No. 2, pp. 157–186 Lang, R., and Danielsen, K. (2005), Review Roundtable: Cities and the Creative Class, Journal of the American Planning Association, Vol. 71, pp. 203–220 Lees, L., H. B. Shin and E. Lopèz-Morales (eds) (2015), Global Gentrifications. Uneven Development and Displacement, Bristol: Policy Press Lui, T. (2008), City-Branding Without Content: Hong Kong’s Aborted West Kowloon Mega-project, 1998–2006, International Development Planning Review, Vol. 3, No. 3, pp. 215–226 Malanga, S. (2004), The Curse of the Creative Class: A New Age Theory of Urban Development Amounts to Economic Snake Oil, Wall St Journal, 19 January Merrifield, A. (1993), The Canary Wharf Debacle: From ‘TINA’ – There Is No Alternative – To ‘THEMBA’ – There Must Be an Alternative, Environment and Planning A, Vol. 25, No. 9, pp. 1247–1265 Miraftab, F. (2004), Public-Private Partnerships. The Trojan Horse of Neoliberal Development? International Journal of Planning Education and Research, Vol. 24, No. 1, pp. 89–101 Mirowski, P., and D. Plehwe (eds) (2009), The Road from Mont Pelerin: The Making of the Neoliberal Thought Collective, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press Murray, C. (1984), Losing Ground: American Social Policy, 1950–1980, New York: Basic Books NION, Brand Hamburg (Initiative Not in Our Name, Marke Hamburg) (2010), Not In Our Name! Jamming the Gentrification Machine: A Manifesto, City, Vol. 14, No. 3, pp. 323–325 OECD (2013), Green Growth in Cities, OECD Green Growth Studies, Paris: OECD Publishing Paddison, R. (1993), City Marketing, Image Reconstruction and Urban Regeneration, Urban Studies, Vol. 30, No. 2, pp. 339–349 Peck, J. (2005), Struggling with the Creative Class, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, Vol. 29, No. 4, pp. 740–770 Peck, J. (2008), Remaking Laissez-faire, Progress in Human Geography, Vol. 32, No. 1, pp. 3–43

116

Neoliberal Planning Peck, J. (2010), ‘Zombie Neoliberalism and the Ambidextrous State’, Theoretical Criminology, Vol. 14, No. 1, pp. 104–110. Peck, J., and A. Tickell (2002), Neoliberalizing Space, Antipode, Vol. 34, No. 3, pp. 380–404 Peck, J., and N. Theodore (2010) Mobilizing Policy: Models, Methods, and Mutations, Geoforum, Vol. 41, 169–174 Peck, J. (2012), Austerity Urbanism: American Cities under Extreme Economy, City, Vol. 16, No. 6, pp. 626–655 Peet, R., and M. Watts (2004), Liberation Ecology: Development, Sustainability and Environment in an Age of Market Triumphalism, in R. Peet and M. Watts (eds), Liberation Ecologies, London: Routledge, pp. 1–45 Peters, D. (2009), The Renaissance of Inner-City Rail Station Areas: A Key Element in Contemporary Urban Restructuring Dynamics, Critical Planning, Summer 2009, pp. 163–185 Poynter, G., and I. MacRury (eds) (2009), Olympic Cities: 2012 and the Remaking of London, London: Ashgate Purcell, M. (2009), Resisting Neoliberalization: Communicative Planning or Counter-hegemonic Movements? Planning Theory, Vol. 8, No. 2, pp. 140–165 Raco, M. (2005), A Step Change or a Step Back? The Thames Gateway and the Re-birth of the Urban Development Corporations, Local Economy, Vol. 20, No. 2, pp. 141–153 Rancière, J. (1998), Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press Sager, T. (2005), Communicative Planners as Naïve Mandarins of the Neo-liberal State? European Journal of Spatial Development, www.nordregio.se/Global/EJSD/Debate/debate051208.pdf (accessed 21 April 2016) Sager, T. (2011), Neo-liberal Urban Planning Policies: A Literature Survey 1990–2010, Progress in Planning, Vol. 76, pp. 147–199 Said, E. (2000), Problems of Neoliberalism, Al-Ahram, 7 Sept. 2000 Scott, A. J. (2006), Creative Cities: Conceptual Issues and Questions, Journal of Urban Affairs, Vol. 28, No. 1, pp. 1–17 Smith, N. (2008), Neoliberalism is Dead, Dominant, Defeatable – Then What? Human Geography, Vol. 1, No. 2, pp. 1–3 Springer, S. (2010), Neoliberalism and Geography: Expansions, Variegations, Formations, Geography Compass, Vol. 4, No. 8, pp. 1025–1038 Stephenson, M. O. (1991), Whither the Public-Private Partnership: A Critical Overview, Urban Affairs Quarterly, Vol. 27, No. 1, pp. 109–127 Swyngedouw, E., F. Moulaert and A. Rodriguez (2002), Neoliberal Urbanization in Europe: Large-scale Urban Development Projects and the New Urban Policy, Antipode, Vol. 34, No. 3, pp. 542–577 The National Archives (2011), PREM 19/578, Richmond United Nations Environmental Program (2011), Towards a Green Economy: Pathways to Sustainable Development and Poverty Eradication, UNEP, Nairobi Valdes, J. G. (1995), Pinochet’s Economists: The Chicago School in Chile, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Wacquant, L. (2008), Urban Outcasts: A Comparative Sociology of Advanced Marginality, Cambridge: Polity Wacquant, L. (2009), Punishing the Poor: The Neoliberal Government of Social Insecurity, Durham, NC: Duke University Press World Bank (2013), Energizing Green Cities in South East Asia: Applying Sustainable Urban Energy and Emissions Planning, Washington, DC: The World Bank

117

10 NEO-PRAGMATIST PLANNING THEORY Charles Hoch

Introduction Pragmatism has a popular cultural meaning that often generates misleading interpretations. The pragmatist lacks principles and integrity, believing that the ends justify the means. The pragmatist shaves corners and clips wings to keep moral problems within reach and so shirks moral accomplishment. These distortions honor the pragmatist focus on practical consequences and the provisional quality of human purpose. However, they ignore the pragmatist commitment to collaborative inquiry that uses inclusive and intelligent problem solving to advance social learning. The common sense appeal of the pragmatist approach can open the door to cynical manipulation and caricature. But the pragmatist approach also offers an especially attractive theoretical framework for urban planning because it focuses explicitly on human judgment as purposeful, anticipatory and future oriented. This chapter provides an overview of the re-emergence of pragmatist ideas among planning theorists from the 1980s through 2015. After a brief introduction, the first part of the chapter covers five contributions that neo-pragmatist ideas brought to planning theory debates among scholars primarily in North America: power, fact–value dichotomy, problem solving, incrementalism and structure agency. The second part explores some of the cross-fertilization of pragmatist ideas with European postmodern and poststructural social theory.

PART I

Pragmatism and Planning Theory Patsy Healey wrote an essay (2009) that offers a cogent account of North American neopragmatist planning theory. She argues that pragmatist ideas re-emerged in response to the social upheaval and social critiques that emerged in the wake of the late 1960s’ social protest movements in the United States and Europe. The urban riots in US cities, the protracted war in Vietnam, and increased sensitivity to environmental pollution challenged not only current policy, but confidence and belief in the systems of liberal governance and the rationales proposed in their defense. The revival of more encompassing structural critiques using Marxist-inspired

118

Neo-Pragmatist Planning Theory

political economy and ecologically inspired environmentalism gained traction among planning intellectuals offering systematic replacements for discredited welfare state liberalism. Healey uses an article by Rittel and Weber (1973) to frame the crisis. The essay warned planning scholars that the urban problems they hoped would be solved through rational analysis remained wickedly untamed. Rittel and Weber argued that the social problems planners seek to solve cannot be tamed by rational order, but stubbornly resist such formulation. They detail how the underlying presuppositions of the engineering and policy sciences that planning theory used to justify professional judgment (e.g., deterministic models) would not work for complex urban problems. Healey describes how the work by John Friedmann (1973) and Donald Schön (1983) adopted pragmatist ideas to reconceive these complex dilemmas as problems susceptible to social learning. Friedmann developed his ideas focusing on forms of democratic planning, while Schön and Martin Rein (1994) focused on recasting how professionals can use democratic intelligence to enhance learning among their clientele. Pragmatism emerged as a philosophical response to the success of scientific knowledge as a persuasive and powerful mode of inquiry. The successful application of insights from the natural sciences fueled technical innovation and invention accelerating the Industrial Revolution and urbanization. The emergence of modernity not only expanded the rational means for mastering navigation, railways, manufacture, mining, agriculture and the uncertainty of nature across the globe; but intensified the spatial interdependence and interaction among these human systems, generating new forms of uncertainty among emerging nations and colonies; as well as within and among rapidly expanding urban regions. Instead of trying to redeem the salience of philosophy as the intellectual foundation for scientific reason, the pragmatists embraced the practice of scientific inquiry as the focus for philosophical reflection. In the US, the pragmatists argued for a more hopeful conception of modernity in the shadow of Civil War trauma, the closing of the frontier and massive waves of immigrants whose labor produced an unprecedented bounty of goods. The exploitation of these workers and the wholesale destruction of natural resources were concentrated in urban and rural areas and became the object of reform for settlement house reformers such as Jane Adams, landscape architects such as Fredrick Law Olmstead, housing advocates including Benjamin Marsh, and many other middle- and working-class activists (Hays 1957, 1959; Wiebe 1967). The concept of a progressive movement that historians later coined to describe the many reform efforts owes some of its intellectual legitimacy to the early pragmatist ideas linking social action and knowledge with democratic participation (Levine 2000). These disparate and ideologically diverse reformers shared a commitment to the practical power of modern scientific knowledge as a remedy for urban problems. Pragmatic ideas proved popular as justification for the application of science to practical affairs. Urban planning emerged as a focus for professional collaboration that tapped this knowledge even as splits emerged between those who insisted on a division between professional expertise and political involvement (Fairfield 2010; Peterson 2003) and those who argued for integration. For instance, Mary Parker Follett (1998 [1918]) studied Dewey and envisioned the political work of governing and administration as an integration of purpose and intelligence. The practice of democracy, on her view, spreads responsibility as it integrates through deliberation what to do and how to do it. Pragmatist planning theory follows the same tack. Instead of casting theory as a conceptual foundation for planning practice, pragmatists imagine theory as a different kind of deliberative social practice. In the spatial planning world pragmatists avoid prescriptions tied to methodological rigor and certainty; making plans that fulfill rational expectations. The pragmatist scholars focus instead on the relevance of social knowledge for the situation at hand attending to the

119

Charles Hoch

meaning and impact of future consequences. They study what people making plans and planning institutions do to cope with messy, complex social and political problems that accompany modern urban development.

Power and Planning: Forester John Forester has emerged as one of the most popular proponents of a critical pragmatist approach to planning theory. Forester studied at Berkeley in the 1970s influenced by the insights of the post positivist language philosophy of Austin (1965) and the later Wittgenstein channeled through the approach to political theory adopted by Hannah Pitkin (1972) and pragmatist philosopher Richard Bernstein (1978). He was also influenced by the pragmatist systems thinking developed by C. West Churchman (1979) and the critical theory of Jürgen Habermas (1970, 1979). Forester understood that the promise of professional expertise delivered through wellintentioned bureaucratic reform did not offer an adequate response to systems critique and the structural political economy accounts of power tied to global capitalism. Adopting a pragmatist approach enabled him to focus on power in a more integrated fashion. The conditions of modern life that reproduce systemic interdependence not only exploit and dominate, but also generate opportunities for resistance and innovation. Forester uses the insights of language philosophy, critical theory and pragmatism to identify how differences in cognitive capacity, gaps in organizational function, legitimation challenges, shifting emotional attachments and beliefs shape choice and action. He elaborates a robust conception of planning practice that urges practitioners to recognize the inherently political feature of their work, and describes how to grasp this as an asset rather than impediment (1989, 1999, 2009). Forester combines interview and observation of planners and managers to interpret how practitioners engaged in various institutional bureaucratic settings conduct deliberations. How did these people embrace the contingent features of the situation engaging others with practical possibilities for change? Forester also expands the critique of social injustice inspired by the political economists beyond the focus on class relations. Forester shows how planning relies upon deliberations about practical judgment that include how exploitation, subordination and domination can undermine the promise of meaningful discourse. The pragmatist approach integrates structural, systemic and personal power asymmetries within specific situations framing deliberations about practical possibilities for each context. The horizon for action does not flow from abstract ideals about sincerity or legitimacy, but attention to the complex competing claims and expectations for justice, efficiency and solidarity expressed in politically charged deliberations about ambiguous and uncertain claims (Forester 2009). Forester adopts a progressive participatory liberalism. Critical of instrumental conceptions of pluralist democracy he shows how the work of public professionals requires learning how to collaborate and conduct democratic inquiry that invites and addresses social complexity, inequality and diversity setting and solving problems for places.

Resolving Fact and Value: Harper and Stein The work by Thomas Harper and Stan Stein has offered some of the most explicit links between the pragmatist ideas of philosophers and their relevance and use for planning theory. They explicitly reviewed several philosophers and political theorists in a 1994 paper that summarized the neo-pragmatic view: Quine, Davidson, Wittgenstein, Rawls, Putnam, Rorty, Habermas and Walzer. The quick overview helped planning analysts understand that philosophy in the United States adopted a strongly analytical focus in the 20th century. Philosophers focused 120

Neo-Pragmatist Planning Theory

on improving the stature and relevance of logical analysis and rationality as a framework and foundation for scientific and moral inquiry. The new pragmatist philosophers, especially Rorty, critiqued this quest for rational correspondence, reviving and expanding the reach of the pragmatist ideas from Dewey, James and Peirce.1 Harper and Stein (1994) identified the following list of claims attributed to the neo-pragmatist philosophical approach:   1 Non-foundational: knowing tied to social learning and not some other authority   2 Anti-essentialist: we learn concepts through use and not correspondence with a core definition   3 Anti-dualistic: facts and values differ not by category, but by use relevant to context and consequence   4 Non-reductive: the dynamic systems we make and inhabit cannot be broken into parts   5 Non-relativistic: truth varies with consequences in context, but not randomly or without purpose   6 Fallibilistic: truth claims subject to revision based on future inquiry and changing conditions   7 De-emphasizes theory: knowing the meaning of an idea comes from using it and not just possessing it   8 Incremental justification: trial and error remain central to how we learn to adapt – prudential   9 Integrates different frames of belief: focusing on outcomes enables people holding different beliefs to find common ground 10 Democratically pluralistic: including deliberation from people holding diverse beliefs and goals improves the quality of democratic judgments 11 Community vs. individual based: integrity is not something I possess, but something we each acquire through practice with others 12 Rejects incommensurable differences between communities: we make and reproduce our social lives as clever social animals. The differences we invent and use are all subject to change. Recognizing and improving (or destroying) imaginative forms of solidarity always possible. Harper and Stein sidestep the fact–value divide by taking Darwin’s conception of evolution to heart. Humans emerged not as rational animals but through species-specific random variation and natural selection. Each of us acquires a version of rationality depending on our unique developmental paths with biological contours shaped by genetic inheritance and environmental setting. Cartesian doubt – the sort of philosophical thinking that imagines an intellectual escape from the messy details of causal interdependence and social history fails us because each of us lives and conceives as embodied persons living a life journey. The pragmatists turned away from this Cartesian doubt with its focus on an epistemic foundation for truth within each individual and focused instead on the conduct of social inquiry using the norms of scientific study to comprehend how the world works and what this means for democratic governance of public affairs and the flourishing of individuals. Harper and Stein’s list can be sorted into those pragmatist claims that critique the pursuit of rational certainty (items 1 through 7) and the pursuit of the good (items 8 through 12). These critiques apply not only to philosophical arguments, but the conventional understanding many planners use to describe and justify what they do. Planners should consider getting pragmatic as they seek justification for their arguments and ideas (being right), as well as when they try to identify, compare and reconcile competing purposes (doing good). Practitioners have too often learned to treat the first sort of problem as a technical problem of analysis or expertise, and the second sort of problem as an ethical problem for professional judgment (Hoch 1984). The pragmatist approach avoids the separation. Right and good merge as we conduct joint inquiry 121

Charles Hoch

about problems we experience. We imagine solutions and evaluate the future effects in terms of specific social purposes relevant for the situation we face. Instrumental and interpretive meanings, together, shape practical judgment. But how does such inquiry work?

Problem Solving: Blanco The wicked problems that planning addresses cannot be grasped adequately using conventional rational expectations. We cannot develop knowledge to explain, predict and control complex problems. However, a pragmatist planning can and should describe and interpret these problems imagining alternatives that resolve them. How does this work? Hilda Blanco (1994) uses the pragmatist concept of abduction to explain the composition of alternatives in plans. She critiques efforts to adopt deductive and inductive analysis from scientific inquiry. Abduction does not offer prediction or explanation, but plausible possibility – educated hunches about what to expect in some future imagined context. These imagined options offer cognitive grip as people compare the meaning of a simulated change in light of current circumstances. Blanco retains and revises the rational model using concepts from Peirce and Dewey to show how each elaborated a form of critical social inquiry that gave abduction a prominent role in how people conceive and respond to problems. Blanco adopts their insights to show how a pragmatic account of plan making starts with the encounter of a problem in a specific situation and not with goals. As people compose alternative accounts of an imagined future each introduces select variations in the order of events. These plausible options might shift the purposes in play, recasting the meaning of potential constraints and solutions. The deliberation with others about the form and meaning of the future effects each option might entail describes the plan. Plans do not implement goals, but articulate goals in relation to specific contextual conditions offering practical alternatives for action and choice. Blanco celebrates Peirce’s conception of abductive thought, but her conception of planning channels what philosopher Steven Fesmire (2003) considers is Dewey’s idea of imaginative planning. Dewey integrated the consideration of consequences, obligations and virtue as aspects of imaginative plan making. He envisions each contributing to the qualities of practical action needed to address a specific situation. The dramatic rehearsal of detailed practical action invites the sensitive application of virtue, the detached assessment of net benefits and the claims of duty. These are composed into a plausible narrative comparison or elaborated as contrasting tests detailing assessments of future effects framed within an imagined order. The plans we imagine may compose stories about future action that narrate how prudent judgments reconcile competing claims about expected consequences and respect for prior obligations. Problem setting and solving for the pragmatist contribute to the quality of rational judgments used to anticipate and prepare for the future in specific ways. It combines representation and intention (Hoch 2007).

Trading in Synoptic Rationality for Progressive Incrementalism Pragmatism can help people cope better with complex problems, not because it resolves longstanding philosophical disputes, but by shifting attention away from philosophy as the final arbiter of theoretical respectability. The planning intelligentia to the extent they want to establish a theoretical enterprise independent of and somehow more fundamental than the knowledge of practice, should consider pragmatism as a competing framework. The pragmatic orientation does not settle the issues central to the quest for basic or grand theory, but makes the pursuit appear tangential and inconsequential to the business of coping with pressing problems of the day. Harper and Stein argue that Charles Lindblom’s (1959) critique of synoptic rationality and 122

Neo-Pragmatist Planning Theory

emphasis on incrementalism were pragmatic in just this fashion and so a good example of a pragmatist approach to problem solving. Harper and Stein interpret incrementalism as a contextually sensitive experientially attentive form of deliberation. Even cast narrowly as Lindblom’s partisan adjustment among parties holding competing interests, the meaning of agreements still include consequences widely conceived. The policy options, action alternatives or potential projects need not be held hostage to a greedy synoptic rationality, but can be evaluated through purposeful systematic comparison. Taking into account the contextual interests, concerns and expectations among the parties and their constituents encounters practical limits that become part of any spatial plan for a place and any meaningful agreement among those involved in making the plan. Deliberate incremental adjustment enables the plan makers to recast options in light of prior attachments. This happens as parties listen to others and weigh the differences among future outcomes for a plan they could adopt. Increment in this sense does not mean ‘small’ and so unimportant, but cognitively accessible, experientially relevant and morally acceptable to someone unfamiliar with how the option works and what it entails (Fung 2007).

Relational Pragmatism Patsy Healey recognized the efficacy of American pragmatism as she struggled to reconcile the practical consequentialism with more ambitious structural demands for social justice and egalitarian democratic inclusion. Her influential book (1997) on collaborative planning made the case for inclusive participation among those likely to be touched by the consequences of a plan. Healey has consistently adopted a relational approach linking a pragmatically inspired conception of collaboration with a critical sensitivity to encompassing social and territorial relationships. She has developed a more refined conception of democratic planning that responds to the conditions of institutional and territorial complexity and plurality across the globe (2007). Healey elaborates a functional vocabulary that she hopes will encompass and interpret complex changes in urban regions – especially those changes susceptible to purposeful and useful modification and those that resist. She uses the concept of strategy to capture the more informal, flexible and dynamic assessment of relations susceptible to change within politically sensitive frames of purposeful action. Healey envisions planning as inclusive strategic thought that informs policy. Strategy refers to savvy decision making by clusters of stakeholders negotiating provisional collective agreements about problems of vulnerable interdependence, common special interests or other contextual situations demanding collective action. The geographic and functional classification of so many relationships challenges the reader to interpret individual planning judgments in light of their prospects for generating important changes in spatial policy and ensuing projects. Healey keeps the pragmatist sensibility, but in the end she focuses on forms of political governance that, in her view, extend beyond planning. The relationships she studies include institutional and geographic relationships that promise in her account to offer a more progressive because inclusive alternative for spatial development than dominant corporate alternatives.

PART II

Postmodern Critique Inspired by postmodern and poststructural theory from philosophy and the social sciences in Europe, some planning theorists challenge the foundational quest for an epistemic trump and the 123

Charles Hoch

confident pursuit of scientific progress as unambiguously transparent and benign. They criticize pragmatist conceptions of planning for ignoring how power relationships undermine the deliberations they champion and adopting a contextual relativism that fails to grasp the impact of structural causes and so overlooks innovations that might effectively challenge and replace the source of systemic problems (Allmendinger & Tewdwr-Jones 2002; Balducci et al. 2011; Hillier 2011). The critique of pragmatism for failing to deal with power relationships flows mainly from a difference in vocabulary. The critics insist that power refers to forms of economic, political or social domination, exclusion, exploitation and subjection that inescapably impose themselves. Pragmatists on this account naively describe power in terms of economic, political or social legitimacy, inclusion, solidarity and consensus (Mouffe 1996). The pragmatists imagine that each person is capable of the full range of vice and virtue, good and evil and that what we learn to believe and how we are taught (socialization or enculturation) to act locates us along the continua of multiple power dimensions. Pragmatists recognize that we acquire our moral capacity and practice within the context of specific cultural and institutional settings that include every sort of power relationship. Ethics always includes social and political motivations, circumstances and effects. The moral meaning of our action depends on the contextual efforts we each face acquiring standing as an individual whose actions speak louder than words. These contexts include institutional, cultural and natural conditions that shape the limits and meaning of our effort. So neo-pragmatists do not ignore power, they just recognize that its inevitable presence does not trump or preclude creative practical moral effort to resist and recast the nasty and destructive plans with less repressive and more useful ones. This makes knowledge for plan making a central part of the effort to achieve practical grounds for the moral recovery of individual freedom in places where this possibility seems remote (Dewey 1927; Bernstein 2010; Forester 2009). The modernism of experimental pragmatism, with its emphasis on democratic inquiry, does not align with the efficiency-focused expertise of hardboiled instrumentalism that has little to say in response to postmodern critique. But reviving and using pragmatist ideas that foster involvement and inclusion offers a useful and coherent response. Snider (2000) sums this up nicely: A century ago, pragmatism recast the terms of the debate between idealists and empiricists; today, it provides a bridge between modernism’s faith in human reason and progress (Gergen, 1992, p. 211) and the seemingly relativistic, or even nihilistic, aspects of postmodernism (Auxier, 1995). The pragmatic theorist does not possess any less passion for freedom than the poststructural theorist. Pragmatic planning theorists criticize the naturalization of uncertainty as an inevitable force removing the possibility for individual freedom (Hoch 1984; Harper & Stein 2006; Verma 1998). The difference is that pragmatic theory recognizes that practical consequences matter for the beliefs we hold and that the current conventions and techniques rely upon and reproduce a complex moral mixture of good and bad, stupid and clever, useless and useful. This makes purposeful planned compromise an important resource for improving the mixtures, even as it entails conflicts (Hoch 2007). The pragmatic theorists focus here on kinds of democracy because they do not believe people possess the knowledge and authority to prescribe a more complete moral order, nor do they want to sacrifice the promise of individual effort to obtain it. That is why pragmatists end up embracing versions of liberal democracy both as a resource for planning knowledge and a target for improvement (Forester 1989; Harper & Stein 2006; Verma 2010). This does not mean that pragmatic theorists squeamishly avoid or snuff out conflict (Hoch 1992, 1994; Forester 1989, 1999, 2010). Pragmatists focus on what people do to subject 124

Neo-Pragmatist Planning Theory

a subordinate, punish a peer, cheat a client, subvert a rule, repress a wish, fix a bet, tempt the weak, humiliate the vulnerable and so on; asking what difference this makes for the parties touched by the situation at hand. The complexity of human personality and social involvement precludes taking a theoretical position independent of the interactive flux and flow of judgment and action. Planning provides a tool that we can use to compose and compare choices for what we can and should do to anticipate and cope with the problems encountered as we make our way in the interactive flux. Planning cannot protect us from temptation to evil or the willful embrace of destructive personal and social acts. The pragmatists turn to action and research rather than abstract theory to provide practical insight and evidence about the consequences for purposeful plans (Forester 1983, 1989; Hoch 1987, 1988, 1992, 1994; Innes & Booher 2010). The differences in method and meaning that ensue in these assessments remain open to debate and refinement. This liberal conception of mutual learning does allow for revision by those who adapt it, even large dramatic revisions. Insisting on adversarial conflict or agonism alone will not offer crucial protection for the liberal polity especially facing complex problems. It can fail to offer practical hope as antagonists seal off from one another. Neo-pragmatists do need to recognize and conceive differences more clearly and fairly, and this requires greater tolerance and acceptance of social conflict. They also need to recognize and conceive forms of solidarity and collective tools that we can use to cope with complexity and plans can do this. The wish for consensus might be too simplistic and exclusive, but expectation for a shared threshold of civility and social order seems necessary for plan making that would remedy unnecessary and destructive forms of uncertainty. People can and do learn how to make plans that better assimilate and balance antagonistic difference and shared civility. This requires less attention to philosophical arguments about ultimate truth and more on how cognitive, psychological, economic, political, spatial, . . . conceptions of the relationships generating practical problems combine causal attribution and purposeful action. The ideas about how our world works and what we should do to change it cohere as people make plans for the future.

Pragmatism Unbound Roberto Unger (2007) offers an ambitious revision of pragmatist ideas that recognizes the contingent and provisional qualities of human social experience. We should not hand off our capacity for critical awakening and individual development to the forces of nature or social structure. He bridles at liberal compromise that treats the legacy of social convention as something only susceptible to incremental adjustments. Unger reconstructs the pragmatist ideas of contingency, agency, experimentalism and focus on the future rejecting a too restrictive naturalism and scientism. Unger goes on to argue that efforts to realize the future should not rely upon blueprints fueled by the contours of structural critique, but the active engagement of ordinary people in practical efforts to expand and improve the cooperative democratic features of economic, social and political life. The meaningful emancipation of individuals requires a vibrant political pluralism among ‘provisional conjectures’ that anticipate and articulate practical steps forward. But Unger does not offer much practical advice for how we might make plans to turn his prophetic pragmatism into useful reforms.

Cosmopolitan Pragmatism Meg Holden and Andy Scerri (2014) explore how ideas from French critical pragmatists contribute to understanding the kind of inclusive critical experimentation that Bridges explores in his work. Holden shows how the complex and messy social interactions that accompany the 125

Charles Hoch

active creation and response to plans for a place in liberal systems include forms of justification that exceed the boundaries of any one mode of deliberation. Compromise and not consensus becomes the crucial threshold for political agreement and collective action. The French scholars Boltanski and Thévenot (2006 [1991]) identify multiple social orders to explain political compromises formed in complex contested social situations that accompany urban planning conflicts. For instance, in their analysis the economic and civic orders parallel and overlap one another as competing justifications for the objects and actions centered in a specific urban dispute. The justification offered for each domain appeals to a general good that exceeds the reach of that specific order. For instance, arguments for profitability and sustainability each appeal, respectively, to a more inclusive good that draws upon institutional practices and conditions that frame the legitimacy of such appeals. Finding common ground justifying these domains generates a new practical horizon for convergence and joint action if not consensus. Holden and Scerri contend that these sociological insights extend the practical scope and efficacy of planning claims about problem situations beyond concerns about the quality of deliberation among stakeholders to include the institutional, technical and material relationships that frame practical changes in social habits. Boltanski and Thévenot appear neo-pragmatic because they provide a theory that integrates the provisional influence of objects and events in the problematic situations where discursive orders compete for attention and support. In their effort to avoid the seemingly idealist and relativist features of the collaborative pragmatist approach, Holden and Scerri distance themselves from the hopeful liberalism that Dewey set in motion and that still inspires scholarship by Forester (1989, 1999), Innes & Booher (2010), Harper & Stein (1996) and Hoch (2010). Botanski and Thévenot, like Latour (1988), offer a systematic scheme to capture the complexity of discursive practice that encompasses space, objects and tools as well as language. However, they remain tied to the philosophical distinction between the epistemic and ontological; knowledge and reality. They hope to escape the philosophical critique that focusing on practical situations as the context for understanding social conflict and action will yield only partial truth claims. Their sophisticated analytical scheme recognizes the pragmatic relevance of compromise as the proper medium for deliberative democratic practice among multiple actors. But the analytic dualism precludes making a normative commitment to a good compromise. Hence they focus on discursive justification rather than persuasion classifying the resolution of competing orders of value (market, industry, sustainability, civic solidarity, . . .) mediating between knowing and being. The collaborative pragmatists frame discourse as persuasive deliberation that promises to yield compromise plans offering better consequences than no plan. The interpretation of the outcomes includes assessing the kinds of justification people made discussing the plan, but also the impacts on changes in belief and the problematic conditions contributing to the problem. Gary Bridge (2005) provides an expansive conception of pragmatist planning that, like Unger, envisions a more radical pluralism envisioning options for the future of places always under construction. He assimilates the postmodern focus on difference to a less skeptical and more engaged sensitivity to not only deliberations, but more expansive practical experiences. Bridges reinterprets the Chicago School of Sociology, arguing that the conception of community and communication includes discourse, but also the unconscious emotional and social habits that shape the contours for meaningful individual action. He proposes a pragmatist rationality that embraces the recognition and pursuit of individual identity and difference across multiple communities – what Dewey called publics. He frames this transactional rationality as a robust form of integration binding instrumental, emotive and interpretive dimensions of complex relationships within provisional judgments about ends and means. Bridges explores how these work in different urban places and settings as situations susceptible to embodied 126

Neo-Pragmatist Planning Theory

social actions along complex continua that defy hierarchical order. The seemingly mundane dimensions of social interaction often overlooked in dualistic and deterministic conceptions of order provide multiple instances of resistance, innovation and compliance. The prospects for change appear more practically hopeful, studying the many different ways that people respond to shifting situations. Barnett and Bridge (2013) take on the claim that poststructural agonistic conceptions of democracy trump liberal conceptions of consensus-based democracy. They craft a neo-pragmatist alternative. On their view poststructural accounts focus on theoretical differences that often exaggerate conflict. As a result they ignore the demands of coordination, institutional design and public good that accompany any effort to put radical forms of democracy to practical use for planning. Barnett and Bridge use the work by pragmatist political theorists (Bohman 2007; Fung 2007; Dryzek 2005) that argue for a more robust democratic inclusion among multiple publics that recognizes and integrates differences through pragmatic deliberation.

Conclusion Pragmatism does not tell us what ends to pursue, but offers a kind of inquiry that compares the value of different courses of action alternately weighing means and ends – facts and values. It binds together what longstanding dualistic thinking kept apart – knowledge and action (or perhaps a bit more precisely) theoretical reflection and practical judgment. Pragmatism provides an antidote to the quest for certainty by exploring how multiple publics can democratically anticipate and prepare for different contingencies using practical and scientific knowledge to inform purposes and plans for a contingent and uncertain future. Pragmatist planning theory supports the historical division of intellectual labor and technical innovation that has produced astonishing feats of invention and engineering; but does not confuse the power of such specialized rationality as a resource for practical judgment. For instance the advertising slogan ‘Smart Cities’ for the pragmatist does not mean adopting the technical innovations of high tech corporations as a guide for slum removal and highway development. Nor does it mean adopting clever professional expertise as a substitute for familiar institutions and conventions. The pragmatist understands that high tech innovations rely upon a vast cultural infrastructure of shared social convention and learning. The effectiveness of specialized knowledge relies upon this taken-for-granted context – a context often ignored or dismissed by undemocratic elites. The pragmatist insists that plans for change include the knowledge and experience of people likely to be touched by the consequences. Their involvement offers crucial insight about the practical meaning of the imagined effects for proposed changes, but also acceptable and feasible means for reconciling complex differences in useful and legitimate compromise. A neo-pragmatist planning theory sidesteps theoretical foundations for practical insight and improvement. Instead of knowing first what to do and how to do it, the pragmatist emphasizes contextual inquiry closely tied to social learning, practical experimentation and democratic deliberations. For the pragmatists everyone plans, so improving plans for complex social and spatial problems requires improvement in the craft of plan making in different cultural, institutional and geographic settings. The scaffolding of spatial breadth and temporal reach remains intact across the variety of uses, but not rigidly scaled or tightly defined. The complexity of human interaction and interdependence requires flexible and provisional practical judgments about the arrangement of future settlement. Then neo-pragmatist planning theory focuses on how to conduct such judgment more intelligently and wisely using inclusive democratic inquiry. 127

Charles Hoch

Note 1 Rorty (1982, 1998) was popular and controversial. His work stimulated an enormous amount of debate among philosophers and also among scholars studying the social sciences and professions.

References Allmendinger, P. & Tewdwr-Jones, M. (2002) Planning Futures: New Directions for Planning Theory. London: Routledge. Austin, J. (1965) How To Do Things with Words. New York: Oxford University Press. Auxier, R. (1995) The decline of evolutionary naturalism in later pragmatism. In R. Hollinger & D. Depew (Eds.), Pragmatism: From Progressivism to Postmodernism (pp. 180–207). Westport, CT: Praeger. Balducci, A., Boelens, L., Hillier, M., Nyseth, T. & Wilkinson, C. (2011) Strategic spatial planning in uncertainty: theory and exploratory practice. Town Planning Review 82(5): 481–502. Barnett, C. & Bridge, G. (2013) Geographies of radical democracy: agonistic pragmatism and the formation of affected interests. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 103(4): 1022–1040. Bernstein, R. (1978) The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory. Philadelphia, PN: University of Pennsylvania Press. Bernstein, R. (2010) The Pragmatic Turn. Cambridge: Polity Press. Blanco, H. (1994) How to Think about Social Problems: American Pragmatism and the Idea of Planning. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press. Bohman, J. (2007) Democracy across Borders: From Dêmos to Dêmoi. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Boltanski, L. & Thévenot, L. (2006 [1991]) On Justification: Economies of Worth. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Bridge, G. (2005) Reason in the City of Difference: Pragmatism, Communicative Action and Contemporary Urbanism. London: Routledge. Churchman, C.W. (1979) The Systems Approach and Its Enemies. New York: Basic Books. Dewey, J. (1927) The Public & Its Problems. Athens: Swallow Press. Dryzek, J. (2005) Deliberative democracy in divided societies: alternatives to agonism and analgesia. Political Theory 33: 218–242. Fairfield, J.D. (2010) The Public and Its Possibilities: Triumphs and Tragedies in the American City. Philadelphia, PN: Temple University Press. Fesmire, S. (2003) John Dewey and Moral Imagination. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Follett, M.P. (1998 [1918]) The New State: Group Organization the Solution of Popular Government. University Park, PN: University of Pennsylvania Press. Forester, J. (1983) The geography of planning practice. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 1: 163–180. Forester, J. (1989) Planning in the Face of Power. Berkeley: University of California Press. Forester, J. (1999) The Deliberative Practitioner. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Forester, J. (2010) Dealing with Differences: Dramas of Mediating Public Disputes. New York: Oxford University Press. Friedmann, J. (1973) Retracking America: A Theory of Transactive Planning. New York: Anchor. Fung, Archon. (2007) Democratic theory and political science: a pragmatic method of constructive engagement. The American Political Science Review 101(3): 443–458. Gergen, K. (1992) Organization theory in the postmodern era. In M. Reed & M. Hughes (Eds.), Rethinking Organization (pp. 207–226). London: Sage. Habermas, J. (1970) Toward a Rational Society. Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1979) Communication and the Evolution of Society. Boston, MA: Beacon Press. Harper, T. & Stein, S. (1994) Neopragmatism and planning. Paper delivered at the annual meeting of the Association of Collegiate Schools of Planning, Pheonix, Arizona. Harper, T. & Stein, S. (2006) Dialogical Planning in a Fragmented Society. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Center for Urban Policy Research. Hays, S. (1957) The Response to Industrialism: 1885–1914. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hays, S. (1959) Conservation and the Gospel of Efficiency: 1890–1920. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press. Healey, P. (1997) Collaborative Planning. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press. Healey, P. (2007) Urban Complexity and Spatial Strategies: Toward a Relational Planning for our Times. London: Routledge.

128

Neo-Pragmatist Planning Theory Healey, P. (2009) The pragmatic tradition in planning thought. Journal of Planning Education and Research 28: 277–292. Hillier, J. (2011) Strategic navigation across multiple planes: towards a Deleuzian-inspired methodology for strategic spatial planning. Town Planning Review 82(5): 503–528. Hoch, C. (1984) Doing good and being right: the pragmatic connection in planning theory. Journal of the American Planning Association 50: 335–345. Hoch, C. (1987) Planning threatened: a preliminary report of planners and political conflict. Journal of Planning Education and Research 6: 99–107. Hoch, C. (1988) Conflict at large: a national survey of planners and political conflict. Journal of Planning Education and Research 7(4): 25–34. Hoch, C. (1992) The paradox of power in planning practice. Journal of Planning Education and Research 11: 206–215. Hoch, C. (1994) What Planners Do: Power, Politics, and Persuasion. Chicago, IL: Planners Press. Hoch, C. (2007) Making plans: representation & intention. Planning Theory 6(1): 15–35. Hoch, C. (2010) Planning craft: how planners compose plans. Planning Theory 8(3): 219–241. Holden, M. & Scerri, A. (2014) Justification, compromise and test: developing a pragmatic sociology of critique to understand the outcomes of urban redevelopment. Planning Theory 14(4): 360–383. Innes, J.E. & Booher, D.E. (2010) Planning with Complexity: An Introduction to Collaborative Rationality for Public Policy. New York: Routledge. Latour, B. (1988) Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Levine, P. (2000) The New Progressive Era: Toward a Fair and Deliberative Democracy. New York: Rowman and Littlefield. Lindblom, C. (1959) The science of ‘muddling through’. Public Administrative Review 19(2): 79–88. Mouffe, C. (1996) Deconstruction, pragmatism, and the politics of democracy. In C. Mouffe (Ed.), Deconstruction and Pragmatism (pp. 1–12). London: Routledge. Peterson, J. (2003) The Birth of City Planning in the United States, 1840–1917. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Pitkin, H.F. (1972) Wittgenstein and Justice. Berkeley: University of California Press. Rittel, H. & Weber, M. (1973) Dilemmas in a general theory of planning. Policy Sciences 4: 155–169. Rorty, R. (1982) Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Rorty, R. (1998) Philosophy & Social Hope. London: Penguin. Schön, D. (1983) The Reflective Practitioner. New York: Basic Books. Schön, D. & Rein, M. (1994) Frame Reflection: Toward the Resolution of Intractable Policy Controversies. NewYork: Basic Books. Snider, K. (2000) Rethinking public administration’s roots in pragmatism. American Review of Public Administration 30(2): 123–145. Unger, R.M. (2007) The Self Awakened: Pragmatism Unbound. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Verma, N. (1998) Similarities, Connections & Systems. Lanham, MD: Lexington. Verma, N. (2010) Governance and planning: a pragmatic approach. In J. Hillier & P. Healey (Eds.), The Ashgate Research Companion to Planning Theory: Conceptual Challenges for Spatial Planning (pp. 399–412). Farnham, Surrey: Ashgate. Wiebe, R. (1967) The Search for Order: 1877–1920. New York: Hill & Wang.

129

11 URBAN PLANNING AND SOCIAL JUSTICE Susan S. Fainstein

This chapter addresses the relationship between urban planning and social justice.1 Since the primary way in which urban planning affects social justice is through spatial arrangements, spatial justice constitutes the focus of the discussion. Underlying all spatial planning is the premise that conscious choice of means and ends produces better cities and regions than unregulated development. Normative planning theory explores the moral basis of planning; that is, what is meant by “producing better cities and regions.” The term “better” implies more attributes than simply more just—it implies more productive, more efficient, more beautiful, more sustainable as well. I begin by addressing the question of why justice should be given priority, examine the role of planners in effecting or blocking its application, look at the history of value emphases in planning, consider current debates, and conclude by discussing what can be done. The issues then become the appropriate process for decision making about the location, content, and form of the built environment; evaluation of approaches to urban and regional growth and decline; and formulation of the values by which process and outcome should be judged. Justice is defined here as incorporating the values of democracy, diversity, and equity.2 Although all three of these principles are constitutive of justice, they exist in tension with each other, and maximizing any of them can result in trade-offs. Within modern political thought the argument for democracy as the basis for the legitimacy of the state began with Enlightenment theory of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries; as a stipulation within planning theory it dates to the 1960s, when demands for community control and citizen participation asserted themselves (Arnstein 1969). Emphasis on diversity, defined by race, gender, and ethnicity, is a somewhat later phenomenon but is also rooted in the movements of the 1960s–70s (see Altshuler 1970; Fainstein and Fainstein 1974; Sandercock 1998; Young 1990). The call for equity can also be traced back to the Enlightenment (Rousseau 1992) but more recently in the writings of neo-Marxist theorists and critical geographers (Lefebvre 1996; Harvey 1973; Soja 2010) as well as those of liberal philosophers (Rawls 1971; Sandel 2009). This demand for justice does not preclude the use of efficiency or economic development as criteria for evaluating policies but rather requires that justice be the first principle. If justice becomes the yardstick for measuring public policy effectiveness, then policy-makers must ask to what end efficiency applies and who benefits from economic growth. A policy that assists the most disadvantaged without wasting resources meets the efficiency criterion even if it does not maximize an aggregate benefit/cost ratio. In contrast, for those who take the position that the 130

Urban Planning and Social Justice

only measure of efficiency is maximizing utility in the aggregate, assisting the disadvantaged is usually considered to waste resources by diverting public investments from their most productive use. Similarly if the measure of economic development consists entirely of increases in per capita product, then distributive effects go unevaluated. Such uncritical applications of aggregate approaches to policy evaluation, however, lead to increased injustice. Within the scholarly literature a critique of urban planning as unjust, rooted in Marxist political economy, began in the 1970s (Fainstein and Fainstein 1971; Castells 1977; Harvey 1978; Dear and Scott 1981; Foglesong 1986). This initial discussion of spatial injustice attacked planning as inflicting disproportionate damage on vulnerable populations. It responded to urban renewal and highway programs in the West, as well as demolition of informal housing and markets in poorer countries. Inspired by the urban social movements of the 1960s and 70s, radicals within the academy exposed the skewed distribution of benefits resulting from ostensibly progressive governmental actions such as slum clearance. Later, negative assessments of planning reacted to neoliberal urban policies that aimed at increasing competitiveness through subsidies to capital, megaproject development, gentrification, and privatization of public services, all rationalized as serving economic development (Harvey 1989, 2005; Smith 1979; Fainstein and Fainstein 2013). Most of these critiques of planning implied standards of justice by which planning could be evaluated, but they did not specify what those standards were, nor did they describe the content of more just policies. Explicit arguments concerning what constitutes spatial justice are more recent (Fainstein 2010; Soja 2010; Campbell and Fainstein 2012).

Giving Priority to Justice Making justice a primary goal for urban policy rests on both moral and practical arguments. The moral argument goes beyond the position shared by Marxists and mainstream economists that people act according to their material interests. While the economic mainstream begins with individual choice, Marxists start with class and consider that the only way to bring about desirable change is through changing the relations of production. Class interests, however, are subject to interpretation, even under capitalism. How do you know what your class interest actually is? There is an assumption that your class interest, if you are a businessperson, is to exploit your workforce as much as possible, while your class interest, if you are a worker, is to resist as much as possible. Normative theory breaks with this position by insisting that people act in accordance with moral judgment not simply self- or group interest. Only by holding that people should take actions because they are right—that is, moral—can one counter narrowly defined interests (Mansbridge 1990). A society organized according to moral principles affords every member the opportunity to thrive (Nussbaum 2000, 2006), and, in fact, class interests encompass a broad spectrum of possibility, including that one’s interest is living in a decent society. Even from a purely practical standpoint, business owners can benefit from a happier and more stable workforce and from customers who have more disposable income. Moreover, people have multiple identities and therefore multiple interests. Openness to difference derives from the recognition of a common humanity; as Edward Soja (2010: 23) argues, a call for justice constitutes a unifying goal among disparate groups: “[It] transcends the defined categories of race, gender, class, nationality, sexual preference, and other forms of homogeneous and often exclusive group or community identity.” Within the currently dominant ideological framework of neoliberalism, governing groups have used competitiveness as their chief justification for spatial policy choices. Efforts to reduce inequality and provide advantages to minority groups, in this view, hinder the workings of the market’s invisible hand, produce moral hazards, and cause the economy to perform at 131

Susan S. Fainstein

a suboptimal level. The counter-argument is that neoliberal policies have resulted in growing inequality and social exclusion, that this outcome cannot be morally justified, and that in the long run it will result in social disruption. The intent of social movements, in the face of neoliberal obduracy, should be to press for the attainment of a decent society and to promote government policies aimed at furthering that end. Formulating what constitutes a decent society requires examining theories of justice. Political philosophy provides abstract definitions of a just society and thus offers a means for thinking about social goals. In this respect the writings of John Rawls (1971), whose difference principle requires governance that insures benefits to the relatively disadvantaged, has been particularly important in framing debates among political philosophers concerning the meaning of justice. In essence, Rawls argues that rational individuals would choose policies that promote equality if, in the original position behind “a veil of ignorance,” they could not foresee where they would end up in a social hierarchy. Political philosophy, however, while supporting democracy, diversity, and equity, does not usually spell out how to achieve its goals. What should be the aims of social movements? What spatial policies would support those aims? Planning comprises the set of regulations and incentives available by which to constrain and develop the built environment. It thus constitutes a target for those demanding justice, but historically it has frequently been an instrument for social exclusion.

The Role of Planning The basis for modern spatial planning evolved in the late 1800s and throughout much of the next century in response to the social and environmental effects of industrialism. It aimed to produce a city organized along rational lines that would allow for the efficient transportation of goods and people, preserve public health, and provide parks and recreation to relieve the effects of overcrowding and environmental pollution. Early planners proceeded without much reflection about the process by which the desired spatial form was formulated—planning’s implicit theoretical argument dwelled on the nature of the good city instead of the method by which to formulate either goals or means. The public interest constituted the moral basis of planning, but little systematic effort was directed at ascertaining its content. It was assumed that the public interest was singular, and that a well-planned city would benefit all its users. Although social critics emphasized the need to rid urban development programs of corruption, eliminate slums, and provide decent housing, they did not differ from more mainstream planners in considering that planning should be sharply separated from politics and that experts should do the planning. The development of an explicit theory directed at prescribing the planner’s modus operandi began with the publication of Karl Mannheim’s Man and Society in an Age of Reconstruction in 1935.3 It laid the philosophical foundations for later theorizing by describing a democratic planning process that would enable experts to plan under the guidance of the public through their elected representatives. Mannheim’s ambition exceeded that of city planning—inspired by the ideals of reform liberalism, he envisioned the national state’s participation in economic and social planning. He argued that, if the planning bureaucracy was subject to parliamentary control, it could apply its technical expertise to the solution of social problems without impinging on freedom: The new bureaucracy brought with it a new objectivity in human affairs. There is something about bureaucratic procedure which helps to neutralize the original leanings towards patronage, nepotism, and personal domination. This tendency towards 132

Urban Planning and Social Justice

objectivity may, in favourable cases, become so strong that the element of class consciousness, still present in a bureaucracy which is chosen mainly from the ranks of the ruling classes, can be almost completely superseded by the desire for justice and impartiality. (Mannheim 1940: 323) As time passed, the demand for impartiality became translated into an emphasis on fair processes based in scientific calculation. Peter Hall (2002: 362) describes how, after World War II, spatial planners adopted methodologies based in economics and the natural sciences, which were “independent of the thing that was planned.” The term used to describe the procedure for goal maximization in planning was “the rational model.” Derived from the scientific method, the model assumed that goals could be named in advance through the political process. Planners would choose among alternative ways of achieving these ends based on an objective calculation of aggregate costs and benefits. By making a sharp distinction between process, context, and outcomes planners could evade responsibility for the normative content of their activities as long as they demonstrated integrity in their analysis. The belief that fact and value can be separated, which underlies the application of the rational model, has been strongly attacked. People can only discern the impact of broad goals when the means of their achievement are described; thus, goal formulation and policy in actuality proceed in tandem. Furthermore, planners might lack the technical capacity to find the means to determine how to reach the desired ends (Altshuler 1965). Charles Lindblom (1959), whose work echoed the skepticism of such management theorists as Herbert Simon, argued that the desire for rationality was both impractical and undesirable. He characterized the actual planning and policy making process as incremental. As reflected in the irony of the title of his famous article on the subject, “The Science of ‘Muddling Through’,” he declared a cautious method of “partisan mutual adjustment” to be more effective in reaching desirable outcomes than the synoptic planning method idealized within the rational model. In the 1960s and 70s, the intellectual current that had questioned the claims of planning to rationality was strengthened by a dissident but nonetheless influential movement within the planning profession itself. Participants in this movement expressed concern over the impacts of decisions on the politically powerless—especially those displaced by highway and urban renewal programs (Hoffman 1989). The view of the Marxist theorists discussed above that only the demise of capitalism would enable planners to act justly proved very discouraging to progressive planners who by then were also working for community-based organizations rather than solely for city governments and business groups (Brooks 2002; Fainstein and Fainstein 1979). One response to this seeming impasse was to chart courses whereby planning could, in fact, achieve redistributional outcomes (Clavel 1986; Krumholz and Forester 1990). The underlying theoretical premises of these efforts, however, were rarely made explicit. Like the academic critics of planning outcomes, practitioners who proposed exemplary remedies did not describe and justify their value position (Fainstein 1999; Sayer and Storper 1997). Beginning in the 1980s, efforts to develop middle-range theory that embeds planning practice within a larger theoretical framework looked at how planners could bring about more just cities and regions (see Friedmann 2011). I use the term middle-range here because, although some of these works extend to countries at various stages of political and economic development, the primary focus was on principles to guide policy within democratic Western societies rather than norms applicable everywhere. Although broad concepts of justice have a universal resonance, their specific content is restricted in relation to both place and time rather than applying to all geographic areas in an entire historical epoch. In the words of Campbell and 133

Susan S. Fainstein

Marshall (2006: 241; my italics), “Just planning which acknowledges its responsibilities to the poor, vulnerable and relatively weak is therefore, we argue, fundamentally about situated ethical judgement.” Increasingly planning theorists have referred to political philosophers concerned with justice in their inquiries regarding the appropriate role of planners. Based on the philosophies of Jürgen Habermas and John Dewey, discussions of communicative rationality have been prominent attempts to give theoretical guidance to planning actions. Rejecting the positivism of the rational model, proponents of communicative planning have accepted critiques of planning as authoritarian. They argue that claims for technical expertise disregard local knowledge and fail to develop understanding among the public subjected to planning. They call for an open process of deliberation in which the planner encourages collaboration and mediates among discordant views (Healey 2006; Forester 1993). Essentially their aim is to produce spatial justice through a just planning process. Although they differ from the technocratic theorists who believed that the planning process could be wholly fact-based, they similarly focus on procedure. In their case the procedure calls for public participation, the acceptance of subjective viewpoints, and limiting the planner to a mediating role. If conducted properly, the process should result in consensus and just outcomes. The concept of the just city has, likewise, been developed as a theoretical response to the injustices of authoritarianism and neoliberalism (Fainstein 2010; Marcuse et  al. 2009). The concept applies to participation (Purcell 2008), public space (Mitchell 2003), infrastructure (Flyvbjerg, Bruzelius, and Rothengatter 2003), the environment (Low and Gleeson 1998), and tourism (Jamala and Camargob 2014). The thoughts of Henri Lefebvre (1991) have been particularly influential in shaping the vision of a just city, especially his concern that all should have a “right to the city.” Lefebvre’s approach goes beyond institutionalized participation to project a utopian goal of space responding to popular will: “The right to the city is not merely a right of access to what already exists, but a right to change it after our heart’s desire” (Harvey 2003: 939). Initial forays into developing theories of spatial justice have led to a number of debates. They concern the relationship between process and outcome, the extent to which meaningful change toward greater spatial justice is possible within global capitalism, the question of whether differences of race, ethnicity, and gender are analytically separate from income inequality, and the tension between equity and environmentalism (S. Campbell 1996).

The Process/Outcome Debate The process/outcome debate within planning theory has its roots in two articles criticizing communicative theory on the grounds that power differentials prevent mediation processes from attaining just results (Fainstein 2000; Huxley and Yiftachel 2000). In my article I criticize the communicative theorists for overemphasizing the centrality of facilitating discussion, assuming that all interests can be represented within the planning process, and ignoring the possibility that any seeming consensus will be dominated by the views of the most powerful participants. In addition, I maintain that when agreement did incorporate the interests of disadvantaged groups, implementation frequently did not occur. Huxley and Yiftachel similarly contend that the communicative model seriously underestimates the issues of power, the state, and the political economy. The relationship between open democratic processes and just outcomes is problematic. The equity outcomes of citizen deliberations are unpredictable and are likely to vary according to the particular values of the active participants. The initial demands for citizen participation in 134

Urban Planning and Social Justice

bureaucratic decision making originated with low-income groups seeking increased benefits and respect. As time passed, however, participatory mechanisms primarily became a vehicle for middle-class interests. As such, they represented a move toward democratizing the planning process but not usually in the direction of redistribution. Context matters—if participants are not backed by widespread mobilization or by powerful interest groups, they are unlikely to prevail. Moreover, in cities suffering from a withdrawal of capital investment, neighborhood participants are no more able than the mayor to stem the tide and often yield to the logic that only through subsidies to developers are any investments likely to happen. In cities under development pressure, they might be able to gain concessions in terms of community spaces, social services, and affordable housing; their ability to halt gentrification, however, is restricted by their lack of control over private-market activities. If planners play a more active role in policy formulation, they can affect the character of deliberation and move participants toward a greater commitment to just outcomes.Without political backing they are unlikely to succeed, but by framing issues in terms of justice and promoting redistributive policies, they can achieve more than by passively letting citizen deliberations take their course. Campbell, Tait, and Watkins (2014) discuss the potential for planners to bring about progressive outcomes in a neoliberal world. They assert that the motivation for planners is to change the world for the better and ask: “Must planning surrender to free market agendas or might there be ways to resist this reductionist but totalizing position?” (Campbell et al. 2014: 45). They argue that an ideally just city constitutes an overly rigid and unattainable goal but that seeking a better—that is, more just—city is achievable. Therefore, planners need to push the boundaries of the possible (Campbell et al. 2014: 56). If they must compromise, their compromises should be principled; it is in silence that they betray their aspirations. My critique of communicative planning does not dismiss the value of democratic participation, which is in itself an element of spatial justice. At the same time, however, it incorporates the arguments that have been made since the time of Aristotle regarding the flaws of democracy: demagogues might mislead the public; ordinary people might lack the necessary expertise or simply the time to understand complicated issues; it is not possible for all interests to be represented in large, pluralistic polities. What we can say positively about institutionalized citizen participation and deliberation is that bringing together affected publics increases the information available to policy-makers by providing local knowledge (Corburn 2005). Further, by causing decision making to be more democratic and open, it legitimates its outcomes. Although it can lead to parochialism and corruption, in that respect it might not be any more dangerous than traditional modes of governance. It is rarely transformative, but it does provide a training ground for developing leadership skills and popular education. The important point is to recognize that fostering participation will not in itself produce just results and that, in a society with unequal power, it can work against the realization of equity and diversity.

The Potential for Reform under Capitalism Within the left the possibility of achieving greater equity within global capitalism has been subject to disagreement since the nineteenth century. Marxists deny that genuine progress can be made under capitalism. In criticizing my concept of the just city David Harvey argues: From the start, it [the concept of the just city] delimits its scope to acting within the existing capitalist régime of rights and freedoms and is thus constrained to mitigating the worst outcomes at the margins of an unjust city. (Harvey with Potter 2009: 46) 135

Susan S. Fainstein

My response is that continued pressure for justice can cause the system to change incrementally. Furthermore, planners necessarily deal with decisions that have the potential to do harm, as has happened often in the past—so simply mitigating these outcomes is progress. Even though planners acting alone cannot force change, they remain the only people expressly charged with governing spatial development and can cause issues to be reframed in ways that give justice prominence (Storper 2013). More humane policies for urban redevelopment, open space, transportation investment, and housing supply can improve the lives of people in the here and now. Waiting for the demise of capitalism postpones moving toward justice in the present and at any rate is not an inevitable event. One aspect of the debate about creating more just cities derives from an assessment of existing cities. In The Just City I named Amsterdam as approaching an ideal of justice, but more recently Amsterdam has retreated from its earlier commitment to social housing and high levels of welfare and committed itself to the precepts of neoliberalism (Uitermark 2009). Novy and Mayer (2009) dispute my identification of the social democratic cities of northern Europe as models and contend that Latin America might be a better place to look, although there too more recent events make their evaluation problematic. From this discussion we can perhaps distill a few truths: European social democracy once presented at least a rough model of spatial justice; such models are not static; and a combination of globalization, immigration, and neoliberal policies can cause them to break down (see Kuttner 2015).

Diversity and Justice Many critics of Rawls and other liberal theorists of justice have asserted that they fail to take group affiliations and gender biases into account.4 Iris Marion Young (1990: 47), who reacts against both liberal individualism and Marxist reductionism of injustice to class oppression, has framed her objection as follows: “I believe that group differentiation is both an inevitable and a desirable aspect of modern social processes. Social justice . . . requires not the melting away of differences, but institutions that promote reproduction of and respect for group differences without oppression.” Under this conception the argument for justice shifts from a fair distribution to “social differentiation without exclusion” (Young 1990: 238). A further objection to much of liberal thought arises from a feminist viewpoint that regards the concepts of reason and rights, defended by theorists ranging from Locke to J.S. Mill to Rawls, as based on a masculinist conception of adversarial democracy. This body of theory, it is argued, universalizes the standpoint of white males, values disputation, and defines interests solely in selfish terms (Mansbridge 1990; Held 1990). As used within planning the term diversity has a variety of meanings. Among urban designers it refers to mixing building types; among land-use planners it can mean mixed uses or class and racial-ethnic heterogeneity in a housing development or a public space. During the 1960s, advocates of physical and social heterogeneity constituted dissident voices against the prevailing doctrine of functional zoning and homogeneity. Most influential among them within the discipline of planning was Jane Jacobs, whose call for a cityscape based on multiple uses resonated widely. She (1961: 14) argued that physical heterogeneity would promote economic and social diversity: One principle emerges … ubiquitously, and in so many and such complex different forms [that] … it becomes the heart of my argument. This ubiquitous principle is the need of cities for a most intricate and close-grained diversity of uses that give each other constant mutual support, both economically and socially. 136

Urban Planning and Social Justice

Her reasoning anticipated the widely publicized argument of Richard Florida (2002: 30), who asserted that urban diversity stimulates creativity, which in turn causes economic growth. Neither Jacobs nor Florida were basing their observations on a justice-based critique, but their concern with the relation between spatial development and social diversity was consonant with emphases among philosophers and sociologists on recognition of the other. The planning theorist Leonie Sandercock (1998) terms her ideal city Cosmopolis. Like Iris Marion Young she links recognition of the other with justice. She describes a metropolis that allows people from a variety of ethnic and racial backgrounds equal rights to city space. The diversity she praises is not the local color appealing to Jane Jacobs and creative class cosmopolitans but rather the one captured by Lefebvre’s phrase “the right to the city.” It refers to the inclusion of all city users within the space of the city, regardless of their cultural differences. Still, despite the seeming unanimity of urban theorists on the merits of diversity, they differ substantially concerning the kinds of environments planners should aim to produce—and how and whether conscious planning can create them. Planned communities designed with the goal of diversity, whether within inner cities or in new-urbanist or neo-traditional greenfield developments, seem inevitably to attract accusations of inauthenticity, of being simulacra rather than the real thing. Thus, planners appear caught in an insoluble dilemma—either leave the market to take its course or impose an oxymoronic diverse order. Although in the past market-driven development produced highly differentiated landscapes as a consequence of local custom, small-plot ownership, minimal regulation, and incremental development, today’s large developers, enmeshed within a globalized architectural and property market, build on a grand scale and in each new project repeat the successful formulas of everywhere else. The paradox is that the internally diverse character of festival marketplaces, entertainment districts, and live/work environments replicates itself, so that places lose their individuality just as much as had been the case under high modernism. The relationship between diversity and equity as components of justice is not straightforward. Richard Florida’s (2002) argument, referred to above, finds a happy reconciliation between the values of economic growth and social diversity. Thus, diversity, until recently a value associated more with politically left cultural critics than pro-growth coalitions, has become a mantra for public officials aiming at fostering urban resurgence. Florida, however, is misinterpreted if he is taken to imply that diversity promotes equity as well as growth. He explicitly states: While the Creative Class favors openness and diversity, to some degree it is a diversity of elites, limited to highly educated, creative people. Even though the rise of the Creative Class has opened up new avenues of advancement for women and members of ethnic minorities, its existence has certainly failed to put an end to long-standing divisions of race and gender. (Florida 2002: 80) He could have added that it not only has failed to end racial and gender divisions, but it has seemingly exacerbated income inequality. Demands for diversity are particularly controversial in relation to policies for inclusionary housing and zoning. Requiring housing in any area to encompass a broad income range and forbidding discrimination on the basis of race, ethnicity, or disability constitute standards conducive to justice. However, requiring people to move against their will in order to achieve racial balance or dispersion of poverty is counterproductive and an infringement on liberty (Goetz 2003). Furthermore, if neighborhoods become diverse as a consequence of gentrification, then the remaining low-income residents might lose their sense of ownership of the area even if they receive improved service (Freeman 2006). 137

Susan S. Fainstein

The touchiest and most difficult aspect of the question of forcing diversity comes in terms of requiring exclusionary places to welcome people who are different. Supporters of increased diversity are made uncomfortable by the seeming irreconcilability of community and diversity. Peter Marcuse (2002: 111) tries to overcome the difficulty by distinguishing between ghettoes and enclaves: ghettoes are involuntary spatial concentrations of a particular population group, while enclaves are voluntary and promote economic, social, political, and cultural development. When the enclave cluster is an ethnic minority or gender-identified group seeking to protect its way of life or overcome disadvantage, the term has a positive spin. In fact, by offering sanctuaries for cultural difference, enclaves, while being homogeneous in the micro, contribute to diversity at the metropolitan level. Citadels, on the other hand, defined as exclusionary areas dominated by the privileged, conform to Harvey’s negative characterization of community as “one of the key sites of social control and surveillance, bordering on overt social repression” (Harvey 1997: 1). Thus, urban neighborhoods characterized by lack of diversity might or might not contribute to greater justice, depending on their contribution to equity and culture. In sum, diversity as a planning doctrine reflects an aspirational goal; at the same time the desirability of pressing for it depends very much on the process by which it is achieved and the class and racial/ethnic context in which it operates.

Environmentalism and Equity Planners have always tried to regulate the physical environment, preserve nature, and promote health through limiting air and water pollution. Over the years the aims of the environmental movement have broadened and, beginning in the 1960s, taken on a new militancy. Critics of the mainstream environmental movement, however, charge that its middle-class social basis makes it oblivious to questions of equity. They charge that protection of pristine environments or forbidding high-density development is rationalized in the name of ecology, but functions to exclude housing affordable to low-income people. These critics have also reframed questions of the placement of undesirable land uses in terms of environmental justice (Harvey 1996) and have sought to incorporate equity into definitions of sustainability. The concern with justice is reflected in the aims developed by the UN’s Brundtland Commission: “Sustainable development is development that meets the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs.” For those in the environmental justice movement, meeting “needs” includes fulfilling the basic necessities of food, housing, and income as well as protecting the neighborhoods of vulnerable populations from polluting sources. The term, however, is ambiguous. For mainstream environmentalists it primarily refers to preservation of natural areas and other species. For right-wing governments, it refers to stimulating economic growth so that prosperity will trickle down to the less fortunate. In the last decade allusions to sustainability have receded, and they have been replaced by references to “resilience” (Davoudi 2012; Gleeson 2014; Fainstein 2015). Prompted by earthquakes, tsunamis, highly destructive hurricanes, and the expectation of global warming, advocates for making places resilient argue for adapting to changed circumstances rather than simply attempting to prevent disasters from occurring. In built-up districts resilience requires restoring wetlands so that water will have somewhere to go under flood conditions. In rural areas it means removing houses in areas where forest fires are a danger. In low-income countries it leads to forced rural to urban migration as fields become deserts. Like sustainability, use of the term resilience connotes ambiguity. The question immediately arises: whose homes will be removed? To the extent that low-income households occupy the areas most susceptible to damage, they are the ones likely to face displacement and rarely receive adequate compensation. 138

Urban Planning and Social Justice

Environmentalism in its various guises of planning for preservation, sustainability, and resilience, is generally considered a progressive force. Within the United States it tends to be opposed by business interests invested in natural resources, by property developers who wish to proceed unrestricted, and by right-wing politicians. Within developing countries opponents consider that it limits the possibilities for economic growth. Yet it is frequently in contradiction to demands for justice and can be used to block redistributive measures. A just environmentalism requires spatial planning that avoids placing environmental hazards where land is cheapest if the outcome is to jeopardize the health of impoverished groups. It further calls for investments in open space that benefit low-income communities and, in cases where households must move to create buffers against water or fire, then they need to be fairly compensated and, if possible, relocated en bloc.

What Can Be Done? As discussed above, the disagreement as to whether or not just policies can be achieved without structural transformation is a persistent one. Comparison of different places does, however, point to situations where groups at the bottom of the economic structure enjoy greater amenities than in other locations. While planning for spatial justice cannot overcome economic inequality, it can provide lower-income populations with a higher quality of life than would otherwise be the case. This is particularly true for housing, transportation, and public space provision. In this respect Singapore provides a useful example. Although Singapore is capitalist, has enjoyed a high rate of economic growth, encourages competitive markets, and promotes foreign investment, it insures that certain economic sectors are insulated from market pressures. Most of the permanent population (85 percent) lives in public housing. Families buy their units and may resell them, but the government subsidizes the buildings and regulates supply to insure that resale prices do not rise too much. The three major ethnic groups of the nation (Chinese, Malay, and Indian) are housed in each building proportional to their percentage of the total population, thereby preventing ethnic segregation. Buildings are high-rise and clustered around establishments that provide all the services needed for daily life. A highly efficient, cheap public transit system connects all the housing developments to the central business district. Automobile travel is minimized through using a combination of tariffs, licensing fees, and congestion pricing to make car ownership and operation very expensive. Although this reserves automobile transport for the elite and thus arguably creates a highly privileged stratum, it has a redistributional effect since the wealthy are heavily taxed for their privilege. Singapore’s government is formally democratic in the sense that it has a two-party system with free and fair elections, and the government is sensitive to public opinion. Given the very high proportion of the electorate that votes for the dominant People’s Action Party (PAP) (70 percent in the 2015 election), the ruling elite apparently enjoys considerable legitimacy. At the same time, compared to cities within Western democracies, Singapore has very limited public participation: critics of the government can be sued for libel; public demonstrations are generally not allowed (there is, however, a yearly gay parade despite homosexuality being nominally illegal); the local media are mostly spokespersons for the government, although Internet access is not restricted. The most egregious deviation from justice lies in the treatment of foreign contract workers; they have no civil rights, may not bring in their families, are subject to arbitrary dismissal, have few days off, and mostly live in undesirable conditions. An overall assessment of Singapore would consider that it does excellent planning; that it provides all citizens and permanent residents a reasonably high quality of life in terms of access to amenities and good housing even though it has high levels of income inequality; and that it 139

Susan S. Fainstein

maintains ethnic peace in a part of the world where ethnic frictions are high. To the extent that democracy is a component of justice, it is clearly lacking; on the other hand, its meritocratic and authoritarian form of government makes consistent, long-range planning possible, and much of that planning provides benefits to the entire population. Even foreign workers have access to exceptional parks, potable water, clean air, and, as a result of recent initiatives, recreational facilities. Key to Singapore’s ability to do good planning is public ownership of most of the land within the city’s boundaries. This enables the government to build public housing when and where it chooses, to preserve rights-of-way for transit development, and to reserve large tracts for parks and recreation. Land banking has thus been enabling, and it offers an important means by which governments can enforce more equitable uses of space. Nevertheless, it alone is not sufficient to guarantee an activist state that will use its resources to create wide benefits. Amsterdam and Stockholm are other cities with substantial public land ownership. Until this century their governments used their holdings to develop considerable amounts of social housing. Recently, however, they have been privatizing the housing stock and retreating from their previous commitments. These examples show that planning for broad benefits requires continued dedication to principles of justice as well as the power to enforce a fair distribution. These brief comparisons illustrate the tensions among the various principles of justice. Very likely if Singapore were more democratic, it might have less income inequality and not rely on cheap foreign labor to work in the least desirable employment categories. At the same time it might be more susceptible to corruption and ethnic antagonism within the citizen population. Moreover, there are far more examples of authoritarian states that are corrupt and do not do exemplary planning, so Singapore is anomalous (Huat 2011). It does, however, show the possibility of using spatial planning within a predominantly capitalist system to implement policies for diversity and equity. Reforms that promote justice can be achieved within democratic capitalist political economies when popular movements back progressive leadership. This outcome depends on the development of programs for redistribution, allegiances that cut across differences based on ascriptive characteristics such as race and gender identity while also recognizing difference, and which respond to the desires of ordinary people. It requires countering the demagoguery of populist leadership that plays on exclusionism, establishes justice rather than growth as the first priority of policy, and encourages planning for equity and improvements in the quality of life even if radical redistribution is not a possibility. The principles of democracy, diversity, and equity are in tension and involve trade-offs. In the ideal case democratic participation is benignly supportive of the other two values; but as we are seeing in both Europe and the United States it is frighteningly easy to arouse populist anger against outsiders and to blame deprivation on lower social strata.

Notes 1 Parts of this chapter are drawn from my book The Just City (2010). 2 The basis for this definition is developed at length in Fainstein (2010). 3 This book was initially written in German and published in Holland. The English-language edition appeared later in 1940 when it was substantially revised and enlarged by the author. 4 Rawls in his later work attempted to incorporate the issue of difference (see Rawls 2001: 64–66).

References Altshuler, A.A. (1970) Community Control. New York: Pegasus. —— (1965) The City Planning Process. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

140

Urban Planning and Social Justice Arnstein, S.R. (1969) “A Ladder of Citizen Participation,” Journal of the American Planning Association, 35 (4): 216–24. Brooks, M.P. (2002) Planning Theory for Practitioners. Chicago: Planners Press. Campbell, H. and S.S. Fainstein (2012) “Justice, Urban Politics, and Policy,” pp. 545–66 in S. Clarke et al. eds., Oxford Handbook of Urban Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Campbell, H. and Robert Marshall (2006) “Towards Justice in Planning: A Reappraisal,” European Planning Studies, 14 (2): 239–52. Campbell, H., M. Tait, and C. Watkins (2014) “Is There Space for Better Planning in a Neoliberal World? Implications for Planning Practice and Theory,” Journal of Planning Education and Research, 34 (1): 45–59. Campbell, S. (1996) “Green Cities, Growing Cities, Just Cities? Urban Planning and the Contradictions of Sustainable Development,” Journal of the American Planning Association, 62 (3): 296–312. Castells, M. (1977) The Urban Question. Cambridge: MIT Press. Clavel, P. (1986) The Progressive City: Planning and Participation, 1969–1984. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Corburn, J. (2005) Street Science. Cambridge: MIT Press. Davoudi, S. (2012) Resilience: A Bridging Concept or a Dead End? Planning Theory & Practice, 13 (2): 299–307. Dear, M. and A.J. Scott (eds.) (1981) Urbanization and Urban Planning in Capitalist Society. London: Routledge Kegan & Paul. Fainstein, N., and S.S. Fainstein (2013) “Restoring Just Outcomes to Planning Concerns,” pp. 32–53 in N. Carmon and S.S. Fainstein, eds., Policy, Planning, and People: Promoting Justice in Urban Development. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Fainstein, S.S. (2015) Resilience and Justice, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 39 (1): 157–67. —— (2010) The Just City, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. —— (2000) “New Directions in Planning Theory,” Urban Affairs Review, 35 (4): 451–78. —— (1999) “Can We Make the Cities We Want?” pp. 249–72 in S. Body-Gendrot and R. Beauregard eds., The Urban Moment. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. —— and N. Fainstein (1979) “New Debates in Urban Planning: the Impact of Marxist Theory in the United States,” International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 3: 381–403. —— and —— (1974) Urban Political Movements. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. —— and —— (1971) “City Planning and Political Values,” Urban Affairs Quarterly, 6: 341–62. Florida, R.L. (2002) The Rise of the Creative Class. New York: Basic Books. Flyvbjerg, B., N. Bruzelius, and W. Rothengatter (2003) Megaprojects and Risk. New York: Cambridge University Press. Foglesong, R. (1986) Planning the Capitalist City. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Forester, J. (1993) Critical Theory, Public Policy, and Planning Practice: Toward a Critical Pragmatism. Albany: State University of New York Press. Freeman, L. (2006) There Goes the ’Hood. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Friedmann, J. (2011) Insurgencies: Essays in Planning Theory. New York: Routledge. Gleeson, B. (2014) “Disasters, Vulnerability and Resilience of Cities,” pp.  10–23 in M. Hodson and S. Marvin, eds., After Sustainable Cities? London: Routledge. Goetz, E.G. (2003) Clearing the Way. Washington, DC: Urban Institute Press. Hall, P. (2002) Cities of Tomorrow, 3rd edition. Oxford: Blackwell. Harvey, D. ( 2005) A Brief History of Neoliberalism. New York: Oxford University Press. —— (2003) “The Right to the City,” International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 27 (4): 939–41. —— (1997) “The New Urbanism and the Communitarian Trap: On Social Problems and the False Hope of Design,” Harvard Design Mazazine, No. 1: 1–3. —— (1996) Justice, Nature and the Geography of Difference. Oxford: Blackwell. —— (1989) “From Managerialism to Entrepreneurialism: The Transformation in Urban Governance in Late Capitalism,” Geografiska Annaler. Series B, Human Geography, 71 (1): 3–17. —— (1973) Social Justice and the City. London: Edward Arnold. —— (1978) “On Planning the Ideology of Planning,” pp.  213–33 in R. Burchell and G. Sternlieb, eds., Planning Theory in the 1980s. New Brunswick, NJ: Center for Urban Policy Research, Rutgers University. Harvey, D. with C. Potter (2009) “The Right to the Just City,” pp. 40–51 in P. Marcuse, J. Connolly, J. Novy, I. Olivo, C. Potter, and J. Steil, eds., Searching for the Just City. New York: Routledge.

141

Susan S. Fainstein Healey, P. (2006) Collaborative Planning: Shaping Places in Fragmented Societies, 2nd edition. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. Held, V. (1990) “Mothering versus Contract,” pp. 287–304 in J.J. Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hoffman, L.M. (1989) The Politics of Knowledge. Albany: SUNY Press. Huat, C.-B. (2011) “Singapore as Model: Planning Innovations, Knowledge Experts,” pp.  29–54 in A. Roy and A. Ong, eds., Worlding Cities: Asian Experiments and the Art of Being Global. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. Huxley, M. and O. Yiftachel (2000) “New Paradigm or Old Myopia? Unsettling the Communicative Turn in Planning Theory,” Journal of Planning Education and Research 19 (4): 333–42. Jacobs, J. (1961) Death and Life of Great American Cities. New York: Random House. Jamala, T. and B.A. Camargob (2014) Sustainable Tourism, Justice and an Ethic of Care: Toward the Just Destination, Journal of Sustainable Tourism 22 (1): 11–30. Krumholz, N. and J. Forester (1990) Making Equity Planning Work. Philadelphia, PN: Temple University Press. Kuttner, R. (2015) “The European Prospect,” The American Prospect 26 (4): 5–6. Lefebvre, H. (1996) “The Right to the City,” pp. 147–60 in Writings on Cities, trans. by E. Kofman and E. Lebas. Oxford: Blackwell. —— (1991) The Production of Space, trans. by Donald Nicholson-Smith. Oxford: Blackwell. Lindblom, C.E. (1959) “The Science of ‘Muddling Through’,” Public Administration Review, 19 (2): 79–88. Low, N. and B. Gleeson (1998) Justice, Society and Nature. London: Routledge. Mannheim, K. (1940) Man and Society in an Age of Reconstruction. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World. Mansbridge, J.J. (1990) “The Rise and Fall of Self-Interest in the Explanation of Political Life,” pp. 3–11 in J.J. Mansbridge, ed., Beyond Self-Interest. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Marcuse, P. (2002) “The Shifting Meaning of the Black Ghetto in the United States,” pp.  109–42 in P. Marcuse and R. van Kempen, eds., Of States and Cities. New York: Oxford University Press. ——, J. Connolly, J. Novy, I. Olivo, C. Potter, and J. Steil (eds.) (2009) Searching for the Just City. New York: Routledge. Mitchell, D. (2003) The Right to the City. New York: Guilford. Novy, J. and M. Mayer (2009) “As ‘Just’ as It Gets: The European City in the ‘Just City’ Discourse,” pp. 103–19 in P. Marcuse, J. Connolly, J. Novy, I. Olivo, C. Potter, and J. Steil (eds.) Searching for the Just City. New York: Routledge. Nussbaum, M.C. (2000) Women and Human Development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. —— (2006) Frontiers of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Purcell, M. (2008) Recapturing Democracy. New York: Routledge. Rawls, J. (2001) Justice as Fairness, edited by E. Kelly. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rousseau, J.J. (1992; orig. pub. 1755) Discourse on the Origin of Inequality. Trans. Donald A. Cress. Hackett Publishing. Sandel, M.J. (2009) Justice. New York: Ferrar, Straus, and Giroux. Sandercock, Leonie (1998) Towards Cosmopolis: Planning for Multicultural Cities. New York: John Wiley. Sayer, A. and M. Storper (1997) “Ethics Unbound: For a Normative Turn in Social Theory,” Environment and Planning D: Society and Space, 15 (1): 1–18. Smith, N. (1979) “Toward a Theory of Gentrification: A Back to the City Movement by Capital, Not People,” Journal of the American Planning Association, 45 (4): 538–48. Soja, E.W. (2010) Seeking Spatial Justice. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Storper, M. (2013) “Review of P. Marcuse, J. Connolly, J. Novy, I. Olivo, C. Potter, and J. Steil (eds.) (2009) Searching for the Just City,” Planning Theory, 12 (2): 215–19. Uitermark, J. (2009) “An In Memoriam for the Just City of Amsterdam,” City, 13 (2–3): 347–61. Young, I.M. (1990) Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

142

12 THE GRASSROOTS OF PLANNING Poor People’s Movements, Political Society, and the Question of Rights Ananya Roy

We are not the grassroots of the city; we are its poisoned soil. (Carolina Gaete, Blocks Together, Chicago, 2015)

On a blustery April day in Chicago, I met with Carolina Gaete at Blocks Together, a community action organization on the west side of Chicago. Its entrance barely visible on a bleak street, with roaring traffic cutting through the neighborhood, the offices of Blocks Together were filled with sunlight, festooned with photographs and posters, and anchored by two dynamic women leaders. I had been introduced to Carolina by Willie (JR) Fleming, the charismatic co-founder of the Chicago Anti-Eviction Campaign, a radical urban social movement that challenges foreclosures and evictions on the south side of Chicago. Drawing inspiration from the Western Cape Anti-Eviction Campaign which once led struggles against evictions and service disconnections in Cape Town, South Africa, the Chicago Anti-Eviction Campaign has a repertoire of tactics of resistance and militancy, from eviction blockades to the occupation of foreclosed homes. At first glance, Blocks Together has a somewhat different agenda of action, seeking to intervene in the city’s urban planning processes through participatory budgeting and pushing for community benefit agreements in relation to tax increment finance funds. But as in the case of the Chicago Anti-Eviction Campaign, it frames its work “through the lens of racial justice and human rights,” and is keenly aware of the global and historical context of such frameworks. When Blocks Together deploys the idea of community, it means, of course, that it is a membership-based organization. But it also means that such community is formed through a long history of racial exclusion, spatialized oppression, and repeated displacement. It is thus that as we sat and talked at a table filled with posters of campaigns and rallies, with the sun streaming in through the glass blocks that made up the street front of the office, Carolina insisted: “We are not the grassroots of the city; we are its poisoned soil.” In this essay, I draw inspiration from this brief moment in Chicago with Carolina to frame an argument about the city and the grassroots. While such a frame refers to the important contributions of Manuel Castells to urban and planning theory, I broaden the discussion to signal how postcolonial and poststructuralist theory makes possible new understandings of the relationship 143

Ananya Roy

between the urban and the political. In doing so, I seek to reorient planning theory, shifting emphasis from the ubiquitous frame of the “right to the city” to other concepts and debates. I undertake such reorientation for three reasons. First, it is my contention that the theoretical dominance of the “right to the city,” and the attendant reliance on Lefebvrian thought, occludes other modes and meanings of spatial politics, be it those concerned with racial justice or those evoking human rights or those negotiating claims through political society. Second, while the “right to the city” has global purchase, and has its most well-developed institutional form in Brazil, as a theoretical genre in urban and planning theory, it tends to ignore what Chatterjee (2006) has called “popular politics in most of the world.” In this essay, rather than undertake a survey of the literature on such popular politics, I foreground a few significant lines of inquiry that emerge from the urban experience of the global South, that put forward conceptual frameworks related to urban citizenship, political society, poor people’s movements, and the figure of the human, and that have direct relevance for planning theory. Third, I pinpoint Castells rather than Lefebvre as the starting point for this essay because I wish to emphasize the importance of a theory of the state for an analytics of planning and politics. In his early work, notably The City and the Grassroots (1983), Castells gives us a theory of the state that is also necessarily a theory of the city. To take account of the state is to once again trouble EuroAmerican genealogies of thought, in particular the reliance on an experience of austerity urbanism rooted in the context of the global North. Whether enacting market rule or not, the state is a prominent force in many parts of the world, and it is often in relationship to the state that a politics of claimsmaking and rights-talk is fought and legislated. This essay hopes to illuminate the conceptual vocabularies that are attentive to such geographies and conjunctures.

A Theory of the City In a scarcely known working paper buried in the library at the University of California, Berkeley, Manuel Castells (1985) reflects on the shift in his work from the seminal, The Urban Question (1977), to the magisterial, The City and the Grassroots. Castells (1985: 1) notes that in the latter, “there is a theory of urban social change as part of a theory of the city.” In particular, he pinpoints urban social movements as a key force in urban social change. But he seeks to broaden the analysis of urban social movements. He argues that while this is “purposive collective action,” it “comes from a plurality of sources and not just one” (Castells 1985: 2, 3). Indeed, such action is not solely concerned with collective consumption, the emphasis of Castells’s early work. Castells (1985: 3) asserts that The City and the Grassroots widens the discussion to consider urban social movements that connect “three dimensions . . . collective consumption . . . political selfmanagement . . . and . . . cultural identity.” Castells (1985: 4) further argues that these urban social movements have “consciousness as citizen movements and not just a derivation from class or other types of movements.” In putting forward such a formulation, Castells (1985: 11) valiantly reflects on theoretical legacies, arguing that for him “Marxist theory is . . . one source of theoretical work among many others,” that it is “blind to some major issues, for instance, feminism and with an inability to understand some key elements like culture, specific political apparatuses etc.” Castells’s work, especially The City and the Grassroots, has had a profoundly important influence in urban studies and planning. It inspired several new generations of theorization concerned with the “grassroots” of the city. It also made possible the conceptual imagination of what Andrew Merrifield (2014: xi) calls a “new political subject,” specifically urban social movements. Of course, there is the question of how Castells’ writings, including his seminal book, The Urban Question, published in 1972, relates to other lines of thought in urban studies. 144

The Grassroots of Planning

Gottdiener (1993: 130) argues that both Castells and Harvey “owe an immense, unacknow­ ledged debt to Lefebvre.” In contrast, Keil (2003: 725) notes that Castells “was at great pains to distance himself from any attempt to save both the city/urban as a distinct object of critical urban research” and thus rejected “the specific brand of Marxism associated with Lefebvre.” Indeed, while Castells sought to “spatialize Althusserian structuralism” by identifying the “functional specificity of the urban,” a broad set of writings were to soon explore “the production of space and spatial configuration under capitalism” (Brenner 2000: 363, 365). The translation of Lefebvre’s writings into English in the early 1990s positioned his work as the main anchor in such concerns. However, in this essay, I return to The City and the Grassroots to draw out a conceptual theme that has received less attention in the urban and planning theory debates: the theory of the state. Castells (1985: 8) notes that the theory of the state that underlines CGR sees the state as the crystallization of class and other social struggles, that is both of processes of dominance of certain classes and groups and genders but also as the expression of the process of resistance to dominance by classes and social groups and genders. This is indeed an important shift in Castells’s work, notably from The Urban Question to The City and the Grassroots. But whether it is collective consumption or some other vector of struggle, the state remains central to the figuration of urban social movements. Put another way, in Castells’ formulation, it is in relation to the state that social change is articulated and enacted. I find this to be an important provocation, one that is valuable for planning theory and one that requires continued theorization of the specific role of planning in processes of social change.

Urban Citizens The relationship between the urban and the political is a matter of long-standing debate in urban studies. While Castells draws our attention to urban social movements, urban theorists have also relied on the ideas of Henri Lefebvre to conceptualize the urban as the site of the political, particularly in the making of forms of life and meaning. This, for Merrifield (2014: 69), is the “new urban question,” how the “complete urbanization society” yields “an urban political movement [not social] that struggles for generalized democracy, that organizes a concerted insurrection” (emphasis in the original). Most boldly, in the arguments of Warren Magnusson (2011: 34), the urban becomes a political ontology, “a particular way of being political.” In my recent essay, “What is Urban about Critical Urban Theory?” I challenge the equivalence of the urban and the political, as I also challenge the claim of a “complete urbanization society” (Roy 2015). I suggest that we take up the question of whether the urban is a particular way of being political as precisely this, a question, rather than an ontological truth. In addition, I argue that it is worth considering how the urban is constituted and lived as a governmental category. In the remainder of this essay, I foreground conceptual frameworks that provide insights into the urban as a governmental category and that thereby return us to that oft-ignored aspect of The City and the Grassroots, the theory of the city in relation to the theory of the state. Nikolas Rose (2013: 95) reminds us that “the city, for at least two centuries, has been both a problem for government and a permanent incitement to government.” Rose’s (2013: 98) analysis of “advanced liberalism” demonstrates how “the activation of the powers of the citizen” is entangled with ways of governing cities. I find this to be a useful way of approaching urban citizenship, but only if we are willing to extend his argument. While Rose notes that this has 145

Ananya Roy

been the case for “at least two centuries,” thinking outside and beyond the West might require posing the formulation as a question rather than a declaration: at what historical moment does the governing of cities become vitally important for the governing of citizens? When formulated thus, this concern with urban government bears resonance with Chatterjee’s (2006) concept of political society. As is now well known, in his conceptualization of the “politics of the governed,” Chatterjee makes a distinction between “civil society” and “political society.” Civil society is an arena of institutions and practices inhabited by a relatively small section of people able to make claims as fully enfranchised citizens. By contrast, political society is the constellation of claims made by those who are only tenuously and ambiguously right-bearing citizens. For Chatterjee, the “paralegal” practices and negotiations of political society is the politics of much of the people in most of the world: “The paralegal then, despite its ambiguous and supplementary status in relation to the legal, is not some pathological condition of retarded modernity, but rather part of the very process of the historical constitution of modernity in most of the world” (Chatterjee 2006: 75). More recently, Chatterjee (2012: 46–7) has emphasized the “deepening and widening of the apparatuses of governmentality,” to how “the activities of the government have penetrated deep into the everyday lives of rural people,” and to the “constant tussles of different population groups with the authorities over the distribution of governmental services.” I draw attention to this expanded formulation because it explicitly links the politics of the governed with modes of governing. While Chatterjee does not tell us much about urban government, his reflection provokes the following questions: Is there a distinctive “politics of the governed” that is at work in the realm of the urban? What is the relationship between such politics and what, following Rose, can we conceptualize as the city as “a problem for government”? I take up these questions in relation to two examples, one drawn from the urban studies debates and one drawn from my recent research. In a series of arguments, Holston (2007), and more recently Caldeira and Holston (2015), have made the case for urban citizenship in Brazil. Theirs is not a formulation of an essential ontology, the urban as a necessarily political identity and identification. Instead, it is a careful argument about historical conjuncture and the activation of citizenship. Caldeira and Holston (2015) trace the history of democratization in Brazil noting that “insurgent citizenship movements” were a vitally important part of this transition. And such forms of citizenship were urban, emerging in the auto-constructed peripheries of Brazilian cities and shaped “not primarily through the struggles of labor but through those of the city” (Holston 2007). Urban residents built homes and neighborhoods “brick by brick” and also organized to “fight for housing, property, infrastructure and services . . . in other words, for the right to the cities they were making” (Caldeira and Holston 2015: 2002). In fact, Caldeira and Holston (2015) go one step further in their argument, noting that the institutional form of such citizenship was also indelibly shaped by the urban experience. The main mark of this democratisation was … the explosion of popular participation in urban social movements, neighbourhood associations, trade unions and political parties. It was the invention inside of these organisations of new forms of citizen participation itself that … established the importance of text-based rights and innovative legislation in democratic struggles. (Caldeira and Holston 2015: 2002) What we have here is the imbrication of city, citizenship, and state. That imbrication is neither a relationship of equivalence nor of ontological necessity. Instead, it is conjunctural and contingent. My call to consider the urban as a governmental category is also then a call to craft a 146

The Grassroots of Planning

conceptual framework attentive to conjuncture and contingency in the contemplation of the relationship between the urban and the political. Under what historical conditions does the urban become the terrain of government and the territory of politics? Caldeira and Holston’s (2015) analysis of urban citizenship in Brazil suggests that the process of democratization, intertwined as it was with the making of urban peripheries, produced distinctive modes of governing the city, most recently participatory urban planning. In my recent research, I take up a related inquiry, focusing on how “inclusive growth,” as a new mode of governing in India, is activating urban local government and urban citizenship (Roy 2013). In India, the start of the new century has been marked by the launch of ambitious national programs of urban modernization and urban governance. If in a previous era of development, the building of infrastructure was the enterprise of building the nation – dams, highways, electricity grids, water systems – then today the city is the site of infrastructural interventions. Urban infrastructure is also the conduit of “reform,” a broad term that includes both economic reforms and the recalibration of systems of governance, notably building and strengthening institutions of local democracy. While the 74th Constitutional Amendment of 1992 created the urban local body as the instrument of urban governance, it is not until the recent proliferation of these national programs and policies that municipal governments have had significant urban planning functions. In particular, slum upgrading initiatives have recast the relationship between city and slum from that between sovereign and encroacher to that between government and beneficiary. It is urban local government that mediates this relationship and that allows the urban poor (more appropriately understood as the rural-urban poor) to stake claims and register complaints as beneficiaries. In fact, my research indicates that each tranche of programs engenders a new repertoire of claims and complaints, managed and negotiated by both local politicians and municipal officers. It is worth noting that the urban politics at work here is not the insurgent citizenship of which Caldeira and Holston write. There are no rights-based social movements, no street politics of occupation and squatting, no auto-constructed peripheries. Instead, there are self-styled beneficiaries, keenly aware of the nature of benefits and the scope of government programs. But it is through this collection of beneficiaries that the urban comes to take shape as a governmental category. Such processes engender a supplemental question: who constitutes urban local government? Needless to say, local political elites play an important role in the distribution of infrastructure and services. This is a familiar story in many parts of the world. But my research indicates that what is much more interesting and much less predictable is the role of local urban planners. I use this term in two ways: to pinpoint those municipal positions that are named as such and thus are seemingly committed to urban planning, and to extend the term to the much broader ambit of planning tasks, which includes municipal engineers and technical assistance consultants. The provision of infrastructure and services, the creation of plans, the shaping of municipal budget allocations takes place in this broader ambit, through the involvement of numerous actors, but especially through a municipal cadre of urban planners. In West Bengal, where I conducted my research, they produce the plans and documents demanded by successive rounds of national government programs. They supervise the unending surveys. They fuss over the social and spatial distribution of benefits. They map and analyze land tenure arrangements. Whether or not they intended this to be the case, they have become keepers of the 74th Constitutional Amendment. They, in dispersed fashion, constitute the state and its relationship to urban citizenship. But in providing these two examples of urban citizenship, I do not mean to suggest that urban planning always serves as the conduit for redistributive policies or that the urban poor are always able to claim the right to the cities they make through their labor and spatial practice. 147

Ananya Roy

Instead, I am interested in the contingent nature of such conduits and claims and how a theory of the city, that is also necessarily a theory of the state, might account for such contingency. As Watson (2012: 8) notes, in various contexts, such as Brazil and South Africa, “relatively progressive constitutions have conferred extensive citizenship rights, but in both countries major income inequalities have left lower income groups unable to realize them.” Rolnik (2013: 54) thus points out that while Brazil’s City Statute, as “an innovative national legal framework,” emerged from “a rights-based . . . urban reform movement,” its implementation has had to contend with a “market-driven competitive cities spatial regime paradigm.” And while Caldeira and Holston (2015) emphasize that insurgent citizenship movements, not electoral politics, was the hallmark of democratization, Rolnik (2013: 58) argues that the “political electoral game – and its connections to economic interests in urban development” largely shape urban policy in Brazilian cities. The City Statute, she concludes, has meaning but only when mobilized by urban social movements as a “form of resistance and litigation.” Rolnik’s (2013: 62) attention to the “litigation of rights” returns us to the “grassroots” of the city, to urban social movements and their role in shaping the city. In the following section of the essay, I analyze poor people’s movements as one instantiation of the relationship between the urban and the political.

Poor People’s Movements In their landmark book, Poor People’s Movements: Why they Succeed, How they Fail, Piven and Cloward (1977: x) call for a “dialectical analysis” of poor people’s movements, one in which they are understood to be “both formed by and directed against institutional arrangements.” Building on such an analytical approach, I am interested in how poor people’s movements are articulated in complex and contradictory ways with bureaucracies of poverty. The emphasis on poor people’s movements does not suggest that “poorness” is the sole or even dominant category, worldwide, of political mobilization. Nor are such movements necessarily urban. I foreground the question of poor people’s movements as a method of understanding the relationship between the urban and the political, and one with direct relevance for planning theory. In this conceptual realm, my own ethnographic and increasingly archival work pays attention to how radical practices of self-determination are often sutured with ideologies of self-help. For example, in the United States, during the 1960s, community action was rapidly transformed into programs of community development, especially those animated by the ethos of self-help. But in cities such as Oakland, the bureaucracy of poverty, notably War on Poverty programs, became the platform for radical visions and practices of self-determination, specifically by the Black Panther Party (Roy, Schrader, and Crane 2014). Piven and Cloward’s “dialectical analysis” is thus immensely useful in thinking about the “grassroots” of the city in relation to urban government. But it is also a provocation to think about the analytical and political category of the “poor” as a mode of organizing and governing. However, the term, poor people’s movements, can raise ire. At a recent conference in Brazil titled “Cities of the Global South and the Rest of the World,” scholars explicitly rejected that term, arguing that “poor” was a label imposed by the government, often marking the humiliating negotiation of welfare programs and their categories of eligibility. Social movements, they noted, did not organize on the basis of poorness. But as I have already indicated in the previous section, the term “poor” might be useful as an analytical category to mark the relationship between citizen and state, specifically the relationship between beneficiary and programs of government. Indeed, it this relationship – this negotiation of the category of “poor” – that might be the linchpin of postcolonial self-government, notably the renewal and reinvention of 148

The Grassroots of Planning

human development in the crucible of new hegemonies in the global South. I also use the term poor when it is a native category for social movements. In these instances, poor is an articulatory politics. Following Stuart Hall, we can think of articulation as a cultural practice crafted in the interstices of hegemony, moments of suturing that congeal subjectifications of solidarity but that are not fixed or permanent identifications. It is worth asking then about the historical conjunctures at which movements organize around poorness. Richard Pithouse thus argues that, in South Africa, poorness is an important category of identification and mobilization for urban subalterns, a way of being out of place with proper politics, be it the proper politics dictated by trade unions or by black consciousness (personal communication). For example, during its iconic mobilizations, the Western Cape Anti-Eviction Campaign was organized as a movement of the “poor . . . not working class people” (Losier 2015). Such ways of thinking about the category of “poor” returns us to Castells and the grassroots of the city, to a consideration of forms of urban politics that are not simply derivative of classbased movements. But such urban politics cannot necessarily be marked as urban citizenship. In the previous section, I outlined some of the contingent conditions under which urban citizenship is expressed and negotiated. As a political category, “poorness” exists in relation to the prescribed and self-inscribed categories of urban citizenship but also exceeds, and possibly defies, these categories. Building on Pithouse’s provocation I want to suggest that “poorness” might provide an important entry point for thinking about the relationship between the urban and the political and for expanding Castells’ theory of the state or even the notion of “political society” advanced by Chatterjee. Thus, it is worth considering how Pithouse (2012: 485) foregrounds the “shack settlement as a political site – be it of an assertion of equal humanity, a defence of clientelism, or xenophobic or homophobic violence.” It is because it is a site that is not fully inscribed within the laws and rules through which the state governs society … The unfixed way in which the shack settlement is indexed to the situation opens opportunity for a variety of challenges … to the official order of things. (Pithouse 2012: 485) In particular, Pithouse (2012: 486) notes that to think about the shack settlement as an important political site requires thinking beyond familiar frameworks of historical agency and familiar tropes of the revolutionary subject: “It is merely to note that a wide range of modes of politics, including emancipatory politics, does exist in the shack settlement and must be taken as seriously as any other expression of human agency.” Indeed, he goes further to note that often the quest for the revolutionary subject has led to a marginalization of the urban poor from the domain of proper politics: “It is a plain fact that Marxism, whether wielded by states or oppositional left projects, has often been mobilized to endorse the expulsion of the urban poor from the agora” (Pithouse 2012: 486). In the concluding section of this essay, I explore how such poor people’s movements generate a distinctive politics, one that can be understood as the transformation of waste into the human. But, once again, the questions of conjuncture and contingency must be raised. Under what conditions does poorness become the grounds for urban mobilization? In what contexts is such identification and collective action rendered fragile? Thus, in the case of India, Bhan (2014) reveals the workings of what he calls the “impoverishment of poverty” – a reduction in the efficacy of poverty and vulnerability as the basis of claims to the elements of citizenship, to resources and entitlements as well as to a place within narratives of belonging and personhood. Such impoverishment uses a range of political technologies, for example, the framing of habitation 149

Ananya Roy

and occupation of the city by the urban poor as “encroachment.” Bhan’s analysis stands in contrast to Appadurai’s (2007: 33) hopeful exposition of the politics of hope: “the galactic explosion of civil society movements,” the democratic practices of poor people which express the “capacity to aspire” and thereby rearticulate cities as places of “deep democracy” (Appadurai 2002).

From Waste to Human In a provocative essay, Gidwani and Reddy (2011: 1642) put forward the concept of “eviscerating urbanism” as a “diagnostic tool to investigate both urban transformations in metropolitan India and their associated architectures for managing bodies and spaces designated as ‘wasteful’.” Conceptualizing the “urban present” as a “post-development social formation,” they argue that the state no longer has an “ethical engagement” with the poor (Gidwani and Reddy 2011: 1642, emphasis in the original). This, they note, is a rupture with “governmental power” which “presupposes nominal engagement with the subjects whose lives it seeks to manage and cultivate” (p. 1640). What is the political when the grassroots of the city has been rendered waste? What is the theory of the city when superfluity and disposability are at work? When the “poisoned soil” – Carolina Gaete’s poignant and poetic phrase – is brought into view, can urban social change still be imagined? Gidwani and Reddy’s formulation of waste, and lives that are rendered waste, is an important challenge to theories of urban citizenship, whether they are formulations of insurgency or political society, all of which assume an ethical engagement by the apparatuses of the state with the governed. Yet, drawing on the ideas and practices of poor people’s movements, I want to note the conditions under which waste is transformed into the human, when the “litigation of rights” demands ethical engagement, and when poorness becomes not a matter of humiliation but of collective action. It is thus that in an essay on democracy, Mbembe (2011) issues the invitation to “retrieve the ‘human’ from the history of waste,” insisting upon humanism in a context shaped by “brutal forms of dehumanization,” including “slavery, colonization, and apartheid.” Mbembe notes that such ideas of the human cannot derive from the West, by which I take him to mean Western legacies of liberal democracy. Instead, the traditions of freedom struggles, Black thought, and decolonization might point to a different possibility of metamorphosis from waste to human. Indeed, in an essay written in homage to Fanon, Mbembe (2012) pinpoints the importance of such “metamorphic thought”: If we owe Fanon a debt it is for his idea that in every human subject there is something indomitable and fundamentally intangible which no domination – no matter in what form – can erase, eliminate, contain or suppress, or at least completely. Fanon tried to grasp how this “something” could be reanimated and brought back to life under conditions of subjugation. (Mbembe 2012: 26) It is this type of metamorphic thought that I find present in the work of poor people’s movements, especially those that, like Blocks Together, seek to advance racial justice and human rights. Take for example the Chicago Anti-Eviction Campaign which is steeped in rights-talk. Eviction blockades and home liberations are waged in the name of defending human rights; members of the campaign enthusiastically endorse the human rights and global goals frameworks of the United Nations. At first glance such an emphasis on human rights might seem to be an expression of global liberalism, precisely the recovery of the human via Western blueprints of liberal democracy. But Hoover (2015: 1092) argues that the invocation of human rights by the 150

The Grassroots of Planning

Chicago Anti-Eviction Campaign must be seen as having “radical potential” because it “uses the ambiguous but universal identity of ‘humanity’ to make claims on the established terms of legitimate authority.” He sees this as related to, but distinct from, human rights as a project of global liberal governance. Here it is worth returning to the question of historical conjuncture: at which historical moments do poor people’s movements invoke an international framework of human rights? Which conjunctures enable, and require, the yoking of militancy and humanism? With these questions in mind, I want to draw attention to some aspects of the present historical conjuncture and genres of metamorphic thought. In a provocative articulation, Opal Tometi, one of the founders of Black Lives Matter, and Gerald Lenoir argue that the movement is not solely about civil rights … it is about the full recognition of our rights as citizens; and it is a battle for full civil, social, political, legal economic and cultural rights as enshrined in the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights. (Tometi and Lenoir 2015) What is at stake, they insist, is “a struggle for the human rights and dignity of black people in the U.S., which is tied to black peoples’ struggle for human rights across the globe” (Tometi and Lenoir 2015). Here then is a humanism that hinges on, and creates, a global imagination of struggle. Steeped in the language and practices of decolonization, it asserts an ethics of freedom that far exceeds the politics of neoliberalization. But such human rights-talk is also a vitally important political strategy. In my recent research and alliances with movements such as the Chicago Anti-Eviction Campaign and the LA Community Action Network, I seek to uncover how militant urban movements deploy the framework of international human rights and engage the symbol of the United Nations. That deployment, it turns out, is a crucial way in which racism in the United States is made legible not only to global audiences but in fact to American ones. If global liberalism, and its defense of human rights, is the familiar language of American progressive thought, then these movements strategically invoke such vocabularies to make evident how human rights violations take place not only “elsewhere” but also “here” – in South Central Los Angeles, on the south side of Chicago, in the Lower Ninth Ward of New Orleans. As Miraftab (2009: 36) has noted in the case of the Western Cape Anti-Eviction Campaign, rights-based discourse and even the litigation of rights exist in combination with “informal survival livelihood practices and with oppositional practices.” These, she notes, range from blocking and postponing evictions to running soup kitchens to “defiant collective actions such as reconnection of disconnected services . . . and relocation of evicted families back into their housing units” to the persistent use of the courts and the legal system. While she describes the repertoire of practices at work in the South Africa movements, quite similar processes are also evident in the Chicago Anti-Eviction Campaign. “They use formal spaces when they are advantageous, and defy them when they prove unjust and limiting. When formal channels fail, they innovate alternative channels to assert their citizenship rights and achieve a just city” (Miraftab 2009: 36). In the case of the Chicago Anti-Eviction Campaign, the metamorphosis of waste into human takes place through the occupation of foreclosed homes, or what the movement calls home liberations. In other words, human rights, and humanism, are defended through claims to property. This presents an important puzzle, one also signaled in Castells’ The City and the Grassroots as he makes note of the ambivalence of certain squatter movements toward the formalization of land claims. In previous work (Roy 2003, 2014), I have suggested that 151

Ananya Roy

poor people’s movements disrupt but also maintain the ideology of property. From slumdweller mobilizations in the global South to homesteading on the American urban frontier, such movements present claims of rightful occupation and legitimate ownership. In doing so, they often shed light on the inherent illegality of assured, state-sanctioned property relations, but they also assert rights to those very same property relations. It is this dilemma that Porter (2014) dubs “possessory politics,” noting that the “frame of possession” dominates struggles to challenge dispossession and claim restitution. Porter’s critique of possessory politics is not simply a concern about the assertion of property rights or other forms of individual rights. Instead it is about personhood. She asks: “For what is to become of those who cannot prove their worth across the thresholds of recognition?” (Porter 2014: 12) and thereby reminds us of the subject who is waste, always less than human, superfluous. This relationship between property and personhood lies at the heart of poor people’s movements contesting urban displacement and their forms of metamorphic thought. It is what haunts the endeavors to create political potentiality amid urban dispossession and displacement. While it is possible to ponder such questions via Lefebvre, as have quite a few of the current debates in urban studies, I seek to do so via postcolonial thought as well as via poststructuralist feminism, in other words through lineages of inquiry that do not take for granted the figure of the human. In Dispossession: The Performative in the Political, Butler and Athanasiou (2013: 32) thus ask a vitally important question: How might claims for the recognition of rights to land and resources, necessarily inscribed as they are in colonially embedded epistemologies of sovereignty, territory, and property ownership, simultaneously work to decolonize the apparatus of property and to unsettle the colonial conceit of proper and propertied human subjectivity? Butler and Athanasiou additionally ask (2013: 32): “Who or what holds the place of the human?” Their questions invoke the “sovereign self” not as pretext or precondition but as a problem. Who is authorized to be this sovereign self? Who has the historical permission for such sovereignty? And what are the stable locations from which such a sovereign self can be deployed, represented, and performed? Who then can claim to be human? Who then can litigate human rights? The power of poor people’s movements is that they claim humanity for those who have never been granted historical permission to be human, for those who through processes of colonization, slavery, and imperialism have been traded as property, for those who are rendered superfluous in the flows of global capitalism. It is obvious by now that such rights-talk far exceeds even the most expansive meanings of the right to the city as derived from Lefebvre. In particular, it reveals the suppressed history of dehumanization that lies in the shadows of EuroAmerican liberal democracy and radical thought. That “sanctioned ignorance” – Spivak’s (1999) felicitous phrase – has pervaded urban studies and its celebration of certain templates of the political. Following Gilroy (1993: 44) these tropes of urban studies can be understood as “an innocent modernity,” “readily purged of any traces of the people without history whose degraded lives might raise awkward questions about the limits of bourgeois humanism.” It is in Black thought, in postcolonial theory, and in the traditions of decolonization that alternatives might be traced. Gilroy (1993: 55) thus calls for the history of modernity to “be reconstructed from the slaves’ points of view.” I see this to be the work of poor people’s movements that are engaged in metamorphic thought. From South Central Los Angeles to the Cape Flats of Cape Town, South Africa, many of these movements invoke Fanon’s notion of revolutionary humanism, of a humanity asserted by the colonized and enslaved. 152

The Grassroots of Planning

Beyond Neoliberalization In this essay, I have analyzed the imbrication of city, citizenship, and state in order to explore the political potentialities of what, in homage to Castells, I term the “grassroots of planning.” While there is a tendency in contemporary theorizations to celebrate the urban as a political ontology and to conceptualize the urban as a revolutionary subject mobilized by the forces of global neoliberalization, I have sought to foreground other instantiations of the relationship between the urban and the political. In particular, I am interested in how the urban is constituted and lived as a governmental category. Such an approach requires careful attention to a theory of the state, which I believe to be one of the most important contributions and yet an oft-ignored aspect of The City and the Grassroots. But there are at least three ways in which this essay expands Castells’ arguments and its implications for critical inquiry within planning theory. First, I argue that a theory of the state must be advanced in relation to a theory of the city. Whether it be the auto-construction of the Brazilian urban periphery, or the South African shack settlement as a political site, or formations of political society as expressions of urban claims-making in India, such processes are necessarily urban. I have also suggested that planning, understood as urban government, mediates this relationship between city and state, whether as a mode of governing or as expressions of insurgency. Second, I have insisted on the question of historical conjuncture. My call to consider the urban as a governmental category is also a call to craft a conceptual framework attentive to conjuncture and contingency in the contemplation of the relationship between the urban and the political. Under what historical conditions does the urban become the terrain of government and the territory of politics? This is a question to be taken up not only outside the West but also in relation to the seemingly stable and teleological history of liberal democracy in the West. Third, while I have relied on conceptualizations of urban citizenship, I have also argued that the imaginations and practices of poor people’s movements exceed the formats and tropes of citizenship. Whether it is “poorness” or revolutionary humanism, the “poisoned soil” of the city often yields political vocabularies and oppositional practices that mark the limits of liberal democracy. At a historical moment when decolonization is once again the matter of visible politics – from city streets to universities – urban planning has an ethical urgency to wage struggle not only against the immediacy of global neoliberalism but also against the long histories of slavery, colonialism, and apartheid through which planning has been constituted and instituted around the world.

References Appadurai, A. 2002. “Deep Democracy: Urban Governmentality and the Horizon of Politics” Public Culture 14, pp. 21–47. Appadurai, A. 2007. “Hope and Democracy” Public Culture 19:1, 29–34. Bhan, G. 2014. “The Impoverishment of Poverty: Reflections on Urban Citizenship and Inequality in Contemporary Delhi” Environment and Urbanization 26:2, 547–560. Brenner, N. 2000. “The Urban Question as a Scale Question: Reflections on Henri Lefebvre, Urban Theory and the Politics of Scale” International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 24:2, 361–378. Butler, J. and A. Athanasiou. 2013. Dispossession: The Performative in the Political. New York: Polity. Caldeira, T. and J. Holston. 2015. “Participatory Urban Planning in Brazil” Urban Studies 52:11, 2001–2017. Castells, M. 1972. The Urban Question: A Marxist Approach. Cambridge: MIT Press. Castells, M. 1983. The City and the Grassroots: A Cross-Cultural Theory of Urban Social Movements. Berkeley: University of California Press. Castells, M. 1985. From the Urban Question to the City and the Grassroots. Urban and Regional Studies, University of Sussex, Working Paper 47.

153

Ananya Roy Chatterjee, P. 2006. The Politics of the Governed: Reflections on Popular Politics in Most of the World. New York: Columbia University Press. Chatterjee, P. 2012. “After Subaltern Studies” Economic and Political Weekly XLVII.35, 44–49. Gidwani, V. and R. Reddy. 2011. “The Afterlives of ‘Waste’: Notes from India for a Minor History of Capitalist Surplus” Antipode 43:2, 1625–1658. Gilroy, P. 1993. The Black Atlantic: Modernity and Double Consciousness. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Gottdiener, M. 1993. “A Marx for Our Time: Henri Lefebvre and the Production of Space” Sociological Theory 11:1, 129–134. Holston, J. 2007. Insurgent Citizenship: Disjunctions of Democracy and Modernity in Brazil. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Hoover, J. 2015. “The Human Right to Housing and Community Empowerment: Home Occupation, Eviction Defence and Community Land Trusts” Third World Quarterly 36:6, 1092–1109. Keil, R. 2003. “Urban Political Ecology” Urban Geography 24:8, 723–738. Losier, T. 2015. “‘We oppose the authorities because we never gave them the authority …’: Aspects of Non-Collaboration in the Political Resonance of Western Cape Anti-Eviction Campaign.” Unpublished paper. Magnusson, W. 2011. Politics of Urbanism: Seeing Like a City. New York: Routledge. Mbembe, A. 2011. “Democracy as a Community of Life” Johannesburg Workshop in Theory and Criticism http://jwtc.org.za/volume_4.htm (accessed May 18, 2015). Mbembe, A. 2012. “Metamorphic Thought: The Works of Frantz Fanon” African Studies 71:1, 19–28. Merrifield, Andrew 2014. The New Urban Question. New York: Pluto Press. Miraftab, F. 2009. “Insurgent Planning: Situating Radical Planning in the Global South” Planning Theory 8:1, 32–50. Pithouse, R. 2012. “Thought Amidst Waste” Journal of Asian and African Studies 47:5, 482–497. Piven, F.F. and R. Cloward. 1977. Poor People’s Movements: Why They Succeed, How They Fail. New York: Pantheon Books. Porter, L. 2014. “Possessory Politics and the Conceit of Procedure: Exposing the Cost of Rights under Conditions of Dispossession” Planning Theory 13:4, 387–406. Rolnik, R. 2013. “Ten Years of the City Statute in Brazil: From the Struggle for Urban Reform to the World Cup Cities” International Journal of Urban Sustainable Development 5:1, 54–64. Rose, N. 2013. “Governing Cities, Governing Citizens.” In E. Isin, ed., Democracy, Citizenship and the Global City (pp. 95–109). New York: Routledge. Roy, A. 2003. “Paradigms of Propertied Citizenship: Transnational Techniques of Analysis” Urban Affairs Review 38:4, 463–491. Roy, A. 2013. “Slum-Free Cities of the Asian Century: Postcolonial Government and the Project of Inclusive Growth” Singapore Journal of Tropical Geography 35, 136–150. Roy, A. 2014. “The Aporias of Poverty.” In A. Roy and E.S. Crane, eds., Territories of Poverty: Rethinking North and South (pp. 1–38). Athens: University of Georgia Press. Roy, A. 2015. “What is Urban about Critical Urban Theory?” Urban Geography, published online December 2. Roy, A., S. Schrader, and E.S. Crane. 2014. “Gray Areas: The War on Poverty at Home and Abroad.” In A. Roy and E.S. Crane, eds., Territories of Poverty: Rethinking North and South (pp. 289–314). Athens: University of Georgia Press. Spivak, G.C. 1999. A Critique of Postcolonial Reason: Toward a History of the Vanishing Present. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Tometi, O. and G. Lenoir. 2015. “Black Lives Matter Is Not a Civil Rights Movement” Time Magazine, December 10, http://time.com/4144655/international-human-rights-day-black-lives-matter/ (accessed December 11, 2015). Watson, V. 2012. “Planning and the ‘Stubborn Realities’ of Global South-East Cities: Some Emerging Ideas” Planning Theory 12:1, 81–100.

154

13 THE DILEMMAS OF DIVERSITY Gender, Race and Ethnicity in Planning Theory Suzanne Speak and Ashok Kumar

Introduction Socio-cultural diversity takes many forms. This chapter explores diversity in the forms of gender, race and ethnicity. It considers how theories relating to gender, race and ethnicity have been absorbed into and expanded on by planning theory. We recognise that planning theory has brought great insight into the way diversity and ‘otherness’ can be created, supported or constrained by the urban environment. However, we seek to present evidence of the limited influence of theoretical developments on planning practice. In particular, the chapter considers how these theories have influenced planning in countries experiencing rapid economic development and urbanisation resulting in social change and social and economic marginalisation of certain groups. We refer to these countries as ‘countries of the South’. However, many of the issues highlighted can equally be seen in cities of Europe, the USA and other countries that do not fit this pattern (referred to here as of the North). The chapter looks first at gender theory and gendered planning theory before tracing theory on race and ethnicity and how this has been adopted by planning. Next we draw some overarching critiques and challenges relating to planning theory and diversity. We conclude by highlighting what we see as the challenges planning theory faces in the 21st century, especially in light of growing civil unrest and right-wing politics resulting from war, fiscal austerity and international migration.

Gender Theory Discussion of gender theory must acknowledge its origins in feminism. As recently as the mid to late 1970s psychologists were trying to present a biological, ‘scientific justification’ for gender difference (Hare-Mustin and Marecek 1988). Early feminists fought against this, highlighting the individual and institutional practices contributing to the reproduction of gender inequality (Ingraham 1994). Initial feminist thinking assumed women to be united by their subjugation by men, social conditioning as girls and their lived experiences, which were perceived as significantly different from those of men (Lennon and Whitford 1994). The Poststructuralist scholars of the late 20th century identified a coercive discourse that tied women to an identity and conception of what 155

Suzanne Speak and Ashok Kumar

it means to be a woman. However, assuming homogeneity among women overlooks their inherent empirical differences, based for example on race, age or ethnicity (Hemmings 2005; Braidotti 1997). Hassim and Gouws (1998: 59) argued that feminist frameworks could not be universally applied and must be relevant to specific socio-cultural contexts. This is unpacked well by Agarwal (1994a: 249), who identifies the different standpoints she can take on Northern feminism, as an educated, privileged Indian woman. Recognition of the limitations of early feminist thinking, and the realisation that changes to women’s lives had a corresponding effect on men’s lives, broadened our understanding of the complexity of socially constructed identities, and the interplay of gender, race and class. By the late 1980s, there was a shift from focusing on women to theorising gender. Gender relationships became recognised as central to every aspect of human experience (Kemp and Squires 1998). The concept has been adopted particularly by sociology and urban geography, where feminist and gendered enquiries opened up deeper and more critical social enquiry into other forms of oppression and disempowerment (Ingraham 1994). There are, however, much broader understandings of the concept of gender. Critical gender studies also include lesbian, gay, bi-sexual and the trans-gendered states, as these are equally conditioned by, and performed within, social relations (Connell 1987). Butler expresses these different genders as a ‘heterosexual matrix’: ‘that grid of cultural intelligibility through which bodies, genders and desires are naturalized’ (Butler 1990: 115). Waites (2005), however, explores the matrix phenomenologically, cautioning that an individual’s ‘sexual orientation’ or ‘gender identity’ should not be considered as either a definitive natural psychological condition, or as irrevocably socially constructed.

Gender and Planning Theory As more women began to work outside the home, feminist epistemology of the late 1960s and 1970s generated insight into women’s experience of and access to the city, housing, public transport or the public realm (Hooper 1992). They also made visible the way in which these experiences served to further their subordination (Ritzdorf 1995; Milroy 1991). Indeed, Markusen (1980) argued that urban policy should be a target for feminist critique. A challenge to the role the planned city plays in reinforcing gendered roles was voiced by Hayden (1980), asking ‘what would a non-sexist city be like?’ In doing so, she called for a new paradigm of the home, neighbourhood and city that would support women’s changing roles. The importance of Hayden’s question for women is obvious. However, of equal importance was the fact that this began to break apart the perceived dichotomy between city and suburb, between productive and reproductive spaces. Reviewing socialist-feminist studies of the interface between production and reproduction in space, Milroy (1991) noted that men’s and women’s activities do not, in reality, fit easily into that dichotomy but play out more along a continuum. In the early 1990s, theorists began considering the role of feminist and gendered approaches in reconstructing the very nature of the planning discipline (Sandercock and Forsyth 1992). Hooper (1992: 49), concerned about what she saw as continued marginalisation of contemporary feminist ideology within planning theory, argued that feminist contributions could have a ‘revitalizing, transformative effect on planning theory and practice’. Both Hendler (1994) and Ritzdorf (1995) challenged planners to question societal norms, arguing for greater use of feminist ethics. Hendler (2005) went on to identify the need for a specific feminist code to both understand what the profession is about and to support planners to make ethical choices. Greed (1993), however, saw planning’s gender blindness as the manifestation of stronger societal forces and the discriminatory attitudes of dominant groups seeking to render others powerless. 156

The Dilemmas of Diversity

Gendered planning theory was, and we assert remains, largely predicated on a Northern understanding of women’s lives. However, by the mid to late 1980s, gender conscious approaches to planning were becoming evident in development literature focusing on the Global South. Moser (1993), discussing a broad range of gender issues within the context of low income countries, recognised that women in those countries generally had triple roles, performing domestic-reproductive, productive and community management roles. Rakodi (1991) made suggestions for more gender sensitive approaches to the planning of transport, land, shelter and infrastructure in the Global South. However, she went further in highlighting that ideas of male superiority and patriarchal control, embodied within the colonial state, had continued postindependence. We argue that this lives on today in the planning policy and practice of many post-colonial nations. Wieringa (1998) criticised the way in which the realities of women’s lives in the Global South were being ‘bent’ to fit planning theoretical frameworks. We agree that they are certainly bent to fit planning’s agendas in many countries of the South. Modernist planning principles, geared toward market demands, have been widely adopted by countries of both the global North and South. In India, for example, the satellite cities of Dwarka in Delhi and Gurgaon in Haryana but close to Delhi both provide housing in gated estates. In both areas retail facilities are clustered separately, away from housing. Public transport is minimal and assumes that the occupants will drive to shops or to work, which, in India, remains a male domain for the middle classes. These communities play directly to concerns about deteriorating urban environment and fear of rape and violence toward women in the city. Only the ubiquity of the motorcar among the middle classes, saves women from complete isolation but now the fear is of carjacking between islands of perceived safety – another gated estate or the city centre in daylight. Conversely, for the urban poor, work is not only a male domain and women’s work is critically important for household livelihoods. As they are predominantly of lower caste, urban poor women are, as Deshpande (2002) argues, doubly disadvantaged, being both poor and having to observe the performance of respectability more associated with such castes. However, in Delhi, many have been relocated from city centre slums to the Municipal relocation colonies. One such colony, Bhalaswa Jahangir Puri, some 15 kilometres from the city centre, will eventually consist of 18,000 three- or five-storey walk-up apartments. It is reminiscent of early Northern, peripheral, isolated, social housing estates. Work and livelihoods, easily and safely accessible from the city slums, are now too distant for a woman to reach safely, respectably or economically (Speak 2011, 2012). As in many other cities of the South, public transport in Delhi can be unsafe for women. Delhi’s approach to encourage women to use the very efficient Metro system was to put a ‘women’s carriage’ on each train, furthering exclusion. The Metro does not reach Bhalaswa but in any case, a woman has to be able to first reach the station safely and second afford the fare. Thus, planning in Delhi, like many other post-colonial cities, has failed to address the disempowering, even threatening, nature of the urban realm for women. It continues to substantiate Tinker’s (1990) concerns about women’s persistent inequalities in the face of development. These settlements discussed above completely overlook feminist planners’ critiques of suburban neighbourhoods as being too rigidly zoned to allow for diverse land uses, isolated, car dependent and lacking a sense of place. Both trap women in location and domestic activity, entirely perpetuate male dominated urban environment and perceived gender roles and reinforce performance of respectability through seclusion. Indeed, one might argue that in these Indian cases, planning has not given women improved access to what still remains a socio-spatial world founded on masculine norms, let alone challenged those norms or offered alternatives. These cases demonstrate that planning in India still sees women as a homogenous group, despite their inherent differences of race, ethnicity, caste or income. 157

Suzanne Speak and Ashok Kumar

In many countries of the South, planning’s adoption of rational, modernising agendas impacts on women’s livelihood strategies. As Payne and Majale (2004) note, ill-conceived regulatory frameworks, often underpinned by a belief in modernisation, render traditional forms of compound housing illegal in favour of nuclear family, villa style dwellings. In some parts of Sub-Saharan Africa, for example, such housing does away with secure, private external space, where women in secluding societies can be at ease, safe from the view of strangers. From the same premise, the upgrading of informal or poor settlements also often brings with it a series of zoning regulations that prohibit certain home-based economic activities so often vital for women’s livelihoods (Tipple 2005). However, there are countries of the South where any attempt at gender sensitive planning is even more constrained by political, institutional and cultural misogyny. Speak (2005) suggests that despite growing acceptance of international conventions, such as the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW), many countries of the South have failed to undertake action to ensure women’s and girls’ rights to land and property, the fundamental tools of planning. Where women’s land rights are enshrined in law, the complexity of customary, religious and constitutional laws often prevents women from owning land. This is true in Uganda and Swaziland, for example, where many women still do not have equal rights to buy or inherit land or property (Asiimwe 2014). As Agarwal (1994c), writing on rural women’s lack of land rights in India, notes, until women’s land and property rights are upheld, planning cannot possibly produce gender sensitive cities.

Race and Ethnicity Race and ethnicity are concepts frequently used without definition, but the terms need untangling. Race categorises populations or groups on the basis of physical characteristics, generally derived from genetic ancestry. Ethnicity, however, refers to the way in which groups of people identify with each other on the basis of common nationality or shared cultural or religious traditions (Smedley and Smedley 2005). Until the early 20th century, the concept of race was firmly located in a biological rationality, as gender had been (Markus 2008). Winant (2000) suggests that the concept of race is arguably a European invention, developed with, and in support of, the rise of a world political economy. It helped rationalise the abuse of one group of people to support the economic goals of another. A belief in white European supremacy justified, for example, the trade in slaves across the Atlantic or the domination of natives by the East India Company. However, ethnicity has long been used as justification for abuse and exclusion within racial groups, as witnessed, for example, by both pre- and post-colonial Hindu–Muslim violence in India (Chakrabarty 1994). However, Blanton, Mason and Athow (2001) argue that even inter-racial ethnic conflict in some parts of Africa can only be understood in relation to the different forms of ethnic stratification, left by contrasting forms of colonial rule. Du Bois’ (1903) early work on race offered the concept of the ‘double consciousness’ of black people, which, as Winant (2004) argues: ‘both afflicts and transfigures the black soul: dividing its experience and self-awareness, “introjecting” racism into the racially oppressed self’ (Winant 2004: 1). Presenting ‘black’ as an overriding identity, condemns the black man or woman to see themselves within the perceived constraints of that identity and to seek to be free of them. In 1905 Washington suggested that Black Americans’ agency was to be earned by material and financial success through which they would ‘buy-in’ to a white world (Schrager 1996). This echoes the way in which early feminist thinking sought to enable women to access a male world while offering no alternative paradigm. 158

The Dilemmas of Diversity

In the mid-1960s, race riots in the USA added power to the American Civil Rights Movement. By the time of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 (Loevy 1990) racial struggles had begun to encompass recognition of African American identity. More subtle, institutional forms of racism led to the development of Critical Race Theory (CRT) in the USA (Bell 1995). CRT highlighted racism’s structural foundations (Crenshaw 1995), reframing issues of oppression as both social and institutional. However, CRT is open to criticism about its own critical pedagogy (see, for example, Ladson-Billings 1998). In Britain, arrival of Caribbean immigrants in 1948, as the answer to post-war labour shortages, made race more visible. From the 1970s, increasing migration made racial and ethnic difference more nuanced within British society, raising discussions of the supremacy of ‘whiteness’. This is increasingly relevant today in relation to migration within the European Union. For example, Fox (2013: 1) notes the way in which some Eastern European migrants use their ‘putative whiteness’ to gain racial supremacy over other immigrants. However, just as Waites (2005) suggests that gender is not necessarily fixed, it appears that in some senses, elements of ethnic or religious identity might be similarly mutable. This chapter is written at a time when protesters from the Gujjar tribe of India are demanding they be effectively downgraded as one of India’s ‘scheduled tribes’, made up largely of the former ‘untouchables’ with whom they would not normally have wished to be associated. In this way they would benefit from reserved jobs and educational places.

Race, Ethnicity and Planning Theory The Chicago School of Urban Sociology began theorising race in relation to planning of American cities by 1945 (Pacione 2002). Concentric Zone Theory argued that, as demand for housing by poor immigrant labourers increased, it pushed middle- and high-income white populations to outer rings of a city. It associated multiple negative aspects of city life with immigrants and ethnic minorities without considering causes. The theory was criticised for its physical determinism by both Castells (1972) and Harvey (1973). Nevertheless, it continued to be used, for example to analyse the sprawling growth of Ibadan, Nigeria (Splansky 1966) or black townships in South Africa (Beavon 1982). Scholars identified that urban policy makers were producing segregation between social groups based on class, race and/or ethnicity, through policies relating to housing, public space and land use (Smith 1989; Eyles 1990). By the mid-1990s growing cultural and ethnic diversity in the global North demanded a shift away from procedural approaches in planning, which Fenster (1996) argued are mainly concerned with difference if it interferes with that which is planned for. A new paradigm of pluralism was developing in many, although not all, Northern countries which acknowledged the rights of diverse groups to have their ethnic differences understood and respected. Recognising the logic and rationales upon which differences are based, Watson (2003, 2006) offers some of the most valuable considerations of what these differences, and conflicts between them, might mean for planning. Unfortunately, respect for difference too often has to give way to political and economic demands. It is questionable, for example, whether an ethnically nuanced understanding of ‘adequate housing’ can override an authority’s need to capitalise on increasing land values by maximising density and minimising construction cost, as is discussed below. Throughout the 1990s communicative planning came to dominate planning theory. Healey (1992) suggests that it has at its heart the promotion of social justice, requiring planners to understand social diversity and its rationality in order to arrive at a consensus as the basis for decision making. There are a number of critiques of communicative rationality pertinent to 159

Suzanne Speak and Ashok Kumar

issues of diversity. It is questionable whether there can ever exist a democratic context in which Habermasian communicative consensus might allow anyone to question the claims of anyone else. Some suggest that such a communicative process might actually negate diversity and difference, hence it can only potentially work in, or to produce, a monoculture (for example, see Tewdwr-Jones and Allmendinger 1998). Others, however, note that consensus might not necessarily counter an acceptance of difference as long as parties agree to concur with positions that they cannot refute (Poster 1989). There are criticisms that communicative or collaborative planning is too strongly focused on the process to the detriment of outcomes, that it assumes an equal voice among disparate and diverse parties and overlooks the power structures both within and between communities and within planning itself (Beauregard 1998). However, for this work, perhaps the most pertinent criticisms come from Huxley and Yiftachel (1998: 7) who have criticised communicative planning theory for its Anglo-American or Northern stance. They argue, and we agree, that communicative planning does little to overturn the modernist assumptions of planning ‘as an unproblematic global activity, adhering to similar rationale and logic everywhere it is found’. Nevertheless, communicative planning did contribute to a rethinking of the role of planning and planners and press for the importance of a multiplicity of knowledges. It called for planners to engage in dialogue and negotiate with minorities based on multiple epistemologies (Sandercock 1998). Watson (2006) recognised, however, that difference exists not only between social or ethnic groups but between the people and governments. It is here where a pluralist paradigm fails, in that we are yet to see a true politics of diversity. Indeed, governments are increasingly driven by their own ethno-nationalist ideals or by dominant, increasingly neo-liberal values (Falah 1989; Yiftachel 1991, 2006; Bollens 1998). Thus, in some countries, far from upholding the right to difference, planning operates as a tool of government to obliterate it. What Fernandes (2004) calls the ‘politics of forgetting’ sees ethnic and other marginalised groups become hidden and invisible both within national political discourse and literally. This is done by reshaping urban space either to further specific ethnic or racial supremacy (Yiftachel 2006) or to pander to the demands of the market (Escobar 1995) and further what Schuurman (2000: 10) considers as ‘a global, exploitative capitalism’. In many cases, this drives the eviction or relocation of diverse ethnic communities through processes of ‘spatial purification’ (Sibley 1995: 78). This is particularly evident in India, where economic growth has given rise to major corporate developments displacing many hundreds of thousands of poorer people, their structures and cultures. In Delhi, a city of multiple ethnicities, planning’s aim is for economic growth and ‘world class city’ status. Expansion, modernisation and privatisation see the laying down of what Speak (2014) refers to as a ‘new urban orthodoxy’, within which behaviour and culture of poor migrant settlers are as much the target of planning as are their spaces and physical structures. This crystallises in the case of the informal settlement of Kathputli. The settlement was established in the early 1970s by artisans and performers from Rajasthan (Banda, Vaidya and Adler 2013). Originally in a relatively peripheral location of limited development value. As the city expanded the community found itself occupying prime development land. Delhi Development Authority (DDA) has kept a watchful eye on the Kathputli settlement for many years. Eventually, using the agendas of adequate housing and improvement, DDA planned an in-situ upgrading project to ‘rehabilitate’ and relocate the community into a 15-storey apartment block. Eviction and relocation, although frequently unjust in themselves, are not the key points here. What is pertinent is the couching of the upgrading in terms of ‘rehabilitation’ and the form of accommodation planned for the community. One artisan noted: ‘Our art dictates our lifestyle and our lifestyle is our identity; the lifestyle of a multi-storey concrete building is not for us’ (Bhowmik 2014). 160

The Dilemmas of Diversity

We can see from this case that planning in Delhi, as in so many other cities of the South, has not engaged with pluralism at all. Nor has planning considered the impact of its actions but focused entirely on the product, the criteria for which are dictated by economics, rather than social justice. The ethnic and cultural nuances of Kathputli, and other settlements like it, are subsumed by authorities into an overarching ethnicity of poverty and multiple deprivation. This is used to categorise residents in support of the authority’s agenda of economic development and modernisation. The resulting planning prescriptions undermine the rationality of long held ways of life and livelihood, either destroying them or imprisoning them in inappropriate solutions. Those inappropriate solutions are overtly used to constrain and render invisible a group of people whose ethnic lifestyles do not fit an unfolding middle class model of the city by normalising not only the physical housing but also the behaviour of its residents. In some respects the area might be seen to be epitomising Yiftachel’s (2009) ‘grey space’, in that it is informal and has existed under a form of ‘permanent temporariness’ (p. 90). We agree also that the authorities saw it as a place to ‘be corrected’, as expressed through the discourse of ‘rehabilitation’. However, we find Yiftachel’s concept does not quite fit our experience. We do not see these spaces as being totally excluded from, or in the shadow of, the city polity and economy. In many cases, in India, Bangladesh and Pakistan at least, they are strongly engaged with, and influential in, the formal polity and governance, through patronage, vote banking and other forms of reciprocity, which very often involve issues of planning and resource. They also have an integral role in the formal economy and the provision of services, such as dry waste control. This gives such places power to negotiate to a greater or lesser extent around issues of planning and resource (Bari 2016). We do accept the limitations of that power, however. We caution, however, that disrespect for ethnic preferences is not only found in the Global South. Ethnic conflicts around planning and land are common also in Europe and the USA. A number of scholars have discussed, for example, the treatment of Gypsy and Traveller or Roma communities in Europe, noting that their lifestyles and housing preferences are often perceived by authorities, and presented by the media, as deviant (Sigona 2005).

Critiques and Dilemmas There have now been decades of rhetoric within planning theory about the importance of understanding and accommodating difference. We agree with Sandercock (1995) about the cultural specificity of social justice and accept, therefore, that diversity must be accommodated within this specificity. However, in accepting that as basis for critique we establish a conundrum. While we are instinctively arguing against the imposition of normative values, a great deal of what planning theory has ‘achieved’ in relation to diversity is itself driven by, and has indeed emboldened, those values that are now normative within the largely Northern contexts where that theory was developed. It is indeed normative to argue that diversity should be accommodated, that gender equality is right and that ethnicity should not be discriminated against. Although we agree with all three suppositions, there are very many in the world who would not, but planning theory has not presented a framework to accommodate this clash of values. Planning theory remains driven by an educated elite with a largely coherent and arguably predominantly Northern sensitivity and value system. We should not reject existing theory, nor accept it uncritically, simply because of this. However, there is an urgent need for planning theory developed by and for other value systems. This might seem to suggest that, in an extreme scenario, we could end up with different theories for different countries, cultures and peoples. In an increasingly globalised society this would be unworkable. However, we do suggest that the development of theory should be a dialectic, evolving in ways that enrich, refine, transform 161

Suzanne Speak and Ashok Kumar

or even dispute the original theory. Indeed, values themselves are not static but constantly evolving as they encounter other values. Planning theory is important here as Rosenberg (2008) suggests that theories in social science have a role to play in influencing values. However, planning practice and theory is, perhaps, too rooted in normative ethical reasoning about the right way to make things better, with little consideration of the validity of those ethical judgements. We suggest that this requires us to step back from normative ethical frameworks for deciding on the fair and just processes and outcomes of planning, to scrutinise how we have arrived at our concept of fair and just. Winkler and Duminy (2014) unpack this well, drawing on Meta-ethics, a branch of moral philosophy that demands a reconsideration of the very nature of what is good, better, just. They point out that there is an assumption that ‘planners know the nature and meaning of “better”’(p. 3). Seen from a normative ethical stance, the danger is that this might drive planning theory away from tolerance and accommodation of diversity and toward different judgements of discrimination, normative in other contexts. It will certainly generate conflicts and concerns that Northern scholars might find uncomfortable. For example, this work has argued in favour of gender sensitive planning. However, that argument grows from a series of ethical assumptions, about equality, fairness and human rights, which most scholars, including the two authors, do not wish to entertain as anything other than absolute truths without scrutinising our deepest basis for that belief. McIntyre’s ‘disquieting suggestion’ (2013) is helpful for the discussion above. He describes a fictitious world in which genuine scientific knowledge has been lost yet pseudo scientists continue to misuse and confuse science’s ideas and language unquestioningly presenting it as objective reasoning. Although contestation and counter theories exist, they are all based on the same invalid and confused language, logic and knowledge. This is valuable in two ways. First, it prompts us to consider what happens when the basis of our ‘knowledge’ is lost. This is helpful at a time when the contexts from which theory on diversity grew (deep misogyny, intense racial discrimination and segregation) are less visible, if not necessarily less experienced, within Northern societies. Second, Macintyre suggests that the contemporary language of morality and ethics is in a similar state to the language of science in the imaginary world. It cannot be challenged effectively because objective challenges are themselves constrained by the state of knowledge and language. The need for planning theory to revisit the grounding for its ideas on diversity is made evident by the fact that much recent planning theory is guilty of homogenising difference by referring to gender, race and cultural diversity collectively. Moreover, in revisiting the origins of our values, we may identify a greater commonality among core human values than current socio-political struggles around the world would suggest. For example, Agarwal (1994b) noted a significant cross cutting of ideas among global feminist thought. This does not, however, overcome the problems that many may still not accept feminism at all. Lessons might also be drawn from Arkaraprasertkul’s (2010: 128) concept of ‘Cryptourbanism’, which refers to urban activities, and we would add cultural behaviours, which rest ‘at the border between the acceptable and unacceptable’. They might not be desirable to many but they are essentially what allows a rich and multi-valued society to exist. Crypto-urbanism is valuable for exploring issues of diversity because as Mishra (2016: 94) suggests it ‘questions the whole gamut of prevalent moral understandings’. Crypto-urbanism is very strongly associated with place and the specific locations within which these contentious activities take place, indeed, literally in some cases, ‘take the place’. It might, therefore, address concerns about the diminution of place as a key element in social analysis of gender, race or ethnicity (Dirlik 2000). 162

The Dilemmas of Diversity

Planning education must also accept its own role in developing new theories and approaches to managing social justice under pressure from politics and the market. By the Indian coauthor’s own admission, planning education in India maintains the dominance of the architect or urban designer planner and does too little to engage students around issues of ethnicity, gender or power. Indeed, theorising these issues in many countries makes a very difficult and self-critical reading of how these aspects are socially practised and performed in the city. In some, although not all, countries what is taught of planning theory is only that generated in the North from an Anglo-US tradition. Watson (2008: 118) notes the suggestions of one UN advisor that: ‘African universities should restructure themselves to become engines of local “community development”, working closely with the private sector’. If this suggestion was followed there would be no academic arena for the production of context-specific theory in Africa. Moreover, without the development of theory for that cultural context, there would be nothing to challenge the dominance of existing theory more generally. Healey (2013: 1513), discussing the international transfer of planning ideas, suggests that critical practitioners of the South have, in the past, struggled to be heard and we fear many still do.

Conclusion Arguments for the celebration of difference have failed to find a convincing theoretical framework to help practitioners mediate the multiple and conflicting demands on land, resources or the environment that lead to social injustice. Unless it does so theory will become even more disconnected from practice than it already is, especially in the South, where the demand for rapid economic growth often overshadows concern for justice. However, in both North and South, in the 21st century the fallout from war and civil conflict in Africa and the Middle East has produced critically high levels of migration and asylum seeking. At the same time, in Europe and the USA, we are witnessing increasingly right-wing politics. The certainties of adequate housing, welfare provision and employment are diminishing rapidly. The relative plenty that has underpinned tolerance of a pluralist society is under threat, making Bollens’ (2002) fractured public interest increasingly evident. As a result social tensions within our cities are reawakening as different groups jostle for position in a hierarchy of ethnic acceptability or economic rights. In Europe, concerns about radicalisation and terrorism take on a spatial dimension as the spotlight falls on specific cities and neighbourhoods within them. In the UK, right-wing political murmurings can be heard about gender rights, for example in relation to employment legislation. Never before has it been so important for planning to engage with diversity in pursuit of socially just cities at all scales (Speak and Kumar 2016; Davoudi and Bell 2016). It is important, therefore, not simply for planning theory to acknowledge or celebrate diversity but to learn from countries that have experienced the conflicts of diversity for longer.

References Agarwal, B. (1994a). Positioning the western feminist agenda: a comment. Indian Journal of Gender Studies, 1(2), pp.249–255. Agarwal, B. (1994b). Gender and command over property: a critical gap in economic analysis and policy in South Asia. World Development, 22(10), pp.1455–1478. Agarwal, B. (1994c). A Field of One’s Own: Gender and Land Rights in South Asia (South Asian Studies, Vol. 58). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Arkaraprasertkul, N. (2010). Crypto-urbanism: retrofitting Tokyo. Journal of Urbanism, 3(2), pp.127–129. Asiimwe, J. (2014). Making women’s land rights a reality in Uganda: advocacy for co-ownership by spouses. Yale Human Rights and Development Journal, 4(1), p.8.

163

Suzanne Speak and Ashok Kumar Banda, S., Vaidya, Y. and Adler, D. (2013). The Case of Kathputli Colony: Mapping Delhi’s First In-situ Slum Rehabilitation Project. CPR Working Paper 3, Centre for Policy Research, New Delhi. Bari, A. (2016). Understanding Urban Informality: Everyday life in informal urban settlements in Pakistan. PhD thesis submitted to Newcastle University. Available from Newcastle University Robinson Library. Beauregard, R.A. (1998). Writing the planner. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 18(2), pp.93–101. Beavon, K.S.O. (1982). Black townships in South Africa: terra incognita for urban geographers. South African Geographical Journal, 64(1), pp.3–20. Bell, Derrick A. (1995). Who’s afraid of critical race theory? University of Illinois Law Review, (1995), p.893. Bhowmick, N. (2014). The World’s Largest Community of Street Performers Is about to Be Torn Apart, Time, 4 March 2014. Online at: http://time.com/12073/india-kathputli-colony-of-street-artists-tobe-demolished/ (accessed 5 May 2017). Blanton, R., Mason, T.D. and Athow, B. (2001). Colonial style and post-colonial ethnic conflict in Africa. Journal of Peace Research, 38(4), pp.473–491. Bollens, S.A. (1998). Urban planning amidst ethnic conflict: Jerusalem and Johannesburg. Urban Studies, 35(4), pp.729–750. Bollens, S.A. (2002). Urban planning and intergroup conflict: confronting a fractured public interest. Journal of the American Planning Association, 68(1), pp.22–42. Braidotti, Rosi. (1997). Comment on Felski’s ‘the Doxa of Difference’: working through sexual difference. Signs, 23(1), pp.23–40. Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble, feminist theory and psychoanalytic discourse. In D. Nicholson ed., Feminism/Postmodernism, London: Routledge, 324–340. Castells, M. (1972). La Question Urbaine. Paris: Maspero. Chakrabarty, D. (1994). Modernity and ethnicity in India. South Asia: Journal of South Asian Studies, 17(s1), pp.143–155. Connell, R. (1987). Gender and Power. Oxford: Polity Press. Crenshaw, K. (1995). Critical Race Theory: The Key Writings that Formed the Movement. New York: The New Press. Davoudi, S. and Bell, D. (2016). Justice and Fairness in the City. Bristol: Policy Press. Deshpande, A. (2002). Assets versus autonomy? The changing face of the gender-caste overlap in India. Feminist Economics, 8(2), pp.19–35. Dirlik, A. (2000). Place-based imagination: globalism and the politics of place. In R. Prazniak and A. Dirlik, eds, Places and Politics in the Age of Globalization. New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 15–52. Du Bois, William Edward Burghardt. (1903). The Souls of Black Folk. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Escobar, A. (1995). Encountering Development. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Eyles, J. (1990). Group identity and urban space: the North American experience. In M. Chisholm and D. Smith, eds, Shared Space, Divided Space: Essays on Conflict and Territorial Organization. Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman, 46–66. Falah, G. (1989). Israeli state policy toward Bedouin sedentarization in the Negev. Journal of Palestine Studies, 18(2), pp.71–91. Fenster, T. (1996). Ethnicity and citizen identity in planning and development for minority groups. Political Geography, 15(5), pp.405–418. Fernandes, L. (2004). The politics of forgetting: class politics, state power and the restructuring of urban space in India. Urban Studies, 41(12), pp.2415–2430. Fox, J. (2013). The uses of racism: whitewashing new Europeans in the UK. Ethnic and Racial Studies, 36(11), pp.1871–1889. Greed, C. (1993). Is more better? Mark II – with reference to women town planners in Britain. Women’s Studies International Forum, 16(3), pp.255–270. Hare-Mustin, Rachel T. and Marecek, Jeanne. (1988). The meaning of difference: gender theory, postmodernism, and psychology. American Psychologist, 43(6), pp.455–464. Harvey, D. (1973). Social Justice and the City. London: Edward Arnold. Hassim, S. and Gouws, A. (1998). Redefining the public space: women’s organisations, gender consciousness and civil society in South Africa. Politikon, 25(2), pp.53–76. Hayden, Dolores. (1980). What would a non-sexist city be like? Speculations on housing, urban design, and human work. Signs: S170–S187. Healey, P. (1992). Planning through debate: the communicative turn in planning theory. Town Planning Review, 63(2), pp.143–162.

164

The Dilemmas of Diversity Healey, P. (2013). Circuits of knowledge and techniques: the transnational flow of planning ideas and practices. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 37(5), pp.1510–1526. Hemmings, Clare. (2005). Telling feminist stories. Feminist Theory, 6(2), pp.115–139. Hendler, S. (1994). Feminist planning ethics. Journal of Planning Literature, 9(2), pp.115–127. Hendler, S. (2005). Towards a feminist code of planning ethics. Planning Theory & Practice, 6(1), pp.53–69. Hooper, Barbara. (1992). ‘Split at the roots’: a critique of the philosophical and political sources of modern planning doctrine. Frontiers: A Journal of Women Studies, 13(1), pp.45–80. Huxley, M. and Yiftachel, O. (1998). New paradigm or old myopia? Unsettling the communicative turn in planning theory. Paper to Planning Theory Conference. Oxford Brookes University. Oxford. April 1998. Ingraham, C. (1994). The heterosexual imaginary: feminist sociology and theories of gender. Sociological Theory, 12(2), pp.203–219. Kemp, S. and Squires, J. (1998). Feminisms. Oxford Reader Series, Oxford University Press. Ladson-Billings, G. (1998). Just what is critical race theory and what’s it doing in a nice field like education? International Journal of Qualitative Studies in Education, 11(1), pp.7–24. Lennon, Kathleen and Whitford, Margaret. (1994). Knowing the Difference: Feminist Perspectives in Epistemology. Psychology Press. Loevy, Robert D. (1990). To End All Segregation: The Politics of the Passage of the Civil Rights Act of 1964. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. Markus, H.R. (2008). Pride, prejudice, and ambivalence: toward a unified theory of race and ethnicity. American Psychologist, 63(8), p.651. Markusen, A.R. (1980). City spatial structure, women’s household work, and national urban policy. Signs, S23–S44. McIntyre, A. (2013). After Virtue. New York: Bloomsbury Academic. Milroy, Beth Moore. (1991). Taking stock of planning, space, and gender. Journal of Planning Literature, 6(1), pp.3–15. Mishra, S.V. (2016). Conflating gray space and crypto urbanism. Journal of Urbanism: International Research on Placemaking and Urban Sustainability, 9(1), pp.93–96. Moser, C. (1993). Gender Planning and Development (p. 298). London: Routledge. Pacione, M. (2002). The City: Land Use, Structure, and Change in the Western City. Vol. 2. Abingdon: Taylor & Francis. Payne, G.K. and Majale, M. (2004). The Urban Housing Manual: Making Regulatory Frameworks Work for the poor. London: Earthscan. Poster, M. (1989). Critical Theory and Poststructuralism: In Search of a Context. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Rakodi, C. (1991). Cities and people: towards a gender-aware urban planning process? Public Administration and Development, 11(6), pp.541–559. Ritzdorf, M. (1995). Feminist contributions to ethics and planning theory. In S. Hendler, ed., Planning Ethics. New Brunswick: Center for Urban Policy Research. Rosenberg, G.N. (2008). The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change? Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Sandercock, L. (1995). Voices from the borderlands: a meditation on a metaphor. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 14(2), pp.77–88. Sandercock, L. (1998). Making the Invisible Visible: A Multicultural Planning History. Berkeley: University of California Press. Sandercock, Leonie and Forsyth, Ann. (1992). A gender agenda: new directions for planning theory. Journal of the American Planning Association, 58(1), pp.49–59. Schrager, Cynthia D. (1996). Both sides of the veil: race, science, and mysticism, in W.E.B. Du Bois. American Quarterly, 48(4), pp.551–586. Schuurman, F.J. (2000). Paradigms lost, paradigms regained? Development studies in the twenty-first century. Third World Quarterly, 21(1), pp.7–20. Sibley, D. (1995). Geographies of Exclusion. London: Routledge. Sigona, N. (2005). Locating ‘the Gypsy problem’. The Roma in Italy: Stereotyping, labelling and ‘nomad camps’. Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies, 31(4), pp.741–756. Smedley, A. and Smedley, B.D. (2005). Race as biology is fiction, racism as a social problem is real: anthropological and historical perspectives on the social construction of race. American Psychologist, 60(1), pp.16–26.

165

Suzanne Speak and Ashok Kumar Smith, S. (1989). The politics of race and a new segregationism. In J. Mohan, ed., The Political Geography of Contemporary Britain. London: Macmillan, 151–171. Speak, S. (2005). The relationship between children’s homelessness in developing countries and the failure of women’s rights legislation, 22(3), pp.129–146. Speak, S. (2011). Point of no return: exploring the issues which trap migrants in a state of homelessness in the city. International Development Planning Review, 32(3–4), pp.225–243. Speak, S. (2012). Planning for the needs of urban poor in the Global South: the value of a feminist approach. Planning Theory, 11(4): pp.343–360. Speak, S. (2014). Desperation, deviance or delight: conflicting cultural landscape of the urban poor in the developing world. In M. Roe and K. Taylor, eds, New Cultural Landscapes. London: Routledge, 136–152. Speak, S. and Kumar, A. (2016). Fit and miss-fit: the global spread of urban spatial injustice. In S. Davoudi and D. Bell, eds, Justice and Fairness in the City: A Multidisciplinary Approach to ‘Ordinary’ Cities. Bristol: Policy Press, 107–124. Splansky, J. (1966). The Concentric Zone Theory of city structure: as applied to an African city: Ibadan, Nigeria. Yearbook of the Association of Pacific Coast Geographers, 28(1), pp.135–146. Tewdwr-Jones, M. and Allmendinger, P. (1998). Deconstructing communicative rationality: a critique of Habermasian collaborative planning. Environment and Planning A, 30(11), pp.1975–1989. Tinker, I. (1990). Persistent Inequalities: Women and World Development. New York: Oxford University Press. Tipple, G. (2005). The place of home-based enterprises in the informal sector: evidence from Cochabamba, New Delhi, Surabaya and Pretoria. Urban Studies, 42(4), pp.611–632. Waites, M. (2005). The fixity of sexual identities in the public sphere: biomedical knowledge, liberalism and the heterosexual/homosexual binary in late modernity. Sexualities, 8(5), pp.539–569. Watson, V. (2003). Conflicting rationalities: implications for planning theory and ethics. Planning Theory and Practice, 4(4), pp.395–408. Watson, V. (2006). Deep difference: diversity, planning and ethics. Planning Theory, 5(1), pp.31–50. Watson, V. (2008). Down to earth: linking planning theory and practice in the ‘metropole’ and beyond. International Planning Studies, 13(3), pp.223–237. Wieringa, S.E. (1998). Rethinking gender planning: a critical discussion of the use of the concept of gender. Gender, Technology and Development, 2(3), pp.349–371. Winant, H. (2000). Race and race theory. Annual Review of Sociology, 26, pp.169–185. Winant, H. (2004). Dialectics of the veil. In The New Politics of Race: Globalism, Difference, Justice. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 25–49. Winkler, T. and Duminy, J. (2014). Planning to change the world? Questioning the normative ethics of planning theories. Planning Theory, 15(2), pp.111–129. Yiftachel, O. (1991). Industrial development and Arab-Jewish economic gaps in the Galilee region, Israel. The Professional Geographer, 43(2), pp.163–179. Yiftachel, O. (2006). Ethnocracy: Land and Identity Politics in Israel/Palestine. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Yiftachel, O. (2009). Critical theory and ‘gray space’: Mobilization of the colonized. City, 13(2–3), pp.246–263.

166

14 POSTCOLONIAL CONSEQUENCES AND NEW MEANINGS Libby Porter

Introduction No matter the definition applied among the many hundreds possible, ‘planning’ as it is conceived in contemporary scholarship and practice is undeniably a Western concept and practice. This is not to say that ‘planning’, in the more broadly conceived sense of organizing peopleplace relations, does not happen within, or is irrelevant to, other philosophies and cultures. But the fundamental concepts we work with in the field (the state, property, space, governance, civil society, markets, regulation) derive their central tenets from Western presumptions about what is in the world, and therefore what can be known and ordered. Maori scholar Hirini Matunga reminds us that planning is “an imperial scholarly discipline and colonial practice located in the ‘West’” (2013). Given the dizzying scale of European imperialism, and the central complicity of planning in the colonial processes of accumulating territory, planning theory can hardly expect to remain unchallenged and unchanged by critiques ‘from below’ that have emerged from these relations of colonial power. This chapter provides theoretical lenses for and upon planning that derive from and are inspired by those critiques and the concepts they articulate. I provide a combined reading across a range of scholarly literatures including settler-colonial studies, postcolonial theory, and critical Indigenous theories. Reading all of these under the awkward phrase, ‘postcolonial theorizing’, I argue that they offer a necessary approach for planning to see, explain and transform situations where colonial power relations are present and where planning is enrolled in colonial processes of domination and subjugation. The chapter proceeds with a very brief sketch of these fields of scholarship, and some qualifications and clarifications. I then set out what I see as the primary points of departure and ethico-political commitments of postcolonial theorizing. Read into planning, such points of departure throw into sharp relief key questions about: difference and identity; land and spatiality; and representation, resistance and recognition. Three substantive sections discuss each in turn before pointing in the final section to areas of work that offer possibilities for ways of theorizing planning that de-privilege colonial viewpoints.

167

Libby Porter

Postcolonial Theorizing: A Short Overview and Some Qualifications Postcolonial critiques seek a critical cognizance of colonial relations of power and the operation of imperialist ideologies by deploying concepts and philosophical lineages that try to render the familiar strange (Sheppard et al. 2013). This achieves what Ananya Roy calls “paying attention to the ways in which the field of action is structured by imperial practices” (2006, p. 8). There is a strong focus on discourse, cultural analysis, and deconstructive criticism, or what Judith Butler has elsewhere called a “variable practice of reading” (Butler 2000, p. 136). While the fields of debate are diverse enough to defy a reductive representation, there are some core projects and concepts that can be discerned. One is an insistence that Western categories, concepts and histories obscure colonial relations of domination and subjugation, because they see ‘from the West’ and occlude the West’s own cultural position of power (see Guha 1998; Chakrabarty 2000; Spivak 1985; Connell 2007). In doing so, Western perspectives are not only privileged, that privilege is operationalized as normal and indeed natural. The West comes to exist in contra-distinction from its Other, always defined in a relation of subjugation and domination (on these points see Said 1978, 1993; Fanon 1963, 1967; Spivak 1994, Spivak 1996). This has both material and psycho-affective consequences for colonized peoples. Not only does it result in the dispossession of land and the economic subjugation and geographic marginalization of colonized people, it also produces, as Fanon (1967) argued, a certain kind of subjectivity and identification of colonized peoples with colonial rule. Consequently, the system of colonial power is reproduced not only through the material operations of power but also through the way that colonized peoples identify with the forms of recognition that maintain colonial rule (Fanon 1967). An important commitment in postcolonial theorizing is to instate and insert definitions, voices, epistemologies and theories ‘from below’ that challenge and unsettle the dominance of Western modes of knowledge production and the processes of Othering in the service of hegemony. Debates in Subaltern Studies have sought to reframe the agency of colonized subalterns, though not without extensive critique (see, for example, the masterful critique by Chibber 2013). Settler-colonial studies and critical Indigenous studies bring a critical acumen to fields that have had an orientalizing and naturalizing approach to the production of knowledge about and of, rather than by and for, Indigenous people (Coulthard 2014; Moreton-Robinson 2000; Simpson 2014; Smith 1999; Cowlishaw et al. 2006; Watson 2002). In so doing, they seek to recover Indigenous histories and knowledge in an anti/de-colonial stance. I acknowledge that the term postcolonial theorizing over-simplifies, and might even distort, the diverse set of literatures and theoretical perspectives that I sketch here. This chapter is also heavily colored by my own interests, life story and perspective, and so the chapter speaks most closely perhaps to settler-colonial contexts (and especially British settler states) than other colonial contexts. I cannot include every author, much less every important author – exclusions are not a comment by default. I have tried to overcome these necessary shortcuts, omissions and skewed perspectives by discussing the threads that offer real illumination for planning theory. Readers will find my characterization in this chapter rather too abstracted, hardly a service to the depth of the discussions that are actually present in each sub-field and so I urge readers to make their own way into these debates. Hopefully this chapter helps point the way. In regard to definitions, I reject the use of the term ‘postcolonial’ as a unified theory, or singular body of work. Most importantly, I reject the definition of the ‘post’ as signaling a moment in time, a historical break articulated at a moment of national independence or the divestment of formal colonial rule. My use of the ‘post’ in postcolonial does not mean after, despite persistent and mostly unhelpful debates about that question. Colonialism does not have an end-date, even 168

Postcolonial Consequences and New Meanings

if the prefix ‘post’ is used as the framework for discussion. It is a present and contemporary phenomenon. Nor is it a geographical site, although it certainly has a geography. Rather, postcolonial theorizing in the way I use it in this chapter is as a mode of critical inquiry. This explains my awkward use of the verb ‘theorizing’, the purpose of which is to draw attention to core political and conceptual commitments to the work of theoretical practice: to expose how colonial relations of power are constituted and reformulated, and with what effects for colonized peoples. It is to signal a way of asking questions, conceptualizing the specifically imperialist modes of power evident in so many situations around the world with which planning is engaged and consequential.

Seeing from Elsewhere: The Ethico-Political Commitment of Postcolonial Theorizing Colonialism is a contemporary, persistent phenomenon. This means that any planning activity, interaction, policy, mediation or conflict that occurs in a context where colonial relations of domination are present is already saturated with all of the complex, ambiguous, hybrid and contested issues to which postcolonial theorizing draws our attention. Consequently, excavating, making visible and in so doing destabilizing the discursive and material operations of planning in the service of colonization are essential. A central part of this work is to expose how the West produces its Others, through discursive and material practices. Using the verb ‘orientalizing’, Edward Said (1978) unraveled what had been long accepted as normal geopolitically determined social categories – the West and the rest, with the West at the pinnacle and the rest subservient and available for study, labor, and appropriation. Recognizing this effect, as Said inspired an entire generation of work to do, then rightly demands a serious questioning of the categories and presumptions of Western thinking because they can now be seen as fundamentally obscuring certain relations of power. This particular conceptual and empirical commitment has found some purchase in urban studies and to some degree also in planning (Robinson 2006; Watson 2006, 2009; Roy 2011). The notion that theory and praxis can come from elsewhere – from ‘the South’, from insurgent practice, from anticolonial struggles – means that concepts of the urban and of planning can be reformulated, allowing different definitions, practices, issues, composition and methods to be foregrounded. Raewyn Connell has called this ‘Southern Theory’ (2007), a project that rejects the homogeneous domains of knowledge as not merely false (although that too) but enrolled in the service of power. This critique is of an urban theory approach that universalizes and extrapolates its explanatory categories. This is much more significant than simply a call for doing more urban and planning research in lots of different places to include more cities under the purview of urban theory. Rather, the assertion is that this is a theoretical blindness arising from an imperialist presumption that only the West can produce a proper form of urbanization, and all other types of experience are diminished as either different from the proper typology and norm of city development, or as interesting case studies of something different. Thus, urban theory has been found to be particularly wanting in its assumption that the political economy of globalization over-determines all urban process everywhere, which connects postcolonial theorizing with work that demands taking seriously the more-than-capitalist processes that structure relations of domination such as racism, gendering and colonialism. This critique has been mounted not only in the places where researchers study, but also operate in the very locations at which scholarly knowledge is sanctioned and legitimized. To this end, some debates in postcolonial urbanism have been criticized for merely locating interesting cases of subaltern resistance and agency (Ong 2011), rather 169

Libby Porter

than relocating the sites of theorization, an ongoing theme for debate in urban geography (see Robinson 2016; Derickson 2015) that is reigniting earlier calls (Chakrabarty 2000) for scholarship to ‘confront its Euro-centricity’ (Robinson 2016, p. 7). These debates bring into view the complicity of urban theory and its categories with imperial ideologies. They expose the normalizing discourses of improvement and benevolence intrinsic to contemporary urban theory. Poor cities, under this purview, require improvement. Improvement means to become more like wealthy Western cities. Western city experience and expertise will help those Othered poor cities to get there. Such normalizing discourses are evident in both contemporary urban scholarship and urban practice. Categorizations such as formal/informal (Roy 2005; Al-Sayyad & Roy 2003), global city and megacity (Roy 2011), planned and impossible cities (Roy 2009) are not innocent categories of analysis. They are projects of power/knowledge, uniting apparently static analytical categories with discourses of developmentalism and improvement. Planning, and our theorizing of it, have been equally charged as having a “duplicitous relationship to processes of capitalist accumulation and liberal notions of benevolent trusteeship” (Rankin 2010, p. 183). The categories of state, citizenship, property and law that we regard as both normal and normative in planning theory miserably fail in the face of quite different organizations of social life in other contexts as the work of scholars such as Vanessa Watson has shown (2008, 2009, 2012, 2014). My own work has attempted to show the limits of planning theory in the face of deep-running conflict over land and sovereignty in settler-colonial contexts (Porter 2010; Porter & Barry 2015, 2016). Theories of governance, state action, deliberation and civil society that misrecognize these contexts not only have little purchase, when dressed up as universalizing standards for planning thinking they work in the service of hegemony. But what should we make of this theoretical commitment to difference?

Identity and Difference in Postcolonial Theorizing Difference exists. Regardless of what it is that makes difference real in the world, it is clear that our experiences of the world are shaped by our position within that world. Postcolonial theorizing seeks to analyze the way colonial hegemony constructs difference in the service of its own power. In this way, difference is mobilized not as a descriptive category of sociological or anthropological interest but as a mode through which power operates. The construction of a core subject position and its Other is quite obviously a relation of power in which planning is also engaged. The demarcation of the urban poor in the majority world as ‘informal’, ‘slum’, ‘illegal’ as against the formal, regularized, legal and proper (Varley 2013; Roy 2005); the imposition of Western planning systems upon Indigenous societies and cultures because the latter are seen to have intrinsically inferior modes of socio-spatial governance (Porter 2010); the appropriation of essentialized cultural traits in the service of urban development (Anderson 1991; Jacobs 1992) – all are clear indications of the Othering processes of planning. Postcolonial theorizing seeks to disrupt those binaries and does so with at least three political projects with significance for planning. First, is to expose Othering as a relation of power where stereotypes of ‘culture’ serve to maintain racial, cultural and geopolitical orders of power. Developmentalist presumptions say less about local conditions than they do about Western perspectives about what there is and should be in the world. Logics of improvement and betterment, based on a stigmatization and Othering of difference serve not only the colonial frontier, but also the frontierist ideologies of urban renewal and redevelopment.

170

Postcolonial Consequences and New Meanings

Second, is to demote Western cultures from their status as not-a-culture (Latour 1991). An essential part of the argument and struggle against the dizzying levels of colonial dispossession and subjugation, has been to illuminate the cultural modes and norms specific to Western worldviews in practicing that dispossession. Important conceptual debates have been made in this regard by Indigenous scholars, who have successfully demonstrated that there are in fact two systems of law, government, culture and economy – indeed two sovereignties – present in settler-colonial states (Coulthard 2014; Alfred & Corntassel 2005; Watson 2015; Dodson 1994; Langton 2002). My own work has tried to demonstrate that the particular spatial rationalities that operate within planning are no less a cultural artifact than the specific spatial rationalities that operate within Indigenous societies (Porter 2007, 2010). Many of the universalizing conceits that operate within planning theory today are derived from being able to artificially remove from planning any hint of its own cultural specificity. Consequently, to hold planning properly to account for its complicity in colonial (and especially settler-colonial) projects of dispossession, first of all demands that we take seriously that planning comes from a cultural perspective – it is not a view from nowhere. Third is to reclaim and restore those subjectivities and voices that have been marked as different (and thus subjugated), so that they can speak on their own terms. Much work has been done on making visible the invisible histories and stories of planning theory and praxis and thus deconstructing the modernist pillars of planning (Sandercock 1995, 1998), and recovering other voices that are speaking to, and about, planning (Sandercock & Attili 2010). The vitality of Indigenous planning has been especially important (Jojola 2000, 2008; Matunga 2013; Hibbard 2006; Walker et al. 2013) with the express purpose to “reclaim and assert Indigenous planning as a necessary field of scholarship and planning practice” (Walker et al. 2013). Yet an immediate problem should strike us here. The critique of binaries inherent in postcolonial theorizing has a real tendency to produce its own binary, Othering forms of thinking (precisely the critique that Chibber (2013) mounts against the Subaltern Studies work). For of course, the ontological categories of cultural difference reproduce all sorts of other binaries, by necessity. Postcolonial theorizing seeks to recover that pole of the binary that has been profoundly subjected to colonial rule. Yet such a project of recovery immediately signals a paradox. What is it that is being recovered – some essential, pure form of voice and subjectivity? The kinds of philosophical lineages and commitments present in postcolonial theorizing usually reject the impetus to locate origins and pure essences, precisely because such an effort can play right back into the hands of colonial power. If the colonialist mentality is that the natives are backward, primitive and uncivilized, then it can hardly be argued that the same mindset can be used to invert the conclusion: that the natives in their pure form are closer to nature, their traditions unsoiled by the West, their solutions and forms of governance alternative, sweet and just. This is merely a reversal, not an undoing, of primitivist binary logic. Significant and important critiques of postcolonial theorizing have been made along these lines. There is a deeply essentializing tendency that lies within the work of recovery and reconstitution, particularly when the form that it takes is a static, essentialized version of colonized peoples, stripped of colonial context. And what would it mean for colonized subjects to speak on their own terms? If culture is not static, as a postcolonial stance would claim, then how can an authentic voice from colonized subjects be asserted and recognized? In social settings marked by the violence of colonialism, dimensions of representation, agency, identity and recognition can never be neutral. It is to those tricky postcolonial questions that I turn in the next section.

171

Libby Porter

Representation, Resistance and the Politics of Recognition From early periods of frontier violence in settler-colonial contexts, to independence and anticolonial resistance movements in the franchise colonies, to vigorous land rights political claims, labor struggles, court cases and any number of other modes of direct and claim-making action, colonized peoples have asserted their identities, sovereignties, laws and voices. Many of those struggles by necessity utilize the essential characteristics of an intrinsic cultural, religious or ethnic difference from the colonizing power because the point is to articulate and claim an ontologically separate space from colonial rule. This essentialized difference is utilized in two ways: as a source of strength, identity and agency; and as a critically important weapon against the standardizing hegemonic forces against which they struggle. What Gayatri Spivak has called ‘strategic essentialism’ becomes defensible when used to “fight off domination by outsiders in order to make themselves heard within their own experience” (Weaver 2005, p. 227). Much of the struggle, especially in settler-colonial contexts against colonizing forces, has been on gaining access to forums of decision-making, reclaiming subjectivity and asserting control over both space and cultural modes of representation. For representation is powerful – words and symbols can be used to harm, to diminish, to objectify as much as they can to acknowledge, recognize, recover and empower. Culture is a powerful trope through which resistance and state recognition is articulated and negotiated, particularly in settler-colonial contexts. It is a keyword signifying difference, rights and sovereignty (a ‘strategic essentialism’ in Spivak’s terms), but is also uttered in a language colonial powers can understand. In Western terms, culture is something different from nature, and thus culture can be mobilized especially in the service of “cultures that know nature differently” (Jacobs 1996, p. 136). Yet we should pay close attention to the profound costs entailed in such an approach. For these acts of anti/de-colonial struggle are by definition and circumstance bound into the persistent shadow of coloniality. Such questions of representation and agency were the subject of Gayatri Spivak’s essay Can the Subaltern Speak? in which she concluded the answer is both yes and no (Spivak 1994). The subaltern must try but cannot speak because in trying, the speaking can only be heard if it is in a language recognizable to the very force against which the subaltern speaks. Trying to be heard automatically marks the limit of being able to speak. The distinct context of settler-colonialism also entails a massive cost for the speaking subaltern, in this case Indigenous people speaking back to settler society. For in settler-colonialism, the politics of position is not just a central issue it is the issue (Wolfe 1999) due to the logic of elimination. Settlers remain, and in remaining seek to reproduce and perform anew their institutions of sovereignty, belonging and property. Indigenous societies are not only superfluous to that endeavor, they have to be eliminated for settler-colonialism to succeed. This means that any practical recourse for Indigenous recognition in settler-colonial states is largely ideological, and the question of who speaks “goes far beyond liberal concerns with equity, dialogue or access to the academy” (Wolfe 1999, p. 3). The assertion of difference and the articulation of a politics of marginality and struggle thus conjures a rather paradoxical politics. For by speaking in certain kinds of ways, the presence and persistence of colonial modes of subjugation are normalized and reified, precisely as Fanon concluded. While colonized subjects most certainly speak, and speak they should, the colonial relations from which they speak are impossible to transcend. The only language through which they can be heard and recognized is the very language they speak against. For this reason there has emerged vigorous debate about the extent to which such forms of representation and recognition are merely a “politics of distraction” (Corntassel 2012). This is not to deny the legitimacy of struggle, but to seek clarity on the actual forms of recognition 172

Postcolonial Consequences and New Meanings

that come to be open for negotiation. This debate has been particularly pronounced in settlercolonial studies. Demands by Indigenous people center on sovereignty, political authority, return of or access to lands and self-determination. They are overwhelmingly cast as claims for recognition upon the settler-state, who seek to settle those claims, either by rejecting them outright as the recent claims of the Bedouin in the Negev attest (Amara & Miller 2013; Yiftachel et al. 2006) or by finding ways to accommodate those claims within existing orders of governance, sovereignty and land ownership (Povinelli 2002). Whether or not those claims are successful, they are all heavily structured through a mode of recognition that seeks to reconcile the affirmation of cultural difference, encapsulating liberal freedom, with the requirements of universal citizenship and state authority assumed by the liberal settler-state (Butler & Athanasiou 2013). The forms of cultural difference might be accommodated, even perhaps positively affirmed, but only within a framing that does not undermine the ultimate sovereignty of the settler-state. James Tully (1995) has called this logic ‘monological recognition’, and a recent very important text by Glen Coulthard (2014) maps the contours and limits of this profoundly seductive contemporary operation of colonial power. The subject position always holding the authority as recognizer is the settler-state. Those asking to be recognized become objects of recognition upon which the settler-state might choose to dole out its benevolence. The asymmetry of such a situation, and the perpetuation of colonial relations of domination that such a mode of recognition performs, are stark. It becomes clear how important the questions of who has authority and the power to represent and create representations of things in the world are for planning in postcolonial settings. Professions, like planning, that authorize certain skillsets and anoint the people who recognizably have those skillsets, produce voices of authority that have the power to represent others and to mark out spaces within which other forms of representative debate can take place. Social subjects marked as Others have less legitimacy (at earlier colonial moments, no legitimacy at all), and are cast as the objects of representation. We only need to think of planning’s invocation of ‘representing the public interest’, and the core aspiration to create consultative settings where different voices representing different perspectives can all be heard, to see with great clarity how expertise, authority and representation are all potentially modes of colonial power in contemporary planning. And yet, this is both an accurate and at the same time fundamentally constraining perspective of postcolonial representational politics. It is, of course, clear that mounting claims for recognition of an essential difference within the very systems against which such claims are asserted is a profound ethical limit. But it is also a functionalist argument: any utterance is immediately distorted by its location in a world after (but not beyond) colonization, rendering any Indigenous or subaltern struggle immediately as opposite to that of colonizer, and automatically co-opted into its workings of hegemonic power. It has the distinct feeling of a dead-end. If this knotty paradox is not worked at both in theory and practice, then nothing can ever be undone, no transformative politics will ever become possible. A number of possible conceptual avenues, with less of a dead-end feeling, present themselves in contemporary scholarship. I will return to them in the concluding section below. For now, the discussion turns to land. For just as postcolonial struggles are about identity and representation they are also, like the colonial conditions that produced them, about space and place.

Planning and the Production of Colonial Space It is not too radical a claim now to reject conceptions of space as a neutral container unencumbered by historical relations, and instead see space as a social product (Lefebvre 1991), soaked 173

Libby Porter

with processes of domination and subordination, solidarity and cooperation (Massey 2005). Producing colonial space (for an empire must have a space) has been the primary location of planning’s enrolment and complicity. Colonialism, through either explicit or nascent practices of planning, dramatically and violently imposed a different spatial order on other societies, reconfiguring geographical activities, social relations, and institutions. In settler-colonial contexts this did the work of dispossession along the way. Oren Yiftachel has called this the dark side of planning (Yiftachel 1998), one that imposes “ethno-national spatial control, often in conflict with groups holding counter territorial claims” (Yiftachel 2006, p. 217). In that essay he lamented the lack of theoretical conversation about it in planning theory. A robust theoretical conversation is even today still emerging, but its contours are present and offer fertile ground for further development and discussion. Two particularly important dimensions for a postcolonial theorizing of planning’s production of colonial space are accumulation by dispossession, and the spatial cultures of planning. For colonial rule to work, it must spatialize. This means it must assert sovereignty: (political) rule over (geographical) territory. This makes Marx’s theory of primitive accumulation particularly important to postcolonial theorizing efforts, and it has indeed been a central theme. But in so doing there has been an important emphasis on reworking primitive accumulation, delinking it from the stadial definition Marx gave it (primitive accumulation came first, and then was superseded by other forms of accumulation) to a view more akin to Rosa Luxembourg’s, who argued that far from being finished, primitive accumulation is a constitutive feature, always, of capitalism. Such an approach has been advanced by David Harvey who has argued that primitive accumulation can be rethought as ‘accumulation by dispossession’ – a colonization of spaces to be accumulated (Harvey 2003), which constitutes an ongoing phenomenon, an ‘omnipresence’ (Roy 2006) in colonial contexts. Settler-colonial contexts exemplify the omnipresence of primitive accumulation par excellence because it is only in settler colonies where the focus of colonial practice is appropriating native lands, rather than native labor. Settlers stay. And in order to stay, lands must be expropriated and brought into the enactment and justification of an imposed sovereignty. The expropriation of land is the foundation on which a replacement society is built in settler colonies, or as Patrick Wolfe (2006, p. 388) put it, “territoriality is settler colonialism’s specific irreducible element”. Dene scholar Glen Coulthard (2014) reads Marx’s theory of primitive accumulation through an anticolonial lens, to make a related argument. For settler-colonialism, the hunger for land is relentless as it is the basis of rule, thus “Settler-colonialism is territorially acquisitive in perpetuity” (2014, p. 152, emphasis in original). Primitive accumulation is thus not a historical event or backdrop, but the mode through which colonial capitalism occurs. Colonialism is a structure of dispossession. Consequently any regime purportedly designed to recognize contemporary Indigenous claims for land is embedded in a system that will insist on denying those claims. So what then of planning in this rather depressing reading of colonial space production? The nascent and explicit practices and impulses of planning are emerging as a key site for understanding exactly how colonialism does its work, for example in relation to settler-colonial contexts, how dispossession is operationalized (Harris 2004). To be produced, space has to be activated, and continuously re-activated, into the social, through specific technologies and practices. As I observed in earlier work (Porter 2010), these actively produce their own mediated realities and this cannot be innocent neither in settler-colonial nor other kinds of colonial contexts. These ‘spatial cultures’ that I define as the “activities, readings, desires, philosophies, technologies and regulatory methods that the historical record shows actively and materially constructed colonies” (Porter 2010), are a diverse set of practices. Our best method to apprehend them is to 174

Postcolonial Consequences and New Meanings

investigate the specific processes that produce space in colonial contexts and ask what forms of domination and subjugation they enlist. There is much important work that planning theory can draw on to do this kind of analysis. Rabinow (1989) articulates colonial design sensibilities and their imposition, indeed full articulation, in colonial settings, while others expose colonial orderings of space through the regulation of colonial space (Legg 2007; Yeoh 1996). Jacobs’ work in settler-colonial Australia (1996) has analyzed not only the hard face of regulatory control of urban space in particular, but the psycho-affective state of settler-colonial relations (Gelder & Jacobs 1998). The importance of city-building to colonial efforts has been well articulated (Edmonds 2010; Yiftachel 1996), and Yiftachel has importantly argued for attention also to the time dimension of colonial spatial control, through his conception of ‘gray space’ (Yiftachel 2009). Such a critical reading is, in my view, essential, and not only for exposing the operations of power. It is also intrinsically important to the search for more hopeful possibilities – in short, for grasping ways of doing, thinking and imagining planning that seek to decolonize. For “exposing the details of the ‘dark side’ is never an end in itself . . . it is only the beginning of unpacking the distorted ‘truth’ disseminated by power, as a necessary foundation for transformative mobilization” (Yiftachel 2006, p. 219). I turn to this issue in the final section.

The Challenge: Decolonizing Planning Theory? Like it or not, planning actors, whether we are scholars, students, researchers, consultants, practitioners or activists, each have a role to play in this twin process of exposing and undoing colonial dynamics. This is so even as we acknowledge the limits imposed by our own positionality. Spivak calls this unlearning our privilege as loss (see Landry & MacLean 1996), marking the dimension of our own personal and structural privilege as a constant focus for critique, given the way it operates to obscure relations of domination. Usually none of us is aware of the daily privileges we inhabit until perhaps we are confronted with a situation where our privilege suddenly becomes uncomfortably obvious. It is patently uncomfortable to have privileges, positionality and even the fundamental tenets of planning so viscerally challenged. Problematizing what has been taken for granted and exposing how we are each implicated in relations of power that produce domination are not easy things to think about. Doing so can often lead to a deep sense of gloom, and anxiety (Gooder & Jacobs 2011) a charge that is often leveled at critical social theories. That bleak view can inculcate what Kowal (2015) has recently identified as an anxious disavowal, particularly, for example, among white settlers who support, in the settler-colonial context of Australia, Indigenous rights. Writing from the context of Canada, Regan (2011) positions this anxiety rather differently, showing how it can produce a more positive process of understanding the ‘settler within’. These are serious concerns of political, theoretical, scholarly and practical import. I want to argue that such critical attention to the structures of power we all inhabit is not only necessary but also offers hope: a promise that allowing our perspectives to be unsettled produces new and potentially transformative possibilities. Critical theoretical stances can be very helpful ways of thinking, as they demand examination of long-held assumptions. They are a reminder that none of us are outside the web of potentially oppressive social relations, none of us innocent of all the various ways that socially unjust practices are perpetuated today. And that is promising because it calls us to account, demanding humility, respect and a critical open-mindedness. Conceptualizing the spaces within which such postcolonial politics unfold as hybrid, rather than one thing or another, is a useful starting point. Homi Bhabha calls this the ‘thirdspace’ (Bhabha 1994), or in Mary Louise Pratt’s terminology the ‘contact zone’ (Pratt 1991), in which 175

Libby Porter

there is an inevitably hybrid and unsettled grappling of cultures and worldviews, never symmetrical, but resulting in unstable, hardly predictable and always contested cultural outcomes. This is hopeful, at the same time as critical, because that unsettled grappling might, tomorrow, just turn out differently. The future is up for grabs. Saturated with coloniality, yes, but not fully over-determined. Counter-hegemonic agency exists and is being thoroughly articulated from the social worlds of those who have been subjected to colonization processes, reminding us of Fanon’s insistence that transformative praxis emerges from the lifeworlds of the colonized (1967). That agency is articulated in modes that are hybrid and relational at the same time as they express a firm oppositional stance and differentiated position from Western hegemony. Two important examples of this kind of work from settler-colonial contexts offer potential analytical frameworks and ethical commitments. Glen Coulthard’s 2014 book is a fine example of this kind of thinking, as he articulates together Marx, Fanon, Dene Elders and a relationship to land to build a theoretical and practical framework for transformative anticolonial praxis. Irene Watson (2015) similarly offers a combined reading of Western and Indigenous law, one that reasserts a primal position of the latter in the face of the power of the former in highly productive ways. These kinds of theorizing toward praxis offer models for the kind of theoretical work ahead for planning. The conceits of research itself, and the systems through which planning knowledge is produced (funding and granting bodies, the structural exclusions of universities) must also be transformed. Linda Tuhiwai-Smith’s work (1999) should be important for planning researchers and theorists for its crucial teachings about how social science research methods reproduce colonial subjectivities, and about the alternatives possible to transform those subjectivities. Those methods must pay attention to knowledge not in the narrow social science sense, but as a relational, active and embodied engagement with the world, as for example Sandercock and Attili (2010), Leanne Simpson (2014) and Irene Watson (2015) do, each in their own way. Also important will be a commitment to theorizing from any context or location. Recent advances made by theorists such as Robinson (2016), Simone (2011), Connell (2007, 2014), Watson (2003, 2006, 2014), Roy (2006, 2010, 2011), Yiftachel (2006, 2009) and Avni and Yiftachel (2014) show how northern sites of theory-making can be de-privileged and the ‘everywhere else’ of northern theorizing re-articulated as much more than simply empirical fodder for naturalized categories. Instead, we could try what Robinson calls ‘thinking cities through elsewhere’ (2016) which involves at least in part an ‘ungrounding’ (ibid., p. 17) rather than a stabilization of concepts about urban life. These approaches offer forms of accountability in the production of planning knowledge and theory, as much as in its practice. Ananya Roy articulated some years ago the importance of planning taking such accountability seriously as part of a more transformative postcolonial ‘praxis in the time of empire’ (2006). Part of the challenge for planning theory, then, is to unlearn the categories and forms of theorizing that have become naturalized in our thinking. But most important is to unlearn them in a way that acknowledges how the privilege intrinsic to those categories and forms has always been a profound loss, obscuring from view other possibilities and purposefully creating conditions of subjugation and domination. This painful process of unlearning is one of producing accountability, as well as a necessary step in liberation.

References Al-Sayyad, N. & Roy, A., 2003. Urban Informality: Transnational Perspectives from the Middle East, Latin America and South Asia, Boulder, CO: Lexington Books. Alfred, T. & Corntassel, J., 2005. Being Indigenous: Resurgences against contemporary colonialism. Government and Opposition, 40, pp. 597–614.

176

Postcolonial Consequences and New Meanings Amara, A. & Miller, Z., 2013. Unsettling settlements: Law, land and planning in the Naqab. In A. Amara, I. Abu-Saad, & O. Yiftachel, eds. Indigenous (In)Justice: Human Rights Law and Bedouin Arabs in the Naqab/Negev. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Anderson, K., 1991. Vancouver’s Chinatown: Racial Discourse in Canada 1875–1890, Buffalo and Kingston: McGill-Queen University Press. Avni, N. & Yiftachel, O., 2014. The new divided city? Planning and ‘gray space’ between global northwest and south-east. In S. Parnell & S. Oldfield, eds. The Routledge Handbook on Cities of the Global South. London: Routledge, pp. 487–505. Bhabha, H.K., 1994. The Location of Culture, London: Routledge. Butler, J., 2000. Competing universalities. In J. Butler, E. Laclau, & S. Žižek, eds. Contingency, Hegemony, Universality: Contemporary Dialogues on the Left. London: Verso, pp. 136–181. Butler, J. & Athanasiou, A., 2013. Dispossession: The Performative in the Political, Cambridge: Polity Press. Chakrabarty, D., 2000. Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference, Woodstock: Princeton University Press. Chibber, V., 2013. Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital, London: Verso. Connell, R., 2007. Southern Theory, Crows Nest, NSW: Allen and Unwin. Connell, R., 2014. Using Southern Theory: Decolonizing social thought in theory, research and application. Planning Theory, 13(2), pp. 210–223. Corntassel, J., 2012. Re-envisioning resurgence: Indigenous pathways to decolonization and sustainable self-determination. Decolonization: Indigeneity, Education & Society, 1(1), pp. 86–101. Coulthard, G., 2014. Red Skins, White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of Recognition, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Cowlishaw, G., Kowal, E., & Lea, T., 2006. Introduction: Double binds. In T. Lea, E. Kowal, & G. Cowlishaw, eds. Moving Anthropology: Critical Indigenous Studies. Darwin: Charles Darwin University Press, pp. 1–16. Derickson, K.D., 2015. Urban geography I: Locating urban theory in the ‘urban age’. Progress in Human Geography, 39(5), pp. 647–657. Dodson, M., 1994. Towards the existence of indigenous rights: Policy, power and self-determination. Race and Class, 35(4), pp. 65–76. Edmonds, P., 2010. Urbanizing Frontiers: Indigenous Peoples and Settlers in 19th Century Pacific Rim Cities, Vancouver: UBC Press. Fanon, F., 1963. The Wretched of the Earth, Harmondsworth: Penguin. Fanon, F., 1967. Black Skin, White Masks, UK: Paladin. Gelder, K. & Jacobs, J.M., 1998. Uncanny Australia: Sacredness and Identity in a Postcolonial Nation, Melbourne: Melbourne University Press. Gooder, H. & Jacobs, J.M., 2011. ‘On the border of the unsayable’: The apology in postcolonizing Australia. Interventions, 2(2), pp. 229–247. Guha, R., 1998. Dominance without Hegemony, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Harris, C., 2004. How did colonialism dispossess? Comments from an edge of empire. Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 94(1), pp. 165–182. Harvey, D., 2003. The New Imperialism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hibbard, M., 2006. Tribal sovereignty, the white problem and reservation planning. Journal of Planning History, 5(2), pp. 87–105. Jacobs, J.M., 1992. Cultures of the past and urban transformation: The Spitalfields Market redevelopment in East London. In K. Anderson & F. Gale, eds. Cultural Geographies. Australia: Longman, pp. 241–261. Jacobs, J.M., 1996. Edge of Empire: Postcolonialism and the City, London: Routledge. Jojola, T., 2000. Indigenous planning and tribal community development. Planners Network, 139(1), pp. 7–9. Jojola, T., 2008. Indigenous planning: An emerging context. Canadian Journal of Urban Research, 17 (Supplement), pp. 37–47. Kowal, E., 2015. Trapped in the Gap: Doing Good in Indigenous Australia, New York: Bergahn Books. Landry, D. & MacLean, G., 1996. The Spivak Reader: Selected Works of Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, New York: Routledge. Lefebvre, H., 1991. The Production of Space, Oxford: Blackwell. Legg, S., 2007. Spaces of Colonialism: Delhi’s Urban Governmentalities, Malden: Blackwell. Massey, D., 2005. For Space, London: SAGE Publications.

177

Libby Porter Matunga, H., 2013. Theorizing Indigenous planning. In R. Walker, T. Jojola, & D. Natcher, eds. Reclaiming Indigenous Planning. Montreal: McGill-Queen University Press, pp. 3–32. Moreton-Robinson, A., 2000. Talkin’ up to the White Woman: Indigenous Women and Feminism, St Lucia: University of Queensland Press. Porter, L., 2007. Producing forests. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 26(4), pp. 466–477. Porter, L., 2010. Unlearning the Colonial Cultures of Planning, Aldershot: Ashgate. Porter, L. & Barry, J., 2015. Bounded recognition: Urban planning and the textual mediation of Indigenous rights in Canada and Australia. Critical Policy Studies, 9(1), pp.22-40. Porter, L. & Barry, J., 2016. Planning for Coexistence: Recognizing Indigenous Rights through Land-use Planning in Canada and Australia, Aldershot: Ashgate. Povinelli, E.A., 2002. The Cunning of Recognition: Indigenous Alterities and the Making of Australian Multiculturalism, Michigan: Duke University Press. Pratt, M.L., 1991. Arts of the contact zone. Profession, pp. 33–40. Rabinow, P., 1989. French Modern: Norms and Forms of the Social Environment, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Rankin, K., 2010. Reflexivity and post-colonial critique: Toward an ethics of accountability in planning praxis. Planning Theory, 9(3), pp. 181–199. Regan, P., 2011. Unsettling the Settler Within, Vancouver: UBC Press. Robinson, J., 2006. Ordinary Cities: Between Modernity and Development, Oxford: Routledge. Robinson, J., 2016. Thinking cities through elsewhere: Comparative tactics for a more global urban studies. Progress in Human Geography, 40(1), pp. 3–29. Roy, A., 2005. Urban informality: Toward an epistemology of planning. Journal of the American Planning Association, 71(2), pp. 147–158. Roy, A., 2006. Praxis in the time of empire. Planning Theory, 5(1), pp. 7–29. Roy, A., 2009. Why India cannot plan its cities: Informality, insurgence and the idiom of urbanization. Planning Theory, 8(1), pp. 76–87. Roy, A., 2010. Informality and the politics of planning. In J. Hillier & P. Healey, eds. The Ashgate Research Companion to Planning Theory Vol. 1. Farnham: Ashgate, pp. 87–107. Roy, A., 2011. Urbanisms, worlding practices and the theory of planning. Planning Theory, 10(6), pp. 6–15. Said, E., 1978. Orientalism, New York: Pantheon Books. Said, E.W., 1993. Culture and Imperialism, New York: Alfred A Knopf. Sandercock, L., 1995. Voices from the Borderlands: A meditation on a metaphor. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 14(2), pp. 77–88. Sandercock, L., (ed.) 1998. Making the Invisible Visible: A Multicultural Planning History, Berkeley: University of California Press. Sandercock, L. & Attili, G., 2010. Finding Our Way, Canada: Moving Images Distribution. Sheppard, E., Leitner, H. & Maringanti, A., 2013. Provincializing global urbanism: A manifesto. Urban Geography, 34(7), pp. 893–900. Simone, A., 2011. The surfacing of urban life. City, 15(3–4), pp. 355–364. Simpson, L.B., 2014. Land as pedagogy: Nishnaabeg intelligence and rebellious transformation. Decolonization: Indigeneity, Education & Society, 3(3), pp. 1–25. Smith, L.T., 1999. Decolonizing Methodologies: Research and Indigenous Peoples, Dunedin: University of Otago Press. Spivak, G.C., 1985. Three women’s texts and a critique of imperialism. Critical Inquiry, 12(1), pp. 243–261. Spivak, G.C., 1994. Can the subaltern speak? In P. Williams & L. Chrisman, eds. Colonial Discourse and Postcolonial Theory: A Reader. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 66–111. Spivak, G.C., 1996. More on Power/Knowledge. In D. Landry and G. MacLean, ed. The Spivak Reader: Selected Works of Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. New York: Routledge, pp. 142–174. Tully, J., 1995. Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Varley, A., 2013. Postcolonialising informality? Environment and Planning D: Society and Space, 31(1), pp. 4–22. Walker, R., Jojola, T., & Natcher, D., 2013. Reclaiming Indigenous Planning, Montreal: McGill-Queen University Press. Watson, I., 2002. Buried alive. Law and Critique, 13, pp. 253–269. Watson, I., 2015. Aboriginal Peoples, Colonialism and International Law: Raw Law, London: Routledge. Watson, V., 2003. Conflicting rationalities: Implications for planning theory and ethics. Planning Theory and Practice, 4(4), pp. 395–407.

178

Postcolonial Consequences and New Meanings Watson, V., 2006. Deep difference: Diversity, planning and ethics. Planning Theory, 5(1), pp. 31–50. Watson, V., 2008. Down to Earth: Linking planning theory and practice in the ‘Metropole’ and beyond. International Planning Studies, 13(3), pp. 223–237. Watson, V., 2009. Seeing from the South: Refocusing urban planning on the globe’s central urban issues. Urban Studies, 46(11), pp. 2259–2275. Watson, V., 2012. Planning and the ‘stubborn realities’ of global south-east cities : Some emerging ideas. Planning Theory, 12(1), pp. 81–100. Watson, V., 2014. Learning planning from the South. In S. Parnell & S. Oldfield, eds. Routledge Handbook on Cities of the Global South. London: Routledge, pp. 111–126. Weaver, J., 2005. Indigenousness and Indigeneity. In H. Schwartz & S. Ray, eds. A Companion to Postcolonial Studies. Malden, MA: Wiley, pp. 221–235. Wolfe, P., 1999. Settler Colonialism and the Transformation of Anthropology: The Politics and Poetics of an Ethnographic Event, London: Cassell. Wolfe, P., 2006. Settler colonialism and the elimination of the native. Journal of Genocide Research, 8(4), pp. 387–409. Yeoh, B., 1996. Contesting Space: Power Relations and the Urban Built Environment in Colonial Singapore, Kuala Lumpur: Oxford University Press. Yiftachel, O., 1996. The internal frontier: Territorial control and ethnic relations in Israel. Regional Studies, 30(5), pp. 493–508. Yiftachel, O., 1998. Planning and social control: Exploring the ‘dark side’. Journal of Planning Literature, 12(4), pp. 395–406. Yiftachel, O., 2006. Essay: Re-engaging planning theory? Towards ‘South-Eastern’ perspectives. Planning Theory, 5(3), pp. 211–222. Yiftachel, O., 2009. Critical theory and ‘gray space’: Mobilization of the colonized. City, 13(2–3), pp. 246–263. Yiftachel, O., Goldhaber, R., & Nuriel, R., 2006. Urban justice and recognition: Affirmation and hostility in Beer Sheva. In P. Marcuse, J. Connolly, J. Novy, I. Olivio, C. Potter & J. Steil eds. Searching for the Just City: Debates in Urban Theory and Practice. Abingdon: Routledge, pp. 120–135.

179

15 POSTPOLITICS AND PLANNING Jonathan Metzger1

Recent years have seen a flurry of discussions about postpolitics or the “postpolitical condition” in relation to a wide range of issues broadly concerning contemporary urban planning and governance. These include – but are not limited to – the regeneration of the London South Bank (Baeten, 2009), the structure of the UK planning system (e.g. Allmendinger & Haughton, 2012, 2015), the professional urban discourse in Sweden (Tunström & Bradley, 2014) mega hospital projects in London (Raco, 2014a), golf courses in Singapore (Neo, 2010), highway tunnels in Melbourne (Legacy, 2015), the enactment of complacent consumerist subjects in urban planning in Helsingborg (Ek, 2011), football-related city branding in Russia (Makarychev & Yatsyk, 2014),‘Big Box’ retail development in Vancouver (Rosol, 2014), Irish “ghost estates” (O’Callaghan et al., 2014), new urbanist developments in Scotland (MacLeod, 2013) and sustainability-related regional development policies in Sweden (Hilding-Rydevik et al., 2011). What unites these scholars is their diagnosis that a number of aspects of contemporary planning practice are deeply troubling, particularly from a democracy perspective. The primary cause of worry is that an exaggerated and uncritical infatuation with ideas of partnership governance and “participatory” consensus-building risks leading to a situation in which planning procedures merely function to window-dress democratically deeply deficient governance processes. Postpolitical practices are thus seen to “paper over the inequalities which run through society, disavowing the rifts in society, and foreclosing potential struggles for alternative political futures” (Van Puymbroeck & Oosterlynck, 2014: 87). Accordingly, the workings of postpolitics must therefore be understood as (anti)political mechanisms that continuously work to veil the possibility of a radically different society. From this perspective, contemporary governance innovations such as stakeholder-based governance regimes and various forms of invited participation, are by no means innocent technical improvements that tackle democratic deficits, but rather produce such deficits by providing “ever more effective forms of disavowing the contingency of contemporary societies” and hiding from sight “the multiple hierarchical differences that structure them” (Van Puymbroeck & Oosterlynck, 2014: 103). In the process they generate “Kafkaesque” governance arrangements (Metzger, 2011) which all but completely lack transparency and legitimacy. Nevertheless, these same opaque networked policymaking mazes of vague responsibilities and blurry accountabilities often become labeled as “good governance” (Deas, 2013), despite the fact that they lead to

180

Postpolitics and Planning

policymaking situations in which it can be difficult to even know if a decision has been made, let alone by whom or on basis of what authority. Thus, the literature on postpolitics and planning aims at pinpointing and flagging up new forms of politics in planning processes which function to suppress or preemptively foreclose possibilities toward dissent through bypassing, short-circuiting or circumscribing difficult and contentious issues concerning the specification of desirable futures (Allmendinger & Haughton, 2010; Metzger, 2011). Yet, this fairly new strand of planning scholarship is far from uncontroversial. Some critics fiercely question whether the phenomenon under debate really exists at all outside the pages of scholarly journals. Others agree that what the postpolitics literature tries to describe might well be real, but nevertheless question the productivity of labeling this phenomenon as postpolitics – arguing that an excessive focus on this type of analysis might risk reproducing the very effects it claims to be exposing. However, there are also more ambivalent commentators to this emerging corpus of scholarship who do not unreservedly pledge allegiance to the postpolitics thesis, but nevertheless see great value in the work being performed under its banner. I, for one, admit to being among these. Therefore, in this chapter I will let this ambivalence shine through by, on the one hand, attempting to do justice to the important contributions made by postpolitical analysis in contemporary planning research, but, on the other hand, to also be forthright about some of the flaws and internal contradictions in parts of the existing literature. Further, and relatedly, I believe that for postpolitical analysis to stay relevant to planning research it needs to keep evolving. Perhaps most important is the need to shed the idea that just labeling something as being postpolitical could ever be a final, enlightening explanation in itself. Rather, for the concept to ever have any real bite it must become a flexible, yet precise analytical tool that can be used to trim the eye to specific and otherwise difficult to grasp insidious developments within contemporary planning practice.

Diagnosing the “Postpolitical Condition” Discussions about postpolitics generally take as their starting point the post-foundational strands of political philosophy that were developed in the 1990s (see Metzger et al., 2014; Wilson & Swyngedouw, 2014; and further Marchart, 2007). The concept is commonly associated with the work of philosophers Chantal Mouffe (2005), Slavoj Žižek (1999) – and probably most distinctly (even though he himself does not use this specific term), Jacques Rancière (1998 [1995]). One of the things that unifies these thinkers is that they all reacted against a specific post-1989 zeitgeist in Europe which was marked by hyperbolic proclamations about “the End of History”, and dreams of a unipolar world imagined to usher in the permanent global reign of liberal democracy and free market capitalism. Within the sphere of political thinking, the corollary of this discourse was the rise to prominence of “big tent” consensual politics, quintessentially embodied in the so-called “Third Way” market-oriented social democracy. The general spirit of the time has been characterized as building upon the assumption that “[p]artisan conflicts are a thing of the past and consensus can be achieved through dialogue” (Mouffe, 2005: 1). For Chantal Mouffe, the postpolitical zeitgeist of the 1990s was marked by a democratically dangerous colonization and suppression of the political by politics. In Mouffe’s vocabulary, the latter refers to the concrete everyday practices, procedures and institutions through which the social is ordered and organized into societies (‘governance’, so to speak), while the former refers to the various fundamental conflict lines that run through any given society. Mouffe’s substantial argument is that the political is an ubiquitous feature of society that risks exploding into violent

181

Jonathan Metzger

confrontation at any time unless recognized and constructively engaged with. Thus, it is of utmost importance that democratic, open societies do not seek to suppress or deny the existence of fundamental political differences. These must instead be allowed to find public forums in which they can be explored and articulated in ways that can contribute to “taming” potentially violent antagonism into democratically productive agonism. The latter term implies that fundamentally opposed political ideals and interests are allowed to play out against each other in democratically acceptable forms based on – if not sympathy or understanding – at least a mutual recognition of legitimacy and respect for difference (Mouffe, 2005). In contrast to democratic political processes in which violent antagonisms are transformed into productive agonism, Mouffe identifies postpolitical situations as those in which the institutions of politics come to function as a mere managerial apparatus that effectively suppresses the political, i.e. fundamental issues regarding the organization of society, in the name of broad consensus and stability. In such situations the ostensibly democratic state becomes so only on paper, forcing truly political issues to play out in more or less violently antagonistic forms in other spheres of society – further generating a general sense of alienation from the institutions of formal politics, thus undercutting the legitimacy of democratic decision-making institutions. In his influential work Disagreement (1995), Jacques Rancière makes a similar analysis to Mouffe, but with some important divergences. In contrast to Mouffe, who places her hope in a re-invigorated representative democracy, Rancière asserts that any apparatus of governance must constitute a “police order” based on a particular “partition of the sensible”, i.e. an assignment of “proper places” and roles in society to various portions of the population. Such an order always inevitably builds upon direct or indirect ascriptions of who or what belongs where and with what rights and obligations. To Rancière, the only properly political moment (or “democratic sequence”) is when the existing police order is put into question by the “part of no part” in the name of equality – i.e. when the entire existing system is put into question on the basis of the exclusions it performs, and those who are not accommodated for within the existing order. Rancière does not himself use the term “postpolitics”, but nevertheless turns vehemently against what he sees to be the blight of democracy in our age – a condition he dubs “post-democracy”,2 marked by a consensual politics within which it is taken as given who and what matters and should be taken into account, and in which ways. Rancière identifies three specific contemporary forms of depoliticization (arche-, para- and meta-politics) that are employed to disavow (in the sense of deny and oppose) that any governance order is fundamentally arbitrary and by necessity exclusionary – and therefore always obfuscates the fundamental conflicts that will mark any specific society. Perhaps most contentious and controversial among the philosophers associated with postpolitical theory, and the originator of the concept itself, is Slavoj Žižek. In contrast to Mouffe who defines the postpolitical condition as one in which the political is repressed but returns as violent antagonism, or Rancière who sees the repeated disavowal of the political which is nevertheless eventually always challenged by “the part of no part”, Žižek (1999) reserves the term postpolitics to describe a situation in which the political is effectively foreclosed (Wilson & Swyngedouw, 2014). Postpolitics to Žižek thus generates a “seemingly complete symbolic order”, in which the political (antagonistic, power-laden and by necessity repressive) foundation of any society is all but completely obfuscated (Žižek, 1999). Thus, for Žižek postpolitics sets a political frame in which disagreements about specific issues are accepted and to some degree even welcomed, but where questioning the frame itself becomes completely out-of-bounds and unacceptable.3 The result of this is that “today’s predominant form of ideological ‘closure’ takes the precise form of mental block that prevents us from imagining a fundamental social change, in the interests of an allegedly ‘realistic’ and ‘mature’ attitude” (Žižek, 2000: 324, 182

Postpolitics and Planning

emphasis in original). This in turn generates a “suffocating” political climate, leaving violent outbursts as the only outlet for suppressed political energy. For Žižek, the only way to get out of this cul-de-sac is through a repoliticization of the structure of the global economy (Žižek, 1999: 432) and a return to attention to that which MacLeod (2013: 2213) has highlighted as the “mammoth unmentionable” of postpolitics: class. Wilson & Swyngedouw (2014a) suggest that a central difference between the key theorists of the postpolitical is that whereas Mouffe is interested in the repression of antagonism and the consequences of failing to transform it to productive agonism, Rancière is more focused on the disavowal of equality, and Žižek’s specific preoccupation is to criticize the foreclosure of a specific form of politics: that of class struggle. Quite obviously, these differences are more than cosmetic and have profound implications with regards to the crucial question concerning the possible remedies against the postpolitical condition that planners (among others) now supposedly find themselves operating within. Somewhat harshly construed, it could be claimed that Mouffe’s correlate project is to find ways to reconfigure the institutional order, Rancière’s to constantly disrupt the institutional order, and Žižek’s to once and for all overthrow the institutional order. These inclinations also map onto the three broad strands of possible responses to postpolitics and other forms of depoliticization suggested by Van Puymbroeck & Oosterlynck (2014: 89): the three-term approach, the purification approach and the relational approach. The three-term approach, which closely dovetails with Mouffian agonism, aims at the creation of distinct spaces that might generate affordances for articulations of the political, i.e. the contentious and fractured foundations of society, in such a way that antagonistic positions can be translated into agonistic encounter, but without highly circumscribed role-scripting (‘stakeholder’ representation). Such forums would further allow for actors to disagree about the issue(s) at stake, how they are involved, and what kind of issues are of relevance in the present context. The purification approach, on the other hand, is based on a call for a full-scale revolution to bring forth an entirely new society. To the thinkers within this fold, such as Žižek, any response to postpolitics but a full-scale revolution will inevitably only provide “palliative damage-control measures within the global capitalist framework” (Žižek, 2000: 321). As a consequence they argue that to break away from postpolitics there is a need for a “violent act” of revolution and an acceptance of the self-proclaimed right of the committed few to speak in the name of the “community as a whole” (Swyngedouw, 2014: 180) – to some degree thus echoing aspects of classic Leninist vanguardism. As an alternative to the above sketched positions, a relational approach to the enactment of the political, primarily inspired by Rancière, centers its attention on moments of interruption that expose the arbitrariness of the existing police order (governance arrangement), thus paving the way for processes leading to its consecutive, iterative reworking. Such an approach, Van Puymbroeck & Oosterlynck (2014) argue, allows for a more concrete examination and discussion of the manifold ways in which fundamental political tension can be addressed, and how the existing order as a consequence can become twisted or jolted into new configurations and vectors of development.

The Postpolitics of Planning In a paper that has become foundational for the postpolitics literature, Erik Swyngedouw (2009) discusses the emergence of what he calls a “postpolitical and postdemocratic condition” in contemporary urban governance which correlates closely with “the rise of a neoliberal governmentality that has replaced debate, disagreement and dissensus with a series of technologies of governing that fuse around consensus, agreement, accountancy metrics and technocratic 183

Jonathan Metzger

environmental management”. He goes on to specify such arrangements as forms of “governancebeyond-the-state” in which traditional government actors in cooperation with select experts and NGOs form a political arena that is evacuated of any deeper conflicts, thus leading to a narrowing of the parameters of democracy itself (Swyngedouw, 2009: 608). An eerie aspect of this form of governance regime which is picked out by Swyngedouw is the way that any form of dissent or disagreement of opinion becomes framed as merely specific and local, or else at least technical – and best solved by reasoned discourse and compromise. Thus, under the postpolitical condition, anything can be made into a point of contestation, but only in a non-committal way, as a “non-conflict”. Compromise and consensus-building become the privileged figures for the negotiation of admittedly contentious issues, such as the reshaping of urban environments, and difficulties or problems along the way are supposedly to be solved by way of managerial and technical expertise. However, within these postpolitical consensus-oriented governance settings, questions regarding fundamental divergences and universal values are all but foreclosed and the articulation of divergent, conflicting and alternative trajectories of future environmental development are effectively forestalled. Thus, [t]here is no contestation over the givens of the situation, over the partition of the sensible; there is only debate over the technologies of management, the arrangements of policing and the configuration of those who already have a stake, whose voice is already recognized as legitimate. (Swyngedouw, 2009: 610) Further, those that question the givens of things are labeled as irresponsible, unreasonable and dangerous. As a consequence, you either become part of the consensual pluralist order, or you are radically excluded from deliberations. In a more concrete operationalization of postpolitical analysis, Guy Baeten (2009) performs an investigation of the redevelopment of London’s South Bank. In his analysis, Baeten shows how the political has been practically “evacuated” from the regeneration process by means of “postpolitical regeneration tactics”, and he particularly pinpoints an “obsessive focus” on cooperation between different interest groups, based on the underlying logic that “communities are now supposed to unite and fight for scarce regeneration resources, leave ‘old’ antagonism behind and become reasonable, rational, sensible, communicative, responsible agents with smooth relations with central government and funding bodies” (p. 248). Adversarial and skeptical groups are dismissed as irresponsible, unreasonable and extremist, which generates a clear line of antagonism between the sensible “us” and the mindless “them”: those “who do not understand how regeneration ‘works today’”, and thus can be safely ignored. This in effect entails what Baeten labels as the “moralization” of political conflict, where instead of discussing fundamental differences between e.g. “right” and “left”, conflicts are instead enacted as between “right” and “wrong”: “With the ‘evil them’ no agonistic debate is possible; they must be ignored if not eradicated. Condemnation, then, replaces proper political analysis”.4 A further tell-tale sign of postpolitics is, according to Baeten, a disarticulation between local issues and universal demands for e.g. welfare, justice or governmental responsibility. Local demands become efficiently “localized” and residents are summoned to participate in the building of local “community”, but at the expense of wider political mobilization – and as a consequence local concerns become precluded from functioning as a starting point for a more general critique of the current governance order and political priorities.5 This practice of particularization is a central aspect of postpolitics also in the eyes of Oosterlynck & Swyngedouw 184

Postpolitics and Planning

(2010: 1581) who argue that within postpolitical governance arrangements, the only actors that become accepted as legitimate are those that do not demand the fundamental transformation of the system, but instead make their demands negotiable within the already given policy framework, which in itself becomes placed beyond questioning. Perhaps the most thorough and long-lasting theoretical engagement with the conceptual apparatus of postpolitics in relation to planning has been provided by Phil Allmendinger and Graham Haughton (e.g. 2010, 2012, 2014). In their analysis of the rise to prominence of the “spatial planning’ paradigm within British planning theory and practice, Allmendinger and Haughton argue that this, in effect, constitutes a form of neoliberal spatial governance, underpinned by a variety of postpolitical techniques. In this governance setting, conflict has not been removed from planning, but has become displaced and “carefully choreographed” with the help of e.g. partnership-led governance arrangements centered around vague objectives and seemingly uncontestable “feel-good” concepts such as “sustainable development”, “climate change”, “zero carbon development”, “urban renaissance” and “smart growth”. Allmendinger and Haughton (2012: 94) argue that such concepts are deeply postpolitical on merit of their fuzzy self-evident desirability, since, as the authors exclaim, “who could be ‘for’ ‘dumb growth’ or ‘unsustainable development’?” (cf. Gunder & Hillier, 2009). In their analysis, Allmendinger and Haughton are very careful to point out that postpolitics in planning does not just occur by a happenstance. It has a purpose: to legitimate hegemonic strategies and projects, which in this case more specifically refers to the expedition of a “rolled out” version of a neoliberal economic growth agenda in ways that generate the “buy-in” and “lock-in” of selected policy partners by way of the inclusion (but also subordination and taming) of issues such as quality of life, sustainable development and social justice in the form of lower order issues that are not allowed to eclipse the mainstream growth agenda. By ostensibly championing such “progressive” causes postpolitical planning practices contribute to “bolster[ing] the legitimacy of the overall approach with some minimalistic concessions” (Allmendinger & Haughton, 2012: 93). Thus, what postpolitical spatial planning efficiently achieved was a reworking of the institutional and discursive framework of planning in such a way that diverse groups such as planners, developers, land owners and community groups all could feel that they became important parts of the system, that they were listened to, even though many of the issues in their hearts were only paid lip-service to and subsumed under an unassailable broader economic growth imperative (cf. also Hilding-Rydevik et al., 2011). Another aspect of the spatial planning paradigm’s “sophisticated obfuscation of the political” was the harnessing of participatory methods to garner support and supplant opposition in planning processes with the help of “carefully stage-managed processes” with “subtly but clearly defined parameters of what is open for debate”. The result was a planning system that presumably promoted involvement, but at the same time actively obscured the contextual restraints on influence – thereby generating a superficial appearance of legitimacy, while minimizing the potential for those with conflicting views to be given a meaningful hearing. In relation to this development Allmendinger & Haughton (2012) slam the planning profession for being at best “compliant and naïve” by persuading themselves that the “public interest” (and their own professional standing) was best served through this democratically corrosive circumvention of democratic process, which has contributed to alienate the profession from the communities they were supposed to serve.

Some Criticisms As already indicated in the introduction, postpolitical analysis is surrounded by quite an amount of academic controversy – even to the degree that some critical commentators fundamentally 185

Jonathan Metzger

question the existence of the phenomenon itself. Jodi Dean (2009, 2014) has for instance repeatedly argued that the identification and critique of postpolitics more than anything else signals the failure of the contemporary political left. Dean argues that what has been labeled as “postpolitics” simply denotes a very efficient assemblage of right-wing hegemony-building practices, which all but completely disarmed and co-opted leftist dissent to conservative and neoliberal policies. Claiming that this successful activism somehow forecloses the possibilities for genuinely political action according to Dean amounts to a cry-baby attitude over the left’s own failure to properly mobilize against a tidal wave of neoliberal and conservative reform. Apart from those who completely dismiss the concept of postpolitics, there are also those who instead aim toward identifying and possibly remedying specific weaknesses in the theory of postpolitics. These less hostile authors often specifically hone in on how the conceptual apparatus of postpolitics needs to be worked through in greater detail. Many of these argumentations particularly focus on how much of the currently dominant theorization of the concept, strongly influenced by Swyngedouw’s writings, often comes across as somewhat sweeping and vague. They therefore suggest that the theory needs to become more sensitized to the nuances of postpolitical phenomena, such as the various types of techniques of depoliticization that are associated with postpolitics, as well as the possible limits of any postpolitical event or episode (see e.g. Paddison, 2009; O’Callaghan et al., 2014; Bylund, 2012; Raco & Lin, 2012; Beveridge et al., 2014; Van Puymbroeck & Oosterlynck, 2014: 95–6). The main focus of this discussion is thus the demand that the analysis of postpolitics needs to become much more precise and specific to be of any real help, and to be guided by nuanced and empirically attentive questions of where and how politics operates in relation to specific policy developments (Johnstone, 2014: 707). An important component of the latter discussion is also the oft-repeated worry that if the analysts of postpolitics fail to become more fine-grained in their efforts, they actually risk playing into their avowed enemies’ hands by efficiently reproducing the effects they profess to uncover and criticize. In this vein, e.g. Davidson and Iveson (2014: 4) posit that “Labelling cities ‘post-political’ risks treating depoliticization as a condition that has been realized, rather than a tendency that has taken hold” and others agree that this risks making planning research “blind to the more subtle mechanisms at work in political power” (Grange, 2014: 56; cf. Loepfe & van Wezemael, 2014). Developing this argument in some more detail, Beveridge et al. (2014: 73) warn that by “universalizing apparent and disturbing trends” analysts of postpolitics could risk contributing to the very tendencies they profess to criticize, and by over-stating the case risk “encourage helplessness rather than action” (cf. also Metzger, 2011).

Potentials for Further Development In light of the more nuanced criticisms of postpolitical analysis it is evident that there still exists a need to work through and explore a number of remaining ambiguities and lacunae in the theoretization of postpolitics. In an attempt to provide some impetus for this I have identified three areas in which new research on postpolitics and planning can be productive by not only simply applying the theory to specific empirical cases, but by also contributing to the further refinement of the theory itself with regard to the definition, specification and contestation of postpolitics.

Defining Postpolitics One of the key issues that remains to be more carefully thought through is the character of postpolitics. What type of “thing” is it really? Here the existing literature on postpolitics is unhelpfully imprecise. The postpolitical has interchangeably been described as an era (e.g. Žižek, 2000), a 186

Postpolitics and Planning

condition (e.g. Swyngedouw, 2009), formation (Kamat, 2014), city (Paddison, 2009), arrangement (Swyngedow, 2009), imaginary (Raco & Lin, 2012), managerial framework (Raco, 2014b), rhetoric (Raco, 2014b), governance techniques (Metzger et al., 2014) and forms and practices (Van Puymbroeck & Oosterlynck, 2014). Relatedly, Van Puymbroeck and Oosterlynck (2014: 103) have challenged analysts of postpolitics to become much sharper and more precise in their identification of what in effect constitutes the postpoliticizing devices and elements of contemporary governance arrangements, urging researchers to “crack open the black box of the post-political condition to see the multifarious generic policing tactics that combine to depoliticize society”. Along the same lines, Loepfe and Van Wezemael (2014: 86–87) identify clear “post-political tendencies” in contemporary Swiss planning, yet remain aloof to any claims of there existing some form of saturated “post-political order” in the Swiss planning system, since there are still ample points of intervention in the planning process at which the issues are open to politicization (cf. also Allmendinger & Haughton, 2010, 2012). Such a more precise understanding of postpolitics as enacted through specific techniques and practices also raises demands for a more concrete interrogation of the specific spatio-temporalities of the postpolitical. If postpolitics is not always everywhere, where does it appear? Under what conditions? And through the application of which techniques and practices? This is not only an academically interesting issue, considering that the answers given to such questions will also set the parameters for the discussion on relevant and efficient responses to the consequent question concerning how these developments then can be efficiently opposed or contested.

Specifying Postpolitics If, as suggested above, postpolitics is more helpfully understood as the effect of concrete practices rather than as an all-encompassing “condition”, what differentiates it from other practices and techniques of depoliticization? Is there anything distinct about postpolitics or should the concept simply be treated as a synonym for depoliticization in general? But if the notion of postpolitics is widened to such an extreme degree, analysts of planning might perhaps find themselves asking: so what’s new? For as Inch (2012: 523) has noted, the fundamentally anti-political side of planning, which can function to defuse conflict by masking value-based decisions in a rational-technical jargon or “efficiently” imposing development in the interest of investors and landowners, has been long recognized (cf. also Metzger, 2011; Allmendinger, 2016). One recurrent way of attempting to specify the particularity of postpolitics in relation to other anti-political practices is by highlighting the connection to neoliberal governance regimes. The problem with such a move is just that postpolitics then risks becoming too much of an imprecise place-holder, substantially merely denoting any and every form of allegedly devious technique of political hegemony construction associated with the neoliberal political project, or even more broadly “really undemocratic ways of governing” in general. In contrast to such a very broad and variegated definition of the term, for instance Japhy Wilson (2013) insists that postpoliticization must be understood as a quite specific modality of depoliticization. In this more specific definition, postpolitics is most often referred to as practices of depoliticization that function less through a direct suppression of dissent than by way of circumscribing, containing and diffusing opposition through the careful engineering of its format and outlets – i.e. through manipulating the places, temporalities, context and focus of how and when issues and grievances can be articulated. In relation to participatory practices in urban governance and planning, often highlighted as a key arena for postpolitics, this has for instance been described as a move from planning practice as characterized by DAD (Decide-Announce-Defend) instead being replaced by 187

Jonathan Metzger

the more insidious and manipulative UNCLE (Unlimited Never-ending Consultation Leading to Exhaustion) (Johnstone, 2014; Metzger et al., 2014). As described by Deas (2013: 2301) such policy processes are characterized by how the parameters of debate are circumscribed to focus on a narrow range of nonessential issues, but where more fundamental substantive disagreement is deemed “unacceptably and unhelpfully ‘political’ and therefore off-limits” (cf. Allmendinger & Haughton, 2012). The consequential result is a superficial charade of politicality centering on narrowly articulated technical issues, which defuses opposition by preemptively channeling contestation and questioning toward relatively minor matters. Thus, fundamentally political questions often curiously appear to always have already been determined “somewhere else” on the basis of some “general interest” which no one in his right mind can supposedly disagree with – thus posing the choice presently at hand as always being one of detail, not principle (Metzger et al., 2014; cf. Johnstone, 2014). “Participatory” processes of this type do not at all function as the arenas for debate and questioning that they are sometimes imagined to be, but instead serve to choreograph events in such a way that they effectively garner consent to potentially contentious policies by way of “techniques of consensual persuasion” (Paddison, 2009; cf. MacLeod, 2011). The ultimate effect of such an arrangement is, as pointed out by Raco (2014b: 27), that under such a regime of “participation”, communities and citizens are paradoxically told that they are “being empowered” at the same time as their capacities to influence policy are being undermined in the drive to “get things done”. Even staunch critics of the postpolitics literature such as Mitchell et al. (2015: 2636) concede that the identification of these anti-democratic mechanisms is an important and noteworthy conclusion from the work on postpolitics and helps explain why “the near-universal acceptance of participatory planning” generally appears to make such little difference to the substantial outcomes of planning processes.

Contesting Postpolitics No matter their other differences, there exists a strong agreement among analysts of postpolitics that this is a phenomenon that is devious and destructive and which therefore needs to be uncovered, countered and opposed. The sense of urgency concerning this task is further strengthened by a fear of the inevitable “return of the political” where it has been suppressed that has been assumed by e.g. Mouffe, and the various destructive forms this can take when a social formation fails to offer sufficient room for turning the ever-present destructive political antagonisms into fruitful agonistic contestation. Mouffe for instance highlights the rise of extreme populist movements in society, such as religious extremism and the racist far-right as one such consequence, while Allmendinger and Haughton (2010, 2012) point toward how the tight formatting of consensus-oriented planning processes forces disagreeing parties into a reactive politics of obstruction, as a consequence bogging the planning system down in over-litigation, and in the process producing “a generation of NIMBYs”, as Andy Inch (2012) succinctly puts it. Nevertheless, Inch also reasons that postpolitical action might nevertheless generate counterreactions that can be positively channeled and contribute to a revival of democratic engagement. Along similar lines, Raco (2014a: 168) contends that the present obvious failure of postpolitical governance arrangements sparks publics into being which might hopefully contribute toward reinvigorating democracy (cf. Legacy, 2015; Raco & Lin, 2012). This suggests that efforts to render planning postpolitical might not necessarily lead toward “the end of politics” but maybe to the contrary trigger movements toward repoliticizing planning, but perhaps by other means and in other spaces than those commonly and traditionally recognized as “properly” and legitimately political in liberal-democratic parliamentary systems of representative democracy (Metzger, 2011: 191). 188

Postpolitics and Planning

Such a perspective, of course, demands that we ask where and among whom such repoliticizing reactions might be expected to be found. In his work, Erik Swyngedouw often center-stages popular urban uprisings such as those associated with the Occupy-movement or the revolutionary Greek, Egyptian and Turkish urban movements. More directly relating to planning processes, Legacy (2015) also highlights the importance of citizen action beyond and against the state as important vehicles for opposing postpolitical governance practices in ways that do not only contest particular planning issues at hand, but also assert themselves as active political subjects in matters that affect their lives. In contrast to the above, the relational approach suggested by Van Puymbroeck and Oosterlynck (2014) is more cautious in pointing out any specific movement or group as constituting a political or politicizing subject in itself, but instead focuses on the fleeting situations in which the given order of things is put into question, wherever these might arise – which generate a “third space” wherein the exclusions, obfuscations and silencings that are performed by the existing police order are exposed and made tangible (Allmendinger, 2016: 153). This approach to some degree also resonates with MacLeod’s (2013) caution that it is important not to automatically preclude and discount the “politics of the everyday”, and in a similar vein Rosol (2014: 80) has asserted the need to pay attention to non-confrontational and individual, unorganized and nonstrategic forms of resistance, perhaps akin to what Inch (2012: 533) has labeled as the “micropolitics of displacement”. Even if I agree on the importance of also staying attentive to the small everyday struggles against the powers that be, it remains pertinent to ask how such interventions are carried forward and connected to broader mobilizations and more general demands for change, so that they do not only turn into fragmented, particularistic local protests (Haughton et  al., 2016). Nevertheless, the relational approach to politicization productively demands that we avoid any strong preconceptions about where we might come to find a “properly political” movement and moment. Or, to quote Johnstone (2014: 707), it suggests that “the presence of political antagonism should always be assumed; the location of where such contestation takes place, however, should not” (cf. Davidson & Iveson, 2014; Dikeç, 2005). Maybe the place of the political could sometimes even be found in a planning office (see e.g. Krumholtz, 1990)? And maybe even, it has been suggested, within the arrangements of spatial planning; albeit not in the search for consensus, but in the strategic dimension of opening up and visioning alternative futures (see Metzger et al., 2014; Albrechts, 2015).

Concluding Discussion Discussing contemporary planning practice as currently being postpolitical poses the risk of conjuring up a misleading, romanticized image of some Golden Age of thoroughly democratic planning which – alas – would now be in the past. Even the most cursory reading of planning history will, however, show that such an era never was, and that the mainstream of planning practice has always been “techno-managerial”. It could even be argued that for some influential theories of planning the technification of politically contentious issues – aiming at transcending politics or “cutting through the clutter” – is even seen to be the essence of planning. Nevertheless, this techno-managerial practice has from time to time been interrupted and subverted by iterations of demands toward the democratization of planning. In the light of such a longer history of planning, the theorization of postpolitics and the wider frame of postfoundational political theory on which it rests, can perhaps be apprehended as but one of the latest of these turns; aiming at upending the current “police order” of planning in the name of democracy and equality. 189

Jonathan Metzger

However, even if one agrees that it is of paramount importance, not least from a democracy perspective, that planning scholarship remains attentive to wherever postpolitics rears its ugly head, it is still nothing but honest to admit that there are lacunae and contradictions in the theoretical underpinnings that the analysis of postpolitics currently rests upon. Nevertheless, the solution to these shortcomings is not to throw the whole analysis over board – but rather to develop it. Based on the preceding survey of the state of the art in the subject area, it is for instance at this point becoming quite obvious that just blurting out that things are postpolitical in general does not seem to generate much interesting friction any more. What is instead needed at this point are studies that can respond in some empirical detail to more precise questions regarding the concrete functions and mechanics of postpolitical devices and techniques – but nevertheless without losing perspective of how unique, situated enactments of postpolitics configure into broader patterns of development. This in turn requires a heightened sensibility toward the spatio-temporal specificity of analysis, which implies asking questions about, on the one hand, the concrete spaces and practices of postpolitics, but also about the institutional arrangements and relations that uphold and reproduce them over time and space. Once the specificities of postpolitics have been more clearly established, another important development would be to break out of the lopsided focus on this single (albeit, admittedly, highly devious) form of depoliticization, so as to also place it within a wider landscape of multifarious types of depoliticizing mechanisms and maneuvers. This would also place a greater demand on a more rigorous theoretization of “the other” of depoliticization, that is: the variegated techniques and forms of politicization, and that which they enact – i.e. “the political”. There are already signs of such a nascent interest in some emerging work on postpolitics and planning, and it is important that this momentum is preserved and channeled into a shift in focus from asserting that postpolitics exists and is bad news for democracy, to instead spending greater effort on figuring out how to contest it and produce opportunities for the political to break through in planning contexts; thereby generating opportunities for the enactment of democracy and the staging of equality within these processes. The relational approach to politicization, which I personally find highly promising, does not bet upon any form of clean break with the past, in which the world is completely born anew. What it nevertheless requires is the courage to pose bold demands for fundamental change that rip away the sense of givenness of the current order of things, and which in their present context therefore might appear as ridiculous or almost irresponsible. However, when it comes to seemingly outrageous demands for social justice and equality, Swyngedouw and Wilson (2014b: 218) remind us that the demands of the last chapter of the Communist Manifesto – such as free and universal health care, education and care for the elderly – appeared as completely scandalous in 1848, but were almost all implemented in one way or the other in most of Western Europe during the twentieth century. Why shouldn’t this ambition for equality and development for the benefit of “the many – not the few” (Healey, 2010) be possible to revive again?

Notes 1 I wish to extend a heartfelt thank you to the editors, Stijn Oosterlynck, Anna Lundgren and the Higher Seminar at the KTH Division of Urban and Regional Studies for their helpful comments on a previous version of the chapter. 2 The sometimes almost interchangeable use of the terms “postpolitics” and “post-democracy” in the literature on postpolitics is at times very confusing, particularly when taking into consideration that influential authors such as Erik Swyngedouw draw both on Rancière and his use of this concept, as well as Colin Crouch’s (2004) use of the term in a related but nevertheless quite distinct way.

190

Postpolitics and Planning 3 To Žižek the figure of postpolitics is also closely related to that of ultrapolitics, a hyper-antagonistic antipolitics moralizing the adversary as “evil” and seeking its complete annihilation. 4 This tendency toward moralizing conflict is also identified by Tunström & Bradley (2014: 82) in the contemporary Swedish debate on urban form. 5 The saliency of “localizing” postpolitical tendencies has been observed in contemporary rural communities as well, see e.g. Kenis & Mathijs (2014).

References Albrechts, L. (2015). Ingredients for a more radical strategic spatial planning. Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design, 42, 1–16. Allmendinger, P. (2016). Neoliberal Spatial Governance. London: Routledge. Allmendinger, P., & Haughton, G. (2010). Spatial planning, devolution, and new planning spaces. Environment and Planning. C, Government & Policy, 28(5), 803. Allmendinger, P., & Haughton, G. (2012). Post-political spatial planning in England: A crisis of consensus? Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers, 37(1), 89–103. Allmendinger, P., & Haughton, G. (2014). ‘Post-political regimes in English planning: from Third Way to Big Society’. In Metzger, J., Allmendinger, P., & Oosterlynck, S. (eds.) Planning against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance. London: Routledge, pp. 29–53. Allmendinger, P., & Haughton, G. (2015). ‘Post-political regimes in English planning: From Third Way to Big Society’. In Metzger, J., Allmendinger, P. & Oosterlynck, S. (eds.) Planning against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance. London: Routledge, pp. 29–53. Baeten, G. (2009). ‘Regenerating the South Bank: Reworking community and the emergence of postpolitical regeneration’. In Imrie, R., Lees, L., & Raco, M. (eds.) Regenerating London: Governance, Sustainability, and Community in a Global City. New York: Routledge, pp. 237–253. Beveridge, R., Hüesker, F., & Naumann, M. (2014). From post-politics to a politics of possibility? Unravelling the privatization of the Berlin Water Company. Geoforum, 51, 66–74. Bylund, J. (2012). Postpolitical correctness? Planning Theory, 11(3), 319–327. Crouch, C. (2004). Post-democracy. Cambridge: Polity. Davidson, M., & Iveson, K. (2014). Recovering the politics of the city: From the ‘post-political city’ to a ‘method of equality’ for critical urban geography. Progress in Human Geography, 39(5), 543–559. Dean, J. (2009). Politics without politics. Parallax, 15(3), 20–36. Dean, J. (2014). ‘After post-politics: Occupation and the return of Communism’. In Swyngedouw, E. & Wilson, J. (eds.) The Post-political and Its Discontents: Spaces of Depoliticization, Spectres of Radical Politics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 261–278. Deas, I. (2013). The search for territorial fixes in subnational governance: City-regions and the disputed emergence of post-political consensus in Manchester, England. Urban Studies, 51(11), 2285–2314. Dikeç, M. (2005). Space, politics, and the political. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space, 23, 171–188. Ek, R. (2011). Creating the creative post-political citizen? The showroom as an arena for creativity. Culture Unbound: Journal of Current Cultural Research, 3(2), 167–186. Grange, K. (2014). ‘In search of the irreducible political moment: Or why planning shouldn’t be too hung up on conflictuality’. In Metzger, J., Allmendinger, P., & Oosterlynck, S. (eds.) Planning against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance. London: Routledge, pp. 56–68. Gunder, M., & Hillier, J. (2009). Planning in Ten Words or Less: A Lacanian Entanglement with Spatial Planning. Farnham: Ashgate. Haughton, G., Gilchrist, A., & Swyngedouw, E. (2016). Rise like lions after slumber: Dissent, protest and (post-) politics in Manchester. Territory, Politics, Governance, 4(4), 472–491. Healey, P. (2010). Making Better Places: The Planning Project in the Twenty-First Century. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan. Hilding-Rydevik, T., Håkansson, M., & Isaksson, K. (2011). The Swedish discourse on sustainable regional development: Consolidating the post-political condition. International Planning Studies, 16(2), 169–187. Inch, A. (2012). Creating ‘a generation of NIMBYs’? Interpreting the role of the state in managing the politics of urban development. Environment and Planning C: Government and Policy, 30(3), 520–535. Johnstone, P. (2014). Planning reform, rescaling, and the construction of the postpolitical: The case of The Planning Act 2008 and nuclear power consultation in the UK. Environment and Planning C: Government and Policy, 32(4), 697–713.

191

Jonathan Metzger Kamat, S. (2014). The new development architecture and the post-political in the global South. In Swyngedouw, E. & Wilson, J. (eds.) The Post-political and its Discontents: Spaces of Depoliticization, Spectres of Radical Politics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 67–85. Kenis, A., & Mathijs, E. (2014). (De)politicising the local: The case of the Transition Towns movement in Flanders (Belgium). Journal of Rural Studies, 34, 172–183. Krumholz, N. (1990). Making Equity Planning Work: Leadership in the Public Sector. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Legacy, C. (2015). Transforming transport planning in the postpolitical era. Urban Studies, 53(14), 3108–3124. Loepfe, M., & Van Wezemael, J. (2014). ‘Rethinking politics and the (post-)political through DeleuzeGuattarian Micropolitics’. In Metzger, J., Allmendinger, P., & Oosterlynck, S. (eds.) Planning against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance. London: Routledge, pp. 85–106. MacLeod, G. (2011). Urban politics reconsidered: Growth machine to post-democratic city? Urban Studies, 48(12), 2629–2660. MacLeod, G. (2013). New urbanism/smart growth in the Scottish Highlands: Mobile policies and postpolitics in local development planning. Urban Studies, 50(11), 2196–2221. Makarychev, A., & Yatsyk, A. (2014). Brands, cities and (post-)politics: A comparative analysis of urban strategies for the Universiade 2013 and the World Football Cup 2018 in Russia. European Urban and Regional Studies, 22(2), 143–160. Marchart, O. (2007). Post-Foundational Political Thought. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Metzger, J. (2011). Neither revolution, nor resignation: (Re)democratizing contemporary planning praxis: a commentary on Allmendinger and Haughton’s ‘Spatial planning, devolution, and new planning spaces’. Environment and Planning C: Government and Policy, 29(2), 191–196. Metzger, J., Allmendinger, P., & Oosterlynck, S. (2014). ‘The contested terrain of European territorial governance: New perspectives on democratic deficits and political displacements’. In Metzger, J., Allmendinger, P., & Oosterlynck, S. (eds.) Planning against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance. New York: Routledge, pp. 1–28. Mitchell, D., Attoh, K., & Staeheli, L. (2015). Whose city? What politics? Contentious and non-contentious spaces on Colorado’s Front Range. Urban Studies, 52(14), 2633–2648. Mouffe, C. (2005). On the Political. London: Routledge. Neo, H. (2010). Unpacking the postpolitics of golf course provision in Singapore. Journal of Sport & Social Issues, 34(3), 272–287. O’Callaghan, C., Boyle, M., & Kitchin, R. (2014). Post-politics, crisis, and Ireland’s ‘ghost estates’. Political Geography, 42, 121–133. Oosterlynck, S., & Swyngedouw, E. (2010). Noise reduction: The postpolitical quandary of night flights at Brussels airport. Environment and Planning A, 42(7), 1577–1594. Paddison, R. (2009). Some reflections on the limitations to public participation in the post-political city. L’Espace Politique. Revue en ligne de géographie politique et de géopolitique, (8). Raco, M. (2014a). ‘Conflict management, democratic demands, and the post-politics of privatisation’. In Metzger, J., Allmendinger, P., & Oosterlynck, S. (eds.) (2014). Planning against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance. London: Routledge, pp. 153–169. Raco, M. (2014b). ‘The post-politics of sustainability planning: Privatisation and the demise of democratic government’. In Swyngedouw, E. & Wilson, J. (eds.) The Post-political and Its Discontents: Spaces of Depoliticization, Spectres of Radical Politics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 25–47. Raco, M., & Lin, W.I. (2012). Urban sustainability, conflict management, and the geographies of postpoliticism: A case study of Taipei. Environment and Planning C, 30(2), 191–208. Rancière, J. (1998[1995]). Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Rosol, M. (2014). On resistance in the post-political city: Conduct and counter-conduct in Vancouver. Space and Polity, 18(1), 70–84. Swyngedouw, E. (2009). The antinomies of the postpolitical city: In search of a democratic politics of environmental production. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 33(3), 601–620. Swyngedouw, E. (2014). ‘Insurgent architects, radical cities and the promise of the political’. In Swyngedouw, E. & Wilson, J. (eds.) The Post-political and its Discontents: Spaces of Depoliticization, Spectres of Radical Politics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 169–188. Swyngedouw, E., & Wilson, J. (2014a). ‘There is no alternative’. In Swyngedouw, E. & Wilson, J. (eds.) The Post-political and Its Discontents: Spaces of Depoliticization, Spectres of Radical Politics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 299–312.

192

Postpolitics and Planning Swyngedouw, E., & Wilson, J. (2014b). ‘Insurgent architects and the spectral return of the urban political’. In Metzger, J., Allmendinger, P., & Oosterlynck, S. (eds.) Planning against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance. London: Routledge, pp. 215–225. Tunström, M., & Bradley, K. (2014). ‘Opposing the postpolitical Swedish urban discourse’. In Metzger, J., Allmendinger, P., & Oosterlynck, S. (eds.) Planning against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance. London: Routledge, pp. 69–84. Van Puymbroeck, N., & Oosterlynck, S. (2014). ‘Opening up the post-political condition: Multiculturalism and the matrix of depoliticisation’. In Swyngedouw, E. & Wilson, J. (eds.) The Post-political and Its Discontents: Spaces of Depoliticization, Spectres of Radical Politics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 87–108. Wilson, J. (2013). The urbanization of the countryside: Depoliticization and the production of space in Chiapas. Latin American Perspectives, 40(2), 218–236. Wilson, J., & Swyngedouw, E. (2014). ‘Seeds of dystopia: Post-politics and the return of the political’. In Swyngedouw, E. & Wilson, J. (eds.) The Post-political and Its Discontents: Spaces of Depoliticization, Spectres of Radical Politics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 1–22. Žižek, S. (1999). The Ticklish Subject: The Absent Centre of Political Ontology. New York: Verso. Žižek, S. (2000). ‘Holding the place’. In Butler, J., Laclau, E., & Žižek, S. (eds.) Contingency, Hegemony, Universality: Contemporary Dialogues on the Left. London: Verso, pp. 308–329.

193

16 ‘CULTURAL WORK’ AND THE REMAKING OF PLANNING’S ‘APPARATUS OF TRUTH’ Andy Inch

Raiding Foucault’s Toolbox The historical and philosophical works of Michel Foucault have become a central reference point in the development of critical theory. Through a series of hugely influential book-length studies, supplemented by various interviews and lectures, Foucault explored aspects of what he called ‘the history of the present’, critically uncovering how socio-cultural ideas and practices about, for example, madness, punishment or sex are produced within ‘regimes of truth’ – systems of power that define what can and cannot be said, done and considered truthful in different societies at different times. Adapted and applied extraordinarily widely across the human and social sciences, Foucault’s work has opened up productive lines of enquiry and often heated debate about the pervasive ways in which power operates to produce particular forms of knowledge, rationality and subjectivity. Many Foucauldian ideas have now become part of the taken-for-granted ‘common-sense’ of critical scholarship. As with many major thinkers, however, Foucault’s philosophical writing can be complex, elliptical, and even somewhat contradictory. I do not set out here in search of a doctrinaire approach, however. Rather, I see Foucault’s philosophy as capable of being read and understood in multiple productive ways. My purpose is to explore how it has been and might continue to be of use to planning theory. I remain wary of some of the potential theoretical and empirical difficulties involved in the appropriation of Foucauldian frameworks to the contemporary study of planning, not least Foucault’s reluctance to centre his own analysis of power on the practices of the state, the traditional locus of much planning activity. However, I take heart from his stated willingness to make his work available as a ‘toolbox’ for exposing and challenging systems of power (Foucault and Deleuze, 1973; Mills, 2003, 7). In this chapter I therefore argue that planning theory’s productive engagement with Foucault’s toolbox can be usefully extended by re-focusing analytical attention on the production of the disciplinary1 ‘apparatus’ of planning – the various institutions, discourses and practices through which the field called ‘planning’ and its truths are constructed at different times and in different places. In doing so, I want to suggest that Foucauldian analytical tools can assist with the pressing task of understanding how ideas and practices of planning are currently being problematised and transformed by neoliberal and managerial rationalities. Considering the oftrepeated criticism that Foucauldian approaches are incapable of providing a political response 194

The Production of Truth in Planning

to the disciplinary and normalising effects of power, I will also explore how such an approach might help us think about the political strategies that could be employed in response to seemingly pervasive dissatisfaction with the idea of planning in many societies. In doing so I will argue that Foucault’s largely historical thinking might be usefully supplemented by attentiveness to the lived experiences of practice and particularly the forms of ‘cultural work’ through which planning’s disciplinary apparatus is actively reshaped. The chapter is set out as follows: In the next section I offer a summary of some of the major uses of Foucauldian approaches within the field of planning theory and the debates these have generated. Following this I argue for the value of thinking about the contemporary (re) formation of planning’s apparatus, particularly in contexts where ideas of planning are increasingly being targeted as a problem requiring governmental intervention. I then introduce a brief empirical example of the ways in which the managerial discourse of efficiency has disciplined planning practices in Scotland, before going on to introduce the idea of cultural work as a means of drawing attention to the range of practices through which the field of planning comes to be remade. In doing so I also consider some of the potential (and perhaps certain limitations) that I feel Foucauldian analysis brings to studies of the contemporary politics of planning.

Planning’s Foucault and His Discontents Work influenced by Foucault’s thinking has generated powerful contributions to planning theory, notably in unsettling the claims of the planning project to be a progressive force for social change. Along with scholarship in the cognate fields of urban studies and geography there has been considerable interest in exploring the spatial effects of power, discipline and surveillance in the production of urban space. This has included studies that critically re-examine the disciplinary histories of planning and their concern with the rational ordering of space as a means of producing healthy, virtuous populations (e.g. Boyer, 1983; Fischler, 1998; Huxley, 2006, 2013; Pløger, 2008; Harris, 2011; Certomà, 2015). Foucauldian work has also explored how the planning discipline constructs its objects of analysis (Kooij, 2015), rationalises its practices (Flyvbjerg, 1998), and authorises particular subjects to speak and act, exposing for example the gendered domination that is inscribed into planning ideas and practices (Huxley, 2002). Elsewhere in this volume, Margo Huxley also reviews some of the productive ways in which Foucault’s neologism governmentality, referring to the rationalities through which attempts are made to govern the conduct of the self and others, has been taken up in planning and related fields. To date, however, Foucauldian scholarship in the field of planning has been most closely associated with a major challenge to the perceived dominance of consensus-seeking theories of planning as a form of communicative practice. The latter have promoted the idea that planning theory should be developed through the study of planners’ practices. Influenced among others by North American pragmatism and the ideas of Jürgen Habermas, a range of scholars have sought to (re)conceptualise planning as a form of ‘communicative action’ in which those practices should be geared toward shaping progressive agreements ‘in the face of power’ (e.g. Forester, 1989; Healey, 1997). In response, however, critics have questioned the very possibility of standing ‘in the face of’ a power that, in Foucauldian terms, is constitutive of knowledge, rationality, truth and subjectivity and which therefore reaches deep down into all planning processes. The work of scholars drawing on Foucauldian ‘tools’ has therefore often been presented as a critical or ‘dark side’ reading of the normative and political potentialities of communicative planning theory (e.g. Flyvbjerg, 1998; Flyvbjerg and Richardson, 2002; Huxley and Yiftachel, 2000). 195

Andy Inch

Fischler (2000) is among those who have responded by arguing that differences between ‘the Foucauldians’ and ‘the Habermasians’ might have been overstated and that it is possible to see Foucauldian insights as adding to understanding of the historical conditions of possibility for any ‘rational’ communicative action. Even if these two camps’ respective positions reflect fundamental differences in sensibility and approach, however, the debates they initiated have played a significant part in the formation of the terrain of contemporary planning theory. Moreover, many elements of those debates remain relevant and important. In this chapter, I will consider two such issues: First, the challenge that a Foucauldian analysis raises to expand the scope of planning theory’s ‘practice turn’ by developing ways of thinking and writing about practices that better account for the wider forces that structure and shape planning episodes (Watson, 2002). Second, what I will here call the ‘so what?’ question that has often been levelled against Foucauldian approaches. The ‘so what?’ question reflects a central problematic for a Foucauldian approach to the analysis of planning and indeed for Foucauldian scholarship more generally. Foucault’s work has often been read as suggesting a totalising conception of disciplinary power that leaves little space for political struggle or the emergence of alternatives, leading critics to suggest that Foucauldian analysis is unable to effectively address the possibility of resistance. Some interpreters see marked shifts in Foucault’s account of power as domination at different stages in his work (Hall, 2001). When Foucault himself sought to address this criticism of his work he consistently emphasised that his understanding of power was not only negative but also positive, in the sense that powerrelations are always productive and not simply repressive. Thus, while there can be little doubt that Foucault saw dispersed, localised power-relations as tending to be shaped by wider patterns of domination, and in turn to have ‘hegemonic effects’ that reproduce ‘global strategies’, he also argued power is always also limited and contingent in its reach and effects: One should not assume a massive and primal condition of domination, a binary structure with ‘dominators’ on one side and ‘dominated’ on the other, but rather a multiform production of relations of domination which are partially susceptible of integration into overall strategies … there are no relations of power without resistances; the latter are all the more real and effective because they are formed right at the point where relations of power are exercised. (Foucault, 1980, 142) In doing so Foucault advocated (and seems to have himself practised) a committed politics of struggle against power and domination (e.g. Foucault, 1980, 1991a). However, he also persistently refused to be drawn on any normative principles that might guide such resistance, insisting instead that ‘strategies’ could only emerge immanently, as responses appropriate to the ‘point where relations of power are exercised’. This aspect of Foucault’s philosophy has drawn widespread criticism (e.g. Walzer, 1986) and is arguably particularly problematic in the field of planning where there is a well-established demand for scholarship that addresses itself to alternatives and exploration of the possibilities of doing better (see e.g. Forester, 2000; Campbell et al., 2014). Indeed, this is arguably what sets much planning theory apart from the concerns of related fields such as critical urban studies; creating a tendency toward strongly normative theory marked by a commitment to what ought to be, rather than simply a critical understanding of how things are. At stake in any response to the ‘so what?’ question then is a concern to demonstrate the productive potential of critique as a means of exposing power-relations, not for its own sake but in order to unsettle established modes of thinking and acting, revealing their contingency as a means of generating new political potentialities and strategies of struggle (Jenkins, 2011). I will 196

The Production of Truth in Planning

return to this crucial question below. First, however, I will explore how and why Foucauldian critique retains importance as a response to the contemporary politics of planning.

From Discursive Formations to the Problematic Apparatus of Planning Foucault described his methodological approach as either archaeological or genealogical and these are often presented as more or less distinctive phases in the development of his thought (Mills, 2003). Put rather simplistically, his archaeological work was concerned to describe the unwritten rules that govern the discursive formation of fields of knowledge in any given historical period; requiring attentiveness to the networks of relations that define how particular statements come to be accepted as authoritative (Foucault, 1972). Genealogical analysis represented a move toward a more dynamic study of power and knowledge, tracing transformations in the meaning of discourses and practices and the roles they play within different historically constituted ‘regimes of truth’ – the formations through which particular practices come to be accepted as truths while others come to be seen as deviant or problematic (Foucault, 1991b). Alongside his ‘genealogical’ studies Foucault also at times emphasised a rather less discursive conception of how regimes of truth come to be formed in and through specific disciplinary fields, describing a ‘dispositif’ or ‘apparatus’ that encompasses: a thoroughly heterogeneous ensemble consisting of discourses, institutions, architectural forms, regulatory decisions, laws, administrative measures, scientific statements, philosophical, moral and philanthropic propositions – in short, the said as much as the unsaid. (Foucault, 1980, 194) The apparatus can be understood as a formation that produces its own particular truths, related in complex ways to the wider regimes operative in a society at any given time. An apparatus is therefore a complex but also contingent formation that is always ‘functionally overdetermined’ – meaning the multiple practices it produces lead, both intentionally and unintentionally, to further, ongoing adjustments in the relations between its various elements. This in turn means that the apparatus and this recursive, ongoing process of change operate at a level beyond the immediate or direct control of any human agency, though both are open to ‘strategic elaboration’ by actors situated within the field (Foucault, 1980, 195). Genealogical rather than archaeological analyses have tended to prevail when Foucauldian tools have been used in planning (e.g. Fischler, 1998; Huxley, 2010, 2013). Such studies have shown the potential of Foucauldian approaches for exploring the construction of planning as a discursive formation or apparatus. This might be productively extended through further interrogation of the historical ‘archive’ or the reshaping of planning’s apparatus to explore the changing constitution of the disciplinary field. In the UK, for example, the historical development of planning has been punctuated by major disjunctures, reorientations and contestations that have transformed how the objects of planning activity are identified and understood, what counts as valid knowledge and who is authorised to speak on planning issues. All of which suggests rich potential for Foucauldian analysis as a means of unsettling established ideas. Analysis of change over time is also indispensable for understanding the history of our present and the potentialities of the contemporary conjuncture. There are clear affinities here with attempts to explore the cultural formation of planning ideas and practices (e.g. Sanyal, 2005). Indeed, Sandercock’s (2005, 310) definition of a planning culture as ‘an ensemble of people, ideas, social values, institutions, politics and power’, hints toward a need for analysis of the contemporary reformation of the apparatus of planning, tracing how ideas of planning are being 197

Andy Inch

constructed, challenged and changed. This is a potentially problematic move since Foucault’s concern was with historical modes of analysis. However, I want to suggest that this task has particular urgency at present due to the widespread perception that the idea of planning has been ‘under attack’ in certain parts of the world. The ‘planning cultures’ project, for example, was conceived in part as a response to concerns about the diminution of local planning ideas and practices in the face of powerful processes of neoliberalisation and globalisation. Elsewhere I have sought to understand aspects of this problematic by studying local manifestations of what might be considered a wider, contemporary phenomenon – attempts to reform planning systems and practices (see e.g. Inch, 2012a, 2012b). Given the status of planning as a primarily state-based activity, these initiatives are clearly related to broader transformations in the rationalities that shape governmental activity. Indeed, the proper limits and purposes of state activity have been central concerns of neoliberal governmentalities (Dardot and Laval, 2014). This has led to what Mitchell Dean (1999) describes as the ‘government of government’ – the widespread problematisation and transformation of state activities through the introduction of new disciplinary techniques, often drawn from private sector managerial practices. Such developments are intended not just to limit the role of the state vis-à-vis the economy, but also to bring governmental practices in line with neoliberal rationalities, governing conduct through the virtues of market competition. If the construction of planning as a ‘problem’ requiring reform is closely related to these broader transformations and their attendant ‘global strategies’, there is a need to understand and explore the ways in which the apparatus of planning has come to be defined as an object of governmental attention in recent years. This in turn implies a shift in focus for critical planning studies which have tended to explore the ways in which planning (or particular aspects of planning) operate as an agent of disciplinary/governmental power, not the processes by which the disciplinary formation of planning is itself strategically targeted as a problem requiring various forms of intervention (cf. Finlayson, 2009). Taking a Foucauldian approach requires resisting any global explanation of these processes of change as somehow ‘determined’ by macro-structures such as neoliberalism, however. Instead, it suggests a need to explore the situated specificities through which such reform initiatives are constructed and enacted, paying close attention to the ‘strategies’ through which planning is constructed as a problem, the solutions that are sought, and the technologies through which these transformations are to be brought about. To illustrate this point, in the next section I will introduce an empirical example taken from research into the modernisation of the land-use planning system in Scotland between 2004–2012 and some of the ways in which a discourse of ‘efficiency’ has operated to discipline the apparatus of planning there.

Efficiency Effects? Understanding the Disciplinary Micro-Politics of Planning Reform As in many other jurisdictions around the world, the land-use planning system in Scotland has been subject to a series of reforms since the mid-2000s that have been presented as a necessary process of ‘modernisation’ for a system that was no longer ‘fit for purpose’.2 Perhaps understandably the problematisation of the performance of planning was at its strongest as the case for new legislation was made in 2005: The commitment to modernisation stemmed from a common perception … that the planning system is not serving Scotland well. Many users of the system have complained that it is over-bureaucratic, slow to respond to commercial and economic 198

The Production of Truth in Planning

needs … Community and voluntary groups and the general public, often see the planning system as complex, intimidating, unresponsive … Local and central government bodies are concerned that their key political objectives … are often frustrated by the planning system. (Scottish Government, 2005) This quotation highlights three key justifications that were presented for modernisation: (1) a pervasive concern with the perceived inefficiency of land-use planning that was viewed as a source of negative economic impacts; (2) a view that planning processes were not sufficiently inclusive of broader public concerns; and (3) concern that planning did not enable integration with other public services. Each of these – efficiency, inclusion and integration – corresponds to broader principles of public service and planning reform that have been central to the definition of ‘modern’ planning; all three problematise different aspects of existing planning processes (reform deliberations were notably less concerned with defining the substantive outcomes that planning might have in terms, for example, of an improved built environment). In Foucauldian terms, each also entails particular understandings of the objects that should be of concern to the planning system, the knowledge, practices social relations and ‘subject positions’ required to plan effectively. As such, each forms a distinctive rationale for reform measures, focusing attention on particular aspects of planning practice in Scotland. The relations between efficiency, integration and inclusion hint at the complexity of the apparatus that these discourses are tools for reforming. There are, for example, likely to be tensions in the relations between these three goals where, for example, the aim of increasing the speed of decision-making in the interests of economic efficiency might work against ensuring decisions are taken in an inclusive manner. In Scotland this has tended to be resolved by the discourse of ‘efficiency’ assuming particular priority. Like administrations in many other places, the Scottish Government has consistently sought to present itself as ‘open for business’ and has therefore been particularly concerned to ensure that any perceived barriers to private sector wealth creation are addressed. This has led to planning processes being geared toward the pursuit of ‘sustainable economic growth’, a focus that was evident when, despite strong public backing, the Scottish Government chose not to introduce a third party right of appeal against the grant of planning permission, a measure promoted as a means of strengthening the inclusion of wider publics in planning decision-making. The main reason cited for this decision was that granting third party rights would be inefficient, slowing development and deterring private investment. Thus the ways in which ‘inclusion’ came to be defined were effectively disciplined, its scope and meaning reshaped in relation to the overarching concern for efficiency. Driven by strong criticism of the inefficiency of public sector bureaucracies, the discourse of efficiency is readily identifiable as a powerful global strategy of problematisation of ideas and practices of planning. Its logic suggests that making planning processes more efficient by reducing unnecessary ‘red-tape’ will free the market to deliver the development on which sustainable economic growth relies. The evidence on which such claims rest has often been questionable and it is unclear whether successive waves of reform that have drawn on this ‘efficiency’ logic have had much appreciable impact on the quantity or quality of new development being ‘delivered’ by planning processes (Adams and Watkins, 2014; Gurran and Phibbs, 2014). This has led to exploration of the ideological function that blaming planning systems for failure might be performing within neoliberal regimes of spatial governance (e.g. Gunder, 2015; see also Inch, 2012a). A Foucauldian approach, however, does not set out to question the fit between the discourse of efficiency and a reality external to it, or read its logic in ideological terms as a front 199

Andy Inch

masking underlying contradictions, but instead seeks to explore how it has actually worked to reshape practices. As a strategy of problematisation, the discourse of efficiency attained disciplinary force by establishing links between powerful macro-economic concerns about the competitiveness of the Scottish economy and the particular ways in which planning ideas and practices have been institutionalised in Scotland – notably the micro-practices through which local authority planning offices process applications for planning permission. The long-standing equation of public sector practices with inefficiency and waste meant that there was a range of familiar governmental technologies available through which the problem of inefficiency could be addressed (arguably contrasting with a lack of immediately available or ‘off the shelf’ tools for effectively addressing the more complex challenges of inclusion and integration). For example, planners and local authority managers were already familiar with the idea that planning was a ‘service’ that needed to be responsive to the needs of its ‘customers’ and whose ‘performance’ could (and even should) be measured and rendered subject to disciplinary pressures for ‘continuous improvement’ in various ways, including, for example, through attentiveness to performance targets, most notably those that measured the speed of decision-making. The problem of inefficiency was forcefully argued by right-wing think tanks and political lobbies operating on behalf of the development industry. However, while certain groups of actors were particularly closely associated with promulgating this strategy, it should not be unambiguously equated with the pursuit and imposition of particular political or economic interests hostile to the idea of planning. Nor should the discourse of efficiency be seen as a purely repressive or disciplinary force, imposing neoliberal or managerial rationalities antithetical to an established (and, by inference, more progressive) planning culture. Rather, the need for greater efficiency in planning had become a widely accepted truth; a requirement to improve performance ‘figures’ broadly accepted by public and private sector professionals as part of what constitutes good planning practices. As a spokesperson for a planning professional body told me in 2012: What it does do is, it puts pressure on us to perform. Again, personally I don’t have a big problem with that. I think as with any kind of profession, we need to continue to improve our performance – as simple as that. Some of the figures we’ve got are pretty bad … And behind it all … I personally think we’ve got a five year window to try and show that we actually can make that progress. It is therefore possible to identify a series of strategic interventions intended to realign the disciplinary apparatus of planning around a particular focus on efficiency – directing attention and resources in particular ways, validating certain practices and subject positions while simultaneously rendering others problematic. Interviews suggested the extent to which this had been effective. For example, one public sector manager suggested to me that most of his staff were signed up to new approaches though: ‘We’ve got a few dinosaurs . . . you know people who find it difficult to change and leave their old working practices behind.’ In this regard, the regime of performance management had become a normal part of how professionals thought about and understood planning as an activity; arguably contrasting with accounts of the ‘culture wars’ that have sometimes waged between professionalism and managerialism in other areas of the local state (Cochrane, 2004). However, managerial language and practices were not adopted entirely uncritically. Rather, they were often subject to more or less strategic processes of reworking. For the most part, in Scotland these could not be described as resistances to either neoliberalism or managerialism; rather, they were, more typically, subtle reshapings of the meaning and emphasis of efficiency in the name of a different 200

The Production of Truth in Planning

understanding of what constituted ‘good planning’. For example, ideas of being ‘open for business’ were incorporated into day-to-day practices in particular ways by public sector planners who committed themselves to new and enhanced forms of dialogue with the development industry and applicants for planning permission. Ironically this was often less cost efficient for public planning authorities. However, it was seen as a way of responding to concerns about efficient customer service while opening up more positive subject positions for public sector planners as ‘facilitators’ of better and not just quicker development. The profession’s representative bodies, meanwhile worked with civil servants to try to devise more holistic means of measuring the quality of such planning services alongside (though not instead of) more standard calculations of the speed with which applications were processed. While a Foucauldian approach requires a more patient and detailed examination of all of these practices than there is space for here, this section has briefly highlighted the potential value of using Foucauldian tools to critically analyse how the apparatus of planning and its truths are being reworked. Efficiency has become a key discourse driving reformation of that apparatus in Scotland. This has had a variety of direct and indirect disciplinary effects on planning ideas and practices, including the marginalisation of other possibilities such as calls for more inclusive or integrative planning (on the former see Inch, 2015). Foucauldian analysis enables critical exploration of the disciplinary or normalising effects of reform discourses, however, it also moves beyond a purely repressive or totalising equation of planning’s shifting apparatus with global strategies of neoliberalisation or managerialisation; focusing attention on the micro-practices through which change is negotiated and in the process rendering visible some of the subtle reworkings and transformations that this can prompt. In other work I have described such practices as forms of ‘cultural work’ (Inch, 2012b). In the next section below I go on to further consider the potential value of this concept in developing and potentially expanding a Foucauldian response to the contemporary politics of planning.

Exploring the Contribution of ‘Cultural Work’ ‘Cultural work’ is a term that I have appropriated from the sociology of the professions, where it has been used to consider how professions organise to protect or expand their spheres of influence; adjusting their practices and knowledge claims in response to new opportunities or threats to their status or societal position (Abbott, 1998; Fournier, 2000). I see this term as having a broader potential usage and value, however, in focusing attention on the range of collective and individual practices through which various actors, including but not limited to professionals, adjust themselves to life within a given regime or apparatus. In this sense it is intended to encompass a wide range of possible practices, from processes of cooptation and accommodation through to strategic action to resist, challenge or reshape particular discourses or practices. The idea of cultural work is therefore broadly compatible with a Foucauldian concern for the micro-practices that emerge at the sites where forms of normalising or disciplinary power meet the lives of those they target and are either incorporated or reworked. It is also useful, however, to the extent that it draws attention to other significant aspects of contemporary realities, perhaps even pushing beyond some limitations of the tools Foucault bequeathed for analysing the ‘lived experience’ of any disciplinary apparatus. As Ian Hacking has argued: There is something missing in those [Foucault’s archaeological] approaches – an understanding of how the forms of discourse become part of the lives of ordinary people, or even how they become institutionalized and made part of the structure of institutions at work. (Hacking, 2004, 278) 201

Andy Inch

Hacking suggests that Foucault’s focus on the discursive ‘making up’ of subjects can be usefully supplemented by concern for the forms of interaction through which people engage with the subject positions that are made up for them – for this he turns to Erving Goffman’s (1959) symbolic interactionism as a means of exploring how people come to perform particular social roles and identities. Through the notion of cultural work I want to draw attention to something similar. This seems valuable because it reintroduces the socio-cultural weight and depth of experience that any given apparatus shapes and how this affects different actors in their ability to speak and act, whether as a form of resistance or just a means of coping with the various demands that are made of them (cf. Abram, 2004; Inch, 2015). The lived texture of this experience matters because it offers a rich understanding of a range of actions, interactions and possibilities that arguably cannot be grasped by purely historical methods. Others, including Judith Butler’s (2005) concern with the performative and how we ‘give an account of ourselves’, might offer alternative routes toward similar insights. However, Hacking’s juxtaposition of Foucault and Goffman, and the roots of symbolic interactionism in North American pragmatist philosophy, usefully invite further reflection on the potential synergies between Foucauldian critique and communicative planning theory (Fischler, 2000). Indeed, notwithstanding some significant differences, others have also suggested intersections between Foucault’s work and pragmatist concerns, for example in a shared orientation to understanding the formation of social problems (e.g. Rabinow, 2011). Turning toward the pragmatist in Foucault also brings us back to the second section, above, where I noted calls to consider how Foucauldian approaches might productively supplement planning theory’s established modes of ‘practice writing’. These have tended to focus on how planners or other actors shape action, rather than on how they themselves are shaped and involved in reshaping themselves and their practices as part of the (re)formation of a wider disciplinary apparatus. This is an omission that is arguably increasingly problematic in an era marked by the ‘government of government’, where various forms of cultural work might be seen to have become increasingly ubiquitous. Practice-focused planning theory arguably also has a tendency to make rather heroic, normative demands of individual planners as subjects who stand ‘in the face of power’; capable of working within a set of institutional structures while acting toward nobler ends. Such theory also therefore risks overlooking some of the more mundane but vitally important work involved in negotiating a ‘fit’ with prevailing cultures and attitudes (Abram, 2004). The concept of cultural work might also, therefore, draw attention to increasingly pervasive forms of practice that have perhaps not been sufficiently considered in planning theory to date and whose incorporation into the stories that theorists tell could help to develop accounts of planning practice attuned to the very ordinary ways in which power reaches down into the practices and self-understandings of actors in planning episodes (for example, why some planners become ‘dinosaurs’ and how that affects what they do!). Attention to the range of cultural work through which people come to make sense of themselves might therefore be a useful way of understanding the very different relations that collective and individual subjects forge with the discourses and institutions within which they act, and the ethical and political potentialities (and limitations) to which those relations give rise. As a result a focus on practices of cultural work also returns attention to the issues of agency raised above, and the challenge posed by those who argue that critical modes of analysis drawing on Foucauldian tools leave the all-important ‘so what?’ question unaddressed. As discussed above, critics have often expressed concern that Foucault’s radically decentred and disciplined conception of the human subject leaves little space to consider the agency 202

The Production of Truth in Planning

available to resist power (Hall, 2001; Mills, 2003). Recent scholarship has focused attention on what seems to have been a distinct attempt by Foucault himself to address this criticism in some of his later work on ethics, the subject and power. As Colin Gordon (1991) has argued, by uncovering the contingency of governmental projects and particularly their reliance on the willingness of the governed to accept their rationalities, Foucault came to emphasise the scope for ‘counter-conducts’. In exploring the link between governmental power and the conduct of the governed, this work also created an explicit connection between ethical practices and a particular form of agonistic politics; highlighting the potential responsibility and agency of subjects who resist, rework, challenge or refuse to be governed in particular ways (ibid.). The idea of cultural work highlights the presence of numerous sites where actors, individually and collectively, more or less actively, negotiate a sense of self and fit with prevailing regimes, sometimes in ways that work to reshape that regime itself. Part of the challenge of understanding the scope for better planning in a world being disciplined by neoliberal and managerial rationalities might, therefore, be to examine under what circumstances cultural work might coincide with what Foucault called the ‘work of freedom’ and the exercise of agency to assert alternative possibilities. This perhaps also requires planning theory to engage with a different Foucault, attuned to the possibilities of freedom as well as the forces of discipline (see Mendieta, 2011), and to forms of critical analysis that consciously seek out the limits of power. So how might this translate into real political practices in response to the ‘so what?’ question? Under what circumstances can cultural work take on strategic political forms rather than being solely concerned with accommodation to change? In strict Foucauldian terms, ethical and political potentialities cannot meaningfully exist as a set of normative orientations outside of the knowledges, practices, relations and subjectivities that constitute a given disciplinary apparatus. Instead they emerge as a range of immanent possibilities; challenging theorists and practitioners alike to critically and pragmatically assess the specific alternative practices that could be cultivated within a given historical conjuncture (Jenkins, 2011). In the Scottish case outlined above, the ways in which the discourse of efficiency became incorporated into planning practices were reworked to some extent by public sector planners and their representatives – evidence of cultural work – that enabled them to incorporate ideas of efficiency into their practices without threatening other valued goals. However, in doing so other opportunities might have been missed to develop alternative forms of planning based on discourses and practices of inclusion or integration. In the period since I studied those changes, planning practices have continued to be problematised as a source of constraint, delay and inefficiency. Exacerbated by severe budget cuts in local government, the negotiated model of ‘efficiency’ is itself under increasing strain and further reforms are being considered at the time of writing. While we might remain sceptical about the capacity of professional planners to actively resist, these developments are likely to give rise to new strategic responses, perhaps leading more planners (and other affected parties) toward more politically engaged forms of cultural work: speaking out or questioning how they might challenge some of the effects of the discourse of efficiency. Above all at this time, it might be that strategies are required that problematise the problematisation of planning as little more than a source of delay and inefficiency. Such strategies could take many forms, including: challenging the longer-term economic inefficiency and costs of poor planning control and unsustainable development; promoting the positive contribution different planning ideas and practices could make to creating better places and achieving more sustainable, inclusive forms of economic growth (e.g. Campbell et al., 2014); or making links between planning and other governmental projects, for example land reform or community empowerment, that have not tended to be part of the contemporary discourse of land-use planning in Scotland. 203

Andy Inch

These suggestions are not premised on radical refutations of neoliberalism or normative recasting of contemporary ideas of planning (though their ultimate intention might be sympathetic to such perspectives). Nor do they assume that the governmental apparatus of planning is necessarily a good thing. Instead, based on a critical analysis of the disciplinary power of the discourse of efficiency and of wider neoliberal and managerial rationalities, they highlight some strategies that might be elaborated in and against planning’s prevailing regime of truth in Scotland, with a view to generating other possibilities and perhaps greater freedom to plan in different, better ways.

Conclusion In this chapter I have explored the continued relevance of part of Michel Foucault’s ‘toolbox’ for planning theory. In particular I have considered the usefulness of thinking about contemporary transformations in the disciplinary apparatus of planning – the framework through which planning ideas and practices and their truths are shaped and reshaped. I have argued that such an analysis is particularly necessary in the face of the seemingly ubiquitous problematisation of planning in many places. Finally, I have suggested that focusing attention on the forms of cultural work through which actors respond, adjust and make sense of themselves in relation to shifts in the disciplinary apparatus of planning might have the potential to productively deepen planning theory’s engagement with practice and to demonstrate the political uses of a distinctively Foucauldian mode of critical analysis.

Notes 1 As will hopefully become clear, the dual meaning of ‘discipline’ as both a form of repressive power and a field of knowledge or practice is central to Foucault’s work, suggesting deep interconnections between power and knowledge. In this chapter the term is therefore used with both senses. 2 This section of the chapter draws on research supported by a grant from the Royal Institute of Chartered Surveyors (RICS) Research Trust (Project No. 433). The project explored how a reform agenda set out to change the culture of planning in Scotland, using documentary analysis, semi-structured interviews and some participant observation to explore how planning ideas, practices and professional identities had been ‘modernised’. For further details see Inch (2013, 2017).

References Abbott, A. (1988) The System of Professions: An Essay on the Division of Expert Labour, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Abram, S. (2004) ‘Personality and professionalism in a Norwegian district council’, Planning Theory, 3(1), 21–40. Adams, D. and Watkins, C. (2014) The Value of Planning, RTPI: London. Boyer, M. (1983) Dreaming the Rational City, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Butler, J. (2005) Giving an Account of Oneself, Ashland, OH: Fordham University Press. Campbell, H., Tait, M. and Watkins, C. (2014) ‘Is there space for better planning in a neoliberal world? Implications for planning practice and theory’, Journal of Planning Education and Research, 34(1), 45–59. Certomà, C. (2015) ‘Expanding the “dark side of planning”: Governmentality and biopolitics in urban garden planning’, Planning Theory, 14(1), 23–43. Cochrane, A. (2004) ‘Modernisation, managerialism and the culture wars: Reshaping the local welfare state in England’, Local Government Studies, 30(4), 481–496. Dardot, P. and Laval, C. (2014) The New Way of the World: On Neoliberal Society, London: Verso. Dean, M. (1999) Governmentality: Power and Rule in Modern Society, London: Sage. Finlayson, A. (2009) ‘Planning people: The ideology and rationality of New Labour’, Planning Practice and Research, 24(1), 11–22.

204

The Production of Truth in Planning Fischler, R. (1998) ‘For a genealogy of planning: Zoning and the welfare state’, Planning Perspectives, 13(4), 389–410. Fischler, R. (2000) ‘Communicative planning theory: A Foucauldian assessment’, Journal of Planning Education and Research, 19(4), 358–368. Flyvbjerg, B. (1998) Rationality and Power: Democracy in Practice, Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press. Flyvbjerg, B. and Richardson, T. (2002) ‘Planning and Foucault: In search of the dark side of planning theory’. In M. Tewdwr-Jones and P. Allmendinger (eds) Planning Futures: New Directions in Planning Theory, London: Routledge, 46–62. Forester, J. (1989) Planning in the Face of Power, Berkeley: University of California Press. Forester, J. (2000) ‘Conservative epistomology, reductive ethics, far too narrow politics: Some clarifications in response to Yiftachel and Huxley’, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 24(4), 914–916. Foucault, M. (1972) The Archaeology of Knowledge and the Discourse on Language, New York: Pantheon Books. Foucault, M. (1980) Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–77. C. Gordon (ed.), Brighton: Harvester. Foucault, M. (1991a) ‘Politics and the study of discourse’. In G. Burchell, C. Gordon and P. Miller (eds) The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press, 53–72. Foucault, M. (1991b) ‘Neitzsche, genealogy, history’. In P. Rabinow (ed.) The Foucault Reader, London: Penguin, 76–100. Foucault, M. and Deleuze, G. (1973) The intellectuals and power: A discussion between Michel Foucault and Gilles Deleuze, Telos, 16, 103–109. Fournier, V. (2000) ‘Boundary work and the (un)making of the professions’. In N. Malin (ed.) Professionalism, Boundaries and the Workplace, London: Routledge, 67–86. Goffman, E. (1959) The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life, New York: Doubleday. Gordon, C. (1991) ‘Governmental rationality: An introduction’ In G. Burchell, C. Gordon and P. Miller (eds) The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press, 1–51. Gunder, M. (2015) ‘Planning’s “failure” to ensure efficient market delivery: A Lacanian deconstruction of this neoliberal scapegoating fantasy’, European Planning Studies, 1–18 DOI:10.1080/09654313.2015. 1067291. Gurran, N. and Phibbs, P. (2014) ‘Evidence free zone? Examining claims about planning performance and reform in New South Wales’, Australian Planner, 51(3), 232–242. Hacking, I. (2004) ‘Between Michel Foucault and Erving Goffman: Between discourse in the abstract and face to face interaction’, Economy and Society, 33(3), 277–302. Hall, S. (2001) ‘Foucault: power, knowledge and discourse’. In M. Wetherell, S. Taylor and S. Yates (eds) Discourse Theory and Practice: A Reader, London: Sage, 72–81. Harris, N. (2011) ‘Discipline, surveillance, control: A Foucaultian perspective on the enforcement of planning regulations’, Planning Theory and Practice, 12(1), 57–76. Healey, P. (1997) Collaborative Planning: Shaping Places in Fragmented Societies, London: Macmillan. Huxley, M. (2002) ‘Governmentality, gender, planning: A Foucauldian perspective’. In M. Tewdwr-Jones and P. Allmendinger (eds) Planning Futures. New Directions in Planning Theory, London: Routledge, 136–153. Huxley, M. (2006) ‘Spatial rationalities: Order, environment, evolution and government’, Social & Cultural Geography, 7(5), 771–787. Huxley, M. (2010) ‘Problematizing planning: Critical and effective genealogies’. In J. Hillier and P. Healey (eds) The Ashgate Research Companion to Planning Theory: Conceptual Challenges for Spatial Planning, Farnham: Ashgate, 135–158. Huxley, M. (2013) ‘Hisoricizing planning: Problematizing participation’, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 37(5), 1527–1541. Huxley, M. and Yiftachel, O. (2000) ‘New paradigm or old myopia? Unsettling the ‘communicative turn’ in planning theory’, Journal of Planning Education and Research, 19(4), 333–342. Inch, A. (2012a) ‘Creating “a generation of NIMBYs”? Interpreting the role of the state in managing the politics of urban development’, Environment and Planning C, 30(3), 520–535. Inch, A. (2012b) ‘“Cultural work”, spatial planning and the politics of renewing public sector planning professionalism in England’, Town Planning Review, 83(5), 513–532. Inch, A. (2013) Changing the Culture of Scottish Planning, Final Report: RICS Research Trust Project No. 433. London: RICS.

205

Andy Inch Inch, A. (2015) ‘Ordinary citizens and the political cultures of planning: In search of the subject of a new democratic ethos’, Planning Theory, 14(4), 404–424. Inch, A. (2017) ‘Opening for business? Neoliberalism and the cultural politics of modernising planning in Scotland’, Urban Studies, Online first 18 January 2017, https://doi.org/10.1177/0042098016684731, 1–17. Jenkins, K. (2011) ‘The difference genealogy makes: Strategies for politicisation or how to extend capacities for autonomy’, Political Studies, 59(1), 156–174. Kooij, H. (2015) ‘Object formation and subject formation: The innovation campus in the Netherlands’, Planning Theory, 14(4), 339–359. Mendieta, E. (2011) ‘The practice of freedom’. In D. Taylor (ed.) Michel Foucault: Key Concepts, Durham: Acumen, 111–124. Mills, S. (2003) Michel Foucault, London: Routledge. Pløger, J. (2008) Foucault’s dispositif and the city, Planning Theory, 7(1), 51–70. Rabinow, P. (2011) ‘Dewey and Foucault: What’s the problem?’, Foucault Studies, 11(Feb.), 11–19. Sandercock, L. (2005) ‘Picking the paradoxes: A historical anatomy of Australian planning cultures’. In B. Sanyal (ed.) Comparative Planning Cultures, Abingdon: Routledge, 309–330. Sanyal, B. (ed.) (2005) Comparative Planning Cultures, Abingdon: Routledge. Scottish Government (2005) Modernising the Planning System: A White Paper, Edinburgh: Scottish Government. Walzer, M. (1986) ‘The politics of Michel Foucault’. In D. Hoy (ed.) Foucault: A Critical Reader, Oxford: Blackwell, 51–68. Watson, V. (2002) ‘Do we learn from planning practice? The contribution of the Practice Movement to planning theory’, Journal of Planning Education and Research, 22(2), 178–187.

206

17 COUNTERING ‘THE DARK SIDE’ OF PLANNING Power, Governmentality, Counter-Conduct Margo Huxley

Introduction This chapter continues an exploration of Foucauldian approaches to planning theory and, like Chapter 16, notes that Foucauldian concepts and perspectives have been productive of significant critical studies of urban/regional/environmental/spatial planning and land-use regulation. The discussion here argues that these sometimes quite disparate approaches to the analysis of planning policy or practice often draw on particular facets of Foucault’s thought in isolation from an interconnected range of concepts across his works: in particular, the notion of ‘counterconduct’ has not been taken up in any detail. I suggest that an examination of counter-conducts opens up more nuanced possibilities than the sometimes rather one-sided use made of Foucault’s work on power, discipline and governmentality. An analysis of counter-conducts, in effect, counters the ‘dark side’ of planning. This is not to suggest that there is a single cohesive theory to be derived from Foucault’s thought that can be neatly incorporated into the field of planning theory; nor is it to attempt to smooth out the contradictory and often ambiguous nature of his work. Rather, it is to point to some of the connections between strands of Foucault’s thought that have tended to be left under-explored in planning studies, particularly by those relying on the early translations into English of influential works such as Discipline and Punish (Foucault 1979a) and The History of Sexuality (Foucault 1979b). In order to begin a consideration of counter-conduct as expanding the range of Foucauldian approaches to the study of planning, the chapter first briefly outlines (only) a few of the ways Foucauldian concepts have been taken up in the planning literature, focusing on three in particular: power and rationality; control, regulation and surveillance; and governmentality and subjectification. I argue that these (and other approaches) have produced extremely useful critical insights into the effects and the limits of planning in terms of constraints and repressions exercised through policy discourses and technologies of land-use categorisation, zoning or surveillance (for example, Allen 1994; Harris 2011; Huxley 1994; McLaughlin and Muncie 1999). But less attention has been paid to productive projects of subjectification (the ‘conduct of conduct’ of the self and others) and ideas of ‘counter-conduct’. In order to explicate this argument, 207

Margo Huxley

I briefly examine Foucault’s (2002a) discussion of ‘the subject and power’, since this is one of the most explicit of Foucault’s statements outlining the connections between power, governmentality, the subject and counter-conducts. These interconnections are suggested as a fruitful way of approaching oppositional practices related to spatial policies and planning regulations. I then suggest some ways in which such perspectives could be developed as creative critiques, and indicate the potential for further analysis of governmental conceptions of space and place in the dynamic relationship between rationalities of planning and counter-conducts.

Planning and Foucault Inch (Chapter 16 in this volume) has provided a thorough overview of aspects of Foucault’s work that have been taken up in planning studies and I will not cover the same ground here. However, it is worth touching briefly on some further critical insights provided by Foucauldian-inspired approaches. Studies of the historical emergence of planning unsettle the often taken-for-granted narrative of the progressive necessity for spatial regulation (Boyer 1983; Fischler 1998; Huxley 2010, 2013; Long 1981, 1982; Sandercock 1998). Post-colonial and development studies point to the need to re-evaluate traditional planning histories of Empire or technical diffusion and rethink the colonialist underpinnings that persist in contemporary governmental projects and planning practices (e.g. Legg 2007; Porter 2006, 2010; Schindler 2015; Watson 2002, 2003; Yeoh 1996). Foucauldian discourse analysis has also proved a fertile source of policy critique (for instance, Tett and Wolfe (1991) on Canadian city plans), while other approaches have highlighted powers of discourse that have been less explored in the communicative planning paradigm (e.g. Richardson 1996; Sharp and Richardson 2001; see also Jacobs 2006). One of the most prominent forms of Foucauldian analysis in planning has focused on critical debates about the relations between power and rationality (e.g. Flyvbjerg 1996, 1998; Watson 2003), in response to communicative planning’s aspirations to create possibilities for minimally distorted communication and agreement on common purposes. The development of aspects of Foucauldian thought in relation to these questions often employs the trope of the ‘dark side of planning’, which is examined in the next section.

Foucault and the ‘Dark Side of Planning’ Here I focus on three strands of analysis that exemplify approaches to Foucault’s work in planning studies: power and rationality; discipline and social control; and governmentality, which in this field tend to have a common emphasis on the way power subverts the overt progressive aims of planning. Flyvbjerg’s (1998) groundbreaking Rationality and Power is an impressively detailed longitudinal study of the realrationalität of political decisions around the location of the Aalborg bus station. In terms of planning theory, the radical insights provided by this study lie in their challenge to the assumptions of normative communicative and collaborative planning approaches, and in their attention to the mundane minutiae of political manoeuvrings. Communicative approaches have tended to assume that planning is, and planners are, capable of minimising the distortions and corruptions attributed to power. Flyvbjerg’s study shows that power cannot be wished away, that rational discourse about technically optimal solutions or socially desirable democratic outcomes are trumped by the realrationalität of power (political, economic and social). He argues that if planning projects are to achieve the kinds of social, environmental or equitable economic aims that communicative planning theorists have espoused, then planning has to engage with 208

Countering ‘The Dark Side’ of Planning

the tactics of power, and understand that they are integral to the arenas in which planning operates (Certomà 2015; Flyvbjerg 1996, 1998; Flyvbjerg and Richardson 2002). This understanding of planning’s ‘dark side’ informs many studies that explore how planning and planners are inevitably caught up in the capillaries of power (see e.g. Certomà 2015; Flyvbjerg 1996; Flyvbjerg and Richardson 2002; Yiftachel 1994, 1998). A second group of approaches to ‘the dark side of planning’ – often influenced by particular readings of Foucault’s works such as Discipline and Punish (1979a) – examine the discipline and surveillance embedded in planning regulations, especially land-use controls and urban design for safety or ‘ethnocratic’ exclusions, and exercised in practices of enforcement of zoning and other forms of spatial regulation (e.g. Boyer 1983; Harris 2011; Huxley 1994; Lewi and Wickham 1996; Yiftachel 2009). These approaches invite planners to examine the disciplinary and normalising effects at work in seemingly neutral technical regulations or well-meaning projects of urban design. They employ Foucault’s notions of spatial order, division, exclusion, visibility and ‘the gaze’. Planning is seen to parallel the principles and aims of Bentham’s Panopticon – invisible monitoring that seeks to produce individuals who come to ‘discipline’ themselves (Foucault 1979a, Part 3.3: see for example, Allen 1994; Harris 2011; Huxley 1994; McLaughlin and Muncie 1999). These aspects of planning regulation can also be seen as overt enactments of state violence against ‘Other’ groups or populations (e.g. Watson 2009; Yiftachel 2009). A third form of analysis prompted by Foucauldian perspectives relates to the concept of governmentality – ‘the conduct of conducts’ of the self and of others, a form of power that seeks ‘to shape possible fields of action’ toward certain ends (Foucault 2002a: 340–342). A prominent approach in the uptake of the idea of governmentality has been the critique of neo-liberal efforts to reframe planning’s redistributive aspirations in the context of ‘the market’. Critical studies of neo-liberal planning and housing policies and programmes have scrutinised the aims and rationalities of projects reconfiguring state-economy-society-individual relations and the aims to produce – sometimes simultaneously – appropriately disciplined, normatively gendered, suitably entrepreneurial, consumerist, tech-savvy neo-liberal subjects (e.g. Cowan and McDermont 2006; Davoudi and Mandanipour 2013; Flint 2003; Huxley 2002; Raco 2003; Raco and Imrie 2003; Vanolo 2014). Approaches employing Foucauldian concepts such as these (often drawing on influential developments by Dean (1999) and Rose (1999)), have been extremely salutary in highlighting the inescapable circulation of power and the implication of planning in it, and contrasting this ‘dark side of planning’ with the somewhat anodyne tendencies of technical-rational or communicative analyses and prescriptions. Very broadly speaking then, in those studies seeking to draw attention to negative implications of planning, the main uses made of critical Foucauldian concepts have been to highlight aspects of the exercise of state and/or professional technical power, whether as political realrationalität, as disciplinary regulation and surveillance or as governmental redirection of the rationales for planning and the neo-liberal subjectification of those involved. However, the trope of the ‘dark side’ tends to replicate the idea that there is a ‘light side’ and that planning can be more like its ideal, just as communicative theory suggests. Flyvbjerg (1998: 234, paraphrasing Pascal), proposes that ‘power has a rationality that rationality does not know. Rationality, on the other hand, does not have a power that power does not know’. This is, in Smart’s (1983: 133) terms, to argue that ‘there remains, in principle, the possibility of a liberating rationality or reason’. But as Foucault (2002a: 328) says: ‘It is senseless to refer to reason as the contrary entity to nonreason’ because ‘there is no absolute form for rationality against which specific forms might be compared or evaluated’ (Smart 1983: 126). 209

Margo Huxley

Similarly, planning studies of ‘the dark side’ imply that there is a dichotomy between repressive power of the state (and/or capital, often in the form of property investment or ownership) as the main source of negatively exercised power that needs to be redressed or resisted. [T]he double-edged nature of the state … is shaped and reshaped by an ongoing tension between oppression and reform. This dialectical process is often ignored by planning theorists, who tend to overlook planning’s oppressive dimension and thereby literally keep planning’s dark side ‘in the dark’. (Yiftachel 1998: 400) While this is a significant insight, it carries the risk of imagining a self-identical, singleinterest source of resistance – an oppressed people, a homogenous constituency – and re-instating a hierarchical unilateral flow of power as control and suppression. Or, in terms of analyses that seek to counter the ‘dark side of planning’, that planning ‘in the face of power’ should, and can be an expression of universally accepted reason through which to attain progressive ends. From a variety of approaches, other planning theorists have pointed out the limitations of thinking in terms of ‘light’ and ‘dark’ sides of planning (Allmendinger and Gunder 2005; Hillier 2002a; Holgersen 2015). Like these critiques, a Foucauldian perspective sees that things are more complicated than ‘light/dark’, ‘progressive/regressive’ dichotomies. Rather, it is a matter of examining the different rationalities at work in different regimes of discourses, rules and procedures and the ‘truths’ that are invoked as reasons and principles for these. Different regimes of rationality are implicated in different regimes of power: and power does not emanate only from a singular ‘state’ or capitalist elite (although, of course, these are very real points of concentration of different powers). Power is productive, capillary, relational, strategic and exercised throughout the social body. Power is employed and exercised through a net-like organisation. Not only do individuals circulate between its threads; they are always in the position of simultaneously undergoing and exercising power. They are not only its inert or consenting target; they are always also the elements of its articulation. In other words, individuals are the vehicles of power, not its points of application. (Foucault 1980: 98) Given this, opposition can take many forms in a multiplicity of instances, and is not only effective or ‘valid’ as social movements or revolutions in the name of fundamental social change. Key to this understanding is the relationship between discipline and subjectification (Foucault 1979a; see also Elden 2001: 133–150), and between subjectification and governmentality: that is, rather than obfuscating the truth or repressing free sovereign individuals, power is productive – it produces, fosters, incites particular forms of subjectivities and behaviours (Foucault 2002a: 341). Governmentality as a form of subjectifying power is not only exercised by the state, but by, in and through social institutions and individuals: and contradictory, overlapping regimes power/ rationality/truth can produce counter-conducts in which the work of self-subjectification can become a form of resistance to particular instances of power. Foucault’s (2002a: 326–348) discussion of ‘the subject and power’ is pivotal to an understanding of these relationships. I examine this discussion next before going on to suggest its significance for Foucauldian studies of planning (theory and practice).

210

Countering ‘The Dark Side’ of Planning

The Subject and Power At the beginning of his discussion, Foucault (2002a: 326) states that the goal of his work has ‘not been to analyze the phenomena of power, nor to elaborate the foundations of such an analysis’: rather, his aim ‘has been to create a history of the different modes by which, in our culture, human beings are made subjects’. He restates his central project in terms of subjectification, in which the study of power is directed to examining the multiple ways in which sciences/disciplines, dividing practices/regulations and exercises of self-formation, have produced forms of subjectivity. The main themes of the discussion of relevance to my argument can be summarised as follows: 1 Power takes the form of ‘governmentality’ circulating throughout society, including but not confined to the state. That is, the focus on the emergence of the ‘governmental state’ in the much cited ‘governmentality’ lecture (Foucault 2007a: 87–114) is only one instance of governmental power. Power is not a substance to be possessed and imposed in a unilateral ‘downwards’ direction, but appears as it is exercised; it is relational, multifaceted and capillary. And importantly, it is distinct from relations of exploitation [Marx] and relations of communication [Habermas] (Foucault 2002a: 337–339). 2 Governmentality is the ‘conduct of conducts’ – training bodies, attending to the welfare of individuals and populations, and fostering appropriate behaviours and inner states. Various institutions of society crystallise the tricky combination of individualising and totalising ‘pastoral power’ (Foucault 2002a: 332), exercising the conduct of conducts through knowledge of the attributes of physical bodies, the characteristics of populations (‘bio-power’) and of individuals’ minds and ‘souls’. 3 Governmentality is the productive power of subjectification: it does not suppress or constrain pre-existing sovereign individuals – it produces subjects. This productive power is multifaceted, such that different regimes of (non-state and state) power and rationality, practices of discipline and regulation produce different subjectivities with specific histories in specific times and places. 4 The conduct of conducts acts on acting subjects: it ‘always act[s] upon one or more acting subjects by virtue of their acting or being capable of action. A set of actions upon other actions’ (Foucault 2002a: 341). A power relationship is articulated on the basis that ‘“the other” (the one over whom power is exercised) is recognised and maintained . . . as a subject who acts; and that faced with a relationship of power, a whole field of responses, reactions, results, and possible inventions may open up’ (Foucault 2002a: 340). This conception of the strategic and open-ended nature of power as the conduct of conducts, and the possibilities of opposition to specific instances of subjectification, is central to the notion of ‘counter-conducts’ that Foucault examines in his 1977–78 lectures (Foucault 2007a: 191–226). 5 Nevertheless, ‘there are also ‘blocks’ – outcomes of previous struggles, in which the adjustment of abilities, the resources of communication, and power relations constitute regulated, concerted systems’ (Foucault 2002a: 338). These stabilised relations are what Foucault calls ‘domination’ and are linked to ‘disciplines’. The prison, the asylum or the Panopticon exemplify in ‘their artificially clear and decanted systems’ (Foucault 2002a: 339) relations of power, the operations of the conduct of conduct, and the processes of subjectification that are present throughout society. But they are not origins of ideas or practices that then somehow ‘escape’ into society: they are crystallisations of aims and

211

Margo Huxley

objectives already present in emerging regimes of governmentality. ‘Blocks’ of domination can be destabilised through critical questioning of their taken-for-granted statuses and by practices of opposition to the relations of power they represent and the kinds of subjectivities they seek to foster (Foucault 2002a: 328–332). The inter-relations of governmentality and subjectification are elaborated and developed throughout Foucault’s writing, and there is not space here to follow up the rich details of his provocative (sometimes puzzling) re-workings of them. But it is important to note that the term draws on ‘government’ in its original wider sense: the government of, for instance, a family, a ship, a workshop, a religious order. Governmental subjectification solicits and fosters particular interior states as well as exterior actions, so that individuals come to act upon themselves in conformity with prevailing (cross-cutting, often contradictory) regimes of government. Organisations and groups throughout society attempt to shape and influence the comportments, behaviours, abilities and goals of different types of individuals toward particular ends, aiming to foster individuals who act as if they are free (Dean 1994: 156). Roughly from the 16th century in the West, the state becomes increasingly ‘governmentalised’; that is, the state begins to take on concerns for the appropriate behaviour and physical/ mental well-being of individuals and populations that were previously the provenance of the Church’s ‘pastoral power’ (Foucault 2002a). Paralleling this, a form of ‘political subjectification’ emerges that sees individuals as political subjects, particularly as ‘sovereign subjects or citizens within a self-governing political community under the conditions of liberal democracy’ (Dean 1994: 155). Analyses of neo-liberal governmentality have focused on this aspect. Foucault’s attention later turned to what he called ‘ethical self-formation’ (e.g. Foucault 2000a), which concerns the government of the self by the self ‘by means of which individuals seek to know, decipher, and act on themselves’ (Dean 1994: 156). Many studies invoking governmentality have tended to neglect ‘that Foucault’s equivocal usage of the term “conduct” means that it incorporates both conducting others (via governmental technologies) and conducting the self (via the ethical relation of the governed subject to its own conduction)’ (Cadman 2010: 548). However, the subject’s practices of self-constitution are ‘not something invented by the individual himself [sic]. They are models that he finds in his culture and are proposed, suggested, imposed on him by his culture, his society, and his social group’ (Foucault 2000a: 291). Ethical self-subjectification involves the subject’s reflection on the relations of the self to regimes of knowledge and power. Examining the government of the self attends to active practices involved in the constitution of various types of shifting, contradictory, forms of (self) subjectification (ibid.; see also Hofmeyr 2006). Since governmentality is diffuse and diverse and subjectivities are formed at the intersections of different regimes of power, rationalities and practices, there is no implication that a singular subjectivity is seamlessly achieved, reproduced or stabilised, even through individual self-subjectification. It is these mismatches and slippages that enable possibilities for ‘counterconducts’ (Cadman 2010: 549).

Counter-Conducts After considering and rejecting various terms for the processes he wants to illuminate – revolt, insubordination, disobedience, dissidence, misconduct – Foucault (2007a: 200–202) proposes the term ‘counter-conduct’: ‘counter-conduct in the sense of struggle against the processes implemented for conducting others’ (p. 201) (Foucault 2007b; see also Cadman 2010; Davidson 2011; Death 2010, 2011; Hofmeyr 2006; and Owen 1995 on critique). 212

Countering ‘The Dark Side’ of Planning

Counter-conducts are refusals of specific forms of governmental power – governmentality that aims to shape comportments, behaviours, states of mind, instantiated in diverse social loci: schools, prisons, private companies, government bureaucracies, local amenity groups, medicine and hospitals, NGOs, families, factories. Implicitly or explicitly, through stubborn refusal to change or through active opposition, counter-conducts pose implicit or specific questions about ‘how not to be governed like that, by that, in the name of those principles, with such and such an objective in mind and by means of such procedures, not like that, not for that, not by them’ (Foucault 2007b: 44, original emphasis). In this, Foucault develops a Kantian notion of critique, a critical attitude – a right to question (Cadman 2010: 545) power and knowledge, in which ‘to bring forth and question a field of subjection means that the subject cannot be quite what it was before’ (p. 547). Foucault (2007b: 47) argues that counter-conducts arise historically in interplay with governmentality. They are co-extensive with, and are both effects of, and productive of governmentality, each provoking and constitutive of the other. In so far as governmental power acts on the actions of others: ‘[R]esistance, commonly seen as an assertion of freedom, is itself bound up within networks of governmentality; and liberal democracy’s toleration of dissent and protest within certain limits works, paradoxically, to reinforce as well as challenge dominant power relations’ (Death 2011: 238–239; see Foucault 2002a: 340–342). The notion of ‘counter-conducts’ necessarily requires an understanding of Foucault’s ‘thin’ notion of the subject (Patton 1998). As previously outlined, it does not rely on humanist conceptions of immanent resistance by rights-bearing individuals, but sees the subject as formed through, and in opposition to cross-cutting, overlapping regimes of governmental (non-state and state) subjectification and self-subjectification. Hence, an approach that works with the idea of ‘counter-conducts’ looks within government (in the Foucauldian sense) – rather than assuming there is an ‘outside’ from where opposition can be mounted – in order ‘to see how forms of resistance rely upon, and are even implicated within, the strategies, techniques and power relationships they oppose’ (Death 2011: 240). But also, as Cadman (2010: 549) argues, ‘governors and governed’ alike are implicated in governmental subjectification: ‘[D]uring governmental contestations or counter-conducts’, governors and governed ‘act on their respective positioning as governors or governed. Indeed, it may well be that in some instances both ‘governors’ and ‘governed’ become subjected to the same mode of objectification and subjectification of their conduct [see for example, Inch this volume; Flint 2003]. Just as there is no ultimate ‘reason’ against which forms of rationality and formulations of truth can be assessed, so there is no mono-centric, ultimate locus of power against which a ‘great Refusal’ can be staged (Foucault 1979b: 95–96). And hence also, there are no universal abstract criteria for judging the ‘rightness’ or ‘progressiveness’ of protest or refusal (Davidson 2011; Death 2010, 2011) (a point I take up below in relation to planning). Rather, counter-conducts that provoke and respond to governmental subjectifications are an active form of critique (Foucault 2007b) that asserts the right to ask how not to be governed in ‘such and such a way’; that asserts the freedom to think and act otherwise; and that, in action and practice, refuses particular subjectivities – whether normalised or excluded (e.g. on the grounds of sexuality, disability, illness, gender, race, religion, politics). However, claims to the right to be included in categories and rationalities of political government – for instance, gay marriage – while demanding that liberal rationalities be consistent and raising questions about the conduct of government – do not necessarily become ‘counter-conducts’ for the very reason that they accept and seek acceptance in terms of the categories of their exclusion (Cadman 2010: 550). 213

Margo Huxley

This might seem pessimistic from the point of view of traditional conceptions of the freely acting individual who has inhabited much political theory and social science – whether as sovereign democratic citizens or autonomous individuals pursing progressive revolutionary change. But examining acts of protest, conflict and refusal of governmental rationalities and aims for the conduct of conducts can unsettle many of the assumed dichotomies between domination and freedom, the state and resistance, public and private, progressive and regressive. And this has the potential to open the way for different approaches that might draw attention to the complexities, contradictions – even the ironies – of acts of counter-conduct (Death 2010, 2011).

Conflict, Counter-Conducts, Subjectification An ‘analytics of counter-conducts’ focuses on the inevitability of contestation, refusal and conflict in any exercise of power as the conduct of conducts. There are, of course, numerous studies of the central and unavoidable role of conflict in planning (for example, Gualini 2015; Hillier 2002b; Huxley 2014; Inch 2015; McClymont 2011; Pløger 2004; Purcell 2009; Roskamm 2015). Many of these draw on the notion of ‘agonism’ (often following Mouffe, e.g. 1999). Agonism emphasises the potentially positive aspects of (certain kinds of) political struggle and links these to radical re-formations of democracy, which rely on conceptions of autonomous human agency and political notions of the rights-bearing individual. A focus on counter-conducts, in contrast, does not imply that any specific instance of refusal to be governed ‘like that’ necessarily leads to greater, more widely spread democracy, and does not seek to make judgements about progressive or regressive protests as such. Studying counterconducts involves ‘the flat and empirical little question: “What happens?”’ (Foucault 2002a: 337). It attends not only to rationalities of power, but to specific acts of governing (Rosol 2014: 72) and acts of refusal of the conduct of conduct in particular situations. An ‘analytics of counter-conduct’ ‘aims to diagnose and critique rationalities and practices of protest, and . . . is not primarily normative or prescriptive, in terms of advocating specific forms of dissent’ (Death 2010: 247). There is a growing body of work in planning studies that examines forms of counterconduct, even when not named as such. For instance, J. Allen’s (1996) study describes the self/ subjectification of a London housing action group; Tooke (2003) examines the possibilities for ‘strategic reversals’ that allow community involvement to influence government; McKee (2011) analyses what amount to refusals to be ‘governed like that’ among tenants affected by housing stock transfers in Glasgow; and Rosol (2014) examines the self/subjectification of a residents’ opposition group in Vancouver. Death’s (2010, 2011) political studies of global protest movements directed at major world summit meetings highlight the fields of visibility, regimes of knowledge, techniques and technologies and the political identities and subjectivities at work in these campaigns (Death 2010: 242–247). He explores the inextricable co-constitution of government as the conduct of what is considered legitimate protest with counter-conducts as opposition, refusal and inventive resistance. What, then, can an ‘analytics of counter-conduct’ bring to critical analyses of the rationalities and practices of planning and oppositions to them?

Planning’s Counter-Conducts: Developments and Openings In suggesting the potential for studying counter-conducts in relation to planning, I outline four of many possible avenues of enquiry: a focus on the subjectifying aspects of the power of planning as a form of the conduct of conducts; attention to the mundane details of ‘what happens’,

214

Countering ‘The Dark Side’ of Planning

examining the specificities of particular instances of governmentality and counter-conducts; exploration of the spatial rationalities and presuppositions integral to planning practices and the counter-conducts they invoke; and unsettling the binaries implied in studies of ‘the dark side’. First, and as outlined earlier, planning can be seen to conduct conducts in various ways. Policies and the problems they construct are variable and changing: but currently most neo-liberal governmentalities rest on assumptions about the kinds of subjects required for the operations of a market economy and a property-owning population. Within these frameworks, formal planning consultations set the boundaries of what can and cannot be said, and require particular sets of behaviours in order for participants to be heard (Abram 2000), in keeping with norms of the liberal political subject. Planning and land-use regulations operate with and through presuppositions about, for example, ‘compatible/mixed uses’, family housing, neighbourly relations, aesthetic and healthy environments. Planning as the conduct of conducts can be seen to be situated at the intersection of dominant stabilised power ‘blocks’, but its (fragile) taken-for-granted status is the result of ongoing work to maintain it against challenges from all sorts of contradictory political, economic and social pressures and shifting rationalities (on the historically contingent ‘cobbling-together’ of an entity known as ‘planning’, see Long (1981, 1982) and Huxley (2010)). Planning is thus ‘a lightning rod for conflict’ (Huxley 2014) and there are always the possibilities for challenge and refusal – whether ‘progressive’ or ‘regressive’. Planning both encounters and calls forth resistances to its particular exercises of governmentality, inciting and enacting counter-conducts that are refusals to be governed ‘like that’. Second, examining ‘what happens’ in instances when counter-conducts illuminate the exercise of power entails an approach to the specificities of time and place, and an alertness to actions, including those that might not necessarily seem intentionally oppositional or particularly progressive. An analytics of counter-conduct asks of any particular set of relations and interactions: What forms of the conduct of conducts, or subjectification, are being refused? And what forms are being defended or transformed? For instance, refusals of colonial regulation of traditional practices (e.g. Yeoh 1996) can be understood as forms of counter-conduct; or subversions of policy by state employees can be seen as refusals to govern ‘like that’. But equally, assessments of the possible effects and contingent outcomes of such encounters must similarly take account of the situated, reversible nature of conducts and counter-conducts. Third, although only relatively recently featuring in the development of governmentality approaches to planning, space was an important element of Foucault’s early interests in the asylum, the hospital, and of course, the prison, taken up more broadly in the Security, Territory, Population lectures (Foucault 2007a; see Foucault 2002b; Crampton and Elden 2007; Elden 2001). Urban, regional, environmental planning policies, programmes, regulations and practices are concerned with questions of space and territory and with the relationships between spaces, places, peoples and individuals – the distributions of activities and populations, the form and functions of cities, the aesthetics and ecologies of environments, the actions and behaviours of residents in communities and neighbourhoods (e.g. Dikeç 2007; Huxley 2006; Nissen 2014; Pløger 2008). Presuppositions about the causal effects of space – the spatial rationalities informing planning practices (Huxley 2006) – are enmeshed in planning’s ways of governing ‘like that’ and need to become an integral focus for any analytics of counter-conducts. Such an analytics would add the dimension of opposition to the idea that spaces are socially constructed and therefore may be re-constructed (Flyvbjerg and Richardson 2002: 56). Such an approach could explore some of the complexities of the practices and actions, the overt struggles and stubborn refusals attending particular projects of spatial governmentality. Refusals are not

215

Margo Huxley

only legal challenges, political conflicts or mass demonstrations, but inventive, creative assertions of different uses of, different ways of being in, different relations between places and subjectivities (Gribat and Huxley 2015). Finally, in Discipline and Punish, Foucault (1979a: 222) speaks of the ‘dark side’ of the Enlightenment – the disciplinary mechanisms and techniques of calculation that accompanied the establishment of juridical frameworks and parliamentary representation. But later developments of governmentality, subjectification and counter-conduct introduced equally important and complex perspectives. The mutual strategies and struggles, provocations and refusals integral to the exercise of the conduct of conducts are not reducible to dark or light, repression or revolution, progress or regression. Governmentality and counter-conduct are not mutually exclusive, heads or tails sides of a coin, but enmeshed, entangled relations, each implying the other. This opens the way to examining ‘flat, empirical questions’ about ‘what happens’ in refusals of planning – whether by NIMBY residents’ groups, displaced Council tenants, neo-liberal politicians, radical environmentalists or property developers. It opens up to scrutiny particular forms of ‘conduction’ and counter-conducts in specific situations: dominant conducts which may ‘become rehearsed and re-embedded . . . [or may] shift in a myriad of directions’ (Hobson 2009: 185). This is unsettling and indeed, risky: it means analysing not just ‘what happens’ in protests over environmental or social justice issues that we might wish to position on ‘the light side’, but paying equal attention to ‘what happens’ when counter-conducts are made visible as economistic or masculinist or racial or homophobic or class-based oppositions to planning processes. Such an attitude invites critical self-reflection on planning by planners, a self-reflection that is itself a form of counter-conduct. It can productively destabilise assumptions about the aims, practices and predictability of the outcomes and effects of actions undertaken in the name of planning and contribute to local, strategic experiments with different actions, different subjectivities, different conducts.

Conclusion Foucault explicitly links this domain [of counter-conduct] to his definition of the ‘critical attitude,’ a political and moral attitude, a manner of thinking, that is a critique of the way in which our conduct is governed … . This critical attitude is part of a philosophical ethos, and no such ethos is effective without a permanent exercise of counter-conduct. (Davidson 2011: 37) I have argued that Foucault’s concept of counter-conduct opens up possibilities for reexaminations of planning that move beyond debates over the ‘communicative turn vs. the dark side’. Foucault sees counter-conducts as strategies of freedom which, because they involve questioning governmental conduction, also involve a form of self-reflection which opens up possibilities for minimising relations of domination or power present in self-formation and in political action. Giving equal weight to the counter-conducts provoked by planning and to practices of planning as themselves possible forms of counter-conducts fosters a critical attitude that challenges taken-for-granted regimes of governmentality. Asking ‘how not to be governed like that’ can become transformative self-reflection on one’s conduction of the conduct of others and of oneself. In the performance of this critical attitude, however, there needs to be an acute awareness of, and attention to those whose governmental subjectification deprives them of the right to action (Cadman 2010: 552). 216

Countering ‘The Dark Side’ of Planning

Engaging with the implications of counter-conducts is a difficult position for those who defend planning as a besieged guardian of the ‘public good’ to accept. Although the defence of planning as an unquestionably Good Thing can raise questions about neo-liberal rationalities of government and the primacy of the market (Rose 1999) – planners need to see that, at the same time, planning seeks to conduct the conducts of others and thereby incites counter-conducts of refusal. The point is not that exercises of power are bad and resistance is good nor that in every case we able to make a priori judgements about which is which, but rather ‘that everything is dangerous, which is not exactly the same as bad. If everything is dangerous, then we always have something to do. So [this] position leads not to apathy but to a hyper- and pessimistic activism’ (Foucault 2000b: 256). It is to understand that in each instance of counter-conduct incited and responded to by planning rationalities and practices – and with no guarantee we have got it right – ‘the ethicopolitical choice we have to make . . . is to determine which is the main danger’ (Foucault 2000b: 256).

References Abram, S. (2000) ‘Planning the public: some comments on empirical problems for planning theory’, Journal of Planning Education and Research, 19: 351–357. Allen, J. (1996) ‘Our town: Foucault and knowledge-based politics in London’, in S. Mandelbaum, L. Mazza and R. Burchell (eds), Explorations in Planning Theory, Brunswick, NJ: Center for Urban Policy Research Press, pp. 328–344. Allen, M. (1994) ‘“See you in the city”: Perth’s citiplace and the space of surveillance’, in K. Gibson and S. Watson (eds), Metropolis Now: planning and the urban in contemporary Australia, Sydney: Pluto Press, pp. 137–147. Allmendinger, P. and Gunder, M. (2005) ‘Applying Lacanian insight and a dash of Derridean deconstruction to planning’s “dark side”’, Planning Theory, 4, 1: 87–112. Boyer, M. C. (1983) Dreaming the Rational City: the myth of American city planning, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Cadman, L. (2010) ‘How (not) to be governed: Foucault, critique, and the political’, Environment and Planning D: Society and Space, 28: 539–556. Certomà, C. (2015) ‘Expanding the “dark side of planning”: governmentality and biopolitics in urban garden planning’, Planning Theory, 14, 1: 23–43. Cowan, D. and McDermont, M. (2006) Regulating Social Housing: governing decline, Abingdon: Routledge. Crampton, J. and Elden, S. (eds) (2007) Space, Knowledge and Power: Foucault and geography, Aldershot: Ashgate. Davidson, A. (2011) ‘In praise of counter-conduct’, History of the Human Sciences, 24, 4: 25–41. Davoudi, S. and Madanipour, A. (2013) ‘Localism and neo-liberal governmentality’, Town Planning Review, 84, 5: 551–561. Dean, M. (1994) ‘“A social structure of many souls”: moral regulation, government, and self-formation’, Canadian Journal of Sociology, 19, 2: 145–168. Dean, M. (1999) Governmentality: power and rule in modern society, London: Sage. Death, C. (2010) ‘Counter-conducts: a Foucauldian analytics of protest’, Social Movement Studies, 9, 3: 235–251. Death, C. (2011) ‘Counter-conducts in South Africa: power, government and dissent at the World Summit’, Globalizations, 8, 4: 425–438. Dikeç, M. (2007) ‘Space, governmentality and the geographies of French urban policy’, European Urban and Regional Studies, 14, 4: 277–289. Elden, S. (2001) Mapping the Present: Heidegger, Foucault and the project of a spatial history, London: Continuum. Fischler, R. (1998) ‘Toward a genealogy of planning: zoning and the Welfare State’, Planning Perspectives, 13: 4, 389–410. Flint, J. (2003) ‘Housing and ethopolitics: constructing identities of active consumption and responsible community’, Economy and Society, 32, 4: 611–629.

217

Margo Huxley Flyvbjerg, B. (1996) ‘The dark side of planning: rationality and “realrationalität”’, in S. Mandelbaum, L. Mazza and R. Burchell (eds), Explorations in Planning Theory, New Brunswick, NJ: Center for Urban Policy Research Press, pp. 383–394. Flyvbjerg, B. (1998) Rationality and Power: democracy in practice, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Flyvbjerg, B. and Richardson, T. (2002) ‘Planning and Foucault’, in P. Allmendinger and M. Tewdwr-Jones (eds), Planning Futures: new directions for planning theory, London: Routledge, pp. 136–153. Foucault, M. (1979a) Discipline and Punish: the birth of the prison, New York: Vintage Books. Foucault, M. (1979b) The History of Sexuality Volume 1: an introduction, Harmondsworth: Penguin. Foucault, M. (1980) ‘Two Lectures’, in Michel Foucault: power/knowledge (ed. C. Gordon), Brighton: The Harvester Press, pp. 78–108. Foucault, M. (2000a) ‘The ethics of concern for the self as a practice of freedom’, in Ethics, Subjectivity and Truth: essential works of Foucault 1954–1984, Volume 1 (ed. P. Rabinow), London: Allen Lane, pp. 281–301. Foucault, M. (2000b) ‘On the genealogy of ethics: and overview of work in progress’, in Ethics, Subjectivity and Truth: essential works of Foucault 1954–1984, Volume 1 (ed. P. Rabinow), London: Allen Lane, pp. 253–280. Foucault, M. (2002a) ‘The subject and power’, in Power: essential works of Foucault 1954–1984, Volume 3 (ed. J. Faubion), London: Penguin, pp. 326–348. Foucault, M. (2002b) ‘Space, knowledge, and power’, in Power: essential works of Foucault 1954–1984, Volume 3 (ed. J. Faubion), London: Penguin, pp. 349–364. Foucault, M. (2007a) Security, Population, Territory: lectures at the Collège de France 1977–1978 (ed. M. Senellart), Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Foucault, M. (2007b) ‘What is critique?’ in The Politics of Truth (ed. S. Lotringer), Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), pp. 41–82. Gribat, N. and Huxley, M. (2015) ‘Problem spaces, problem subjects: contesting policies in a shrinking city’, in E. Gualini (ed.), Planning and Conflict: critical perspectives on contentious urban developments, Routledge: New York, pp. 164–184. Gualini, E. (ed.) (2015) Planning and Conflict: critical perspectives on contentious urban developments, Routledge: New York. Harris, N. (2011) ‘Discipline, surveillance, control: a Foucaultian perspective on the enforcement of planning regulations’, Planning Theory and Practice, 12, 1: 57–76. Hillier, J. (2002a) Shadows of Power: an allegory of prudence in land-use planning, London: Routledge. Hillier, J. (2002b) ‘Direct action and agonism in democratic planning practice’, in P. Allmendinger and M. Tewdwr-Jones (eds), Planning Futures: new directions for planning theory, London: Routledge, pp. 110–135. Hobson, K. (2009) ‘On a governmentality analytics of the “deliberative turn”: material conditions, rationalities and the deliberating subject’, Space and Polity, 13, 3: 175–191. Hofmeyr, B. (2006) ‘The power not to be (what we are): the politics and ethics of self-creation in Foucault’, Journal of Moral Philosophy, 3, 2: 215–230. Holgersen, S. (2015) ‘Spatial planning as condensation of social relations: a dialectical approach’, Planning Theory, 14, 1: 5–22. Huxley, M. (1994) ‘Panoptica: Utilitarianism and land-use control’, in K. Gibson and S. Watson (eds), Metropolis Now: planning and the urban in contemporary Australia, Sydney: Pluto Press, pp. 148–160. Huxley, M. (2002) ‘Governmentality, gender and planning: a Foucauldian perspective’, in P. Allmendinger and M. Tewdwr-Jones (eds), Planning Futures: new directions for planning theory, London: Routledge, pp. 136–153. Huxley, M. (2006) ‘Spatial rationalities: order, environment, evolution and government’, Social and Cultural Geography, 7, 5: 771–787. Huxley, M. (2010) ‘Problematizing planning: critical and effective genealogies’, in J. Hillier and P. Healey (eds), The Ashgate Research Companion to Planning Theory: conceptual challenges for spatial planning, Farnham: Ashgate, pp. 135–158. Huxley, M. (2013) ‘Historicizing planning, problematizing participation’, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 37, 5: 1527–1541. Huxley, M. (2014) ‘Planning means conflict’, FOReTHOUGHT: making space for planning, Urban Studies and Planning Research Blog, University of Sheffield. www.sheffield-planning.org/2014/12/16/planningmeans-conflict/ (accessed 28 January 2015).

218

Countering ‘The Dark Side’ of Planning Inch, A. (2015) ‘Ordinary citizens and the political cultures of planning: in search of the subject of a new democratic ethos’, Planning Theory, 14, 4: 404–424. Jacobs, K. (2006) ‘Discourse Analysis and its utility for urban policy research’, Urban Policy and Research, 24, 1: 39–52. Legg, S. (2007) Spaces of Colonialism: Delhi’s urban governmentalities, Oxford: Blackwell. Lewi, H. and Wickham, G. (1996) ‘Modern urban government: a Foucaultian perspective’, Urban Policy and Research, 14, 1: 51–64. Long, M. (1981) Planning: ‘Birth’ or ‘Break’? Problems in the historiography of British town planning, Working Paper 18, Department of Civic Design, University of Liverpool, Liverpool. Long, M. (1982) Moral Regime and Model Institutions: precursors of town planning in early Victorian England, Working Paper 20, Department of Civic Design, University of Liverpool, Liverpool. McClymont, K. (2011) ‘Revitalising the political: development control and agonism in planning practice’, Planning Theory, 10, 3: 239–256. McKee, K. (2011) ‘Sceptical, disorderly and paradoxical subjects: problematizing the ‘Will to Empower’ in social housing governance’, Housing, Theory and Society, 28, 1: 1–18. McLaughlin, E. and Muncie, J. (1999) ‘Walled cities: surveillance, regulation and segregation’, in S. Pile, C. Brook and G. Mooney (eds), Unruly Cities? Order/disorder, London: Routledge/The Open University, pp. 103–148. Mouffe, C. (1999) ‘Deliberative democracy or agonistic pluralism?’ Social Research, 66, 3: 745–758. Nissen, N. (2014) Nordhavn: a governmentality analysis of urban planning, Copenhagen: Copenhagen Business School. Owen, D. (1995) ‘Genealogy as exemplary critique: reflections on Foucault and the imagination of the political’, Economy and Society, 24, 4: 489–506. Patton, P. (1998) ‘Foucault’s subject of power’, in J. Moss (ed.), The Later Foucault: politics and philosophy, London: Sage, pp. 64–79. Pløger, J. (2004) ‘Strife: urban planning and agonism’, Planning Theory, 3, 1: 71–92. Pløger, J. (2008) ‘Foucault’s dispositif and the city’, Planning Theory, 7, 1: 51–70. Porter, L. (2006) ‘Planning in (post)colonial settings: challenges for theory and practice’, Planning Theory and Practice, 7, 4: 383–396. Porter, L. (2010) Unlearning the Colonial Cultures of Planning, Farnham: Ashgate. Purcell, M. (2009) ‘Resisting neoliberalization: communicative planning or counter-hegemonic movements?’ Planning Theory, 8, 2: 140–165. Raco, M. (2003) ‘Governmentality, subject-building, and the discourses and practices of devolution in the UK’, Transactions of the British Institute of Geographers NS, 28: 75–95. Raco, M. and Imrie, R. (2003) ‘Governmentality and rights and responsibilities in urban policy’, Environment and Planning A, 32: 2187–2204. Richardson, T. (1996) ‘Foucauldian discourse: power and truth in urban and regional policy making’, European Planning Studies, 4, 3: 279–292. Rose, N. (1999) Powers of Freedom: reframing political thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Roskamm, N. (2015) ‘On the other side of “agonism”: the “enemy”, the “outside” and the role of antagonism’, Planning Theory, 14, 4: 384–403. Rosol, M. (2014) ‘On resistance in the post-political city: conduct and counter-conduct in Vancouver’, Space and Polity, 18, 1: 70–84. Sandercock, L. (ed.) (1998) Making the Invisible Visible: a multicultural planning history, Berkeley: University of California Press. Schindler, S. (2015) ‘Governing the twenty-first century metropolis and transforming territory’, Territory, Politics, Governance, 3, 1: 7–26. Sharp, L. and Richardson, T. (2001) ‘Reflections on Foucauldian discourse analysis in planning and environmental policy research’, Journal of Environmental Policy and Planning, 3: 193–209. Smart, B. (1983) Foucault, Marxism and Critique, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Tett, A. and Wolfe, J. (1991) ‘Discourse analysis and city plans’, Journal of Planning Education and Research, 10, 3: 209–214. Tooke, J. (2003) ‘Spaces for community involvement: processes of disciplining and appropriation’, Space and Polity, 7, 3: 233–246. Vanolo, A. (2014) ‘Smartmentality: the Smart City as disciplinary strategy’, Urban Studies, 51, 5: 883–898.

219

Margo Huxley Watson, V. (2002) Change and Continuity in Spatial Planning: metropolitan planning in Cape Town under political transition, London: Routledge. Watson, V. (2003) ‘Conflicting rationalities: implications for planning theory and ethics’, Planning Theory and Practice, 4, 4: 395–407. Watson, V. (ed.) (2009) ‘“The planned city sweeps the poor away …” Urban planning and 21st century urbanisation’, Progress in Planning, 3: 151–194. Yeoh, B. (1996) Contesting Space in Colonial Singapore: power relations and the urban built environment, Singapore: Singapore University Press. Yiftachel, O. (1994) ‘The dark side of modernism: planning as control of an ethnic minority’, in S. Watson and C. Gibson (eds), Postmodern Cities and Spaces, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 216–234. Yiftachel, O. (1998) ‘Planning and social control: exploring the dark side’, Journal of Planning Literature, 12, 4: 395–406. Yiftachel, O. (2009) ‘Critical theory and “gray space”: mobilization of the colonized’, City, 13, 2–3: 246–263.

220

18 CO-EVOLUTIONARY PLANNING THEORY Evolutionary Governance Theory and Its Relatives Kristof Van Assche, Raoul Beunen and Martijn Duineveld

Introduction In this chapter we analyze the presence, the origins and the potential of co-evolutionary perspectives in planning theory. We pay special attention to Evolutionary Governance Theory, as a comprehensive perspective on co-evolution in governance and in spatial planning (Van Assche et al., 2014b). Co-evolution is conceptualized in different manners in the landscape of planning theory and the wider setting of social theories (von Tunzelmann, 2003; Kemp et al., 2007; Volberda and Lewin, 2003; Healey, 2004, 2006). Evolution is an ongoing process of change, in which existing elements and structures are shaping and changing each other in an ongoing interplay, with each step, each change in structures and elements building on the previous ones. Co-evolution is the entwined evolution of two or more systems or entities, whereby changes in one affect changes in the other. What can co-evolve will be different depending on discipline and theory: systems, species, networks, organizations, societies, perspectives. This basic understanding is compatible with most co-evolutionary theories. A few features of co-evolution recur in most versions: •• •• ••

Co-evolution requires a concept of a system in which several things co-evolve, more than a sum of loosely coupled elements, structures, processes; it requires an idea of an iterative, recursive process, where one operation is input for the next one; and it relies on an idea of selectively triggered responses in the system: not all things co-evolve in the same way, not all changes in an entity cause changes in all other entities.

The concept of contingency plays a central role: whatever exists is considered to be the product of evolution, hence could have been different. It is possible, yet not necessary, and certainly not necessarily like this. Co-evolution reinforces the idea of contingency, as a next evolutionary step can be triggered by other entities in the system. 221

K. Van Assche, R. Beunen and M. Duineveld

In spatial planning, one can for example consider the co-evolution of discourses, actors, institutions, or the co-evolution of the overall planning systems with the particular governance context or the wider community in which it is embedded. A planning system evolves out of an older one, it co-evolves with other domains of governance, and within it, different organizations and forms of knowledge co-evolve. ‘Gaps’ in knowledge or in actor participation will be observed, change will be advocated for, in a web of co-evolving entities, with planning critics and supporters responding to each other, actors within the planning system reacting to each other, and when change itself is enacted, this will be modified in its form and effects through the same system of co-evolving entities. In one community, planning will respond directly to changes in social policy, in others, it is co-evolving more with environmental policy, is more sensitive to shifts in the development community, or to innovations in the academic reflection on planning. The various versions of co-evolutionary theory differ in the elements they focus on, in what is seen as the overall structure, and in the way in which interrelations between systems, and between structures and elements are understood. Different theories focus on people, actions, or communications as, sometimes fixed or essentialized, elements, and on institutions, discourses, or social systems as the main structures. The co-evolutionary approach to planning we develop in this chapter presents a middle ground between (social) engineering approaches toward planning on the one hand and theories disqualifying planning and steering on the other (cf. Easterly, 2006), a middle ground between overestimating the steering possibilities of governments and overestimating the organizing capacities of markets. The critique of modernist and technocratic versions of planning theory, and the concomitant push for concepts of contingency and co-evolution were particularly poignant in the poststructuralist theories and reflections that entered the field of planning in the 1990s (Hillier, 2002; Gunder and Hillier, 2009; Healey, 1997; Flyvbjerg, 1998; for an overview, see Van Assche et al., 2014a). In parallel, other perspectives, sometimes older than post-structuralism, understand planning as muddling through (Forester, 1984; Fischer and Forester, 1993; Lindblom, 1959) or self-organizing and emergent processes (Dam et al., 2014; Hillier, 2008). In geography, anthropology and sociology, critical studies often relegate spatial planning to the domain of contested hierarchies in economic, political and bureaucratic elites, to control space as a profitable resource (Ferguson, 1994). The planning enterprise as such is then understood as incapable of grasping its own co-evolutionary nature. Detailed analyses of different forms of planning can help us to discern more sharply how certain planning approaches work out better in one place than another and why some attempts at planning reform are more successful than others. Within such analyses both theory and practice have to be considered. Planning theories are often inspired by strong familiarity with particular planning practices, while planning practice itself is often shaped by academic expertise, including planning theories. The ways in which planning is understood, and the theories that are considered relevant and useful within a particular planning system, can strongly influence and co-constitute planning practices (cf. Voß and Freeman, 2016; MacKenzie et al., 2007). Theories are part and parcel of the pattern of co-evolution in planning systems; which role they play hinges on their contingent evolutions. A planning system that does not understand itself as a cohesive system of spatial organization, with little interest in comprehensive planning aiming at multiple policy goals, is not likely to be driven by planning theories existing somewhere else, while a system where planning practice and theory have been tightly coupled for a long time, is more likely to transform itself using new theoretical ideas. We make a case here for theories of co-evolution and contingency as theories best capable of mapping out the terrain between steering for utopia and laissez-faire. We argue that planning 222

Co-Evolutionary Planning Theory

systems can be flexible and rigid; they converge and diverge, and they are unpredictable but path-dependent. Unraveling patterns of co-evolution is revealing the unique balance between flexibility and rigidity, the specific sorts and weight of path dependencies, while the exercise can increase reflexivity, which in turn makes it easier for a planning system to see itself as a unity, rather than a set of elements and practices. In the following paragraphs, we first reflect on the notion of co-evolution in social theory and planning theory. Then we devote more attention to what is called Evolutionary Governance Theory (EGT), a theory that borrows elements from post-structuralism, institutional economics and social systems theory, and incorporates them, together with new elements, in a novel conceptual architecture. EGT develops a co-evolutionary understanding of society into a co-evolutionary theory of governance, administration and planning. It is a theory of organization, steering, and planned change. EGT is partly rooted in planning research and aims to delineate planning and its possibilities in different governance paths. Planning within this perspective is understood as a political activity that can and does take many forms that change over time, in evolutions that alter both the structures and elements of planning systems.

Co-Evolution in Social Theory Many theories of society share the idea that elements are co-evolving. Elements can be understood as groups, as functions of government, as parts of government, as areas, as structures in narrative, and so on. In this sense, structuralism and post-structuralism, as well as functionalism, complexity theory, and systems theories incorporate notions of co-evolution. Sociological functionalism, exemplified by Talcott Parsons, understood evolution as progress (Parsons, 1966). In this approach social complexity was assessed as positive, if specialized functions are developing and balancing out. Similarly, in evolutionary anthropology (e.g. Lieberman, 2007), evolution toward complexity is appreciated, if complexity equals progress. Anthropological functionalism in the line of Malinowski (1944) saw such evolution as necessarily co-evolution, since different features of social life are part of one evolving social fabric in which their meaning and function change together with other features. In classic sociology, Weber and other theorists of nation states and bureaucracy highlight co-evolution as specialization, organization, division of labor, and professionalization (Weber, 2009). Freud and later psycho-analysts such as Lacan subscribed to their own version of co-evolution, with social and psychological features co-evolving, and the contingent evolution of symbolic media, language and other sign systems, linking the social and the individual (Gunder and Hillier, 2009; Lacan, 2006). Niklas Luhmann and his version of social systems theory represent, in our view, the most formidable achievement in co-evolutionary social theory (Luhmann, 1995, 2012). Luhmann, more explicitly than the aforementioned social theorists, harks back to theories of biological evolution and leans on the work by the Chilean biologists Maturana and Varela (1987), who explored the biological roots of human understanding by looking at the interplay between biological, cognitive and social processes. They explain human understanding as the contingent outcome of the co-evolution of self-reproducing systems. Maturana and Varela coined the concept of autopoiesis, self-reproduction, as the main feature of the evolution of life. Biological structures, elements and processes are all the result of previous structures, elements and processes. They argued that the adaptation of a system relies on its existing features, on repertoires of interpretation, and on possible responses. The features of any system are the result of a history of previous adaptation, which took place in autopoietic fashion. 223

K. Van Assche, R. Beunen and M. Duineveld

For Luhmann, this was the key to a new co-evolutionary theory of society. The evolving elements in his systems theory of society, however, were not people or groups, but communications (Luhmann, 1992; Moeller, 2006). Social systems are modes of communication. In his theory society is an encompassing social system, including co-evolving systems, most importantly function systems (such as law, religion, politics, and art) and organizations (Luhmann, 1995). All social systems have their own logic of reproduction, and unique understanding and observation of the world. The selective understanding and observation of the world is key to social systems theory. Societies can be understood as collections of evolving and dividing modes of interpretation. Although the label co-evolution is not always explicitly mentioned in post-structuralist theories, one can observe many notions of co-evolution. For Lacan, for example, the sub-conscious was structured like a language, and our understanding and construction of self and society is a co-evolution necessarily enabled by contingent and evolving sign systems (Lacan, 2006). (This radically constructivist and dynamic view also makes him a post-structuralist, even if he belongs to an earlier generation than Foucault, Barthes and Derrida) Deleuze gave matter more agency, but argues that it is the meeting of mind and matter that produces meaning and the world (Deleuze and Guattari, 1987). Social life in a Deleuzian perspective is co-evolutionary because all structures producing or supporting the production of meaning – which he calls territories, plateaus, or machines – rest on each other and respond to each other. Foucault (1979), arguably the most influential post-structuralist, explains in his histories of the present, his genealogies, how power and knowledge are entangled and mutually constitutive and are together constituting discourses that build and change our world. In other words: power and knowledge co-evolve and they are continuously evolving in an ongoing interplay with other power/knowledge configurations. Discourses generate meaning and other effects in a world with other discourses.

Co-Evolution in Planning Theory Within the planning discipline, theory itself has had a precarious existence, and theories that stepped back from immediate normativity, to deepen analysis first, had an even tougher time. Nevertheless, Foucault, Lacan, and to a lesser extent Deleuze and Luhmann entered the fray of the debate, greatly helped by the mainstream publication of the journal Planning Theory in 2001. Sociological and anthropological versions of co-evolution did not play an immediate role, but exerted influence via their embedding in institutional approaches to planning which proliferated in the 1990s, building on political theory, sociology and several versions of institutional economics (e.g. Ostrom, 2005; North, 1990a). Institutions, as rules, are generally understood there as co-emerging with actors, in economic transactions and in other types of social interaction (Milgrom and North, 1990). Institutions emerge out of older patterns of coordination and of identities and interaction rules. Meanwhile, in geography and anthropology, a contextualizing critique of planning could be found (Scott, 1998; Verdery, 2003; Soja, 1996; Harvey, 1973). Within these disciplines, planning was placed in a frame of evolving social, political, economic structures, of changing cultures, and of co-evolving groups, but these insights found little resonance in planning theory itself. Other theories in neighboring disciplines or in inter-disciplinary fields such as environmental studies did leave a mark on planning theory, which created new openings for concepts of co-evolution (Dietz et al., 2003). We refer to theories of adaptive governance coming out of general resilience and sustainability thinking and to complexity theory, revolving around concepts of non-linearity, feedback loops, catalysts and tipping points (see other chapters in this 224

Co-Evolutionary Planning Theory

book for more detailed discussion). The adaptive governance literature seizes on nature/culture as the basic distinction and is generally less aware of internal co-evolutions within society, while being more ambitious in terms of steering toward perfect adaptation. Complexity theory tends to be more sensitive to the internal complexity of society, its creation of interdependent elements, which can enter into altered relations because of unforeseen feedback loops, because of general opacity (as correlate of complexity). Complexity theory has therewith given rise to planning theories wary of bold practical ambition and cautious about steering and prediction (de Roo, 2012; Silva and de Roo, 2012; Batty and Marshall, 2012; Healey et al., 2015). For the understanding of the absence/presence, and the potential of certain versions of coevolutionary theory in planning, we needed to provide the reader with more context, the context of broader social theories, neighboring disciplines, and their ideas of co-evolution.

Co-Evolution in Evolutionary Governance Theory (EGT) A few years ago, we proposed to give co-evolution its due weight in planning and developed a theory of evolutionary governance (Van Assche et al., 2014b). Planning, we argued, needs contextualizing and a broadening of perspective to figure out its actual and possible place in society and its potential and limits in a particular context. The most important context for EGT is politics, more specifically governance. Governance here is understood as the overall processes of collectively binding decision-making. These processes include public and private actors and decisions can be made in many different ways. This a-moral, non-normative definition of governance is broader and more conceptual than in the popular notion as a recent shift away from government (Rhodes, 1996). Collectively binding decisions have always been taken in configurations of actors inside and outside the formal system of politics (Mansfield, 1998). Governance always existed, although this was not always acknowledged in modernist theories of state and steering. Conversely, the role and importance of state actors and state institutions in governance is regularly delimited too much or even completely overlooked in more recent publications on self-organization (Bell and Hindmoor, 2009). Not everything in governance is a collectively binding decision, but we cannot speak of governance without such decisions being taken. Not all actors in governance understand themselves as actors; ‘actor’ is a theoretical ascription of an individual or group/organization with a practical role in governance. Spatial planning, as the coordination of policies and practices regarding the organization of space, as spatial governance, is firmly embedded in governance as such. It concerns collective binding decisions about the use and development of space, in which numerous actors are involved (Van Assche and Verschraegen, 2008; Van Assche et al., 2014a). For EGT planning systems are configurations of actors and institutions involved in the organization of space. They include evolving discourses about what and how to plan. They emerge out of previous planning systems and out of evolving governance contexts. What planning is and can do will be unique for each community and for each governance context (Van Assche et al., 2011a). This immediately becomes clear if one compares the planning systems that evolved in different countries. Whereas some planning systems are very extensive and strongly embedded in state organizations, others are much more limited, mainly revolving around the upholding of property rights or avoiding harm. Each country or smaller community has its unique planning system, but each country also has its own governance context in which this planning system emerged. Some communities do not have a clear concept and an organizational unity for spatial governance, nor a single specialized role called ‘planner’, but this does not mean planning does not take place, cannot be analyzed as co-evolution. The fact that planning depends on the governance context in which 225

K. Van Assche, R. Beunen and M. Duineveld

it is embedded, implies that the issues planning can deal with and the means by which it can do so will largely diverge. It also implies that the possibilities to use planning for particular issues will differ between places and change over time. EGT is a theory that helps to analyze and explain the embedding of planning practices within a particular governance context and to explore and implement planning approaches that better fit that particular context. It is theoretical and practical at the same time. In line with complexity theory, EGT acknowledges that planning is ambiguous, opaque and non-linear, but EGT also provides a particular version and explanation of that complexity and the effects this produces (Beunen et al., 2013; Van Assche et al., 2012). Another distinctive and important feature of EGT is that it is first and foremost a theoretical framework and not a normative or prescriptive one. It is a theory, and although practice based on theory is possible and sometimes theories can improve practice, it does not aim to prescribe a particular form of planning. EGT is a lens through which one can observe and explain how practice works. Qualifications such as good or bad, efficient or non-efficient, democratic or nondemocratic planning, are all ascriptions within a planning system that could be the object of study for EGT, but not the immediate result of applying the theoretical framework. EGT deliberately distances itself from literatures that jump too quickly to prescriptions based on normative assumptions, since we believe that, in general, mixing description and prescription undermines the quality of analysis and, hence, also the quality of the proposed solutions that follow from such analysis. Planning, for EGT, is always part of several contexts that make it possible to do something we can call planning and for plans to have effects. Those contexts, which could be cultural, material, economic, or political, should not be ignored or forgotten. EGT avoids an understanding of planning as a technocratic, scientific, procedural, or sometimes an artistic island, since this is omitting the political nature of planning itself. Planning is always about power, about collectively binding decisions, about winners and losers, and about participation and representation as lines of power. For that reason planning is understood as embedded in governance, with governance referring to the multitude of systems, processes and practices of collective binding decision-making by governmental and other actors. To provide a more comprehensive understanding of EGT we now introduce its main themes and concepts of special importance for the analysis and explanation of planning practices and ambitions.

Governance Configurations: Formal and Informal Institutions For EGT, governance, as the key context for spatial planning, is best described in terms of coevolving structures that we will call configurations. Each configuration can, itself, be analyzed as a composite of co-evolving elements. First of all, there is the actor/institution configuration. This is not merely a sum of actors and institutions involved in spatial organization, but an interplay between actors, and between actors and the institutions they use to coordinate their interactions. A typology of actors would create an infinite list, yet two types of institutions can be distinguished: formal and informal institutions. The distinction between formal and informal cannot be made a priori. It is a labeling that takes place in each decision-making situation. In modern states, formality is regularly associated with the state, with rules written down on paper, and with state organizations, but this is not necessarily always the case. Informal institutions are alternative coordination mechanisms to formal institutions. They can sustain, modify, undermine, reinforce and complement formal institutions. Formal and informal institutions 226

Co-Evolutionary Planning Theory

co-evolve, in a dialectics where each shapes the effects of the other. Over time, the distinction between formal and informal, as well as their interrelation, can change. Informal can become formal and vice versa. Plans, policies and laws are institutions that are often used as tools in planning. These institutions co-evolve and they co-evolve with the actors using them. Actors create, maintain, change and discard institutions. Part of this institutional work is intended and planned, but a large part is an emergent outcome of the everyday actions and interactions of people within a community (Lawrence et al., 2009). Conversely, the behavior of actors is structured by the institutional framework in place. In most situations there are multiple options for coordination and decision-making and actors need to make decisions about which rules to follow (French, 1995). Parallel and underlying forms of coordination, present inside and outside the particular governance contexts, determine what happens to plans, planning laws and planning policies. The working of particular institutions, such as plans, policies or legislation, should therefore always be understood in relation to the wider configuration of institutions and in interaction with the strategizing of actors. Informality in planning is not just corruption, therefore, nor the recognition of weak planning power. Informality can both undermine and reinforce the formal plans or spatial policies. Informal negotiations between governmental and other actors before the formal process started can be the basis of implementation. A slight tracing of a most basic design on a napkin at a table by people who were not supposed to be at that table might have more influence than anything else in the planning process, might give it teeth and might make it possible that design plays a prominent role further on. Likewise, a sensitivity by planners and designers for local perceptions, values and traditions, for informal institutions coordinating land use, can lead to new formal institutions with a greater power of coordination and more real impact. This in turn can lead to a stronger perception that planning can work, and this can enhance performativity, the reality-creating character of planning.

Governance Configurations: Power/Knowledge Second, there is the power/knowledge configuration. Power and knowledge in planning systems co-evolve. Knowledge cannot be understood without reference to power. Within the domain of ‘knowledge’, one has to include narratives, discourses and ideologies. All these drive each other’s development and are influencing each other’s use and interpretation. Which form of expertise and other knowledge is used in a planning process, how it is interpreted, opposed, combined, or ignored, depends on a web of power relations. Furthermore the perspective in and on planning, the objects and subjects of planning, and the position of planning within the wider governance setting are all constituted in power relations. These power relations are themselves the result of previous power/knowledge interactions. Actor/institution and power/knowledge configurations co-evolve in many non-trivial senses. Actors and institutions are discursive constructs whose meaning and role is constructed in power/knowledge configurations. Conversely power/knowledge is influenced by the actions and interactions of actors, while institutions can embed and codify particular configurations of power/knowledge. A simple example can illustrate this co-evolution between the two configurations. Consider attempts to improve planning systems: it can be seen that this usually includes inserting new expert knowledge, new actors, and new plans, policies or laws. These attempts for improvement always take place in a context characterized by existing institutions and the presence of actors with their own perspectives, interests and knowledge. Understanding planning as part of governance configurations, including linked actor/institution and power/knowledge 227

K. Van Assche, R. Beunen and M. Duineveld

configurations, and discerning the role of informal institutions in the process, makes it easier to grasp the reasons for starting with certain assumptions, problem definitions, analytic tools, or coordination tools (institutions) and to understand the process of negotiation about the plans and other formal institutions and the intricate pathways of interpretation and implementation. Because of the coupling of several co-evolving configurations, causes and effects can originate and reverberate far from an original agency or intention: shifting relations between formal and informal institutions can undermine the implementation of a plan, leading to power shifts in administration, to inclusion of new actors, or to the production of a new plan with high hopes for implementation because of presumed superior quality, a presumption underpinned by a new narrative recently spread through the governance configuration.

Object and Subject Formation Objects and/or subjects, in an EGT perspective, do not exist as fixed entities in planning. Objects and subjects are not given in reality. They are actively constructed in discourses that are present inside and outside the evolving planning process. The main difference between the emergence of objects and objects is an ontological one: it is unlikely objects produce and reproduce discourse and define themselves, while subjects can. Subjects, contrary to objects, have the ability to internalize and embody different subjectivities (Foucault, 1994), this is named subjectification. Subjects thus can become actors within planning. For EGT the ways in which objects and subjects come into existence can be explained by a largely similar conceptual framework. It adds to Foucault (1972) in the depiction of this mechanics within governance, and its linkage with the functioning of the other configurations. Objects and subjects are constituted in power/knowledge configurations, at different sites of decision-making, as the result of different pathways that map their emergence and as a result of different techniques. Sites, like planning organizations, as the context for the formation of objects and subjects, can influence their formation in a unique way, since each site can have unique power/knowledge configurations. Some sites can have more authority than others to define objects and subjects, e.g. universities or governmental organizations (Foucault, 1972). Informal relations between governmental and other actors affect what happens to objects and subjects and they influence their construction and stabilization, their distribution or destruction (Kooij, 2015). Paths of object formation are the series of events, decisions and sites in which objects and subjects are formed. By techniques we refer to the power/knowledge relations that can be used to deepen the analysis of objects and subject formation in governance. Elsewhere the following techniques were distinguished: reification, solidification, codification, objectification, naturalization, and institutionalization (Duineveld and Van Assche, 2011; Duineveld et al., 2013). Planning is bound to be an arena under pressure, a network of sites and paths of decisionmaking, of tightly coupled configurations, where power/knowledge and actor/institution are continuously close, triggering mutual transformation. Actors perform roles as they function in a governance system. Sometimes these roles pre-exist that particular configuration, sometimes they are created in that configuration. Strong professional identities might exist in some cases, but not always, and strong role identities might exist, yet not necessarily. Even if these identities exist, they need not be deeply subjectified, leading to a transformation of politics into identity politics. The existence of roles, of professional and participatory subjects, of degrees of subjectification, renders the fabric of spatial governance more intricate. People never coincide with a role and a role is never the same as an identity. This complicates the patterns in which knowledge and power entwine, which conceptual objects are allowed to emerge in planning, and what impact they can have in evolving spatial governance. 228

Co-Evolutionary Planning Theory

In some cases planners and designers can be considered the most important subjects in a governance context. Although some persons have both labels they can internalize one of the roles and define themselves as planners or designers, sometimes even expressing very distinct features: designers wearing sleek designer glasses, planners looking like bureaucrats. In governance many other subjects come into existence, like ‘good’ and ‘bad’ citizens, politicians, sorts of experts, developers, lay people and so on. Governance creates subjects and is transformed by these subjects, and the same is true for objects. Objects and subjects are formed, sometimes temporally, sometimes very locally, and sometimes more enduring and more difficult to undo.

Path, Inter and Goal Dependencies Dependencies refer to different aspects of rigidity in governance paths. Each governance path involves rigidity and flexibility which, in combination, leave an openness for path creation. EGT distinguishes between three sets of dependencies: path dependencies, interdependencies and goal dependencies. Path dependencies refer to the influence of the past on the current reproduction of governance. This influence can stem from old narratives, forms of knowledge, power relations, institutional frameworks, actor configurations, or the absence or presence of particular planning tools. Interdependence is the restricting and guiding effect of current relations between actors and between actors and institutions on decision-making. The third set are goal dependencies. These are especially interesting for planning as they concern the effects of ideas about the future and visions for the future on the current functioning of governance. Planners are always looking toward the future, intending to codify preferable versions of the future in new institutions. Therewith they create goal dependencies. Once a certain vision of the future is institutionalized, it will become a point of reference for new decisions. It can create a blind spot for alternative futures, but it can also inspire the development of alternative visions if certain actors do not agree with the institutionalized version. One only has to think about local groups protesting against planned developments to see how certain future-oriented ideas can have a very strong influence on the evolution of governance. Planners ought to look keenly at the diversity of goal dependencies introduced by previous plans and other planning tools. Here we touch on the topics of conformity and implementation. Plans with the most abhorrent implementation can still have many effects, including positive ones. Abominable implementation of a former plan can be hailed now as the saving of a community – think for example about many of the modernist monster-projects or the work of Jane Jacobs. Annoying opponents of a plan can later become heroes, after shifts in planning narratives and underlying ideologies. Descendants of these opponents can now be prominent actors in planning. Goal dependencies, like the other dependencies, come in different weights and colors. They can take the form of ideas, visions, or scenarios, both as positive images of a future or as a specter. They can be more or less realistic, more or less concrete, and about a near or faraway future. The ways in which these goal dependencies influence decision-making in the present can be manifold. Planning could thus also be conceptualized as the management of goal dependencies, based on an understanding of the influence of the two other sets of dependencies. Planners try to use appropriate coordination tools to give shape to an appropriate narrative about the future, with appropriate measures of ambition and certainty. All these instances of appropriateness can and will shift over time. Planning thus has to be a highly reflexive and evolving activity itself, sensitive to the balance between flexibility and rigidity in the system. Rigidity is neither good nor bad per se. One old and acknowledged benefit of planning is exactly that it increases rigidity in spatial governance, by stabilizing expectations of actors, clarifying ground rules of interaction 229

K. Van Assche, R. Beunen and M. Duineveld

(property rights, zoning, infrastructure development, property tax), basic orientations toward the future (in zoning etc.), and rules to change the rules (planning processes and democratic political processes). The same is true for flexibility, which is also neither good nor bad. Good governance is adaptive governance, but limits to adaptive capacity are not always bad things. Rash decisions inspired by a new narrative taking over governance, one new actor rising to power, or a broken web of interdependence, can be sorely regretted later. The effects of a vision for the future, say a plan, will hinge on a variety of things. Some have been mentioned before. In the sphere of power/knowledge they will hinge on the discursive configurations in the governance system and outside it, in turn coupled with the informalities existing in and outside the governance system and the power relations between actors inside governance and between others outside the sphere of governance. Discursive configurations refer to the patterns of embedding and competing discursivity in and outside governance: concepts compete, are linked to other concepts in discourses and in narratives; narratives make sense in ideologies; ideologies produce metaphors appearing in narratives giving new meanings to space and new substance to ideas for the future. Certain actors are clearly linked to certain concepts, narratives, ideologies, metaphors, or forms of expertise. If powerful actors identify with one form of expertise, then politics becomes identity politics. Planning will then become more rigid and the version of the future that stems from the application of that expertise will dominate in planning. If a powerful actor identifies directly with one version of the past, which inspires a version of the future, a similarly rigid identity politics will guide planning directly in the direction of such a desirable future, without interference of other expertise and other narratives, unless they can function as support or give content or detail. In general, plans produced in the governance system which are compatible with expectations or informal coordination mechanisms in the wider community, will more likely have strong reality effects. These will tend to produce a new reality resembling the planned one, or, shift the interpretation of later reality so it resembles the intention of the plan. We again speak of performativity here, referring to the reality effects of plans. Plans do create realities, and the performative effects are those effects that alter the later perception of reality. Plans can have more effects because more people become convinced of the underlying reasoning, charmed by the esthetics of the design, or by a changing discursive configuration in the community at large. What can enhance or modify performativity is the performance of the plan and the performance, we add, of actors in the making of the plan. Performance in the process contributes to the quality of support or consensus. Performance in execution can have the same effect, by showing or creating qualities not perceived before in the plan, or by endowing the performer with more prestige, trust or power. Performance, performativity and goal dependencies are useful concepts to refine the analysis of plan effects and plan implementation. The concept of goal dependence links future, past and present in a novel way, by placing the dependencies in a triad with two other forms of dependencies. Together these different dependencies help in analyzing the influences of past, present and future on what happens now. The basic insight that both past and future influence the present in concrete manners, and that, concomitantly, the effects of present decisions extend far beyond people doing what they are told, we consider a useful addition to the planning literature and a key insight coming out of the specification of EGT into planning theory.

Final Thoughts The emergence of planning theories that focus on governance, complexity, non-linearity and ambiguity might for some create the impression that planning is becoming an anachronism or 230

Co-Evolutionary Planning Theory

that planning is dissolving in a sea of practical and theoretical objections, and in larger contexts planning cannot grasp itself. In response increasing attention is given to non-hierarchical, organic, insurgent, or self-organizing forms of planning; forms of planning that are presumably emerging by themselves. We argue that a focus on self-organization, presented as natural and moral, cannot avoid the problems observed with other theories. The tendency to translate ideas of failing theories and practices quickly into a new normative framework is still there. The new normativity also fails to explain how planning actually works. Just as free markets and social engineering approaches miscast planning power, and just as the theoretical analyses of complications and ambiguities tend to overlook its positive powers, we believe resorting to self-organization and localism is not a solution. All these theories deserve full recognition of course, and appreciation in their critical and constructive moment. What we propose here, is that reframing their diagnosis and solutions, presenting them as real options which are not the only ones, however, but more or less real and useful, contingent on governance paths, is what can help us to map the middle ground between social engineering and laissez-faire. Sometimes local self-organization is what is missing. In some situations aspects of social engineering are desired and possible, while in others lack of incentives for private actors, in line with classical economics, are the problem, and sometimes planning politics is rigid identity politics (Van Assche et al., 2011b, 2014b). Diagnosis and remedy have to follow out of path mapping, out of governance analysis, and this is primarily a mapping of co-evolving configurations. EGT is a theoretical frame that can assist in this process but, as we indicated in the introductory paragraphs, it is not the only manifestation of co-evolutionary and contingencyoriented theory in planning, and not the first one. Most versions of post-structuralism and institutionalism espouse concepts of co-evolution and contingency and already include the core idea that both reality and the tools to intervene in it are the product of co-evolution and thus supported and constrained by this. As argued before, the possibilities for planning and their potential impacts on the socialspatial organization depend on context. Most important among those, we argued here, is the governance context, which includes discourses, narratives, dependencies, and the different power/knowledge and actor/institution configurations. Understanding this context is key to an understanding of the limits and possibilities of change in a community and thus to planning or the impossibility of planning. Planning theory embedded in governance theory can help to analyze and understand a particular governance context, to delineate the possibilities and limits of planning in that context, and to determine which planning efforts are most likely to have a positive impact. In a coevolutionary perspective, context as such, and governance context in particular, are never fixed and never stable: all elements and structures are continuously influencing each other. A coevolutionary perspective that acknowledges this radical contingency is a very useful lens for both analysis and change, for the development of new planning perspectives, or the deliberate circumvention of a current planning system. The co-evolutionary perspective as developed in EGT opens up planning theory to a series of relevant concepts from different disciplines, relevant for the analysis of current and potential forms of planning in a community, while conversely giving theories and practices of planning a firm place within governance. Planning theory, after some of the more novel recent reconceptualizations has become less naive and more relevant than ever before to tackle the contemporary societal challenges of today such as climate change adaptation, urbanization, food security, water management, cultural and identity politics, or biodiversity conservation. All these societal challenges have a clear and important spatial dimension and all could benefit from perspectives that seek to unravel their complex dynamics and the points of leverage for planned change. 231

K. Van Assche, R. Beunen and M. Duineveld

References Batty, M. & Marshall, S. 2012. The origins of complexity theory in cities and planning. In J. Portugali, H. Meyer, E. Stolk & E. Tan (eds) Complexity Theories of Cities Have Come of Age: An Overview with Implications to Urban Planning and Design. Berlin: Springer, 21–46. Bell, S. & Hindmoor, A. 2009. Rethinking Governance: The Centrality of the State in Modern Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Beunen, R., Van Assche, K. & Duineveld, M. 2013. Performing failure in conservation policy: The implementation of European Union directives in the Netherlands. Land Use Policy, 31, 280–288. Dam, R. V., Duineveld, M. & During, R. 2014. Delineating active citizenship: The subjectification of citizens’ initiatives. Journal of Environmental Policy and Planning, 17(2), 163–179. de Roo, G. 2012. Spatial planning, complexity and a world ‘out of equilibrium’: Outline of a non-linear approach to planning. In G. de Roo, J. Hillier & J. Van Wezemael (eds) Complexity and Spatial Planning: Systems, Assemblages and Simulations. Farnham: Ashgate, 129–165. Deleuze, G. & Guattari, F. 1987. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. London: Continuum. Dietz, T., Ostrom, E. & Stern, P. C. 2003. The struggle to govern the commons. Science, 302(5652), 1907–1912. Duineveld, M. & Van Assche, K. 2011. The power of tulips: constructing nature and heritage in a contested landscape. Journal of Environmental Policy and Planning, 13, 1–20. Duineveld, M., Van Assche, K. & Beunen, R. 2013. Making things irreversible: Object stabilization in urban planning and design. Geoforum, 46, 16–24. Easterly, W. 2006. Planners versus searchers in foreign aid. Asian Development Review, 23, 1. Fischer, F. & Forester, J. (eds) 1993. The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Flyvbjerg, B. 1998. Rationality and Power. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Forester, J. 1984. Bounded rationality and the politics of muddling through. Public Administration Review, 23–31. Foucault, M. 1972. The Archaeology of Knowledge & The Discourse on Language. New York: Pantheon Books. Foucault, M. 1979. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. Foucault, M. 1994. The subject and power. In J. D. Faubion (ed.) Power: Essential Works of Foucault 1954–1984. Volume 3. New York: The New Press, 326–348. French, R. 1995. Plans, Pragmatism and People: The Legacy of Soviet Planning for Today’s Cities. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. Gunder, M. & Hillier, J. 2009. Planning in Ten Words or Less: A Lacanian Entanglement with Spatial Planning. Surrey: Ashgate. Harvey, D. 1973. Social Justice and the City. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Healy, P. 1997. Collaborative Planning: Shaping Places in Fragmented Societies. Hampshire: MacMillan. Healey, P. 2004. The treatment of space and place in the new strategic spatial planning in Europe. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 28, 45–67. Healey, P. 2006. Urban Complexity and Spatial Strategies: Towards a Relational Planning For Our Times. London: Routledge. Healey, P. 2015. Civic capacity, place governance and progressive localism. In S. Davoudi & A. Madanipour (eds) Reconsidering Localism. New York: Routledge, 105–125. Hillier, J. 2002. Shadows of Power: An Allegory of Prudence in Land-Use Planning. New York: Routledge. Hillier, J. 2008. Plan(e) speaking: A multiplanar theory of spatial planning. Planning Theory, 7(1), 24–50. Kemp, R., Loorbach, D. & Rotmans, J. 2007. Transition management as a model for managing processes of co-evolution towards sustainable development. International Journal of Sustainable Development & World Ecology, 14, 78–91. Kooij, H. J. 2015. Object formation and subject formation: The innovation campus in the Netherlands. Planning Theory, 14(4), 339–359. Lacan, J. 2006. Ecrits: The First Complete Edition in English. New York: W.W. Norton & Co. Lawrence, T. B., Suddaby, R. & Leca, B. 2009. Institutional Work: Actors and Agency in Institutional Studies of Organizations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lieberman, P. 2007. The evolution of human speech. Current Anthropology, 48, 39–66. Lindblom, C. E. 1959. The science of ‘muddling through’. Public Administration Review, 79–88. Luhmann, N. 1992. What is communication? Communication Theory, 2, 251–259. Luhmann, N. 1995. Social Systems. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

232

Co-Evolutionary Planning Theory Luhmann, N. 2012. Theory of Society. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Mackenzie, D., Muniesa, F. & Siu, L. (eds) 2007. Do Economists Make Markets? On the Performativity of Economics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Malinowski, B. 1944. A Scientific Theory of Culture, and Other Essays. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press. Mansfield, H. 1998. Machiavelli’s Virtue. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Maturana, H. R. & Varela, F. J. 1987. The Tree of Knowledge: The Biological Roots of Human Understanding. Boston, MA: Shambhala Publications. Moeller, H.-G. 2006. Luhmann Explained: From Souls to Systems. Chicago, IL: Open Court. North, D. 1990a. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ostrom, E. 2005. Understanding Institutional Diversity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Parsons, T. 1966. Societies: Evolutionary and Comparative Perspectives. California: Prentice-Hall Incorporated. Rhodes, R. A. W. 1996. The new governance: Governing without government. Political Studies, 44, 652–667. Scott, J. C. 1998. Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Silva, E. A. & de Roo, G. 2012. A Planner’s Encounter with Complexity. Farnham: Ashgate Publishing Ltd. Soja, E. W. 1996. Thirdspace: Journeys to Los Angeles and Other Real-and-Imagined Places. Oxford: Blackwell. Van Assche, K. & Verschraegen, G. 2008. The limits of planning: Niklas Luhmann’s systems theory and the analysis of planning and planning ambitions. Planning Theory, 7, 263–283. Van Assche, K., Beunen, R., Jacobs, J. & Teampau, P. 2011a. Crossing trails in the marshes: Rigidity and flexibility in the governance of the Danube Delta. Journal of Environmental Planning and Management, 54, 997–1018. Van Assche, K., Duineveld, M., Verschraegen, G., During, R. & Beunen, R. 2011b. Social systems and social engineering: Niklas Luhmann. In S. Vellema (ed.) Transformation and Sustainability in Agriculture: Connecting Practice with Social Theory. Wageningen: Wageningen Academic Publishers, 35–48. Van Assche, K., Beunen, R. & Duineveld, M. 2012. Performing failure and success: Dutch planning experiences. Public Administration, 90, 567–581. Van Assche, K., Duineveld, M. & Beunen, R. 2014a. Power and contingency in planning. Environment and Planning A, 46, 2385–2400. Van Assche, K., Beunen, R. & Duineveld, M. 2014b. Evolutionary Governance Theory: An Introduction. Heidelberg: Springer. Verdery, K. 2003. The Vanishing Hectare: Property and Value in Postsocialist Transylvania. Ithaca, NY and London: Cornell University Press. Volberda, H. W. & Lewin, A. Y. 2003. Co-evolutionary dynamics within and between firms: From evolution to co-evolution. Journal of Management Studies, 40, 2111–2136. Von Tunzelmann, N. 2003. Historical coevolution of governance and technology in the industrial revolutions. Structural Change and Economic Dynamics, 14, 365–384. Voß, J. P. & Freeman, R. 2016. Knowing Governance. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Weber, M. 2009. From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. Abingdon: Routledge.

233

PART III

Networks, Flows, Relationships and Institutions

19 THE GOVERNANCE OF PLANNING Flexibly Networked, Yet Institutionally Grounded Raine Mäntysalo and Pia Bäcklund

Introduction: Governance as an Analytical Concept in Planning Theories Since the rise of neoliberal political ideology in the late 1970s, the redistributive welfarism of public planning has been under attack as bureaucratic, inefficient and reactive. The oil crisis in the mid-1970s marked the end of the post-war growth era, during which planning institutions had been established to regulate this growth, in view of the public interest and avoidance of negative externalities. Since economic growth was no longer self-evident, but still the main target, public planning was expected to shift from ‘passive’ regulation to active facilitation of the economy and the functionality of the globalizing markets. In urban planning, local governments were expected to engage in private land development initiatives as a potential public partner and/or provider of different sorts of incentives (see a comprehensive account by Sager (2011)). This development has continued ever since. Hence, urban planning has been changing from sectored and regulative land-use planning into an integrative and proactive agent in spatial planning (Davoudi et al., 2009). This change of planning is part of a broader transition that in the fields of administrative and management studies has been termed as a change from government to governance (e.g. Pollitt & Bouckaert, 2011). In this chapter, we review the theoretical argumentation explaining this change and the reasons behind it, and make related connections to the planning realm. The review discusses how the concept of governance is far less clear-cut than often assumed, when different institutional contexts, their path dependencies and legitimacy challenges are considered. The change from government to governance rather means that public sector activities become layered and mixed in fuzzy ways. As part of this development, planning practices have become blurred, too. We see that planning theories have had difficulties in gaining a proper analytical insight into this fuzziness. It is also important to note that local planning cultures and contexts present unique responses to the globally spreading innovations concerning the operating principles of the public sector, as they bring their own legislative steering and national and regional policy guidance into the mix (e.g. Davoudi et al., 2009; Skelcher et al., 2011; Stead, 2012; Bäcklund et al., forthcoming). 237

Raine Mäntysalo and Pia Bäcklund

Although governance can be seen as a central factor in planning practice, empirical accounts of how and in which issues it impacts in different planning systems are much needed, especially if ‘best practices’ are to be transferred between local contexts. First, we take a broad look at how the change from government to governance has taken and is taking place, utilizing especially discussions within administrative studies. We will then continue with focused contemplation of the uses of governance as an analytical concept, and conclude with what we see would be its fruitful uses in the planning theoretical discourse. We also provide clues for seeing the conceptual discussion through local contexts.

From Government to Governance Rosenau (1992) was among the first to make the distinction between government and governance, by referring with ‘government’ to activities that are backed by formal authority, and with ‘governance’ to a more encompassing phenomenon that embraces not only governmental organizations but also non-governmental actors and informal mechanisms in a pursuit for shared goals. The idea of governance was introduced in the Anglo-American research circles as a paradigm shift for public administrations. In their influential book Reinventing Government (1992), Osborne and Gaebler deemed ‘government’ as a dysfunctional remnant of past times: The kind of governments that developed during the industrial era, with their sluggish centralized bureaucracies, their preoccupation with rules and regulations, and their hierarchical structures, no longer work well … They became bloated, wasteful, and ineffective. And when the world began to change, they failed to change with it. Hierarchical, centralized bureaucracies designed in the 1930s or 1940s simply do not function well in the rapidly changing, information-rich, knowledge-intensive society and economy of the 1990s. (Osborne & Gaebler 1992, 11–12) Drawing largely from business management literature, Osborne and Gaebler introduced a number of operating principles for public governance, including the ideas of the government: •• •• •• ••

encouraging community empowerment and private competition; adopting the role as a supervisor and purchaser of public service provision, instead of a producer; being mission, customer and output oriented instead of focusing on rules, bureaucracy and input; concentrating more on income generation than its redistribution, e.g. by influencing market forces rather than creating public programs. (Osborne & Gaebler, 1992)

In broad terms, this concept of governance echoes the principles of the so-called New Public Management (NPM) that took shape in the 1980s as a model for public governance in Thatcher’s UK. NPM promotes a shift from bureaucratic administration to business-like professional management, with the assumption that market rationality would provide the cure for the perceived lack of efficiency of the bureaucracies. Hence, the public sector’s cooperation with market actors was enhanced by outsourcing public functions, introducing purchaser-provider models for public service provision, and even by introducing market-like structures within the government itself. From business management, strategic leadership ideas were adopted, including strategic goal setting, performance control and management by results. 238

The Governance of Planning

Although Osborne and Gaebler, with their principles of reinvented government presented above, promoted market-oriented or ‘entrepreneurial’ government, they saw that markets are only half the answer. They pointed out that markets are impersonal, unforgiving, and, even under the most structured circumstances, inequitable. “To complement the efficiency and effectiveness of market mechanisms, we need the warmth and caring of families and neighborhoods and communities. As entrepreneurial governments move away from the administrative bureaucracies, they need to embrace both markets and community” (Osborne & Gaebler 1992, 309, emphasis in the original). Similarly to Osborne and Gaebler, many later governance researchers have perceived the governance paradigm to represent a ‘Third Way’ that, on the one hand, enables us to overcome the rigidities of bureaucracies, and, on the other hand, the inequities of markets, through the incorporation of a wide range of groups into policy making (Leadbeater, 2004; Horelli, 2013). For more critical researchers, it represents neoliberal governance that has led to the domination of institutional and economic elites through their cooperation arrangements that bear serious democratic deficits (Swyngedouw, 2005; Allmendinger & Haughton, 2013, 2015; Inch, 2010; Grange, 2013). Both arguments may be true, depending on the empirical case at hand. For example, Blanco (2013) has identified signs of both in his recent case studies in Barcelona, regarding whether the forms of urban governance adopted foster strong political-economic interests or bottom-up community development. While many would portray the ‘Barcelona model’ as a showcase of urban governance, with its positive impacts on urban development and local democracy, others, according to Blanco (2013), criticize it for the lack of opportunities for citizens to participate in main urban development projects, the dominance of architects and urban planners over other professionals, the resulting gentrification of the historic centre and the sea front, and the high social costs of the model. As it turned out in Blanco’s empirical studies, both arguments are valid, depending on whether the area studied is centrally or more peripherally located, from the perspective of economic buoyancy. Comparing the cases of Raval (in the historic centre of the city) and Trinitat Nova (at the urban periphery), Blanco argues that a variety of urban governance practices can be adopted, even within a single city: I have discovered that governance networks are not necessarily linked to the neoliberal project – nor do they necessarily represent an alternative to it – as some theorists seem to assume. I have found different types of governance networks grounded on alternative political values and principles. (Blanco, 2013, 288)

The Path Dependence of Governance Practices The empirical perspective brings us to the question of analytical sharpness of the governance concept, as a tool in describing and understanding urban policy and planning processes. The concept of governance has been used in varying ways and approached from various disciplines, but there seems to be broad agreement that governance refers to the development in governing where boundaries between public and private sectors and between different public organizations have become blurred (Stoker, 1998). It is a process of blending and coordinating public and private interests where the local government, in concert with private interests, seeks to attain collective goals (Pierre, 1999, 374; Hajer, 2009). As actors organize around a particular problem, and the political drive to act and find novel cooperative forms is issue based, governance models are also expected to be more efficient and innovative in the pursuit of complex, multilevel public goals than government endeavours (Aarsæther et al., 2011; Klijn & Koppenjan, 2012). 239

Raine Mäntysalo and Pia Bäcklund

But if governance were to be used to refer to any kind of public–private interaction, soon everything would become governance, and the concept would lose its analytical edge (Pierre, 1999, 376). Pierre suggests that urban governance processes should be studied in connection to the different institutional contexts in which they are embedded. These contexts provide the economic, political and ideological frameworks that determine the participation and influence of different actors, the policy instruments used, the goals to be pursued and the resulting outcomes. Here, ‘institution’ refers to “overarching systems of values, traditions, norms, and practices that shape or constrain political behavior” (Pierre, 1999, 373). From this perspective, Pierre arrives at four different models of urban governance: the managerial, the corporatist, the progrowth, and the welfare model. Managerial and progrowth governance models are market-conforming forms of urban governance, whereas corporatist and welfare governance models seek to control and contain market forces, although in different ways. Managerial and progrowth governance models are also outcome-focused, drawing on entrepreneurial zeal and skills that tend to bypass the due process. In turn, corporatist and welfare governance models emphasize entitlements and representation and are hence process driven. In broad terms, managerial and progrowth governance models are more typical of the Anglo-American context, while the corporatist and welfare governance models are more familiar in continental Europe. However, a clear-cut association of governance models with different country contexts cannot be made, as the different governance models may coexist in different countries, with different emphases (Pierre, 1999). What is more, they may coexist even in individual local governments, according to Pierre – despite their different organizational logics and goals. Different government sectors may favour different governance models: For instance, one should not expect social workers to support progrowth governance, nor is it very likely that the local economic development office is a key player in welfare governance. To assume otherwise would be to exaggerate the logic and coherence of the local state. (Pierre, 1999, 398) While governance researchers have focused on the issue of managing the relations between the public and the private sector, they have often overlooked the changes in steering modes within the public sector itself. For example, as Pollitt and Bouckaert (2011) have noted, administrative reforms have been systematic and comprehensive in the OECD countries since the 1990s. However, these reforms have rarely if ever fully replaced the former structures but are, rather, interlaced with them (Hajer, 2009; Bäcklund & Mäntysalo, 2010). Hence, public administration does not form a homogenous collective with a unified mind to be discovered (e.g. Olsson & Hysing, 2012; Bäcklund et al., 2014). This evolving development within the public sector might also have notable indirect effects. For example, it has been argued that administrative reforms might have a much larger impact on the future of democracy than specific projects aiming at improving participation and democratic practices (e.g. Hirst, 2000; Mäntysalo & Saglie, 2010; Skelcher & Torfing, 2010). However, there are further complications, as the paradigm shift from government to governance is usually, in practice, incomplete. For Rhodes, governance signifies “a change in the meaning of government, referring to a new process of governing; or a changed condition of ordered rule; or the new method by which society is governed” (Rhodes, 1996, 652–653, emphasis in the original). What really changes and what is new in local practices, is an empirical question. For example, economic preconditions affect the possibilities of organizations to 240

The Governance of Planning

develop their operations in relation to both the institutional structures of the government and the supra-local networks of governance. While Rhodes, among others, promotes the view of governance as autopoietic, self-organizing networks of public and private actors, relatively free to establish themselves around shared goals (Rhodes, 1996, 660), the institutional approach promoted by Pierre (1999) emphasizes the frictions in transforming governance. We see that it is important not to overlook the institutional rootedness of ‘government’ in the legislative system and political-administrative culture. As first shown by North (1990), institutions are characterized by path dependence. When institutions are established, they often require high fixed set-up costs and, once established, they are powerful in reinforcing development that guarantees their own existence. Mahoney (2000) adds that, besides North’s utilitarianist view, there are other viewpoints that are relevant in explaining the path-dependent self-reinforcement of institutions. These viewpoints include the functional role the institution gains in the larger systemic framework; the institution’s distribution of power among actors, as the dominant groups support the institutional settings maintaining and fostering their power; and the institution’s legitimation, when it is increasingly perceived as the only legitimate authority in its domain (Mahoney, 2000, 519–526; see also Pierson, 2000). When ‘government’ as a political-administrative institution indicates strong path-dependent resistance to change, the governance reform might only lead to shallow changes and can thus become a source of various sorts of ambiguities in politico-administrative processes. A complex reality of governing might result where different understandings of the determinants of legitimate conduct, due policy process, and the professional identities and roles of different actors in producing and managing valid knowledge coexist and compete with one another. Embedded in the institutionalized structures and normative prescriptions of ‘good governance’, the deepseated regulative model of planning and the associated model of representative democracy are still holding fast, framing what is possible or even conceivable. Government actors are still central agents in public governance networks and they have their own ‘institutional baggage’ with them when operating in governance networks. The given roles, legal duties and formal authority relations, between the political decision-makers, public administrators and non-government actors, are carved deep into these institutional structures, and these inscriptions can be very difficult to overwrite with the new governance ideas.

The Legitimacy of Governance Networks? Indeed, the many dilemmas that Stoker (1998) identified in the governance paradigm, can be associated with the institutional friction of transforming government to governance. According to Stoker: ••

There is a divorce between the complex reality of decision-making associated with governance and the normative codes used to explain and justify government.

••

The blurring of responsibilities can lead to blame avoidance or scapegoating.

••

Power dependence exacerbates the problem of unintended consequences for government.

••

The emergence of self-governing networks raises difficulties over accountability.

••

Even where governments operate in a flexible way to steer collective action governance failure may occur. (Stoker, 1998, 19) 241

Raine Mäntysalo and Pia Bäcklund

A central problem, according to Stoker (1998, 20), is that a legitimation framework, in which to place the new practice of governance, is missing. Similarly, many scholars see that the juxtaposing of government and governance models implicitly enables practices that have ambiguous relations to democracy and publicity ideals. For example, Allmendinger and Haughton (2010, 813) have argued, concerning the planning context, that the new practices are “short circuiting some of the formal democratic processes of statutory planning”. However, the rootedness of actions in issue-related performative and technical aspects of problem-solving means that legitimacy is claimed by reference to established institutions. Responsibilities become blurred and diluted into the ambiguity of networks. As a concept, legitimacy, too, has traditionally been perceived as institutionally bounded. It concerns the level of political-administrative system itself. Legitimacy is the moral justification of an entity in wielding political power (Buchanan, 2002, 689–690). As noted by Sager (2013, 8), it is mainly addressed to sources of political authority: the governments, institutions and regimes making political decisions. The change from government to governance is, of course, problematic, if legitimacy and political accountability continue to be addressed to government. Rhodes acknowledges that there is “an obvious conflict between the tenets of accountability in a representative democracy and participation in networks which can be open without being formally accountable” (Rhodes, 1996, 667). But he argues that political accountability can no longer be specific merely to the institutional hierarchies of government, “but must fit the substantive policy and the several institutions contributing to it” (Rhodes, 1996, 667, our emphasis). Indeed, the scope of legitimacy has been shifting from procedural considerations (who is the legitimate authority and what is the due process for preparing and making decisions) to substantive issues (what policy goals are justifiable and who are needed as resourceful actors in pursuing them). Following Scharpf’s terminology, this transition can be termed as the shift away from input legitimacy to output legitimacy (Scharpf, 1999; see also Mäntysalo & Saglie, 2010). While input legitimacy focuses on the general acceptability of political processes, output legitimacy focuses on the acceptability of the outcomes of political decisions and policies. Whereas the former is concerned with the democratic quality of decision-making processes, the latter is concerned with the efficient achievement of common good in implementing the decisions made. Bang and Esmark (2009) go as far as to argue that the new conditions of globalized and networked society require a reorientation from politics-centred (input) to policy-centred (output) public governance. They emphasize the forward mapping of policy risks and challenges, rather than backward mapping of how conflicting interests and identities acquire free and equal access to, and recognition in, democratic politics (Bang & Esmark 2009, 16–17). Despite the persuasive argumentation of Bang and Esmark, among others, such aspirations have recently been heavily criticized. It is argued to transform from declared pursuits of inclusive procedures toward a variety of ‘depoliticizing’ practices, with managerial shadow-practices effectively reducing the realm of participation and ‘the political’ (see e.g. Metzger et al., 2015). The argument, again, is that neoliberal motives (e.g. growth, competitiveness) are pushed forward by presenting them as societal necessities, instead of goals to be subjected to political deliberation. Be that as it may, the question of legitimacy remains an unresolved issue in the transition toward governance. In the next sections we examine what implications this ambiguity of change from government to governance has for planning theory and practice.

Neoliberal Governance in Planning Theory In the field of urban planning, two approaches to understand the shift toward governance can be identified. The first approach celebrates the governance model for expanding planning 242

The Governance of Planning

from regulative and expert-dominated land-use planning to proactive and networked community development and co-governance (e.g. Horelli, 2013). The latter approach rather perceives community engagement as a mere guise for ensuring the dominance of neoliberal interests. For example in the UK, some researchers (e.g. Davoudi & Madanipour, 2013; Allmendinger & Haughton, 2015; Grange, 2013) argue that with its Neighbourhood Planning initiative Cameron’s coalition government is framed crucially community involvement by encouraging it to find ‘local solutions’ to planning problems that, however, are determined centrally around neoliberal growth. Bottom-up local participation was welcomed regarding how new development should take place, not on whether there should be new development or not in the first place. Whether the governance paradigm promotes community engagement or domination of neoliberal interests in planning, is, of course, not just a theoretical issue, but crucially an empirical one, too. For example, Sager (2009) argues that the Nordic planners are torn between the deliberative ideals of communicative planning and the realpolitik of neoliberal planning (see also Grange, 2014, 2016). Mäntysalo, Saglie and Cars (2011) further argue that, in order to cope with this tension, the Nordic planners have to develop defensive routines, unreflectively misrepresenting exclusive public–private partnership and developer-oriented planning in terms of communicative procedures, as prescribed by the Nordic planning laws. Inch (2010) has found similar tensions in England. The neoliberalization discourse has ambiguous relations to planning theory. What the governance paradigm and communicative planning theory share in common, is their aversion to planning as bureaucratic control. While the former perceives it as inefficient, the latter perceives it as undemocratic. But if the governance paradigm, with its involvement of private and third sector ‘stakeholders’ (cf. Swyngedouw, 2005) in the planning and decision-making processes, ultimately leads to the domination of the strong political and economic stakeholders, would the communicative planning theory’s criticism of ‘government’ then be counterproductive? Does the intention of communicative planning theory to enable bottom-up civil society participation, and relax bureaucratic control of planning processes, inadvertently serve neoliberal aims (Bengs, 2005; Allmendinger & Haughton, 2013; Purcell, 2009; Sager, 2013; Fainstein & Fainstein, 2013; Gunder, 2010; Puustinen et al., 2017)? A shift from one form of domination to the other? This questioning largely stems from the (neo-)Marxist critique of seeing structural power imbalances as inherent in the planning system itself. If planning is seen to be structurally inclined to facilitate growth and the accumulation of capital, this condition might be maintained and further legitimized by communicative planning ideals – if they were to minimize predefined restrictions and guidelines, relax checks and controls, and increase flexibility of legally binding land-use plans. Thereby they would open further possibilities for the powerful stakeholders to strike bargains on privately initiated development projects. The pressure of neoliberal domination tends to be much stronger when areas with a high property development potential are concerned, in comparison to more peripheral areas, not to mention socio-economically deprived areas. Brindley, Rydin and Stoker (1989) noticed this in their review of the different ‘planning styles’ that were adopted in the UK in the 1980s, in the aftermath of Thatcher’s reforms. Besides the regulative and communicative planning styles, they noticed the emergence of three market-oriented planning styles: trend planning, leverage planning and private management planning. The adopted planning styles varied in relation to the economic buoyancy of the area in question. In the most buoyant areas, usually the central districts of growing cities, the style of trend planning was adopted. In such areas, the planners narrowed their scope of planning to concern urban architecture and landscape, thereby leaving room for the investors and developers to (re-)determine the core areas of investment, with their impacts on the broader urban infrastructure. In the marginal areas, such as abandoned industry 243

Raine Mäntysalo and Pia Bäcklund

and harbour areas that were located close to the urban centres, the public sector used the leverage planning style to facilitate private investment in different ways, e.g. by establishing public–private Urban Development Corporations, and Enterprise Zones with significantly reduced planning regulations. The planning style of private management planning, in turn, was practised in the socioeconomically depressed neighbourhoods or areas. Here, management-type entrepreneurial means were used in the attainment of social purposes in such areas, in collaboration with the local residents. Much of its funding and administrative back-up rested on the shoulders of the government. But as involvement in such projects was often not profitable for the investors, they sooner or later tended to leave them (Brindley et al., 1989). Local planning cultures and structures play a paramount role: the more government processes define and steer planning practices, the less can governance networks redefine and guide the planning agendas in a legally legitimate way. On the one hand, planning is expected to grasp and dynamically engage in development initiatives and potentialities for strategic mobilization; on the other hand, the statutory practices confine the scope of planning substantially and procedurally. In the next section, we look at these questions more closely.

Governance in Practice: Soft and Hard Planning As Healey (2004, 2007) observes, the shift from government to governance has been paralleled by a shift from statutory planning toward governance-based strategic spatial planning (cf. Albrechts et al., 2003; Allmendinger & Haughton, 2010; Balducci, 2011). The emergent strategic spatial planning attempts to free the imaginative potentials of urban regions and transform these into development that mixes regulative and visionary approaches (cf. Healey, 2004; Mäntysalo et al., 2015). In the realm of spatial planning, the change toward network governance has been met with the formation of ‘soft spaces’, in distinction to the existing ‘hard spaces’ of government. With ‘soft spaces’, Haughton, Allmendinger and Oosterlynck refer to the “‘in-between’ spaces of governance that exist outside, alongside or in-between the formal statutory scales of government, from area masterplans to multi-regional growth strategies” (Haughton et al., 2013, 219; see also Salet, 2006; Majoor & Salet, 2008). The planning of soft spaces, or ‘soft planning’, challenges ‘hard planning’ in many regards, as argued by Purkarthofer (2016, 8; cf. Faludi, 2013; Stead, 2014): It creates new spatial entities, introduces new scales and mechanisms of policy- and decision-making and brings new actors to the table – but at the same time the ‘rules’ how these processes are established are neither universal nor transparent. Lacking a legal basis, it is not clear who has the right to participate, make proposals and decide when it comes to soft planning, let alone how plans are implemented and who has to abide them. New ‘soft’ planning instruments have also emerged, alongside the ‘hard’ instruments of statutory land-use planning. They are aimed at facilitating the networking of planning by surmounting the traditional boundaries, either between different administrations or between the public and private sectors. Thus they may be devised, for example, to bridge boundaries between planning sectors and/or scales, reach broader regional coverage beyond municipal boundaries in urban and metropolitan regions, or to focus selectively on certain development themes or non-jurisdictional places or ‘neighbourhoods’.

244

The Governance of Planning

Further, the soft planning instruments are conceived to enhance the strategic character of planning. In this perspective, the hard planning tools of the statutory planning systems are perceived as non-strategic, with their extensive comprehensiveness, ‘blueprint’ determinism, functionalistic zoning, and rigid and hierarchical preparation processes. In turn, the soft planning instruments are aimed to enable strategic selectivity, dynamic orientation to visions with caution to alternative scenarios, relational configuration of spatial realities, timeliness of preparation, and engagement of stakeholders in the co-production of spatial strategies (Albrechts & Balducci, 2013). However, the statutory land-use planning tools cannot simply be bypassed. Their hardness is still very much required in managing spatial relationships, as there are several uses and users of plans that need to be taken into account: the courts require legal clarity and certainty when ruling on appeals to plans, the real estate investors and land-owners expect predictability in land and real estate value development, and the planners themselves prefer legal weight to their plans, in order to commit other actors to obey them (Van den Broeck, 2013). Further, despite their often burdensome and rigid character, the statutory planning procedures, in their reliance on the law, guarantee that the use of public authority in these procedures has a legitimate basis (Van den Broeck, 2013; Mäntysalo et al., 2015). In such conditions, aspirations to transform the ‘hard’ planning systems to ‘soft’, to comply with the governance paradigm, tend to fall short. According to Davoudi et al. (2009, 78), this is often due to the lack of due attention to the wider institutional context of which the planning system is a part: “What is important in any initiative to redesign a planning system . . . is to pay careful attention to the institutional context within which it is situated and to how planning system initiatives will interact with the evolution of that context” (Davoudi et al., 2009, 78; see also Bäcklund et al., forthcoming). Moroni (2010; see also Salet, 2002) further argues that while planning organizations might be redesigned, their institutional linkages cannot be a subject of ‘institutional design’, as institutions can be transformed only through gradual evolution. Perhaps the most central institution in this context is the institution of land property, as an object of commodity in the land and real estate market, mortgage in financing, legal right of occupancy and use, cultural value, object of land management and planning, etc. Therefore, soft planning should not be seen as an alternative to hard planning, in the same way that governance cannot do without government. Instead, measures should be developed for their ‘hybrid’ coexistence. Rather than associating strategic spatial planning with soft planning tools (Albrechts & Balducci, 2013), strategic spatial planning should aspire to manage the uneasy coexistence of soft and hard planning tools (Mäntysalo et al., 2015; Mäntysalo, 2013). This brings our attention to problem settings requiring strategic capacity the most, such as: how to achieve both procedural legitimacy and sufficient informal flexibility; how to both fix legal certainties and work with uncertainty; how to both use essentialist zoning tools and maintain a relational view of planning. Hence, strategic spatial planning ought to focus on managing the relationships of e.g. certainty-uncertainty and essentialism-relationality in spatial development, acknowledging their paradoxical nature of being both mutually dichotomous and interdependent (Mäntysalo, 2013). According to Mäntysalo (2013, 52), “[s]trategic spatial planning is about transcending certainty and essentialism, while acknowledging them as necessary attributes of the realm of planning and dealing with them from a broader horizon of uncertainty and relationality”. Finally, the categories ‘soft’ and ‘hard’ are neither clear-cut nor fixed. When set against local juxtaposing of legal frameworks, governance models and planning system characteristics, they dissolve into a variety of degrees of softness and hardness for spaces and instruments of planning – as Metzger and Schmitt (2012, 277) state, these spaces of planning are “relative, gradient positions on a shared continuum of spatial closure and territorial definition”. Furthermore, as Metzger and

245

Raine Mäntysalo and Pia Bäcklund

Schmitt (ibid.) argue, soft spaces may solidify through, for example, practices of spatial planning that provide identity and agency. Similarly, according to Paasi and Zimmerbauer (2015), hard spaces are subject to softening when ‘new’ soft planning ideals and spaces are superimposed on and across ‘old’ institutionalized territories. The discussion about soft and hard planning must also account for the varying nature of planning instruments. In the systems with rigid land-use plan hierarchies, such as Finland, there might indeed be high degrees of ‘hardness’ in statutory plans. In turn, in systems with policy orientation and positioning of statutory spatial planning alongside other spatial strategy-making instruments, for example the UK and the Netherlands, the statutory plans may be relatively ‘soft’ when considering their direct steering powers.

Concluding Remarks In this chapter, we have reviewed the theoretical discussion around (urban) governance and its implications to planning. The researchers have been debating the repercussions to planning of the paradigm shift from government to governance, some focusing on its emancipatory potential over bureaucratic planning control, others perceiving it as the increase of neoliberal domination of selected interests in planning. However, less attention has been paid to the empirical conditions of the transformation of governance. Since administrative reforms rarely affect all of the adjoining practices and institutional conditions, conflicting systems and rationalities appear. The public sector organizations are differentiated and do not represent a single and unified will. Besides defining the governance paradigm and its implications to planning at the theoretical level, there is a pressing need to identify and develop conceptual tools for the empirical analysis of governance in its different institutional contexts – otherwise governance would become a mere buzzword in planning theories. This view should also include a more profound understanding of the nature of institutions, conditioning our governmental bodies and partnerships and being inclined to path-dependent development. What follows is that proper attention should also be paid to the institutional rootedness of ‘government’ and its ‘resilience’ in the governance reforms. Instead of a neat paradigm shift from government to governance we are dealing with institutional ambiguity of blurred responsibilities, mixed roles and unclear accountabilities of different actors that have become involved in different networks, partnerships and agreements, while still being expected to obey the rules and legitimacy-ensuring procedures of the government (e.g. Hajer, 2009; Bäcklund & Mäntysalo, 2010). Moreover, the institutional level is not to be considered as a mere hindrance to governance reforms, but as a necessary provider of continuity in such reforms. In the form of legally based normative rules or norms it enables action in conditions of uncertainty. The normative rules establish the codes of behaviour that enable people to orientate to each other with expectations of mutual reliability (Van Rijswick & Salet, 2012). On such orientations the governance networks ultimately rest, too. Regarding planning, this all means that ‘soft’ spatial planning should not be perceived, nor aspired, as decoupled from ‘hard’ land-use planning, however emancipatory or neoliberal it could be. How do – and how should – soft and hard planning mix in different institutional contexts, to enable co-productive capacity without jeopardizing legitimacy, is a highly relevant, but a largely unresearched question. As remarked by Faludi (2015, 15), “the issue . . . is whether there is soft democratic legitimacy”. Indeed, when concentrating only on soft forms of planning, the developers of strategic spatial planning have not been broadminded enough to address the strategic mindset needed in bridging soft and hard planning. 246

The Governance of Planning

References Aarsæther, N., Nyseth, T. & Bjørnå, H. (2011) Two networks, one city: democracy and governance networks in urban transformation. European Urban and Regional Studies, 18 (3), 306–320. Albrechts, L. & Balducci, A. (2013) Practicing strategic planning: in search of critical features to explain the strategic character of plans. disP, 49 (3), 16–27. Albrechts, L., Healey, P. & Kunzmann, K. R. (2003) Strategic spatial planning and regional governance in Europe. Journal of the American Planning Association, 69 (2), 113–129. Allmendinger, P. & Haughton, G. (2010) Spatial planning, devolution, and new planning spaces. Environment and Planning C, 28 (5), 803–818. Allmendinger, P. & Haughton, G. (2013) The evolution and trajectories of English spatial governance: ‘neoliberal’ episodes in planning. Planning Practice & Research, 28 (1), 6–26. Allmendinger, P. & Haughton, G. (2015) Post-political regimes in English planning: from Third Way to Big Society. In J. Metzger, P. Allmendinger & S. Oosterlynck (eds) Planning against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance. London: Routledge, 29–54. Bäcklund, P. & Mäntysalo, R. (2010) Agonism and institutional ambiguity: ideas on democracy and the role of participation in the development of planning theory and practice – the case of Finland. Planning Theory, 9 (4), 333–350. Bäcklund, P., Kallio, K. P. & Häkli, J. (2014) Residents, customers or citizens? Tracing the idea of youthful participation in the context of administrative reforms in Finnish public administration. Planning Theory and Practice, 15 (3), 311–327. Bäcklund, P., Häikiö, L., Leino, H. & Kanninen, V. (forthcoming) Bypassing publicity and transparency for getting things done: between informal and formal planning practices in Finland. Balducci, A. (2011) Strategic planning as exploration. Town Planning Review, 82 (5), 529–546. Bang, H. & Esmark, A. (2009) Good governance in network society: reconfiguring the political from politics to policy. Administrative Theory & Praxis, 31 (1), 7–37. Bengs, C. (2005) Planning theory for the naïve? European Journal of Spatial Development, July (Debate), 1–12. Retrieved May 30, 2013, from www.nordregio.se/EJSD Blanco, I. (2013) Analysing urban governance networks: bringing the regime theory back in. Environment and Planning C, 31, 276–291. Brindley, T., Rydin, Y. & Stoker, G. (1989) Remaking Planning: The Politics of Urban Change in the Thatcher Years. London: Unwin Hyman. Buchanan, A. (2002) Political legitimacy and democracy. Ethics, 112 (4), 689–719. Davoudi, S. & Madanipour, A. (2013) Localism and neo-liberal governmentality. Town Planning Review, 84 (5), 551–561. Davoudi, S., Healey, P., Vigar, G. & Majale, M. (2009) The institutional and regulatory framework for planning. In: Planning for Sustainable Cities: Global Report on Human Settlements 2009. United Nations Human Settlements Programme. London: Earthscan, 72–92. Fainstein, N. & Fainstein, S. (2013) Restoring just outcomes to planning concerns. In N. Carmon & S. Fainstein (eds) City in the Twenty-First Century: Policy, Planning and People: Promoting Justice in Urban Development. Philadelphia PA: University of Pennsylvania Press, 43–64. Faludi, A. (2013) Territorial cohesion, territorialism, territoriality, and soft planning: a critical review. Environment and Planning A, 45 (6), 1302–1317. Faludi, A. (2015) Place is a no-man’s land. Geographia Polonica, 88 (1), 5–20. Grange, K. (2013) Shaping acting space: in search of a new political awareness among local authority planners. Planning Theory, 12 (3), 225–243. Grange, K. (2014) In search of radical democracy: the ideological character of current political advocacies for culture change in planning. Environment and Planning A/ 46 (11), 2670–2685. Grange, K. (2016) Planners – a silenced profession? The politicisation of planning and the need for fearless speech. Planning Theory, doi: 10.1177/1473095215626465. Gunder, M. (2010) Planning as the ideology of (neoliberal) space. Planning Theory, 9 (4), 298–314. Hajer, M. (2009) Authoritative Governance. Policy-making in the Age of Mediatization. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Haughton, G., Allmendinger, P. & Oosterlynck, S. (2013) Spaces of neoliberal experimentation: soft spaces, postpolitics, and neoliberal governmentality. Environment and Planning A, 45 (1), 217–234. Healey, P. (2004) The treatment of space and place in the new strategic spatial planning in Europe. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 28 (1), 45–67.

247

Raine Mäntysalo and Pia Bäcklund Healey, P. (2007) Urban Complexity and Spatial Strategies: Towards a Relational Planning for Our Times. London: Routledge. Hirst, P. (2000). Democracy and governance. In J. Pierre (ed.) Debating Governance: Authority, Steering and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 13–25. Horelli, L. (ed.) (2013) New Approaches to Urban Planning: Insights from Participatory Communities. Espoo: Aalto University, Science+Technology 10. Inch, A. (2010) Culture change as identity regulation: the micro-politics of producing spatial planners in England. Planning Theory & Practice, 11 (3), 359–374. Klijn, E.-H. & Koppenjan, J. (2012) Governance network theory: past, present and future. Policy & Politics, 40 (4), 587–606. Leadbeater, L. (2004) Personalisation through Participation: A New Script for Public Services. London: Demos. Mahoney, J. (2000) Path dependency in historical sociology. Theory and Society, 29 (4), 507–548. Majoor, S. & Salet, W. (2008) The enlargement of local power in trans-scalar strategies of planning. GeoJournal, 72 (1–2), 91–103. Mäntysalo, R. (2013) Coping with the paradox of strategic spatial planning. disP, 49 (3), 51–52. Mäntysalo, R. & Saglie, I.-L. (2010) Private influence preceding public involvement: strategies for legitimizing preliminary partnership arrangements in urban housing planning in Norway and Finland. Planning Theory & Practice, 11 (39), 317–338. Mäntysalo, R., Saglie, I.-L. & Cars, G. (2011) Between input legitimacy and output efficiency: defensive routines and agonistic reflectivity in Nordic land-use planning. European Planning Studies, 19 (12), 2109–2126. Mäntysalo, R., Kangasoja, J. K. & Kanninen, V. (2015) The paradox of strategic spatial planning: a theoretical outline with a view on Finland. Planning Theory and Practice, 16 (2), 257–272. Metzger, J. & Schmitt, P. (2012) When soft spaces harden: the EU strategy for the Baltic Sea region. Environment and Planning A, 44 (2), 263–280. Metzger, J., Allmendinger, P. & Oosterlynck, S. (eds) (2015) Planning against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance. London: Routledge. Moroni, S. (2010) An evolutionary theory of institutions and a dynamic approach to reform. Planning Theory, 9 (4), 275–297. North, D. C. (1990) Institutions. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5 (1), 97–112. Olsson, J. & Hysing, E. (2012) Theorizing inside activism: understanding policymaking and policy change from below. Planning Theory & Practice, 13 (2), 257–273. Osborne, D. & Gaebler, T. (1992) Reinventing Government. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Paasi, A. & Zimmerbauer, K. (2015) Penumbral borders and planning paradoxes: relational thinking and the question of borders in spatial planning. Environment and Planning A, 48 (1), 75–93. Pierre, J. (1999) Models of urban governance: the institutional dimension of urban politics. Urban Affairs Review, 34, 372–396. Pierson, P. (2000) Increasing returns, path dependence, and the study of politics. The American Political Science Review, 94 (2), 251–267. Pollitt, C. & Bouckaert, G. (2011) Public Management Reform: A Comparative Analysis. New Public Management, Governance and the Neo-Weberian State. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Purcell, M. (2009) Resisting neoliberalization: communicative planning or counter-hegemonic movements? Planning Theory, 8 (2), 140–165. Purkarthofer, E. (2016) When soft planning and hard planning meet: conceptualising the encounter of European, national and sub-national planning. European Journal of Spatial Development, 61, May, 1–20. Retrieved May 30, 2016, from www.nordregio.se/Global/EJSD/Refereed articles/refereed61.pdf Puustinen, S., Mäntysalo, R., Hytönen, J. & Jarenko, K. (2017) The ‘deliberative bureaucrat’: deliberative democracy and institutional trust in the jurisdiction of the Finnish planner. Planning Theory & Practice, 18 (1), 71–88. Rhodes, R. A. W. (1996) The new governance: governing without government. Political Studies, 44, 652–667. Rosenau, J. N. (1992) Governance, order, and change in world politics. In J. N. Rosenau & E.-O. Czempel (eds) Governance without Government: Order and Change in World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 3–6. Sager, T. (2009) Planners’ role: torn between dialogical ideals and neo-liberal realities. European Planning Studies, 17 (1), 65–84. Sager, T. (2011) Neo-liberal urban planning policies: a literature survey 1990–2010. Progress in Planning, 76 (4), 147–199.

248

The Governance of Planning Sager, T. (2013) Reviving Critical Planning Theory. Dealing with Pressure, Neo-liberalism, and Responsibility in Communicative Planning. London: Routledge. Salet, W. G. M. (2002) Evolving institutions: an international exploration into planning and law. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 22, 26–35. Salet, W. G. M. (2006) Rescaling territorial governance in the Randstad Holland: the responsiveness of spatial and institutional strategies to changing socio-economic interactions. European Planning Studies, 14 (7), 959–977. Scharpf, F. (1999) Governing in Europe: Effective and Democratic? Oxford: Oxford University Press. Skelcher, C. & Torfing, J. (2010) Improving democratic governance through institutional design: civic participation and democratic ownership in Europe. Regulation and Governance, 4 (1), 71–91. Skelcher, C., Klijn, E. H., Kübler, D., Sørensen, E. & Sullivan, H. (2011) Explaining the democratic anchorage of governance networks: evidence from four European countries. Administrative Theory & Praxis, 33 (1), 7–38. Stead, D. (2012) Best practices and policy transfer in spatial planning. Planning Practice & Research, 27 (1), 103–116. Stead, D. (2014) European integration and spatial rescaling in the Baltic region: soft spaces, soft planning and soft security. European Planning Studies, 22 (4), 680–693. Stoker, G. (1998) Governance as theory: five propositions. International Social Science Journal, 50 (155), 17–28. Swyngedouw, E. (2005) Governance innovation and the citizen: the Janus face of governance-beyondthe-state. Urban Studies, 42 (11), 1991–2006. Van den Broeck, J. (2013) Balancing strategic and institutional planning: the search for a pro-active planning instrument. disP, 49 (3), 43–47. van Rijswick, M. & Salet, W. (2012) Enabling the contextualization of legal rules in responsive strategies to climate change. Ecology and Society, 17 (2), 18.

249

20 NEW INSTITUTIONALISM AND PLANNING THEORY André Sorensen

New Institutionalism (NI) has been an influential project in social science theory for over 40 years, with major impacts on disciplines as diverse as political science, sociology, economics, and geography. A number of these ideas have been taken up in planning theory, but this work is still at a relatively early stage with much still to be done. This chapter reviews the main currents in new institutionalist thought, outlines several ways in which these ideas have been developed in planning theory, and points to some paths forward. It seems obvious that a robust theorization of institutions is important to planning theory, as institutions and institutional design are central to the planning project of creating better, more just, more liveable, and more sustainable cities. Cities are densely institutionalized spaces, with multifaceted institutions shaping everything from the regulation of sidewalks to conceptions of good neighborhoods to the legal structure of property. Planners have been the authors of many institutions designed to manage processes of urban change, from land-use zoning to infrastructure building and management systems. The challenge facing efforts to develop an institutionalist approach in planning theory is that the various branches of institutional theory contradict each other, combined with an extraordinary lack of attention by mainstream NI theorists to issues specific to cities, space, and urban planning. Significantly, NI is not a single coherent body of thought, and in recent years new branches have proliferated. Hall and Taylor (1996) identified three main branches, Peters (1999) identified seven, and Lowndes and Roberts (2013) distinguish nine. Still, since Hall and Taylor’s seminal paper of 1996, a division into three main branches of NI has been widely followed: sociological (or normative) institutionalism (SI) arising in part from organizational analysis in sociology; and historical institutionalism (HI) and rational choice institutionalism (RI) emerging within political science. These draw on new institutional economics (NIE), from which many concepts are borrowed. More recently feminist institutionalism and discursive (or constructivist) institutionalism (DI) which is treated here as a variant of HI, have rapidly growing literatures of their own. Each branch includes multiple competing and sometimes contradictory ideas, with significant overlaps and ambiguous borders, and some planning theories draw on multiple branches. This proliferation of institutionalisms has generated vigorous debates over key issues. In addition to defining ‘institutions’ differently, each has its own interpretation of the relationships between institutions and behavior, conceptions of structure/agency issues and of power, and theories of institutional change. This diversity makes a review of the impacts of these ideas 250

New Institutionalism and Planning Theory

on planning theory challenging, as varied institutionalisms have been taken up by planning theorists, and the several branches of the family have seldom been on good speaking terms. Competing institutionalisms are rooted in different social ontologies, generate alternative conceptions of the roles institutions play in social processes, and suggest different research questions. While RI draws on neoclassical economic models of rational actor behavior, SI and HI focus on the social construction of knowledge, power, and rules. Although attempts have been made to bring the various approaches together under a single umbrella (Hall and Taylor 1996; Thelen 1999; Lowndes and Roberts 2013), others reject those attempts as pointless, or worse, arguing that the neoclassical economics ontology and methodological individualism of RI approaches are incompatible with those of HI and SI (Hay and Wincott 1998; Healey 2006a). While I agree that it makes little sense to attempt to fuse the various NI approaches into a single theory, I argue that we cannot simply ignore RI, as this approach has had a major impact on planning theory. The first part of this chapter introduces core concepts and outlines major areas of agreement and disagreement between the main new institutionalisms. The second section provides a concise introduction to each of the three major branches of new institutionalist thinking, and outlines the major ways that these have been incorporated into planning theory. The third part suggests an institutionalist approach to planning theory that draws primarily on HI, as this is the most notable gap in the existing literature.

Core Concepts in NI The ‘new’ institutionalism has been around for almost half a century, so it is new only relative to the ‘old’ institutionalism in political science that focused primarily on the formal institutions of public administration, and their arrangements, structure, and functioning in comparative perspective. The old institutionalism was criticized as being largely descriptive, without any compelling theoretical framing (March and Olson 1984; Hall and Taylor 1996). NI has grown, since the 1970s, out of attempts, particularly in political science and organizational sociology, to understand the roles that institutions play in social and political life. The fundamental premise of NI is that ‘institutions matter’ in social and political processes, and require careful theorization to understand how they matter, and how they develop and change over time (March and Olsen 1984). All NIs include a much wider range of phenomena – including formal rules, shared norms and understandings, and standard operating practices – in their definition of institutions than did the old institutionalism. All reject the equation of ‘institution’ with organizations, or particular government agencies such as hospitals and prisons, and define institutions instead as sets of rules and shared understandings that shape action. All share the premise that “political behavior and political outcomes are best understood by studying the rules and practices that characterize institutions” (Lowndes and Roberts 2013: 7), but each branch defines institutions differently. Definitions of ‘institutions’ vary greatly, but all share a number of elements: First, institutions are sets of formal and informal rules that shape behavior, that have developed in different societies through specific historical processes. North’s definition of institutions as the formal and informal “rules of the game . . . the humanly devised constraints that shape human interaction” (North 1990: 3) is widely agreed, but is particularly associated with RI. Sociological institutionalists define institutions broadly, including “not just formal rules, procedures or norms, but the symbol systems, cognitive scripts, and moral templates that provide the ‘frames of meaning’ guiding human action” (Hall and Taylor 1996: 947). Most historical institutionalists define institutions more narrowly as “the formal or informal procedures, routines, norms and conventions embedded in the organizational structure of the polity or political economy” (Hall and Taylor 251

André Sorensen

1996: 938). This approach excludes ‘culture’ and links institutions more closely with specific organizational settings and enforceable rules (see Sorensen 2015a). All institutionalisms attempt to explain the ways in which institutions shape behavior, the ways in which institutional genesis and change occur, and the relationship between structure and agency, but they approach these questions differently. RI sees individuals as rational actors who act to maximize their self-interest. In this view, groups create institutions to overcome collective action problems, to ensure greater certainty, and to reduce risks. Such institutions shape behavior directly, by creating enforceable rules and imposing costs or sanctions on those who do not conform. SI frames institutions as deeply embedded norms and shared understandings that affect the way individuals understand and interpret different situations, and shape the range of actions that seem appropriate or even conceivable in each case. HI conceives institutions to evolve historically through political conflicts and compromises, and to shape action both by imposing enforceable rules and by shaping the political economy of power relations, social preferences and interpretations, and the rewards and opportunities experienced by actors in a given setting. A second major difference between institutionalisms is in conceptions of institutional origins and change processes. For RI, institutions are deliberate creations of groups of rational actors, which over time are subject to processes of creative destruction through which (in successful societies) effective institutions persist, while less efficient solutions are weeded out by market processes. In contrast, the ‘symbol systems, cognitive scripts, and moral templates’ of SI are not deliberate creations, but are shared understandings that evolve slowly over time (Roland 2004), sometimes as a result of deliberate governance innovations, as discussed below. Initially, the focus of HI on path dependence led to conceptions of ‘punctuated equilibrium’ in which institutions originate primarily during critical junctures of major institutional change, in response to exogenous pressures. In between critical junctures, institutions were understood to change less, and to follow developmental pathways of incremental change. More recently, HI theorists see processes of endogenous and evolutionary change as being equally important in explaining institutional change, and focus on the factors that structure such change (Mahoney and Thelen 2010)(also see Chapter 18 on Co-evolutionary Planning Theory in this volume). A third major distinction between institutionalisms is in approaches to the role of power in institution creation and change, and the role of institutions in reinforcing or subverting existing power imbalances. For HI, institutions are seen to have significant roles in the distribution of scarce resources. As Mahoney puts it, institutions are “distributional instruments that allocate resources unevenly and thereby help constitute asymmetrical collective actors” (2010: 15). Institutions that benefit or disadvantage groups of individuals in particular ways will tend to shape the perceived self-interest of those groups, and might encourage them to identify as a group for purposes of collective action. Political power is thus reinforced by the fundamentally distributive character of institutions. Concepts of power are not as central for sociological institutionalists. While recognizing systemic power and the pervasive impacts of powerful actors, institutions such as norms and shared understandings are usually conceived as operating beyond the scale of individual actors or groups, although in some situations relatively powerless groups can also generate and articulate new ideas and visions for shared spaces through local collaborative action (Healey 2006b). For RI the significance of political power is diminished by the fact that institutions are seen as coordinating devices that generate mutual benefits by facilitating cooperation and overcoming collective action problems. The basic assumption is voluntary exchange among rational individuals, so if a particular institution does not benefit an actor, they can opt out or develop an alternative, competing institution. Moe (2006) argues that even though a number of RI theorists have investigated power, it remains peripheral to the theory. 252

New Institutionalism and Planning Theory Table 20.1  Key approaches of the three main branches

Origins

Definition of institutions

Main characteristic of institutions Models of institutional change

Conceptions of structure and agency

Analysis of power

Rational Choice Institutionalism

Sociological Institutionalism

Historical Institutionalism

Institutional economics, rational choice political science The formal and informal “rules of the game . . . the humanly devised constraints that shape human interaction” (North 1990: 3)

Organization theory in sociology

Political science and comparative historical social science “the formal or informal procedures, routines, norms and conventions embedded in the organizational structure of the polity or political economy” (Hall and Taylor 1996: 938)

Coordinating effects, providing certainty, information, and credible commitment Institutions change primarily in response to market forces, as rational actors adjust behavior, groups create institutions to overcome collective action problems Individual actors are self-interested agents, who sometimes devise collective rules to ensure cooperation Power is not a major focus of RI, which tends to see institutions as generating mutual benefits by facilitating cooperation and overcoming collective action problems

“not just formal rules, procedures or norms, but the symbol systems, cognitive scripts, and moral templates that provide the ‘frames of meaning’ guiding human action.” (Hall and Taylor 1996: 947) Shared understandings that shape action, and imagination Institutions change slowly, as larger cultural and cognitive systems evolve incrementally

Social and cultural contexts and shared understandings provide settings for and shape agency As institutions are so broadly defined, and change slowly, SI is less focused on overt political power than HI, and pays more attention to systemic and hegemonic power

Distributional instruments that regulate social and political processes Punctuated equilibrium models of critical junctures and developmental pathways, and recent concepts of structured processes of endogenous change Institutions generated historically through political conflicts provide settings for and shape agency Power is central to the analysis of institution formation and change. Institutions have major distributional impacts, so actors have incentives to mobilize to shape institutions

All institutionalisms provide valuable insights into the relationship between structure and agency in shaping processes of social and political change. Institutions shape agents’ capacity to make a difference in the short term, and to transform institutions and eventually structures in the longer term, where structures are social properties that cannot be changed by individual agents within particular periods (Moulaert and Jessop 2006). Institutions mediate between structure and agency by providing sets of rules and norms that both constrain and enable agency (Giddens 1984). Constraints function both through formal and informal norms, and through the exercise of power and coercion. Institutions enable agency by establishing legitimate processes and ideas 253

André Sorensen

with which to engage in social and political action. Actions to challenge institutions are important political moments that are highly likely to be contested, as discussed below.

The Three Major Branches RI is one of two major strands of new institutionalist thinking originating in political science (for major reviews see Shepsle 1989; Hall and Taylor 1996; Immergut 1998; Weingast 2002; Lowndes and Roberts 2013). RI has its origins in the rational choice school of political science that has been prominent particularly in the U.S. since the 1960s as part of attempts to develop a quantitative basis for political science. RI draws on the toolkit of neoclassical economics, game theory, and equilibrium theory assumptions about agent preferences and profit maximizing behaviors, but also challenges neoclassical economics by focusing on the institutional settings within which such processes take place (Riker 1980; Shepsle and Weingast 1987). Most accept North’s (1990: 3) definition of institutions as “the rules of the game in a society or, more formally, . . . the humanly devised constraints that shape human interaction.” Some institutions are deliberately created, such as constitutions, and some evolve as the norms and “standard operating practices” of particular settings. North distinguished between three major types of institutions: formal rules, informal constraints, and enforcement mechanisms, and showed convincingly that such institutions are major determinants of long-run economic performance. A major focus of RI is to develop models of individual political motivation and action that can be aggregated to understand the actions of political actors at larger scales (Riker 1980; Shepsle and Weingast 1987). As Weingast put it, the major questions posed by RI concern “the effects of institutions; why institutions are necessary at all; and the endogenous choice of particular institutions” (Weingast 2002: 660). RI draws on NIE, and economic theories of the firm initiated by Coase in the 1930s, particularly his seminal insight that even though the price system of markets provides valuable information and coordination functions, using it entails significant costs of negotiation, making contracts, and enforcing compliance, known as transaction costs (Coase 1937). Coase suggested that firms exist largely because they are able to reduce transaction costs by using non-market coordinating mechanisms within firms, and that this should produce an optimum of planning, as in competitive markets firms will survive only if they perform these coordinating functions at lower costs than would exist in competitive markets (Coase 2008: 34). In its focus on transaction costs, NIE critiques neoclassical economics, which ignores these issues almost entirely. Transaction-cost economics therefore assumes that where the costs of carrying out and enforcing transactions are high, institutions can lower those costs, either by providing more certainty, reduced risks, and better information, or by internalizing transactions costs within a firm (Williamson 1985). The work of Coase and Williamson is foundational for NIE, as was North’s work on the role of institutions in economic development, and Ostrom’s (1990) work on institutions developed to manage small and medium sized common pool resources, such as common grazing lands, fisheries, or irrigation systems. Ostrom showed that institutions allow groups to avoid tragedies of overexploitation of commons, that there is enormous variety of such institutions, and that many have been enduring. RI theories have been influential in planning theory, particularly in the application of transaction-cost theories to land-use planning. Early efforts challenged the standard welfare economics arguments for public planning based on market failures, suggesting that transactions costs theory offers greater precision and insight (Alexander 1992, 2001; Lai 1994, 1997; Webster 1998). This work largely supported public planning interventions based on the benefits of increased certainty and reduced transactions costs, while also pointing to the possibility that

254

New Institutionalism and Planning Theory

these benefits might be more efficiently achieved through private planning. Later work pushed these ideas further, arguing that the rapid global spread of private communities was clear evidence that private planning could and did substitute for public planning, and that part of the advantage of such communities is reduced transactions costs, and greater variety of institutional structure and public goods than provided by local governments (Webster 2002; Webster and Lai 2003). Alexander (2005) argued that it depends on the specific case whether regulatory planning can best be supplied either by public regulations, or by private contracts, while Buitelaar (2004) builds on Alexander (2001) and proposes and tests a method of measuring and comparing transaction costs in different cases. Lai (2005) suggests that the study of NIE in relation to planning is valuable primarily because it provides research tools that allow empirical testing of such propositions, particularly in evaluations of the impacts of development control in urban economics and real estate finance analysis. A second major debate has been on evolutionary theories of institutional change versus ideas of institutional design. Moroni has argued that institutions develop in an evolutionary manner and that existing institutions are the end product of long-term selection processes, and given complexity and unintended consequences, deliberate institutional design – including most planning interventions – is likely to fail (Moroni 2010a, 2010b). Others have challenged this conclusion (see the debate between Alexander (2011) and Moroni (2011)). RI is often criticized for its reliance on neoclassical microeconomics assumptions that individuals are rational actors who seek to maximize their own benefits, that efficiency is promoted by competition between options as in market processes, and that political preferences can be understood as aggregations of large numbers of individual decisions, and is accused of methodological individualism in its focus on modeling individual behavior. As Pierson argues, “micromodelling exercises that are centered on strategic interaction among individuals encourage a highly restricted field of vision, both in space and time” (2004: 9). He suggests that RI tends to miss the macro social structure and the role of sequencing of events, as well as most longer-term processes that are not captured by the ‘snapshot’ approach of rational choice models. Further, RI approaches reduce institutions to the aggregation of individual choices and preferences, yet many institutions, such as nation states, simply cannot be adequately explained in this way (Immergut 1998). Similarly, RI tends to assume that institutions are the result of rational choices, even though many enduring institutions are actually the unintended by-products of other choices (Shepsle 1989; Pierson 2004). Pierson suggests that RI is of value, but that its tools should be kept in proper perspective, whereas Hay and Wincott (1998) argue that RI be rejected altogether. HI is the second major branch originating in political science. HI has been primarily concerned with large-scale and long-term processes of institutional development and evolution at the national and international scales (Hall and Taylor 1996; Thelen 1999; Pierson 2004). Major works include Skocpol’s (1979) comparative analysis of revolution in France, Russia, and China; processes of institutional change in the US federal government (Skowronek 1982); studies on international relations (Keohane 1989); Hall’s (1989) comparison of the impact of changing economic ideas in different countries; Thelen’s (2004) analysis of processes of institutional change in skills training regimes in Germany; and Mahoney’s (2010) analysis of the long-term impacts of colonial institutions on post-colonial development. HI commonly defines institutions as the formal or informal procedures, routines, norms and conventions embedded in the organizational structure of the polity or political economy. They can range from the rules of a constitutional order or the standard operating procedures of a bureaucracy to

255

André Sorensen

the conventions governing trade union behaviour or bank-firm relations. In general, historical institutionalists associate institutions with organizations and the rules or conventions promulgated by formal organization. (Hall and Taylor 1996: 938) Similarly, Streeck and Thelen (2005: 9) define institutions as “collectively enforced expectations with respect to the behavior of specific categories of actors or to the performance of certain activities.” Institutions are sets of rules or shared expectations within particular settings, a much narrower conception than the symbol systems, cognitive scripts and moral templates of SI. A fundamental premise is that institutions emerge from and are embedded in concrete historical processes (Thelen 1999: 371), and that these are best understood through careful attention to the timing and sequencing of major institutional change and to the positive feedback effects that tend to reinforce continuity (Pierson 2004; Mahoney 2000), and ‘process tracing’ is a prominent research method (Collier 2011). A major contribution of HI is the concept of path dependence. This has been popularized as meaning simply that ‘history matters’ or that early events influence later ones. Mahoney (2000) and Pierson (2000) argued that the concept be more narrowly defined as referring to positive feedback effects that support institutional continuity. Where self-reinforcing positive feedback exists, evolutionary change processes will not necessarily lead to efficient outcomes because the early dominance of a particular approach can mean that it becomes hard to displace. The most famous example is the QWERTY typewriter keyboard, which was deliberately designed to slow down the fastest typists so that mechanical typewriters did not jam. Later attempts to introduce more efficient keyboard layouts failed because so many individuals and firms had invested in the QWERTY design (David 1985). Where self-reinforcing processes exist, contingent choices early on in a process can have large and long-lasting consequences, and the timing and sequencing of institutional development will be crucial for outcomes (Pierson 2004: 44). Positive feedback generates branching processes of institutional development, with initial steps along a particular pathway of institutional development leading to further steps along that pathway. Rather than converging on a single most efficient approach, different organizations, firms or states might continue to follow different trajectories over extended periods, and inefficient approaches might persist (North 1990; Pierson 2004). The suggestion is not that institutions become frozen and unchanging, but that contingent choices made early in a process can preclude whole ranges of possibilities, while enabling others. North also argued that the sets of complementary institutions, which he referred to as “interdependent webs of an institutional matrix,” can be mutually reinforcing, and can have profound impacts on patterns of institutional development. Interlocking sets of institutions can produce particularly path dependent and enduring institutional regimes, as they have evolved together, and their effectiveness is interdependent. This insight contributed to the “Varieties of Capitalism” hypothesis, that such institutional complementarities have encouraged the persistence of different approaches to capitalism in different countries (Hollingsworth and Boyer 1997; Hall and Soskice 2001). As it is not assumed that social processes automatically select for efficiency, the functionality or dysfunctionality of particular institutional regimes is an empirical question (North 1990; Hay and Wincott 1998). This focus on path dependence and enduring institutions initially led to a relatively limited interest in processes of institutional change, which were explained as resulting primarily from exogenous shocks, or ‘critical junctures’ that separated longer periods of relative stasis (see Collier 256

New Institutionalism and Planning Theory

and Collier 1991; Capoccia and Kelemen 2007). Katznelson (2003: 277) described critical junctures as moments when existing institutional structures fail to provide adequate solutions to pressing problems, and thus lose legitimacy and their ability to determine action, creating opportunities for actors to develop new institutions. While this ‘punctuated equilibrium’ model of change might apply to many social processes, however, over the last decade a major focus of HI scholarship has been the analysis of endogenous and incremental processes of institutional change (Thelen 2003; Streeck and Thelen 2005; Mahoney and Thelen 2010). Thelen (2004) argued that most institutional change occurs outside of critical junctures, in incremental but potentially transformative processes. One focus has been on the ways existing institutions structure patterns and processes of incremental change. For example, Hacker (2004) argues that patterns of institutional change are likely to be structured both by the degree to which institutions allow discretion in policy application, and whether there are significant barriers to decisive policy revision, for example significant veto points or veto players (Tsebelis 2000). These two axes combine to generate a typology of four major types of policy change that are most likely under different circumstances (see Mahoney and Thelen 2010; Sorensen 2011, 2015a). A core feature of HI is its explicitly power-political approach to understanding institution formation, continuity, and change, in which actors compete to deploy and revise institutions in their own interests. Mahoney suggests that while RI sees institutions primarily as “coordinating devices that solve collective action problems,” HI sees institutions primarily as “distributional instruments that allocate resources unevenly and thereby help constitute asymmetrical collective actors” (2010: 15; emphasis in original). Mahoney argues that all institutions privilege some actors over others, even when they are intended to be neutral. It is because of their uneven distributional consequences that those who benefit from a particular institution are often willing to fight to defend it, and the politically powerful are better able to ensure the creation or maintenance of institutional arrangements that favor themselves. As he argues: “it is essential to treat institutions as the objects of contestation among actors . . . Only this perspective can capture the prominent role that power and conflict play in actual processes of institutional formation and change” (Mahoney 2010: 16). This approach suggests that institutions are the outcomes of earlier rounds of political conflict, and that institutions do not simply aggregate interests, but constrain certain forms of action while facilitating others. As Moe (2006) put it “institutions are not only structures of coordination but may also be structures of coercion, power and domination.” The victors of institutional conflicts have a powerful incentive to defend their gains, and the resources provided can help prevent unwanted changes (Lowndes 2009). Hacker and Pierson (2010) provide a persuasive example in their analysis of the success of the minority of wealthy Americans in shifting the federal tax burden disproportionately toward the majority of less well off Americans, even though in theory this should be difficult in a democratic polity. This engagement of HI scholars with incremental and endogenous institutional change, and with dynamic and contested processes of institution formation and revision undercuts claims by discursive/constructivist institutionalists that DI was necessary because HI had failed to explain institutional change and was stuck in a punctuated equilibrium world-view (see Hay 2006; Schmidt 2008). Yet as a leading proponent, Hay (2006: 62) argues, if HI is predicated on the “dynamic interplay of structure and agent . . . then the difference between historical and constructivist institutionalisms is at most one of emphasis.” But even if seen as a branch of HI, DI’s engagement with ideas and discourse in politics, with policy coordination and legitimation, and with norms as dynamic constructs that evolve in part through legitimating discourses, is a valuable contribution that has clear applications in planning theory. For example, Taylor (2013) 257

André Sorensen

frames an institutionalist strategy to move forward from comparative planning cultures debates through study of the role of institutions in the production and reproduction of planning ideas and professional norms. Historical institutionalists have focused primarily on national level political systems, and the ways in which states shape political processes and possibilities. Although some HI scholars have analyzed local governance issues (Rast 2007; Dilworth 2009; Lowndes 2009), little attention has been paid to HI by planning theorists (but see Sorensen 2015a, 2015b, 2016). Sociological Institutionalism emerged from organizational sociology in the 1970s. Powell and DiMaggio’s edited collection (1991) was a foundational work that shaped SI by bringing together reprints of seminal papers with key contemporary work and a number of original chapters that pointed to major new research directions. A defining characteristic of SI is its expansive definition of institutions as “not just formal rules, procedures or norms, but the symbol systems, cognitive scripts, and moral templates that provide the ‘frames of meaning’ guiding human action” (Hall and Taylor 1996: 947). Institutions provide the templates with which individuals are able to understand and interpret particular situations, and learn to act in socially appropriate ways. As DiMaggio and Powell put it, “Institutions do not just constrain options: they establish the very criteria by which people discover their preferences.” (1991: 11). This is a much more encompassing understanding of the role of institutions than either HI or RI. For SI, institutions affect behavior not just by creating enforceable rules, but by shaping individuals’ understanding of the situations they find themselves in. SI downplays the premise of instrumental, rational action at the core of RI, and develops a conception of meaning and action based on social norms, conventions, and legitimating myths. Received cognitive systems form the scaffolding with which people make sense of the world and imbue it with value, meaning, and emotion (Scott 2014). And as individuals have inherent cognitive limits, institutions aid decisionmaking by turning many decisions into streamlined, habitual processes based on received codes. A major insight was that many of the institutional forms and procedures adopted by modern organizations are not particularly efficient, and are best explained as attempts to conform to established norms, and create legitimate ways of working (Meyer and Rowan 1991). This is described as ‘institutional isomorphism,’ the reproduction of institutional arrangements that are seen as legitimate because they fit with established templates (DiMaggio and Powell 1983; Mahoney and Thelen 2010: 5). Similarly, Meyer and Rowan argue that for many complex organizations, organizational structures and institutional myths are legitimated primarily externally by congruence with larger social structures, rather than through enhanced efficiency. Such ‘ceremonial’ structuration promotes the success and survival of organizations by enhancing confidence and stability within the organization, and by reducing turbulence and conflict with external organizations (Meyer and Rowan 1991). Conceptions shifted from equating culture with belief systems and values in collective life toward conceptions of “culture as complex rulelike structures that constitute resources that can be put to strategic use” (DiMaggio 1997: 265). For all these reasons, SI usually sees institutions as changing slowly as wider cultural and normative settings change. Zucker (1991) argued that in highly institutionalized settings cultural persistence is greater, even without direct social controls, because subjects internalize the myths and expectations of the institution, and change is incremental, occurring primarily as larger cultural frameworks change. Similarly, Roland (2004) distinguishes between fast and slow moving institutions, with specific rules being more amenable to fast changes, and broader cognitive scripts changing more slowly. A more recent contribution is that many institutions co-evolve in interdependent and complementary ways, with two or more entwined systems evolving together in mutually shaping and reinforcing ways, as explored in Chapter 18 on Co-evolutionary Planning Theory in this volume. 258

New Institutionalism and Planning Theory

Patsy Healey has undoubtedly been the main interpreter of SI in planning theory, and has also made significant contributions to SI itself. Healey’s major contribution is a productive interpretation of Giddens’ (1984) reframing of the structure/agency dualism, integrating it with communicative planning theory and institutionalism, suggesting that individuals are not simply constrained by institutions, but also continuously reproduce them, and can therefore act to change them. As Healey puts it: We make structural forces, as we are shaped by them. So we ‘have power’ and, … can work to make changes by changing the rules, changing the flow of resources, and, most significantly, by changing the way we think about things. (Healey 1997: 49) Healey showed brilliantly that the municipal scale is key for collaborative planning processes that allow the institutionalization of new norms and ideas, because they link to people’s understanding of place. As she argued, managing our co-existence in shared spaces … becomes an exercise not merely in consensus-building but in local culture-building, and in creating a public realm. It is an interactive and discursive effort, through which new understandings and institutional capacities are built. (1997: 48) This work can transform institutions at multiple scales from the smallest to the largest. Healey developed a social constructivism that sees individuals as actors embedded in particular social and cultural settings, who are continually learning about how to reproduce and creatively reinvent institutional structures. Gualini (2001) similarly focuses on institutionalization processes through place-based collective action and the development of relationships, ways of working, and operational rules that generate shared knowledge and practices. Healey extended this core insight to work on processes of building social capital and institutional capacity through collaborative planning approaches (Healey 1998, 1999), to social innovation in governance (Gonzalez and Healey 2005; Healey 2006b), and the role of spatial planning and communicative practices in a revitalization of democratic practice (Healey 2006a, 2013). Healey frames institutions as particularly relevant to re-imagining planning and place. Institutions “structure the interactional processes through which preferences and interests are articulated and decisions made. They are a kind of ‘soft infrastructure’ of the governance of social life” (Healey 2006a: 64). Institutional innovation is therefore essential to be able to create governance processes that can contribute positively to transformative change of places.

HI and Planning Theory Significant contributions to planning theory have been made in both RI and SI, so here the focus is on the potential of HI, which has had surprisingly little influence. Five HI concepts are particularly relevant to planning theory: (1) contingent critical junctures of institution formation; (2) positive feedback to institutional power that in some cases generates path dependence and branching patterns of institutional development; (3) the unavoidably unequal distributional effects of institutions that structure political opportunity and mobilization; (4) structured processes of incremental institutional change that privilege certain actors and pathways over others; and (5) the institutional complementarities and co-evolution processes that constitute and help 259

André Sorensen

maintain great variation among urban planning systems (see Sorensen 2015a). HI provides a coherent framework for analyzing processes of institutional development and change. In HI perspective, urban planning systems can be understood as multifaceted sets of institutions that regulate the production, use, and change of urban space. These sets of institutions developed over extended periods, both during major ‘critical junctures’ of institutional innovation such as the development of modern planning in response to the 19th-century urban crisis, and through longer periods of incremental and evolutionary change. Because institutions are unequal in their distributive impacts, providing greater benefits to some actors than others, institutional change is contested, and those who benefit from particular institutions can be expected to try to prevent changes that weaken their position, while those who benefit less are more likely to press for change. HI studies the political dynamics of processes of institution formation and incremental change, without assuming that such dynamics can be ‘read off’ the institutions themselves, as unintended consequences are common. Planning institutions have specific origins, genealogies, characteristics, and change processes that are key to understanding how planning systems work in practice, and how they change over time. Because the timing and sequencing of contingent moments of institutional change matter, and self-reinforcing path dependent processes are common, there are often large and enduring differences in planning institutions between jurisdictions. These include varied ways in which institutions structure urban space, actors can participate in urban change processes, and divergent qualities of the places produced. Urban planning institutions are the product and legacy of recurring political conflict. The exercise of power at contingent points of institutional change is important, but so are ongoing contests over the implementation and enforcement of rules on the ground. HI approaches provide valuable tools for comparison and analysis of different developmental pathways that help to explain the evolutionary trajectories and diversity of planning systems. HI, therefore, provides valuable tools for comparative planning studies, which must be a central element of planning theory investigations that ask questions like: What can planning achieve? How do political dynamics affect the differentiation of planning approaches in different places? How have the circumstances and timing of the development of planning institutions in different jurisdictions affected approaches? How have governance institutions enabled particular institutional development trajectories in different jurisdictions? How can we explain profoundly varied and enduring planning institutions, and why is there such great variation in the distributional impacts of planning in different jurisdictions? How do positive feedback effects reinforce some institutional change trajectories more than others? What aspects of planning systems are open to reform, and why is institutional design so hard? A more robust comparative theorization of the origins and developmental pathways of modern planning systems from an HI perspective promises insights into the origins and dynamics of fundamental differences in urban governance between jurisdictions, and the different capacities and approaches in different countries. Comparative analysis of particular urban institutions in different jurisdictions will be one approach to a reconceptualization and reframing of planning theory toward a focus on the institutional dynamics of planning evolution, and the role of power in institutional change.

Acknowledgments The author is grateful for valuable comments on an earlier draft by the editors, and by John Friedmann, Patsy Healey, and Zack Taylor. Support for the research in this chapter was provided by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada fund number 491073. 260

New Institutionalism and Planning Theory

References Alexander, E. (1992). ‘A transaction cost theory of planning.’ Journal of the American Planning Association 58(2): 190–200. Alexander, E. (2001). ‘A transaction-cost theory of land use planning and development control: towards the institutional analysis of public planning.’ Town Planning Review 72(1): 45–75. Alexander, E. (2005). ‘Institutional transformation and planning: from Institutionalization theory to Institutional design.’ Planning Theory 4(3): 209–223. Alexander, E. (2011). ‘An evolutionary theory of institutions – prescriptive implications: institutional design lives, but prudential principles apply.’ Planning Theory 10(2): 187–189. Buitelaar, E. (2004). ‘A transaction-cost analysis of the land development process.’ Urban Studies 41(13): 2539–2553. Capoccia, G. and R. D. Kelemen (2007). ‘The Study of Critical Junctures: Theory, Narrative, and Counterfactuals in Historical Institutionalism.’ World Politics 59(3): 341–369. Coase, R. H. (1937). ‘The nature of the firm.’ Economica 4: 386–405. Coase, R. H. (2008). The institutional structure of production. In C. Ménard and M. M. Shirley (Eds.) Handbook of New Institutional Economics. Berlin, Springer: 31–39. Collier, R. B. and D. Collier (1991). Shaping the Political Arena. Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press. Collier, D. (2011). ‘Understanding process-tracing.’ Political Science and Politics 44(4): 823–830. David, P. (1985). ‘Clio and the economics of QWERTY.’ American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings of the Ninety-Seventh Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association 75(2): 332–337. Dilworth, R. (2009). The City in American Political Development. New York, Routledge. DiMaggio, P. (1997). ‘Culture and cognition.’ Annual Review of Sociology 23: 263–287. DiMaggio, P. J. and W. Powell (1983). ‘The iron cage revisited: institutional isomorphism and collective rationality in organizational fields.’ American Sociological Review 48: 147–160. DiMaggio, P. J. and W. W. Powell (1991). Introduction. In W. W. Powell and P. J. DiMaggio (Eds.) The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis. Chicago and London, University of Chicago Press: 1–38. Giddens, A. (1984). The Constitution of Society, London, Polity. Gonzalez, S. and P. Healey (2005). ‘A sociological institutionalist approach to the study of innovation in governance capacity.’ Urban Studies 42(11): 2055–2069. Gualini, E. (2001). Planning and the Intelligence of Institutions: Interactive Approaches to Territorial Policy-making between Institutional Design and Institution-building. Aldershot; Burlington, Ashgate. Hacker, J. S. (2004). ‘Privatizing risk without privatizing the welfare state: the hidden politics of social policy retrenchment in the United States.’ American Political Science Review 98(2): 243–260. Hacker, J. S. and P. Pierson (2010). Winner-take-all Politics : How Washington Made the Rich Richer – and Turned its Back on the Middle Class. New York, Simon & Schuster. Hall, P. A. (1989). The Political Power of Economic Ideas: Keynesianism across Nations. Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press. Hall, P. A. and D. W. Soskice (2001). Varieties of Capitalism: The Institutional Foundations of Comparative Advantage. Oxford, Oxford University Press. Hall, P. A. and R. C. R. Taylor (1996). ‘Political science and the three new institutionalisms.’ Political Studies 44(5): 936–957. Hay, C. (2006). Constructivist institutionalism. In R. A. W. Rhodes, S. A. Binder and B. A. Rockman (Eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Political Institutions. Oxford, Oxford University Press: 56–75. Hay, C. and D. Wincott (1998). ‘Structure, agency and historical institutionalism.’ Political Studies 46(5): 853–1027. Healey, P. (1997). Collaborative Planning: Shaping Places in Fragmented Societies. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Macmillan Press. Healey, P. (1998). ‘Building institutional capacity through collaborative approaches to urban planning.’ Environment and Planning A 30(10): 1531–1546. Healey, P. (1999). ‘Institutionalist analysis, communicative planning, and shaping places.’ Journal of Planning Education and Research 19: 111–121. Healey, P. (2006a). The new institutionalism and the transformative goals of planning. In N. Verma (Ed.) Institutions and Planning. Amsterdam; Boston, Elsevier: 61–87. Healey, P. (2006b). ‘Transforming governance: challenges of institutional adaptation and a new politics of space.’ European Planning Studies 14(3): 299–320.

261

André Sorensen Healey, P. (2013). ‘Re-enchanting democracy as a mode of governance.’ Critical Policy Studies 6(1): 19–39. Hollingsworth, J. R. and R. Boyer (1997). Contemporary Capitalism: The Embeddedness of Institutions. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Immergut, E. (1998). ‘The theoretical core of new institutionalism.’ Politics & Society 26(1): 1–46. Katznelson, I. (2003). Periodization and preferences: reflections on purposive action in comparative historical social science. In J. Mahoney and D. Rueschemeyer (Eds.) Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press: 270–301. Keohane, R. O. (1989). International Institutions and State Power: Essays in International Relations Theory. Boulder, CO, Westview Press. Lai, L. W. C. (1994). ‘The economics of zoning: a literature review and analysis of the work of Coase.’ Town Planning Review 65: 77–98. Lai, L. W. C. (1997). ‘Property rights justifications of planning and a theory of zoning.’ Progress in Planning 48: 161–245. Lai, L. W. C. (2005). ‘Neo-institutional economics and planning theory.’ Planning Theory 4(1): 7–19. Lowndes, V. (2009). New institutionalism and urban politics. In J. S. Davies and D. L. Imbroscio (Eds.) Theories of Urban Politics. Los Angeles, CA, Sage: 91–105. Lowndes, V. and M. Roberts (2013). Why Institutions Matter: The New Institutionalism in Political Science. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire, Palgrave Macmillan. Mahoney, J. (2000). ‘Path dependence in historical sociology.’ Theory and Society 29(4): 507–548. Mahoney, J. (2010). Colonialism and Postcolonial Development: Spanish America in Comparative Perspective. New York, Cambridge University Press. Mahoney, J. and K. A. Thelen (2010). Explaining Institutional Change: Ambiguity, Agency, and Power. Cambridge; New York, Cambridge University Press. March, J. G. and J. P. Olsen (1984). ‘The new institutionalism: organizational factors in political life.’ American Political Science Review 78(3): 734–749. Meyer, J. W. and B. Rowan (1991). Institutionalized organizations: formal structure as myth and ceremony. In W. W. Powell and P. J. DiMaggio (Eds.) The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis. Chicago and London, University of Chicago Press: 41–62. Moe, T. M. (2006). Power and political institutions. In I. Shapiro, S. Skowronek and D. Galvin (Eds.) Rethinking Political Institutions: The Art of the State. New York, New York University Press: 32–71. Moroni, S. (2010a). ‘An evolutionary theory of institutions and a dynamic approach to reform.’ Planning Theory 9(4): 275–297. Moroni, S. (2010b). ‘Rethinking the theory and practice of land-use regulation: towards nomocracy.’ Planning Theory 9(2): 137–155. Moroni, S. (2011). ‘The role of deliberate intervention on organizations and institutions: a response to Alexander.’ Planning Theory 10(2): 190–197. Moulaert, F. and B. Jessop (2006). Thematic Synthesis Paper 1: Agency, Structure, Institutions, Discourse (ASID). Demologos project. North, D. C. (1990). Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance. Cambridge; New York, Cambridge University Press. Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Peters, B. G. (1999). Institutional Theory in Political Science: The ‘New Institutionalism’. London and New York, Pinter. Pierson, P. (2000). ‘Increasing returns, path dependence, and the study of politics.’ American Political Science Review 94(2): 251–267. Pierson, P. (2004). Politics in Time: History, Institutions, and Social Analysis. Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press. Powell, W. W. and P. J. DiMaggio (1991). The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis. Chicago; London, University of Chicago Press. Rast, J. (2007). ‘Annexation policy in Milwaukee: an historical institutionalist approach.’ Polity 39(1): 55–78. Riker, W. H. (1980). ‘Implications from the disequilibrium of majority rule for the study of institutions.’ American Political Science Review 74(2): 432–437. Roland, G. (2004). ‘Understanding institutional change: fast-moving and slow-moving institutions.’ Studies in Comparative International Development 38(4): 109–131. Schmidt, V. (2008). ‘Discursive institutionalism: the explanatory power of ideas and discourse.’ Annual Review of Political Science 11: 303–326.

262

New Institutionalism and Planning Theory Scott, W. R. (2014). Institutions and Organizations: Ideas, Interests and Identities. Los Angeles, SAGE. Shepsle, K. A. (1989). ‘Studying institutions: some lessons from the rational choice approach.’ Journal of Theoretical Politics 1(2): 131–147. Shepsle, K. A. and B. Weingast (1987). ‘The institutional foundations of committee power.’ American Political Science Review 81(1): 86–108. Skocpol, T. (1979). States and Social Revolutions: A Comparative Analysis of France, Russia, and China. Cambridge; New York, Cambridge University Press. Skowronek, S. (1982). Building a New American State: The Expansion of National Administrative Capacities, 1877–1920. Cambridge; New York, Cambridge University Press. Sorensen, A. (2011). ‘Evolving property rights in Japan: patterns and logics of change.’ Urban Studies 48(3): 471–491. Sorensen, A. (2015a). ‘Taking path dependence seriously: an historical institutionalist research agenda in planning history.’ Planning Perspectives 30(1): 17–38. Sorensen, A. (2015b). Transforming land into property: varieties of institutionalism and the production of urban space. In J. Hillier and J. Metzger (Eds.) Connections: Exploring Contemporary Planning Theory and Practice with Patsy Healey. Farnham, Surrey; Burlington, VT, Ashgate: 423–436. Sorensen, A. (2016). ‘Periurbanization as the institutionalization of place: the case of Japan.’ Cities 53: 134–140. Streeck, W. and K. Thelen (2005). Introduction: institutional change in advanced political economies. In W. Streeck and K. Thelen (Eds.) Beyond Continuity: Institutional Change in Advanced Political Economies. Oxford, Oxford University Press: 1–39. Taylor, Z. (2013). ‘Rethinking planning culture: a new institutionalist approach.’ Town Planning Review 84(6): 683–702. Thelen, K. (1999). ‘Historical institutionalism in comparative politics.’ Annual Review of Political Science 2: 369–404. Thelen, K. (2003). How institutions evolve: insights from comparative historical analysis. In J. Mahoney and D. Rueschemeyer (Eds.) Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press: 208–240. Thelen, K. (2004). How Institutions Evolve: The Political Economy of Skills in Germany, Britain, the United States, and Japan. Cambridge; New York, Cambridge University Press. Tsebelis, G. (2000). ‘Veto players and institutional analysis.’ Governance: An International Journal of Policy and Administration 13(4): 441–474. Webster, C. (1998). ‘Public choice, Pigouvian and Coasian planning theory.’ Urban Studies 35(1): 53–75. Webster, C. (2002). ‘Property rights and the public realm: gates, green belts, and Gemeinshaft.’ Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design 29: 397–412. Webster, C. and L. W. C. Lai (2003). Property Rights, Planning and Markets: Managing Spontaneous Cities. Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, MA, Edward Elgar. Weingast, B. (2002). Rational-choice institutionalism. In I. Katznelson and H. V. Milner (Eds.) Political Science: The State of the Discipline. New York, Norton: 660–692. Williamson, O. E. (1985). The Economic Institutions of Capitalism: Firms, Markets, Relational Contracting. New York; London, Collier Macmillan. Zucker, L. G. (1991). The role of institutionalization in cultural persistence. In W. W. Powell and P. J. DiMaggio (Eds.) The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis. Chicago; London, University of Chicago Press: 83–107.

263

21 CONFLICT AND AGONISM John Pløger

Introduction Planning is permanent conflict. Conflict is partly a matter of how planning institutions are supposed to act according to regulations, but also planning institutions’ own ideas about power, consensus and democracy (Forester 1989, Hillier 2007, Sandercock 2003). Agonism is a critical mode of thinking about conflict and conflictual consensus. Chantal Mouffe has been a key figure in planning theory in this endeavour (e.g. 2005, 2013), and her political philosophy has transfused into studies on how to take better care of disagreements and differences in planning (e.g. Barnett & Bridge 2013, Bond 2011, Bäcklund & Mäntysalo 2010, Innes & Booher 2014, van Leeuwen 2014). This chapter explores how planning praxis can work with conflict as agonistic conflict; what challenges does this give planning; positioned, as it is, within and relying on political legitimacy, consensus processes, and political decisions? A key question is: how can planning work with conflict as dissensus? The ‘how’ of transforming the philosophy of agonism into a mode of planning involves planning’s governmentality. The governmentality of late modern planning can be described as a politicised endeavour to improve the efficiency and governing capacity of politics. Its public raison d’être is democratic communication on the basis of knowledge, analysis and deliberation with interests.2 The chapter first outlines three threads on agonism within planning theory and, second, gives a brief introduction to the philosophy of agonism. Third, the challenges to planning theory given by the political philosophy on agonism from Chantal Mouffe are discussed, introducing her key concepts hegemony and ‘war of position’. Using Jacques Rancière, the next section introduces dissensus as a challenge to Mouffe’s agonism and to planning. The chapter will end by discussing possible ways to work productively with agonism as ‘a permanent provocation’ (Michel Foucault) and often representing dissensus to institutionalism and planning politics. The target is how can planning praxis acknowledge contestation and inadmissible difference as key forces of a multiverse democracy; a democracy of many interpretations. 1

Critical Planning Theory – Now It is possible to identify three threads on agonism within planning theory. The reformist approach focuses on improving public planning democratically by participation: how public interests can 264

Conflict and Agonism

get more influence, where on the timeline and on what issues. The goal is a strong consensus among participants in an attempt to tame time-consuming conflict. Here, studies, for instance, focus on planners as mediators, facilitators and catalysts within the planning process (e.g. Laws & Forester 2007, Innes & Booher 2010). The procedural approach is a departure from the legal ground and political legitimacy framing planning. This approach follows ideas of legitimate compromises, negotiation and deliberation as the main tools of planners. The public planning process is seen as a collaborative and communicative process of ‘trading’ between interests, and one main goal is to improve communication with weak voices within the legal planning process (e.g. Mäntysalo, Balducci & Kangasoja 2011). The third thread could be called neo-radical planning with its roots in Healey’s (2006) reflexive communication and relational planning, but owing its agonistic perspective to Hillier’s (2002, 2007) writings on agonism, post-representational theory and strategic navigation (2011). Seeing planning as contingency, affect, and becoming has provided a different path for considering conflict as productive. Agonistic strife not only contests endeavours to make planning more efficient and rational, and contests communicative and pragmatic planning theory on how to achieve consensus, but also challenges the ‘how’ of making decisions. The tension between the positions is far from gone. It is claimed it is time to ‘advance the dialogue’ between consensus and conflict thinking (Innes & Booher 2014), and to find better ways of practising for instance by using facilitators (Laws & Forester 2007). Innes, Booher and Forester want to create a dialogue that builds on shared meanings of the problems and a shared understanding of the problems. They look for a communicative form and a rationality of arguing that builds on openness, sincerity, trust, and honesty (‘everything is on the table’), and a process that can reflect on sources of ‘differences’ among the interests involved (Innes & Booher 2014: 205). To respect that ‘we can never agree’ – to ‘understand they [planners and the public] live in two worlds, each with different rules’ (p. 205) – is vital. It is vital to keep in mind that every interest and suggestion can be questioned (‘genuinely addresses’) (p. 205), which means ‘solutions are never permanent’ and need to be seen as a ‘work in progress’ and ‘a solution is for now’ (p. 206). It is the facilitators’ or mediators’ task to find meeting points. Innes and Booher are admitted consensualists who want to build ‘discourse coalitions’ (p. 207) through consensus or compromises, while Mouffe steadily adds that ‘consensus is always accompanied by dissent’ (2005: 31). Others have looked at how to turn conflict into consensus and agonism into collaborative consensus-making processes. One of the most inventive is what we might call a ‘procedural agonism’, which is a matter of how to institutionalise agonism within consensus politics (e.g. Mäntysalo, Saglie & Cars 2011). Planning has to treat conflicts in an agonistic manner, but in a way that makes it possible to domesticate critics through the work of adversaries. An adversarial process ‘entails agonistic tolerance of tensions and disagreements’ (p. 2121) as a way to cope with ‘tensions between different logics’ (p. 2120), and thus paradoxes of every kind should be ‘continuously discussed and coped with without being resolved for good’ (p. 2121). Bäcklund and Mäntysalo (2010) in a Finnish study show how there is ambiguity within cities on how to allow citizens’ participation a stronger position within planning. They conclude that we need to look at the institutional governing of planning.3 Agonism is understood as a mode of planning that has an ‘openness to new ideas and complementary views’ (p. 347), and public planning should be about negotiation (‘a trading zone’) based on ‘tolerance and respect between the adversaries’ (Mäntysalo et al. 2011a: 268). Bond (2011), too, claims if communicative planning wants ‘reciprocity’ between participants, it requires ‘an engagement with disagreement and conflict’, and a particular focus on revealing and exploring the use or misuse of the ‘undecidability’ that underpins an agonistic space (p. 179). 265

John Pløger

The post-structuralists have pointed to ‘planning as becoming’ as a way to respect difference and disagreement within a horizon of the ineradicability of antagonistic conflicts. Agonistic planning might be planning as becoming if engaging with a process that ‘promotes on-going trust and buy-in for contested site-specific decisions and strategic directions’ (Mouat, Legacy & March 2013: 150). The challenge is to have actors see conflict as ongoing and to give space to the challenge from critique, contestation and the incoming of new ideas. Many cities around the world prefer a management approach to conflict rather than engaging with critique, and they see consensus-based decisions as one aspect of this management. A case study from St Kilda in Melbourne shows how an agonistic approach toward ‘problems’ – including what is usually left out: the question of identities, adversaries’ treatment of time, space and place, and the treatment of conflict – gives potential for solving ‘wicked problems’ within the idea of collaborative planning. However, the potential productive strife in this case lost ‘against councilors ultimately decided to the outcome’ (Moat, Legacy & March 2013: 164). Jean Hillier (2002) claims planning has to live with both consensus and agonistic forces at play, which might force planning to learn to live with ‘incompleteness, inconsistencies, contradictions’ (p. 269) and ‘aporetic’ decisions (p. 291). She follows Mouffe and says it is about ‘domesticating’ antagonism to agonism (p. 15) by realising that ‘there can always be a reasonable dissent’ (p. 256). The balance between opponents – ‘conflictual consensus’ (Mouffe), ‘agonistic respect’ (Connolly) – can be reconciled according to the ‘there is no right answer’ or one understanding of issues (p. 269), which opens up for the praxis of provisional agreements rather than a belief in final decisions. Hillier may be read as pre-empting later attempts to see planning as a ‘trade-off’ or trading zone (Mäntysalo et al. 2011a), but she takes an agonistic turn and points to the need to look at the decision itself as ‘incumbent’ to planners, but in a manner that is aporetic (Hillier 2002: 279). These studies invite us to keep an interest in critical thresholds such as how to make a decision ‘open’ to a conflictual consensus, how to respect inconceivable disagreements, how to move from conflictual consensus to dissensus. The crucial question is how is it possible to govern through planning by means other than a hierarchical decisional system? Could making a temporary relation between negotiation and dissensus the driving force of planning be an answer? It is here we see the tension between Chantal Mouffe’s and Jacques Rancière’s elaboration of dissensus against consensus at its core. If the discussion of consensus–dissensus departs from agonism as contestation, they are both challenged by the ‘how’ of practice. If contestation is built into a system, an institutionalisation of planning building on final decisions, it becomes an exclusion of ‘the other’ and a closure of ineradicable difference or dissensus. How can difference be kept alive within a politicised planning apparatus?

The Agon of Agonism The Greek demos (democracy) is the public agon or meeting in the agora. The demos builds on the full citizenry of free expression and agonistic respect that requires full openness and a full civil dialogue on politics. Foucault calls the agonistic game typical for Greek life, and ‘the parrhesia’ (speaking openly and frankly) is the will to set one’s discourse at risk. You have to persuade, but might experience ‘the discourse of others . . . may prevail over your discourse’ (Foucault 2010: 105). A demos builds on contestation and the possible articulation of an opposition of something different and incommensurable to one’s own discourses and values. The agon is the core of democracy. Contestation and competition in politics are derived from the will to power (Nietzsche 1967: §§751–753) and this will is constituted by the resistance toward something (e.g. values). The will to power is a will to change society, the city, or life. 266

Conflict and Agonism

The agonistic ‘attitude’ thus comes from a self that is ‘constituted in and through what it opposes and what opposes it’ (Hatap 2002: 135). Democracy as demos is never a meeting among equals, but the balancing of power relations. Democracy is an unequal distribution of legal or legitimate power, for instance, when ‘a rightholder has a claim against some treatment by others or for some provision that might be denied by others’ (Hatap 2002: 143). Power in itself has to be permanently addressed. The agon is more than a matter of adversaries (Mouffe) and contestation (Connolly). It more precisely refers to a ‘critical “encounter”, a “confrontation”’, because ‘only in Auseinandersetzung does a productive interpretation arise’ (Martin Heidegger, here Milchman & Rosenberg 2003: 6). This Auseinandersetzung – literally the ‘setting-apart-of-each-other’ (Heidegger 2014: 146) – is to Heidegger a strife as a confrontation that for ‘all (that comes to presence) is the sire (who lets emerge),4 but (also) for all the preservers that holds sway’ (p. 65). The ‘agonal moment’ which Heidegger refers to as Polemos (from Heraclitus) means, confrontation as strife. Strife ‘allows what essentially unfolds to step apart from each other in opposition’, and it is in ‘con-frontation [the] world comes to be’ (p. 67). The struggle ‘projects and develops of the un-heard of, the hitherto un-said and un-thought’ (p. 68), and to Heidegger it is this ‘becoming-a-world’ that is ‘authentic history’ (p. 68). Heidegger, here, claims the conflicting struggle – or in Heidegger’s words, ‘the strife of the striving’ (p. 125) – is a confrontation between ineradicable differences. The struggle is required, because ‘the other’ or ‘otherness’ is a way to find out ‘what is one’s own’. The Auseinandersetzsung is thus, according to Heidegger, an ‘engagement in which differences appear sharpened, in which question are posed, not answered’ (Milch & Rosenserg 2003: 10). It is more than adversarial and contested, it is a ‘critical encounter’ (p. 6) as a ‘confrontational settingasunder (Auseinandersetzung) (of Being)’ that lets ‘gods and human beings step forth in their Being’ (p. 160) and otherness. Such a meeting is a clash between differences transformed into ‘a thoughtful confrontation of minds at odds’ (Charles Scott, cited in Milchman & Rosenberg 2003: 10). The confrontation implies contestation, but as a form of ‘problematisation’ (Foucault 1986: 388–389); the ‘problematizing experience and thinking’ of both oneself and others (Milchman & Rosenberg 2003: 11).

Conflict, Consensus, Hegemony, Politics – ‘The Ineradicable Antagonism’ and the ‘War of Position’ The agonism of Chantal Mouffe’s political philosophy highlights irreducible difference, or as she describes it, ‘the ineradicability of antagonism’ (Mouffe 2013: 11).5 The discussion of agonism, to her, places too much emphasis on persuasion, and she is also critical of any idea of agonism as contestation for at least one reason: contestation implies a possible reconciliation, but antagonism and hegemonic order are ineradicable to politics (p. 14). This means, on the one hand, we can never find the perfect moment for a just decision (there will always be antagonism toward it) and, on the other hand, every decision is only a temporary hegemony to be challenged. The key element to working with this antagonism–agonism relation is that of ‘adversary’. These are opponents that disagree, but ‘see themselves belonging to the same political association, as sharing a common symbolic space within which the conflict takes place’ (Mouffe 2005: 20). It is a shared symbolic space that builds on a ‘common allegiance to the democratic principles of “liberty and equality for all”, while disagreeing in their interpretation’ (Mouffe 2013: 7). The ‘presence of antagonism is not eliminated but “sublimated” so to speak’ (Mouffe 2005: 21). Such agonism is a form of meeting that ends up in a ‘conflictual consensus’: a recognition that we disagree but share a symbolic space that secures this disagreement as legitimate, but constitutive, to the continuing war of position within politics (Mouffe 2013: x, xii). 267

John Pløger

Power is crucial to Mouffe’s way of political thinking. She claims, following Antonio Gramsci, (discursive) hegemony is necessary to be able to confront the political establishment of society, and the war of position is necessary to form the hegemony of politics. The war of position is about ‘winning decisive positions’ and requires an ‘interventionist’ government that is strong enough to secure ‘the “impossibility” of internal disintegration implying control of every kind of political, administrative etc., reinforcement of the hegemonic “position” of the dominant group’ (Gramsci 1999: 495). The position once won is ‘decisive finitely’ (p. 495). Mouffe is, however, clear that hegemony is not won forever, but always contested. Gramsci writes, ‘the ruler has to muster all his resources to demonstrate how seriously he takes his adversary’ (1999: 495), meaning positions have to have a discursive and praxis legitimacy too. The idea of war of position is Gramsci’s way of thinking about the position of civil society toward ‘the long development of democratic inroads on the power of capital’ (Egan 2013: 535). This political issue is key to make strategies and tactics toward positions or actors with agendas, values, and interests. When Mouffe says, ‘we cannot escape the moment of decision’ and this will make ‘a space of inclusion/exclusion’ (2014: 153), then it is planning’s task to make this space for decision for politicians on planning issues. Planning has to set the line of inclusion/exclusion of arguments according to law and regulations. It is the planner’s discursive praxis (persuasion, deliberation, arguments) and dispositive techniques (such as legislations and the planning and building act) that must do the work. The public, on the other hand, only has the power of critique and counter-arguments against discourses, arguments and figures, and their interpretation against planning as a governing apparatus. The public’s war of position must become politics or oppositional political work. Planning itself might be an entry to politics, but the struggle for hegemony and the war of position are a matter of organised and ordered politics. To Mouffe, the opponent stands as a ‘competitor’ (2013: 8). Not all kinds of antagonism or agonism are legitimate, particularly not those questioning or threatening democracy. On the other hand, societies need a discursive and political hegemony to govern from and the need for closure of ineradicable disagreements. This is why ideas of contestation, to Mouffe, are an impasse. An opposition needs ‘hegemonic articulations’ as a ‘necessity not only of challenging what exist but also of constructing new articulations and new institutions’ (p. 11). Contestation, to Mouffe, is not a change of hegemony, just a challenge, and will only ‘disrupt the solid positionalities of identity’ (p. 12). Agonism as streiten (strife) (p. 11) and contestation ignores the necessary war of position, and the need to make new hegemonic discourses and institutionalise them. Planning is part of what Mouffe terms ‘politics’ as part of ‘the ensemble of practices and institutions whose aim is to organize human co-existence’ (2013: xii). An agonistic planning democracy means an openness to plurality and disagreement, and antagonism means any consensus must be seen as a ‘stabilization of something essentially unstable and chaotic’ (Mouffe 1997: 9) and thus temporary. Mouffe, back then, in fact saw deconstruction as a form of thinking and analysing that ‘forces us to keep the democratic contestation alive’ (1997: 9). Her later argument is that we have to acknowledge ‘the existence of conflicts that cannot have a rational solution’ (Mouffe 2014: 150). Politics, the institutionalisation of order by political decisions, must respond to antagonism by aiming for ‘constituting a “we”’ within a context of diversity and conflict (p. 150) ending up with a ‘shared symbolic space’ and a ‘conflictual consensus accompanied by dissensus’.

War of Position, Hegemony, Agonism – and Planning It is common to say ‘planning is politics’, but it is how planning is politicised that matters. Planning is a governing apparatus6 to politics and an apparatus that is supported by certain 268

Conflict and Agonism

dispositive techniques – planning and building law, regulations, guidelines, an ordered public planning process, rational planning paradigms – that give the apparatus its disciplinary power to serve politics. If one agrees with Mouffe on the impossibility of consensus without dissensus, and if there is agreement that institutions are needed to govern disagreements, her political philosophy is important to planning praxis. She wants to mobilise differences created by passion, pluralism, desire and dissent, while she also believes that consensus is needed in order to manage and develop society. Her conflictual consensus is thus to be seen as a both-and argument: the unavoidability of dissensus toward decisions and the need for moving forward by order and decisions. Societies have built ‘a battlefield’ called politics ‘on which hegemonic projects confront each other, with no possibility of a final reconciliation’ (Mouffe 2014: 151). Conflictual consensus – ‘divergent interpretations of shared ethico-political principles’ (2013: 23) – is possible using institutions to ‘institute an order in the context of contingency’ (2014: 151). However, order is only a ‘temporary and precarious articulation of contingent practices’ (Mouffe 2005: 18) always to be challenged, and hegemony is challenged by ‘the war of position’ (Mouffe 2013: 75). This war of position is not just a war on contesting the legitimacy of common sense or transforming partisans’ consciousness, but also a matter of shaping new institutional hegemonies through a combination of ‘parliamentary and extra-parliamentary struggles’. The task is to create synergy effect through ‘chains of equivalences’ between the movements (pp. 75, 77) in order to create ‘new hegemonic articulations’ (Mouffe 2014: 152) within political institutions. To Mouffe, an order or a decision is not necessarily ‘just’, but ‘proper’.7

Critical Paths Using Mouffe Caution is necessary when using Mouffe in planning theory. First, she is talking about politics, but planning means working from decided plans and has to implement policies. It is, as such, a politicised praxis. Second, the war of position has a different institutional path to follow within planning than within politics. Planning is not ‘representative politics’, but a ‘war of position’ and communication between particular – single or collective – interests. Third, participants cannot, within the formal planning process, exclude formal or informal politics, the ‘rules of the game’, or influencing the lines and rules of decision. Fourth, making a planning decision is a political task that excludes citizens’ influence on final decisions. Public planning is politically legitimised as a way to avoid endless disagreements and the process is supposed to prevent political ‘informality’ from flourishing (e.g. corruption, nepotism, etc.). The position as opponent or ‘adversary’ means planning becomes politically treated as a way to tame conflicts and disagreements. Within an apparatus guided by law and politics, and not a debate on values or mutual talks, planning decisions are not seen as conjunctures to work within, but where a disagreement is eradicated for consensus. Planning should close voids that can delay or endanger plans. Accepting Mouffe’s view that a democratic society ‘cannot treat those who put its basic institutions into question as legitimate adversaries’ (Mouffe 2005: 120), and that ‘legal pluralization cannot become the norm without endangering the permanence of the democratic political association’ (p. 122), the question, then, is what is dissensus to Mouffe? Is it a ‘social fact’ within a pluriverse society to be tamed by form (order)? Is dissensus not, as Althusser suggests, to ‘think in the conjuncture’, to acknowledge all circumstances that make ‘an inventory’ (2000: 17–19)? And is it not then to work from the ‘permanent provocation’ and contestation of modes of thinking, values, interests, plans and decisions, which Foucault points at? 269

John Pløger

Understanding politics as hegemony institutionalised is one of the reasons why Mouffe is hostile to movements that will not ‘build institutions’ or political leaderships. Such ‘basic institutions’ are, however, not a form of governing given a priori or ahistorically. For one thing, even legitimate actors and democratic societies’ basic institutions can be corruptive, suppressing opposition and the revelation of misuse of power (see how ‘democratic’ societies such as Denmark and the US treat whistle-blowers and the freedom of speech; see how the EU allows total surveillance of its citizens because ‘the people’ are said to threaten their basic institutions of bank capital, speculative economy, and politics). Is the institutionalisation of our societies and its apparatus not made to cover up for contingency by knowing ‘the enemy better than they know themselves’? In using the words legitimacy, order and adversaries, we should not forget Foucault claiming that ‘the exercise of power consists in guiding the possible outcome’ (Foucault 1986: 221). Government is ‘the way in which the conduct of individuals or groups must be directed’, and thus ‘to govern is to govern the possible field of action to others’ (p. 221). Every political and politicised institution in society is part of this kind of government regime. Mouffe’s and Gramsci’s ‘war of position’ does not belong to the sphere of civil society, but that of politics and political institutions. Mouffe may put the question of agonistic politics and the political on its head instead of on its feet. When Mouffe states ‘every order is the temporary and precarious articulation of contingent practices’ (2005: 18), politics and planning are still thought of as a closing of contingency for certainty and permanence. Following Foucault, planning has to be seen as a set of dispositive techniques (e.g. planning law, legal binding plans) made to avoid provisionality or preventing political decisions just becoming ‘a resting place’.

Dissensus, the Inadmissible, Politics – and Planning Politics to Mouffe is to create ‘unity’ facing conflict and diversity, and, to her, politics is ‘the ensemble of practices, discourses and institutions, which seek to establish a certain order and organise human co-existence in conditions that are always conflictual’ (2000: 101). She further states that ‘consensus exists as a temporary result of a provisional hegemony, as a stabilization of power’ (p. 104) and that an ‘agonistic pluralism’ always includes consensus with an exclusion of interests, why democracy has to ‘make room for dissent’ (p. 105). Because of this, she is critical of any belief in ‘rational consensus’ and ‘impartial procedures’, and looks for how to make ‘a vibrant “agonistic” public sphere of contestation where different hegemonic political projects can be confronted’ (2005: 3). To Rancière, agonistic disagreement is what cannot be defined as proper within the hegemonic consensus-proper. It is a dissensus in the sensible itself (reason), that the sensible cannot explain or understand itself. To a consensus-based process, this kind of improper acting is to be tamed, neutralised or ignored. To agonistic thinking, however, it is a matter of how to save the content of the improper as a contestation of the proper sensible. To Rancière ‘“real” politics is the irruptive event’ that challenges politics’ hierarchical order (Bassett 2014: 887, Rancière 2010: 35). The ‘so-far invisible’ (Bassett 2014: 888) parts of conflicts cannot be ‘heard’ by any identity-politics or participatory community-politics, because ‘the invisible’ is what contests the possibility of a legitimate ‘collective’ that can be institutionalised. The ‘Occupy movement’ is one such example. They represent a dissensus as inadmissible, because the movement questions politics ‘as we know it’: the need for leadership and decisional hierarchies, the need for a ‘programme’. They wanted to remain an ‘insubstantial’ movement (p. 892) always on the move, always unfinished. Like Rancière, they call for an ‘egalitarian dissent [that] is activated not by existing classes or social groups, but the emerging voices of the “part of no part”’ (p. 894). 270

Conflict and Agonism

The challenge to a demos of our time is, for Rancière, to give those who have no legitimate voice within the sensible a legitimacy and voice. He formulates the task like this, ‘the whole of those who are nothing, who do not have specific properties allowing them to exercise power’ (2000: 124). As it is now, they are not ‘entitled’ to exercise any form of power, so their way to be seen is to make a ‘rupture in the order of legitimacy and domination’. This is, according to Rancière, why these people can only manifest themselves and get power ‘within the act’, because if the act has a manifestation of a dissensus they might be seen (p. 124). An act of dissensus ‘creates a fissure in the sensible order, the established framework of perception, thought and action with the “inadmissible”’ (Rancière 2006: 85). ‘The inadmissible’ is to Rancière a radical concept referring to ‘a specific measure of incommensurables’ (2011a: 12, 2011b) that shapes disjunctions and represents the incommensurable difference that gives a situation of openness and contingency within politics that it cannot close, because there is no hegemonic representation. Dissensus thus cannot, according to Rancière, build a community, because this will be a community of ‘dis-identification’ and not substance. Dissensus therefore cannot be institutionalised (e.g. politically). To be inadmissible and incommensurable means to have a position outside, not inside. This is exactly what consensualism rejects; the multiple that stays multiple or stays as ‘a break in the auto-representational logic of society’ (Rancière 2000: 125). Consensualists stick to the claim that disagreements have to be institutionalised to obtain legitimacy. The Occupy movement seems to say, ‘we stay as multiples outside politics and play our politics on the demos’. This way the movement will question ‘the consensualist logic’, as Rancière defines it (2000: 126), and this way the movement is indicating that what we might call ‘the unfinished’ is the only thread to challenge power as consensus hegemony. As we know from Foucault, politics, governing forces and institutions are afraid of the unfinished, and what is on the move and has no ‘head to cut’. If agonistic planning is to be seen as a praxis of change, of being egalitarian, then the critique from the agonistic positions of Rancière is important. He points at how planning studies need to problematise the institutionalisation of how power becomes politics (Rancière 2010: 53), and how institutions create a ruling that legitimises itself by the claim of the necessity of order, but that it is also de-legitimising itself by not having space for the ‘autos or self’ (p. 52). Democracy cannot, according to Rancière, ‘consist of a set of institutions’ (p. 54), because democracy itself has to become political. This is done by ‘blurring and displacing the borders of the political itself’ (p. 54), meaning for instance that planning should always question itself, its legitimacy, its way of working, its position within the institutional net, and as a democratic process. Mouffe (for many good reasons) fears political disorder, and admits there is ‘a moment of decision to be confronted’ acknowledging it ‘implies closure’ (2014: 153). Her answer is a ‘collective will’ (p. 157) that can go into the war of positions and here planning certainly might have a role to play. Rancière conversely claims distinction, dis-junction, ‘the inexistent’ (that which is not seen, given words, worded) (2010: 213) and the self (subjectification, particularity) are at the heart of democracy. We cannot find a principle of democracy or a common ground of equality. Politically we should, according to Rancière, look to how ‘forms of subjectivation re-configure the topography of the common’ and this is ‘a matter of composition and not of constitution’ (p. 213). A constitution such as politics can never achieve equality; it is only the compositions of difference in praxis that can fight for it. Where Mouffe accepts the act of exclusion within politics as part of making (necessary) decisions, Rancière focuses on the mode of exclusion of dissensus and how we think about the ‘givens’ such as democracy and equality. Societies exclude what does not fit their hegemonic mode of thinking: the inexistent, the inadmissible. He wants to see a political that exists as ‘the 271

John Pløger

gap in the sensible, of the givens’; not only rupturing the order of legitimacy and domination but inaugurating ‘a manner of “doing politics” otherwise than politics does’ (Rancière 2011a: 8). Planning actors face planning ‘focused on control, steering, and management of land-use and physical change’ (Mouat et al. 2013: 152). Consensus planning, as Mouat, Crystal and March point out, does not ‘show us the choices made, the alternatives’ (p. 152). Rancière says contest and act. Agonism is thus the permanent problematisation of hegemonies, legitimacy and decisions made by consensus or majority force. Is this to be seen as a claim for contextualism, sensitive to compositions of arguments and choices, and a temporary resting made from within what is the here-and-now sensible?

Conflict and Agonism as an Inadmissible – and Planning The aim of the war of position is to be able to constitute hegemony within proper planning politics. In fact, it seems to be a war on how to get a position. The difference is here to be seen, not as something to be excluded, governed, or mastered, but a thread of becoming different kinds of ‘desires’ (for profit, ‘good life’, investment, community, etc.). Public planning is a social situation, where participants are involved in a legitimacy play that involves the war on position. Politics and hegemony, however, always end up by ‘compromising their [people’s] autonomy’ (Honig 2007: 5). If you do not accept the ‘shared symbolic space’, you are not allowed a position. Injustice, deception and defeat haunt any democracy and its communicative and deliberative processes. The question is how to work with this coercive, power-ridden, subjugating reality, and simultaneously contest its permanence as decisions and a hegemonic institutionalisation. If planning theory has a one-sided attention to agonism as a form of institutionalisation, this might be caused by following Chantal Mouffe instead of Rancière or Foucault. Mouffe makes agonism a matter of power (hegemony, war of position) and the making of collective identities arising from the shared symbolic space of common understandings and interests. Foucault says the agonism between power and freedom – it is always about this relation – is where we have ‘the permanent political task inherent in all social existence’ (1986: 223). We should, Foucault says, focus on politics as a ‘system of differentiation which permits one to act upon the actions of others’; as ‘types of objectives pursued by those who act’; as ‘the means of bringing power relations into being’ (how is power exercised, by which effects and means); as ‘forms of institutionalization’ (legal structures, etc.); and as ‘the degrees of rationalization; the bringing into play of power relations as action in a field of possibilities’ (p. 223). Mouffe’s war of position and hegemony will rely on such modes of institutionalised powermechanisms, and such institutions work against Foucault’s agonism as ‘the recalcitrance of the will and the intransigence of freedom’ (Foucault 1986: 221–222). Foucault’s lecture emphasises that power is not interesting in itself (1986: 217), it is power as ‘a part of our experience’ that should interest us (p. 209). Mouffe and Foucault have an inherent assumption about selves and interests as not being fixed, but rather always porous and exposed to processes and forces. The strife within politics and planning is a strife between ever-changing positions and cannot build on fixed identities. Thus, politics and planning need to discover how to keep differences and irreducible disagreements alive facing a system of apparatus and public processes framed by closure and exclusionary decisions. Hillier (2002: 261) suggests seeing agonistic democracy as ‘a contestation of multiple representations and interpretations through which identities and positions are formed’, and planning might be able to work and respect strife by being a ‘strategic navigation’ part of a ‘multiplanar 272

Conflict and Agonism

planning’ (Hillier 2007). Strategic navigation is ‘a conversation that weaves between specific episodes or events and local or micro stories, the networks and coalitions, assemblages and agancements of governance processes and the macro of governance cultures’ (Hillier 2011: 518). Hillier, however, leaves out the question about the institutionalisation of decisions and legitimacy Mouffe defends in her ‘war’ for hegemonic positions.

Outlook – Agonism and Futures? Many cities and planning institutions are responding to the publicly claimed democratic deficit and they try to interact otherwise with a more diverse public (e.g. by making pre-plan workshops). Cities now try to find more dynamic ways to include people and interests in urban design and development. ‘Urban gardening’ and ‘temporary space’ strategies are but two examples. ‘Tactical urbanism’ is a third, and they are an attempt to make planning more iterative and flexible. In the US some have suggested looking at urban planning as a ‘series of phases’ over, for example, 15 years, where each small project might add up to be a comprehensive plan. At least it allows for ‘cheap’ experiments that might pave the way or give new ideas (Grego 2012). The main challenge however, if we follow Rancière and Foucault, is how planning can keep agonism and strife alive. How can planning institutions work productively with contest and the inadmissible? Planning not only has to work with its institutionalism and mode of conversation, but in particular its mode of procedural decisions. To make contest and strife productive, planning might need a ‘wandering planner’ that ‘botanises’ streets and places (to paraphrase Walter Benjamin); that is, a planner that listens to and knows the ‘street voice’. It needs a planner that is allowed to work with agonism as a discussant within people’s everyday lives and as an ‘editorial’ organiser of dialogues on everyday life questions, sense of place, aesthetics, design, art, feelings, and desires contesting planning (see Haggärde 2008, Hillier 2007, Nyseth et al. 2010). To allow for an agonistic war of position, planning might need a system that sees any political and planning decision as a ‘temporary resting place’ (Healey 2009), acknowledging that planning is acting in a pluriverse world of changing configurations and constellations of forces that will affect development, everyday life, values, economy, culture and social conditions on a microscale. A planning inclusive of strife needs to be allowed to make a non-excluding ‘strategic navigation’, and give a robustness to plans from planners’ capacity and readiness to work with(in) the ever-changing and emergent forces of place development.

Acknowledgements Thanks to Ali Madanipour, Vanessa Watson and Michael Gunder for their constructive comments, and Jean Hillier for her critique on several drafts, advice and inspiration.

Notes 1 There are many planning systems around the world and any attempt to make generalisations will fail. Further, an introduction is always based on a selection of themes and sources, and there are many more interesting studies on conflict and agonism available within planning studies than are shown in this chapter. 2 See for instance Flyvbjerg (1991), Healey (2006), Hillier (2002) and Huxley (2007).The chapter is speaking from a global north perspective. 3 Disagreement leads to a political decision (Mäntysalo et al. 2011b). In the UK disagreement is met with public inquiries – between inspectors, the public, private interests and ‘specialists’ (if needed) – for a process of negotiation (McClymont 2011). Decisions are made by the inspector.

273

John Pløger 4 By ‘sire’ Heidegger is referring to ‘the father’ that ‘allows’ and ‘preserves’ the positions within a confrontation (as free, slave, human). 5 Mouffe is here referring to Jean François Lyotard’s ‘le Differend’, which refers to ‘the unstable mode’ when something that should be put into words or sentences cannot be (Lyotard 1990: 147). 6 In Louis Althusser’s understanding of apparatus: diverse and specialised institutions that ‘serve’ the state within the state apparatus (e.g. government offices, courts) as well as in ‘civil society’ (e.g. schools) (see Althusser 1983). 7 Gramsci was not talking about a peaceful war of position, but using the military word ‘war’ as a metaphor for an ‘interventionist government’ taking an offensive role ‘against the oppositionists and [to] organise permanently the “impossibility” of internal disintegration’ (Gramsci 1999: 495). It is not a matter of improving the position of weak voices in deliberation, but the power to govern by being in power.

References Althusser, Louis (1983) Ideologi og ideologiske statsapparater (from: ‘Ideologie und ideologische Statsapparatet’), Aarhus, Grus Arbejdstekster. Althusser, Louis (2000) Machiavelli and Us, London, Verso. Bäcklund, Pia & Mäntysalo, Raine (2010) Agonism and Institutional Ambiguity: Ideas on Democracy and the Role of Participation in the Development of Planning Theory and Practice – the Case of Finland, Planning Theory, 9(4), 333–350. Barnett, Clive & Bridge, Gary (2013) Geographies of Radical Democracy: Agonistic Pragmatism and the Formation of Affected Interests, Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 103(4), 1022–1040. Bassett, Keith (2014) Rancière, Politics and the Occupy Movement, Environment & Planning D: Society and Space, 32, 886–901. Bond, Sophie (2011) Negotiating a ‘Democratic Ethos’: Moving Beyond the Agonistic-communicative Divide, Planning Theory, 10(2), 161–186. Egan, Daniel (2013) Rethinking War of Maneuver/War on Position: Gramsci and the Military Metaphor, Critical Sociology, 40(4), 521–538. Flyvbjerg, Bent (1991) Makt og rationalitet (Power and Rationality), Copenhagen, Akademisk Forlag. Forester, John (1989) Planning in the Face of Power, Berkeley, University of California Press. Foucault, Michel (1986) The Foucault Reader, New York, Peregrine. Foucault, Michel (2010) The Government of Self and Others: Lectures on the Collège de France 1982–1983, London, Palgrave MacMillan. Gramsci, Antonio (1999) Selections from Prison Notebooks, London, ElecBook. Grego, JoAnn (2012) From Pop-Up to Permanent: Small, Nimble Projects Are Adding Value to Public Spaces, Planning, 1–4. Haggärde, Magdalena et al. (2008) Öppenhet och experiment (Openness and experiment), Conference paper ‘Architectural Inquiries’, Göteborg, 1–20. Hatap, Lawrence J. (2002) Prospects for a Democratic Agon: Why We Can Still Be Nietzscheans, Journal of Nietzsche Studies, 24, 132–147. Healey, Patsy (2006) Urban Complexity and Spatial Strategies: Towards a Relational Planning for Our Times, London, Routledge. Healey, Patsy (2009) The Pragmatic Tradition in Planning Theory, Journal of Planning Education & Research, 28(2), 277–292. Heidegger, Martin (2014) Introduction to Metaphysics (second edition), New Haven, CT & London, Yale University Press. Hillier, Jean (2002) Shadows of Power: An Allegory of Prudence in Land-Use Planning, London, Routledge. Hillier, Jean (2007) Stretching Beyond the Horizon: A Multiplanar Theory of Spatial Planning and Governance, Aldershot, Ashgate. Hillier, Jean (2011) Strategic Navigation across Multiple Planes: Towards a Deleuzian-inspired Methodology for Strategic Spatial Planning, TRP, 82(5), 503–527. Honig, Bonnie (2007) Between Decision and Deliberation: Political Paradox in Democratic Theory, American Political Science Review, 101(1), 1–17. Huxley, Margo (2007) Geographies of Governmentality, in Jeremy W. Crampton & Stuart Elden (eds), Space, Knowledge and Power: Foucault and Geography, London, Ashgate, 185–204. Innes, Judith & Booher, David E. (2010) Planning with Complexity: An Introduction to Collaborative Rationality for Public Policy, London, Routledge.

274

Conflict and Agonism Innes, Judith and Booher, David E. (2014) A Turning Point for Planning Theory? Overcoming Dividing Discourses, Planning Theory, 14(2), 195–213. Laws, David and Forester, John (2007) Learning in Practice: Public Policy Mediation, Critical Policy Studies, 1(4), 342–370. Lyotard, Jean François (1990) Det uartikulerede eller striden selv (The Unarticulated and the Strife Itself), in Niels Brügger (ed.), Lyotard og striden: Læsninger af le Differend (Lyotard and the Strife: Readings of Le differend), Aarhus, Slagmarks Skyttegravsserie, 147–160. Mäntysalo, Raine, Balducci, Alessandro & Kangasoja, Jonna (2011a) Planning as Agonistic Communication in a Trading Zone: Re-Examining Lindblom’s Partisan Mutual Adjustment, Planning Theory, 10(3), 257–272. Mäntysalo, Raine, Saglie, Inger-Lise & Cars, Göran (2011b) Between Input Legitimacy and Output Efficiency: Defensive Routines and Agonistic Reflectivity in Nordic Land-Use Planning, European Planning Studies, 19(12), pp. 2109–2126. McClymont, Claire (2011) Revitalising the Political: Development Control and Agonism in Planning Practice, Planning Theory, 10(3), 239–256. Milchman, Alan & Rosenberg, Alan (2003) Towards a Foucault/Heidegger Auseinandersetzung, in Alan Milchman & Alan Rosenberg (eds), Foucault and Heidegger: Critical Encounters, Contradiction Series, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1–29. Mouat, Clare, Legacy, Crystal & March, Alan (2013) The Problem Is the Solution: Testing Agonistic Theory’s Potential to Recast Intractable Planning Disputes, Urban Policy and Research, 31(2), 150–163. Mouffe, Chantal (1997) Deconstruction and Pragmatism, London, Routledge. Mouffe, Chantal (2000) The Democratic Paradox, London, Verso. Mouffe, Chantal (2005) On the Political, London, Routledge. Mouffe, Chantal (2013) Agonistics: Thinking the World Politically, London, Verso. Mouffe, Chantal (2014) By Way of a Postscript, parallax, 20(2), 149–157. Nietzsche, Friedrich (1967) The Will to Power, New York, A Vintage Giant. Nyseth, Torill, Pløger, John & Holm, Trine (2010) Planning beyond the Horizon: The Tromsø experiment, Planning Theory, 9(3), 223–247. Pløger, John (2014) Impossible Common Ground: Planning and Reconciliation, in Jonathan Metzger, Phil Allmendinger & Stijn Oosterlynck (eds), Planning Against the Political: Democratic Deficits in European Territorial Governance, London, Routledge, 107–128. Rancière, Jacques (2000) Dissenting Words: A Conversation with Jacques Rancière (by David Panagia), Diacritics, 30(2), 113–126. Rancière, Jacques (2006) The Politics of Aesthetics, London, Continuum. Rancière, Jacques (2010) Dissensus: On Politics and Aesthetics, London, Continuum. Rancière, Jacques (2011a) The Thinking of Dissensus: Politics and Aesthetics, in Paul Bowan & Richard Stamp (eds), Critical Dissensus: Reading Rancière, London, Continuum, 1–17. Rancière, Jacques (2011b) Against the Ebbing Tide: An Interview with Jacques Rancière, in Paul Bowan & Richard Stamp (eds), Critical Dissensus: Reading Rancière, London, Continuum, 238–251. Sandercock, Leonie (2003) Cosmopolis II: Mongrel Cities in the 21st Century, London, Continuum. Van Leeuwen, Bart (2014) Absorbing the Agony of Agonism? The Limits of Cultural Questioning and Alternative Variations of Intercultural Civility, Urban Studies, 1–16 (DOI: 10.1177/0042098014528548).

275

22 INSURGENT PRACTICES AND DECOLONIZATION OF FUTURE(S) Faranak Miraftab

This chapter further elaborates the concept of insurgent planning (IP) and why it needs to be taken seriously in planning education, scholarship, and practice. Without strong conceptual elaboration, ideas can be easily dismissed as fanciful or become buzzwords that fail to engage deeply with transformative practices and actions. I therefore build this chapter on three sections. The first section describes the crises and social contradictions of the late 20th and early 21st centuries and the implications of the resulting political and ideological shifts for planning. This supposedly post-political era, which has exposed the liberal democratic promises of inclusion and equity, places citizens’ insurgent practices high on the political and intellectual agendas. I discuss the political philosophies that drive liberal democratic and insurgent citizenship practices and argue that IP ontologically departs from liberal traditions of so-called inclusive planning that have held the inclusion of disadvantaged groups as an objective of professional intervention. The second section takes a closer look at the range of citizens’ direct actions and conceptualizes them through the analytic devices I offer as invited and invented spaces of citizenship. I discuss the potential flexibility of these forms of action and dispel a binary misconception of invited versus invented spaces for citizens’ direct action; instead, I focus on the theoretical construct of IP as practices that are transgressive, counter-hegemonic, and imaginative. In the third section, inspired by anticolonial scholars and activists of liberation, I discuss the urgency in decolonizing the future as a realm of political contestation and imagination. I conclude the chapter by stressing the opportunities ahead as the crisis of capitalism leads to aggressive shutdowns of democratic spaces and citizens innovate strategies and practices to invent new spaces of action. IP is not a set of blueprints for action but a conceptual and normative construct to guide planning thought and action that promotes humane urbanism into the future.

Insurgent Planning: An Ontological Break with Liberal Inclusive Planning The planning profession as institutionalized in the West has traditionally served to mediate state relations with citizens and the market. Conditions that have reconfigured the state’s relationship with citizens and the market have placed the idea and the practice of insurgent citizenship high on the political agenda; those same conditions have also had important implications for planning thought and theorization. 276

Insurgent Practices, Decolonized Future(s)

The end of the Cold War, which removed the threat of the socialist bloc to the West, unleashed a domination of free market economy that has resulted in seismic shifts of the political terrain and has also produced significant recalibrations in planning theorization and practice. With the fall of the Berlin Wall, some commentators claimed to see the end of ideological war between the capitalist and socialist blocs—and therefore “the end of history” (Fukuyama 1992) and “the end of politics.” The subsequent hegemony of free market capitalism and global restructuring of the capitalist state in this era have dramatically reconfigured the relationship between the state and its citizens. When all political struggles and tensions are subsumed under the free will and reach of the capitalist market, everything is privatized—from nature to public services and public resources, and even the government and state (Watts 1994)—and the capitalist state no longer defines its role in mediation between labor and capital through provision of basic needs and development, but primarily in protection of optimal market functioning for capital. These shifts in the broader political dynamics of state vis-à-vis citizens and market invite us to reflect on how the planning profession has redefined itself and its obligations with respect to the public good. In the 1950s and 60s, the capitalist state relied on developmental and welfare programs, and public planning saw its role as serving public good through a scientific managerial approach that claimed to find the best solution to problems that politicians defined. Planning as “problem solving, not problem framing” was the mantra of the time (McLoughlin 1969; Faludi 1973). In the 1960s and 70s, with the rise of social movements demanding inclusion, the planning profession was also politicized. Planning’s professional role in addressing the public good was to frame social problems and secure the inclusion of the most vulnerable citizens in the state’s developmental and welfare programs. Advocacy planning and equity planning, originated by US planning practitioners and scholars, are outcomes of this era when state welfare programs were still in effect and progressive planners saw their role as helping vulnerable citizens win a fair share of these public goods (Hillier and Healey 2008). But with the increasingly diminishing responsibilities of the state vis-à-vis citizens since then, the intermediary role of planning professionals was redefined from a redistributive, political role to a facilitating role, which is managerial and de-politicized. Communicative planning and collaborative planning, for instance, which have dominated planning theorization, scholars argue, epitomize this post-political society in which all is de-politicized and “ideology is past its ‘sell-by date’” (Gunder 2010, 303, citing Habermas 1987, 196; Purcell 2009; Sager 2005). In this post-ideological neoliberal reign of the free market, professional planning practice has boomeranged to its original managerial role— one that believed in equilibrium. While the earlier genre of planning professionals believed in reaching such equilibrium through scientific system analysis, this new genre—communicative and collaborative planning—believes that an equilibrium among competing interests can be reached through communication and ideal speech: in other words, if we find the right pitch, the right keynote, we can all sing in harmony. Moreover, decades of professional planning practice that advocates inclusion through participation have shown that its conception within liberal ideals obscures, and at best is unable to address, complex layers of conflict, oppressive power, and imposition. A liberal notion of inclusion might recognize difference and call for citizen participation, but this inclusion is in ways that do not challenge power but merely incorporate differences. Scholars document that inclusive planning through citizen participation has, indeed, often served as an alibi for elitist, private-sector-driven decisions, or as cheap compensation for state withdrawal from public and social services (Angotti 2008; DeFilippis 2001; Mayer 2003; Miraftab 2003; Harwood 2007). At this historical juncture of neoliberalism, where formal politics of inclusion is an alibi for exclusion and normalization of neocolonial domination, the bankruptcy of liberal inclusive planning urges us to rethink the epistemological and ontological parameters of planning 277

Faranak Miraftab

theorization and practice. Planning theorization needs to make an ontological and epistemological break with the ideas, ideals, and political philosophies that guided it through much of the 20th century. IP, I argue, pursues such ontological and epistemological breaks in our contemporary conjuncture. IP builds on an earlier radical tradition in planning theory that recognized the practices of citizens and local communities as forms of planning. This theoretical intervention, initiated by Friedmann in the 1980s, reflected on citizens’ struggles in the global South cities and was continued by Sandercock’s work in the 1990s reflecting on realities of North American cities. Barrio planning (Friedmann 1987) and covert planning (Beard 2002) reflected predominantly on grassroots practices in the global South, taking seriously the practices of subordinate groups in shaping the plans, policies, and spaces. In the global South, where, among other historical conditions, the state has had less ability to cover up capitalist contradictions through its welfare programs, citizens hold fewer illusions about the state’s benevolence and have had determining insurrectional urban interventions outside the state apparatus of inclusion. Radical planning in its epistemic shift paid attention to the fact that residents of squatter settlements, favelas, and townships make their own living space and livelihoods not because of, but often despite, the state’s institutions, planning regulations, and laws. From this perspective, the informal settlements that mark urban landscapes of most cities of the global South provide material, spatial evidence of citizens’ insurgencies and direct action to plan and address their livelihood (Holston 1998). Drawing on Holston’s concept of insurgent citizenship (1998) and Young’s “politics of difference” (1990), Sandercock (1998a, 1998b) articulated the notion of insurgent historiographies and IP to reflect on dynamics of power and production of urban space in increasingly multicultural North American cities. In dealing with recognition of difference, Sandercock furthers the earlier epistemological shift in radical planning by moving away from professioncentered liberal North American traditions of inclusive planning, and recognizing the practices of citizens and local communities as forms of planning—IP. Today urban political insurgencies have gained traction in theorizing insurgent practices as forms of planning (Stello 2012; Meir 2005; Meth 2010; Sweet and Chakars 2010; Harvey 1999; Friedmann 2002, 2011; Sandercock 1998b; Roy 2009). This in part reflects the unprecedented rise of citizens’ direct action in Western European and North American cities, which are now experiencing the neoliberal unsettling of welfare capitalism and joining the rest of the world in takeovers of urban space (Occupy movements). But the growing attention to citizens’ insurgent practices and the urge to think through them in respect to planning also reflects the crisis of legitimacy the profession faces in its inability to deliver on the promise of inclusion and service to public good through a framework of inclusive representation. Planning theory, along with planning education and practice, has had to deal with key questions of this century with respect to difference and justice, where citizens reimagine and practice different kinds of democracies, ideals, and citizenship. IP builds on the epistemological contribution of the radical planning approach to make a move that I argue is ontological—that is, it shifts the understanding of justice from a liberal Rawlsian notion of justice as fairness to a Youngian notion of justice based on recognition of difference and its politics. Rawlsian theory seeks justice in terms of individualized rights and fair treatment. Young’s notion highlights the limitation of liberal policies of inclusion that might satisfy beneficiaries’ rights as individuals yet, through stigma, oppress them as a group (1990). This philosophy insists on recognizing self-determined and group-based forms of oppression in reaching justice. Such an understanding of justice changes the terms of debate about inclusion from representation to self-determination—a shift that validates citizens’ direct action and has substantial implications for planning. In representative democracy, citizens as individuals 278

Insurgent Practices, Decolonized Future(s)

delegate their rights to others—political representatives, bureaucrats, or technical experts. In contrast, in participatory democracy disadvantaged and marginalized citizens who recognize the inadequacy of formal rights turn to direct action to achieve justice. They do not hand the advocacy of their interests to others but instead directly take part in shaping decisions that affect their lives. Participatory democracy consequently promotes a form of citizenship that is multicentered and has multiple agencies, including the citizens and their direct social actions. As IP de-centers the role of representation and relies on direct action as a means of inclusion, a shift in the subject of its theorization is also noteworthy. In previous variations of inclusive planning, the subjects of theorization are professional planners and their professionalized practices. For example, in advocacy and equity planning, the planners’ role is to advocate for citizens, speak in the face of power, and get the best deal on behalf of the citizens. In communicative planning, the professional planner is responsible for bringing all parties to a consensus through ideal speech. In that theoretical framework, planning is conceptualized as a realm outside the community, and its agent is the professional planner. The core concern is with how this “outsider” (the planner) needs to redefine his/her role and responsibility vis-à-vis the disadvantaged community. In IP, however, planning is no longer the prerogative of professionals or trained planners. Professional planners are but one of the actors that shape the contested field of action known as planning. In the conceptual architecture of IP, the core concern is therefore a set of practices independent of their actors: the theoretical object shifts from planner to planning. The discussion is not about insurgent planners as a category, nor do we expect actors to adhere to a specific category of practice. Insurgent practices ontologically break with liberal inclusive planning because IP calls for a different kind of participation and inclusion. It does not aim for a bigger share of the pie but for a different kind of pie. It does not seek inclusion in liberal democracy through better representation (be it by experts or politicians); it seeks to create a humane urbanism wherein people’s rights are real and practiced. Moreover, while building on the earlier critical tradition of radical planning, IP expands the notion of planning practice to include not only select forms of action by citizens and their organizations sanctioned and tolerated by the dominant groups, what I call invited1 spaces of action, but also the insurrections that state and corporation seek to ostracize and criminalize—what I call invented spaces of action. IP makes an ontological intervention in understanding the relationship between planning and citizens; I will expand on this in the following section. To summarize, the ontology of IP departs from that of its predecessors, which were guided by the assumption that representative democracy works in the best interests of all with citizenship rights, including disadvantaged groups. To the contrary, IP is guided by the principles of participatory democracy—that is, understanding citizenship as a practice constructed from below through citizens’ direct action for the development of their self-determined political community. This difference does not, however, position insurgent and inclusive planning as binaries: they are ontologically different but have a dialectic relationship. Just as participatory and representative democracy dialectically influence each other, IP and inclusive planning can do the same, so untangling them conceptually is crucial while engaging in the complex terrain of planning today.

A Theoretical Elaboration: Invited and Invented Spaces of Action and Misconceptions about Them Because concepts of invited and invented spaces of citizens’ action are critical to my approach in theorizing IP, I first offer a brief definition. Over a decade ago, reflecting on grassroots movements in black townships of post-apartheid South Africa, I conceptualized their actions 279

Faranak Miraftab

in these terms: invited spaces are defined by grassroots actions through community-based informal groups and their allied nongovernmental organizations that are legitimized by donors and government interventions and aim to cope with systems of hardship. Invented spaces I defined as collective actions by the poor that directly confront the authorities and challenge and destabilize the status quo. These two sorts of spaces, however, can stand in a mutually constituted, interacting relationship, not a binary one. They are not solidified, and they change character as dominating groups seek to appropriate them whenever a threat is posed. On-the-ground evidence also shows that grassroots practices that seek to make structural changes in power relations often move across invited and invented spaces of action. If they are to reach more than individualized needs (the goal of liberal inclusion), they often have to move across and between those spaces as called for by specifics of the struggle. Insurgent practices are fluid, moving across all spaces of participation and engaging both the formal and informal arenas of politics; they aim to combine the struggles for redistribution and recognition, echoing Nancy Fraser’s (1997) theorizations. But institutions of power, such as the mainstream media, the state, and international donor organizations, configure these invited and invented spaces as binary, and tend to criminalize the latter by designating only the former as the “proper” space for citizens’ voices and participation. The authorities tend to vilify and criminalize one set of actions and celebrate another because they try to steer citizens to a certain model of activism and to contain them within a space of activism that can be more easily controlled. Svirsky (2010, 5), quoting Buchanan, points out that “from conformity it is but a short step to complicity” (Buchanan 2000, 75), because activism that “treads established paths of dissent is always in danger of being besieged and contained by the organism of the State.” Radical activists therefore need to shift strategies and create new spaces through “practices of rupture and creation” (2010, 5). “Activisms that seek only to guarantee the workings of representative democracy,” Svirsky writes, “are essentially slave activisms; they dwell in safety and their impact and potential is expected to be absorbed without drawing the system into new structures of resonance” (2010, 3). This kind of slave activism is what de-politicized planning theorization has celebrated and popularized as participatory planning, citizen participation, and grassroots involvement. IP breaks away from this mode of thinking in radical ways. It defies confinement and conformance of citizens’ actions to liberal state and market norms, but also recognizes how citizens might use those norms to induce a rupture and create something new. In the recent South African student movement against raising university tuition, for example, Julian Brown (2015) points out how the South African police would beat up students when claims were made through protests (invented spaces), but also invite them to dialogues between the administration and students’ leaders (invited space). For the authorities, binary construction is an effective means of weakening progressive movements, but insurgent activists recognize the fallacy of binary constructions and use all available means and spaces to make their demands heard and addressed. In this instance, the invited space itself was politicized by activists when they failed to produce “a set of leaders” to negotiate with authorities. The politics of containment works through introducing a range of binaries—invited versus invented, leaders versus masses—so as to identify and subdue projects of grassroots autonomy. On the other hand, the insurgent student movement—precisely because it shifts attention from actors to practices—evaded this construction by creating an ambiguous liminal space within which authorities lose their points of reference (Irazabal 2014). For authorities the question was how to double down with the force of law to make these spaces, times, and bodies legally legible. For insurgent citizens, the question is how to sustain this illegible threshold long enough to frustrate and suffocate existing modalities of law, state power, and capital accumulation. 280

Insurgent Practices, Decolonized Future(s)

Invited and invented spaces of citizenship practice should be thought of as spaces with “porous borders,” borrowing from Steven Robins’ (2014) reflection on the Toilet Wars waged by the poor in Cape Town townships over the last few years. In that struggle, citizens used a range of actions and strategies, some criminalized by the state (e.g., the Ses’khona movement’s throwing of poop at the Cape Town international airport terminal) and others tolerated by the state (e.g., the Social Justice Coalition [SJC] documenting lack of toilets and authorities’ false promises). Whereas the sanitized terminology of formal politics such as “service delivery backlog” obscured their plight and the urgency of their demands, “poop protestors” used abrupt acts of insurgency to create spectacle and shock that moved the problem of defecation and lack of toilets to the center of political debate—indeed it became top of the agenda in an electoral campaign. But “politics of shit,” or “poolitics” as McFarlane and Silver (2016) call it, as practiced by activist citizens was not limited to acts of sabotage or insurgency, such as throwing poop at the mayor’s house or lining up by the hundreds to use toilets in plush suburbs and outside City Hall. They drew on a rich repertoire of grassroots action which also includes practices of organizations like the SJC that predominantly concern remuneration and auditing using the language and perspective of the state (McFarlane and Silver 2016). We should note that a binary construction of these practices taking place through invited and invented spaces risks an embedded misconception of stability in each space. It disregards the flexibility and innovative nature of capitalism, which folds in whatever lies at its margin and seeks to incorporate whatever might be a threat. What is today an alternative, or radical, might become mainstreamed and de-politicized by containment and entrapment tomorrow, with its transformative force hollowed out—leaving activists holding “a toy telephone with no lines that reach anywhere,” a metaphor used by my colleague Ken Salo for such stolen movements. Movements thus need to continually reinvent their spaces of action. Similarly, movements can appropriate a space that has been created by the establishment to contain the creative actions of dissent and use it to invoke new imaginations of inclusion. Neoliberal inclusion wants to contain the grassroots actions in invited spaces where their demands are controlled and appropriated, but insurgent practices seek to push these limits by occupying those and other spaces. These transgressions are necessary particularly because of capitalism’s ability to occupy the alternative imaginations and spaces of being and action. In fact, the power of insurgent practices lies in their agility and ability to transgress and destabilize hegemonic normality and open up new political terrains for the imagination of a different future. To use the Deleuze and Guattari (1980) concept of nomadized politics that are agile, insurgent movements must constantly reinvent and innovate new spaces as the oppressive state appropriates whatever lies outside it. Clearly, citizens’ successful political action requires agility. There can be no rigid joining of actors to actions. The point to reiterate here is that the theorizing objects of IP are practices, not the actors. The point is not to label a particular actor, or a particular organization or movement, but to take into account the range of actions that move toward a particular outcome—a more just and humane urbanism. But skeptics raise important questions: How do we recognize insurgent practices that contribute to building a participative democracy and create the foundation on which to develop humane urbanism? Is every act of insurrection and interruption progressive in that it seeks a participative democracy, or could it be anti-democratic, reactionary, or even fascist? Moreover, do insurgent practices necessarily need to be in the form of insurrections, riots, and loud protests? The answers are embedded in what we have so far discussed, but, to clarify, the response is negative on both counts. Not all insurgency is theorized here as the democratic insurgent practice of citizenship; not all invented spaces of activism, nor all forms of insurgency by poor and disadvantaged groups, are celebrated in this theoretical endeavor. Moreover, far from a unifying 281

Faranak Miraftab

form of action, invented spaces can take as many forms as their context calls for, be it loud and collective protest or quiet and under-the-radar politics of encroachment. What determines radical practices and their promise for a humane urbanism is a set of conceptual guideposts that I have discussed at length elsewhere: transgression (in time, place, and forms of action), counter-hegemony, and imagination (Miraftab 2009). These practices transgress false dichotomies, by public actions spanning formal and informal arenas of politics and invited and invented spaces of citizenship practice. They also transgress national boundaries by building transnational solidarities of marginalized people and move beyond time bounds by seeking a historicized consciousness and promoting historical memory of present experiences (Salo 2015). IP practices are counter-hegemonic in that they destabilize normalized relations of dominance and insist on citizens’ rights to dissent, rebel, and determine their own terms of engagement and participation. IP practices seize advantage from the contradictory nature of neoliberal capitalism, exposing the rift between inclusion and redistribution. They understand the world of such contradictions contrapuntally, looking not only at how systems of oppression are conceptualized and exerted, but also at how they are contested. IP practices are imaginative. They recover idealism for a just society. Insurgent practices recognize the symbolic value of insurgent citizenship activities that offer hope from which to work toward alternatives. In short, IP consists of purposeful transgressive actions that aim to disrupt relationships with oppressors, and to destabilize the status quo through consciousness of the past and imagination of an alternative just future. Understood against these principles, not all acts of insurgency or invented spaces of activism outside the normalized, routinized spaces of citizen participation have an anti-hegemonic agenda. Nor do all counter-hegemonic practices need to be through confrontation, insurrection, or collective protest. Let’s take those on the far right of the political party spectrum, such as Tea Party insurgency in the United States or the poor people’s protests against African migrants in South Africa.2 In the latter case, xenophobic attacks in 2015 reinforced the interest of the black entrepreneurs in Durban, who, subsequent to the attacks, used the riots to funnel funds their way and enrich themselves, increasing the gap between the haves and have-nots.3 It would be a grave mistake, therefore, to assume that any insurgency by the poor is an insurgent practice—which we theorize here as radical planning and ontologically shifting planning discourse beyond the limits of liberal democratic inclusion. Paula Meth (2010), studying a vigilante group in Durban, offers another example that poignantly reminds us of the complexity and social thickness of the grassroots actions and warns against idealizing those as necessarily progressive. While in some regards they might promote a just cause, they might also adhere to violence, sexism, or racism. The vigilantes Meth studies are engaged in practices that are both liberating and oppressive, and we cannot flatten the complexities of grassroots movements and their practices; we have to see these practices in relation to their overarching dimensions. First, we need to remember that in theorizing the relationship between citizens and planning through an IP framework, the focus is on practices, not actors. Actors—e.g., vigilantes or social movement activists or organizations—might adopt practices that are progressive and transformative at one point, but they might be coopted or misled into taking part in practices that are oppressive at another point (or even at the same time). I therefore insist on terminologies that do not rigidly link spaces of action we conceptualize as invited and invented to a particular actor, movement, or organization—hence insurgent planning, not planner. Moreover, the form of action, whether it is a “quiet encroachment” under the radar or an act of insurrection and “loud takeovers,” does not determine the political potential of the action for broader social transformation. It is important to inquire into the historical and transnational consciousness as well as the organizational matrix and strategic arc within which insurgent practices are nested. If citizens’ practices 282

Insurgent Practices, Decolonized Future(s)

contribute to the fulfillment of a broader strategy of capital and colonialism, they are merely episodes of reactionary tactics—regardless of their loudness or quietness. To wrap up, whoever the actors (be it professional planners, activists, or regular citizens) and whatever the specific form of an action, particular practices can be identifiable as IP practices if they are guided by certain principles that I articulate as follows: transgression; destabilizing hegemonic order; and imaginative of an alternative and just future. In evaluating any set of citizen practices, we need to ask how they temporally and spatially historicize their struggles that might lead or draw on transnational solidarities; how they engage in counter- or anti-hegemonic practices; and how they evoke an alternative, just future—a key principle to which I now turn.

Imagination and the Urgency in Decolonizing the Future The writings of African intellectuals teach us that liberation of the colonies could happen only through “decolonizing the mind” (Fanon 1986 [1967]) and liberating imagination. Liberation needs a new consciousness, one that is recovered from the colonial moral injury, the profound alienation that believed development of the colony could happen only “upon condition of rejecting itself” and wholesale importing of non-African scenarios and solutions (Davidson 1992, 199). Anticolonial scholars and activists of liberation expose means of domination beyond direct use of brute force, and how tropes of inclusion can be used to subordinate groups. Domination can work through internalized values and voices of the dominant groups—a condition that colonizes our imagination and validates only the knowledge of the West and the forms of knowing and being under Western eyes, to borrow from Mohanty (1991). In planning, the colonial gaze, to evoke Fanon, is the only contemplation that matters in how we theorize planning and see the outcome of plans as human habitats. I move slowly in the world, accustomed now to seek no longer for upheaval. I progress by crawling … under the white eyes, the only real eyes. I am fixed. Having adjusted their microtomes, they objectively cut away slices of my reality. I am laid bare. (Fanon 1995, 292) African cities, for example, are dissected, critics remind us, under Western eyes as incomplete, crawling, and not causing upheaval because they have not yet become like the superior models they are expected to become; they are invisible to the colonial gaze (De Boeck and Pilssart 2004; Watson 2006, 2009; Simone 2004). In this normalized relation of power, inclusion means erasure of difference and incorporation of subordinate groups into the norms, values, and ideals of the dominant group. For planning in this era, decolonizing planning imagination is by questioning the very assumptions, norms, values, and ideals that shape every plan and policy—for example, that plans and policies must insist on economic growth, or that planning models developed and implemented in the West are models to be emulated. Echoing Steve Biko (1978), I assert the need for a new consciousness that liberates planning imaginations. The elitist and consumerist planning ideals persist in our post/neocolonial, neoliberal time, through suppression of any alternative conceptualization of cities and of planning. IP scholarship aims at decolonizing the planning imagination by taking a fresh look at subaltern cities to understand them by their own rules and values rather than by the planning prescriptions and fantasies of the global and local elite. History and future are intense sites of struggle and contestation. Concerning power and history, the struggle is between forgetting and remembering, as Kundera (1999) calls it; and concerning the future, the struggle is in imagining. Future is the political terrain of the core 283

Faranak Miraftab

struggle this generation faces over opening and closing the realm of possibilities—that is, the struggle between expanding the realm of imagination and closing it down. The future is inevitable. It is open and it is plural (Pieterse 2000, 6). People need it like they need air, writes Pieterse (2000, xxi). But the future is also empty, meaning that what it constitutes depends on how it is imagined, susceptible to be reinvented and be “opened by a horizon of possibilities” (Santos 1995, 479). Because of its openness and its multiplicity/plurality, the future should be understood as an object of dispute; should be thought of as open-ended collages with the power to create interruptions, involving sense of direction, playfulness, and pleasure at the same time (Santos 1995, 499). But the open-endedness, plurality, and unpredictability of the future also makes it a political territory, a site of fierce contestation over its content. If we do not dare to imagine the unimaginable, then the future is less open and more predetermined as persistence and perpetuation of the present. The concept of “colonization of future” is of key importance. In the first colonies land, natural resources, and slave labor were objects of wealth creation. In the 1980s Mies and her colleagues (1988) provocatively wrote about Women: The Last Colony. That is, Europeans’ global colonization had raped land that did not belong to them and which allowed their jump-start in wealth creation, and now colonization had turned to women and their cheaply obtained labor for more wealth creation. In that new international order, women’s bodies and labor were subjects of colonial accumulation. Today, however, I argue that it is the imagination that must be invoked as the last colony—imagination as a political territory, a “territory” to be “occupied” to secure closure through totalitarian imaginations and through erasure of alternative imagined futures. The latest subject of “colonial occupation,” then, is the ability to imagine a different future, and the struggle for its emancipation is urgent. The struggle between past, present, and future is inevitable, ongoing, and nonlinear (Browne 2014). The emancipation of one without the others is not possible. It is from historicizing and understanding the past that we can understand the present struggles; it is by understanding our present struggles that we can imagine a future similar or different. But without an imagination of a future, we cannot change the present. We also need guidance to choose desirable future paths—a necessity that makes imagination of futures an intrinsically political exercise (Friedmann 2000, 463). Imagination of an alternative future requires a deep understanding of the present, what Santos (1995, 481) calls the virtual archaeology of the present. Archaeology of the present involves understanding the historical roots of contemporary realities. This understanding of the present has been a site of contestation against the production of a sanitized past that washes off the conflicts, contradictions, and power struggles that have shaped it. Harvey (2000, 168) notes this entanglement of past, present, and future through Benjamin’s (1969) observations of Parisian arcades. Benjamin observed how—through museums and heritage centers, exhibitions, arenas of spectacle, and festivals—a sanitized collective memory is produced, an uncritical aesthetic sensibility nourished, and the future possibilities absorbed into a supposedly conflict-free arena that is eternally present. Browne’s (2014) Feminism, Time, and Nonlinear History, in which she discusses polytemporal pasts and futures and relational temporalities, helps us better understand IP’s heralding of multiple futures. As opposed to Fukuyama’s argument for the end of history, which seeks to bring closure to the future, our citizens’ struggle is to overcome such closure and open the terrain of imagination to conceive of alternatives. The end of history as we know it is also the beginning of history as we want it. To open the realm of possibilities for an imagined ideal future, we need to seek practices, ideals, and ideas that allow us to overcome analytic and imaginative closures. Some might employ performative actions that evoke imagination of a different world—for example, the performative practices of Turkish youth in the 2013 Gezi Park struggles recreated the imagination of 284

Insurgent Practices, Decolonized Future(s)

an urban commons even if momentarily and temporarily (see Ay and Miraftab 2016). Others among new social movements might turn to science fiction for social justice movements and imagining a just world.4 Acts of insurgency that simply invoke such imagination can sometimes produce enduring gain in this struggle for future. The communal spaces that Occupy movements create, whether in Gezi Park or Madrid or New York, help us imagine a different world and, for the participants, even provide a short experience of living in a different world. Both the imagination and the experience are key to winning the struggle. This performative aspect of IP superimposes future(s) on the present, entwining multiple times. In short, politicization of imagination and the future as a terrain of struggle for justice is key if we are to plan for a world more just, and an urbanism more humane. The potential of insurgency for humane urbanism lies in the normality that it disrupts and the new common sense that it helps to create; in assuming equality and solidarity as normality interrupted by structures of domination, not the other way around;5 and in its aspiration to recover an idealist imagination of a different, more just future.

Conclusion: The Way Forward Moving into the future, the editors of the volume before us ask, “What are the implications for this theoretical construct of planning—insurgent planning?” I wish to first stress the understanding of IP not as a set of blueprints for action but as a conceptual and normative construct to guide planning thought and action to promote humane urbanism into the future. I next stress that, because we live in times of crises of both capitalism and of the planning profession, IP will have important contributions to make. The bottom line is that the capitalist state, and the experts that seek to maintain the status quo through liberal democratic inclusion, are facing the limitations of its promise. Planning as we know it is faced with a crisis of legitimacy, and the spatial injustices it facilitates are glaring evidence of “an emperor with no clothes.” We need a different kind of planning, and IP as a theoretical construct offers elements of that. The notion of IP expands planning from the prerogative of a selected group of professionals to a contested field of action by a range of actors, which includes professionals but also other organized individuals and communities deeply involved in shaping our human habitats and environments. This expanded notion of planning is more in tune with the reality of the 21st century, discussed earlier in the chapter, whereby the state’s welfare and development programs, of which planning professionals have traditionally been in charge, have increasingly diminished. Moreover, as the crisis of capitalism leads to aggressive shutdown of democratic spaces, citizens will innovate strategies and practices that invent new spaces of action and new means of shaping the spaces we inhabit. These innovative practices and invented spaces are not fixed; indeed, to survive threats of cooption or incorporation by dominant powers, they need to constantly shift with agility. They might move to “under-the-radar politics,” or create ambiguous spaces of action through performative acts, or opt for politics of agitation and protest. The point is not the specific forms of action, but the range of innovative practices guided by principles of transgression, counter-hegemony, and decolonized imagination discussed in this chapter, which promises to invent new spaces of action previously shut down by powerful interest groups that govern the cities and dominate human habitat. If we are to achieve a humane urbanism, professional planning must recognize these other critical actors and the important spaces of citizenship they innovate and invent, because their role and weight in bringing about change are even more important than in the previous century. Professional planning educators, practitioners, theorists, need to recognize the wide range of actors and actions undertaken to shape a city more humane. (A qualifier: I take city and urbanism as broad terms, by no means referring 285

Faranak Miraftab

to city as discrete territory binary to rural or other forms of human habitat.) In other words, in the global North in particular, as the illusion of inclusion through the formal and representative channels of inclusion wears off, citizens’ insurgent practices are taking center stage as means of shaping a new world, one that is more just and embodies a humane urbanism. What IP needs to develop, however, is greater imagination of what we want. It is easier to mobilize action around negating the present. As important as that is, it does not replace the need for what we wish to replace the present reality by. A greater understanding of the elements constitutive of humane urbanism is what we must develop as we mobilize to transgress and destabilize present hegemonies—hence the extended discussion in this essay on the importance of decolonizing the future and imagination of what that future entails. An important opportunity, and challenge, of progressive planning in this particular historic moment is to decolonize the imagined futures and dare to imagine a radically different world. In this age of “realism,” where ideals are looked down on and dreaming is stigmatized, the exercise of collective or individual imagination of a just world and what elements a humane urbanism embodies, are of prime radical value. For planning scholars, the frontier of anticolonial and anti-hegemonic struggle is indeed the fight to decolonize the planning imagination, in its theoretical construct as well as its pedagogy and practice. IP offers the theoretical guideposts for such an endeavor as we move into the future we wish to construct.

Notes 1 I borrow the term “invited spaces of citizenship” from Cornwall (2002, 50) to develop the notions of invited and invented spaces of citizenship. 2 In April 2014, I witnessed the unfortunate outbreak of violence against poor black African migrants in Cape Town, South Africa. These attacks, which started in Durban and spread to other South African cities, took place by and large in townships, informal settlements, and areas poor people inhabit.There were eight deaths and hundreds of injuries, and thousands of people were displaced, seeking refuge at police stations, churches, and temporary accommodation set up by NGOs. Attackers looted or burned small businesses owned by African foreign nationals, accusing them of “stealing jobs from citizens”—discourses too similar to those we hear about immigrants in the United States. 3 Riding on the anti-immigrant discourse of “foreigners steal our jobs” the KwaZulu-Natal government announced investment of over R300 million to assist local small businesses in competing with their foreign counterparts (Hans 2015). 4 For example, see Imarisha and Brown (2015). 5 See Purcell (2015), drawing on Rancière’s work.

References Angotti, T. 2008. New York for Sale: Community Planning Confronts Global Real Estate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Ay, D., and F. Miraftab. 2016. “Invented Spaces of Activism: Gezi Park and Performative Practices of Citizenship.” In The Handbook of International Development, edited by Daniel Hammett and Jean Grugel, 555–74. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan. Beard, V. A. 2002. “Covert Planning for Social Transformation in Indonesia.” Journal of Planning Education and Research 22 (1): 15–25. Benjamin, W. 1969. “Paris: Capital of the Nineteenth Century.” Perspecta 12: 165–172. Biko, S. 1978. Black Consciousness in South Africa. New York: Random House. Brown, J. 2015. “You Can’t Choose Your Interlocutors.” Business Day Live November 23. www.bdlive. co.za/opinion/2015/11/23/you-cant-choose-your-interlocutors (accessed May 14, 2017). Browne, V. 2014. Feminism, Time, and Nonlinear History. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. Buchanan, I. 2000. Deleuzism: A Metacommentary. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Cornwall, A. 2002. “Locating Citizen Participation.” IDS Bulletin 33 (2): 49–58. Davidson, B. 1992. The Black Man’s Burden: Africa and the Curse of the Nation-State. New York: Times Books.

286

Insurgent Practices, Decolonized Future(s) De Boeck, F., and M. F. Pilssart. 2004. Kinshasa: Tales of the Invisible City. Ghent: Ludion; Tervuren: Musée Royal de Afrique Centrale. DeFilippis, J. 2001. “The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development.” Housing Policy Debate 12 (4): 781–806. Deleuze, G., and F. Guattari. 1980. Mille plateaux (Capitalisme et schizophre). Vol. II. Paris: Minuit. Faludi, A. 1973. “The Rationale of Planning Theory.” In Planning Theory, 35–53. Oxford: Pergamon Press. Fanon, F. 1986. Black Skin, White Mask. London: Pluto Press. Fanon, F. 1995. “The Fact of Blackness.” In The Post-Colonial Studies Reader, edited by Bill Ashcroft, Gareth Griffiths, and Helen Tiffin, 291–4. New York: Routledge. Fraser, N. 2017. Justice Interruptus: Critical Reflections on the “Postsocialist” Condition. New York: Routledge. Friedmann, J. 1987. Planning in the Public Domain: From Knowledge to Action. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Friedmann, J. 2000. “The Good City, in Defense of Utopian Thinking.” International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 24 (2): 460–72. Friedmann, J. 2002. The Prospect of Cities. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Friedmann, J. 2011. Insurgencies: Essays in Planning Theory. New York: Routledge. Fukuyama, F. 1992. The End of History and the Last Man. New York: Free Press. Gunder, M. 2010. “Planning as the Ideology of (Neoliberal) Space.” Planning Theory 9 (4): 298–314. Habermas, J. 1987. The Theory of Communicative Action. Volume 1. Cambridge: Polity Press. Hans, B. 2015. “KZN Vows Aid for Locals amid Xenophobic Violence.” Business News April 16. www. iol.co.za/business/news/kzn-vows-aid-for-locals-amid-xenophobic-violence-1845871#comments_ start (accessed September 28, 2016). Harvey, D. 1999. “Frontiers of Insurgent Planning.” Plurimondi 1 (2): 269–86. Harvey, D. 2000. Spaces of Hope. Berkeley: University of California Press. Harwood, S. A. 2007. “Geographies of Opportunity for Whom? Neighborhood Improvement Programs as Regulators of Neighborhood Activism.” Journal of Planning Education and Research 26 (3): 261–71. Hillier, J., and P. Healey (eds.). 2008. Foundations of the Planning Enterprise: Critical Essays in Planning Theory. Hampshire: Ashgate. Holston, J. 1998. “Spaces of Insurgent Citizenship.” In Making the Invisible Visible: A Multicultural Planning History, edited by L. Sandercock, 37–56. Berkeley: University of California Press. Imarisha, W., and A. M. Brown (eds.). 2015. Octavia’s Brood: Science Fiction Stories from Social Justice Movements. Edinburgh: AK Press. www.thenation.com/article/why-science-fiction-fabulous-toolfight-social-justice/ (accessed September 28, 2016). Irazabal, C. (ed.). 2014. Transbordering Latin Americas: Liminal Places, Cultures, and Powers (T)here. New York, London: Routledge. Kundera, M. 1999. The Book of Laughter and Forgetting. New York: Harper Perennial Modern Classics. Mayer, M. 2003. “The Onward Sweep of Social Capital: Causes and Consequences for Understanding Cities, Communities and Urban Movements.” International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 27 (1): 110–32. McFarlane, C., and J. Silver. 2016. “The Poolitical City: “Seeing Sanitation” and Making the Urban Political in Cape Town.” Antipode Version of Record online: 27 July 2016 | DOI: 10.1111/anti.12264. McLoughlin, J. B. 1969. “The Guidance and Control of Change: Physical Planning as the Control of Complex Systems.” In Urban and Regional Planning: A Systems Approach, 75–91. London: Faber and Faber. Meir, A. 2005. “Bedouin, the Israeli State and Insurgent Planning: Globalization, Localization or Glocalization?” Cities 22 (3): 201–15. Meth, P. 2010. “Unsettling Insurgency: Reflections on Women’s Insurgent Practices in South Africa.” Planning Theory and Practice 11 (2): 241–63. Mies, M., V. Bennholdt-Thomsen, and C. Von Werlhof. 1988. Women: The Last Colony. London: Zed Books. Miraftab, F. 2003. “The Perils of Participatory Discourse: Housing Policy in Post-Apartheid South Africa.” Journal of Planning Education and Research 22 (3): 226–39. Miraftab, F. 2009. “Insurgent Planning: Situating Radical Planning in the Global South.” Planning Theory 8 (1): 32–50. Mohanty, C. T. 1991. “Under Western Eyes: Feminist Scholarship and Colonial Discourses.” In Third World Women and the Politics of Feminism, edited by Chandra Talpade Mohanty, Ann Russo, and Lourdes Torres, 51–80. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Pieterse, J. N. 2000. Global Futures: Shaping Globalization. London: Zed Books.

287

Faranak Miraftab Purcell, M. 2009. “Resisting Neoliberalization: Communicative Planning or Counter-hegemonic Movements?” Planning Theory 8(2): 140–65. Purcell, M. 2015. “Equity at the Beginning: Rancière and Democracy Today.” In Cities and Inequalities in a Global and Neoliberal World, edited by F. Miraftab, D. Wilson, and K. Salo, 188–206. New York, London: Routledge. Robin, K. 1994. Race Rebels: Culture, Politics, and the Black Working Class. New York: Free Press. Robins, S. 2014. “The 2011 Toilet Wars in South Africa: Justice and Transition between the Exceptional and the Everyday after Apartheid.” Development and Change 45 (33): 479–501. Roy, A. 2009. “Why India Cannot Plan Its Cities: Informality, Insurgence and the Idiom of Urbanization.” Planning Theory 8 (1): 76–87. Sager, T. 2005. “Communicative Planners as Naїve Mandarins of the Neo-liberal State?” European Journal of Spatial Development, December. ISSN 1650-9544, www.nordregio.se/EJSD/ (accessed September 28, 2016). Salo, K. 2015. “Local Practices and Trans-local Solidarities: Reflections on Anti-eviction Practices on the Cape Flats, South Africa and in South Side Chicago.” In Cities and Inequalities in a Global and Neoliberal World, edited by F. Miraftab, D. Wilson, and K. Salo, 217–26. New York, London: Routledge. Sandercock, L. 1998a. Towards Cosmopolis: Planning for Multicultural Cities. London: John Wiley. Sandercock, L. 1998b. “Framing Insurgent Historiographies for Planning.” In Making the Invisible Visible: A Multicultural Planning History, edited by L. Sandercock, 1–35. Berkeley: University of California Press. Santos, Bonaventura de Sousa. 1995. Toward a New Common Sense: Law, Science and Politics in the Paradigmatic Transition. London: Routledge. Simone, A. 2004. For the City Yet to Come: Changing African Life in Four Cities. Durham and London: Duke University Press. Stello, B. 2012. “Insurgent Planning and Its Interlocutors Studio Pedagogy as Unsanctioned Practice in Santo Domingo, Dominican Republic.” Journal of Planning Education and Research (33) 2: 228–40. Svirsky, M. 2010. “Introduction: Beyond the Royal Science of Politics.” In Deleuze Studies: Special Issue on Deleuze and Political Activism, edited by M. Svirsky, 1–6. Sweet, E., and M. Chakars. 2010. “Identity, Culture, Land, and Language: Stories of Insurgent Planning in the Republic of Buryatia, Russia.” Journal of Planning Education and Research 30 (2): 198–209. Watson, V. 2006. “Deep Difference: Diversity Planning and Ethics.” Planning Theory 5 (1): 31–50. Watson, V. 2009. “Seeing from the South: Refocusing Urban Planning on the Globe’s Central Urban Issues.” Urban Studies, 46 (11): 2259–79. Watts, M. 1994. “Development II: The Privatization of Everything?” Progress in Human Geography 18 (3): 371–84. Young, I. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

288

23 HEGEMONIC PLANNING AND MARGINALIZING PEOPLE Yosef Jabareen

Introduction Often viewed as a public undertaking aimed at creating a better society and better cities, planning has long been portrayed as a state responsibility that is visionary, utopian, progressive, and reformist in nature and that is intended to serve as a fair and legitimate process for producing preferable physical and social spaces (Bridge & Watson, 2000; Hillier, 2010). Indeed, in both theory and practice, it has typically been taken for granted “that planning is, could, or should be, A Good Thing” (Huxley, 2010: 136). Despite these claims, however, planning is often not what we were promised and can have catastrophic impact on different populations. Some scholars have used the metaphor of a “dark side” of planning to draw attention to the negative outcomes of the process (Flyvbjerg, 2002; Huxley, 2010; Jabareen 2017; Sandercock, 1998; Yiftachel, 1994). This chapter interrogates the role of state planning in marginalizing and oppressing religious, racial, national, ethnic, and other kinds of social groups with the aim of exploring the existing theories and contributing to the theorization of the subject. Interestingly, the literature review reflects that although much has already been written on this issue, little theorization has thus far considered the role of planning as an instrument of marginalization and domination. To begin filling this gap, this chapter pursues a theory of planning that engages with broader society but that also sheds light on the state’s implementation of spatial planning on a practical level. Drawing on Lacanian, Žižekian, and Laclauian concepts of fantasy, lack, and desire I theorize and propose the theoretical framework of “hegemonic planning,” which, I argue, serves to approach fulfilling the fantasy of the state apparatuses, or precisely the politically hegemonic groups, regarding their own ethnonationalist or ideological hegemony. This fantasy is related to the “harmony” and “wholeness” of this hegemonic group, while excluding disadvantaged groups, the “others,” from this total fantasy, and perceiving them as alien to their home-state frameworks and as “others” who need to be addressed through marginalization, oppression, exclusion, and dispossession. In this chapter, I suggest that hegemonic planning plays a powerful role in promoting and accomplishing state supremacy on the ground by fulfilling state fantasies through the use of common professional spatial planning practices and sophisticated, manipulative, and often veiled planning measures aimed at displacing and marginalizing people.

289

Yosef Jabareen

The next section reviews the literature on the darker side of planning and is followed by a detailed analysis of examples of state spatial planning practices from three different countries around the world: Iraq, Israel, and South Africa. The chapter’s final two sections discuss the dearth of planning theory on the marginalization and oppression of people, and propose an outline for a new direction in the conceptualization of hegemonic planning.

Theories on the Planning of Oppression and Marginalization The past half century has witnessed a steady increase in literature that acknowledges the darker side of planning and its adverse impact on minorities and immigrants. In the 1960s and 1970s, planning theorists such as Davidoff (1965), Friedmann (1973), Grabow & Heskin (1973), and Goodman (1971) began to draw attention to planning’s detrimental impact on social and ethnic groups. During the 1960s, the decade of civil rebellion, some practitioners started to question the premises of traditional land use and redevelopment planning, as well as the racial bias that was inherent in the profession (Manning & Ritzdorf, 1997), and by the 1970s, some African American communities had begun to realize the relationship between environmental problems in their communities and discriminatory exposure to toxic substances and unwanted land uses (Manning & Ritzdorf, 1997). In After the Planners (1971), Robert Goodman argued that planning had already had disastrous effects on the lives of the poor and the disenfranchised in the US and – though allegedly “value free,” “scientific,” and “rational” – had contributed to social oppression and marginalization. Planners, he contended, were “not the visible symbols of oppression like the military and the police” but “more sophisticated, more educated, more socially conscious than the generals” (Goodman, 1971: 13). Under the mask of rationality, efficiency, and science, planning had become a sophisticated weapon for maintaining existing controls on populations. “Advocacy planning” and “participatory planning” helped maintain this veneer by allowing the poor to administer their own dependency (p. 172). More recently, a number of scholars have reached conclusions regarding the racial sides of early zoning in the United States (Manning & Ritzdorf, 1997; Shertzer & Walsh, 2016; Fischel, 2001). In their examination of the initial comprehensive zoning ordinance adopted by Chicago in 1923, which was one of the first and most influential policies of its kind, Shertzer & Walsh (2016) find zoning and racial and ethnic composition to be mutually constitutive; that is to say, not only was zoning in the city influenced by the racial and ethnic composition of neighborhoods, but it also served to reshape the urban landscape faced by black and immigrant city residents. For example, neighborhoods that were home to higher percentages of black residents were more likely to be zoned for higher density buildings, and neighborhoods with larger populations of black residents or recent immigrants were disproportionately zoned for manufacturing (Shertzer & Walsh, 2016). According to Rothwell & Massey (2009), the higher population densities in minority neighborhoods in comparison to white neighborhoods leads to the concentration of poverty and creates an additional exit barrier for racial and ethnic minorities who wish to move elsewhere. Others have shown how zoning has been used to prevent the entry of immigrants and poorer households into wealthier white neighborhoods, for example, by means of minimum lot size requirements, which contribute to segregation by race and income (Shlay & Rossi, 1981; Rothwell & Massey, 2009; Sharkey, 2013). In some cases, mixed use zoning has been disproportionately allocated to low-income and minority communities, yielding disparities in environmental quality across neighborhoods and depressed land values (Wilson et al., 2008). Wilson et al. (2008: 212) also argue that zoning and land-use policies are often discriminatory and exclusionary, resulting in the “inequitable distribution of health-enriching resources to poor 290

Hegemonic Planning, Marginalizing People

and minority communities.” Regarding the disastrous outcomes of state planning, James Scott (1999) interrogates failed cases of large-scale state plans and argues against state planning that disregards the values, desires, and objections of its subjects. Additional critiques of negative planning outcomes have been advanced from different viewpoints, including feminist (see Fainstein & Servon, 2005; Sandercock & Forsyth, 1992) and postcolonial (Legg, 2007; Rabinow, 1989) perspectives and indigenous studies (Howitt & Lunkapis, 2010). Since the late 1990s, the field of planning has also produced a rich body of knowledge regarding conflict in cities, based largely on investigations of specific cities in states of deep ethnic, religious, and social conflict that are polarized along ethnic and ideological lines. In the literature, such cities have been referred to using a plethora of different designations, including “cities under conflict,” “divided cities,” “deeply divided cities,” “ethno-nationally divided cities,” “polarized cities,” “contested cities,” and “frontier cities.” This scholarship explores the role of planning in such contexts, with a focus on conflict mitigation and resolution. Conflict in such cities has revolved around a wide range of issues such as sovereignty, legitimacy, territory, collective identity, narrative, social control, the spatial division of labor, economics, and the control of resources, culture, and administration (Kotek, 1999; Paasi, 2003; Anderson, 2010; Kliot & Mansfield, 1999; Gaffikin & Morrissey, 2011). The cities examined in this context have included Brussels, Johannesburg, Belfast, Beirut, Sarajevo, Jerusalem, and Nicosia. Some scholars have suggested that, depending on how we use it, planning can result in disempowerment and marginalization or empowerment and the achievement of peace and political compromise in contested cities. Gaffikin and Morrissey (2011), who examine spatial planning in the context of deeply contested cities, maintain that all cities are divided, as their stakeholders are characterized by differential access and vested interests marked by categories of class, ethnicity, and gender. Their analysis distinguishes between two primary forms of contested urban space: one in which dispute and antagonism is related to issues of pluralism, and another that is largely about sovereignty, stemming from an ethnonational conflict over the legitimacy of the state itself. The latter form of contested urban space incorporates many more problematic features, as the notion of indivisible territory minimizes the scope for political compromise. Planners in these contexts, they explain, tend to present themselves as “apolitical technical professionals,” though their professed “neutrality” in the midst of urban conflict is a delusion. They also maintain that new forms of justice and comprehensive, inclusive, and participatory spatial planning interventions that transcend the narrow ambitions of physical land-use planning have the power to resolve such conflicts, and that planning that remains within its traditional confines will continue to promote inequalities, enclaves, and violence and inhibit democratic politics. Ultimately, however, Gaffikin and Morrissey (2011) conclude that even collaborative planning has its limitations, particularly in highly contested places. Bollens (2013) has also framed planning as a force with resolving capacity that has a powerful impact on contested cities. According to his analysis, planning reflects the intention and role of the government in contested places (Bollens, 2007). Bollens also shows how planning can play supportive and even catalytic roles in regional and national peace-building, help create physical and psychological spaces that can contribute to and actualize political stability and co-existence in such cities, and empower marginalized people (Bollens, 2007). Elsewhere, I have shown how, under conditions of ethnic conflict, planning in the service of hegemonic ethnic groups has the power to reshape, foster, and generate conflicts among urban identities by creating “spaces of risk” in cities (Jabareen, 2006, 2015, 2017),as well as the power to create “spaces of trust” (Jabareen & Carmon, 2010). 291

Yosef Jabareen

Yiftachel (1994, 2006) highlights the dark side of state policies implemented in the context of ethnic conflict and emphasizes their role in effecting territorial ethnicization. To better understand these dynamics, he proposes the political-geography concept of “ethnocracy”: a regime type that “surfaces in disputed territories, where one ethnonational group is able to appropriate the state apparatus and mobilize its legal, economic, and military resources to further its territorial, economic, cultural, and political interests” and that “facilitates and promotes the process of ethnicization” (Yiftachel, 2006: 295). However, this concept does not provide a theorization of the type of planning such regimes typically employ. Overall, the planning literature conveys a vivid account of the disastrous, unjust, and detrimental impact of state planning practices on social and ethnic groups but also highlights planning’s dual capacity for the empowerment/disempowerment and enfranchisement/disenfranchisement of people and groups.

Three Cases of Oppression and Marginalization This chapter analyzes state planning and its outcomes in three countries characterized by acute ethnonational tension and conflict. Many states around the world, from the most advanced to the least developed in both the North and the South, have employed planning for the purpose of marginalizing and oppressing social and ethnic groups. This chapter considers three countries based on two criteria: (1) the type of ethnic domination in place, and (2) the existence of a domestic ethnonationalist state ideology, as such ideologies are typically clearly reflected in state planning. Based on these criteria, this chapter will consider the following three cases: (1) Iraq, which for an extended period (1968–2004) was ruled by a single dominant political party with a nationalist state ideology; (2) Israel, which is governed by a dominant majority with a clear nationalist state ideology; and (3) apartheid South Africa, which during its years in existence was governed by a dominant minority with a clear race-focused ideology.

Case 1: Iraq Iraq is replete with multiethnic sectarian strife. One predominant element of Iraqi state administration that has remained relatively consistent in recent decades has stemmed from Iraqi ethnonationalist state ideology, specifically with regard to the Kurdish minority, which accounts for between 15% and 20% of the Iraqi population (as opposed to a 75% Arab majority). Since the establishment of Iraq in 1932, the Kurds, a people indigenous to the northern and eastern regions of the country, have been struggling for self-determination (Aziz, 2011). Since the establishment of modern Iraq, the hegemonic political power has desired to alter Iraq to be an exclusively Arab-dominated country. Accordingly, the state political power has been intervening in resetting the spatial-demographic distribution of ethnic groups in the country, and displacing the Kurds, the major minority of the country, and concentrating them in specific designated areas. In 1968, a coup led by the Ba’ath Party seized control of the state apparatus and continued to govern the country for 35 years, until 2003. The Ba’ath Party espouses an Arab nationalist ideology that celebrates the glories of Arab civilization and calls for rejuvenation and political union of the Arab countries (Khalidi, 1993). In an effort to promote the party’s conception that both the state and its territories should be dominated by Arabs, the country’s centralist totalitarian government used a combination of nationalism, ethnopolitics, and a centralized ideology of modernization to heavily intervene in the management and design of territory (Recchia, 2012). 292

Hegemonic Planning, Marginalizing People

The desire to fulfill this ideology on the ground was implemented through national state planning, which had two major objectives: Arabization and modernization. The Arabization of Iraq in general and a number of Kurdish minority areas in particular emerged as a critical tool for contending with “the Kurdish question” and with other minorities in Iraq. Accordingly, successive Iraqi governments have applied different tactics to transform the ethnic character of the Kirkuk region and to force Kurds, Turkmen, and Assyrians from their homes and replace them with Arabs from other parts of Iraq (Aziz, 2011). Primary goals of this geographical focus have been to promote an Arab presence throughout the country, to safeguard Arab national hegemony, and to ensure state control over the Kurdish region’s rich oil fields and valuable arable land (Talabany, 2000; Recchia, 2012). Under the fantasy of having a “clean” and “whole” Arab state, the Arabization mission during the 1970s and 1980s was set forth with the government forcibly displacing hundreds of thousands of Kurds, Turkomans, and Assyrians from their homes and replacing them with Arab settlers (Human Rights Watch, 2004). Arabization on a massive scale first occurred in the second half of the 1970s following the Iraqi government’s creation of an autonomous zone in parts of Iraqi Kurdistan, when some 250,000 Kurds and other non-Arabs were expelled from a wide strip of northern Iraq where Arabs were subsequently settled in their stead. During this process, the land ownership rights of Kurds and other non-Arabs were negated and land in the area was declared government land and leased to new Arab farmers by annual contract. Moreover, the Ba’ath Party embraced a socialist nationalist ideology that, in the 1970s, led the state to implement a grand national socialist-inspired plan aimed at reorganizing the country based on Soviet projects of collectivization and agrarian transformation. The plan called for a massive reallocation of resources from industrial development to agriculture, and to that end the government engaged in a massive confiscation project that affected 64% of the privately owned land in the country (Springborg, 1981). The reforms included the establishment of dozens of Collective Towns throughout Iraq, based on the socialist government’s desire to develop a Soviet model of socialist villages throughout the country. The Collective Towns initiative was based on the premise that merging multiple villages into large towns would improve infrastructure, and was implemented not only in Kurdistan but throughout Iraq. Through this effort, the Iraqi government encouraged people to live more modern lives in new houses with running water and sanitation, and because their agricultural land was located in close proximity to the Collective Towns, the people did not oppose it. However, in the 1980s, the state began to use this framework to achieve ethnic goals rather than fulfill the government’s socialist agenda as initially planned. Now, people were forced to move to Collective Towns where the land had already been divided, and engineers supervised the forced construction of structures by the local population. The aim was no longer the modernization of rural life but rather the Arabization of Kurdish areas; the incorporation of the inhabitants of Kurdish villages into large Collective Towns in order to control the Kurdish population. Ultimately, the government constructed 35 Kurdish Collective Towns, with some containing a population of almost 60,000. Town and housing design – which was centralized, conducted in Baghdad, and applied in equal measure to Collective Towns all over Kurdistan – also facilitated the imposition of control. The towns were gated, located in close proximity to military outposts, and positioned on a grid of wide perpendicular roads that divided the neighborhoods into orderly blocks allowing for easy mobility, access, and visibility for purposes of control (Recchia, 2012). The fantasy of having a purely Arab state has sustained, as well as infused the desire of the state hegemonic power to fulfill this fantasy through spatial planning alongside other military and policy measures. Overall, national planning, which had served the state to achieve its desire 293

Yosef Jabareen

of ethnic hegemony, had a catastrophic impact on minorities in Iraq, especially Kurds. The grand plan of the Collective Towns, which in effect became Kurdish camps with dismal socioeconomic and spatial conditions, resulted in the depopulation and destruction of approximately 4,000 Kurdish villages. The impact of three decades of hegemonic planning, forced displacement, and Arabization was immense, with approximately 900,000 displaced persons living in the Kurdish governorates of Arbil, Duhok, and Sulaimaniyya in 2001, toward the end of the period in question (Human Rights Watch, 2004).

Case 2: Israel The fantasy of complete control and possession of the “promised land of Israel,” the historic, pre-1948 Palestine, as an exclusively “Jewish State,” or what has politically evolved in recent years as a “Jewish Democratic State,” despite the presence of some millions of indigenous Palestinians, has been infusing the Israeli desire for certain territorial and demographic policies, at least since the state’s establishment in 1948. The Palestinian minority within Israel has been perceived as a demographic and territorial threat to fulfilling the national fantasy, which needs to be addressed, tackled, and confronted through spatial planning and other security and national policies (Jabareen, 2014, 2015, 2017). During the 1948 war in Palestine that resulted in the establishment of the state of Israel, 780,000 Palestinians were dispossessed and displaced and an estimated 400 Palestinian cities, towns, and villages were completely uprooted (Abu-Lughod, 1971). In this way, the overwhelming Palestinian majority of pre-1948 Palestine was transformed almost overnight into a Palestinian minority in Israel, with most Palestinian inhabitants of the state’s territory becoming refugees in the West Bank, the Gaza Strip, and neighboring Arab countries. Within the borders of Israel, only 156,000 Arabs remained, becoming citizens of Israel and constituting an ethic minority of about 20% of the country’s population. The roots of Israeli planning ideology reach back to the Zionist movement, which was founded in 1897 as a Jewish national organization aimed at building a homeland for Jews in Palestine through land acquisition and colonization. The Zionist movement conceived the territory of Palestine as “under-cultivated,” “pure,” “empty,” and devoid of its indigenous Palestinian population (Shafir, 2008; Kimmerling & Migdal, 2008; Ram, 2003) and framed it as a “terra nullius” (an empty land) awaiting Jewish redemption after centuries of neglect. This approach is reflected in the assertion by Chaim Weizmann, the first president of the state of Israel, that “the Jews alone were capable of rebuilding Palestine and giving it a place in the modern family of nations” (Said, 1979: 13). On this basis, concludes Said (1979), the constitutive energies of Zionism were premised on the excluded presence of “native people” in Palestine. This traditional form of Zionism continues to provide the political and ideological foundation for Israeli government planning practices up to the present. Since its establishment in 1948, Israel has acknowledged the power of national spatial planning. Israel’s first national plan, known as the Sharon Plan (1951), portrayed the country’s landscape as “lost,” “under-cultivated,” “abused,” and “neglected” by the native Palestinians, and, most importantly, as only sparsely inhabited by Jews. On this basis, from Israel’s first national plan to its most recent, the major concern of state and spatial planning has been to address the “lack” of sufficient Jewish presence in various parts of the country, as well as the “gap” in development. In an effort to fill this lack, Israeli state authorities immediately embarked on a grand spatialdemographic project of Jewish settlement and internal colonization, which continues today. Spatial planning has dramatically served Israel in its endeavor to achieve hegemony of the territory and demography of Israel itself and beyond its border in the occupied West Bank 294

Hegemonic Planning, Marginalizing People

and East Jerusalem. Although Israel has employed various strategies to actualize its spatial conception, all have reflected the unifying approach of “Judaization”; this concept has been a Master-Signifier, which has led the entire planning agenda. This concept was initially used by state authorities to refer to the exclusionary ethnonationalist policy by which planning and economic development has been used to promote the interests of the “Jewish People” rather than the overall population of the country. Judaization, and its prevailing planning tool of “population dispersal,” enabled the state to use the country’s new Jewish immigrant population as a vehicle for extensive colonization and for filling the territorial void. In this context, Israeli leaders and planners have perceived the country’s indigenous Palestinian population as a dangerous demographic entity (Jabareen, 2015). This approach has been vividly manifested in national and district plans, which have related to Palestinians in a hostile and antagonistic manner, portraying them as “illegal builders” and “illegal invaders” of state lands, a “spreading and expanding population,” and a “demographic threat.” Laws facilitating the “Judaization of land” have enabled the state to effect a massive confiscation of Palestinian land that has resulted in state ownership of 93% of all land in the country, with only approximately 2.5% of the country’s land owned by members of Israel’s Palestinian minority (even though they account for nearly 21% of the overall population). The state’s Jewish dominated military apparatus also plays a significant role in spatial planning in the country, enjoying complete control, with almost no civilian involvement, over vast swaths of territory which together account for nearly 50% of Israel’s overall land area (Oren & Regev, 2008).

Case 3: South Africa Despite their status as a minority, albeit a dominant hegemonic minority, the fantasy of the white minority during the apartheid regime was to wholly control South Africa; to use its human and material resources while neglecting the very basic interests of the vast majority. The dominant minority fantasy of creating separate “homelands” for indigenous ethnic groups in the same country had infused, channeled, and organized the apartheid desires and its subsequent social, economic, and spatial practices. The racially inspired social and economic divisions that characterized apartheid South Africa (1948–94) were spatially constructed and systemized through national legislation and local planning (Maylam, 1995; Hart, 1990; Watson, 2002). Spatial oppression, exploitation, and separation were based firmly on minority domination, as well as on a “scientific racial” ideology that held that different races should remain separated from one another for their own mutual interest. The cultural-anthropological rationalization of apartheid, at least initially, was that different cultures are incommensurable; that the integrity of each culture should be respected and its survival safeguarded; and that the only way to do this in a multi-cultural society was through political and geographical separation, that is, by creating separate “homelands” for each ethnically defined cultural group (Van der Merwe, 1996). The resulting social engineering program for the sweeping and violent institutionalization of separation, and the very real way in which this program isolated communities from one another, brought about misunderstanding, bigotry, and animosity (Van der Merwe, 1996: 85). Afrikaners held that it was impossible, impracticable, and ungodly for the different races and cultures to live together. Apartheid itself was a totalitarian system that specifically reinforced and politicized ethnic diversity and deliberately accommodated the values, norms, and interests of the society’s white “Eurocentric” ruling class at the expense of others (Van der Merwe, 1996). It was upon this vision that apartheid was constructed and that the country’s successive white governments pursued a policy of separate development (Brits, 2007). 295

Yosef Jabareen

In response to the Afrikaner National government’s request in 1948 to conduct research into the implementation of the official policy of apartheid, Professor Frederik Tomlinson advised that a separation of the races could be effective if the government were to prepare a financial apartheid policy. The Tomlinson Report also recommended that reserves be set up in seven areas as Bantu (native) homelands, or Bantustans (Roberts, 2001), which would remain separated from the white community and eventually become independent. The report also recommended the construction of factories at the edges of these areas and the relocation, over time, of all blacks in South Africa to prescribed Bantustans, from which they would be able to enter white areas only for the purpose of work and with appropriate documentation (in the form of a “passbook”). The key function of this system was to keep blacks and whites entirely separate, thereby preserving the purity of the white race (Brits, 2007). The ideology of territorial racial-oriented segregation, spatial surveillance and control, and ethnic-oriented economic growth guided spatial planning policies for many decades throughout the apartheid years and during the decades that preceded it. Yet, the legal system made perhaps the most dramatic contribution to segregation and its spatial planning. The major piece of legislation that served to facilitate racial-spatial segregation in South Africa was the Natives Land Act of 1913, which decreed that only certain areas of the country could be owned by natives. These areas initially totaled 7.13% (9,709,586 acres) of the entire land area of the Union, but were later expanded under the Natives’ Trust and Land Act of 1936 to include approximately 13.6% of the total area of South Africa (Collins & Burns, 2007; Harrison et al., 2008), although it appears that this goal was never reached. Urban racial segregation became an explicit policy of the South African government, and town planning was viewed as the primary tool for shaping the new urban landscape (Mabin & Smit, 1997). Generally speaking, state spatial planning had long been used in South Africa to play both a managing role in relation to the spatial separation of racial groups and a welfareoriented role in relation to the planning of housing and facilities for those of the African and colored population deemed necessary for the urban economy. In the post-1948 years, however, urban racial segregation became an explicit policy of government, and town planning was viewed as the primary tool through which the new urban landscape should be fashioned. Planners justified their plans as reflecting a scientific approach to land allocations, and, as shown by Watson, planning as a “tool of racial segregation” gained legitimacy from its discourse of “improving welfare and modernization” (Watson, 2002: 25–26). The spatial policy of apartheid incorporated separate development for black people, in their own reservations according to their own national character, with the deprivation of political rights for black people in “white” areas, the division of black labor among the country’s various economic sectors, and influx control and apartheid in industry (Brits, 2007). State planning had long been used to play both a managing role, in relation to the spatial separation of racial groups, and a welfare-related role, in relation to the planning of housing and facilities for the members of the Black African population deemed necessary for the urban economy (Harrison et  al., 2008). In this context, planners were involved in designing the new racially segregated townships as discrete residential neighborhoods surrounded by green belts with few access routes. And this, in turn, allowed for more effective policing and control (Collins & Burns, 2007) and the imposition of coercive structures through which the racially exclusionary city was engineered (Harrison et al., 2008). Planners took part in designing “Grand Apartheid” and in building the new large public housing estates required to both house the workforce and accomplish more comprehensive segregation. They were also involved in planning the “township,” a term used in the South African

296

Hegemonic Planning, Marginalizing People

planning lexicon to refer to the large segregated public housing estate that was usually located on or beyond the urban periphery (Mabin & Smit, 1997). In apartheid South Africa, state planning resulted in highly segregated socio-spatial spaces throughout the country, as well as distinctive socio-economic spaces based primarily on race. It also resulted in cities and towns with distinctive spatial forms (Harrison et al., 2008). The new townships created for “people of color” – to which people were forced to relocate, breaking up communities and social networks – were extremely poor in terms of land use and facilities. These spatially segregated forms impeded the mobility of non-whites and physically trapped them in poor areas (Harrison et al., 2008). Under apartheid, planning not only produced new racially segregated townships but also employed various land-use related measures to enhance security and policing, including the design of discrete residential “neighborhoods”; the encircling of such neighborhoods by green belts or buffer zones; and the designation of few access routes, facilitating more effective policing and control (Watson, 2002).

Planning, Oppression, and Marginalization: The Dearth of Theory In the three countries considered in this study, state planning and its products reflect the dismal status of minorities, marginalization, oppression, and dispossession. This chapter highlights the influence of race and ethnicity on spatial planning in these case studies and concludes that spatial planning is racially and ethnically differentiated. In addition to planning, which, as reflected in the existing planning literature, has had disastrous effects on the lives of disenfranchised groups in the guise of supposed rationality, professionalism, and scientific planning (Goodman, 1971), land use and zoning have also been discriminatorily applied to the disenfranchised in different ways, resulting in the restriction of movement, segregated areas, densely populated places, the lack of economic resources, and inadequate social and physical facilities and infrastructures (Manning & Ritzdorf, 1997; Sharkey, 2013; Shertzer & Walsh, 2016; Fischel, 2001; Rothwell & Massey, 2009; Shlay & Rossi, 1981; Watson, 2002; Wilson et al., 2008). State planning has also been used to enhance the control and hegemony of dominant groups, for example, in ethnocratic regimes aimed at the ethnicization of the state at the expense of other groups (Yiftachel, 2006). However, the existing literature reflects that although much has already been written on this issue, little theorization has thus far considered the role of planning as an instrument of marginalization and domination, leaving unanswered major questions such as: Why do states use planning to marginalize their own citizens in general and the members of specific social and ethnic groups in particular? What justifications have been offered for national spatial agendas of oppressing citizens? How do states legitimize their planning ideologies, values, discourses, and missions and succeed in achieving consensus within dominant groups? And, on a theoretical level, what is the ontological foundation for this approach to planning, which motivates states to channel vast resources into oppressing their own citizens? In this way, the literature on planning theory reflects a current need for theorization that is capable of illuminating the “overarching ideological societal framework” in which such state planning resides. To begin filling this gap, this chapter pursues a theory of planning that engages with broader society but that also sheds light on the state’s implementation of spatial planning on a practical level (see Gunder & Hillier, 2009: 192). More specifically, the literature on the subject provides little ontological insight into the nature of this type of planning, why it occurs, and its relationship to state and society, all of which must be thoroughly understood in order to theorize it. The final section of this chapter seeks to begin filling this gap by suggesting a future theoretical direction and proposing a theoretical approach to the role of state planning in human oppression and marginalization.

297

Yosef Jabareen

Theorizing Hegemonic Planning: Outlining a Future Theoretical Direction One direction for theorization, which I tentatively outline here, is that of “hegemonic planning” which is carried out by states whose apparatuses oppress and marginalize different groups. Building on the Lacanian perspective, I suggest that planning in general, and state hegemonic planning in particular, are constructed around the “imaginary mode” and the concept of fantasy. Lacan suggests that at the “mirror stage” the child in early months “primordially identifies with the visual gestalt of his own body. In comparison with the still very profound lack of coordination in his own motor functioning, that gestalt is an ideal unity, a salutary imago” (Lacan, 2006: 113). This imaginary mode “turns out fantasies that proceed from a fragmented image of the body” to a “form of its totality” (Lacan, 2006: 97). The difference between the whole, total, and ideal image and the fragmented experience of the infant constitutes lack (Lacan, 2006: 186), which must be understood not as “lack of this or that” but as “the lack of being, properly speaking” (Lacan 1988: 223). Furthermore, “lack” is always related to desire, and it is lack that causes desire to arise (Lacan, 1988). Thus, desire is a relation of being to lack (Lacan, 1988), a metonymy of the lack of being. The desire for being is to “fill” the “lack” and become “whole” and “complete.” Therefore, “desire is the metonymy of the want to-be” (Lacan, 2006: 623). Fantasy, another central concept of Lacan’s perspective, in its fundamental use, “is the means by which the subject maintains himself at the level of his vanishing desire, vanishing inasmuch as the very satisfaction of demand deprives him of his object” (Lacan, 2006: 637). Thus, fantasy is what sustains the subject as desiring. Its aim is not to ratify the fulfillment of desire but to sustain the subject’s desire by telling it how to desire (Glynos, 2001). According to Žižek, desire is not something given in advance, but something that has to be constructed and articulated through fantasy (Žižek, 1989: 9). Fantasy is “a scenario that realizes the subject’s desire” (Žižek, 1989: 6) and “teaches us how to desire” (Žižek, 2009: 40). It sustains the subject as a desiring subject by providing it with a mode of jouissance. Here, I use Lacan’s abstraction to theorize hegemonic planning. Yet, this methodological transition, from the psychoanalytical approach to a socio-political analysis is uncomfortable and may raise some skepticism (Butler, 2000; Glynos, 2001). Here, I follow Laclau (2000) who posits that if lack occurs at the level of the individual subject, then it also occurs in similar ways at the level of the social. Moreover, I pay particular attention to Gunder & Hillier (2009), who highlight the “critical awareness and insight” offered by Lacan into “the role of identification, fantasy and belief in spatial planning,” and discuss how this is often synonymous with the development of power as it shapes our communities (Gunder & Hillier, 2009: 181). Hegemonic planning, I posit, is intimately linked to the desires, lacks, and fantasies of the state’s hegemonic group and apparatus regarding their own ethnonationalist hegemony, or ideological hegemony. The national fantasy of “wholeness” sustains the emptiness of the MasterSignifier of “We,” “Our Nation,” “Our Lands,” “Our Security,” “Internal Threat,” etc. Yet, the function of the fantasy is in filling in the void of the Master-Signifier (Žižek, 2009: 373). The hegemony fantasy serves to bridge a perceived lack and is aimed at achieving ethnonationalist “harmony” and “wholeness” while excluding, marginalizing, oppressing, and dispossessing other collective groups of citizens or residents, the “others,” those who are perceived as aliens in their homelands and who prevent “us” from being a “whole.” Planning has a central function in serving the hegemony fantasy and desire of the hegemonic group and their state apparatuses. More specifically, hegemonic planning plays a powerful role in filling the “lack” of incompleteness on the ground. Ironically, this lack is related to the very presence of “other” ethnic or social groups and their spatial and demographic distributions as well as their hold of lands within the state. The hegemonic groups perceive this presence 298

Hegemonic Planning, Marginalizing People

and territorial distribution as “holes” and “voids,” which harm the fantasy of the “total” and “complete” “Nation,” “Ethnic,” and/or “Territory” and so forth. In this context, the power of planning is supreme since it has the power to manipulate both the settings and futures of geography and demography, i.e. territory and people. As such, hegemonic planning addresses what the hegemonic group “would like to be” in terms of territoriality through the use of common professional planning practices and sophisticated, manipulative, and often veiled planning measures aimed at displacing and marginalizing people. The main thrust of the fantasy of the hegemonic groups in our three cases, involves filling the “lack,” which is related to the very presence of “other” groups: the Kurds in Iraq, the Palestinians in Israel, and the majority of Africans in South Africa. In these countries, various terminology of Master-Signifiers, such as “security,” “historic rights,” “destiny,” and “divine promise,” conceive the “others” as “inferior,” “threatening,” “unwanted,” and “disruptive” groups. In our cases, we identified fantasies regarding singular national ethnic purity, uniformity, uniqueness, exceptionalism, cohesion, homogeneity, and purging, typically accompanied by a belief in one national ethnic group’s unique form, if not superiority to others. In our three cases, hegemonic planning appears as a powerful tool with the ability to manipulate territories and spaces using a multiplicity of commonplace planning practices, such as: changing land uses and allocating resources in ways that result in the moving and removal, replacement and displacement, and dispersal and concentration of people; the construction, destruction, and rebuilding of settlements and neighborhoods; the allocation and confiscation of land and materials; and the renaming of places. These practices tend to work to the advantage of dominant, privileged groups and to the detriment of the underprivileged. These observations are consistent with the literature’s previously noted assessment that although it typically operates behind a veneer of “objectivity,” “science,” “rationalism,” and “the public interest,” planning has the power to oppress and marginalize, and that although not “the visible symbols of oppression,” planners often possess a sophistication, education, and social consciousness lacked by the police and the military (Goodman, 1971: 13). Ultimately, hegemonic planning is a coercive process involving the manipulation of spatial, demographic, and other material and symbolic resources; the sometimes unscrupulous translation of “ideological” agendas into planning; and the employment of dynamic spatial practices and strategies (based on modern and postmodern planning professionalism) that may be violent, racist, and oppressive, and that often raise profound ethical questions. Finally, the history of Iraq, Israel, and South Africa tells us that the fantasy of hegemony is premised on the impossible: the vanishing of its disruptive others, who in many cases are simply ordinary citizens whose fault is that they belong to the “other” skin, nation, or simply social group. Finally, the framework that suggests the grand fantasies of “wholeness,” “total,” and “completeness”; the lack, the holes of incompleteness, which the presence of others impose; and the desire of the hegemonic group or the state apparatuses to fill the lack, addresses this chapter’s main questions of why do states use planning to marginalize people, what are the justifications for oppressing people, and what is the ontological foundation for this approach to planning that motivates states to channel vast resources into oppressing their own citizens? In this manner, planning is central to the mission of hegemonic fantasy.

References Abu-Lughod, J. (1971). “The Demographic Transformation of Palestine.” In A. Abu-Lughod (Ed.), The Transformation of Palestine (pp. 139–163). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press Anderson, J. (2010). Democracy, Territoriality and Ethno-National Conflict: A Framework for Studying EthnoNationally Divided Cities. Part II. Divided Cities/Contested States. Working Paper No. 18.

299

Yosef Jabareen Aziz, M. (2011). The Kurds of Iraq: Ethnonationalism and National Identity in Iraqi Kurdistan. London: Tauris Academic Studies. Bollens, S. A. (2007). Cities, Nationalism and Democratization. Oxford and New York: Routledge. Bollens, S. A. (2013). “Urban Planning and Policy.” In R. MacGinty (Ed.), Routledge Handbook of Peacebuilding (pp. 375–386). Oxford and New York: Routledge. Bridge, G. and Watson, S. (eds.) (2000). A Companion to the City. Oxford: Blackwell. Brits, P. (2007). Modern South Africa: Afrikaner Power, the Politics of Race, and Resistance, 1902 to the 1970s. Pretoria: University of South Africa Press. Butler, J. (2000). “Restaging the Universal: Hegemony and the Limits of the Universal.” In J. Butler, E. Laclau, and S. Žižek (Eds.), Contingency, Hegemony, Universality (pp. 11–43). London: Verso. Collins, R. O. and Burns, J. M. (2007). A History of sub-Saharan Africa. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Davidoff, P. (1965). Advocacy and pluralism in planning. Journal of the American Institute of Planners, 31(6), 331–337. Fainstein, S. and Servon, L. J. (2005). Gender and Planning: A Reader. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Fischel, William A. (2001). The Homevoter Hypothesis: How Home Values Influence Local Government Taxation, School Finance, and Land-Use Policies. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Flyvbjerg, B. (2002). Bringing power to research: one researcher’s praxis story. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 21(4), 353–366. Friedmann, J. (1973). Retracking America: A Theory of Transactive Planning. Arden City, NY: Anchor. Gaffikin, F. and Morrissey, M. (2011). Planning in Divided Cities. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. Glynos, J. (2001). The grip of ideology: a Lacanian approach to the theory of ideology. Journal of Political Ideologies, 6(2), 191–214. Goodman, R. (1971). After the Planners. New York: Simon and Schuster. Grabow, S. and Heskin, A. (1973). Foundations for a radical concept of planning. Journal of the American Institute of Planners, 39(2), 106–114. Gunder, M. and Hillier, J. (2009). Planning in Ten Words or Less: A Lacanian Entanglement with Spatial Planning. Farnham: Ashgate. Harrison, P., Todes, A., and Watson, V. (2008). Planning and Transformation: Learning from the Post-Apartheid Experience. London: Routledge. Hart, D. (1990). “Master Plans: The South African Government’s Razing of Sophiatown, Cato Manor and District Six”, unpublished PhD thesis, Syracuse University. Hillier, J. (2010). “Introduction.” In J. Hillier and P. Healey (Eds.), The Ashgate Research Companion to Planning Theory: Conceptual Challenges for Spatial Planning (pp. 1–37). Farnham: Ashgate. Howitt, R. and Lunkapis, J. (2010). “Coexistence: Planning and the Challenge of Indigenous Rights.” In J. Hillier and P. Healey (Eds.), The Ashgate Research Companion to Planning Theory: Conceptual Challenges for Spatial Planning (pp. 109–133). Farnham: Ashgate. Human Rights Watch (2004). “Claims in Conflict: Reversing Ethnic Cleansing in Northern Iraq.” Vol. 16, No. 4E. www.hrw.org/reports/2004/iraq0804/iraq0804.pdf (accessed 5 May 2017). Huxley, M. (2010). “Problematizing Planning: Critical and Effective Genealogies.” In J. Hillier and P. Healey (Eds.), The Ashgate Research Companion to Planning Theory: Conceptual Challenges for Spatial Planning (pp. 135–158). Farnham: Ashgate. Jabareen, Y. (2006). Conceptualizing space of risk: the contribution of planning policies to conflicts in cities – lessons from Nazareth. Planning Theory and Practice, 7(3), 305–323. Jabareen, Y. (2014). ‘The Right to the City’ Revisited: Assessing Urban Rights in Developing Cities - The Case of Arab Cities in Israel, Habitat International, 41: 135-141. Jabareen, Y. (2015). Territoriality of negation: co-production of “creative destruction” in Israel. Geoforum, 66, 11–25. Jabareen, Y. (2017). The right to space production and the right to necessity: Insurgent versus legal rights of Palestinians in Jerusalem. Planning Theory, 16(1), 6-31. Jabareen, Y. and Carmon, N. (2010). Community of trust: a socio-cultural approach for community planning and the case of Gaza. Habitat International, 34(4), 446–453. Khalidi, W. (1993). The Jewish-Ottoman Land Company: Herzl’s blueprint for the colonization of Palestine. Journal of Palestine Studies, 22(2), 30–47. Kimmerling, B. and Migdal, J. (2008). “Introduction to The Palestinian People: A history.” In L. J. Silberstein (Ed.) Postzionism: A Reader (pp. 56–60). Rutgers, NJ: The State University Press. Kliot, N. and Mansfield, Y. (1999). Divided cities: case studies of conflict and territorial organization. Progress in Planning, 52, 167–226.

300

Hegemonic Planning, Marginalizing People Kotek, J. (1999). Divided cities: in the European cultural context. Progress in Planning, 52, 227–237. Lacan, J. (2006). Ecrits. Trans. Bruce Fink. New York: W. W. Norton. Lacan, J. (1988). The Seminar. Book II: The Ego in Freud’s Theory and in the Technique of Psychoanalysis, 1954–55. Trans. Sylvana Tomaselli. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Laclau, E. (2000). “Identity and Hegemony: The Role of Universality in the Constitution of Political Logics.” In J. Butler, E. Laclau and S. Žižek, Contingency, Hegemony, Universality: Contemporary Dialogues on the Left (pp. 44–89). London: Verso. Legg, S. (2007). Spaces of Colonialism: Delhi’s Urban Governmentalities. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. Mabin, A. and Smit, D. (1997). Reconstructing South Africa’s cities? The making of urban planning 1900–2000. Planning Perspectives, 12, 193–223. Manning, J. and Ritzdorf, M. (1997). Urban Planning and the African American Community: In the Shadows. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Maylam, P. (1995). Explaining the apartheid city: 20 years of South African urban historiography. Journal of Southern African Studies, 21(1), 19–38. Oren, A. and Regev, R. (2008). Land in Uniform: Territory and Defense in Israel. Jerusalem: Carmel Press (in Hebrew). Paasi, A. (2003). “Territory.” In J. Agnew, K. Mitchell and G. Toal (Eds.), A Companion to Political Geography (pp. 109–122). Oxford: Blackwell. Rabinow, P. (1989). French Modern: Norms and Forms of the Social Environment. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Ram, U. (2003). From Nation-state to nation-state: nation, history and identity struggles in Jewish Israel. In E. Nimni (Ed.), The Challenge of Post-Zionism: Alternatives to Fundamentalist Politics in Israel (pp. 20–37). London: Zed Books. Recchia, F. (2012). From Forced Displacement to Urban Cores: The Case of Collective Towns in Iraqi Kurdistan. Critique: Erbil, Iraq and London, United Kingdom. Online: https://architexturez.net/doc/az-cf123984 (accessed May 5, 2015). Roberts, M. (2001). South Africa 1948–2000: The Rise and Fall of Apartheid. Harlow: Pearson Educational Limited. Rothwell, J. and Massey, D. S. (2009). The effect of density zoning on racial segregation in U.S. urban areas. Urban Affairs Review, 44(6), 779–806. Said, E. (1979). The Question of Palestine. New York: Vintage Books. Sandercock, L. (1998). Making the Invisible Visible: A Multicultural Planning History. Berkeley: University of California Press. Sandercock, L. and Forsyth, A. (1992). “Feminist theory and planning theory: the epistemological linkages.” Planning Theory Newsletter 7–8, 45–48. Scott, J. (1999). Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Shafir, G. (2008). “Land, labor, and the origin of the Israeli-Palestinian conflict: 1882–1914.” In L. J. Silberstein (Ed.) Postzionism: A Reader (pp. 46–55). Rutgers, NJ: The State University Press. Sharkey, P. (2013). Stuck in Place: Urban Neighborhoods and the End of Progress Toward Racial Equality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Shertzer, A. and Walsh, R. (2016). Racial Sorting and the Emergence of Segregation in American Cities. NBER Working Paper No. w22077. Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2747197 (accessed May 5, 2017). Shlay, A. B. and Rossi, P. H. (1981). Keeping up the neighborhood: estimating the net effects of zoning. American Sociological Review, 46(6), 703–719. Springborg, R. (1981). “Baathism in practice: agriculture, politics, and political culture in Syria and Iraq. Middle Eastern Studies.” 17(2), 191–209. Talabany, N. (2000). The Kurds of Iraq: Ethnonationalism and National Identity in Iraqi Kurdistan. London: Tauris Academic Studies. Van der Merwe, W. L. (1996). Philosophy and the multi-cultural context of (post)apartheid South Africa. Ethical Perspectives 3(1), 76–90. Watson, V. (2002). Change and Continuity in Spatial Planning: Metropolitan Planning in Cape Town under Political Transition. London and New York: Routledge. Wilson, S., Hutson, M., and Mujahid, M. (2008). “How planning and zoning contribute to inequitable development, neighborhood health, and environmental injustice.” Environmental Justice 1(4), 211–216. Yiftachel, O. (1994). “The Dark Side of Modernism: Planning as Control of an Ethnic Minority.” In S. Watson and C. Gibson (Eds.), Postmodern Cities and Spaces (pp. 216–234). Oxford: Blackwell. Yiftachel, O. (2006). Ethnocracy: Land and Identity Politics in Israel/Palestine. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Žižek, S. (2009). The Parallax View. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Žižek, S. (1989). Looking Awry: An Introduction to Jacques Lacan through Popular Culture. October Books.

301

24 ACTOR-NETWORK THEORY Yvonne Rydin

Introduction When the term ‘actor-network theory’ or ANT is raised, probably the most immediate thought conjured up is that ANT proposes material ‘things’ have agency like human actors. As this chapter will explore, this is not exactly what ANT in any of its varieties proposes, nor is it a sufficient account of what theoretical perspectives drawing on ANT can offer planning analysts. This chapter will set out the origins and development of ANT thinking, explain the key concepts and discuss the mode of argumentation and research implied by adopting an ANT perspective. It will consider some of the key criticisms made of ANT – including those relating to the abovementioned agency of things – and consider some responses. It concludes by outlining some possible trajectories for ANT research within planning studies. In setting out this account of ANT and planning, a claim is being made for the importance of ANT thinking to understanding key aspects of how planning processes work. The claim rests on ANT’s ability to develop a relational analysis appropriate for the complexity of the world we live in and which planning practice seeks to impact. It implies an acceptance of the critiques of rational modes of planning theory and practice, with their emphasis on seeing planning actions in terms of a set of prescriptions and on implementing agreed policies and plans. It also shies away from developing grand narratives of social order or economic crisis within which the operation of planning systems can be set. Both of these perspectives have their roots in a modernist view of the world and ANT is, above all, against a singular modernism. As a result ANT cannot provide a comprehensive and dominant account of planning practice. Like any theoretical perspective, it highlights some aspects and downplays or even ignores others. If those areas on which it shines a spotlight seem significant and even practically useful, then ANT has a role to play.

Origins and Applications To appreciate the contribution that ANT can make to planning scholarship, it is important to realise how and where it arose. ANT was originally a contribution to science studies, understanding how scientific expertise is accredited and scientific knowledge generated. It fitted within the social constructivist turn of the 1980s that saw knowledge claims not as objective 302

Actor-Network Theory

reflections of reality but rather as created and maintained through social processes. The discursive construction of knowledge claims was considered worthy of attention, including the detailed processes by which scientific institutions worked and thus the early work of Bruno Latour (the theorist most closely associated with ANT although the contributions of Michel Callon, John Law and Annemarie Mol should also be acknowledged) concerned detailed ethnographic studies of laboratories. This emphasis on how social processes are involved in generating scientific knowledge led at the time to a rather crudely drawn debate over whether there was a material reality or whether the social constructivist perspective denied the physical reality of our world (Collins and Evans, 2002). This proved an arid debate and Latour himself (1999a) has made it quite clear that he is a realist as well as a social constructivist. Indeed the controversial claims over the agency of the material arise from the desire to have both a realist as well as a constructivist element within ANT. While Latour and Callon pursued this line through widely cited studies of Pasteur’s ‘discovery’ of bacteria (Latour, 1993) and the role of expertise in promoting scallop fishing (Callon, 1986), ANT was providing inspiration to a range of researchers working in different fields. Mol (2002), for example, has used it to explore health issues and Feldman and Pentland (2005) to consider business management. But there is also an increasing number of planning-related applications. Latour and Yaneva (2008) have used it to provide an ethnographic account of architectural practice and Murdoch (1997, 1998) was an earlier pioneer in considering how spatial planning could be understood through ANT, while Rydin (2012) drew on ANT concepts to understand the regulation of office development; further planning-related references are provided below. Also highly influential have been the variant of ANT termed assemblage thinking (see also Chapter 26 in this volume). As will be explained below, this shares certain common features of the ANT framework but does not utilise all the conceptual toolbox. Farias and Bender’s edited collection (2009) applying assemblage thinking to urban studies has been widely cited and there are more specific applications such as Brownill’s research (2016) on the Localism agenda in Oxfordshire, England and Guy et al.’s (2016) analysis of an innovative district heating system in the Hague, Netherlands. These works suggest the value that ANT and related theorising can bring to planning studies (see also the introduction to Rydin and Tate, 2016).

Key Concepts and Dynamics The central image at the heart of ANT is the network, an image that suggests linkages between different elements. ANT is a relational perspective which means that it places emphasis on the qualities of relationships between elements in accounting for what is happening and how outcomes occur, rather than the characteristics of the elements. The inclusion of an actor in a network depends on the capacity for linking within the network, not the strength, mobility and intentionality of the actors. This puts the emphasis on power and agency as relational effects not the result of actors’ inherent or acquired characteristics. Within ANT the term ‘associations’ is commonly used to describe such relationships. Assemblage thinking focuses almost exclusively on such associations and how they are built (DeLanda, 2006; see also Murray Li, 2007); this is the key point of contact between ANT and assemblage approaches. Both also see the ‘networks’ as something rather different to the fixed network graphs of, say, engineering or mathematics or social network analysis. The network image is meant to highlight the importance of relationships or associations but not suggest a fixed pattern of connections between nodes. Hence a variety of other terms have been suggested: 303

Yvonne Rydin

the biological metaphor of ‘rhizomes’ or the more fluid ‘gel’. Assemblage itself is a metaphor taken from the translation of the French term ‘agencement’ which suggests the work undertaken to bring things together, to create associations; the English word ‘assemblage’ puts more emphasis on the fixture that results. Here the term ‘network’ will be deployed but in the understanding that the theoretical interest is in the associations it represents and how they came to be forged. For Latour, the persistent riddle is not how society creates order but how it comes to be ordered through such associations. Order and stability in relationships is not to be taken for granted but, rather, is the result of active work, what Ren et al. (2012) describe as “a precarious achievement”. Murdoch was particularly prescient in seeing plan-making in terms of networks that were in flux, either being actively stabilised or destabilising (1997, 1998; see also Tate (2013) for her study of growthmanagement planning in Vancouver). For Star this stabilisation is not a given fact but always from a particular perspective; there are “critical differences between those for whom networks are stable and those for whom they are not, where those are putatively the ‘same’ network” (1991, p. 42). Ren et al. (2012) emphasise that ANT has a radical ontology whereby multiple realities take shape according to how they are enacted (see also Latour, 2005, p. 36). The emphasis is, therefore, more on how the connections work from multiple perspectives rather than the static ordered thing. The work of building associations is also cross-scalar. ANT operates with a flat ontology in which relationships can be between elements operating at a number of different scales. A network might involve a local site, local communities, national developers, national and international policy artefacts, global flows of finance, global climate change and – down again – to regional water courses, regional commuting patterns, urban housing markets, site-specific habitats, etc., etc. ANT rejects the idea of layered scales whereby the higher one(s) influences the lower one(s) in a cascade: macro to meso to micro; global to European to national to regional to urban to local. It sees network relationships as existing across all these scales at the same time and thus tracing the connections will necessarily and repeatedly take the analyst to and from the localised site. Tait’s work (2002) on central–local relations in plan-making makes good use of this aspect of ANT. The work of forging and stabilising (always temporarily) relationships within networks is done by intermediaries or – a more active term – mediators. Callon (1991, p. 135) sets out four types of intermediary: “texts or more generally literary inscriptions (books, articles, patents, notes); technical artefacts (scientific instruments, machines, robots, consumer goods); human beings and the skills, knowledge and know-how that they incorporate; and money in all its different forms.” So the agency in the network is provided by these mediators bringing actors into association with each other, a process that is called ‘enrolment’. Enrolment is also one of the four stages proposed by Callon (1986) as a framework for analysing network dynamics. Before enrolment can take place, the focus of the network is determined by problematisation – the identification of the focal problem – and actors have to be gathered as potential network participants, a process called interessment. Enrolment then follows, with Callon particularly identifying the way that mediators can persuade actors that it is in their interests to associate with each other. The final stage is then mobilisation, in which the further actors are made active through their relationships within the network (see also Murdoch, 1997). The entire process through these four stages is called translation, a term that sounds like linguistic rewording or reframing; while this can be an important facet of all four stages, translation is a much broader dynamic, more akin to the mathematical meaning of the term: “To translate is to displace” (Callon, 1986, p. 75). Translation forges and stabilises the networks of ANT but it also plays a particular role in actually generating actors and their identities. Translation enables 304

Actor-Network Theory

actors to speak, act and represent others through defining their roles vis-à-vis each other. It links characteristics to entities and establishes provisionally stable relations between them. In this way, actors’ identities, the possibilities of interaction and the scope for manoeuvre are all negotiated and delimited (Ren et al., 2012). The role of mediators which “transform, translate, distort and modify the meaning or elements they are supposed to carry” is central to this dynamic (Latour, 2005, p. 39). ANT, therefore, does not attribute any essence to actors so that they come to be – to have identities, characteristics and functions – through the associations they are engaged with: “as entities come to be enrolled, combined, and disciplined within networks so they gain shape and function” (Murdoch, 1997, p. 741). And if they resist enrolment, this too alters identities and functions. Thus a ‘community’ involved in networks being built around an urban regeneration project is not a pre-existing entity but formed through the network-building. This helps explain why ‘this’ kind of community, with its specific social character, becomes part of the urban regeneration effort. The account of network dynamics so far could apply to many relational perspectives. Where ANT and also assemblage thinking differ is that they include non-human elements as actors. This is the so-called symmetry principle, whereby human and non-human actors are treated equally within the analysis. Latour (2005) goes further at times to suggest this means actors are always both human and non-human. Latour coined the term actant to cover this but the jointly human and non-human nature of actants can be difficult to operationalise and so the distinction is commonly maintained. Pickering gives a good account of the way in which human and non-human elements are “mutually and emergently productive” of each other (1993, p. 567). Non-human actants can take a variety of forms: animals, aspects of the physical environment such as rivers or mountains, technology including pipes and wires, and paper artefacts such as forms, files and plans. This is where the idea that the non-human can exercise agency comes in. However, following the above account it should be clear that it is not the actant that is imbued with agency but the relationships within the network that carry agency. Thus the argument is that associations with non-human actants can be agentive; although the language of some analysts can often suggest more direct agentive properties of material actants – even Latour himself (2005, p. 72). Turning the discussion of agency into one of power, individual actors or actants do not hold power as a resource. Rather, power is something that is distributed across the network, arising from how the relationships are formed and activated. For example, McGuirk’s analysis (2000) of property-led regeneration in Dublin emphasises the distributed nature of power. This aspect has led, as we will see, to the criticism that ANT does not recognise structures and inequalities of power within society. This basic account of ANT can be supplement by few more relevant concepts. First, the idea of a black box is taken from computing, where a complex set of transformations within a circuit is represented by a box and reduced to an overall relationship between input and output. As long as input and output are known, there is no perceived need to explain all the activities involved in transforming the former into the latter. ANT takes this idea and uses it to understand how some social transformations within a network are black-boxed so that the internal dynamics are never questioned. This idea of a black box can be applied in planning contexts to sustainability classification schemes for urban developments such as BREEAM (the UK BRE’s Environmental Assessment Method) or LEED (the US equivalent – Leadership in Energy and Environmental Design) (Spinks, 2015) or to the capturing of a building as a ‘high-rise’ with all that implies (Jacobs et al., 2007). 305

Yvonne Rydin

Black-boxing often involves calculation, as with the transformation of a complex set of characteristics of a city into an aggregated sustainability index or score. The processes of calculation play a relational role in bringing actors and material actants together but the black box of the sustainability metric then discourages people from asking how that metric was calculated, what relationships went into its calculation, and so on. Cost-benefit analysis and Landscape Assessment are other examples of quantitative and qualitative calculative exercises within planning and Collins et al. (2009) analyse ecological footprinting in these terms. Another useful concept is that of the inscription device or immutable mobile, an artefact that has stability but also centrally mobility and combinability (Murdoch, 1997, p. 742). Such immutable mobiles can take the form of black boxes and sometimes involve calculation. The key emphasis though is on how they can play a role in multiple locations; the materiality of these artefacts is often central to such mobility. Thus Tait and Jensen (2007) analyse the concepts of the Business Improvement District and urban village and how they are carried by key documents (artefacts), leading to mobility of the ideas. There are links here with the idea of a boundary object that can operate within different networks and thus opens up the possibility of new connections between networks. Star and Griesemer (1989) suggest that standardisation protocols often play an important role as boundary objects so that network-building and standardisation are inter-linked. In a planning context, one could see building regulations or standards, say for energy efficiency or broader sustainability, as performing this work, connecting construction, planning and design networks through their mobility, a mobility that does not threaten their form as fixed standards.

Modes of Researching and Arguing It is worthwhile spending a little time considering the distinctive nature of researching and arguing implied by an ANT perspective. In part this is because ANT is a perspective driven by a methodology informed by a specific conceptual understanding, rather than a fully fledged theory that invites empirical inquiry by a variety of means (see Ruming (2009) on the operationalisation of the methodology). ANT offers no causal hypotheses for empirical testing and so the outcome of analysis can seem rather circular in its reasoning (see Amsterdamska (1990) for such a critique). ANT has been heavily influenced by the anthropological background of its chief proponent, Latour. This suggests ethnography as the methodology of choice, involving the researcher’s immersion in the context being studied and a willingness to observe and absorb actors’ perceptions and practices through observation, although other means of tracing associations (such as document analysis) might be appropriate. Latour also describes ANT as “a very crude method to learn from the actors without imposing on them an a priori definition of their world-building capacities” (1999b, p. 20). This has led to the famous ANT dictum that the researcher should ‘follow the actor’ or actant (Latour, 2005, p. 12). So ANT research involves identifying a starting point – a social actor such as a planner or developer or a material actant such as a planning application form, a site or a water flow – and then building the network by tracing the associations outwards. The networks are followed rather than mapped in any fixed and formal way. The result should be a rich description of actants and their associations, how they come to be in relation to each other, how the relationships become stable and ordered (or not), and the implications of these relationships. Such a narrative depends heavily on the skill of the researcher, both in tracing the associations and also telling the story of the network in an interesting and convincing way. This is not a methodology that can just be followed step-bystep for its successful implementation. Discretion and choice remain at the core of an ANT 306

Actor-Network Theory

methodology, implying that two researchers might come up with different accounts of a network that they both choose to trace, starting from a different actant and finding a different story to tell. The ANT field of knowledge will then comprise the collectivity of such stories and not competition between alternative stories for the ‘true’ account. The relational and constructivist heart of ANT applies to itself as well as its object of study. This does not mean that all ANT accounts are necessarily a contribution to knowledge; some accounts might be poorly done and some might be more true than others. There is still scope for debate between ANT researchers on the relative insights to be gained from their accounts. Latour is clear that current notions of explanation as following on from description and being essentially different are wrong: Explanation does not follow from description; it is description taken that much further. We do not look for a stabilized and simplified description before we begin to propose an explanation … it is from them [the actors] and them alone that we extract any “cause” we might need. (1991, p. 121) Callon makes a similar point: Some will say that I have offered a methodology for describing [his case] and their asymmetries, but not a theoretical framework for their explanation. But the opposition between description and explanation is in large part undermined by the method I have proposed. The more convergent and less reversible a network, the more the descriptions delivered by the intermediaries turn into explanations or predictions. Talk of explanation assumes that network evolution can be described using a small number of variables or concepts. But this requires a very strong assumption about the shape of the network and the convergence of its translation. (1991, p. 154) The emphasis on contingency in ANT analyses is also at odds with the search for generalisations. Callon makes this clear: “networks only stabilise at certain places and at certain times” so that it does not make sense to look for regularities and laws (1991, p. 155). Confusion can also arise from the richly metaphoric nature of the language deployed (see Fine (2005) for a failure to appreciate this). As indicated above, the term network is used to convey something about the understanding of connections between actants. It is not a mathematical graph (although some analysts, including Latour himself, have utilised networks graphs as heuristic snapshots). Rather the term ‘network’ was the result of a search for an insightful term in a particular analysis at a particular time. This metaphor could be replaced by another and often is. The key lesson here is that the language of an ANT analysis matters, not because it is ‘right’ or ‘wrong’ but because it carries the import of the analysis.

Critiques and Responses ANT has certainly not been without its critics. These criticisms can be summarised as focusing on the symmetry between human and non-human actors, the treatment of structure, the approach to power and the inability to underpin a normative agenda for change. Taking the vexed questions of the agency of the material and whether or not some primacy should be given to human agency, there are two aspects to consider. First, there is the argument 307

Yvonne Rydin

that human actors are essentially different to non-human actants because they have motivation, intentions and, one might add, consciences and a sense of ethics. Second, it can further be argued that means human actors are in a position to take action for social ends, including the goal of reducing inequality and addressing structural imbalances of power. Murdoch (1997) recognises that many ANT theorists are not interested in ideas of intentionality or motivation. But there is scope for handling these with ANT. ANT requires human or social and non-human/material elements to be treated equally within the analysis; it sees agency as resulting from relationships between actants and does not distinguish those involving the material from those involving the social. This does not mean that ANT assumes the social/ human and the material are the same; it is capable of accepting that humans are different from material elements. As DeLanda (2006) states clearly (from an ANT-inspired assemblage perspective) only humans can have motivations or intentions in a social setting. In planning contexts, motivations and intentions ‘to plan’ are central and thus they can be built into the analysis of how different actants (human and material) are associated to generate outcomes. Pickering proposes a way of looking at the agency of the human and non-human through the temporal dimension. He argues that material agency is temporally emergent in practice, i.e. it is “never decisively known in advance” but has to emerge through resistances (1993, p. 564). Because human agency involves intentionality, this also has a temporal dimension: “we humans live in time in a particular way. We construct goals that refer to presently nonexistent future states and then seek to bring them about” (1993, p. 566). Such intentionality exists on a longer time-scale than the practices of resistance. Given the way that timescales are inherent to planning practice, this might offer a fruitful way of characterising human and non-human agency in planning studies. Turning to the treatment of structure within the analysis, it is clear from the above account of ANT as rooted in an ethnographic methodology that it begins from micro-description, of necessity at the most local scale. But the flat ontology that ANT espouses implies attention to associations across scale. The macro-scale is not ignored but the idea of ‘structure’ as an entity only existing at the macro-scale is not relevant. For some, the loss of a structural dimension to an analytic account means the loss of a proper understanding of how power operates and societal inequalities are produced. And, further, without such an understanding – it is argued – it becomes impossible to consider how measures might be taken to redress such inequality, to make a contribution to critical studies. Law acknowledges that ANT can “miss out on the ways in which the great distributions are laid down and sustained” (1991a, p. 14). Interestingly he suggests this arises because of “its propensity to select heroes for deconstruction” (ibid.). He is proposing that because ANT studies have tended to focus on cases where networks have been stabilised and the agency of network relationship demonstrated, this has led it to overlook distributional outcomes. Star makes a related point, arguing that ANT tends to focus on higher-status social actors alongside the material; thus, ANT looks at the role of the scientist and the material elements in the laboratory but not the janitor (1991, p. 33). She suggests that the impact of this is personal and that exclusion from a stabilised network ‘hurts’: “A stabilized network is only stable for some . . . And part of the public stability of a standardized network often involves the private suffering of those who are not standard”. Focusing particularly on the implications of societal standards, she sees the imposition of standards on those who are not part of the stabilised standard-setting network as “annihilating our personal experience, and there is suffering” (p. 48). This is a novel take on the way that ANT analysis can miss the experience of weaker, excluded sections of society. Star then offers a potential solution, suggesting that analysts should pay attention to the nonuser, the as-yet-unlabelled: “that which is permanently escaping, subverting, but nevertheless in 308

Actor-Network Theory

relationship with the standardized” (1991, p. 39). So she wants a wider appreciation of experience beyond that suggested by the standardised (powerful) network. What and who lie just beyond this network but are impacted by it? She suggests that this would involve ‘splitting’ by which she means recognition of multiple network memberships and zones of ambiguity, making space for multivocality and allowing for the costs of this (p. 49). This would acknowledge the centrality of marginality to the experience of many. She points out (p. 43) that “heuristic flattening does not mean the same thing as empirical ignoring of differences in access or experience.” These are key lessons here for all planning research that wishes to include the voice of the marginalised in society. Stabilisation centrally is linked to the exercise of power across networks. For Latour (1991), power and stabilisation are descriptions of states that have come into being: “Power and domination are the words given to those stabilizations and not an account of their coming into being. They are only one possible state of the associations” (p. 123). Furthermore, “When actors and points of view are aligned, then we enter a stable definition of society that looks like domination. When actors are unstable and the observers’ points of view shift endlessly we are entering a highly unstable and negotiated situation in which domination is not yet exerted” (p. 129). Star (1991) sees power in terms of things becoming accepted and of creating irreversibilities (such as certain standards): “Irreversibility is clearly important for an analysis of power and of robustness in networks” (p. 40). In robust, irreversible networks, knowledge in particular becomes stripped of its contingency and thus of its ability to be challenged. This is an unnegotiable aspect of ANT; the way it sees power as distributed among multiple relationships between actors and actants. Latour (2005) makes it clear that power is not a stock, reservoir or capital: “Power and domination have to be produced, made up and composed” (p. 64). Or again, the power of society is “some sort of summary for all the entities already mobilized to render asymmetries longer lasting” (p. 68). There are links here to the Foucauldian approach to power; Law pairs Latour and Foucault, arguing that: “These writers want to reverse a long-standing convention in social theory which assumes the unequal distribution of power and as a consequence tends to ignore or conceal the techniques, strategies or ‘microphysics’ by which it is created” (1991b, p. 169). Murdoch also agrees that Latour takes a Foucauldian perspective on power in which forms of domination and control are established within multiple and complex associations or networks, where power lies not in the properties of actors but in the relations established between them. Power thus emerges as an outcome once the translations are complete and the networks are stabilised. (1997, p. 737) For Law, this makes it difficult to talk about the distribution of power in a conventional sociological way. But he does propose an alternative pathway for research interested in power. He thus recasts the question, from a relational perspective, as: “for me the crucial research question has to do with how it is that relations are stabilised for long enough to generate the effects and so the conditions of power. Or, indeed, what ‘for long enough’ might mean” (1991b, p. 172). For some, the radical symmetry of ANT and its proposed methodology seem to render it lacking as a critical mode of analysis and unable to support a normative agenda, say for ethical ends such as reduced inequality. This view might be answered by saying that ANT was never intended to do all these things, that there is no requirement for a theoretical perspective to be radical in terms of critiquing existing power structures or linked to very specific goals of reducing inequality or poverty or addressing environmental impacts. But leaving this to one side, it is possible to argue that an ANT analysis could address some of these concerns. 309

Yvonne Rydin

First, there are considerable analytic merits in deriving a thick description of situations. This enables one to understand how multiple relationships are involved in creating and sustaining (or not) that situation. It avoids crude and simplistic accounts that see a very small set of factors as determining a situation. Such a perspective does not lend itself to simple policy solutions. It does not identify a specific lever as operating across cases in ways that suggest policy option for changing or replacing that lever. Neither does it identify a specific actor or set of actors as holding power so that better outcomes could be achieved by removing their power. ANT does imply a critique of its own with regard to such simplistic approaches which, one might argue, are typical of both empiricist and political economy approaches. Rather, ANT analyses will tend to emphasise the specifics of each case – a transport project, a neighbourhood plan, strategic direction of economic activity, a resource conservation initiative – and consider how outcomes are contingent on the sets of relationships involved. Achieving change from this perspective involves thinking about how those relationships might be altered in that specific context. Could new actants be enrolled and to what effect? How might an artefact change modes of calculation and to what effect? This might seem too localised a way to achieve change but ANT does offer a way of thinking actively about achieving change that can travel across situations; it just does not offer a solution that can travel. Thus ANT implies ‘small work’ but not exclusively local work. It might seem that what is proposed is not proportionate to the problems that we face. Poverty, environmental degradation, social anomie require more than these multiple instances of adjusting associations in specific contexts. This might be true but ANT implies that this is all that is on offer.

Future Directions As this chapter has stressed, ANT is a broad church and there are many different analysts exploring its application in new areas, often far from the original issue of how scientific knowledge is constructed. This means predicting where ANT scholarship will go can be a tricky exercise. This chapter has sought to make the claim that ANT has much to offer planning scholarship. In conclusion, I would like to suggest areas that seem particularly likely to be fruitful for future research. Two of these relate primarily to analyses of current planning practice; two take on board the challenge of developing a normative, even radical agenda from an ANT perspective. While most planning research has focused on the interaction of social actors – communities, developers, landowners, planners themselves – ANT draws our attention to material artefacts. This is one of its distinctive characteristics that might be able to offer something new to planning scholarship. There are two possible directions here: considering the artefacts of planning and reconsidering the relationship of planning practice to the natural environment. Thinking of the artefacts of planning first, it is perhaps surprising that these have not been explicitly considered to a greater extent. Planning departments and consultancies are full of these: plans, planning application forms, files, models, etc. What is their role? How do they shape planning practice? How do they act as mediators? How do they help enrol other actors and on what terms? A particular aspect of the role of artefacts to consider is how they shape calculation. Planning is about decision-making on particular projects, on future visions. This is a calculative exercise in itself but so often within planning practice there are tools and assessments along the way that contribute to this decision-making. Among these we can count: cost-benefit analysis, risk assessment, environmental assessment (both project-specific impacts and strategic), habitat assessment, sustainability indicators, widely used standards such as ALARP (As Low As Reasonably Practical) or BPEO (Best Practicable Environmental Option) within pollution control, the use 310

Actor-Network Theory

of building standards for energy based on the Standard Assessment Procedure (SAP), the accreditation systems of BREEAM, LEED, etc. And so on . . .. It is extraordinary how many aids to calculation there are, all constituted through artefacts of manuals, software, etc. Many of these have quantitative dimensions, others are more qualitative. The detailed operation of these calculative artefacts would be a major contribution to understanding how planning works. There has been scholarship within the Foucauldian tradition that has seen these as shaped by and shaping discourses, but ANT would provide a more nuanced account of how these tools are implicated in the networks of planning. The other area where the distinctive focus on materiality has much to offer planning research concerns the natural environment. While planning practice is obviously involved with the natural environment, this has tended to be considered in modernist terms as the control of the environment by planning systems. ANT invites a different perspective. It asks how the materiality of the environment shapes planning practice and, in particular, how knowledge of environmental systems is involved and makes a difference. Again, this goes beyond the Foucauldian perspective on environmental knowledge as power, seeing it as constructed through discourse. Rather, ANT takes the resistance of the material environment to knowledge construction seriously and looks to how this resistance, alongside the social construction dynamics, influences planning outcomes. This could provide a new perspective on planning for sustainability, looking at nuanced engagements between social and material actants in pursuit of nature conservation, circularity of resource use, pollution prevention and so on. Looking more toward the ways that an ANT analysis can support a progressive normative agenda regarding planning practice, two areas look particularly fruitful: the role of path dependencies and silences; and the scope for specifying directed agency through procedural innovations. ANT has been criticised for describing current situations rather than provide an account of change. It might be fairer to say that ANT can helpfully identify how planning networks are stabilised and the work involved in such stabilisation. This can be turned to advantage. ANT can provide a means for understanding path dependencies, where stabilised networks are actively maintained. Rather than just identify the path dependency, ANT could help understand how they work. Given that such patterns are ‘taken for granted’ and usually not actively discussed (this being part of the way they are maintained), ANT’s ability to understand silences through processes such as black-boxing could be helpful. This then has programmatic potential by suggesting points of pressure for breaking associations or creating new associations in such a way as to disrupt the established pathway. While the world of planning practice might seem a crowded one with many stakeholders, goals and dimensions to consider, this emphasis on silences and path dependencies would search for avenues that have not been fruitfully explored. Finally, there is clearly a need to understand more fully exactly how ANT analysis can lead to directed action – through alternative network building – for progressive change. Creating new or different networks can be difficult. It has been suggested that this might occur through many cases of ‘small work’ encouraging new associations in a variety of ways but this is subtle work (Rydin and Tate, 2016). To be effective this would require much more guidance on how practitioners can come to understand their practice in network terms and then build effective action on the back of that understanding. The more ANT case studies of different areas of planning practice that can be conducted with a view to not just understanding but also acting, the closer ANT will come to a normative planning theory. Such links can also be fostered by considering the implications of ANT thinking for the procedural innovations that planning theory has emphasised, notably those based on deliberation. As other chapters in this volume identify, deliberation as a practice and deliberative democracy 311

Yvonne Rydin

as an ideal have been hugely influential within planning theory. Latour has considered modes of politics that could fit with the radical symmetry of ANT under the banner of a Parliament of Things, suggesting an enhanced form of deliberation that includes the ‘voices’ of material and environmental elements. This has opened up a fresh avenue of debate about the value of deliberation. For Marres, this is a wrong turning, since the emphasis on procedural models is at odds with the insights of ANT itself. She sees ANT as committed to following practices as they are made and thus the effects of a given procedural model cannot be assumed nor any such model generally recommended (2007, p. 763). However, Whiteside (2013) sees the potential for a much more productive engagement between ANT and deliberative democracy, which might lead to a re-invigoration of normative planning theory and, indeed, wider political theory. Thus ANT has much to offer planning studies. It can provide a detailed relational account of how links and associations generate outcomes, create stabilised situations and give rise to power (understood as distributed agency). In this it has much in common with other post-modern relational approaches but it also provides a rich ‘toolbox’ of concepts that can be useful to the researcher in exploring these links and associations in specific cases. ANT’s most innovative (and perhaps contentious) aspect is its insistence on treating social and material, human and non-human actants equally. This opens up new avenues of research and allows a spotlight to be shone on planning practices that practitioners (often implicitly) know involve the material or non-human but researchers have tended to treat only in social terms. The possibilities this affords are exciting but also challenging. Not only does using ANT involve some considerable investment in understanding and learning to use its ‘toolbox’ but the kinds of narrative that emerge require the audience to accept new models of empirical investigation and knowledge generation. With openness to the possibilities of such narratives, though, ANT can offer new insights and enhance planning scholarship.

References Amsterdamska, O. (1990) “Surely you are joking, Monsieur Latour!” Science, Technology and Human Values 15(4) 495–504. Brownill, S. (2016) “Assembling Localism: practices of assemblage and building the ‘Big Society’ in Oxfordshire, England”, in Y. Rydin and L. Tate (eds) Materiality and Planning: exploring the influence of Actor-Network Theory, London: Routledge, pp. 79–94. Callon, M. (1986) “Some elements of a sociology of translation: domestication of the scallops and the fishermen of St. Brieuc Bay”, in J. Law (ed.) Power, Action, Belief: a new sociology of knowledge? Sociological Review Monograph No. 32, London: Routledge, pp. 57–78. Callon, M. (1991) “Techno-economics networks and irreversibility”, in J. Law (ed.) A Sociology of Monsters: essays on power, technology and domination, Sociological Review Monograph No. 38, London: Routledge, pp. 132–163. Collins, A., Cowell, R. and Flynn, A. (2009) “Evaluation and environmental governance: the institutionalisation of ecological footprinting”, Environment and Planning A 41 1707–1725. Collins, H. and Evans, R. (2002) “The third wave of science studies: studies of expertise and experience”, Social Studies of Science 32(2) 235–296. DeLanda, M. (2006) A New Philosophy of Society: assemblage theory and social complexity, London: Bloomsbury. Farias, I. and Bender, T. (2009) Urban Assemblages: how actor-network theory changes urban studies, London: Routledge. Feldman, M. and Pentland, B. (2005) “Organizational routines and the macro-actor”, in B. Czarniawska and T. Hernes (eds) Actor Network Theory and Organizing, Copenhagen: Business School Press, pp. 91–111. Fine, B. (2005) “From actor-network theory to political economy”, Capitalism, Nature, Socialism 16(4) 91–108. Guy, S., Sherriff, G., Goodier, C. and Chmutina, K. (2016) “Assembling energy futures: seawater district heating in The Hague, Netherlands”, in Y. Rydin and L. Tate (eds) Materiality and Planning: exploring the influence of Actor-Network Theory, London: Routledge, pp. 142–156.

312

Actor-Network Theory Jacobs, J., Cairns, S. and Strebel, I. (2007) “‘A tall storey … but, a fact just the same’: the Red Road highrise as a black box”, Urban Studies 44(3) 609–629. Latour, B. (1991) “Technology is society made durable”, in J. Law (ed.) A Sociology of Monsters: essays on power, technology and domination, Sociological Review Monograph No. 38, London: Routledge, pp. 103–131. Latour, B. (1993) The Pasteurization of France, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Latour, B. (1999a) Pandora’s Hope: essays on the reality of science studies, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Latour, B. (1999b) “On recalling ANT”, in J. Law and J. Hassard (eds) Actor Network Theory and After, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 15–25. Latour, B. (2005) Reassembling the Social: an introduction to actor-network-theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Latour, B. and Yaneva, A. (2008) “Give me a gun and I will make all buildings move: an ANT’s view of architecture”, Explorations in Architecture 80–89. Law, J. (1991a) “Introduction: monsters, machines and sociotechnical relations,” in J. Law (ed.) A Sociology of Monsters: essays on power, technology and domination Sociological Review Monograph No. 38, London: Routledge, pp. 1–25. Law, J. (1991b) “Power, discretion and strategy,” in J. Law (ed.) A Sociology of Monsters: essays on power, technology and domination Sociological Review Monograph No. 38, London: Routledge, pp. 165–191. Marres, N. (2007) “The issues deserve more credit: pragmatist contributions to the study of public involvement in controversy”, Social Studies of Science 37(5) 759–780. McGuirk, P. (2000) “Power and policy networks in urban governance: local government and property-led regeneration in Dublin”, Urban Studies 37(4) 651–672. Mol, A. (2002) The Body: multiple ontology in medical practice, Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Murdoch, J. (1997) “Inhuman/nonhuman/human: actor-network theory and the prospects for a nondualist and symmetrical perspective on nature and society”, Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 15 731–756. Murdoch, J. (1998) “The spaces of actor-network theory”, Geoforum 29(4) 357–374. Murray Li, T. (2007) “Practices of assemblage and community forest management”, Economy and Society 36(2) 263–293. Pickering, A. (1993) “The mangle of practice: agency and emergence in the sociology of science”, American Journal of Sociology 99(3) 559–569. Ren, C., Jόhannesson, G.T. and van der Duim, R. (2012) “How ANT works”, in G.T. Jόhannesson, R. van der Duim and C. Ren (eds) ANT and Tourism: ordering, materiality and multiplicity, London: Routledge, pp. 13–25. Ruming, K. (2009) “Following the actors: mobilising an actor-network theory methodology in geography”, Australian Geographer 40(4) 451–469. Rydin, Y. (2012) “Using Actor-Network Theory to understand planning practice: exploring relationships between actants in regulating low-carbon commercial development”, Planning Theory 12(1) 23–45. Rydin, Y. and Tate, L. (eds) (2016) Materiality and Planning: exploring the influence of Actor-Network Theory, London: Routledge. Spinks, M. (2015) “Understanding and actioning BRE environmental assessment method: a socio-technical approach”, Local Environment 20(2) 131–148. Star, S.L. (1991) “Power, technologies and the phenomenology of conventions: on being allergic to onions”, in J. Law (ed.) A Sociology of Monsters: essays on power, technology and domination, Sociological Review Monograph No. 38, London: Routledge, pp. 26–56. Star, S.L. and Griesemer, J.R. (1989) “Institutional ecology, translations and boundary objects: amateurs and professionals in Berkeley’s Museum of Vertebrate Zoology, 1907–1939”, Social Studies of Science 19(3) 387–420. Tait, M. (2002) “Room for manoeuvre? An actor-network study of central-local relations in development plan making”, Planning Theory and Practice 3(1) 69–85. Tait, M. and Jensen, O. (2007) “Travelling ideas, power and place: the cases of urban villages and Business Improvement Districts”, International Planning Studies 12(2) 107–128. Tate, L. (2013) “Growth-management implementation in Metropolitan Vancouver: lessons from actornetwork theory”, Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design 40(5) 783–800. Whiteside, K.H. (2013) “A representative politics of nature? Bruno Latour on collectives and constitutions”, Contemporary Political Theory 12 185–201.

313

25 SPATIAL PLANNING AND THE COMPLEXITY OF TURBULENT, OPEN ENVIRONMENTS About Purposeful Interventions in a World of Non-Linear Change Gert de Roo

About Planning, a Biased Mindset and the Idea of Change What planners should know: revolution and evolution are as real and essential to life as water and air. Traditionally, planners’ concerns are about effectively intervening in space and place, hence the desire for controlled environments. Since the 1990s, planners have also preferred to act on the basis of consensus among the various parties involved to attain an agreed-upon world. Revolution, evolution or whatever kind of change is current is usually not part of a planner’s ideas about what the world should look like. Here we challenge the suggestion of a controlled world and an agreed reality. The message here is that aside from controlled environments, we should also accept that our daily environments can be full of unintended, autonomous and surprising change. We would be wise to live by this understanding, whether we like it or not. In this chapter we will construct a kind of reasoning that is supportive of this alternative frame of reference. We will argue that discontinuous change is the only constant factor in the world we are part of, and what seems stable to us is actually nothing more than a temporary period of persistence, a frozen instant within a dynamic world, the lee side of a world in flux. As there is no permanent stability, how can we reach an ideal situation? Instead, we have to acknowledge that tensions, frictions, mismatches and breaks will be more or less ever-present (de Roo, 2016a; Weinstock, 2010). This means we continuously have to consider and reconsider how the world around us is ‘becoming’, and to what it is we have to adapt (de Roo, 2012; Hillier, 2007). This understanding is fundamental: instead of the planner being the creator of space and place, we are acknowledging that the world also creates itself, often develops beyond our control and progresses autonomously despite our intentions. It might be worth considering planners as guides to coping with autonomous and non-linear change. This contribution starts by exploring the meanings and background of the relevant ideas in this discussion, such as non-linearity, complexity and uncertainty. Together, these notions represent the complexity sciences, processes of discontinuous change and evolutionary pathways through time. We will see, among other things, how these notions can be instrumental to the 314

Spatial Planning and Complexity

evolution of settlements. This route to transforming settlements will be framed by an evolutionary model that not only explains the transformation of settlements as complex adaptive systems, but also frames the transformative space at the edge of order and chaos. Consequently, we will see how transformations and bifurcations can be understood as mechanisms of non-linearity and change. Finally, this contribution confronts contemporary planning theory with our set of ideas from the complexity sciences and our evolutionary model, and how the model frames reality in a non-linear and transformative way. It will demonstrate the relevance of a non-linear, transformative and dynamic understanding to the planning debate.

Time, Non-Linearity and the Complexity Sciences I would argue 1963 is the year that certainty lost its absolute sense on a human scale and its supremacy as the route of knowledge to which science contributes. In this year, Edward Lorenz (1917–2008), mathematician and meteorologist, published an article that had tremendous impact on science as well as on our view of the world. In the 1950s meteorologists, like all other scientists at that time, struggled with models based on mathematical formulae which were relatively simple and which straightforwardly described a reality that behaves decently, and in orderly and predictable ways. Meteorologists were meant to predict the weather correctly, and their systematic approach was initially linear. Linear primarily means proportional. Weather does not show proportional change, which made Lorenz go for an alternative systems approach that resonates better with our daily environment responding non-linearly and therefore unpredictably. Using a non-linear model, Lorenz (1963) noticed a strong deviation in results when repeating his calculations using the same input. He used the same data, but with a different number of decimals. Instead of using 76.853 over and over again, he used a shorter version as well: 76.8. This small difference entered at the beginning of the calculations resulted in output that cannot be expected in a linear and proportional world. Dynamic and iterative models, however, are able to produce major differences between inputs that hardly differ. Such effects result from a circular causality which became known as the ‘Butterfly effect’, a metaphor for a small event (a butterfly flapping its wings) triggering turbulence that, at some point, evolves into devastating forces (a hurricane). This discovery is substantial and fundamental: it means the end of exactness and the claim of certainty. In 1975 Li and Yorke coined the term ‘chaos’ to label non-linear deterministic systems and their unpredictable behaviour. The academic interest in a contextual and dynamic world rapidly increased in the 1990s (Waldrop, 1992). Various fields of research were grouped together as the complexity sciences (Keller, 2009), including Chaos theory. Currently there is a wide range of research streams focusing on non-linearity, such as self-organization (de Roo, 2016a; Portugali, 2000), coevolution (Garnsey & McGlade, 2006), socioecological systems (Holling, 2001; Kauffman, 1990), resilience (Davoudi, 2012; Folke, 2006), transitions (Geels, 2013) and complex adaptive systems (Cilliers, 1998; de Roo, 2012; Miller & Page, 2007). All these ideas share a common reference to a world that is open, multilayered and dynamic, and which behaves in a non-linear and unpredictable way. These ideas beg for an alternative world view. In this world view systems are, to various degrees, open to change in a reciprocal relationship with their environment. Instead of considering situations and systems as being permanent and stable, they are temporal and in a continuous state of becoming (de Roo, 2010, 2012). To survive the system has to interact with, adapt to and coevolve with its environment. This interdependency has consequences that depend on the dynamics of the environment varying from being placid to turbulent 315

Gert de Roo

(Emery & Trist, 1965), and which depend on the flow of energy, matter and information between environment and system (Prigogine, 1980). The ordering principle – so much the focus of the planner – is no longer order, balance or symmetry. Instead the focus shifts to change and transformation (de Roo & Silva, 2010; de Roo, Hillier & Van Wezemael, 2012; de Roo, 2015). The complexity sciences have concentrated extensively on understanding how this change might happen, to what this change will lead and what this tells us in abstract (Pagels, 1988). At various levels of scale we can see a flow of energy, matter and information. This flow is more than a Newtonian response of action and reaction in isolation, and a repositioning of some body, node or entity. These flows do not leave systems untouched. At the macro level we can see an environment of multiple systems interacting in such a way that patterns emerge (Allen, 1997, 2016). The individual system (or agent) in search of a fit with its environment deviates toward such patterns, independently from other systems and unintentionally adding to the presence of these patterns. The system’s search for a good fit – a city, for example – goes hand-in-hand with the system adapting to its environment. This has consequences for the system internally, within which a process of self-organization is triggered, through which structure and function might coevolve into something new, resulting in a change of the system’s identity and functioning. For our story it is important to consider thermodynamics, the weather, population dynamics and cities and their development as representations of the same type of system, all behaving in the same way: non-linearly and dynamically. Traditionally, science focuses on isolated entities, systems and situations, taking into consideration the parts out of which these are formed. This is helpful in understanding these entities, systems and situations as they ‘are’, and is supportive of understanding their structures and functions, and content and process (Prigogine, 1980). This reductionist approach brought us the universal laws in physics and chemistry. However, it kept us from considering entities, systems (also known as ‘complex adaptive systems’) and situations as being positioned in an environment that is ‘out of equilibrium’; and it does not say much about them undergoing change, this change being the consequence of energy, matter and information floating around and being passed on, allowing fluxes, flows and potentialities to exist, and generating progressive dynamics (Prigogine, 1980). This is particularly the case in biosphere environments, where matter, energy and information conjoin to evolve into living creatures and all that comes with that: ecological, social and economic networks, and sociospatial structures ranging from termite hills to urban agglomerations.

Settlements as Non-Linear Dynamic Systems Van der Leeuw (2009), archaeologist by origin, adopts a non-linear perspective, which he describes as ‘the archaeology of innovation’, to elaborate on how humans have created a socialized environment. Central to this reasoning are humans absorbing energy from their environment to become organized and to socialize, ensuring a shared capacity for information processing, an activity out of which societies emerge (Figure 25.1(b)). Far back in time, humans had the option to adapt to the conditions they were confronted with, taking resources (matter and energy) from their environment to stay alive until these ran out, after which moving was the only option. Around 10,000 bc, groups increased in size and started living together in settlements, beginning to cultivate their environment. It meant they started investing in their environment, securing an organized living, reducing nature-related risks and working with an increased energy production capacity. As settlements grew, societal problems increased, and institutional responses were needed to solve them. Institutional arrangements did not just enable life in settlements; their organizational effects began to extend 316

Spatial Planning and Complexity Resource oriented

Object oriented focus

ENERGY: affluent – constrained MATTER: elementary – composition INFORMATION: explicit – induced

CAUSALITY: direct – remote ENTITY: clear – fuzzy CONTEXT: stable – unstable Communicative rationality

Technical rationality

Axiomtic behaviour

Capacity building SHARING: well defined – conceptual ORGANIZING: routine – collaborative LEARNING: prescriptive – explorative

PERSPECTIVE: unifocal – plural CONSENSUS: implicit – explicit STORYTELLING: explaining – exploring

Collective oriented

Intersubjective reasoning

Figure 25.1  (a) A transformative model in between planner’s rationalities (de Roo, 2015, 2016b); (b) The transformative model of the evolutionary patterns of clustering society (de Roo, 2016b). For explanation, see text.

into their wider environment. This was rather essential as the difficulty of taking energy from the environment began to amount to a serious constraining factor. While the growth of individual settlements was constrained due to limited natural resources, it stimulated the emergence of groups of settlements. A new balance was found between the ability to share information among increasing numbers of groups and the dispersion of settlements to maintain their capacity for energy production. These groups of settlements and their institutional design required administrative structures, including methods for keeping accounts and records, which is only one step away from the emergence of a ruling class. Consequently, the capacity for information sharing increased as the footprint of settlements began to cross societal borders, with energy and material remaining the constraining factors. Unsurprisingly, infrastructure also began to be developed to secure access to resources. The moment printing technology became widely known, the sharing of knowledge exploded and the existence of different cultures and behaviours resulted not only in global trade routes but also in competing markets and monetized urban developments. A further increase in information sharing led to a rise of a global economic system and to civil society, which at some point stood up for its rights and for better living conditions. Innovations were no longer found within existing frames of reference, which focused on survival risks and resources. In the nineteenth century, thinking outside the box made innovations endemic, with an energy revolution, an industrial revolution and a technical and a scientific revolution which altered urban life fundamentally. A sequence of rapid changes in economic prosperity, social behaviour and cultural attitude led to what our world is today: a global village, with time and space shrinking fast; an urbanized way of life all over the planet, with schools as institutionalized knowledge-sharing nodes; the creation of surpluses in various ways, including through an amazing extension of property and life expectancy, and an unprecedented change in information sharing, due to the rise of the digital era. Today we find ourselves in a world of extremes, in which a strong belief in functionality and economic value burdens us with a narrow focus on life values and contextual influences, as a consequence of which we struggle (often happily) from one crisis to another. These crises are perhaps part of life, and while some might feel that crises must be avoided, crises are also occurrences that are quite ‘natural’ in a world we consider to be non-linear and dynamic. Central to this understanding of societal evolution is a balance between the ability to gain access to energy sources and the ability to share information among collectives and communities, to exploit and manage the availability of energy intelligently. Energy becomes available through processing matter, on the basis of experience. In this respect information is experience shared among many actors, who organize themselves in collectives, to optimize the shared information and to enhance their capacity to generate energy. Figure 25.1(b) presents a circular 317

Gert de Roo

and iterative evolutionary model that represents the sharing of energy, matter and information, and which challenges collectives to organize themselves to enable them to learn from the difficulties encountered. The moment a circular or iterative situation is confronted with a break, mismatch, crisis or barrier, society’s response is to require innovation. This could result in a great many different actions meant to secure or increase the capacity for access to energy, which results in additional, surplus or advanced information. This information would then be the result or the consolidation of the innovation society has experienced. If this is done successfully, society as such will evolve to a higher standard of living (see Figure 25.2); while failure will result in lower living standards. Whichever direction is followed, it will affect society’s settlements and their environments.

Framing Dynamics The evolutionary model (Figure 25.1(a)) represents the world at the edge of order and chaos. The model is built around a spectrum connecting these two extreme environments: on the left, an orderly environment, on the right an environment that is diverse – chaotic even – and full of uncertainty. The evolutionary model has a cognitive orientation, with the spectrum representing our mental capacity to understand the world as it comes to us: on the right, clarity and certainty – which we claim on the basis of a factual reality – versus fuzziness and uncertainty on the left, which forces us to relate to each other to create an agreed reality. When certainty diminishes and uncertainty cannot be ignored and is increasingly present, humans change their attitude toward how to consider the world around them. This finds expression in the shift on the spectrum from left to right: mentally, the intersubjective attitude gains the upper hand the moment our world becomes fuzzy, while our object orientation diminishes. Figure 25.1(b) on settlement development qualifies object orientation as ‘resource oriented’ and intersubjective interaction as ‘collective oriented’. In Figure 25.1(b) we have added to the ‘resource oriented’ triangle the conditions under which the system ‘lives’ while moving along the spectrum, explained in terms of content, process and context. In Figure 25.1(b) content, process and context are considered to be energy, matter and information. The same is done for the ‘collective oriented’ triangle, which includes the conditions under which actors perceive the system. It conditions them to come to a common understanding, which is explained in terms of perspectives, framing and acknowledgement. In Figure 25.1(b) perspectives, framing and acknowledgement are explained as sharing, organizing and learning. What we get out of this exercise is an understanding of the world at the edge of order and chaos, as it comes to us through the senses (object orientation – Figure 25.1(a)) and as it can be understood through the views of the various actors involved (intersubjective interaction – Figure 25.1(a)). A mutual relationship between what we observe and what we agree about how to see and value what we observe results in an understanding of what we perceive and a position about how to act. Out of this mutual relationship, a circular process of development emerges, as we can see in Van der Leeuw’s elegant explanation of human settlements. This circular process is acknowledged in Figure 25.1. As it moves along this circular path the world no longer remains the same. It has been enriched in a transformative way. We can call this change, growth, development or progress. It is relevant to recognize that such developments are expressed as iterative processes, feedback loops or rounds of progression (Coveney and Highfield, 1995). These iterative processes can be perceived as cognitive shifts from object orientation on a reality that becomes increasingly 318

Spatial Planning and Complexity

Figure 25.2  Transitions representing a coevolutionary process in a non-linear dynamic system

dynamic, fuzzy and interpretable, to the intersubjective interaction needed to get to grips again with reality, producing a new and shared storyline that includes lessons learned and offers guidance for taking actions. At some point we find ourselves back at the beginning and the round of progression can start again. However, we are not ‘exactly’ back where we started. Along the circle, things have changed. There has been progress and a new level of development has been reached (see Figure 25.2). The cycles of progress encounter enabling and constraining conditions that produce, feed and support a transition or bifurcation (See Figure 25.3), which consequently gives expression to the iterative process and the change occurring somewhere along the circle. This transition is a coevolutionary process in which the structure (object orientation) and function (intersubjective value) of what we observe will fundamentally change (de Roo & Rauws, 2012). And as a transformed construct it will continue to develop further at a new level of existence.

Bifurcations and Transitions A transition becomes feasible within the action space that is allowed by the frame of dynamic change. This frame is explained in detail for human settlements (Figure 25.1). The rounds of progression have also been discussed. These rounds of progression are the stepping stones to other levels of development. Within the complexity sciences, bifurcations and transformations are possible routes toward these other levels of development. A bifurcation is considered to be the moment the trajectory of a system encounters an unstable environment that is likely to lead to change in the system’s trajectory as well as to the system itself (Ruelle, 1989). The bifurcation is subject to a new kind of order within a chaotic environment: the bifurcation can go either way, but whatever the route, it will affect the system. The system will adapt to its new environment and therefore will change fundamentally. The uncertainty that comes with this adds to the non-linearity a system is confronted by while floating around in a dynamic environment. Our daily environment is full of change, transitions and bifurcations. Conditions allow or force this change to happen. Conditions both enable and constrain change. A couple of trajectories are presented in Figure 25.3, with bifurcations that relate to the presence of enabling and constraining conditions. 319

Gert de Roo



Figure 25.3  P  athways with moments of instability resulting in bifurcations as a consequence of enabling (ᴗ) and constraining ( ) conditions

The first example presents us with developments of residential areas, here labelled as ‘home vicinity ambience’. In the distant past there were hardly any regulations to secure liveable housing conditions. At the turn of the eighteenth century the urban was heavily constrained by diseases, including highly contagious cholera. This led various European countries to introduce legislation intended to prevent the spread of contagious diseases (Wagenaar, 2011). Consequently, housing programmes were established. This marked the beginning of serious spatial planning (De Klerk et al., 2012). While cholera can be regarded as the constraining factor, the new legislation proved to be an enabling factor for new and highly planned developments in support of much more than a healthy environment. While the planning regime remained throughout the twentieth century, various developments were made affecting the ‘home vicinity ambience’. Around the turn of the twenty-first century, another fundamental change emerged. In some countries this started relatively mildly with authorities and housing corporations no longer being able to ‘control’ or to guarantee environmental standards, and gestures and invitations were made to residents to take responsibility as well (Tonkens, 2014). The 2008 financial, housing and mortgage crisis made this desire only more prominent. While this crisis can be regarded as a constraint, enabling factors can also be observed with various residents collectively taking the initiative to explore, develop and maintain public space near their homes (Warren, 2009), resulting in collective gardening, urban food farming and so forth. Another example is the use of cars within the urban. At the turn of the nineteenth century, horse-drawn carriages were a common mode of transport. Horse manure, however, began to contribute substantially to cities becoming malodorous and unhealthy places (Wagenaar, 2011). The combustion engine made it possible to replace the horse with an alternative transport mode which did not leave any droppings behind. In the 1960s, mass production of cars exploded thanks to a rapidly emerging middle class. The rise of the car-driven society resulted in multiple car owners per family. In particular, in the US the lack of public transport companies (cleverly bought up by various car companies with the intention of bankrupting them in the period before the Second World War (Kunstler, 1993)) supported this process. The car was everywhere and people wanted to be able to go everywhere using their cars. Eventually, the car became a destructive force in urban life, with traffic jams, noise pollution, smog and a lack 320

Spatial Planning and Complexity

of recreation space. Even before the turn of the century, various strategies were proposed and implemented to restrain car use and constrain the omnipresence of the car, in particular in city centres and residential areas (Newman & Kenworthy, 1999). A response to some of the nuisance is the hybrid and electric car. It is likely that cars will soon be able to operate autonomously, without drivers, using sensors connected to the internet and interacting with their environment to keep on course. No doubt this will again result in a bifurcation and a fundamental change of our understanding of transport.

Complexity and the Planning Debate Cities coevolve, which means that they do not simply emerge from nowhere, grow linearly or come as the result of a planner’s ‘command and control’. Coevolution is the non-linear transformation of the various structures and functions of cities through which cities change physically and socially in fundamental, discontinuous ways (Shane, 2005; Weinstock, 2010). Throughout their evolution cities’ institutional realities will also be redesigned repeatedly. It is a course of discontinuous adjustment toward a fit between what communities value and the changes that emerge within the physical and social environment. Such a course will obviously also transform communities themselves. The result is an institutional design which – like any design – is strongly influenced by the societal and scientific perspectives championed and valued at any given moment. This is particularly visible in the domain of spatial planning. In 1969 Horst Rittel (1972), with Weber (Rittel & Weber, 1973; see also Ackoff, 1974), made a challenging contribution to the planning debate by introducing ‘wicked’ problems. ‘Wicked’ problems differ from ‘tamed’ problems, which are well defined, with a clear beginning that results in – if dealt with properly – a clear end, after which the problem is ‘solved’. ‘Wicked’ problems have no clear beginning and no clear end, they are hard to define precisely and undisputedly, and they cannot be solved. ‘Wicked’ problems are intrinsically uncertain. For example, when is the right moment to conclude a neighbourhood is in decline? At which point do we conclude that a city centre has too much car traffic? What is the effect of hypermarkets and factory outlet centres on inner city development? The answer is ‘We don’t know’, at least not exactly. Rittel’s ‘wicked’ problems did not make it into the mainstream planning debate. Perhaps they were not the right answer to the debate at that time, which was very much focusing on bounded rationality (Simon, 1960). ‘Wicked’ problems did not provide an answer to boundedness. On the contrary, they made the difficulty of boundedness even more complicated. The planning debate eventually took a ‘communicative turn’ (Fischer & Forester, 1993). The complexity sciences, however, rediscovered Rittel and embraced his ‘wicked’ problems fully (Conklin, 2005). Wickedness represents precisely the fundamental uncertainties that were observed by the complexity sciences in the real world: ‘wicked’ problems are a consequence of non-linear behaviour. The planning debate (Figure 25.1(a)) started in the 1950s with a technical rationale attitude: it builds on the assumption of certainty being within reach and capable of being understood by facts that are open to us – a factual reality. In the 1960s this attitude came under severe pressure, with various notions, methods and arguments being proposed to find realistic alternatives. The technical rationale proved to be an illusion, an ideal that would only work in theory. The more realistic alternatives were all still very much object oriented, assuming that certainty is still somewhere to be found, and aiming for it despite the fact that complete certainty will never be achieved. Humans are bounded (Simon, 1960), muddle through, behave incrementally (Lindblom, 1959) and are best advised to follow Etzioni’s mix-scan approach (Etzioni, 1967). Probably the best response at that time – in the 1970s now – was to replace the ideal of 321

Gert de Roo

a one true and certain world by various possible worlds. These were proposed and constructed through a process of scenario planning. The constructs were basically linear extrapolations of past developments. In the early 1990s the idea of certainty was set aside and replaced by the ‘communicative turn’ (Fischer & Forester, 1993; Forester, 1993). Quite suddenly the planning community was ready to become participative (Innes, 1995), interactive and collaborative (Healey, 2003). It was a major jump, a true paradigm shift, which brought us the communicative rationale (see Figure 25.1(a); Sager, 1994). This is a shift from goal maximization to optimizing processes. The communicative rationale brought us an agreed reality. This agreed reality creates an agreed certainty. This might be a different kind of certainty from the one promised to us within a technical rationale; however, it is something to hold on to, again. The communicative rationale also proved to be ideal and quite extreme in relation to everyday difficulties. The difference between the two is that a technical rationale attitude is valid in situations that are clear, certain and straightforward. Fuzzy, diverse and plural situations with multiple actors and their various interests are often decentralized to a level where these situations become manifest: integration of policies, approaches, responsibilities and actions is recommended in such cases. What effectively happens is a process of communication between stakeholders. In other words, integration – seemingly object oriented – will not work as a strategy without accepting a communicative rationale (Figure 25.1(a)). The communicative rationale works quite well in situations full of uncertainties due to the involvement of various interests, power relationships and multiple actors and factors. Communication strategies are intended to achieve consensus about the issues in question, the parties involved, their shared responsibilities, their actions and so forth: the construction of an agreed reality. The moment such an agreed reality is internalized and resonates effectively with events in the daily environment, clarity, straightforwardness and certainties begin to reappear, bringing a technical rationale again within reach . . . the circle is complete (see Figure 25.1(a)). In addition to the contemporary approaches in planning, we propose alternatives that relate to an autonomous, emergent, adaptive and self-organizing reality. In such unstable and dynamic realities planning issues should not be regarded as isolated problems or as difficulties that need to be agreed upon on the basis of consensus. Situations become manifest due to various pathways and their path-dependencies coming together at a particular moment. It would be strange to view such situations as fixed, frozen and utterly stable. Aside from content and process, it becomes relevant to consider what conditions such a spontaneous, emergent situation. Complexity reasoning does not provide clear-cut solutions (there are no clear-cut problems either), which requires another attitude toward planning and decision-making. This means being prepared to deconstruct traditional and contemporary views on planning (not that these become redundant or outdated), to constructing a new mindset on non-linear reasoning. This is the background against which spatial institutions, their organization, development and evolution can be viewed, accepting a dynamic environment at the edge of order and chaos. It is a radically different view from what we are used to.

Synopsis Certainty, the predictability of a future to come and the creation of a world according to plan, all these promises connect to scientific approaches that relate to logic-positivism: but they are an illusion. Nevertheless, it is a kind of planning that is still greatly appreciated. While it can no longer be regarded as a universal kind of planning, it is still relevant in a situational sense. It relates to situations in which certainty is not only thought of as a given but an essential 322

Spatial Planning and Complexity

condition: housing sites, building blocks, systems for energy, drinking water and waste disposal, infrastructure – we do not want these to collapse. Such situations require certainty and the avoidance of risk, but even in these situations, certainty is not a given. Moreover, even those practices that include blueprints, vertical decision-making lines and functionality as their guiding principles must acknowledge that reality is not always susceptible to planners’ proposals, assumptions and perspectives. Planning is also a social project with purposeful interventions intended to add value to a civil society (Sandercock, 1975). Through communication processes the need and appreciation of such interventions can be considered collectively. Collaborative approaches are meant to result in commonly defined and agreed-upon understandings of issues that could be dealt with via a planning regime. These agreements are particularly relevant in situations that are highly normative, fuzzy and unclear. Here, too, uncertainties cannot be ignored, which affects the planning process and drives it in unexpected directions. Complexity thinking and spatial planning seem almost antagonistic, a conflict of reasoning. Complexity labels theories of spontaneous change. Spatial planning relates to a science of purposeful intervention. At first glance a dichotomy, and at the very least paradoxical. For most planners, decision-makers and all those somehow involved in spatial interventions, reasoning in terms of complexity is not immediately their cup of tea. Some assume it is about issues being complex and therefore beyond their competences. Some stubbornly translate it into ‘being complicated’ and therefore ‘being problematic’, which – with a bit of luck, goodwill and a prayer – can be dealt with in due time. Complexity thinking has nothing to do with these assumptions and beliefs. Complexity relates above all to a world full of developments we can describe as non-linear. In such a world jumps, shocks and surprises are all part of the game, succeeded by periods of temporary stability. A non-linear understanding means we consider the world as undergoing discontinuous change, which is fundamentally uncertain, and which is and becomes manifest largely beyond our control. A non-linear, unstable and uncertain world is likely to be more real than a world that is stable, linear and certain. This does not mean that planners are being out-manoeuvred. On the contrary – non-linear situations require alternative approaches in addition to approaches that relate to factual, possible and agreed realities. Instead of focusing primarily on content and process, such adaptive approaches should focus first on the conditions under which reality unfolds and on conditions that keep systems together. In non-linear environments planning becomes conditional.

References Ackoff, R.L. (1974) Redesigning the Future: A Systems Approach to Societal Problems, John Wiley & Sons, New York/London. Allen, P.M. (1997) Cities and Regions as Self-Organizing Systems: Models of Complexity, Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, Amsterdam (NL): 32–52. Allen, P.M. (2016) The Role of Planning in Self-Organizing Urban and Regional Systems. In: G. De Roo & L. Boelens (eds) Spatial Planning in a Complex Unpredictable World of Change, InPlanning, Groningen (NL). Cilliers, P. (1998) Complexity and Postmodernism: Understanding Complex Systems, Routledge, London. Conklin, J. (2005) Dialogue Mapping: Building Shared Understanding of Wicked Problems, Wiley, Hoboken (US). Coveney, P. & Highfield, R. (1995) Frontiers of Complexity: The Search for Order in a Chaotic World, Faber & Faber, New York. Davoudi, S. (2012) Resilience: a bridging concept or a dead end? Planning Theory and Practice, 13(2), 299–307. De Klerk, L., Dekker, G., Witsen, P.P. & Van der Cammen, H. (2012) The Self Made Land: Culture and evolution of urban and regional planning in the Netherlands, Spectrum, Amsterdam.

323

Gert de Roo de Roo, G. (2010) Planning and complexity: an introduction. In: G. de Roo & E.A. Silva (eds) A Planner’s Encounter with Complexity, Ashgate, Farnham (UK): 1–18. de Roo, G. (2012) Spatial planning, complexity and a world ‘out of equilibrium’: outline of a non-linear approach to planning. In: G. de Roo, J. Hillier & J. Van Wezemael (eds) Planning & Complexity: Systems, Assemblages and Simulations, Ashgate, Farnham (UK): 129–165. de Roo, G. (2015) Going for Plan B – conditioning adaptive planning: about urban planning and institutional design in a non-linear, complex world. In: R. Geyer & P. Cairney (eds) Handbook on Complexity and Public Policy, Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham (UK): 349–368. de Roo, G. (2016a) Self-organization and spatial planning: foundations, challenges, constraints and consequences. In: G. de Roo & L. Boelens (eds) Spatial Planning in a Complex Unpredictable World of Change, InPlanning, Groningen (NL): 54–96. de Roo, G. (2016b) Framing the planning game. In J. Portugali & E. Stolk (eds) A Cognitive Understanding of the Planner’s Rationale in a Differentiated World, Springer, Heidelberg & Berlin: 153–197. de Roo, G. & Silva, E.A. (eds) (2010) A Planner’s Encounter with Complexity, Ashgate, Farnham (UK). de Roo, G., Hillier, J. & Van Wezemael, J. (eds) (2012) Complexity and Planning: Systems, Assemblages and Simulations, Ashgate, Farnham (UK). de Roo, G. & Rauws, W. (2012) Positioning planning in the World of order and chaos … On perspectives behavior and interventions in a non-linear environment. In: J. Portugali, H. Meyer, E. Stolk & E. Tan (eds) Complexity Theories of Cities Have Come of Age: An Overview with Implications to Urban Planning and Design. Springer-Verlag, Berlin and Heidelberg: 207–220. Emery, F.E. & Trist, E.L. (1965) The causal texture of organizational environments. In: F.E. Emery (ed.) Systems Thinking, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth: 241–257. Etzioni, A. (1967) Mixed-scanning, a ‘Third’ approach to decision-making, Public Administration Review, 27: 385–392. Fischer, F. & Forester, J. (eds) (1993) The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and Planning, Duke University Press, Durham, NC & London. Folke, C. (2006) Resilience: The emergence of a perspective for social–ecological systems analyses, Global Environmental Change, 16(3): 253–267. Forester, J. (1993) Critical Theory, Public Policy and Planning Practice: Toward a Critical Pragmatism, State University of New York Press, Albany. Garnsey, E. & McGlade, J. (eds) (2006) Complexity and Co-Evolution: Continuity and Change in SocioEconomic Systems, Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham (UK). Geels, F.W. (2013) The impact of the financial–economic crisis on sustainability transitions: Financial investment, governance and public discourse, Environmental Innovation and Societal Transitions, 6: 67–95. Healey, P. (2003) Collaborative planning in perspective, Planning Theory, 2(2): 101–123. Hillier, J. (2007) Stretching beyond the Horizon: A Multiplanar Theory of Spatial Planning and Governance, Ashgate, Aldershot (UK). Holling, C.S. (2001) Understanding the complexity of economic, ecological, and social systems, Ecosystems, 4(5): 390–405. Innes, J.E. (1995) Planning theory’s emerging paradigm: Communicative action and interactive practice, Journal of Planning Education and Research, 14(3): 183–189. Kauffman, S.A. (1990) The Sciences of Complexity and Origins of Order, Philosophy of Science Association, vol. 2: Symposia and Invited Papers, East Lansing, MI: PSA, 299–322. Keller, E.F. (2009) Organisms, machines, and thunderstorms: A history of self-organization, Part Two, Complexity, emergence, and stable attractors, Historical Studies in the Natural Sciences, 39(1): 1–31. Kunstler, J.H. (1993) The Geography of Nowhere: The Rise and Decline of America’s Man-made Landscape, Touchstone, New York. Li, T.Y. & Yorke, J.A. (1975) Period three implies chaos, American Mathematical Monthly, 82: 985. Lindblom, C.E. (1959) The science of muddling through, Public Administrator Review, 19: 78–88. Lorenz, E.N. (1963) Deterministic nonperiodic flow, Journal of the Atmospheric Sciences, 20(2): 130–141. Miller, J.H. & Page, S.E. (2007) Complex Adaptive Systems: An Introduction to Computational Models of Social Life, Princeton Studies in Complexity, Princeton University Press, Princeton (US). Newman, P. & Kenworthy, J. (1999) Sustainability and Cities: Overcoming Automobile Dependence, Island Press, Washington, DC. Pagels, H.R. (1988) The Dreams of Reason: The Rise of the Sciences of Complexity, Simon & Schuster, New York. Portugali, J. (2000) Self-Organization and the City, Springer, Heidelberg.

324

Spatial Planning and Complexity Prigogine, I. (1980) From Being to Becoming, Freeman, New York. Rauws, W.S. (2015) Why planning needs complexity: Towards an adaptive approach for guiding urban and peri-urban transformations, PhD Thesis, InPlanning, Groningen (NL). Rittel, H. (1972) On the planning crisis: Systems analysis of the ‘first and second generation’, Bedriftsøkonomen, 8: 390–396. Rittel, H.W.J. & Weber, M.M. (1973) Dilemmas in a general theory of planning, Policy Sciences, 4: 155–169. Ruelle, D. (1989) Chaotic Evolution and Strange Attractors, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (UK). Sager, T. (1994) Communicative Planning Theory, Avebury, Aldershot (UK). Sandercock, L. (1975) Public Participation in Planning, a Report for the Monarto development commission, Government Printer South Australia, Adelaide (Australia). Shane, D.G. (2005) Recombinant Urbanism: Conceptual Modeling in Architecture, Urban Design, and City Theory, Wiley-Academy, Chichester (UK). Simon, H.A. (1960) The New Science of Management Decision, Harper & Row, New York. Tonkens, E. (2014) Vijf misvattingen over de participatiesamenleving [Five misconceptions about the participation society], Valedictory Oration, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam. Van der Leeuw, S. (2009) The Archaeology of Innovation, a collection of seminars, https://vimeo.com/ 117926157. Wagenaar, C. (2011) Town Planning in the Netherlands Since 1800: Responses to Enlightenment Ideas and Geopolitical Realities, 010 Publishers, Rotterdam (NL). Waldrop, M.M. (1992) Complexity: The Emerging Science at the Edge of Order and Chaos, Simon & Schuster, New York. Warren, M.E. (2009) Governance-driven democratization, Critical Policy Studies, 3: 3–13. Weinstock, M. (2010) The Architecture of Emergence: The Evolution of Form in Nature and Civilisation, John Wiley & Sons, Chichester (UK).

325

26 ASSEMBLAGE THINKING IN PLANNING THEORY Joris Van Wezemael

Introduction The aim of this chapter is to show how and why Assemblage Theory matters for planning theory, to explain how it deals with the critique of collaborative approaches toward rationalist planning, and how it fixes important shortfalls of collaborative approaches. Assemblage Theory is a young strand of thinking within the field of planning theory. It draws on Deleuze’s idea1 that social and material formations are assemblages of other complex configurations, and they in turn play roles in other, more extended configurations. It has been introduced to the field in the late years of the first decade of this century (Van Wezemael 2008) and developed significant influence since then in planning, urban geography, urban studies and architecture (Anderson and McFarlane 2011; Anderson, Kearnes, McFarlane and Swanton 2012; Ballantyne 2007; Farías and Bender 2009; Hillier 2007; De Roo, Hillier and Van Wezemael 2012; Hillier and Abrahams 2013; McCann 2011; McFarlane 2011a, 2011b; Palmas 2007; Van Wezemael 2009; Van Wezemael and Silberberger 2016). I will argue here that we should pay attention to the context and to the reasons of its introduction to planning theory. This will lay the ground for its explanation and evaluation in this chapter. Both content and reason for an interest of planning theorists in Assemblage Theory refer to the need of a stronger appreciation of materiality, technology and space – without losing the power of dealing with uncertainty or fluidity (Healey 1996) that made collaborative approaches so influential. But there is also planning as an academic field that reacted rather late to notions and theories of complexity of all sorts (De Roo et al. 2012). The mobilization of ‘complexity’ in planning theory and a clarification of language or processes of negotiation can be seen as another virtue of Assemblage Theory.

Assemblage Theory and Traditions of Thought in Planning Theory2 Planning theory has never been one consistent body of theory. Nevertheless, different traditions of thought can be identified. In their collection of essays, Jean Hillier and Patsy Healey (2008a, 2008b, 2008c) identify and name such traditions. They used different organizing principles3 in order to identify the strands; one of these is the role of the planner and the question of agency. Let us take a brief look at those two important theory traditions (rational and collaborative planning) in order to clarify what Assemblage Theory has to offer for planning theory. 326

Assemblage Thinking in Planning Theory

Rational Planning If we look at rational planning, a key concept is its positivistic underpinning, the assumption that there is one, even if partially hidden, essential or sometimes transcendental logic on which the world is operating. Knowledge about this world would be achieved through systematic, deductive thinking. Therefore, planning theory is to provide scientific methods that should be applied in planning practice, a practice that in turn is seen as social management. Accordingly, the significant academic influence came from economic and management science, and from them planning theory inherited the traditions of a reduction to the micro-level (the individual) or the macro-level (society or ‘national’ economy as a whole). Furthermore, it inherited a form of realism that is based on a correspondence theory of truth and a realism deeply committed to essentialism and linearity. In the rational planning model, the planner is a scientist with an objective outside view who has the task of rational trade-offs between (given) interests on the basis of scientific methods. The planner, as collaborative planners will criticize, is apparently defined as value-free. The representatives of this approach, as Healey and Hillier (2008a) argue, understood the value conflicts in society, but believed that with a joint effort, politicians and experts could achieve better, more informed decisions. However, due to increasing social dynamics in urban development (diversification, strongly fluctuating economies) and obvious implementation deficits, the call for new approaches became stronger.

Communicative Planning Very much born form the criticism that the prevailing logic of rational planning failed in its planning attempts and could not meet the increasing diversity of lifestyles, a new branch in planning theory emerged in the 1990s: collaborative or communicative planning4 (Healey 1997; Forester 1980, 1999). The core of this tradition of thought is a more inclusive form of decision-making according to the logic of negotiation, based on a relativistic worldview that acknowledged different subjectivities. A crucial conceptual resource was the German philosopher Jürgen Habermas, who decisively shaped the ‘communicative turn’ with his work Theory of Communicative Action (Habermas 1981). Various lines of development led to the establishment of collaborative planning theories. I would like to highlight important connections to a particular Zeitgeist5 that included the acknowledgement of fragmented identities and diversity in human perception, the centrality of discourse in the production of collectively accepted realities and a focus on agency and practice (Allmendinger and Tewdwr-Jones 2005). This basic perspective has been enriched with references to the work of Pierre Bourdieu (1976) and Anthony Giddens (1984), which became, in addition to Habermas’s work, an important basis for the development of a more inclusive approach in planning. With what some call the practice turn, collaborative approaches also give in to a form of meso-reductionism (practice as an intermediate global level or Bourdieu’s habitus as a master process; see DeLanda 2006a). Communicative or collaborative planning situates the planner in a context that is shaped by the logic of negotiation. This moves attention of planning theory to the planner him/ herself, in other words: it focuses on the subject(s), not the object of planning. The who and the why replace the what. Planners take on the roles of innovators of joint learning processes and as communication specialists (moderator, mediator, and transformer of power relationships). Collaborative planning assumes that a planning process allows, despite subjectivities, the production of a temporary collective frame of reference. Openness of process and the fuzzy distinction between expert and lay knowledge were key to expelling planning theory 327

Joris Van Wezemael

from rationalist, deterministic approaches and alleged ‘objective’, linear thinking. Collaborative approaches bring the fluidity, uncertainty and complexity of the world to the fore, but this comes at a price. They do so by placing them on a symbolic/linguistic plane. In order to grasp the contribution of Assemblage Theory, it is important to notice this specific philosophical operation which is shared among approaches that sail under the flag of post-modernism and partly also post-structuralism (see Doel and Clarke 2004; Arbor and Hirt 2003). So, broadly speaking, communicative rationality reinforces a perspective where almost everything is related to hermeneutic, linguistic or sociological constructions (Srnicek, no year: 300). Within this paradigm change in wider social sciences, planning theorists have reconciled themselves to the idea of observers as active participants (Healey 2006) in the research of social reality, giving them a central and pivotal role. However, collaborative approaches provide a second order representation by reading all instances of human/non-human relations as somehow culturally determined (Hinchcliffe 2003). A sort of linguistic idealism has become a predominant paradigm that has accepted the fortification of the symbolic/linguistic dimension (and also an anthropomorphic view of the world). As a consequence the term ‘construction’ is not used in the sense in which, for example, Foucault (1995) talks of the construction of soldier bodies through drill and discipline, but to the way our minds (socially) ‘construct’ the world of appearances via linguistic categories (DeLanda, Protevi and Thanem 2006). This consequently reinforces an essentialist perception of matter as inert, passive and docile (Van Wezemael 2012). The result is a theoryled and systematic overestimation of the capacity of human action – in our case, of planner’s interventions – as it is cut off from the relations of forces that govern hybrid and non-human systems that are so common to planners.

A Relational Turn Since the 2000s various ‘relational’ approaches (e.g. institutionalist thinking and various traditions of complexity thinking such as Assemblage Theory) have tried to deal with some points of criticism toward collaborative planning. Whereas institutionalist perspectives are an attempt to have a concept of structure without being too deterministic, as in rational scientific management or critical political ecology, Assemblage Theory goes much further as it leaves such a framework and provides different ontological foundations. On this basis, planning theory can 1

avoid the essentialism that characterizes naive realism and forms of rationalism (collaborative planner’s critique toward rationalism), and simultaneously 2 remove one of the main objections that non-realists make against the postulation of an autonomous reality as it offers an integration of language and negotiation into a realist and materialist worldview. Because Assemblage Theory introduces a realist and neo-materialist perspective, complexity is no longer placed on the plane of interpretation, meanings or linguistic structures – as collaborative approaches suggest – but rather on the plane of a relational materiality and a realistic constructivism6 (Law and Urry 2004). The Leitmotiv might be that every observable order, including every spatial setting or social or communicative ensemble, is a product of interactions of (usually amazingly heterogeneous) elements. The resulting focus on the dynamics of non-equilibrium and on multiple futures, historical path dependency and intrinsic uncertainty, describes systems on the basis of interaction, non-linearity, instability, self-organization and unpredictability. 328

Assemblage Thinking in Planning Theory

What Is Assemblage Theory? The following thought embraces the basic idea of Assemblage Theory (see DeLanda 2002; Van Wezemael 2008). An individual person, a population of individual persons, project teams, organizations, interorganizational networks, community networks, or cities do not differ in ontological status; they are all historically produced individuals, which work on different spatial scales (or different layers) and which are produced by connections on the next lower scale. The parts – such as a subject or a project team – would not dissolve into the next scale – such as the project team or the organization. They can unplug from one entity (e.g. the subject from a project team) and connect to parts of another entity (such as a family or a sports club or another project team) without changing its constitutive elements. The scales are not self-referring, essential entities, but statistical results from the connections on the lower scale. Which one is part and which one is whole consequently is a solely relative question. The question what a thing ‘is’ (its ‘essence’) would be replaced by the question what it ‘does’. The production of an entity becomes a constituent element of its definition.

A Brief Outline of Assemblage Theory In the section above, the mentioned individuals are conceptualized as assemblages. The relations, which upkeep heterogeneity, are called relations of exteriority.7 The concept of the ‘exteriority of relations’, originally from the Philosopher David Hume (Deleuze 1994, 1991) offers the opportunity to think many intermediate levels between an absolute ‘micro’ and ‘macro’, between a ‘structure’, and an ‘individual’. It thus turns these terms into relative ones at any given scale. Due to such relations the heterogeneity of an assemblage’s parts does not dissolve into the next larger scale, but attests to a creative process and thus remains active for new and different connections and thus for (immanent) change. An assemblage can conceptually and empirically be grasped along two axes. The first one refers to the processes of production (de-stabilization and re-stabilization); the second one refers to the question what it can do, which role it can play. The first axis defines the variable roles that an assemblage’s components might play, from a purely material role at one extreme of the axis, to a purely expressive role at the other extreme. ‘These roles are variable and may occur in mixtures, that is, a given component may play a mixture of material and expressive roles by exercising different sets of capacities’ (DeLanda 2006a: 12). However, expressivity – in Assemblage Theory – is not reduced to language and symbols; there are also bodily and behavioural forms of expression, as well as the direct expression of colour or design and so on. Material elements in a social assemblage, such as a lobby or pressure group, also include the time and energy expended, for instance, in maintaining the assemblage’s relations, negotiating agendas, hiding struggles from public view (Hillier and Van Wezemael 2008). Similarly the material parts of a planning competition would consist of the energy and labour involved in setting up and maintaining a jury, patching together provisional coalitions, hiding internal struggles from public view. The representation hardware – plans, texts, design models, computer animations – play a material role, too. DeLanda argues that specialized expressive media (such as language) can be seen as an additional dimension or a differentiation of the expressive roles in social assemblages. Specialized expressive media consolidate and rigidify the identity of the assemblage (e.g. by shared stories, metaphors, professional design discourses and architectural or planning ‘schools of thought’) or allow the assemblage certain latitude for more flexible operation while benefiting from linguistic (and other) resources in processes of coding and decoding. (DeLanda 2006a: 18–19). 329

Joris Van Wezemael

The second axis in Assemblage Theory concerns ‘variable processes in which these components become involved: processes either stabilizing or destabilizing the identity of an assemblage’ (DeLanda 2006a: 12). The former are referred to as processes of (re)territorialization, the latter as processes of deterritorialization. De- and reterritorialization can be understood as a movement that produces change. It indicates the creative potential of an assemblage to become; to connect differently and to grow in a disorganized way. The emergence of semi-stable patterns, of coalitions between projects and people can be viewed as movements that introduce change into other coalitions. To deterritorialize means to free up the fixed connections that contain an assemblage, all the while exposing it to new organizations (reterritorialization). Processes of (re)territorialization increase an assemblage’s degree of internal homogeneity or the degree of sharpness of its boundaries. By contrast, processes of deterritorialization either destabilize an assemblage’s boundaries or increase its internal heterogeneity. Assemblage Theory thus is all about assembling, about relational processes of assembly of heterogeneous entities. Such entities might, for instance, be cities or regions (viewed as agglomerations of heterogeneity; see Amin 2002). Assemblage Theory defines the rules or the basic concepts one must follow when studying or interfering with processes of assembly in order to avoid the essentialism that characterizes naive realism and forms of rationalism. DeLanda (2006b) relates the terms micro and macro to the terms molecular and molar in the philosophy of Deleuze. What is molecular at any one ‘scale’ is that which plays the role of component, while the molar is the statistical result of molecular populations at any given level of scale (Deleuze and Guattari 1987). Thus, which one is the part (the molecular) and which one the whole (the molar is a statistical rather than a causal product) is a relative question. An assemblage can be seen as a mostly unintended and not completely determined product. Therefore, the ‘larger’ entity is not self-referring but an emergent result of the connections at the lower level. However, once a larger scale entity emerges, it immediately starts acting as a source of resources as well as a limitation for its components. Consequently forms of path dependence will start to evolve. Its molar lines enable the parts in specific ways and constrain them in others. This introduces a top-down aspect to the so far bottom-up approach. The striking characteristic of this approach is that heterogeneous assemblages do not homogenize when they build a larger – or simply another – assemblage by connecting with other entities. For instance, internal hierarchies of a public administration unit do not cease to matter or exist when they become involved in a flat hierarchy of heterarchic governance, neither do the persons and groups that form the unit on the basis of their connections. It is important not to trivialize the approach so as not to cause the concept of assemblage to lose meaning and its explanatory force. At the highest level we do not get ‘society as a whole’, but simply another concrete, singular entity (DeLanda 2006b: 252). The assemblagebased ontology is open to any connections or expansions as long as any addition is defined in a non-essentialist way and as long as any new entity introduced maintains relations of exteriority with those that are already included (DeLanda 2006b: 265). This is precisely what I meant with the rules to apply above.

Assemblages Are Virtual-Actual The discussion so far indicates that assemblages are more or less concrete arrangements of ‘actual’ things (like networks and organizations, or buildings, streets and trees). However, their mode of functioning cannot be understood independently of the ‘scripts’ (Belliger and Krieger 2006) that they embody. At this point I turn to the virtual-actual character of the real. The key credit of Deleuze for urban governance lies in his deeper insight that nothing can be understood if it 330

Assemblage Thinking in Planning Theory Table 26.1  A realist ontology Virtual

Intensive

Actual

Virtual continuum formed by multiplicities

Fields of individuation/ morphogenesis

Extensities and qualities

⇒ Progressive differentiation ⇒ Source: author’s draft based on Deleuze (1994)

is reduced to the properties that it displays at any given moment. Deleuze introduces a realist ontology which I roughly map out in Table 26.1. Real assemblages consist of a field of actualities (exercised properties), a possibility space, which refers to the virtual, containing potential properties, and a generative field: the intensive, individuating level (DeLanda 2002: 143; Deleuze 1994: 173). The virtual is necessarily structured since different assemblages exhibit different sets of capacities. We can address the virtual by means of unactualized tendencies (‘singularities’) and unactualized capacities to affect and be affected (‘affects’) (DeLanda 2002: 62). Singularities are virtual, but they are individuated in assemblages, and so they are vital to the operation of those assemblages (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 100). Resource interdependencies between agents in governance settings might be a good example: resource interdependence would be the virtual diagram that guides the actualization and the dynamics of any governance setting (or assemblage) – independent of its actual form. Since no individual is ever (ontologically) independent from its environment, every individual must be viewed as an open system through which matter, information and energy pass. Therefore, all individuals need certain singularities in order to maintain their identity; those singularities, however, are not transcendent types. Rather they are generated on the basis of the relations that give rise to the system itself. In other words they are immanent. This means that every assemblage must be understood not only on the basis of its actual relations, but also with regard to a space of possibilities that is structured by singularities (see Table 26.1). However, singularities do not exist independently of the specific assemblage in which they are expressed and thus incarnated. On the basis of different connections of component parts, singularities are modulated. Thus we can say that a space of possibilities is structured by a map of relations between forces or a map of intensity. It is not a copy of the actual, but it constructs a real-to-come, or a becoming. Singularities allow for a variety of actualizations to one problem. Since actualizations are (temporary) solutions that are derived from processes of individuation, real (not actual) problems are defined by singularities. Problems, therefore, maintain certain autonomy from their particular solutions. Or as DeLanda (2002: 115–116) poses it: ‘To give consistency to these well-posed problems . . . means to endow them with a certain autonomy from their particular solutions, just like the virtual multiplicities do not disappear behind their actualised individuals’.

What Does Assemblage Theory Do for Planning Theory (and What Does It Not Do)? DeLanda (2006a) provides an excellent conceptual outline of assemblages and how they can work for the social. However, his illustrations of intermediate entities such as social groups, markets or cities do not match that quality. Rather, planning theory is challenged to build specific theories in and for planning on the basis of a philosophy of assemblages. Thus we can answer the negative part in this section’s title. Assemblage Theory is not a theory that can be ‘used’ in planning. What does it do for planning theory? It provides a foundational framework with 331

Joris Van Wezemael

regard to ontological rules to build planning theories. Its strategy and plane for experimentation to re-address the what (content) in planning theory will be addressed in the next section. There are, however, two specific contributions to the field of planning and planning theory that I want to discuss here. The first addresses the planner’s specific question of agency. Assemblage Theory addresses this problem within a framework of complexity thinking. The second concerns those intermediate scales and heterogeneous settings that planning deals with and that planning theory must address. As mentioned earlier Assemblage Theory clarifies their ontological status.

Agency as an Emergent Phenomenon Assemblage Theory offers some important conceptual tools for planning theory in order to deal with the planner’s capacity to make a difference, while maintaining a fully relational perspective. At this point it becomes necessary to introduce a key differentiation that has found its way into the debate as a translation issue. As Phillips (2006) points out, the translation of the French term agencement (which Deleuze and Guattari originally used) into the English term assemblage is not the best choice, although most authors now retain it (as I do). In contrast to the English word assemblage, the French word ‘agencement’ has a far broader meaning. In its everyday use it refers to an arrangement of parts of a body or of a machine, fitting or fixing two or more parts together and it can be used to refer to the activity of fixing as well as to the arrangement itself. As Hillier and Abrahams (2013) explain, an agencement is more than simply an assemblage. The term agencement implies agency and strategy, which assemblage does not. It is an active bringing-intoexistence of its own agency. In asking ‘what makes an assemblage into an agencement’, Hillier and Abrahams (2013) suggest that one would critically investigate the relations between the entities or elements in the collective. What are important are the relations between the elements and their space of possibilities, rather than the elements themselves. A planner would identify the relations of people, infrastructure, discourses and policies that might pick up speed and create agency of the collective as an emergent property. Analytically and backward-looking we call this tracing. Tracing asks how something came to be. It would explore, in particular, the force relations between heterogeneous component parts, between human and non-human actors. Tracing is concerned with understanding path dependencies, transformations and ruptures, investigating how elements and processes (such as human and non-human actors) involved in a governance setting or a planning competition respond to their own relational logics and to external pressures and stimuli. Tracing, then, overlays a product (what happened) onto the process of its production (how it happened) (Hillier and Abrahams 2013: 57). Forward looking we refer to a mapping of possibilities. As Hillier and Abrahams (2013: 58) explain, mapping involves the creative discovery and perception of landmarks, useful for orientation purposes as something to head toward. This would not be an attempt to define long-term detailed programmes of action, but to raise questions of potential agency and of socio-economic-political and institutional conditions of change. The idea is to attempt to anticipate the ways in which force relations and alliances might be redistributed in different circumstances and situations and to work out what kinds of changes in relations between humans and non-humans could be vitally important: ‘It is never filiations which are important, but alliances’ (Deleuze and Parnet 2002: 69). For instance, the various project proposals that are submitted by the teams in a planning competition explore a space of possibilities, but they also map it out. This relational map piecewise appears as a framework for evaluation criteria to emerge in the jury debates. Coalitions form between parts of discourse, representations in the projects, identifications and affects and so form alliances (Van Wezemael 2010). 332

Assemblage Thinking in Planning Theory

And at the time when one starts to interfere into the relations in order to trigger change, one can call this machining. It concerns the evaluative study of assemblages and their potentialities with a view to intervening strategically (agencement). Key elements in machining are questions of ‘what might happen if . . .?’ (Hillier 2007). However, this questioning is very different to that generally associated with more rational comprehensive forms of strategic planning. Deleuze and Guattari emphasize the importance of the force relations between elements rather than simply the elements themselves.

Intermediate Scales and Heterogeneous Settings Given the general importance of heterogeneous settings in the field of spatial planning DeLanda’s (2006a) critique of the micro-, meso-, and macro-reductionism of social sciences and their inability to adequately deal with intermediate entities obtains major relevance. He states that the ontological status of various scales which are neither micro nor macro – such as project teams, peers, organization segments, organizations, cities – ‘has not been properly conceptualized’ (DeLanda 2006a: 5). He claims that scientists that deal with these intermediate levels ‘without ontological foundations . . . are typically using an implicit and thereby uncritically accepted ontology’ (DeLanda 2006a: 7). Assemblage Theory allows for a proper dealing with the heterogeneous entities of different and differing scales that planning has to come to terms with. There are countless other forms of ‘planning assemblages’ waiting to be adequately theorized (from participation to network governance; from strategic planning to planning competitions.

Content Theories as Actualizations of Assemblage Theory In his seminal work Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy, DeLanda (2002) mobilizes Deleuzian concepts. He uses them to explain with regard to the study of non-linear dynamics (such as in thermodynamics under far-from-equilibrium conditions), that classical mechanics and ‘lowintensity’ thermodynamics dealt with special cases.8 This thought paves the way for an experimental method to work with Assemblage Theory in the field of planning theory: many classical planning theories and concepts, broadly understood, can be treated as special cases. DeLanda obviously had this – as a strategy – on his mind in his New Philosophy of Society (2006a). He draws largely on the work of urban geographers, but also on the work of sociologist Pierre Bourdieu, and he shows where Bourdieu’s Field Theory contradicts the rules of Assemblage Theory. DeLanda argues that Field Theory ‘works’ as an Assemblage Theory if the habitus were not reified as a ‘master process’. Besides, the suggestion to mobilize Assemblage Theory in order to contribute to planning theory by means of experimentation with existing specific bodies of thought/theory has a very strong precursor in the Work of Deleuze. Deleuze did not interpret Kant, Hume or Spinoza. He experimented with their potentialities, traced their own singularities of thought and mapped out what their thinking could become. The experimentation with mid-range theories and with content-oriented theories must be understood in an analogous way. DeLanda (2006b: 265) argues that ‘the assemblage-based ontology is open to any connections or expansions as long as any additions are defined in a non-essentialist way and as long as any new entity introduced maintains relations of exteriority with those that are already included’. The theories and conceptions that deal with such expansions (content) have to follow the non-essentialism and the rules of exteriority, too. Those content-oriented theoretical expansions include management and decision-making, urban governance, city development, neighbourhood outreach, strategic regional planning or 333

Joris Van Wezemael

infrastructure networks and much more. The experimentation with content-oriented theories allows bringing the what (content) back into planning theory while re-addressing these fields on the basis of a sound and complexity-based theory of social assemblages. Examples of such work can be found in Loepfe (2014) who embeds urbanist concepts of place quality into assemblage thinking. Silberberger (2011) conceptualizes planning competitions as nested assemblages and works on design and decision-making theories. I have elaborated on theories of knowledge creation, planning competitions, surveillance (Craviolini, Van Wezemael and Wirth 2011), network governance or neighbourhood development, or collaborative planning in order to show how existing approaches can be adequately accustomed in order to work on a proper assemblage basis. The mobilizing of existing theories within an assemblage framework opens the doors to a precious treasure – theories that are the key to empirical fields, while avoiding their reductionisms and their widespread ignorance with regard to ontology. This redefines and clarifies the position and function of Assemblage Theory. It is not a theory. It lays ground for theories.

Conclusion In this chapter I have sketched out a discursive space using rational and comprehensive planning in order to argue why Assemblage Theory has been a major contribution to planning theory in recent years and how it contributes. Furthermore, I have outlined Assemblage Theory and highlighted its most important concepts. These basic concepts have been addressed very pragmatically as rules. Rules that must be respected when novel elements are added to an assemblage, but also as rules that can be mobilized in order to experiment with theories that have been developed to deal with precisely those elements that can be reconceptualized as assemblages or component parts of nested assemblages. In times when everyone claims to be a relationalist, Assemblage Theory might be a good companion in order to make sure that one walks the walk. However, Assemblage Theory is also an ethical approach. Why is that? As I explained above, it must not be used as a ready-made ‘tool’. Assemblage Theory makes us question given identities on the basis of a radical immanentism (and does away with essentialism and transcendental shortcuts). By this means it allows for novel identities to emerge, for novel connections to materialize. Therefore Assemblage Theory itself can be understood as a diagram that must be actualized with respect to (and with respect for) the empirical field where it should work. Assemblage Theory lays ground for theories to be generated in an experimentation of what they might become. This inherent procedural logic helps avoiding the subjugation of the researched under the researcher, or the empirical field under a theoretical conception that already defines what will be voice, and what will be neglected as noise. However, this ethical aspect also moots the question of how Assemblage Theory can help us develop theories about what to do. The contribution of Assemblage Theory to the normative foundations of planning must still be written.

Notes 1 DeLanda (2002) does not examine a direct interpretation of Deleuze’s texts, rather he reconstructs his philosophy, using entirely different theoretical resources and lines of argument. The main focus lies on Deleuze’s ‘world’, not his ‘words’, in the sense of his ontology. DeLanda identifies Deleuze as a realist philosopher. 2 For a good overview see Loepfe (2014). 3 They include: interface theory and practice, self-conception (the idea of planning), role and identity of the planner, kind of knowledge and its production, interface planning and politics, political and social background.

334

Assemblage Thinking in Planning Theory 4 For our purpose here I will treat them synonymously. 5 There were several precursors before the 1990s. For example, John Forester (critical pragmatism; Forester 1980), inspired by the pragmatist philosophers of the early 20th century, argued for planning that mobilizes the potential of situated knowledge through social learning processes. In a similar vein, John Friedmann (transactive planning; Friedmann 1973) argued to see planning as an instrument of innovation, not (only) as an instrument for control. 6 See also Latour (2005) who explains that the world is constructed, but not socially. 7 This is opposed to relations of interiority, where component parts are constituted by the very relations they have to other parts in the ‘whole’. This means that a ‘part detached from such a whole ceases to be what it is, since being this particular part is one of its constitutive properties’ (DeLanda 2006a: 9). 8 Social scientists inherited their classical vocabulary (like social strata) from these special cases. And, one could argue, also much of their thinking.

References Allmendinger, P. & Tewdwr-Jones, M. (2005) Planning Futures: New Directions for Planning. London: Routledge. Amin, A. (2002) ‘Spatialities of globalisations’, Environment and Planning A, 34(3): 385–399. Anderson, B. and McFarlane, C. (2011) ‘Assemblage and geography’, Area, 43(2): 124–127. Anderson, B., Kearnes, M., McFarlane, C. and Swanton, D. (2012) ‘On assemblages and geography’, Dialogues in Human Geography, 2(2): 171–189. Arbor, A. and Hirt, S. (2003) ‘Measuring Postmodernism: Placing Urban Planning in the Context of a Broader Cultural Values Tradition’. Paper presented at the 2003 Distinguished Faculty and Student Symposium: Crossing Disciplinary Boundaries in the Urban and Regional Context. Ballantyne, A. (2007) Deleuze and Guattari for Architects. London: Routledge. Belliger, A. and Krieger, D. J. (Eds) (2006) ANThology. Ein einführendes Handbuch zur Akteur-NetzwerkTheorie. Bielefeld: Transcript. Bourdieu, P. (1976) Entwurf einer Theorie der Praxis auf der ethnologischen Grundlage der kabylischen Gesellschaft. Frankfurt a/M: Suhrkamp. Craviolini, C., Van Wezemael, J. and Wirth, F. (2011) ‘The spatiality of control: intertwining ICT and physical space in social protest’, Journal of Critical Studies in Business and Society, 4: 95–115. de Roo, G., Hillier, J. and Van Wezemael, J. (eds) (2012) Complexity and Planning: Systems, Assemblages and Simulations (New Directions in Planning Theory). Farnham: Ashgate. DeLanda, M. (2002) Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy. London: Continuum. DeLanda, M. (2006a) A New Philosophy of Society: Assemblage Theory and Social Complexity. London: Continuum. DeLanda, M. (2006b) ‘Deleuzian social ontology and assemblage theory’, in M. Fugsland and B. Meier Sorensen (eds) Deleuze Connections. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 250–266. DeLanda, M., Protevi, J. and Thanem, T. (2006) ‘Deleuzian interrogations: a conversation with Manuel DaLanda, John Protevi and Torkild Thanem’, Journal of Critical Postmodern Organisation Science, 3(4): 65–88. Deleuze, G. (1994) [1968] Difference and Repetition. London: Athlone. Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. (1987) [1980] A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. London: Athlone Press. Deleuze, G. and Parnet, C. (2002) [1977] Dialogues II. New York: Continuum. Doel, M. A. and Clarke, D. B. (2004) ‘Gilles Deleuze’, in P. Hubbard, R. Kitchin and G. Valentine (eds), Key Contemporary Thinkers on Space and Place. London: Sage, pp. 100–105. Farías, I. and Bender, T. (eds) (2009) Urban Assemblages: How Actor-Network Theory Changes Urban Studies. London: Routledge. Forester, J. (1980) ‘Critical theory and planning practice’, Journal of the American Planning Association, 46(3): 275–286. Forester, J. (1999) The Deliberative Practitioner: Encouraging Participatory Planning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Foucault, M. (1995) Discipline & Punish. New York: Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group. Friedmann, J. (1973) Urbanization, Planning, and National Development. Beverly Hills: Sage Publications. Giddens, A. (1984) The Constitution of Society. Outline of a Theory of Structuration. Cambridge, MA: Polity Press.

335

Joris Van Wezemael Habermas, J. (1981) The Theory of Communicative Action. London: Beacon Press. Healey, P. (1996) ‘The communicative turn in planning theory and its implications for spatial strategy formation’, Environment and Planning B, 23(2): 217–234. Healey, P. (1997) Collaborative Planning: Shaping Places in Fragmented Societies. Vancouver: UBC Press. Healey, P. (2006) Urban Complexity and Spatial Strategies: Towards a Relational Planning for Our Times. London: Routledge. Hillier, J. (2007) Stretching beyond the Horizon: A Multiplanar Theory of Spatial Planning and Governance. Aldershot: Ashgate. Hillier, J. and Abrahams, G. (2013) Deleuze and Guattari: Jean Hillier in Conversation with Gareth Abrahams. ASEAP Young Academics: Exploring Foundations for Planning Theory. Cardiff: Cardiff University. Hillier, J. and Healey, P. (2008a) Critical Essays in Planning Theory. Vol. 1, Foundations of the Planning Enterprise. Aldershot: Ashgate. Hillier, J. and Healey, P. (2008b) Critical Essays In Planning Theory. Vol. 2, Political Economy, Diversity and Pragmatism. Aldershot: Ashgate. Hillier, J. and Healey, P. (2008c) Critical Essays in Planning Theory. Vol. 3, Contemporary Movements in Planning Theory. Aldershot: Ashgate. Hillier, J. and Van Wezemael, J. (2008) ‘‘Empty, swept and garnished’: the Public Finance Initiative case of Throckley Middle School’, Space and Polity, 12(2): 157–181. Hinchcliffe, S. (2003) ‘“Inhabiting”: landscapes and natures’, in K. Anderson, M. Domosh, S. Pile and N. Thrift (eds) The Handbook of Cultural Geography. London: Sage, pp. 207–225. Latour, B. (2005) Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network Theory. New York: Oxford University Press. Law, J. and Urry, J. (2004) ‘Enacting the social’, Economy and Society, 33(3): 390–410. Loepfe, M. (2014) The Invisible Processes of Urban Design: A Qualitative Investigation into the Dynamics of Collective Decision-Making in Urban Development and their Potential for Spatial Quality. Doctoral thesis. Fribourg: University of Fribourg. McCann, E. (2011) ‘Veritable inventions: cities, policies and assemblage’, Area, 43(2): 143–147. McFarlane, C. (2011a) ‘The city as a machine for living’, Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers, NS, 36: 360–376. McFarlane, C. (2011b) ‘The city as assemblage: dwelling and urban space’, Environment and Planning D, Society and Space, 29: 649–671. Palmas, K. (2007) ‘Deleuze and DeLanda: A new ontology, a new political economy?’, paper presented at the Economic Sociology Seminar Series, the Department of Sociology, London School of Economics & Political Science. Phillips, J. (2006) ‘Agencement/assemblage’, Theory, Culture & Society, 23(1–2): 108–109. Silberberger, J. (2011) ‘Organizing the Space of Possibilities of an Architectural Competition’, Geographica Helvetica, 66(1): 5–12. Srnicek, N. (no year) ‘Assemblage theory, complexity and contentious politics: the political ontology of Gilles Deleuze’. Strategy formations. EBP, 23(2): 217–234. Van Wezemael, J. (2009) ‘Housing studies between romantic and baroque complexity’, Housing, Theory and Society, 26(2): 81–121. Van Wezemael, J. (2008) ‘The contribution of assemblage theory and minor politics for democratic network governance’, Planning Theory, 7(2): 165–185. Van Wezemael, J. E. (2010) ‘Modulation of singularities: a complexity approach to planning competitions’, in J. Hillier and P. Healey (eds) The Ashgate Research Companion to Planning Theory: Conceptual Challenges for Planning Theory. Farnham: Ashgate, pp. 273–290. Van Wezemael, J. (2012) ‘Transformative practice as an experimentation of possibility spaces’, in G. de Roo, J. Hillier and J. Van Wezemael (eds) Complexity and Planning: Systems, Assemblages and Simulations (New Directions in Planning Theory). Farnham: Ashgate, pp. 93–116 Van Wezemael, J. and Silberberger, J. (2016) ‘Emergent places’, in Y. Rydin and L. Tate (eds) Actor Networks of Planning: Exploring the Influence of ANT. New York: Routledge, pp. 175–185.

336

27 LINES OF BECOMING Jean Hillier

Introduction A theory is exactly like a box of tools …. A theory does not totalise; it is an instrument for multiplication and it also multiplies itself. (Deleuze, in Deleuze and Foucault 1977: 208) Several concepts derived from the work of Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari have provided powerful exploratory tools for planning theorists who have begun to advance a range of visions, strategies and governance agendas for planning in contrast to the traditional objective/goal setting of instrumental planning. In this chapter I explore Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of becoming and the potentialities it might offer theorisation in spatial planning. Uncertainties are inherent in planning practices. Plans and legislation that present fixed rules or policies project inflexibility and do not allow for commitment to less precise goals, provisional advice and adaptive futures. Inflexibility may relate to an essentialism prevalent in planning (what constitutes a “sustainable” city, a “good” city, a “healthy” city and so on): a Platonist “being”. I concentrate not on specific issues as such, but on the ontological ground that prefigures and makes possible such structural relations and argue instead for a theoretical grounding in non-essentialist becoming rather than being. Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of becoming resonates with a world marked by uncertainty. Everyday “glimmers of becoming” (Connolly 2011: 7), include the contingent globalisation of capital and enhanced visibility of natural disasters. Further, Braidotti (2002: 118) refers to a crisis of humanism in which what were typically regarded as the world’s “others” (women, nature, the Global South and so on) challenge the structures and boundaries of traditional subjectivity dominated, as it has been, by male anthropocentric performativities of being. I discuss becoming as an encounter between elements which effects a transition of those elements from one state to another. Becoming is concerned with how something emerges and with what it can do, rather than what it is. For Deleuze, “things have essences, but essences are not things” (Baugh 2006: 39). Deleuze offers ideas and concepts designed to challenge and disrupt our theoretical and practical understanding and a “tool-box” (Deleuze and Foucault 1977: 208) for thinking and working differently

337

Jean Hillier

in the more-than-human worlds we encounter. Following brief discussion of uncertainty and essentialism, I outline Deleuze’s concept of becoming, emphasising its alterity to traditional notions of being. I then consider becomings of specific types, which Deleuze and Guattari term becomings-minor. The authors’ first specific becoming is that of becoming-woman, followed by becoming-animal, both of which are relevant for planning theory and practice. Savini et al. (2015: 309) suggest that “today’s [planning] practice does not seem to recognise the urgency for the inclusion of openness and complexity in generally linear planning processes”. As such, I explore potentialities for development of DeleuzoGuattarian-inspired pragmatics with regard to emergent forms of law and strategic spatial planning before engaging in discussion of the potential for “revolutionary-becoming”. I inconclude that becomings undermine the essentialist identities and fixed terms of majoritarian planning cultures. In so doing, they offer us ways to think and act differently: to become with the world rather than in it.

On Expecting a Non-essentialist Unexpected Uncertainty is rapidly becoming a buzzword in urban studies and related fields and is receiving increasing attention in spatial planning theory (see, for example, Balducci et  al. 2011; Portugali 2012; Savini et al. 2015). It has long been known that planning practice is faced with the contingencies of “wicked problems” (Rittel and Webber 1973) and inherent uncertainties. While many planning theorists (notably Albrechts 2015; Albrechts and Balducci 2013; Christensen 1985; Gunder and Hillier 2009; Healey 1997, 2007; Hillier 2007, 2011, 2013; Innes and Booher 2010; Portugali 2012) have proposed and debated theoretical approaches and associated methodologies for potential planning practice, it appears that regardless “of reality, planners, managers, and politicians persist in their efforts to impose certainty (administratively, bureaucratically, legally, and politically) in an uncertain world” (Silva 2002: 336–338). Practitioner strategies of coping with uncertainties by ignoring them or through attempts to eliminate, reduce and manage them (Abbott 2005, 2009, 2012) are inherently paradoxical (Portugali 2008). The challenge to theorists and practitioners is thus not to “open additional boxes fitting the same models” (Lagadec 2009: 473) – which only offers an illusion of certainty (Gunder and Hillier 2009) – but to cultivate disconcertment with these models and think anew. Abrahams (2016) claims that a key problem is the majoritarian, essentialist nature of planning. Essentialism “holds that any material or non-material entity has a number of traits that are deemed essential to its identity and/or its function” (Abrahams 2015: 33). Ranging from conceptualisations of space as a measurable continuum in which things are located and of time as progressing at even speed from past to future, to universalist codes and guides for determination of things including urban deprivation or wellbeing, sustainable homes, town centre vitality, etc., essentialist representations impede creativity and flexibility as they encourage practitioners to apply rules rather than to respond to specific issues (Abrahams 2015: 36). Deleuze offers a non-essentialist alternative to such transcendent fixities. He proposes an ontology of “real essences” (Baugh 2006) which do not restrict possible forms of existence, or preclude new forms from emerging. Deleuzean essences are mobile and immanent: “a power of metamorphosis” (Deleuze 1990a: 266), inherent in a world that is “open, divergent and creative” (Baugh 2006: 32). As Deleuze (1988: 125) explains, “the speed or slowness of metabolisms, perceptions, actions and reactions link together to constitute a particular individual in the world”; the particular, individual essence of a body as any entity comprised of parts (a non-human animal, a practice, an idea and so on). Each “whole” then endures “as long as its 338

Lines of Becoming

parts remain under the relation which characterises it” (Deleuze 1990b: 213). An essence, for Deleuze, is a capacity of a body, which might or might not be realised. An essence is constituted through its relations and dynamic interactions with other essences. Essences are thus particular rather than general, immanent rather than transcendent: essence, but not essentialist. I have argued that planning practitioners should “expect the unexpected” (Hillier 2007: 315; 2014: 40). As I demonstrate below, the work of Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari offers a range of conceptual ideas that might assist us, not least of which is that of becoming.

How Is Becoming? What Does Becoming Do? Becoming is a cornerstone of Deleuze’s thinking. Deleuzean becoming refers to “the continual production . . . of difference immanent within the constitution of events, whether physical or otherwise” (Stagoll 2010: 26). Becoming, however, is not a phase between states of being through which something passes, but the dynamism of change itself: “there is no being beyond becoming” (Deleuze 1983: 22). Deleuze thus attempts to render becoming ontologically independent from being. Being is a post-facto social abstraction of the becoming of forces that encounter each other and manifest themselves together. An ontology of being in which change reflects being’s temporal becoming, both ignores the different means of becoming and is bound by essentialist representation. It insists on a singular truth – the truth of being – that reduces difference to identity. In contrast, an ontology of becoming (such as that of Deleuze) regards change as transformation to creatively express non-linear, differential becoming (Rae 2014). For Deleuze and Guattari (1987) the question is not “what is a thing?” (as thinking of what threatens to reduce a thing to the essentialism of an identity), but rather “how does it become?” Consequently a thing is determined by its relationality and by what it can do rather than by what it is. Becoming is an encounter between bodies and/or essences or forces that effects a transition of both. It constitutes passage toward a new assemblage (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 257–258) while retaining some former resemblance. Deleuze and Guattari (1987: 10) offer the wasp-orchid assemblage by way of explanation. The Drakaea (wasp-orchid) is a genus of Australian orchid, pollinated only by the Thynnid wasp. Female Thynnid wasps are flightless and need to wait on top of flower stems for male wasps in order to mate. A Drakaea flower assumes the resemblance of/codes itself as a female wasp in the colour of its labellum and production of similar pheromones. When a male wasp lands on the labellum, pollen adheres to it. Eventually, the male wasp realises that the orchid is not a female wasp and flies away to try again. When he lands on another orchid, he transfers pollen to this plant, thereby effecting pollination (Hillier 2014: 40–41). One must be careful not to fall into an ontological trap here. Regarding an orchid and/ or a wasp as of essentialist quality will privilege being. Instead, focus is on the wasp-orchid assemblage of essences in its becoming. In the wasp-orchid assemblage, both the wasp and the orchid are changed by their incorporation into the assemblage (by the addition of pollen) which is marked by emergent properties greater than the sum of the parts (pollination). The becoming of a wasp-orchid assemblage is a creative alliance of heterogeneous essences. In the process of becoming wasp-orchid, the encounter between the wasp and the orchid releases something from each (a process of destabilisation or decoding which Deleuze and Guattari term “deterritorialisation”) and, in the process, releases a series of enabling and potentialities by which the entity is transformed (“reterritorialisation”). Deleuze and Guattari see the world in terms of varied lines: “we are made of lines” (1987: 194). Being, as a point, is “an inflection of lines” (Deleuze 1995: 161). Lines can be rigid, hierarchised 339

Jean Hillier

and segmentary (molar), such as social class, gender, species and so on, which perform modes of ordering. Or they can be supple (molecular) lines of desire and affect. A third form of line ruptures the other lines, in flight from what has been. A line of flight is an abstract molecular line; a vector of escape toward a destination that is unknown. It marks a threshold of lowered resistance to something (“you can no longer stand what you put up with before”; Deleuze and Parnet 2002: 126), a change in desire or the intensity of desire, a new anxiety and so on. Lines of flight might be born out of resistance, but they can be positively creative. “It’s along this line of flight that things come to pass, becomings evolve, revolutions take shape” (Deleuze 1995: 45). For Deleuze and Guattari, lines are always in motion, never static, lines may leave lingering traces, but they are vectors, trajectories, courses of movement and becoming, some [molar lines] so predictable in their journeys that they may be charted, demarcated by intersecting regular trajectories, graphed by grids of coordinated vectors, but others [molecular lines, including lines of flight] as … a vital, nonorganic zigzag passing between things. (Bogue 2013: 157) Molecular lines always pass between things, where “the between” is a set of relations or inbetween: the middle (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 293). Such lines are perpetually in progress, branching and folding. While molecular lines often return to a reterritorialised molar state, lines of flight perform creative disordering. They are dynamic relations moving toward destinations that are generally unpredictable: a terra incognita (Deleuze 1994: 136). The three types of lines are entangled in complex interrelations of ordering and disordering. De Vries (2013: 127–128) writes that because lines entangled in a complex play of movements and relations can turn anywhere, one must establish and predict where or how the line will pass; however, this cannot be done without producing the forces from which one seeks to escape. If planners seek to predict what will take place, therefore, they risk capturing and reterritorialising creative change, stymieing its productivity and foreclosing becoming. Deleuze and Guattari (1987: 270) suggest, nevertheless, that we should experiment, because while reterritorialisation might recapture and foreclose our attempts, it also produces a platform for creative becomings. As Deleuze (1998: 65) explains, “it is becoming that turns the slightest of trajectories, or even a fixed immobility, into a journey (un voyage); and it is the trajectory that turns the imaginary into a becoming” (my translation). I now turn to becomings of specific types, as Deleuze and Guattari (1987) suggest that it is specific becomings that affirm the nature of becoming.

Becomings-minor All becomings are, first and foremost, becoming-minor (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 291): becoming-woman, becoming-animal, becoming-world. It should be explained that “minority” does not refer to specific numbers or quantities, but is the counterpart to “majority”, the dominant, mainstream of stable identities that frames cultural ideals and behaviours. Majority and minority are mutually determined through their positions in relations of domination, rather than through possession of a defining characteristic, although typically in our societies, the two go together. 340

Lines of Becoming

When we say majority, we are referring not to a greater relative quantity but to the determination of a state or standard in relation to which larger quantities, as well as the smallest, can be said to be minoritarian: white-man, adult-male, etc. Majority implies a state of domination, not the reverse. (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 291) There are two simultaneous movements in processes of becoming-minor: one in which majorities are dissolved and one in which more fluid identities are created. Minor and minority imply a positive subversion of the domination of the majority. For this reason, there can be no becoming-man, becoming-human and so on. For Deleuze and Guattari (1987: 248) all becomings-minor start with becoming-woman as woman is the main other against which men have defined their self-image. While the authors identify becoming-woman, becoming-animal and becoming-imperceptible (1987: 279), they stress that there is no linear sequence of becomings. Becoming-woman or becoming-animal does not imply mimicking or becoming “like” a woman or animal. “Becoming is certainly not imitating, or identifying with something; neither is it corresponding” (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 239). When Deleuze and Guattari (1987: 243ff.) discuss Captain Ahab in the novel Moby Dick as possessing “an irresistible becomingwhale”, they do not mean that Ahab imitates or sympathises with the white whale, Moby Dick. Rather, the subjectivity of Ahab, as sea-captain, is pushed over a critical threshold into a creative synthesis of symbolic, physical and mental forces. Ahab encounters Moby Dick and becomes something between the two of them, outside them both.

Becoming-Woman Becoming-woman is a fundamental becoming that is necessary in order to challenge the hierarchical dualisms constructed round man as the dominant figure: male/female, white/non-white, rational/emotional, strong/weak, breadwinner/homemaker and so on. Becoming-woman ruptures the rigid gender binaries that have traditionally organised human bodies, experiences, institutions and histories (Sotirin 2005: 103). In order to deterritorialise such binaries, both men and women must become-woman because women, too, are prey to particular body images and sexual behaviours constructed by male-dominated machines of commodification and consumerism (for example, Grabe and Hyde 2009; Hamilton 2009; Shaikh et al. 2015). The concept of becoming-woman allows us to consider, discuss, challenge and subvert such issues in terms of how they work and what are the forces that drive them. Braidotti (2010: 307) reminds us, however, that the “woman” in becoming-woman is not an empirical referent or homogeneous aggregate of same-sex subjects with a shared identity, but a topological position of intensities and affective states (see Braidotti (1993, 2002, 2011), Colebrook (2010, 2013), Grosz (1994, 2005), Irigaray (1985) and Jardine (1985) for positive and negative appreciations of becoming-woman). It is a question of expressing and actualising new ways of affective interaction; of the reconfiguration of becoming-woman as a post-feminist concept which abandons both man and woman as basic political units (Colebrook 2013: 436). Hillier (2016) utilises materialities of cultural heritage – the former women’s Venereal Disease (VD) Clinic in Melbourne, Australia – to explore new potentialities of becoming-woman-inprostitution. She discusses the performative role of buildings, such as the clinic, in gendered practices of spatial planning and argues that the location of the heritage VD Clinic, in what was the core area of sex work in early twentieth-century Melbourne, could trigger people to think about attitudes to planning and health-related legislation referring to adult entertainment premises today. The monument of the VD Clinic could also trigger people to question how societies have 341

Jean Hillier

typically reduced sexuality to sex and women to purveyors of sex, whether as wives/partners, mothers or sex workers. Perhaps Deleuze and Guattari’s discussion of becoming-woman can perform as starting-point to challenge essentialist appropriations and to acknowledge the intensities and actualities hidden in such insufficiently nuanced terms as woman, prostitute and sex worker.

Becoming-Animal The world that Deleuze and Guattari invoke is one of connection between human and nonhuman behaviours. Every species participates in a multiplicity of intersecting assemblages comprising human and non-human encounters. Houston et al. (2016) suggest that two important questions for planning theorists and practitioners are how multispecies relationships might be ethically and politically considered in planning decision-making and how non-humans can be engaged meaningfully with humans in deliberative practice without reducing non-humans to objects or symbols of political struggle (Metzger 2014a). Geographers have recognised for some time that it is impossible to separate the non-human into its own ontological space and the “cry of the nonhuman” (Johnston 2008: 636) is gradually finding voice in planning-related literature. Approaches are advocated that focus on new modes of human-non-human animal existence which go beyond traditional anthropocentric spatial orderings (see, Hinchliffe et al. 2005; Metzger 2014a, 2014b). For Deleuze and Guattari, non-human animals can potentially “dislocate our commonsense understandings of the world” (Young 2008: 245) as we encounter non-human animals in creative alliances of heterogeneities. Essentialist categories would dissolve into the more-thanhuman. Becoming-animal would involve processes of encounter in which humans accept the alterity of the more-than-human and introduce such a manner of existence into the way they think and act. As mentioned above, becoming-animal does not consist in imitating the essential nature of an animal, but in enhancing one’s sensory appreciation of smell, colour, sound, rhythm and the milieu that we inhabit. Houston et  al. (2016) advocate processes of planning becoming open to the capacities of all non-humans in Deleuze and Guattari’s (1987: 10–11, 280) notion of “becoming-world”: “we are not in the world; we become with the world” (Deleuze and Guattari 1994: 169). Becoming-world refers to a relational process of ethico-political interaction that moves away from speciesism and from human and non-human rights (see Braidotti 2006: 106–109) toward an ethical appreciation of what more-than-human bodies (including water, fire, rock and so on) can do. Becoming-world is a post-human process that appreciates the shared, common condition of the world as a whole (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 200). We are all in this together (Houston et al. 2016). As such, we have a responsibility to develop new ways of copoietic planning the meshwork of relations we share with non-humans. What might be the usefulness of becomings-minor for planning? I suggest that it relates to the question of minor politics explored below. Deleuze and Guattari (1986) suggest that minor politics arises in the “cramped spaces” and “impossible positions” (Thoburn 2012) of those who feel constrained by majoritarian societal relations and the identities which they impose. Minor politics, however, is not the same as minority politics which is often essentialist, concerned with issues of self-expression and recognition by the majority. Minor politics is concerned not with representation, but with creation. It engages those “who are missing from majoritarian social relations” (Deleuze 1989: 216); those “to come” in what would be a de- and reterritorialisation of civil society and its determinations (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 106). Minor politics is, therefore, a mode of engagement that always begins “in the middle” of any situation and is specific to that situation. 342

Lines of Becoming

Pragmatics “We are; we live; we think on the fringe, in the probable fed by the unexpected, in the legal nourished with information” (Serres 1982: 127). A major tension in spatial planning is that between the increasing theoretical and empirical recognition of the world as contingent, complex, non-linear and unpredictable and the essentialist codified predictability of plans, regulations and laws through which planning is practised (Savini et al. 2015). One of the main concepts that Deleuze and Guattari offer planning theory is that of pragmatics: “a set of tools for undoing certain habitual [or path-dependent] ways of being in the world” (O’Sullivan 2006: 309) and for creatively doing things differently. For Deleuze and Guattari (1987: 146) pragmatics – or cartography as they sometimes refer to it – is a material practice concerned with conditions for potentiality of creativity and transformation; of lines of becoming that disrupt thought and practices, such as planning law and strategic spatial planning.

Emergent Law: Becoming-Law? As Hillier (2015) illustrates, legal certainty is valued in planning, defining what is expected, permitted and prohibited. Such juridical “certainties” are designed “to help and protect (potential) property owners, investors and residents, and safeguard public goods” (Savini et al. 2015: 298). This very characteristic, however, might actually prohibit more flexible or adaptive forms of practice able to work with contingency and uncertainty (see Hillier 2015; Moroni 2007; Savini et al. 2015). Law is a social construct that invests space with particular valences and possibilities (Blomley 2003). It harbours a danger of rigidity, attempting to force the unexpected into material norms and standards. There is thus a need to rethink planning law more radically than is usual, where existing regulations tend to be amended (frequently streamlined) incrementally (Savini et al. 2015). Abrahams (2015, 2016) demonstrates how Deleuze’s non-essentialist thinking can assist in the creative construction of a new (minoritarian) form of methodology more in tune with the contingencies and unpredictability of the real world. The question is how might we establish “general legal conditions and open procedures” (Savini et  al. 2015: 306) while offering some form of certainty for particular issues without creating an essentialist machine to block or encourage potentialities in predetermined visions of “what should be”. Deleuze (1996) advocates processes of jurisprudence as a creative, open practice of case law which is more flexible than the civil law systems in continental Europe and elsewhere. We can build on Deleuze’s ideas to develop the concept of emergent law as a hybrid, or both/ and, which would follow the flows of problem spaces, searching out the significant conditions of possibility in a problem through which connections can be made to trigger change (Murray 2013). Emergent law is not a fixed set of normative laws, but “continuous processes of know how to organise things in relation to the problematic of legality, organising processes and events through immanent processes and events” (Murray 2013: 148). I suggest (Hillier 2015) that Deleuze and Guattari’s (1987) distinction between logos and nomos is helpful for development of a more emergent form of law. The traditional legal model of law is that of principle of order or logos: rationality and sovereign/state judgement. In contrast, nomos does not rely on permanent structures. It implies a rhizomatic form of organisation (the Deleuzean logic of “and” rather than “is/is not”) and changes of direction. Often self-organised, it is a fractal motion demonstrating an emergent order (Cowan 1996). Perhaps law can work in a less limited, more open, democratic, inclusionary direction, as outlined in Abrahams and Hillier’s (2016) exploration of nomos as a loose organising principle (or refrain) that is locally defined appropriate to circumstances and which avoids the transcendence of logos. 343

Jean Hillier

Strategic Spatial Planning: Planning for Not Having a Plan? The “concrete tendency” of many spatial plans is to “produce a particular target in space and time” (Savini et al. 2015: 304). I argue a need for a more flexible, adaptive form of strategic spatial planning that “must advance towards a future which is not known, which cannot be anticipated” (Derrida 1994: 37). I regard strategic spatial planning as a set of practices concerned with the future transformation of place, folding together social, environmental, economic and political values. I have proposed (Hillier 2011, 2013) that planning practice be concerned with strategically navigating pathways (or lines) rather than points; with speculation and experimentation rather than prediction. As such, Deleuze and Guattari’s pragmatics offers a basis for thinking potential methodologies. For Deleuze and Guattari, pragmatics comprises four components: a generative component – the retrospective tracing of concrete conditions of possibility and pointing toward the potentiality of what might emerge; a transformational component – making a map of assemblages and their possibilities for creation and transformation; a diagram of the relational forces that are in play either as potentialities or as effective emergences; and a machinic component – the outline of programmes of what new assemblages might emerge and what might take place (Hillier 2011: 508). Pragmatics involves processes that allow heterogeneous elements to encounter each other in an essentially open future. As Deleuze and Guattari (1987: 329) write, “it is no longer a question of imposing a form upon matter but of elaborating an increasingly rich and consistent material, the better to tap increasingly intense forces”. Hillier (2011) attempts to develop Deleuze and Guattari’s conceptualisation of pragmatics into a methodology of strategic navigation for strategic spatial planning. Calling for planning theorists and practitioners to “step outside what’s been thought before, . . . venture outside what’s familiar and reassuring, . . . to invent new concepts for unknown lands” (Deleuze 1995: 103) to allow possibilities for something new to emerge, Hillier, nevertheless, agrees with Deleuze and Guattari (1994: 201) that there is a need for “just a little order to protect us from chaos” and that some form of coding or territorialisation is inevitable. A plan might, in Purcell’s (2015) words, provide us with a “home” in the midst of chaos. But it is important to point out both that Deleuze and Guattari do not regard chaos and order as equivalent and also that such a “plan” would no longer feature as a complete ordered entity that can be divorced from the processes of actualisation. A plan would be designed to guide decisions as they are being made in the maelstrom of practice, rather than specifying the outcomes of those decisions (Abrahams and Hillier 2016). It would “help us commune with chaos without getting overwhelmed” (Purcell 2015: online). Deleuze and Guattari (1987: 161) advise that this is how it should be done: Lodge yourself on a stratum, experiment with the opportunities it offers, find an advantageous place on it, find potential movements of deterritorialisation, possible lines of flight, experience them, produce flow conjunctions here and there, try out continuums of intensities segment by segment, have a small plot of new land at all times. The stratum, then, is functionally necessary for us to “commune with chaos, as fully as we can, without going up in flames” (Purcell 2015: online). We cannot “live in chaos” (Purcell 2015), but we can experiment with potentialities and opportunities to encourage as many becomings as possible (Abrahams and Hillier 2016).

344

Lines of Becoming

On Revolutionary-Becoming Deleuze (1995) refers to his work as a pragmatic, political philosophy. He suggests that “we don’t need an ethical committee of supposedly well-qualified wise men, but user-groups” and continues “this is where we move from law into politics” (1995: 170). The intention is to transform existing forms of thought and practice: “men’s [sic] hope lies in a revolutionary becoming” (1995: 171). Deleuze is careful to distance his ideas of revolutionary-becoming or becomingrevolutionary from actual historical revolutions (the “old model”, [Purcell, 2014a]), which are blind to the dimension of becoming (Žižek 2004: 12). He concentrates on the political creativity of minoritarian becomings of “user groups” and their role in “reshuffling” the “binary distributions of sexes, classes and parties” (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 217). Becoming-revolutionary is concerned with challenging and overturning existing, normalising orders in order to diagram and machine something new. Mark Purcell (2013a, 2014b) interprets Deleuze and Guattari’s conceptualisation as referring to social revolution such that people come to govern themselves in Deleuze and Guattari’s “plot of new land”, escaping from “capture” by the state apparatus. As Purcell (2013b) explains, a “new land” is a generalised condition in which becoming pervades a community of association, repelling capitalism, the state and other apparatuses of capture for a time. Escape is only temporary, as fleeing elements might be recaptured, flee again and so on. Each escape, however, has an impact on the apparatus or system as a whole, “reshuffling” and weakening it potentially to the point of collapse. Since apparatuses can never be eliminated entirely, escape attempts “continue the active process of warding off these apparatuses, preventing the formation of institutions” (Purcell, 2013a: 29) that try to organise, code and control. The “new land” would be a land of association between elements that link together in relations (“revolutionary connections” [Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 220]) of mutual support. Yet, while some form of coordination will likely develop, Purcell (2014b: 175) explains that it cannot constitute a new system of rule, since becoming and flight by definition cannot rule. They cannot dominate, or establish a hegemony, or constitute an apparatus of capture. They are an association of “becomings”, a plane, a land traced out by flows in motion, a rhizome without a ruling order. As Purcell (2013a) suggests, it is difficult to imagine a role in such a new land for traditional, or even any, forms of planning practice. Purcell asks what a city without planning might be in a future of emergent self-organisation. He envisions a planning “that entirely refuses the state and capitalism” (2013a: 35); a planning that fights against organisation, institution and hierarchy, which does not try to coordinate activity or take autocratic decisions. “Planning would have to be conceived of as a power that is immanent to society, that is not done intently by any specialised group, but by everyone acting together to coordinate activity” (ibid.). I ask whether this is practicable or whether anarcho-socialist networks could be subject to domination by power-plays of the “usual suspects” (see Pløger this volume). Marie-Sophie Banville (2014) agrees with Purcell about the need to reject constructions of state-led planning. Banville explores the notion of becoming-imperceptible (the most radical form of becoming), not only with regard to planners, but to planning itself. She engages Deleuzean immanent ethics as creative, always-dynamic action concerned with what someone or something can do, rather than what they are, and offers a set of six proposals for the becoming-imperceptible of planning. Banville’s proposals include fostering autonomy through

345

Jean Hillier

inaction or through enabling action; a flexible, horizontal rhizomic structure; emergent law; agonism; multiscalar practice and engaged, reflexive practitioners who are themselves becomingimperceptible (Banville 2014: 72–88, my translations). It is difficult to imagine a revolutionary-becoming of societal constructs, such as planning, as becoming-imperceptible. Several authors (such as Nail 2012; Patton 2000, 2009, 2012; Tampio 2009) read revolutionary-becoming as including problem-based participatory forms of inclusive, democratic organisation. They suggest that Deleuze and Guattari do not necessarily mean the abolition of molar (e.g. state) organisations, but their transformation into a “fabric of immanent relations” (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 358). As Deleuze and Parnet (2002: 145) tell us, the question of a revolution has never been utopian spontaneity versus State organisation. When we challenge the model of the State apparatus or of the party organisation which is modelled on a conquest of that apparatus, we do not, however, fall into the grotesque alternatives: either that of appealing to a state of nature, to a spontaneous dynamic, or that of becoming the self-styled lucid thinker of an impossible revolution. I suggest that there remains scope for new actualisations of planning that might operate from within, immanent to the system under scrutiny. This would be the realm of the middle, where destabilisation, fissures and cracks may undermine essentialist structures and where experiments may transform the mainstream. The choice is not between control or chaos, stasis or emergence, being or becoming, but perhaps a messy in-between: “just enough to extend the crack, but not enough to deepen it irremediably?” (Deleuze 1990a: 156). This realm of ambiguity might be where “a new type of revolution is in the course of becoming possible” (Deleuze and Parnet 2002: 147). Is it possible to overcome path-dependencies sufficient to “extend the crack”, however? Although pure Deleuzean becoming infers transcending the context of historical conditions out of which something emerges (Žižek 2004), Deleuze recognises that the past (paths followed or not followed, structures and so on) can have a wide range of effects, triggering continuation of trajectories or lines of flight. For any emergent perspective, there will be the influence of sediments of the past: “it’s just the set of more or less negative preconditions that make it possible to experiment with something beyond history” (Deleuze 1995: 170).

In Conclusion Becomings belong to [planning]. (Deleuze and Parnet 2002: 2, adapted) I am acutely aware of the necessary and paradoxical task of concluding a chapter on becomings which are themselves inconclusive. If becoming is inherently polyvocal and non-reductive, it defies summary or conclusion. Nevertheless, for this chapter, it is, in Deleuze and Guattari’s words “time to die” (1987: 200). One of the key points I attempt to make in this chapter is that change is not linear from one state to another along some teleological trajectory that can be predicted or predetermined. Deleuze writes of lines of becoming, which do not join static points, but flow relationally between them. Lines of becoming are journeys where one does not know the destination, but where “other worlds are possible” (Escobar 2009). Becoming is more important than being: becoming different – thinking and acting differently, outside the essentialist box. 346

Lines of Becoming

Deleuze and Guattari suggest that minoritarian politics offers a way to resist capture and appropriation by mainstream hegemonic structures such as the state, sexism, anthropocentrism, essentialist regulations and so on. They call for a “revolutionary movement (the connection of flows, the composition of nondenumerable aggregates, the becoming-minoritarian of everybody/everything)” (Deleuze and Guattari 1987: 473). Becoming “explodes the ideas about what we are and what we can be” (Sotirin 2005: 99). Deleuze and Guattari highlight the absurdities of ready-made solutions and emphasise “the experimental, the ambiguous . . . and the aleatory nature of becoming and of life itself” (Deuchars 2011: np). The concept of becoming opens up space to reconceptualise the assemblage of spatial planning as replete with the radical contingency of emergent possibilities: to value, rather than deny, its paradoxical nature in-between structures offering certainty and identity and indeterminate potentialities for living differently. Becoming, for spatial planning, relates to “experimental intervention in a world that exceeds human powers of attunement, explanation, prediction, mastery, or control” (Connolly 2011: 10). Becoming “moves beyond our need to know (the truth, what is real, what makes us human), beyond our determination to control (life, nature, the universe)” (Sotirin 2005: 99). It offers “a series of hopes”; that we can “negotiate more wisely” (Connolly 2011: 15), to become with the more-than-human world in which we live. However, there can be no essentialist, ready-made formulae or “best practice guides” for becoming or for negotiating in complex worlds; communing with chaos. Becomings pulsate through encounters: wasp/orchid, Ahab/Moby Dick, and so on and so forth. Thought itself is an encounter with something that forces us to think (Deleuze 1994: 139). Lines of becoming offer us opportunities to think and act differently. Their value lies in their ability to “move us in a direction of possibilities that had before been beyond our ken” (May 2003: 151).

Acknowledgements My thanks to the referees and particularly to John Pløger for his insightful comments and questions on a previous draft.

References Abbott, J. (2005) “Understanding and managing the unknown,” Journal of Planning Education and Research, 24(3), pp. 237–251. Abbott, J. (2009) “Planning for complex metropolitan regions: a better future or a more certain one?” Journal of Planning Education and Research, 28, pp. 503–517. Abbott, J. (2012) “Planning as managing uncertainty: making the 1996 Livable Region Strategic Plan for Greater Vancouver,” Planning Practice and Research, 27(5), pp. 571–593. Abrahams, G. (2015) Deleuze’s Philosophy and its Usefulness to Planning: a case study of BRE Assessments, PhD thesis, Cardiff: Cardiff University, published as Abrahams (2016). Abrahams, G. (2016) Making Deleuze’s Philosophy Useful to Planning: proposals for a speculative and immanent assessment method, Oxford: Ashgate. Abrahams, G. and Hillier, J. (2016) “The (essentialist) ghost in the planning machine: Unlocking potentials in Western Australia’s R Codes”, paper to be presented at World Planning Schools Congress, Rio de Janeiro, 3–8 July. Albrechts, L. (2015) “Ingredients for a more radical strategic spatial planning,” Environment and Planning B, Planning and Design, 42, pp. 510–525. Albrechts, L. and Balducci, A. (2013) “Practising strategic planning: in search of critical features to explain the strategic character of plans,” disP – The Planning Review, 49(3), pp. 16–27. Balducci, A., Boelens, L., Hillier, J., Nyseth, T. and Wilkinson, C. (2011) “Strategic spatial planning in uncertainty: theory and exploratory practice,” Town Planning Review, 82(5), pp. 481–501.

347

Jean Hillier Banville, M.-S. (2014) Le Devenir-imperceptible de I’urbaniste: une lecture de l’éthique chez Gilles Deleuze, Masters thesis, Institut de l’urbanisme, Université de Montréal. Available at https://papyrus.bib.umon treal.ca/xmlui/handle/1866/11870 [accessed 06/05/17]. Baugh, B. (2006) “Real essences without essentialism,” in C. Boundas (ed.), Deleuze and Philosophy, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 31–42. Blomley, N. (2003) “Law, property, and the geography of violence: the frontier, the survey, and the grid,” Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 93(1), pp. 121–141. Bogue, R. (2013) Deleuze on Literature, New York: Routledge. Braidotti, R. (1993) “Discontinuous becomings: Deleuze and the becoming-woman of philosophy,” Journal of the British Society of Phenomenology, 24(1), pp. 44–55. Braidotti, R. (2002) Metamorphoses: towards a materialist theory of becoming, Cambridge: Polity. Braidotti, R. (2006) Transpositions, Cambridge: Polity. Braidotti, R. (2010) “Woman,” in A. Parr (ed.), The Deleuze Dictionary, revised ed., Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 306–308. Braidotti, R. (2011) Nomadic Subjects, 2nd ed., New York: Columbia University Press. Christensen, K. (1985) “Coping with uncertainty in planning,” Journal of the American Planning Association, 51, pp. 63–73. Colebrook, C. (2010) “Introduction Part 1,” in C. Colebrook and J. Weinstein (eds), Deleuze and Gender, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 1–19. Colebrook, C. (2013) “Modernism without women: the refusal of becoming-woman (and post-feminism),” Deleuze Studies, 7(4), pp. 427–455. Connolly, W. (2011) A World of Becoming, Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Cowan, B. (1996) “The nomos of Deleuze and Guattari: emergent holism in A Thousand Plateaus,” Annals of Scholarship, 11(3), pp. 271–287. Deleuze, G. (1983) [1962] Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. H. Tomlinson, London: Athlone Press. Deleuze, G. (1988) [1970] Spinoza, Practical Philosophy, trans. R. Hurley, San Francisco, CA: City Light Books. Deleuze, G. (1989) [1985] Cinema 2: the time-image, trans. H. Tomlinson and R. Galeta, Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Deleuze, G. (1990a) [1969] The Logic of Sense, trans. M. Lester and C. Stivale, London: Athlone. Deleuze, G. (1990b) [1968] Expressionism in Philosophy, Spinoza, trans. M. Joughin, New York: Zone Books. Deleuze, G. (1994) [1968] Difference and Repetition, trans. P. Patton, London: Athlone. Deleuze, G. (1995) [1990] Negotiations 1972–1990, trans. M. Joughin, New York: Columbia University Press. Deleuze, G. (1996) L’Abécédaire de Gilles Deleuze (avec Claire Parnet) Dir. Boutang P.-A., trans. D Hurth. Available at: www.after1968.org/app/webroot/uploads/ABCDelAnimal.pdf [accessed 06/05/17]. Deleuze, G. (1998) [1993] Essays Critical and Clinical, trans. D.W. Smith and M. Greco, London: Verso. Deleuze, G. and Foucault, M. (1977) “Intellectuals and power,” in M. Foucault (ed.), Language, Countermemory, Practice, trans. D. Bouchard and S. Simon, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, pp. 205–217. Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. (1986) [1975] Kafka: toward a minor literature, trans. D. Polan, Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. (1987) [1980] A Thousand Plateaus: capitalism and schizophrenia, trans. B. Massumi, London: Athlone Press. Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. (1994) [1991] What Is Philosophy? trans. H. Tomlinson and G. Burchill, London: Verso. Deleuze, G. and Parnet, C. (2002) [1977] Dialogues II, trans. H. Tomlinson and B. Habberjam, New York: Continuum. Derrida, J. (1994) “Nietzsche and the machine: interview with Jacques Derrida,” Journal of Nietzsche Studies, 7, pp. 7–66. Deuchars, R. (2011) “Creating lines of flight and activating resistance: Deleuze and Guattari’s war machine,” AntePodium, Victoria University, Wellington. Available at: www.victoria.ac.nz/atp/articles/ pdf/Deuchars-2011.pdf [accessed 13/08/2015]. de Vries, L.A. (2013) “Politics on the line,” in B. Evans and J. Reid (eds), Deleuze and Fascism, London: Routledge, pp. 126–147. Escobar, A. (2009) “Other worlds are (already) possible: self-organisation, complexity and post-capitalist cultures,” in J. Sen and P. Waterman (eds), World Social Forum Challenging Empires, New York: Black Rose Books, pp. 393–404.

348

Lines of Becoming Grabe, S. and Hyde, J.S. (2009) “Body objectification, MTV, and psychological outcomes amongst female adolescents,” Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 39(12), pp. 2840–2858. Grosz, E. (1994) “A thousand tiny sexes: feminism and rhizomatics,” in C. Boundas and D. Olkowski (eds), Gilles Deleuze and the Theater of Philosophy, New York: Routledge, pp. 187–210. Grosz, E. (2005) “Bergson, Deleuze and the becoming of unbecoming,” parallax, 11(2), pp. 4–13. Gunder, M. and Hillier, J. (2009) Planning in Ten Words or Less, Farnham: Ashgate. Hamilton, M. (2009) What’s Happening to Our Girls? Sydney: Penguin. Healey, P. (1997) Collaborative Planning, Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan. Healey, P. (2007) Urban Complexity and Spatial Strategies: towards a new relational planning for our times, Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan. Hillier, J. (2007) Stretching beyond the Horizon: a multiplanar theory of spatial planning and governance, Aldershot: Ashgate. Hillier, J. (2011) “Strategic navigation across multiple planes: towards a Deleuzean-inspired methodology for strategic spatial planning,” Town Planning Review, 82(5), pp. 503–527. Hillier, J. (2013) “On relationality and uncertainty,” disP – The Planning Review, 49(3), pp. 32–39. Hillier, J. (2014) Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari for Planners: Jean Hillier in conversation with Gareth Abrahams, InPlanning e-book. Available at: www.aesop-planning.eu/downloads/Other/en_GB/aesop-ya-book let-series-a-vol-1-deluze-and-guattari-jean-hillier-in-conversation-with-gareth-abrahams [accessed 06/05/17]. Hillier, J. (2015) “If Schrödinger’s cat miaows in the suburbs, will anyone hear?” Planning Theory, 14, pp. 425–443. Hillier, J. (2016) “Deterritorialising the face of the city: how Treponema pallidum planned Melbourne,” in H. Frichot, C. Gabrielsson and J. Metzger (eds), Deleuze and the City, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 128–144. Hinchliffe, S., Kearnes, M., Degen, M. and Whatmore, S. (2005) “Urban wild things: a cosmopolitan experiment,” Environment and Planning D: Society and Space, 23, pp. 643–658. Houston, D., Hillier, J., Byrne, J., Steele, W. and MacCallum, D. (2016) “Make kin, not cities! Multispecies entanglements and ‘becoming-world’ in planning theory,” Planning Theory, first published online February3, 2017. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/1473095216688042. Innes, J. and Booher, D. (2010) Planning with Complexity, New York: Routledge. Irigaray, L. (1985) This Sex Which Is Not One, trans. C. Porter, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Jardine, A. (1985) Gynesis: configurations of women and modernity, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Johnston, C. (2008) “Beyond the clearing: towards a dwelt animal geography,” Progress in Human Geography, 32(5), pp. 633–649. Lagadec, P. (2009) “A new cosmology of risks and crises: time for a radical shift in paradigm and practice,” Review of Policy Research, 26(4), pp. 473–486. May, T. (2003) “When is a Deleuzian becoming?” Continental Philosophy Review, 36, pp. 139–153. Metzger, J. (2014a) “The moose are protesting: the more-than human politics of transport infrastructure development,” in J. Metzger, P. Allmendinger and S. Oosterlynck (eds), Planning against the Political, New York: Routledge, pp. 191–213. Metzger, J. (2014b) “Commentary: spatial planning and/as caring for more-than human place,” Environment and Planning A, 46(5), pp. 1001–1011. Moroni, S. (2007) “Introduction: land-use, planning and the law,” Planning Theory, 6(2), pp. 107–111. Murray, J. (2013) Deleuze & Guattari: emergent law, Abingdon: Routledge. Nail, T. (2012) Returning to Revolution: Deleuze and Guattari and Zapatismo, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. O’Sullivan, S. (2006) “Pragmatics for the production of subjectivity: time for probe-heads,” Journal for Cultural Research, 10(4), pp. 309–322. Patton, P. (2000) Deleuze and the Political, London: Routledge. Patton, P. (2009) “Deleuze’s practical philosophy,” in C. Boundas (ed.), Gilles Deleuze: the intensive reduction, London: Continuum, pp. 187–203. Patton, P. (2012) “Deleuze’s political philosophy,” in D.W. Smith and H. Somers-Hall (eds), A Cambridge Companion to Deleuze, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 198–219. Portugali, J. (2008) “Learning from paradoxes about prediction and planning in self-organising cities,” Planning Theory, 7(3), pp. 248–262. Portugali, J. (2012) “Complexity theories of cities: first, second or third culture of planning,” in G. de Roo, J. Hillier and J. Van Wezemael (eds), Complexity and Planning, Farnham: Ashgate, pp. 117–140.

349

Jean Hillier Purcell, M. (2013a) “A new land: Deleuze and Guattari and planning,” Planning Theory and Practice, 14(1), pp. 20–38. Purcell, M. (2013b) “Planning, food movements in Oaxaca and (natch) Deleuze and Guattari.” Available at: www.pathtothepossible.wordpress.com/2013/08/05 [accessed 12/08/2015]. Purcell, M. (2014a) “Introduction: for a politics we have yet to imagine,” Space and Polity, 18(2), pp. 117–121. Purcell, M. (2014b) “Ranciere and revolution,” Space and Polity, 18(2), pp. 168–181. Purcell, M. (2015) “Chaos and Control 2: Deleuze and Guattari,” posted 28 September 2015. Available at: https://pathtothepossible.wordpress.com/2015/09/28/chaos-and-control-2-deleuze-guattari-2/ [accessed 05/10/2015]. Rae, G. (2014) Ontology in Heidegger and Deleuze: a comparative analysis, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Rittel, H. and Webber, M. (1973) “Dilemmas in a general theory of planning,” Policy Sciences, 4(2), pp. 155–169. Savini, F., Majoor, S. and Salet, W. (2015) “Dilemmas of planning: intervention, regulation and investment,” Planning Theory, 14(3), pp. 296–315. Serres, M. (1982) [1980] The Parasite, trans. L. Schehr, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Shaikh, M., Bughio, F.A. and Kadri, S.A. (2015) “The representation of men and women in advertisements: a critical discourse analysis,” Women, 7, pp. 108–141. Silva, E. (2002) “Indecision factors when planning for land use change,” European Planning Studies, 10(3), pp. 335–358. Sotirin, P. (2005) “Becoming-woman,” in C. Stivale (ed.), Gilles Deleuze: key concepts, Chesham: Acumen, pp. 98–109. Stagoll, C. (2010) “Becoming,” in A. Parr (ed.), The Deleuze Dictionary, revised ed., Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 25–27. Tampio, N. (2009) “Assemblages and the multitude: Deleuze, Hardt, Negri and the postmodern left,” European Journal of Political Theory, 8, pp. 383–400. Thoburn, N. (2012) “Minor politics, territory and Occupy,” Mute, 3(3). Available at: www.metamute. org/editorial/articles/minor-politics-territory-and-occupy [accessed 06/08/2015]. Young, K. (2008) “Deleuze and Guattari: the animal question,” in B. Herzogenrath (ed.), An [Un]Likely Alliance: thinking environment[s] with Deleuze/Guattari, Newcastle-upon-Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, pp. 245–265. Žižek, S. (2004) Organs Without Bodies: Deleuze and consequences, London: Routledge.

350

INDEX

abduction 122 Abrahams, G. 332, 338 absolute space 17–18, 19 accountability 176 accumulation by dispossession 174 actants 305, 307–8 action 34; communicative 20–1, 22, 86, 195–6; direct and insurgent planning 279–83; legitimacy of communicative planning 97, 98–9 actor-network theory (ANT) 10, 302–13; critiques and responses 307–10; future directions 310–12; key concepts and dynamics 303–6; modes of research and arguing 306–7; origins and applications 302–3 actors 32–3, 226–7, 227–8, 230 Adams, J. 119 adaptive governance 224–5, 230 administrative reforms 240 adversary 267, 268, 269 advocacy planning 277, 279 Africa 88–9; South Africa see South Africa agency 202–3; counter-hegemonic 176, 282–3; as an emergent phenomenon 332–3; structure and 253–4, 259 agglomeration economies 58 agon 266–7 agonism 9, 182, 183, 214, 264–75; hegemony 267–9, 270, 272; as inadmissible 272–3; threads on 264–6; war of position 268–9, 270, 272 agonistic pluralism 22, 101–2 Allmendinger, P. 113, 185 American Institute of Planners 42–3 American Planning Association 48 Amsterdam 136, 140 ancient cities 41

Angel, S. 48 antagonism: ineradicability of 267–8; violent 181–2 Anthropocene, the 6, 53–66; economics for 60–3; evidence-based planning 57–9 anthropological functionalism 223 anti-paternalism 97, 98, 99 apartheid 295–7 Appadurai, A. 150 apparatus 197; disciplinary apparatus of planning 194, 197–201 Arabization 292–4 archaeological approach 197 archaeology of the present 284 Aristotle 83, 84 Arkaraprasertkul, N. 162 artefacts of planning 310–11 articulation 149 assemblage theory 10, 303–4, 326–36; axes in assemblage theory 329–30; content theories as actualizations of 333–4; contribution to planning theory 331–3; and traditions of thought in planning theory 326–8; virtualactual character of assemblages 330–1; wasp-orchid assemblage 339 associations 303–4 Assyrians 293 Athanasiou, A. 152 attraction of the creative class 109 Auseinandersetzung (setting-apart-of-each-other) 267 austerity policies 107 Ba’ath Party 292–3 Bäcklund, P. 265 Baeten, G. 184 Bang, H. 242 351

Index Banville, M.-S. 345–6 Barcelona 239 Barcelona model 29, 30, 32, 37, 239 Barnett, C. 127 basic institutions 270 becoming 10–11, 34–5, 331, 337–50; emergent law 343; nature of 339–40; non-essentialist unexpected 338–9; pragmatics 343; revolutionary-becoming 345–6; strategic spatial planning 344 becoming-animal 341, 342 becoming-imperceptible 345–6 becoming-woman 341–2 becoming-world 342 becomings-minor 340–1 behaviour: social 48–9; and sustainability 63 being 339 Benjamin, W. 284 Bhalaswa Jahangir Puri colony 157 Bhan, G. 149–50 bifurcations 319–21 binary constructions 171, 280–1 biological evolution 223 biophysical systems perspective 54–6 bioregions 57–9 black-boxing 305 Black Lives Matter 151 Blanco, H. 122 Blanco, I. 239 ‘blocks’ of domination 211–12 Blocks Together 143, 150 Bogue, R. 340 Bollens, S.A. 291 Boltanski, L. 126 Booher, D.E. 265 boundary objects 306 Bourdieu, P. 327, 333 Brazil 146–7, 148; City Statute 148 Bridge, G. 126–7 Brundtland Commission 138 Butler, J. 152 butterfly effect 315 calculation 306 Caldeira, T. 146–7, 148 Callon, M. 303, 304, 307 Campbell, H. 84, 135 Canada 42, 44, 45, 46 Cape Town: protests against African migrants 282, 286; Toilet Wars 281 capital 60 capitalism: free market capitalism 277; justice and the potential for reform under 135–6; varieties of capitalism hypothesis 256 capitalist state 277 cars 320–1 Cartesian doubt 121

Castells, M. 7, 16, 143, 144–5 change: institutional 252, 253, 255, 256–7, 258, 25960; non-linear 10, 314–25 change agents 32 chaos theory 315 Chatterjee, P. 146 Chicago 290; Anti-Eviction Campaign 143, 150–1 Chicago University 3, 106 Chile 106 China 2, 103 circular flow of exchange value 59–60 citadels 138 ‘Cities of the Global South and the Rest of the World’ conference 148 citizen participation 95–6, 134–5, 185, 187–8, 276–9 citizenship, urban 145–8 city beautiful movement 42, 43 city marketing 109 civil society 146, 317; see also grassroots of planning, social movements class interests 131 class struggle 183 classical liberalism 70, 72–4, 76–7 climate change 50, 62 Cloward, R. 148 Club of Rome report, Limits to Growth (LTG) 53–4, 63 Coase, R.H. 254 Cochrane, A. 20 co-evolution 8–9, 221–33, 321; evolutionary governance theory (EGT) 8–9, 225–30, 231; planning theory 224–5; social theory 223–4 collaborative planning 20–2, 86, 277; see also communicative planning collective orientation 317, 318 Collective Towns 293–4 colonial space 173–5 colonialism 2, 168–9; see also postcolonial theorizing colonization of future 283–5 common good 69–70; see also public interest communicative action 20–1, 22, 86, 195–6 communicative planning (CP) 6–7, 86, 93–104, 243, 265, 277, 327–8; and citizen participation 95–6; core ideas and progress of 93–4; critiques of 21–2, 99–102; debates 99–102; and diversity 159–60; legitimising 97–9; and neoliberalism 112; planner role 21, 96–7, 279; process/outcome debate 134–5; and spatial planning 20–2, 23, 24 communicative rationality 93–4, 317, 322, 328 Communist Manifesto 190 communitarian conceptions of the public interest 73 community engagement 243 352

Index complexity theory 10, 224–5, 314–25; bifurcations and transitions 319–21; and the planning debate 321–2; settlements as non-linear dynamic systems 316–21; time, non-linearity and complexity 315–16 compromise 126 concentric zone theory 159 Condorcet jury theorem 98, 99 conflict 291; and agonism 9, 264–75; counterconducts, subjectification and 214; ethnonational and the dark side of planning 290–7, 299; historical institutionalism 257; moralization of political conflict 184; neo-pragmatism 124–5; see also agonism conflictual consensus 267, 269 consensus: agonism and 266, 267, 270, 272; communicative planning 20–2, 23, 101–2; conflictual 267, 269; postpolitics 112–13, 181, 184 constant capital stocks criterion 61 constructivist institutionalism 250, 257 contagious diseases 320 content 33 content-oriented theories 333–4 contestation 267, 268 context of strategic planning 32–3 contingency 221, 222 controlling growth 44, 45 Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW) 158 corporatist governance model 240 cosmopolitan pragmatism 125–7 Coulthard, G. 174, 176 counter-conducts 8, 203, 207, 211, 212–17; conflict, subjectification and 214; planning’s 214–16 counter-hegemonic agency 176, 282–3 creative class 137; attraction of 109 crises 317; financial crisis 111 critical attitude 216 critical gender studies 156 critical junctures 256–7, 259–60 critical race theory 159 Crouch, D. 111 crypto-urbanism 162 cultural work 8, 201; exploring the contribution of 201–4 culture: planning culture 197–8; postcolonial theorizing 171, 172; values and smart growth 48–9 DAD (decide-announce-defend) 187 dark side of planning 174; countering 8, 207–20; Foucault and 208–10; marginalization and oppression 10, 289–301; planning’s counterconducts 216

Davidoff, P. 74 Davidson, A. 216 Davoudi, S. 19, 83, 85, 245 De Vries, L.A. 340 Dean, J. 186 Dear, M. 18 Death, C. 214 decolonization 2; of the future 283–5; of planning theory 175–6 de-development 61 de-growth movement 62–3 DeLanda, M. 10, 329, 330, 331, 333 Deleuze, G. 10, 224, 330–1, 333; becoming 337–47 Delhi 157, 160–1 deliberation 311–12 deliberative democracy 96, 311–12 democracy 124, 130, 140; deliberative 96, 311–12; as demos 266–7; participatory 279, 281; representative 278–9; Singapore 139–40 democratization 146–7 dependencies 229–30; path dependencies see path dependencies depoliticization 187; see also postpolitics description 306–7 designers 229 desire 298–9 deterritorialization 330, 339 developing countries (global South) 48, 59, 157–8, 278 development 62; vs growth 59–60, 61; sustainable 45–6, 138 development committees 107 development industry 47 Dewey, J. 122, 134 dialogical proceduralism 70, 71–2, 76 Dierwechter, Y. 49 difference: in postcolonial theorizing 170–1; principle 132 DiMaggio, P.J. 258 direct action 279–83; see also social movements disavowal of equality 182 disciplinary apparatus of planning 194, 197–201; reform 198–201 discipline 209, 210 discourse structuralization 34 discursive configurations 230 discursive institutionalism 250, 257 dispossession 174 dissensus 269, 270–2 dissent, suppression of 112–13 dissipative structures 54–5 distribution 259–60 divergentism 70–1, 75–6 diversity 4, 7–8, 130, 140, 155–66; critiques and dilemmas 161–3; gender 155–8; and justice 136–8; race and ethnicity 158–61 353

Index domination 196, 211–12, 283 ‘double consciousness’ of black people 158 duration 36–7 Durban 282, 286 dynamic systems 10, 314–25; bifurcations and transitions 319–21; settlements as non-linear 316–21 Eastern Europe 2 ecological crisis 6, 53–66; alternative economic paradigm 60–3; biophysical systems perspective 54–6; cities as dissipative structures 54–5; cities as ecosystems 55–6; evidencebased planning 57–9; need for new economic theory 59–60 ecological economics 60–3 ecological footprints 56–7, 59, 62, 64 economic growth see growth economics 47, 49–50; for the Anthropocene 60–3; need for new economic theory 59–60 economies of scale 58 ecosphere 55 ecosystems: cities as 55–6; regional 57–9 Eddington, A.S. 54 efficiency 130–1, 199–201, 203–4 Einstein, A. 17, 18 emancipation 36 emergent law 343 enclaves 138 enduring institutions 256 energy 317–18 enrolment 304 Enterprise Zones 244 entitlements 78 entrepreneurial cities 108 entropy 55 environment, natural 311; see also ecological crisis environmentalism 4; and equity 138–9 envisioning 34 equality 190; disavowal of 182 equity 88, 130, 140; environmentalism and 138–9 equity planning 277, 279 Esmark, A. 242 essences 338–9 essentialization 171 essentialism 338–9; strategic 172 ethical self-formation 212 ethics 6, 81–92; normative 81–2, 83–8, 89, 161–2; pragmatism and 124; Southern epistemologies 88–9 ethnicity see race and ethnicity ethnocracy 292 Euclidean geometry 17–18 European social democracy 136 European Spatial Development Perspective 16, 19 European Union 159

evidence-based planning 57–9 eviscerating urbanism 150 evolution: co-evolution see co-evolution; of planning theory 1, 2–5; societal 316–19 evolutionary governance theory (EGT) 8–9, 225–30, 231; governance configurations 226–8; object and subject formation 228–9; path, inter and goal dependencies 229–30 explanation 307 expressivity 329 exteriority, relations of 329 fact–value divide 120–2 factors of production 60 Fainstein, N. 99–100 Fainstein, S.S. 99–100 Faludi, A. 3 Fanon, F. 150, 283 fantasy 298–9 feminism 136, 155–6 field theory 333 finance capital 60 financial crisis of 2008 111 Fleming, W. 143 flexibility 229–30 flight, lines of 340 Florida, R. 107, 109, 137 Flyvbjerg, B. 84, 86–7, 208–9 Follett, M.P. 119 foreclosed homes 151–2 Forester, J. 94, 96, 120, 265 formal institutions 226–7, 227–8 Foucault, M. 4, 8, 207–20, 228, 266; counterconducts 203, 207, 211, 212–17; and the dark side of planning 208–10; ethics 83–4, 89–90; Foucauldian analytical tools and the discipline and practice of planning 8, 194–206; power 101, 196, 211–12, 224, 270, 272, 309; the subject and power 211–12 Fraser, N. 82 free market capitalism 277 Friedman, M. 106 Friedmann, J. 18, 35, 94, 119 functionalism 223 future, decolonizing the 283–5 Gaebler, T. 238–9 Gaete, C. 143 Gaffikin, F. 291 Gans, H.J. 70 garden city movement 42, 45 Geddes, P. 19 gender 7–8, 155–8; and planning theory 156–8 genealogical approach 197 geometry 17–18 ghettoes 138 Giddens, A. 23, 327

354

Index Gidwani, V. 150 Gilroy, P. 152 Glasgow 109 Glendening, P. 45 global protest movements 214, 270, 271, 284–5 global South (developing countries) 48, 59, 157–8, 278 goal dependencies 229–30 Goffman, E. 202 Goodman, R. 290 Gordon, C. 203 governance 9, 180–1, 231, 237–49; adaptive 224–5, 230; as an analytical concept in planning theories 237–8; evolutionary governance theory (EGT) 8–9, 225–30, 231; from government to 237, 238–9; legitimacy of governance networks 241–2; neoliberal 185, 187, 239, 242–4; path dependence of governance practices 239–41; in practice 244–6; scale of 47–8 governance-beyond-the-state 183–4 government: of government 198, 202; shift to governance 237, 238–9 governmental state 211, 212 governmentality 8, 195, 209, 264; counterconducts and 213, 215, 216; and subjectification 210, 211–12 Gramsci, A. 268 grassroots of planning 7, 143–54; human rights 150–2; poor people’s movements 148–52, 153; theory of the city 144–5; urban citizenship 145–8 grassroots movements see social movements Gray, J. 74 green regeneration 111–12 greenbelts 44 grey space 161, 175 growth 62, 137; vs development 59–60, 61; inclusive 147; sustainable economic growth 199 growth management 5, 41–52; approaches 43–5; future of 49–50; history of 41–3; smart growth 5, 45–9 Guattari, F. 10, 337, 339–41, 342, 343, 344, 345, 347 Habermas, J. 4, 20–1, 86, 134, 195, 327 Hacking, I. 201–2 Hall, P. 133, 250, 255–6 hard planning 244–6 Harper, T. 120–2 Harvey, D. 17, 18, 105, 135 Haughton, G. 113, 185 Hayden, D. 156 Hayek, F. 106, 114 Healey, P. 29, 71, 96, 118–19, 123, 259, 326 hegemonic planning 10, 289, 298–9

hegemony 267–9, 270, 272 Heidegger, M. 267 heritage VD clinic 341–2 Heseltine, M. 107 heterogeneous settings 333 heterosexual matrix 156 Hillier, J. 266, 272–3, 326, 332, 341, 344 historical conjuncture 149–50, 151, 153 historical institutionalism (HI) 250, 251, 251–2, 253, 255–8; and planning theory 259–60 Holden, M. 125–6 Holston, J. 146–7, 148 home liberations 151–2 home vicinity ambience 320 homelands 295, 296 Homo sapiens 63 Hoover, J. 150–1 hope, politics of 150 housing 48, 137; Singapore 139 Howard, E. 42 human rights 150–2 humane urbanism 285–6 Huxley, M. 22, 160 hybrid spaces 175–6 ideal speech situation 20–1 identity 170–1 imaginary mode 298 imagination 282–3, 286; and the urgency in decolonizing the future 283–5 imaginative planning 122 immutable mobiles 306 impartiality 132–3 implementation 34 impoverishment of poverty 149–50 inadmissible, the 271, 272–3 inclusion 199 inclusive growth 147 inclusive planning, liberal 276–9 incommensurability thesis 75 incremental institutional change 259–60 incrementalism 133; progressive 122–3 India 147, 157, 159, 160–1, 163; Delhi 157, 160–1 indigenous peoples 171, 172–3 individualism 5; moral 72, 77 infinity 87 informal institutions 226–7, 227–8 informal settlements 149, 160–1, 278 information sharing 317 Innes, J. 96, 265 innovation 317–18; procedural innovations 311–12 input legitimacy 242 institutional change 252, 253, 255, 256–7, 258, 259–60 institutional design 255

355

Index institutional isomorphism 258 institutionalism 231, 328; new see new institutionalism institutions: basic 270; definitions of 251–2, 253, 254, 255–6, 258; enduring 256; formal and informal 226–7, 227–8; institutional context of strategic planning 32–3; path dependence 241 instrumental rationality 3, 93, 94 insurgent planning (IP) 9–10, 276–88; break with liberal inclusive planning 276–9; decolonizing the future 283–5; invited and invented spaces of action 279–83 integration 199 intention 308 interdependencies 229–30 interessment 304 intermediate scales 333 intersubjective reasoning 317, 318 invented spaces 95, 279–83 invited spaces 95, 279–83 Iraq 292–4, 299 Israel 294–5, 299 Jacobs, J. 136–7 Jonas, A. 107 Judaization 295 just city 134, 135, 139–40 justice 7, 88, 120, 130–42, 190, 278; diversity and 136–8; environmentalism and equity 138–9; giving priority to 131–2; potential for reform under capitalism 135–6; process/ outcome debate 134–5; role of planning 132–4; what can be done 139–40 justifications 126 Kathputli settlement 160–1 Kekes, J. 74, 75 Kelly, R. 106 Keynesianism 114 knowledge 60; and power 224, 227–8, 230; legitimacy of communicative planning 97, 98, 99 Kurds 292–4 labour 60 Lacan, J. 4, 224, 298 lack 298–9 Ladrillo, El 106 land 60; confiscation in Israel 295; planning and the production of colonial space 173–5; public ownership 140; urban 54, 56–7 land rights 158 Latour, B. 303, 304, 305, 306, 307, 309, 312 Law, J. 308, 309 law: emergent 343; rule of 78 Lefebvre, H. 7, 17, 134, 145

legitimacy: governance networks 241–2; legitimization of communicative planning 97–9; strategic planning 35–6 Leibniz, G.W. 18 Lenoir, G. 151 leverage planning 243–4 liberal inclusive planning 276–9 liberalism: classical and public interest 70, 72–4, 76–7; neoliberalism see neoliberal planning, neoliberalism limiting growth 44 Limits to Growth (LTG) 53–4, 63 Lindblom, C. 133 lines of becoming 339–40, 346–7 Liverpool 107 local government, urban 147 Loepfe, M. 187 logos 343 London 42, 57, 107; redevelopment of the South Bank 184 Lorenz, E. 315 Luhmann, N. 223–4 machining 333, 344 Mahoney, J. 257 majority 340–1 Malmö 111 managerial cities 108 managerial governance model 240 Mannheim, K. 132–3 Mäntysalo, R. 35, 265 many minds, advantage of 97, 98, 99 mapping of possibilities 332, 344 Marcuse, P. 138 marginalization 10, 289–301; ANT and the marginalized 308–9; cases of 292–7; hegemonic planning 10, 289, 298–9; theories on the planning of 290–2 markets: free market capitalism 277; governance 238–9; regulation of 23; and smart growth 47; state and market in neoliberal planning 105 Marsh, B. 119 Marx, K. 174 Marxism 131, 144, 149 Massey, D. 18 master planning 16, 28 master-signifiers 298, 299 materiality 329 Maturana, H.R. 223 Mbembe, A. 150 McIntyre, A. 162 mediators 304, 305 Mees, P. 99 Melbourne 341–2 meta ethics 82–3, 84, 90, 162; Southern scholarship 88–9 Meth, P. 282

356

Index new urbanism 45, 46 Newtonian view 17–18 nomocratic universalism 77–8 nomos 343 non-humans: actants 305, 307–8; becominganimal 341, 342 non-linearity 10, 314–25; bifurcations and transitions 319–21; complexity and the planning debate 321–2; settlements as non-linear dynamic systems 316–21; time, complexity sciences and 315–16 non-sceptical value-pluralism 74, 76 Nordic countries 23, 243 normative agenda 309–10, 311–12 normative ethics 81–2, 161–2; planning’s dominant focus on 83–8, 89 North, D.C. 254 Nozick, R. 72

Meyer, J.W. 258 Mies, M. 284 migration 163 Mill, J.S. 64 Millennium Development Goals (MDGs) 30 Minkowski, H. 18 minor (minoritarian) politics 342, 347 minority 340–1; becomings-minor 340–2 Miraftab, F. 151 mobilization 304 Moby Dick 341 modernization 293; modernizing agendas 157–8 modus vivendi 74 molar lines 339–40 molecular lines 340 monological recognition 173 Mont Pelerin Society 106 moral individualism 72, 77 moralization of political conflict 184 Moroni, S. 255 Morrissey, M. 291 motivation 308 Mouffe, C. 21–2; agonism 101–2, 264, 267–70, 271, 272; postpolitics 181–2, 183, 188 Murdoch, J. 309 Murray, C. 107 natural environment 311; see also ecological crisis Neighbourhood Planning initiative 243 neoclassical microeconomics 255 neoliberal economics 59, 60–1 neoliberal governance 185, 187, 239; in planning theory 242–4 neoliberal planning 7, 105–17; crisis and its aftermath 111–12; established tools and policies 109–11; neoliberalization of spatial planning 22–4, 25; normalising 107–9; pioneering 106–7; postpolitical planning 112–14 neoliberalism 3, 4–5, 28, 99–100, 131–2 neo-pragmatism see pragmatism neo-radical planning 265 Netherlands, the 16; Amsterdam 136, 140 networks: actor-network theory see actornetwork theory (ANT); legitimacy of governance networks 241–2; social capital networks 97, 98–9 New Haven, Connecticut 42 new institutionalism (NI) 9, 250–63; core concepts 251–4; historical institutionalism (HI) 250, 251, 251–2, 253, 255–60; rational choice institutionalism 250, 251, 251–2, 253, 254–5; sociological institutionalism 250, 251, 251–2, 253, 258–9 ‘new land’ 345 New Public Management (NPM) 238 new regionalism 45, 47–8

object formation 228–9 object orientation 317, 318 objective meanings 85 Occupy movement 270, 271, 284–5 Olmstead, F.L. 119 Ontario 46 Oosterlynck, S. 183, 184–5, 187, 189 oppression 10, 289–301; cases of 292–7; hegemonic planning 10, 289, 298–9; theories on the planning of 290–2 orientalization 169 Osborne, D. 238–9 Ostrom, E. 254 Othering 169, 170, 171 outcome/process debate 134–5 output 33–4 output legitimacy 242 Paasi, A. 19, 20 Palestinians 294–5 paradigm shift 19 Paris 43 Parnell, S. 88 Parnet, C. 346 participation: citizen 95–6, 134–5, 185, 187–8, 276–9; postpolitics and 187–8 participatory democracy 279, 281; see also insurgent planning (IP) particularization 184–5 paternalism 98 path dependencies 229–30, 256; ANT 311; of governance practices 239–41 Peirce, C.S. 122 phronesis 86–7 performance management 200–1 performativity 230 personhood 152 Pickering, A. 308

357

Index Pierre, J. 240 Pierson, P. 255 Pieterse, E. 88 Pinochet, General 106 Pithouse, R. 149 Piven, F.F. 148 place 15–16 place-bundles 17–19 planner role: communicative planning 21, 96–7, 279; justice 132–4 planning culture 197–8 planning debate 321–2 planning education 163 planning ethics see ethics planning styles 243–4 pluralism 159; agonistic 22, 101–2; inexistence of the public interest 71, 71–2, 73–4, 75; valuepluralism 70, 74–5, 76, 77 police order 182, 183 policy evaluation 130–1 political economy 4 political instability 50 political society 146 political will 47–8 politics: agonism and conflict 267–73; grassroots of planning 7, 143–54; of hope 150; minoritarian 342, 347; political context of strategic planning 32–3; of recognition 172–3; right-wing 163; see also postpolitics poor people’s movements 148–52, 153, 282, 286 population dispersal 295 Porter, L. 152 positive feedback 256, 259–60 positivism 19 possessory politics 152 possibility space 331 post-1989 zeitgeist 181 postcolonial theorizing 8, 167–79; decolonization of planning theory 175–6; ethico-political commitment of 169–70; identity and difference in 170–1; production of colonial space 173–5; representation, resistance and the politics of recognition 172–3 postpolitics 8, 112–14, 180–93; contesting 188–9; criticisms 185–6; defining 186–7; diagnosing the postpolitical condition 181–3; of planning 183–5; potentials for further development 186–9; specifying 187–8 post-positivism 4 post-structuralism 4, 222, 231 poverty: impoverishment of 149–50; poor people’s movements 148–52, 153, 282, 286; urban 107 Powell, W. 258 power 268; ANT 305, 309; communicative planning 98, 100–2; dark side of planning 8, 208–9, 209–10; Foucault 101, 196, 211–12,

224, 270, 272, 309; and knowledge 224, 227–8, 230; legitimacy of communicative planning 97, 98, 99; neo-pragmatic planning theory 124–5; new institutionalism 252, 253; Othering as a relation of 170; pragmatism and planning theory 120; and rationality 208–9, 209–10; the subject and 211–12 pragmatics 343, 344 pragmatism 4, 7, 118–29, 202; cosmopolitan 125–7; and planning theory 118–23; postmodern critique 123–5; relational 123; Unger’s view 125 primitive accumulation 174 private management planning 244 problem solving 122 problematization 198–200, 304 procedural discourse ethics 86 procedural innovations 311–12 procedural planning 16, 19, 20–2, 265 procedural principles 99–100 proceduralism, dialogical 70, 71–2, 76 process/outcome debate 134–5 progressive incrementalism 122–3 progressive movement 119 progressive planners 133 progrowth governance model 240 projects 29, 30, 34 promoting growth 43–4 property rights 151–2 proximity 87 public interest 3, 6, 69–80; fall from grace of the idea 69–70; ineliminability of the concept 78–9; rethinking 75–8; typology of conceptions 78, 79; views on inexistence of 69, 70–5 public land ownership 140 public-private partnerships (PPPs) 106, 107, 110–11 Purcell, M. 112, 345 purification approach 183 Purkarthofer, E. 244 quasi-sustainability 59, 64 QWERTY keyboard 256 race and ethnicity 7–8, 158–61; conflict, marginalization and oppression 290–7, 299; and planning theory 159–61 racial segregation 295–7 radical planning 278 radical strategic planning 36 Ramirez de la Cruz, E.E. 48 Rancière, J. 113, 181, 182, 183, 270–2 rational choice 3 rational choice institutionalism (RI) 250, 251, 251–2, 253, 254–5 rational planning 19, 20, 133, 327

358

Index rationalistic conception of the public interest 69 rationality: communicative 93–4, 317, 322, 328; instrumental 3, 93, 94; and power 208–9, 209–10; technical 317, 321–2 Rawls, J. 85–6, 132, 278 Reagan, R. 107 realist ontology 331 reality effects 230 reasonable disagreement 77 recognition, politics of 172–3 Reddy, R. 150 reformist planning 264–5 reforms: administrative 240; of planning systems and practices 198–201 regimes of truth 8, 194, 197 regional ecosystems 57–9 rehabilitation 160–1 Rein, M. 119 relational approaches 328; politicization 183, 189, 190; relational nature of strategic planning 35 relational goods 97, 98–9 relational pragmatism 123 relational space 16, 17–20, 24; critiques of 19–20 relations of exteriority 329 relocation settlements 157, 160–1 repoliticization 188–9 representation 172–3 representative democracy 278–9 resilience 138 resistance 172–3; counter-conducts see counter-conducts resource interdependencies 331 resource orientation 317, 318 reterritorialization 330, 339, 340 revolution 183 revolutionary-becoming 345–6 Rhodes, R.A.W. 240–1, 242 right to the city 7, 144 right-wing politics 163 rights 7, 78; human 150–2; land 158; property 151–2 rigidity 229–30 risk 48–9 Rittel, H. 75, 119, 321 roll-back neoliberalism 107–8 roll-out neoliberalism 108 roll-with-it neoliberalism 108 Rolnik, R. 148 Roma communities 161 Rorty, R. 121, 128 Rose, N. 145–6 Rosenau, J.N. 238 Rowan, B. 258 Royal Town Planning Institute (RTPI) 16 rule of law 78 rules 330, 334; social 85

Sager, T. 22, 109 Said, E. 169 Sandercock, L. 137, 278 Santiago 106 sceptical value-pluralism 75, 76 Scerri, A. 125–6 Schön, D. 119 Scotland 8, 198–201, 203–4 Secchi, B. 28 Second World War 42 segregation 295–7 selectivity 33 self-organization 231 settlements: informal 149, 160–1, 278; as non-linear dynamic systems 316–21; relocation settlements 157, 160–1 settler-colonialism 172–3, 174 shack settlements 149 silences 311 Simmie, J. 70 simulacra 137 Singapore 7, 139–40 singularities 331 ‘smart cities’ 127 smart decline approaches 49 smart growth 5, 45–9; challenges to 47–9; as a paradigm 45–7 Snider, K. 124 ‘so what?’ question 196–7, 202–3 social behaviour 48–9 social capital networks 97, 98–9 social constructivist turn 302–3 social control 209 social democracy 23, 136 social diversity see diversity social justice see justice Social Justice Coalition (SJC) 281 social movements 118–19; global protest movements 214, 270, 271, 284–5; grassroots of planning 7, 143–54; insurgent planning see insurgent planning; poor people’s movements 148–52, 153, 282, 286 social rules 85 social science planning perspective 3 social systems theory 223–4 social theory 223–4 socialism 114 societal evolution 316–19 socialist countries 2 sociological functionalism 223 sociological institutionalism (SI) 250, 251, 251–2, 253, 258–9 soft planning 244–6 Soja, E. 18 South Africa 149, 280–1; Cape Town 282, 286; Durban 282, 286; marginalization and oppression 295–7, 299; Natives Land

359

Index Act 1913 296; Natives’ Trust and Land Act 1936 296; poor people’s protests against African migrants 282, 286; Western Cape Anti-Eviction Campaign 149, 151 Southern epistemologies of ethical actions 88–9 sovereign self 152 space: absolute 17–18, 19; hybrid spaces 175–6; invited and invented 95, 279–83; planning’s counter-conducts 215–16; possibility 331; production of colonial space 173–5; relational 16, 17–20, 24; temporary 273 spatial justice see justice spatial planning 5, 15–27, 132, 225; ascendance of 15–16; cases of marginalization and oppression 292–7; complexity and nonlinearity 10, 314–25; neoliberalization of 22–4, 25; postpolitics and 185; theoretical contexts and their critiques 16–22 spatial purification 160–1 specific becomings 340–2 Spivak, G. 172 sprawl 43 Springer, S. 105 stabilization 308–9 Star, S.L. 308–9 state: capitalist 277; governmental 211, 212; grassroots of planning 144, 145, 146–7, 153; and market in neoliberal planning 105; welfare 2, 23 statutory plans 31 steady-state economy 61–3, 64 Stein, S. 120–2 Stockholm 140 Stoker, G. 241–2 strategic essentialism 172 strategic navigation 272–3, 344 strategic planning 5, 28–40, 244, 245; becoming and 344; history 29–31; logic, aims and critiques 31; potential critical features 32–6 strategy 123 structure: and agency 253–4, 259; ANT 308–9 subaltern studies 168, 172 subject formation 228–9 subjectification 210; conflict, counter-conducts and 214; governmental 213; power and 211–12 subjective meanings 85 sustainable development 45–6, 138 sustainable economic growth 199 Svirsky, M. 280 Swaziland 158 Switzerland 187 Swyngedouw, E. 110, 183, 183–4, 184–5, 189, 190 symbolic interactionism 202

symmetry principle 305, 307–8 systems theory 19, 20; biophysical systems perspective 54–6; complex dynamic systems 10, 314–25; social systems theory 223–4 tactical urbanism 273 Tait, M. 135 Taylor, R.C.R. 250, 255–6 technical rationality 317, 321–2 temporary space 273 terrorism 163 Thatcher, M. 106, 108 thermodynamics, laws of 54–5 Thévenot, L. 126 three-term approach 183 Tibaijuka, A.K. 30 time 315–16 Toilet Wars 281 Tometi, O. 151 Tomlinson Report 296 townships 296–7 tracing 332, 344 trade 59 transaction costs 254–5 transactive planning 94 transcendental conceptions of the public interest 73 transgression 282–3 transitions 319–21 translation 304–5 transportation 48 Traveller communities 161 trend planning 243 truth, regimes of 8, 194, 197 Tuhiwai-Smith, L. 176 Tunisian National Dialogue Quartet 103 Turkmen 293 Uganda 158 UN-Habitat 30 uncertainty 337, 338–9 UNCLE (unlimited never-ending consultation leading to exhaustion) 188 Unger, R. 125 United Kingdom (UK) 159; ecological footprint 56–7, 64; Liverpool 107; London 42, 57, 107, 184; National Ecosystem Assessment 56; Neighbourhood Planning 243; neoliberal planning 106–7; New Public Management 238; planning styles 243–4; Scotland 8, 198–201, 203–4; spatial planning 23–4 United States of America (USA) 3, 158–9; Chicago 143, 150–1, 290; Civil Rights Act 159; Civil Rights Movement 159;

360

Index growth management 42, 43, 45; neoliberal planning 107; poor people’s movements 148, 150–1; pragmatism 118, 119; zoning and marginalization 290 universalism 77–8 unlearning 175–6 urban citizenship 145–8 Urban Development Corporations (UDCs) 107, 244 Urban Development Projects (UDPs) 106, 109–10 urban gardening 273 urban land 54, 56–7 urban regeneration 106–7; green 111–12 urban renewal 42–3 urban social movements see social movements urban theory 169–70 utilitarianism 73 value–fact divide 120–2 value-pluralism 70, 74–5, 76, 77 values: cultural 48–9; diversity and 161–2 Van der Leeuw, S. 316–18 Van Puymbroeck, N. 183, 187, 189 Van Wezemael, J. 187 Varela, F.J. 223 varieties of capitalism hypothesis 256 venereal disease (VD) clinic 341–2 viable universalism 77–8 Viganó, P. 28 vigilantes 282 violent antagonism 181–2

virtuality 36–7; virtual-actual nature of assemblages 330–1 visions 33, 34 ‘wandering’ planner 273 war of position 268–9, 270, 272 Ward, K. 20 wasp-orchid assemblage 339 waste, transformed into the human 150–2 Watkins, C. 135 Watson, I. 176 Watson, V. 88, 148 Webber, M.M. 75 Weber, M. 119 welfare governance model 240 welfare state 2, 23 Western Cape Anti-Eviction Campaign 149, 151 Western perspectives 171; privileged 168 ‘wicked’ problems 321, 338 Wilson, J. 183, 190 Winnipeg, Canada 42 Wolf, M. 59 woman, becoming- 341–2 world, becoming- 342 Yiftachel, O. 22, 160, 174, 210, 292 Young, I.M. 136, 278 Zimmerbauer, K. 19, 20 Zionism 294 Žižek, S. 8, 181, 182–3 zoning 290–1

361