120 20 8MB
English Pages 620 [621] Year 2020
THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF PHENOMENOLOGY OF EMOTION
The emotions occupy a fundamental place in philosophy, going back to Aristotle. However, the phenomenology of the emotions has until recently remained a relatively neglected topic. The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Emotion is an outstanding guide and reference source to this important and fascinating topic. Comprising forty-nine chapters by a team of international contributors, this handbook covers the following topics: • • • • •
historical perspectives, including Brentano, Husserl, Sartre, Levinas and Arendt; contemporary debates, including existential feelings, situated affectivity, embodiment, art, morality and feminism; self-directed and individual emotions, including happiness, grief, self-esteem and shame; social emotions, including sympathy, aggressive emotions, collective emotions and political emotions; borderline cases of emotion, including solidarity, trust, pain, forgiveness and revenge.
Essential reading for students and researchers in philosophy studying phenomenology, ethics, moral psychology and philosophy of psychology, The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Emotion is also suitable for those in related disciplines such as religion, sociology and anthropology. Thomas Szanto is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the Center for Subjectivity Research, University of Copenhagen, Denmark. Hilge Landweer is Professor of Philosophy at Freie Universität Berlin, Germany.
ROUTLEDGE H A N DBOOKS IN PHILOSOPH Y
Routledge Handbooks in Philosophy are state-of-the-art surveys of emerging, newly refreshed, and important fields in philosophy, providing accessible yet thorough assessments of key problems, themes, thinkers, and recent developments in research. All chapters for each volume are specially commissioned, and written by leading scholars in the field. Carefully edited and organized, Routledge Handbooks in Philosophy provide indispensable reference tools for students and researchers seeking a comprehensive overview of new and exciting topics in philosophy. They are also valuable teaching resources as accompaniments to textbooks, anthologies, and research-orientated publications. Also available: THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF METAPHYSICAL GROUNDING Edited by Michael J. Raven THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF PHILOSOPHY OF COLOUR Edited by Derek H. Brown and Fiona Macpherson THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF COLLECTIVE RESPONSIBILITY Edited by Saba Bazargan-Forward and Deborah Tollefsen THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF PHILOSOPHY OF EMPATHY Edited by Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY Edited by Kelly Arenson THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF TRUST AND PHILOSOPHY Edited by Judith Simon For more information about this series, please visit: https://www.routledge.com/RoutledgeHandbooks-in-Philosophy/book-series/RHP
THE ROUTLEDGE HANDBOOK OF PHENOMENOLOGY OF EMOTION
Edited by Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
First published 2020 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN and by Routledge 52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2020 selection and editorial matter, Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer; individual chapters, the contributors The right of Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer to be identified as the authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual chapters, has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Szanto, Thomas, editor. | Landweer, Hilge, editor. Title: The Routledge handbook of phenomenology of emotion / edited by Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer. Description: Abingdon, Oxon; New York, NY : Routledge, 2020. | Series: Routledge handbooks in philosophy | Includes bibliographical references and index. Identifiers: LCCN 2019056589 (print) | LCCN 2019056590 (ebook) | ISBN 9781138744981 (hbk) | ISBN 9781315180786 (ebk) Subjects: LCSH: Emotions (Philosophy) | Phenomenology. Classification: LCC B815 .R68 2020 (print) | LCC B815 (ebook) | DDC 128/.37—dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2019056589 LC ebook record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2019056590 ISBN: 978-1-138-74498-1 (hbk) ISBN: 978-1-315-18078-6 (ebk) Typeset in Bembo by codeMantra
CONTENTS
Acknowledgments x Notes on contributors xi
PART 1
Historical perspectives 39 1 Franz Brentano 41 Michelle Montague 2 Edmund Husserl 53 James Jardine 3 Alexander Pfänder 63 Genki Uemura and Toru Yaegashi 4 Max Scheler 72 Matthias Schloßberger 5 Moritz Geiger 87 Alessandro Salice 6 Else Voigtländer 96 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran v
Contents
7 Martin Heidegger and Otto Friedrich Bollnow 104 Gerhard Thonhauser 8 Dietrich von Hildebrand 114 Jean Moritz Müller 9 Edith Stein 123 Antonio Calcagno 10 Gerda Walther and Hermann Schmalenbach 133 Linas Tranas and Emanuele Caminada 11 Aurel Kolnai 144 Íngrid Vendrell Ferran 12 Aron Gurwitsch 153 Eric Chelstrom 13 Jean-Paul Sartre 159 Anthony Hatzimoysis 14 Emmanuel Levinas 168 Sophie Loidolt 15 Hannah Arendt 177 Judith Mohrmann 16 Simone de Beauvoir 187 Maren Wehrle 17 Maurice Merleau-Ponty 197 Joel Krueger 18 Frantz Fanon 207 Alia Al-Saji 19 Hermann Schmitz 215 Henning Nörenberg PART 2
Systematic issues and contemporary debates 225 20 Affective intentionality and the reactive attitudes Bennett W. Helm vi
227
Contents
21 The varieties of affective experience 239 John J. Drummond 22 Existential feelings 250 Matthew Ratcliffe 23 Emotional atmospheres 262 Tonino Griffero 24 Values, norms, justification and the appropriateness of emotions 275 Roberta De Monticelli 25 Morality and the emotions 288 John J. Drummond and Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl 26 Situated affectivity 299 Achim Stephan and Sven Walter 27 Feminism, embodiment and emotions 312 Luna Dolezal 28 Embodied interaffectivity and psychopathology 323 Thomas Fuchs 29 Art and emotion 337 Noël Carroll PART 3
Self-directed and individual emotions 347 30 Shame 349 Dan Zahavi 31 Self-esteem, pride, embarrassment and shyness 358 Anna Bortolan 32 Humility, humiliation and affliction 369 Anthony J. Steinbock 33 Disgust 380 Sara Heinämaa 34 Fear, anxiety and boredom 392 Lauren Freeman and Andreas Elpidorou vii
Contents
35 Grief 403 Line Ryberg Ingerslev 36 Joy and happiness 416 Michela Summa PART 4
Other-directed and collective emotions
427
37 Empathy, sympathy and compassion 429 Thiemo Breyer 38 Aggressive emotions: from irritation to hatred, contempt and indignation 441 Hilge Landweer 39 Hetero-induced shame and survivor shame 455 Alba Montes Sánchez 40 Joint feeling 466 Héctor Andrés Sánchez Guerrero 41 Political emotions 478 Thomas Szanto and Jan Slaby PART 5
Borderline cases of emotions 495 42 Forgiveness and revenge 497 Fabian Bernhardt 43 Gratitude 509 Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl 44 Trust 522 Nicolas de Warren 45 Feeling solidarity 532 Jan Müller 46 Pain 543 Fredrik Svenaeus
viii
Contents
47 The uncanny 553 Dylan Trigg 48 Hate of evil 564 Hans Bernhard Schmid 49 Love 575 Angelika Krebs Index 589
ix
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
We are very grateful to the excellent team at Routledge, and in particular to Tony Bruce and Adam Johnson, for their keen interest in this project from its very inception, and their patience and support throughout the editorial process. We appreciate the helpful suggestions of two anonymous reviewers of the book proposal. We also wish to thank Jenny Stupka, who assisted us at the final editorial stages. We are deeply indebted to Lucy Osler, Matthias Schloßberger, and especially Íngrid Vendrell Ferran, who have read and commented drafts of the Introduction. Thomas’ work on this volume was generously supported by a number of research agencies, notably his European Union Horizon-2020 Marie Skłodowska-Curie Individual Fellowship (655067): “Shared Emotions, Group Membership, and Empathy” at the University of Copenhagen, Sara Heinämaa’s Academy of Finland research project: “Marginalization and Experience: Phenomenological Analyses of Normality and Abnormality” at the University of Jyväskylä, and his research project “Antagonistic Political Emotions” (P 32392-G) at the University of Vienna, funded by The Austrian Science Fund (FWF).
x
CONTRIBUTORS
Alia Al-Saji is Associate Professor of Philosophy at McGill University, Montreal. Her work brings together phenomenology, critical philosophy of race, and feminist theory, with an abiding interest in questions of time, affect, and racialization. She is the author of “The Racialization of Muslim Veils” (Philosophy and Social Criticism, 2010) and “Decolonizing Bergson: The temporal schema of the open and the closed” (Beyond Bergson, SUNY 2019). Al-Saji argues for the philosophical, political, and lived importance of affective hesitation, notably in “A Phenomenology of Hesitation” (Living Alterities, SUNY 2014). Fabian Bernhardt received his PhD from Free University Berlin, where he was part of the research cluster “Languages of Emotion.” He has co-edited (with H. Landweer) a volume on law and emotion (Recht und Emotion II. Sphären der Verletzlichkeit; Alber 2017) and published a monograph on forgiveness (Zur Vergebung. Eine Reflexion im Ausgang von Paul Ricœur; Neofelis 2014) and on revenge (Rache. Über einen blinden Fleck der Moderne; Matthes & Seitz 2020). Anna Bortolan is a Lecturer in Philosophy in the Department of Political and Cultural Studies at Swansea University. Prior to this, she was a Lecturer in the School of Divinity, History and Philosophy at the University of Aberdeen, and Postdoctoral Fellow at University College Dublin. Her research interests lie at the intersection of philosophy of emotion, phenomenology, and philosophy of psychiatry, and her work explores questions concerning the role of affective experience in psychopathology, the relationship between affectivity and moral experience, and the connection between emotions, self-consciousness, and self hood. Thiemo Breyer is Heisenberg Professor for Phenomenology and Anthropology at the University of Cologne. His research focuses on issues of perception, embodiment, and affectivity. Among his publications are three monographs: On the Topology of Cultural Memory (Königshausen & Neumann 2007), Attentionalität und Intentionalität (Fink 2011), Verkörperte Intersubjektivität und Empathie (Klostermann 2015). Antonio Calcagno is Professor of Philosophy at King’s University College at Western University, Canada. He works on the early phenomenological movement and is a Member of the College, Royal Society of Canada. He is the author of Giordano Bruno and the Logic of xi
Contributors
Coincidence (Peter Lang 1998), The Philosophy of Edith Stein (Duquesne University Press 2007), Badiou and Derrida: Politics, Events and Their Time (Bloomsbury 2007), and Lived Experience from the Inside Out: Social and Political Philosophy in Edith Stein (Duquesne University Press 2014). Emanuele Caminada is Academic Archivist and Senior Researcher at the Husserl Archives of the Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven. His main research interests and publications include: phenomenological methods and movements, social ontology, interdisciplinary anthropology, the phenomenology of common-sense, aesthetics, philosophy of religion and politics. He is on the editorial board of the journal Metodo. Recently, he published the monograph Vom Gemeingeist zum Habitus: Husserls Ideen II. Sozialphilosophische Implikationen der Phänomenologie (Springer 2019). Noël Carroll is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the Graduate Center of the City of New York. He has written over fifteen books including, most recently Living in an Artworld (Spectrum Press 2012), Art in Three Dimensions (Oxford University Press 2012), and Humour: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford University Press 2014). Eric Chelstrom is Associate Professor of Philosophy at St. Mary’s University in San Antonio, Texas, where he is also an Edward and Linda Speed Peace and Justice Fellow. He is the author of Social Phenomenology: Husserl, Intersubjectivity, and Collective Intentionality (Lexington 2013) and contributor to volumes on social phenomenology and collective intentionality. His current research is on the relationship between systemic forms of injustice and collective intentionality, as well as on topics in the history of early phenomenology. Roberta De Monticelli is Professor of Philosophy at San Raffaele University of Milan and Fellow of the IAS Paris. She is Editor-in-Chief of the international journal Phenomenology and Mind, and Director of the Research Centre PERSONA. Her most recent book is The Gift of Bonds (Berlin 2020). Previous monographs include L’ascèse philosophique: Phénoménologie et Platonisme (Paris 1997), L’avenir de la phénoménologie. Méditations sur la connaissance personnelle (Paris 2000) and El conoscimiento personal (Madrid 2002). Nicolas de Warren is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the Pennsylvania State University. He is the author of Husserl and the Promise of Time (Cambridge University Press 2009) and A Momentary Breathlessness in the Sadness of Time (Jonas ir Jokūbas 2018). He is also the co-editor of New Approaches to Neo-Kantianism (Cambridge University Press 2015) and Philosophers at the Front: Phenomenology and the First World War (Leuven University Press 2018). Luna Dolezal is a Senior Lecturer in Medical Humanities and Philosophy at the University of Exeter. Her research is primarily in the areas of applied phenomenology, philosophy of embodiment, philosophy of medicine and medical humanities. Her publications include the monograph The Body and Shame: Phenomenology, Feminism and the Socially Shaped Body (Lexington Books 2015), and the co-edited books Body/Self/Other: The Phenomenology of Social Encounters (SUNY 2017) and New Feminist Perspectives on Embodiment (Palgrave 2018). John J. Drummond is the Robert Southwell, S. J. Distinguished Professor in Philosophy and the Humanities at Fordham University. He has authored A Historical Dictionary of Husserl’s Philosophy (Scarecrow 2008) and Husserlian Intentionality and Non-Foundational
xii
Contributors
Realism: Noema and Object (Kluwer 1990). He has written extensively on Husserl’s theory of intentionality, including evaluative and volitional intentionality, the emotions, value theory, and ethics. Andreas Elpidorou is an Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Louisville who specializes in the philosophical study of the mind. In addition to having published numerous journal articles and book chapters, he is the author of Propelled! How Boredom, Frustration, and Anticipation Can Lead us to the Good Life (Oxford University Press 2020) and the co-author of Consciousness and Physicalism: A Defense of a Research Program (Routledge 2018). Lauren Freeman is an Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of Louisville, Kentucky, an affiliated faculty member in the Department of Women’s, Gender, and Sexuality Studies, and a core faculty member in the MA in Health Care Ethics. She works in the areas of feminist bioethics, analytic feminism, phenomenology, and philosophy of emotion. She’s writing a book called Microaggressions and Medicine, coediting Microaggressions and Philosophy (Routledge 2019), and is the Editor of the APA Newsletter on Feminism and Philosophy. Thomas Fuchs is Karl Jaspers Professor of Philosophy and Psychiatry at Heidelberg University, Germany. His main areas of research include phenomenological philosophy and psychopathology, embodied and enactive cognitive science, and interactive concepts of social cognition. His most recent book is Ecology of the Brain. The Phenomenology and Biology of the Embodied Mind (Oxford University Press 2018). Tonino Griffero is Professor of Aesthetics, University of Rome “Tor Vergata.” He directs some book series (“Sensibilia,” “Atmospheric Spaces”) and an e-journal (“Lebenswelt”). Latest books include Atmospheres. Aesthetics of Emotional Spaces (Routledge 2014); Il pensiero dei sensi. Atmosfere ed estetica patica (Guerini 2016); Quasi-Things. The Paradigm of Atmospheres (Suny 2017); Places, Affordances, Atmospheres: A Pathic Aesthetics (Routledge 2019). He recently co-edited Atmosphere/Atmospheres. Testing A New Paradigm (Mimesis International 2018) and Psychopathology and Atmospheres. Neither Inside nor Outside (Cambridge Scholar 2019). Anthony Hatzimoysis is Associate Professor of Contemporary Philosophy at the University of Athens, Greece. His main publications include the monographs The Philosophy of Sartre (Routledge 2008), Fear (MIET), and the edited volumes Philosophy and the Emotions (Cambridge University Press 2003), and Self-Knowledge (Oxford University Press 2011). Sara Heinämaa is Academy Professor (2017–2021 Academy of Finland) and Professor of Philosophy at the University of Jyväskylä, Finland. She specializes in phenomenology, philosophy of mind and history of philosophy, and has published extensively in all these fields, especially on questions of embodiment, personhood, intersubjectivity, emotions and gender. She is co-author of Birth, Death, and Femininity: Philosophies of Embodiment (2010) and author of Toward a Phenomenology of Sexual Difference: Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, Beauvoir (2003). She has co-edited several volumes in phenomenology and philosophy of mind, including Phenomenology and the Transcendental (2014), New Perspectives to Aristotelianism and Its Critics (2014), and Consciousness: From Perception to Reflection in the History of Philosophy (2007).
xiii
Contributors
Bennett W. Helm is the Elijah Kresge Professor of Philosophy at Franklin & Marshall College. His work focuses on what it is to be a person and the role emotions and various forms of caring play in our being moral creatures. He has received fellowships and grants from the ACLS, NEH, NSF, Templeton Foundation, and Princeton’s Center for Human Values. He is the author of Emotional Reason (Cambridge University Press 2001), Love, Friendship, and the Self (Oxford University Press 2010), and Communities of Respect (Oxford University Press 2017). James Jardine is a Postdoctoral Researcher at the University of Jyväskylä, Finland, where he works within the Academy of Finland-funded ‘MEPA’ project, and was previously Irish Research Council Postdoctoral Fellow at University College Dublin. Jardine has published on empathy and emotion in Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie and Human Studies, and coauthored a chapter for Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Empathy. He is author of Empathy, Embodiment, and the Person (Springer 2020) and co-editor of Perception and the Inhuman Gaze (Routledge 2020). Angelika Krebs is Chair of Philosophy at the University of Basel. She was educated in Freiburg, Oxford, Konstanz, and Berkeley. She did her PhD in Frankfurt with Friedrich Kambartel, Bernard Williams, and Jürgen Habermas. Her research focuses on ethics, aesthetics, and the philosophy of emotion. Major books are Ethics of Nature (De Gruyter 1999); Arbeit und Liebe (Suhrkamp 2002); Zwischen Ich und Du (Suhrkamp 2015). She is the editor of Naturethik (Suhrkamp 1997); Gleichheit oder Gerechtigkeit (Suhrkamp 2000); and co-editor (together with Aaron Ben-Ze’ev) of Philosophy of Emotions I-IV (Routledge 2017); and The Meaning of Moods (Philosophia Special Issue, 2017). Joel Krueger is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Exeter, UK. He works on various issues in phenomenology, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of cognitive science—particularly, 4E (embodied, embedded, enacted, extended) approaches to cognition, emotions, social cognition, and psychopathology. He also does work on comparative philosophy and philosophy of music. Hilge Landweer is Professor of Philosophy at Freie Universität Berlin. Her areas of interest include phenomenology, social philosophy, ethics, and interdisciplinary gender studies. Major books are Scham und Macht. Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Sozialität eines Gefühls (Mohr Siebeck 1999) and, with C. Demmerling, Philosophie der Gefühle. Von Achtung bis Zorn (Metzler 2007). She co-edited among others Wie männlich ist Autorität? Feministische Kritik und Aneignung (Campus 2018), the Yearbook for Eastern and Western Philosophy 2 “Embodiment. Phenomenology East/West” (De Gruyter 2017), and Recht und Emotion, Vols. I and II (Alber 2016 and 2017). Sophie Loidolt is Professor of Philosophy at the Technical University Darmstadt, Germany, and a member of the “Young Academy” of the Austrian Academy of Sciences. Her books include Anspruch und Rechtfertigung. Eine Theorie des rechtlichen Denkens im Anschluss an die Phänomenologie Edmund Husserls (Springer 2009), Einführung in die Rechtsphänomenologie (Mohr Siebeck 2010), and Phenomenology of Plurality. Hannah Arendt on Political Intersubjectivity ( Routledge 2017). Judith Mohrmann is a Postdoctoral Researcher at the Institute for Social Research, Frankfurt. Her areas of interest include political theory, social philosophy, and aesthetics. xiv
Contributors
In her book Affekt und Revolution – Politisches Handeln nach Arendt und Kant (Campus 2015) she explores the relationship of politics and emotions in the French Revolution. Michelle Montague is an Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of Texas at Austin. She works primarily in philosophy of mind and metaphysics. She is the author of The Given: Experience and its Content (Oxford University Press 2016) and co-editor of Non-propositional Intentionality (Oxford University Press 2018) and Cognitive Phenomenology (Oxford University Press 2011). She has also published many articles in philosophy of mind, metaphysis, and philosophy of language. Alba Montes Sánchez is an independent scholar, last employed as a Postdoctoral Researcher at the Center for Subjectivity Research, University of Copenhagen, Denmark. Her research focuses on topics from the philosophy of emotions and moral psychology, with an emphasis on shame and other emotions of self-assessment. Her contributions have been published in journals such as the European Journal of Philosophy, Frontiers in Psychology, Journal of Consciousness Studies or Etica e Politica / Ethics and Politics. Jan Müller is Assistant Professor in philosophy at University of Basel, Switzerland. He works primarily at the intersection of action theory, metaethics, and Critical Theory, currently finishing a book project on the relation of the second person and forms of life in metaethics. He has published several articles and book chapters and co-edited two volumes on these issues, Lebensform und Praxisform (mentis 2015), Praxis und “zweite Natur” (mentis 2017). Jean Moritz Müller is a Research Associate at the University of Bonn, Germany. His general philosophical interests are in the philosophy of mind and related areas of meta-ethics. He is the author of The World-Directedness of Emotional Feeling (Palgrave Macmillan 2019) as well as of several articles and book chapters on the emotions. Henning Nörenberg is Postdoctoral Researcher at the Department of Philosophy in Rostock, Germany. He has published on various topics in phenomenology, social ontology, political philosophy, and philosophy of religion; his current work focuses on shared normative background orientations and their affective dimension. He is author of Der Absolutismus des Anderen (Alber 2014). Matthew Ratcliffe is Professor of Philosophy at the University of York, UK. His recent work addresses issues in phenomenology, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of psychiatry. His publications include the books Feelings of Being: Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality (Oxford University Press 2008), Experiences of Depression: A Study in Phenomenology (Oxford University Press 2015), and Real Hallucinations: Psychiatric Illness, Intentionality, and the Interpersonal World (MIT Press 2017). Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Graz, Austria. Her research focuses on Husserl’s phenomenology and its contributions to recent discussions in metaethics, value theory, emotion theory and epistemology. She has published on a variety of topics including first-person perspective, critique of psychologism, naturalizing subjectivity, and the fact/value dichotomy. She is the author of Edmund Husserl. Zeitlichkeit und Intentionalität (Alber 2000). With John Drummond, she has edited the volume Emotional Experiences: Ethical and Social Significance (Rowman & Littlefield 2018). xv
Contributors
Line Ryberg Ingerslev is a Postdoctoral Fellow at the Department of Philosophy at Julius-Maximilian University, Würzburg, Germany. She works on passivity, responsiveness, habit, and on aspects of emotional distress that play a role in weaker forms of agency, where knowledge of intention might not be present to oneself in the moment of acting. Her research also focuses on how the temporal aspects of agency affect self-understanding and our sense of responsibility. Alessandro Salice is Lecturer at the Department of Philosophy of University College Cork. He has extensively published on a variety of topics related to phenomenology, philosophy of mind and action, and moral psychology. His current work mainly addresses issues concerning human sociality. Recently, he has edited The Phenomenological Approach to Social Reality (Springer 2016) with Hans Bernhard Schmid. He is co-editor of the Journal of Social Ontology. Héctor Andrés Sánchez Guerrero works as a child and adolescent psychiatrist at the University Hospital Münster, Germany. Currently, he is Postdoctoral Research Associate at the Research Training Group Situated Cognition, at Ruhr-University Bochum and Osnabrück University, Germany. His research interests include the philosophy of emotion, the philosophy of collective intentionality, and phenomenologically inspired philosophy of psychiatry. He is author of Feeling Together and Caring with One Another: A Contribution to Debate on Collective Affective Intentionality (Springer 2016). Matthias Schloßberger works as a DFG Heisenberg Fellow in the Department of Philosophy at the Humboldt Universität zu Berlin. He mainly works on Scheler, philosophical anthropology, early phenomenology, social ontology, and the history of ideas. He is the author of three books: Die Erfahrung des Anderen (Akademie 2005), Geschichtsphilosophie (Akademie 2013) and Phänomenologie der Normativität (Schwabe 2019). Hans Bernhard Schmid is Professor of Political and Social Philosophy at the University of Vienna. His areas of specialization include joint action, collective intentionality, and social ontology. Jan Slaby is Professor of Philosophy at Freie Universität Berlin. His main research areas include philosophy of mind and social philosophy, with particular emphasis on affect and emotion theory. With Suparna Choudhury, he was co-editor of Critical Neuroscience: A Handbook of the Social and Cultural Contexts of Neuroscience (Wiley 2012), and with Christian von Scheve he edited Affective Societies: Key Concepts (Routledge 2019). Other recent publications are “More Than a Feeling: Affect as Radical Situatedness” (Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2017), and “Affective Arrangements” (with R. Mühlhoff and P. Wüschner, Emotion Review, 2019). Anthony J. Steinbock is Professor of Philosophy, Stony Brook University and Director, Phenomenology Research Center. He works in the areas of phenomenology, social ontology, aesthetics, and religious philosophy. Book publications include It’s Not about the Gift ( Rowman & Littlefield 2018), Limit-Phenomena and Phenomenology in Husserl (Rowman & Littlefield 2017), Moral Emotions (Northwestern University Press 2014), Phenomenology and Mysticism (Indiana University Press 2007/2009), and Home and Beyond (Northwestern University Press 1995). He is editor-in-chief of Continental Philosophy Review and general editor of the Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy (SPEP) series of Northwestern University Press. xvi
Contributors
Achim Stephan is Professor of Philosophy of Cognition at the Institute of Cognitive Science, Osnabrück University, Germany. His published work considers philosophical questions relating to human affectivity, philosophy of mind, and theories of emergence, including Handbuch Kognitionswissenschaft, co-edited together with Sven Walter (Metzler 2013) as well as Depression, Emotion and the Self, co-edited together with Matthew Ratcliffe (Imprint Academic 2014) and Emergenz. Von der Unvorhersagbarkeit zur Selbstorganisation (mentis, 4th ed., 2016). Michela Summa is Junior Professor for Theoretical Philosophy at Julius-Maximilians University Würzburg, Germany. She is the author of the monograph Spatio-temporal Intertwining. Husserl’s Transcendental Aesthetic (Springer 2014). Other recent publications include: Imagination and Social Perspectives. Approaches from Phenomenology and Psychopathology, co-edited with Thomas Fuchs and Luca Vanzago (Routledge 2018) and a special issue of the journal Phänomenologische Forschungen entitled “Modes of Intentionality. Phenomenological and Medieval Perspectives,” co-edited with Jörn Müller. Fredrik Svenaeus is Professor of Philosophy at the Centre for Studies in Practical Knowledge, Södertörn University, Sweden. His main research areas are philosophy of medicine, bioethics, medical humanities, and philosophical anthropology. Current research projects focus on existential questions in association with various medical technologies and on the phenomenology of suffering in medicine and bioethics. He has published widely in these fields; the most recent book is Phenomenological Bioethics: Medical Technologies, Human Suffering, and the Meaning of Being Alive (Routledge 2017). Thomas Szanto is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the Center for Subjectivity Research, University of Copenhagen. He works at the intersection of phenomenology, social cognition, social ontology, and the philosophy of emotions. His publications include the monograph Bewusstsein Intentionalität und Mentale Repräsentation: Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes (de Gruyter 2012), and the co-edited volumes The Phenomenology of Sociality: Discovering the ‘We’ (with D. Moran; Routledge 2015), and Empathy, Shared Emotions and Group Membership (with J. Krueger; Topoi Special Issue, 2019). Gerhard Thonhauser teaches philosophy at the Technical University Darmstadt, Germany. He holds a PhD in philosophy and MAs in philosophy and political science from the University of Vienna. His research focuses on social and political philosophy, and theories of emotion and affectivity from a phenomenological perspective. Linas Tranas is a PhD Fellow at the a.r.t.e.s. Graduate School for the Humanities Cologne, University of Cologne. His research focuses on questions pertaining to collective intentionality, social ontology, and shared emotions. Dylan Trigg is an FWF Lise Meitner Senior Fellow at University of Vienna, Department of Philosophy. He is the author of several books, including: Topophobia: a Phenomenology of Anxiety (Bloomsbury 2016); The Thing: a Phenomenology of Horror (Zero Books 2014); and The Memory of Place: a Phenomenology of the Uncanny (Ohio University Press 2012). With Dorothée Legrand, he is co-editor of Unconsciousness Between Phenomenology and Psychoanalysis (Springer 2017). His research concerns phenomenology, philosophies of subjectivity and embodiment, aesthetics and philosophies of art, and philosophies of space and place. xvii
Contributors
Genki Uemura is Associate Professor at Graduate School of Humanities and Social Sciences, Okayama University, Japan. His research areas include Husserl’s phenomenology, early realist phenomenology, and the opposition or mutual influence between them. He is also interested in developing phenomenological approaches to some topics from the contemporary metaphysics, philosophy of perception, and philosophy of action. Íngrid Vendrell Ferran is a DFG Heisenberg Fellow in Philosophy at the Goethe University Frankfurt. Her research interests are phenomenology, philosophy of mind, aesthetics and epistemology. Beyond a number of articles, she has published two monographs, Die Emotionen (Akademie 2008) and Die Vielfalt der Erkenntnis (mentis 2018), and co- edited among others Wahrheit, Wissen und Erkenntnis in der Literatur (with C. Demmerling, De Gruyter 2014); Empathie im Film (with M. Hagener, Transcript 2017), and Empathy, Fiction, and Imagination (with S. Schmetkamp, Special Issue of Topoi). Sven Walter is Professor of Philosophy of Mind and Cognition at the Institute of Cognitive Science, Osnabrück University, Germany. His published work considers philosophical questions relating to mental causation, free will, and situated accounts of cognition, including The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind, co-edited together with Brian McLaughlin and Ansgar Beckermann (Oxford University Press 2009) as well as Kognition (Reclam 2014), Illusion freier Wille? (Metzler 2016) and Grundkurs Willensfreiheit (mentis 2018). Maren Wehrle is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the Erasmus University Rotterdam. From 2012 to 2017, she worked as a Postdoctoral Researcher and Lecturer at the Center for Phenomenology, Husserl Archives, KU Leuven, Belgium. Her areas of specializations are phenomenology, philosophical and historical anthropology, feminist philosophy and cognitive psychology. Wehrle has authored the monograph Horizonte der Aufmerksamkeit (Wilhelm Fink 2013), and co-edited (with M. Ubiali) Feeling and Value, Willing and Action (Springer 2015) and (with S. Luft) Husserl Handbuch. Leben–Werk–Wirkung (Metzler 2018). She has published many journal articles and book chapters on the topics of embodiment, habit, normality, and normativity. Toru Yaegashi is Associate Professor at the Faculty of Engineering, Hiroshima Institute of Technology, Japan. His recent publications are Husserl ni okeru kachi to jissen (Husserl on Value and Practice) (Suisei-sha 2017) and “A Husserlian Account of the Affective Cognition of Value,” in New Phenomenological Studies in Japan (Springer 2019). His research areas are classical phenomenology (Husserl, Pfänder, Reinach, Scheler, Otaka, etc.), ethics, and philosophy of emotion. Dan Zahavi is Professor of Philosophy at University of Copenhagen and University of Oxford, and Director of the Center for Subjectivity Research in Copenhagen. Zahavi’s primary research area is phenomenology and philosophy of mind, and their intersection with empirical disciplines such as psychiatry and developmental psychology. His most important publications include Self-awareness and Alterity (Northwestern University Press 1999), Husserl’s Phenomenology (Stanford University Press 2003), Subjectivity and Selfhood (MIT Press 2005), The Phenomenological Mind (with Shaun Gallagher, Routledge, 2008/2012), Self and Other (Oxford University Press 2014), Husserl’s Legacy (Oxford University Press 2017), and Phenomenology: The Basics (Routledge 2019).
xviii
INTRODUCTION The phenomenology of emotions—above and beyond ‘What it is like to feel’ Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
1. The rediscoveries of the (phenomenology of) emotions: a historical vignette Following a brief period of marginalization, emotions are firmly back in the philosophical arena. This is certainly not news. Indeed, just stating that there has been a ‘rediscovery of the emotions in philosophy’ almost amounts to a platitude by now. What is a fairly new development, however, is the recent surge of interest in phenomenological perspectives on emotions. The decades-long jettisoning of the phenomenology of emotions, not just within the still largely analytic orientated philosophy of emotions but also within the phenomenological movement itself, is rather surprising. Over a century ago, early and classical phenomenologists such as Scheler, Stein, Husserl, Heidegger, Kolnai, and Sartre were already engaged in intensive discussions about the nature and function of emotions. Moreover, they offered detailed, sometimes book-length, analyses of specific emotions such as anxiety, fear or boredom (Heidegger), shame (Sartre, Scheler), disgust, hatred (Kolnai), or Ressentiment (Scheler). How did this rediscovery of the phenomenology of emotions come about, why (only) now, and what exactly is ‘rediscovered’ in the first place? To address these questions, we have to take a glance at the recent history of the philosophy of emotions in general, and the short but rich history of phenomenological work on emotions in particular.1 Before doing so, a caveat regarding the very notions of ‘emotions’ and ‘rediscovery’ is in order. First, our use of ‘emotions’ in the title, throughout this introduction, but also in many of the chapters should be taken as an umbrella-term, encompassing a vast range of diverse affective phenomena and, in particular, affects such as short-lived fear or disgust, distinct episodic emotions such as indignation or anger, sentiments, affective dispositions or affective attitudes such as Ressentiment or hatred, and affective character traits such as being disposed to humility or jealously. Emotions, in the sense employed here, further include varieties of what is sometimes subsumed under the concept of moods, and which phenomenologists in the wake of Heidegger tend to further divide into moods and fundamental moods (Stimmungen, Grundstimmungen) such as profound boredom, and other forms of affective disposedness or attunement (Befindlichkeit) such as anxiety or the so-called existential feelings (see Ratcliffe’s and Drummond’s chapters for details). 1
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
Second, talking of a ‘rediscovery’ of emotions in philosophy is, in fact, highly misleading. After all, emotions have never been completely ignored in the history of philosophy. Quite the contrary, the nature of affectivity and the role of emotions in human existence and social reality as well as the notorious relation of emotions and rationality always been at issue in philosophy—even where explicit discussion of the emotions is missing or is deliberately relegated to the conceptual background. Moreover, the relation of philosophical reasoning to emotions, and the role that emotions (ought to) play therein, has never been philosophically neutral. ‘What’s your take on emotion’ seems, then, to be the 64,000- dollar question for philosophers, ever since emotions entered philosophical thinking (see L andweer and Renz 2012).2 Affects and emotions have played a central role in Western 3 philosophy ever since they were introduced by Plato, Aristotle, and the Greek and Roman (Neo-)Stoics (cf. Nussbaum 2001). They were extensively discussed as key factors in rhetoric, political life, moral psychology, and social interaction. Most classical authors, such as Aquinas, Montaigne, Pascal, Descartes, Malebranche, or Spinoza, up until the Scottish moralists, explored a panoply of particular affects, sentiments, and emotions, taxonomizing the so-called ‘passions of the soul’ (Descartes); many of these authors also offered general theories of emotions. It is, however, also true that after Kant and Rousseau, starting roughly with the dominance of German Idealism, emotions ceased to play any systematic role in philosophy.4 In this period of relative marginalization, we find only a few isolated discussions of specific emotions, such as compassion in Schopenhauer5 or anxiety and fear in Kierkegaard. After this period of marginalization, the emotions found their way back to philosophy, albeit through the side-door of the social and natural sciences and, in particular, the socalled ‘empirical’ or ‘experimental’ psychology of the time.6 The initial step toward a new systematic exploration of the nature and function of emotions set in with Darwin’s evolutionary theory (esp. Darwin 1872) and James’ and Lange’s philosophical psychology ( James and Lange 1885–1893). In the German-speaking world, specifically, it was the philosophically trained psychologists Brentano, Stumpf, and Lipps and their students from the Munich Circle of Phenomenology, Pfänder and Geiger,7 and the Leipzig School of Gestalt psychologists, such as Krueger or Stern,8 who again developed general theories of our affective life. Eventually, it was the successors, colleagues, or students of the Brentano School and of the Munich Circle phenomenologists, such as Husserl, Scheler, Voigtländer, Haas, Stein, and Walther, who put discussions about the nature of emotions on a broader philosophical basis at the beginning of the 20th century.9 The detachment of psychology from philosophy and psychology’s eventual academic institutionalization in the latter half of the 19th century was not without friction. What philosophers took issue with and which led to philosophy’s break was not so much psychology as an empirical science as psychologizing assumptions. Various critiques of psychologism between the 1880s and 1920s initially, and rather unexpectedly, united such philosophers as Frege, leading Neo-Kantians such as Cohen,10 Husserl, and Wittgenstein, before their successors parted ways in the so-called analytic-continental divide. They were allied in their rejection of psychologistic reductions of meaning, truth, and epistemic rationality to the genesis and psychological laws of reasoning. In the foundational text of classical phenomenology, Logical Investigations, Husserl directed his sweeping criticism against the view that logic is founded upon some psychological basis (Husserl 1900). The controversy around psychologism is particularly noteworthy in the present context if we consider the Janus-faced impact it had on the (phenomenological) rediscovery of emotions: On the one hand, it was psychologists avant-la-lettre or philosophers-turned-psychologists 2
Introduction
who, after the post-Kantian century of relative silence, first systematically explored human affectivity; on the other hand, it was in reaction to the reductionist conception of psychology—viz. psychologism—that the philosophical engagement with emotions was placed on new grounds. The catalyst of the latter development was arguably classical phenomenology. Husserl’s establishment of intentionality as the defining mark of conscious mental acts—including, notably, emotions—in the wake of Brentano, thus cannot be underestimated with regard to the general philosophical rediscovery of the emotions in the 20th century. Clearly influenced by Husserl, Scheler made the first systematic attempt since Hume’s tableau of affects in the Treatise to present a metaphysically grounded and a priori order of emotions and values. From the work of Scheler through Sartre to Goldie’s (2000) influential notion of emotions as “feeling towards,” Husserl’s theory of intentionality has left its mark. Even in the tradition of Heidegger, which is skeptical of the concept of the intentionality of emotions and reformulates it in terms of spatiality, Husserl’s conception is alive as a matter of critique (Schmitz 1969; cf. Landweer 2011). Certainly, what might be called the ‘first wave’ of the phenomenological rediscovery of the emotions in the 20th century was not uninterrupted. The golden age of phenomenological research on emotions lasted from the early 1910s to the late 1930s, ending rather abruptly with Sartre’s Sketch of a Theory of Emotions (1939). In the following decades, any systematic engagement with emotions seems to have been banned from philosophers,’ and even most psychologists,’ agenda. The few notable exceptions include the following work: Bollnow’s neo-Heideggerian account of ‘moods’ in Das Wesen der Stimmungen (The Nature of Moods) (1956/2017) (see Thonhauser’s chapter); Strasser’s Das Gemüt: Grundgedanken zu einer phänomenologischen Philosophie und Theorie des menschlichen Gefühlslebens (1956) (Phenomenology of Feeling: An Essay on the Phenomena of Heart, 1977) from the same year (see more below); and, finally, Schmitz’s project of establishing the so-called ‘New Phenomenology’ in his multi-volume System der Philosophie (1964–1980), whose core elements are a new conceptualization of the felt body (Leib), of emotions and moods as atmospheres, and a sweeping attack on any form of internalization of affectivity (see Nörenberg’s chapter). All three works, however, represent solitary and internationally still hardly known work, and were almost completely ignored by their more prominent phenomenological peers,11 not to speak of mainstream analytic philosophy. In this, they share the fate of Sartre’s Sketch12 but also Kenny’s Action, Emotion and Will (1963; see below). The second break in systematically thematizing emotions in philosophy, marked by World War II, seems to be due to a general suspicion of the role of emotions in society, politics, and ideology after the two Great Wars and the Schoah. Indeed, around 1914, even otherwise clear-sighted public intellectuals from France to the crumbling Austrian Empire and Prussia were caught up in the general nationalist pro-war ideology, and phenomenologists certainly were no exception.13 This is best exemplified by Scheler’s fervent Anti-English war-propaganda essay Der Genius des Krieges und der Deutsche Krieg (“The Genius of War and the German War” 1915), but also permeates his more philosophically toned, but no less ideological, essay Der Krieg als Gesamterlebnis (“The War as Communal Experience” 1916). On the surface, the latter essay offers an analysis of the collective intentionality of shared emotions and their role in facilitating the unification of nations; in fact, it’s not much more than a piece of political ideology (see Schmid 2015). Though Scheler’s further systematic work on shared emotions is far more sober and analytically sound, it is certainly not immune to the political ideologies of the time. The same goes for Scheler’s contemporaries, Stein, Walther, and Schmalenbach, whose work on communal experiences is also partly rooted 3
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
either in Marxism (as for Walther) or ideas of the so-called “Conservative Revolution” of the Weimar Republic.14 Hence, especially in Germany, it is no wonder that work on collective emotions was banished from the curriculum, which was soon dominated by Adorno and Critical Theory.15 If we add to this that key figures in the phenomenology of emotions were either forced to emigrate from Nazi Germany or Austria, as Geiger and Kolnai, or murdered in Auschwitz, as Stein, we can better understand the lapse of phenomenological engagement with emotions after World War II. That some of the surviving authors who have focused on emotions in postwar Germany, such as Bollnow and most prominently Heidegger, were in ideological complicity with Nazism sadly completes this picture. It is, then, no wonder that in this poisonous atmosphere, no unbiased reception of the traditional or phenomenological philosophy of emotions could flourish. In short, both the anti-Enlightenment doctrines of the “Conservative Revolution” and of National Socialism seemed to justify the intellectual distrust of emotion research after World War II, even beyond the borders of the German-speaking world. Viewed from this perspective, this second break in philosophical emotion research from the 1940s to the 1980s and 1990s mirrors the first one between the late 18th and the latter half of the 19th century: In both, what is more or less explicitly at issue is the relationship of rationality and emotions. Thus, the first interruption is largely due to Kant’s authoritative condemnation in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals of actions arising from desires and inclinations. Kant famously excludes such actions, which arise from sensuality and are merely in the pursuit of individual happiness, from playing a role in grounding morality, and allows only the morality of “actions from duty.” Eventually, in the wake of war and totalitarianism and under the guise of sociopolitical criticism, the second rupture in emotion research seems to reestablish this allegedly Enlightenment-based dichotomy, as if reason can only rule and lead to morality if freed from affectivity.16 Looking back on the history of philosophy from a bird’s-eye perspective, then, emotions have been sidelined only for brief periods. This alone makes the use of the notion of a ‘rediscovery’ somewhat arbitrary. But there is another reason why we should be careful when talking of a ‘rediscovery of emotions’—one that is probably more relevant in the context of the present volume. It has to do with the fact that, as should have become already clear, there is no one single rediscovery. Rather, we can only speak, if at all, of rediscoveries in the plural. The rediscovery of the emotions in the analytic tradition in the latter quarter of the 20th century took a very different shape and had different motivations than its phenomenological counterpart. Moreover, these rediscoveries didn’t even happen simultaneously: For the analytic tradition, we can trace it around 1980; in phenomenology, the rediscovery of its own heydays (i.e., 1910s–1930s) is only a very recent development and started on a broader international scale just a few years ago.
1.1 The rediscovery of the emotions in analytic philosophy Let’s first look in more detail at the analytic discussions, as it gives us a contrast-foil to better understand the story of the ‘phenomenological rediscovery.’ From its very inception with Frege and Russell to Quine and Putnam, analytic philosophy has, broadly speaking, focused on issues in philosophy of language, epistemology, philosophy of science, and metaphysics, domains that seem to be, more or less, ‘purified’ of affectivity. There were only few prominent exceptions to this general trend, most notably Wittgenstein (cf. Mulligan 2017), and they haven’t had much influence on the mainstream debates. If affective states have figured at all in mainstream analytic discussions, with rare exceptions, such as Bedford (1956/1957), 4
Introduction
they were reduced to either erratic impulses, agitations, or dispositions to act, as in Ryle (1949), or conceived of as nothing more than propositional states capable of entering rational and causal mental connections as in Davidson (e.g., 1982). But the disregard of the emotions is probably most telling in analytic work on practical philosophy and moral psychology up until the last two decades or so of the 20th century. The change starts in the wake of early virtue-ethical approaches, with feminist-inspired critiques of utilitarian or deontological moral and contractualist political theory, as well as of rationalist trends in moral psychology.17 But the omission of emotions in these areas is particularly curious. After all, emotions were at the forefront not just in Ancient Greek and Roman moral and political philosophy and psychology,18 but in neo-Aristotelian (especially Aquinas) and in early modern political and moral psychology (especially Spinoza); moreover, emotions played a central role for the British and Scottish moralists, including Hume, Shaftesbury, Smith, and Reid, but also political philosophers such as Hobbes—that is, for authors who represent standard historical points of reference for analytic philosophy. The reason for the disregard of emotions besides the general mistrust of emotions after World War II is probably to do with the influential ‘emotive theories of ethics,’ proposed by dominant figures of the time (viz. around the 1940s) such as A. J. Ayer and C. L. Stevenson. Ironically, the discounting of emotions in this period resulted from the emotive theorists’ claim that the entire domain of practical and aesthetic theory cannot be subject to rational assessment or verification, but only to a subjective, affective-evaluative one, and hence cannot sensibly be a part of philosophical discussions. Incidentally, it was some decades later, in meta-ethical work on moral sentimentalism and projectivism, that emotions, sentiments, and passions were discussed from fairly early on in this tradition, roughly coinciding with the otherwise unrelated feminist critiques.19 Now, it has become customary to point to Kenny’s Action, Emotion and Will (1963) as the start of the resurgence of interest in emotions in analytically oriented theoretical philosophy.20 But this is misleading. The book appeared in the Routledge and Kegan Paul series “Studies in Philosophical Psychology,” which has become famous for its groundbreaking short monographs, but initially represented a niche outpost of a nascent post-behaviorist philosophy of mind. The work was prominent but arguably not influential in the dominant strands of analytic philosophy of its time. In fact, it was not until the late 1970s with the appearance of Solomon’s The Passions (1976), Neu’s Emotions, Thought, and Therapy (1977), Lyons’ Emotion (1980), and Rorty Oksenberg’s seminal edition Explaining Emotions (1980) that research on emotions was placed on a broader philosophical footing. The dominant thread within these earlier theories was a broadly cognitivist account of emotions,21 challenging the traditional dichotomy between reason and passion, and highlighting emotions’ intrinsic rationality. These ideas culminated in de Sousa’s The Rationality of Emotions (1987), Elster’s Alchemies of the Mind: Rationality and the Emotions (1999), and Nussbaum’s comprehensive treatment in The Upheaval of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (2001). Nussbaum was also among the first within the analytic tradition to systematically engage with literary and historical, especially ancient and early modern resources (Nussbaum 1990).22 Around the shift away from the cognitivist paradigm, Wollheim published On the Emotions (1999), drawing heavily on Freudian psychoanalysis. Wollheim suggests that emotions originate in desires and are, roughly, sedimented mental dispositions. It is worth noting that, for Wollheim, emotions are more often than not unconscious. Somewhat paradoxically, even though Wollheim’s work can be seen as one of the most sustained projects of ‘re-psychologizing’ the mind and of refurbishing it with affective states within the analytic tradition, he sidelines the experiential character of occurrent emotions, and indeed holds 5
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
that occurrently experienced emotions are the exception. This, to be sure, stands in direct opposition with most of the otherwise more or less congenial phenomenological accounts (see more below). One such account from the broadly analytic tradition deserves special attention, since it has had an enormous influence both on the still-ongoing ‘second wave’ phenomenological rediscovery of emotions and on the philosophy of emotions in general. This is Goldie’s (2000) conception of emotions as “feelings towards,” or a “thinking of with feeling.” According to Goldie, emotions have—above and beyond a number of other components, such as bodily, motivational, expressive, or regulative—a sui generis kind of intentionality, which has also become known as “affective intentionality.”23 The ‘intentionality of emotions’ and, what Goldie calls, the “phenomenology of emotions,” or their experiential and felt quality, are inextricably interlinked, as Goldie argues against the so-called “add-on” theory. More specifically, the affective phenomenology of emotions is not just a matter of their intentional content but also “infuses” the very attitudinal aspect of emotions (Goldie 2002, 242). Moreover, affective intentionality also “infuses” the very “bodily feeling,” and “in turn, the feeling towards is infused with a bodily characterization” (Goldie 2000, 57). Goldie’s account at the turn of the millennium can be seen as the herald of the postcognitivist era in the philosophy of emotions. And today—as typically in any ‘post’ era—we have a variety of alternative models on offer: multi-componential theories (Ben Ze’ev 2000), concern- or value-based construals of emotions,24 neo-Jamesian perceptual and embodied (Prinz 2004) and cognate perceptual accounts,25 narrative accounts (Goldie 2012), and most recently the so-called ‘4E’-conceptions (embodied, enactive, embedded, and extended).26 These predominantly Anglo-Saxon discussions were eventually received in Germany (Döring 2009; Berninger 2017) and enriched with an interest in historical and phenomenological contextualization.27 Above and beyond their contribution to a general theory of emotions, some have also offered refined classifications of different types of affective states, such as dispositional emotions, moods, and sentiments.28 Some have also contributed to the analysis of a rich roster of particular emotions (esp. Ben-Ze’ev 2000; Roberts 2003), and especially social and moral emotions, such as sympathy or compassion, jealousy, shame, envy, forgiveness, pride, or self-esteem.29 Others have focused on specific key dimensions or functions of emotions, such as their epistemology (Brady 2013; Candiotto 2019), or their moral and normative,30 and bodily dimensions (Prinz 2004; Maise 2011; Colombetti 2014) or their relation to law.31 In recent years, philosophers have also increasingly focused on the relation of emotions and aesthetics, and in particular the issue of fictional emotions,32 as well as on discussions about the truth, appropriateness, authenticity, or integrity of emotions,33 or the nature of shared and political emotions.34
1.2 The second-wave phenomenological rediscovery of emotions To complete this historical vignette, let us now briefly turn back again to phenomenologists’ rediscovery of their own tradition, or what we have baptized the ‘second wave phenomenological rediscovery.’35 As we have seen, even among phenomenologists, with few exceptions, systematic work on affectivity and emotions was buried for a number of decades. So why this ‘phenomenological affective turn’ now (again)?36 Obviously, the reasons are manifold, concerning socio-historical and institutional shifts, as well as systematic conceptual changes, and we list here only the most salient ones. 6
Introduction
In the first place, in the past two to three decades, we see an increasing interest in various issues relating to bodily dimensions of our being-in-the-world, from the role of kinesthesia or motor-intentionality in perception to the so-called “drive-intentionality” (Husserl 1929–1935; cf. 1908–1937) to the role of embodiment in empathy and affectivity.37 Embodiment is, of course, a core issue of phenomenology ever since Husserl, and was elaborated in further detail in the work of such post-Husserlian phenomenologists as Stein, Merleau-Ponty, Henry, and Schmitz (see more below). In the wake of the establishment of gender and cultural studies and their affective turn, as well as the so-called embodied and enactive approaches to cognition, action, and emotion (see Stephan’s and Walther’s chapter), the connection between embodiment and affectivity, which was always part and parcel of the phenomenological theorizing, found its way back to the frontline of more mainstream philosophical discourse.38 Similarly, we can witness a veritable explosion on work on empathy in recent years, which again always figured as a core concept of classical phenomenology. And even though no phenomenologist holds that empathy is an emotion as such, or that it should be construed as some form of emotional sharing,39 empathy and its related ‘forms of sympathy’ (Scheler) do have important affective elements. Phenomenologists also long recognized that empathy affords us with a more or less direct access to affective states of others, and hence plays a crucial epistemic role not just regarding knowledge of other minds but also regarding emotions. This brings us to the third key systematic factor, namely the abundance of work in the last two decades on sociality and collectivity, in general, and social and collective emotions, in particular. Classical phenomenologists from Husserl, Stein, and Walther, through phenomenological sociologists such as Scheler, Schütz, and Gurwitsch, to existential phenomenologists such as Heidegger and Sartre first systematically addressed not only interpersonal forms of empathic engagement and intersubjectivity but also various forms of collective intentionality, including collective affective intentionality (see Szanto 2020). Thus, it should come as no surprise that they too were the ones to turn to for the analysis of the sociality and collectivity of emotions.40 Moreover, the growing interest in affective atmospheres (see Griffero’s chapter) also readily resonates with Heidegger’s or Bollnow’s conceptualization of moods (Stimmungen), and in particular Schmitz’s (1969, 2014) radical conception of emotions as atmospheres (cf. Krebs 2017). Two further points of convergence between classical phenomenology and contemporary philosophy of emotions should be noted: First, there has been a surge of interest in psychopathological disturbances in empathizing, emotional experience and expression, for example in patients with depression, autism spectrum disorders, Möbius syndrome, schizophrenia, or Parkinson’s disease.41 Given their emphasis on the complex connections between emotional experience, expression or regulation and embodiment, as well as the intrinsic link between the lived body (Leib), affectivity, and the social environment,42 phenomenological accounts have been particularly adept at accounting for these affective disturbances. Finally, the themes found in the above-mentioned contemporary discussions concerning the normativity of emotions—i.e. on how, when, why, and which emotions can be appropriate or not, authentically or inauthentically felt, etc.—were foreshadowed in classic phenomenological discussions almost a century earlier, in particular in the work of Voigtländer, Haas, Scheler, Stein, Sartre, and Merleau-Ponty.43 Above and beyond these systematic reasons, to a non-negligible degree, the phenomenological affective turn is also due to certain new meta-theoretical developments of intra- and interdisciplinary reception. Thus, the resurging interest in early phenomenological accounts is partly to do with developments within analytic philosophy and its turn to emotions, and especially the emergence of congenial affective-intentional accounts. Phenomenology has opened 7
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
itself more to concepts and debates in analytic philosophy and also to neighboring disciplines discussing emotions, above all psychology, psychiatry, sociology, and the cognitive sciences.44 A natural corollary of this methodological opening in phenomenology has been a decrease of historical-exegetic work on past ‘grandmasters’; instead, we can witness an increased attention on topical or systematic issues. And much of this topical and systematic work is now focusing on emotions. Moreover, phenomenologists have lately become more integrative with regard to sociocultural and political issues and social criticism (cf. Bedorf and Herrmann 2020). They have also shown a renewed interest in post-structuralist thinkers such as Foucault (Oksala 2016), and especially in recent discussions in cultural and gender studies, feminist philosophy, and critical race theory.45 This has led to the emergence of the so-called ‘feminist phenomenology’ (Fielding and Olkowski 2017), ‘queer phenomenology’ (Ahmed 2006), and ‘critical phenomenology’ (Salamon et al. 2019). And, again, in all these new directions of phenomenology, the study of affectivity, and in particular of social emotions, and their normatively and culturally shaped forms of corporeal sedimentation take center-stage.
2. The phenomenology of emotions—above and beyond ‘What it is like to feel’ As we have seen, phenomenological theories of emotions were simultaneously developed with the establishment of phenomenology as a distinct philosophical tradition. Indeed, virtually all phenomenologists up until 1940 systematically worked on some version of a phenomenology of emotions. So why is it that many phenomenologists, who otherwise dealt with such theoretical issues as consciousness, intentionality, imagination, perception, time-consciousness, or metaphysical and epistemological discussions on idealism versus realism, were not only interested in emotions but thought that affectivity ought to play a central role in phenomenology? This is far from obvious, and was certainly not the case in the broader philosophical landscape. The reasons for early and classical phenomenologists’ keen interest in emotions largely overlap with those that motivated the second-wave phenomenological discovery just listed, notably, phenomenology’s focus on the affective dimension of perception, of personhood, on the felt body, on empathy and other forms of sympathetic stances, on social interaction and shared experiences, as well as the normativity of emotions. Above and beyond these, one crucial factor is also phenomenologists’ conviction that there is an intrinsic link between emotions and evaluations or values. This conviction is shared by most early phenomenologists from Pfänder, Geiger through Husserl to the so-called ‘realist’ phenomenologists such as Scheler, Reinach, Stein, and Hildebrand, while New Phenomenologists such as Schmitz focus on the evaluative aspects of atmospheres. Though phenomenologists certainly do not agree on all details (see more below), they all emphasize the role of emotions in disclosing values or the affective aspects of evaluations, and stress the intrinsic normativity of emotions like shame or resentment. Accordingly, phenomenologists conceptualize emotions as what today would be called “felt evaluations” or “evaluative feelings” (Helm 2001). Viewed generally, the fact that affectivity plays a pivotal role in phenomenology reflects the most fundamental ontological and epistemological tenets of phenomenology about human cognition, volition, and (inter)action, indeed about human nature and (social) existence. Thus, almost all phenomenologists agree that any form of conscious experience has a core affective dimension, even on the most basic level of a simple perceptual experience. As Husserl first pointed out, before subjects take any active cognitive, epistemic, or evaluative stance, their perceptual environment exerts a certain “affective allure,” which makes objects salient and motivate subjects’ attentional modifications (Husserl 1918–1926, 1938; Heidegger 1927, 8
Introduction
see also Merleau-Ponty 1945). Famously, Heidegger, and subsequent German and French phenomenologists, such as Bollnow, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, and Schmitz, ontologically generalized this picture, arguing that our very being-in-the-world is always and already a way of being affectively attuned to oneself, others, and the world (cf. Vendrell Ferran forthcoming). According to phenomenology, then, our very experiential fabric or being-in-the-world is affective through and through, long before subjects take more complex evaluative or social stances. Now, on the face of it, and especially if one is not already familiar with the core tenets of phenomenology, it might seem that the reason for the co-emergence of phenomenology and the phenomenology of emotions has something important to do with phenomenologists’ focus on the first-personal, qualitative contents of experience, or, roughly what has become known as ‘qualia.’ This impression could also be vindicated by the fact that work on emotions found their way into traditional publishing outlets of analytic philosophy around the same time as work on philosophy of mind and phenomenal consciousness. Curiously, but certainly not coincidentally, books with titles such as The Rediscovery of the Mind (Searle 1992) appeared just few years before their philosophy of emotion equivalents, such as Rediscovering Emotion (Pugmire 1998). But the impression that classical or contemporary phenomenology of emotions has anything relevant to do with phenomenology in the notorious sense of ‘what is it like’ to have conscious mental states, or qualia, or even just with ‘what it is like to feel’46 is simply false. The primacy of the first-person perspective in phenomenology in no way limits the scope of analysis to the qualitative ‘feeling’ aspect of emotions—be it their bodily, sensory, or any other subjective ‘what is it like to undergo them’ aspect. One is prone to such reduction only if one undercuts the intrinsic connection between affective, sensory, or bodily, on the one hand, and intentional or evaluative components in emotions’ affective intentionality, on the other (see again Goldie 2000, also de Monticelli’s chapter). We find a correlative pseudo-problem in recent discussions on cognitive phenomenology in recent philosophy of mind, where the issue of whether thoughts have a certain qualitative aspect, or ‘phenomenology,’ predominantly arises by falsely dichotomizing the qualitative, conscious, on the one hand, and the cognitive, propositional, and intentional dimension of mental states, on the other.47 Taking the subjective standpoint seriously when addressing emotions, for phenomenologists, means thematizing emotions in light of a whole series of relevant experiences and evaluations of the affected subjects. From a phenomenological standpoint, emotions are only meaningful in light of the conduct of subjects’ personal life and in the context of their lifeworld. Importantly, this is not a private, inner-mental realm but essentially involves subjects’ interpersonal and sociocultural environment as well as their collective strivings and engagements. This, by no means, implies that a phenomenological analysis of the nature of affectivity or of particular emotions has to stop short at the level of everyday emotional experience, nor will descriptions suffice that only take into account folk-psychological or scientific preconceptions about the sedimentation of emotions in ordinary experience. However, an adequate phenomenological analysis must take these dimensions into account—along with their bodily feeling, intentional-evaluative, etc. aspects—since they articulate a conceptual background that is relevant for a proper understanding of emotions—or, of what they mean for the subjects undergoing them (cf. also Steinbock 2014).
2.1 Main points of convergence within the phenomenology of emotion So far, we have spoken of ‘the phenomenology of emotion’ as if it is a more or less univocal account, and only alluded to differentiations regarding different topical foci among 9
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
phenomenologists. This, of course, is a massive oversimplification and needs to be qualified. First of all, just as there is no ‘analytic,’ or ‘cognitivist’ philosophy of emotion simpliciter, there is no single account that could be taken as a paradigm of a phenomenological conception. To claim otherwise would only be applying strategic considerations, as it is, alas, too often the case in academic turf-wars. So what are the major points of convergence and what are the major fault lines among phenomenologists of emotions? As we have already seen, most phenomenologists are in basic agreement with regard to the following points: (i) The irreducibility of emotions to other mental or cognitive but also to other bodily states; (ii) the fundamental role of the first-person (singular or plural) perspective in the study and description of emotional experiences, without ignoring the embeddedness of emotions in the life-world of individuals and social groups, which is shared and hence can be accessed intersubjectively; (iii) the importance of taking the sociality of emotions seriously; but also (iv) distinguishing empathy from sympathetic emotional stances toward others, such as sympathy or compassion, as well as from various forms of affective sharing. (v) Most, and in particular early and ‘realist’ phenomenologists, believe that emotions bear important, broadly epistemic, relations to different types of values, and hence that axiological considerations must be part of a systematic philosophy of emotions. (vi) Relatedly, many hold that emotions can be appropriate/authentic or not, and hence normative considerations play a fundamental role in a proper phenomenology of emotions. There are further important points of agreement, some of which are already implied in what we have said so far, but which are worth making explicit: (vii) To begin with, phenomenologists not only stress the role of embodiment in emotional experience in a general sense; ever since Husserl and Merleau-Ponty, they pay careful attention to the distinction between the subjectively felt body (Leib) and the objective body, or the body under some third-personal, physical description (Körper). This distinction, in turn, must always be taken into account when thematizing emotions in phenomenology as bodily feelings.48 (viii) Relatedly, virtually all phenomenologists take an anti-Jamesian stance regarding the identification of bodily feelings and emotions. In contrast, they markedly distinguish bodily sensations (such as itches, pains, etc.), purely bodily feelings, and sensations of bodily changes (i.e., roughly Jamesian emotions), on the one hand, from emotions, moods, or sentiments, on the other. Moreover, some, and in particular Scheler, Stein, and Schmitz, also emphasize the difference between the bodily feeling aspect of emotions and the more complex experience of emotions, especially regarding their differing affective intentionality. Building on and further developing these differentiations, some phenomenologists introduce complex stratifications within our affective life and taxonomize affective states above and beyond the standard classification of episodic emotions, moods, sentiments, etc. For example, Scheler, Stein, or Kolnai discuss such affective states as vital feelings (Vitalgefühle) or life-feelings (Lebensgefühle), while Schmitz distinguishes between stirrings of the felt body (leibliche Regungen), bodily being-affected (leiblich-affektive Betroffenheit), and emotions as atmospheres (see more in the respective chapters). (ix) According to most phenomenologists, emotions are not passive states that subjects simply undergo and cannot control or regulate—emotions are not passions in this sense. Rather, in contemporary terminology, they are ‘enactive,’ acting upon their environment, or, as Sartre would put it ‘spontaneous.’ Indeed, as we have seen, many hold that the very experiential receptivity of subjects is always and already affective, or is a “being affected” (Affiziertsein; Husserl 1908–1937). Arguably, many phenomenological analyses of emotions can be viewed as undermining altogether any neat active/passive distinction 10
Introduction
regarding emotions, and in particular Husserl’s, Sartre’s, Merleau-Ponty’s, or, more recently, Waldenfels.49 Some, and in particular New Phenomenologists, such as Schmitz or Griffero, go even further in this regard. They hold that any distinction between internal and external aspects of subjects’ “bodily being-affected” (leiblich-affektives Betroffensein) in experiencing emotions is altogether inappropriate. Rather, their conceptions of being affected, of emotions as having “bodily orientations” (leibliche Richtungen), or of emotions as socially “extended atmospheres” aim to capture the sense in which even bodily feelings and atmospheres can interact in a shared “emotional space” (Gefühlsraum).50 Put more generally, according to most phenomenologists, emotions are not simply ‘felt responses,’ registering purportedly ‘internal’ (bodily) or ‘external’ (worldly, social, etc.) events; rather, they are responsive to and disclosive of the world and others, as well as disclosive of oneself. (x) In the latter feature, the self-disclosive nature of emotions, lies a further central contention of phenomenological accounts, most prominently defended today by authors such as Pugmire (2005) and Goldie (2000, 2012). Emotions stand in an essential relation to what it is to be a person. According to some, such as Scheler or Stein, emotions indeed are constitutive of personhood. Numerous phenomenologists, and notably Pfänder, Husserl, Scheler, Voigtländer, Stein, Walther, Merleau-Ponty, or Schmitz, further hold that emotions have certain depths, which correspond, roughly, to how they affect the core personal evaluations of the emoters (see more in the respective chapters). An interesting, yet, in the English-speaking world fairly little known, alternative account is provided by Henry, who stresses the essentially bodily and affective dimension of one’s basic, pre-intentional and pre-reflexive, relation to oneself, or what he calls “self-affection” (auto-affection) or “selffeeling” (Henry 1963, 2003).51 (xi) Unsurprisingly, all phenomenologists in the tradition of Husserl and early phenomenology hold that emotions are intentional states, or states that are directed upon and present their objects in certain ways (which is, to be sure, a view shared by virtually all philosophers of emotion since Aquinas). Moreover, in the wake of Brentano’s original conception (see Montague’s chapter), many, and most explicitly Pfänder, Husserl, and Stein, also hold that emotions as intentional acts are dependent upon, though not reducible to, some kind of intentional ‘presentation’ (Vorstellung) of the target object. The claim is sometimes expressed in terms of a foundational relation between emotional and non-emotional acts. The idea is that emotional experiences are founded upon certain cognitive acts, or, better, acts of intentional acquaintance with the object that bears the value-properties that the emotion discloses. The founding act is sometimes construed as an “objectifying act” (Husserl), such as a perception or some other “intuitive” act, such as remembering or imagination.52 Furthermore, according to this view, emotions derive their intentionality from those objectifying acts that they are founded upon. Call this the ‘foundational thesis’ regarding the intentionality of emotions (Drummond 2018). Phenomenologists in the tradition of Heidegger also accept a version of the foundational thesis, but reverse the order of foundation. They argue that any representational, propositional, or properly speaking epistemic act, and in particular understanding and discourse, is founded in one’s original attunement (Befindlichkeit). However, many of the details of this foundational thesis are unclear or contested (see below), though what is clear is that the phenomenological intentionality thesis does not entail any form of emotional cognitivism, according to which emotions would be reducible to the cognitive content of intentional representations, let alone to mere evaluative judgments. Nor does any phenomenologist believe that the foundational thesis entails propositionalism regarding emotional states, i.e., the claim that they necessarily have a propositional structure (of the sort: ‘S fears that p’), or that they must at least be translatable 11
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
to propositional attitudes. In contrast, many, if not most, phenomenologists would arguably subscribe to the view that paradigmatic emotions such as fear, anger, envy, or jealousy are more complex and more fine-grained than propositional attitudes and judgments, but, somewhat paradoxically, also more ‘primitive’ in terms of their conceptual contents. Consequently, also pre-linguistic humans, and presumably some non-human animals, are capable of experiencing emotions. The fact that the intentionality of emotions is more fine-grained than the cognitive content of propositional attitudes partly explains why emotions, in Goldie’s (2000) terms, are “cognitively impenetrable”: That is to say, they are more or less unaffected by relevant beliefs about their intentional objects, without necessarily being really irrational or unwarranted. For example, I can be deadly afraid of the mere sight of a bee as an adult if I had a traumatic experience as a child, having fallen into a bee nest and being repeatedly stung, even if the memory of the pain is actually not bodily felt or eludes my occurrent consciousness (see Drummond 2004).53 (xii) This links to a further point stressed by phenomenologists, namely that emotions are structured and holistically embedded both in subjective, or personal, and objective, intersubjective, or life-worldly contexts. The evaluative properties that emotions disclose are not discrete instances but, due to the structure and experiential nature of emotions, embedded in situations of certain types. Emotions are part of the personal situation of those who have them—they have a history. This pre-history—or what Elster (1999) calls “antecedents” and de Sousa (1987) “key scenarios”—is always idiosyncratic. Now, especially, though not uniquely, in the case of traumatization, this can result in intersubjective conflicts of appropriateness: The involved emotions may seem inappropriate in their felt evaluation or ‘disproportionate’ in their felt intensity (cf. Goldie 2000; Pugmire 2005) vis-à-vis a given situation or, at worst, as irrational. This does not mean, however, that their motivation or personal genesis cannot be, at least in principle, rationally reconstructed and understood by others; the given emotion is then meaningfully fitted into the respective set of experiences of the emoter. To conclude, according to most phenomenologists, emotions are subject to norms of rationality, at least in the sense of a broad concept of rationality according to which there must be some concordance between the motivational and personal backgrounds, the intentional structure, and the experiential quality of emotions, on the one hand, and evaluative features of situational context they disclose, on the other. (xiii) As mentioned, some, if only a few, philosophers of emotion from the analytic tradition hold that emotions are not necessarily felt or consciously experienced. There are various possible readings of this claim. One can construe unfelt emotions as unconscious dispositions to feel something (e.g., Wollheim 1999) or as “emotions that pass unfelt, or are felt only on the periphery of consciousness” (Roberts 2003, 80). Some suggest that on closer inspection, there is no outright inconsistency in claiming that there are unconscious emotions in a Freudian, dispositional, or other sense, and that emotions are essentially felt (Deonna and Teroni 2012; cf. Hatzimoysis 2007). In contrast, it seems that there is no phenomenological sense in which emotions can be unfelt, where ‘unfelt’ is understood as not experientially given. However, as we will see in the next section, it is true that according to some interpretations of the distinction of the so-called ‘value-feelings’ and emotions proposed by early phenomenologists, one can say that an emotion that corresponds to a given value-feeling is not (adequately) felt. Obviously, there is another reading of the claim that most phenomenologists could readily endorse, namely one that builds upon the distinction between grasping an emotion and being bodily or else affected by it. Thus, it seems perfectly possible, and quite ubiquitous, to empathically grasp emotions of others or to simply perceive their expressions, 12
Introduction
without feeling those emotions in any relevant sense of the term (cf. Landweer’s chapter). Finally, some phenomenologists, such as Stein (1922), recognize cases in which a group of individuals shares an emotion without each member experiencing or feeling it.54
2.2 Main fault lines So much, then, for the broad agreements between phenomenological accounts of emotions; what about the divergences? Some of the disagreements are systematic or metaphysical in nature, relating, for instance, to: the role of emotions vis-à-vis values and the ontological status of evaluative properties; the role and nature of affective intentionality; possible taxonomies and the stratification of affective phenomena; the possibility of unfelt or not consciously experienced emotions; or the issue of whether emotions should primarily be construed as conscious mental or psychological states at all, or, for example, as spatial atmospheres. There are also some meta-theoretical divergences: Whereas some phenomenologists are more interested in general theories of the nature and structure of emotions (like Husserl or the early Sartre), others focus on specific types of emotions, such as social, collective (Scheler, Stein, and Walther), moral (Scheler; cf. Steinbock 2014), or hostile (Kolnai, Scheler); or on emotions in specific socio-normative or political contexts (e.g., Arendt, Fanon, or Beauvoir). Yet, others analyze particular emotions, such as love (Scheler), shame (Scheler, Sartre), anxiety (Heidegger), hatred or disgust (Kolnai), or Ressentiment (Scheler); or, as notably Scheler and Schmitz, they provide comprehensive accounts on all of the above. Lastly, some study emotions and moods more in terms of their specific existential-ontological and worlddisclosing function (Heidegger and Bollnow; cf. also Ratcliffe 2014; Saarinen 2014, 2018). Certainly, almost none of the 13 converging points sketched above are wholly uncontested among phenomenologists (save, perhaps, the possibility of unfelt emotions). Without being able to go through each in detail, we will only highlight the most significant controversies. Let us start with the intentionality thesis. However broad the agreement regarding its general contours—namely regarding the fact that emotions have a sui generis affective intentionality—there are a number of moot points. For one, it is contested whether specific types of affective phenomena are intentional phenomena at all, or at least in the standard sense of object-directedness or mental ‘aboutness’; this concerns, first, sensory or bodily feelings, such as pain or bodily pleasures (are they, for example, directed upon felt locations in the body?) but, above all, it concerns Dasein’s affective attunement (Befindlichkeit), moods, and in particular fundamental moods (Grundstimmungen), existential or the so-called “oceanic feelings” (Saarinen 2018) and affective atmospheres. Some, like Stein, argue that even paradigmatic moods are intentional and have an “objective correlate” (as, e.g., the rosy shimmer that the world is submerged in when someone is cheerful; see Stein 1917, 108–109; 1922, 181).55 According to other radical proposals, and based on a general criticism of the concept of intentionality, not even allegedly ‘ordinary’ emotions such as basic fear can, without qualifications, be properly conceived of as intentional phenomena (Schmitz 1969, 2011). Moreover, as we have seen, phenomenologists in the Heideggerian tradition reverse the foundational relation concerning emotions and objectifying acts. In contrast to the Brentanian-Husserlian line of thought, they argue that telling (Rede) and understanding (Verstehen) are founded in attunement (Befindlichkeit), and Schmitz traces self-consciousness back to one’s being bodily affected (leiblich-affektive Betroffenheit). Indeed, New Phenomenologists defend the view that emotions cannot be reduced to conscious mental or psychological states, but should rather be conceived as spatially extended atmospheric phenomena, which are subjectively incorporated in one’s being bodily affected by them.56 In the broadest brush-strokes, in this respect, 13
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
we can register a fault line between two broad paradigms in the phenomenology of emotions: the affective-intentionalist paradigm, on the one hand, and the affective-bodily-impact or the bodily being-affected paradigm of New Phenomenology, on the other.57 There is another aspect of this fault line which concerns the issue of embodiment. Specifically, it concerns the claim that all affective phenomena are bodily felt, or in some sense body-bound. Thus, key figures of the early phenomenology of emotions, and notably Scheler and Stein, hold that not all affective phenomena are “body-bound.” The reason for this striking claim is that certain types of affective experiences, and in particular what Scheler and Stein call “spiritual feelings” (geistige Gefühle), or “emotions in the pregnant sense,” do not always covary with changes in bodily feelings or with any bodily feelings at all. For example, one can be anxious about one’s hostile neighbors without any sensible heart beating or trembling of one’s hand, or one can remain fearful after all visceral or other bodily felt sensations have ceased to manifest themselves. New Phenomenologists would say in these cases that bodily contraction, which characterizes anxiety, must be felt to speak of fear or anxiety at all. Notice, however, that neither Scheler nor Stein, nor any other phenomenologist for that matter, would, therefore, simply give up on the distinction between Leib and Körper, nor would they no longer emphasize the role of the felt body for affectivity. Quite the contrary: Both Stein and Scheler, for example, clearly accommodate the Leib/Körper-distinction, and further distinguish—within the sphere of the lived body (Leib)—between purely “sensory feelings” (Gefühlsempfindungen) and the so-called “vital” or “common feelings” (Vitalgefühle, Gemeingefühle). The former include sensations such as itching, bodily pain, the pleasure of tastes, or of the touch of a soft texture, which are interoceptively perceived but concern specific sensations in specific bodily locations, whereas the latter concern the overall “attunement of the lived body” (leibliche Befindlichkeit; Stein 1917, 87), such as weariness, freshness, or irritability. In unprecedented detail, these authors provide descriptions of the complex stratifications of bodily feelings and their psycho-dynamic interaction (e.g., the affect of bodily weariness on the experience of spiritual joy, etc.). They, thus, prefigure later conceptions of bodily attunement by Heidegger and Schmitz.58 Moreover, in concordance with the affective intentionality paradigm, all early phenomenologists still hold fast to the idea that—for all affective phenomena which, in fact, have bodily components—their bodily feeling and their intentional-evaluative dimension are inextricable and can only analytically, if at all, be distinguished.59 Coming back to the intentionality thesis, even among those who wholeheartedly subscribe to the affective-intentionalist paradigm (in contrast to the affective-bodily-impact paradigm), it is far from clear how exactly to spell out the affective or “emotional intentionality” at stake (cf. Ratcliffe 2019). Is it a sui generis kind of intentionality, like the intentionality of empathy according to Husserl or Stein,60 as Goldie (2000) argues? Relatedly, the construction of the above-mentioned foundational thesis regarding the intentionality of emotions is far from clear-cut: What does it mean to say that the intentionality of emotions is ‘derived’ from the intentionality of acts of perception or imagination upon which emotive acts are founded, as Husserl, for example, claims in some of his writings? Specifically, it is unclear in what sense emotions are intentional presentations of values, i.e., so-called ‘value-ceptions’ (Wertnehmen), as Husserl, Scheler, Stein, and others construe emotive acts; and in what sense do value-ceptions involve originary presentations of values, analogous to perception (Wahrnehmen).61 In other words, it is a matter of dispute whether the emotive acts of value-ception really constitute, in the Husserlian sense, the evaluative properties of their intentional objects, or the ‘value-objects’ as such, or if it is the case that emotions are only directed upon those objects and disclose their evaluative properties. If the latter, what, then, does ‘disclosing’ here exactly mean?62 14
Introduction
With this, we touch upon one of the central discussions of early phenomenology of emotions, namely on the nature of values and the intricate relation between emotions and values.63 This issue bears important connections to the above-mentioned appropriateness of emotions. All early phenomenologists, including not only the so-called ‘realist’ phenomenologists, such as Scheler, Reinach, Stein, or Hildebrand, but also the transcendental-idealist Husserl, hold, explicitly or implicitly, a form of value realism. (In the following, we will discuss only this strand of the debate and leave aside the more general criticism of the concept of values by the bodily being-affected-paradigm.)64 However, it is far from clear what value realism exactly entails, or how to conceive of the ontological and phenomenological status of values. To recap, the most important alternative conceptions on offer are these: Either values and value-objects are first constituted by emotive acts, or values are independent objects or properties of things, persons, or events. There is an admittedly problematic middle-way that we can uncover implicitly in some phenomenological accounts, such as Stein’s (1922).65 According to this view, though values are intentional correlates of emotions qua acts of value-feeling (Wertfühlen), value-feelings still can appropriately or inappropriately track those values and are thus sensitive to reasons ‘of the heart.’66 Values, thus, retain a certain ontological independency vis-à-vis the emotive acts that at the same time constitute and disclose them. According to one interpreter, Scheler would also conceive of values as both felt qualia and intentional objects (Theodorou 2018, 152f.). Values are not particular properties of concrete, existing objects, like the color of a concrete patch, hence do not depend on the existence of concrete objects as their bearer; they are rather like “eidetic essences” or “species” (cf., critically, Vendrell Ferran 2008a, 198f.). If this were so, we are at a “dead-end” (Theodorou 2018, 153), since one could never directly access the values that one’s emotions are supposed to disclose, at least not in ordinary affective experiences. Rather, value-feelings would be some affective analogue of Husserl’s categorical intuitions, and values some sort of higher-order categorical object or, even more confusingly, some “species of a felt quality” (ibid.). But this would amount to an arch-cognitivist view of emotions, which doesn’t seem to be true to the phenomenology of emotional experience and doesn’t square with Scheler’s overall account of emotions either.67 What, then, are values? As none of this seems quite right nor does it help illuminate the phenomenological nature of felt evaluations. Probably, the closest one can get to an answer is by considering the early phenomenologists’ view on how emotions disclose values in the acts of value-ceptions or value-feelings (Wertfühlen)—a view that is, in turn, unfortunately rather ambiguous.68 Without going into too much detail, let us just highlight one contentious issue, namely whether or not emotions should be conceived of as identical to acts of value-feeling. Some classical phenomenologists, and in particular Scheler, Stein, or Kolnai, hold a non-identity view: Value-feelings belong to a distinct type of intentional act and should be contrasted with feelings or emotions properly speaking (Mulligan 2008, 2010a, 2010b, 2017; Vendrell Ferran 2008a, 2015). According to this view, it’s not feelings that present or disclose values, but precisely value-feelings. Thus, I am not ashamed because my feeling of shame discloses the shamefulness of my behavior, but rather because, in having a corresponding value-feeling, I become acquainted with its shamefulness. And the feeling, viz. the emotional experience of shame, is a response to the disvalue of shamefulness that the value-feeling is disclosing. Value-feelings do not represent a distinctive type of feeling or emotional experience. However, it is not unanimous whether they are just an aspect of a properly speaking emotional experience, or instead some affective ‘knowledge by acquaintance,’ or as Mulligan puts it, “acknowledgements” or “responses to acquaintance with values” (Mulligan 2010a, 2010b). For example, Stein does not contrast value-feelings with the feeling or the emotional 15
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
reaction that is motivated by those values; for Stein, they are precisely just two aspects of the affective intentionality of emotions.69 In any case, the most promising way to approach a resolution to this issue seems to conceive of the phenomenological relation between emotions and values in terms of a double-aspect evaluative intentionality of emotions. Emotions, then, are disclosing not only values but also something about the appropriateness and the depth of the felt evaluation, or the emotional experience as such (see, again, for a similar account de Monticelli’s chapter). Thus, when I have a feeling (e.g., joy over x), what is disclosed to me is not only the evaluative property ( joyfulness) of x but that and how x matters to me or impacts me in a certain way (as meriting a joyful response from me). Yet, importantly, realist phenomenologists do not simply identify the act of value-feeling and the experiential dimension or felt quality of an emotion. The reason for distinguishing the two has to do with their claim that emotions can appropriately or inappropriately track values, and, moreover, be appropriately and inappropriately felt. Only by distinguishing these two aspects of emotions—their value-disclosing and their function of ‘affecting’ subjects— can phenomenologists take into account cases in which a value is indeed appropriately disclosed but precisely doesn’t affectively (fully) impact the emoter (‘leaves one cold’) or is not accompanied by a corresponding emotion at all (cf. Stein 1922, 133–136). In other words, realist phenomenologists aim to accommodate the intuition that we can clearly—and also emotionally—grasp values without necessarily being affected by them in a way, in which others or we ourselves think we ought to. For example, we may grasp the appalling nature of an injustice but instead of being outraged by it (even if only in the sense of a moral outrage), we remain in a state of slight indignation. According to this picture, the perceptual and the moral world is more complex and more fine-grained than our emotional repertoire (cf. Vendrell Ferran 2015).70 Others would claim that divergences between (alleged) values and those actually felt are an indication that something is wrong not necessarily with the feelings but, rather, with the moral norms and values to which one considers oneself to be committed. According to this perspective, it is not an independent moral world which is too complex to be grasped by emotions; it is the moral self-concept and self-image which are susceptible to self-deception concerning one’s own commitments. Here, one would need to differentiate between (i) a wider concept of value and (ii) the narrower concept of norms which are dependent on emotions with strict normative demands like shame, guilt, and moral anger, which are emotions of conscience and have moral authority for us (see Landweer 2007, 2013). How to resolve this problem of a divergence, or even a conflict, between emotions and values—whether emotions can ever be considered inadequate, inappropriate, or inauthentic in some sense, or whether, in some cases, it is our moral ideas or normative framework that are too wooden or prone to self-deception—is an open question that begs further phenomenological research.
3. Rationale and synoptic overview Against the historical and meta-theoretical background just sketched, let us now say a few words about the rationale of this volume, about our reasons for selecting the given authors and topics and give a synoptic overview of the parts and chapters. The volume consists of five interlinked parts which center around three focal aims: (a) A more historical focus (Part I), (b) a systematic focus on the most important classical and contemporary issues and debates (Part II), and (c) a focus on the analyses of specific types and forms of emotions, notably self- and other-directed, collective and political emotions (Parts III and IV ), as well as of affective phenomena that we call ‘borderline cases of emotions’ (Part V ). 16
Introduction
Thus, first, the handbook critically, and in contemporary terms, re-evaluates the rich historical resources that we can find in the phenomenology of emotions. Accordingly, in Part I: Historical Perspective, the chapters offer state-of-the-art assessments of central pre- and postwar, and also little-known phenomenologists of emotions. Some of the accounts are systematically introduced to an English-speaking audience for the first time (e.g., Bollnow71 or Voigtländer). In presenting the views of classical as well as yet only marginally considered authors, we certainly aim beyond a mere cultivation of the tradition; rather, we contend that a historically informed gaze is better suited to detect and also to challenge conceptual and methodological background assumptions and their implications for current philosophical theorizing. Yet, anybody who seriously engages with the (pre-)history of the phenomenology of emotions will realize that there is no one-dimensional, and much less teleological, narrative. One will, of course, also discover that the conceptual repertoires, methods, and claims of classical phenomenological accounts are not neatly reflected in current discussions in the philosophy of emotions. Rather, we hope that what come into relief are both the continuities and divergences across these accounts, and hence an overall more balanced view on the present state of emotion research. In terms of the selection of authors, we aim to provide the most exhaustive treatment of all those phenomenological thinkers who have significantly contributed to the philosophy of emotions. Thus, 19 chapters give overviews of the theory of emotions of authors from the pre-history or the very beginning of the phenomenological movement (see the chapters on Brentano, Pfänder, Geiger, Husserl, Voigtländer, Scheler, Scheler, Walther, Schmalenbach, Hildebrand, and Kolnai) to the most important Inter- or Post-war French (Sartre, Beauvoir, Merleau-Ponty, Fanon, and Levinas) and German-speaking phenomenologists (Heidegger, Bollnow, Gurwitsch, Arendt, and Schmitz). Given their distinctive contribution to a systematic phenomenology of emotions, a special emphasis in this part is on the so-called early or realist phenomenologists. Many of these authors are next to unknown within analytic philosophy of emotions, and some even within phenomenological scholarship; yet, they were not only highly influential for the establishment of the phenomenological movement (see Spiegelberg 1994) but also offer numerous valuable insights for contemporary debates on social, collective, and moral emotions (notably Voigtländer, Stein, Walther, Schmalenbach, von Hildebrand, and Kolnai). Some of the contributions in this part not only present authors individually, but, wherever it makes systematic sense, the respective work is considered in light of mutual influences or criticism (see the chapters on Walther and Schmalenbach and Heidegger and Bollnow). Now, some might wonder whether all these authors can sensibly be listed among phenomenologists. To be sure, in terms of traditional fault lines, we have endorsed a fairly liberal notion of phenomenology. Thus, we have included authors who might, on first glance, not immediately be recognized as belonging to the phenomenological tradition, such as Fanon, Arendt, Beauvoir, or the forefathers of phenomenology Pfänder, Geiger, or Brentano. The same goes for unquestionably phenomenological authors who, however, might not be readily counted as phenomenologists of emotions (such as Schmalenbach, Gurwitsch, Merleau-Ponty, or Levinas). Above and beyond our generally inclusive notion of what phenomenology was, is, and should be in future research, our choice is motivated by more specific considerations. In some cases, it is motivated by considering certain ‘conceptual constellations’ (Begriffskonstellationen, as Adorno or German historians of philosophy would put it) or influences that need to be taken into account to understand central authors and concepts. For example, Husserl’s, Scheler’s, Stein’s, or Walther’s phenomenology, and their phenomenology of emotions, cannot be fully appreciated without considering the theories of Brentano, 17
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
Pfänder, or Geiger. The same can be said of Merleau-Ponty and Levinas, who had a key impact on both traditional and contemporary discussions on affectivity, even though they have not provided systematic phenomenologies of emotions, or Arendt, Fanon, or Beauvoir, who proved to be eminently influential on contemporary critical phenomenology. Similarly, Schmalenbach or Gurwitsch were among the important voices for the development of a phenomenology of collective emotions, which was fully developed only in the work of Scheler, Stein, or Walther. In terms of topical discussions, we were not only guided by what phenomenologists have traditionally regarded as the central issues in the theory of emotions, such as intentionality, values, appropriateness, the morality of emotions, or a taxonomy of different affective phenomena; we were also guided by what we take to be equally essential for a comprehensive phenomenology of emotions with a view to contemporary discussions (analytic or not), and for the future phenomenological research generally speaking. This brings us to the second aim of the volume, represented by Part II: Systematic Issues and Contemporary Debates. Here, the chapters provide comprehensive overviews of both the central traditional and the recently discussed issues in the philosophy of emotions from a phenomenological perspective. These ten chapters offer lines of arguments that partly complement, partly challenge, current discussions on the ontology, epistemology, or morality of emotions and contextualize classical phenomenological accounts of emotions with a view to current discussions on affective stratification and taxonomies of affective states (Drummond), existential feelings (see Ratcliffe’s chapter), trends in moral psychology and moral phenomenology (Helm, De Monticelli, and Drummond and Rinofner-Kreidl), situated and 4E-approaches to emotions (Stephan and Walter), the growing literature on emotional atmospheres (Griffero), the ph ilosophy of embodiment and the relevant discussions in feminist thought (Dolezal), and psychopathology (Fuchs), as well as the philosophy of art (Carroll). In the remaining parts of the volume, 19 chapters provide detailed analyses of the central, but also often sidelined or non-standard categories, types, and forms of particular emotions. In these three parts, contributors investigate self-directed, other-directed, and collective emotions, as well as discussions of particular ‘borderline cases’ of emotions. With these analyses, we aim to close a gap in emotion research that still exists, despite many dozens of texts published in recent years on particular emotions. Most philosophical approaches were and still are devoted to formulating general theories of emotions, or have the tendency to paradigmatically generalize certain features of particular emotions, from which they then distill some general insights about the nature of certain types of emotions (e.g., moral or aversive ones) or emotions in general.72 Cases in point, for example, are grief for narrative theories (Goldie 2012; cf. Ryberg Ingerslev’s, and also Bortolan’s chapters), or resentment and forgiveness for the morality of hostile emotions.73 Phenomenologists were certainly not immune to this strategy. Just think of Sartre’s analysis of shame (cf. Zahavi’s chapter), or Heidegger’s conceptualization of anxiety and boredom (cf. Thonhauser’s, and Freeman’s and Elpidorou chapters). Obviously, this strategy has some shortcomings for a phenomenologically adequate description of many emotions, as they do not readily fit the paradigm cases. Consider, for instance, the problem of conceiving of the morality of Ressentiment (in contrast to resentment) or of hatred (cf. Schmid’s, Landweer’s and Szanto’s and Slaby’s chapter) or the arguably doomed attempt to construe a narrative theory of episodic forms of anger or joy. In this volume, we pursue a multi-dimensional strategy, discussing general conceptions of emotions and their role in our experiential, cognitive, moral, and social lives, as well as more than 30 particular emotions. Moreover, in a number of chapters throughout the last three 18
Introduction
parts, particular emotions are further differentiated, such as hate and hate of evil (see the chapters of Landweer and Schmid), or shame, hetero-induced shame, and survivor shame (see Zahavi, and Montes Sánchez), and various transformations and interlinked dynamics between distinct but cognate emotions are elaborated upon (see Summa, Freeman and Elpidorou, Landweer, Bortolan, Steinbock, Breyer, and Bernhardt). This also explains why some emotions or types of emotions are discussed in more than one chapter, as they are considered from different perspectives or in the context of different affective phenomena, or in the work of different phenomenologists. This applies to forms of shame (see Zahavi, Montes Sánchez, and Dolezal), and to various, distinctively social, antagonistic, and/or collective emotions, such as Ressentiment or hatred (see Vendrell Ferran’s two chapters, as well as Landweer, Schmid, and Szanto and Slaby), and forms of emotional sharing (see Calcagno, Schloßberger, Tranas and Caminada, Fuchs, J. Müller, Sánchez Guerrero, Szanto and Slaby, and Krebs). Part III deals with Self-Directed and Individual Emotions. The chapters, here, display discussions of central instances of emotions and affectively charged attitudes whose subjects are typically—though not necessarily—single individuals and/or whose affective focus essentially has a self-reference to the respective emoters, such as joy and happiness (Summa), disgust (Heinämaa), fear, anxiety and boredom (Freeman and Elpidorou), pride and selfesteem and its related contrast-phenomena embarrassment and shyness (Bortolan), and shame (Zahavi). The emotions covered in this part also include often neglected but highly pertinent feelings such as the affective reaction to humiliation or the feeling of humility and affliction (Steinbock). Part IV is dedicated to what we call Other-Directed and Collective Emotions. Under this title, we subsume three different types of emotions: (i) Moral, antagositic, and (pro-)social emotions, which all have an intrinsic social focus, or are intentionally directed at others, such as grief (Ryberg Ingerslev), including: ‘pro-social’ sentiments, and in particular sympathy and compassion (Breyer); hostile or ‘aggressive’ emotions, such as indignation, envy, anger, jealousy, contempt, and hatred (Landweer); and the little-explored variants of shame, namely survivor shame and shame felt in the face of something shameful being committed by another with whom one socially identifies (Montez Sánchez); (ii) collective and/or political emotions (Guerrero Sanchéz; Szanto and Slaby); (iii) in one case, namely empathy, a sui generis intentional state that is, according to most phenomenologists, though not an affective state as such (see above), indispensable for the grasp of emotions of others and lies at the basis of ‘pro-social’ emotions (Breyer). It is also in light of our multi-dimensional approach that we have included contentious cases of affective phenomena, the so-called Borderline Cases of Emotions, in Part V— counting on raised eye-brows and, indeed, welcoming skepticism as to whether these actually are fully fledged emotions. We believe that only phenomenologically detailed analyses and ongoing conceptual refinements regarding any psychologically, morally, socially, or politically relevant phenomena that potentially bear an affective dimension can determine—everinconclusively—the scope of the class of phenomena that we can rightly call ‘emotions.’ Accordingly, this concluding part is devoted to dispositional states, attitudes, or other phenomena that may not be properly speaking emotions but have either important functions for generating affective states or are themselves affectively ‘charged’ in one way or another. Moreover, a number of contributions in this section return to issues and discussions from previous parts, in particular on bodily felt aspects of emotions, the morality of emotions, emotions of aggression and destruction, or emotional sharing. Specifically, these chapters discuss morally or socio-politically relevant attitudes, such as forgiveness and revenge ( Bernhardt), gratitude (Rinofner-Kreidl), feelings of solidarity ( J. Müller), trust (de Warren), or the hate 19
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
that is specifically directed at allegedly ‘evil’ agents, or its opposite, the complex dispositional sentiment love (Krebs). But we find here also discussions of a central affective bodily affliction, such as pain (Svenaeus), or the affliction that befalls one in the loss of the sense of the world as a locus of familiarity, as in experiences of the uncanny (Trigg).
4. Desiderata for future research There probably exists no handbook in which something is not missing, no matter how comprehensive the collection may be. This is, of course, no different in the present case. So, who or what is missing? We have aimed for maximal comprehensiveness regarding the treatment of phenomenologists, presenting 20 authors from the phenomenological tradition. However, some little discussed or almost unknown but still important figures and their work could not be included. The list comprises almost a dozen German-speaking, Spanish, French, and Hungarian authors from the beginning to the late 20th century, notably: the Munich phenomenologists and Pfänder-students Willy Haas,74 Karl Konstantin Löwenstein-Freudenberg, and Paul Kananow, but also figures such as Nicolai Hartmann, Hans Reiner, José Ortega y Gasset, Helmuth Plessner, the already mentioned Stephan Strasser and Michel Henry, or Paul Ricœur and Agnes Heller. Let us say a few words on these authors, thus outlining potential avenues for future research (for Henry, see above). Haas published his essay Über Echtheit und Unechtheit von Gefühlen (“On the Authenticity and Inauthenticity of Emotions”) in 1910, in which he develops an original framework for the appropriateness of emotions. Roughly, the idea is this: There are no authentic or inauthentic emotions as such; rather, the authenticity of emotions is correlative with the strata of the ego or self in which they are realized. Authentic emotions are those which are integrated into the “unity of the proper personality” (Einheit der eigentlichen Persönlichkeit) or the “dominant affective orientations” (Grundrichtungen der Gefühle) of the relevant instance of the self, i.e., the “ego that actually bears the given emotion” (das Ich, welches Träger des Gefühls ist). For example, joyfulness is authentic if it is integrated into the actually dominant background orientation of relaxation and blissfulness of the emoter and not into that of her irritability or disgruntlement (Haas 1910, 352–356). Haas not only argues against correlating the (in)authenticity of emotions with the diachronically fluctuating “phenomenal ego,” but also warns us not to misidentify the relevant layer of the self with some personal character or characteristics. Overall, Haas seems to echo Stein’s similar considerations, but also partly prefigures recent accounts of emotional “soundness.” 75 Other work that has almost been completely forgotten are two dissertations from the Munich school of phenomenology: the Pfänder-student Löwenstein-Freudenberg’s thesis Über das Gefallen (“On Pleasing”) (1913), which aims at a detailed “phenomenology of the act of pleasure” (“Phänomenologie des Gefallensaktes”), distinguishing it from love and partly drawing on Freud; and the Russian student Kananow’s dissertation Über das Gefühl der Tätigkeit (“On the Feeling of Agency”) (1910), written under the direction of Pfänder and Lipps, which elaborates a taxonomy of feelings of intentional agency, such as feelings of excitement (Erregungsgefühle), of power (Kraftgefühle), or feelings accompanying intentional decision (Entscheidungsgefühle). Both treatises deserve more attention, especially given their focus on still wholly underexplored affective states.76 Nicolai Hartmann, in the second volume of his three-volume Ethics (1926), puts forth an a priori axiology or a so-called ‘material ethics of value,’ in which he details different types 20
Introduction
of emotional and moral evaluations and their relation to different types of values (see Poli 2017). Despite strong links between Hartmann’s axiology and Scheler’s (see Kelly 2011) and Hartmann’s occasional references to other realist phenomenologists, such as von Hildebrand or Reinach, he doesn’t endorse a phenomenological methodology, even broadly conceived. Nevertheless, the Ethics contains many phenomenologically detailed descriptions of a range of emotions, or what he calls ‘special moral values’ (e.g., happiness, courage, love, humility, trust, modesty, or aloofness). Phenomenological reassessments of these or further comparative research elaborating Hartmann’s and other phenomenologists’ take on particular emotions could thus be fruitful (e.g., Kolnai’s ‘haughtiness’ (Hochmut) and Hartmann’s ‘aloofness’ (Wahrung der Distanz)). In this regard, we should also mention Reiner’s alternative phenomenological account of values (Reiner 1959; see also 1932). In a somewhat deflationary move, Reiner correlates values with the valence of emotions (as do many classical accounts, such as Spinoza’s or Aquinas’). Values and disvalues are simply what is either agreeable/pleasant or disagreeable/ unpleasant. He also explicitly cuts across the traditional divide between realist and idealist conceptions of values (Reiner 1959) and provides a succinct critical discussion of Heidegger’s Nietzsche-inspired rejection of the notion of value altogether (e.g., in Heidegger 1938).77 Ortega y Gasset is a better known, though today little read, author, who was educated in the context of the Neo-Kantianism of Cohen and Natorp. However, in his earlier years, he also intensively engaged with the broader phenomenological movement, in particular with Pfänder, Husserl, and Scheler, and later, critically, with Heidegger (Pintor Ramos 1994; Holmes 2017). Although Ortega y Gasset did not present any systematic work on phenomenology of emotions, his essays in On Love (1941) are noteworthy. Here, he follows Pfänder’s theory of sentiments. He also agrees with Scheler that love and hate are dispositional acts, insofar as they incline an “inner doing,” an active intention toward their objects (see Vendrell Ferran 2008a). Stephan Strasser’s work Phenomenology of Feeling: An Essay on the Phenomena of Heart (1956) deserves special attention. In this systematic work, Strasser (a previous Husserl-assistant) critically discusses Scheler and, probably for the first time in the German-speaking world, also Sartre’s theory of emotions at length. Moreover, he deals with the first- and secondgeneration Leipzig School Gestalt psychologists’ accounts of emotions. But Strasser is certainly of more than mere scholarly interest as he attempts to develop an original and comprehensive phenomenological “typology of feeling.” He also offers the most systematic phenomenological account of happiness to date (see Summa’s chapter). Fortunately, Strasser’s work has been translated into English decades ago, and Ricœur’s foreword and the translator Robert Wood’s comprehensive introduction provide a good starting point for a longoverdue rediscovery. The rich work of Paul Ricœur also contains interesting material for future work on affectivity. For example, in The Fallible Man (a part of his monumental Philosophy of the Will) (1960), he, too, discusses happiness in some detail. More importantly, he introduces the notion of “affective fragility,” which refers to the phenomenon that humans are capable of what one would today call ‘mixed feelings,’ 78 or, in Ricœur’s Freudian terms, a “disproportion between the principle of pleasure and the principle of happiness,” as when one experiences “Joy in and through anguish” (ibid., 106). Relatedly, Ricœur discusses the alleged “paradox” of affective intentionality, the phenomenon that the intentionality of emotions grasps felt qualities pertaining to intentional objects, and, at the same time, “manifest[t] and revea[l] the way in which the self is inwardly affected” (ibid., 84). As we have seen, the latter point regarding emotions’ self-related and self-revelatory character is a central issue in both 21
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
phenomenological and analytic philosophy of emotions; it has also been discussed in terms of the radically ‘passive’ intentionality of self-affection by Henry. Another notion of the paradox nature of human existence and its relation to affectivity was proposed earlier by one of the most eminent German-speaking philosophical anthropologists, Helmuth Plessner. Plessner was a student of Husserl, Neo-Kantians, and the sociologist Max Weber, but was also influenced by Scheler. Plessner’s core idea is that the defining feature of humans, which distinguishes them from non-human animals and inorganic matter alike, lies in their so-called “eccentric positionality.” Plessner means by this a form of perspectival distance toward one’s organic and inorganic environments, as well as to one’s own body. Importantly, for Plessner, this distance or transcendence vis-àvis oneself manifests itself not only in human’s linguistic capability but also, and indeed distinctively so, their emotional expressivity. Specifically, eccentric positionality manifests itself in the uniquely human expression of smiling (Lächeln), laughing, and crying (Plessner 1941/1961, 1950). Plessner conceives of laughing and crying as “limit-cases of human behavior,” as they express “the brokenness of man’s relation to his body,” which is “the basis of his existence, the source, but also the limit, of his power” (1941/1961, 32). Plessner has had a considerable influence on German postwar philosophy, but has not yet been sufficiently recognized in the English-speaking world. Both his original existential-anthropological theory of laughter and crying and his analysis of shame and vanity (Plessner 1924) await a broader discussion in the philosophy of emotions (see, however, Berger 1997).79 Finally, let us mention the unduly little-known work A Theory of Feelings (1979) by the Hungarian philosopher Heller, who later became the successor of Arendt’s chair at the New School for Social Research. In this book, Heller provides an intriguing, explicitly phenomenologically founded, critical sociology of emotions. Heller was arguably among the first to discuss the idea of culturally sedimented and internalized “emotional regimes” (Reddy 2001) or normative sets of affective practices. This is well reflected in her Marx-inspired, historical, and conceptual elaborations on the “housekeeping of feelings.” For Heller, such an affective “economy” is not just a matter of individual emotional “regulation” but, rather, functions by means of internalized, socially stratified norms. Heller, thus, also prefigures the influential conceptions of feminist sociologists of emotion such as Hochschild’s (1979, 1983) “emotion management” and “emotion norms” or Illouz’s (2007) notions of “emotional capital” and “emotional habitus.” As we have seen, the range of affectively relevant phenomena in our bodily felt, moral, and social world is probably more complex than our (folk-)psychological, philosophical, and phenomenological conceptual frameworks can capture. But some affective phenomena that have, in fact, been conceptualized still lack their own treatment or are only partly covered in the following chapters for reasons of space. Several are treated by the authors just mentioned, such as feelings of agency (Kanonow), courage (Hartmann), or laughing and crying ( Plessner); some are discussed across the chapters in the context of other affective phenomena or dynamics, such as Ressentiment80 and feelings of powerlessness, frustration, or malicious joy (see the chapters of Vendrell Ferran on Voigtländer, and Schloßberger, Landweer, and Szanto and Slaby), regret (Bernhardt), feelings or a sense of justice (Rinofner-Kreidl, and Landweer) or feelings of belonging and exclusion (Szanto and Slaby); some affective phenomena, such as surprise or curiosity, that certainly deserve more attention from phenomenologists, are altogether missing.81 We hope, though, that the material in this handbook will inspire future research on these and further emotions.
22
Introduction
5. A final note A final, general note on what—and what not—to expect from reading the contributions is in order. Given the nature of a handbook, and the fact that there are as yet hardly any introductory sources or overview material available on the phenomenology of emotions, these being especially scarce in English, all the chapters are devised so as to give a comprehensive and accessible overview of the authors, topics, and discussions at issue. However, we believe that it is illusory to think that philosophical analysis could ever be entirely neutral. Indeed, we contend that while philosophy should be charitable and sensitive to opposing views and interpretations, it is also, to some degree, always partial. Accordingly, throughout the volume, the contributors’ own voices, conceptual preferences, and own research foci will be present, but that, we trust, will be perceived as a benefit.
Notes
23
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
8 9 10 11
12 13
14
15 16
17 18 19 20 21 22
23 24 25
26
on emotions, see esp. Stumpf (1928); on Pfänder and Geiger, see the respective chapters in this volume. See Strasser (1956, ch. 3). For a concise discussion, see Vendrell Ferran (2015); cf. also Salice (2016). In this context, it is worth mentioning that even an eminent figure of the allegedly ‘emotion-proof ’ Neo-Kantianism such as Cohen dedicated a comprehensive work to the theory of emotions, see his Ästhetik des reinen Gefühls (1912) (“Aesthetic of Pure Feeling”). An exception among these exceptions seems to be Strasser’s book Das Gemüt, whose English translation, more than 20 years after its German publication, was introduced by Ricoeur, but even this translation has not had any real effect on its reception, which—unduly—remains almost nonexistent to this very date. Straddling analytic and continental work on emotions, Solomon is the only notable exception who, from early on in his work, repeatedly refers to Sartre’s work on emotions (see, e.g., Solomon 1976). See Rutkevič (2014); de Warren and Vongehr (2018); cf. also Stein (1985). A noteworthy and almost wholly unknown critical essay, albeit from the interwar period, is Voigtländer’s “Zur Psychologie der politischen Stellungnahme. Eine massenpsychologische Studie” (1920). It is a sad irony of history that Voigtländer, an early proponent of Freud in Germany, became a member of the NSDAP in 1937, though her sympathies with Nazism remain unclear; see also Vendrell Ferran’s chapter. Cf. also Plessner (1935). On Stein, Scheler, Walther, and Schmalenbach, see the respective chapters. In this context, it should be noted that there were some interesting and exceptional conservative, catholic phenomenologists who were staunch critics of Nazism, such as Scheler, the Jewish convert to Catholicism, Kolnai, and von Hildebrand; see also Gubser (2014, 2019). Although see Heller’s (1979) neo-Marxist reassessment of emotions in the last section. Against a one-sided reading of Kant as somebody who altogether expels emotions and affectivity from moral life, see, however, Mohrmann (2015). For general post-liberal rejections of this picture, see the references in Szanto’s and Slaby’s chapter. Note also that this dichotomy between emotions and morality, supposedly originating in Enlightenment thought is not as clear-cut as often thought; just think of what Nussbaum (2013, 54) calls “Rousseau’s civic emotion culture.” See also the powerful counter-narrative in Mishra (2017). See, e.g., Rorty Oksenberg (1980), Baier (1986), Nussbaum (1990), and Jones (1996). Rorty Oksenberg and Nussbaum were among the first to remind the Anglo-Saxon world of this. See, e.g., Gibbard (1990), McDowell (1998), and Blackburn (2001). Solomon (1984) also highlights the importance of Bedford’s paper “Emotions” (1956/1957), which critically draws on Ryle (1949), though the impact of this paper seems quite marginal compared to the monographs appearing only decades later. Let us stress the qualifier ‘broadly’ given the diversity and indeed ambiguity of the concept of ‘cognitivism’ in relation to emotions. Caution should be applied even in relation to those philosophers typically listed as ‘arch-cognitivists’; for a good discussion of this, see Solomon (2002). Other influential work from this earlier cognitivist period includes Marks (1982), Deigh (1994), Gordon (1990), and Greenspan (1988); cf. also Stocker (1983). Also, the use of literary examples and their phenomenological analysis has become more customary within analytic work on the emotions, most notably in the work of Wollheim and Goldie. See also Slaby (2008a, 2008b) and Slaby et al. (2011); cf. also Helm’s congenial account in his chapter. Note that ‘concern or value-based construal of emotions’ is a fairly broad umbrella-term that houses some still divergent accounts such as Helm (2001, 2017), Roberts (2003), Deonna and Teroni (2012), or Tappolet (2016). Mapping perceptual accounts is almost impossible by now, however young the field, as the label has been used, more or less appropriately, to characterize (or self-applied to) such widely diverging authors as de Sousa, Roberts, Goldie, Helm, Tappolet, Prinz, or Döring among many others; for a useful, brief orientation in this conceptual minefield, see Döring and Lutz (2015); and for the most sustained criticism to date, see Brady (2013). For a discussion of classical phenomenological (esp. regarding Scheler and Sartre) and recent perceptual accounts, see Poellner (2016). See Griffiths and Scarantino (2009), Colombetti (2014), De Jaegher (2015), Krueger and Szanto (2016), and more references in Stephan’s and Walter’s chapter.
24
Introduction
25
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
26
Introduction
27
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer
76 77 78 79 80 81
Psychischen),” which “attributes ‘psychological entities’ the ‘intuitive’ determination of extendedness, voluminosity or fullness and orders of depths (anschaulichen’ Bestimmtheiten der Ausgebreitetheit, der Voluminosität oder Fülle und der Tiefenordnung). This doesn’t concern, of course, a form of physical extension, etc., but are still phenomena that “stem from the form of space” (Binswanger 1922, 119). (Binswanger later on in the book also criticizes Haas’ and Pfänder’s “psychization” (Psychisierung) of the depth of psychological states as a sort of psycho-affective ‘intensification’ of those states (ibid., 333).) This is particularly interesting in light of the New Phenomenologists’, and especially Schmitz’s, similar conceptions of emotions decades later. However, in Schmitz’s view, what is described as the spatiality of the soul are felt-bodily experiences which do not need an additional ‘inner space’ in any metaphorical sense; see above and Landweer’s chapter. See brief descriptions of both Löwenstein-Freudenberg and Kananow in Spiegelberg and Avé-Lallemant (1982). See additional references to both Reiner and Hartmann in De Monticelli’s as well as Drummond’s and Rinofner-Kreidl’s chapters. For a recent overview of the discussion on mixed feelings, see Zaborowski, forthcoming. Prütting has recently published a truly monumental, 2,000-page monograph Homo Ridens (2013/2016) dedicated to the phenomenology of laughter, heavily drawing on Plessner, but even more on Schmitz’s New Phenomenology. For the most sustained and phenomenologically grounded treatment of Ressentiment published recently, see Aeschbach (2017). For a recent volume on “neglected” emotions, see Elpidorou (2020).
References Aeschbach, Sebastian (2017). Ressentiment. An Anatomy. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Genève. doi:10.13097/archive-ouverte/unige:103621. Ahmed, Sara (2004). The Cultural Politics of Emotion. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. ——— (2006). Queer Phenomenology. Orientations, Objects, Others. Durham, NC, London: Duke University Press. Al-Saji, Alia (2000). The Site of Affect in Husserl’s Phenomenology: Sensations and the Constitution of the Lived Body. Philosophy Today 44 (Suppl.), 51–59. ——— (2010a). Bodies and Sensings: On the Uses of Husserlian Phenomenology for Feminist Theory. Continental Philosophy Review 43(1), 13–37. ——— (2010b). The Racialization of Muslim Veils: A Philosophical Analysis. Philosophy & Social Criticism 36(8), 875–902. Angerer, Marie-Luise (2015[2007]). Desire After Affect. Transl. by N. Grindell. London, New York: Rowman and Littlefield. Bagnoli, Carla (Ed.) (2011). Morality and the Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Baier, Anette (1986). Trust and Antitrust. Ethics 96(2), 231–260. Barrett Feldman, Lisa (2017). How Emotions Are Made: The Secret Life of the Brain. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. Bedford, Errol (1956/1957). Emotions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series) 57, 281–304. Bedorf, Thomas, and Herrmann, Steffen (Eds.) (2020). Political Phenomenology: Experience, Ontology, Episteme. London, New York: Routledge. Ben-Ze’ev, Aaron (2000). The Subtlety of Emotions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Berger, Peter L. (1997). Redeeming Laughter. The Comic Dimension of Human Experience. New York, Berlin: De Gruyter. Bernasconi, Robert (2010). Fanon’s The Wretched of the Earth as the Fulfillment of Sartre’s “Critique of Dialectical Reason”. Sartre Studies International 16(2), 36–47. ——— (2020). Dialectical Praxis and the Decolonial Struggle: Sartre and Fanon’s Contributions to Political Phenomenology. In: T. Bedorf, and S. Herrmann (Eds.). Political Phenomenology: Experience, Ontology, Episteme. London, New York: Routledge. Berninger, Anja (2017). Gefühle und Gedanken: Entwurf einer adverbialen Emotionstheorie. Paderborn: mentis. Binswanger, Ludwig (1922). Einführung in die Probleme der Allgemeinen Psychologie. Berlin: Julius Springer. Blackburn, Simon (2001). Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
28
Introduction Bollnow, Otto Friedrich (1956). Das Wesen der Stimmungen. Frankfurt a.M.: Klostermann. [Translated excerpts in: Bollnow, Otto Friedrich (2017). The Nature of Stimmungen. Philosophia 45(4), 1399–1418.] Bortolan, Anna, and Salice, Alessandro (2018). Philosophical Perspectives on Affective Experience and Psychopathology. Special Issue of Discipline Filosofiche 2. Brady, Michael S. (2013). Emotional Insight. The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brewer, Talbot (2011). On Alienated Emotions. In: C. Bagnoli (Ed.). Morality and the Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 276–299. Brudholm, Thomas (2008). Resentment’s Virtue: Jean Améry and the Refusal to Forgive. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Brudholm, Thomas, and Johansen Schepelern, Birgitte (Eds.) (2018). Hate, Politics, Law: Critical Perspectives on Combating Hate. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Candiotto, Laura (Ed.) (2019). The Value of Emotions for Knowledge. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan. Carroll, Noël (1990). The Philosophy of Horror. Or, Paradoxes of the Heart. New York, London: Routledge. Cataldi, Suzanne L. (1993). Emotion, Depth, and Flesh. A Study of Sensitive Space. Albany: State University of New York Press. Cohen, Hermann (1912). Ästhetik des reinen Gefühls. Berlin: Bruno Cassirer. Cohen, Alix, and Stern, Robert (Eds.) (2017). Thinking about the Emotions: A Philosophical History. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Colombetti, Giovanna (2014). The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Damasio, Antonio (2003). Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain. New York: Harcourt. D’Arms, Justin (2005). Two Arguments for Sentimentalism. Philosophical Issues 15, 1–21. D’Arms, Justin, and Jacobson, Daniel (2000). The Moralistic Fallacy: On the “Appropriateness” of Emotions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51(1), 65–90. Darwin, Charles (2009[1872]). The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. London: Penguin. Davidson, Donald (1982). Paradoxes of Irrationality. In R. Wollheim, and J. Hopkins (Eds.). Philosophical Essays on Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 289–305. De Jaegher, Hanne (2015). How We Affect Each Other: Michel Henry’s “pathos-with” and the Enactive Approach to Intersubjectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies 22(1–2), 112–132. De Monticelli, Roberta (2000). La connaissance personnelle. Paris: Aubier Flammarion. De Sousa, Ronald (1987). The Rationality of Emotions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ——— (2011). Emotional Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press. de Warren, Nicolas, and Vongehr, Thomas (Eds.) (2018). Philosophers at the Front: Phenomenology and the First World War. Leuven: Leuven University Press. Deigh, John (1994). Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions. Ethics 104(4), 824–854. Deonna, Julien A., and Teroni, Fabrice (2012). The Emotions. A Philosophical Introduction. London, New York: Routledge. Dewalque, Arnauld (2017). Emotional Phenomenology: Toward a Nonreductive Analysis. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 41, 27–40. Döring, Sabine A. (Ed.). (2009). Philosophie der Emotionen. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Döring, Sabine A., and Lutz, Anika (2015). Beyond Perceptualism: Introduction to the Special Issue. Dialectica 69(3), 259–270. Drummond, John J. (2004). ‘Cognitive Impenetrability’ and the Complex Intentionality of the Emotions. Journal of Consciousness Studies 11(10–11), 109–126. ——— (2018). Emotion, Value, and Action. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy XVI, 3–25. Drummond, John, and Rinofner-Kreidl, Sonja (Eds.) (2018). Emotional Experiences: Ethical and Social Significance. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. Ekman, Paul (1992). An Argument for Basic Emotions. Cognition and Emotion 6(3/4), 169–200. Elpidorou, Andreas (Ed.) (2000). Neglected Emotions. Special Issue of The Monist 103(2). Elpidorou, Andreas, and Freeman, Lauren (Eds.) (2014). The Phenomenology and Science of Emotions. Special Issue of Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13(4). Elster, Jon (1999). Alchemies of the Mind: Rationality and the Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
29
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer Engelsen, Søren (2018). Feeling Value: A Systematic Phenomenological Account of the Original Mode of Presentation of Value. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy XVI, 232–247. Fielding, Helen A., and Olkowski, Dorothea E. (Eds.) (2017). Feminist Phenomenology Futures. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. French, Peter A., Wettstein, Howard K., and Wrathall, Mark A. (Eds.) (2017). Phenomenology of Affective Life. Midwest Studies in Phenomenology 41. Fuchs, Thomas (2005). Corporealized and Disembodied Minds. A Phenomenological View of the Body in Melancholia and Schizophrenia. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology 12(2), 95–107. ———— (2013). The Phenomenology of Affectivity. In: G. Stanghellini et al. (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 612–631. Furtak, Rick Anthony (2018). Knowing Emotions. Truthfulness and Recognition in Affective Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gallagher, Shaun (2006). How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gendler, Tamar Szabó, and Kovakovich, Karson (2006). Genuine Rational Fictional Emotions. In: M. Kieran (Ed.). Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art. Oxford: Blackwell, 241–253. Gibbard, Allan (1990). Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Gilbert, Margaret (2002). Collective Guilt and Collective Guilt Feelings. The Journal of Ethics, 6(2), 115–143. ——— (2014). How We Feel: Understanding Everyday Collective Emotion Ascription. In: C. v. Scheve and M. Salmela (Eds.). Collective Emotions. Perspectives from Psychology, Philosophy, and Sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 17–31. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2002). Emotions, Feelings and Intentionality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1(3), 235–254. ——— (2012). The Mess Inside: Narrative, Emotion, and the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gordon, Robert M. (1990). The Structure of Emotions: Investigations in Cognitive Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Greco, Monica, and Stenner, Paul (Eds.) (2008). Emotions. A Social Science Reader. London, New York: Routledge. Greenspan, Patricia (1988). Emotions and Reasons: An Enquiry Into Emotional Justification. London, New York: Routledge. Gregg, Melissa, and Seigworth, Gregory J. (Eds.) (2010). The Affect Theory Reader. Durham: Duke University Press. Griffiths, Paul E., and Scarantino, Andrea (2009). Emotions in the Wild: The Situated Perspective on Emotion. In: P. Robbins, and M. Aydede (Eds.). The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 437–453. Gubser, Michael (2014). The Far Reaches. Phenomenology, Ethics and Social Renewal in Central Europe. Stanford: Stanford University Press. ——— (2019). Phenomenology contra Nazism: Dietrich von Hildebrand and Aurel Kolnai. Miscellanea Anthropologica et Sociologica 20(1), 115–132. Gunther, York H. (2004). The Phenomenology and Intentionality of Emotion. Philosophical Studies 117(1), 43–55. Gyemant, Maria (2018). Is Feeling Something Knowing Something? On the Intentionality of Feelings in Husserl’s Early Writings (1894–1913). The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy XVI, 87–107. Haas, Willy (1910). Über Echtheit und Unechtheit von Gefühlen. Nürnberg: Benedikt Hilz. Reprinted (1914) in: Zeitschrift für Pathopsychologie 2, 349–381. Hadjioannou, Christos (Ed.) (2019). Heidegger on Affect. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. Harding, Jennifer, and Pribram, Deidre E. (Eds.) (2009). Emotions. A Cultural Studies Reader. London, New York: Routledge. Hartmann, Nicolai (1932[1926]). Ethics. Transl. by S. Coit. London: George Allen & Unwin. [Orig.: Ethik. Berlin: de Gruyter.] Hatzimoysis, Anthony (2007). The Case against Unconscious Emotions. Analysis 67(4), 292–299.
30
Introduction Hegel, Georg Wilhem Friedrich (2007[1830]). Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences III: Philosophy of Mind. Rev. Transl. by M. Inwood. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Orig.: Enzyklopeädie der Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse 1830. Dritter Teil Die Philosophie des Geistes. Mit den muündlichen Zusätzen. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: Werke 10. Frankfurt: Suhkamp.] Heidegger, Martin (1927). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell. [Orig.: Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Niemeyer 1967.] ——— (2002[1938]). The Age of the World-Picture. In: M. Heidegger: Off the Beaten Track. Transl. by J. Young and K. Haynes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 57–85. [Orig.: Die Zeit des Weltbildes. In: Martin Heidegger Gesamtausgabe, Vol. 5: Holzwege (1935–1946). Frankfurt: Klostermann 2003.] Heinämaa, Sara (2003). Toward a Phenomenology of Sexual Difference: Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, Beauvoir. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield. Heiner, Brady T. (Ed.) (2008). Affectivity and Intersubjectivity: Perspectives from Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Special Issue of Continental Philosophy Review 41(2). Heller, Agnes (2009[1979]). A Theory of Feelings. Transl. by M. D. Fenyö. Lanham: Lexington. Helm, Bennett W. (2001). Emotional Reason. Deliberation, Motivation, and the Nature of Value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2017). Communities of Respect: Grounding Responsibility, Authority, and Dignity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Henry, Michel (1973[1963]). The Essence of Manifestation. Transl. by G. Etzkorn. The Hague: Nijhoff. [Orig.: L’Essence de la manifestation. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.] ——— (1975[1965]). Philosophy and Phenomenology of the Body. Transl. by G. Etzkorn. The Hague: Nijhoff. [Orig.: Philosophie et phénoménologie du corps. Essai sur l’ontologie biranienne. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.] ——— (2003). Phénoménologie de la vie: Tome I: De la phénoménologie. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Hochschild, Arlie (1979). Emotion Work, Feeling Rules, and Social Structure. American Journal of Sociology 85(3), 551–575. ——— (1983). The Managed Heart. Commercialization of Human Feeling. Berkley: University of California Press. Holmes, Oliver (2017). José Ortega y Gasset. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/gasset/. Husserl, Edmund (2001[1900]). Prolegomena to Pure Logic. Logical Investigations, Volume 1. Transl. by J. N. Findlay. London, New York: Routledge. [Orig.: Logische Untersuchungen. Erster Band: Prolegomena zur reinen Logik. Ed. by E. Holenstein (=Husserliana XVIII). The Haag: Nijhoff 1975]. ——— (2013[1908–1937]). Grenzproblem der Phänomenologie. Analysen des Unbewusstseins und der Instinkte. Metaphysik. Späte Ethik. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1908–1937). Ed. by R. Sowa and T. Vongehr (=Husserliana XLII). Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (2001[1918–1926]). Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis. Lectures on Transcendental Logic. Transl. by A. Steinbock. Dordrecht: Kluwer. [Orig.: Analysen zur passive Synthesis. Aus Vorlesungs- und Forschungsmanuskripten 1918–1926. Ed. by M. Fleischer (=Husserliana XI). The Haag: Nijhoff 1966.] ——— (1973[1929–1935]). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil: 1929–1935. Ed. by I. Kern (=Husserliana XV). Den Haag: Nijhoff. ——— (1975[1938]). Experience and Judgment. Investigations in a Genealogy of Logic. Transl. by J. Spencer Churchill and K. Ameriks. Evanston: Northwestern University Press 1975. [Orig.: Erfahrung und Urteil. Ed. by L. Landgrebe. Hamburg: Meiner 1999.] Illouz, Eva (2007). Cold Intimacies. The Making of Emotional Capitalism. Cambridge: Polity. James, William, and Lange, Carl Georg (1922[1885–1893]). The Emotions. Ed. by K. Dunlap. Baltimore: Williams & Wilkins. Johnston, Mark (2001). The Authority of Affect. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63(1), 181–214. Jones, Karen (1996). Trust as an Affective Attitude. Ethics 107(1), 4–25. Kananow, Paul (1910). Über das Gefühl der Tätigkeit. Philosophical Dissertation: München. Kelly, Eugene (2011). Material Ethics of Value: Max Scheler and Nicolai Hartmann. Dordrecht: Springer. Kenny, Anthony K. (1963). Action, Emotion and Will. London: Routledge and Keagan Paul. Kosofsky Sedgwick, Eve (2003). Touching Feeling: Affect, Pedagogy, Performativity. Durham, NC, L ondon: Duke University Press.
31
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer Krebs, Angelika (2015). Zwischen Ich und Du: Eine dialogische Philosophie der Liebe. Berlin: Suhrkamp. ——— (2017). Stimmung: From Mood to Atmosphere. Philosophia 45(4), 1419–1436. Krebs, Angelika, and Ben-Ze’ev, Aaron (Eds.) (2017). The Meaning of Moods. Special Issue of Philosophia 45(4). Kriegel, Uriah (2014). Towards a New Feeling Theory of Emotion. European Journal of Philosophy 22(3), 420–442. Kristjánsson, Kristján (2010). The Trouble with Ambivalent Emotions. Philosophy 85(4), 485–510. Krueger, Joel (2016). The Affective “We”: Self-regulation and Shared Emotions. In: T. Szanto, and D. Moran (Eds.). Phenomenology of Sociality: Discovering the We. New York, London: Routledge, 263–277. Krueger, Joel, and Colombetti, Giovanna (2018). Affective Affordances and Psychopathology. Discipline Filosofiche 28(2), 221–246. Krueger, Joel, and Szanto, Thomas (2016). Extended Emotions. Philosophy Compass 11(12), 863–878. Landweer, Hilge (2007). Normativität, Moral und Gefühle. In: H. Landweer (Ed.). Gefühle – Struktur und Funktion. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 237–254. ——— (2011). Affektive Intentionalität oder zentrierte Affektivität? Die Atmosphärentheorie der Gefühle. In: J. Slaby, A. Stephan, H. Walter, and S. Walter (Eds.). Affektive Intentionalität. Zur welterschließenden Funktion der Gefühle. Paderborn: Mentis, 230–251. ——— (2013). The Sense of Appropriateness as an Emotional Capability. In: T. Staehler (Ed.). Existentialism. Vol. II: Basic Themes and Concepts. London, New York: Routledge, 301–312. ——— (2019). The Spatial Character of Atmospheres. Studi di Estetica XLVII, IV Serie, 2 Sensibilia, 153–168. Landweer, Hilge, and Bernhardt, Fabian (Eds.) (2017). Recht und Emotion II. Sphären der Verletzlichkeit. Freiburg, München: Alber. Landweer, Hilge, and Koppelberg, Dirk (Eds.) (2016). Recht und Emotion I. Verkannte Zusammenhänge. Freiburg, München: Alber. Landweer, Hilge, and Marcinski, Isabella (Eds.) (2016). Dem Erleben auf der Spur: Feminismus und die Philosophie des Leibes. Bielefeld: transcript. Landweer, Hilge, and Renz, Ursula (Eds.) (2012). Handbuch Klassische Emotionstheorien. Von Platon bis Wittgenstein. Berlin, New York: de Gruyter. León, Felipe, Szanto, Thomas, and Zahavi, Dan (2019). Emotional Sharing and the Extended Mind. Synthese 196(12), 4847–4867. Lipps, Theodor (1889). Bemerkungen zur Theorie der Gefühle. Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie 13, 160–194. ——— (1902). Vom Fühlen, Wollen und Denken. Eine psychologische Skizze. Leipzig: Ambrosius Barth. Löwenstein-Freudenberg, Karl Konstantin (1913). Über das Gefallen. Inaugural Dissertation. Print: H. Freise. Lyons, William (1980). Emotion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Maiese, Michelle (2011). Embodiment, Emotion, and Cognition. London: Palgrave Macmillan. Marks, Joel (1982). A Theory of Emotion. Philosophical Studies 42(2), 227–242. McDowell, John (1998). Mind, Value, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (2014[1945]). Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by D. Landes. London, New York: Routledge. [Orig.: Phénoménologie de la perception. Paris: Gallimard.] Mertens, Karl, and Müller, Jörn (Eds.) (2014). Die Dimension des Sozialen: Neue Philosophische Zugänge zu Fühlen, Wollen und Handeln. Berlin, New York: de Gruyter. Mihai, Mihaela (2016). Negative Emotions and Transitional Justice. New York: Columbia University Press. Mishra, Pankaj (2017). The Age of Anger. A History of the Present. London: Penguin. Mohrmann, Judith (2015). Affekt und Revolution: Politisches Handeln nach Arendt und Kant. Frankfurt: Campus. Müller, Jean Moritz (2019). The World-Directedness of Emotional Feeling: On Affect and Intentionality. London: Palgrave MacMillan. Mulligan, Kevin (1998). From Appropriate Emotions to Values. The Monist 81(1), 161–188. ——— (2008). Max Scheler. Die Anatomie des Herzens, oder was man alles fühlen kann. In: H. Landweer and U. Renz (Eds.). Klassische Emotionstheorien von Platon bis Wittgenstein. Berlin: de Gruyter, 589–612. ——— (2010a). Emotions and Values. In: P. Goldie (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 475–500.
32
Introduction ——— (2010b). Husserls Herz. In: M. Frank and N. Weidtmann (Eds.). Husserl und die Philosophie des Geistes. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp, 209–238. ——— (2017). Thrills, Orgasms, Sadness, and Hysteria. In: A. Cohen and R. Stern (Eds.). Thinking about the Emotions: A Philosophical History. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 223–252. Murphy, Jeffrie G. (2012). Punishment and the Moral Emotions. Essays in Law, Morality, and Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Murphy, Jeffrie G., and Hampton, Jean (1988). Forgiveness and Mercy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Neu, Jerome (1977). Emotions, Thought, and Therapy: A Study of Hume and Spinoza and the Relationship of Philosophical Theories of the Emotions to Psychological Theories of Therapy. Berkeley: University of California Press. Nörenberg, Henning (forthcoming). Moments of Recognition: Deontic Power and Bodily Felt Demands. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-019-09622-9. Nussbaum, Martha C. (1990). Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2001). Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2013). Political Emotions: Why Love Matters for Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Oakley, Justin (1992). Morality and the Emotions. London, New York: Routledge. Oatley, Keith (2004). Emotions: A Brief History. Malden, MA: Blackwell. Oksala, Johanna (2016). Feminist Experiences: Foucauldian and Phenomenological Investigations. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Ortega, Mariana (2016). In-Between: Latina Feminist Phenomenology, Multiplicity, and the Self. Albany: State University of New York Press. Ortega y Gasset, José (1957[1941]). On Love: Aspects of a Single Theme. Transl. by T. Talbot. Cleveland: The World Publishing Company. [Orig.: Estudios sobre el amor. In: Ortega y Gasset: Obras Completas V (1939–1941). Madrid: Revista de Occidente 1947.] Parker, Rodney K. B., and Quepons, Ignacio (2018). Phenomenology of Emotions, Systematical and Historical Perspectives. Issue of The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy XVI. Perler, Dominik (2011/2018). Feelings Transformed. Philosophical Theories of the Emotions, 1270–1670. Transl. by T. Crawford. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pintor Ramos, Antonio (1994). Schelers Einfluß auf das Denken der spanischsprachigen Welt. Phänomenologische Forschungen 28/29, 314–331. Plamper, Jan (2015[2012]). The History of Emotions: An Introduction. Transl. by K. Tribe. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Plessner, Helmuth (1999[1924]). The Limits of Community. A Critique of Social Radicalism. Transl. by A. Wallace. New York: Humanity Book. [Orig.: Grenzen der Gemeinschaft. Eine Kritik des sozialen Radikalismus. In: Helmuth Plessner Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. V: Macht und menschliche Natur. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp 2003.] ——— (1974[1935]). Die verspätete Nation. Über die Verführbarkeit des bürgerlichen Geistes. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. ——— (1970[1941/1961]). Laughing and Crying. A Study of the Limits of Human Behavior. Transl. by J. Spencer Churchill, and M. Grene. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Orig.: Lachen und Weinen. Eine Untersuchung der Grenzen menschlichen Verhaltens (1941). In: Helmuth Plessner Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. VII: Ausdruck und menschliche Natur. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp 2003.] ——— (2003[1950]). Über das Lächeln. In: Helmuth Plessner Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. VII: Ausdruck und menschliche Natur. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Poellner, Peter (2012). Value. In: S. Luft and S. Overgaard (Eds.). The Routledge Companion to Phenomenology. London, New York: Routledge, 297–306. ——— (2016). Phenomenology and the Perceptual Model of Emotion. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society CXVI(3), 261–288. Poli, Roberto (2017). Nicolai Hartmann. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/nicolai-hartmann/. Prinz, Jesse (2004). Gut Reactions. A Perceptual Theory of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press ——— (2007). The Emotional Construction of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Prütting, Lenz (2013/2016). Homo Ridens: Eine phänomenologische Studie über Wesen, Formen und Funktionen des Lachens. München: Alber. Pugmire, David (1998). Rediscovering Emotion. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
33
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer ——— (2005). Sound Sentiments. Integrity in the Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Quepons Ramírez, Ignacio (2015). Intentionality of Moods and Horizon Consciousness in Husserl’s Phenomenology. In: M. Ubiali and M. Wehrle (Eds.). Feeling and Value, Willing and Action. Dordrecht: Springer, 93–103. Ratcliffe, Matthew (2014). Experiences of Depression: A Study in Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2017). Real Hallucinations: Psychiatric Illness, Intentionality, and the Interpersonal World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ——— (2019). Emotional Intentionality. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 85, 251–269. Reddy, William M. (2001). The Navigation of Feeling: A Framework for the History of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reiner, Hans (1932). Der Grund der sittlichen Bindung und das sittliche Gute. Halle: Niemeyer. ——— (1959). Der Ursprung der Sittlichkeit dargestellt auf Grund der phänomenologischen Methode. Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 13(2) (Erweitertes Heft zum 100. Geburtstag von Edmund Husserl), 263–287. Ricœur, Paul (1986[1960]). Fallible Man. Rev. transl. by C. A. Kelbley. New York: Fordham University Press. [Orig.: L’Homme faillible. In: P. Ricœur: Philosophie de la Volonté II: Finitude et Culpabilité. Paris: Aubier.] Rinofner-Kreidl, Sonja (2013). Husserls Fundierungsmodell als Grundlage einer intentionalen Wertungsanalyse. Metodo 1(2), 59–82. Roberts, Robert C. (2003). Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Roeser, Sabine, and Todd, Cain (Eds.) (2014). Emotion and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rorty Oksenberg, Amélie (Ed.) (1980). Explaining Emotions. Berkley: University of California Press. Rutkevič, Aleksej M. (2014). The Ideas of 1914. Studies in East European Thought 66(1–2), 1–15. Ryle, Gilbert (2000[1949]). The Concept of Mind. London: Penguin. Saarinen, Jussi A. (2014). The Oceanic Feeling: A Case Study in Existential Feeling. Journal of Consciousness Studies 21(5–6), 196–217. ——— (2018). A Critical Examination of Existential Feeling. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17(2), 363–374. Salamon, Gayle, Weiss, Gail, and Murphy, Ann V. (Eds.) (2019). 50 Concepts for a Critical Phenomenology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. Salice, Alessandro (2016). The Phenomenology of the Munich and Göttingen Circles. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/ phenomenology-mg/. Salice, Alessandro, and Schmid, Hans Bernhard (Eds.) (2016). Social Reality. The Phenomenological Approach. Dordrecht: Springer. Salmela, Mikko (2005). What is Emotional Authenticity? Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 35(3), 209–230. ——— (2006). True Emotions. The Philosophical Quarterly 56(224), 382–405. Salmela, Mikko, and Mayer, Verena (Eds.) (2009). Emotions, Ethics, and Authenticity. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Sánchez Guerrero, Héctor A. (2016). Feeling Together and Caring with One Another: A Contribution to the Debate on Collective Affective Intentionality. Cham: Springer. Sander, David, and Scherer, Klaus (Eds.) (2014). Oxford Companion to Emotion and the Affective Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1994[1939]). Sketch for a Theory of Emotions. Transl. by P. Mairet. London, New York: Routledge. [Orig.: Esquisse d’une théorie des émotions. Paris: Hermann.] Scanlon, Thomas M. (1998). What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Scheler, Max (1982[1915]). Der Genius des Krieges und der Deutsche Krieg. In: Max Scheler: Politisch-Pädagogische Schriften. Gesammelte Werke, Vol. IV, ed. by M. S. Frings. Bern, Bonn: Franke/ Bouvier, 7–250. ——— (1982[1916]). Der Krieg als Gesamterlebnis. In: Max Scheler: Politisch-Pädagogische Schriften. Gesammelte Werke, Vol. IV, ed. by M. S. Frings. Bern, Bonn: Franke/Bouvier, 268–282. Schmid, Hans Bernhard (2009). Plural Action: Essays in Philosophy and Social Science. Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (2015). Collective Emotions: Phenomenology, Ontology, and Ideology. What Should We Learn from Max Scheler’s War Propaganda? Thaumàzein 3, 103–119.
34
Introduction Schmitz, Hermann (1964–1980). System der Philosophie. 5 Bände in 10 Teilbänden. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1981[1969]). System der Philosophie Vol. III. 2.: Der Gefühlsraum. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1999). Der Gefühlsraum unter anderen Raumstrukturen. Geographische Zeitschrift 87(2), 105–115. ——— (2019[2009]). New Phenomenology – A Brief Introduction. Mimesis International. [Orig.: Kurze Einführung in die Neue Phänomenologie. München, Freiburg: Alber.] ——— (2014). Atmosphären. Freiburg, München: Alber. Schmitz, Hermann, Owen Müllan, Rudolf, and Slaby, Jan (2011). Emotions Outside the Box: The New Phenomenology of Feeling and Corporeality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10(2), 241–259. Searle, John R. (1992). The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Sheets-Johnstone, Maxine (1999). Emotion and Movement. A Beginning Empirical-Phenomenological Analysis of their Relationship. Journal of Consciousness Studies 6(11/12), 259–277. Slaby, Jan (2008a). Gefühl und Weltbezug: Die menschliche Affektivität im Kontext einer neo-existentialistischen Konzeption von Personalität. Paderborn: mentis. ——— (2008b). Affective Intentionality and the Feeling Body. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7(4), 429–444. ——— (2020). The Weight of History: From Heidegger to Afro-Pessimism. In: L. Guidi, and T. Rentsch (Eds.). Phenomenology as Performative Exercise. Leiden: Brill. Slaby, Jan, Stephan, Achim, Walter, Henrik, and Walter, Sven (Eds.) (2011). Affektive Intentionalität. Beiträge zur welterschließenden Funktion der menschlichen Gefühle. Paderborn: mentis. Slaby, Jan, and von Scheve, Christian (2019). Affective Societies: Key Concepts. London, New York: Routledge. Solomon, Robert C. (1976). The Passions. Garden City, NY: Doubleday. ——— (1995). A Passion for Justice: Emotions and the Origins of the Social Contract. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. ——— (2002). Emotions, Cognition, Affect: On Jerry Neu’s “A Tear is an Intellectual Thing”. Philosophical Studies 108(1–2), 133–142. ——— (2007). True to Our Feelings: What Our Emotions Are Really Telling Us. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (Ed.) (1984). What is an Emotion? Classic and Contemporary Readings. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Spiegelberg, Herbert (1994). The Phenomenological Movement. A Historical Introduction. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Spiegelberg, Herbert, and Avé-Lallemant, Eberhard (Eds.) (1982). Pfänder-Studien. Dordrecht: Nijhoff. Stanghellini, Giovanni, Broome, Matthew, Fernandez, Anthony Vincent, Fusar-Poli, Paolo, Raballo, Andrea, and Rosfort, René (2019). The Oxford Handbook of Phenomenological Psychopathology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stein, Edith (1989[1917]). On the Problem of Empathy. Transl. by W. Stein. Washington, D.C.: ICS Publication. [Orig.: Zum Problem der Einfühlung. Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe, Vol. 5. Freiburg, Basel, Wien: Herder 2008.] ——— (2000[1922]). Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities. Transl. by M. C. Baseheart and M. Sawicki. Washington D.C.: ICS Publications. [Orig.: Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie und der Geisteswissenschaften. Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe, Vol. 6. Freiburg, Basel, Wien: Herder 2010.] ——— (1986[1985]). Life in a Jewish Family 1891–1916. An Autobiography. Transl. by J. Koeppel. Washington D.C.: ICS Publications. [Orig.: Aus dem Leben einer jüdischen Familie und weitere autobiographische Beiträge. Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe, Vol. 1. Freiburg: Herder 2002.] Steinbock, Anthony (2014). Moral Emotions: Reclaiming the Evidence of the Heart. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Stets, Jan E., and Turner, Jonathan E. (Eds.) (2006). The Handbook of the Sociology of Emotions. New York: Springer. ——— (Eds.) (2011). The Handbook of the Sociology of Emotions II. New York: Springer. Stocker, Michael (1983). Psychic Feelings: Their Importance and Irreducibility. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61(1), 5–26. Strasser, Stephan (1977[1956]). Phenomenology of Feeling: An Essay on the Phenomena of the Heart. With a foreword by P. Ricœur. Transl. by R. E. Wood. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
35
Thomas Szanto and Hilge Landweer [Orig.: Das Gemüt. Grundgedanken zu einer phänomenologischen Philosophie und Theorie des menschlichen Gefühlslebens. Utrecht, Freiburg: Herder.] Streubel, Thorsten (2015). Phänomenologie des Mitleids. Analyse eines moralischen Gefühls im Anschluss an Husserl und Schopenhauer. In: M. Ubiali and M. Wehrle (Eds.). Feeling and Value, Willing and Action. Dordrecht: Springer, 207–227. Stumpf, Carl (1928). Gefühl und Gefühlsempfindung. Leipzig: Ambrosius Barth. Summa, Michela, and Fuchs, Thomas (2015). Self-experience in Dementia. Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 6(2), 387–405. Švec, Ondrej (2013). La phénoménologie de l’émotions. Lille: Presses Universitaires du Septentrion. Szanto, Thomas (2012). Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes. Berlin, New York: de Gruyter. ——— (2015). Collective Emotions, Normativity and Empathy: A Steinian Account. Human Studies 38(4), 503–527. ——— (2017). Emotional Self-Alienation. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 41, 260–286. ——— (2018). The Phenomenology of Shared Emotions: Reassessing Gerda Walther. In: S. Luft and R. Hagengruber (Eds.). Women Phenomenologists on Social Ontology. Dordrecht: Springer, 85–104. ——— (2020). Phenomenology and Social Theory. In: P. Kivisto (Ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Szanto, Thomas, and Moran, Dermot (2020). Edith Stein. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Szanto, Thomas, and Krueger, Joel (Eds.) (2019). Empathy, Shared Emotions, and Social Identity. Special Issue of Topoi 38(1). Szanto, Thomas, and Moran, Dermot (Eds.) (2015). Empathy and Collective Intentionality: The Social Philosophy of Edith Stein. Special Issue of Human Studies 38(4). Szanto, Thomas, and Moran, Dermot (Eds.) (2016). The Phenomenology of Sociality. Discovering the ‘We’. London, New York: Routledge. Tappolet, Christine (2016). Emotions, Values, and Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Tengelyi, László (2009). Self hood, Passivity and Affectivity in Henry and Levinas. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17(3), 401–414. Theodorou, Panos (2018). Scheler’s Phenomenology of Emotive Life in the Context of his Ethical Program: Achievements and Abeyances. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 16, 139–175. Tomkins, Silvan S. (1962/1963). Affect, Imagery, Consciousness. 2 Vols. New York: Springer. Ubiali, Marta, and Wehrle, Maren (Eds.) (2015). Feeling and Value, Willing and Action. Dordrecht: Springer. Varga, Somogy (2019). Scaffolded Minds: Integration and Disintegration. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (2008a). Die Emotionen. Gefühle in der realistischen Phänomenologie. Berlin: Akademie. ——— (2008b). Emotionen und Sozialität in der frühen Phänomenologie. Über die Möglichkeiten von Frauen in der ersten Phase wissenschaftlicher Schulenbildung. Feministische Studien 26(1), 48–64. ——— (2015). The Emotions in Early Phenomenology. Studia Phaenomenologica 15, 349–374. ——— (2018). Phenomenological Approaches to Hatred: Scheler, Pfänder, and Kolnai. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 16, 158–179. ——— (forthcoming). Emotions in the 19th and 20th Century Phenomenological Tradition. In: A. Scarantino (Ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Emotion Theory. London, New York: Routledge. Virág, Curie (2017). The Emotions in Early Chinese Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Voigtländer, Else (1920). Zur Psychologie der politischen Stellungnahme. Eine massenpsychologische Studie. Deutsche Psychologie 3(3), 184–206. von Scheve, Christian, and Salmela, Mikko (Eds.) (2014). Collective Emotions. Perspectives from Psychology, Philosophy, and Sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Vongehr, Thomas (2011). Husserls Studien zu Gemüt und Wille. In: V. Mayer, C. Erhard, and M. Scherini (Eds.). Die Aktualität Edmund Husserls. Freiburg: Alber, 335–360. Waldenfels, Bernhard (2011[2006]). Phenomenology of the Alien: Basic Concepts. Transl. by A. Kozin and T. Stähler. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Orig.: Grundmotive einer Phänomenologie des Fremden. Berlin: Suhrkamp.] Walton, Kendall L. (1991). Mimesis as Make-believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
36
Introduction Walton, Roberto, Shigeru Taguchi, and Rubio, Roberto (Eds.) (2017). Perception, Affectivity, and Volition in Husserl’s Phenomenology. Dordrecht: Springer. Wehrle, Maren (2015). “Feelings as the Motor of Perception”? The Essential Role of Interest for Intentionality. Husserl Studies 31(1), 45–64. ——— (2020). Doing Gender Differently? The Embodiment of Gender Norms in between Permanence and Transformation. In: T. Bedorf and H. Steffen (Eds.). Political Phenomenology: Experience, Ontology, Episteme. London, New York: Routledge. Welpinghus, Anna (2018). Is the Appropriateness of Emotions Culture-Dependent? The Relevance of Social Meaning. Journal of Social Ontology 4(1), 67–92. Wetherell, Margaret (2012). Affect and Emotion: A New Social Science Understanding. London: Sage. Wollheim, Richard (1999). On the Emotions. New Haven: Yale University Press. Zaborowski, Robert (2018). Is Affectivity Passive or Active? Philosophia 46(3), 541–554. ——— (forthcoming). Revisiting Mixed Feelings. Axiomathes, 1–26. doi:10.1007/s10516-019-09447-w. Zahavi, Dan (2015). You, Me and We: The Sharing of Emotional Experiences. Journal of Consciousness Studies 22(1–2), 84–101. Further reading Ben-Ze’ev, Aaron, and Krebs, Angelika (Eds.) (2019). Philosophy of Emotion. 4 vols. London and New York: Routledge. De Monticelli, Roberta (1998). L’ascèse philosophique. Phénoménologie et Platonisme. Paris: Vrin 1998 Deigh, John (Ed.) (2008). On Emotions. Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Goldie, Peter (Ed.) (2010). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Griffiths, Paul E. (2013). Current Emotion Research in Philosophy. Emotion Review 5(2), 215–222. Hart, James G., and Embree, Lester (Eds.). Phenomenology of Value and Valuing. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Hatzimoysis, Anthony (Ed.) (2003). Philosophy and the Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mickunas, Algis (1997). Emotion. In: L. Embree (Ed.). Encyclopedia of Phenomenology. Dordrecht: Springer, 171–176. Mulligan, Kevin, and Scherer, Klaus R. (2012). Toward a Working Definition of Emotion. Emotion Review 4(4), 345–357. Osler, Lucy (forthcoming). Feeling Togetherness Online: A Phenomenological Sketch of Online Communal Experiences. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-019-09627-4. Scarantino, Andrea (Ed.) (forthcoming). The Routledge Handbook of Emotion Theory. London, New York: Routledge. Solomon, Robert C. (Ed.) (2004). Thinking about Feeling. Contemporary Philosophers of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
37
.
(
Taylor & Francis Taylor & Francis Group
http://taylorandfrancis.com
PART 1
Historical perspectives
.
(
Taylor & Francis Taylor & Francis Group
http://taylorandfrancis.com
1 FRANZ BRENTANO Michelle Montague
1. Introduction In this chapter, I consider Franz Brentano’s theory of emotion. I focus on three of its central claims: (1) Emotions are sui generis intentional phenomena, (2) emotions are essentially evaluative phenomena, and (3) emotions provide the basis of an epistemology of objective value. (2) is intimately connected to (1) and (3) in that the evaluative nature of emotions not only accounts for their sui generis status but also provides the basis for Brentano’s epistemology of value. In what follows, I will be concerned with only conscious emotion, putting aside attributions of emotional states or conditions that may be true even if the person is, say, in a dreamless sleep. Brentano himself explicitly rejects the existence of unconscious mental states, and therefore takes it that to give a theory of mind is to give a theory of consciousness. In order to understand Brentano’s theory of emotion, one needs to know how it relates to his overall theory of mind, particularly to his claims about the intentional nature of mental phenomena, the self-intimating nature of consciousness, and the fundamental classification of mental phenomena. A full treatment of these topics is not possible here, but I hope to say enough to show how each relates to his theory of emotion.
2. Two senses of ‘phenomenology’ Most contemporary theories of emotion accept the idea that emotions ‘have a phenomenology’. Phenomenology understood in this way can be characterized in a familiar way as the phenomenon of there being ‘something it is like’, experientially, to be in a mental state, something it is like for the creature who is in the mental state. It is a matter of a state’s having an experiential character. Consider tasting warm cornbread, or feeling sleepy, or faintly uneasy, or finding something funny. This contemporary use of ‘phenomenology’ should be distinguished from ‘phenomenology’ understood as a method of theorizing about consciousness which studies it specifically from the first-person perspective, the perspective of the experiencing subject. Husserl (1900, 1901), Sartre (1943), Heidegger (1927), Merleau-Ponty (1945), and de Beauvoir (1949) are most commonly associated with phenomenology in this sense, but Brentano is arguably 41
Michelle Montague
its founder. In his later work, he explicitly calls his method ‘descriptive psychology’ and distinguishes it from ‘genetic psychology’ (1995[1887], 4). The aim of descriptive psychology, he says, is nothing other than to provide us with a general conception of the entire realm of human consciousness. It does this by listing fully the basic components out of which everything internally perceived by humans is composed, and by enumerating the ways in which these components can be connected. (1995[1887], 4) In contrast, genetic psychology is concerned with contingent causal laws, laws governing how mental phenomena arise and the connections between the mental and the physiological. Brentano conceived of (descriptive) psychology as a ‘Cartesian science’ in the sense that it had an epistemologically certain foundation.1 With Descartes (1641), Brentano argued that we can know truths about our mentality with certainty. His conception of psychology was at the same time fully empirical, not because it was based on experimentation that could be repeated and observed from the third-person standpoint, but because its truths were based on experience itself. Descriptive psychology, in short, was a first-person empirical science that provided necessary truths about our mental lives. Given this methodological approach to psychology, the connection between the two senses of ‘phenomenology’ is not hard to see: Phenomenology qua phenomenological method studies phenomenology qua the what it’s likeness or experiential character of conscious experience.
3. Demarcating the field of psychology One of Brentano’s main goals in Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint was to demarcate the field of psychology in a way that showed it to be a distinctive and unified discipline.2 He had two central motivations. First, he believed that psychology contained the roots of aesthetics, logic, ethics, and politics. Logic, he thought, was rooted in ‘immediately evident’ judgments, ethics was rooted in ‘immediately evident’ emotions, and these immediately evident judgments and emotions provided us with knowledge of the necessary truths that constitute the foundations of logic and ethics.3 Second, he believed that a unified discipline could be established only by dispelling the lack of clarity and disagreement among his contemporaries about psychology’s subject matter and method. Much of the Psychology is dedicated to this second undertaking.4 All the sciences study phenomena, according to Brentano, where ‘phenomena’ is taken in its original meaning of ‘appearances’. Physics, chemistry, biology, and psychology all study appearances, appearances understood as the ‘data of consciousness’: What is given to consciousness, what shows up in consciousness. “All the data of our consciousness are divided into two great classes,” he says, “the class of physical and the class of mental phenomena” (1874, 59/77), and it is in terms of these two great classes that the subject matter of the natural sciences is distinguishable from the subject matter of psychology. The natural sciences study physical phenomena. Psychology studies mental phenomena: It is, precisely, ‘the science of mental phenomena’. What are physical phenomena? What are mental phenomena? The first thing to do, perhaps, is to note the fundamental respect in which both physical phenomena and mental phenomena in Brentano’s sense are mental phenomena in our sense (i.e., our standard present-day sense), simply because they are appearances. 42
Franz Brentano
Brentano’s examples of physical phenomena are color, light, sound, spatial location, and heat. At first glance, this list seems like a familiar starting point for characterizing physical objects and their properties. It seems to connect directly with our ordinary view of things, according to which there is a world of mind-independent physical objects that have various mind-independent physical qualities that are the proper objects of study of the natural sciences. In asserting that physical phenomena are mere appearances, however, Brentano is not advocating any kind of common-sense realism. On his terms, ‘physical phenomena’ are not part of any experience-transcending mind-independent reality, but only signs of something that is transcendent in this way. A physical phenomenon is an appearance created by our causal relation to something independent of us. As such, physical phenomena cannot give us knowledge of how things ‘really and truly are’: The phenomena of light, sound, heat, spatial location and locomotion (…) are not things which really and truly exist. They are signs of something real, which, through its causal activity, produces presentations of them. They are not, however, an adequate representation of this reality, and they give us knowledge of it only in a very incomplete sense. We can say that there exists something which, under certain conditions, causes this or that sensation. We can probably also prove that there must be relations among these realities similar to those manifested by spatial phenomena, shapes and sizes. But this is as far as we can go. We have no experience of that which truly exists, in and of itself, and that which we do experience is not true. The truth of physical phenomena is, as they say, only a relative truth. (1874, 14/19) So the subject matter of the natural sciences, according to Brentano, is physical phenomena, for example color, sound, warmth, and odor, all of which are appearances. Natural sciences do not directly study ‘things in themselves’. What about mental phenomena? Brentano’s examples include hearing a sound, seeing a colored object, thinking a general concept, loving a dog, and judging that grass is green. Since mental phenomena and physical phenomena are both phenomena, things ‘of the mind’ so to speak, to fully understand how psychology is distinguished from the natural sciences, Brentano must distinguish mental phenomena from physical phenomena. Examples provide a sense of their difference, but Brentano needs a principled way of distinguishing them. Of the four distinct criteria for distinguishing mental and physical phenomena that Brentano considers, his preferred and most well-known proposal is that all and only mental phenomena have intentionality: Every mental phenomenon is characterized by what the Scholastics of the Middle Ages called the intentional (or mental) inexistence of an object, and what we might call, though not wholly unambiguously, reference to a content, direction toward an object (which is not to be understood here as meaning a thing), or immanent objectivity. Every mental phenomenon includes something as object within itself, although they do not all do so in the same way. In presentation, something is presented, in judgment something is affirmed or denied, in love loved, in hate hated, in desire desired and so on (…) This intentional in-existence is characteristic exclusively of mental phenomena. No physical phenomenon exhibits anything like it. We can, therefore, define mental phenomena by saying that they are those phenomena which contain an object intentionally within themselves. (1874, 68/88–89) 43
Michelle Montague
This passage has resulted in much debate, but for present purposes, we can put these aside and accept the intuitive characterization of Brentano’s claim that all mental phenomena are intentional phenomena in the sense of being ‘of ’ or ‘about’ something.
4. Psychology’s evidence and Brentano’s theory of consciousness With Brentano’s criterion for determining the subject matter of psychology in hand, we can now ask for more detail about its method and source of evidence. This requires turning to his theory of consciousness. The fundamental pillar of Brentano’s theory of consciousness is that conscious mental phenomena are constitutively self-intimating. That is, in addition to any external phenomena that may be its objects, a conscious mental act 5 or mental phenomenon takes itself as object, not as the focus of attention, but only ‘in passing’ or ‘by the way’. Its taking itself as object in this way is constitutive of its existence as a conscious mental phenomenon— essential to its existing at all as a conscious mental phenomenon.6 One shouldn’t, therefore, suppose that to say that a mental act takes itself as object only ‘in passing’ is to suggest that this taking itself as object is unimportant or inessential. Brentano calls this essential self-intimation ‘inner perception’ 7 and distinguishes it from external perception. External perception is always of physical phenomena in Brentano’s sense—color, sound, and spatial location. Inner perception is always of mental phenomena, and it is in Brentano’s view immediate and infallibly self-evident (1874, 70/91). We can know that mental phenomena are real and we can know their real nature through inner perception: “The phenomena of inner perception (…) are true in themselves. As they appear to be, so they are in reality, a fact with is attested to by the evidence with which they are perceived” (1874, 15/19–20): Psychology, like the natural sciences, has its basis in perception and experience. Above all, however, its source is to be found in the inner perception of our own mental phenomena. We would never know what a thought is, or a judgement, pleasure or pain, desires or aversions, hopes or fears, courage or despair, decisions and voluntary intentions if we did not learn what they are through inner perception of our own phenomena. Note, however, that we said that inner perception (Wahrnehmung) and not introspection, i.e. inner observation (Beobachtung), constitutes this primary and essential source of psychology. These two concepts must be distinguished from one another. (1874, 22/29) ‘Inner perception’ is not what contemporary theorists typically call ‘introspection’, or what Brentano and his contemporaries also call ‘inner observation’ (Beobachtung). Introspection or inner observation is one mental act taking a distinct mental act as an object or as the focus of attention. In contrast, inner perception is built into the very act it is perceiving. For Brentano, there is a very tight connection between (1) what makes a conscious state conscious, (2) the correct method of theorizing for psychology, and (3) psychology’s fundamental source of evidence. It is in virtue of what a conscious state is—a self-intimating phenomenon involving inner perception—that it provides the best and most certain evidence for our psychological theorizing. Since this unassailable evidence can only be delivered from the first-person perspective, the phenomenological method is the natural approach for psychology.
44
Franz Brentano
5. Emotions are sui generis intentional phenomena We can now consider how this applies to Brentano’s theory of emotion. Emotions, like the other two fundamental kinds of mental phenomena, presentations and judgments, display the essential mark of the mental: They have intentionality, object-directedness: “There is no hoping unless something is hoped for, no striving unless something is striven for; one cannot be pleased unless there is something one is pleased about (…)” (1969[1889], 14). Brentano’s main consideration in favor of the intentionality of emotions seems to be the simple phenomenological observation that all emotions appear to be object-directed. The three fundamental kinds of mental phenomena are distinguished from each other by the way in which they ‘mentally relate’ or ‘mentally refer’ to objects. All the finer distinctions we make between mental acts, for example, between desiring, wondering, deciding, entertaining, expecting, hoping, fearing, and so on, fall under one of these three fundamental headings. By ‘presentation’, Brentano does not mean what is presented, but an act or event of presentation. An act of presentation—an event of one’s being presented with something—is required for anything to appear in consciousness at all. Acts of presentation, therefore, form the foundation of every judgment and emotion. Just as judgments require antecedent presentations of objects, so too loving or hating requires that an object be presented in a presentation: This act of presentation forms the foundation not merely of the act of judging, but also of desiring and of every other mental act. Nothing can be judged, desired, hoped or feared, unless one has a presentation of that thing. (1973[1874], 80) Accordingly, we may say that the basic kind of ‘mental reference’, the basic way for a subject to ‘mentally relate’ to an object, is to simply get that object into consciousness, to have that object in mind. Once an object is presented in a presentation, a judgment can either ‘affirm’ or ‘deny’ the existence of that object. Brentano has what can be described as an ‘objectual’ theory of judgment, according to which judgment is a sui generis mental phenomenon in which we either affirm or deny the existence of an object, but this is not to be understood as predicating existence of an object. We can represent the nature of judgment roughly as follows: For some object o, one either Affirms (o) or Denies (o). In the case of a judgment about an object, the mind is concerned with the object in a twofold way: Not only is the object presented, but the mind now relates to it in a second way, by either affirming or denying its existence. Brentano then goes on to explicate loving and hating in terms of “inclination or disinclination, being pleased or displeased” (1969[1889], 16)—what we may call ‘pro-attitudes’ and ‘anti-attitudes’. Very generally, pro-attitudes (love, joy, and worship) take an object to be good, and anti-attitudes (anger, fear, and sadness) take an object to be bad. “Just as every judgment takes an object to be true or false, in an analogous way every phenomenon which belongs to this class takes an object to be good or bad” (1874, 154/199). By analogy with judgment, we can roughly represent the nature of emotion as follows: For some object o, in having an emotion toward o, one either takes the stance Good (o) or the stance Bad (o). Accordingly, in the case of emotion, the mind relates to an object in a twofold way: Not only is the object presented, but the mind additionally either loves it (takes a ‘good/pro’ stance toward it) or hates it (takes a ‘bad/anti’ stance toward it).
45
Michelle Montague
The fundamental basis for this classification involves an appeal to inner perception: Is there anything we can do besides appeal to inner experience which teaches us that the relation of consciousness to its object is either exactly the same or similar in one set of cases and a radically different one in the other? It would seem that no other means is available. Inner experience is clearly the only arbiter which can resolve disputes about the sameness or difference of intentional reference. (1874, 154/200) Brentano’s claim that emotions are intrinsically evaluative phenomena has gained wide acceptance in recent theories of emotion, although there is still a lot of disagreement about what exactly the claim amounts to. Solomon (1976) and Nussbaum (2001), for example, claim that emotions are evaluative judgments, while other contemporary philosophers claim that emotions are evaluative perceptions.8 Part of what distinguishes Brentano’s theory from both of these contemporary views is that he holds that emotions are sui generis intentional phenomena that cannot be reduced to either judgments or perceptions.9 In the following passage, Brentano explicitly disavows a perceptual theory of emotion: I do not believe that anyone will understand me to mean that phenomena belonging to this class are cognitive acts by which we perceive the goodness or badness, value or disvalue of certain objects. Still, in order to make such an interpretation absolutely impossible, I explicitly note that this would be a complete misunderstanding of my real meaning. In the first place, that would mean that I viewed these phenomena as judgements; but in fact I separate them off as a separate class. Secondly, it would mean that I would be assuming quite generally that this class of phenomena presupposes presentations of good and bad, value and disvalue. This is so far from being the case, that instead I shall show that such presentations can stem only from inner perception of these phenomena. (1874, 186/241)
6. The foundation of Brentano’s epistemology of value: opposing mental relations give rise to the possibility of correctness and incorrectness I now turn to Brentano’s epistemology of value. To begin, it is worth making two preliminary points. First, Brentano is concerned with objective value, about whose reality he has no doubt: Is there a moral law that is natural in the sense of being universally and incontestably valid—valid for men at all places and all times, indeed valid for any being that thinks and feels—and are we capable of knowing that there is such a law? (…) My own answer is emphatically affirmative. (1969[1889], 6) Second, although Brentano is concerned with objective value, he does not take this to mean that objects or states of affairs have objective value properties like ‘good’ and ‘bad’. According to Brentano, the terms ‘good’, ‘bad’, and ‘better’ are syncategorematic. That is, when they are used in sentences where they seem to be predicates, they aren’t really predicating 46
Franz Brentano
goodness and badness of anything. Rather, a sentence like ‘insight is good’ translates roughly as it is correct to love insight. An epistemology of value aims to provide an explanation of how we can come to know what value and disvalue are. This task is more difficult if one takes value to be objective, as Brentano does. Brentano’s epistemology of value is based on an extended treatment of an analogy he draws between judgments and emotions. He begins by noting that both kinds of mental phenomena intrinsically involve the possibility of taking opposing relations to an object. Judgments can either affirm or deny an object, and emotions can either love or hate an object. The kind of opposition exhibited by judgments and emotions gives rise to the possibility of their being either correct or incorrect. But opposition in and of itself doesn’t give rise to the possibility of correctness or incorrectness. Neither does merely presenting or thinking of opposing things. One can see this by considering oppositions such as black and white, up and down, negative and positive charges, and thinking of such oppositions. It is only when mental relations can take opposing stands on the same object that we get the possibility of correctness or incorrectness: In the case of judgement there is the opposition between affirmation or acceptance, on the one hand, and denial or rejection, on the other. In the case of the emotions there is the opposition between love and hate or, as we may also put it, the opposition between inclination and disinclination, between being pleased and being displeased. In the case of [ judgements], one of the two opposing modes of relation—affirmation and denial—is correct and the other is incorrect, as logic has taught since ancient times. Naturally, the same thing is true of [emotions]. Of the two opposing types of feeling— loving and hating, inclination and disinclination, being pleased and being displeased— in every instance one of them is correct and the other incorrect. (1969[1889], 10–11) The possibility of correctness and incorrectness in the category of judgment allows us to ask: What does truth consist in, and what is the origin of our concept of truth? Similarly, the possibility of correctness and incorrectness in the category of emotion allows us to ask: What does goodness consist in, and what is the origin of our concept of goodness? And now Brentano gives his answer. Just as [w]e call a thing true when the affirmation relating to it is correct, [so too] we call a thing good when the love relating to it is correct. In the broadest sense of the term, the good is that which is worthy of love, that which can be loved with a love that is correct. (1969[1889], 11) To articulate the proposed analogy between judgment and emotion further, it will be helpful to say something about Brentano’s views on the relationship between judgment and truth. These views are most explicitly laid out in The True and the Evident (Brentano 1966[1930]), a book that consists of some of Brentano’s unpublished writings, mainly taken from his notebooks for his lectures and letters from the years 1889 to 1916. A lthough in his early work Brentano accepted the correspondence theory of truth—the idea that truth consists in a correspondence between our judgments and reality—he later came to reject it. In lieu of the correspondence theory, Brentano offers an epistemic characterization of truth. It is empiricist in the sense that according to Brentano, any “concept (…) has its origin 47
Michelle Montague
in certain intuitive presentations” (1969[1889], 13). This means that all of our concepts must be based in experience. For Brentano, the experiential element that gives us our fundamental insight into what truth consists in, and so anchors our concept of truth, is the experience of an immediately self-evident and infallible judgment. If a judgment is immediately selfevident, it constitutes certain knowledge, and no reason can override it. So our concept of truth, our concept of a correct judgment, is based on our experiences of self-evident judgments.10 Following Chisholm (1986), it may be helpful to distinguish between a ‘loose’ and ‘strict’ sense of correctness. All self-evident judgments are correct in a ‘strict’ sense. However, not all true judgments are self-evident, and sometimes Brentano refers to non-self-evident true judgments as ‘blind judgments’. Blind judgments can be either true or false, and when they are true, they are true because they are in agreement with self-evident judgments.11 True but blind judgments are, therefore, correct in a ‘loose’ sense. For human beings, there are two kinds of self-evident judgments. First, as mentioned above, there are judgments of inner perception, affirmative judgments about our current conscious mental acts. According to Brentano, all conscious experiences constitutively involve a self-evident affirmation (non-propositional judgment) of their own existence. Since the very existence of a conscious experience is partly constituted by an affirmation of its existence, one cannot possibly doubt its existence. That is, one cannot simultaneously affirm and doubt a conscious experience’s existence. Second, there are apodictic judgments that arise from negative judgments about what cannot exist and are the source of a priori knowledge. For example, in making a self-evident judgment to the effect that all squares are rectangles, one thinks of a square that is not rectangular and one rejects it ‘apodictically’. Apodictic judgments are caused or motivated in a special way. The judgment is immediately caused by the judger’s contemplation of the content of the judgment: “if this kind of motivation is not present, the judgment is said to be assertoric” (Brentano 1966[1930], 128–129). In making the judgment that all squares are rectangles, we consider a square-that-is-not-a-rectangle. Our consideration of a square-that-is-not-a-rectangle causes (motivates) us to reject it, and we perceive this causation (or motivation). This apodictic rejection is the source of our a priori knowledge that all squares are rectangles, and so is a generalization from a single instance. That is, in rejecting this instance, we see that any instance of such a square-that-isnot-a-rectangle must be rejected. It is one thing to have experiences of self-evident judgments, but how exactly do we acquire the concept of a correct (true) judgment from them? According to Brentano, “concepts are made manifest to us [when] we consider a multiplicity of things each of which exemplifies the concept and we direct our attention upon what these things have in common”.12 To begin to notice the commonalities between self-evident judgments, we can first compare self-evident judgments to blind judgments or judgments that contradict self-evident judgments, and by doing this, we notice that self-evident judgments are different from these other kinds of judgments. Brentano describes this comparative process as follows: The fact that we affirm something does not mean that it is true, for we often judge quite blindly. Many of the prejudices that we acquired in our infancy may take on the appearance of indubitable principles. And all men have by nature an impulse to trust certain other judgements that are equally blind—for example, those judgements that are based upon so-called external perception and those that are based upon memories of the recent past. What is affirmed in this way may often be true, but it is just as likely to be false. For these judgements involve nothing that manifests correctness. But they may 48
Franz Brentano
be contrasted with certain other judgements which are “insightful” or “evident”. The law of contradiction is one example. Other examples are provided by so-called inner perception, which tells me that I am now having such-and-such sound or colour sensations, or that I am now thinking or willing this or that. What, then, is the essential distinction between these lower and higher forms of judgement? Is it a distinction with respect to degree of conviction or is it something else? It does not pertain to degree of conviction. Many of those blind, instinctive assumptions that arise out of habit are completely uninfected by doubt. Some of them are so firmly rooted that we cannot get rid of them even after we have seen that they have no logical justification. But they are formed under the influence of obscure impulses; they do not have the clarity that is characteristic of the higher form of judgement. If one were to ask, “Why do you really believe that?”, it would be impossible to find any rational grounds. Now if one were to raise the same question in connection with a judgement that is immediately evident, here, too, it would be impossible to refer to any grounds. But in this case the clarity of the judgement is such as to enable us to see that the question has no point; indeed, the question would be completely ridiculous. Everyone experiences the difference between these two classes of judgement. As in the case of every other concept, the ultimate explication consists only in a reference to this experience. (1966[1930], 20; my emphasis) By comparing a self-evident judgment with a blind (or non-self-evident) judgment or with a judgment that contradicts a self-evident judgment, one can notice an experiential difference. This experiential difference, namely the experience of the self-evident that accompanies a self-evident judgment, allows one to acquire the concept self-evident (or as it was called above ‘strict correctness’), and once one has this concept, whenever one makes a self-evident judgment, one can know that one is making an evident judgment because one is able to identify its experiential marker. With this in place, we may turn to the case of the emotions. Based on the opposing relations emotions can take to the same object, we have the idea that emotions can be correct, and with this idea, according to Brentano, we have found the source of our concepts of good and bad: And now we have found what we have been looking for. We have arrived at the source of our concepts of the good and the bad, along with that of our concepts of the true and the false. We call a thing true when the affirmation relating to it is correct. We call a thing good when the love relating to it is correct. In the broadest sense of the term, the good is that which is worthy of love, that which can be loved with a love that is correct. (1966[1930], 18) By identifying the source of the concept good, we now say what the good consists in—a thing is good when the love relating to it is correct. (Recall, Brentano uses ‘love’ widely to essentially mean any ‘pro-attitude’.) But how do we know that a thing is good? How do I know whether I’m correctly loving something? People love different things; what one person loves, another hates. Mere love is not enough for something to be good, nor is it enough to know the good, and so Brentano argues that there is an analogue of the experience of self-evident judgment in the sphere of emotions. In a self-evident judgment, the evidence of that judgment is experienced. In the case of a correct emotion (in the strict sense), the emotion is experienced as being correct. According to Brentano, therefore, we have two ways of experiencing correctness— experiencing 49
Michelle Montague
the self-evidence of a judgment and experiencing the correctness of an emotion. (Brentano only uses the term ‘self-evident’ with respect to judgments.) From experiences of correct emotion, we can then acquire the concept correct emotion. Brentano offers the following examples of emotions that manifest themselves as being correct: Love of insight, Love of joy (that is not Schadenfreude), and Love of correct love. Emotions experienced as being correct are not feelings of compulsion. But how are we to distinguish a feeling of correctness from a feeling of compulsion? Compulsion has nothing to do with correctness. According to Brentano, one only has to consider one’s own compulsions. I have a feeling of compulsion to smoke cigarettes, but this is utterly unlike what it feels like to love insight. Acquiring the concept of correct emotion is anchored in comparing correct emotions with emotions that lack this experiential correctness. Brentano offers the following example: Imagine now another species quite different from ourselves; not only do its members have preferences with respect to sense qualities which are quite different from ours; unlike us, they also despise insight and love error for its own sake. So far as the feelings about sense qualities are concerned, we might say that these things are a matter of taste, and “De gustibus non est disputandum”. But this is not what we would say of the love of error and the hatred of insight. We would say that such love and hatred are basically perverse and that the members of the species in question hate what is indubitably and intrinsically good and love what is indubitably and intrinsically bad. Why do we answer differently in the two cases when the feeling of compulsion is equally strong? The answer is simple. In the former case the feeling of compulsion is merely instinctive. But in the latter case the natural feeling of pleasure is a higher love that is experienced as being correct. When we ourselves experience such a love we notice not only that its object is loved and capable of being loved, and that its privation or contrary hated and capable of being hated, but also that the one is worthy of love and the other worthy of hate, and therefore that the one is good and the other bad. (1966[1930], 22) Our knowledge of what is truly and indubitably good arises from the type of experience we have been discussing, where a love is experienced as being correct (…) (1966[1930], 24) Once I acquire the concept of correct emotion through this comparative process, I can know the good, according to Brentano, because I can identify when I am experiencing an emotion that manifests correctness. I know insight is good, because I experience my love of insight as correct and I recognize the correctness, which is part of this experience.13 In conclusion, I have tried to show the way in which Brentano’s theory of emotion is interwoven with his overall theory of mind, and to emphasize the way in which the phenomenological character of conscious experience plays a central role in grounding his claims about the emotions.
Notes
50
Franz Brentano
References Brentano, Franz Brentano, Franz (1973 [1874]1973[1874]). Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Transl. by L. McAlister, A. Rancurello, and D. B. Terrell, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. ——— (1995[1887]) Descriptive Psychology. Transl. by B. Muller. New York: Routledge. ——— (1969[1889]). The Origin of Our Knowledge of Right and Wrong. Transl. by R. Chisholm and E. Schneewind. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. ——— (1966[1930]). The True and the Evident. Transl. by R. Chisholm, I. Politzer, and K. Fischer. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Chisholm, Roderick (1976). Brentano’s Theory of Correct and Incorrect Emotion. In: L. McAlister (Ed.). The Philosophy of Brentano. London: Duckworth, 160–175. ——— (1986). Brentano and Intrinsic Value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. de Beauvoir, Simone (1997[1949]1997[1949]). The Second Sex. Transl. by H. M. Parshley. London: Vintage. de Sousa, Ronald (1987). The Rationality of Emotion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Deonna, Julien, and Teroni, Fabrice (2012). The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction. London, New York: Routledge. Descartes, René (1985[1641]). Meditations and Objections and Replies. In: The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. 2, transl. by J. Cottingham et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frege, Gottlob (1974[1884]). The Foundations of Arithmetic: A Logico-Mathematical Enquire into the Concept of Number. Transl. by J. L. Austin. Oxford: Blackwell. Heidegger, Martin (1962[1927]). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Husserl, Edmund (2001[1900–1901]). Logical Investigations, vols. 1 and 2. Transl. by J. N. Findlay with revised transl. by D. Moran. London, New York: Routledge. Kriegel, Uriah (2009). Subjective Consciousness. A Self-Representational Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
51
Michelle Montague Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1962[1945]). The Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by Colin Smith. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Montague, Michelle (2016). The Given: Experience and its Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nussbaum, Martha (2001). Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Parsons, Charles (2004). Brentano on Judgment and Truth. In: D. Jacquette (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Brentano. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1956[1943]). Being and Nothingness. Transl. by H. Barnes. New York: Philosophical Library. Solomon, Robert (1976). The Passions. Garden City: Doubleday. Williford, Kenneth (2006). The Self-Representational Structure of Consciousness. In: U. Kriegel and K. Williford (Eds.). Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Further reading Gordon, Robert (1987). The Structure of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Greenspan, Patricia (1988). Emotions and Reasons. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. James, William (1884). What is Emotion. Mind 9, 188–205. Kriegel, Uriah (2018). Brentano’s Philosophical System: Mind, Being, and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lyons, William (1980). Emotion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Montague, Michelle. (2009). The Logic, Intentionality, and Phenomenology of Emotion. Philosophical Studies 145(2), 171–192. ——— (2014). Evaluative Phenomenology. In: S. Roeser and C. Todd (Eds). Emotion and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 32–51. ——— (2017). A Contemporary View of Brentano’s Theory of Emotion. The Monist 100, 64–87. Mulligan, Kevin (2004). Brentano on the Mind. In: D. Jacquett (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Brentano. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Oakley, Justin (1992). Morality and the Emotions. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Prinz, Jesse (2004). Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion. New York: Oxford University Press. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1994[1962]). Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. Transl. by P. Mairet. London, New York: Routledge. Textor, Mark (2017). Brentano’s Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
52
2 EDMUND HUSSERL James Jardine
While Husserl is widely recognised as the founder of the phenomenological movement, and as responsible for important positions on a number of central philosophical topics (such as perception, intentionality, self-consciousness, and the tenability of naturalism), he is frequently regarded, even within phenomenological circles, as having a fairly impoverished understanding of the emotions. And indeed, there is some validity to the observation that, while essential roles are accorded to emotion in Husserl’s phenomenological analyses of personhood, (axiological) reason, value-theory, and ethics (to name just a few examples), it emerges less frequently in his writings as a central theme of inquiry. The following chapter offers the reader an opportunity to reconsider such an assessment, by highlighting and explicating a number of key claims that emerge in those writings where Husserl deals directly and thematically with the phenomenology of emotional life. Focusing mainly on his most productive and significant period as a phenomenologist of the emotions—dating between the publication of Logical Investigations in 1900 and Ideas I in 1913—I hope to indicate that Husserl’s published and unpublished writings contain important contributions to the phenomenological study of emotional life, and to our understanding of the emotions more broadly.
1. Intentional and non-intentional feelings in the Logical Investigations While attempts to describe the peculiar character of emotional experience can already be found in manuscripts dating from the early 1890s (cf. Husserl 2004, 163–167), it was not until the turn of the century that Husserl first offered the reading public a sketch of his phenomenology of the emotions. In the second volume of Logical Investigations, Husserl briefly takes up the question of whether the phenomenologist ought to class feelings (Gefühle) as intentional experiences (Husserl 2001, 106–111). In living through an occurrent feeling, are we thereby experientially directed to an object or situation that is, in some way, consciously given or referred to? Husserl argues that there is indeed a (broad and internally differentiated) class of feelings that are experientially related to objects in this way, while at the same time acknowledging that not everything typically described as a ‘feeling’ falls under this description, and he accordingly distinguishes between intentional and non-intentional feelings. 53
James Jardine
Non-intentional feelings are exclusively confined to what Husserl calls sensory feelings (sinnliche Gefühle) or affective sensations (Gefühlsempfindungen). He focuses here on those feelings which are located somewhere on a spectrum between pain (Schmerz) and pleasure (Lust), encompassing not only the pain felt in a burnt hand but also the pleasure frequented by the scent of a rose or the taste of a delicious meal, or the displeasure of “a pang in the heart” (Husserl 2001, 109, 111; transl. modified). Husserl’s characterisation of such feelings as akin to sensations has a twofold motivation. On the one hand, as the fusion of pleasure and olfactory sense in smelling a rose nicely illustrates, such sensory pains and pleasures are always blended with various (exteroceptive or interoceptive) forms of sensory awareness. On the other, such feelings exhibit a degree of homogeneity or similarity (Gleichförmigkeit) with the sensations involved with sensory perception, and with touch in particular. In illustrating this similarity, Husserl notes that tactile sensations are not yet intentional acts, only involving a non-objectifying awareness of certain sensory contents (such as ‘rough’ or ‘smooth’). Nevertheless, such sensations constitute a form of bodily self-awareness, in that they are experientially related to a “touching member” of the subject’s lived body (Leib). Moreover, tactile sensations are able to function as presentative contents (darstellende Inhalte) in intentional acts: It is through their undergoing perceptual apprehension or construal (Auffassung) that the surface of a touched object appears (tactually) as rough or smooth. Like tactual sensations, the sensory feelings are nothing more than an inarticulate awareness of certain non-intentional contents (e.g., the non-objectified ‘pain’ felt in touching a hot pan). But through their ‘blending’ with interoceptive and exteroceptive sensations, sensory feelings also permit a more-or-less definite localisation in the lived body of the feeling subject (such that, e.g., the pain is felt ‘in’ the burnt finger). And crucially, such feelings may themselves provide presentative contents for intentional acts. For instance, if we now perceive or imagine the event which has elicited an occurrent feeling of pleasure, then this act of presentation (Vorstellung) will contain an additional intentional character which passes through and animates the pleasure-sensations, such that the event now appears, not only as bearing certain perceptible features, but also “as if bathed in a rosy gleam” (Husserl 2001, 109–110 [406–408]; transl. modified). At this stage, one might expect Husserl to identify the intentional feelings with such “affectively determined” (gefühlsbestimmt) apprehensions of objects and situations, in which the affective sensations provide an additional source of contents for the (cognitive) acts of presentation to assimilate. Indeed, to his evident frustration, a view of this kind was occasionally attributed to Husserl by his contemporaries (cf. Geiger 1911, 139; Husserl 2018, 149). And yet, in the Investigations, Husserl explicitly distances himself from such a move (which he associates with Brentano), suggesting that the classification of such presentative acts as ‘ feelings’ is an error only made understandable by their essential intertwinement with affective sensations (Husserl 2001, 110–111). Rather, intentional feelings in the strict sense encompass that class of conscious acts in which, to adopt a more familiar parlance, we first undergo emotional experience proper. The key examples Husserl offers of intentional feelings in the Investigations are joy and sorrow felt about an object or situation already consciously presented (vorgestellt) in some way (Husserl 2001, 107 [402–403]; transl. modified). In explicating the intentional structure of such feelings, Husserl sides with the Brentanian thesis that emotional acts are founded upon acts of presentation (cf., e.g., Brentano 1995, 61–63; see Chapter 1; Drummond 2013). In order to live through joy or sadness, in the sense of an intentional feeling that responds to and targets a ‘joyous’ or ‘saddening’ situation, that situation must first be concurrently presented to consciousness (by way of, for example, perception, memory, or imagination), and in some 54
Edmund Husserl
cases also conceptually and predicatively articulated in judgement (Husserl 2001, 107–109). This is not to say that the intentional feeling is reducible to its underlying presentation, for the latter is not yet a specifically emotional experience, but merely involves an apprehension of the situation which the feeling responds to and, in some cases, of those features of the situation by virtue of which it ‘demands’ such a response from us (Husserl 2001, 109). Moreover, Husserl maintains that intentional feelings must be regarded not merely as additional layers built upon underlying foundations but as “complex and eo ipso concrete” lived experiences which “have” or incorporate within themselves the presentations to which they owe their intentional object. In fact, the feeling of joy concerning some happy event includes or appropriates not merely the base-level presentation of the event and its ‘factual’ features but also the affectively determined mode of this presentation mentioned above: “The event coloured by pleasure as such serves as the first fundament for our turning to the object in joy, our being pleased or charmed by it” (Husserl 2001, 110, 108 [408, 404]; transl. modified). Consequently, we can locate emotional intentionality, at least in its most primitive instance, in a multi-layered experiential act that includes (a) an underlying presentation of the factual object or situation to which the emotion responds, this ‘factual’ awareness being, in some cases, augmented and articulated through attention and thought; (b) an affectively determined modality of this presentation which draws upon the non-intentional feelings elicited by the object or situation; and (c) a higher-order component of intentional feeling, that is directed towards and responds to, and in this sense intentionally appropriates, the object as presented in (b).
2. Emotion and value in Ideas I While the brief analysis of emotional life in the Investigations contains a number of important claims concerning the phenomenology of emotion, one question left unanswered there is whether emotive acts, rather than merely being directed towards and responding to worldly objects and situations, might also disclose the latter in novel ways. This deceptively simple question animates much of Husserl’s work on the emotions, and he explicitly grapples with it in the book that announced his mature phenomenological project, Ideas I. With the newly introduced methodology of epoché and reduction, Husserl is now able to furnish phenomenology with a delimited but demanding task: That of investigating the relations of correlation and motivation holding between the manifold acts and act-strata of intentional consciousness (or ‘noeses’) and the worldly matters just as they are intended and experienced in such acts (or ‘noemata’). It is within this context that he attempts to clarify the noematic correlates of the noeses specific to the emotive sphere, that is, the worldly objects and situations disclosed in emotional experience just as so disclosed. Husserl focuses here on that specific kind of affective experience in which the subject is emotionally “turned towards” the matter to which it responds, such that the emotive act is not a mere “stirring” in the obscure background of consciousness (which will already have its own unimplemented noeses and unthematic noemata), but an intentionality in which the experiencing subject pre-eminently “lives,” or in which its thematic interest primarily lies (Husserl 2014, 64–65, 226–227). Developing the account of the Investigations, Husserl maintains that such “implemented” (vollzogen) emotive acts necessarily include, as a fundamental component, an attentive “grasp” (Erfassung) of the matter to which the emotion relates (Husserl 2014, 65 [76]; transl. modified). To vividly and explicitly live through a joyful emotive response as such, it is necessary that the event to which I respond joyfully is both presented to consciousness in some way, and “noticed.” However, what I thereby have in “focus” experientially, as the “ full intentional correlate” of my 55
James Jardine
thematic emotive consciousness, is not “the mere subject matter” which I grasp attentively, but something more: What Husserl simply terms “the value” (Husserl 2014, 64–65). With this talk of ‘values,’ Husserl does not mean to suggest that emotional experiences are intentionally correlated with ideal entities (e.g., ‘goodness’ or ‘beauty’ as such), or even with specific axiological properties of the worldly matters to which they relate (e.g., their concrete goodness or beauty). Rather, a value in this (somewhat idiosyncratic) sense is simply the concrete object as disclosed in the underlying act, but now also furnished with “new, inherent noematic aspects” (Husserl 2014, 229). In occurrently fearing someone upon noticing their aggressive glare, my cognisance of their testy demeanour needn’t be accompanied by any consideration of the ideal, nor by a separate act that simply intuits ‘threateningness’ as a pure axiological property; rather, when frightened by someone’s behaviour as grasped in this concrete situation, the person simply stands there for me experientially as threatening. While we can legitimately speak of noeses specific to the emotive sphere that are uniquely correlated with the ‘threateningness’ of the person’s behaviour, these are merely non-independent moments or “inherent aspects” (Momente) of the concrete emotive experience, such that the “valuing (…) encompasses the presenting” (Husserl 2014, 229–230, 65). And correlatively, the other’s threateningness is not felt as a free-floating feature, but as “a new layer of the object,” in that “the full ‘sense’ of valuing includes What (das Was) it values, with the complete fullness in which there is consciousness of it in the relevant experience of value” (Husserl 2014, 190–191). While we may be able to single out specific features of the other’s behaviour which particularly strike us as threatening (say, their stony glare, furrowed brows, and clenched fists), such “value-features” (Werteigenschaften) are features of the concrete value itself and accordingly share its internal complexity, being experienced simultaneously as factually present features of the person before us, and as threatening or frightening (Husserl 2014, 190–191 [221]; transl. modified).1 In claiming that emotive acts are not only ‘related’ to presented objects but also intentionally ‘correlated’ with concrete values, one might suspect that Husserl has now abandoned his earlier emphasis on the difference between emotional experience and presentative acts. Indeed, the account of emotive acts offered in Ideas I might initially recall those affectively determined acts of presentation in which objects and situations appear bathed in an affective colouration, that were explicitly distinguished from emotional intentionality proper in the Investigations. And yet, a closer look at Husserl’s analyses reveals a more complex picture. To begin with, and even with regard to explicit and thematic emotive consciousness, Husserl maintains that the moment of evaluation operative here is not a form of attentive grasping, or an apprehension or presentation of any kind. As he puts it, concrete values are only properly presented to consciousness in an attentive and objectifying modification of emotive experience, but since such an objectification must occur if we are to bring felt values to expression in thought and speech, we tend to overlook the non-objectifying way in which they are first (emotionally) experienced (Husserl 2014, 65, 64). Rather than being a presentational act, emotive evaluation is best characterised as a form of “position-taking,” and it is, in this sense, analogous to the element of doxic positing or “belief ” contained, for instance, in all “normal perception,” and the modifications of such belief in conjecture and doubt (Husserl 2014, 231–232, 205–206). To this extent, the noematic characters of ‘threatening,’ ‘beloved,’ or ‘joyful’ that worldly matters evince in emotive experience are non-identical, but structurally similar, to the noematic characters of ‘being,’ ‘possibly being,’ or ‘doubtfully and questionably being,’ which are correlated with doxic positionality and its modal modifications (Husserl 2014, 230, 207). Such noematic characters are not first experienced as apprehended properties of a presented object: Feeling joyful about an event does not involve apprehending it as ‘joyful,’ just as perceiving the event does not involve apprehending it as ‘existing.’ 56
Edmund Husserl
However, Husserl significantly complicates matters by emphasising that “new kinds of ‘apprehensions’ are also combined” with the new noematic characters that surface in emotional experience, and that it is only by means of such apprehensions that the emotions are able to function in the disclosure of “a totally new dimension of sense” (Husserl 2014, 227–228 [266–267]; transl. modified). Husserl’s claim here is that the objectification of concrete values through which they become available for expression in thought and speech is not, after all, something wholly alien to emotional experience. Fearfully experiencing a person as threatening does not involve a presently actualised apprehension of their behaviour as ‘threatening,’ nor the actual doxic positing of their ‘being threatening.’ Nevertheless, Husserl maintains that such doxic objectifications are essentially “prefigured as ideal possibilities” in all evaluating consciousness. In this way, all emotive acts are implicitly objectifying, and harbour an implicit doxic or logical component that is merely explicitly implemented when, for instance, we occurrently apprehend and judge as ‘threatening’ a person previously merely feared (Husserl 2014, 234). One can detect two motivations for this move in Ideas I. First, Husserl claims that all founded acts of emotional position-taking involve a tacit sense of certainty, uncertainty, or doubt; while we are often (pre-reflectively) confident in our emotive attitudes, sometimes this confidence slips away: “We are conscious of the value in valuing, the pleasing in being pleased, the joyful in enjoying, but at times in such a way that, in valuing this or that, we are simply not entirely ‘sure’” (Husserl 2001, 233). Husserl takes this to be direct phenomenological evidence for an implicit doxic component in all emotive acts. A further motivation for this thought is that it allows us to understand how the mode of value-consciousness specific to emotive experience can be non-objectifying in character, while simultaneously enabling the disclosure of a richly meaningful world that permits expression in logical thought and speech (Husserl 2001, 65–66, 252).2 That is, Husserl regards such a fusion of explicit valuing and implicit belief in emotional experience as a necessary precondition for our recognising worldly matters as personally (and ultimately interpersonally and culturally) significant, rather than as mere ‘things.’ Or as Levinas succinctly formulates Husserl’s view: “The intentionality that runs through our affective and active lives confers the dignity of objective experience upon all our concrete engagements; values belong to the real just as do ideal structures. The real is human and inhabitable” (Levinas 1998, 132).
3. Themes from Husserl’s manuscripts: pleasure, value-reception, and reactive emotions In the intermediary period between the publication of Logical Investigations and Ideas I, Husserl set aside time and effort to carefully reflect upon the life of the emotions. His thoughts from this productive era were recorded and, one suspects, actively developed in a series of five long manuscripts dating from 1909 to 1911, and in a significant body of shorter texts written in those years and the preceding decade (Husserl 2018, 1–190, 263–507; cf. Melle 2012). These rich and somewhat experimental texts move far beyond the relatively narrow focus on the generic intentional structure of emotive acts found in his published writings, and in the following, I can only offer a hint of some of their more dominant and, to my mind, especially promising themes. In his published writings, Husserl only inadequately addresses a central issue for the phenomenology of emotion: Namely, the role played by non-intentional feelings within emotional intentionality itself. We saw earlier that Husserl raises this matter in the Investigations, and responds by claiming that sensory feelings function in emotional experience merely indirectly. On this view, sensory feelings can only participate in emotional intentionality 57
James Jardine
by undergoing apprehension through a presentational act which is not itself a feeling of any kind. In his manuscripts, Husserl attempts to sharpen his earlier position by contrasting the intentional function of sensory feelings with the primary functional role of other kinds of sensation, that is, their undergoing empirical apperception or apprehension (Husserl 2018, 4ff.). Empirical apperception, in this sense, is a structural feature of sensuous perception that configures sensibility in such a way that, at any given point in time, the currently appearing profile of the perceptual object is taken to be accompanied by a horizon of profiles which do not so appear at present. Husserl maintains that this configuration, rather than being an inexplicable event, has a “motivational” structure or norm-governed intelligibility, and he emphasises two kinds of “motivational circumstance” that determine, in a lawgoverned fashion, how empirical apperception functions in concrete perceptual situations. On the one hand, empirical apperception is motivationally tied to the bodily motility of the perceiving subject. The spatial profiles of the thing which do not currently meet the eye, being merely “apperceived,” are delineated perceptually as what would appear, if I were to enact the relevant course of movement. On the other hand, empirical apperception is also motivationally conditioned by “associative” ties with earlier perceptual encounters. When walking past something whose kind we are already familiar with perceptually, we anticipate that the thing will progressively reveal certain perceptible aspects and properties that are currently invisible. Husserl maintains that such an anticipation of perceptual reality, which can, of course, be confirmed or frustrated by the actual course of experience, is configured by the associative links to past perceptual episodes operative in empirical apperception itself (see, e.g., Husserl 1997, 186, 252–253, 257–258, 319f.). The question now is whether nonintentional feelings serve to disclose objects in new ways merely by providing an additional field of sensory material for such empirical apperception. Husserl acknowledges that, under specific circumstances, sensory feelings do enter into empirical apperception in this way. For instance, the sensory pain lived through in touching the metal handle of a hot pan informs our comprehension of this handle as not merely hot but ‘burning hot,’ and our prior familiarity with burning pans motivates an apperception of the entire surface of the pan as infused with the same quality. Sensory pain is drawn upon in an (associatively and kinaesthetically motivated) empirical apprehension of the pan as burning hot, and in such a case, we may even say that affectively disclosed qualities are experienced as properties which “belong to the object in the same way that colour and warmth do” (Husserl 2018, 5; own transl.). However, Husserl now distinguishes between the ability of sensory feelings to provide additional sensory materials for empirical apperception, and what he maintains is their primary experiential function, namely that of suffusing the sensuously given with an “affective colouration” (Gefühlsfärbung, Gemütsfärbung). Importantly, Husserl characterises such affective colouration as a primordial form of “valuing” (Wertung), and he maintains that apperception can only legitimately be spoken of here if one recognises a non-empirical kind of “affective apperception” that is oriented not towards mere things but towards concrete values (Gefühlsapperzeption, Wertapperzeption) (Husserl 2018, 4–5, 9–10, 38–39). The most basic instance of such colouration occurs in the “tonation by affective sensations” (Gefühlsempfindungsbetonung) of other sensory fields, a wholly passive and embodied form of valuing that takes place irrespective of any form of intentional construal which the sensations might undergo (Husserl 2018, 59, 61–62). For instance, the rhythm of flavours lived through when chewing on a morsel of food involves, on the one hand, the processual emergence and fading away of diverse sensory contents belonging strictly to gustatory sense, and, on the other hand, the affective tonation of such contents through which they acquire the characters of ‘pleasant’ or ‘unpleasant,’ and perhaps even ‘indifferent’ 58
Edmund Husserl
(Husserl 2018, 63–64). As Husserl notes, these two aspects of the unitary impressional episode are so intimately fused that any talk of discrete “layers” is not appropriate (Husserl 2018, 63). In a brief manuscript likely written in 1909 or 1910, he even proposes that, rather than being bestowed by a distinct class of affective sensations, affective tones belong intrinsically to the content of all (first-order) sensations, such that episodes of sensory experience are always and already experiential processes, not merely of ‘sensing,’ but also and simultaneously of ‘feeling’ (Husserl 2018, 420). However, in these writings, Husserl extends the function of sensory feelings far beyond such a pre-intentional tonation of the senses, emphasising that feelings of pleasure and pain can also be oriented towards, and affectively colour or value, the transcendent objects and situations of the world of experience. A particularly vivid example of this can be found in a text from 1910, which describes the manner in which a passive form of “liking” or “being pleased” (Gefallen) can be experientially intertwined with the progressive perception of a beautiful rug, a form of affective experience which he also characterises as “‘[d]irect’ pleasure (Lust), pleasure in an object for the sake of the object itself.” In entering an unfamiliar home and seeing a radiant velvet rug, we may well have a ‘pleasant impression’ of the rug that is irreducible to any complex of affectively toned sensations. What we are pleased with here is the rug itself, and it is no mere sensory content but the “colour and pattern” of the appearing thing which first “awaken” our liking. Moreover, this liking may even be responsive to features of the rug that have not yet been originally perceived. The surface of the rug, seen but not yet caressed, pleases us in part because it looks pleasant to touch (it is as if the velvet fabric invites us to genuinely ‘feel’ it), just as its striking pattern inclines us to adopt a spatial orientation in which it would look even more appealing (Husserl 2018, 395; own transl.). ‘Being pleased’ or ‘liking’ thus designates, in this context, an affective orientation towards a perceived worldly matter that unfolds and develops over time. It is a pre-predicative form of felt valuation that is, at any moment, motivationally responsive to the (apperceptively configured) perceptual sense we have of the object as a whole. But what role do feelings of pleasure play in such a dynamic experience of something as ‘pleasant’? Is being pleased with a perceived object simply a matter of (non-intentional) pleasure-sensations undergoing objectification, or are we rather dealing here with pleasure as an intrinsically intentional feeling? Husserl’s response is unambiguous: “It is clear that the feeling has its intentionality here, that is, its transcendence or transience, in total analogy with the act of perception” (Husserl 2018, 396; cf. 16; own transl.). In the process of being pleased with the velvet rug, we live through “individual feelings of pleasure and displeasure,” each specifically “founded” upon an “inherent aspect” of the perceptual object (say, its purple hue, velvety touch, or slightly stale odour). These individual feelings increase or diminish in intensity as certain aspects of the object are given more or less optimally or emerge from merely anticipatory to actual perceptual givenness. Accordingly, one can say that the concrete experiential episode involves a specific “rhythm of feeling” whose contours map onto the particular way that the object is temporally disclosed (Husserl 2018, 396; own transl.; cf. 71, 176, 278). Now, the liking of the object which imbues every moment of this episode is not reducible to the unfolding of this specific and actualised rhythm of feeling, since it also involves the delineation of other possible affective rhythms as motivationally tied to the pleasing object’s other possible courses of perceptual exhibition. As Husserl emphasises, however, this “anticipatory” configuration of pleasure is not an achievement of the intellect, nor can it be found in the underlying perceptual presentation qua empirical apperception. Such configuration rather belongs to being pleased itself, which shows itself here as an integrated totality of actual and potential individual feelings of pleasure that, at any point 59
James Jardine
in time, functions as an affective valuation of the (ap)perceived object: “the ‘anticipation of pleasure,’ the pleasure-interpretation, is not ‘presentation’ but feeling, and feeling fulfils itself as feeling. The interpretation peculiar to the feeling is itself something affective, something that belongs specifically to the feeling” (Husserl 2018, 397, 400; cf. 128; own transl.). Husserl repeatedly highlights the close analogy with perception (Wahrnehmung) exhibited here, describing such passively and dynamically object-responsive and object-oriented feelings as instances of value-reception (Wertnehmung), and employing terms such as valuegivenness (Wertgegebenheit), value-apperception (Wertapperzeption), and even value-perception (Wertwahrnehmung). Just as an object increasingly reveals its true nature as we bring to direct givenness those of its aspects and features that were previously merely apperceived, so do we acquire a gradual and intuitive acquaintance with a concrete value (e.g., the rug as pleasing) through bringing more of its (perceptible and valuable) features explicitly into our affective focus (cf., e.g., Husserl 2018, 28–29, 100–101, 400–401). While feelings of pleasure and pain are relatively passive affective experiences that may even be characterised as forms of sensibility—insofar as the latter is understood as affording receptivity to the world of values and not merely to nature—Husserl acknowledges that many emotions are more active and self-involving modes of comportment, in that they manifest a kind of spontaneity or position-taking peculiar to the emotive sphere (Gefühlsstellungnahme, Gefühlsspontaneität). This is not to say that such emotions are acts of judgement, nor that they stand under our volitional control, but simply that anger, joy, fear, and the like are lived as ways that we respond or react to experienced objects, rather than merely as new kinds of affective receptivity (Husserl 2018, 101–102, 120–121). Such reactive emotions correspond to what Husserl had earlier termed ‘intentional feelings,’ and he now reinterprets a central claim of the Investigations by noting that they are typically motivationally responsive to worldly matters, not merely as perceived, but also as felt in value-reception. For instance, our “delight” over a beautiful picture will typically be motivated by and responsive to its very beauty, while our recognition of such beauty already involves (occurrent or anticipated) aesthetic feelings. In this sense, the “emotional position-taking reckons with the object in, and ‘for the sake of,’ its value-character” (Husserl 2018, 121–122; own transl.; cf. 55). As his research manuscripts document, Husserl became gradually convinced that the most vivid, passionate, and explicitly intentional emotional reactions involve two intimately intertwined experiential components. Firstly, an emotional response will only be lived as having an explicit intentionality if it, as a “totality of feeling,” has as its “core” an intentional feeling of liking or disliking (Husserl 2018, 113–115; own transl.). Liking or being pleased, in this context, is something more than the more receptive form of liking discussed earlier; it is not simply a matter of pleasure but is rather an intentional feeling of, say, “appreciation” (Wohlgefallen) or “joy” (Freude), while examples of reactive disliking include “concern (Besorgnis) over an imminent disaster” or “the displeased feeling of being disgusted (Abgestoßensein) by a suffered insult” (Husserl 2018, 110, 115; own transl.). However, Husserl ranks both kinds of intentional feeling under the generic heading of being pleased, simply because they are both occurrent experiences in which we are “conscious of something pleasing” (Husserl 2018, 23; own transl.). While feelings of this kind are motivated by the objects of sensory and affective receptivity, and are lived most vividly when we attend to such objects, the rich variety of value-characters that surface in their noematic correlates goes far beyond what the sensory feelings alone are able to disclose. The second component of reactive emotions resides in the ‘streams of feeling’ that flow through the embodied self and manifest its passionate emotional arousal, such as a specific rhythm of more-or-less localisable bodily feelings or a general ambience of corporeal arousal (Husserl 2018, 111–112). 60
Edmund Husserl
Husserl regards it necessary to distinguish between these two components of reactive emotions, if only because they frequently come apart. We sometimes experience an object as agreeable without finding ourselves passionately moved by it, and equally a residue of the feelings elicited in a passionate emotional arousal will remain, as a mere “affective state” (Gemütszustand), even when the arousing object or situation is no longer attended to or presented in any way (Husserl 2018, 104–105, 121–123). However, in cases where we turn towards some matter in appreciation or concern and simultaneously feel ourselves moved by it, these two aspects function together as integrated components of a single emotional reaction. In such optimally manifest cases of emotive intentionality, the “stream of aroused feelings” is lived as a corporeal “expansion” (Verbreitung) and further articulation of the core act of liking or disliking; and in correlation with this ‘fleshing out’ of the evaluative stance, so to speak, the object as emotively experienced already acquires a richer axiological significance. As Husserl puts it: “It is the delight, and not the liking without arousal, that directs itself to the object, and the object does not merely stand there as pleasing, but rather (corresponding to the modification of the act) as delightful” (Husserl 2018, 123; own transl.). In his research manuscripts, then, Husserl supplements and sharpens the basic conception of emotive intentionality found in Logical Investigations, and works out (while abundantly transcending) the noematically oriented account of Ideas I. The overview here has highlighted one important strand of these probing analyses, tracing Husserl’s efforts to further clarify the function of sensory feelings in emotional experience. While the Investigations had understood this function merely in terms of the ability of sensory feelings to undergo objectification in (non-affective) presentational acts, Husserl now locates their primary role in directly affording an intuitive consciousness of value. While this already takes place in the affective tonation of other sensory fields, integrated totalities of sensory feeling also enable the objects and situations of the perceptual world to passively affect us as pleasing or displeasing. Finally, sensory feelings contribute to the reactive emotions insofar as the latter contain a dimension of sensory arousal, a dimension that “expands” our core emotive stance towards the matter concerned and “modifies” or enrichens its affective and evaluative character (ibid.). Indeed, Husserl suggests that this intertwinement of ‘active’ position-taking and ‘passive’ sensory arousal is precisely what enables the reactive emotions to function both as manifestations of the distinctive personality of the subject (see Chapter 21), and as ( higher-order) ways in which concrete values are intuitively given: “When I am angry, when I am passionately aroused over the baseness of someone’s way of acting, then the seeing of this baseness will reside in the emotional arousals themselves” (Husserl 2018, 128; own transl.; cf. 62–63, 115, 130–131, 507–508).3
Notes
61
James Jardine
References Brentano, Franz (1995). Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Ed. By Oskar Kraus and transl. by A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and L. L. McAlister. London, New York: Routledge. Drummond, John J. (2013). The Intentional Structure of Emotions. Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy / Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse 16, 244–263. Geiger, Moritz (1911). Das Bewusstsein von Gefühlen. In: A. Pfänder (Ed.). Münchener Philosophische Abhandlungen. Theodor Lipps zu seinem sechzigsten Geburtstag gewidmet von früheren Schülern. Leipzig: Johann Ambrosius Barth, 125–162. Heinämaa, Sara (2010). Embodiment and Expressivity in Husserl’s Phenomenology: From Logical Investigations to Cartesian Meditations. SATS 11, 1–15. Husserl, Edmund (1989). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. Transl. by R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (1997). Thing and Space. Lectures of 1907. Transl. by Richard Rojcewicz. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (2001). Logical Investigations. Volume II. Ed. by Dermot Moran and transl. by J. N. Findlay. London, New York: Routledge. ——— (2004). Wahrnehmung und Aufmerksamkeit. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1893–1912) [=Hua XXXVIII]. Ed. by T. Vongehr, and R. Guiliani. Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (2014). Ideas for a Pure Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy. First Book: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Transl. by D. O. Dahlstrom. Indianapolis: Hackett. ——— (2018). Gefühl und Wert. Studien zur Struktur des Bewusstseins. Band II. Texte aus dem Nachlass [=Hua XLIII/2]. Ed. by U. Melle and T. Vongehr. Dordrecht: Springer. Jardine, James, and Szanto, Thomas (2017). Empathy in the Phenomenological Tradition. In: H. Maibom (Ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Empathy. London, New York: Routledge, 86–97. Levinas, Emmanuel (1998). Discovering Existence with Husserl. Transl. and ed. by R. A. Cohen and M. B. Smith. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Melle, Ullrich (2012). Husserls deskriptive Erforschung der Gefühlserlebnisse. In: R. Breeur, and U. Melle (Eds.). Life, Subjectivity & Art: Essays In Honor of Rudolf Bernet. Dordrecht: Springer, 51–99. Mulligan, Kevin (2010). Husserls Herz. In: M. Frank and N. Weidtmann (Eds.). Husserl und die Philosophie des Geistes. Berlin: Suhrkamp, 209–238. Further reading Drummond, John J. (2006). Respect as a Moral Emotion: A Phenomenological Approach. Husserl Studies 22(1), 1–27. Mulligan, Kevin (2017). Thrills, Orgasms, Sadness, and Hysteria: Austro-German Criticisms of William James. In: A. Cohen, and R. Stern (Eds.). Thinking about the Emotions: A Philosophical History. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 223–252. Parker, Rodney K.B., and Quepons, Ignacio (Eds.) (2018). Phenomenology of Emotions: Systematical and Historical Perspectives. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy XVI. London, New York: Routledge. Ubiali, Marta, and Wehrle, Maren (Eds.) (2015). Feeling and Value, Willing and Action: Essays in the Context of a Phenomenological Psychology. Cham: Springer.
62
3 ALEXANDER PFÄNDER Genki Uemura and Toru Yaegashi
1. Introduction Alexander Pfänder is perhaps best known for his works on volition (cf. Uemura and Yaegashi 2012; Uemura forthcoming). But his discussion of emotions also merits attention. Like many other early phenomenologists, he deals with emotions under the heading of “feelings (Gefühle),” which may refer to a broader range of experience than “emotions.” For example, when he attempts to analyze feelings in detail for the first time in his Einführung in die Psychologie (1904), he does not confine himself to what many of us now would call emotions. Later in his “Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen” (1913/1916), however, he deals with a certain class of feelings called “sentiments (Gesinnungen),” which are certainly a class of emotions. In the present chapter, after giving a summary of Pfänder’s early view on feelings (Section 2), we reconstruct and assess his discussion of sentiments in the later period (Sections 3–6).
2. Feelings as states of mental subjects In his early work Einführung in die Psychologie, Pfänder mentions the following examples of feelings: Feelings of pleasure/displeasure, joy, annoyance (Unmut), moods of feeling (Gefühlsstimmungen), aesthetic feelings, feelings of sympathy/antipathy, and feelings of satisfaction/dissatisfaction (Befriedigung/Mißbefriedigung) (Pfänder 1904, 227). Obviously, they are not limited to emotions in the narrow sense. Pfänder’s early conception of feelings should be understood in its own context. In Einführung in die Psychologie, he discusses feelings as one of the three fundamental classes of mental reality (psychische Wirklichkeit). Feelings, together with what he calls “objectconsciousness” and “striving,” make up our mental life as a whole.1 Therefore, one way of characterizing feelings is to compare them with the other two fundamental classes. According to Pfänder, “feelings are, in a certain sense, ways in which the mental subject is attuned, or they are states (Zuständlichkeiten) of the mental subject or the I” (Pfänder 1904, 238). This characteristic of feelings becomes salient when contrasted with objectconsciousness such as sensation, perception, thought, and so on. While these experiences have entities outside of mental reality as their objects (Pfänder 1904, 208), the same does not hold true for feelings. According to Pfänder, therefore, feelings, as such, are intrinsic states of 63
Genki Uemura and Toru Yaegashi
their subjects, which have nothing to do with external objects (however, this does not mean that they are totally isolated from those objects; see below). It is most probably in reference to such an idea that Pfänder later claims that those moods, insofar as they are feelings, are objectless (Pfänder 1913, 354). Another important characteristic of feelings is highlighted by their difference to strivings such as desire and volition. “While feelings are in and for themselves simply static states of the mental subject, strivings are rays of activity or force, as it were, emanating from the mental subject” (Pfänder 1904, 251). In other words, there is a sense in which feelings are passive, but strivings are active. Note that the above characterizations should not be understood as a definition of feelings per se. Denying the definability of feelings, Pf änder claims that the difference between object-consciousness and feelings can be grasped only by “self-reflexion (Selbstbesinnung)” (Pf änder 1904, 231–232). Therefore, the expressions he introduces to analyze feelings could be understood as instructions for one to contemplate on those experiences by and for oneself. Even though Pfänder holds that feelings as such are intrinsic states of subjects, he does not make them totally unrelated to objects outside of those subjects. Being based on objectconsciousness, they are states of subjects “with regard to objects (angesichts der Gegenstände)” (Pfänder 1904, 229). This idea enables him to conceive of feelings in a broader sense in which they are not necessarily purely sensational. Even though a paradigmatic case of feelings is pleasure and displeasure based on sensation (Pfänder 1904, 228), he admits that there are also “logical” or “intellectual feelings” (Pfänder 1904, 238–240). For instance, when I doubt something, or my doubt has dissolved, he claims that I feel unpleased, or pleased in the literal sense, even in the total absence of sensation related to my feeling. As the above discussion suggests, feelings come in great varieties. Pfänder himself does not fail to note this (Pfänder 1904, 241). How, then, are they classified? According to him, different classes of feelings are organized not only in terms of polarity and intensity but also other experiential characters called “features (Beschaffenheiten)” (Pfänder 1904, 241–242). The same polarity and intensity may be found in two distinct feelings such as, to use his own examples, a pleasure aroused by the taste of something or a joy with regard to a work of art. Some may observe that they are differentiated by their objects (i.e. taste and the work of art). Indeed, Pfänder himself admits that feelings are divided into groups also by their objects (Pfänder 1904, 239). But he adds that such a division must be supplemented by the division of those experiential features (Pfänder 1904, 242). Pfänder acknowledges the importance of investigating the various feelings’ characteristics (Pfänder 1904, 242), but he does not touch upon this issue in any detail in Einführung in die Psychologie. It is in “Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen” that he discusses the topic. As we will see at the end of the next section, however, at that moment, he no longer holds that his earlier view is universally valid for any form of feelings. Rather, he now admits that some feelings have direction toward objects.
3. Sentiments as object-directed feelings In “Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen” (1913/1916), Pfänder devotes himself to a detailed discussion of what he calls “sentiments.” His own examples of such experiences include love, friendliness, liking (Zuneigung), favor (Gunst), benevolence, hate, hostility, dislike, disfavor, and malevolence (Pfänder 1913, 334). As these examples show, sentiments have polarity; they are either positive or negative. 64
Alexander Pfänder
To be more precise, Pfänder’s target here is not sentiments in general. Distinguishing actual, virtual, and habitual forms of sentiments, he limits his discussion to the first one (Pfänder 1913, 330–332). As he observes, a sentiment may not be actual, i.e., thematically occurring in one’s mental life. Rather, it may occur only in the background of consciousness (virtual sentiments), or it may remain in one’s mind without even occurring (habitual sentiments). Given this distinction, it is natural for Pfänder to begin with actual sentiments. For he writes: Psychological knowledge of sentiments must necessarily begin with the phenomenology of sentiments. The phenomenology of sentiments has to proceed toward a direct grasp of the mental itself and then give a fully adequate description of the whole mental make-up (psychischer Bestand) itself. (Pfänder 1913, 328) Arguably, describing sentiments phenomenologically would be quite difficult, if they are virtual or habitual in the above sense. In what follows, unless otherwise noted, we use the term “sentiments” to mean what he calls “actual sentiments” or “stirrings of sentiment (Gesinnungsregungen).” Pfänder’s initial characterization of sentiments points to three features of those experience: their embeddedness (Eingespanntheit) between subjects and objects, centrifugal direction toward objects, and centrifugal streaming from subjects toward objects (Pfänder 1913, 332–335). To illustrate them, let us take Pfänder’s analysis of his own example, namely a subject who, being interrupted by another subject, has a hostile sentiment. In this case, even though only the first subject has the sentiment in question, it is not enclosed to her, as it were. Rather, it bridges a mental distance between the two subjects; to the first subject, the second one is no longer unrelated. In other words, the first subject’s hostile sentiment has the second subject as an object of a certain sort (i.e., say, an enemy). Such embeddedness between the subject and the object of a sentiment has a certain direction. The first subject is hostile toward the object (i.e., the second subject). It is to capture this circumstance that Pfänder uses the term “centrifugal.”2 Embeddedness and centrifugalism are insufficient to characterize sentiments as actual experiences. For, even though Pfänder is not explicit about it, they are also found in non-actual sentiments. If you have hated someone for many years, the aforementioned connection with centrifugal direction has been maintained; this person has been and remained an enemy for you. But in this case, your hate may not always be actual. The actuality of sentiments, therefore, is not due to its embeddedness and centrifugalism. What, then, makes a sentiment actual? It is such a missing element that Pfänder calls “streaming” from subjects to objects; actual sentiments stream from their subjects to objects, since they are “not something that rest in themselves, but something that is moving within itself (in sich Bewegtes)” (Pfänder 1913, 334). While Pfänder does not say anything more on this point, we can make sense of it by considering the following case. Suppose that you have habitual hate toward someone, but usually you do not remember it. Someday, you happen to hear about the recent situation of this person and, suddenly, a sentiment of hate actually comes upon you. Such a change of your experience may well be described by the phrase “your hate suddenly begins to stream toward the person you hate.” Contrary to what one may assume from the above discussion, Pfänder, unlike Stein (1922, 245–246), admits that objects of sentiments are not limited to human persons. According to 65
Genki Uemura and Toru Yaegashi
him, non-human animals and even plants can be objects of sentiments too, but he leaves it open whether we take those creatures as if they were human persons when we have sentiments toward them (Pfänder 1913, 337). Be that as it may, he further claims that sentiments can, and in fact are, directed toward lifeless, physical objects, social communities, cultural objects, and superhuman beings such as God(s) (Pfänder 1913, 337–339). In this way, Pfänder maintains that any sentiment has an object. Even if a sentiment does not seem to have any object, he claims, it merely lacks any particular object and yet it has the world or “life in general (Leben überhaupt)” as its objects (Pfänder 1913, 340). While the centrifugal direction is characteristic of sentiments in general, they cannot be identified with other types of centrifugal experience. According to Pfänder, attending (Aufmerken), apperceiving, meaning something (Meinen),3 striving, and willing are also centrifugally directed to their objects (Pfänder 1913, 341; note that he does not deal with the difference between sentiments and volition). Those experiences can occur without sentiments. Let us reconstruct how Pfänder argues for this claim. It is not difficult to see that one can pay attention to something without any love or hate for it (Pfänder 1913, 341). The same holds for apperception, under which he classifies varieties of (perhaps conceptual or intellectual) activity of articulating one or more objects, for instance, grasping something as such and such or distinguishing one thing from something else (Pfänder 1913, 342). Pfänder’s discussion of meaning something and its difference from sentiments is a bit more complicated. According to Pfänder, meaning something is an activity of taking something to have F, where F may be natural (i.e., non-axiological and non-moral) properties, axiological properties, and moral properties. Arguably, we can and, in fact, do take something to have a property of the first type even if we do not have any sentiment toward it (Pfänder 1913, 343). For instance, to take this statue to be white, you do not have to have any love or hate for it. The situation might be different when it comes to axiological and moral properties. Can I take the statue to be beautiful while not having any (positive) sentiment toward it? According to Pfänder, we must accept such possibilities. We can take an art piece to be of positive value even if we dislike it (Pfänder 1913, 343). We can take an action to be morally good, even if we do not love it (Pfänder 1913, 344). Pfänder distinguishes sentiments from strivings for two main reasons. First, they are different in terms of polarity (Pfänder 1913, 350–351). If love is identical to the striving for promoting well-being (Wohlförderung), its opposite, namely hate must be the reluctance (Widerstreben) to promote well-being. But this cannot be the case. The opposite of the striving for promoting well-being is the striving for harming well-being (Wohlschädigung). To put it differently, while the polarity of sentiments is between two different types of experience, that of strivings is between two different contents of type-identical experiences. Second, sentiments may not have “urges (Drängen)” which Pfänder considers essential to strivings (Pfänder 1913, 351–352). The above discussion has also shown that sentiments are neither intellectual (like apperception or meaning something) nor conative (like striving). Thus, it may seem that we are left with the idea that they are a peculiar kind of feelings. According to Pfänder, however, such a move is phenomenologically unacceptable. The classification of the experience must be grounded in the facts of the experience (Pfänder 1913, 353). In fact, sentiments are not to be identified with feelings without any qualification. According to Pfänder in 1904, the latter do not have direction toward objects. As we have seen in the previous section, he keeps this view in 1913 when he claims that moods are objectless. Also, Pfänder points to two further differences between sentiments and feelings of pleasure and displeasure. First, painful love and pleasant hate serve as counterexamples to 66
Alexander Pfänder
the claims that love=pleasure and that hate=displeasure (Pfänder 1913, 357–358). Second, feelings of pleasure and displeasure do not show centrifugalism even though they may be, to borrow his expression in 1904, with regard to objects (Pfänder 1913, 359–360). At the same time, Pfänder holds that sentiments have some similarities to the feelings under discussion (Pfänder 1913, 363). They are qualitatively similar to each other. Also, they originate from the same part of the self, which he calls, somewhat metaphorically, the “center of feeling (Gefühlszentrum).” Thus, while he keeps his idea that feelings are intrinsic states of the self (without explicitly mentioning the 1904 book), he is now in need of expanding his notion of feelings. In this way, he comes to characterize sentiments as “centrifugal streams of feeling (zentrifugale Gefühlsströmungen),” which are directed toward objects provided by object-consciousness (Pfänder 1913, 363–364).4
4. The threefold structure of “deep and high” sentiments Even though Pfänder takes the centrifugal stream of feeling as the essence of sentiments (Pfänder 1913, 364, 372), these experiences often have two further characteristic components. First, a sentiment contains either “inner unification (innere Einigung)” or “inner division (innere Entzweiungen),” depending on whether it is positive or negative (Pfänder 1913, 366–367). When I have, say, a sentiment of love for someone, I feel myself to be closer to her (“feeling of unification (Einigungsgefühl)”). In contrast, if I have a sentiment of hate against her, I feel myself to be more distant from her (“feeling of division (Entzweiungsgefühl)”). In this way, sentiments of love and hate not only bridge the mental distance between subjects and objects, but they also determine its extent. It should be noted, however, that the distance at stake is merely a felt relationship rather than intersubjectively valid one. My feeling myself to be closer to her does not in itself imply my being closer to her.5 Second, a sentiment often contains an act of affirmation or denial (Bejahungs- oder Verneinungsakt), depending on whether it is positive or negative (Pfänder 1913, 368–370). While, according to Pfänder, I give someone a right to exist when I have a sentiment of love for her, I deny that right when I have an opposite sentiment. It is such entitlement/deprivation of the right to exist that Pfänder attempts to describe in terms of acts of affirmation/denial. As with the case of inner unification/rupture, those acts do not, in themselves, establish that objects of relevant sentiments do or do not have the right to exist. Now, since Pfänder holds that the three components of sentiments—centrifugal stream, inner unification/division, and the act of affirmation/denial—cannot be reduced to each other (Pfänder 1913, 372), he has to explain what role each of them plays in a sentiment. As we have already seen, centrifugal streaming is regarded as the essential feature of sentiments. It is because of this feature that an experience is a sentiment. What about the other two? According to Pfänder, while inner unification lets a sentiment to go “deeper,” an act of affirmation lets it go “higher” (Pfänder 1913, 373). His metaphorical claim is not easy to understand, but it seems to be illustrated by the following examples. The closer I feel myself to be to someone, the deeper my love gets rooted. The more seriously I give her the right to exist, the higher my love for her reaches. In this way, Pfänder provides a multi-dimensional analysis of degrees of sentiments.
5. Varieties of modified sentiments After discussing the general forms of actual sentiments, Pfänder proceeds to four varieties of modified sentiments, which he calls “non-genuine,” “floating,” “suppressed,” and 67
Genki Uemura and Toru Yaegashi
“aesthetic,” respectively. In this and the following sections, we deal with Pfänder’s analysis of those sentiment variants. Note, however, that our reconstruction is more like a spoiling trailer of a movie than a recapitulation of its story. Pfänder’s lengthy discussion on those sentiment variants, which is conducted with rich and detailed descriptions of examples, resists any attempt at summarization. Non-genuine sentiments, which are opposed to “genuine (echt)” ones, are most typically found in cases where sentiments emerge from playful behavior and lies. When, to take Pfänder’s own example, an adult playfully threatens a child, the former has and expresses a non-genuine, playful sentiment of hostility. Being just a “schematic imitation” (Pfänder 1916, 383) of the genuine hostility, such a non-genuine sentiment is nevertheless an actual sentiment that is experienced by the subject as centrifugally streaming toward the other. We will discuss the non-genuine sentiments in more detail in the next section. Floating sentiments, which are opposed to “fully real (vollwirklich)” ones, are illustrated by the following example (Pfänder 1916, 4). When an orator uses exaggerated words to express her non-genuine sentiment in felicitations, she may lead to a genuine sentiment of, say, love for the person she praises. Such a sentiment, however, still seems to lack something. It is not grounded in the mental reality (seelische Realität/Wirklichkeit) of the orator. In other words, the sentiment in question goes beyond the standards that fit to her ordinary way of living. Pfänder calls such a floating sentiment “super-real (überwirklich)” or “transcendent” too (Pfänder 1916, 5, 9). Floating sentiments are not limited to super-real or transcendent ones. According to Pfänder, there are two other forms of floating sentiments: “Parallel-real (nebenwirklich)” or “episodic” ones and “sub-real (unterwirklich)” or “provisional” ones. Episodic sentiments are those one has when one is preoccupied with something else (Pfänder 1916, 19). You may have such an experience when, for instance, you look at your beloved person while working hard on various tasks you have to complete as soon as possible. Provisional sentiments are those that stop short of fully real sentiments (Pfänder 1916, 33–34). For example, if you show friendliness to someone with the hope that a certain wish be satisfied by that, your sentiment of friendliness is provisional and thus not fully real yet as long as your wish remains unsatisfied. The super-, parallel-, and sub-real characters of sentiments are not only found in nongenuine sentiments. Genuine sentiments can also be floating, episodic, or provisional, as Pfänder shows by several examples (Pfänder 1916, 14, 19). Therefore, these characters are irreducible to non-genuineness. As its name suggests, suppressed sentiments are characterized by second-order attitudes that subjects take toward them. For example, Pfänder again takes the hostility of the subject who is interrupted by someone else (Pfänder 1916, 43). In this case, the subject of the sentiment may try to keep her hostile episodic in the above sense by trying to concentrate on her work. If this is successful, her hostility gains pressure (Zusammendrückung) as its experiential feature, by which it is distinguished from merely provisional hostilities. In this case, the second-order attitude toward the sentiment of hostility is negative, but that is not always the case for any suppressed sentiment. Here, the second-order attitude toward a sentiment is either affirmative or negative (Pfänder 1916, 44–45). If it is affirmative, the subject of hostility keeps her sentiment provisionary but does not attempt to annihilate it. If negative, she not only suppresses it; she also annihilates it. Aesthetic sentiments are also characterized by second-order attitudes. A sentiment is aesthetic if it is evaluated as “beautiful” or “ugly” by its subject (Pfänder 1916, 46). Following his teacher, Theodor Lipps, Pfänder holds that a subject grasps the object of such a sentiment only aesthetically (Pfänder 1916, 47–48). In other words, the sentiments in question have nothing to do with what the object in itself is. 68
Alexander Pfänder
6. More on genuine and non-genuine sentiments In this section, we will evaluate Pfänder’s discussion of non-genuine sentiments, which has an interesting implication for moral philosophy. We will also briefly consider the discussion of non-genuine feelings by Willy Haas on whom Pfänder draws (Pfänder 1913, 382). According to Pfänder, the genuineness of the sentiments does not depend on intensity or other parameters (Pfänder 1913, 383–384). A non-genuine sentiment can be as intense and persistent as a genuine one (e.g., the sentiments that method actors may have). It is only artificial. Even though artificial, these sentiments do not necessarily emerge from playful behavior or lies. An intention to deceive may be absent (Pfänder 1913, 385). There are also nongenuine sentiments that emerge from prosocial considerations. For example, some people not only behave in a friendly manner but also have actual friendly feelings toward others because they think it is better to be friendly in their social life. Their sentiments of friendship are non-genuine, though they do not necessarily derive from an intention to deceive. They may even be honest and serious. Nevertheless, Pfänder adds, such serious but non-genuine sentiments are unintentionally deceptive, because others may confuse them with genuine sentiments. Importantly, Pfänder appreciates the moral value of non-genuine sentiments (Pfänder 1913, 397–399). Some moral principles demand us to have some sentiments: “Love your neighbor,” “Be kind to others,” etc. They demand genuine sentiments. However, it is impossible for human beings to directly control their genuine sentiments intentionally. Thus, the above principles would seem to contradict the Ought-Implies-Can principle. But you can intentionally come to have corresponding non-genuine sentiments, since they are artificial, schematic imitations of genuine ones. And yet, non-genuine sentiments can make it easier for the subject to have the corresponding genuine sentiments. This facilitating role of the non-genuine sentiments can make such moral principles intelligible, even though it does not sufficiently justify them. As Pfänder emphasizes, to call a certain sentiment non-genuine does not imply underestimating it (Pfänder 1913, 382). This idea bears on the issue of emotional education discussed in contemporary virtue ethics. Rosalind Hursthouse emphasizes the need for emotional (self-)re-training of badly trained people, for example persons with inculcated racism (Hursthouse 1999, 113–120). The methods of such emotional training are widely discussed by moral philosophers, psychologists, and educational theorists. However, the strategy of facilitating genuine, desirable sentiments through non-genuine sentiments, suggested by Pfänder, may contribute to these debates. Three years before the publication of the first part of Pfänder’s “Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen,” his student Willy Haas published his dissertation Über Echtheit und Unechtheit von Gefühlen (On Genuineness and Non-Genuineness of Emotions).6 This work explains the distinction of genuine and non-genuine feelings in terms of their relations to the self. According to Haas, the self has, in each moment, a certain basic direction (Grundrichtung), a general tune of the mind. The feeling that corresponds to the basic direction of its time is characterized as a genuine feeling. On the contrary, the feeling that does not is non-genuine (Haas 1910, 11–12). For example, if you are enjoying a party, yet simultaneously irritated by a long speech, one of the two feelings may be genuine and the other non-genuine, depending on which corresponds to your basic direction at that moment. If you are basically happy, i.e., your overall mind is colored by the feeling of happiness at that moment, your joy is genuine, and your irritation is non-genuine. But if you are basically upset, your irritation is genuine, and your joy is non-genuine. 69
Genki Uemura and Toru Yaegashi
Note that the feeling’s relation to the basic direction of the self should not be confused with its relation to the character of the person. If you are a happy person, always enjoying the situation you are in, the joy you feel at the party is a characteristic feeling of yours. This is not what Haas intends to illustrate by the above example. Since character is an essentially diachronic property of the self, the subject must have a temporal, extended personal unity, in order to have a characteristic emotion. However, having a genuine (and non-genuine) feeling does not presuppose the diachronic unity of the personal self but only the synchronic unity of the self. It may even be the case that a certain non-genuine feeling, not a genuine one, is really characteristic of the subject (Haas 1910, 22). Haas further claims that, for the subject to be conscious of her own genuine and nongenuine feelings as such, she has to have still another feeling, the feeling of their genuineness and non-genuineness. This experience of “explicit approval (or disapproval) from the depth (of the self ) (ausdrückliche Zustimmung aus der Tiefe)” (Haas 1910, 19) constitutes the necessary condition of subject’s knowledge of her own genuine and non-genuine feelings. In sum, Haas explains the genuineness and non-genuineness of feelings as being constituted by matching the relationship between the emotion and the basic direction of the mind at the time. The subject might come to know her genuine and non-genuine feelings through the feeling of inner approval or disapproval of her own emotions as corresponding or contradicting her basic direction. Haas’s theory of the genuine and non-genuine feelings complements his teacher’s explanation of genuine and non-genuine sentiments. As Haas does for non-genuine feelings in general, Pfänder also claims that non-genuine sentiments are not always recognized by their subjects as what they are. The subject may even be unconscious of them (Pfänder 1913, 389). Though Pfänder does not further elaborate on the consciousness and recognition of non-genuine experiences, he could have developed a theory based on Haas’s.
7. Conclusion In the present chapter, we have explained the framework of Pf änder’s theory of feeling in general and reconstructed his detailed discussion of sentiments in “Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen.” He provides a multi-dimensional analysis of sentiments, introducing the concept of depth and height, and several modifications of sentiments such as being non-genuine, floating, and suppressed. We have also briefly discussed an ethical implication of his theory of non-genuine sentiments. In conclusion, Pf änder’s work can be, even though almost ignored in the contemporary philosophy of emotion, a rich source of inspiration.7
Notes
70
Alexander Pfänder
References Goldie, Peter (2002). Emotions, Feelings and Intentionality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1, 235–254. Haas, Willy (1910). Über Echtheit und Unechtheit von Gefühlen. Inaugural-Dissertation. LudwigMaximilians-Universität zu München. Hursthouse, Rosalind (1999). On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mulligan, Kevin (2009). Was sind und was sollen die unechten Gefühle? In: U. Amrein (Ed.). Das Authentische. Referenzen und Repräsentationen. Zürich: Chronos, 225–242. ——— (2011). Meaning Something and Meanings. Grazer Philosophische Studien 82, 255–284. Pfänder, Alexander (1904). Einführung in die Psychologie. Leipzig: J. A. Barth. ——— (1913). Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen (I). In: E. Husserl (Ed.). Jahrbuch für Phänomenologie und phänomenologische Forschung, vol. 1. Halle: Max Niemeyer, 325–404. ——— (1916). Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen (II). In: E. Husserl (Ed.). Jahrbuch für Phänomenologie und phänomenologische Forschung, vol. 3, Halle: Max Niemeyer, 1–125. Stein, Edith (1922). Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie und der Geisteswissenschaften. In: E. Husserl (Ed.). Jahrbuch für Phänomenologie und phänomenologische Forschung, vol. 5, Halle: Max Niemeyer, 1922. Uemura, Genki (forthcoming). Alexander Pfänder. In: T. Keiling and C. Erhard (Eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Agency. London, New York: Routledge. Uemura, Genki, and Yaegashi, Toru (2012). Alexander Pfänder on the Intentionality of Willing. In: A. Salice (Ed.). Intentionality. Munich: Philosophia, 243–247. Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (2008). Die Emotionen. Gefühle in der realistischen Phänomenologie. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Walther, Gerda (1923). Zur Ontologie der soziale Gemeinschaften. In: E. Husserl (Ed.). Jahrbuch für Phänomenologie und phänomenologische Forschung, vol. 6, Halle: Max Niemeyer, 1–138.
71
4 MAX SCHELER Matthias Schloßberger
1. Introduction Max Scheler is—horribile dictu—a system thinker. Ethical, epistemological, ontological, and metaphysical issues are variously intertwined in his work. This renders an understanding of any specific systematic topic he discusses, if approached in isolation, difficult. Scheler’s theory of emotions provides a key to grasping those interconnections and some of his most central philosophical claims. Few other phenomenologists have dealt as extensively with the phenomenology of emotions as Scheler. He developed a general account of emotions, suggested his theory of the so-called ‘feelings of sympathy’ (Sympathiegefühle), but also discussed a number of distinct emotions. His works on love and hatred, shame, suffering, repentance, and Ressentiment are well known and considered the most influential parts of his theory of emotions. From a systematic perspective, it should be emphasized that Scheler takes the point of departure from the assumption that every human relation to the world is primarily an emotional one. According to Scheler, things, people, and even ideas are not given to us first in a neutral, objectifying way and only then—after we have applied some aesthetic or ethical criteria—as bad, good, appealing, or appalling. Surprisingly, this crucial point is frequently overlooked when it comes to the reception of important themes in Scheler’s philosophy. In the following, I will try to show that only his theory of emotions renders some of these themes comprehensible. Thus, I will be considering Scheler’s epistemology, his moral philosophy, and his theory of intersubjectivity—and the latter both in the narrow sense of the so-called problem of other minds as well as in the broader sense encompassing social ontology, sociology, and social philosophy. Following Scheler, the traditional understanding of the nature of feelings must be fundamentally revised. Scheler explicitly formulates his opposition to the traditional understanding of feelings and his theory. His main adversary here is the Kantian dichotomy between the sensuality and pure reason, and the assignment of feelings to sensuality: According to this Kantian account, feelings are considered mere physical states. If one follows Kant and his ilk, when it comes to this assignment “our whole emotional life—even love and hate must be assigned to ‘sensibility’. According to this division everything in the mind which is alogical,
72
Max Scheler
e.g., intuition, feeling, striving, loving, hating is dependent on man’s psychophysical organization” (Scheler 1973a, 253ff.). Scheler seeks to overcome this position by showing that there are certain kinds of feelings which are indispensable functions of our mind. These kinds of feelings do not necessarily depend on bodily sensations, and even if bodily sensations are involved, they are not the determining factor.
2. The stratification of our emotional lives: four strata of feelings A central idea of Scheler’s theory of emotions is the assumption of a stratified emotional life. The initial question that leads to this assumption is the following: How can we understand the two intertwined aspects of feelings in general: their intentional character (i.e., their being feeling of something) and their nonintentional character (Empfindung)? To understand Scheler’s approach, we have to question the ambiguity of the concept of feeling. Scheler seems to follow Husserl’s remarks on the difference between feelingsensations (Gefühlsempfindungen) and feeling-acts (Gefühlsakte). In the Fifth Logical Investigation on “Intentional Experiences and their Contents,” Husserl addresses the question of what we mean when we speak of feelings. Discussing the example of joy, he distinguishes the sensual quality and the interpretive act-character of feelings: Joy, e.g., concerning some happy event, is certainly an act. But this act, which is not merely an intentional character, but a concrete and therefore complex experience, does not merely hold in its unity an idea of the happy event and an act-character of liking which relates to it: a sensation of pleasure attaches to the idea, a sensation at once seen and located as an emotional excitement in the psycho-physical feeling-subject, and also as an objective property—the event seems as if bathed in a rosy gleam. The event thus pleasingly pointed now serves as the first foundation for the joyful approach, the liking for, the being charmed, or however one’s state may be described. (Husserl 2001, 110; see Chapter 2 in this volume) In Husserl’s example, the sensation of pleasure is interwoven with the feeling’s intentional character (the joy about something). Together, both aspects constitute a complex emotional experience. The first step of Scheler’s theory of emotions follows the Husserlian distinction: The intentional feeling of something (das intentionale Fühlen von etwas) differs from mere feeling-states (Gefühlszuständen) (Scheler 1973a, 261). On the basis of this analysis, Scheler goes further: He aims to understand how some feelings greatly differ from others when it comes to their dependence on sensuality. In other words, how is it that we use the same concept for phenomena as different as amor dei, falling in love, and the sensations of hunger or grumpiness? This guiding question leads Scheler to distinguish four different strata of emotive life: (1) sensible feelings (sinnliche Gefühle) or sensations, (2) vital feelings (Vitalgefühle) or feelings of the lived body (Leibgefühle) (like tiredness) and life-feelings (Lebensgefühle) (like wariness), (3) psychic feelings (seelische Gefühle) (like happiness, sadness, sorrow, grief, and anger), and (4) purely spiritual feelings (geistige Gefühle) (like deep serenity or deep despair) (Scheler 1973a, 332). Purely sensible feelings (for example, the sensation of a needle-prick) require additional intentional acts to become meaningful.1 In other words, they lack intentionality: “There is no ‘signifying’ in it, nor is there any immanent directedness in it” (Scheler 1973a, 257).
73
Matthias Schloßberger
Sensible feelings are characterized as being given in certain localizable places of the body. They are isolated occurrences without any meaningful connection to the experienced continuum of sense.2 Their lack of meaning and intentionality becomes particularly evident by the fact that one and the same sensory feeling can be felt quite differently, for example as pleasant or painful (Scheler 1973a, 333f.). The needle-prick-sensation can be painful and annoying if one is mending a shirt or it can be part of an elaborate pleasure-scheme in an erotic context.3 However, that by no means implies that sensations are passively received “material” that must be somehow “interpreted” by active cognitive acts. It seems important to point out that intentionality, in general, does not amount to active object-directedness for Scheler. It is in a much broader sense the title for any kind of awareness of something in a certain way and oscillates between activity and passivity. Active directedness toward something, propositional thinking, and conscious judgment make up just a few varieties of our intentional life but surely not all. The second and third strata of emotions lie in sharp contrast to the first. Vital as well as psychic feelings are not localizable within body parts. They “participate in the total extension of the lived body” (Gesamtausdehnungscharakter des Leibes) (Scheler 1973a, 338). These feelings are experienced in and with the whole body. However, this holistic experience is far from being the result of a combination of bodily sensations on the one hand and cognitive processing on the other, but rather stems from the original and inseparable unity of sensuality, intentionality, and expressive behavior. Here lies one of the core arguments of Scheler’s theory of intersubjectivity: The way we experience shame, for example, can be described by three necessarily connected components. There is first the interoceptive aspect: We feel the heat of shame spreading over our bodies, we feel it under our skin, on our face, and so on. Then, there is the aspect of intentionality: We are ashamed of something and we are ashamed that others perceive us in a certain way. Finally, this feeling is—although in varying degrees of obviousness—a visible phenomenon, i.e., others can perceive it. Vital and psychic feelings express themselves corporeally: This is the very condition of existing as a social being, a human being living among other human and non-human beings. There is so to speak a universal expression-grammar of vital and psychic feelings that renders living in a social world possible in the first place: Based on the experience of our lived bodies, we are able to share our feelings, to get to know our own emotional range and the feelings of others. Thus, Scheler holds that the bodily expressions of joy or shame, for example, are not contingently habitualized gestures which vary from culture to culture. Rather, they are inseparable from the interoceptive and the intentional aspect of those feelings. Scheler speaks of “intentional functions of feeling” (intentionale Fühlfunktionen) when he refers to vital and psychic feelings that enable us to receive certain values (Scheler 1973a, 259). In the process of feeling (fear, hope, etc.), the world opens up to us in a very specific way: We perceive the value-side of things. We perceive, for example, the encounter with X as hopeful and the situation Y as dangerous. These intentional functions of feeling bring advantages and disadvantages or outright dangers directly to our awareness—even before we can grasp them intellectually or conceptually. The third stratum of feelings, the so-called psychic feelings (seelische Gefühle), differs from the second stratum in having a much clearer or deeper ego-quality. According to Scheler, a deep feeling of sorrow, for example, does not have the same relation to corporeal sensations and therefore does not participate in bodily extension to the same extent as feelings of wellbeing and ill-being (Scheler 1973a, 342). Psychic feelings are much more “intimately attached to the constellation of contents of the individual consciousness” (Scheler 1973a, 336). Finally, there is a fourth stratum: spiritual feelings. They are distinguished from psychic feelings “by the fact 74
Max Scheler
that they can never be states. For in true bliss and despair, and even in cases of serenity (serenitas animi) and ‘peace of mind,’ all ego-states seem to be extinguished” (Scheler 1973a, 343). But is Scheler’s theory of the stratification of emotions plausible? One could argue that the stratification serves as a means of elucidating the ambiguities of the concept of “feeling”: The scope here reaches from fleeting corporeal sensations to a special kind of intentionality, a kind of perception of something, which necessarily precedes all propositional or factual knowledge. Scheler advocates the significant cognitive value of emotions. Another argument in favor of his stratification-theory lies in the fact that we can actually experience our stratified emotional life. We can experience very different and separate kinds of feelings at the same time: “A human being can be blissful while suffering from bodily pain” (Scheler 1973a, 330). Finally, there are various correlations between feelings and values that the theory of stratification can account for: Different kinds of feelings make different kinds of values experienceable (Zaborowski 2011; Geniusas 2015).
3. Ethics as epistemology of moral judgment Scheler claims that there is such a thing as an a priori ethics of feelings. The argument for this claim is connected to several assumptions about the intentional nature of feelings. Values are not given to us through any other perceptual means than through feelings. Why does Scheler hold that values have to be felt? His point of departure is the ultimate principle of phenomenology (…) that there is an interconnection between the essence of an object and the essence of intentional experiencing. (…) In other words, according to their essence, values must be able to appear in a feeling consciousness. (Scheler 1973a, 265) Every kind of object corresponds essentially to a different mode of experiencing. This a priori interconnection works the other way around as well: Corresponding to the theory of the four strata of emotions, Scheler develops a theory of non-formal values (materiale Werte). These values rank from morally neutral, primitive ones (corporeal pleasure or displeasure) to aesthetic and moral values, upon which moral norms are based. They are all brought to light through different emotional acts and functions. That allows Scheler to speak of “a priori relations of rank among value modalities” (Scheler 1973a, 104). Scheler describes the values of the agreeable and the disagreeable as belonging to the lowest value-modality. They are sensually given (with their modes of enjoyment and suffering). They correspond to the states that are perceived as sensual pleasure or displeasure/pain. The values correlated with vital feelings (quickening, declining, weakness, strength) differ greatly from the first modality. Scheler underlines that they are in no way reducible to the first modality: They are values in their own right, and are encompassed by the noble and the vulgar (and not by the agreeable and the disagreeable or by good and evil) (cf. Scheler 1973a, 105f.). The third modality of values includes the beautiful and the ugly, the morally right and wrong. They are given through spiritual acts and functions. The fourth modality consists of the values of the holy and the unholy, which, according to Scheler, can be grasped only by a certain kind of love. Scheler insists on the hierarchical structure of these values in the described order. However, he does not provide any arguments for the hierarchy. For Scheler, due to their evidential givenness, values are experienced in a certain hierarchy; thus, one cannot really argue why, for example, the experience of beauty, while listening to a cantata by Bach, ranks higher than the enjoyment of a nice cold beer on a hot day. Some philosophers reject Scheler’s 75
Matthias Schloßberger
hierarchy of values as dogmatic and phenomenologically unwarranted—or even as a telltale sign of a conservative worldview (cf. Römer 2018, 15).4 To my knowledge, however, none of his critics has yet argued for the equivalence of, say, hedonistic and moral values. Only a staunch (moral) relativist would be able to consistently reject Scheler’s assumption that there are lower and higher modes of value. In any case, ethically relevant values are not dependent on sensually caused mental states; in this respect, Scheler can certainly not be accused of grounding his non-formal values on a naturalistic presupposition. According to Kant, feelings are attributed to a purely mechanically functioning sensuality, while morality can only be based on pure reason. Scheler rejects this basic assumption. In contrast to Kant’s pure practical reason, he develops the concept of an “ideal ought” that is founded in love and renders actions of moral obligation motivationally possible. Against the idea that we could ever act upon purely formal intellectual insight (i.e., the Kantian imperative), he holds that only the emotional givenness of what is good, i.e., of value, can deploy moral necessity and move us to action: “Values are never based on the necessity of the ought! Thus, only what is good can become ‘duty’; or it is because it is good (in the ideal sense) that it necessarily ‘ought’ to be” (Scheler 1973a, 75).
4. Forms of sympathy Scheler has a well-developed theory of the crucial role of feelings in human interactions. In this theory, he tackles (1) the basic problem of other minds: what renders our experience of others as fellow human beings possible? (2) Scheler provides some lucid descriptions of the phenomena of partaking in the emotional life of others and of shared feelings. In keeping with the systematic impetus of his philosophy, he tries to shed light on the foundational relation between different phenomena of intersubjective life. Scheler starts with the assumption of the direct perception of other minds. All attempts to reconstruct the experience of others as mediated through some kind projective process necessarily fail, because they presuppose what they try to explain. They become mired in a vicious circle: Any attempt to recognize others through inferential processes or conscious/ unconscious projections of one’s own mental states requires us to be already familiar with the other as another human being. In other words, the sphere of intersubjectivity has to be already fully established for us to be able to project or infer anything onto or about other persons. Another important point of Scheler’s theory is his criticisms of the theory of empathy (Einfühlung) prevalent among his contemporaries—and notably of Theodor Lipps’ isomorphic concept of empathic understanding. Lipps holds that in order to understand another’s emotion, we have to synchronously feel the (qualitatively) same feeling as the other. Scheler opposes this view.5 He characterizes the specific way in which we grasp what the other feels with the term sensing the other’s feeling (Nachfühlen). The term means feeling the other’s feeling without being immersed in the same emotional state.6 Scheler compares Nachfühlen to a kind of remembrance: “The other’s feeling is given exactly like a landscape which we see subjectively in memory, or a melody which we hear in similar fashion” (Scheler 2008[1954], 9). He also clearly rejects theories which argue that we first experience the other’s body and grasp their inner life through secondary acts of analogization and inference. To say that our only initial datum is the body is completely erroneous. This is true only for the doctor or the scientist, i.e., for man in so far as he abstracts artificially from expressive phenomena, which have an altogether primary givenness. (Scheler 1973a, 398) 76
Max Scheler
The first encounter with other human beings does not present us mere bodies (in the sense of Cartesian res extensa) that we have to animate somehow (e.g., through mental acts of projection or analogization) to make lived bodies out of them. Our first encounter with fellow human beings occurs long before we would even be able to accomplish such cognitively demanding acts. Accordingly, Scheler holds that our first encounter with others occurs in a so-called psychophysically neutral sphere. We experience them directly through their expressive behavior: Now to begin with, it only needs the simplest of phenomenological considerations to show that at any rate there is nothing self-evident about this. For we certainly believe ourselves to be directly acquainted with another person’s joy in his laughter, with his sorrow and pain in his tears, with his shame in his blushing, with his entreaty in his outstretched hands, with his love in his look of affection, with his rage in the gnashing of his teeth, with his threats in the clenching of his fist, and with the tenor of his thoughts in the sound of his words. If anyone tells me that this is not “perception”, for it cannot be so, in view of the fact that a perception is simply a “complex of physical sensations”, and that there is certainly no sensation of another person’s mind nor any stimulus from such a source, I would beg him to turn aside from such questionable theories and address himself to the phenomenological facts. (Scheler 2008[1954], 260)7 The basic experience of others as others is about understanding their emotions. This involves neither the faculty of speech nor any other complex cognitive mental faculty. Scheler is quite clear, however, in marking the fundamental difference between the givenness of different strata of feelings. Only the so-called vital and psychic feelings are directly given in the psychophysically neutral sphere of expressive behavior (e.g., grief, joy, shame), whereas the other’s physical pain remains necessarily private. In the latter cases, we can only understand what his or her experience contains per analogiam: In order to understand the other’s toothache, I need to be familiar with this horrible sensation. The second stratum of feelings, which we have no direct access to, are spiritual feelings, like true bliss or deep despair. According to Scheler, these feelings take over our whole being, so that they cannot be separated from the person we are. We do not feel and express them anymore—we somehow are them (Scheler 1973a, 344). The two strata of feelings we can directly understand in the manner described above (v ital and psychic feelings) are not known to us because they are innate or develop somehow independently from any outer influences. According to Scheler, the very foundation for our ability to directly grasp the other’s feeling lies in a primordial form of sympathy he calls emotional unity (Einsfühlung). During infancy, long before we are able to experience others as others— that is, before any conscious act of emotional identification would be even possible8 —we can share the others’ feeling in emotional unity. We would not grow into sociality unless we first shared in other people’s feelings; moreover, we would not get to know our own emotional life in the first place. The sphere of emotional unity is situated, as Scheler emphasizes, in an “intermediate region of human nature,” distinguished from the “spiritual personality and the physical body” (Scheler 2008[1954], 34). Neither purely sensual nor spiritual feelings but only vital and psychic feelings, which are necessarily bound to expressional behavior (e.g., grief, joy), can be shared in such a way. But what does the term “Einsfühlung” exactly mean? Emotional unity plays a crucial role in early childhood development. However, it is not confined to a developmental stage, nor is it limited to infants. According to Scheler, we can 77
Matthias Schloßberger
be drawn into the sphere of emotional unity and experience that peculiar feeling of oneness with other persons, groups, nature, family, mankind, etc., at any stage of our lives. The defining characteristics of this feeling are as follows: (1) The shared feelings in question are always unconsciously initiated—one cannot freely choose to enter a relationship of emotional unity. (2) It all takes place in our “vital centre” (Vitalbewusstsein)—the cognitive, rational, and spiritual spheres (personhood), as well as the sphere of corporeal sensation (animalitas), have to be ‘empty,’ as it were, in order to enter the sphere of emotional unity. It means becoming “something less than a human, being having reason and dignity, yet something more than an animal of the kind that lives and has its being only in its physical circumstances” (Scheler 2008[1954], 35). (3) When Scheler speaks of emotional unity, he always implies a sphere before or beyond the I-Thou-difference. This applies to very different social phenomena. Some of these phenomena of emotional unity can be considered as cognitively regressive, for example: losing crucial aspects of one’s humanity by becoming part of a faceless hateful mob (cases of emotional contagion). Other cases of emotional unity can even serve as a source of metaphysical knowledge. Scheler’s example for such an experience is “the truly loving sexual intercourse,” where the partners “relapse into a single lifestream in which nothing of their individual selves remains any longer distinct” (Scheler 2008[1954], 25), rendering “a sense of cosmic unity” possible (kosmovitale Einsfühlung) (Scheler 2008[1954], 110). There is a founding relation between emotional unity and sensing the other’s feeling: In the “timeless order of functional dependence as well as in that of genetic evolution,” sensing the other’s feeling is only possible on the basis of emotional unity (Scheler 2008[1954], 96; transl. modified). The subsequent form of sympathy, the so-called fellow-feeling (Mitfühlen)—which includes compassion (Mitgefühl/Mitleid) and feelingwith-one- another (Miteinanderfühen)—is only possible on the ground of sensing foreign feelings. Scheler argues against the assumption that one must experience the other’s feeling in order to feel compassion. He does not deny the possibility of such an emotional experience, but refuses to acknowledge it as real compassion. After all, in such cases, one remains within the confines of one’s own emotional life. The question: What would I feel in the other’s place? rather prevents to reach out to the other person in her otherness than really opening up a true connection. Real compassion requires an understanding of the other’s otherness, it requires, as Scheler puts it, “an outreaching beyond the individual self ” (Scheler 2008[1954], 52). Compassion as a crucial form of sympathy entails sharing in the other’s suffering but at the same time remaining separated from the other (cf. Chapter 37 in this volume). Scheler speaks of a “twofold transcendence”: The other’s individuality and her absolute privacy. In order to feel real compassion, the other’s feeling has to remain hers alone: “it must remain absolutely inaccessible to any sort of community of experience.” We can never see right into one another’s hearts, nor can we “even have full and adequate knowledge of our own hearts [this] is given as an essential feature in all experience of fellow-feeling (not excluding spontaneous love)” (Scheler 2008[1954], 66). Due precisely to this twofold transcendence, compassion enables us to experience the other’s reality: “For fellow feeling essentially involves the ascription of reality to the subject whose feelings we share. It therefore disappears when the supposedly real subject is replaced by one which is presented as figurative or fictitious” (Scheler 2008[1954], 98). However, despite the great ethical significance of fellow-feeling, Scheler qualifies it as essentially “blind to value” (wertblind), because it cannot 78
Max Scheler
replace value-perception and ethical judgment (I can feel compassionate toward the wrong people and sympathize with the wrong cause). Apart from compassion, there is a second kind of fellow-feeling, the so-called feeling-withone-another (Miteinanderfühlen). The famous example Scheler gives is shared parental grief: Two parents stand beside the dead body of a beloved child. They feel in common the “same” sorrow, the “same” anguish. It is not that A feels this sorrow and B feels it also, and moreover that they both know they are feeling it. No, it is a feeling-in-common. A’s sorrow is in no way an “external” matter for B here, as it is, e.g. for their friend C, who joins them, and commiserates “with them” or “upon their sorrow”. On the contrary, they feel it together, in the sense that they feel and experience in common not only the self-same value-situation, but also the same keenness of emotion in regard to it. The sorrow, as value-content, and the grief, as characterizing the functional relation thereto, are here one and the same. It will be evident that we can only feel mental suffering in this fashion, not physical pain or sensory feelings. There is no such thing as a “common pain.” (Scheler 2008[1954], 12)9 What applies to the conception of emotional unity (Einsfühlung) and the sensing of the other’s feeling (Nachfühlen) applies here as well: Only the vital and psychic emotions are shareable in the sense of a feeling-with-one-another (Miteinanderfühlen). Moreover, and importantly, to collectively feel the same pain does not entail feeling the pain in the same way. The sensual quality of an emotion (how grief feels in my stomach or ‘heart’ …) is nothing we can share with another person. “Hence an identical sorrow may be keenly felt (though in one’s own individual fashion), but never an identical sensation of pain” (Scheler 2008[1954], 255). One crucial aspect of Scheler’s account of emotional sharing is his rejection of the traditional conception of consciousness: Traditionally, every psychic experience—be it a thought or a feeling—is considered to be bound to one individual mind and every experiential content realized in one individual consciousness alone (cf. also Schmid 2009). Scheler questions this assumption. Moreover, he casts doubt on the absolute authority of the experiencing ego when it comes to the experience of feelings (see esp. Scheler 1911, 1912). Only purely sensual or spiritual feelings are bound to the privacy of our minds, while psychic and vital feelings can be shared with others in a variety of ways: (a) We can have feelings that are not genuinely ours—in these cases, Scheler speaks of emotional contagion. If, for example, we enter a pub filled with cheerful people, our grumpiness might involuntarily turn into a cheerful mood—that is, until we leave the pub and leave our unwarranted cheerfulness behind as well. There is also the above-mentioned (b) emotional unity (Einsfühlung)—the sharing of a feeling with others before, and beyond, the experience of the distinction of mind and body, as well as of you and me. And there is, not least, as we have seen, (c) the feeling-with-another (Miteinanderfühlen). Thus, according to Scheler, whenever a couple or a group of people share an emotional state, we have an emotional dimension that is not reducible to the fact that individuals involved happen to feel the same feeling alongside each other.10
5. Love According to Scheler, our very being toward the world is primordially emotional and grounded in love. As he programmatically states, man is an ens amans even before he is an ens cogitans or an ens volens. Scheler has an epistemological, a metaphysical, and an anthropological perspective on love. 79
Matthias Schloßberger
The well-known saying is wrong: Love does not blind us. Quite the contrary, love makes us seeing and, therefore, has the most crucial epistemic role. For Scheler, the supposed blinding character of love is a “bourgeois opinion” that reveals nothing but the widespread assumption that the sphere of truth and knowledge has to be free from everything emotional (Scheler 1992, 147). According to Scheler, love is creative when it comes to values, but it does not create or somehow construct them. Rather, it discloses and actualizes new values. However, love is nonetheless active—actio and not just reactio. It is not just an emotional reaction to preexisting values but rather the decisive movens when it comes to the comprehension of new values: “For love is that movement of intention whereby, from a given value A in an object, its higher value is visualized. Moreover, it is just this vision of a higher value that is of the essence of love” (Scheler 2008[1954], 153). Scheler’s claim about the value-disclosing role of love is best understood by an example: Children feel and understand the care and goodness of their parents “without having even vaguely comprehended an idea of the good” (Scheler 1973a, 166). Later, they will be able to make ethical judgments only because they are already familiar with how goodness feels, long before they are able to grasp the corresponding concept. During infancy, where the I/Thou-difference is not yet established (within the sphere of emotional unity), we enter the realm of moral values through the sharing of love and care (Einslieben). Love is an immediate emotional movement toward the “value-complex” (Wertverhalt) itself which precedes any value-judgment. It is not in our nature to love someone or something based on a thorough evaluation and transparently communicable reasons. “Nothing shows this better than the extraordinary perplexity which can be seen to ensue when people are asked to give ‘reasons’ for their love or hatred” (Scheler 2008[1954], 149).11 For Scheler, all intentional feeling is ultimately founded in love. Love is not just a feeling among other feelings but the one driving force when it comes to the perception of new values. Scheler holds that love extends our realm of values (whereas hatred narrows it). Other kinds of feelings only receive what love has already disclosed: I do not mean to say that the nature of the act of love is such that it is directed in a “responding” fashion to a value after that value is felt or preferred; I mean, rather, that strictly speaking, this act plays the disclosing role in our value-comprehensions, and that it is only this act which does so. This act is, as it were, a movement in whose execution ever new und higher values flash out, i.e., values that were wholly unknown to the being concerned. Thus, this act does not follow value-feeling and preferring but is ahead of them as a pioneer and a guide. (Scheler 1973a, 261) For Scheler, love is the foundation of morality because of its spontaneity when it comes to the disclosure of values: Ultimately, every ethical judgment is grounded in love because it deals with the original comprehension of values. If there were no love, there would be no ethical judgment properly speaking: There would only be appropriation and reproduction of already existing social norms. In Scheler’s metaphysical system, love is defined as participation. The following speculative assumption is underlying this definition: Knowledge as a relationship of being (Seinsverhältnis) presupposes whole and part. Knowledge is the participation of a being who participates in a whole through acts of self-transcendence. ‘Love’ is the term Scheler uses to describe this movement of self-transcendence within being (part) that is necessary to participate in being (whole). All conscious knowledge is based on a kind of pre-reflexive ecstatic knowledge— the participation of a particular being in being as a whole. 80
Max Scheler
There would not be knowledge at all without this tendency of every knowledgeable being to surpass and transcend itself in order to participate in another being. I do not know any better term for this tendency than ‘love’ or devotion when it means surpassing the limits of one’s own being. (Scheler 1980, 203; own translation) Apart from his rather speculative metaphysics (and indeed ‘epistemology’) of love, Scheler presents an anthropological theory of love, in which he distinguishes three forms of love (in accordance with the upper three of the four strata of feelings): the vital or passionate love, the psychic love which involves the ego, and the spiritual love which aims at the (spiritual) person. In keeping with the a priori correlation between acts and given objects, every form of love is essentially bound to a certain value as its correlate: The vital acts unearth values of the vulgar and noble, the psychic acts are bound to values like beauty and knowledge, and the spiritual acts aim at the holy and the unholy. A purely sensual love, a form of love that would correspond (only) with the value of the agreeable does not exist for Scheler—simply because such a feeling could not be rightfully called love. We do not sensu stricto ‘love’ our favorite pasta dish, and we cannot call it ‘love’ if we had similar feelings toward a person. “A purely ‘sensual’ attitude to a person, for example, is at the same time an absolutely cold and loveless attitude. (…) This is an attitude wholly incompatible with any sort of intentional love for the other, as such” (Scheler 2008[1954], 170). With regard to love, Scheler’s theory of stratification seems readily plausible: We can be lovingly attached to a person in very different ways. It is possible to deeply love a person without desiring him or her in a vital sense; and the opposite may also be the case: We passionately love someone without any spiritual relationship and finally, of course, both forms of love can exist at the same time for the same person (Scheler 2008[1954], 170).
6. Shame Scheler attaches an existential significance to the sense of shame: No other feeling is better suited to express the unique position of human beings in the world. His approach is quasi-transcendental: The first condition for the appearance of the sense of shame is our need to appear in the social space as an embodied being. The expressive behavior of the lived body makes us understand others’ feelings, and conversely, it makes them understand our feelings—and this is, of course, vitally important for our constitution as persons. Through the mutual understanding of expressive behavior, human intersubjectivity, i.e., the social space, emerges, and human interaction takes place. The second condition consists in the fact that we cannot completely control our feelings nor our expressional behavior, and this makes us vulnerable—even if we learn to develop a public persona, which helps us hide our feelings to a certain degree. The possibility of shame arises from this tension between the private person and the public persona, between our need for proximity and our need for distance. We cannot escape being seen by others but at the same time—in order to thrive as human beings—we want to be seen and recognized. Scheler explains this dynamics with an often cited (and often misinterpreted) example: the case of a nude model and a painter. Initially, the woman is not ashamed of her nakedness, even though she is exposed to the painter’s attentive gaze, even though—one could say—she is liable to be objectified. In this situation, she knows that she is not a person for the painter but an aesthetic object and that is exactly the reason why she is not ashamed. Now let us imagine that the painter suddenly speaks with her and thereby addresses her as an individual. What is likely to happen is that she is suddenly ashamed of her nakedness. The painter’s 81
Matthias Schloßberger
behavior will appear to her inappropriate, even though he might be just trying to engage in some small talk. According to some accounts of shame, the main reason for feeling shame consists in being objectified; in this peculiar example, however, we encounter quite a different situation. Of course, as Scheler points out, the contrary is equally plausible: If we sense that our beloved partner does not see us as an irreplaceable and unique person, but as an arbitrarily interchangeable object of sexual gratification, it could happen that we suddenly feel ashamed. Scheler sums up what the two—in fact adverse dynamics—reveal about the nature of shame: Shame requires a sudden and involuntary turn toward ourselves. The “turning to” one’s self in whose dynamics shame has its origins, does not occur if one is “given” to oneself as something general or as individual. It occurs when the feelable intention of the other oscillates between an individualizing and generalizing attitude and when one’s own intention and the experienced counterintention have not the same but an opposite direction. (Scheler 1987b, 16) Both Scheler’s phenomenological description and his evaluation of the feeling of shame deviate in some important respects from other well-known theories of shame (for example, that of Sartre; see Chapter 30 in this volume). Indeed, for Scheler, shame has a crucial function: It helps us to distinguish between the public and the private spheres (Scheler 1987b, 15). Shame also has a crucial role when it comes to erotic love. According to Scheler, shame is the “assistant of love”: “Shame is a shell, as it were, in which love grows until it genuinely breaks this shell” (Scheler 1987b, 34). In other words, only when our love encounters the other’s love does shame give way to intimacy. Scheler rejects the claim that shame is nothing but a negative byproduct of our upbringing and socialization. Theories claiming that shame is somehow unnaturally instilled into us through contingent social norms mistake shame for prudishness. For Scheler, the opposite is true: As humans are beings who can feel shame by nature, some social norms prove useful and meaningful but they do not create shame. Tact and discretion, according to Scheler, have the task of inhibiting us from prying into other people’s private sphere: “For discretion rests on a [compassion] with the psychic shame of another person” (Scheler 1987b, 84; translation modified). Let us illustrate the importance of the separation between the two spheres (private and public) with another example: If a teacher speaks to her student as if she were her best friend and asks her about private matters, the student in question will probably feel ashamed. Why is this the case? Because the student expects to be seen as a student and not as a friend. The encounter of student and teacher happens in the public sphere and every participant of this sphere is expected to act according to a certain social role. However, it is not a regrettable social fact that we cannot be intimate friends with everybody, but a social necessity based on our very nature and tangible through our sense of shame.
7. The reality of feelings and the feelings of reality Scheler’s view on the ontological status of emotions deserves special attention. As already mentioned, he rejects both the widespread assumption that emotions are private states of isolated minds and that they are mere bodily states.12 Rather, they are intersubjectively accessible occurrences in the world. Along with Moritz Geiger (1921),13 Scheler represents a
82
Max Scheler
position that can be described as “psychic realism.” It is characterized by the following four assumptions: (1) Mental occurrences (Psychisches) (such as feelings, thoughts, and desires) are not only or not necessarily the content of an individual consciousness. They can exist independently of a particular consciousness in two ways: (a) They can be shared by several individuals, and (b) they can transcend the consciousness they appear to: “Not the psychic experience itself but its appearances are given to our inner sense (…) Psychic experiences are as little dependent on our ‘brain’ or ‘senses’ as the sun, moon, and stars are” (Scheler 1911, 107; own translation). (2) Mind doesn’t stand in opposition to matter, and hence psychic occurrences cannot be characterized as essentially non-spatial—as we can clearly see when it comes to the experience of our lived bodies (Leiberfahrungen). (3) There are phenomena that are neutral regarding the psychophysical dichotomy— neither mind nor matter—such as expressive behavior. (4) The experience of—others’ as well as one’s own—feelings is just as prone to error as the experience of physical objects. There is no greater authority of the experiencing ego when it comes to her feelings as when it comes to objects of perception. According to Scheler, ‘reality’ and ‘illusion’ (Sein und Schein) are categories that not only apply to the realm of facts and objects but also to emotions. It is only against the background of this assumption that it becomes clear how emotional contagion works: We feel someone else’s feeling and take it as our own, while eventually we are puzzled by the strangeness of what we have felt: It turns out that this was indeed not our own feeling (Schloßberger 2019). Scheler illustrates the fallibility of feelings by the example of love and hate: There is a difference whether love and hate cease to exist, or whether the person has been deceiving himself and mistook something for love and hatred, which turned out to be not love or not hate. It makes also a difference, whether there was no love from the beginning or one feels it only temporarily or whether one is simply not able to admit one’s love. For cases of such great diversity it is impossible to assert that all emotions (of love and hate) are equally real and that it does not matter whether one was in love (or hate) for five minutes or three weeks, or that any statement that one was mistaken expresses only that a certain expectation (...) was not fulfilled.” (Scheler 1911, 110; own translation) Finally, it should be mentioned that emotions also play a fundamental role in Scheler’s theory of the experience of reality—or what he calls “voluntative realism” (Scheler 1973b, 301). Reality itself becomes an “emotional problem” for him (Scheler 1976). “To be real does not amount to being a permanent object [in time], i.e., the identical correlate of every intellectual act—but rather being resistant against the original spontaneity” (Scheler 1973b, 363; own translation). Scheler assumes that the very first experience we have of the world is an experience of the resistance of the world. We have neither special sensations nor some kind of a supernatural sense of reality on top of our other senses, nor do we reflectively or pre-reflectively infer that what we experience is indeed the so-called ‘exterior world,’ i.e. the world of extended bodies, other people, etc. Quite the contrary, we are able to grasp reality only because of our primordial experience of its resistance. Every quality ( jedes Sosein) we experience, be it of objects or of other people, requires prior experience of their reality (Dasein).
83
Matthias Schloßberger
Existence (=being real) is given to us in the experience of resistance of an already disclosed sphere of the world—and this resistance occurs only in our striving and drives, in our central life impulsion. No inference can be made which could lead us to posit the reality of the exterior world (whose sphere is also given in dreams); there is also no concrete content of perception (as ‘forms’, ‘gestalts’), no objectiveness (which occurs also in phantasy) (…) that could give an impression of reality. (…) The original experience of reality, the experience of resistance of the world, precedes, therefore, any and all consciousness (Bewusstsein); resistance precedes all re-presentation and perception. (Scheler 2009, 38) Reality only exists for a striving, desiring consciousness—only a being moved by its striving (be it a human or otherwise) can experience resistance. There is no reality for a hypothetical being which has no drive or no desire whatsoever. In some cases, the experience of resistance manifests itself in anxiety. However, contrary to Heidegger, anxiety, according to Scheler, is not the original or authentic way in which we come in touch with reality (Heidegger, 1962, 53; Scheler 1976, 267; cf. Chapters 7 and 34 in this volume). Anxiety only occurs when desire meets an insurmountable resistance. If, conversely, resistance can be overcome, the emotional outcome is joy and pleasure—but an experience of reality, nonetheless.
Notes
84
Max Scheler
References Gallagher, Shaun (2005). How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gallagher, Shaun, and Zahavi, Dan (2008). The Phenomenological Mind. London, New York: Routledge. Geiger, Moritz (1921). Fragment über den Begriff des Unbewussten und die psychische Realität: Ein Beitrag zur Grundlegung des immanenten psychischen Realismus. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 4, 1–137. Geniusas, Saulius (2015). Max Scheler and the Stratification of the Emotional Life. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy XIV, 355‒376. Heidegger, Martin (1962). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Husserl, Edmund (2001). Logical Investigations. Transl. by J. L. Findlay. London, New York: Routledge. Joas, Hans (2001). The Genesis of Values. Transl. by G. Moore. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Krebs, Angelika (2011). The Phenomenology of Shared Feeling. Appraisal Journal 8(3), 6–21. León, Felipe, Szanto, Thomas, and Zahavi, Dan (2019). Emotional Sharing and the Extended Mind. Synthese 196(12), 4847–4867. Massin, Olivier (2011). On Pleasures. Thèse de doctorat ès lettres. Université de Genève (unpublished dissertation, University of Geneva). Mulligan, Kevin (1998). From Appropriate Emotions to Values. The Monist 81(1), 161–188. ——— (2010). Emotions and Values. In: P. Goldie (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 475–500. Römer, Inga (2018). Das Begehren der reinen praktischen Vernunft. Kants Ethik in phänomenologischer Sicht. Hamburg: Meiner. Rutishauser, Bruno (1969). Max Schelers Phänomenologie des Fühlens. Eine kritische Analyse seiner Untersuchung von Scham und Schamgefühl. Bern, München: Francke. Sánchez Guerrero, Héctor A. (2016). Feeling Together and Caring with One Another: A Contribution to the Debate on Collective Affective Intentionality. Dordrecht: Springer. Scheler, Max (1911). Über Selbsttäuschungen. Zeitschrift für Pathopsychologie 1(1), 87–164. ——— (1912). Über Ressentiment und moralisches Werturteil. Leipzig: Wilhelm Engelmann. [Engl.: Ressentiment. Transl. by W. W. Holdheim. New York: Schocken 1972]. ——— (1973a). Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values. A New Attempt toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism. Transl. by M. Frings and R. L. Funk. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. ——— (1973b). Idealism and Realism. In: Selected Philosophical Essays. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 288–356. ——— (1976). Zusätze aus den nachgelassenen Manuskripten [Idealismus, Realismus], Teil 5: Das emotionale Realitätsproblem. In: Gesammelte Werke, Band 9, Späte Schriften, Bern, München: Francke, 254–293. ——— (1980). Erkenntnis und Arbeit. Eine Studie über Wert und Grenzen des pragmatischen Motivs in der Erkenntnis der Welt. In: Gesammelte Werke, Band 8: Die Wissensformen und die Gesellschaft. Bern, München: Francke, 191–382. ——— (1987b). Shame and Feelings of Modesty. In: Person and Self-Value: Three Essays. Transl. by M. Frings. Dordrecht: Nijhoff.
85
Matthias Schloßberger ——— (1992). Love and Knowledge. In: M. Scheler: On Feeling, Knowing, and Valuing, Selected Writings. Ed. by H. J. Bershady. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. ——— (2008[1954]). The Nature of Sympathy. Transl. by P. Heath. New Brunswick, London: Transaction Publishers. ——— (2009). The Human Place in the Cosmos. Transl. by M. Frings. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Schloßberger, Matthias (2005). Die Erfahrung des Anderen. Gefühle im menschlichen Miteinander. Berlin: Akademie. ——— (2019). Beyond Empathy: Compassion and the Reality of Others. Topoi. doi:10.1007/ s11245-019-09636-7. Schmid, Hans Bernhard (2009). Plural Action: Essays in Philosophy and Social Science. Dordrecht: Springer. Steinbock, Anthony (2014). Moral Emotions: Reclaiming the Evidence of the Heart. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Tappolet, Christine (2016). Emotions, Values, and Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (2008). Gefühle in der realistischen Phänomenologie. Berlin: Akademie. Zaborowski, Robert (2011). Max Scheler’s Model of Stratified Affectivity and Its Relevance for Research on Emotions. Appraisal 8(3), 24–34. Zahavi, Dan (2014). Self and Other. Exploring Subjectivity, Empathy and Shame. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Zhang, Wei (2009). The Foundations of Phenomenological Ethics: Intentional Feelings. Frontiers of Philosophy in China 4(1), 130–142. ——— (2010). Die Intentionalität des Fühlens und die Schichtung der emotionalen Sphäre: Die fundamentalen Fragen in Max Schelers Phänomenologie des Fühlens. Bulletin d’Analyse Phénoménologique 6(5), 1–19. Further reading Mulligan, Kevin (2008). Scheler: Die Anatomie des Herzens oder was man alles fühlen kann. In: H. Landweer, and U. Renz (Eds.). Klassische Emotionstheorien. Berlin: de Gruyter, 587–612. Scheler, Max (1974). The Meaning of Suffering. In: Max Scheler: Centennial Essays. Ed. by M. Frings. Dordrecht: Njihoff, 121–163. Schloßberger, Matthias (2016). The Varieties of Togetherness: Scheler on Collective Affective Intentionality. In: S. Salice, and H. B. Schmid (Eds.). The Phenomenological Approach to Social Reality. History, Concepts, Problems. Cham: Springer, 173–195.
86
5 MORITZ GEIGER Alessandro Salice
1. Introduction Emotions ubiquitously pervade, enrich, and color our mental life. They are complex, multi-layered, and variegated mental phenomena. For instance, suppose you are informed about a forthcoming event: Your friend will visit you in a couple of days, which makes you feel joy about that. Even a cursory look at this only apparently simple emotion unveils its fascinating and delicate complexity. To begin with, the joy acquires a determined position in your mental life: Perhaps you were in a somewhat depressive mood before realizing your friend’s visit, but now the emotion of joy helps you overcome that mood. Suddenly, you begin to live in the pleasant expectation of your friend’s visit. Also, the emotion enters a complicated network of relations with other experiences: You have been informed that your friend will come, and it is based on your awareness of that future event that you elicit joy. Not only are you aware of the forthcoming event, you can also become aware of feeling joy about the visit. However, if you pay too much attention to the joy you are living through— maybe because you want to find out why, precisely, the visit of your friend gives you joy— the emotion may vanish. But this also reveals that joy—just as many other emotions—is motivated: Generally, one has a motive for being joyful and this motive can be more or less transparent to the subject. But this suggests that the object of your joy (the visit of your friend), which the emotion is intentionally directed at, must be distinguished from its motive (the reason why the visit of your friend generates joy in you). The various relations that these mental phenomena enter with the world and with other mental states have been made the topic of a series of important articles by the Munich phenomenologist Moritz Geiger (1880–1937). These contributions aim at clarifying important aspects of our emotional life by disentangling the intricate relations I briefly touched upon above. This chapter reconstructs Geiger’s ideas about emotions by mainly focusing on two articles: “The Consciousness of Emotions” (Das Bewusstsein von Gefühlen) from 1911 and “Contributions to the Phenomenology of Aesthetic Pleasure” (Beiträge zur Phänomenologie des ästhetischen Genusses) from 1913. However, it should be noted that Geiger’s work on emotions is certainly not confined to the ideas discussed in these two essays. For instance, his paper “On the Problem of Empathy regarding Moods” (Zum Problem der Stimmungseinfühlung) (1911) represents one of the very first contributions to the philosophy of moods, although it 87
Alessandro Salice
is hardly discussed in the relevant literature. Furthermore, it should not be left unmentioned that Geiger’s aesthetics—one of his long-standing main areas of research—heavily relies on his view about emotions (see the collection of articles “Approaches to Aesthetics” (Zugänge zur Ästhetik) (1928) and, in particular, the essay “On Dilettantism in the Artistic Experience” (Vom Dilettantismus im künstlerischen Erleben). The chapter is organized as follows: The second section discusses Geiger’s views on the intentionality of feelings and on the forms of awareness that may accompany emotions, which are the main topics of his 1911’s “The Consciousness of Emotions”. As we will see, Geiger’s insights on these points have methodological importance for the study of emotions. In the third section, I present Geiger’s theory of affective motivation, as this is developed in his 1913 essay. One of the reasons why Geiger’s ideas on affective motivation are particularly interesting is because they can be applied to describe cases of ill-motivated emotions, on which I will briefly elaborate at the end of that section.
2. Emotions: intentionality and consciousness Let us go back to the initial example. While going through your emails during the morning, you find your friend’s message that informs you of his visit. You feel joy and, almost imperceptibly, your worries and preoccupations wane: You now look forward to welcoming your friend. One way to describe this situation is by saying that you now “live through (erleben)” the emotion or that the emotion is in an “experiential position (Erlebnisstellung)”1 (Geiger 1911a, 133). Note that, more often than not, we are too deeply immerged in our daily life to pay attention to our lived-through experiences. In fact, it could well be that, after reading your friend’s email, you go back to work without even thinking of your emotion, while living “in” or “through” it nevertheless (see also Pfänder 1904, 228). Suppose now that, albeit your mental life has been colored by the emotion since the morning (precisely because you are living through it), during lunch you ask yourself why your emotional register has changed and, to answer your question, you direct your attention introspectively. In this case, while still living through the emotion, you activate a consciousness’ ray (Bewußtseinsstrahl), which is directed at the emotion: You have become explicitly aware of your joy. The joy is now given to you as a unified experience (as a ‘whole’) in what Geiger calls “simple attention (schlichte Aufmerksamkeit)” (Geiger 1911a, 130). Simple attention, Geiger claims, is basic for this form of attention and is presupposed by all other forms (these are “qualitative” and “analyzing” attention, see below). Note that, clearly, the range of simple attention is not limited to our mental life. Imagine you have to cross a street: There are indefinitely many objects in your visual field, but your simple attention goes to one single car that is waiting for the green light. Again, the car is given to you as a ‘whole’, which means that—even if you know the car is composed of several parts—your attention is not concerned with those parts. Yet, this is precisely what “qualitative attention (qualitative Aufmerksamkeit)” is concerned with. To slightly modify the example, imagine that you are crossing a street without traffic lights or zebra crossings. In this case, you are not ‘simply’ attentive to the car, as you were above, but rather you are paying ‘qualitative’ attention to it: What you are attentive to is how fast the car is approaching (Geiger 1911a, 131f.). You need to retrieve that information from the environment precisely because you want to cross the street without being hit. In this case, a specific part or aspect of the object (its speed, in this example) is revealed to you. Interestingly, some—but not all—emotions can be made object of qualitative attention, while their subjects still live through those emotions. In the above case of joy, once you made it the 88
Moritz Geiger
thematic object of your attention, you are also able to determine how ‘deep’ or ‘superficial’ your emotion is—maybe depending on how close you are to your friend. (The idea of depth, height, superficiality, etc. of emotions stems from Pfänder; see Chapter 3 in this volume.) A similar consideration applies to many emotions, although not to all. Geiger (1911a) distinguishes between “sensory feelings (sinnliche Gefühle)” and “emotional feelings (emotionale Gefühle)” or “emotions” tout court. Sensory feelings—a category Geiger adopts from Pfänder (see Pfänder 1904, 236)—are all those emotions of pleasure or displeasure which are attached to sensations (e.g., the pleasure one gains from drinking a nice pint of IPA). The subject, Geiger contends, can direct qualitative attention to sensible feelings while having them. In fact, while drinking one’s favorite beverage, not only can one be aware of the felt pleasure, one can also appreciate it in its many nuances (think of the precise descriptions coffee tasters are able to provide on the note and intensity of their pleasure). The notion of emotional feelings is more complex as it encompasses at least two different kinds of emotions (Geiger 1911a, 128): emotions of pleasure and displeasure “in the proper sense” and self-emotions or, perhaps better, self-conscious emotions (Selbstgefühle).2 In 1911, Geiger only offers ostensive definitions of these two kinds of emotions (see Geiger 1911a, 128f )—emotions of pleasure and displeasure “in the proper sense” include joy or enthusiasm, but also what Geiger calls “affects (Affekte)” like sadness or anger, and moods like boredom or anxiety. Self-conscious emotions comprise pride, envy, humility, vanity, etc. Although Geiger is not entirely clear on this point, it seems that all emotions have something in common: They are motivated or have a motive. The next section will investigate this notion in more detail, but for the time being, it suffices to say that an emotion has a motive if its subject is at least in principle able to answer the question why she feels that particular emotion (in a particular sense of ‘why’, which I will discuss in Section 3). By contrast, sensory feelings may be aroused (erregt) by sensations, but do not have motives: We do not know why (in the above sense of ‘why’) certain objects give us sensory pleasure and others do not. As we have already seen, some emotions can be made the target of qualitative attention: Joy or annoyance (Ärger), for instance, can survive qualitative attention without experiencing modification (Geiger 1911a, 135). Moods, too, are not particularly affected by this form of attention. However, affects dissolve or water down the moment in which the subject directs his or her qualitative attention to them. This is particularly the case for affects like anger or fear. Geiger contends that this is due to the particularly close link that binds these emotions with their motives. The moment in which the subject makes them targets of qualitative attention, that link is relaxed and a gap opens up between the emotional response and its motive: The subject, by losing grip on the emotional motive, is not emotionally moved any longer and thus stops living through the emotion. Simple attention can also be at the basis of a third form of attention—this is “analysing attention (analysierende Beachtung)”, which Geiger sometimes qualifies as observation (Beobachtung). This sort of attention ‘analyses’ the object in the sense that it separates its component parts to identify the species and genera under which the object falls. To put this differently, the object is grasped as this or that. For instance, a melody is decomposed into its constituents and those constituents are grasped as notes of the kind a, b, or c … Adopting an analyzing stance toward a feeling, be it sensory or emotional, necessarily implies removing the emotion from its ‘experiential position’ mentioned earlier in order to theoretically dissect it. For instance, a token emotion could be analyzed by identifying the kind of its hedonic valence, of its intentional content, of its founding experience, etc. However, the moment the emotion is dislocated from its experiential position, the subject does not live through it anymore.3 89
Alessandro Salice
At this juncture, it should be noted that, when the subject pays simple attention (and, in the cases mentioned earlier: Qualitative attention) to his or her emotion, the subject simultaneously is in two different mental states: The emotion and the attentional act directed toward the emotion. Yet, this is not the only—or the most fundamental—way in which the subject is ‘aware’ of her own emotions. Geiger contends that it is possible for the subject to be aware of her emotion in virtue of merely living through that very emotion, without occupying any other state. To understand how that is possible, however, one needs to do a short detour on the intentionality of feelings. Sensory and emotional feelings, Geiger maintains, are ‘about’ objects and facts in the world: If I feel pleasure when drinking my favorite IPA, there is a sense in which my pleasure is about something in the world. Similarly, the joy you feel is about the visit of your friend. Accordingly, feelings certainly have an “intentional direction (Gegenstandsrichtung)”. But it is interesting to remark that, while assigning “intentional direction” to feelings, Geiger, at the same time, denies that they literally are intentional or literally have intentionality (“it does not seem felicitous to qualify the joy about something as ‘intentional’” Geiger 1911a, 141). It goes beyond the scope of this article to exhaustively elucidate this point, but it suffices to say that Geiger aligns with many other phenomenologists (though, crucially, not with Husserl in his Logical Investigations) in distinguishing different kinds of intentional directedness, which do not have an overarching genus (see Salice 2012; Crespo 2015; and Salice 2015, for the relation between Geiger and Husserl on this specific point). To put it differently, the sense in which feelings are about objects, events, or facts is merely analogous, but ultimately different from the sense in which, say, beliefs or acts of thinking are about objects, events, and facts. On this view, the term ‘intentionality’ captures only the (roughly) cognitive, but not the affective sense of aboutness. Early phenomenologists do not settle on one technical term for the non-cognitive sense(s) of aboutness—their expressions vary and include: “objectual consciousness (Gegenstandsbewußtsein)”, the “(mere) having of an object (bloß rezeptives Haben des Gegenstandes)”, etc. (see Salice 2015). More importantly, this short detour on the intentionality of feelings enables us to clarify another feature that typically characterizes these experiences: When living through them, the subject can adopt two different attitudes or mental orientations. The first orientation is called by Geiger “outer concentration (Außenkonzentration)”—when one adopts this orientation, the subject is entirely absorbed by the intentional object of the feeling. The object is the element on which the conscious accent is put (das Bewußtseinsbetonte). So, for instance, in the moment in which you elicit joy, the focus of your emotion entirely gravitates around the future visit of your friend. You do live through the emotion, but the thematic object of your concerns is its object (not the emotion). However, this is not to say that you totally ignore your emotion of joy: Crucially, even if you activate no simple or qualitative attention toward your joy, you are still aware of your joy—albeit in a merely non-thematic or peripheral sense (Geiger 1911a, 153). Outer concentration contrasts with the other orientation the subject can adopt: This is inner concentration (Innenkonzentration). In inner concentration, the qualitative aspects of the emotion become salient to the subject. Here, the conscious accent is put on the emotion rather than on the object: The emotion has qualitative features that the subject appreciates— and sometimes savors—while living through it. Note that this happens, Geiger claims, without the subject directing his or her attentional ray to the emotion. One particularly helpful example to illustrate the distinction between outer and inner concentration comes from the aesthetic domain (Geiger 1928, 14ff ): When a subject enjoys an artwork, the emotion can be lived through in two different ways. The first one, which typically describes the attitude of 90
Moritz Geiger
the expert, is outer concentration: While being peripherally aware of his or her enjoyment, the expert is concerned with the artwork itself, its features, values, etc. The second one, which contradistinguishes the amateur, is inner concentration: The subject savors the qualitative aspect of aesthetic enjoyment itself and considers the object a mere instrument for the elicitation of the emotion, thereby relegating it to the intentional background. However, and to reinforce this point, even in inner concentration, the subject is not making the emotion the thematic target of an additional cognitive act (simple or qualitative attention), for inner ( just as outer concentration) is a way of experiencing the emotion. Geiger’s discussion of the manifold ways in which we can be aware of our feelings has an important methodological implication. When it comes to investigating our emotional experiences, the qualitative features of these phenomena can only be revealed to us when we introspect our mental life. We have seen that what may be called “theoretical introspection” (the introspection enabled by qualitative and analyzing attention) has clear limitations, insofar as adopting that stance—depending on the kinds of theoretical introspection and on the kinds of feelings at stake—dissolves the very emotions the subject intends to pay attention to. But Geiger identifies another form of introspection which is not essentially theoretical: By simply living through our emotions, we are always peripherally aware of them and sometimes we can also delve into them and explore them in inner concentration. In this case, we become acquainted with their qualities—we appreciate those qualities—even though this appreciation is not theoretical in nature.
3. Emotions and motives In his paper “Contributions to the Phenomenology of Aesthetic Pleasure”, Geiger addresses the notion of motivation in a brief, but dense passage (1913, 584–591). Geiger’s investigations on this topic are highly interesting for two interrelated reasons. First, on this view, motivation is not confined to volition, but it also applies to the affective dimension.4 Put another way, emotions have motives and, as such, they are subject to certain norms of rationality.5 Second, this means that emotions, like actions, can be well-, but also ill-motivated. In fact, Geiger’s theory of motivation can give fruitful indications on how to describe cases of emotions that are ill-motivated, as we will see at the end of this section. Now, in which sense can one say that emotions have motives? Suppose I see you enjoying something, then it does not seem (at least rationally) inappropriate of me to ask you: ‘why do you feel joy?’ And yet, this question is ambiguous as it may refer to disparate and partly unrelated aspects. More precisely, Geiger identifies at least four different senses of this question as applied to emotions—only one of which targets the proper motive of the emotion. The first sense of the ‘why?’ concerns “real” causality (Geiger 1913, 590f.). Under certain descriptions, emotions qualify as neurobiological states and, as such, they have (neurobiological) causes. Against this background, the feeling of joy about your friend’s visit is related to a complex chain of physiological reactions that, say, ends up by releasing serotonin. If joy, under a certain description, coincides with or is related to serotonin, then reconstructing that complex chain of reactions is to indicate the ‘real’ causes of the emotion. However, since this level of causality is below the threshold of consciousness, it is phenomenologically irrelevant. The second sense of the why-question as applied to emotions concerns their phenomenal (not their real) causes (Geiger 1913, 590f.). Back to the example: You read the message of your friend. Your conscious understanding of the message can then be said to be the phenomenal cause of your emotion of joy. Another way of putting this is that the given cognitive state (here: the conscious understanding) is the trigger that puts your emotional life in motion. 91
Alessandro Salice
Now, when I ask you “why do you feel joy?”, do I intend to ascertain the real or the phenomenal cause of your emotion? Perhaps in some situations, these indeed are the relevant causes at stake. But generally, and to paraphrase Anscombe (2000, 9), the sense of the question ‘why?’ that applies to emotions does not concern its phenomenal or real cause, but rather its reason or motive. In a similar vein, Geiger writes: Why (weshalb) do you feel joy at his arrival? The answer could sound: because I like him or: because he will act in my place at my office and hence I can go on the planned trip— therefore I feel joy. (Geiger 1913, 586) Now, those answers clearly indicate the motive of the emotion (Gefühlsmotiv). But then, what is the motive of an emotion? As a first approximation, Geiger tells us that “the affective motive is an immediate experience” (1913, 589). And this experience is further explained as follows: In great many cases, when you feel an emotion (say, joy), you are aware of a peculiar relation that the intentional object of your emotion (the visit of your friend) enters with other states of affairs (e.g., the fact that you like him or the fact that you can go on vacation). That particular awareness is the experience of motivation and the other state of affairs that is given to you in the experience is what Geiger calls “the motive” of your emotion. So, when you answer the question “why?” by saying “I feel joy because I can go to vacation”, the preposition “because” expresses the experience of motivation and the sentence “I can go to vacation” the motive of your emotion. It is important to highlight that being a motive (of an emotion) is a mind-dependent property: A state of affairs qualifies as a motive only to a subject and insofar as this is given to the subject in the particular experience of motivation (1913: 588). This implies that, without the experience of motivation, that very state of affairs (the possibility to go on vacation) would not qualify as a motive of the emotion. Sometimes, the experience of motivation can wane: The motive “evaporates (verflüchtigt sich)” (1913, 587). This may happen in different ways. For instance, when the affective object is constantly associated with the affective motive, the latter can volatilize, as it were, in the sense that the subject cannot grasp the relation between affective object and motive anymore. To illustrate, imagine that it has become a working routine that the visit of your friend marks the fact that you go on vacation. When this happens, Geiger contends, the object itself appears to the subject as having an emotional character: The visit of your friend assumes a character that makes it immediately enjoyable, while the relation between the object and the motive fades in the background. Obviously, such a relation can become salient again, e.g., if another individual instead of your friend replaces you at your working place. In this case, you realize: I am enjoying the arrival of this individual because I can then have my holiday (where the ‘because’, here again, expresses the experience of motivation). The lack of experience of motivation has an important consequence. Under these circumstances, the emotion can be said to be no longer motivated (motivlos), which means that the subject is not able to formulate an answer to the why-question. But does that mean that the emotion has become irrational? No. In fact, Geiger claims that the emotion’s ‘rationality’ can be assessed in some other respect. It is at this juncture that Geiger discusses the fourth sense of the why-question that can be raised with regard to emotions. Sometimes, by asking that question, we do not refer to the motives of the emotion, but to its grounds (Begründungen), and emotions that lack a motive can still have a ground. The main difference between these two aspects is that motives are mind-dependent, whereas grounds are mind-independent. In the example discussed above, the possibility to go on vacation—this very state of affairs 92
Moritz Geiger
(as distinguished from the experience of this state of affairs, which, as we saw, identifies the motive of the emotion)—is the ground of the emotion of joy. Precisely because the ground is mind-independent, Geiger maintains that it is not phenomenologically evident: In fact, it is not immediately clear to us what grounds our emotions and we generally need to engage in some (often counterfactual) reasoning to get a grip on that. For instance, to identify the ground of the emotion of joy in the example, you could reason as follows: If being replaced at my office by my friend would not open for me the possibility to go on vacation, then I would not have a ground for rejoicing at my friend’s visit. Generally, motives and grounds are closely related: The motive often is the experience of a ground. When you report your emotional motive, you are reporting an experience that is about its ground. However, Geiger argues that motives and ground can also fall apart (cf. 1913, 589). Although he does not develop this claim in any detail, his remarks provide indications for how to assess cases of affective ill-motivation. It seems that one can draw the following classification: A theory of ill-motivated emotions could start by considering (i) emotions that have grounds, but no motives; (ii) emotions that have motives which diverge from the grounds; (iii) emotions that have motives, but no grounds; and (iv) emotions that have neither motives nor grounds. Let us start with (i): As we have seen, Geiger describes grounded emotions lacking a motive (maybe as a result of the constant association between emotional object and emotional motive). Such emotions are ill-motivated in the sense that they suffer from phenomenological opacity: If confronted with the question ‘Why?’, the subject would not be able to answer it. Yet, it appears that these cases escape the charge of irrationality. In fact, there seems to be nothing rationally wrong in these cases: Provided the adequate psychological circumstances are at place (e.g. if the subject reflects on the emotion), the subject would be able to experience motivation again. This gives us the opportunity to move to category (ii): The emotion is grounded and the subject experiences motivation, but the object of the experience diverges from the ground of the emotion. Suppose you feel joy about your friend’s arrival and you link this to the fact that it is precisely your friend’s arrival that makes you happy because you like him so much. In reality, however, what grounds your emotion is the fact that your friend’s arrival grants you the possibility to go on vacation (such that the arrival of another individual would still make you feel in a similar way). In this case, one may conclude, the emotion is ill-motivated—for, if confronted with the question ‘Why?’, the subject would give an answer which misidentifies the element that motivates the emotion. An implication that can be drawn from this is that the experience of being motivated does not yet guarantee that the motivational structure of the emotion is transparent to its subject. In fact, as highlighted above, grounds are not phenomenologically evident—that is, whether the object of a motive coincides with a ground is not reflected in the phenomenology of our emotions, but has to be ascertained by other means, e.g., by counterfactual reasoning. Geiger does not explicitly discuss the possibility for emotions to entirely lack grounds. But if such emotions were possible, then they would instantiate a more serious form of illmotivation, which can be possibly associated with certain forms of disturbed affectivity in mental disorders. To briefly illustrate how this idea can be put to use: Category (iii) seems apt to encompass phobias and the so-called ‘recalcitrant emotions’. The subjects of such emotional reactions are able to identify their motives, although phobias do not have external grounds that motivate or, as in the case of recalcitrant emotions, rationally justify them6: There is no danger that justifies the response. And finally, category (iv) may help 93
Alessandro Salice
conceptualize more severe syndromes like bipolar disorder: In fact, bipolar patients do not seem able to indicate any motive for the manic and depressive episodes that accompany their condition. Moreover, these emotional episodes or moods do not seem to be motivated by grounds in the world.
4. Conclusion In this chapter, I have reconstructed the main aspects of Geiger’s phenomenology of emotions. The second section discussed Geiger’s ideas about the various senses according to which a subject can be aware or conscious of his or her emotions. As we have seen, Geiger’s views on this topic have methodological relevance as they ascertain the possibilities—but also the limits—of introspection in the investigations of emotions. But his theory bears systematic relevance, too: In particular, his considerations about the motivational structure of emotions seem very helpful to account for different forms of ill-motivated emotions.7
Notes
References Anscombe, Elizabeth (2000). Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Averchi, Michele (2015). The Disinterested Spectator: Geiger’s and Husserl’s Place in the Debate on the Splitting of the Ego. Studia Phaenomenologica 15, 227–246.
94
Moritz Geiger Brady, Michael S. (2007). Recalcitrant Emotions and Visual Illusions. American Philosophical Quarterly 44(3), 273–284. Crespo, Mariano (2015). Moritz Geiger on the Consciousness of Feelings. Studia Phaenomenologica 15, 375–393. Geiger, Moritz (1911a). Das Bewusstsein von Gefühlen. In: A. Pfänder (Ed.). Münchener Philosophische Abhandlungen. Theodor Lipps zu seinem sechzigsten Geburtstag gewidmet von früheren Schülern. Leipzig: Barth, 125–162. ——— (1911b). Zum Problem der Stimmungseinfühlung. Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft 6, 1–42. ——— (1913). Beiträge zur Phänomenologie des ästhetischen Genusses. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und Phänomenologische Forschung 1, 567–684. ——— (1921). Das Unbewusste und die psychische Realität. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und Phänomenologische Forschung 4, 1–138. ——— (1928). Vom Dilettantismus im künstlerischen Erleben. In: Moritz Geiger: Zugänge zur Ästhetik. Leipzig: Der Neue Geist Verlag, 1–42. Helm, Bennett (2015). Emotions and Recalcitrance: Reevaluating the Perceptual Model. Dialectica 69(3), 417–433. Lipps, Theodor (1903). Leitfaden der Psychologie. Leipzig: Engelmann. Métraux, Alexandre (1975). Edmund Husserl und Moritz Geiger. In: H. Kuhn, et al. (Eds.). Die Münchener Phänomenologie. Vorträge des internationalen Kongresses in München, 13–18 April 1971. Den Haag: Nijhoff, 139–157. Mulligan, Kevin (2008). Max Scheler: Die Anatomie des Herzens oder was man alles fühlen kann. In: H. Landweer, and U. Renz (Eds.). Klassische Emotionstheorien: Von Platon bis Wittgenstein. Berlin: De Gruyter, 587–612. Pfänder, Alexander (1904). Einführung in die Psychologie. Leipzig: Barth. ——— (1911). Motive und Motivation. In: A. Pfänder (Ed.). Münchener philosophische Abhandlungen. Theodor Lipps zu seinem sechzigsten Geburtstag gewidmet von seinen früheren Schülern. Leipzig: Barth, 163–195. Salice, Alessandro (2012). Phänomenologische Variationen. Intention and Fulfillment in Early Phenomenology. In: A. Salice (Ed.). Intentionality. Historical and Systematic Perspectives. München: Philosophia, 203–242. ——— (2015). The Phenomenology of the Munich and Göttingen Circles. In: Ed Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2015 Edition) http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ win2015/entries/phenomenology-mg/ Salice, Alessandro, and Montes Sánchez, Alba (2016). Pride, Shame and Group Identification. Frontiers in Psychology 7(557). Uemura, Genki, and Salice, Alessandro (2019). Motives in Experience: Pfänder, Geiger and Stein. In: A. Cimino, and C. H. Leijenhorst (Eds.). The Ideas of Experience. Leiden: Brill, 129–149. Voigtländer, Else (1910). Vom Selbstgefühl. Ein Beitrag zur Förderung psychologischen Denkens. Leipzig: Voigtländer Verlag.
95
6 ELSE VOIGTLÄNDER Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
Else Voigtländer (1882–1946) provided one of the first substantial contributions to the phenomenology of the emotions. Her writings, which unfortunately have remained mostly unexplored, anticipate many of the issues that would become major focal points for later phenomenologists working on the topic. Within the phenomenological movement, Voigtländer was one of the first to study phenomena such as Ressentiment, inauthentic feelings and erotic love. In her book Vom Selbstgefühl (On the Feeling of Self-Worth) (1910), she undertakes an exhaustive study of the feelings of self-worth as part of a more ambitious project of elaborating a study of character.1 Further discussions on feelings, emotions and their relation to values can be found in a series of papers devoted to character traits, political emotions, erotic love and the psychology of sentiments (Voigtländer 1920, 1923, 1928, 1933). This chapter is divided into four sections. The first presents Voigtländer’s notion of feelings of self-worth (Selbstgefühle). The remaining sections are devoted to her analyses of inauthentic feelings, Ressentiment and other negative attitudes, and erotic love, respectively.
1. Voigtländer’s concept of the feeling of self-worth Else Voigtländer’s main work on the emotions is Vom Selbstgefühl (1910) (which is identical to her PhD thesis Über die Typen des Selbstgefühls published the same year). Originally written as a dissertation under the supervision of Lipps and Pfänder, the book is embedded in the tradition of the Munich phenomenological circle (Smid 1982, 110), but Voigtländer also engages with and develops arguments put forward by the likes of Nietzsche, Simmel and Klages.2 Her aim is to provide an analysis of a type of feeling that she calls “feelings of self-worth”.3 The concept of “feelings of self-worth”, which was first employed by Lipps, is used to refer to an emotional phenomenon belonging to the family of self-regarding attitudes. More specifically, it refers to those feelings in which we experience our own value. Phenomena such as confidence, self-affirmation, pride, vanity, shame, cowardice, haughtiness, remorse, embarrassment, ambition, self-abandonment or self-esteem belong to this class (Voigtländer 1910, 5). They all share a common feature: In them, we experience ourselves as elevated, low-spirited, depressed, etc., and in them, we sense our own value with respect to the possession of certain features, abilities or achievements. As such, a feeling of self-worth is subjected to changes that pertain to our failures, successes and accomplishments in our life experiences. 96
Else Voigtländer
Voigtländer defines the feeling of self-worth as follows: “an affective valuating consciousness of one’s own Self which each of us has and which is subjected to fluctuations” (Voigtländer 1910, 19, own transl.). With this term, Voigtländer points to a specific emotional phenomenon whose reality we cannot doubt: There are some emotional experiences in which our own sense of self-worth is given to us. Though there is no parallel discussion of this phenomenon in contemporary philosophy, some of the notions that circulate in current debates— such as the notion of existential feeling as a background orientation of our experience (see Chapter 22 in this volume), of the feeling of ability as a sense of one’s own capacities or of self-conscious emotion as an emotion through which aspects of the Self are revealed (for an overview of these concepts, see Chapter 31 in this volume)—seem to approach from different angles the phenomenon that Voigtländer has in mind. It is not easy to place the notion of “feelings of self-worth” within the standardly employed emotional categories. Voigtländer rejects any assimilation of these feelings to the class of the emotions and she often refers to them as a form of mood (Stimmung). Emotions and feelings of self-worth differ from each other in at least three respects: (1) While emotions are mental states, feelings of self-worth are affective background orientations; (2) unlike the emotions that are directed toward particular objects, feelings of self-worth are focused on the Self; and finally, (3) emotions are responses to certain features of the objects toward which they are directed, while in feelings of self-worth, it is one’s own value that is affectively given (1910, 10, 19). These differences can be illustrated by way of an example: Grief (an emotion) is a mental state directed toward an event or situation given to us as incarnating a disvalue, while low-spiritedness (a feeling of self-worth) is a background affective orientation in which we experience ourselves as depressed and worthless. A central feature of feelings of self-worth is that they imply self-assessment, i.e., we are aware of our own value or disvalue. Thus, inherent in them is a cognitive moment in which the value of ourselves is given to us. Voigtländer speaks here of an “apprehension of value” (Wertauffassung) (1910, 11). According to her, however, it would be a mistake to interpret feelings of self-worth as mere judgments about our own value (1910, 13). Two arguments speak against this reduction. First, a person might have knowledge about her own intelligence, and yet this positive judgment about her own value does not necessarily lead to a feeling of haughtiness or vanity. Second, one might be aware of one’s own virtues and nevertheless have a low feeling of self-worth. Now, while not reducible to each other, Voigtländer states that judgments about one’s own value and feelings of self-worth might be related to each other in at least two respects: (1) An objective stance taken toward oneself, which leads to the consideration of one’s own talents, capacities and achievements, might prompt an elevation or depression of one’s feeling of self-worth (in this case, a value judgment gives rise to a feeling of self-worth); (2) on the other hand, it is possible that the experiencing of feelings of self-worth gives rise to a certain value judgment (1910, 45–46). Feelings of self-worth are characterized by three main features. (1) Qualitative Feeling: They are characterized by a phenomenal, experiential or qualitative moment, i.e., they are felt. Voigtländer uses the expression “affective moment” to refer to this aspect. Pleasure and pain belong to our experiences of feeling uplifted or depressed. When our feeling of self-worth is elevated, we have a pleasant experience, while a degradation in our feeling of self-worth is unpleasant, but these experiences are not merely feelings of pleasure and pain. (2) Value-Awareness: As already mentioned, a cognitive moment, involving an awareness of our own value, is always active in feelings of self-worth. However, far from constituting a judgment, such awareness is conceived as a non-conceptual grasping of one’s own worth. Rather than being the product of an objective stance toward oneself that culminates in a 97
Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
self-evaluation, the form of self-assessment that Voigtländer has in mind here is an affective valuating awareness of our Self. (3) Self-Awareness: Feelings of self-worth are also necessarily accompanied by an awareness of the Self, which—depending on the feeling in question, the personality, the activities in which we are engaged or the general concern for others—might occupy a central or peripheral position (Voigtländer 1910, 54). For some people who tend to affirm themselves and relate everything to themselves, it is difficult to adopt a stance without involving oneself, while others are selfless and abandon themselves to the activities in which they are engaged. Generally, two main kinds of feelings of self-worth can be distinguished (Voigtländer 1910, 21–22). a
b
Vital feelings of self-worth (vitales Selbstgefühl) are instinctive, natural and innate. They are unconscious and unrelated to an object or achievement, expressing a basic affective background orientation that is characteristic for each individual. These, in turn, might be classified in the following subclasses: (1) Feelings of courage, confidence and selfaffirmation and their opposites (faintheartedness, insecurity and self-negation), as well as the feeling of vitality, health and buoyancy and their opposites (tiredness, decadence and depression); (2) the feeling of the noble and the mean; (3) the feeling of superiority and inferiority; and (4) the feeling of ability and incapacity (1910, 25–30). Such feelings are primarily characterized by their qualitative feeling or “affective moment”. Rather than by the awareness of our own value or of the Self, these feelings are chiefly shaped by their qualitative moment. The latter is felt as either an uplifting (Erhebung) or a depression (Depression) of the feeling, and it is linked to pleasure and pain (1910, 37). Conscious feelings of self-worth (bewusstes Selbstgefühl) are neither innate nor unconscious, but fluctuate in accordance with our achievements, successes, failures and defeats. They also depend on our attitude toward life. For instance, after having successfully completed a task, one experiences an elevation in the feeling of self-worth. Unlike vital feelings, conscious feelings of self-worth depend on an objective appreciation of one’s own talents and accomplishments. Thus, they imply what Voigtländer calls a “division” or “split of the self ” (Teilung des Selbst) (1910, 21). As a result, the awareness of one’s own value emerges, which is a precondition for a conscious feeling of self-worth (1910, 39). Thus, the cognitive moment is predominant for this class of feelings: They are primarily shaped not by the qualitative feeling, but rather by the value awareness.
Vital and conscious feelings of self-worth belong to different strata or layers of the personality and, in some cases, they might exhibit contrary directions (1910, 40). A low-spirited person with a weak feeling of self-worth might be able to elevate this feeling by focusing on her achievements, and thereby generate a positive conscious feeling of self-worth. In the same vein, the consciousness of one’s own failures might depress a person who by nature has a strong vital feeling of self-worth. I will return to these differences between vital and conscious feelings in the explanation of the phenomenon of Ressentiment.
2. Inauthentic feelings An intriguing topic introduced by Voigtländer concerns the possibility for a feeling to be inauthentic. Crucial in her book is the distinction between genuine feelings of self-worth (eigentliches Selbstgefühl) and “non-genuine or mirror feelings of self-worth” (uneigentliche oder Spiegelselbstgefühl) (1910, 22). Inauthentic are those feelings that arise by way of joking, 98
Else Voigtländer
make-believe, pretending, acting as if we are moved by an affect, posing, attitudinizing, presenting oneself, boasting, as well as in imagining experiences, deceiving ourselves, l iving a lie, and experiencing ourselves from the perspective of a possible other (1910, 94–95). As employed by Voigtländer, the term is neither reduced to self-deceptive emotions nor to intentional fraud, but rather embraces a wide range of phenomena that arise when we experience ourselves from the perspective of a hypothetical other. As she puts it: It is “a feeling of self-worth experienced with regard to what one is in the imagination, in the opinion of others, to what refers to an ‘image’ of oneself ” (1910, 76; own transl.). Inauthentic feelings, rather than being anchored in the kernel of the self, are experienced as having their origins in the image that one thinks others have of oneself. The underlying idea here is that there are some feelings that are experienced as constitutive parts of us, which cannot be manipulated or changed at will and which belong to the core of our person. Notice that the term “non-genuine” (uneigentlich) does not have the negative connotation of being necessarily something morally wrong. With this characterization, Voigtländer is underscoring an important aspect of our affective life, which directly reflects our intrinsically social nature. Non-genuine feelings of self-worth presuppose that we are able to imagine how we are seen by a hypothetical observer, and that we incorporate this image into our consciousness and experience ourselves from this hypothetical perspective. The point here is that the awareness of the image that others might have of us leads to fluctuations in our feeling of self-worth, intensifying or degrading it. This process involves a special form of empathy with the image that we think others might have of us (1910, 86). Here, we have a feeling which is rooted not in the actual life of the self, but in the “external” perspective that we imagine others might have of us. Because they are not rooted in the kernel of the self, i.e., but in its social image, they are experienced as distant, and Voigtländer characterizes them as having a “coreless”, “airy” and “playful nature” (1910, 97). According to her taxonomy, there are two main kinds of non-genuine feelings of selfworth: (a) When we experience ourselves from the perspective of a hypothetical other, we can focus on our own experiencing self, or (b) we can concentrate on the image that we think others have of our self. To the first group belong the need for recognition, ambition, honor or thirst for glory; typical cases for the second group of experiences include feelings of vanity, smugness or those that arise when attitudinizing (the lack of such an experience is characteristic of modest, straightforward and frugal personalities). In a later paper entitled “Über die ‘Art’ eines Menschen und das Erlebnis der ‘Maske’” (On the Nature of a Person and the Experience of the “Mask”) (1923), Voigtländer deepens her analysis of these issues. More concretely, she investigates the relation between those features that we attribute to others as a result of the impression we have of them (a phenomenon that she calls Eindruckswerte) and the real qualities of their character. Voigtländer’s account of non-genuine feelings highlights the fact that while feelings are felt, not all feelings belong to the same dimension of existence. Some do not arise from the core of our self and have their origins in one’s (social) image. In this respect, Voigtländer’s research was groundbreaking as this issue of emotional authenticity would come to preoccupy later phenomenologists such as Scheler (1972[1911/1915]), Heidegger (2008[1927]), Sartre (2014[1939]) and Merleau-Ponty (2012[1945]). But looking no further, shortly after her work was submitted, two other phenomenologists of the Munich circle published substantial accounts that examined inauthentic feelings (curiously, none of them cited her work).4 Just one year after her book appeared, Willy Haas—who was also one of Pfänder’s PhD-students— published Über Echtheit und Unechtheit von Gefühlen (On the Authenticity and Inauthenticity of Emotions) (1910). In this book, Haas develops a model according to which an emotion 99
Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
is authentic or inauthentic only in respect of the psychological frame in which it occurs. Emotions are authentic when its general direction is coherent with the general affective orientation of the self. Joy is authentic when it fits with an emotional background of positivity, but it is inauthentic when the general orientation of the subject is dominated by bad humor (1910, 12). In addition, Pfänder in his Psychologie der Gesinnungen (Psychology of Sentiments) (1913/1916) developed an account of inauthenticity for the case of sentiments. Inauthentic sentiments, in the moment of being experienced, are not in tune with other sentiments, feelings, thoughts, etc. of the self. Though constituting part of the self, inauthentic sentiments do not fit with other aspects of it (for instance, they are not supported by thoughts, perceptions, etc.). Using a terminology that recalls the one previously employed by Voigtländer, Pfänder describes them as “schematic, hollow, thin, coreless or light” (1913/1916, 383). These phenomena are “inauthentic” and are felt in a different manner, because they have their origins in the social world, but—as already observed by Voigtländer— they might come to form an essential part of our emotional life. They have the capacity to be converted into authentic sentiments when the subject changes her general attitude, and the sentiment that was not initially in tune with the rest of the psychic life is now felt as spontaneously originating from the self.
3. Ressentiment and negative attitudes One of the issues touched on by Voigtländer in her book (1910) is the phenomenon of Ressentiment. Following Nietzsche, Voigtländer—like Scheler some years later—uses the concept as a technical term to refer to a self-defeating hostile attitude, which implies a degradation of values. For both phenomenologists, Ressentiment aims at reducing unpleasant feelings (such as that of inferiority, impotence, etc.) that arise when one cannot achieve one’s desired goals. More specifically, it consists in devaluating objects previously felt as worthy. This adaptive strategy is best illustrated by the fable of the fox who, upon discovering that he is unable to reach the grapes, exclaims that they are sour. The fox does not merely change its judgment about the grapes, i.e., it is not the case that the fox first considers the grapes to be sweet and then claims they are sour. The matter is more complex. It involves an inversion of values. Thus, the fox now considers sweetness itself to be bad. Notice here the difference to resentment, which is an emotional displeasure that arises from a sense of injury and is a legitimate response to a moral wrong. In contrast, what is essential to Ressentiment, and what makes it a morally wrong or, better, inappropriate reaction, is precisely the inversion of values that it entails. However, despite these points of agreement regarding the general nature of Ressentiment, there are also some striking differences between the Voigtländer’s and Scheler’s accounts. According to Voigtländer, Ressentiment originates from a negative feeling of self-worth that arises from the awareness of a weakness and which motivates an exaggerated and unrealistic positive evaluation of the Self (1910, 48). Ressentiment is an attempt to transform a negative feeling of self-worth into a positive one. Once Ressentiment arises, the overrated evaluation of the Self obfuscates the knowledge of the weakness which, though still in the background, is not at the center of our awareness. In this regard, Ressentiment is akin to self-deception: That is, it implies a psychological twist, which consists in elevating the feeling of self-worth by devaluing what, in fact, one takes to be valuable. The person imbued with Ressentiment cannot achieve the desired values, becomes aware of their own inferiority and experiences a negative degradation of the feeling of their own value. As a result, she tries to avoid this outcome by degrading those values that were once deemed worthy. 100
Else Voigtländer
The process involves two mechanisms. First, values once felt as worthy are deprived of their value and, as a result, an “inversion of values” (Umkehrung der Werte) and a change of value preferences occurs (1910, 50). Second, though still given, the awareness of their own inferiority is pushed into the background of our consciousness and, consequently, a person with feelings of Ressentiment experiences an elevation in their feeling of self-worth. However, as is typical of self-deceptive mechanisms, a tension between the awareness of one’s own inferiority and the artificially uplifted feeling of self-worth remains. There is only one remedy for this: the cultivation of love and benevolence. The differences between Voigtländer’s and Scheler’s phenomenologies of Ressentiment can be summarized as follows: (1) While Voigtländer underscores the feeling of inferiority (a negative feeling of self-worth) as crucial in the formation of Ressentiment, Scheler sees its origins in the feeling of impotence or inability to change an unpleasant and unbearable situation; (2) Voigtländer’s person of Ressentiment inverts values and changes her preferences, but she does not replace the real values with illusory negative ones, since she is still capable of perceiving the real positive nature of the values and their bearers. By contrast, Scheler’s process of an inversion of values entails a much deeper process whereby the self-defeating turn of mind leads to a change in the perception of values and a replacement of these values with illusory negative ones (Scheler 2010[1912/1915], 25, 45–46; see also Vendrell Ferran (2018) and Chapter 4 in this volume). (3) At the core of Voigtländer’s notion of Ressentiment lies a tension between a vital negative feeling and a conscious positive feeling of selfworth. In Scheler’s account, there is no such tension: He explains Ressentiment mainly as a progression of negative feelings that cannot be expressed. When negative feelings—such as revenge, hatred, malice, envy, rancor and spite—do not find expression and are sustained and repressed, Ressentiment emerges as a hostile and self-poisoning attitude (2010[1912/1915], 45–46). (4) Finally, Voigtländer’s main interest is a study of character and, accordingly, she focuses on the psychological mechanism that is typical of individuals, while Scheler is interested in showing that not only individuals but also collectives might be imbued with Ressentiment. In a later text entitled “Zur Psychologie der politischen Stellungnahme” (Towards a Psychology of Political Attitudes) (1920), Voigtländer explores the nature of negative attitudes such as antipathy and hatred. One of the main aims of the text is to elaborate an analysis of hostile feelings and their role in politics (see also Chapters 38 and 41 in this volume. More specifically, she is interested in establishing how aversive emotions might explain the existence of different attitudes toward the phenomenon of war. The text should also be considered within a broader socio-historical perspective: Like many other intellectuals and phenomenologists of her time, such as Scheler, Voigtländer also seeks to attain a better understanding of World War I and how it affected political attitudes both in and toward Germany.
4. Love and sexuality One of Voigtländer’s enduring interests is the nature of love and how, in love, the loved one appears to embody the properties of the charming, lovely, attractive, etc. Her correspondence with Johannes Daubert during the 1930s reveals that she was preparing a monograph dedicated to the topic, but there are already crucial references to this phenomenon in her first book.5 According to Voigtländer, love is not a reaction to certain values of the loved person. After all, it is possible to love somebody despite their mistakes and imperfections (and to hate somebody despite their virtues), but love is responsible for presenting the other in a positive light. In her view, love is sentiment rather than an emotional reaction. This distinction between the two kinds of emotional phenomena can be already found in her first 101
Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
book. Although there Voigtländer employs the term feeling (Gefühle) for both, according to the terminology used in later publications, one can distinguish between emotional reactions and sentiments (Gesinnungen). (a) Emotional reactions, such as grief, fear, joy, etc., are responses to an object or an event (e.g., in fear, we react to an object or an event given to us as dangerous). (b) Sentiments, such as love, admiration or tenderness, make objects appear to us in a certain light and present them as having certain qualities, such as charming, beautiful, lovely, marvelous, etc. (which she calls Eindruckswerte; 1910, 111; for the use of the term “sentiment” with explicit reference to Pfänder, see Voigtländer 1928, 1933). Voigtländer’s interest in sexuality (she composed, for example, the entries on “gender trait” and “neglect” for the Handwörterbuch der Sexualwissenschaft edited by Max Marcuse) led her to explore the nature of erotic love in “Über das Wesen der Liebe und ihre Beziehung zur Sexualität” (On the Nature of Love and its Relation to Sexuality) (1928). Her main thesis is that erotic love, rather than being derived from the sexual instinct, is a sentiment (1928, 189). As such, it displays all of the three main features that, according to Pfänder (1913/1916), are typical of sentiments: It streams from the subject to the object giving it support, with the intention of uniting with it and accepting it (negative sentiments aim at destroying the object, disunifying from it and rejecting it). Once identified as a sentiment, Voigtländer goes on to determine the specific nature of erotic love. Erotic love is a subspecies of the sentiment of love and as such it exhibits specific nuances for each of the three features mentioned above. It is a warming movement of the heart that leads us to experience the loved one as personifying certain properties (Verkörperungserlebnis), tends to melt with her (Verschmelzung) and aims at creating a perfect unity with them (vollkommenen Einigung). The comparison with friendship (another subspecies of love) is helpful as a clarification at this point. In using a metaphor, Voigtländer maintains that while friendship is a bridge that unifies two poles, erotic love is the convergence of two flows (1928, 193). The link between erotic love and sexuality is explained as follows. First, she maintains that, like all emotions and sentiments, erotic love is linked to expressive movements and expressive actions, which remain in a symbolic relation with the expressed phenomena. Then, Voigtländer contends that expressive movements and actions intrinsic to erotic love converge with the already existing sexual impulse. She concludes the text by identifying “attractiveness” as the main value of the erotic domain (she distinguishes aesthetic from erotic values, since we might feel attracted to someone who is ugly). In erotic love, the beloved person appears to the lover as charming, interesting, lovable, etc., and it is due to these qualities that we feel attracted to the beloved. In “Bemerkungen zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen” (Observations on the Psychology of Sentiments) (1933), published in the Pfänder Festschrift, Voigtländer discusses theories of love developed by Pfänder, Scheler, Hildebrand and Hartmann. In so doing, she underscores her original claim that love is not a response to the values of beloved, but a form of attributing values to her (Voigtländer 1933, 153). Rather than being an answer, a response or a reaction, love is a creative force that discovers values in the person one loves.6
Notes
102
Else Voigtländer that she prepared by commission of the ministry of Saxony on criminal women (cf. Bayerische Staatsbibliothek München, Daubertiana B.I. Voigtländer, Else [letters from Daubert to Voigtländer 3.VIII.1930 (6 Bl.)]. Transcribed by Rodney Parker and Thomas Vongehr), written during her time as the director of the women’s prison in Waldheim (1926–1945). Voigtländer was a member of the NSDAP from 1937 onward (her relation with Nazism has still to be investigated). I thank Kristin Gjesdal and George Heffernan for a lively exchange about Voigtländer’s later publications and activities in Waldheim.
References Haas, Willy (1910). Über Echtheit und Unechtheit von Gefühlen. Nürnberg: Benedikt Hill. Heidegger, Martin (2008[1927]). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Macquarrie, and E. Robinson. Being and Time. New York: Harper & Row. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (2012[1945]). Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by D. A. Landes. London, New York: Routledge. Mulligan, Kevin (2006). Was sind und was sollen die unechten Gefühle? In: U. Amrein (Ed.). Das Authentische. Referenzen und Repräsentationen. Zürich: Chronos, 225–242. Pfänder, Alexander (1913/1916). Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen. In: Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung I, 325–404, and III, 1–125. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer. Sartre, Jean-Paul (2014[1939]). Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. Transl. by P. Mairet. London, New York: Routledge. Scheler, Max (1972[1911/1915]). Die Idole der Selbsterkenntnis. In: Gesammelte Werke, vol. 3. Ed. by M. Scheler. Bern: Francke. ——— (2010[1912/1915]). Ressentiment. Transl. by W. W. Holdheim. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. Smid, Reinhold Nikolaus (1982). “Münchener Phänomenologie” – Zur Frühgeschichte des Begriffs. In: E. Avé-Lallemant, and H. Spiegelberg (Eds.). Pfänder-Studien. Den Haag: Nijhoff, 109–154. Szanto, Thomas (2017). Emotional Self-Alienation. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 41, 260–286. Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (2008). Die Emotionen. Gefühle in der realistischen Phänomenologie. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. ——— (2018). Phenomenological Approaches to Hatred: Scheler, Pfänder, and Kolnai. In: R. K. B. Parker, and I. Quepons (Eds.). The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, 176–197. Voigtländer, Else (1910). Über die Typen des Selbstgefühls. Leipzig: R. Voigtländers Verlag. ——— (1920). Zur Psychologie der politischen Stellungnahme. Eine massenpsychologische Studie. Deutsche Psychologie 3(3), 184–206. ——— (with Adalbert Gregor) (1922). Charakterstudie verwahrloster Kinder und Jugendlicher. Leipzig: Barth. ——— (1923). Über die “Art” eines Menschen und das Erlebnis der “Maske”. Zeitschrift für Psychologie 92, 326–336. ——— (1928). Über das Wesen der Liebe und ihre Beziehung zur Sexualität. Verhandlungen des I. internationalen Kongresses für Sexualforschung, 10. bis 16. Okt. 1926. Berlin: Marcuse &Weber, 189–196. ——— (1933). Bemerkungen zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen. In: E. Heller, and F. Löw (Eds.). Neue Münchener Philosophische Abhandlungen. Leipzig: Barth, 143–164.
103
7 MARTIN HEIDEGGER AND OTTO FRIEDRICH BOLLNOW Gerhard Thonhauser
Martin Heidegger and Otto Friedrich Bollnow’s essential contribution to the phenomenology of emotions is their discovery of the primordial role of Stimmung (attunement) for human intentionality and the intelligibility of the world. In his characterization of Dasein’s being-in-the-world, Heidegger introduces Befindlichkeit (the ontological condition of being attuned) together with understanding and discourse as three equiprimordial existentiale of Dasein. Bollnow builds on Heidegger in developing his main contribution to philosophical anthropology: the introduction of attunement as the most primordial level of human life.1 I will begin by introducing Heidegger’s account of Befindlichkeit and attunement in B eing and Time. Heidegger’s conception of Befindlichkeit has served as the kernel of a productive philosophical perspective on affectivity (Ratcliffe 2008, 2013; Slaby and Stephan 2008; Withy 2014, 2015). In contrast, the work of Bollnow has not received much attention. I will use the second section to discuss his seminal work Das Wesen der Stimmungen (The Nature of Attunements). In the third section, I will come back to Heidegger and discuss his idiosyncratic understanding of fundamental attunements, which shows the close link between Befindlichkeit and the core of his overall philosophical project.
1. Attuned world disclosure in Heidegger’s Being and Time One of the ground-breaking insights of Being and Time is that our most primordial mode of being is constituted by the way in which we find ourselves in the world.2 Heidegger introduces Befindlichkeit as a general condition of an entity existing in the mode of being-in-the-world. We experience Befindlichkeit by always being attuned one way or the other. Attunements are ubiquitous and pervasive: We are never devoid of attunements; even if our attunements change, that does not mean that we can free ourselves of them: “The fact that attunements can be spoiled and change only means that Dasein is always already attuned in a way”3 (Heidegger 1953, 134). Even the lack of attunement is a particular way of being attuned: “The often persistent, smooth, and pallid lack of attunement, which must not be confused with a bad attunement, is far from being nothing” (ibid.). Moreover, when we influence or control an attunement, this is not done by “being free of attunement, but always through a counter attunement” (ibid., 136). Attunements are not simply modes of coloring our experience, but rather serve a fundamental disclosive function. Attunements 104
Martin Heidegger and Otto Friedrich Bollnow
play into the most basic disclosure of the world: “The prior disclosedness of the world which belongs to being-in is co-constituted by Befindlichkeit” (ibid., 137). At the same time, attunements disclose one’s own situation; they are modes of finding oneself: “Attunement makes manifest ‘how one is and is coming along’” (ibid., 134). These two dimensions are inextricable elements of the way in which attunements constitute being-in-the-world. Being attuned is what constitutes world and self in their essential relatedness: “The attunedness of Befindlichkeit constitutes existentially the openness to world of Dasein” (ibid., 137). What does it mean that attunements constitute Dasein’s being-in-the-world? Being attuned is first and foremost experienced in Dasein finding things and actions mattering to it. The most primordial encounter with things has the character of “being affected or moved” (Betroffenwerden) (ibid.). In other words, I encounter all entities as mattering to me one way or the other; I always experience them with some kind of significance. Even if I experience something as meaningless, this is just another mode of significance; in such a case, I do not experience nothing; rather, I experience something as not speaking to me. Heidegger points out that significance is always connected to my possibilities, i.e. my potential activities: All my comportment presupposes a sense of things mattering to me, and the way in which things matter to me depends on what I consider within my realm of possible comportment. Moreover, Heidegger shows that the significance of a single entity cannot be seen in isolation. Instead, he suggests a holistic view on significance according to which the significance of an entity depends on a nexus of significant things. All particular meanings are established against the background of a world as the realm of significance: “In Befindlichkeit lies existentially a disclosive submission to world out of which things that matter to us can be encountered” (ibid.). It is our Befindlichkeit that constitutes the sense of a meaningful world and the sense of our belonging to this world. To be sure, Heidegger does not claim that a meaningful world is constituted solely by Befindlichkeit. Rather, the constitution of the world happens in an interplay of Befindlichkeit with understanding (Verstehen) and discourse (Rede). Among these equiprimordial features of being-in, understanding emphasizes the agential dimension, i.e., the possible ways of interacting with entities against the background of our projects. Understanding is here not conceived of as a mental ability in the vicinity of knowledge, but rather, along pragmatist lines, as the way of encountering things as meaningful in everyday comportment. For instance, the most ordinary way of understanding a door is by opening it. According to this pragmatist notion of understanding, the everyday mode of understanding an entity does not consist in making assertions about it, but in using it properly. Discourse, the third existentiale of being-in, is understood best with reference to the Latin origin of articulation, articulare, which means structuring. Discourse is the “articulation of intelligibility” (Heidegger 1953, 161). On the basic level, this structuring does not need to take conceptual form, but is articulated in differentiations of meaning that are not yet cast in concepts, let alone written or spoken words. Within this tripartite constitution of being-in, Befindlichkeit indicates the experience of always already being situated in meaningful structures. Without such situatedness, entities would not matter to me, and hence, they would not matter at all. Finding entities meaningful goes hand in hand with finding oneself within meaningful structures. Heidegger’s central claim is that the primordial sense of significance is constituted by Befindlichkeit, i.e., affectivity, rather than cognition: Indeed, we must ontologically in principle leave the primary discovery of the world to ‘mere attunement’. Pure beholding (reines Anschauen), even if it penetrated into the 105
Gerhard Thonhauser
innermost core of the being of something objectively present, would never be able to discover anything [as mattering to me]. (ibid., 138) The world-disclosure in and through attunements is prior to contemplation, deliberation, or any form of propositional attitude: “The possibilities of disclosure belonging to cognition fall far short of the primordial disclosure of attunements” (ibid., 134). To understand why this is the case, we need to take a closer look at the status of attunements in comparison to familiar mental states. Attunements cannot be classified as an additional type of intentional states directed toward something in the world. Rather, they set up a world in the first place. Attunements are constitutive of a world within which we can experience concrete, object-directed states, among them affective states like emotions. In Heidegger’s words: “Attunement has already disclosed being-in-the-world as a whole and first makes it possible directing oneself toward something” (ibid., 137). Attunements thus constitute the background that structures our worldrelatedness as a whole. It becomes clear now that attunements are not a separate class of affective states besides emotions, moods, sentiments, etc.; rather, all these affective states presuppose attunement. Matthew Ratcliffe has carved out this thought in terms of “existential feelings”. Existential feelings “are not directed at specific objects or situations but are background orientations through which experience as a whole is structured” (Ratcliffe 2008, 2). They are ‘ways of finding oneself in the world’, which establish both a ‘sense of reality of the world’, and a ‘sense of one’s belonging to the world’ (cf. Ratcliffe 2008; see also Chapter 22 in this volume). It is central for Heidegger to emphasize that attunements cannot be properly conceived of as ‘subjective’ or ‘psychic’ phenomena: “Prior to all psychology of attunements (…) we must see this phenomenon as a fundamental existential and outline its structure” (Heidegger 1953, 134). Heidegger repeatedly emphasized the claim that, “Befindlichkeit is far removed from anything like finding a psychical condition” (ibid., 136). “Being attuned is not initially related to the psychical, it is itself not an inner condition which then reaches out and leaves its mark on things and persons” (ibid., 137). Attunements are not elements to be found in the psychological life of an individual, rather, they are constitutive features of being-in-theworld. In other words, attunements are constituents of our relatedness with the world and others, rather than experiences in concrete encounters. By locating attunements in the complex structure of being-in-the-world rather than in the ‘inner’ life of an individual or in the ‘outer’ world, Heidegger overcomes the dualism between the experience of self and the experience of world. Attunements do not disclose the self or the world; they rather make manifest self and world in their essential relatedness. Jan Slaby and Achim Stephan have developed this account further in terms of their notion of affective intentionality. Affective intentionality is at once a disclosure of world and of self: Affective states are “an evaluative awareness of which goes hand in hand with a registration of one’s existential situation” (Slaby and Stephan 2008, 506). Heidegger’s account of attunement also implies an overcoming of the dualism between activity and passivity. The self is neither an active creator nor a passive recipient of attunement. Instead, “attunement assails. It comes neither from ‘without’ nor from ‘within’, but rises from being-in-the world itself as a mode of that being” (Heidegger 1953, 136). In short, the disclosure of world and self in attunements is neither active nor passive. Katherine Withy (2014, 2015) has elaborated on this in terms of “disclosive postures”. Attunements encompass modes of comportment (posture) and ways of encountering (disclosure). 106
Martin Heidegger and Otto Friedrich Bollnow
Finally, Heidegger’s account of attunement challenges the dualism of cognition and affect: Existentially and ontologically there is not the slightest justification for minimizing the “evidence” of Befindlichkeit by measuring it against the apodictic certainty of the theoretical cognition of something merely objectively present. But the falsification of the phenomena, which banishes them to the sanctuary of the irrational, is no better. (Heidegger 1953, 136) That attunements constitute the fundamental way of being oriented in the world implies that we cannot push them aside with reference to their alleged irrationality. Since all significance is co-constituted by Befindlichkeit, we cannot establish a separated realm of reason unaffected by attunements. On the contrary, Heidegger urges us to see that the theoretical attitude also presupposes a specific attunement, namely the attunement of letting things “come towards us in tranquil staying” (ibid., 138). To sum up, attunements are a form of disclosure that outstrip any cognitive grasp or mental representation, forming the world- and self-disclosing background for all object-directed mental states, may they be cognitive, conative, or affective.
2. Bollnow’s Das Wesen der Stimmungen In Das Wesen der Stimmungen, Bollnow builds on Heidegger’s discussion of Befindlichkeit while adopting a critical stance toward Heidegger’s overall project.4 Bollnow mentions two Heideggerian claims as his major source of inspiration: (1) We are always already attuned in some way. (2) Our entire psychic life builds on attunements; attunements shape all our experiences, enabling some while disabling others (cf. Bollnow 1953, 54). Bollnow identifies as the main weakness of Heidegger’s approach that he does not account for different types of attunements. To be fair, Heidegger does mention several specific attunements in Being and Time. He refers to “hope, joy, enthusiasm, and gaiety” as well as “sadness, melancholy, despair” (Heidegger 1953, 345). Moreover, he introduces other affective conditions without established names, such as a “pallid lack of mood” (ibid.), an “undisturbed equanimity”, or an “inhibited discontent” (ibid., 134). However, he does not analyze them in any detail. Moreover, he does not pay any attention to their potential differences. According to Bollnow, this is not simply an omission, but based on the methodology of Heidegger’s existential analysis. Following Bollnow’s interpretation, the existential analysis presupposes that the essential structures of human existence can be obtained by analyzing one single example, since all examples lead to the same invariant structures of existence. This presupposition leads Heidegger to focus on a single attunement—angst in the case of Being and Time—for analyzing the structure of attunement in general. In contrast to Heidegger, Bollnow suggests that philosophical anthropology needs to account for human life in the plurality of its manifestations. Following this approach, we should expect each type of attunement to make manifest new dimensions of the human being and its relation to the world and others (Bollnow 1953, 27–28). Despite these methodological differences, Bollnow, for the most part, follows the general thrust of Heidegger’s account of Befindlichkeit. To begin with, he identifies “vital feelings” (Lebensgefühle) or “attunements” as the most primordial level of psychic life (ibid., 33). Bollnow speaks of basic attunements (Grundbefindlichkeiten or Grundstimmungen) as forming the foundational level of human life. He provides a non-comprehensive list of basic attunements: Cheerfulness and sadness; examples of high spirits like gaity and jollity, and examples of low spirits like lassitude and stifling stubor; a calm and relaxed manner, or tense anxiety and solicitude (ibid., 34). 107
Gerhard Thonhauser
In line with Heidegger, Bollnow suggests an order of constitution according to which encompassing attunements are necessary to enable concrete emotions (and all other intentional states). In contrast to Heidegger, Bollnow draws a sharp distinction between attunements and emotions. Heidegger appears not to distinguish attunements and emotions. In §30 of Being and Time, for instance, Heidegger discusses fear as a “mode of attunement”, although what he describes is clearly an emotion. It seems that Heidegger wants to subsume all affective states under the term attunement. In my opinion, Heidegger’s radical anti-mentalism led him to throw the baby out with the bath water, aiming to eliminate all psychological talk about emotions. However, it seems more promising to follow Bollnow in drawing a sharp distinction between attunements and emotions while maintaining both concepts: “Emotions in a proper sense are always intentionally related to a specific object. (…) The attunements, on the other hand, do not have a specific object. They are states of being (Zuständlichkeiten), colorations of the entire human Dasein” (ibid., 34–35). Bollnow adds the qualification that in specific cases, it might be difficult to determine whether something is an attunement or an emotion. Consider the example of grief, which sometimes is a distinct, episodic emotion, and sometimes becomes so encompassing that it shapes our entire orientation in the world. Bollnow is again in line with Heidegger in attempting to overcome the dualisms of world-experience and self-experience, activity and passivity, cognition and affect. First, Bollnow suggests that basic attunements involve an evaluation of one’s situation. They are forms of becoming aware of oneself. One can argue—as Slaby and Stephan (2008) have done—that basic attunements are the most primordial form of self-awareness. Moreover, Bollnow places attunements as the foundational level of psychic life prior to a sharp distinction of self and world: “The attunements still entirely live in the undivided unity of self and world, both pervaded by a common coloration of attunement” (Bollnow 1953, 39). He also speaks of a primordial “unity of human mind (Gemüt) and surrounding world” (ibid., 40). Second, Bollnow addresses the question whether a regulation of attunements is possible. On the one hand, we are overcome by attunements; this is most apparent in the way in which we cannot voluntarily educe an attunement, at least not directly. On the other hand, we are not totally at the mercy of our attunements; we can comport ourselves vis-à-vis our attunement in different ways, and we can attempt to indirectly influence how we are attuned. A dualistic understanding of activity and passivity cannot account for the complex ways in which we are related to our attunements. Bollnow explores this further by discussing the relationship of attunement to character and posture (ibid., 131–163). Third, the experience of concrete objects and events within the world is pre-shaped by basic attunements: “Only in an anxious attunement I encounter something threatening, and only in a cheerful state of mind (Gemütsverfassung) I come across felicific experiences almost as a matter of course” (ibid., 53). Similarly, the fearless person does not encounter anything fearsome, and the deeply depressed person does not experience anything uplifting. As Bollnow writes, such individuals have become ‘blind’ for certain aspects of the world, which shows the “dependence of all grasping on the state of attunement (Stimmungslage)” (ibid., 57). It would be wrong to assume that an originally neutral experience is subsequently colored by attunement. Rather, attunement frames all experiences. Attunement has always already ‘interpreted’ the world in a certain way that guides concrete experiences. Going beyond Heidegger, Bollnow explores in more detail how shifting attunements transform our entire mode of being. First, attunements transform our awareness of community (Gemeinschaftsbewußtseins), i.e., our relatedness to others. Chastened attunements tend to close someone off and lead her into solitariness, as they direct her attention to her own self. Elevated attunements, on the other hand, tend to open up a person and make her more 108
Martin Heidegger and Otto Friedrich Bollnow
sociable (cf. Bollnow 1953, 97–112). Second, attunements transform our sense of reality, i.e., our relatedness to the world. Bollnow suggests that certainty about reality cannot be gained by means of a theoretical operation, but only rises from basic affective experiences. This anticipates the work of Ratcliffe, who draws on psychopathology to explore how the sense of reality can be disturbed (cf. Ratcliffe 2008, 2014). Bollnow suggests that chastened attunements lead us to experience the world as resisting and inhibiting, whereas it is experienced as sustaining and fostering in elevated attunements (Bollnow 1953, 112–131). Third, attunements transform our awareness of time. Our estimation of time is contingent upon our affective state. In chastened attunements, time can become unbearably long, whereas in elevated attunements, time tends to ‘fly by’ and it happens to us that we ‘lose track of time’. German offers the terms langweilig and kurzweilig to express these experiences. When something is boring, time is experienced as long—langweilig literally means ‘a long while’. In contrast, when something is diverting, time is experienced as short—kurzweilig literally means ‘a short while’. Furthermore, Bollnow points to the intriguing fact that in retrospection, the proportions turn around. In our recollection, an eventful time appears as long, while an uneventful time appears as short. Thus, when having a great time, we experience it as short and recollect it as long, whereas we experience a time of waiting as long and recollect it as short (Bollnow 1953, 165–182). These examples are meant to show how our entire relation to others, the world, and the flow of time is shaped and modulated by attunements, and how exploring these nexuses requires us to consider a plurality of attunements and their contrasting modes of disclosure.
3. Heidegger’s fundamental attunements and the path to philosophizing Whereas Bollnow contextualizes his investigation of attunements within philosophical anthropology, Heidegger denies any interest in anthropology, claiming that his existential analysis of Dasein is prior to all regional ontologies, including anthropology as the regional ontology of the human being. Heidegger drives at a very specific point with his account of Befindlichkeit. He focuses on certain attunements that serve a crucial methodological role for his ontological project. To understand this role, we need to consider the forth existentiale of being-in-the-world: Falling (Verfallen). Falling implies that the existential features of Dasein are usually not experienced and enacted as what they actually (eigentlich) are, but rather in the mode of average everydayness, a modality in which Dasein avoids or misconstrues its own ontological makeup. As all other features of Dasein, Befindlichkeit is also prone to fa lling. Thus, the usual way in which we experience Befindlichkeit is an “evasive turning away” (Heidegger 1953, 136), i.e., being attuned in a way that keeps us from seeing and grasping the disclosive function of attunements: “For the most part Dasein evades the being that is disclosed in attunements in an ontic and existentiell way” (ibid., 135). If this is the case, however, a methodological problem for Heidegger’s project arises: If it is true that falling is so pervasive as to constantly keep Dasein from genuinely (eigentlich) experiencing its true ontological structure, how could we ever experience that structure, or even assume that such a structure exists? Heidegger solves this problem by granting certain attunements a very specific status: These attunements have the power to draw us out of average everydayness and set us on the path to potential existential insights.5 In Being and Time, Heidegger focuses on ‘angst’6 as an attunement that is capable of disclosing the ontological structure of Dasein in particular clarity. Heidegger introduces angst in contrast to fear. Fear refers to the familiar emotion in which we experience an 109
Gerhard Thonhauser
entity as dangerous. In contrast, “that about which one has angst” is totally indeterminate, it is “nothing and nowhere” (ibid., 186). In angst, we are not afraid of any particular entity, but of “ being-in-the-world itself ” (ibid., 187). Angst is an attunement that radically unsettles Dasein’s absorption in everyday activities and confronts it with the uncanniness at the bottom of its being: “Angst (…) fetches Dasein back out of its entangled absorption in the ‘world’. Everyday familiarity collapses. (…) Being-in enters the existential ‘mode’ of not-being-at-home. The talk about ‘uncanniness’ means nothing other than this” (ibid., 189). What the experience of angst does is setting Dasein on the path of ontological inquiry: It takes Dasein from the realm of entities (Seiendes)—the realm of everyday comportment—to the realm of being (Sein)—the realm of ontological investigation. That Heideggerian angst primarily concerns the possibility of ontology becomes particularly obvious in the lecture What is Metaphysics? (1929). Heidegger claims here that certain attunements (he mentions profound boredom and joy) manifest “being as a whole” (Heidegger 1998, 87). Angst goes beyond these attunements in that it also “makes manifest the nothing” (ibid., 88). If questioning the nothing is a genuinely metaphysical question, as Heidegger claims, then angst is the access to this kind of questioning: “With the fundamental attunement of anxiety we have arrived at that occurrence in Dasein in which the nothing is manifest and from which it must be interrogated” (ibid., 89). Heidegger discusses the aforementioned attunement of profound boredom in his lecture course The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics (1929/1930). He distinguishes three forms of boredom: In the first form—‘becoming bored by something’—a specific entity or event bores us. Heidegger’s example is waiting at a shabby train station in the middle of nowhere. In the second variety—‘being bored with something’—a certain episode is experienced as emptied of meaningful activity and thus as a lost portion of lifetime. Heidegger’s example is attending a dinner party where we might outwardly participate in an engaged fashion but afterward have to admit that we were bored throughout. In the third form—profound boredom or ‘it is boring for one’—not one particular episode but our entire existence becomes utterly meaningless: “Entities have—as we say—become indifferent as a whole, and we ourselves as these people are not excepted” (Heidegger 1995, 208). Whereas the first two varieties of boredom describe affective episodes that can be psychologically investigated, profound boredom appears to go beyond the realm of psychology. Heidegger claims as much when he instructs his students that it is not necessarily an objection to our claim of a fundamental attunement being there in our Dasein if one of you, or even many, or all of you assure us that you are unable to ascertain such an attunement in yourselves when you observe yourselves. For in the end there is nothing at all to be found by observation. (ibid., 60) As the introduction to this part of the lecture shows, Heidegger is not concerned with the psychology of boredom, but with the possibility of philosophizing. Boredom only becomes relevant insofar as profound boredom is identified as a fundamental attunement enabling philosophizing. In the case of boredom, as in the case of Angst, we can see that Heidegger grants fundamental attunements a central role within his approach to philosophy. According to him, genuine philosophical questioning has to arise “ from out of a fundamental attunement” (ibid., 57). (For more on fear, anxiety, and boredom in Heidegger, see Elpidorou and Freeman 2015a, 2015b, and Chapter 34 in this volume). To wrap things up, I can only briefly mention that Heidegger continues to see such a connection between philosophy and attunement in his later writings. In Contributions to 110
Martin Heidegger and Otto Friedrich Bollnow
Philosophy (1936–1938), he writes about the “grounding-attunement” of thinking: In contrast to “wonder”, which he identifies as the grounding-attunement of the first beginning of philosophy in Greek Antiquity, Heidegger identifies “startled dismay” (Erschrecken), “reservedness” (Verhaltenheit), “deep awe” (Scheu)—and a few pages later “deep foreboding” (Er-ahnen) (Heidegger 1999, 15)—as the “grounding-attunement of thinking in the other beginning” (ibid., 11).
4. Conclusion We have seen that in Being and Time, Heidegger introduces Befindlichkeit as an existentiale of Dasein that (in interplay with understanding, discourse, and falling) co-constitutes beingin-the-world. Building on this framework, he continues to claim that certain attunements do not simply contribute to the regular course of events, but rip Dasein out of everyday familiarity and confront it with the depth of its being. These attunements thereby serve a crucial methodological function for Heidegger’s overall project by setting Dasein on the path of existential analysis. In later works, Heidegger generalizes the methodological role of attunements by claiming that all philosophizing has to arise from out of a fundamental attunement. Bollnow’s book Das Wesen der Stimmungen is an attempt to systematically apply the gist of Heidegger’s Befindlichkeit for the purpose of philosophical anthropology. Bollnow investigates attunement as the most basic level of human life, claiming that the primordial disclosure of self and world happens in being attuned. Attunements are fundamental ways of world-relatedness prior to a sharp distinction of self and world, activity and passivity, cognition and affect. Although Bollnow’s work has not received much attention, he anticipated many aspects of current approaches to affectivity in a broadly Heideggerian framework (e.g., those of Matthew Ratcliffe, Jan Slaby, and Katherine Withy). Thus, it would be worth discussing Bollnow’s work within these contexts. Whereas the discovery of attunements is a crucial deepening of our understanding of affectivity, neither Heidegger nor Bollnow presents fully satisfying accounts. One particularly obvious shortcoming is that they say very little about the role of the body with regard to affectivity. Bollnow briefly mentions the body (Bollnow 1953, 42–43) and Heidegger offers a few remarks in his Zollikon Seminars (Heidegger 2001), but both fail to systematically bring together embodiment and affectivity. In particular, it remains unclear if and how attunements are bodily felt. Moreover, the combination of neglecting embodiment and supporting strong anti-mentalism led Heidegger—and to a lesser extent Bollnow—to leaving the relationship between attunements and other affective states underdeveloped. Finally, going beyond locating attunements in the relatedness of self, others, and world, one can raise the question whether attunements are individual phenomena or whether they are intertwined with the intersubjective or collective realm.
Notes
111
Gerhard Thonhauser
2 3 4 5 6
is particularly present in his discussion of Befindlichkeit. In the 1996 edition of Being and Time, Stambaugh translates Befindlichkeit as “attunement” (cf. Heidegger 1996). This is a suitable solution accepted by most scholars. However, I suggest that it is more appropriate to use “attunement” as translation of Stimmung. The term Stimmung is related to Stimme, which not only refers to voices, but also to the score of an instrument. Instruments need to be gestimmt, i.e., tuned. If they are tuned, they are also attuned to one another. “Attunement”, although taken from a mechanical register, does well to capture the literal meaning of Stimmung. Meanwhile, several other translations of Befindlichkeit have been suggested. Hubert Dreyfus, for instance, initially suggested “disposition” and “situatedness”, then suggested the unwieldy phrase “where we’re at-ness”, and finally settled for “affectedness” (Dreyfus 1991, 168). Other suitable translations are “so-findingness”, suggested by John Haugeland (2013) and “disposedness”, suggested by William Blattner (2006). As no English translation will fully capture the meaning of Befindlichkeit, I decided to leave it untranslated for the purpose of this text. I borrow this phrase from Matthew Ratcliffe (2008, 2013). As is common practice in Heidegger scholarship, all citations of Being and Time refer to the page numbers of the German edition of Sein und Zeit published by Niemeyer. These page numbers can be found in all English translations of Being and Time as well as in volume 2 of the Gesamtausgabe. There is no English edition of Bollnow’s book; all translations are my own. Two chapters (chaps. 2 and 3) of the book, however, have recently been translated into English and published in Bollnow (2017). Ratcliffe draws on this thought without making the claim that only certain attunements play this role. In his view, “changes in existential feelings serve to reveal structures of experience that are ordinarily taken for granted” (Ratcliffe 2008, 10). I leave the term Angst untranslated as it is doubtful whether what Heidegger drives at with it comes close enough to what is meant by anxiety in colloquial English. In particular, it is important to avoid reminiscences to psychological understandings of anxiety.
References Blattner, William (2006). Heidegger’s Being and Time. A Reader’s Guide. New York: Continuum. Bollnow, Otto Friedrich (1953). Das Wesen der Stimmungen. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann. ——— (2017). The Nature of Stimmungen. [Engl. Transl. of Chaps. 2 and 3 of Das Wesen der Stimmungen. Transl. by A. Krebs, et al.]. Philosophia 45(4), 1399–1418. Dreyfus, Hubert L. (1991). Being-in-the-World. A Commentary on Heidegger´s Being and Time, Division 1. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Elpidorou, Andreas, and Freeman, Lauren (2015a). Affectivity in Heidegger I: Moods and Emotions in Being and Time. Philosophy Compass 10(10), 661–671. ——— (2015b). Affectivity in Heidegger II: Temporality, Boredom, and Beyond. Philosophy Compass 10(10), 672–684. Haugeland, John (2013). Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland’s Heidegger. Ed. by J. Rouse. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Heidegger, Martin (1953). Sein Und Zeit (7th ed.). Tübingen: Niemeyer. ——— (1962). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Macquarrie, and E. Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell. ——— (1995). The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics. World, Finitute, Solitute. Transl. by William McNeill, and Nicholas Walker. Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. ——— (1996). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Stambaugh. Albany: SUNY Press. ——— (1998). Pathmarks. Transl. by W. McNeill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (1999). Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning). Transl. by P. Emad, and K. Maly. Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. ——— (2001). Zollikon Seminars. Protocols – Conversations – Letters. Transl. by F. Mayr, and R. Askay. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Ratcliffe, Matthew (2008). Feelings of Being. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2013). Why Mood Matters. In: M. Wrathall (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger’s Being and Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 157–176. ——— (2014). Experiences of Depression: A Study in Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
112
Martin Heidegger and Otto Friedrich Bollnow Slaby, Jan, and Achim Stephan (2008). Affective Intentionality and Self-Consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 17(2), 506–513. Withy, Katherine (2014). Situation and Limitation: Making Sense of Heidegger on Thrownness. European Journal of Philosophy 22(1), 61–81. ——— (2015). Owned Emotions: Affective Excellence in Heidegger and Aristotle. In: D. McManus (Ed.). Heidegger, Authenticity and the Self: Themes from Division Two of Being and Time. London, New York: Routledge, 21–36. Further reading Hadjioannou, Christos (Ed.) (2019). Heidegger on Affect. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. Krebs, Angelika (2017). Stimmung: From Mood to Atmosphere. Philosophia 45(4), 1419–1436.
113
8 DIETRICH VON HILDEBRAND Jean Moritz Müller
It is sometimes alleged that the study of emotion and the study of value are currently pursued as relatively autonomous disciplines. As Kevin Mulligan notes, “[t]he philosophy and psychology of emotions pays little attention to the philosophy of value and the latter pays only a little more attention to the former” (2010b, 475). Arguably, the last decade has seen more of a rapprochement between these two domains than used to be the norm (cf., e.g., Roeser and Todd 2014). But there still seems to be considerable potential for exchange and dialogue if the situation is compared with their intimate relationship in central strands of early realist phenomenology. The philosopher perhaps most representative of this ecumenical approach is Husserl’s early student Dietrich von Hildebrand (1889–1977). From the very early stages of his philosophical career, Hildebrand has developed one of the most original, comprehensive and nuanced accounts of emotions at whose core is a detailed examination of their connection to value. While his central concern with the ethical significance of our affective life is in many ways continuous with Scheler’s work1 and draws crucially on Reinach’s philosophy of mind, Hildebrand’s own reflections considerably expand on and substantially modify the picture of the ontology and normative role of emotions defended by these authors. In the following, I reconstruct Hildebrand’s view of emotions with a particular focus on those aspects which represent his most distinctive contribution to this subject.2
1. Emotion and position-taking Hildebrand, in fact, rarely uses the term “emotion” for the phenomena at the center of his work on affectivity. This is, at least in part, in order to distance himself from metaethical emotivists about value judgments who are seen as misconceiving these phenomena by assuming that what they call “emotions” is a non-intentional type of experience.3 However, despite these terminological reservations, it is evident that his main concern is with phenomena that are both in ordinary and philosophical discourses known as emotions. These include affective phenomena such as joy, anger, sadness, fear, admiration, contempt, respect, gratitude, love and hatred. In order to highlight their specific intentional structure, Hildebrand refers to these phenomena as affective position-takings or affective responses.4 In what follows, I explicate this characterization in some detail. In doing so, I will, pace Hildebrand, keep with common parlance and refer to them as emotions. 114
Dietrich von Hildebrand
It is worth adding that von Hildebrand distinguishes affective position-takings from a further class of closely related intentional affective phenomena. This class comprises experiences such as being moved by a piece of music or being wounded by an offensive remark, which he groups under the heading “being affected” (cf. 1953, chap. 17).5 There is an interesting question as to whether experiences of this kind are emotions, too (cf. Cova and Deonna 2014), and whether Hildebrand is correct to distinguish them from positiontakings. In what follows, I shall, however, set these questions aside and focus only on those paradigmatic emotions, which are in the center of Hildebrand’s work.
1.1 The intentional structure of position-taking Within early phenomenology, the notion of a position-taking (Stellungnahme) first appears in Reinach’s article “Zur Theorie des negativen Urteils” (1911). On Reinach’s account, position-takings are mental occurrences that are characterized by an opposition between positivity and negativity. More specifically, for Reinach, the mark of a position-taking is that it has a polar opposite: Belief is opposed to disbelief, striving after something to struggling against something (Widerstreben), pleasure to displeasure.6 Hildebrand applauds Reinach for calling attention to an important and neglected type of intentional phenomenon. At the same time, he gives it a considerably more detailed treatment and delineates the class of positiontakings in a different way.7 For Hildebrand, it is emotions that display most clearly its essential features. As he notes at the start of his dissertation Die Idee der sittlichen Handlung (1969a, 11): If we consider joy about something, enthusiasm, longing, love of something, then all these experiences display a common character. Despite their qualitative differences, they all constitute position-takings of mine towards the world of objects. The moment of joy or the moment of enthusiasm are contents (Gehalte), which are embedded into the experience on the subjective side, and which are directed at (gelten) a content (Inhalt) in front of me. (own transl.) On Hildebrand’s account of position-taking, there is no explicit mention of polar opposites. Instead, what is seen as essential to position-takings is the possession of a directed qualitative content, which corresponds to the specific intentional mode (or, in Husserl’s terms, ‘act quality’) of the respective phenomenon and ‘fills’ the mind of its subject (e.g., we can be full of joy or conviction). Hildebrand describes the directedness of this content in terms of an “intention”, which goes from the subject to the object (e.g., 1953, 196; 1969a, 13). Moreover, in being directed at something, a position-taking constitutes a response (Antwort) to certain features of its object: We are pleased about an object because or in light of some of its qualities (1969a, 13). In being directed and responsive, position-takings are in a specific sense active, that is, manifestations of spontaneity: In taking a stand, one is active inasmuch as one oneself brings forth a specific qualitative content which is aimed at the world.8 To bring out more clearly these marks of position-taking, it is helpful to contrast this account with his Hildebrand’s characterization of a different type of intentional phenomenon, which he calls “apprehension” (Erfassen) or “coming to be acquainted with something” (Kenntnisnahme).9 Paradigmatic cases of apprehension are sensory perceptions and other forms of intuition (Anschauung). In these experiences, there is a content (Inhalt) on the side of the object (we are conscious of something), but no qualitative content on the subjective side (e.g., 1953, 196; 1969a, 11): One cannot be “filled with” perception. Correspondingly, 115
Jean Moritz Müller
although apprehension is of something and thus intentional, it is not directed at anything. In visually perceiving an object, something is presented to us; here, the “intention” goes from the object to the subject (1953, 196). Similarly, it makes no sense to suppose that we apprehend things in light of anything. Accordingly, apprehension is a case of receptivity rather than spontaneity. While in feeling joy about a scene, we “make something” of the scene before us by bringing forth a qualitative content that is aimed at that scene; in perceiving that scene, aspects of it simply impress themselves on us.10 Since, in contrast to Reinach’s account of position-taking, Hildebrand’s considerations focus on its intentional structure, he ends up recognizing many phenomena as positiontakings that do not count as such for Reinach. For example, surprise has a directed, qualitative content, but no polar opposite.11 What is more, in arguing that paradigmatic emotions exhibit this intentional structure, Hildebrand undermines a widely held misconception of emotions as a type of apprehension. Both Husserl (e.g., 1989, 196) and Meinong (1972) conceive of emotions as a kind of perception or intuition of value (cf. also Tappolet 2000; Roberts 2003; Döring 2004; Deonna 2006). Yet, to suppose that emotions are apprehensions of value is to ignore their character as position-takings. Their assimilation to value apprehensions can be seen to conflict also with Hildebrand’s view of what emotions are motivated by. While intellectual position-takings like belief are responsive to truth, emotions and volitional responses are responsive to axiological properties. In joy, we respond to positive importance (goodness in some respect); similarly, in indignation, we respond to negative importance (injustice). However, to respond to x, one must be aware of x prior to responding. Thus, emotions presuppose grasp of importance. Yet, in this case, they cannot themselves apprehend importance: What is already within one’s ken can no longer be brought within one’s ken (cf. also Mulligan 2004, 2010a; Teroni 2007; Müller 2017).12 Incidentally, Hildebrand does not give a substantial account of what it is for an action or attitude to be a response or to have motivating reasons. This may seem surprising given the centrality of this concept to his overall account. At the same time, Hildebrand offers a detailed account of the types of axiological properties that emotions and volitions are responsive to and how these bear on their specific character as responses. I will address this conception in some detail in the following section. Before turning to this issue, I shall, however, complete the present outline of his basic account of affective position-taking by specifying how Hildebrand distinguishes them from other types of position-taking.
1.2 The specific characteristics of affective position-taking Hildebrand recognizes three basic classes of position-takings—intellectual, volitional and affective—each of which possesses its distinctive marks. In characterizing affective responses, Hildebrand’s main focus is on specifying how they differ from volitional responses, which are likewise responsive to importance. One such difference concerns freedom and control: Although volitional responses are motivated by importance, they can be freely engendered and directly command our bodily activities, while affective responses are bestowed on us and cannot be directly controlled. As we will see, this difference plays a crucial role for his account of the moral significance of affective position-takings. The perhaps most telling difference for Hildebrand, however, concerns their qualitative richness or plenitude. Hildebrand sometimes proposes that, in affective responses, “the entire person in involved” (1953, 202), while the will has a “one dimensional, linear character” (ibid., 202), which commits the entire person, but nonetheless constitutes a stance taken exclusively by her “free personal center” (ibid., 203). 116
Dietrich von Hildebrand
At first sight, this proposal may seem counter-intuitive. When I am enthusiastic about the result of the soccer match, I am taking a particular position insofar as I favour a particular team. Similarly, in being indignant about funding cuts in the humanities, it is me inasmuch as I value the humanities who is taking a stand. There is a straightforward sense in which it is specific attitudes or concerns of a person,13 rather than the entire person, which shape the respective response. To be fair, in his earlier writings, Hildebrand is sensitive to this point. In Sittlichkeit und ethische Werterkenntnis (1969b, 204–206), he acknowledges that affective position-takings can have their source in specific attitudes of a person. Hildebrand denies that this is true of all affective responses (e.g. annoyance and desire (Begehren) are supposed to be exceptions). But he adds that even where there is no such foundation in particular attitudes, affective position-takings are still to some extent constrained by the person’s most fundamental attitudes and her overall character or nature. For example, these may impose constraints on which emotions it is possible for someone to feel in a given situation (1969b, 206). Moreover, this constraint is meant not to apply in the same way to volitional responses (ibid., 206). In light of this, Hildebrand is perhaps best read as proposing that the distinctive feature of affective responses is a specific kind of dependence on the person’s attitudes and her overall character, which is not displayed by exercises of the will.
2. Responding to importance Hildebrand’s most innovative claim about the emotions concerns a distinction between different kinds of axiological property to which they can be responsive. This distinction has important implications for his account of their normative significance and their connection to personhood. It is indeed fundamental for his entire moral philosophy, including his proposal that emotions can possess moral value.
2.1 Hildebrand’s taxonomy of importance Put in simple terms, Hildebrand’s central axiological proposal is to recognize fundamentally different ways in which something can matter (as opposed to being neutral or insignificant). As he uses the term “importance” (Bedeutsamkeit), it denotes the specific respect under which an object or event is apt to motivate specific emotional or volitional responses. Crucially, the terms “value” and “disvalue” are reserved for one specific category of importance, which is taken to sharply contrast with another axiological category which he terms the “subjectively (dis)satisfying”. For something to possess (dis)value is for it to be important in itself.14 For something to be subjectively (dis)satisfying, on the other hand, is for it to be important relative to a person’s interests and concerns. On Hildebrand’s account, the saving of another’s life is important in itself, while the fact that some monetary deal comes out in one’s favor is subjectively satisfying insofar as it holds the potential to satisfy one’s concern to be materially well off. In both cases, the respective importance of the event makes it apt to motivate a particular response (e.g., joy or enthusiasm); yet, it does so differently in each case: While (dis)values demand a certain response, the subjectively (dis)satisfying tempts us into responding in a specific way. This has an immediate consequence for the normative assessment of the corresponding response. To feel joy about another’s recovery in response to its value is to give this event its due qua valuable (cf. 1953, chap. 18). In complying with this demand, a specific harmony is established between the response and the value, which bestows value on the response itself. No such value is bestowed on responses to the subjectively (dis)satisfying. 117
Jean Moritz Müller
To fully appreciate the theoretical significance of Hildebrand’s distinction between responses to (dis)value and responses to the subjectively (dis)satisfying, it is helpful to highlight how the type of importance to which an emotion or volition is responsive makes a difference to the character of the response itself, as well as to relate his distinction to Kant’s familiar opposition between the categorical and the hypothetical. Roughly, the phenomenon that features on Kant’s ethical theory as the conformity with a categorical demand is reconceived by Hildebrand in terms of responsiveness to value, while the systematic place of Kant’s notion of conforming to hypothetical imperatives is occupied by the response to the subjectively (dis)satisfying. As Hildebrand characterizes value responses, they display a specific aspect of self-transcendence. In giving a (dis)value its due (in contrast to being lured in by the subjectively (dis)satisfying), we do not approach the bearer of the (dis)value from the point of view of our own concerns, but move beyond our interests to engage with something important for its own sake. There are strong echoes here with a Kantian notion of autonomy. In a spirit similar to Kant’s recognition of autonomy as the mark of personhood, Hildebrand goes on to claim that affective and volitional value responses reveal our most decisive feature as persons. That said, there are also important differences between these respective strands of Kant’s and Hildebrand’s thinking. Crucially, Kant does not recognize emotions as potential manifestations of the core of personhood. Moreover, for him, categorical demands are not grounded in value; hence conformity with them is not a case of value response. But for Hildebrand, it is crucial precisely to look beyond the demand to its axiological ground in order to make proper sense of the opposition between the categorical and the hypothetical, as well as to explicate the corresponding difference at the level of our conduct by substituting responsiveness to this ground for simple conformity with a demand.15 It is this focus on value, and the distinction between different species of importance, that brings emotions within the purview of (broadly) Kantian considerations on personhood.16 Perhaps this picture will seem to come at a rather high metaphysical price, given that Hildebrand conceives of (dis)values in strictly realist terms, i.e., as fully mind-independent properties. It is worth noting, though, that one might develop a structurally similar account of responsiveness to importance independently of Hildebrand’s notion of (dis)value. For example, one might distinguish between different ways in which something may be important relative to the subject’s concerns by identifying a subset of those concerns as constitutive of her normative self-conception, i.e. of the person she finds worth being.17 A somewhat similar contrast might then be seen between responses to what is important relative to concerns that are integral to a person’s normative self-conception and responses to what is significant in relation to concerns that fall outside it. Although these two types of responses do not contrast as sharply as responses to (dis)value and responses to the subjectively (dis)satisfying and cannot be related in the same way to the contrast between conformity with categorical demands and conformity with hypothetical demands, they can arguably be distinguished by an aspect of self-transcendence that is specific to the former: In these cases, the subject distances herself from her superficial interests and engages with objects under the respect of what bears on whom she actually finds worth being. In fact, this proposal echoes a distinction that Hildebrand himself draws in later work between the subjectively (dis)satisfying and what he calls the objectively good (harmful) for a person (cf., e.g., 1953, chap. 3).18 This additional category of importance is exemplified by things that (positively or negatively) bear on the persons true interest. It is worth stressing, though, that responding to what is significant to concerns that are integral to one’s normative self-conception is not the same as responding to what is objectively good (harmful) for one since what is objectively good (harmful) for one need not depend on one’s concerns: It may be in a child’s true interest to acquire moral 118
Dietrich von Hildebrand
virtues even if she has no concern to be morally virtuous. Relatedly, if something may be objectively good (harmful) for a person independently of her mindset, this further axiological category of importance is not obviously less objectionable to opponents of axiological realism than the category of (dis)value.19 Certainly, it will seem no less contentious in light of the fact that Hildebrand takes objective goods (harms) for a person to be grounded in (dis) value.
2.2 The moral value of affective position-takings Affective and volitional responses to (dis)value are themselves valuable. However, the value conferred on an emotion which is responsive to (dis)value is not necessarily moral value. Thus, to admire an artwork in response to its aesthetic excellence is valuable, but not morally significant. As the same time, it is Hildebrand’s declared aim to show that affective position-takings can be bearers of moral value: To rejoice in the saving of another’s life—as opposed to being indifferent toward it—can be morally worthy.20 Accordingly, Hildebrand devotes a crucial part of his opus magnum Christian Ethics (1953) to specifying the conditions under which paradigm emotions count as morally valuable (cf., e.g., 1953, part II, esp. chap. 27). One of these conditions is that the emotion be responsive to a morally relevant value.21 Morally relevant values include, for example, the value of a man’s life and his dignity. They are not themselves moral values, but possess moral relevance since responding adequately to them (e.g., in being glad that another’s life has been saved or by willing to save it) can be morally valuable. Whether an affective response to a morally relevant value is actually morally valuable crucially hinges on further constraints. Most importantly, it depends on whether it is suitably related to our capacity for freedom. Hildebrand identifies the capacity for freedom as an essential mark of personhood and takes great efforts to show that legitimate ascriptions of moral value to a response are premised on its exercise. The exercise of freedom is required since the presence or absence of moral value is necessarily a matter of a person’s responsibility. Accordingly, we must be able to make sense of our being responsible for emotions if they are to become intelligible as bearers of moral value. Yet, how is this supposed to be possible if we can neither freely engender nor directly control them? Hildebrand answers this question by introducing the idea of a cooperative freedom with affective responses. This capacity constitutes for Hildebrand the core of human freedom and allows us to sanction or disavow affective responses (cf., e.g., 1953, chap. 25). Like willing, the higher-order position-takings of sanction and disavowal originate in our free personal center. Crucially, they modify the respective first-order response “from within” rather than affecting only its expression. In sanctioning a response, we identify with it, while in disavowing position-takings, we dissociate from them and thereby revoke a certain kind of implicit identification with them which is in place as long as we do not disavow them. It is, in fact, only by sanctioning a response to (dis)value that it becomes a genuine case of self-transcendence or conformity with the call of the (dis)value for its own sake (e.g., 1953, 323). Moreover, and crucially, when sanctioning an affective response to a morally relevant value, the response is thereby itself accorded moral worth.22 Hildebrand’s notion of cooperative freedom is evocative of familiar higher-order views of autonomy. On these accounts, for a desire or emotion to be autonomous, it must be the object of a second-order attitude (typically, a second-order volition) which properly authorizes it as one’s own. However, this analogy is imperfect. One important difference is that Hildebrand recognizes an important “external” constraint on the second-order endorsement 119
Jean Moritz Müller
of first-order affective responses in that it is possible to sanction only responses which are motivated by (dis)values.23 Moreover, unlike in the case of the higher-order endorsement invoked on hierarchical accounts of autonomy, the primary significance of cooperative freedom is ethical. That said, Hildebrand’s conception suffers from similar difficulties as the former. Chiefly, his notions of sanction and disavowal remain somewhat obscure.24 In which sense precisely are these attitudes supposed to modify the affective response “from within”? And what types of attitudes precisely are they? While actualizations of the free personal center, they are not supposed to be acts of willing in the strict sense of the term, but a distinct kind of position-taking which endorses or rejects extant responses. In light of this, it is hard to disperse the impression that Hildebrand’s attempt at making intelligible emotions as bearers of moral value remains less developed and perspicacious than the underlying distinction between different kinds of responses to importance. However, this is not to dismiss it as by and large failing its declared aim. Aside from the numerous examples Hildebrand adduces to motivate this proposal, he helpfully focuses the problematic on the connection between moral value and responsibility and thereby identifies the most difficult obstacle to a plausible account of morally valuable emotion while also pointing toward novel conceptions of the control we may exercise over our emotions. Hildebrand thereby lays the grounds for further attempts to work out and defend such an account.
Notes
120
Dietrich von Hildebrand
References Cova, Florian, and Deonna, Julian A. (2014). Being Moved. Philosophical Studies 169(3), 447–466. Crosby, John F. (2002). Dietrich von Hildebrand: Master of Phenomenological Value-Ethics. In: J. J. Drummond, and L. Embree (Eds.). Phenomenological Approaches to Moral Philosophy: A Handbook. Dordrecht: Springer, 475–496. Deonna, Julien (2006). Emotion, Perception and Perspective. Dialectica 60(1), 29–46. Döring, Sabine (2004). Gründe und Gefühle: Rationale Motivation durch emotionale Vernunft. Habilitationsschrift. University Duisburg-Essen. Frankfurt, Harry (1987). Identification and Wholeheartedness. In: F. Shoeman (Ed.). Responsibility, Character and the Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 27–45. Heathwood, Chris (2016). Desire-Fulfillment Theory. In: G. Fletcher (Ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being. London, New York: Routledge, 135–147. Hildebrand, Dietrich von (1953). Christian Ethics. New York: McKay. ——— (1969a). Die Idee der sittlichen Handlung. In: D. von Hildebrand: Die Idee der sittlichen Handlung + Sittlichkeit und ethische Werterkenntnis. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. ——— (1969b). Sittlichkeit und ethische Werterkenntnis. In: D. von Hildebrand: Die Idee der sittlichen Handlung + Sittlichkeit und ethische Werterkenntnis. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. ——— (2007). The Heart: An Analysis of Human and Divine Affectivity. South Bend: St. Augustine’s Press. Husserl, Edmund (1989). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy— Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. Transl. by R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
121
Jean Moritz Müller Meinong, Alexius (1972). On Emotional Presentation. Transl. by M.-L. Schubert Kalsi. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Müller, Jean (2017). How (Not) to Think of Emotions as Evaluative Attitudes. Dialectica 71(2), 281–308. ——— (2018). Emotion as Position-Taking. Philosophia 46(3), 525–540. Mulligan, Kevin (2004). Husserl on the “Logics” of Valuing, Values and Norms. In: B. Centi and G. Gigliotti (Eds.). Fenomenologia della Ragion Pratica: L’Etica di Edmund Husserl. Naples: Bibliopolis, 177–225. ——— (2008). Scheler: Die Anatomie des Herzens oder was man alles fühlen kann. In: H. Landweer and U. Renz (Eds.). Klassische Emotionstheorien von Platon bis Wittgenstein. Berlin: de Gruyter, 589–612. ——— (2009). On Being Struck by Value. In: B. Merker (Ed.). Leben mit Gefühlen: Emotionen, Werte und ihre Kritik. Paderborn: Mentis, 141–161. ——— (2010a). Husserls Herz. In: M. Frank and N. Weidtmann (Eds.). Husserl und die Philosophie des Geistes. Berlin: Suhrkamp, 209–238. ——— (2010b). Emotions and Values. In: P. Goldie (Ed.). Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 475–500. ——— (2013). Acceptance, Acknowledgment, Affirmation, Agreement, Assertion, Belief, Certainty, Conviction, Denial, Judgment, Refusal and Rejection. In: M. Textor (Ed.). Judgment and Truth in Early Analytic Philosophy and Phenomenology. London: Palgrave, 97–136. ——— (2017). Thrills, Orgasms, Sadness and Hysteria: Austro-German Criticisms of William James. In: A. Cohen and R. Stern (Eds.). Thinking about the Emotions: A Historical Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 223–252. Reinach, Adolf (1911). Zur Theorie des negative Urteils. In: A. Pfänder (Ed.). Münchener Philosophische Abhandlungen: Festschrift für Theodor Lipps. Leipzig: J. A. Barth, 196–254. Roberts, Robert (2003). The Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Roeser, Sabine, and Todd, Cain (Eds.) (2014). Emotion and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Salice, Alessandro (2015). The Phenomenology of the Munich and Göttingen Circles. In: E. Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/ phenomenology-mg/. (01.02.2018) Scheler, Max (1973). Formalism in Ethics and Non-formal Ethics of Values. Transl. by M. S. Frings and R. L. Funk. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Tappolet, Christine (2000). Émotions et valeurs. Paris: Presses Universitaire France. Teroni, Fabrice (2007). Emotions and Formal Objects. Dialectica 61(3), 395–415. Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1984). Bemerkungen über die Philosophie der Psychologie, vol. I. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
122
9 EDITH STEIN Antonio Calcagno
In her Introduction to Philosophy, Edith Stein claims that “feeling is a multiply differentiated form of consciousness” (Stein 2004, 13, own transl.). Undoubtedly, her understanding of the emotions may be viewed as a particular form of feeling, but precisely what kinds of feelings are they? I argue here that, phenomenologically speaking, emotion, for Stein, must be understood as a capacity for an affective, expressive conscious experience that concomitantly operates within the domains of the lived body, the psyche, and the spirit. Emotion coexists not only as a sign of some underlying corporeal or psychic affective reality but also as a web or expression of meaning or coherence of sense (Sinn) that makes manifest the unity of body, psyche, and spirit, what Stein calls the person. Emotions, then, can be understood to permeate and draw upon different, complex aspects of our personhood, including gender. They express the senses of different aspects of our person and they help us acquire self-knowledge and knowledge of others and the world.
1. What is an emotion? An emotion is a type of feeling that is distinguished from feelings that arise from sense perception, sensual feelings like pleasure, moods, and life-feelings like fatigue. All feelings have a noetic and a hyletic component (Stein 2000, 158). This means that all feelings have a pre-conscious and conscious aspect to them. Unconscious or pre-conscious sensory impressions (Empfindnisse), drives, instincts, and even some memories form, in part, the hyletic building material for our conscious, lived experience of emotions. In direct and immediate perception, we can experience some aspect of an object that is before us; for example, we can feel the content of a visual or auditory perception. A loud bang will not only be painful to the ears but may also startle us. Any sense perception comes to consciousness as largely being lived in and through the body. Sense impressions, like all perceptions, are intentional in two senses: We can draw our attention to the very object of the sense impression that is part of a perception (noema) and can also turn our attention to our very consciousness of the object (noesis) (Stein 2000, 155). We can analyse, therefore, not only the elements constitutive of the sense experience itself, but we can also analyse what it is for us to undergo or live a sense perception. Sensual feelings are described grosso modo
123
Antonio Calcagno
by Stein as affects produced by certain experiences that include but also extend beyond the organic operation of the senses and extend into the realm of psyche. She observes: Sensations of feelings (Gefühlsempfindungen) or sensual feelings (sinnliche Gefühle) are inseparable from their founding sensations. The pleasantness of a savory dish, the agony of a sensual pain, the comfort of a soft garment are noticed where the food is tasted, where the pain pierces, where the garment clings to the body’s surface. However, sensual feelings not only are there but at the same time also in me; they issue from my “I.” General feelings have a hybrid position similar to sensual feelings. Not only the “I” feels vigorous or sluggish, but I “notice this in all my limbs.” Every mental act, every joy, every pain, every activity of thought, together with every bodily action, every movement I make, is sluggish and colorless when “I” feel sluggish. My living body and all its parts are sluggish with me. Thus, our familiar phenomenon of fusion again appears. Not only do I see my hand’s movement and feel its sluggishness at the same time, but I also see the sluggish movement and the hand’s sluggishness. We always experience general feelings as coming from the living body with an accelerating or hindering influence on the course of experience. This is true even when these general feelings arise in connection with a “spiritual feeling”. (Stein 1989, 48–49) Moods are described as a general feeling that is non-somatic in nature. Stein distinguishes them from life feelings and notes: Moods are “general feelings” of a non-somatic nature, and so we separate them from strictly general feeling as a species of their own. Cheerfulness and melancholy do not fill the living body. It is not cheerful or melancholy as it is vigorous or sluggish, nor could a purely spiritual being be subject to moods. But this does not imply that psychic and bodily general feelings run beside one another undisturbed. Rather, one seems to have a reciprocal “influence” on the other. For instance, suppose I take a trip to recuperate and arrive at a sunny, pleasant spot. While looking at the view, I feel that a cheerful mood wants to take possession of me, but cannot prevail because I feel sluggish and tired. “I shall be cheerful here as soon as I have rested up,” I say to myself. I may know this from “previous experience,” yet its foundation is always in the phenomenon of the reciprocal action of psychic and somatic experiences.” (Stein 1989, 49) Finally, life feelings result from the work of the life force (Lebenskraft) in us (Stein 2000, 79). If our lifepower is diminished, we will feel fatigue, but if it is strong and vibrant, we may experience our living as full of vitality, and may feel ourselves energised or full of life. For example, illness will bring about a feeling of lethargy. The feelings produced by sense perception, sensuality, moods, and life feelings operate within the realms of the lived body and the psyche. They are largely marked by psychic causality, which functions like the action-reaction, cause-effect, or if-then structure of physical causality, although they all can come to impact the life of spirit. Though emotions can draw upon the aforementioned types of feelings (Szanto 2015, 505–508), they are distinguished by Stein as having certain unique spiritual aspects in addition to their bodily and psychic ones. Emotions, then, are not to be understood merely as signs, but as operating within the framework of meanings (Sinn); they spring from the depths of the I and, therefore, are personal; they help make manifest values and have objects; they are gendered; they make manifest a self; and they can be collective as well as individual. 124
Edith Stein
In her Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities, Stein takes up the traditional Husserlian critique against positivism and psychologism by claiming that emotions are not simply reducible to manifest signs of an underlying physical or bodily stimulus. For example, anger is not simply the result of the stimulation of certain nerves and organs (i.e., heart and lungs) that produces responses traditionally associated with anger, including accelerated heart rate, rapid breathing, constriction of the chest, flushed face, clenched jaws, etc. In this kind of physicalist account, emotions become the signs of a foundational physical process. For Stein, emotions are complex and also work at the level of meaning. She does not negate the underlying physical and bodily structure operative in all emotions, but maintains that emotions are distinguished from other feelings in that they function within a framework of expressed meaning or Sinn. Stein gives Lipps’ example of smoke and sadness (Stein 1989, 76–77). In the direct perception of smoke, one can understand smoke as indicating the possibility of fire. Smoke directly leads to an association with fire. But when one sees a sad face, one is not led immediately to the cause of sadness: There is more to the appearance of the countenance than what the face simply externally expresses. The sense of the sadness cannot come to full expression in the same way that smoke and fire appear. To enter into the essence of sadness, one requires empathy, Stein argues, in order to bring the mind of the other to some form of givenness within the I. She remarks: Both cases have something in common: An object of outer perception leads to something not perceived in the same way. However, there is a different kind of givenness present. The smoke indicating fire to me is my “theme,” the object of my actual t urning-toward, and awakens in me tendencies to proceed in a further context. Interest flows off in a specific direction. The transition from one theme to another is carried out in the typical motivational form of: If the one is, then the other is, too. (There is already more present here than mere association. The smoke reminds me of fire, even though this may also lead us to association.) Sadness “being-co-given” in the sad countenance is something else. The sad countenance is actually not a theme that leads over to another one at all, but it is at one with sadness. This occurs in such a way that the countenance itself can step entirely into the background. The countenance is the outside of sadness. Together they form a natural unity. (Stein 1989, 76–77) Stein is applying here Husserl’s distinction between sign and expression taken up in the First Logical Investigation (Husserl 2008, 183–188) in which meanings point beyond the representational nature of signs. To acquire the essence of sadness requires an understanding of internal aspects like motivation (and not only causality), values, personality, self hood, etc., in order to understand the full sense of the experience of the emotion, all aspects that transcend purely physicalist accounts, according to Stein. But how do these other aspects come to be situated within the structure of emotion? An emotion first comes to expression in the lived body. Some event, words, or thought produces in the body a reaction. We feel the body responding to such stimulus. As we have seen, emotions cannot be reduced simply to the status of a caused sense experience. There is also a psychic component. Stein gives the example of joy to illustrate her point. Suppose that while I am hearing a report, and thus while this objectivity, “report,” is developing for me into a series in the current of self-generating intellective acts, a joy at this report is beginning to fill me up. “Joy,” this unity of experience, is oriented toward 125
Antonio Calcagno
something “external” to the current. Indeed, it is joy “at” the report, therefore an “act.” And something on the objective side corresponds to it: the joyousness of the report, which attaches to it by virtue of its positive value. Like all experiences, the joy is causally determined: it is duller or more lively according to the condition of the prevailing life feeling. And it’s also possible that the life feeling doesn’t even let the joy in, that in its place a feeble phantom enters, in which I very well apprehend the joyousness without being able to “really rejoice”. (Stein 2000, 75) We can certainly understand the emotion of joy as having an intentional object (namely, the report)—emotions have intentional objects perhaps with the exception of anxiety, understood as free-floating fear—but the joy is not simply reducible to the report itself. The joy begins to colour, Stein, say our life feelings, perhaps intensifying the very feeling of what we are living as we listen to the report. We feel more vitalised, energised, and fresh (Stein 2000, 75). The experience of the emotion of joy, however, not only has a bodily and psychic aspect (i.e., its effect on the feeling of life produced by the lifepower), but also begins to move into the realm of spirit, understood as the domain of reason, freedom, will, and motivation: The feeling [of joy] is motivated by the object that it’s turned toward. The “depth” of feeling is dependent upon the height of the felt value, and so is the strength of the feeling. The specific coloring of the feeling is dependent upon the particular kind of value. The feeling is insightfully and rationally motivated only insofar as it corresponds in all its dimensions to the value. Accordingly, whatever there is about the feeling that is not “owing” to the value (its greater or lesser strength, perhaps) is unmotivated, uninsightful, and to be explained as merely the effect of the present life feeling. Now you can designate the impact itself as motivated, inasmuch as the effect that the arising emotional experience exerts upon the life feeling depends upon its specific character, its strength and depth, which are rationally motivated; however it’s not possible to construe this effect as motivation. (Stein 2000, 76) The emotion experienced expresses a value, that is, the joy expresses that we hold something dear or valuable about the content of the report. It is not simply the news of the report that affects us, but the joy is connected to a value that comes to expression in the report. For example, the report can be about someone whom we love. Drawing from the work of Max Scheler (Scheler 1973, 2008), values are objective for Stein, that is, they have intentional, objective content that can be seized by a subject. Scheler, for example, maintains that love and hate come to the fore in relation to a specific content: One loves and/or hates x or y (Scheler 2008, 169–175). A person, and therefore a subject, consciously loves or hates x or y. Love can generate a certain emotion, for example, the joy discussed above. The feelings that values generate are different than the feeling of life, sensuality, or sense perception, for they bespeak a different kind of relation than causality. Emotions can come to express certain values, but the affect of the emotion and the value itself may be freely subjected to the analysis and activity of the reason and the will. So, we may understand that a certain value produces a certain affect or emotion in us, but we can deliberate and either accept or reject (that is judge) the accompanying emotion as valid or not, correct or mistaken, deceptive or true. Because emotions can be evaluated and assessed, the affect they generate is not to be understood in 126
Edith Stein
terms of a strict causal relation of if-then or stimulus-response; rather, the emotion generated must be understood as motivated insofar as one can rationally assess and judge whether the emotion and/or value are legitimate or illegitimate. Moreover, one can freely decide to neglect certain emotional responses in us, if we should so choose. For example, a community can experience collective values or disvalues in the emotions they generate in us. Values come to the fore as a lived experience of community wherein the members live in the experience of others; the members experience solidarity: They share a collective experience of value or disvalue. One can think of patriotic pride, and the ensuing emotion of joy, for one’s home state as a collective value insofar as members of the community share solidarity over love of their specific countries of national cultures. Likewise, a community can experience collective hate, for example, hate of one’s enemies that seek destruction of a particular community. History is replete with examples where collectivities describe their collective loves and hates. Edith Stein often describes her love for Germany, especially during World War I (Stein 1985, 245). Likewise, she describes the collective hate of Nazis for Jews (Stein 1985, 25). Values have a markedly different motivational structure than drives or instincts. In the case of the latter, reason, motivation, will, and judgement, all aspects belonging to the realm of spirit, do not come to bear on the expression and push of the drives. Here, natural causality plays a key role. In the case of the former, reason, will, motivation, and judgement come to condition and shape our values or disvalues. Motivation, Stein argues, allows to experience ourselves within a whole web of sense (Stein 1989, 84). Also, it should be noted that values can and do change as they come under the objectivating lens of spirit. The foregoing discussion of value was meant to demonstrate how Stein conceives of the relation between value, emotion, and motivation. The realm of spirit, understood as the lawfulness of the work of reason, motivation, and will, comes to its fullest manifestation within personhood. The human person is distinguished from other living beings precisely because of the constituent role of spirit (Geist) in the life of human beings. Emotions, in addition to being situated within the motivational structure of value, also express and manifest the very personhood of a person, or what Stein calls the “core of personality” (Persönlichkeitskern): Now we come to feelings [emotions] in the pregnant sense. As said earlier, these feelings are always feelings of something. Every time I feel, I am turned toward an object, something of an object is given to me, and I see a level of the object. But, in order to see a level of the object, I must first have it. It must be given to me in theoretical acts. Thus, the structure of all feelings requires theoretical acts. When I am joyful over a good deed, this is how the deed’s goodness or its positive value faces me. But I must know about the deed in order to be joyful over it— knowledge is fundamental to joy. An intuitive perceptual or conceptual comprehension can also be substituted for this knowledge underlying the feeling of value. Furthermore, this knowledge belongs among acts that can only be comprehended reflectively and has no “I” depth of any kind. On the contrary, the feeling based on this knowledge always reaches into the “I’s” stability and is experienced as issuing out of it. And this even takes place during complete immersion in felt value. Anger over the loss of a piece of jewellery comes from a more superficial level or does not penetrate as deeply as losing the same object as the souvenir of a loved one. Furthermore, pain over the loss of this person himself would be even deeper. This discloses essential relationships among the hierarchy of felt values, the depth classification of value feelings, and the level classification of the person exposed in these feelings. Accordingly, every time we advance in the value realm, we also make acquisitions in the realm of our own personality. (Stein 1989, 100–101) 127
Antonio Calcagno
The personal core mentioned earlier is experienced in two fundamental senses for Stein. First, it is understood as a depth of the I. Emotions issue out of the I and manifest the depth of the I. The values discussed previously form a hierarchy based on the importance or intensity of specific values. For Stein, values that directly affect the person, for example, love, occupy the highest place on the hierarchy. Second, the personality core is what lies at the centre of the experience of personhood, which is understood to be the experience of a unity of the body, soul, and spirit. The experience of these three aspects all working together is what constitutes personhood. The personal core is the centre of this profound experience of personal unity. The relation Stein establishes between emotion and personhood means that the personal is not only a source of emotion but also “colours” the very experience of the motion in two senses: First, personality has the potential to colour the experience of the emotion in certain ways. For example, the emotion of joy does not simply consist of the usual bodily and psychic signs, but it also bears the stamp of the personality of the person experiencing the joy. Hence, the way joy is expressed by each person also contains a unique colouration brought to it by the personality. Second, the feelings that arise out of emotion can, in turn, affect the expression of a personality. For example, a trauma may induce such deep emotions that they alter personality in a dramatic way. One here thinks of lost love, betrayal, or even death of a loved one and how the grief and sadness produced by such events permanently alter a person. Furthermore, the connection between emotions and values, Stein notes, can convey rationality and irrationality, and the lawfulness of rationality can assist in judgement, especially in making moral judgements (Stein 1989, 101–102). Finally, all emotions, for Stein, have intensity, depth, reach, and duration (Stein 1989, 105). Intensity refers to the force of the emotion, whereas reach and duration refer to the extension and length of time of the emotion. Depth is the quality that belongs to the personal I. The experience of emotion is grounded in an ego-pole of experience. The I is often described by Stein as a kind of centre or ground and even, borrowing from Husserl, a zero-point of orientation. And though the I acts as a kind of base for all conscious experience, including emotions, the I can reflect upon itself as an ego. In reflection, one experiences the I not only as a kind of centre of orientation but also as possessing a certain quality of depth, that is, one experiences the very ground of the I as consisting of many aspects and layers, all of which may not be readily accessible, including passive aspects of the I. For example, Stein says that in reflection on the I, art of its depth consists of the experience of self hood, which is understood as a positum of collected past experiences about one’s own self and life. The self is a collection of memories that one has about one’s own I experiences (Stein 2010, 111). The self is reflected back into conscious experience and consists of a series of selected memories that manifest a sense of oneself at a moment in time or over time. It is a formation of reflection of selected memories.
2. Others’ emotions and collective emotions An understanding of the Steinian conception of emotion would be incomplete, if we did not mention how we come to know the emotional experience of another in empathy or a group of persons, in what Stein calls a Gemeinschaftserlebnis or lived experience of community. Recently, much interesting work has been carried out on the aforementioned possibilities (Zahavi 2010; Szanto 2015; Vendrell Ferran 2015). Empathy, according to Stein, is a particular act of mind that allows one individual to grasp the mind of another, which ultimately yields knowledge about oneself and the other. Empathy is distinguished from other acts of presentification, including memory and phantasy; while the latter do not necessarily require 128
Edith Stein
the content of the experience to be focused on the I, for example, I can remember a pleasant city of past travels, empathy requires both the manifest presence of the I and the content of experience of another person (Stein 1989, 10). How does an act of empathy occur? When I encounter the other, certain presentations are given to me and brought to my awareness. For example, I may notice details of the other’s body or face. In an act of empathy, I grasp the content of what is given by the other and I bring that content into relief, or I compare it, with what I know or perceive about myself. Taking the place of the other, I compare what the other has presented with what I know about myself. By bringing what the other presents into relation with my own knowledge, I can analogously grasp that the other may be experiencing something I have experienced; the sad countenance of another, for example, may indicate an emotion of grief. I understand both that the other is sad and what a state of sadness means (i.e., its psychic causality, its content, the various feelings it produces, its temporality, values, and aspects of the personality experiencing the grief ): Its sense is communicable in empathy. Dan Zahavi has argued that empathy is not to be identified with or understood as mindreading or grasping a simulation of the other’s mind (Zahavi 2010, 286). In empathy, though one cannot experience exactly what the other is experiencing, one directly perceives and comes to understand the other’s expressions and experiences. One is drawn into the place of the other and lives the experience of the other’s sense of sadness; empathy draws and leads one into the mind of the other (Stein 1989, 10–11). For Stein, empathy allows one to grasp what it is for another to experience herself as a living body, a psyche (affectivity), and a spirit (free and/or motivated). In the lived experience of community, however, Stein defines community as an intense social bond in which one lives in the experience of another (Ineinandergreifen) in solidarity. Communal relations are deeply personal, for in them, one grasps the meaning of living in and with another’s life as persons. In a community, an individual not only understands what the sense or meaning of the lived experience is in general, but also lives the experience of the group. Stein gives the example of the death of a beloved troop leader. The members of the troop are deeply affected by sadness and loss at their leader’s death. She claims not only that one can understand their sadness in general as well as the individual sadness of individual members through empathy but also that one can understand and experience the collective sadness of the troop. There are three distinct forms of sadness that arise in this communal experience: Sadness in general, the sadness of another troop member, and the collective sadness of the group as a whole. Each of these forms is distinct and is experienced differently as it shifts from smaller to larger, more encompassing social configurations. As Stein observes: [t]he individual lives, feels, and acts as a member of the community, and insofar as he does that, the community lives, feels, and acts in him and through him. But when he becomes conscious of his experiencing or reflects upon it, the community does not become conscious of what it experiences, but, rather, he becomes conscious of that which the community experiences in him. (Stein 2000, 140) It is clear from the foregoing discussions of empathy and the lived experience of community that Stein sees emotions as experiences either of another or of a group that can be grasped or known. Many questions arise from Stein’s claims about emotions and how we know/ experience them in others and as a group. For example, Szanto addresses the normativity of Stein’s argument and its implications for the mutual awareness required for collective 129
Antonio Calcagno
emotional sharing (Szanto 2015, 523). I cannot take up in detail here the implications and challenges presented by Stein’s views on emotion and its relation to empathy and community. All I can do here is alert the reader to the communal and empathic aspects that come to bear on Stein’s understanding of emotion and how it is experienced and lived through from the first-person (singular and plural) perspectives.
3. Emotion and gender: Das Weibliche Most of Stein’s more extensive philosophical writings on women have been assembled in the volume Essays on Woman (Stein 2013), but it should be noted that one finds other of her writings on women in her texts on religion and mysticism, in which she wrote about female saints and mystics, particularly Carmelite women saints (Stein 1992). Much has been written about Stein’s texts on women, especially by scholars such as Joyce Berkman Avrech (2006a, 2006b), Sarah Sharkey Borden (2006, 2009), Angela Ales Bello (1992), and Linda McAlister Lopez (2006). Though Stein often deployed phenomenological analysis in her treatment of the nature, essence, ethos, or vocation of women, her conception of women must not be understood in a narrowly essentialist manner: Stein saw the male and the female as complementary beings that share a common human essence and whose distinct forms of sexuality constitute different expressions of that very human being; however, one should be careful not to read her dualist anthropology in an essentialising manner. Though, for Stein, there are male and female essences, they appear in a plethora of expressions and forms. Linda Lopez McAllister reminds readers that, taken together, Stein’s notion of types and her discussion of personality provide ample room for differentiated and multiple manifestations of humanity, masculinity, and femininity (McAlister Lopez 2006). Stein also remarked that all human beings possess combinations of male and female traits (Stein 2013, 118). Stein’s writings on women focus on three broad questions: The essence of woman, vocation, and education, and especially the education of young women. Stein describes the essence or nature of woman (das Weibliche) in a variety of ways: As complementary to men; as a helper; as more empathic than men; as possessing rich emotional lives that allow them to experience themselves, others, and the world differently than men, who tend to compartmentalise emotion and reason; as potential wives and mothers; as unmarried persons; and as religious persons (Stein 2013, 60–72). The capacity of the feminine for emotion is seen as manifesting not only a wide range of feelings but also knowledge or insight that stems from those emotions (Berkman 2015, 2016). For Stein, the unique features of women, especially in comparison to men, were not to be viewed as deficiencies. In fact, she regarded these unique differences as empowering and meaningful. She also recognised that not every woman necessarily possesses all of the essential characteristics she described. For example, the distinct physical constitution of women predisposes them towards child-bearing, which makes some women more inclined towards motherhood. Stein’s view of female education was truly unconventional for her time, a time in which women’s educational opportunities, as Stein’s own search for a university position in philosophy demonstrated, were limited. She was an avid advocate for women’s equal educational opportunities. She maintained, however, that because women experienced the world differently than men—for example, they tend to have richer emotional lives—part of their education should be separate from that of men. She argued that, as the minds and bodies of adolescent girls develop differently than those of boys, an all-female learning environment would free adolescent girls from male expectations and dominance; they would thus be 130
Edith Stein
better able to focus on their unique attitudes and desires with respect to their future development. Though deeply influenced by German liberal sensibility, Stein’s pedagogical model left room for religion and the free practice of the professions. Her claims about gender and emotion are philosophically provocative and, as in the case with her views on empathy and communal experience, they raise certain challenges, especially about essentialism, that exceed the scope of this article. Ultimately, Stein’s view of emotion touches upon various aspects of our being, including the body, psyche, spirit, personhood, value, empathy, community, gender, and education. Her discussion of emotion shapes a large part of her corpus, from her early writings to her later ones. As her work becomes better known, the complexity of her thought about emotion will become more evident.
References Ales Bello, Angela (1992). Fenomenologia dell’essere umano: Lineamenti di una filosofia al femminile. Rome: Città Nuova. Berkman Avrech, Joyce (Ed.) (2006a). Contemplating Edith Stein. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. ——— (2006b). Edith Stein: A Life Veiled and Unveiled. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 82(1), 5–30. ——— (2015). The Blinking Eye/I: Edith Stein as Philosopher and Autobiographer. In: M. Lebech and J. Haydn Gurmin (Eds.). Edith Stein’s Phenomenology and Christian Philosophy. Frankfurt: Peter Lang, 20–29. ——— (2016). Edith Stein and Theatrical Truth. In: A. Calcagno (Ed.). Edith Stein: Women, SocioPolitical Philosophy, Theology and Public Life. Dordrecht: Springer, 227–238. Husserl, Edmund (2008). Logical Investigations. Transl. by J. N. Findlay. New York: Routledge. McAlister Lopez, Linda (2006). Edith Stein: Essential Differences. In: J. A. Berkman (Ed.). Contemplating Edith Stein. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 201–211. Scheler, Max (1973). Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values. Transl. by Manfred Frings and Roger L. Funk. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. ——— (2008). The Nature of Sympathy. Transl. by P. Heath. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers. Sharkey Borden, Sarah (2006). What Makes You You? Edith Stein on Individual Form. In: J. Avrech Berkman (Ed.), Contemplating Edith Stein. Stein. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 283–300. ——— (2009). Thine Own Self: Individuality in Edith Stein’s Later Writings. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press. Stein, Edith (1985). Life in a Jewish Family: Edith Stein: An Autobiography: 1891–1916. Transl. by J. Koeppel OCD. Washington, DC: ICS Publications. ——— (1989). On the Problem of Empathy. Transl. by Waltraut Stein. Washington, DC: ICS Publications, 48–49. ——— (1992). The Hidden Life: Hagiographic Essays, Meditations, Spiritual Texts. Transl. by W. Stein. Washington, DC: ICS Publications. ——— (2000). Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities. Transl. by M. C. Baseheart and Marianne Sawicki. Washington, DC: ICS Publications. ——— (2004). Einführung in die Philosophie. Ed. by C. Mariéle Wulf. In: Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe, vol. 10. Freiburg i.B.: Herder. ——— (2010). Der Aufbau der menschlichen Person: Vorlesungen zur philosophischen Anthropologie. Ed. by B. Beckmann-Zöller. In: Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe, vol. 10. Freiburg: Herder. ——— (2013). Essays on Woman, 2nd ed. revised. Transl. by Freda Mary Oben. Washington, DC: ICS Publications. Szanto, Thomas (2015). Collective Emotions, Normativity, and Empathy: A Steinian Account. Human Studies 38(4), 503–527. Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (2015). Empathy, Emotional Sharing and Feelings in Stein’s Early Work. Human Studies 38(4), 481–502. Zahavi, Dan (2010). Empathy, Embodiment and Interpersonal Understanding: From Lipps to Schutz. Inquiry 53, no. 3, 285–306.
131
Antonio Calcagno Further reading Ales Bello, Angela (2007). The Study of the Soul between Psychology and Phenomenology in Edith Stein. Cultura: International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology 4(2), 90–108. ——— (2010). Causality and Motivation in Edith Stein. In: R. Poli (Ed.). Causality and Motivation. Heusenstamm: Ontos, 135–149. Betschart, Christof (2009). Was ist Lebenskraft? Edith Steins erkenntnistheoretische Prämissen in “Psychische Kausalität” (Teil 1). Edith Stein Jahrbuch 15, 154–183. ——— (2010), Was ist Lebenskraft? Edith Steins anthropologischer Beitrag in “Psychische Kausalität” (Teil 2). Edith Stein Jahrbuch 16, 33–64. Calcagno, Antonio (2014). Lived Experience from the Inside Out: The Social and Political Philosophy of Edith Stein. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. ——— (2018). Edith Stein’s Challenge to Sense-Making: The Role of the Lived Body, Psyche, and Spirit. In: D. Zahavi (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Maskulak, Marianne (2007). Edith Stein and the Body-Soul-Spirit at the Center of Holistic Formation. New York: Peter Lang. Moran, Dermot, and Parker, Rodney (Eds.) (2015). Early Phenomenology. Special Edition of Studia Phaenomenologica: Romanian Journal for Phenomenology 15, 11–26. Szanto, Thomas, and Moran, Dermot (2020). Edith Stein. E. N. Zalta (Ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Zahavi, Dan (2015). Self and Other: Exploring Subjectivity, Empathy and Shame. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
132
10 GERDA WALTHER AND HERMANN SCHMALENBACH Linas Tranas and Emanuele Caminada
1. Introduction We sometimes experience emotions as ‘ours’, not as ‘mine’: ‘we rejoice the victory’ as opposed to ‘I rejoice the victory’. In the contemporary debate, a consensus has been that there is a sense of ‘our’ that is stronger than and cannot be captured by “‘I (A) feel X’ and ‘I (B) feel X’ and we are mutually aware that both of us feel X”. Such experiences are called (genuinely) shared or collective emotions. But what makes them ‘shared’ (in this strong sense) as opposed to individual? The German early phenomenologist Gerda Walther (1897–1977) proposed a rich analysis of such genuinely shared emotions, as part of her analysis of an intentional structure of community membership. In this chapter, we will systematically reconstruct her proposal. In addition, we will briefly discuss how, if at all, Walther’s analysis could benefit from another German early phenomenologist and sociologist Hermann Schmalenbach’s (1885–1950) analysis of the basic sociological categories. This chapter is structured as follows: After some preliminary remarks about Walther’s understanding of the modes of experiential givenness and of the structure of the self (1), we will introduce her analysis of communal emotions (2), distinguishing three kinds thereof (3). Finally, we will introduce Schmalenbach’s analysis of the basic sociological categories in order to address the question whether shared emotions are constitutive of a particular form of social structure (4).
2. Modes of experiential givenness and the structure of the self To begin with, strictly speaking, Walther does not present a theory of collective emotions as such. Her primary aim is to analyze the ontological structure of social communities, which she—following Tönnies (2001)—conceives as one of the two basic sociological categories, society being the other. Nevertheless, she characterizes community as essentially based on a form of emotional participation (innere Einigung, Walther 1922, 34f.). On her account, ‘our’, shared emotions are “communal emotions”. Participants in a society do not experience their emotions as ‘our’ (ibid., 33). 133
Linas Tranas and Emanuele Caminada
To properly understand Walther’s account, we need to briefly say who are the ones sharing emotions. The subjects of communal emotions in Walther’s account are persons (ibid., 13). There are two aspects of persons that are of great importance to our reconstruction of Walther’s account of communal emotions. First, a person can have lived experiences (Erlebnisse) in three modes of givenness (Gegebenheitsweise)—actual-present (aktuelle), subconscious (untererlebte, unterbewusste), and habitual (habituelle) (ibid., 12–13, 37ff.). Second, a person is a unity of two parts—the I-center and the self—both of which are embedded in her intentional background. Actual-present experiences are conscious; they are, as it were, the lucid psychological life. They occur in the I-center, which is the experiencing point of consciousness (der erlebende Kern), and the locus of subject’s deliberate acts (ibid., 13). The I-center is exclusively individual, and it is because of this I-center that we cannot talk about fusion of their consciousnesses. On the other hand, not every experience is necessarily private: The self is not alone in the background but intentionally and emotionally intertwined with its social environment (Caminada 2014). As other early phenomenologists (see Vendrell Ferran 2008, 78), Walther argues that actual-present experiences are only the tip of the mental life (das Psychische), part of which exists inactually (inaktuell). Walther distinguishes between two modes of inactual experiences—subconscious and habitual. Subconscious experiences are experiences that resonate in the I-center, while the I is filled with other actual-present experiences (Walther 1922, 12). These experiences occur at the fringes of conscious life but can still be thematized by paying attention to them, like in the case of listening to music while doing something that requires primary attention, for instance driving. Both actual and subconscious experiences are present experiences. But present experiences can sediment and transform into an intentional framework in the habits of the subject’s intentional background, within which subsequent experiences of the same type are experienced (see Husserl, 1973). For instance, our perception is enacted on the basis of previous encounters with similar objects of the same type. These encounters are “saved” in habits that help us in dealing with new objects of the same type: We know that behind a door, there is usually another room and our habits embody the implicit know-how of how to open it. Habitual experience persists in the background of consciousness and, under certain circumstances, emerges as an actual or subconscious structure (Pfänder 1913, 330) of the horizon of experience (Husserl 1973). Following Pfänder, Walther understands the person as a unity of two parts—I-center and the self. Whereas the I-center is the point of present conscious experiences, the intentional background is the locus of the self and of her habitual experiences (Walther 1922, 14). Importantly, the I-center is tightly embedded in the self and the relationship between the I-center and the self is bi-directional: Whereas the experiences a subject presently has shape herself, all of person’s present experiences are experienced within the context of her intentional background. Thus, how I perceive and emotionally respond to a situation is shaped by the intentional background I have. To sum up, a person has an I-point and a self in her intentional background. To the latter belong also all her habitual experiences that can shape new actual experiences (and vice versa).
3. Walther’s analysis of shared emotions Walther argues that communal emotions are constituted by a complex web of reciprocal, intentionally interwoven experiences (the parts of which are nevertheless not experienced as 134
Gerda Walther and Hermann Schmalenbach
separate experiences, but as one unity). For emotions of two subjects to be communal emotions, they have to satisfy the following four general conditions: a b c d
Both subjects experience emotions that are intentionally directed at the same object in the same or similar sense. They are mutually aware of one another’s emotions in question. They are mutually “unified” with one another’s emotions in question (and eventually with one another). They are mutually aware of reciprocating one another’s unification with one another’s emotions in question.
First, both subjects experience emotions that are intentionally directed at the same object in the same or similar sense (a). Note that the same object towards which their emotions are intentionally directed is different from an object as it is experienced, which is part of the experience (Walther 1922, 25–26). To illustrate, this object is not a stone that is an object in my experience, but the stone that my experience refers to. While the object of emotions has to be the same for them to be shared, it is sufficient that the senses of those emotions are only similar (ibid., 25). A sense of an experience is a mode through which its object is presented to the experiencing subject. The same object can be referred to in different senses (Moran and Cohen 2012, 297). What is crucial to the ‘sufficient similarity’ of the senses of the participating emotions is their coherence. For emotions to be communal (i.e., ’our’), their senses should be at least minimally coherent. Specifically, they need coherent motivational backgrounds and ensue coherent actions and expressions ( Walther 1922, 27). Thus, a team member and a fan of a football club can rejoice the victory in different senses, but they experience their joy as being coherently the same. However, having emotions with the same intended object and coherent senses is not sufficient for sharing them (ibid., 20). For the participating subjects—A and B—can be unaware of one another’s emotions in question. And if that is the case, their emotions do not figure in one another’s experiences and there is nothing that would make them conceive their emotions as shared with others as opposed to their individual ones. Thus, for emotions to be genuinely shared, the participating subjects have (b) to be aware of one another’s emotions in question (ibid., 80–84). Subjects can be aware of one another’s emotion both directly, in empathic acts (which are perception-like experiences of other subjects and their experiences) or mediately, e.g., via testimonies (ibid., 82). However, mutual awareness of one another’s experiences that are coherently directed at the same object is still not sufficient to transform them into shared emotions (ibid., 73). Even in the most direct experience of the other’s emotions—in empathic acts—a subject grasps the other’s experience precisely as belonging to the other. Then, if both participating subjects feel individual emotions with the same object and with coherent senses and if each is empathically aware of one another’s emotion, each subject is aware of one another’s individual emotions precisely as the other’s emotion and simultaneously feels one’s own emotion as an analogous, parallel individual emotion (ibid., 74). For them, their emotions belong to two separate subjects. Therefore, even though mutual empathy to some degree makes B’s experience part of A’s experience and vice versa, it is still not sufficient to integrate them in such a way that they would belong to both of them and they would experience their emotions as “our emotions”. So, what else is needed to integrate individual emotions in such a way that they are experienced as “our” experiences? 135
Linas Tranas and Emanuele Caminada
Walther proposes that a crucial element to the transformation of parallel individual emotions to shared ones is an act of unification (Einigung). She borrows this notion from Pfänder (1913, 1916) who presents it as one of the constitutive elements of positive sentiments ( Walther 1922, 34, 48; Caminada 2014). Sentiments (Gesinnungen) are affective intentional attitudes towards the objects (primarily but not exclusively other persons) in the world. Briefly, unification is an intentional, but not necessarily deliberate, act. Persons can unify both with other persons and other objects, such as concerns, experiences, social communities, material objects, etc. (Walther 1922, 49; cf. Pfänder 1913). Unification is given in a feeling of unification and of belongingness (Walther 1922, 34, 47). Walther argues that it is necessary for the constitution of a community that subjects “unify” with one another. However, they do not have to unify directly with the other person: Their unification may be mediated by unification with some other objects—they can first unify with those objects and only then with the other subject. These different intentional directions of unification found a basic distinction between two kinds of communities: personal and objectual. So, here are two cases of unification, relevant to our discussion of those emotions that are “ours” in the strong sense of the word: A is unified with a concern or emotion X and B is unified with a concern or emotion X, A then unifies with B because of B’s unification with the concern X and vice versa; A is unified with B as a person, which somehow aligns their concerns and then they unify with one another’s concerns. When a subject unifies with another’s emotion, she takes that other’s emotion (and the subject of that emotion) into her inner realm (innerseelischer Bereich), her intentional background. She feels that this emotion now belongs to her, even though it is the other who experiences that emotion. For instance, when A unifies with B’s grief, she feels that B’s grief belongs to her; A now co-owns B’s grief. If this emotion endures in A, the object (or subject) of unification will, under certain circumstances, emerge from A’s intentional background as an actual or subconscious emotional pattern that will structure the horizon of A’s experience also according to the sense of B’s grief. Since unification is an individual, one-sided act, A’s unification with B’s emotion does not entail that B also unifies and feels that A’s emotion belongs to him. Therefore, a genuine mutual sharing of emotion requires that (c) B unifies with A’s emotion as well. Or, in general, all participating subjects have to unify with the relevant emotions of all other participating subjects (Walther 1922, 63). However, even everyone’s unification with the relevant emotions of all relevant others is not yet sufficient to constitute a genuine sharing of emotions, because this allows for situations where A unifies with B, B unifies with A, but neither of them knows that the other reciprocates the unification. Such a unification of all with the emotions of all others would amount to a sum of one-sided, subjective communities (Gemeinschaften für sich), but not to one objective community (Gemeinschaft an und für sich) of subjects mutually sharing emotions (ibid., 63). Thus, the constitution of genuinely shared emotions requires that the unification of all participating subjects with the relevant emotions of all other participating subjects is also experienced as a reciprocated unification (Wechseleinigung, Erwiderungseinigung) (ibid.). That is, A has to experience that B has reciprocated her unification and unified with A’s emotion and vice versa. Or, in general, every participating subject has to experience that every participating subject unifies with all other subjects. Thus, participating subjects have to be aware of one another’s unification with one another’s emotions (and them). Reciprocal unification (Erwiderungseinigung) effects a peculiar transformation of the sense of ownership of the emotions at hand by integrating the perspectives of the participating subjects into one communal perspective—one now conceives of the other’s perspective as 136
Gerda Walther and Hermann Schmalenbach
part of “our perspective”. Their emotions now entail a sense of belonging to both of them, which is consciously experienced in a feeling of belonging together, i.e., of participating in the same communal experiences. Furthermore, this emotional intertwining affects the background of each participating subject: On the basis of reciprocal unification the We exists in the intentional backgrounds of the participating subjects and occurs and actualizes itself in the experiences of the individual subjects, in their I-centers (that are exclusively individual) (ibid., 70). Communal experiences manifest as emerging “in me from them and in them from me, from us” (ibid., 72).
4. Kinds of communal emotions Walther’s four conditions for emotions to be communal ones can be satisfied in different ways. Based on these differences, we can distinguish in her account between—at least— three basic kinds of communal emotions: communal emotions in a narrow sense, communal emotions in a broad sense, and emotions in the name of community.
4.1 Communal emotions in a narrow sense Communal emotions in a narrow sense are emotions in situations when the participating subjects are spatiotemporally immediately co-present to one another and all elements constituting communal emotions are actual-present (ibid., 85). It is important to distinguish between two ways of how subjects come to be aware of and unified with one another in actual-present we-emotions. Our presentation above seems to imply that each person first has individual, emotional response to the situation, then becomes aware of the other’s emotion, then reciprocally unify with it, and then they both feel that their emotions belong to them together. This is, for instance, the case in Walther’s example of two hikers who get in touch with each other while enjoying the same landscape and on the basis of this mutual experience feel that they can trust each other as (at least temporarily) hiking mates. However, there seem to be cases of communal emotions in which persons experience their emotions as ‘our’ from the very beginning and as the expression of an extant community. One illustration of such sharing is Scheler’s classic example of grieving parents (Scheler 1954, 12–13; see also Chapters 4, 40, 45, and 49 in this volume). Can Walther explain how such an immediate sharing is possible? The crucial element to her explanation of the immediacy of this grief is the habitual mode of experiences that we have introduced above. Walther argues that unification can sediment in subject’s intentional background and persist as habitual (Walther 1922, 39). When this happens, subjects’ related experiences stream from their intentional backgrounds. Their backgrounds are interwoven by reciprocal unification with the others and therefore are co-constituted by that subject and the others. Accordingly, communal experiences stream “from me and the others in me”. Importantly for our purposes here, such experiences are not preceded by individual emotional responses and are communal even prior to entering subject’s I-center. As Walther puts it, “Well before these experiences come to the fore of the I-point, before they are actualized, they are lived experiences of the community, because they already arise as motions from me and the others in me” (ibid., 71). This notion of communal emotions based on habitual unification helps Walther capture the aspect of immediacy of sharing in Scheler’s example of the grieving parents. Schmid (2005, 132–138) has argued that Walther’s (alleged “reductive individualist”) account is susceptible to the issue of the infinite regress: For individual emotions to become 137
Linas Tranas and Emanuele Caminada
communal, persons will have to perform an infinite number of empathic acts about one another’s unification, and therefore shared emotions will be impossible. There seems to be a way to defend Walther’s account from Schmid’s objection. Schmid (2018) notes that he is sympathetic to Walther’s notion of habitual, subconscious unification. He takes it to be similar or even equivalent to his notion of plural pre-reflective self-awareness. Moreover, he is sympathetic to Walther’s concept of communal experiences based on habitual or subconscious unification, where participating persons are immediately and pre-reflectively aware of their togetherness. Given that actual we-experiences can be based on habitual reciprocal unification, actualization of reciprocal unification is needed only for the constitution of actual communal emotions. Therefore, Schmid must be rejecting Walther’s actual we-emotions as constituted in the situation step-by-step. Unfortunately, this response is only partly helpful, if habitual reciprocal unification is always based on actual reciprocal unification and actual we-experiences. However, Wa lther distinguishes between two kinds of habitual unification. Habitual unification, as we have discussed so far, is based on the sedimentation of actual experiences of unification. But subjects can also unify subconsciously in merely growing together (bloßes Zusammenwachsen) (Walther 1922, 36). When subconscious unification sediments, it founds habitual subconscious unification. Subjects can be unified, live (act and experience) in accordance with their unification, and become consciously aware of their unification (and community) only later, when, e.g., their community is threatened (ibid., 36). Furthermore, Walther suggests that it may be that subconscious growing together should be considered as the very first kind of community the subjects enter (ibid., 99). Thus, it is not the case that Walther argues that actual we-experiences necessarily lie at the foundation of shared experiences (and emotions). On the contrary, she is stating that habitual unification is more important in the constitution of communities than actual experience of unification. Thus, Walther’s account of communal emotions is not susceptible to the infinite regress (Caminada 2014). On the other hand, Walther requires subjects’ mutual awareness of one another’s unification to ensure a bi-directional sense of sharing that makes up their community. Giving up the condition of mutual awareness would risk failing to ensure the bi-directionality of sharing and the communality of emotions. Schmid, who criticizes the mutual awareness condition, would have to demonstrate how to ensure the bi-directionality of collectivity without mutual knowledge.
4.2 Communal emotions in a broad sense Walther argues that communal emotions are not restricted to the situations where the participating subjects are immediately co-present to one another. First, subjects may know about one another, or one another’s relevant concerns and emotions, only indirectly—for example, by reading about them or hearing testimonies of the third parties (Walther 1922, 82). Second, subjects do not have to be immediately co-present to one another to reciprocally unify with one another’s emotions and one another, since unification is “primarily based on intentionally grasping the shared object of appraisal” (Szanto 2018, 97) and does not require direct emotional expressions and communication between the participating subjects. Thus, in virtue of their communal intentional background, parents from Scheler’s example could grieve communally even if they had learned about the child’s death in different locations or at different times, or even if one of them was deceased.
138
Gerda Walther and Hermann Schmalenbach
4.3 Feeling in the name of community So far, in none of the intentional acts constituting communal emotions, community itself has been an intentional object because actual-present experiences do not entail the subject’s reflective awareness of the community as such: Subjects live in communal emotions in virtue of being intentionally related in a certain way, without being aware of their community. It is only when the participating subjects become reflectively aware of their communal experiences and communal intentional relatedness that a new social object is constituted in their experience: Their community “is objectified as a psychological, synthetic collective objectivity of higher order” (Walther 1922, 97). When this happens, the participating subjects can conceive themselves as members of a community in a strict sense. Persons can know about it as a distinct object in the world, they can unify with a community as such, and they can interact with it (ibid., 100). The objectification of a community has two important implications for communal emotions: First, it is only now that communal emotions are genuinely of a community as such. The source of communal emotions in the intentional background is a community instead of others with whom one is reciprocally unified. This also makes it possible to share emotions with others without even having met them in person, as of “people who also” (Menschen, die auch) belong to the same community. Second, based on reflective awareness of being part of a community, a new kind of communal experiences is possible: Community members can feel ‘in the name of ’ a community and represent it (ibid., 103). This is evident in every institutional form of social life where persons are attributed a representative function and the responsibility to take decisions for the whole community.
5. Shared emotions and the sociological categories of community, society, and Bund At the outset of our discussion, we have mentioned that Walther, following Tönnies (2001), distinguishes between two social categories—community and society. Furthermore, she argues that only members of communities can share emotions in proper sense (Walther 1922, 33). Let us now briefly look at whether this restriction of shared emotions to community is tenable. Walther argues that a society is constituted when several subjects are (1) intentionally directed at the same object in a coherent sense (Sinnzusammenhang), (2) they know about one another and their relation to the same intended object, and (3) they intentionally interact with one another (Wechselwirkung) on the basis of this knowledge. “[Suppose several persons] build a wall, some of them take the bricks, others pass them on to someone else and give them to the brick layers, who apply the mortar and place the bricks one on top of the other” (ibid., 31). Although satisfying these conditions is sufficient to constitute a common life ( gemeinsames Leben) (ibid., 29–30), conditions (1)–(3) allow that its members are hostile or indifferent to one another (ibid., 31). In comparison, according to Tönnies’ notion of community, a feeling of belonging together and inner unification are essential elements of community (ibid., 33). Thus, in a nutshell, Walther argues that the basic intentional structure of social communities is conditions (1)–(3) of society plus reciprocal and habitual inner unification among the participating subjects. Hermann Schmalenbach (1922) has criticized Tönnies for arguing that positive affective experiences play a constitutive role in community. He argues that the absence of positive
139
Linas Tranas and Emanuele Caminada
affective relationships does not withdraw one’s community membership. On the contrary, brothers may become mortal enemies and yet they would remain members of the same family community (ibid., 57). Thus, positive affective relationships cannot be a necessary condition for the constitution of community, as it is presupposed by Walther. However, Schmalenbach acknowledges that some groups are constituted by affective experiences. He proposes to introduce a third social modal category “Bund” to capture such groups. “Bund” can be translated as ‘communion’, ‘union’, ‘bond’, ‘band’, ‘covenant’, ‘oath’, ‘league’, or ‘federation’ depending on the context. Schmid (2016) translates it with ‘social bond’, Zahavi and Salice (2017) with ‘communion’. The main source of inspiration for Schmalenbach’s description was the charismatic leadership of the poet Stefan George and the movement of his disciples (that was also the blueprint for Weber’s classification of charismatic groupings). George’s movement had a strong spiritual and religious connotation, which, according to Schmalenbach, is due to the fact that a Bund, if taken seriously by its members, has an affinity to religiosity, as a holy covenant, a sacred pact (Schmalenbach 1922, 41). On the other hand, every religious grouping is, at its very foundation, based on the bond between a spiritual leader and his disciples.1 According to Schmalenbach, the paradigmatic example of community is the family, while the Bund is at best expressed in (male)2 friendships and discipleship: To enter adulthood means leaving the family and joining new friendships, i.e. becoming member of a Bund (ibid., 41). A Bund is characterized by forms of common enthusiasm and effervescence which are based on emotional waves of love (or hatred) that stream out of the heart, of the soul, of its members (ibid., 45). Schmalenbach’s main effort is to distinguish Bund from community. While the Bund is based on conscious, actual-present emotions, the community is grounded in unconscious growing together (ibid., 50). Communities are, in the awareness of their members, obvious; they are given and simply extant. In an actual community, there is nothing like “experience of feelings” (ibid., 53): On the contrary, something like a consciousness of the community, an awareness of being a community is “expression of embarrassment” (ibid., 54) and occurs only when the community is endangered or disturbed (ibid., 55). There are, indeed, forms of communal consciousness such as the feeling of tenderness, happiness in the awareness of solidarity, pride, gratitude, etc.; however, the naturally-beinggrown-together and the belonging together is prior to these feelings which are not to be considered the ground of the community (ibid., 58). On the contrary, “feeling experiences are constitutive for the Bund, they are its ‘basis’” (ibid., 59), the Bund is “made of ” actual-present, “conscious experiences of feeling” (ibid., 62). For example, the followers, passionately acclaiming their leader, unite in and are united by their actual emotions and not on the basis of previous communality. Schmalenbach goes even further, saying that the comrades do not have to be explicitly mutually aware of one another’s emotions in question (ibid., 62). Their experience and feelings are firstly “individual” occurrences, not communal ones, because they consciously choose to adhere to it.3 Whereas the Bund in this respect is closer to society, once it is established, it brings the experiences of its members to a grade of fusion (Verschmelzung) that is more intensive than in communal growing together (Verwachsung) and that removes the kind of separation (Sonderung) of individual experiences that is essential to society (ibid., 72). Regarding their duration, whereas communities are characterized by their continuance and society are guaranteed by contracts, lability, fragility, and discreteness are symptomatic to the Bund: It consists only in individual, discrete actual-present acts, “in ecstatic, effervescent, 140
Gerda Walther and Hermann Schmalenbach
emotional waves” (in rauschhaften Gefühlswogen) which are constitutively ephemeral. Though they have the power “to deeply agitate the soul, to completely annihilate people or to drive them to madness or even to death, [these elective affiliations called Bund] are not enduring. Ecstasy blows over” (ibid., 73–74). To sum up, Schmalenbach’s conceptual tripartition goes as follows. Community is based on unconscious growing together, and it manifests itself as obviously extant and in the experience of continuance and belonging together. Society is a deliberate formation of individuals who associate for a clear goal and thus are temporary bound by a contract for their private benefit without any emotional involvement. Bund is based on actual-present feelings; it is an elective social formation to which its members devote themselves deliberately and in total dedication and donation. This total commitment to and identification with the common cause expresses itself in the alleged fusion of their experiences. Comparing Schmalenbach’s and Walther’s accounts, we can say that while Schmalenbach provides no detailed description of the experiential structure of either community or Bund, Walther, highlighting the role of subconscious intentionality, depicts a vivid phenomenological account of the dynamics of habitual unification (habituelle Einigung) that, according to her, are at the basis of shared emotions in the strong sense of the word, as “we-experiences”. If we consider again Walther’s four conditions for an experience to be “shared” (see above), we can clearly state that these conditions, according to Schmalenbach’s own definitions, are neither constitutive of a community nor of a society. For if communal feelings are an “expression of embarrassment” (ibid., 54), the occurrence of shared emotions would be symptomatic of the transformation of the community into something else than an obvious extant community of growing together. The same goes for a society: If the members of a society, let’s say the wage workers of the above-mentioned example by Walther, build a team spirit that makes of their collective work something more than the sum of what they individually have to do to get their own wages but rather a collective enterprise to which everyone identifies with, then this work team would become something more than a society and would have some traits of a Bund. On the other hand, the fulfillment of Walther’s four conditions occurs as soon as the comrades of a Bund become mutually aware of their common enthusiasm or concern and reinforce it mutually. For instance, reflecting on religious grouping, Schmalenbach claims that the ‘Bund’ blazes between individuals who separately experienced [the same] god as soon as they meet each other, recognize the common and same direction of their ‘passionate feeling’ and ‘on the basis’ of it ignite each other (aneinander entzünden): the ‘Bund’ arises only here, and arises through such new ‘feeling’ that, now and only now is ‘social’ ‘Bund’-feeling. (ibid., 63) These examples suggest that shared emotion is more than simply sharing an experience plus “an elaborate structure of mutual empathy and identification” (Schmid 2016, 207) but is, as Schmalenbach vividly depicts it, a shared passion that is inflamed and reinforced in mutual awareness. It is a mutual igniting each other passions in one shared emotional wave. It seems plausible that Schmalenbach would consider the emotional basis of what Walther calls ‘community in a broad sense’ as a derivate from a former Bund. But how would his account square with Scheler’s example of the grieving parents? Would they have to form a Bund to share their grief? 141
Linas Tranas and Emanuele Caminada
Schmalenbach does not address this example, but he lingers extensively on the example of marriage (Schmalenbach 1922, 74–84) to show how the sociological categories of community, society, and Bund work as ideal types that describe structures that are, in fact, intricately interwoven. In the case of a married couple, marriage is, at first instance, a traditional form of legal union. As such, it is a society. However, if marriage is based on genuine love, the married couple, as lovers, are intrinsically a Bund and are characterized as such as long as they can keep their passion alive. Moreover, living together, they grow together, thus becoming a community as well. This means that parents can be, according to Schmalenbach, at the same time a society, a Bund, and a community if they committed in a legal union and still love each other genuinely. Nevertheless, being parents of the same child requires neither being legally united nor (however unfortunate) mutual love. In Schmalenbach’s account, therefore, parents can grieve together their own child only if they grew up together with that lost child. According to Schmalenbach’s categories, a grieving can be a genuinely shared, conscious feeling only within a Bund. This would imply that if the parents ceased to love each other or are not friends anymore, they could not share such a grieving.
6. Concluding remarks Both Schmalenbach and Walther, in their account of social community and of social Bund, attempt to conceptually capture the elusive phenomenon of mutual excitement through which a passion burns and beats in two or more hearts as in one. When this is the case, the web of mutual awareness, which is a necessary condition for such a passion to occur, shifts in the background of the experienced feeling of unity.
Notes
References Caminada, Emanuele (2014). Joining the Background: Habitual Sentiments Behind We-Intentionality. In: A. Konzelmann Ziv, and H. B. Schmid (Eds.). Institutions, Emotions, and Group Agents. Dordrecht: Springer, 195–212. George, Stefan (1984[1914]). Stern des Bundes. In: S. George: Werke. Ausgabe in zwei Bänden. Band I. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta. [Engl. Transl.: Poems. Transl. and ed. by C. North Valhope, and E. Morwitz. New York: Pantheon 1946.] Husserl, Edmund 1973[1938]. Experience and Judgment: Investigations in a Genealogy of Logic. Transl. by J. Spencer Churchill, and K. Ameriks. Evanston: Northwestern University Press 1975. [Orig.: Erfahrung und Urteil. Ed. by L. Landgrebe. Hamburg: Meiner 1999.] Moran, Dermot, and Cohen, Joseph (2012). The Husserl Dictionary. London: Continuum. Pfänder, Alexander (1913). Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 1(1), 325–404.
142
Gerda Walther and Hermann Schmalenbach ——— (1916). Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen II. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 1(3), 1–125. Scheler, Max (1954). The Nature of Sympathy. Transl. by P. Heath. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Schmalenbach, Herman (1922). Die Soziologische Kategorie des Bundes. Dioskuren 1, 35–105. Schmid, Hans Bernhard (2005). Wir-Intentionalität. Freiburg: Alber. ——— (2016). Communal Feelings and Implicit Self-Knowledge. Hermann Schmalenbach on the Nature of the Social Bond. In: A. Salice and H. B. Schmid (Eds.). The Phenomenological Approach to Social Reality. Dordrecht: Springer, 197–217. ——— (2018). We-experiences with Walther. In: S. Luft and R. Hagengruber (Eds.). Woman Phenomenologists on Social Ontology: We-Experiences, Communal Life, and Joint Action. Dordrecht: Springer, 105–117. Szanto, Thomas (2018). The Phenomenology of Shared Emotions: Reassessing Gerda Walther. In: S. Luft and R. Hagengruber (Eds.). Woman Phenomenologists on Social Ontology: We-Experiences, Communal Life, and Joint Action. Dordrecht: Springer, 85–104. Tönnies, Ferdinand (1926). Gemeinschaft und Gesellschaft. Grundbegriffe der reinen Soziologie. Berlin: Karl Curtius. ——— (2001). Community and Civil Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (2008). Die Emotionen. Gefühle in der realistischen Phänomenologie. Berlin: Akademie. Walther, Gerda (1922). Zur Ontologie der sozialen Gemeinschaften. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 6, 1–158. ——— (1960). Zum anderen Ufer: Vom Marxismus und Atheismus zum Christentum. Remagen: Otto Reichl. Zahavi, Dan, and Salice, Alessandro (2017). Phenomenology of the We: Stein, Walther, Gurwitsch. In: J. Kiverstein (Ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of the Social Mind. London: Routledge, 515–527.
143
11 AUREL KOLNAI Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
Aurel Kolnai (1900–1973) is best known for his political and moral writings, but he also chiefly contributed to the phenomenology of the emotions. In a series of papers between 1929 and 1935 devoted to hostile and aversive emotions and, in particular, to disgust, haughty pride, fear, and hatred, Kolnai presents his most comprehensive views on the affective life and its ethical significance (Kolnai 2007; see also Kolnai 1998). Scattered discussions on the emotions can also be found in an early paper written on Scheler and under the influence of psychoanalysis (1925), in his dissertation Der ethische Wert und die Wirklichkeit (Ethical Value and Reality) (1927), which is his first phenomenological writing, and in later papers “On the Concept of the Interesting” (1964) and “The Concept of Hierarchy” (1971). This chapter is divided into four sections. The first reconstructs Kolnai’s general approach to the emotions as embedded within the larger context of early phenomenology. Sections 2–4 present Kolnai’s analyses of hostile emotions by focusing on disgust, haughty pride, and hatred.
1. Kolnai’s general approach to the emotions “Max Schelers Kritik und Würdigung der Freudschen Libidolehre” (Max Scheler’s Criticism and Praise of Freud’s Doctrine of the Libido) (1925), published in Imago, is the first writing in which Kolnai directly approaches the topic of the emotions. The text was written during a period in which Kolnai embraced psychoanalysis (he was trained in this movement by Ferenczi and Rank). His aim here is to defend Freud’s theory of the libido against Scheler’s criticisms in The Nature of Sympathy. Yet, anticipating his imminent turn to phenomenology, Kolnai ends by praising the phenomenological concept of the mind, as well as its methodology and ethics. Indeed, he even proposes to use phenomenology for a better understanding of psychoanalytical issues around normality and pathology, psychic development, repression, and sublimation. Like Scheler, Kolnai rejects in this early writing a simplistic interpretation of the libido, according to which there is a single form of psychic energy able to generate the multifarious manifestations of our mind. Both agree that such a simplistic interpretation would lead to a flattening of our psychic lives. For instance, applied to the case of the emotions, it would imply that all the different forms of love have their origins in the sphere of the libido and are derived from sexual love and can be explained as such. The simplistic interpretation would also 144
Aurel Kolnai
suggest that it is impossible to distinguish between levels of emotional depth according to the hierarchy of the values toward which they are directed (1925, 143). That is, if all emotions were derived from the same kind of psychic energy, then they would be blind to different value-complexes and would intend the same type of value. These points of agreement with Scheler are mentioned in this text only en passant, but they are crucial in light of Kolnai’s later contributions to the phenomenology of the emotions (see below and Section 4). Unlike Scheler, however, Kolnai claims that the Freudian concept of the libido already entails the possibility of making such differentiations in the field of the emotions. Furthermore, still against Scheler, he also considers the possibility that some emotions might be derived from others, observing that our emotions toward one and the same object might change, and that in this change, one emotion is the source of the other. According to Kolnai’s example, the love we experience for someone might transform unnoticed into hatred (or indifference). When this happens, the hatred conserves all the passion and energy of the previous emotion of love from which it emerged and which has now disappeared (1925, 143–144). Furthermore, he takes the possibility of mixed emotions for granted. In fact, he considers each transformation of an emotion into another to be a case of mixed feeling, claiming that though nobody experiences green as the mixture of blue and yellow, green can emerge from the combination of both. These topics will reappear in his analyses of the aversive emotions, and one can assume here that it is the influence of psychoanalysis that explains Kolnai’s lifelong predilection for topics concerning negative, ambivalent, and mixed emotions. Apart from this early writing at the intersection between psychoanalysis and phenomenology, throughout the rest of his philosophical work on the emotions, Kolnai embraces the views of the early phenomenologists. This output comprises his three essays on the hostile attitudes: “Der Ekel” (On Disgust) (1929), “Der Hochmut” (Haughty Pride) (1931), and “Versuch über den Hass” (Essay on Hatred) (1935), as well as the later paper “The Standard Modes of Aversion: Fear, Disgust and Hatred” (1998) written during the 1970s at the request of David Wiggins as a summary of his key claims about phenomenology of the aversion and posthumously published in Mind.1 In all these texts, Kolnai employs exemplarily the phenomenological method (and, in particular, the eidetic reduction), distinguishing the analyzed phenomena from cognate ones, identifying and describing their essential traits, and elaborating taxonomies. In his analyses of the hostile attitudes, Kolnai also endorses a specific view of the emotions according to which they are intentional phenomena based on cognitions, which are capable of disclosing the realm of values to us. In embracing this view, Kolnai echoes the general idea of emotions as intentional phenomena put forward by Brentano’s followers within early phenomenology and the Graz School: namely Scheler, Pfänder, and Meinong.2 However, in his texts on the aversive emotions, Kolnai only explicitly refers to such a view on one occasion. More concretely, in his later text “The Standard Modes of Aversion”, he refers to the emotions in terms of “emotive responses”, a concept that he describes as follows: [Emotive responses are] something closely germane I think to Meinong’s emotionale Präsentation, meaning thereby acts or attitudes or conative states of consciousness which on the one hand are clearly governed by an intentional object, and on the other hand express something like a passion aroused in the self, an impact exercised upon it down to its somatic sounding-board; in other words intention (Gegenständlichkeit) as linked essentially, though not in a uniform or unequivocal or causally necessary fashion, to condition (Zuständlichkeit). (2004b, 94) 145
Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
There are two features of the emotions mentioned in this passage that I will take as a point of departure to reconstruct Kolnai’s more general view using the references, observations, and comments scattered among his other works. Kolnai characterizes emotions as having an intentional and an experiential moment, which he refers to as “intention” and “condition”, respectively. Regarding the moment of intentionality, Kolnai’s view might be characterized by way of the following three aspects: (1) First, he endorses a “cognitive model” according to which emotions require cognitive bases in order to occur. More concretely, perceptions, thoughts, and beliefs present us the objects toward which the emotions are directed. This view can be directly derived from Kolnai’s examples: To feel fear requires a perception or a thought (2004a, 36), to feel disgust toward an insect requires a perception of it, and to feel contempt requires a belief in another’s inferiority (2004a, 82) (for similar views on the bases of the emotions, see, for instance, Meinong 1968, 35). (2) Yet, Kolnai does not conceptualize the intentionality of the emotions in terms of the intentionality of these other states on which the emotions are based, but rather, like many of Brentano’s followers, he understands such intentionality of the emotions as a sui generis form of reference toward their objects (illustrative of this view is Scheler 1973, 256). In other words, the fact that emotions require cognitive bases does not imply that emotional experience might be reduced to them, nor does it suggest that emotions’ intentionality is derived from their cognitive bases. (3) To be precise, this original emotive intentionality consists in disclosing values. That is to say, values can only be grasped or presented by our emotions. Emotions are unique not only insofar as they are directed toward an object, but also insofar as they present this object to us as having a certain quality. Kolnai defends this position already in his dissertation, but it also appears in his text on disgust, in which he attributes to this emotion a cognitive and ethical function (Kolnai 2002, 67; 2004a, 81). In this regard, Kolnai advocates a “perceptual model” of the emotions (for a similar model, see Meinong 1968, 117; for a different idea of the relation between emotions and values within early phenomenology, see Scheler 1973, 256). These three claims should be interpreted within the boundaries of value realism. Value realism is a term used to encompass a wide range of positions, which claim that values are objective. Such value realism was widely accepted among early phenomenologists. In this view, rather than constituting a projection of my emotional state onto the world, my disgust reveals a certain quality of the object toward which it is directed. Kolnai’s commitment to value realism is clear not only in his dissertation on the ethical values and in his texts on the hostile emotions, but also in later texts such as in “On the Concept of the Interesting” (1964). Here, he claims that while people are interested in different things, the concept of “interesting” cannot be reduced to a mere sense of being interested in something. In contrast, Kolnai characterizes the interesting as that which evokes interest without appealing to one’s interests (1968, 167–169). It is in the frame of value realism that we have to understand Kolnai’s description of emotions as emotive response. This idea implies that values are given to us with the sufficient authority to “call”, “demand”, and “require” us to react emotionally in a certain way. In this sense, the early phenomenologists spoke of the emotions as “responses”, “answers”, or “reactions” to a certain kind of object, as “stances” or “act of position-taking” toward such objects. Although he mentions Meinong here, this idea can also be found in early phenomenologists like Scheler, Reinach, or von Hildebrand (see, for instance, Scheler 1973, 256; Kolnai employs this terminology in his dissertation: Kolnai 1927, 14).
146
Aurel Kolnai
Related to the feature of intentionality is the idea of emotional depth, which Kolnai already mentions in his earlier text. The idea of emotional depth, also known as the “stratification thesis”, was originally proposed by Scheler, according to whom we can distinguish between different levels, strata, or layers in our emotional life: sense feelings, vital feelings, psychic feelings, and feelings of the personality. In Scheler’s view, each of these strata constitutes a class and is responsible for being directed toward specific value-complexes, which, according to Scheler, exist in a hierarchy (Scheler 1973, 330). In general terms, Kolnai will take up this claim as is clear in his analysis of hatred as a phenomenon that is rooted in deep strata of our personality. However, he will also introduce some refinements of his own. In “The Concept of Hierarchy” (1971), Kolnai considers Scheler’s model as an expression of a hierarchical and rigid form of thought, in which some aspects of life, which usually appear merged together, are isolated, whereby some layers of values are overestimated over others (for instance, he deems vital values to be inferior to the spiritual ones) (Kolnai 1971, 203–221; see also Kolnai 2004c, 56). Besides intentionality, emotions are also characterized by an experiential moment. Kolnai observes that emotions are linked to bodily responses, and that by virtue of these, some emotions are more “bodily bound” (Leibgebundenheit) than others (2004a, 32). Although he does not develop this point further, it is important to note that this idea of body-boundness is committed to a specific view of emotions according to which they are phenomena of the lived body (Leib) and not just mental states accompanied by concomitant physical manifestations of the physical body (Körper) (cf. Scheler 1973, 398). In this regard, he speaks of a “coloring”, “accent”, and “quality” (2004a, 29), or of a “fundamental tone” that is characteristic of each emotion (Kolnai 2007, 100). It is precisely by virtue of this feature that he claims that the aversive feelings of disgust, haughty pride, and hatred share a similar coloration, namely a refusal of their object (2007, 100).
2. On Disgust The first of Kolnai’s writings on the hostile attitudes is “Der Ekel” (On Disgust) (1929). The contribution is unique not only because, at the time of its publication, disgust was typically dismissed as a topic of philosophical research, but also because, rather than treating disgust as a biological reaction or an instinct, Kolnai’s approach signals that the phenomenon of disgust performs an important cognitive and ethical function. More specifically, with differences of coloring, all types of physical and moral disgust point to the same quality of the disgusting and are reactions to certain objects, “which are constituted in such a way that they refer in a determinate manner to life and to death” (2004a, 72). Disgust is analyzed in the text by means of a comparison with fear (which, in Kolnai’s view, comprises both fear (Furcht) and anxiety (Angst) (2004a, 36) (cf. Chapter 34 in this volume). Disgust and fear are associated with strong bodily reactions; both have the character of a response toward an aspect of the world; and both display “psychic depth” in the sense of being able to mobilize central aspects of the person who experiences them. Furthermore, both display a twofold intentional reference toward their objects: They intend the object or state of affairs that provokes them and, at the same time, they intend the well-being of the subject who experiences them (2004a, 36). Despite these similarities, Kolnai also notes significant differences between fear and disgust. Fear is intentionally directed toward an object that concerns the survival of the subject. As Kolnai puts it, it is inseparable from the concept of “threat, danger, rescue and need of
147
Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
protection” (2004a, 37). Disgust displays an intentionality of a different kind, which, according to Kolnai, is more “uniform”, i.e., focused more on the object and less on the survival of the subject, in part because the feeling of disgust does not affect the totality of the subject’s existence (2004a, 40). In short, unlike fear, disgust is more outwardly oriented toward the object and it is not directed toward the self in the same way. Relatedly, there is a second key difference. According to Kolnai’s perceptual model of the emotions set out above, while in fear we become aware of a danger, in disgust it is not just that we become aware of some object as disgusting, but we are also able to grasp specific moments and features of the disgusting object. Disgust is directed toward the intrinsic constitution of the object, which is grasped in its details. Thus, Kolnai attributes to disgust a cognitive dimension that is lacking in fear. A further common feature concerns the mode in which both emotions are experienced. Both fear and disgust appear to be connected to strong bodily reactions and bodily movements that suggest the avoidance of their respective objects. However, also in this respect, there are interesting differences. While the evasive behavior of fear culminates in flight, disgust avoids its object while remaining attached to and captured by it. As a result, Kolnai identifies a further essential feature of disgust: the paradoxical and ambivalent relation to its object. This claim—namely that in disgust there is a moment of desire—has clear psychoanalytical resonances, but Kolnai, at the same time, distances himself from this tradition: While psychoanalysis understands disgust as a consequence of a desire suppressed by civilizational norms, Kolnai attributes to this emotion a cognitive function that cannot be explained as an expression of internalized social norms. On the basis of this characterization, Kolnai elaborates a typology of disgust concerning its objects and functions. In terms of its objects, he distinguishes between a physical and a moral disgust. Physically disgusting are phenomena associated with the process of putrefaction, excrement, bodily secretions, materials that adhere to the subject (such as dirt), some animals (such as insects and rats), the unwanted nearness of the human body, an exuberant fertility, disease, and bodily deformation.3 Moral disgust appears in cases of satiety, of an unfurling vitality that is misplaced or excessive, in cases of lies, falsehoods, and moral weakness. Both types of disgust differ in their respective objects, but according to Kolnai, they both share a similar structure: There is an isomorphism between the physically and morally disgusting. In this vein, he describes the phenomena of lying and mendacity—which for him are paradigmatic cases of moral disgust—as phenomena that display a slimy and dirty vitality, which is analogous to the disorganized vitality characteristic of the objects of physical disgust (2004a, 69). Regarding their function, he distinguishes between disgust aroused by breaking a norm and disgust aroused by satiety (2004a, 59). The first type emerges after the violation of a rule that forbids putting us in contact with certain objects that are dirty, rotten, or that might endanger us. The idea of a surfeit disgust, which is one of Kolnai’s original contributions in this paper, refers to an experience that in normal circumstances is pleasurable, but in being constantly repeated, its object and its enjoyment become disgusting (2004a, 63). This might happen, for instance, when over a long period of time, we are offered our favorite cake every day, but after a while, we come to think that enough is enough. The most striking claim of the paper concerns Kolnai’s attribution of an ethical function to disgust. Kolnai ascribes to disgust the capacity of indicating the presence of an unethical quality: the morally putrid or putrescent (2004a, 81). The subject of disgust experiences in this sense a visualization of the process of moral putrefaction of the person. Thus, although it is not a primary experience of evil, the experience of disgust might point to it. In addition,
148
Aurel Kolnai
from another perspective, disgust can also play a role in one’s moral life: Disgust can give rise to moral judgments. These judgments, however, can never be sufficiently grounded to determine our general attitude toward an object. Moral judgments based on disgust might be inappropriate, since they tend to lead to an incorrect stigmatization of its object. By the end of the paper, Kolnai touches on the topic of love as the only means at our disposal to overcome the strong aversive emotion of disgust.
3. On Haughty Pride (Hochmut) “Über den Hochmut” (On Haughty Pride) (1931) is the second of Kolnai’s papers devoted to the phenomenology of the hostile.4 The term Hochmut is used to refer to a specific phenomenon whereby the subject remains self-centered and is unable to recognize the values of others. The main features of this phenomenon are fleshed out by means of a comparison with feelings of self-worth, pride, vanity, conceit, individualism, and haughtiness, as well as with attitudes such as the epistemological subjectivism. One of the text’s main achievements consists in establishing a distinction between two different phenomena, which in lieu of a better expression in English I will refer to as two variants of “pride”: intentional pride (Stolz) and haughty pride (Hochmut). On the one side, according to Kolnai, there is a kind of pride (Stolz) that is intentional in nature. It is directed toward an object, another person or oneself. In this regard, we can be proud of something we possess or something we have achieved, we can be proud of someone and of ourselves. In either case, this pride is based on the value of the object toward which it is directed. On the other hand, there is the phenomenon of Hochmut in which, rather than being directed toward an object or a person, the subject remains self-centered. This kind of pride is grounded not on objective values, but rather on an accentuation of one’s own self. Kolnai also observes that this self-centeredness is not reflected in the English term of “haughtiness” (2007, 67). Haughty pride is characterized by blindness toward the values of others and by an impoverishment of the nexus between the human being and the interpersonal world. Kolnai determines the difference between the two phenomena by observing that someone who feels proud of something (Stolz) enjoys the splendor of his valuable things, whereas in the case of haughty pride, the subject experiences herself as the source of magnificence. The differences between the two phenomena make it impossible to interpret haughty pride as derived from or as an extension or generalization of intentional pride. Haughty pride is not a form of intentional pride directed toward oneself. The two emotional phenomena differ in their structure. First, as already mentioned, to be proud of something (Stolz) has an intentional structure, i.e., it is directed toward something or someone, while haughty pride remains focused on oneself. Second, intentional pride presupposes that we have grasped the values of the object or of the person we feel proud of. Thus, intentional pride might fulfill a positive function in our lives, making us aware of the values we care for. Haughty pride, by contrast, does not result from a comparison between the values of the subject with the values of the objects and the others; rather, it is an a priori attitude of the subject, which considers the world to be lacking value (2007, 77, 92). From this, we can conclude that intentional pride exhibits the typical features of an emotional response: It is intentionally directed toward its objects, based on cognitions, it grasps values, and it is bodily felt, while haughty pride has the character of an emotional attitude, is deeper rooted in our personality, and affects how we encounter the world.
149
Íngrid Vendrell Ferran
Kolnai elaborates a typology of some of the manifestations of haughty pride. (1) Isolating pride (Abschließungshochmut) denies the value and the reality of all things that are not one’s own self, which leads the subject to being isolated and lacking an interest in the world. This attitude becomes manifest when the subject focuses only on those few things that represent one’s own self or when one has only a practical interest in them (2007, 77). (2) Haughty pride also becomes manifest in the demands of domination and success (Herrschafts- und Leistungsansprüche) (2007, 80). Think, for instance, of the tyrant whose attitude toward his subordinates is one of contempt, or those types of the arriviste who fight to achieve their goals just because they are theirs. (3) Kolnai also considers certain forms of pantheism as cases of haughty pride. (4) He analyzes forms of haughty pride derived from a person’s ‘inner’ (in)security. (5) In respect of the value objects of pride, he establishes a distinction between internal and external pride. And finally (6) Kolnai analyzes some nuances in the conduct of the person pervaded by haughty pride by attending to how this attitude is related to contempt and inattention. Haughty pride, as a human attitude, can be combated only with the cultivation of humility (Demut), which Kolnai deems to be an affective attitude in which the human being, in comparing herself with an ideal, recognizes and accepts her own finitude, fragility, and imperfection (2007, 96).
4. On Hatred Kolnai’s “Versuch über den Hass” (Essay on Hatred) (1935) can be considered the first attempt to give hatred a place of its own in the phenomenology of the emotions.5 Like other forms of hostility—such as enmity, rejection, antipathy, disgust, and contempt—hatred is also characterized by a negative tone (Grundtönung) (Kolnai 2007, 100). But unlike those others, hatred represents and involves the entire person. Thus, Kolnai attributes to hatred “depth” as well as “centrality” (2007, 101), which means not only that hatred is rooted in those strata of our personal life that cannot be controlled at will, but also that it fills these strata to a maximal extent. Typically, hatred is associated with an annihilating action tendency toward its object. This destructive impulse might be real or symbolic (e.g., humiliation, insult) (2004b, 105; 2007, 105). In contrast to other forms of destructive behavior, the annihilation inherent to hatred is always for its own sake. Thus, when in fear we destroy the dangerous object, we do so only because we consider this to be the only way to ensure our own safety, not because there is an intrinsic destructive impulse inherent to fear. In addition, all the manifold forms of destructive behavior motivated by hatred are univocal in intention: All aim at the destruction of their respective objects. Hatred appears when there is a situation of fight and rivalry with someone to whom we attribute responsibility and ethical consciousness. The hated object must be apprehended as significant, powerful, and dangerous. According to its intentional structure, hatred is experienced toward what threatens and harms us and toward that which we consider to be evil. As Kolnai puts it, The intention of hatred is inquisitive, aggressive, propulsive. It impinges not only on the object as such but on its existential status in the world and thereby on the world itself, with an eye on its finiteness: the world is, as it were, ‘too narrow a place to hold us both’. (2004b, 107) In Kolnai’s view, hatred is accompanied by a demonization of its object, which reveals what we take to be evil in the world (Kolnai refers to this as the “worldview of hatred” 150
Aurel Kolnai
(Weltbild des Hasses) (2007, 132). Furthermore, the object of hatred is influenced by biographical elements. Thus, while disgust is a reaction to an aspect of the world, hatred is not a response toward a felt value because there is no such hypothetical quality of the “odious” (cf. also Schmid’s contribution to this volume). There are two important questions regarding the relation between love and hatred that Kolnai addresses in his texts on the phenomenology of aversion. First, while the term love refers to the entire sphere of pro-attitudes, hatred has a much narrower scope (2004b, 105). In Kolnai’s text, we can find two important observations in favor of the “asymmetry thesis” according to which love and hatred are not symmetrical opposites: (1) There are more objects that can be loved than objects that can be hated. One reason for this claim is that hatred can only be experienced toward persons and spiritual entities, but not toward physical objects. A second reason is that when we experience pleasure in something—when we like it and we affirm it—this might lead more easily to love than a dislike might lead us to hatred. (2) There are also more forms of love than forms of hatred. The ways in which we can engage with others are multiple and manifold, but the scope of our antagonistic relations to others is more limited. Only when the interpersonal nexus with others and/or oneself is broken might hatred appear. The entire web of life, however, is mostly dominated by love (2004a, 35; 2004b, 105; 2007, 128). A further question concerns the possibility of emotional ambivalence (2007, 125). Kolnai vigorously rejects the possibility of simultaneously loving and hating the same object and denies emotional ambivalence. However, he acknowledges that both attitudes (love and hatred) might appear intertwined in the phenomenon of hatred. Whereas we can experience a love free of hatred, there is no hatred free of love. Love is a far more primary and pervasive attitude than hatred, since the latter only appears where and when the positive bonds with the world are broken. This observation already gives us an idea of the possible ways of overcoming hatred: the cultivation of an attitude of love.
Notes
References Balázs, Zoltán, and Dunlop, Francis (Eds.) (2004). Exploring the World of Human Practice. Readings in and about the Philosophy of Aurel Kolnai. Budapest, New York: CEU Press. Dunlop, Francis (2002). The Life and Thought of Aurel Kolnai. Aldershot: Ashgate. Honneth, Axel (2007). Nachwort. In: A. Kolnai: Ekel, Hochmut, Hass: Zur Phänomenologie feindlicher Gefühle. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp, 143–175.
151
Íngrid Vendrell Ferran Kolnai, Aurel (1925). Max Schelers Kritik und Würdigung der Freudschen Libidolehre. Imago. Zeitschrift für Anwendung der Psychoanalyse auf die Geisteswissenschaften XI, 135–146. ——— (1927). Der ethische Wert und die Wirklichkeit. Freiburg i.B.: Herder. ——— (1968). On the Concept of Interesting. In: H. Osborne (Ed.). Aesthetics in the Modern World. New York: Weybright and Talley, 166–187. ——— (1971). The Concept of Hierarchy. Philosophy 46(177), 203–221. ——— (1999). Political Memoirs. Ed. by F. Murphy. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. ——— (2002). Early Ethical Writings of Aurel Kolnai. Ed. by F. Dunlop. Aldershot: Ashgate. ——— (2004a). On Disgust. Ed. by B. Smith, and C. Korsmeyer. Chicago and La Salle: Open Court, 29–92. ——— (2004b[1998]). The Standard Modes of Aversion: Fear, Disgust and Hatred. In: A. Kolnai: On Disgust. Ed. by B. Smith, and C. Korsmeyer. Chicago and La Salle: Open Court, 93–108. ——— (2004c). A Note on the Meaning of Right and Wrong. In: Z. Balázs, and F. Dunlop (Eds.). Exploring the World of Human Practice. Readings in and about the Philosophy of Aurel Kolnai. Budapest, New York: CEU Press, 45–58. ——— (2007[1929, 1931, 1935]). Ekel, Hochmut, Hass: Zur Phänomenologie feindlicher Gefühle. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Korsmeyer, Carolyn, and Smith, Barry (2004). Visceral Values: Aurel Kolnai on Disgust. In: A. Kolnai. On Disgust. Ed. by B. Smith and C. Korsmeyer. Chicago and La Salle: Open Court, 1–28. Meinong, Alexius (1968). Über emotionale Präsentation (1917). In: A. Meinong: Gesamtausgabe III. Ed. by R. Haller, and R. Kindiger. Graz: Akademische Druck-u. Verlagsanstalt, 1–181. Miller, William Ian (1998). The Anatomy of Disgust. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Pfänder, Alexander. (1913/1916). Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen, I und II. Teil Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung I und III, 325–340, 1–125. Scheler, Max (1973). Formalism in Ethics and Non-formal Ethics of Values. A New Attempt Toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism. Transl. by M. S. Frings, and R. L. Funk. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Wiggins, David (2004). Afterword by David Wiggins. In: A. Kolnai: On Disgust. Ed. by B. Smith and C. Korsmeyer. Chicago, La Salle: Open Court, 108–109.
152
12 ARON GURWITSCH Eric Chelstrom
Aron Gurwitsch is an important figure in the historical development of phenomenology. What he has to contribute to the phenomenology of emotion is limited but interesting. Gurwitsch ultimately denies that emotion is a necessary constituent of consciousness. However, the claim means only that emotion is not formally necessary for consciousness; it may be materially necessary for embodied beings like ourselves. Even then, one should recognize the possibility of cognitive deficits. The present work intends to locate emotion’s place in Gurwitsch’s understanding of consciousness. After briefly commenting on what he says about emotion, this essay reconstructs Gurwitsch’s view of emotions in the light of his general theory of consciousness. Central to Gurwitsch’s mature understanding of consciousness are his functional categories of theme, thematic field, and margin. Finally, I shall also respond to Giovanna Colombetti’s critique of Gurwitsch’s view of emotion. In an appendix to the originally unpublished An Outline of Constitutive Phenomenology, Gurwitsch writes: That is the world in which we find ourselves, in which we act, react, and work. It is in that world that we encounter our fellow human beings, to whom we are bound by the most diverse relationships. All our desires and hopes, all our apprehensions and fears, all our pleasures and sufferings (in short, all our affective and emotional life) are related to that world; all our intellectual activities, both practical and theoretical, also refer to it. (Gurwitsch 2009a, 411–412) This establishes two things for present concerns. First, Gurwitsch recognizes that emotion and affect play an important role in the natural attitude. Second, Gurwitsch understands emotions in relation to perception. For Gurwitsch, perception is the key to understanding consciousness. What Gurwitsch says that directly concerns emotions includes his work on expressive phenomena and his criticisms of Maurice Pradines. Neither is of substantive interest, so succinct comment is sufficient. The former deals with phenomena that express or indicate something other than or beyond what their perceptual qualities entail, e.g., a hand gesture that expresses one’s anger, or a movement expressing the living nature of the being moving (cf. Grathoff 1989, 232, 236; Zahavi and Salice 2017, 522; Gurwitsch 1979, 30ff. and 53ff.). 153
Eric Chelstrom
That one expresses to another that they are angry does not itself necessarily involve anger. It is indicative of anger, or perhaps only an intention to indicate said state of affairs, in the event one is being disingenuous or speaking of the past. Gurwitsch also criticizes Pradines’ idiosyncratic understanding of “passions.” Pradines defines passions as “passive impressional states” out of which perceptual experiences are constituted (Gurwitsch 2009a, 212). They are distinguished from emotional responses to perceptions, which Pradines believes are additive of experience, where passions are constitutive of experience (ibid., 218). Gurwitsch ultimately rejects Pradines’ claim that all perceptions are composed of passions. Such a view is not only misguided regarding the constitution of experience, but also has trouble understanding the identity of objects with multi-modal qualities (ibid., 229ff.) and fails to grasp the adumbrated nature of experience (ibid., 233ff.). What’s more, experience does not depend on eventual affective contact, as Pradines’ account requires; one might never directly interact with objects in the far distance (ibid., 225). It is necessary to briefly outline Gurwitsch’s view of consciousness in order to situate emotion within his thought. Gurwitsch rejects the claims that contents of consciousness are either strictly externally determined or strictly built up internally from a pre-interpreted ground; instead, “the percept depends upon both external and internal conditions” (Gurwitsch 1964, 95). Consciousness is understood in field terms, not solely in terms of its object. The field of consciousness is a product of the interactions between the agent and her context. The significance of any part of a Gestalt contexture is determined by its functional role. Hence, Gurwitsch argues, “any part of a Gestalt may then be said to be determined as to its existence by its functional significance in the sense that the part only exists in, and is defined by, its functional significance” (ibid., 121). Organization is an internal feature of each experiential field. A constituent of a Gestalt contexture is phenomenally defined and made to be what it is by the role which it plays for, and the function which it has within, the Gestalt contexture as a whole, that is, with respect to the other constituents. (Gurwitsch 1974, 252) What constitutes a part–whole relation depends on a given contexture and is variable and in a dynamic relation that is subject to modification. Part and whole are defined in functional terms without statically defined relations. This involves that experience is interpreted within a subject’s socio-historical context (Gurwitsch 1964, 1; 1974, 8; 1979, §9; 2009b, xxiv). Gurwitsch understands each moment of consciousness to involve three distinctive kinds of functional roles relative to the organizational principles at play in a given experience: theme, thematic field, and margin. The theme is “that which engrosses the mind of the experiencing subject, or as it is often expressed, which stands in the ‘focus of his attention’” (Gurwitsch 1964, 4). Through focusing on some thematic content, a given conscious whole takes shape. The thematic field is the “totality of those data, co-present with the theme, which are experienced as materially relevant or pertinent to the theme and form the background or horizon out of which the theme emerges as the center” (ibid.). It includes that which is “experienced to be of direct concern to, and of immediate bearing upon, the theme” (ibid., 381). Finally, there is the margin, “data which, though co-present with, have no relevancy to, the theme” (ibid., 4). The margin is also identified by Gurwitsch as “a domain of irrelevance (…) a domain of contingency” (Gurwitsch 1985, xliv). He stresses that marginal consciousness as such is necessary; what serves that functional role in an experience is contingent in relation to thematic relevancy (ibid., xlv, 29). Gurwitsch employs the metaphor of a circle to think about these 154
Aron Gurwitsch
relations: The theme is the center, the thematic field is the interior of the circle, and the margin what lies outside the circle itself (Gurwitsch 2009b, 296). Imagine that I am grading logic homework at a local café. The thematic field is all of that which bears immediate relevance to that focus: problems assigned, and instructions; principles or rules students have at their disposal; proof procedures they are to work with; grading rubric, etc. The theme is whichever problem I am presently grading. Everything else is in the margins, the café, its inhabitants, and any other thoughts that might enter my mind as I grade, for example remembering to pick up my kids after school. If I neglect my grading to focus on one of those thoughts at the margin, the conscious field is reorganized, rendering that thematic with grading falling into the margins. What is marginal may become thematic, “in the margin itself there are structured and unified wholes which can become themes” (ibid., 270). As such, “marginal consciousness must not be misconstrued as an amorphous, chaotic accumulation of contents utterly lacking form, structure, and articulation” (ibid.). Context in mind turns into emotions. Giovanna Colombetti puts it correctly when she notes that Gurwitsch “does not discuss emotions,” but that one might infer parallels between what he does say about bodily awareness with what he should or could say about emotion (Colombetti 2013, 124–125). Colombetti takes this to mean that, for Gurwitsch, emotions, like bodily awareness, will almost always be in the margins of consciousness (ibid., 125; cf. Colombetti 2011, 299–300). Given his general view of consciousness, Gurwitsch would have to allow that emotion may potentially occupy each of the three functional domains of experience. There is nothing in principle preventing one from making one’s emotion the theme of experience, but it would not be the norm. One might reflect on an emotion as the theme of experience. One might experience emotion in relation to the theme of experience, thus occupying the thematic field. Or one might experience emotions unrelated to the theme of experience, i.e., emotion in the margins. Why does Gurwitsch contend that bodily awareness is generally in the margins? He argues, we are aware of our bodily condition and of eventual changes that may occur in this condition. However, this bodily condition pertains in no sense whatever to the problem situation with which we are confronted and no change in our bodily condition affects the problem situation. No feature, tinge, or aspect of the theme derives from the actual bodily condition or is modified by an alteration of this condition. (Gurwitsch 1985, 29) All everyday muscular and motor actions are marginal, as are all bodily and kinesthetic moments. However, he is also clear that there is no moment in conscious life when we are completely unaware of our bodily posture, of the fact that we are walking, standing, sitting, lying down, etc., however absorbed we may be in our mental activity, e.g., our reasoning about a scientific problem. (ibid., 31) The body provides a constant backdrop for and orientation towards objects of experience; it is generally not of thematic relevance as such. For example, we perceive a bird in flight, not our eye and head movements that correspond to that experience (ibid., 32). While one might reflect on those bodily moments, they are not typically part of experience. The body may be rendered thematic, though that is not typical in everyday experience (ibid., 34). 155
Eric Chelstrom
In sum, Gurwitsch argues, “every particular bodily experience appears, so to speak, with an index of appurtenance to the realm of corporeity and is thus given as a somatic fact” (ibid., 35). The body is experienced for the most part in relation to other things: a strain in one’s eye in relation to reading; the tightening of one’s calf muscle in relation to running, etc. Further contextualizing the margin as a functional role, Gurwitsch argues that awareness of the natural world is marginal (Gurwitsch 2009b, 296). Thoughts about the natural world as a thing, even of most of the things encountered in the natural world, are not prevalent in everyday experience. They are a byproduct of a certain kind of thematization of conscious life, i.e., a modification of experience in a reflective attitude. The “natural world” itself is not generally one’s theme, nor is most of what one calls the natural world generally relevant to one’s theme. Even if the body is in the margins of experience, that doesn’t diminish its importance. Colombetti overstates the analogy with bodily awareness. Emotion cannot generally be just in the margins for Gurwitsch. Emotions are thematically relevant in any case where they are responsive to the theme of experience. This is unlike somatic bodily awareness, which underlies experience but which may lack immediate thematic relevance. The body is critically important and is ever present to experience, even if it doesn’t always carry thematic relevance. If I am able-bodied and my body does what I need it to, it will not assert itself into experience. My emotions, on the other hand, are generally intentional, i.e., about something I am experiencing, and assert themselves as modifications of thematic content. A further issue with Colombetti’s analysis concerns her example of danger, given as a counter-example to her interpretation of Gurwitsch (Colombetti 2011, 299–300; cf. 2013, 125–126). Consider being afraid of a dog while riding one’s bike. Colombetti claims that Gurwitsch’s view would overlook that “the theme, in the example, is not just the noises made by the dog, but the danger they signify for me” (Colombetti, 2011, 300). She argues on that ground that this is “not indifferent to how I feel my body in the background” (ibid.). Given that, she believes that one’s fear is relevant to the theme. In responding to Colombetti’s criticisms, one should be careful to note that Colombetti is avoiding the mistake of claiming that fear of the dog is the theme of experience, even if she mistakenly identifies noises in the background as thematic in their own right and not parts of the thematic field. Her assertion has to be that the fear is relevant and not marginal, given that escaping danger is the theme of experience. In fearful or frightening experiences, we experience fear or fright in response to something else, and that generally comes with an aversive reaction to the fearful thing. Fear itself is not the theme of fearful experiences, as fear is a response to something else. If one finds oneself driving in very dangerous circumstances, one will experience fear. But one is still primarily focused on driving the vehicle in the circumstances that provoke the fearful response. The claim that danger includes fear as part of the thematic field further makes sense if one considers that danger or fear involves worry about possibilities, even if felt with a kind of urgency since they are experienced as near possibilities to avoid. If the above reconstruction is correct, however, this is just what Gurwitsch’s own position would have to be in the first place. Colombetti is correct to claim that bodily feelings and emotions “can affect the theme,” but wrong if she contends that they are themselves the theme in cases like these. Additionally, Colombetti fails to account for Gurwitsch’s crucial distinction within the margin between the halo and the horizon. The halo includes that which may have relevance to the theme, but presently lacks actual relevance. The horizon includes that which lacks potential relevance to the theme (Gurwitsch 2009b, 296). The halo includes broader possibilities, including the possibility that one might reflect on the object of experience. 156
Aron Gurwitsch
A felt experience of emotion is not the same as a reflective consideration of that emotion, nor generally does the former include the latter as part of experience. The possibility for that noetic modification remains, even if it is remote from experiential relevance generally. One might distinguish between actual relevancies and potential relevancies in distinguishing those things that are “in” the thematic field from those that are just “outside” in the halo of the margin. The horizon of the margin includes everything beyond that potential relevancy in relation to the present theme. It’s worth remembering that, for Gurwitsch, being in the margin is a function of gestalt and carries no global implication of significance. Being in the margin of consciousness is a functional role something inhabits at a given moment. It is not a blanket claim about relevancy, nor a claim to unintelligibility. Gurwitsch’s distinction between halo and horizon represents a problem for Colombetti’s criticisms of Gurwitsch’s position on bodily awareness. If Gurwitsch’s view is that for the most part the body is of marginal concern, he can readily acknowledge that some bodily moments are in the halo, some in the horizon. The feel of one’s fingers while typing is not thematically relevant to what one is typing, but may be of potential relevance. Contrast this with the somatic feedback of my autonomous functions and general body posture, or the feel of my toes while typing. Those can readily be in the horizon of that experience. True, circumstances may change, but Gurwitsch acknowledges that throughout. His understanding of how this might work is akin to Heidegger’s understanding of tool-being and readiness-to-hand. Thus, if Colombetti wants to argue against the position that the experience of the body was always in the margins, she is correct. But Gurwitsch gives us a reason to think that while that’s true of much of everyday experience, there may be a range of everyday experiences for which the body’s state of affairs presents itself in the thematic field, e.g., attending to hygiene. In either case, Gurwitsch gives strong reasons to think the body is not generally thematic in experience. To conclude, Gurwitsch’s understanding of emotion must be understood in relation to how he understands the functional roles that constitute the field of consciousness. Generally speaking, emotions will either occupy the thematic field or the margins of experience, depending on their relation to the theme of experience, and it will be unusual for emotion to be the theme of experience, except perhaps where one reflects on emotions in experience. If I’m focused on teaching in order to set aside my grief for a tragic personal loss at the moment, I render my grief to the margins. That doesn’t mean it lacks importance or won’t return to my attentions later. Similarly, consider how some task requires us to do this. I might have to focus on my driving and push strong emotions aside so as not to present a danger to myself and others. If I cannot do so, I should acknowledge that my emotion’s urgency is such that I ought not attempt driving or teaching. None of that is problematic in any global sense. Emotion while perhaps not necessary for consciousness itself may be a necessary feature for beings like us. Its place in our lives varies according the significance it bears in relation to the thematic concern of our experience at a given moment, and that thematic concern is subject to modification at any time. It should be noted that Gurwitsch is not only concerned with emotion in the individual case but also offers some contribution to our understanding of emotion in collective cases. Contrary to Gerda Walther (Walther 1923; see Chapter 10 in this volume), Gurwitsch does not accept that all forms of community with others are founded on positive sentiment (Gurwitsch 1979, 119–122). And yet, contrary to Margaret Gilbert (Gilbert 1996, 18f.; see Chapter 40 in this volume), Gurwitsch also rejects the idea that emotional or affective content plays no constitutive role in forms of sociality (Chelstrom 2016). 157
Eric Chelstrom
Gurwitsch accepts that there is a plurality of possible social forms of life. Each form has its own constitutive character; in some, emotional content plays a co-constitutive role in the formation of that form of sociality; in others, emotional content plays no constitutive role. Forms of togetherness like friendships will be constituted, in part, by shared positive emotional content that is directed towards the other party to the relation. While a group might come to collectively experience negative emotions towards others, as happens in cases of xenophobic reactions groups associated with traumatic events, groups can also be constituted by or around negative emotional contents directed toward others, e.g., hate groups (see Chapter 41 in this volume). Again, Gurwitsch also argues that not all forms of sociality are constituted with emotive content, for example being co-workers in a business environment. One need not feel any particular way about one’s co-workers, or the group that is a company, particularly about those whose roles in the group do not intersect with the functional dimensions of one’s own role within the group. These positions are consistent applications of his general understanding of the functional roles constitutive of conscious life. Emotions may be thematic of our collective experiences, as in a case where our collective attention is on our shared feeling. Emotions may be part of the thematic field, where it is materially relevant to the object of our shared experience, but not itself the object of our shared experience. Or they may be shared in the margins, functioning as background dimensions of our experiences that lack immediate relevance to the thematic focus of our collective intention or action.
References Chelstrom, Eric (2016). Gurwitsch and the Role of Emotion in Collective Intentionality. In: T. Szanto, and D. Moran (Eds.). Phenomenology of Sociality: Discovering the ‘We’. London, New York: Routledge, 248–262. Colombetti, Giovanna (2011). Varieties of Pre-Reflective Self-Awareness: Foreground and Background Bodily Feelings in Emotion Experience. Inquiry 54(3), 293–313. ——— (2013). The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gilbert, Margaret (1996). Living Together. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. Grathoff, Richard (Ed.) (1989). Philosophers in Exile: The Correspondence of Alfred Schutz and Aron Gurwitsch, 1939–1959. Transl. by J. C. Evans. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Gurwitsch, Aron (1964). The Field of Consciousness. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. ——— (1974). Phenomenology and the Theory of Science. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. ——— (1979). Human Encounters in the Social World. Ed. by A. Métraux, and transl. by F. Kersten. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. ——— (1985). Marginal Consciousness. Ed. by Lester Embree. Athens: Ohio University Press. ——— (2009a). The Collected Works of Aron Gurwitsch (1901–1973), vol. I. Ed. by J. García-Gómez. Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (2009b). The Collected Works of Aron Gurwitsch (1901–1973), vol. II. Ed. by F. Kersten. Dordrecht: Springer. Walther, Gerda (1923). Zur Ontologie der sozialen Gemeinschaften. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung VI, 1–158. Zahavi, Dan, and Salice, Alessandro (2017). Phenomenology of the We: Stein, Walther, Gurwitsch. In: Julian Kiverstein (Ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of the Social Mind. London: Routledge, 515–527.
158
13 JEAN-PAUL SARTRE Anthony Hatzimoysis
1. Introduction Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–1980) wrote one of the first philosophical treatises of the 20th century to bear the word ‘emotion’ on its title. Published in 1939, the Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions culminates in an extended “Outline for a Phenomenological Theory”, whose aim is to do justice to the signification of the emotion, by revealing which aspects of reality are signified, in what way, and to what purpose, when one is emotionally engaged with the world. I shall offer an overview of the Sartrean theory of emotion, focusing mainly on the account delineated in the Sketch. My overview will draw as well on certain texts immediately preceding and following that monograph, so as to provide a more rounded picture of the Sartrean theory. Those texts, as their subtitles emphasize, are placed under the heading of phenomenology. They include three books: The Transcendence of the Ego: Outline of a Phenomenological Description (1937), The Imaginary: A Phenomenological Psychology of the Imagination (1940), and Being and Nothingness: An Essay in Phenomenological Ontology (1943). To those books, we should add a seminal article, composed around 1934: “A Fundamental Idea of Husserl’s Phenomenology: Intentionality”. Reading the Sketch in the midst of those works might help us avoid two misunderstandings. One is to think that Sartre overlooks affective phenomena which could not be easily identified as emotions. The other is to assume that what Sartre says about emotions is intended to apply to all types of affective phenomena. Another preliminary remark is due regarding the relation of the Sartrean theory to the phenomenological tradition. It might be thought that Sartre’s interest in emotion arose through his reading of some classic phenomenological texts, which include important ideas about the nature of affective experience. Given that Sartre begun drafting his views about emotion around the time of studying those texts, it is not unreasonable to hypothesize that his theory builds upon the views encountered in Husserl’s texts, elaborated with a pragmatist twist, found in Heidegger’s work; that hypothesis, though, is i naccurate. Let me recount some pertinent facts about Sartre’s reception of phenomenology.
159
Anthony Hatzimoysis
2. Sartre’s encounter with phenomenology The Sketch is a product of Sartre’s systematic work on conscious activity in its perceptual, conceptual, imaginative, and affective exemplifications. That work began to acquire its shape around 1934, when Sartre studied in the original Edmund Husserl’s published monographs, including the Logical Investigations, the Lectures on Inner Time Consciousness, the Ideas, and the Cartesian Mediations. However, Sartre’s reading of Husserl should be placed in a proper context, if we are to appreciate both Sartre’s serious debt to the Husserlian opus and the originality of Sartre’s reconception of the practice and range of phenomenological inquiry. My understanding of that issue is that while Sartre’s encounter with phenomenology was an eye-opening experience, the way he read—or, arguably, misread—Husserl’s own work, depended heavily on the intellectual concerns that occupied Sartre before that encounter, and which subsequently flourished thanks to Sartre’s unique talent of making lived experience resonate through even some of the most demanding pieces of philosophical writing (the “Introduction” of Being Nothingness is a case in point). From September 1933 to June 1934, Sartre is a visiting researcher at the Institute Français in Berlin, with a view to explore, as stated in his candidature dossier, “the relations of the psychological to the physical”. That project was to develop an issue already discussed in Sartre’s 1927 dissertation on “The Image in Psychological Life: Its Role and Nature”. Hence, when Sartre embarks on the study of Husserlian phenomenology, he is already familiar with some of the research in the analysis of consciousness, mainly from three sources. The first is the attendance to the fluid character of human experience, intuitively given to the first-person perspective, as detailed in Bergson’s writings. The second is the field of cognitive psychological experiments, especially on perceptual and imaginative processes, for which Sartre would frequently volunteer as a subject. The third is the domain of pathological phenomena, about which he read in Karl Jaspers’ Allgemeine Psychopathologie, and in which he kept a live interest during the 1930s, as testified by his regular visits, as an observer, at a major clinic in Paris, St Anne’s Psychiatric Hospital. Even more prominent than the scientific approach to psychological events, though, was Sartre’s preoccupation with the narrative understanding of human experience. That preoccupation bared two fruits. The first was a series of essays on the work of Sartre’s favorite novelists: “With the American writers, with Kaf ka and with Camus in France, the contemporary novel has found its style” (1947, 220). The theme that runs through those essays is how consciousness lives its body through one’s interaction with both the human and the inanimate world. The second fruit was the completion of Sartre’s first novel—and one of the most widely read works of 20th-century literature—whose subject matter is an affective phenomenon: Nausea (1938).
3. Affectivity in Nausea Although it used to be taken as the entry point to Sartre’s thought, Nausea does not figure large in contemporary discussions of Sartre’s philosophy. That is to an extent justified by the need to keep separate things which should not be confused, such as prose fiction and rigorous argumentation. However, when it comes to the Sartrean view of emotion, Nausea remains an invaluable source of insights into the phenomenology of affective experience. We may restate, in summary form, some of those insights as follows. As experienced by the subject, the qualities characteristic of an emotional experience are not freak mental occurrences, sprung up without reason, and which are then spread out onto 160
Jean-Paul Sartre
a neutral world; rather, during an affective experience, it is a value loaded world that comes in contact with the affected subject: Now I see; I remember better what I felt the other day on the sea-shore when I was holding that pebble. It was a sort of sweet disgust. How unpleasant it was! And it came from the pebble, I am sure of that, it passed from the pebble into my hands. Yes, that’s it, that’s exactly it: a sort of nausea in the hands. (1938, 22) The affective state is not some internal affair, cut off from the external world, since it encompasses elements of the experienced environment. Two features of surrounding objects are particularly pronounced in the affective experience recounted in the novel: colors and contours—here is a characteristic extract: The bartender is in shirt-sleeves with mauve braces (…) which can scarcely be seen against the blue shirt; they are (…) buried in the blue, but this is false modesty; in fact they won’t allow themselves to be forgotten, they annoy me with their sheep-like stubbornness, as if setting out to become purple, they had stopped somewhere on the way without giving up their pretensions (…) His blue cotton shirt stands out cheerfully against a chocolate-colored wall. That too brings on the nausea. Or rather it is the nausea. The nausea isn’t inside me: I can feel it over there on the wall, on the braces, everywhere around me. (1938, 34–35) Sartre appears to push that thought to its anti-subjectivist extreme. In a reversal of traditional priorities, the novel’s hero denies that the affective state dwells inside himself: Nausea “is one with the café, it is I whom am inside it” (1938, 35). Of particular significance for the subsequent development of Sartre’s theory of emotion is the way that the novel’s hero responds to the onset of nausea: It is out of laziness, I suppose that the world looks the same day after day. Today it seemed to want to change. And in that case anything, anything could happen (…) An absolute panic took hold of me (…) [But] as long as I could fix objects nothing would happen: I looked at as many as I could (…) my eyes went rapidly from one to the other to catch them out and stop them in the middle of their metamorphosis (…) I tried to reduce them to their everyday appearance by the power of my gaze. (1938, 114–115) It might be thought that trying to affect the constitution of things, or to halt oncoming events “by the power of one’s gaze”, is not sensible, since it is nothing sort of relying on magic. And yet, as we shall see, that involvement of magic into the constitution of an emotional experience is a crucial aspect of the phenomenological account of emotion that Sartre will draw in the Sketch. Another phenomenon explored in the novel is that of feeling something as felt by others, even when that is as unusual an intentional object as a particular stretch of time: I could feel the afternoon all through my heavy body. Not my afternoon, but theirs, the one thousand citizens of Bouville were going to live in common. At this moment, after 161
Anthony Hatzimoysis
their long copious dinner, they were getting up from the table and for them something had died. Sunday had spent its light-hearted youth. (1938, 76–77) The narration of such experiences brings to the fore the elusive character of what—in contemporary philosophical literature—goes by the name of ‘atmosphere’: I don’t like these peculiar days: the cinemas put on matinees, the school-children have the day off; there is a vague holiday feeling in the streets which never stops appealing for your attention but disappears as soon as you take any notice of it. (1938, 91) It is worth mentioning, finally, one out of the several instances of the narrative’s attention to certain aspects of cognitive phenomenology: “if only I could stop thinking, that would be something of an improvement. Thoughts are the dullest things on earth (…) They stretch out endlessly and they leave a funny taste in the mouth” (1938, 144). Nausea offers a vivid narration of affective phenomenology, in the sense of what it is like for a subject to have an affective experience. However, Sartre is also intent to articulate a phenomenology of the affective, in the sense of a systematic analysis of the structure of consciousness during an emotional episode. Let us see the main elements of that phenomenological analysis.
4. Aims and methods of phenomenological analysis The philosophy of Sartre is characterized by certain methodological and conceptual distinctions, which inform his analysis of emotions. Methodologically, Sartre highlights the importance of the perspective from which an affective phenomenon is approached, for example whether our outlook is that of an involved agent, or of a disengaged observer. Conceptually, he works with different modalities of conscious awareness, such as unreflective versus reflective, positional versus non-positional, and thetic versus non-thetic, whose distinct character helps us capture what is distinctive about the different ways in which one is affectively related to the world. Blurring the limits between different notions of consciousness, or running together methodological standpoints that are clearly different, is an error whose frequency in the history of philosophy is not coincidental. According to Sartre, that theoretical error has important practical implications, since it sustains a picture of the human being as a passive spectator of psychological events for which he cannot hold himself accountable. On the contrary, Sartre brings questions of accountability to the forefront of his phenomenological agenda, by approaching affectivity in terms of how one responds to the demands and affordances of a situation; he thus invites us to look at an emotional episode in light of a subject’s affective project. To take a rather simple case: In having a headache, “I can discover in myself an intentional affectivity directed toward my pain in order to ‘suffer’, in order to accept it with resignation, or in order to reject it, in order to value it (…) in order to escape it” (1943, 356). What constitutes the emotional aspect of each of those experiences, what the subject himself experiences as an instance of resignation, or of despair, or of pride—or, more accurately, of proud suffering—is not the ache as such, localized in the head, but how one engages with it; and that engagement is part of (and thus can only be made intelligible in light of ) the subject’s fundamental project—what he makes himself to be in and through the way he 162
Jean-Paul Sartre
responds to the givens of his situation (1943, Part I, chap. 2; Part II, chap. 1; cf. Barnes 1984; Cabestan 2004). The normative character of each person’s fundamental project is evident not only in the way the person responds emotionally to his situation, but also in the way he himself conceives of that response. The traditional conception of emotional response is as the manifestation of psychical forces that live in mind’s netherworld. Affective states supposedly lie dormant in one’s psyche, waiting for an external trigger that would let them loose, hence the grammar of passive voice (‘my anger was triggered …’, or ‘my hate was awakened …’, etc.), and the literature on the human heart as a field of untamed forces, which move independently of each other, pushing around the human subject, which is sometimes successfully, sometimes vainly, trying to resist their power; the most a subject can do is watch, record, or ruminate about the upheavals, the turbulences, and the tribulations of those states. That conception casts affectivity as an internal, self-referential occurrence, disengaged from the world: It, thus, results in a misrepresentation of lived experience, which is actually an unceasing engagement with a value-laden world (correcting that misconception is one of the primary aims of existential psychoanalysis; cf. Sartre 1943, 578–595). A phenomenological account needs to reestablish our connection to reality, by achieving two explanatory ends: (i) It ought to show how exactly in an emotional episode our consciousness finds itself out there, in a welcoming, or menacing, in a joyful, or horrible world (Sartre 1934, 44), and (ii) it should do justice to the ways we are both affected by, and effecting changes to a situation (Sartre 1939, 40–52). That double aim partly accounts both for the richness and the tensions that characterize the Sartrean approach.
5. Consciousness and the structure of the affective domain Sartre’s phenomenological account begins at the plane of affective experience before one’s reflection upon, and theorizing about, that experience takes off. Pre-reflective consciousness is the ordinary consciousness of objects in the world; reflective consciousness is the consciousness of being conscious of an object. Pre-reflective consciousness is a positional consciousness of a certain object, in the sense that consciousness posits, sets before itself, the object as a target of its intentional activity. However, when one is positionally conscious of a particular object, one is non-positionally conscious of being conscious of that object. Pre-reflective consciousness is thus non-positionally aware of itself as being directed towards its objects. For Sartre, every positional consciousness of an object is at the same time a non-positional consciousness of itself (1937, 9–16; 1943, 9–12). When we think and talk about our experience, the life of consciousness is represented under certain headings, such as ‘qualities of character’, ‘physical acts’, and ‘affective states’ (1937, 21–26). Those headings impose some order into past conscious experience, transforming continuous instances of conscious activity into isolable states. However, according to Sartre, this picture presents conscious experience the wrong way round. In reality, what comes first is the conscious activity directed at the world; the psychological state follows, as the outcome of grouping—by means of reflection—several activities under one heading. That grouping generates psychological categories that transcend consciousness, in the sense that those states appear as fixed entities with set boundaries, which share nothing of the fluid and luminous character of conscious experience. Those transcendent psychological states are then erroneously conceived as pre-existing members of one psychological whole, which embraces and governs every aspect of our conscious life. 163
Anthony Hatzimoysis
Sartre asserts that affective states make their appearance when one reflects on one’s past mental or physical activities, on one’s actions, judgments, or feelings. Take, for instance, the relation between the feeling of lust and the state of love. Feeling lust at the sight of a particular person is an experience absorbed with the attractive qualities of that individual. Experienced as a direct engagement with the world, the upheaval of a particular feeling towards someone marks the intentional connection between my consciousness and that being. The feeling of lust is a conscious activity occurring instantaneously or through a limited time span, and one that meets Sartre’s absolute principle of consciousness, i.e., to be an instant of lust and to feel as an instant of lust are one and the same thing: There is no gap within the ‘consciousness (of ) lust’ between appearing and being (1937, 22–23). The genitive construction ‘consciousness (of ) lust’ might give the impression that in the course of ordinary encounter with the world, there is a thing called ‘lust’ to which consciousness pays attention. That interpretation is misleading. Lust is not an object for consciousness; it is consciousness itself as it experiences its intentional object. The genitive participle ‘of ’ is put in brackets so as to signal that the grammatical construction purports to characterize what a particular consciousness is (namely, lust), not what the consciousness is about (its intentional object, the particular person who has arrested my sexual attention). However, if we were to move from the level of emotional encounter with the world, to the higher level of reflection upon that type of encounter, our consciousness could take in its purview the emotion-consciousness. At that level, lust or other emotional experiences would themselves become an object of conscious examination and, thus, the locution ‘consciousness of lust’ (free of internal brackets) would denote the second-order activity of (reflective) consciousness focusing upon its (pre-reflective) conscious activities. The confusion of the first-order level of the (lustful, despairing, or joyous) experience of the world, with the second-order level of the consideration of such an experience by the (reflective) subject is a major source of difficulties for the adequate analysis of affective phenomena. A feeling, according to Sartrean phenomenology, is a distinct manner in which consciousness is directed at the world, while a state is the reflective product of consciousness’ taking purview of its past activities. To the activity of feelings, we may contrast the passivity of states. Affectivity is first and foremost a consciousness, and all consciousness is directed at an object. Sartre’s account of feeling is premised on those two claims. “Feelings have special intentionalities”, they represent a way of consciousness’ transcending itself toward the world. “To hate Paul is to intend Paul as a transcendent object of consciousness” (1940, 69). Or, as Sartre put it in his very first essay on phenomenology, affective consciousnesses are ways of “discovering the world” (1934, 45).
6. Emotion, meaning, and function Feelings and psychical states form an important part of our affectivity. They have not, though, attracted as much attention, nor have they enjoyed so detailed philosophical exploration, as emotional episodes. Sartre’s account of emotions is justly celebrated for the original and ingenious way it attempts to account for the significance of emotion. Emotion for Sartre is not an optional clog of mental machinery that can be added to, or subtracted from the traditional list of psychological faculties; nor is emotion an aggregate of various parts—physiological, conceptual, perceptual, volitional—each of which has a fixed meaning, identifiable independently from what goes on in the rest of the agent’s conscious engagement with reality. Rather, emotion for Sartre is the synthetic totality of a human being in a situation: “it is that human reality itself, realizing itself in the form of ‘emotion’” (1939, 12). 164
Jean-Paul Sartre
In the Sketch, Sartre presents emotion as the conscious transformation, by means of one’s body, of a situation: What changes is how the world is experienced by the subject and, consequently, how the subject responds to a thus transformed world (1939, 34–61). The world is understood as a totality of phenomena linked in a network of mutual references. The way in which each phenomenon relates to others defines the type of world encountered by the subject. We should, thus, distinguish between at least two worlds: the world of action and the world of emotion (1939, 74–78). In the former, we experience reality as a combination of demands and affordances; the link between them is itself perceived as governed by deterministic processes between causes and effects. The instrumental world of action is captured in the pragmatic intuition of the situation that makes certain moves available for the subject, while denying him others. The emotional apprehension of the world, on the other hand, hooks on to those qualities or aspects that carry affective meaning for the agent. The joyful, hateful, or bleak world, far from being identical to the word of action, is clearly distinguished from the instrumental world. What appears to bring forth the emotional stance towards the world is that the situation presents the agent with demands that he is unable to meet—and his emotional response (be it joyous, angry, or sad) consists in a pattern of cognitive and physiological changes which reduce the urgency, lower the intensity, or neutralize the force of those demands. The Sketch purports to analyze affectivity in terms of the functions served by our emotive reactions to a situation: “We cannot understand an emotion unless we look for its signification. And this, by its nature, is of a functional order. We are therefore led to speak of the finality of emotions” (1939, 28). Faced with a situation that makes strong or unbearable demands, the agent responds not in order to effect changes in the world (that would be a practical response), but with a view to alter the evaluative parameters of the situation, so that the demands raised by the situation are diffused: We can now conceive what an emotion is. It is a transformation of the world. When the paths before us become too difficult, or when we cannot see our away, we can no longer put up with such an exacting and difficult world. All ways are barred and nevertheless we must act. So then we try to change the world; that is, to live it as though the relations between things and their potentialities were not governed by deterministic processes but by magic (…) Emotional behaviour seeks by itself, and without modifying the structure of the object, to confer another quality upon it, a lesser existence or a lesser presence. (1939, 39–41) At the center of this transformation is the living body—or what in Being and Nothingness Sartre calls “the body as being-for-itself ” (1943, 330)—“during emotion, it is the body which, directed by consciousness, changes its relationship with the world so that the world should change its qualities” (1939, 41). Our bodies are the “instruments of incantation” (1939, 47), and that is why “to believe in magical behavior”—as opposed to merely feigning an emotion—“one must be physically upset” (1939, 50). Emotional consciousness lives the new world it has thereby constituted, “lives it directly, commits itself to it, and suffers from the qualities that the concomitant behavior has outlined” (1939, 51). Within that emotionally transformed world, the qualities that make up one’s social environment are not recognized as one’s projections, but as genuine features of the situation, which exercise a pull on the agent: “the man who is angry sees on the face of his opponent the objective quality of asking for a punch on the nose” (1943, 248). 165
Anthony Hatzimoysis
7. The emotional transformation of the world Since the changes effected in an emotional episode do not alter the material constitution of things, nor do they concern a prudential choice of some alternative course of action, which would result in different practical outcomes, Sartre calls the transformation brought about by emotion ‘magical’. Relatedly, in the final section of the Sketch, emotion is characterized as a fall: “an abrupt fall of consciousness into the magic” (1939, 60). The exact role of magic in Sartre’s theory has recently been at the center of an intense scholarly debate. In spelling out his conception of emotional world as a world of magic, Sartre appears to offer two different, and at a first reading, equally compelling, accounts of how a subject may experience affectively a situation. On the one account, that is prevalent in most of the Sketch, it is the emotive subject which transforms the world through the transformation of his non-reflective consciousness of the world; an emotion is thus understood as a process of constitution of a magic world, by making use of one’s body as instrument of incantation (1939, 47). On the other account, during an emotional episode, the subject apprehends the world as already magical: “the magic and the meaning of the emotions came from the world and not from ourselves (…) magic [is experienced as] as a real quality of the world (…)” (1939, 58). The difference between the two accounts is crucial, as it concerns how and why the relations between objects are changed. According to the former account, “it is we who constitute the magic of the world to replace a deterministic activity which cannot be realized”; according to the latter account, “the world itself is unrealizable and reveals itself suddenly as a magical environment” (1939, 57). Whether, and if so, how exactly the two accounts can be rendered compatible is a matter of some controversy (Hatzimoysis (2014a) makes a case for the coherence of Sartre’s different remarks, whose consistency is astutely put into question by Richmond’s (2010) seminal discussion of magic in the Sartrean corpus; cf. Richmond (2014). Hartmann (2016) and Elpidorou (2016) purport to resolve that debate, by offering alternative detailed readings of Sartre’s conception of emotion; cf. Vanello (2019) and Chapter 34 in this volume). It might facilitate the analysis of that issue to draw certain distinctions, which might lead to an approach that is perhaps more complicated, yet also more faithful to the phenomenology of affective experience. One distinction concerns the emotions upon which each of the two Sartrean accounts applies: Hence, the first account (where magic is effected by bodily consciousness) might be taken to concern only cases of fear, joy, and sadness, while the second account (where magic is encountered as being already in the world) may apply to cases of horror and wonder. That division among emotion types sounds reasonable, and enjoys textual support, as indicated by Sartre’s claim that the “there are two forms of emotion” (1939, 57, emphasis added). However, it is not obvious that it also enjoys phenomenological support—at least, it is not clear that a subject would himself distinguish his pre-reflective experiences of fear, horror, panic, or terror, in anything other than intensity of feeling, or the amount and imminence of perceived threat (see Hatzimoysis 2014b for related psychological research). Another distinction that deserves our attention is between two aspects of the Sartrean theory, that Sartre himself tends to present at one breath: the transformation of the world, on the one hand, and the arising of emotion as a distinct way of resolving a problem faced by the subject, on the other. It might be argued, for instance, that, in contradistinction to most emotions, horror and wonder consist in experiences of a magic world; yet, no attempted solution of a practical problem takes place. However, although that proposal sounds independently plausible, it seems to be in tension with Sartre’s explicit insistence on the finality 166
Jean-Paul Sartre
of emotions. If there are affective phenomena, which, according to that proposal, serve no end, then it is hard to see how their occurrence should be accounted for in the functional terms singled out as the hallmark of emotion (1939, 28). Perhaps the above difficulties, encountered in the interpretation of the Sketch, are indicative of the character of Sartre’s classic text as a work in progress. They also point to Sartre’s gradual transition from delineating a phenomenological psychology of emotions (1939, 62), toward articulating a full-blown phenomenological ontology of the human way of being (1943, 18–23). Hence, the questions raised through the study of Sartre’s highly original take on affective phenomena may help the reader appreciate the significance of the remark, placed near the beginning of the Sketch, about the enormity of the task involved in articulating a systematic theory about the facts that we encounter in our research into emotions: “they, in their essential structure, are reactions of man to the world: they therefore presuppose man and the world, and cannot take on their true meaning unless the two notions have first been elucidated” (1939, 7–8).
References Barnes, Hazel E. (1984). Sartre on the Emotions. The Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 15(1), 71–85. Cabestan, Philippe (2004). What is it to Move Oneself Emotionally? Emotion and Affectivity According to Jean-Paul Sartre. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 3(1), 81–96. Elpidorou, Andreas (2016). Horror, Fear, and the Sartrean Accounts of Emotions. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 54(2), 209–225. Hartmann, Martin (2016). A Comedy We Believe In: A Further Look at Sartre’s Theory of Emotions. European Journal of Philosophy 25(1), 144–172. Hatzimoysis, Anthony (2014a). Consistency in the Sartrean Analysis of Emotion. Analysis 74(1), 81–83. ——— (2014b). Passive Fear. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13(4), 613–623. Richmond, Sarah (2010). Magic in Sartre’s Early Philosophy. In: J. Webber (Ed.). Reading Sartre: On Phenomenology and Existentialism. London, New York: Routledge, 22–44. ——— (2014). Inconsistency in Sartre’s Analysis of Emotion. Analysis 74(4), 612–615. Sartre, Jean-Paul (2010[1934]). A Fundamental Idea of Husserl’s Phenomenology: Intentionality. In: J.-P. Sartre. Critical Essays (Situations I). Transl. by J. Fell. London: Seagull, 40–46. [Orig.: Une Idée fondamentale de la phénoménologie de Husserl: L’intentionnalité. In: Situations I. Paris: Gallimard, 1947, 31–34.] ——— (2004[1937]). The Transcendence of the Ego. Transl. by A. Brown. London, New York: Routledge. [Orig.: La transcendence de l’ego. In: Recherches Philosophiques (1937)]. ——— (2000[1938]). Nausea. Transl. by R. Baldick. London: Penguin. [Orig.: La Nausée. Paris: Gallimard 1938.] ——— (2004[1939]). Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. Transl. by P. Mariet. London: Routledge. [Orig.: Esquisse d’une théorie des émotions. Paris: Hermann 1939.] ——— (2004[1940]). The Imaginary: a phenomenological psychology of the imagination. Transl. by J.Webber. London, New York: Routledge. [Orig.: L’Imaginaire: psychologie phénoménologique de l’imagination. Paris: Gallimard 1940.] ——— (2003[1943]). Being and Nothingness. Transl. by H. Barnes. London, New York: Routledge. [Orig.: L’être et le néant: Essai d’ontologie phénoménologique. Édition corrigée par A. Elkaïm-Sartre. Paris: Gallimard 1976]. ——— (2010[1947]). Critical Essays. Transl. by C. Turner. London: Seagull Books. [Orig.: Situations: Critiques Littéraires, vol. 1. Paris: Gallimard 1947]. Vanello, Daniel (2019). Sartre on the Emotions. In: M. Eshleman, C. Mui, and C. Perrin (Eds.). The Sartrean Mind. London, New York: Routledge.
167
14 EMMANUEL LEVINAS Sophie Loidolt
1. The role of emotions and affectivity in the work of Emmanuel Levinas Many central terms of Levinas’ philosophy have a clear emotive connotation, such as desire, enjoyment, indolence, horror, love/eros, sensibility, proximity, and obsession. But are these emotions? And does this make Levinas a “phenomenologist of emotions”? The answer must be “no” if emotion is understood in the classical phenomenological sense: That is, either as a certain class of acts or intentional directedness that reveals certain properties and values of a given, or as a mood that is a mode of Dasein’s existential understanding—of Being, of itself, of the world, or of others. It must also be “no” if this would lead to subsuming Levinas’ ethics under the dualism of rationalist and sentimentalist ethics. Levinas neither attributes conventional cognitive nor hermeneutic functions to emotions, nor does he advocate that it is rather “moral feelings” than reason that make us morally responsive and responsible beings. Instead, Levinas is concerned with showing that the orders of (cognitive as well as emotive) intentionality, visibility, and intelligibility build on and answer to a primary affective exposedness. He describes this exposedness as a radical passivity of “sensibility” that is ruptured and imbued by an ethical imperative. In this sense, Levinas generally conceives subjectivity in affective terms. And in this sense, the answer to the question if he plays an important role in the phenomenology of emotions can be “yes.” I will use the terms “affectivity” and “emotion” often interchangeably in this chapter; Levinas prefers to talk about the former and only seldomly uses the latter.1 There is certainly a conceptual differentiation to be made between “emotion” and “affectivity”: Affectivity describes the overall disposition of being able to be approached and touched. It is being susceptible, receptive, sensitive, and open to touch. Emotions arise as specific feelings and modes of being of the subject on the basis and background of affectivity. For Levinas, subjectivity is essentially affectivity, which, as we shall see, means that subjectivity is essentially “for the other.” Furthermore, Levinas is eager to point out that affectivity is anchored in the lived body and conditioned by its “sensibility” (cf. Tengelyi 2014, 259). As the latter term indicates, the sensible “makes sense” before or beneath intentional consciousness. As such, affectivity is essentially “sensible,” and the sense it makes, as it were, is “being for the other” before any mode of thinking or understanding can take place. 168
Emmanuel Levinas
Let us first take a look on Levinas’ break with traditional philosophy and its movement of understanding as a return to the self. Against the paradigmatic Greek figure of Ulysses, finally returning to his home after years of war and adventure, Levinas mobilizes the Judaic tradition in the story of Abraham. Abraham follows God’s call to a foreign land never to return to his home again. Levinas reads both stories as tales of the structure of subjectivity and ontology. While Hegel philosophically epitomizes the themes of “Odysee” and “homecoming” in the Phenomenology of the Spirit, and Heidegger finalizes the immanence of ontology in Being and Time, Levinas takes an Abrahamic path into philosophy—and that means: setting out to leave the self and escaping the suffocating return to the self (cf. Levinas 2003). By following the call of the other, Levinas looks for the fissures and ruptures in experience that open up the self to transcendence. This happens up to the point where these ruptures have always already pervaded “home” with the primacy of the other, beyond ontologically conceivable structures. This is how Levinas conceives of ethics as “first philosophy,” transcending the translucent structures of Being, in my world- and self-relation. Hence, the primacy of the other is conceptualized from the outset as contesting the Western philosophical primacy of the theoretical, of understanding, of light and visibility, and of distance. An alterity that is understood loses its otherness. It remains only “different” within a system of totality. But what Levinas is after is what moved Abraham without knowing. Affectivity, being approached in darkness, without being able to distance and see, and without being able to swallow and digest, are thus the states where he looks, maybe surprisingly, for traces of transcendence—a transcendence that never ceases to inscribe itself in our most basic sensibility. This perspective makes Levinas a radical and original philosopher of sensibility and affectivity, one who grants utmost importance to the dimension in which the encounter with alterity actually happens. And this happening has always already taken place without ever being able to be assimilated into an analytic language—a paradoxical trait for a philosophical method, which is reflected in the very style of Levinas’ writing. The central point for understanding the role and phenomenology of emotions and affectivity in Levinas’ work is thus: (1) First, to see how he subverts Husserl’s concept of intentional consciousness, as well as Heidegger’s tool-handling and project-orientated Being-in-the-world. While Dasein “understands” something even in the peaks of anxiety, namely itself and always only itself 2 (e.g., in the call of conscience), Levinas’ subjectivity is literally torn apart and pointing beyond its self-relatedness. To put it in Husserlian terms: Instead of an act of putting in question, this is an experience of being put in question, which, according to Levinas (1986, 353), cannot be conceived in the framework of an intentional correlation—not even that of a nonobjectifying emotion and a value. Levinas makes a fundamental phenomenological claim here: This sort of affectivity, of proximity in darkness, beyond intentionality, which he calls “the social relation,” for Levinas, is “experience preeminently” (Levinas 1969, 109), and thus a “truer” or more original form of experiencing than any intentional experience, be it objectifying or non-objectifying. Affectivity and emotionality, at least in the sense in that they are relevant for Levinas’ work, must be conceived along these lines. (2) Second, none of what has been said is meant to imply that Levinas would position this approach simply against or in competition with an ethics of practical reason (cf. Craig 2010, 104).3 Rather, Levinas would argue that the rigor of practical reason, as we see it in Kant, can only be drawn from the social relation. Universality in itself means nothing and commands nothing. This is why the moral law and reason can only be understood as an answer to a deeper, unintelligible withdrawing law that has cut through my affectivity with its ethical imperative. Like Kant’s “fact of practical reason,” this is not an empirical fact to 169
Sophie Loidolt
be examined. Instead, it describes the arrival and installment of the normative dimension in the subject, namely through its affectivity (cf. Crowell 2015, 579). Thus, Levinas connects sensibility/affectivity and reason, but reverses the order. He neither construes a hierarchical and commanding relation between “irrational inclination” and “rational activity” (like Kant or Plato), nor a continuity between the two, where passive affectivity is taken up and governed in active position-taking (like in Aristotle or Husserl), nor a transition from a “dark” to a “clarified existential understanding,” where the normative measurement is always and only my authenticity (Heidegger and Sartre). Levinas’ alternative to all these approaches is to conceive reason, theory, and the intellect in the service of the “higher truth” of “proximity.” All these capacities are needed in the wake of the “third,” i.e. alterity in the plural, which equals the call for justice. Reason, therefore, has its genesis in the call for justice and in the rigor by which subjectivity is imperatively addressed and affectively obsessed by the other (cf. Levinas 1991, 157–162). (3) Third, as has become already clear, emotionality and affectivity are deeply tied to sensibility and the lived body. For Levinas, it would not make sense to differentiate between “bodily” and “spiritual feelings,” and even less would he demand to “purify,” for example, sensuous feelings of love toward more “personal” ones in order to climb to a higher order of values (as Scheler, for example). The “spiritual” is right there in the most sensuous. It is there in the sense that the erotic experience is enjoyment but at the same time transcends my enjoyment and my need. What makes it erotic is this ambivalence that is heightened by the naked presence, but withdrawing otherness of the other: That which caressing hands and lips passionately seek, but can never find. Desire, a term so metaphysically loaded in Levinas, a hunger that lives of its hunger (Levinas 1969, 179), is not at all unrelated to the erotic encounter. But the ethical relevance of affectivity is rooted even deeper. As we will see below, subjectivity rises in enjoyment, in a basic sensibility. And only thanks to this condition, which makes the subject feel itself and consummate its nourishment, can it be a separate, selfenjoying self that can be ruptured by transcendence: The bread I tear from my mouth is the bread I need and enjoy myself. In the following sections, I will give a rough portrait of subjectivity, described in ethical terms in Levinas, focusing on the role that affectivity and particular emotions play in the genesis of the self/other relation.
2. The rise and rupture of the self in affectivity and emotion 2.1 I enjoy, I am From his early work onward, Levinas develops what one could call a dialectical genesis of subjectivity. This genesis proposes a relation between Being and Beings4 that is not dominated by Dasein’s understanding of Being but rather by its “ownness” ( Jemeinigkeit), its “thrownness” (Geworfenheit), and the burden of being (Lastcharakter)—all Heideggerian terms from Being and Time that Levinas appropriates, rethinks, and thereby accentuates differently. To find myself “thrown” into existence means, in the Levinasian reformulation, that I experience myself as having been “established” within an anonymous Being, which has become my own. A Being that I—since I exist—have to be. Having to be is having taken a position, a stand within Being. Levinas calls this “hypostasis,” an equivalent for subjectivity. The pre-state of anonymous Being, within which this positioning has taken (its) place, glimpses up in experiences of horror, insomnia, and indolence. Levinas calls this pre-state the “there is” (il y a). 170
Emmanuel Levinas
Instead of making anxiety the central existential feeling in which Dasein encounters its own finitude and death like in Heidegger (see Chapter 34 in this volume), Levinas stresses the horror of the indeterminate, the anonymous noise and murmur of the il y a, of pure Being equaling senselessness. In this context, we find one of the most significant and most explicit passages on emotion in Levinas’ work. It speaks of the disintegration of subjectivity, which, for Levinas, is a central trait of emotion: The antithesis of position is not the freedom of a subject suspended in the air, but the destruction of the subject, the disintegration of the hypostasis. It is announced in emotion. Emotion is what overwhelms. Physiological psychology, which started with emotional shock and presented the emotions in general as a disruption of equilibrium, seems to us here to have grasped the true nature of affectivity, despite its rudimentary language, more faithfully than the phenomenological analyses, which after all keep something of the character of comprehension, and consequently of apprehension, in emotions (Heidegger), and speak of emotional experience and of objects clothed with new properties (Husserl, Scheler). Emotion puts into question not the existence, but the subjectivity of the subject; it prevents the subject from gathering itself up, reacting, being someone. What is positive in the subject sinks away into a nowhere. Emotion is a way of holding on while losing one’s base. All emotion is fundamentally vertigo, that vertigo one feels insinuating itself, that finding oneself over a void. The world of forms opens like a bottomless abyss. The cosmos breaks up and chaos gapes open—the abyss, the absence of place, the there is. (Levinas 1978, 68) “Holding on while losing one’s base”—the ontologically overthrowing role of emotion is evident here, and it will be even further extended to a force that transcends the ontological realm itself. It is not a subject that has an emotion but an emotion that has a subject. It even threatens to destroy or to dissolve the subjectivity of the subject. In this sense, Levinas’ concept of emotion is fundamentally conceived through the lens of passion,5 and of something that transcends the subject. Yet, subjectivity itself is also characterized as a basic affective mode, namely one of immanence. Levinas conceptualizes the origin of subjectivity not in intentional consciousness but in a sensual world-relation, which is, at the same time, a self-relation that coincides with the opening of the “inner space” and “interiority” of consciousness. According to Levinas, the basic form of how we encounter the world is not the “in-order-to” but the world as nourishment. The mode of “living of …” is hence more fundamental than intending and tool-handling. “Living of …” is experienced as enjoyment. And this constitutes the basic structure of subjectivity: The self-sufficiency of enjoying measures the egoism or the ipseity of the Ego and the same. Enjoyment is a withdrawal into oneself, an involution. What is termed an affective state does not have the dull monotony of a state, but is a vibrant exaltation in which dawns the self. (Levinas 1969, 118) It is clear from this passage that “living of…” and “enjoyment” for Levinas have an ontological and ethical relevance which surpasses any biological or psychological, even psychoanalytical approaches to these phenomena. “Subjectivity originates in the independence and 171
Sophie Loidolt
sovereignty of enjoyment” (Levinas 1969, 114). This self-constitution in enjoyment is the “egoism of life,” which is questioned in and by the face of the other. On the other hand, enjoyment is separation from the il y a, from an anonymous totality. It is the birth of an interiority, which, in its enjoyment, is the paradigmatic structure of all forms of return to the self. It is pure affective self-feeling as self-relation. In Totality and Infinity and earlier works (cf. Levinas 1978, 1987, 2003), Levinas sees this primary movement of “involution” as the condition for the metaphysical relation with the other. The relation with the other as an inter-locutor presupposes a separate being, one that can be addressed. This fundamental separation from Being (through the beings we consume) happens in enjoyment. So far, we have encountered two modes of affectivity: one which the early Levinas calls “emotion”—a term he does not continue to use—which dissolves and questions the subjectivity of the subject. The other is a mode which founds and grounds this very subjectivity. “Life is affectivity and sentiment; to live is to enjoy life. To despair of life makes sense only originally because life is happiness” (Levinas 1969, 115). This double-structure within the concept of affectivity is reflected in the structure of the self–other relation. This relation needs the immanence of a self that holds on while losing its base. And both “holding on” and “losing one’s base” happen in “vibrant exaltation,” which is far from being a “state” the subject is “in.” Rather, it must be described as “vertigo” that gives and questions the very subjectivity of the subject.
2.2 Pure future: eros and caress We also find such an ambivalence of “holding on while losing one’s base” in Levinas’ “phenomenology of eros.” Levinas construes this complex piece of his theory around the heterosexual couple and the future dimension of fecundity: “Sexuality, paternity, and death introduce a duality into existence, a duality that concerns the very existing of each subject. Existing itself becomes double. The Eleatic notion of being is overcome” (Levinas 1987, 92). I cannot dwell upon this complex issue nor on the problems regarding the gender issue, that Levinas introduces at this point. My focus, instead, is on the affective state in erotic desire which is enjoyment, “vibrant exaltation,” but essentially reaches beyond it. Therefore, even if this is surely over-simplified, I take the affective structure as essentially the same for whoever encounters the other erotically.6 Erotic desire expresses itself in caress. Certainly, a caress is not an emotion. But it is also hard to imagine it not being permeated by various emotions and emotional states: love, voluptuosity, passion, compassion “for the passivity, the suffering, the evanescence of the tender” (Levinas 1969, 259), shame, and shamelessness. Hence, the caress is carried and sustained by an emotionality and affectivity which is specific to it. Levinas denies that caressing would be something we do in the sense of an act (Levinas 1969, 259). The caress “does” nothing and it does not aim at anything. It rather loses itself in its search for nothing, in “no man’s land” (Levinas 1969, 256), becoming more and more an experience of passivity and, again, of vertigo, where the “I can” continuously ceases. In a famous passage from Time and the Other, Levinas describes the caress as a “mode of the subject’s being, where the subject, who is in contact with another, goes beyond this contact” (Levinas 1987, 89). Contact as sensation is part of the world of light. But what is caressed is not touched, properly speaking. It is not the softness or warmth of the hand given in contact that the caress seeks. The seeking of the caress constitutes its essence by the fact that the caress does not know what it seeks. This “not knowing,” this fundamental disorder, is 172
Emmanuel Levinas
the essential. It is like a game with something slipping away, a game absolutely without project or plan, not with what can become ours or us, but with something other, always other, always inaccessible, and always still to come (à venir). The caress is the anticipation of this pure future (avenir), without content. It is made up of this increase of hunger, of ever richer promises, opening new perspectives onto the ungraspable. It feeds on countless hungers.7 (Levinas 1987, 89) What constantly withdraws in caressing becomes pure future, a future that is not mine and not my projection. Being and Time’s carefully elaborated ekstatic time-structure is transcended here toward the time of the other, happening beyond “Being” and my time. Strictly speaking, this is a time-dimension I cannot anticipate. It is not one of my “possibilities.” Still, I encounter it—as withdrawal, enigma, as “less than nothing” (Levinas 1969, 258). This is why Levinas calls it “pure future,” an anticipation of something I cannot anticipate. The continuous decline of the “I can” announces the ethical relation. But it is not yet taken up in the erotic encounter. According to Levinas, eros takes place “beyond the face,” and in ambivalence. Yet, it is a personal encounter, and as such “presupposes the face” (Levinas 1969, 262). In this sense, eros discovers something that refuses it, and becomes “profanation” (Levinas 1969, 260) which is always near to obscenity, shame, and laughter. An exorbitant indiscretion. And, again, destabilizing for the subjectivity of the subject: “An amorphous non-I sweeps away the I into an absolute future where it escapes itself and loses its position as a subject” (Levinas 1969, 259). Like in the vertigo of emotion before anonymous Being, we have an affective state here that tears the subject into a “night,” extending alongside the night of the “there is” (Levinas 1969, 258). But the erotic encounter leaves subjectivity intact, even if Being is transcended here toward a future beyond the self: “Love is not a possibility, it is not due to our initiative, is without reason. It invades and wounds us and nevertheless the I survives in it” (Levinas 1987, 88f.).
2.3 The other in me: proximity and obsession Finally, the ethical relation in itself has no more erotic components that would lead into ambivalence. In Totality and Infinity, Levinas speaks of the “face-to-face” as an asymmetrical encounter with infinity. Along the lines of his critique of the primacy of the theoretical, Levinas makes clear that what he means by “the face” is not “given” in intuition or vision (Levinas 1969, 187). Hence, the face of the other—at least that which is ethically relevant about it and decisive for Levinas’ use of the term—is not graspable in an intentional relation. Instead, the face speaks. This dimension of language, of being spoken at and appealed to, equals experiencing the dimension of the imperative or normative. And again, this experience, the “work of language” itself, is affectively loaded: “Discourse is (…) the experience of something absolutely foreign, a pure ‘knowledge’ or ‘experience,’ a traumatism of astonishment” (Levinas 1969, 73). Subjectivity is once more, and now in an ultimate way, destabilized, put in question. But this time it is called to respond, and that means to be and to speak as this first person, the “only” first person. However, these new demands do not imply a shift to the grown-up, masculine imperative to “finally take responsibility” and “pull oneself together.” What happens is rather an even deepened encounter with one’s absolute passivity in responding. It amounts more to losing oneself to the act of responding than to pulling oneself together. This response is never to “return home” in order to understand, but extends into infinity. This is 173
Sophie Loidolt
what Levinas calls “infinite responsibility” for the other, a responsibility I do not decide for or take over, but a responsibility that has taken over me. The sense of the imperative comes with the experience of a “height,” of an asymmetrical, traumatizing directness, a “nudity,” by which the face addresses me and commands (cf. Crowell 2015, 578). As meaning in and by itself, not dependent on a context of “understanding,” the nudity of the face appears not as a privation but “as an always positive value” (Levinas 1969, 74). At the same time, I experience the other as foreign to the world, and this foreignness becomes a destitution. The nudity of the face flips and extends into “the nakedness of the body that is cold and that is ashamed of itself ” (Levinas 1969, 75). Here, the sensible and affective are deeply intertwined with the rise of the imperative and normative dimension: To recognize the Other is to recognize a hunger. To recognize the Other is to give. But it is to give to the master, to the lord, to him whom one approaches as ‘You’ [‘Vous’] in a dimension of height. (Levinas 1969, 75) In his later work, Otherwise than Being, Levinas’ language becomes even stronger in terms of interrelating the affective and the sensible with the ethical imperative. In fact, it becomes painful and violent (cf. Tengelyi 2009, 411). This is because Levinas now focuses more on the interruption of the self that has always already taken place. Levinas conceives this in terms of a diachrony I cannot remember, but that is sensibly felt, affectively given as a non-givenness. Alterity is thereby not conceptualized as an “exteriority” anymore, but becomes inscribed in an incarnated subjectivity, constituting a fundamental category of its experience. Subjectivity is “for the other” before ever being a “self,” and this is primarily shown by analyzing the intrinsic relation between “sensibility” and “proximity.” In these analyses, subjectivity is described as a “hostage,” as “obsessed” by the other, “exposed like a bleeding wound” (Levinas 1991, 161): “It is to be like a stranger, hunted down even in one’s home, contested in one’s identity and one’s very property (…). It is always to empty oneself anew of oneself, to absolve oneself, like in a hemophiliac’s hemorrhage” (Levinas 1991, 92). It would be wrong to speak of “emotions” here. However, “incarnation” and its affectivity are so crucial for describing subjectivity in ethical terms that the systematic relevance of how to conceive this affectivity can hardly be underestimated. Levinas does not change his position in this respect. He still criticizes that the “content called affective in sensation” is conceived as a “modality of manifestation” in phenomenology, “a light ‘of another color’ than that which fills the theoretical intentionality, but still a light” (Levinas 1991, 66): The affective remains an information: about oneself, about values (as in Max Scheler), about a disposition, an understanding of essence (as in the Stimmung of Heidegger), an ontology, whatever be the modalities and structures of existence that overflow all that the intellectualist tradition understood by thought, but which are nonetheless packed into a logos of being. (Levinas 1991, 66) Against this dominant conception, Levinas holds on to another order, an “outside-of-order” we experience in affectivity: “Here the blow of affection makes an impact, traumatically, in a past more profound than all I can reassemble by memory (…)” (Levinas 1991, 88). Affectivity as an always past “affection” by the other overwhelms us with transcendence, within and beyond ourselves. And what we feel in this encounter, or rather, this state of 174
Emmanuel Levinas
being overwhelmed, is certainly not a “natural” feeling. Levinas reminds us that his concept of “obsession” goes way beyond the conventional feelings of “benevolence” and altruism: If obsession is suffering and contrarity, it is that the altruism of subjectivity-hostage is not a tendency, is not a natural benevolence, as in the moral philosophies of feeling. It is against nature, non-voluntary, inseparable from the possible persecution to which no consent is thinkable, anarchic. (Levinas 1991, 197)
3. Conclusion We have seen that Levinas repeatedly uses affective vocabulary in order to establish his new approach to “ethics as first philosophy.” As he states in an interview with Philippe Nemo, his goal is not to develop a normative theory, but to “describe subjectivity in ethical terms” (Levinas 1985, 95). To this end, affectivity and emotionality are so central that one could even claim that Levinas describes subjectivity in affective terms. However, this is not just a shift of perspective within the ontology of the subject. Levinas explicitly wants to go beyond ontology. For this enterprise, the reconceptualization of affectivity/emotionality is crucial. Instead of conceiving it as “another mode of light” or understanding, Levinas makes it the point of entrance for transcendence, for the “otherwise than Being.” Emotion for Levinas is essentially “vertigo,” passivity, and passion. It interrupts a subjectivity that dwells in its affective mode of enjoyment, either by exposing it to the horrors of the il y a, to the future of the other in eros and fecundity, or by calling it to its infinite responsibility, inscribed in its basic sensibility.
Notes
175
Sophie Loidolt lasting, exclusive, shared, and does not fill a pre-existent lack. Among the “passions”, Lingis counts “vehement wonder, lust, rage, courage, or terror, jealousy, grief ” (Lingis 2017, 6). These distinctions, however, as helpful as they are, cannot be mapped directly on Levinas, who remains rather blurry in his respective terminology. 6 I am aware that this is already a strong interpretation. For an instructive collection of discussions on this topic, see Chanter (2001). 7 By contrast, the peak of orgasm is a return to the self. It is not the fulfillment of the encounter with the other, but a different fulfillment that leaves me alone in my immanence of enjoyment. This, as it were, is the Levinasian version of the proverb “post coitum omne animal triste.”
References Bergo, Bettina (2011a). The Face in Levinas. Angelaki 16(1), 17–39. ——— (2011b). Emmanuel Levinas. In N. E. Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/levinas/ Chanter, Tina (Ed.) (2001). Feminist Interpretations of Emmanuel Levinas. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. Craig, Megan (2010). Levinas and James: Toward a Pragmatic Phenomenology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Crowell, Steven G. (2015). Why is Ethics First Philosophy? Levinas in Phenomenological Context. European Journal of Philosophy 23(3), 564–588. Levinas, Emmanuel (1969). Totality and Infinity. Transl. by A. Lingis. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. ——— (1978). Existence and Existents. Transl. by A. Lingis. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. ——— (1986). The Trace of the Other. Transl. by A. Lingis. In M. C. Taylor (Ed.). Deconstruction in Context. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 345–359. ——— (1985). Ethics and Infinity. Conversations with Philippe Nemo. Transl. by R. A. Cohen. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. ——— (1987). Time and the Other. Transl. by R. A. Cohen. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. ——— (1991). Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence. Transl. by A. Lingis. The Hague: Nijhoff. ——— (2003). On Escape. De l’évasion. Transl. by B. Bergo. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Lingis, Alphonso (2017). Aconcagua. In: R. C. Wheeler (Ed.). Passion in Philosophy. Essays in Honor of Alphonso Lingis. Lanham: Lexington, 3–16. Tallon, Andrew (1995). Nonintentional Affectivity, Affective Intentionality, and the Ethical in Levinass Philosophy. In: A. Peperzak (Ed.). Ethics as First Philosophy. The Significance of Emmanuel Levinas for Philosophy, Literature and Religion. New York, London: Routledge. Tengelyi, László (2009). Self hood, Passivity and Affectivity in Henry and Levinas. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17(3), 401–414. Tengelyi, László (2014). Die Rolle der persönlichen Freiheit in der Antwort auf fremde Ansprüche. In: I. Römer (Ed.). Affektivität und Ethik bei Kant und in der Phänomenologie. Berlin: de Gruyter, 253–268. White, Richard (2012). Levinas, the Philosophy of Suffering, and the Ethics of Compassion. The Heythorp Journal 53(1), 111–123.
176
15 HANNAH ARENDT Judith Mohrmann
Arendt’s approach to emotions is novel not so much for her phenomenology of emotions, but for the phenomenology of the connection between politics and emotions: Instead of establishing and maintaining a taxonomy of (political) emotions, Arendt distinguishes systematically between emotions in the political sphere and emotions in the private sphere. While she highly values certain emotions in the private sphere, she argues that the same emotions are bound to wreak havoc in the political sphere. Thus, Arendt’s critique of emotions is a critique in the original sense of the Greek word krinein: to distinguish. She refrains from evaluating emotions by either praising them for their humanistic potential or condemning them as condescending or irrational gestures. (To be sure, for Arendt, emotions generally are irrational, but that is not her primary concern.) Instead, she distinguishes between emotions that occur in the political domain and those that occur in the private sphere, judging them accordingly. Compassion is her prime example: In Arendt’s view, it is pivotal whether compassion occurs in the private realm, where she values it highly, or in the political realm, where she considers it entirely destructive. Herein lies Arendt’s originality. To Arendt, it makes no sense to condemn emotions per se, as Nietzsche does. Neither does it make sense to label certain emotions as “political” and others as “apolitical”, like Nussbaum (Nussbaum 2015) does. Instead, she explores the interconnectedness of emotions and the political in On Revolution (Arendt 1963): If emotions appear in the political field, this affects the emotion and the political alike. Her analysis, however, rests upon very specific and arguably idiosyncratic preconceptions of emotions that ought to be revised.1 This article explores Arendt’s critique of political emotions, taking compassion in the French Revolution as its vantage point.
1. Compassion in the French Revolution Initially, Arendt differentiates between compassion and pity. For her, compassion entails empathy with others, the ability to feel someone else’s pain like one’s own (see Chapter 37 in this volume). Typically, this emotion arises in situations in which one person is confronted with the suffering of another and acts instantaneously to alleviate this pain: For example, one person is hurt and someone else tries to help. Structurally, this situation is bound to
177
Judith Mohrmann
two individuals interacting with one another: One particular person is confronted with the pain of another individual, and this configuration excludes third parties, bystanders, and the public. To Arendt, genuine compassion has astounding qualities, as the empathy it involves allows one person to ease someone else’s pain by feeling it like their own. Yet, when compassion manifests itself in the political sphere, it becomes corrupted: It turns into a sentimentalized version of itself that Arendt calls “pity”. It is not only the emotion that is corrupted, however, for the political side is affected as well. According to Arendt’s critical assessment, if and when compassion enters the political realm, both are transformed into deprived versions of themselves: The political realm is destabilized to the point of its eventual demise, and the emotion is perverted to kitsch. Most salient to Arendt’s theory of the connection between politics and emotions is her account of the role compassion played in the French Revolution. While in Kant’s perception, the French Revolution successfully established a legacy of political freedom, Arendt makes the opposite argument, claiming that the French Revolution failed in its attempt to create a new political order based on democracy and freedom (cf. Mohrmann 2015). Hence, in her view, the narrative about and the analysis of the French Revolution ought to be revised. Arendt maintains that systematic rather than contingent reasons caused the French Revolution to fail—its revolutionary leaders chose an inadequate strategy for political legitimization. Arendt considers the American Revolution the one successful democratic revolution, because in her view, emotions played little to no role. In the absence of pity for those in dire need, the American founding fathers focused upon establishing protodemocratic structures, such as town hall meetings. The town hall meetings of the American Revolution provided a place for debate, where people deliberated and found a consensus. In France, however, the French revolutionaries were confronted with pauperized masses, whose situation was too miserable to allow for the somewhat tedious democratic processes. Therefore, the French revolutionaries tried to circumvent establishing these foundations of democracy and instead substituted democratic processes for compassionate identification as a political tool. Emotions and the role they played in the French Revolution were thus paramount to its failure. The relationship between politics and emotions is crucial in the situation of the revolution, Arendt explains, because it is closely intertwined with the signature question of democratic revolutions: How to act democratically if the mechanisms of democratic legitimization are, by definition, not yet in place? For Arendt, the new beginning for a potential democracy after a seizure of power is always coupled with the problem of legitimization: The revolutionary leaders claim to act in the name of the people, albeit without their democratic consent. The French revolutionaries faced a dual conundrum: First, they had to legitimize their action democratically, even more so as they strikingly resembled their predecessors: “The magic of compassion was that it opened the heart of the sufferer to the sufferings of others, whereby it established and confirmed the ‘natural’ bond between men which only the rich had lost” (Arendt 1963, 76). Second, they faced a starving and impoverished Parisian population. Due to the dire needs of the Parisian people, forming town hall meetings was not an option, since supplying food was the most urgent task. Compassion provided an allegedly adequate solution to both of these problems. It allowed for identification with those in whose name the revolutionaries claimed to act—le peuple—when at the same time no formal and procedural way of generating debates and consensus could be established. As a substitute for consent, the revolutionary leaders felt the emotions of those in whose name they claimed to act.
178
Hannah Arendt
2. The underlying assumptions about politics and emotions in Arendt For Arendt, substituting compassion for the process of debate and deliberation is by no means an innocent change of parameters. It proves fatal for the political, as it marks a t ransformation of the framework that defines political legitimization. In her view, this is intertwined with the Rousseauian notion of the volonté générale, a concept Arendt deems disastrous. She sees the compassionate imitation of an apparent will of the people as a tool for executing the volonté générale. According to Rousseau’s volonté générale, the general will of the people is the governing principle of a democratic society. The volonté générale differs from the Roman notion of an established consent, which represents each and every one in their arguments and thus establishes common ground. In this notion of consent, Arendt argues, the plurality of individual opinions remains intact, and so the volonté générale indicates a shift: The general will, unlike an established consensus, is indivisible and erases the traces of individuals and their different interests and opinions. It was of greater relevance that the very word ‘consent,’ with its overtones of deliberate choice and considered opinion, was replaced by the word ‘will’, which essentially excludes all processes of exchange of opinions and an eventual agreement between them. The will, if it is to function at all, must indeed be one and indivisible. (Arendt 1963, 71) The image of one general will is modeled upon the image of one homogenous individual with such a will: The outstanding quality of this popular will as volonté générale was its unanimity, and when Robespierre constantly referred to ‘public opinion,’ he meant by it the unanimity of the general will; he did not think of an opinion upon which many publicly were in agreement. (Arendt 1963, 71) In Arendt’s understanding, this will is homogenous and so runs counter to her central concept of plurality as a constitutive element of politics. Furthermore, it is volatile and unstable: Just as one person can shift her will, so the masses shift theirs. “Rousseau took his metaphor of a general will seriously and literally enough to conceive of the nation as a body driven by one will, like an individual, which can also change direction at any time without losing its identity” (Arendt 1963, 71). That the volonté générale struck a chord among the revolutionaries was a result of the picture the Parisian people presented and embodied, Arendt argues. The masses unified by impoverishment and the “unison cry for bread” moved through the streets of Paris in a way that created the image of one person and one body with a single will. Hence, the mere sight of the people of Paris in the streets made the Rousseauian notion of one people governed by a single volonté générale more plausible. As the need for bread and shelter was too urgent and prevented proto-democratic structures from flourishing, compassionate identification with the will of the people seemed to offer a possibility to act in their name. Yet, the problem is this: Arendt considers the volonté générale an antidemocratic idea in itself. It promotes the idea of one formed will, which bears no traces of the discursive
179
Judith Mohrmann
process of deliberating and shaping consent. This consent always remains informed by the heterogeneity of those who participated in the process. The idea of a homogenous will as the foundation for the political is antidemocratic for Arendt, because it is unifying and leaves no room for plurality. Here, it is crucial to note that underlying these assumptions is a very particular, Arendtian notion of the political, for which plurality is constitutive. To her, the political is the realm of persuading, debating, deliberating, and reaching consent. Only for this specific Arendtian notion of the political is the conflict between the political and emotions that Arendt stages possible. To Arendt, the volonté générale is an antidemocratic concept. If the revolutionaries’ actions link this concept with pity, the general will is acted out in an antidemocratic manner. Volonté générale and pity are fatally intertwined: The volonté générale suggests a homogenous unified will, and pity, with its immediate tendency to action, creates the impression that this will requires only immediate execution. Democracy, as Arendt argues, needs the checks of the publicly reached consensus. If the revolutionaries want to monitor whether their actions are democratic, they need an external mode of correction like the debates and decisions of the town hall meetings in the American Revolution. Yet, politically, the lack of an external yardstick results in an escalation to terror and paranoia: The yardstick for political action is not a mutual process of decision-making that leads to certain decisions, providing checks and balances for the action of the revolutionary leaders. Instead, the only yardstick for political action that serves the interest of the Parisian population is if one feels correctly, if compassionate identification conforms to what the masses feel and want. Thus, the yardstick for democratic processes is the revolutionary’s own emotional landscape, disconnected from public interaction. According to Arendt, this internalization causes the revolutionaries to feel mistrust and paranoia: This mistrust concerns their own doings first and foremost, because the question as to what they did was right and democratic is subject to their own inner turmoil of ever-shifting emotions. Without any external means of measurement, however, there is no possibility of proving if one’s opinion about one’s own actions is correct. Since to Arendt, the individual’s inner world is perpetually shifting and unstable, it cannot serve as an instrument of evaluating one’s own deeds. Exclusive trust in one’s own inner landscape necessarily engenders distrust of oneself, as the inner self is unreliable in its instability. This distrust of oneself is then projected into the outside world, heightening paranoia amidst the revolutionaries and unleashing terror in their own ranks. Arendt argues that the revolutionaries are additionally driven by a very particular yearning marked by the zeitgeist: the need to cultivate a large and differentiated scope of emotions. This zeitgeist, partly represented by the advent of the literary novel, provoked an entirely new cultivation of the self and its inner motifs and emotions. The revolutionaries sought any outside occasion that would enable them to unleash their inner potential of moods and feeling. This sentimentalized version of self-stimulation became increasingly incompatible with susceptibility for real suffering: Since the days of the French Revolution, it has been the boundlessness of their sentiments that made revolutionaries so curiously insensitive to reality in general and to the reality of persons in particular, whom they felt no compunctions in sacrificing to their ‘principles’, or to the course of history, or to the cause of revolution as such. (Arendt 1963, 85) This process fueled a dynamic in which the revolutionaries’ actions were accompanied by increasing paranoia, unleashing a spiral of terror within the revolutionaries’ own ranks.
180
Hannah Arendt
In addition, Arendt argues, compassion almost always tends to glorify the suffering of those who are pitied. As a result, pity is unwilling to erase this suffering, because by erasing suffering, pity (and compassion) would undermine their own base of existence. This sounds like an odd argument at first, as though compassion was a rational agent, unwilling to eradicate the base of its existence for the sake of self-interest. Hence, the status of this argument seems to be somewhat unclear. At second glance, however, Arendt’s claim can be reconstructed as follows: If the revolutionaries used compassion/pity as the (rhetorical or actual) base for their legitimization, they would lose the principle of their legitimization once misery and poverty ceased to exist. Thus, if the revolutionaries succeeded in abolishing poverty—in this way executing the will of the people—they would simultaneously abolish their base of legitimization. Arendt’s analysis and conclusion of the fatal connection between emotions and politics rest on specific premises about the political and about emotions. Since Arendt is a political philosopher, her premises about the political are much clearer than her premises about emotions. In terms of emotions, her description unfolds from quotidian observations and is congruent with familiar (folk-)psychological notions about emotions. But closer inspection demonstrates that this phenomenology of emotion is deeply rooted in intellectual history. The phenomenological observation is overtly or covertly modeled upon powerful ideas of Descartes and, more importantly and in Arendt’s case surprisingly, of Rousseau. For Arendt, compassion means to feel somebody else’s feelings and emotions like one’s own. In this regard, what is at stake is not so much a distinct emotion but rather a metaemotion: empathy towards the emotions of another person.2 Hence, we may understand Arendt’s account of compassion and the relationship it entertains with the political as representative of her account of the relationship between emotions and the political in general— Arendt herself deduces more general claims about emotions from her analysis of compassion (Arendt 1963, 90). Three elements are paramount to Arendt’s analysis of compassion in its relation to politics: Compassion is (a) linked to direct action rather than to speech, (b) boundless, and (c) particular and unable to make abstractions. These characteristics render compassion incompatible with the realm of the political. (a) In Arendt’s view, compassion entails feeling the pain of another person like one’s own. In doing so, compassion strives to offer an immediate remedy to the sufferer. It shows itself rather in gestures and deeds, Arendt argues, than in speech. It is an immediate reaction and is not mediated by speech; it is a mute interaction. “Passion and compassion are not speechless, but their language consists in gestures and expressions of countenance rather than in words” (Arendt 1963, 81). To Arendt, its immediate character is incompatible with verbal communication and more akin to direct action and ultimately to violence. Compassion has an urgent and pressing quality, in contrast to the political, which, as Arendt puts it, relies heavily on the tedious and laborious practices of persuasion und negotiation: As a rule, it is not compassion which sets out to change worldly conditions in order to ease human suffering, but if it does, it will shun the drawn-out wearisome processes of persuasion, negotiation, and compromise, which are the processes of law and politics, and lend its voice to the suffering itself, which must claim for swift and direct action, that is, for action with the means of violence. (Arendt 1963, 82)
181
Judith Mohrmann
This hostility toward speech and communication and its kinship with violence make compassion incompatible with politics. In Arendt’s view, violence and politics are opposites: Violence is not a political means, but rather destroys the political. This is what makes compassion dangerous for the political, even if it appears in its authentic and uncorrupted form. (b) To Arendt, emotions are also boundless, as she considers them a sweeping force. Since they are not mediated, they cannot be handled as political forces but are unruly, cannot be reckoned with, and are as such hostile to plurality, to Arendt one of the cornerstones of the political: The direction of the American Revolution remained committed to the foundation of freedom and the establishment of lasting institutions, and to those who acted in this direction nothing was permitted that would have been outside the range of civil law. The direction of the French Revolution was deflected almost from its beginning from this course of foundation through the immediacy of suffering; it was determined by the exigencies of liberation not from tyranny but from necessity, and it was actuated by the limitless immensity of both the people’s misery and the pity this misery inspired. The lawlessness of the “all is permitted” sprang here still from the sentiments of the heart whose very boundlessness helped in the unleashing of a stream of boundless violence. (Arendt 1963, 87) The interest of the people is constitutive to the realm of the political in Arendt’s view. She understands “interest” etymologically: The condition for interest between people is the inter-esse, the space between them. This is no mere pun. As Arendt also argues in The Origins of Totalitarianism (1976), it is one of the trademarks of totalitarian societies that they abolish every space between people, refusing all plurality. “Because compassion abolishes the distance, the worldly space between men where political matters, the whole realm of human affairs are located, it remains, politically speaking, irrelevant and without consequence” (Arendt 1963, 81). Emotions in their boundlessness have the very same quality of erasing the space between people, according to Arendt. Thus, they are counterproductive to this in-between, which is the precondition for any interaction and mediation of interests. (c) Third, Arendt argues, emotions can only address particular individuals and are unable to abstract or to generalize. One can only feel compassion towards the suffering of one particular person, since it means to feel someone else’s pain like one’s own. Facing “mankind as a whole”, an abstract and general notion, this concrete and particular quality vanishes. To feel compassionate towards the people of Paris or the suffering of humanity would mean to lose the compassionate identification with one other person. In doing so, compassion is stripped of its defining characteristics, and it is this generalization and abstraction from one particular person and their situation that turns compassion into something else: pity. “Pity”, to Arendt, is the sentimentalized version of compassion, something that occurs if one rids compassion of its constitutive particular nature and deploys it for large, abstract groups of people: For compassion, to be striken with the suffering of someone else as though it were contagious, and pity, to be sorry without being touched in the flesh, are not only the same, they may not even be related. Compassion, by its very nature, cannot be touched off by
182
Hannah Arendt
the sufferings of a whole class or a people, or, least of all Mankind as a whole. It cannot reach out farther than what is suffered by one person and still remain what it is supposed to be, co-suffering. Its strength hinges on the strength of passion itself, which, in contrast to reason, can comprehend only the particular, but has no notion of the general and no capacity for generalization. (Arendt 1963, 80) This means that if emotions enter the realm of the political, it is detrimental not only to the political but also to compassion. If and when compassion enters the political sphere, it is bound to become corrupted. For in Arendt’s definition, compassion is bound to the interaction between two people and thus to the private realm. If it is applied to a larger group of people, it needs to generalize individual suffering, and it must also abstract from the suffering of the individual. Thus, it is no longer the suffering of one particular person that is at stake. This process takes place independently of the actors’ intentions. Even if the revolutionaries of Paris were truly driven by compassion, Arendt argues, what they felt towards the Parisians as a large group could not manifest itself as compassion but only as pity. Confronted with a large number of people, the other ceases to be the object of compassion and turns into the trigger for a different kind of affection—the affection of the self. To Arendt, this movement satisfies the desire for nuanced stimulations of the soul: Emotions are used in their literal sense of e-movere, to move. In order to feel internally stimulated, the revolutionaries created self-stimulation, using the suffering of the other as pure means. Arendt claims that emotions in the political realm ought to be replaced by principles, and in the case of pity, the principle is solidarity (see Chapter 45 in this volume). “For solidarity, because it partakes of reason, and hence of generality, is able to comprehend a multitude conceptually, not only the multitude of a class or a nation or a people, but eventually all mankind” (Arendt 1963, 84). In the case of compassion, the emotion ought to be replaced by solidarity, because solidarity is a principle and as such part and parcel of reason. Reason, unlike emotions, can abstract and generalize, and so it can relate to large groups or even humanity as such, Arendt argues. Although plausible at first sight, this argument seems to rest on wrong assumptions about the nature of emotions. Most theories of emotions suggest not that reason and emotions are opposites, but to the contrary, that they are closely intertwined. To give just one prominent example, Martha Nussbaum (2003) has argued that emotions are evaluative and contain judgments in an emotive form. Thus, very little today points to the fact that Arendt’s suggested dichotomy between reason and emotion can be maintained. Whether or not emotions concern someone else’s suffering or serve as a means of self-stimulation, to Arendt, it is crucial that they are, in some sense or another, “inner” entities. The talk of emotions as “inner” entities, however, seems somewhat dubious and unconvincing—and points to central weaknesses in Arendt’s argument. Her conception of emotions as inner entities is hard to maintain, even if it is only used metaphorically, and certainly not without alternatives, as I shall explain later. She states that “they certainly are located in the human heart” (Arendt 1963, 91) and as a result are not subject to interpersonal verification: The heart, moreover (…) keeps its resources alive through a constant struggle that goes on in its darkness and because of its darkness. When we say that nobody but God can see (and, perhaps, can bear to see) the nakedness of a human heart. “Nobody” includes
183
Judith Mohrmann
one’s own self—if only because our sense of unequivocal reality is so bound up with the presence of others that we can never be sure of anything that only we ourselves know and no one else. (Arendt 1963, 92) Only I myself—not other people—can determine what my emotions are or know what I feel, Arendt claims. But since to Arendt, only things that are visible to the public can persist and be subject to verification, emotions, which are only subject to introspection, are, by definition, unverifiable. Throughout her work, Arendt stresses the idea of emotions as inner, solipsistic states, to which no conditions of truth can be applied. In a letter to Mary McCarthy about a lover who seemed to have a rather liberal notion of truth, she writes, “What belongs to this charm is that their lies usually only concern only facts which will come out and show them to be liars no matter what they do. (Whereas if one lies about his ‘feelings’, he is really safe, who can find out?)” (Arendt and McCarthy 1995, 49). If emotions are inner, private entities, which are accessed by the individual’s introspection, it is impossible to apply truth conditions to them, regardless of whether or not the individual is sincere or insincere. Their internality is another factor that makes emotions and politics incompatible in Arendt’s view: Politics must be illuminated by the public and its discourse, whereas emotions need the shelter of privacy. With their immediate tendency to action, their boundlessness, their muteness, and their private quality, emotions are antidemocratic. In the French Revolution, Arendt argues, they helped bring to life the antidemocratic qualities of the volonté générale in an antidemocratic manner. It is in this twofold way that emotions were fatal to the political in the French Revolution: They possess antidemocratic qualities in and of themselves and help execute the antidemocratic idea of the volonté générale. Arendt derives her critique from, arguably loosely, phenomenological observations of how people react when they are driven by emotions. This phenomenology might seem persuasive at first glance, as it resonates with how ordinary folk-psychologically theorizing thinks about emotions. Yet, Arendt’s phenomenology of emotion remains heavily influenced by Rousseau and Descartes, and this seems, from the perspective of contemporary conceptualizations of emotions, and political emotions in particular (see Chapter 41 in this volume), a serious shortcoming of her theory. Arendt ignores philosophical traditions, which paint a more complex picture of emotion. For example, the entire tradition of aesthetic emotions, starting with Aristotle (2006), is left out in her considerations. Including these strains of philosophical thinking would have allowed her to draw a more complex picture, in which emotions are, by no means, “inner” unmediated entities provoking direct action—quite the contrary. In this tradition, aesthetic theory endorses the claim that emotions do not entail a tendency to action, but are highly context-sensitive, can be judged as adequate or inadequate, and are intertwined with reason rather than being opposed to it. More importantly, they are, by no means, ‘inner’ entities subject to personal introspection only. On the contrary, they can only be conceived of as depending on social norms and interaction (cf. Mohrmann 2015). Although Arendt’s observations and descriptions of emotions remain within the broader perspective of Rousseau and Descartes, she never makes this underlying theoretical framework explicit and, consequently, debatable. Descartes, however, develops the notions of internality and infallibility of emotions in The Passions of the Soul (Descartes 1649), in an attempt to find the foundations of knowledge: I can be wrong about the object of my fear, Descartes elaborates, but I cannot be wrong about the fear I felt myself. Rousseau then followed this trajectory not in order to epistemologically ground knowledge but so as to 184
Hannah Arendt
establish the foundations of a less morally corrupt society. In the Second Discourse (Rousseau 1755), and in Émile, or On Education (Rousseau 1762), Rousseau presents emotions as one prime natural resource for re-establishing human bonds that he deems have been corrupted in aristocratic society. There, he suggests that emotions are unmediated, inner, and uncorrupted entities, impulses that need to be pursued. In his view, emotions are natural reactions to pain or injustice. An individual is confronted either with injustice inflicted upon him, like Émile, his apprentice in the book of the same name, or with the pain of a fellow citizen, as described in the Second Discourse. As natural, inner, and unmediated entities, emotions prove ideal to Rousseau as an antidote to aristocracy’s overly mannered and conventional style. Although Arendt virtually despised most of Rousseau’s theory in particular, she ultimately remains heavily influenced by both the Cartesian and Rousseauian conceptions of emotions.
3. Conclusion In The Human Condition (Arendt 1998), Arendt draws her famous distinction between the private, the social, and the political. This appears like an exact differentiation, in which each realm can be separated neatly from the next and trouble arises especially when the social starts to permeate the sphere of the political. Arendt scholars have repeatedly criticized this distinction (e.g., Benhabib 2003), as it seems that she is depoliticizing a very important field, that of the social, which ought not to be depoliticized. Her discussion of pity and compassion in On Revolution sheds a different light on this matter, however. The revolutionaries are not accused because they blur the lines between the social and the political realms. Arendt argues that the political requires certain preliminary conditions for the decision-making process. In conditions of extreme poverty, the urge to find food and shelter will—necessarily—be more pressing than establishing discursive and thus proto-democratic structures. Her argument is not ontological regarding the essence of the political and the social, but it concerns Arendt’s theory of democracy. If proto-democratic structures like town hall meetings must be established in order to legitimize revolutionary action, the “social question”—that is, the supply of the population with food and shelter—is “pre-political”. Thus, the relative absence of poverty is the precondition for proto-democratic institutions to flourish. If matters of food and shelter are too urgent, “the political” as a realm that depends on discursive structures cannot be founded. Consequently, strategies of legitimization that bear resemblance to proto-democratic structures, such as the compassionate identification deployed by the revolutionaries, seemingly circumvent political stabilization and lead to the escalation of terror and paranoia described above. Arendt is highly original in establishing a phenomenology of emotions resting on the distinction between the private and the political. She aims to explain why it only makes sense to talk about emotions in the political if one presumes that this differs from an analysis of emotions in the private sphere (otherwise, the intrinsic structures of the political remain ignored and very little is being said about politics and emotions). Arendt forges a theory of the mutually destructive relationship between emotions and the political that does not rest on a taxonomy of (political) emotions but instead determines why emotions must clash structurally with the political. Their defining qualities are mutually exclusive to Arendt. The elaboration of this trajectory hinges on her particular notion of the political, and more surprisingly, on a Rousseauian and to a lesser extent Cartesian notion of what emotions are. In Arendt’s definition, emotions are private, inner entities, and since she sees the private and the political as oppositions, emotions must be bound to the private realm. If the private 185
Judith Mohrmann
and the political are opposites and emotions are private entities, however, the apolitical quality of emotions is not explained but rather presupposed in the analysis itself. Although Arendt sets out to structurally define why politics and emotions are incompatible, her argument seems indeed to rest on a petitio principii: The private, apolitical nature of emotions is nothing that is “discovered” in phenomenological analysis of the political but is presumed instead. Broadening the horizon of her discussion of emotions would have allowed Arendt to offer an account of emotions and politics in which both can be conceived as constitutive for one another; Kant, to cite a classic whom she knew by heart, offers just such a theory in The Conflict of the Faculties (Kant 1992) in terms of enthusiasm and the French Revolution.
Notes 1 For an alternative conceptualization of the relation between politics and emotions, see Chapter 41 in this volume. 2 This is an idiosyncratic conceptualization of empathy by Arendt and quite different from current phenomenological conceptions of empathy. See Chapter 37 in this volume for a broader view on the phenomenology of empathy.
References Arendt, Hannah (1963). On Revolution. London: Faber and Faber. ——— (1976). The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt. ——— (1998). The Human Condition. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Arendt, Hannah, and McCarthy, Mary (1995). Between Friends. The Correspondence of Hannah Arendt and Mary McCarthy 1949–1975. San Diego, New York, London: Harcourt. Aristotle (2006). Poetics. Indianapolis, Cambridge: Hackett. Benhabib, Seyla (2003). The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield. Descartes, René (1989[1649]). The Passions of the Soul. Transl. by S. H. Voss. Indianapolis, Cambridge: Hackett. Kant, Immanuel (1992). The Conflict of the Faculties. Lincoln, London: Nebraska University Press. Mohrmann, Judith (2015). Affekt und Revolution. Politisches Handeln nach Arendt und Kant. Frankfurt, New York: Campus. Nussbaum, Martha C. (2003). Upheavals of Thought. The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2015). Political Emotions. Why Love Matters for Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1992[1755]). Discourse on the Origin of Inequality. Transl. by D. E. Cress. Indianapolis, Cambridge: Hackett. ——— (1979[1762]). Émile, or On Education. Transl. by A. Bloom. New York: Basic Books. Further reading Chiba, Shin (1995). Hannah Arendt on Love and the Political Love, Friendship, and Citizenship. The Review of Politics 57(3), 505–535. Hall, Cheryl (2005). The Trouble with Passion: Political Theory beyond the Reign of Reason. London, New York: Routledge. Kingston, Rebecca (2011). Public Passion: Rethinking the Grounds for Political Justice. Montreal: McGill Press. Nelson, Deborah (2004). Suffering and Thinking: The Scandal of Tone in Eichmann in Jerusalem. In: L. Berlant (Ed.). Compassion. The Culture and Politics of an Emotion. London, New York: Routledge, 219–244. Tevenar, Gudrun von (2014). Invisibility in Arendt’s Public Space. In: M. Ure and M. Frost (Eds.). The Politics of Compassion. London, New York: Routledge, 37–50.
186
16 SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR Maren Wehrle
What, if anything, could Simone de Beauvoir contribute to a philosophy of emotions? At first glance, emotions don’t play an important role in her philosophy. She never explicitly formulated the role of emotions in either her existentialist ethics or feminist thought; neither can one find detailed descriptions of specific emotions or a systematic evaluation of the role of affectivity in general. Nonetheless, emotions in terms of affectivity and feelings are at the heart of her existential thinking. Without a fundamental bodily sensitivity, no engagement with the world or others would be possible; without passion, joy and fear, as primary feelings of the human condition, there would be neither freedom nor violence and domination. From the start of her philosophical and novelist work until her last writings, Simone de Beauvoir was concerned with existential problems like singularity, absolute freedom and responsibility. These are the problems that accompany the temptation of bad faith, and tensions in relation to the other. Although her thought developed out of the intellectual environment of Paris before, during and after World War II, along with Sartre, Merleau-Ponty and Levinas,1 as well as influenced by Husserl and Heidegger (Kruks 1990; Heinämaa 2003; Bauer 2006; Gothlin 2006; Langer 2006; McWeeny 2017; Wilkerson 2017),2 de Beauvoir transforms their concepts to develop a genuine existential ethics based on the ambiguity of the human condition.3 As Sartre, Simone Weil and Iris Murdoch, de Beauvoir was a philosopher and philosophical novelist.4 In her autobiography, de Beauvoir emphasizes how her novels and her autobiography contribute to her ethical analysis of the paradoxies of human existence and to a philosophico-political account of women’s condition. This includes ethical philosophical discussions of human finitude, the self–other relation, repetition and the relation between individuals and universals (de Beauvoir 1960, 625–629; 1963, 92–98, 367). Especially, the novels She Came to Stay (1984)5 and the Mandarins (1955) focus on topics of emotions and motivations that are central to her philosophical thinking. Although she did not build a system in which a theory of emotions would have its proper place, she reflected on emotions philosophically in the form of fiction and autobiography. The most central emotions that de Beauvoir discusses thereby are: (a) Love in its many forms (She Came to Stay, Mandarins), (b) envy (She Came), (c) courage and fear, and (d) friendship, loyalty and disappointment. Her first novel She came to Stay (1984), about a ‘love triangle’ between the characters Pierre, Xavière and Françoise, begins with Hegel’s statement that ‘each consciousness seeks 187
Maren Wehrle
the death of each other’ and ends with Françoise’s murder of Pierre. But instead of confirming the mere theoretical antagonism, where each consciousness wants to objectify or even kill the other to claim its freedom, de Beauvoir dives deeper into the complex intertwinement of the metaphysical with the concrete: the stickiness of interrelations and emotional involvements between subjects. In the subsequent essay Pyrrhus and Cinéas (2004), de Beauvoir explicitly addresses the philosophical and political questions of differentiating between ethically correct or incorrect realizations of singular freedoms and projects. In this context, she shows that individual freedom is necessarily related to the freedom of others. Her reflections on the emotion of love in Mandarins (1955) further elaborate on and illuminate crucial philosophical problems like emotive motivation, repetition and variation of love, and the contextuality or situatedness of emotional experiences in general (cf. Heinämaa 2017). The issues raised in her early novels return again in her non-novelist philosophical writings: the ambiguity of our existence; the responsibilities and limits of freedom; our singularity and intertwinement with others; and how all of these give rise to feelings of passion expressed in joy, and fear, as well as violence. De Beauvoir further explored the existential problems posed by ethical situations in more systematic and theoretical terms in her Ethics of Ambiguity (1976[1947]). Her thinking is then applied to concrete situations in The Second Sex (2011a[1949]) and “Must we burn Sade” (2011b[1953])? By focusing on these latter three works here, I will carve out the role of affectivity and emotions in her existential ethics. I claim that her approach can be interpreted as an affective or responsive ethics, in which freedom and vulnerability, mind and body are necessarily intertwined.
1. The ambiguity of freedom: passion, joy and fear ‘Ambiguity’ refers to the fact that we are objects and subjects alike, and that we are a part of this world of which we are conscious.6 Although we assert ourselves as an “internality against which no external power can take hold”, we simultaneously experience ourselves as a “thing crushed by the dark weight of things” (de Beauvoir 1976, 7). The existential condition breaks through at any opportunity, “the truth of life and death, of my solitude and my bond with the world, of my freedom and my servitude, of the insignificance and the sovereign importance of each man and all men” (ibid., 9). In this regard, humans can never be a thing as such, nor a pure subject, but are free and bounded, infinite and finite, subjects and objects, i.e., find themselves situated within these paradoxical poles of being and have the existential task to deal with their essential ambiguity (see also Kierkegaard 1843). In other words, we are both subjective agents that freely project themselves into the world, a world that appears there for us, as well as material, visible and vulnerable objects within that world. In this ambiguous situation, humans must will and perform their freedom. Freedom is made manifest by the constant possibility of failure. To embrace one’s freedom, then, one must face their ambiguity. This demands the assumption of oneself not as a fixed existence, rather a “lack of being” (cf. Sartre 1956), to elicit a space for being to unfold. The ambiguity of life is not something we think or reflect on, but primarily something we feel—and are anxious about. According to de Beauvoir, existentialism is the only philosophical approach that tries to face and accept this ambiguity. In fact, the ambiguity of life is the precondition for real ethics. This involves granting the concept of ‘evil’ a genuine role in one’s ethical considerations and accepting the fact that there are real risks (both of danger and failures), but also moments of joy and success: “Nothing is decided in advance, and it is because man has something to lose and because he can lose that he can also win” (de Beauvoir 1976, 34). 188
Simone de Beauvoir
Such a lack or indefiniteness of existence is what makes the disclosing of the world and transcending of the subject onto this world possible. For de Beauvoir, it is this movement that lies at the heart of every human existence and is accompanied with a certain feeling, the joy of existing. The primal condition of existence is thus a “free generosity” that expresses itself in vitality, curiosity, activeness and creativity.7 Joy is the primordial mood of existing: “in this movement even the most outcast sometimes feel the joy of existence. They then manifest existence as happiness and the world as a source of joy” (ibid., 41). As such, not only the physical, but also the lived body becomes central. We experience joy because of the affective and responsive connection we have with the world and others: de Beauvoir describes the body that feels and its sensitivity as a presence, “which is attentive to the world and to itself ” (ibid., 42). In this regard, the body is not only determined by physiological conditions, but also the condition and expression of our affective relation with the world. It can be thus an object of sympathy or repulsion. In this context, de Beauvoir introduces Husserl’s concept of intentionality, which she transforms into a two-staged affective intentionality.8 Joy is what accompanies the first stage of intentionality, which is defined as an operative mode of disclosure or discovering (of the meaning) of the world. The second stage comprises the explicit act of fixating or creating meaning whereby one posits oneself as an author of this meaning. The latter can be accompanied with the dual mood of hope or domination. Depending on which mood prevails, this can ground a movement of liberation (from a constraining or oppressive situation) or an act of exploitation (of the world and others), respectively. According to de Beauvoir, the human condition is thus characterized by a passion for meaning or a drive towards being, a passion that can never be completely fulfilled, because we are unable to disclose the absolute meaning of the world or become its autonomous authors. Therefore, this drive “always misses its goal” (ibid.).9 The passion thus remains dissatisfied and comes with an experience of contingency, finitude and lack of control. The joy of existence is thus necessarily interwoven with or even overshadowed by an existential anxiety. As de Beauvoir describes, this fear typically manifests itself at adolescence, upon leaving the protected universe and playful disclosing of the child’s world. Adults are forced to make choices and assume responsibility. They are not only confronted with the contingency, but also the irreversibility of their actions. The joy of disclosing and transcending is no longer easily playful as it is now always paired with fear and the risk of potential failure.
2. Responsive intersubjectivity: passion and the appeal to others Not everyone is able to face this contingency and responsibility, and thus fulfill one’s freedom. De Beauvoir characterizes various modes of escaping or misinterpreting this freedom, which, in turn, results in a lack of passion or, better, indifference. Such indifference is the cause of all evil. De Beauvoir describes five characteristic types that all withdraw or escape their freedom in different ways; the first three are the sub-man, the serious man and the nihilist. All of them are characterized by a fundamental apathy, indifference or lack of vitality, motivated by the fundamental fear of existence. They restrain from the original movement of disclosing the world and numb, in turn, their original sensitivity and openness to it. The one with the lowest vitality is termed the sub-man: “in the face of risks and tensions, the sub-man rejects the passion, which is the human condition” (ibid.). In a sense, he does not will his freedom. But because there is no real escape, neither from freedom nor from passion manifest, such a rejection of existence is “still another way of existing” (ibid., 43). 189
Maren Wehrle
Therefore, he masks his anxiety and indifference and takes refuge in the ready-made values of the social world, easily follows leaders or succumbs to ideologies. But behind this mask, there lures his indifference. The negation of himself shows in his boredom and lack of meaningful interactions with the world (ibid., 45). Because the sub-man cannot escape his freedom and needs to find a way to engage it, his attitude toward the world manifests as one of rejection and so, he becomes the serious man. The serious man also denies himself, but through the focus on an external object or social value in which he attempts to lose himself. In order to negate his subjectivity, he subordinates his freedom under a “great” cause or esteemed value that is reified in some form of objective being like nature, God, state, humanity or spirit. The appropriation of these values, in turn, confers a “stable” value on himself. The serious man is thus guilty of a denial of freedom; he refuses to recognize “that he is freely establishing the value of the end he sets up” (ibid., 48). He thus escapes his personal responsibility and instead acts without question as a member of a herd or gives himself over to something supposedly higher than himself. The sub-man and the serious man deny their freedom and thus lack passion. De Beauvoir stresses that such indifference is, in fact, dangerous and eventually lead to evil in that they systematically neglect responsibility for one’s own role in value constitution (cf. Heinämaa 2017). Indeed, with their attitude, one can easily become a tyrant: They ignore the desires and values of concrete subjects in favor of an absolute object or goal, thus instigating a kind of fanaticism. If the serious man fails to achieve this object or goal, his disappointment leads to nihilism: effectively, the desire to be nothing. But, this is a paradoxical desire as it belies itself: Even the will to negation has to “manifest itself as a presence at the very moment that it displays itself ” (de Beauvoir 1976, 54). Although the attitude of the nihilist expresses the truth of the ambiguity of the existence—that is indeed a lack, nothingness, as well as radical finitude— he fails to live his ambiguity. Instead of defining its lack as an opportunity for becoming, such death is not integrated into life, but appears the only truth of life. The second class of types, who betray the human condition, are the adventurer and the (wrong-headed) passionate. At first glance, the adventurer seems to affirm his freedom, lives through passion and enjoys the incomplete character of all disclosure and meaning. If existentialism would be solipsistic, the adventurer would be its perfect hero. But, for de Beauvoir, existentialism is always an intersubjective endeavor—freedom can never be embraced or performed alone, but with and among others. The adventurer, who wants to be free without willing the freedom of others, is thus not able to genuinely realize his freedom. Each of our actions is intertwined and ultimately depends on others; therefore, we must declare ourselves to others. To will one’s freedom actually means give oneself over to an open future, and that, in turn, necessarily inheres to an intertwinement with and appeal to fellow men. The adventurer is not able to fully realize his freedom, because it has no content. In a sense, his passion is empty: He does not take the desires and needs of others into account; rather, he uses others as means for his own leisure and adventure. De Beauvoir leaves no doubt that such an “external availability” is not freedom. Quite the contrary, the adventurer is also dangerous insofar as, in order to keep his privileges, he either has to submit to influential masters or make himself supreme master or dictator (ibid., 62). In this manner, he is dependent on others: not only with regard to his privileges but also because he needs the recognition of others: “His fault is believing that one can do something for oneself without others and even against them” (ibid., 63). The same fault holds true for the passionate man, although he stands as the antithesis of the adventurer. While the adventurer fails in affirming his existential condition, i.e., the content 190
Simone de Beauvoir
of his freedom, the passionate man fails to fulfill freedom’s need for subjectivity. Instead, the latter sets the object of his passion as absolute. Such an inauthentic or manic passion is not generous or open toward the other, but rather wants to possess its object. Although the passionate man succeeds in making himself a lack of being, he does so not with the intention of acting freely as such, but to simply just be (ibid., 65).10 De Beauvoir concludes that existentialism cannot be solipsistic. We are not living in a world where everyone creates their own values and tries to impose them on others, or where there is only a conflict of opposed wills enclosed in their solitude (ibid., 72). An existential ethics must condemn these “inauthentic” ways of living, not in the name of an abstract law, but because these forms neglect the intersubjectivity that lies at the heart of every ambiguous existence.11 If it is true, as de Beauvoir argues, that every project emanates from subjectivity, it is also true that these subjective movements must surpass their subjectivity. Neither a project nor a choice or norm can be realized or last without the recognition, belief and support of others: “Man can find a justification of his own existence only in the existence of other men” (ibid.). Therefore, oppression is an inauthentic form of existence for “a freedom will itself genuinely only by willing itself as an indefinite movement through the freedom of others” (ibid., 90). The existence of others defines my situation and is even the condition of my freedom (ibid., 91). We are bound up with others in the most fundamental way, namely, in an existential (ontological), volitional and affective manner. Existence is an “urgent interrogation”, as soon as one exists one has to “answer”. Existence as affectivity, transcendent movement as well as vulnerability, means that “I concern others and they concern me” (ibid., 72). Therefore, intentionality as the disclosing and constituting of meaning must be affective as well as intersubjective. In disclosing the world, we connect to others affectively; in constituting meaning or engaging in projects together, we establish the basis for a proper form of we-intentionality. Genuine or “authentic” passion and joy is thus only possible when it is shared.
3. In/Authentic love: control and emotional intoxication In the feminist classic, The Second Sex (1947), de Beauvoir explains why a patriarchal society distorts an authentic (ethical) performance of freedom as well as an authentic love relation between men and women. To this end, she interprets the binary gender order that comes with a strict separation and asymmetric valuation of labor (domestic vs. salaried), spaces (private vs. public) and roles (serving and caring vs. leading and producing), as an attempt to escape our ambiguous human condition—this time not merely on a personal psychological but also on a societal level. Ambiguity, i.e., that existence is both, subject/object, transcendent/immanent, active/passive, is resolved within patriarchal societies by assigning each of these poles to one of the supposed two sexes or genders.12 The first betrayal of ambiguity (and, therefore, freedom and passion) is the preemptive attempt to fixate and stabilize a female (or male) essence. Female (or male) existences do not have the chance to make and shape their essence through their own doings (as the existential relation to being requests). While masculinity supposedly embodies rationality, control, agency, transcendence and culture, the myth of the “eternal feminine” (de Beauvoir 2011a, 19f., 158, 163ff.) ascribes to them an intimate closeness to nature, passivity, irrationality and emotion, and perceives their main function in “immanent” processes like preserving, repeating and caring. While ‘the man’ represents the absolute autonomous subject that transcends 191
Maren Wehrle
itself into the world and shapes this world through his projects, women are identified only in relation to them as ‘the other’. The second betrayal of ambiguity is the reduction of a large group of members of human existence to immanence. In de Beauvoir’s context of post-World War II, many women in Western societies still faced evident oppression—they did not have equal rights and were highly dependent economically, socially and politically on men. Women are thus bound to men if they desire to partake in acts of transcendence (world disclosing and shaping). This situation of immanence is enforced spatially as women’s daily activities are confined to the domestic sphere, and characterized by a routine and repetition, that hinders them to authentically embrace their freedom. Because of their bodily as well as social situation as mothers and caregivers, they are rendered dependent and bound to bodily vulnerability and finitude (cf. Groenhout 2017, 77). In contrast, man, with his emphasis on transcending and producing, hides his vulnerability and contingency behind the illusion of agency, control and rationality. Indeed, as de Beauvoir shows, the projection of a rational universe of human (masculine) mastery is only possible because all the contingent and ‘sticky’ aspects of our existence (i.e., materiality, emotions, nature, passivity, finitude) are outsourced to one half of human mankind. Although de Beauvoir rightly criticizes woman’s situation as oppressive in contrast to that of man’s, she leaves us in no doubt that both parties reap certain rewards (at least, in the context of the 1940s France). In this patriarchal order, women are not overtly concerned by the fears, responsibilities and risks that accompany freedom and transcendence (the subject position), while men retain their position of superiority and strive to ignore their dependence, passivity and finitude (the object position). Although this order is “dialectically unstable” (cf. Bauer 2017, 151), because no one can only ever be a subject or an object, merely immanent or transcendent, it sometimes appears to work out for both. But, in this manner, both fail to face their ambiguity. They are thus unable to fulfill their freedom: Instead of accepting their existential singularity, they hide behind the predefined essence of a ‘group’; instead of actually facing one another as individuals, one just labels the other according to typified characteristics. In such a patriarchal order, passion or ‘authentic’ love is deformed as both women and men are unable to fulfill their genuine human potential. In order to experience a less distorted and more authentic love, humans (whatever gender) must affirm their ambiguity, make oneself vulnerable and take the risk of an intimate encounter, rather than stick to predefined roles and conventions. Authentic love is only possible when one respects the other as a ‘real other’, i.e., in their singularity, equality and difference, and together try to enact a “relational autonomy” (cf. Petterson 2017). What is needed for such an authentic love as well as freedom is the acceptance of one’s vulnerability and affective openness or empathy for the other, and correspondingly the freedom of the respective other. In Must we burn Sade (1951/1952), de Beauvoir describes this as “emotional intoxication”. According to de Beauvoir, Sade fears and thus rejects his ambiguity and vulnerability and thereby lacks the ability of being emotionally intoxicated. She describes him as someone who “mistook power for freedom and misunderstood the erotic desires of the flesh” (Bergoffen 2011, 42).13 De Beauvoir acknowledges the importance of Sade’s writings and experiences as they confront us with the singularity of the subject, and the tensions between me and the other. Sade was authentic in that he tried to develop an existential ethics and criticized the hedonistic and despotic order of its time, the “resigned hypocrisy that we decorate with the name of virtue” (ibid., 84). Against the organized criminality of the state that masks itself as ‘virtue’, he puts the brutality of
192
Simone de Beauvoir
nature and the honest cruelty of man. He claims that the former, the hypocrisy of virtue, is the real evil, while cruelty is the only possibility to establish a real connection between people. De Beauvoir agrees that cruelty can indeed create an affective relationship with another— it reveals in us the ambiguity of our bodily existence in that it breaks down the barriers of flesh that separates us. She denies, however, that there can be real passion without affirming one’s ambiguity. In a careful analysis of his transcribed sexual experiences and criminal acts, de Beauvoir shows that Sade, who argues for the spontaneous and violent forces of nature, is unable to get rid of his own singularity and consciousness: “Not for one instant does he lose himself in animality” (de Beauvoir 2011b, 59). Quite the opposite: His sexual encounters are carefully planned; he needs imagination and philosophical discourse as preparation and aphrodisiac; and he remains lucid until the very end. His sensual pleasure is never spontaneous, “self-forgetting” or “swooning”. De Beauvoir concludes that Sade and sadism itself is neither a natural force nor an ethical act, but it actually tries to compensate for an absence, that is, the inability of “emotional intoxication”. Only through such an emotional intoxication can existence be “grasped in oneself and in the other as at once subjectivity and passivity” (ibid., 59–60), and so achieves an “ambiguous unity, in which the two partners merge”, and “each is delivered from its self-presence and attains and immediate communication with the other” (ibid., 60). Sade’s escape of emotional intoxication “rejoin[s] the other only via representation” as his “autism” prevents him from forgetting himself and “from ever realizing the presence of the other” (ibid.). It is this missing presence and connection that he tries to substitute with the other’s pain and suffering (ibid., 65). Sade remains enclosed in the solitude of his consciousness. He is a cold lover and needs to affirm himself as the author of the feelings of the other because he has “no other means of attaining his own fleshly condition” (ibid., 60).14 *** Clearly, for de Beauvoir, although some of us are unable to live this ambiguity and affectively connect to others, one must still continue to find ways to achieve recognition from and support others. After all, our existences are intertwined bodily and emotionally, and our freedom is tied to the freedom of others. In all of the mentioned works, the necessary and inescapable bond between individuals comes to the fore. This bond can either lead to evil and violence (i.e., conflicts, denials or misinterpretation of freedom) or to a (shared) passion and love as when we pursue our freedom together in joined projects or connect affectively and achieve an “ambiguous unity” in intimate relationships. Existence thus comprises the challenge to keep, establish and share passion, that is, to accept the fear of finitude, contingency and our dependence on others, and take the risk to appeal to their freedom.15
Notes 1 Levinas also guided her reading of Husserl’s and Heidegger’s phenomenology, cf. Levinas (1930, 1947, 1979). 2 For her reading and application of Hegelian concepts as master/slave dialectics, etc., cf. Hutchings (2017), Direk (2017), Gothlin (1996), Bauer (2001), and Green and Roffey (2010); for influences from Marx, see Kruks (2017). 3 For the genuine collaborative character of the work of de Beauvoir and Sartre, see Sartre’s ethical notebooks from the 1940, published in 1980 (Sartre 1983), and therein De Beauvoir’s letters to Sartre and Algren.
193
Maren Wehrle
194
Simone de Beauvoir ——— (2011a[1949]). The Second Sex. Transl. by C. Borde and S. Malovany-Chevallier. New York: Vintage. ——— (2011b[1953]). Must We Burn Sade? Transl. by K. A. Gleed, M. J. Rose, and V. Preston. In: M. A. Simons and M. Timmermann (Eds.). Political Writings. Urbana: University of Illinois Press. Direk, Zeynep (2017). Simone de Beauvoir’s Relation to Hegel’s Absolute. In: L. Henghold and N. Bauer (Ed.). A Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Oxford: Wiley, 198–211. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions. A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gothlin, Eva (1996). Sex and Existence: Simone de Beauvoir’s “The Second Sex”. London: Athlone. ——— (2001). Simone de Beauvoir’s Existential Phenomenology and Philosophy of History in Le Deuxième sexe. In: L. Embree and W. O’Brien (Eds.). The Existential Phenomenology of Simone de Beauvoir. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 41–51. ——— (2006). Reading de Beauvoir with Heidegger. In: C. Card (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Simone De Beauvoir. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 45–65. Green, Karen, and Nicholas Roffey (2010). Women, Hegel and Recognition. The Second Sex. Hypatia 25(2), 376–393. Groenhout, Ruth (2017). Beauvoir and the Biological Body. In: L. Henghold, and N. Bauer (Eds.). A Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Oxford: Wiley, 73–83. Heinämaa, Sara (2003). Toward a Phenomenology of Sexual Difference. Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, Beauvoir. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. ——— (2006). Through Desire and Love: Simone de Beauvoir on the Possibilities of Sexual Desire. In: E. Mortensen (Ed.). Sex, Breath and Force: Sexual Difference in a Post-Feminist Era. Lanham: Lexington, 129–166. ——— (2008). Simone de Beauvoir. In: H. R. Sepp and L. Embree (Eds.). Handbook of Phenomenological Aesthetics. Dordrecht: Springer, 41–44. ——— (2012). Sex, Gender and Embodiment. In: D. Zahavi (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 216–242. ——— (2017). Ambiguity and Difference Two Feminist Ethics of the Present. In: A. Parker, and A. van Leeuwen (Eds.). Differences: Rereading Beauvoir and Irigaray. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 137–173. Husserl, Edmund (1973). Experience and Judgment. An Investigation in a Genealogy of Logic. Transl. by J. S. Churchill, and L. Eley. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Hutchings, Kimberly (2017). Beauvoir and Hegel. In: L. Henghold, and N. Bauer (Eds.). A Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Oxford: Wiley, 187–198. Kierkegaard, Søren (1959[1843]). Either/Or Volume I. Transl. by D. F. Swenson, and L. M. Swenson. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Kruks, Sonja (1990). Situation and Human Existence: Freedom, Subjectivity and Society. London: Unwin Hyman. ——— (2017). De Beauvoir and the Marxism Question. In: L. Henghold, and N. Bauer (Eds.). A Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Oxford: Wiley, 236–249. Langer, Monika (2006). Beauvoir and Merleau-Ponty on Ambiguity. In: C. Card (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Simon de Beauvoir. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 87–106. Levinas, Emmanuel (1995[1930]). Theory of Intuition in Husserl’s Phenomenology. Transl. by A. Orianne. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. ——— (2001[1947]). Existence and Existents. Transl. by A. Lingis. Pittsburg: Duquesne University Press. ——— (1987[1979]). Time and Other. Transl. by R. A. Cohen. Pittsburg: Duquesne University Press. McWeeny, Jennifer (2017). Beauvoir and Merleau-Ponty. In: L. Henghold, and N. Bauer (Eds.). A Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Oxford: Wiley, 211–224. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1992[1948]). Sense and Non-Sense. Transl. by H. Dreyfus, and P. Dreyfus. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. ——— (1968[1964]). The Visible and the Invisible. Transl. by A. Lingis. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Petterson, Tove (2017). Love – According to Simone de Beauvoir. In: L. Henghold, and N. Bauer (Eds.). A Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Oxford: Wiley, 160–174. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1956[1943]). Being and Nothingness. A Phenomenological Essay on Ontology. Transl. by H. E. Barnes. New York: Philosophical Library. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1992[1983]). Notebooks for an Ethics. Transl. by D. Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
195
Maren Wehrle Wehrle, Maren (2015). “Feelings as the Motor of Perception”? The Essential Role of Interest for Intentionality. Husserl Studies 31(1), 45–64. Wilkerson, William (2017). Beauvoir and Merleau-Ponty on Freedom and Ambiguity. In: L. Henghold and N. Bauer (Eds.). A Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. Oxford: Wiley, 223–236. Further reading Lennon, Kathleen, and Wilde, Anthony (forthcoming). Alienation and Affectivity: Beauvoir, Sartre and Levinas on the Ageing Body. Sartre Studies International. doi:10.3167/ssi.2019.250104.
196
17 MAURICE MERLEAU-PONTY Joel Krueger
1. Introduction Phenomenologists have long argued that emotions play a central role in framing our experience of the world. Scheler, Stein, and Levinas, for example, insist on the centrality of emotions in shaping our empathic engagement with others (Krueger 2008; Jardine 2015). For Heidegger and Sartre, moods and emotions are core structures of our being-in-theworld insofar as they disclose the significance of our worldly projects and future possibilities (Hatzimoysis 2009; Elpidorou and Freeman 2015). Merleau-Ponty is an outlier. He spends little time explicitly addressing emotions—and when he does mention them, it’s often in the service of another topic such as language, gesture, sexuality, or aesthetics (Cataldi 2008). The main objective of this chapter is, therefore, the following: I will bring together some of Merleau-Ponty’s scattered remarks about emotions and integrate them with his more general claims about embodiment, mind, and self to illuminate his view of emotions. I will argue that Merleau-Ponty defends an externalist approach anticipating current debates in philosophy of emotions.1 For Merleau-Ponty, emotions are not exclusively head-bound; rather, they are styles of bodily comportment or “variations of being in the world” realized not only by the dynamics of our embodied agency but also by the objects and institutions around us. Merleau-Ponty’s externalism is philosophically interesting because it challenges some traditional assumptions about the ontology of emotions. It can also enrich current debates by highlighting under-investigated themes worthy of further attention.
2. Embodied emotions For Merleau-Ponty, emotions are embodied. This amounts to more than the trivial claim that emotions depend upon our brain and central nervous system. And it’s an even stronger view than approaches which argue that emotions are perceptions of bodily changes tracking features or events in our environment (e.g., the presence of threats) (Damasio 1994; Prinz 2004). Instead, Merleau-Ponty endorses an embodied constitution thesis: the claim that some emotions are partially made up of bodily processes beyond the brain. We find versions of this thesis in embodied cognitive science. Embodied cognition theorists reject the idea that cognitive phenomena such as seeing a bottle of Belgian beer or 197
Joel Krueger
solving a mathematical problem are constituted entirely by computational processes in the brain. For example, sensorimotor or “enactive” approaches argue that perception is a mode of action, and the bodily processes that comprise the latter (e.g., movements of the eyes and head; focusing and refocusing attention; reaching, grabbing, manipulating, etc.) are thus constituents of the former (Noë 2004). Similarly, some embodied cognition theorists argue that gestures can be part of cognitive processes like mathematical reasoning or working memory (Clark 2008) (see also Chapter 26 in this volume). What is Merleau-Ponty’s constitution claim about emotions? Simply put, for Merleau-Ponty, emotions are constituted not only by brain processes but also by bodily processes and the dynamics of our embodied agency. Merleau-Ponty’s view is, therefore, a kind of embodied externalism in that the vehicles of emotions span neural and extra-neural bodily processes. They are realized not just in but also across the body’s “expressive space” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 147). To further clarify this view, we can first consider Merleau-Ponty’s general rejection of Cartesian “intellectualism”. This is a picture of mind that “by definition, eludes the ‘outside spectator’ and can only be recognized inwardly” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 391). Merleau-Ponty instead argues that mental phenomena are not hidden inside our bodies like marbles in a container. Rather, our body as a whole is constitutive of subjectivity. I don’t simply have a body—“I am my body” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 205). Elsewhere, he summarizes his core thesis: The perceiving mind is an incarnated mind. I have tried, first of all, to re-establish the roots of the mind in its body and in its world (…) the insertion of the mind in corporeality, the ambiguous relation which we entertain with our body and, correlatively, with perceived things. (Merleau-Ponty 1964b, 3–4) For Merleau-Ponty, my awareness of myself as a locus of experience and action is inextricably bound up with my body and the way I bodily engage with the world. As a consequence, “the body, then, is not an object” but instead a being with “an ambiguous mode of existence” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 204). My body is a physical object with properties like size, weight, color, shape, and texture, but it is also and at the same time a subject, something I experience and live through from the inside as I interact with the people and things around me. For example, I can unthinkingly reach for and grasp my coffee mug while focusing on the newspaper, or tenderly stroke my daughter’s cheek as I kiss her goodnight, because I have an immediate proprioceptive and kinesthetic sense of where my limbs are in space and what sort of bodily actions are possible within that space. I possess a prereflective sense of myself as an embodied and situated subject. To be a body for Merleau-Ponty is thus to exist within the tension of this “ambiguous” existence where subjectivity and objectivity are interwoven within the dynamics of everyday life. And acknowledging this structural ambiguity of the embodied mind shows us that we are “no longer dealing with a material reality nor, moreover, with a mental reality, but with a significative whole which properly belongs neither to the external world nor to internal life” but simultaneously to both (Merleau-Ponty 1963, 182). A consequence of this view is that it rejects a picture of mind as a private inner realm that only the owner of that mind has direct access to: We must abandon the fundamental prejudice according to which the psyche is that which is accessible only to myself and cannot be seen from the outside. My psyche is 198
Maurice Merleau-Ponty
not a series of “states of consciousness” that are rigorously closed in on themselves and inaccessible to anyone but me. My consciousness is turned primarily toward the world, turned toward things; it is above all a relation to the world. The other’s consciousness as well is chiefly a certain way of comporting himself toward the world. Thus it is in his conduct, in the manner in which the other deals with the world, that I will be able to discover his consciousness. (Merleau-Ponty 1964b, 116–117) For Merleau-Ponty, we see mind directly in action (Krueger 2012). As fundamentally embodied and animate beings, we are open and responsive to our environment; this openness is constitutive of our bodily being-in-the-world. Accordingly, mind is continually externalized—and thus directly available to others—via the integrated suite of skills, capacities, and habits that enable us to act on and respond to the people and things around us. These features of our embodiment and agency are constitutive of mindedness. And “the mental thus understood is comprehensible from the outside” (Merleau-Ponty 1963, 183). Merleau-Ponty argues that emotions are similarly embodied and externalized; they are styles of bodily comportment or “variations of being in the world” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 372). This means that emotions should not be thought of as discrete states that arise inside of us, fully formed, only to pass away after some time as a new emotion takes its place (i.e., the common view of feelings as “a preordination, of a nature calling forth a feeling” (Merleau-Ponty 2010, 28)). As styles of bodily comportment, emotions are inextricably linked with our agency (Colombetti 2014; Slaby and Wüschner 2014; Hufendiek 2017). They are enacted over time—not things that just passively happen to or in us but rather things that we do: We can, for example, see quite clearly what is shared between the gesture and its sense in the expression of emotions and in the emotions themselves: the smile, the relaxed face, and the cheerfulness of the gestures actually contain the rhythm of the action or of this joy as a particular mode of being in the world. (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 192) A substantive consequence of this view is to see emotions as concretely articulated in what we might refer to as an individual’s “affective style”: their habitual way of moving, acting, expressing, and regulating emotions (Colombetti and Krueger 2015).2 Other remarks support this externalist reading. They affirm that, for Merleau-Ponty, the bodily dynamics of our affective style—gestures, facial expressions, idiosyncratic mannerisms, mimicry, etc.— are not merely expressions of hidden feelings but instead outwardly visible parts of the emotions themselves: I perceive the other’s grief or anger in his behavior, on his face and in his hands, without any borrowing from an “inner” experience of suffering or of anger and because grief and anger are variations of being in the world, undivided between body and consciousness, which settle upon the other’s behavior and are visible in his phenomenal body. (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 372) Consider an angry or threatening gesture (…) I do not perceive the anger or the threat as a psychological fact hidden behind the gesture, I read the anger in the gesture. The gesture does not make me think of anger, it is the anger itself. (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 190) 199
Joel Krueger
Since emotion is not a psychic, internal fact but rather a variation in our relations with others and the world which is expressed in our bodily attitude, we cannot say that only the signs of love or anger are given to the outside observer and that we understand others indirectly by interpreting these signs: we have to say that others are directly manifest to us as behavior. (Merleau-Ponty 1964a, 53) To be clear, Merleau-Ponty is not endorsing a brand of crude behaviorism according to which mental phenomena like emotions are reducible to their behavioral expressions. Rather, they have a kind of hybrid reality—“a significative whole which properly belongs neither to the external world nor to internal life”—that cuts across that “old antithesis” between a hidden inner realm of mental phenomena and an observable outer arena of behavior and action (Merleau-Ponty 1963, 182). Merleau-Ponty has no desire to explain away the experiential character of emotions as we live through them from our first-person perspective. He notes that “[t]he other’s grief or anger never has precisely the same sense for him and for me. For him, these are lived situations; for me, they are appresented” within his behavior (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 372). Merleau-Ponty acknowledges an asymmetry with respect to my emotions and those of others. When I experience an emotion, I feel it immediately “from the inside”; I know it directly as mine. But I lack this sort of first-person access to other’s emotions, as they do mine. This asymmetry is phenomenologically constitutional for intersubjectivity. Nevertheless, acknowledging this asymmetry does not entail accepting the ontological assumption generating the “old antithesis” that cleaves inner (mental) from outer (behavioral) realms. Asserting the irreducibility of the first-person perspective, which is necessary to preserve this asymmetry, is compatible with the embodied constitution thesis. And the take-away point, then, is that for Merleau-Ponty, minds—including emotions—are hybrid entities. They are constituted by both internal (neural, physiological, phenomenal) and external (behavioral, expressive) parts and processes, integrated into a unified whole. While space precludes an in-depth survey, we can briefly note that this view receives support from different streams of empirical work in current emotion science. For example, there is evidence that moods are partially constituted by an array of integrated extra-neural processes looping throughout the body and operating at multiple timescales, including fluctuating rates of blood glucose in the bloodstream, hormonal processes (released by endocrine glands in the brain and body), and even mood- and behavior-influencing gut microbiota (Colombetti 2017). Other work indicates that the ontology of emotions is not exhausted by neural components but may also include expressive and behavioral components ( Niedenthal 2007). People who receive Botox injections inhibiting facial expressions (Baumeister et al. 2016), cases of acquired (temporary) facial paralysis such as Bell’s Palsy (Cole 1998), or individuals who suffer severe spinal cord injuries (Chwalisz et al. 1988) report less-intense feelings of emotions. A similar effect is found in the narratives of people with Moebius Syndrome, a congenital form of bilateral facial paralysis (Krueger and Henriksen 2016). This and other evidence lends support to Merleau-Ponty’s claim that the ontology of emotions cuts across both inner and outer components, integrated into a unified expressive whole.
3. Scaffolded emotions An embodied constitution thesis about emotions flows from more general discussions of embodied cognition. However, a family of recent views push this brand of externalism even further. They argue for a kind of environmental externalism according to which our cognitive 200
Maurice Merleau-Ponty
capacities are realized not just by our brains and bodies but also by the complex ways our embodied brains interact with our material and social environments. For these externalist approaches, the tools, technologies, and social resources we use to “scaffold” (i.e., set up, drive, and regulate) our thinking play such a crucial cognitive role that this beyond-thehead scaffolding ought to be considered a literal part of cognition (Clark 2008)—or more conservatively, as at least contributing environmental support essential for understanding its character and functional integrity (Sterelny 2010). Versions of this environmental externalism are found in recent debates about the scaffolded nature of affectivity and emotions (Colombetti 2014; Krueger 2014; Slaby 2014; Stephan et al. 2014; Colombetti and Krueger 2015; Colombetti and Roberts 2015; Greenwood 2015; Carter et al. 2016; Krueger and Szanto 2016). Proponents observe that we routinely manipulate our emotions by actively manipulating things, places, and people around us. These manipulative processes loop back onto us and scaffold our emotions by synchronically and diachronically shaping their temporal and phenomenal development, often in a fine-grained way. And they may even help realize experiences and self-regulative capacities that we might not otherwise be able to achieve without their ongoing input. Merleau-Ponty appears amenable to at least two varieties of a scaffolded approach to emotions. We can make this clearer by looking at his remarks on emotions and incorporation, and emotions and institutions.
3.1 Emotions and incorporation For Merleau-Ponty, our embodiment is dynamic and open-ended. As lived bodies— “ambiguous” beings constituted by a synthesis of subjectivity and objectivity—we are open to various forms of structural augmentation (i.e., scaffolding) which reconfigures how we experience and use our bodies. More precisely, our bodies can be scaffolded by processes of “incorporation”: the ability of our lived body to take something else into itself. For example, we routinely incorporate new skills and habits that alter the configuration of our embodied agency. This is a process of “habit-incorporation” (Colombetti 2016). Learning to walk down the stairs, play a musical instrument, adopt new gestures, dance the waltz, ride a bicycle, or become a skilled rock climber all involve the development of unique skills that expand the range of things we can do with our bodies in different contexts. Incorporating these skills into our bodily-affective style thus has functional significance insofar as this process structures “our typical and cultivated ways of integrating and interacting with the environment” (Cuffari 2011). But habit-incorporation also has phenomenological (i.e., affective and emotional) significance, too. Once I acquire the skills needed to play the guitar, for instance, I now encounter guitars and guitar-playing contexts with a new-found confidence and attentive focus. Processes of habit-incorporation establish an “affective frame” (Maiese 2016) through which we orient, focus, and skillfully integrate with the things and spaces of our environment in new ways. And since we acquire—and also lose—skills and habits throughout our life, part of the ontological ambiguity of our lived body stems from the fact that it is constantly undergoing this kind of development and change. But bodily incorporation is not restricted to skills and habits. Merleau-Ponty is also attuned to a second sense of incorporation—“object-incorporation”—which occurs when we integrate material objects into our lived body. From birth, Merleau-Ponty observes, we are situated in a world of things—not just natural things but also cultural things, objects that the child, with a sense of wonder, finds “around himself at birth like meteorites from another planet” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 370). Soon, however, their novelty fades and the 201
Joel Krueger
child “takes possession of them and learns to use them as others use them”—both through observation and mimicry, and also because these cultural objects, designed by other embodied subjects, are crafted to invite specific forms of bodily manipulation and incorporation (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 370). Merleau-Ponty offers several examples: a woman instinctively ducking when walking through a door to avoid damaging the feather in her hat, carefully negotiating a tight space while driving by feeling how close we are to obstacles, and a blind person skillfully exploring and responding to the environment with their cane. In these and other cases, the objects “have ceased to be objects whose size and volume would be determined through a comparison with other objects. They have become voluminous powers” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 144). In other words, we incorporate these objects into the dynamics of our “ambiguous” lived body. When we skillfully use a cane to explore our environment, for instance, that cane becomes experientially transparent. It is no longer experienced as an object but instead becomes the perceptual vehicle through which we access the world in new ways Processes of object-incorporation, which occur throughout everyday life, likewise scaffold our emotional experiences. For example, wearing the right kind of hiking shoes while making our way down a slippery path—instead of walking the same path in flimsy flat-soled tennis shoes— directly modulates our emotions. Drawing upon Merleau-Ponty’s analysis of the lived body and incorporation, Colombetti (2016) argues that we are not directly aware of the shoes themselves as thematic objects of experience. We focus instead on the path. But our shoes are nevertheless experientially present as scaffolding through which we experience the path, in that they become transparently integrated into our bodily-affective style. And the continual feedback we receive from our shoes regulates our emotional engagement with that environment; it specifies the “affective frame” regulating both how we feel and how the world shows up for us via this feeling (i.e., as affording confident walking vs. a nervous descent). Similar scaffolding occurs when, for instance, a blind person learns how to explore and navigate their environment with a cane, a devout Catholic down-regulates their anxiety before an important job interview by praying the Rosary and habitually manipulating their prayer beads, or an individual riding a crowded bus listens to their MP3 player to elevate their mood and occlude the outside world. These and many other cases like them are examples of emotional object-incorporation. For Merleau-Ponty, the dynamics of the “ambiguous” body mean that embodied subjects are always poised and ready to enact these habit- and object-incorporations—and in so doing, enact “the simultaneous articulation of their body and their world in the emotion” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 195).
3.2 Emotions and institutions Merleau-Ponty can make another contribution by emphasizing themes that have not yet found a prominent place in current discussions of scaffolded emotions. This can be seen by looking at Merleau-Ponty’s claim that emotions are “institutions”. This idea is first presented in the following quote: [T]he gesticulations of anger or love are not the same for a Japanese person and a Western person. More precisely, the difference between gesticulations covers over a difference between the emotions themselves. It is not merely the gesture that is contingent with regard to bodily organization, it is the very manner of meeting the situation and of living it. When angry, the Japanese person smiles, whereas the Westerner turns red and stamps his foot, or even turns pale and speaks with a shrill voice. Having the same organs and 202
Maurice Merleau-Ponty
the same nervous system is not sufficient for the same emotions to take on the same signs in two different conscious subjects. What matters is the manner in which they make use of their body, the simultaneous articulation of their body and their world in the emotion. The psycho-physical equipment leaves so many possibilities open, and here we see that—just as in the domain of instincts—there is no human nature given once and for all. The use that a man makes of his body is transcendent with regard to that body as a mere biological being (…) Just like words, passionate feelings and behaviors are invented. Even the ones that seem inscribed in the human body, such as paternity, are in fact institutions. (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 195) There is much to unpack here. One interpretive challenge is that this topic is not really developed until nine years later, in Merleau-Ponty’s 1954 lecture-course on institutions (Merleau-Ponty 2010; cf. Maclaren 2017). But in light of what we’ve already considered, there are at least two points worth noting. First, this passage reaffirms Merleau-Ponty’s embodied externalism about emotions. We cannot understand the ontology of emotions without also accounting for their realization in our “psycho-physical equipment”, our bodily-affective style. However—and this is the second point—our bodily-affective style is not fixed by features of our embodiment alone. What we do with our psychophysical equipment, the bodily-expressive dynamics by which we “invent” emotions, also matters: “psycho-physical equipment leaves so many options open”. And this process of inventing emotions is scaffolded not just by features of our embodiment and agency—or even the cultural objects we incorporate into our embodiment—but also by sociocultural institutions that regulate our embodiment. For example, consider how our emotional expressions and habitual dispositions (i.e., elements of our affective style) are regulated by the interaction routines distinctive of our local subcultures: corporate workplaces, social web-based groups, academic circles, the world of sports, fashion, or police and military cultures. Over time, as we inhabit these domains, they exert an increasing top-down influence on the dynamics of our affective style; they scaffold and regulate ways of speaking, gesturing, moving, interacting, experiencing, and expressing emotions that are normative in the domain in question. This may even happen without our full awareness or consent. Slaby (2016) argues that the “presence bleed” of contemporary knowledge work—the tendency to be online and available for work-related communication via email or instant messaging software, night and day, 365 days a year—erodes the boundaries of work time and leisure, with significant emotional consequences. Ever-present communication technologies like smartphones, which are transparently incorporated into the routines of everyday life, along with the institutional expectations and practices they support (e.g., persistent availability, rapid-fire responses), scaffold an array of emotions operative in contemporary white-collar work: feelings of guilt, responsibility, fears, and anxieties, along with the excitement of being part of corporate culture or glimpsing internal drama unfolding in real-time via these technologies. This case study highlights the emotional institution of modern white-collar work—socially instituted “structures of feeling”, as Slaby puts it, that are scaffolded by technological infrastructures, interaction routines, and normative practices distinctive of that subculture. Emotional institutions organize our social world and regulate our affective style from the moment we are born. For the first few months of life, newborns lack the ability to self-regulate attention and emotion. Accordingly, they rely upon close bodily contact of caregivers to help scaffold their cognitive and emotional function. Within these exchanges, 203
Joel Krueger
caregivers employ a range of expressive strategies—mimicry, smiles, exaggerated vocalizations, singing, caressing, etc.—to arouse and regulate infant emotion (Krueger 2013; Ta ipale 2016). For our purposes, what is significant about these early dyadic exchanges is that they are already culturally saturated institutions. In other words, they are from the start infused with the norms, scripts, and patterned practices distinctive of their sociocultural milieu. For example, within Zulu culture, children are expected to be less socially prominent than in North American or European culture—and the regulatory strategies that Zulu women use to engage with their babies and regulate their emotional displays differ accordingly (Spurrett and Cowley 2010). The important point is that even these early emotional institutions teach infants about “the simultaneous articulation of their body and their world in the emotion”, as Merleau-Ponty puts it. Our habits of emotional experience and expression—our bodilyaffective style—are not fixed by our embodiment alone but are rather “transcendent with regard to [our] body as a mere biological being”, insofar as these habits are scaffolded and shaped by the regulatory institutions in which we develop and connect with others. These emotional institutions regulate experience and expression throughout our life—often with profound political consequences, such as the way that emotional experiences of women, minorities, or society’s “untouchables” are constrained and regulated by the institutions of the dominant class (Cataldi 1993, 137–149). With few exceptions, however, these cultural and political dimensions of emotional scaffolding have not been a prominent part of current discussions.3 Merleau-Ponty’s characterization of emotions as “institutions” thus reminds us of the need to broaden the scope of these debates.
4. Conclusion As we’ve seen, emotions for Merleau-Ponty are not exclusively head-bound entities. They are styles of bodily comportment or “variations of being in the world” that are scaffolded not only by the dynamics of our embodiment and agency but also by the objects and institutions around us. So where does this leave us? This externalist picture can impact several philosophical debates. First and most obviously, it suggests that Merleau-Ponty has much to contribute to ongoing discussions of embodied and scaffolded emotions—currently an active area of philosophical research. As we’ve seen, more attention should be paid to cultural and political (i.e., “institutional”) dimensions of these debates. Second, this view can fruitfully impact debates about social cognition and other minds. Several theorists have recently argued that if mental phenomena like emotions are externalized via the expressions, skills, capacities, and habits that comprise our bodily-affective style, there is no problem of other minds. We see minds (or at least parts of minds) directly, within another’s bodily-affective style (Krueger 2018a). Of course, this does not settle the debate; there are many “problems of other minds”, some of which remain untouched by this claim (Overgaard 2017). But it does suggest that perception is not as indirect a path to other minds as it’s often thought to be. Finally, Merleau-Ponty’s view of emotions can help shed light on affective disturbances in psychiatric disorders like schizophrenia, severe depression, and autism. Many psychiatric disorders involve disturbances of an individual’s bodily-affective style—e.g., depersonalization, diminished expressivity, motor difficulties with habit-incorporation, etc.—which leads to global disturbances in their emotional life (Fuchs and Koch 2014). One of the important lessons of Merleau-Ponty’s analysis is that our emotions are deeply regulated, at multiple 204
Maurice Merleau-Ponty
timescales, by scaffolding provided by the objects and institutions around us. This scaffolding constrains our bodily-affective style, but more positively, it also brings regulative stability and predictability to the lived spaces we move through and inhabit on a daily basis. However, some individuals with psychiatric disorders lose reliable access to this scaffolding and its regulative potency, which may help explain some of the difficulties they have managing their emotions on both a moment-to-moment and long-term basis. The interrelation between material culture and affective disorders in psychopathology has not received much focused attention, however, an oversight which may impede a fuller understanding of the phenomenon (Krueger 2018b). Once again, Merleau-Ponty’s analysis can point the way toward new and promising lines of inquiry.
Notes 1 For two book-length treatments of Merleau-Ponty on emotions that cover themes I lack space to discuss here, see Mazis (1989) and Cataldi (1993). 2 These observations can help clarify Merleau-Ponty’s assertion that “The body cannot be compared to a physical object, but rather to the work of art” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 152). 3 Although see Slaby (2016) and Merritt (2014).
References Baumeister, Jenny C., Papa, Giovanni, and Foroni, Francesco (2016). Deeper than Skin Deep – The Effect of Botulinum Toxin-A on Emotion Processing. Toxicon 118, 86–90. Carter, J. Adam, Gordon, Emma C., and Palermos, S. Orestis (2016). Extended Emotion. Philosophical Psychology 29(2), 198–217. Cataldi, Suzanne L. (1993). Emotion, Depth, and Flesh: A Study of Sensitive Space: Reflections on Merleau-Ponty’s Philosophy of Embodiment. Albany: SUNY Press. ——— (2008). Affect and Sensibility. In: R. Diprose, and J. Reynolds (Eds.). Merleau-Ponty: Key Concepts. Stocksfield: Acumen, 163–173. Chwalisz, Kathleen, Diener, Ed, and Gallagher, Dennis (1988). Autonomic Arousal Feedback and Emotional Experience: Evidence from the Spinal Cord Injured. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 54(5), 820–828. Clark, Andy (2008). Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cole, Jonathan (1998). About Face. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Colombetti, Giovanna (2014). The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ——— (2016). Affective Incorporation. In: J. A. Simmons and J. E. Hackett (Eds.). Phenomenology for the Twenty-First Century. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 231–248. ——— (2017). The Embodied and Situated Nature of Moods. Philosophia 45(4), 1437–1451. Colombetti, Giovanna, and Krueger, Joel (2015). Scaffoldings of the Affective Mind. Philosophical Psychology 28(8), 1157–1176. Colombetti, Giovanna, and Roberts, Tom (2015). Extending the Extended Mind: The Case for Extended Affectivity. Philosophical Studies 172(5), 1243–1263. Cuffari, Elena (2011). Habits of Transformation. Hypatia 26(3), 535–553. Damasio, Antonio (1994). Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Harper Collins. Elpidorou, Andreas, and Freeman, Lauren (2015). Affectivity in Heidegger I: Moods and Emotions in Being and Time. Philosophy Compass 10(10), 661–671. Fuchs, Thomas, and Koch, Sabine C. (2014). Embodied Affectivity: On Moving and Being Moved. Frontiers in Psychology 5(508), 1–12. Greenwood, Jennifer (2015). Becoming Human: The Ontogenesis, Metaphysics, and Expression of Human Emotionality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hatzimoysis, Anthony (2009). Emotions in Heidegger and Sartre. In: P. Goldie (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 215–235.
205
Joel Krueger Hufendiek, Rebekka (2017). Affordances and the Normativity of Emotions. Synthese 194(11), 4455–4476. Jardine, James (2015). Stein and Honneth on Empathy and Emotional Recognition. Human Studies 38(4), 567–589. Krueger, Joel (2008). Levinasian Reflections on Somaticity and the Ethical Self. Inquiry 51(6), 603–626. ——— (2012). Seeing Mind in Action. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 11(2), 149–173. ——— (2013). Merleau-Ponty on Shared Emotions and the Joint Ownership Thesis. Continental Philosophy Review 46(4), 509–531. ——— (2014). Varieties of Extended Emotions. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13(4), 533–555. ——— (2018a). Direct Social Perception. In: A. Newen, L. de Bruin, and S. Gallagher (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2018b). Schizophrenia and the Scaffolded Self. Topoi. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-0189547-3 Krueger, Joel, and Henriksen, Mads Gram (2016). Embodiment and Affectivity in Moebius Syndrome and Schizophrenia: A Phenomenological Analysis. In: J. A. Simmons and J. E. Hackett (Eds.). Phenomenology for the Twenty-First Century. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 249–267. Krueger, Joel, and Szanto, Thomas (2016). Extended Emotions. Philosophy Compass 11(12), 863–78. Maclaren, Kym (2017). The ‘Entre-Deux’ of Emotions: Emotions as Institutions. In: K. Jacobson, and J. Russon (Eds.). Perception and Its Development in Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 51–80. Maiese, Michelle (2016). Affective Scaffolds, Expressive Arts, and Cognition. Frontiers in Psychology 7(359), 1–11. Mazis, Glen A. (1989). Merleau-Ponty, Inhabitation, and the Emotions. In: H. Pietersma (Ed.). Merleau-Ponty: Critical Essays. Washington DC: University Press of America, 251–268. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1963). The Structure of Behavior. Transl. by A. L. Fisher. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. ——— (1964a). Sense and Nonsense. Transl. H. L. Dreyfus, and P. A. Dreyfus. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. ——— (1964b). The Primacy of Perception, and Other Essays on Phenomenological Psychology, the Philosophy of Art, History, and Politics. Ed. by James M. Edie. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. ——— (2010). Institution and Passivity: Course Notes from the Collège de France (1954–1955). Transl. by L. Lawlor, and H. Massey. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. ——— (2012). Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by D. A. Landers. New York, London: Routledge. Merritt, Michele (2014). Making (Non)sense of Gender. In: M. Cappuccio, and T. Froese (Eds.). Enactive Cognition at the Edge of Sense-Making: Making Sense of Non-Sense. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 285–306. Niedenthal, Paula M. (2007). Embodying Emotion. Science 316(5827), 1002–1005. Noë, Alva (2004). Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Overgaard, Søren (2017). Other Minds Embodied. Continental Philosophy Review 50(1), 65–80. Prinz, Jesse J. (2004). Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Slaby, Jan (2014). Emotions and the Extended Mind. In: C. von Scheve, and M. Salmela (Eds.). Collective Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 32–46. ——— (2016). Mind Invasion: Situated Affectivity and the Corporate Life Hack. Frontiers in Psychology 7(266), 1–13. Slaby, Jan, and Wüschner, Philipp (2014). Emotion and Agency. In: S. Roeser, and C. Todd (Eds.). Emotion and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 212–228. Spurrett, David, and Cowley, Stephen (2010). The Extended Infant: Utterance-Activity and Distributed Cognition. In: R. Menary (Ed.). The Extended Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 295–323. Stephan, Achim, Walter, Sven, and Wilutzky, Wendy (2014). Emotions beyond Brain and Body. Philosophical Psychology 27(1), 65–81. Sterelny, Kim (2010). Minds: Extended or Scaffolded? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 9(4), 465–481. Taipale, Joona (2016). Self-Regulation and Beyond: Affect Regulation and the Infant–Caregiver Dyad. Frontiers in Psychology 7(889), 1–13.
206
18 FRANTZ FANON Alia Al-Saji
1. A phenomenology of racialization: spectacle and affect Late in Peau noire, masques blancs, Frantz Fanon says: “we need to touch all the wounds that score the black livery (toucher du doigt toutes les plaies qui zèbrent la livrée noire).”1 And then, citing Aimé Césaire: “for life is not a spectacle, for a sea of sorrows is not a proscenium, for a man who screams is not a dancing bear” (PN 181/187/164; Césaire 2017, 94). While Fanon often deflects questions of formal method (PN 12/12/xvi), to touch the wounds of racialization, to make them felt and to dwell in them, brings us closest to his phenomenological method. This allows us to understand why a phenomenology of racialization is a phenomenology of affect, and not primarily a phenomenology of (visual) perception or the visible.2 At stake is affectivity that remains beneath the level of intentional sense-giving (even as it motivates perception and emotion), more atmospheric or thalassic than object or act.3 Yet, this Fanonian approach also questions and reconfigures phenomenology—just as his work, in its irreducible methodological plurality, questions psychoanalysis, psychiatry, political philosophy, and ontology. The challenge is not only that of “expressing” or “inventorying the real” (PN 134/137/116; 181/187/164), when Fanon has insisted on the multiplicity of racialized and colonized experience and on the differential positionalities within Blackness (PN 14/14/xviii), and when that “real” has been repressed through the spectacle staged in its place (Hartman 1997, 39). I argue that the difficulty for phenomenology is threefold: the risk of specularization (Section 1); how racialization structures affect, calling into question immediacy (Section 2); and the failure of phenomenological reductions to account for the weight of colonization (Section 3). First is what I would call the methodological trap of specularization—the tendency to take phenomenology to be equivalent to making experience visible. Even when the invisible workings of the flesh are revealed in their activity as well as their passivity (to use Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s vocabulary), their being rendered a spectacle introduces not only the danger of “thingification” (“Chosification”; Césaire 1955, 23), but also the circumscription and elision of the very affectivity that I am trying to describe. For a phenomenology of racialization, this is doubly problematic, since it means converting the experiences of racialized subjects—suffering, enjoyment, reaction, redress, and resistance, even the “feeling of nonexistence” (PN 135/139/118)—into phenomena available to a racializing and surveilling gaze. 207
Alia Al-Saji
More so, it exposes and spreads out the racialized body: “my body was returned to me spread-eagled, disjointed, recoated, draped in mourning on that white winter’s day,” says Fanon (PN 111/113/93). Not only does this spatialization elide the nonlinear temporalities of racialized experience, it also distorts lived space, pulling and projecting the body onto a spatial grid wherein experience can be seen, grasped, and measured. This repeats the logic of racialization that fixes and dissects the body (for “white looks”), cuts instantaneous cross-sections of its experience, making it again the slave of an appearance (PN 113/116/95).4 But this appearance has itself been constructed—recoating and wearing out the body (rétamé), plunging it in mourning (endeuillé) as Fanon says—through a process of colonization which has recalcitrantly rephrased and adapted itself in a longue durée.5 What is at stake here is the assumed transparency and self-evidence of experience that is given in the immediacy of affect. Neither is affect unmediated, since colonization structures it from within, nor can it be made externally perceptible without loss. Eschewed is the density, opacity, temporality, and ambivalence of racialized affect that cannot be easily expressed in visual or discursive terms (because these dimensions are also overdetermined by colonization). As Saidiya Hartman has argued—in refusing to reproduce the scene of the beating of Aunt Hester from Frederick Douglass’ 1845 Narrative of the Life of Frederick Douglass—the routine and repeated display of the slave’s pained body at once reinforces “the spectacular character of black suffering” and circumscribes and naturalizes that suffering (Hartman 1997, 3, 20). While scenes of violence claim to give evidence of black sentience, they instrumentalize suffering and make it legible and familiar. This immures the witness to that pain, while inviting them to projectively grasp and measure it, opening it to voyeuristic repulsion and enjoyment (3–4). For Hartman, the hypervisibility of racialized bodies risks reproducing the affective economy of slavery—where the fungibility of the slave body as commodity makes it an “empty vessel,” dispossessed and vulnerable to projection and prosthesis (21). Even empathetic accounts repeat this specularization and projective reduction (Hartman 1997, 17–19). Through the spectacle that defines their pain and puts it in its place, racialized subjectivity comes to be selectively seen as limited sentience—as circumscribed humanity, person, and property (Hartman 1997, 35). In a move that uses the subjectivity and sentient embodiment of the racialized as instruments against them, the very spectacle—exposure and assumed transparency—of black affectivity becomes a tool to intensify subjection. This risk of specularization looms large when Peau noire, masques blancs is read as explicitating the sense, and shedding light on the constitution, of racialized and colonized suffering through the application of a predefined phenomenological method—a reading I resist here. Instead, I argue that Fanon works to interrupt specular and spectacular renderings of suffering and colonial violence. What he puts his finger on, and puts us in touch with, are the structuring and destructuring times of colonization, in their quotidian and pathologizing normalcy; Fanon’s memory of the child on the train saying “Tiens, un nègre!” is a terrorizing example in its repetition and everydayness (PN 109/112/91). “Toucher du doigt” (PN 181/187/164) means both to touch with one’s finger and to put one’s finger just there at the source of the wound and flaring of the pain. The touch that Fanon advocates is neither optimal grip, violent grasp, nor uniform pressure, nor can it be predicted in advance. His writing touches colonial wounds; by palpating these wounds and dwelling in them, it resuscitates colonial wounds as feelings that are flesh, and does not leave them behind as if their scar tissue was merely a numb object of the past.
208
Frantz Fanon
2. Touch and affective memory Fanon seems to reiterate here Edmund Husserl’s phenomenological discovery in Ideas II that the hand that touches the surface of a table, as it moves across it, also feels itself touched. Husserl describes touch-sensings (Empfindnisse) given through the dynamic and fluid intertwining of kinestheses (sensations of the movement of my own body) and sensations of being-touched (Husserl 1998, 146). Rather than being intentional, sensings are reflexive and non-objectivating, founding the lived-through sensibility of my own body—indeed, the possibility of having a lived body (Al-Saji 2010, 18–19). Since touch is not a compartmentalized sense, sensings happen anywhere where the body is touched. The whole body is a touch-surface, but skin also folds in on itself and flesh has felt depth (Husserl gives the example of the heart (1998, 165)). Thus, the body can also touch itself, as in Husserl’s famous example of one hand touching the other (1998, 144–145). This self-perception doubles and localizes sensings on the skin and gives the body as a field of sensings—appearing to itself as living body (Leib) and not mere extended physical body (Körper). Yet, Fanon’s method of touch is at once more painful and more temporally complex—in at least three ways. First, that upon which Fanon’s method touches has already been touched and wounded by colonial violence, recursively in a longue durée. This past and ongoing colonial (de)structuration cannot be bracketed to focus on a domestic scene of innocuous touch, as Husserl does6; there is no flesh that has not been touched, reconfigured, through colonial duration.7 For the colonized, the very sensibility of flesh registers the weight of this duration—as memory immanently woven into its texture—and responds to the instituted violence of the colonial world. Colonized flesh is “susceptible” (PN 114/116/96), Fanon notes, “sensitive” (PN 117/120/99)—hypersensible and prickly. Thus, second, that which Fanon’s method touches feels itself touched not only in the present but also in its wounded and misrepresented past, remembering and reliving the wounding, in a mode of affect-memory (which is more than recollection). This past weaves through Fanon’s nonlinear phenomenological account.8 It can be felt in the affects of punishments from Le Code Noir that flare up, spasmodically, within the present: “I tried to escape without being seen, but the Whites fell on me and hamstrung me on the left leg” (PN 126/130/109), says Fanon, living through the punishment for a fugitive slave who has tried to escape a second time.9 The immediacy of affect, assumed in the Husserlian picture of touching-touched, is interrupted and deferred. Fanon makes us feel the colonial glue (past and present) that mediates sensing and structures the auto-affective interval between touching and touched.10 So much so that, rather than discovering one’s own living body (Leib) through selftouch, as Husserl does, what Fanon often encounters is a carcass—the living death of the enslaved (Hartman 1997, 106), the famished body-as-fodder of the colonized, their hollowed-out stereotypes—that touch needs to warm back to feeling, if not to life (PN 9/9/ xiii). There is an unpredictable temporal interval between touching and a wound coming back to feeling; phenomenological touch finds its tonality and texture in the wound and the colonial duration that it holds, but this needs preparation and waiting. Moreover, the interval is overloaded with foreboding, stifling, and taut (PN 136/140/119); and much of our “sensitivity” as colonized subjects may be oriented to protecting against reliving colonial violence— shuddering and contracting so as to avoid its touch (PN 114/117/97). Rather than moving away or moving on, Fanon’s “toucher du doigt” advocates other modes of waiting and dwelling in the interval, and with colonial wounds, without inscribing a teleology
209
Alia Al-Saji
of healing or hope.11 Elsewhere, Fanon describes this as descent into “le grand trou noir” (PN 14/14/xviii, PN 189–90/195/172; citing Césaire 2017, 148). If Fanon escapes the trap of specularization, then it is by inventing a different phenomenology. Rather than applying a “neutral” phenomenological method to racialized bodies, this critical and anticolonial phenomenology of affect takes its point of departure within experiences of racialization, in their colonial durations, creating concepts as responses to their calls. Indeed, Fanon’s phenomenology holds together affects of racialization in a temporal palimpsest that plunges us into differential temporal rhythms of colonization, without giving us a position from which to survey them. As “socio-diagnostic” (PN 11/11/xv), this phenomenology is not mere description; for by making us feel social structures, it makes possible other ways of existing and changing them (PN 97/100/80).12
3. The affective weight of colonization While Peau noire, masques blancs can be read as a phenomenology of colonized experience (Antillian, Malagasy, Arab, African), once we attend to how colonization works, it becomes clear that there is no dimension of “modern” life, no region of being, that is left untouched by it. Colonization cannot be compartmentalized or reserved to the “colonies,” nor can it be circumscribed as a layer added to societies being colonized, a supplement that leaves the rest intact. In arguing that French colonization of Madagascar provoked “an absolute wound”—that Madagascar “underwent destructuralization” (PN 94/97/77)—Fanon’s argument has ontological dimensions. Fanon’s aim is not simply to calculate the destructive effects of colonization, against arguments for its partial “civilizing” benefits.13 Rather, Fanon insists that there is colonization of being—destructuration, corrosion, pathology, and rot on multiple levels and through differential temporalities—which is why Les damnés de la terre aims to decolonize being (Fanon 2002, 40). Indeed, this is not only an “existential deviation” (PN 14/14/xviii) on the individual level, which transmutes both the body schema and its emotional and physiological reactions (PN 17/19/3); it is also a structural transformation of the social, economic, and political sphere. More precisely, we can understand the corrosiveness of colonization to be at work within the individual and the social, in literal, imaginary, and metaphorical senses inseparably. Of the civilizing colonial mission, Fanon notes: “It is utopian to expect the black man or the Arab to exert the effort of embedding abstract values in their Weltanschauung when they have barely enough food to survive (alors qu’ils mangent à peine à leur faim)” (PN 93/95/75). Because, he adds, they “lack the possibility” (PN 92–93/95/75). Here, material, embodied conditions and foreclosed possibilities, eating and thinking, are held together in the affect of hunger. The overall point is that hunger is an obstacle to conceptual creation. But Fanon is also making the more subtle point that colonization wants to block imagination and invention, and uses all material and affective means to do so, including turning the bodies of the colonized into instruments against them and into material resources to be exploited—kept barely alive while being digested, “walking manure ( fumier ambulant)” he says citing Césaire (PN 95/98/78; Césaire 2017, 114). The affect of colonized hunger calls for more than nutrition; it calls for inventing sociality and ways of living and dying, on one’s own terms, from the reconfigured ruin of foreclosed and dead possibilities.14 It is worth emphasizing that there is no affect that escapes the violence of colonization. Both colonial and colonized bodies undergo “aberrations of affect” (PN 8/6/xii)—“become abnormal” (PN 141/143/122)—condemned to non-relationality and the repeated failure of intersubjective reciprocity, if sought along a white–black axis. It is through such aberrant 210
Frantz Fanon
affect, I argue, that colonialism and racism expose the limits of the phenomenological reduction (in its Husserlian and even Merleau-Pontian formulations). Neither can colonization be bracketed to reveal a core of sense, as if racism were an afterthought; nor can it be put out of play to conceive a universalizable subject free of historical violence. Critical phenomenology cannot stay at the level of constitution of sense, for colonization already structures the phenomenological field of sense and draws the borders that differentiate sense from nonsense (PN 9/9/xiii). In Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis, Husserl points to affection as a level that precedes the constitution of objects, where passivity is on the verge of turning into activity. Affection can be understood from two sides: As the “pull” of the world on my body, or my body “turning toward” that which is affecting it (Husserl 2001, 151). The perceptual field has an “affective relief ” that differentially motivates meaning-making: What is noticed, what comes to matter, from that which stays in the background (unconscious “tendencies toward affection” (2001, 149)). But affective relief is shaped by diachronic and synchronic contrast, that shifts contextually and with the direction of bodily desire and sensibility (2001, 150). More deeply than Husserl’s method admits, however, how contrast comes to be felt (and by whom) is a function of the colonial duration that structures the phenomenological field. While Husserl’s account allows for differentially mapped affective reliefs, it insists on the leeway that consciousness feels in relation to the affective pull of “objects”—without which the free practice of phenomenological bracketing would not be possible. Merleau-Ponty’s description of the phenomenological reduction as “loosen[ing] the intentional threads that connect us to the world in order to make them appear” (2012[1945], 14) relies implicitly on a concept of “scope of life.” Such “scope of life” allows the subject to step back and distance itself from, or rupture its familiarity with, the world—and, following Eugène Minkowski, allows “leeway (Spielraum)” and room to breathe (2012[1945], 338). While Fanon may agree on “the impossibility of a complete reduction” for reasons different than Merleau-Ponty’s (Merleau-Ponty 2012[1945], 14), he may wonder at the familiarity and comfort of a world in which such spatiotemporal leeway is norm, and from which Merleau-Ponty begins. If we put affect back in its place and time, as Fanon asks (PN 101–2/104/84), we experience a world that stifles and weighs on racialized bodies—bogs them down (engluer) (PN 32/35/18)—without a feeling of leeway. Here, the phenomenological reduction as suspension of theoretical and natural attitudes, as putting out of play the object-in-itself and the particularity and habituality of the ego, is not only incomplete but fails to begin or be motivated. Thus, we encounter split modes of affectivity: While colonial affectivity is “ankylosed” and insensitive, colonized subjects are hypersensitive and risk being “tetanised.” But this is not merely a subjective difference; we live split worlds, with starkly different affective relief. It is from a different affective territory that the project of phenomenological reduction becomes imaginable: One that compartmentalizes racism to a surface layer of existence, where colonization can be treated with indifference. Fanon calls this “affective ankylosis (ankylose affective),” one of the more puzzling socio-diagnostic neologisms he invents (PN 119/122/101). Ankylosis should be read in medical, anatomical, and metaphorical senses at once; it describes a condition where joints become fused and coalesce, so that articulations are restricted and movement is no longer possible between them. Fanon associates affective ankylosis with an inability to make the past fluid,15 to reconfigure, rearticulate, or feel that past differently. What is ankylosed is colonial affectivity—a “white” world that excludes and dominates racialized subjects through gluey formations of time. This is not simply a question of fixity; as an organic pathology, ankylosis diagnoses a past that coalesces and adheres, repeatedly over time, but that may also numb and gangrene.16 This temporal schema highlights both the recalcitrance 211
Alia Al-Saji
and disregard that structure colonial affectivity. (And it can be contrasted to the sensitivity of colonized affect, described earlier.) Racialization is a peculiar form of othering that cultivates, as its infrastructure, forgetting and disregard of the “others” who are its objects. Racism is affectively ambivalent. Its recalcitrance, Fanon shows, relies on adapting to its social time and place, taking on the guise of prevailing norms (2006, 40). But racism also covers over this rephrasing; it represses the histories and operations of power, which constitute it, and blames its victims (PN 188/194/170). Disavowed is the very guilt and corrosive destructuring that colonization brings about— projected onto its colonized others.17 Racialized bodies are, at once, the material and affective labor, the disposable lives that colonization exploits—the “fertilizer” that nourishes colonialism, says Fanon (PN 209/216/190)—and they are the scapegoats upon which the need for colonization and its constitutive violence are projected. Thus, racialization has more to do with drawing lines of domination—policing the borders of “whiteness” and Eurocentric modernity—than with the concrete colonized lives who are its ostensible objects and which it actively misrepresents. More than “active ignorance” (Medina 2013, 39, 57), then, key to understanding the recalcitrance of racism is affective disregard.18 Colonial duration weighs lightly on colonial citizens and heavily on colonized subjects, a differential weighting that translates temporal and spatial leeway. By calibrating the affective relief of the perceptual field, racism already operates at the level of passivity and habituality (for which we remain responsible). It motivates and circumscribes the ways in which contrast is felt in the phenomenological field, what makes sense and what remains nonsense. That which colonized bodies feel most sensitively and acutely, that toward which they turn, often cannot find a way to register its weight within the ankylosed affective field of colonialism (for colonial citizens). In this way, colonized affect and agency are flattened; appearing not only unreasoned but temporally unmotivated, they do not matter (and are only recognized within the stereotypical terms that colonization sets out in advance). Phenomenology is symptomatic of this differential weighting. Fanon’s socio-diagnostic shows how phenomenology needs to redress and decolonize social structures, to be world transformation, in order to create the leeway to reflect. It cannot assume a transparent, unobstructed interval. Racialized subjects are stuck in a colonial past that makes them perpetually late (PN 118/121/100), so that their meaning-making lacks traction. With a past impossible to bracket, a future sheared off, the interval in which colonized subjects live is affectively overloaded, sensitive, and “tetanised.” Fanon diagnoses “affective tetanisation” as the useless spasming of the muscles of the colonized.19 If colonization is tetanus, then it is an infection that penetrates colonized bodies through colonial wounds; it leads to spasms that may look externally like paralysis but that hide, in their depth, intense activity and (appropriate) sensitivity to the violence of the colonial world. I have argued that Fanon invents a phenomenology from dwelling in this affective interval, from touching the wounds of colonial duration that constitute it.
Notes
212
Frantz Fanon
213
Alia Al-Saji Fanon, Frantz (1952) [=PN]. Peau noire, masques blancs. Paris: Éditions du Seuil. [Engl. Transl.: Black Skin, White Masks. Transl. by C. Lam Markmann. New York: Grove Press 1967. / Black Skin, White Masks. Transl. by R. Philcox. New York: Grove Press 2008]. ——— (2002[1961]). Les damnés de la terre. Paris: La Découverte. [Engl. Transl.: The Wretched of the Earth. Transl. by C. Farrington. London: Penguin 2001.] ——— (2006[1964]). Pour la révolution africaine. Paris: La Découverte. Hartman, Saidiya (1997). Scenes of Subjection: Terror, Slavery, and Self-Making in Nineteenth-Century America. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Husserl, Edmund (1989). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy: Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. Transl. by R. Rojcewicz, and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (2001). Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis: Lectures on Transcendental Logic. Transl. by A. J. Steinbock. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (2012[1945]). Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by D. Landes. London, New York: Routledge. Medina, José (2013). The Epistemology of Resistance: Gender and Racial Oppression, Epistemic Injustice, and Resistant Imaginations. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mills, Charles W. (2007). White Ignorance. In: S. Sullivan, and N. Tuana (Eds.). Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance. Albany: State University of New York Press. Morrison, Toni (2004). Beloved. New York: Vintage Books. Slaby, Jan (2020). The Weight of History: From Heidegger to Afro-Pessimism. In: L. Guidi, and T. Rentsch (Eds.). Phenomenology as Performative Exercise. New York, Leiden: Brill. Stoler, Ann Laura (2011). Colonial Aphasia: Race and Disabled Histories in France. Public Culture 23(1), 121–156. Further reading Al-Saji, Alia (2013). Too Late: Racialized Time and the Closure of the Past. Insights 6(5), 1–13. ——— (2014). A Phenomenology of Hesitation: Interrupting Racializing Habits of Seeing. In: E. Lee (Ed.). Living Alterities: Phenomenology, Embodiment, and Race. Albany: State University of New York Press, 133–172. Bernasconi, Robert (2007). On Needing Not to Know and Forgetting What One Never Knew: The Epistemology of Ignorance in Fanon’s Critique of Sartre. In: S. Sullivan, and N. Tuana (Eds.). Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance. Albany: State University of New York Press, 231–239. Fanon, Frantz (2001[1959]). L’an V de la révolution algérienne. Paris: La Découverte. ——— (2018). Alienation and Freedom. Ed. by J. Khalfa, and R. Young. Transl. by S. Corcoran. L ondon: Bloomsbury. Gordon, Lewis R. (2015). What Fanon Said: A Philosophical Introduction to his Life and Thought. New York: Fordham University Press. Keeling, Kara (2003). “In the Interval”: Frantz Fanon and the “Problems” of Visual Representation. Qui Parle 13(2), 91–117. Macey, David (2012[2000]). Frantz Fanon: A Biography. London: Verso. Spillers, Hortense J. (1987). Mama’s Baby, Papa’s Maybe: An American Grammar Book. Diacritics 17(2), 64–81.
214
19 HERMANN SCHMITZ Henning Nörenberg
The German phenomenologist Hermann Schmitz belongs to the postwar-generation of philosophers such as Jürgen Habermas and Karl-Otto Apel, both of whom he studied with under Erich Rothacker. The focus of Schmitz’s work, however, is not so much on the rational of public reasoning but on questions of personhood and bodily existence. According to Schmitz, the latter aspects are crucially involved in the way in which something emerges as a compelling reason or as demanding one’s respect. Schmitz’s claims about the central, though often neglected role, of the bodily dimension draw on an investigation of a plethora of phenomena pertaining to the feeling body (Leib). Bodily, in this sense, is whatever someone feels as “belonging to themself in the vicinity— not always within the boundaries—of their material body without drawing on the five senses and the perceptual body schema parasitic on them” (Schmitz et al. 2011, 253). The stirrings of one’s own body (e.g., pain), as well as meaningful aspects in the environment (e.g., another person’s glance), are felt through various instances of contraction, tension, pulsation, or expansion (Schmitz 1965, 73–98). Unlike the so-called neo-Jamesian accounts of bodily feeling, Schmitz does not assume that these felt contractions or pulsations primarily tell us about our organs and limbs and are only indirectly or secondarily representing the significance of what is going on in the environment in terms of the organism’s wellbeing ( Damasio 2004; Prinz 2004). For Schmitz, the piercing gaze or the serene landscape communicates a feeling of contraction or expansion directly, as the body is fundamentally attuned to the world and thus sensitive to movement-related cues and intermodal aspects in the perceived environment (Schmitz 1977, 622–636). Schmitz’s account of the feeling body provides the ground for his theory of pre-personal subjectivity and also for his complex theory of affectivity. It is only in terms of actual—or protended or retended—instances of bodily felt contractions, pulsations, etc., that the subject is affectively involved or engaged with states of affairs, programs, and problems (Schmitz et al. 2011, 248–251). And it is the body that is the working point for emotions that are conceived of as “atmospheres poured out spatially” (Schmitz et al. 2011, 247). While it may not seem that controversial to relate atmospheres to, for instance, the notion of existential feelings as pre-intentional bodily orientations toward the world (cf. Ratcliffe 2008, and Chapter 22 in this volume), a claim about emotions actually being atmospheres may appear implausible. The latter, however, is precisely the view that Schmitz proposes. 215
Henning Nörenberg
He distinguishes between feeling (Fühlen) as undergoing an emotion and the emotion itself (Gefühl) as an atmospheric force that is either felt or merely perceived. In Schmitz, this claim is systematically connected to the rejection of views which view emotions as internal states of the psyche that are closed off from the rest of the world (Schmitz 1969, 6ff.; 1993, 33; 1994, 17ff.). As a first approach to what his claim implies, we might acknowledge that we sometimes refer to emotions as seizing forces with a more or less explicitly stated spatial dimension. We say, for instance, that someone is depressed, agitated by fear, drunk with joy, seized with remorse, awe-struck, grief-stricken, falling into despair, filled with rage, wonder, or anxiety. According to Schmitz, such metaphors do not come out of the blue, but seek to articulate the specific way in which the relevant emotions are experienced. The conception of emotions as spatial atmospheres that seize, stir, or move the feeling body is supposed to capture precisely that experiential dimension of emotional life. On this perspective, it makes an important methodological difference whether we set out to account for emotions as something we undergo or as something we simply have, for we will go on highlighting different structural relations and arrive at different models. According to Schmitz, the notion of emotion as something we have is an abstracted view that is derived from an implicit, though insufficient, understanding of what it means to undergo an emotion. In the following, I will sketch some of the central claims and main arguments by which Schmitz arrives at this view, which he has developed in his 1969 book Der Gefühlsraum (The Space of Feeling) and refined in later writings. In particular, these claims concern the bodily dimension of emotions, the spatial dimension of feelings, the motivational force that emotions as atmospheres have, the distinct ways in which we sense atmospheres, the thematic center around which an atmosphere may form, and the ontological status of atmospheres. Moreover, I shall contextualize these claims, as Schmitz only seldom does, with a view to ongoing discussions in the philosophy of emotion.
1. The atmospheric model highlights the spatial dimension of feelings Atmospheres, according to Schmitz, are “complete occupation[s] of a surfaceless space in the region of experienced presence” (Schmitz et al. 2011, 255). They are specific ways in which the surrounding space, insofar as it is accessible to or rather resonating in the feeling body, is experienced. Similar claims have been made in pragmatism, existential phenomenology, and enactivism. Dewey, for example, suggests conceiving of emotions as particular types of what he calls “pervasive qualities” and which are felt rather than thought by us: “When, for instance, anger exists, it is the pervading tone, color, and quality of persons, things, and circumstances, or of a situation” (Dewey 1931, 99). Sartre holds that, whenever we undergo an emotion, our environment ceases to appear in terms of our usual orientations toward things and, in turn, reveals itself as “magical” (Sartre 2002, 57f.). He illustrates this with the horror induced by a face suddenly appearing at the window: the subject’s usual orientation within the environment breaks down; the window does not appear as an “object that must first be broken” by the other nor is the spatial environment experienced in terms of some measurable distance (“ten yards”) that must first be covered (ibid., 59f.). Rather, the face “annihilates the distance and enters into us” (ibid., 57). Last but not least, Colombetti describes the situation on a delayed, slowly proceeding train to the airport, just before a flight, as “tight and confined”. This trait is also manifested in the subject’s orientation to objects and events in the environment such as “the time indicated by my watch, the speed of the train, the conductor’s announcements” (Colombetti 2014, 122). In all these examples, the surrounding 216
Hermann Schmitz
space is experienced in a manner distinctively related to the emotional episode—and the atmospheric model of emotions is supposed to capture precisely this as a central feature. Beyond such descriptions, however, some authors, such as Sartre, also suggest that atmospheric feeling is merely some form of projection unto the world originating in the relevant person’s mind (Sartre 2002, 49ff.). In contrast, Schmitz argues that atmospheres are ontologically prior to such projections (Schmitz 2014, 53); rather than skewing the reality in which we find ourselves, atmospheres help disclose it.
2. Atmospheres engage the body Schmitz further elucidates the spatial nature of emotions as atmospheres by conceiving of them as holistic syntheses of kinesthetic forces and intermodal qualities affecting the feeling body. Compare the respective impacts of a sticky weather and a clear morning on the body. If we abstain from more or less convincing hypotheses about the physiological underpinnings of our experiences, Schmitz claims, our body senses impacts of a similar kind in the context of grief and joy, for instance. Grief comes as a contractive tendency in the form of a downward pressure (Schmitz 1969, 120ff.; 1989) that has an echo in expressions such as “bowed with grief ”, “my heart sinks”, “heavy at heart”, or “depressed”. Grief also manifests as an encompassing void with the environment receding into distance. The surrounding space affords rumination and fewer possibilities of engaging with others. Joy, on the other hand, is felt as an expansive tendency with an upward vector and a sense of surrounding, elevating repletion (Schmitz 1993, 50f.) echoed in idioms such as “flying high” or “filled with joy”. Indeed, this claim is not too removed from other accounts in the philosophy of emotions: Sartre’s example of the face behind the window “entering into us”, as well as Colombetti’s description of the situation on the delayed train as being “tight and confined” seem, for instance, to articulate particular instances of the very same contractive tendency that Schmitz’s account refers to and contrasts with other tendencies such as expansion. When it comes to describing emotions, this account seems more informative than a somewhat “naturalistic” perspective on sensations and symptoms such as twinges and pangs, sweating in the armpits, accelerated heart rate, hairs going up on the back of one’s neck, etc. Schmitz has worked out a complex conceptual apparatus that allows us to distinguish, for instance, the entire gestalt of the downward pressure in grief from intimidation even though we might use superficially similar metaphors in everyday talk (e.g., “my heart dived”) in order to articulate it (Schmitz 2011, 16–19). In this regard, Schmitz’s atmospheric model is an interesting alternative to both naturalistic, neo-Jamesian perspectives and those that reject the former but marginalize the role of the body in emotions (cf. Roberts 2003, 152, 162ff.).
3. Atmospheres induce programs for conduct Emotions move and motivate. In a variety of accounts, emotions—or central traits of them— are described in terms of felt “action readiness” (Frijda 1988, 351) or as bodily felt tendencies “to move away, towards or against a given object (…), to attend to an object, to submit or to be drawn to it, to disengage from it, or even to suspend any inclination to interact with it” (Deonna and Teroni 2012, 80). For instance, “in joy, I may feel the urge to run, jump, and throw my arms up in the air; in anger, I can feel like hitting the desk, grabbing and shaking objects around me” (Colombetti 2014, 119). Schmitz links this widely acknowledged claim with the atmospheric nature of emotions. In the case of grief, for instance, the depressing kinesthetic force is manifest in the griever’s slumped posture as well as in the sluggishness 217
Henning Nörenberg
of all their movements. The grieving person takes up the impulse of the relevant force and moves along with it (Schmitz et al. 2011, 254). The affordances of rumination and the shrunk possibilities of engaging with others as characters of the surrounding space create a backdrop against which the other person’s initiatives of bringing comfort, say, sometimes appear as out of place or even intrusive. This implies, Schmitz argues, that emotions as atmospheres communicate or at least enforce specific norms such as, for instance, devoting oneself to engrossing the theme of one’s grief (Schmitz 1989, 125–134; 1993, 64) or, in the case of anger, a cathartic discharge channeled toward a specific target in the immediate or mediate environment (Schmitz et al. 2011, 254; Schmitz 2012a, 63f.). In this regard, Schmitz ascribes a certain “authority” to emotions (Schmitz 1973, 131ff.; 1993, 63ff.)—a view with many implications worthy of discussion but that I must pass over in this chapter (cf. Griffero 2014). Initially, the normative impulse is achieved on a pre-personal level at which the person has no distance to the impulse in question so that she simply goes along with it for some time: Before the person can intentionally take a stance towards it, they always find themself already situated in a stance one way or another and can no longer confront it in an unbiased way [as would be possible with regard to mere corporeal stirrings such as hunger or pain which are not atmospheres; H.N.]. (Schmitz et al. 2011, 254) Only later is a genuinely personal response possible in terms of, say, resisting the impulse of the seizing force, further succumbing to it, or converting it, for instance, from shame to envy (Schmitz 2015). Certainly, this claim does allow for various ways in which we can actively shape, regulate, cultivate, or even emancipate ourselves from our affects (Schmitz 1993, 81ff.; 2012a, 60; Schmitz 2014, 104f.). However, it also highlights an irreducibly passive dimension of our emotional life that is underexposed by claims such as “What we currently feel is shaped by what we are—individually or jointly—doing in the world, especially by language” (Krebs 2015, 217; own transl.). Schmitz’s theory has its main focus on precisely that phase of an emotional episode in which critical distance, strategies of emotional selfregulation and actively shaping one’s feelings are not (yet) at play.
4. We sense atmospheres in two distinct ways The atmosphere model allows for two distinct ways of being bodily engaged by an emotion. The first and most obvious way is the one I have referred to above, i.e., being “seized” by atmospheric forces of joy, grief, shame, anger, anxiety, etc. Sometimes, this “seizure” is conscious, for instance, if a person feels their anger rising. Sometimes, however, we become aware of our being in the grip of an emotion only later, for instance, when we suddenly realize our anxiety in that delayed train as something that has conditioned our conduct for quite some time. In all these cases, the subject becomes directly involved in the impulses and affordances defining the relevant atmospheric force. Another way of being bodily engaged by an emotion roughly amounts to a mere perception of the atmosphere in question. In such cases, the subject is not seized by but is bodily communicating with the surrounding atmosphere in a more dialogue-like manner. We may illustrate such cases with a party guest who clearly notices the jolliness around them, but just cannot or does not want to go along with it—perhaps because they are too grief-stricken (Schmitz 1993, 31). The possible outcome of their feeling of grief actually being intensified in this situation seems to imply that the person in question does not only “feel” their own 218
Hermann Schmitz
grief as an atmosphere, but is also sensitive to the kinesthetic impulses and affordances communicated by the surrounding jolly atmosphere—obviously without being seized by the latter themself. In a similar manner, a person may very well be sensitive to an atmosphere of embarrassment around them precisely in terms of kinesthetic impulses, affordances, etc., and may feel somewhat irritated though not embarrassed themself. Some forms of social cognition by which we are immediately acquainted with the other person’s emotion may be regarded as special cases of being touched-though-not-seized by an atmosphere emanated by that person. According to Schmitz, there can be transitions from merely perceiving an atmosphere to being seized by it (Schmitz et al. 2011, 257). Under certain conditions, a person’s grief may not only be mitigated by the surrounding jolliness, but even be replaced by it. Among the many factors that should be taken into account, emotional contagion is only one (Scheler 1973, 25ff.). The person who senses the atmosphere of embarrassment around them may eventually be seized by it once they become aware of what it is that is warranting the emotion in the situation in question. Though the transition from perception to seizure may involve different cognitive mechanisms in these two examples, on the level of our bodily orientation toward the world, the description would be this: first, mere perception and then, actual seizure by the atmosphere in question. Since Schmitz takes this level of description as his point of departure, the possibility of such transitions, regardless whether it comes about by emotional contagion or by identifying and sharing the reason of the other’s emotion, has an important ontological implication: the atmosphere as a percept and the atmosphere by which one is seized are one and the same entity (Schmitz et al. 2011, 257). That is, there is a sense in which the jolliness, the embarrassment, anxiety, etc. perceived in others is the same by which the subject finds themself seized later on. Thus, Schmitz seeks to circumvent a conception of emotions as individual mental states that are ascribed to the respective subjects (Schmitz 1969, 83ff.).
5. Atmospheres can have a thematic center One may wonder why the account presented so far has not yet focused on what most accounts consider to be the central feature of emotions: intentionality. Emotional states are about something, they are related to things or events in the world, and they have an intentional structure. Are my fear, anger, or joy indeed best described as seizing atmospheres to the force of which I am exposed, when there is no mention of what it is that I am afraid of, angry or happy about? Isn’t it more adequate to conceive of emotions as a particular class of intentional states rather than atmospheres? Schmitz is highly skeptical if not polemical regarding the concept of intentionality. In his view, the identification of an intentional object is a problematic abstraction from the more holistic traits of experiencing.1 According to him, taking the intentional structure as the point of departure will result in difficulties in accommodating more pervasive phenomena such as atmospheres. One might conclude that Schmitz’s critique is only plausible if directed against a too-narrow conception of intentionality. However, at least when it comes to moods and pervasive atmospheres, even current propositions of a considerably broader notion of intentionality are of limited help when they describe these as “not without a reference to the world” and somehow “taken up into the intentional structure of our experiences” as they “articulate or modify our existential possibilities” (Gallagher and Zahavi 2012, 133). The specific relation between seizing forces and the intentional structure of emotional states is far from being self-evident. 219
Henning Nörenberg
On the basis of intentionalist accounts of emotions, it is possible to regard the atmospheric feeling as the implicitly co-intended, but nevertheless irreducible bodily, dimension of the so-called “formal object”. The latter denotes the specific evaluative property attributed to the target of the relevant emotion (Deonna and Teroni 2012, 78). So, for instance, in fearing the dog you evaluate it as being dangerous and in joy you evaluate your birthday party as being delightful, etc. In the current discussion on the philosophy of emotion, this technical distinction between target and formal object is broadly accepted and accounts that conceive of emotions as “felt evaluations” (Helm 2002) seem convincing. Furthermore, approaches that more systematically take the bodily dimension into account suggest that there is a constitutive link between the evaluative quality (the formal object) and bodily felt tendencies. From this perspective, shame of oneself, for instance, “is an experience of oneself as degraded, precisely because it consists in feeling one’s body ready to act so as to disappear into the ground or perhaps from the view of others” (Deonna and Teroni 2012, 81). We have already seen how Schmitz links such bodily felt tendencies to the atmospheric nature of emotions (Section 3). In this case, the centripetal kinesthetic vectors that make up the atmospheric feeling of shame engage the body and induce a tendency to “disappear into the ground”. And, according to Schmitz, as well as to other authors such as Deonna and Teroni, Colombetti, etc., this would not only be a negligible epiphenomenon but part and parcel of evaluating oneself as degraded in the context of shame. Schmitz himself, however, is not overly keen to connect his view to the intentionalist framework. Rather than interpreting a seizing atmosphere as the bodily dimension of the relevant emotion’s formal object, he regards values or evaluative properties as a more abstract “substitute for the atmospheric and its meaningfulness” (Schmitz 1994, 304; own transl.). Schmitz also insists that the atmosphere itself is what we mean by “emotion”, whereas the intentional state or feeling roughly corresponds to what he calls “affective involvement” with states of affairs, programs and problems. Thus, he suggests accommodating what is usually called the intentional object of a feeling in his atmosphere model of emotions with the gestalt-psychological notion of “centeredness” (Zentrierung): The surrounding space communicated in terms of atmospheres is not necessarily unstructured; like in other cases of gestalt, it can appear as formed around a specific thematic center. Taking up a proposal by gestalt theorist Wolfgang Metzger (1975, 178f., 181–183), Schmitz distinguishes the “condensation area” (Verdichtungsbereich) of an emotion from its “anchor point” (Verankerungspunkt) (Schmitz 1969, 314ff.). On the level of bodily orientation, the condensation area is the equivalent to what an analysis of the intentional structure would call the “target” of an emotion (Helm 2002, 15), say the teeth-baring dog you are afraid of, the birthday party you rejoice at or the person you feel embarrassed for. While the condensation area is something atmospherically salient, the anchor point roughly correlates with what other accounts regard as the typically unthematic object in the “focus” of the relevant emotion (cf. Helm 2002): In the case of fearing the dog, the focus would be on my cared-for physical integrity, whereas the anchor point would be the anticipated harm. In general, the background object in the focus of an emotion is someone or something the subject cares for, while the anchor point is a particular state of affairs in terms of which the object is presented. However, such correspondences between emotions as atmospheres and intentional feelings only hold with respect to a certain group of phenomena. According to Schmitz’s atmosphere model, we may also be seized by emotions having a thematic center that cannot be differentiated in terms of condensation area and anchor point or having no thematic center at all. A sudden, groundless joy may be “unwarranted” in terms of normative accounts of emotions or regarded as a mood rather than an emotion as it lacks the specific intentional structure. 220
Hermann Schmitz
In the framework presented here, however, it would count as an emotion since it has the relevant kinesthetic impulses characteristic of joy. Once more, Schmitz justifies this claim by pointing to phenomena of affective transitions and arguing that structural distinctions between emotion and mood, target and focus, etc., can be accounted for in terms of additional modifications of one and the same atmospheric feeling (Schmitz 1993, 53f.). Consider, for example, a very effective narrative technique in thriller movies or, say, fairy tales: When entering her grandmother’s cottage, little Red Riding Hood immediately feels uneasy in the form of a diffuse fear. This uneasiness, then, centers on the alleged grandmother who appears somehow strange. The relevant atmosphere now has an area of condensation, but not yet an anchor point. The fear is eventually furnished with such an anchor point when Red Riding Hood realizes that the figure is a wolf intending to eat her. Another ideal-typical modification of one and the same atmospheric feeling would be an instance of embarrassment that begins with noticing the gazes of others and sensing that there must be something wrong with what one does or how one appears. Obviously, the atmosphere of embarrassment has a condensation area, that is, the person who suddenly finds themself awkwardly exposed to the look of the others. However, the concrete anchor point—An open fly? Something said?—is not (yet) present to that person, though obvious to the others. The possibility of such transitions and diffusions suggests that the intentional structures pointed out in often cited emotional episodes, such as fearing the dog, may refer to additional, sometimes even quite unstable, modifications of a more pervasive atmospheric feeling.
6. Atmospheres and their ontological status The previous arguments have important ontological implications which, taken together, amount to the following point: We need to distinguish clearly between the process of feeling something and the emotion as a phenomenon that is felt as an atmospheric force beyond and other than the subject. The atmosphere, and thus the emotion, is an entity prior to the process of feeling. However, it would be a misunderstanding to conceive of atmospheres as some sort of invisible cloud hanging in the environment (Schmitz 2009, 84). Emotions are “half-entities” (Halbdinge) (Schmitz et al. 2011, 256; cf. Andermann 2011) or “quasi things” (Griffero 2017; cf. also Chapter 23 in this volume). “Full-entities”, such as stones, exist continuously and without interruption; with regard to them, causality is divided into cause (e.g., falling stone), mode of influence (e.g., thrust) and effect (e.g., damage to the object hit). The duration of half-entities, in contrast, can be interrupted and, with regard to them, cause and mode of influence are unified (Schmitz et al. 2011, 256). One of the many examples Schmitz cites is the characteristic voice of someone: Bracketing naturalistic assumptions about sonic waves and neurology, that voice simply “resounds, falls silent and resounds again” (ibid.), whereby it is pointless to ask what it did or where it was in the meantime. Moreover, its resounding is both the cause and the mode of influence on the hearer. Likewise, being a half-entity, the very same atmosphere of grief with its specific thematic center can seize you at different occasions, being cause and mode of influence at the same time.
7. Concluding remarks Schmitz arrives at his conception of emotions as seizing atmospheres by proceeding from the idea of a feeling body in communication with its environment. However, even those 221
Henning Nörenberg
sympathetic to Schmitz’s theory often deem his conception of emotions as atmospheres a misleading metaphor (Schmid 2014), misty (Krebs 2015), a contra-intuitive exaggeration (Slaby 2010, 2011), or doubtable (Demmerling 2011). Although I cannot address these criticisms in detail here, the main concern seems to be that conceiving of emotions as atmospheres would imply an implausible reification of emotions in relation to which, in turn, the subject is construed as too passive. I have explicitly dealt with the question of passivity in this chapter and we have also seen how Schmitz would defend his view against the reification charge by referring to the notion of half-entities. I hope to have shown that Schmitz’s atmosphere model should be taken seriously when it comes to grounding emotions in the bodily dimension; moreover, it can accommodate important insights from competing accounts such as the intentional structure of emotions, the evaluative qualities to which they respond and the felt action-readiness they involve.2
Notes 1 At the root of the matter, one of the most central worries seems to be this: Schmitz takes the talk of intentionality to imply what he himself rigidly denies, namely the claim that there would be single, potentially even unrelated portions of meaning prior to the holistic meaningfulness of situations in which the subject finds themself (Schmitz 1994, 136f., 214; 2004, 220; 2012b, 14f.). I have to bracket the question of to what extent this view is fair, precisely because it deserves a broader discussion. 2 This chapter was written as part of the DFG-project “The embodied affective dimension of collective intentionality” (NO 1148/1-1).
References Andermann, Kerstin (2011). Die Rolle ontologischer Leitbilder für die Bestimmung von Gefühlen als Atmosphären. In: K. Andermann and U. Eberlein (Eds.). Gefühle als Atmosphären: Neue Phänomenologie und philosophische Emotionstheorie. Berlin: Akademie, 79–95. Colombetti, Giovanna (2014). The Feeling Body. Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Damasio, Antonio (2004). Emotions and Feelings: A Neurobiological Perspective. In: S. R. Manstead, N. Frijda, and A. Fischer (Eds.). Feelings and Emotions: The Amsterdam Symposium. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 49–57. Demmerling, Christoph (2011). Gefühle, Sprache und Intersubjektivität: Überlegungen zum Atmosphärenbegriff der Neuen Phänomenologie. In: K. Andermann and U. Eberlein (Eds.). Gefühle als Atmosphären: Neue Phänomenologie und philosophische Emotionstheorie. Berlin: Akademie, 43–56. Deonna, Julien, and Teroni, Fabrice (2012). The Emotions. A Philosophical Introduction. London, New York: Routledge. Dewey, John (1931). Philosophy and Civilization. New York, London: G. P. Putnam’s Sons. Frijda, Nico (1988). The Laws of Emotion. American Psychologist 43(5), 349–358. Gallagher, Shaun, and Zahavi, Dan (2012). The Phenomenological Mind (2nd ed.). London, New York: Routledge. Griffero, Tonino (2014). Who’s Afraid of Atmospheres (and of Their Authority)? Lebenswelt 4(1), 193–213. ——— (2017). Quasi-Things. The Paradigm of Atmospheres. Albany: State University of New York Press. Helm, Bennett W. (2002). Emotions as Evaluative Feelings. Emotion Review 1(3), 248–255. Krebs, Angelika (2015). Zwischen Ich und Du. Eine dialogische Philosophie der Liebe. Berlin: Suhrkamp. Metzger, Wolfgang (1975). Psychologie. Darmstadt: Steinkopff. Prinz, Jesse (2004). Gut Reactions. A Perceptual Theory of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ratcliffe, Matthew (2008). Feelings of Being. Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Roberts, Robert C. (2003). Emotions. An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
222
Hermann Schmitz Sartre, Jean-Paul (2002). Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. Transl. by P. Mairet. London, New York: Routledge. Scheler, Max (1973). Wesen und Formen der Sympathie. Gesammelte Werke 7. Bern, München: Francke. Schmid, Hans Bernhard (2014). The Feeling of Being a Group: Corporate Emotions and Collective Consciousness. In: C. von Scheve and M. Salmela (Eds.). Collective Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schmitz, Hermann (1965). System der Philosophie. Band 2-1: Der Leib. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1969). System der Philosophie. Band 3-2: Der Gefühlsraum. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1973). System der Philosophie. Band 3-3: Der Rechtsraum. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1977). System der Philosophie. Band 3–4: Das Göttliche und der Raum. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1989). Die Autorität der Trauer. In: H. Gausebeck and G. Risch (Eds.). Leib und Gefühl: Materialien zu einer philosophischen Therapeutik. Paderborn: Junfermann, 125–134. ——— (1993). Die Liebe. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1994). Neue Grundlagen der Erkenntnistheorie. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (2004). Phänomenologie als Anwalt der unwillkürlichen Lebenserfahrung. Erwägen Wissen Ethik 15, 215–228. ——— (2009). Kurze Einführung in die Neue Phänomenologie. München, Freiburg: Alber. ——— (2011). Der Leib. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter. ——— (2012a): Das Reich der Normen. München, Freiburg: Alber. ——— (2012b). Die Weltspaltung und ihre Überwindung. Rostocker Phänomenologische Manuskripte 14. ——— (2014). Atmosphären. München, Freiburg: Alber. ——— (2015). Von der Scham zum Neid. In: M. Großheim, A. K. Hild, C. Lagemann, and N. Trčka (Eds.). Leib, Ort, Gefühl: Perspektiven der räumlichen Erfahrung. München, Freiburg: Alber, 19–34. Schmitz, Hermann, Müllan, Rudolf Owen, and Slaby, Jan (2011). Emotions Outside the Box: The New Phenomenology of Feeling and Corporeality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10(2), 241–259. Slaby, Jan (2010). Gefühl und Weltbezug: Eine Strukturskizze der menschlichen Affektivität. Rostocker Phänomenologische Manuskripte 8. ——— (2011). Möglichkeitsraum und Möglichkeitssinn: Bausteine einer phänomenologischen Gefühlstheorie. In: K. Andermann and U. Eberlein (Eds.). Gefühle als Atmosphären: Neue Phänomenologie und philosophische Emotionstheorie. Berlin: Akademie, 125–138.
223
.
(
Taylor & Francis Taylor & Francis Group
http://taylorandfrancis.com
PART 2
Systematic issues and contemporary debates
.
(
Taylor & Francis Taylor & Francis Group http://taylorandfrancis.com
20 AFFECTIVE INTENTIONALITY AND THE REACTIVE ATTITUDES Bennett W. Helm
How should we understand the phenomenology of emotions? One standard way is to distinguish sharply between the intentionality and the phenomenology of emotions, understanding their phenomenology in terms of something like “bodily sensations”, which are simply added on to an independent account of their intentionality (cf. Goldie 2000, 40–41). Thus, according to cognitivist accounts of emotions, in feeling fear I am not only aware of the presence of a danger of some sort, but also have a certain sensation in my gut, where it is this bodily sensation that accounts for the phenomenological experience of fear. In an earlier paper (Helm 2011), I argued that this strategy fails, that we cannot separate out the intentionality from the phenomenology in this way. Rather, emotions are what I call “felt evaluations”: phenomenological feelings with evaluative content or, alternately, a distinctively affective form of intentionality. This chapter repeats those arguments and extends them to thinking about the reactive attitudes: emotions like gratitude, resentment, approbation, and guilt. While I shall provide an initial argument for this account in the context of relatively simple emotions like anger and fear (Sections 1 and 2), the motivating intuition is perhaps clearer when we consider the phenomenology of more complex emotions like the reactive attitudes. For with the reactive attitudes, it becomes quite clear that appealing to bodily sensations to make sense of their phenomenology, which might have seemed to work for simpler emotions like fear or anger, is inadequate. While anger and resentment are closely related emotions, the phenomenological difference between them is surely not intelligible merely in terms of bodily sensation. It will not do, for example, to say that this difference is merely a difference in intensity, say. Rather, that phenomenology itself has a complexity to it that cannot be neatly distinguished from the thought that you are responsible for wronging me (as distinct from the thought in anger that you are an obstacle to accomplishing my ends). This suggests that the “affectivity” or “phenomenology” of emotions cannot neatly be separated from their intentionality—that emotions have a distinctively affective form of intentionality. Others who have offered versions of this affective intentionality thesis include: Stocker (1983), Goldie (2000, 2002, 2009), Roberts (2003), Ratcliffe (2005a, 2008a), Döring (2007), and Slaby (2008). Even if we grant such affective intentionality, in which we cannot pull apart the intentionality and the phenomenology of emotions, precisely how we understand that intentional content is important. Here, I differ from other proponents of affective intentionality. For, as 227
Bennett W. Helm
I shall argue, we cannot understand emotions primarily as cognitive perceptions (with mindto-world direction of fit) of an independently existing world (Goldie 2002; Döring 2007); nor can we understand them primarily as conative strivings (with world-to-mind direction of fit) projecting value onto the world (Roberts 2003; Prinz 2004). Rather, the evaluative objects of emotions, or their “import” as I shall call it, are both that to which emotions are properly responsive and that to which we commit ourselves in such a way as to constitute that import. Inasmuch as mind-to-world and world-to-mind directions of fit are supposed to be mutually exclusive and exhaustive, such simultaneous responsiveness to and constitution of the objects of emotions by the emotions themselves reveals that their affective intentionality cannot be understood in terms of the notion of a direction of fit. And yet that emotions are responsive commitments to import is crucial to understanding their phenomenology, for understood this way our felt, committed awareness of emotional objects as good or bad in some way just is a matter of our being emotionally pleased or pained by these objects. There is, of course, a kind of circularity implicit in my rejection of the notion of direction of fit, but, as I shall argue, such circularity is not vicious given the holistic nature of affective intentionality, a holistic nature that is missed by alternative accounts of emotions. My aim in Section 1 is to provide an account of emotions as felt evaluations, an account in which we can recognize this implicit holism. In Section 2, I shall turn to draw out the implications this account has for understanding the affective nature of emotional intentionality. Finally, in Section 3, I shall apply this account of affective intentionality to the reactive attitudes, arguing that this account can make apparent commonly ignored aspects of the affectivity of the reactive attitudes, whereby they bind us together through our having shared values and communal norms.
1. Emotions as felt evaluations Emotions, I have long argued (Helm 1994, 2001, 2002, 2015), should be understood as felt evaluations: feelings of pleasure or pain that are essentially evaluations of their objects. Thus, to feel fear is to be pained by danger, where the evaluation of the object of fear as dangerous is implicit in the feeling of pain; similarly, to feel satisfaction is to be pleased by success. Such feelings are not mere phenomenal states insofar as they are intentional and evaluative. How is it possible for feelings of pleasure or pain to be evaluative and intentional? And how is it possible for such feelings to be not merely components of emotions but actually identical with emotions? In responding to these worries, I shall first discuss the intentional character of emotions before turning in Section 2 to show how this intentionality is distinctively affective. It is commonplace to argue that emotions have several kinds of intentional objects. In particular, the target of an emotion is the object at which the emotion is intuitively directed: In feeling fear as I look out of my house to see some thugs approaching my car, baseball bat in hand, they are what I fear. In feeling emotions, we implicitly evaluate the target in some way, though each emotion type involves a different evaluation that distinguishes it from other emotion types. The kind of evaluation characteristic of a given emotion type is an emotion’s formal object. Thus, roughly, the formal object of fear is dangerousness, for in feeling fear of the thugs, I am implicitly evaluating them as dangerous; likewise, the formal object of anger is offensiveness. The warrant of the fear or anger, therefore, depends on whether its target really is (or intelligibly seems to be) dangerous or offensive (see, e.g., D’Arms and Jacobson 2000). What is not widely recognized in the preceding example is that the warrant of my fear of the thugs depends on whether (and how) the car matters to me—on the import it has to me. 228
Affective intentionality
Thus, if the car was the 1957 Chevy that my father and I lovingly restored before his death, then it is reasonable to think that I care about preserving and protecting it, so that my fear of the thugs would be warranted. On the other hand, my unscrupulous twin, who has an old clunker that he is trying to have totaled for the insurance money, fear of what the thugs might do would be unwarranted; rather, we might think, he ought to hope they do a good job bashing it up. Finally, someone might not care about the car at all (since it’s not hers, say), and her utter indifference would mean that no emotional response would be warranted in the circumstances. The possibility of these other cases points to the idea that understanding my fear in this case and assessing it for warrant requires understanding the relationship between the thugs (the targets of my fear) and my car as something I care about, for it is only in terms of this that we can see how the thugs are intelligibly dangerous. This suggests that we should understand my fear to involve not only a formal object (i.e., dangerousness) and a target (i.e., that which gets evaluated as dangerous: The thugs), but also a focus: That background object having import in terms of which, given the circumstances, the formal object intelligibly applies to the target.
1.1 Emotional commitment to import Some cognitivist theories of emotions try to make sense of how emotions evaluate their objects by providing a reductive account of emotions in terms of beliefs and desires (e.g., Marks 1982). Thus, anger is understood in terms of the belief that its target is offensive and the desire to lash out at it, and fear is understood in terms of the belief that its target is dangerous and the desire to avoid or mitigate that danger. Of course, as cognitivists recognize, to have an emotion is more than just to have such a belief and desire, for one can clearly have the belief and desire without having the emotion. So something more needs to be added to the account to specify the distinctively affective character of the overall intentional state that is the emotion. The trouble is, many attempts to account for the distinctive affective nature of emotions— in terms of an appeal to a special kind of desire (e.g., Marks 1982), to a special kind of belief (e.g., Nussbaum 1994, especially Chapter 10; Solomon 1973, 1976), and to bodily pleasures and pains (e.g., Lyons 1980)—simply fail.1 After all, how is it possible to cash out the special kind of desire (as being especially “strong”) or of belief (as involving “full assent”) without making what in this context would be a viciously circular appeal to the emotions? More fundamentally, to understand the distinctive affectivity of emotions in terms of bodily pleasures and pains (caused in the right way by the relevant beliefs and desires) is to diminish the importance of emotions in our everyday lives in a way that misunderstands emotional pleasure and pain. For emotions do not merely involve some pleasant or painful sensation among other components, as cognitivist theories require. Rather, they are pleasures and pains and can be redescribed as such: To be afraid is to be pained by danger (and not by one’s stomach); such a pain is not a component of, but is rather identical with, one’s fear. This means that emotional pleasures and pains, namely what one feels in having the emotion, are essentially intentional and evaluative, a sense of how things are going—whether well or poorly; this is the root of affective intentionality. Understanding this will require understanding the sense in which emotions are feelings more generally. Phenomenologically, when we are afraid that something might well happen, we feel the dangerousness of some object impressing itself on us in feeling, in something like the way colors impress themselves on us in perception. In this way, the capacity for emotion is a kind of receptivity to evaluative content, to import, and particular emotions are passive exercises 229
Bennett W. Helm
of that receptivity. This implies that the import to which our emotions respond must have a kind of objectivity as that which our emotions apprehend (or misapprehend) and so as that in terms of which particular emotions are to be evaluated for warrant. Nonetheless, that very import to which our emotions ought to respond is itself relative to the individual, constituted by our cares and concerns, as is clear in the difference in attitude between my unscrupulous twin and me with respect to our cars. Indeed, import cannot be understood as independent of emotions in general, for someone’s not being affected emotionally by something no matter what happened to it is pretty solid evidence that it does not have import to them. In short, import is both objective, as rationally prior to particular emotions, and subjective, as conceptually dependent on the shape of one’s emotions generally. The problem, therefore, is to make sense of this objectivity of import and how it can impress itself on us in a way that is consistent with its also being subjective and so somehow constituted by us, and to do so in a way that can make sense of the distinctive kind of affective intentionality emotions involve. The key to solving this is to appeal to the notion of an emotion’s focus. Emotions are not simply responses to some apparent import in one’s situation; they are commitments to the import of their focuses. Such a commitment to the import of the focus is a commitment to feel other emotions with that same focus in the relevant actual and counterfactual situations. As I have argued elsewhere (Helm 2001), when one feels these related emotions in response to such a commitment, the resulting pattern of such emotions itself constitutes the import of that focus. This may seem puzzling: How can it be both that our emotions are responses to import impressing itself on us and that our emotions are commitments that constitute that very import? After all, it might seem that such commitments must be either cognitive, with mind-to-world direction of fit, or conative, with world-to-mind direction of fit; insofar as these directions of fit are mutually exclusive, nothing could have both. Nonetheless, I think that the very notion of direction of fit does not apply to these emotional commitments. (See Helm 2001 for detailed arguments.) For something to have import is for it to be a worthy object of attention and action. That is, other things being equal, if something has import for you, you ought to pay attention to it and act on its behalf when otherwise appropriate. This requires that you be consistently vigilant for its being affected favorably or adversely and prepared to act on its behalf; to fail in general to exhibit such vigilance and preparedness undermines the idea that it really has import to you—that you care about it. Of course, it is consistent with this requirement that you sometimes fail to attend to it or act on its behalf when this is called for; the point is that, absent some legitimate excuse—as when something more important demands your attention—such failures cannot be the rule if it is to be intelligible that you genuinely care about it. Now, the relevance of emotions to constituting import becomes clear. The kind of commitment to import that emotions essentially are is precisely that which constitutes the relevant vigilance and preparedness to act.
Vigilance The commitment to the import of my car that is a part of my anger at the thugs for vandalizing it is in part a commitment to feel a pattern of other emotions with the same focus in the relevant actual and counterfactual situations. Thus, it is a commitment to feeling fear at the approach of a hailstorm (and to being relieved when it passes by leaving my car unscathed), to be worried about the effects of road salt on its finish, to be pleased with how 230
Affective intentionality
easily the salt comes off now that I’ve applied the fancy wax finish, and so on. In this way, having a particular emotion commits me to feeling a broad pattern of other emotions with the same focus. Indeed, other things being equal, it would be hard to make sense of my initial response as that of anger if I were indifferent to the subsequent fate of the car and so felt no fear, relief, worry, pleasure, etc., precisely because the purported commitment I make to the import of the car in feeling the anger would then be shown to be no commitment at all: Being in general responsive to the import of the focus of one’s emotions is a condition of the intelligibility of having the capacity for emotions in the first place. Consequently, genuine commitments to import are not merely intellectual assents to an evaluation but also dispose one to be vigilant for what happens to this focus, where this vigilance consists in the broader pattern of emotions with the same focus projecting into the future. Actually, to have such a projectible pattern of emotions with a common focus, then, is to be vigilant in a way that is necessary for that focus to have import. Moreover, such a pattern of emotions also makes intelligible the idea that its focus is worthy of attention. For the pattern, once it is in place, is no mere disposition to attend; it is rather partly definitive of the warrant of its elements as a rational response to their common focus. For example, given the pattern it would be rationally inappropriate not to be sad when I am forced to sell the car by my financial circumstances, for such a failure would be a failure to attend to my circumstances as I ought, precisely because of the pattern of commitments these emotions focused on the car involve. Conversely, it is the presence of that pattern of other emotions that makes intelligible the warrant of my current anger. In short, the pattern of emotions with a common focus is not merely projectible, but it is rational as well; this rationality makes the focus of that pattern intelligible as worthy of attention.
Preparedness Of course, emotions are not merely ways of attending to the import of one’s circumstances, for they also, in many cases, move us to intentional action. (Emotions can move us to mere non-intentional behavior as well, as when we tremble from fear; such non-intentional behaviors are arational expressions or evincings of the emotions, and I shall simply set them aside here as not relevant to the kind of preparedness for action that is partly constitutive of import, though see Helm 2016 for some details.) Thus, fear might lead us to escape the danger, and anger or jealousy to seek revenge. In such cases, the emotion explains the action by motivating it in such a way as to make it intelligible within a broader context of rationality: The evaluation implicit in the emotion’s formal object justifies the action by revealing it to have a point, to be (other things being equal) worthwhile in the present circumstances. Such a point can be an end to be achieved, as in the examples just provided, but it need not be. Jumping for joy and crying out of sadness are not goal-directed activities. Nonetheless, each has a point: The point of jumping for joy is to celebrate a success, and the jumping just is that celebration; likewise, the point of crying out of sadness is to mourn a loss, and the crying just is that mourning. In each case, this point is made intelligible by the specific kind of import to which joy and sadness are properly responsive. For this reason, I understand such nongoal-directed intentional actions given a point by an emotion to be rational expressions of that emotion and so of one’s commitment to the import of its focus. We can now see that to have not merely a single emotion but a whole pattern of emotions to which one is committed by virtue of each emotion’s commitment to the import of its focus involves not merely a kind of vigilance for what happens to that focus but also a preparedness to act on its behalf when otherwise appropriate. As before, such a pattern makes 231
Bennett W. Helm
intelligible that focus as worthy of action: It would be rationally inappropriate, other things being equal, for me to fail to lash out at those who intentionally seek to damage my car, precisely because the more general pattern of emotions of which this anger is a part, each of which is itself a commitment to import, is essentially a rational pattern.
1.2 Constituting import The upshot is that these projectible, rational patterns of emotions with a common focus constitute that focus as being worthy of attention and action and so as having import. In short, to have import is to be the focus of such a pattern of emotions, and it is these patterns that make intelligible the subjectivity of that import. To emphasize this subjective aspect of import, I shall sometimes speak of the subject’s caring about something, intending by this the overall evaluative attitude of the subject constitutive of the import things have to her. Nonetheless, these patterns also make intelligible the objectivity of import. For to have such a pattern of emotions is to be disposed to respond to situations of a certain kind, where we cannot specify that kind of situation except in terms of the import of the focus of that pattern. Hence, the pattern of emotions is in effect an attunement, a habituation of one’s sensibilities, to that import. Given the rationality of the pattern, any particular emotional response (or even failure of emotional response) is assessed for warrant in terms of whether it fits into this pattern as an intelligible projection of it—as, that is, a proper or improper response to the import of its focus. (Of course, there is the further question about whether it is rational to have the whole pattern—whether it is rational for the focus of that pattern to have import for one. This further question is about a richer kind of objectivity I cannot discuss here. See Helm (2000, 2001) for details.) And given the projectibility of this attunement of our sensibilities, we can make sense of that import as impressing itself on us: It is situations of this kind—i.e., those involving import—that engage our emotions because these emotions are already attuned to that import by virtue of the broader projectible, rational pattern of which they are a part. Import, therefore, impresses itself on us by not only grabbing and holding our attention but also priming us to act appropriately. In short, particular emotions are feelings of things going well or poorly, the result of import impressing itself on us. This is possible only because these emotions are commitments to the import of their focuses, commitments which, when they are non-defective, define and institute a broader projectible, rational pattern that both constitutes that import and makes possible its impressing itself on us, grabbing our attention and motivating us to act. Thus, I shall say, emotions are felt evaluations insofar as they are commitments of this kind: Commitments that both are passive responses to attend to and be motivated by import and are simultaneously constitutive of that import by virtue of the broader rational patterns of which they are a part and which they serve to define. (This account of import as constituted by projectible, rational patterns of felt evaluations is developed in more detail in Helm 2001, in the context of a more general account of value.)
2. Affective intentionality In light of this account of emotions as felt evaluations, we can understand the sense in which they are pleasures and pains, thereby confirming the phenomenological description of emotions presented above (Section 1.1). Emotions are pleasant or painful—they feel good or bad—precisely because, as felt evaluations, they are feelings of positive or negative import, where such feelings are modes of caring about something as a proper focus of one’s concern. 232
Affective intentionality
Thus, to feel fear is to be pained by danger, this distinctive kind of import, in the sense that the danger impresses itself on one, grabbing one’s attention and motivating one to act; the emotional response, the feeling of this danger, just is the pain. Likewise, to feel joy is to be pleased by some good in the sense that the good impresses itself on one in feeling and motivating celebration. This account of pleasure and pain as felt evaluations, therefore, both reveals how pleasures and pains intrinsically motivate and explains the intuition that pleasure and pain have a special connection to import. Notice that this understanding of the phenomenology of emotions does not have anything to say about bodily sensations that may accompany the emotions. This is intentional: The phenomenology that is distinctive of emotions, I have argued, is to be understood in terms of a distinctive kind of evaluation now revealed to be felt evaluations. What it is like to feel emotional pleasure or pain is to have one’s attention gripped by the goodness or badness of something in such a way that one thereby feels the pull to act appropriately. Of course, we often do feel accompanying bodily sensations which themselves contribute to the overall phenomenal experience. Indeed, insofar as our human responsiveness to import takes place by means of the ways our body responds to the environment, it would seem that James (1884) is right to point to the way our bodies are a kind of “sounding board” for significance (for an interpretation of James along these lines, see Ratcliffe (2005b, 2008b), and Slaby (2008) is right to point to this as central to our human-affective intentionality. However, while such bodily sensations are central to our human experience of emotions, I do not see that this is essential for affective intentionality: There is nothing incoherent about the thought that a disembodied creature or someone anesthetized and unable to feel their body might nonetheless have distinctively emotional pleasures and pains of the sort I have described. (In his postscript, James (1884, 204–205) discusses the case of someone “entirely anaesthetic, inside and out, with the exception of one eye and one ear” who nonetheless, it is claimed, “had shown shame on the occasion of soiling his bed, and grief, when a formerly favourite dish was set before him, at the thought that he could no longer taste its flavour”. James argues that this case does not refute his theory; I read it as further evidence for the account of felt evaluations I have offered.) The upshot is that the affective character of emotions, their phenomenology, cannot be separated from their evaluative character. Indeed, this points us to the idea that emotions have a distinctive affective intentionality: pleasant or painful feelings involving a characteristic evaluation (via the formal object) of the target in light of its bearing on the focus. Such affective intentionality, I have argued, is made intelligible in terms of an understanding of emotions as felt evaluations. Two features of affective intentionality are worth drawing out explicitly here. First, this sort of emotional feeling of import is neither a response to an antecedently existing object nor a response that simply projects its object onto the world: It has neither mind-to-world nor world-to-mind direction of fit. Rather, our affective intentionality is simultaneously both responsive to and constitutive of import, and it—this single, indecomposable mental state—is simultaneously both perceptual and motivating. Such an account of affective intentionality is fundamentally at odds with that offered by cognitivist theories of emotions, which presuppose the notion of direction of fit and, therefore, understand the perceptual and motivational aspects of emotions to be distinct. Moreover, this is at odds with the still common understanding of mental states as propositional attitudes, which supposes that such propositional content is independent of any attitude we might take toward it. Rather, affective intentionality cannot be understood as attitude-independent in this way. Consequently, we must reject what Goldie (2000) calls “add-on” theories of emotions, including cognitivist accounts. 233
Bennett W. Helm
The second feature of affective intentionality is made intelligible by the first: Affective intentionality is essentially holistic. By this, I mean not merely that a felt evaluation in one circumstance is rationally connected to felt evaluations in other (actual and counterfactual) circumstances by virtue of their commitment to the import of a common focus. In addition, this rational pattern of emotions involves a commitment to import that constitutes that very import, thereby making intelligible how such import can impress itself on us in feeling particular emotions. That one, in general, exhibits such a holism of affective intentionality, therefore, is a condition of the possibility of one’s having the capacity for affective intentionality at all. (Of course, it is possible to have emotions that are isolated from such a general pattern of emotions; in such a case, the emotions will be responsive to something that does not, in fact, have import and consequently will be unwarranted. Such unwarranted emotions cannot be the rule, or we would be unable to make sense of the subject as having the capacity for emotions: Rationality is the constitutive ideal of the mental (Davidson 1980; Dennett 1987). This is why I have understood the sense in which holism is necessary for affective intentionality at the level of the capacity for it, rather than the exercise of that capacity in particular cases.) This understanding of affective intentionality as having neither mind-to-world nor world-to-mind direction of fit and as essentially holistic is at odds with alternative accounts of affective intentionality that understand that intentionality in quasi-perceptual terms (Goldie 2000, 2002, 2009; Roberts 2003; Prinz 2004; Döring 2007). As felt evaluations, emotions are not merely a registering of how our concerns bear on the world, of import, for to understand them merely in these terms is wrongly to understand these concerns to be independent of and prior to our emotions themselves. While it is correct to understand import to impress itself on us pleasantly or painfully in our having particular emotions, this is intelligible only insofar as those emotions themselves are simultaneously commitments to that import, commitments that partially constitute it. In this way, the feeling of import just is a feeling of one’s commitment to the emotion’s focus, a dimension of affective intentionality that alternative accounts miss.
3. Phenomenology of the reactive attitudes The distinctive affective intentionality of emotions, I have argued, is intelligible in terms of the idea that emotions are felt evaluations: feelings of pleasure or pain simultaneously responsive to and constitutive of import, of one’s caring about something. I now want to consider how this account of affective intentionality applies to the reactive attitudes, which are much richer and more complex emotions and whose phenomenology is, therefore, more challenging to understand. The notion of the reactive attitudes was introduced by Strawson (1962); they are emotions like resentment, gratitude, indignation, approbation, guilt, and pride whereby we hold each other responsible, or ourselves take responsibility for certain actions. Part of what is distinctive of the reactive attitudes is that they are interpersonal not merely in the sense that they are responsive to the actions of persons but more fundamentally in the way in which the reactive attitudes of different people are interpersonally linked. For example, if I elbow you out of the way as I jump into the buffet line, you ought to feel resentment, I ought to feel guilty, and others ought to feel disapprobation or even indignation. It is no accident that these all occur together. Indeed, part of what coordinates our emotional responses is that your resentment and their indignation are not merely private emotions but amount to blaming me, such that my feeling of guilt will often be a response to the sting of that blame. 234
Affective intentionality
There are two puzzles here that an account of affective intentionality can resolve. First is a phenomenological puzzle concerning the “sting” of blame (or the “warm glow” of praise): How is it that your responding to the negative (or positive) import of my norm violation (or upholding) other things being equal ought to cause me a distinctive kind of pain (or pleasure)? Why should your expressing a negative (or positive) attitude toward what I have done have this sort of effect on me? Note here that it is not good enough to say that it is because I care about what you think of me, for part of the question is what that caring consists in and, crucially, what motivates it. As will become apparent, resolving this puzzle requires simultaneously resolving a second puzzle: the intentionality puzzle. To what are we each responding that can motivate our concern for each other and that can thereby explain why our respective reactive attitudes are non-accidentally coordinated? We can begin to see how to resolve the intentionality puzzle by considering first your resentment. In resenting me, you are responding not merely to the fact that I have harmed you with my sharp elbows, but also to the fact that in doing so, I have violated the norm of taking turns, and your resentment expresses your caring about that norm—expresses the import it has. Yet to make sense of the blaming character of your resentment, we must recognize that your concern is also with me as having a certain standing as someone who is bound by this norm, as well as with yourself and others—certain witnesses—as having the authority to hold me responsible to it. After all, if you were a visitor to my community or culture, one in which we do not have norms of taking turns but instead normally use our elbows to jockey for position, you would not have the authority to hold me to norms from your community, nor would I have the standing as being bound by your norms; in such a case, your resentment would be unwarranted. This suggests that for your resentment to be warranted, you and I must both be members of the same community one of whose norms I have violated in a way that harms you. Likewise, others’ indignation will be warranted only if they are also members of this community. This points us to a common object that can resolve the intentionality puzzle. Central to the reactive attitudes is that the concern they manifest is for these norms as communal norms and for standing and authority as communal statuses. From the subjective perspective, this means that the commitment you have is to the import these things have not merely to you but rather to us: It is a joint commitment to our norms, our standing and authority. In this way, your resentment addresses me and calls on me to feel guilty and on others to feel disapprobation and thereby to reaffirm our shared commitment to the communal norm and to each of our communal status. It is in virtue of this call that I ought to feel guilt and that they ought to feel disapprobation, for it is a call you make from your position of authority as one of us and it is through this call that you blame me and thereby hold me responsible for what I have done (Helm 2017, 2018). Consequently, the relevant rational patterns constitutive of the import of these norms and of our standing and authority are an essentially interpersonal pattern in virtue of which we jointly care about the norms and about our standing and authority. So far, I have described the reactive attitudes from the subjective perspective from which we can appreciate the distinctively interpersonal form of intentionality these emotions involve. In particular, the interpersonal nature of the focus of the reactive attitudes is never far from the surface through our joint commitment to its import, through our holding each other responsible, and through the recognition this involves of the communal status we each have as being bound by the communal norms and as having the authority to enforce them. Indeed, as I have argued elsewhere (Helm 2017), we should understand the focus of the reactive attitudes ultimately to be the community to which we belong, so that we are committed to the import of the norms and of our standing and authority only as a part of that 235
Bennett W. Helm
broader commitment to the import of the community itself. This distinctively interpersonal form of intentionality found in the reactive attitudes thus depends on the essentially holistic nature of that intentionality and on the way this makes sense of how the reactive attitudes both constitute the import of their focuses and are responsive to that very import. Such responsiveness brings us to the objective perspective on import from which we can resolve the phenomenological puzzle about why I feel the sting of blame expressed in your resentment. As discussed in Section 1.2, particular emotions are a kind of attunement to import such that in feeling an emotion, one feels this import impressing itself on one pleasantly or painfully, thereby making sense of the affectivity of emotional intentionality. The same is true of the reactive attitudes, though the essentially interpersonal character of the reactive attitudes somewhat complicates the resulting phenomenology. When I elbow my way into line, the negative import of my violation of this communal norm ought to impress itself on us painfully: on me in being pained by the wrong I have inflicted on you (a pain that is identical with my guilt), on you in being pained by my culpability in thus harming you (a pain that is identical with your resentment), and on witnesses in being pained by that same culpability (a pain that is identical with their disapprobation). Of course, even though I ought to feel the pain of guilt, I may not: I may not recognize that I have just violated a communal norm, being inadequately attuned to the import this norm has for us. It is in part here that the interpersonal nature of the affective intentionality of the reactive attitudes shows through. When you express your resentment, what you express is something’s having not merely private import but communal import: the import this norm violation has to us. In this way, you are doing something to impress—you are pressing—that import on me. (The same is true of witnesses’ pressing that import on me through the expression of their disapprobation.) That is, you (and they) are not merely calling my attention to the import of my norm violation, something I should have noticed all along. In addition, your reproach and your authority as one of us press on me your pain and my role in causing it: This is the “sting” of blame. (The same holds true, mutatis mutandis for your gratitude pressing on me the positive import of my notably upholding a communal norm, giving rise to the “warm glow” of praise.) Moreover, the interpersonal character of the affective intentionality of the reactive attitudes is not confined to just praise and blame. My guilt likewise presses on you both the negative import of my norm violation and my recognition of your authority to hold me responsible for this. (This indicates that what explains the coordination of our reactive attitudes cannot simply be the fact that I feel the sting of blame from your resentment because I somehow have an antecedent concern for what you think of me: The concern is for mutual standing and authority of each other, and it is a concern I ought to manifest even prior to your resentment’s pressing that import on me.) In each case, what impresses itself on us is the joint import not only of someone’s notably upholding or violating a communal norm but also of the standing and authority we each have as bound by the norm and able to hold each other responsible to it. That such joint import can do so depends on our emotional capacities already being a kind of attunement and receptivity to that joint import of both the relevant norms and of others as fellow members of a community.
4. Conclusion My aim in this chapter has been to present an account of the richness and depth of affective intentionality and thereby to argue against alternative accounts that understand emotions to be much less rich and interesting. We cannot assimilate the affective intentionality of our emotions to some non-affective intentionality of other mental states or to non-intentional 236
Affective intentionality
affectivity of anything like “raw feels”, an all-too-common thought that makes emotions out to be relatively uninteresting mental states. Rather, the picture of emotions I have presented here is of something much more interesting and far more complex than is often allowed. The holism of affective intentionality not only is a central part of the capacity for emotions quite generally; it also grounds our deepest interpersonal connections. We ought not ignore the potential for such complications in initially formulating a more general theory of emotions and affective intentionality.2
Notes 1 Of course, the few brief remarks I provide here are far from a knock-down argument against cognitivist theories of emotions. (For more fully worked-out arguments, see Helm (2001, especially Chapter 2). My aim here is merely to suggest that a different tack might prove fruitful: In order to understand the nature of affective intentionality, we need to understand the sense in which their implicit evaluations are pleasures or pains. 2 This chapter derives from Helm (2011), updated slightly to extend the point to my recent account of the reactive attitudes. Thanks to mentis for permission to reprint a modified version of §§1–2 of the original article.
References D’Arms, Justin, and Jacobson, Daniel (2000). The Moralistic Fallacy: On the “Appropriateness” of Emotions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61(1), 65–90. Davidson, Donald (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. New York, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Dennett, Daniel C. (1987). The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Döring, Sabine A. (2007). Seeing What to Do: Affective Perception and Rational Motivation. dialectica 61(3), 363–394. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2002). Emotions, Feelings, and Intentionality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1, 235–254. ——— (2009). Getting Feelings into Emotional Experience in the Right Way. Emotion Review 1(3), 232–239. Helm, Bennett W. (1994). The Significance of Emotions. American Philosophical Quarterly 31(4), 319–331. ——— (2000). Emotional Reason: How to Deliberate About Value. American Philosophical Quarterly 37(1), 1–22. ——— (2001). Emotional Reason: Deliberation, Motivation, and the Nature of Value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2002). Felt Evaluations: A Theory of Pleasure and Pain. American Philosophical Quarterly 39(1), 13–30. ——— (2011). Affektive Intentionalität: Holistisch und vielschichtig. In: J. Slaby, A. Stephan, H. Walter, and S. Walter (Eds.). Affektive Intentionalität: Beiträge zur welterschließenden Funktion der menschlichen Gefühle. Paderborn: mentis, 72–99. ——— (2015). Emotions and Recalcitrance: Reevaluating the Perceptual Model. dialectica 69(3), 417–433. ——— (2016). Emotional Expression, Import, and the Reactive Attitudes. In: C. Abell and J. Smith (Eds.). Expression of Emotion: Philosophical, Psychological and Legal Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 95–114. ——— (2017). Communities of Respect: Persons, Dignity, and the Reactive Attitudes. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2018). Personal Relationships and Blame: Scanlon and the Reactive Attitudes. In: K. Hutchison, C. Mackenzie, and M. Oshana (Eds.). Social Dimensions of Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press. James, William (1884). What Is an Emotion? Mind 9(34), 188–205. Lyons, William (1980). Emotion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Marks, Joel (1982). A Theory of Emotions. Philosophical Studies 42, 227–242.
237
Bennett W. Helm Nussbaum, Martha C. (1994). The Therapy of Desire. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Prinz, Jesse J. (2004). Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ratcliffe, Matthew (2005a). The Feeling of Being. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12(8–10), 43–60. ——— (2005b). William James on Emotion and Intentionality. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 13(2), 179–202. ——— (2008a). Feelings of Being: Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2008b). What William James Really Said. In: Feelings of Being: Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Roberts, Robert C. (2003). Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Slaby, Jan (2008). Affective Intentionality and the Feeling Body. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7(4), 429–444. Solomon, Robert C. (1973). Emotions and Choice. The Review of Metaphysics 27(1), 20–41. ——— (1976). The Passions. New York: Anchor Press. Stocker, Michael (1983). Psychic Feelings: Their Importance and Irreducibility. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61(1), 5–26. Strawson, Peter F. (1962). Freedom and Resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy 48, 187–211.
238
21 THE VARIETIES OF AFFECTIVE EXPERIENCE John J. Drummond
1. Introduction Affective experience broadly construed encompasses several related and interwoven, but non-identical, kinds of experiences and states. These different kinds overlap, mixing with one another in various ways. Moreover, each is itself a complex phenomenon requiring detailed analysis. Consider, for example, Peter Goldie’s description of an emotion as “complex, episodic, dynamic, and structured” (2000, 12). An emotion is complex insofar as it contains many elements: perceptions, thoughts, or beliefs; bodily changes; feelings; and a variety of dispositions (2000, 12–13). It is episodic and dynamic insofar as elements come and go as the emotion waxes and wanes (2000, 13). And it is structured, on Goldie’s view, in that it is part of a narrative in which it is embedded (2000, 13, see also 144). Whether one agrees with the details of Goldie’s analysis, his brief description of jealousy provides an example of how characterizing one affective state—an emotion—points to others, in this case, a character trait: If you are a jealous sort of person, then you are a person who, in some sense, is disposed to be jealous in your relationships. And when you become jealous of Jane’s relationship with John, then you are actually having the emotion. And this emotion—your jealousy of that relationship—can itself involve all sorts of episodes and dispositions regarding that specific relationship. Thus, both the character trait of being jealous and the emotion of being jealous involve dispositions, but the latter are more specific than the former. So, to say, for example, that James is jealous can, according to context, mean one of three things: it can mean that he is a jealous type (the character trait); it can mean that he is jealous of this relationship (the emotion); or it can mean that he is currently experiencing a particular jealous thought or feeling (the emotional episode). (Goldie 2000, 13–14) Goldie also notes that emotions are distinguished from moods in having more specific objects than moods (2000, 17); they are distinguished, in other words, as specific and nonspecific emotions (2000, 144). But, despite their difference, emotions and moods can morph into the other (2000, 148). 239
John J. Drummond
Taking Goldie’s distinctions as a starting point, this chapter will investigate the different kinds of affective experience. I shall, like Goldie, consider an emotion to be the compound of emotion-episodes and emotion-states. I shall, however, construe the specifically dispositional character of an emotion as an affective trait, and I shall distinguish this, in turn, from a character trait. Finally, I shall distinguish sentiments from both affective and character traits and also from moods. The limitations of space mean that these distinctions can only be sketched, but the discussion will serve to illuminate both the differences between and the relations among affective phenomena.
2. Emotions My discussion will focus on the intentional structure of the emotions. Let us briefly consider an emotion-episode. When a subject encounters a situation as affectively and evaluatively charged—a fearful subject experiencing a dangerous situation, say, or an indignant subject experiencing an unjust situation—there are “facts of the case” in terms of which we understand what it is about the object of the emotion that motivates it. To put the matter another way: Objects affect us and evoke feelings in us such that we apprehend the object as (dis)valuable just insofar as we apprehend it as having certain non-axiological properties. There are two philosophical claims embedded in this description: (1) Valuing an object involves intentional feelings or emotions, and (2) this feeling or emotion is rooted in what Franz Brentano (1995, 60–61) calls a “presentation” or what we might more generally call a cognitive state (perception, memory, imagination, judgment) that grasps the object’s non-axiological features. The early phenomenologists—those working (roughly) in the first third of the 20th century, such as Edmund Husserl (see 1988, 2004), Adolf Reinach (1912/13), Edith Stein (1989, 2007), Max Scheler (1973), Nicolai Hartmann (1963), and Dietrich von Hildebrand (1916, 1922, 1953)—agree with the first claim. There is, however, significant disagreement regarding the second claim, a disagreement best exemplified in the difference between Husserl and Scheler. Husserl claims that an intentional feeling-act is founded on an act, e.g., a perceiving or judging, that presents an object (Husserl 1970a, 569–576; 1988, 252). I have elsewhere argued for three modifications to the Husserlian view, although the modifications are to some extent motivated by Husserl’s own texts. First, I stress the fact that mind is essentially an openness to the world, that mind is an intertwining of cognitive-theoretical, axiological, and practical aspects and interests, and that intentionality is first predicated of the directedness of mind as a whole, by virtue of intentionality’s temporal and horizonal character, to the world as a whole (Drummond 2012, 115, 125; 2013, 251). Second, this entails that our original encounter of the world is a complex mixture of these aspects and interests, a point that becomes clear in Husserl’s description of the natural and personalistic attitudes (Husserl 1989, 183–210; 2014, 48–52); hence, “pure” perception and judgment are abstractions from concrete experience rather than founding experiences (Drummond 2013, 251). Third, this, in turn, entails that the foundational relations belong primarily to the significance an object has for us; the axiological significance of the object is founded on the cognitive sense of the non-axiological properties that motivate the intentional feeling or emotion (Drummond 2013, 252). This last is my version of claim (2) above. Scheler (1973), by contrast, affirms a feeling-intentionality through which value-objects are directly apprehended a priori. The prior apprehension of the value-object (typically an ideal value-characteristic) underlies the grasp of the object bearing the value as good or bad. Said another way, the experience in an emotion-episode of the object as good(bad) 240
The varieties of affective experience
apprehends the instantiated value as the good(bad)-making characteristic of the bearer. The (dis)value does not depend on any non-axiological properties of the bearer or any psychological features of the subject experiencing it. As Scheler puts it, We know of a stage in the grasping of values wherein the value of an object is already very clearly and evidentially given apart from the givenness of the bearer of the value. Thus, for example, a man can be distressing and repugnant, agreeable, or sympathetic to us without our being able to indicate how this comes about; in like manner we can for the longest time consider a poem or another work of art “beautiful” or “ugly,” “distinguished” or “common,” without knowing in the least which properties of the contents of the work prompt this. Again, a landscape or a room in a house can appear “friendly” or “distressing,” and the same holds for a sojourn in a room, without our knowing the bearers of such values (…) Clearly, neither the experience of values nor the degree of the adequation and the evidence (…) depends in any way on the experience of the bearer of the values. Further, the meaning of an object in regard to “what” it is (whether, for example, a man is more “poet” or “philosopher”) may fluctuate to any degree without its value ever fluctuating. In such cases the extent to which values are, in their being, independent of their bearer clearly reveals itself. (Scheler 1973, 17–18) Hence, the feeling-apprehension of the value remains divorced, as it were, from the experience of the bearer’s non-axiological features. This divorce leads to some paradoxical results. Consider an episode of fear, as when a growling Doberman Pinscher is charging you with its teeth bared. We would ordinarily think that this fear is directed at the charging dog taken as dangerous. The dog is the proper object of the fear, the danger its “improper” object (see Mulligan 2017, 233). On Scheler’s view, however, the value-characteristic is the proper object of the intentional feeling; that is, we fear danger itself (rather than the dog). That does not, however, fit the phenomenology of particular emotion-episodes in which we are directed to objects. Moreover, insisting on the independence and priority of the value-apprehension makes it difficult to understand how one would answer the question, why are you fearful? Consider now the first example that Scheler mentions: Taking an immediate dislike to someone you have never before met but now see entering the room where a lecture is to be delivered. Suppose, however, that someone who knows the person and to whom you report your dislike challenges you because she thinks your dislike is unjustified. You respond, “I don’t know; there was just something about the way he walks and surveys the room—kind of haughty.” Your interlocutor might then seek to change your judgment by evoking a different sense of the person. She will attempt to lead you to “see” the person in a new way, to conjure a new understanding, highlighting aspects previously absent from your view and thereby leading you first to see and then to feel differently about the person. To successfully “persuade” you, she must evoke a different feeling grounded in a different understanding of the person (Drummond 2005, 368). These appeals to reasons—more specifically, to nonaxiological features of the object or situation motivating the emotion—are precluded by Scheler’s view. They also clearly point in the direction of the second claim: That feelings or emotions are rooted in cognitive states grasping the object’s non-axiological properties. Consider also Scheler’s claim that “the meaning of an object in regard to ‘what’ it is (whether, for example, a man is more ‘poet’ or ‘philosopher’) may fluctuate to any degree without its value ever fluctuating.” This claim points even more fundamentally toward the 241
John J. Drummond
need for a cognitive basis for evaluation. The problem arises from the difference between logically predicative adjectives and logically attributive adjectives (Geach 1956; see also Williams 1993, 38–47; Drummond 2005, 2013). Adjectives that name properties predicable of different species and transferable from species to genus are logically predicative, e.g., yellow lemon, yellow banana, and yellow fruit. By contrast, those adjectives that cannot be transferred from species to genus are logically attributive, and evaluative terms belong to this class. The problem can be put this way. Logically predicative adjectives determine a substantive without regard to the kind of substantive determined and without regard to the subject experiencing them. They name a property-species, one that can be instantiated without equivocation in objects of different kinds. Logically attributive adjectives are related differently to their substantives. They determine the sense of an object only in relation to a particular (natural or non-natural) kind; they attribute something to the object as an instance of a kind. There is no single property-species ‘good’ that is unequivocally instantiated in both houses and persons or in both poets and philosophers. When the adjective “good” is used in relation to a house, it means one thing, and when it is used in relation to a hammer, it means another; when used in relation to a poet, it means one thing, when used in relation to a philosopher, it means another, and when used in relation to a person, yet another. That the logically attributive adjective does not name a property-species is the reason why inferences permissible with logically predicative adjectives are impermissible with logically attributive adjectives. One cannot validly infer ‘Jones is good’ from ‘Jones is a good poet.’ Being good does not necessarily belong to Jones both as poet and as person. Similarly, were Jones to abandon poetry for philosophy, we cannot infer from ‘Jones is a good poet’ that ‘Jones is a good philosopher.’ The good that belongs to Jones as a poet is not the same good that belongs to Jones as a philosopher. An identical value-attribute ‘good’ will not transfer if one is more a poet than a philosopher or vice-versa, unless Scheler is suggesting that Jones is a good person regardless of whether poet or philosopher. However, if this is all Scheler means, then his point is simply irrelevant in establishing the independence of the valuecharacteristic across different kinds. The fact that value-attributes make sense only in relation to a kind underscores the claim that our evaluation of things is rooted in the non-axiological sense that belongs to the presentation of an instance of a particular kind. We can say, for example, that Jones is a good poet or a good philosopher or a good person only if we have general beliefs about what it is to be a poet or a philosopher or a person as well as particular beliefs regarding Jones’ characteristics relevant to the kind under consideration (Drummond 2005, 365–367). These arguments against the Schelerian view support my understanding of the second (foundational) claim mentioned at the outset of this section. Turning to Husserl’s view of the role of feelings in affective experience, we note first that Husserl’s notion of feeling is multi-faceted. He distinguishes bodily feelings—feeling-sensations, as he calls them—from feeling-acts (Husserl 1970a, 569–576). A bodily feeling is a sensory state of the organism, the sensory awareness of physiological changes undergone in the emotional experience, such as changes in facial expressions, skeletal muscles, vocal expression, and the autonomic nervous system as well as changes underlying the hedonic valence of the emotion. A feeling-act, by contrast, is an intentional feeling directed upon an object. This distinction is best understood, in my view, non-ontologically. A single set of feelings is considered in two different respects, in relation to the body and in relation to the object. While feeling-sensations are distinct awarenesses of, say, the tightening of abdominal muscles and the horripilation on the back of the neck characteristic of fear, intentional feelings 242
The varieties of affective experience
arise insofar as the distinct feeling-sensations “are typically aspects of a whole pattern that constitutes a world-directed attitude,” a “bodily attitude” as Julien Deonna and Fabrice Teroni call it (2012, 79). This feeling-Gestalt is what I am calling the intentional feeling (but cf. Claparède 1928, 128), although I do not accept Deonna and Teroni’s view that the emotion is exhausted by a bodily attitude. The intentional feeling is motivated by the object’s non-axiological properties and rooted in the feeling-sensations, but it is also informed by the subject’s experiential history, interests, concerns, and commitments. When these elements come together, the intentional feeling or emotion discloses the object, broadly speaking, as (dis)valuable. Intentional feelings and emotions lie on a continuum, where the place on the continuum is a function of the degree of determination in our sense of the object’s underlying non-axiological properties. An intentional feeling alone intends “thin” axiological attributes (unpleasant or distressing), whereas the emotion-episode intends “thick” axiological attributes (dangerous or unjust). Think of the difference, for example, between disliking (and disvaluing) a steak’s taste (an intentional feeling) and experiencing disgust in seeing that the steak is infested with maggots (an emotion). The episode of disgust is grounded in a more determinate cognitive content—the meat being maggot-infested (the example is from Goldie 2004, 97–98)—than is disliking the taste. Or recalling Scheler’s first example, we can say that the sense of the non-axiological features underlying your intentional feeling of dislike directed toward the person entering the room is highly indeterminate. Supposing your acquaintance fails to persuade you, and as the person’s continued behavior confirms your view of him as pompous, boastful, dismissive of others, and so forth, your dislike “thickens” into contempt. Your initial indeterminate intending is now more determinate; the indeterminate intention has been, as Husserl puts it, more precisely determined (Husserl 1997, 49–50). You now have more reasons supporting your view of the person. To summarize: the emotion-episode is inclusive of the following intertwined elements: (1) A (more or less determinate) cognitive grasp of the object; (2) physiological changes caused by the object (some of which are also expressive of the emotion); (3) the sensory awarenesses of those changes (feeling-sensations); (4) a Gestalt-like felt attitude rooted in the feeling-sensations and directed toward the object of the emotion (intentional feeling); and (5) the influence of the subject’s physiological constitution, experiential history, interests, concerns or cares, and commitments. All these contribute to the evaluative appraisal of the object in the emotion-episode. There is no emotion without at least one emotion-episode. As noted above, however, an emotion can extend beyond the initiating episode. Suppose I become angry at a colleague for a false and defaming remark at a department meeting. Such anger might endure for several days (or more) even though my attention has turned to other matters and the physiological changes and feeling-sensations associated with anger have dissipated. A second episode of this anger might be triggered by encountering the offending faculty member in the hallway two days later, only to have the anger subside again as I move on and once again attend to other matters. The anger ceases only upon sinking far enough into the past to be forgotten (although even then the anger can be rekindled), or when the offense is forgiven, or when the offender apologizes, or when a decision is made to put it aside. The emotion as enduring beyond and between emotion-episodes is the emotion-state. The emotion-state, however, does not possess all five elements of the emotion-episode. When attention is turned to other matters, although I continue to be angry, the anger becomes, as it were, unconscious. It is experienced (erlebt) unthematically. More importantly, since the motivating experience of my colleague’s remark is no longer perceptually present 243
John J. Drummond
to me and the anger has become non-thematic, the characteristic physiological changes cease and, along with them, the feeling-sensations. How does the emotion continue in the absence of these features? Husserl’s notion of retention provides the key. Retention is the holding-in-grasp of an experiential moment that has elapsed (Husserl 1991, 29–36). Husserl’s classic example is the retention of a musical tone as it slips into the past and is replaced by a new tone. The retention, Husserl notes, is as present as the hearing of the new tone, but the elapsed tone is present only in an extended sense; it is present as fading way. The present phase of an experience is an extended present that encompasses not only the presently sounding tone and the elapsed tone, but also an anticipation (protention) of yet-to-come tones. In the case of an emotion, the cognitive base of the emotion-episode is retained in a continuing experience of the emotion. And while the physiological changes and feelingsensations cease, the felt Gestalt, the bodily attitude, that presents the object as (dis)valued is also retained. Consider again the case of anger directed at my colleague. When the meeting is over, the offense is done, and I am physically separated from my colleague’s presence, the motivating source of the anger—my colleague and his actions—is no longer perceptually available, and I no longer undergo physiological changes and feeling-sensations. My interests, concerns, and commitments draw my attention to other things, and my anger, while not ceasing, becomes non-thematic. When I see my colleague two days later or when an associated interest or commitment turns my memory to the original remarks (the retained cognitive base), I experience another emotion-episode. Although the offending remarks re-occur only as remembered, as past, the retained intentional feeling as a bodily stance toward my colleague and his actions is reawakened and organizes my physiological states as though the offending remarks were themselves re-actualized. My bodily attitude toward my (perceived or memorially present) colleague re-presents him as having offended. In this way, the emotion cycles through periods of emotion-episodes. Throughout the emotion-state, the intentional feeling stands ready to recognize as (dis)valued the thing that was originally presented in the cognitive base of the initiating emotion-episode and is now re-presented in the continuing course of experience. It is my whole being, as embodied mind, that experiences the emotional response to the object upon which the emotion is directed.
3. Traits Emotions can be either appropriate or inappropriate. An emotion is appropriate when (1) its cognitive base is true and justified; (2) its cognitive base, given a subject’s physiological condition, experiential history, interests, concerns, and commitment, rationally motivates the emotion; and (3) the emotion is rationally justified (Drummond 2017, 156). We can rephrase (2) and (3) to say that the cognitive base provides both (a) motivating reasons for a subject having a particular physiological constitution, experiential history, interests, concerns, and commitments to have an emotion that attributes a (dis)value to its object and (b) epistemically justifying reasons for the attribution of the value. The justification presumes an acquaintance with the relevant emotion- and value-concepts so that one can determine whether the emotion experienced is fitting given the circumstances and whether the intensity and duration of the emotion are fitting to the provocation. The determination that an emotion is not a fitting response involves a second-order emotion directed to the first and evaluating it as inappropriate. For example, my anger at my colleague might have been an overreaction, and experiencing embarrassment, regret, or shame will signal that fact to me. 244
The varieties of affective experience
Moreover, the acquaintance with the relevant emotion- and value-concepts is necessary to determine whether the justifying reasons, in fact, support the valuation or instead support some other valuation of the object (Drummond 2017, 156–160). When a subject experiences an object and, as is true in ordinary experience, believes in the existence of that object as experienced, the subject acquires a “conviction” that becomes an enduring part of that subject’s experiential life (Husserl 1970b, 66). The subject believes that the above-mentioned conditions for appropriateness are satisfied and that the experience is truthful. When the subject’s experience takes the form of a judgment and the judgment is confirmed, the conviction gains strength and is understood as a conviction to which the subject can and does return again and again. The more continuous and consistent the confirmation is (or the subject takes it to be), the more the conviction determines future experience. It takes on the character of an “abiding habitus” (Husserl 1970b, 67). The same pattern for developing convictions is true for the emotions (whether they have a non-propositional or propositional content) and their value-correlates. I adopt an emotional attitude toward things and the world, and this emotional attitude takes the form of a conviction, an abiding habitus that affectively shapes subsequent experiences. Such “habitualities,” as Husserl calls them (1970b, 66), are dispositional in character. They dispose me to experience the world in ways that conform to the convictions I hold. It is in this context that we should understand the notion of traits. Imagine, for example, that my colleague who angered me regularly angers me. Meeting after meeting, I come away experiencing anger and judging that this colleague has offended me or others in the department. These continued judgments regarding the wrongdoing of my colleague form a habitus that disposes me to feel anger when dealing with this colleague. This emotional disposition is what I am calling an affective trait. A character trait differs from an affective trait. The affective trait disposes me to feel one emotion—anger—and to feel it in relation to only one person—this colleague. This is not to say, of course, that I do not occasionally get angry at other people. It is to say only that if I possess the affective trait only in relation to my colleague with whom I am regularly angry and disposed to get angry, then my occasional anger at others does not manifest the trait. I am not irascible in general. Of course, it is clear that some people are accurately described as hot-tempered, quick-tempered, or irascible. If I were to get angry regularly in my interactions with other people, I would be such a person, and my irascibility would be considered not merely an affective trait but a feature of my character, a character trait. Similarly, if someone were to react with fear to a broad range of things and situations— whether or not the fear is appropriate, the subject believes it is—then that person could be described as fearful or timorous. Here, again, the disposition to experience fear—the character trait—is limited to the one emotion, but the object of the fear is not limited to any one object or even one type of object. The character trait—fearfulness or timidity—disposes the subject to fear many different and many different kinds of things and situations. Affective traits and character traits are similar in that they involve one emotion, but they differ in that the affective trait targets one object, whereas the character trait targets many. It is important to note that traits—whether affective traits or character traits—are not natural dispositions characteristic of a kind of substance. Solubility in water is a natural disposition of salt and sugar, but irascibility and timidity are not natural dispositions of persons. Traits are acquired over a course of experience, and, as such, they are personal and normative in character insofar as they reveal to us what a person “ought” to do. This “ought” is not deontic (Goldie 2000, 142); it is a way of stating what we can expect the person to do given his or her traits. 245
John J. Drummond
4. Sentiments and moods Two kinds of affective experiences—sentiments and moods—have a broader scope than emotions and the affective and character traits associated with them. Sentiments are like emotions in that they involve emotion-episodes and -states. However, the dispositional character of the traits rooted in an emotion differs from that of a sentiment. The dispositions associated with traits are dispositions to experience one emotion; they are what Deonna and Teroni call “single-track dispositions” (2012, 8). The dispositions associated with sentiments, by contrast, can motivate different kinds of emotional experience; they are “multi-track dispositions.” The most obvious example of a sentiment is love (and, conversely, hatred). Love manifests itself in emotions such as affection, admiration, pride (in the beloved’s accomplishments), grief (at the loss of the beloved), fear (of the loss of the beloved’s affection), jealousy (of the beloved’s relations with a rival—supposed or real—for the beloved’s affection), and anger (at the beloved’s supposed or real betrayal). Similarly, hatred manifests itself, for example, in episodes of enmity, anger, resentment, loathing, and joy at the misfortune of the hated (Schadenfreude). Moods are a more complicated matter. Moods can be distinguished from emotions in a variety of ways: (a) Emotions have specific objects and moods have non-specific objects such that “mood can ‘focus’ into emotion and emotion can blur out of focus into mood” (Goldie 2000, 8), which indicates that their difference is a matter of degree (Goldie 2000, 17–18, 143ff.); (b) emotions have specific or particular objects; moods do not and, therefore, are not intentional (Deonna and Teroni 2012, 4, 105); (c) moods are the unity of feelings as manifested in a dominant affective attitude directed toward the world as a whole, and they provide the horizon for particular, individuated emotional experiences (see, e.g., Husserl [1900–1914] Ms. M III 3 II 1, 29–30; [1931] Ms. A VI 34, 19–22); and (d) moods are the manifestation of the transcendental structure of disposedness (Befindlichkeit), and they “first make possible directing oneself toward something” such that “things that matter to us can be encountered” (Heidegger 2010, 133–134). Each of these suggestions has something to recommend it. I shall, however, focus briefly on (c) and (d) because they represent the two most significant phenomenological alternatives, although I shall at least comment on their relation to (a) and (b). The major differences between (c) and (d) concern the grounding of moods and their relation to emotions. Disposedness (Befindlichkeit), along with understanding and discourse, is for Heidegger an ontological structure of Dasein (i.e., of being-in-the-world). Disposedness, like understanding and discourse, is not an intentional act in the Husserlian sense of being directed to a worldly entity; it is pre-intentional (Crowell 2013, 70). Disposedness manifests itself in Dasein’s affective life and, in particular, in moods. In structuring Dasein’s Being-in-theworld, mood further makes possible the disclosure of things in the world. Mood accounts, in particular, for the disclosedness of the world as a whole (Heidegger 2010, 133), and mood underlies emotions, which are directed to particular entities within the pattern of meaning structured by mood. To this extent, Heidegger agrees with (b)—moods do not have particular objects—and rejects (a). For Husserl, by contrast, a mood is a unity of intentional feelings (Gefühlseinheit), which Husserl conceives as a “passive association of feelings” (Husserl [1931] Ms. VI 34, 19). This unity can be viewed as a Gestalt that organizes the varied feelings of a subject into a dominant affective attitude toward the world as a whole, i.e., what Husserl later specifies as the lifeworld (Lee 1993, 36). Recalling my modifications to the Husserlian view outlined above, we can say that mood is the affective dimension that belongs to intentional mind as a whole. 246
The varieties of affective experience
Stated so simply, the view seems similar to Heidegger’s, but there are important differences, for on the Husserlian (and my) view, intentionality is a basic notion, whereas it is not for Heidegger. A mood arises from an emotion whose defining characteristic informs—Husserl uses the well-worn metaphor “colors”—a subject’s entire outlook on the world: If I am in a good mood, then it propagates itself easily, as long as contrary tendencies or opposite affects do not intervene (…) In the process the mood always retains an “intentionality.” I distinguish between what is given, its value-character, and what, motivated by them, serves as my mood. This is a unitary feeling (Gefühlseinheit) that lends a color, a unitary color, to everything that appears—a unitary glow of joy, a unitary darkness of sorrow (…) Is this cheerful mood itself intentionally directed? We must affirm this (…). (Husserl [1900–1914] Ms III 3 II 1) Moods not only arise from emotions; they are distinguished by the emotions from which they arise. A pattern of joyful experiences gives rise to a cheerful mood, and a pattern of fearful experiences gives rise to an anxious mood. In this, Husserl agrees with (a) that emotions can transmute into moods, although he differs with Goldie’s view that the transformation reflects only a matter of degree in the specificity of the object. Moreover, while Husserl, here agreeing with Heidegger, thinks moods underlie emotions, they do not transform themselves into emotions by specifying their object. Instead, a positive mood disposes me to positive emotions, while a negative mood disposes me toward negative emotions. A person in a cheerful mood is likely to more frequently and fully experience emotions such as serenity, gratitude, kindness, contentment, and enthusiasm than someone who is not in a cheerful mood. Similarly, someone who is depressed is more likely to experience negative emotions such as worry, frustration, hopelessness, and despair. In this way, a mood and the individual emotions from which the mood arises and which it underlies are inseparable. The emotions and the bodily comportments belonging to them are manifestations of mood. Heidegger stressed the fact that moods reveal Dasein’s thrownness. “Mood assails,” says Heidegger (2010, 133), thereby disclosing Dasein to itself “before all cognition and willing and beyond their scope of disclosure” (Heidegger 2010, 132; Heidegger’s emphases). The view of mood I am developing here runs counter to this view. It claims instead that moods arise out of the emotional experiences of particular objects. Does this mean that moods do not assail us? No. Recalling that emotions are rooted not only in non-axiological properties of their objects but also that an object’s relation to a subject’s physiological constitution, experiential history, and interests, concerns, and commitments, it is possible to recognize that all these subjective conditions can contribute to a mood’s assailing us. The passive constitution of a unitary feeling directed to the world as the horizon of all our experience can, precisely because it is passive, force itself upon us. For example, a person’s genetic inheritance (physiological constitution) can dispose one to depression or, at the least, make one vulnerable to it. Medical conditions (e.g., physical conditions such as paraplegia, substance abuse, cancer) can all occasion depression. Childhood experiences (experiential history) can motivate depression, or a previous, strongly negative emotional experience associated with a place can, upon returning years later to that place, motivate a sad or angry mood, or if the earlier experiences were positive, a nostalgic mood. Continuing and permanent frustration of the satisfaction of one’s interests, concerns, or commitments—current stressors, as it were—can occasion irascibility or depression. And so on. In such cases, the mood is not motivated by the separate emotional experience of an object. Rather, the mood 247
John J. Drummond
is motivated by a multiplicity of experiences having a similar hedonic valence passively associating with one another such that they form the Gestalt, the unitary feeling characteristic of moods. This notion of mood as a kind of universal affective state is the frame for all our affective experience. As the affective dimension of mind as a whole and its world-directed intentionality, and given its dispositional character, it is central not only to mind’s disclosure of an affectively charged world but to our affective experiences of particular objects.
References Brentano, Franz (1995). Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Transl. by A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and L. L. McAlister. New York, London: Routledge. Claparède, E. (1928). Feelings and Emotions. In: M. Reymert (Ed.). Feelings and Emotions: The Wittenberg Symposium. Worcester, MA: Clark University Press, 124–139. Crowell, Stephen (2013). Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. New York: Cambridge University Press. Deonna, Julian, and Teroni, Fabrice (2012). The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction. New York: Routledge. Drummond, John (2005). Value-Predicates and Value-Attributes. In: J. Marek and M. Reicher (Eds.). Erfahrung und Analyse / Experience and Analysis: Proceedings of the 27th International Wittgenstein Symposium. Vienna: öbv & hpt, 363–371. ——— (2012). Intentionality without Representationalism. In: D. Zahavi (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 115–133. ——— (2013). The Intentional Structure of Emotions. Logical Analysis and the History of Philosophy / Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse 16, 244–263. ——— (2017). Having the Right Attitudes. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 15, 142–163. Geach, Peter (1956). Good and Evil. Analysis 17, 33–42. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2004). Emotion, Feeling, and Knowledge of the World. In: R. Solomon (Ed.). Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 91–106. Hartmann, Nicolai (1963). Ethics. Transl. by S. Coit. New York: Humanities Press. Heidegger, Martin (2010). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Stambaugh. Albany: State University of New York Press. Hildebrand, Dietrich von (1916). Die Idee der sittlichen Handlung. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 3, 126–251. ——— (1922). Sittlichkeit und ethische Werterkenntnis. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 5, 463–602. ——— (1953). Ethics. Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press. Husserl, Edmund (1900–1914). Unpublished archival manuscript M III 3 II. ——— (1931). Unpublished archival manuscript A VI 34. ——— (1970a). Logical Investigations. Transl. by J. N. Findlay. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. ——— (1970b). Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. Transl. by D. Cairns. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. ——— (1988). Vorlesungen über Ethik und Wertlehre 1908–1914, Ed. by U. Melle. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (1989). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. Transl. by R. Rojcewicz, and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (1991). On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time (1893–1917). Transl. by J. Brough. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (1997). Thing and Space: Lectures of 1907. Transl. by R. Rojcewicz. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (2004). Einleitung in die Ethik: Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1920/1924. Ed. by H. Peucker. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (2014). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. First Book: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Transl. by D. Dahlstrom. Indianapolis: Hackett.
248
The varieties of affective experience Lee, Nam-In (1993). Edmund Husserls Phänomenologie der Instinkte. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Mulligan, Kevin (2017). Thrills, Orgasms, Sadness, and Hysteria: Austro-German Criticisms of William James. In: A. Cohen, and R. Stern (Eds.). Thinking about Emotions: A Philosophical History. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 223–252. Reinach, Adolf (1989[1912/1913]). Die Überlegung: ihre ethische und rechtliche Bedeutung. In: K. Schuhmann, and B. Smith (Eds.). Sämtliche Werke. Textkritische Ausgabe. München: Philosophia, 279–312. Scheler, Max (1973). Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values: A New Attempt toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism. Transl. by M. Frings and R. Funk. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Stein, Edith (1989). On the Problem of Empathy. Transl. by W. Stein. Washington, DC: ICS Publications. ——— (2007). An Investigation Concerning the State. Transl. by M. Sawicki. Washington, DC: ICS Publications. Williams, Bernard (1993). Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
249
22 EXISTENTIAL FEELINGS Matthew Ratcliffe
1. What are existential feelings? For all of us, there are times when the world seems somehow distant, not quite there, when we feel strangely dislodged from everything and everyone. On other occasions, we feel unusually at home in the world, secure, at peace, even ‘at one’ with our surroundings. Such experiences are not localized; they concern an all-enveloping sense of reality and of being rooted in a world. For most of us, most of the time, this changes only in subtle ways. However, more pronounced changes, which can be fleeting or enduring, are phenomenologically conspicuous and often remarked upon. They are usually described in terms of ‘feelings’, rather than ‘moods’ or ‘emotions’. My attention was first drawn to these feelings in 2005. I was writing a paper and thought about calling it ‘The Feeling of Being’. So I did a Google search to check whether anybody had already used that title. I was immediately struck by the variety of feelings that appeared among the results, most of which did not feature in standard inventories of moods and emotions. To illustrate this, I selected the following examples from the first 50 hits: The feeling of being: ‘complete’, ‘flawed and diminished’, ‘unworthy’, ‘humble’, ‘separate and in limitation’, ‘at home’, ‘a fraud’, ‘slightly lost’, ‘overwhelmed’, ‘abandoned’, ‘stared at’, ‘torn’, ‘disconnected from the world’, ‘invulnerable’, ‘unloved’, ‘watched’, ‘empty’, ‘in control’, ‘powerful’, ‘completely helpless’, ‘part of the real world again’, ‘trapped and weighed down’, ‘part of a larger machine’, ‘at one with life’, ‘at one with nature’, ‘there’, ‘familiar’, ‘real’. (Ratcliffe 2005, 45) This list encompasses considerable diversity. Even so, most of the above have two features in common: They are ‘feelings’ (in some sense of the term) and they also amount to ways of relating to the world as a whole. Some established ‘emotions’ and ‘moods’ share these characteristics, but most do not. To be more specific, some tokens of some emotion- and mood-types are like this, while others are not, an observation that applies to hope, guilt, and despair (Ratcliffe 2015). However, most of the ‘feelings of reality and belonging’ that feature in everyday discourse and other contexts are not referred to as moods or emotions at all. Some do not even have established names and are instead conveyed through elaborate 250
Existential feelings
experiential descriptions, of a kind that can be found in good literature. In other cases, successful reference is achieved without recourse to description. For instance, one can appeal to familiar causes with which certain experiences are reliably associated, as when feeling jetlagged or hung-over. In other cases, we rely on metaphors and analogies. A feeling is often said to be ‘like’ something more localized and concrete, such as like looking at the world from behind a sheet of glass, being on a different planet from everyone else, or having a head full of cotton wool. To distinguish these experiences from a wider range of affective phenomena, I introduced the term ‘existential feeling’ (Ratcliffe 2005). It is a technical term, intended to single out a distinctive and philosophically neglected aspect of human experience that cuts across established categories of phenomena. In short, existential feelings are variants of a non-localized, felt sense of reality and belonging, something that all intentionally directed experiences and thoughts presuppose. When I have an emotional experience of p, perceive q, or think about r, I already find myself in a world, situated in a realm where it is possible to direct oneself towards entities, events, and situations in these and other ways. Two characteristics are jointly necessary and together sufficient for distinguishing existential feelings from other kinds of experience (Ratcliffe 2008, 2012a, 2015, 2017a). First of all, they are ‘feelings’, meaning that they are essentially bodily experiences. Nevertheless, they are not exclusively bodily. Rather, they are relational—a feeling of the body is also that through which one experiences something else. This observation is not specific to existential feeling, and others have plausibly argued that a wider range of feelings are not merely ‘bodily’. For instance, Goldie (2000) distinguishes ‘bodily feelings’ from ‘feelings towards’, where the latter are intentionally directed experiences with objects external to the body. In later writings, he makes clear that the two are not mutually exclusive; some but not all bodily feelings are also feelings towards (Goldie 2009).1 Existential feelings comprise a distinctive subset of those feelings that are not exclusively bodily. What singles them out is a second characteristic: They also constitute a sense of how one finds oneself in the world as a whole. Other feelings involve experiencing and relating to something more specific, against the backdrop of this wider relationship with the world. In addressing what it is to ‘find oneself in the world’ in one or another way, I have drawn on the work of several philosophers. For instance, my account of existential feeling is influenced by Heidegger’s discussion of ‘mood’ (Stimmung) and ‘attunement’ or ‘moodedness’ (Befindlichkeit) in Being and Time (Heidegger 1927). Several works by William James (e.g., 1902, 1912), which describe how felt relationships with the world shape all experience and thought, also provide valuable insights. And one could draw on numerous other historical sources when investigating this aspect of experience, including discussions of ‘self-feeling’ (Selbstgefühl) in philosophy and psychiatry, from the 18th century onwards (Rzesnitzek 2014). One might worry that talk of a ‘felt sense of reality and belonging’ or a ‘way of finding oneself in the world’ is too vague and suggestive. I have, therefore, sought to provide a more specific and discerning account of what existential feelings consist of, by emphasizing the manner in which we experience possibilities. Drawing on phenomenologists such as Husserl (1948, 1952, 2001) and Merleau-Ponty (1945), I maintain that our experiences of things include a sense of various practical and perceptual possibilities involving them. For instance, the visual experience of a drinking glass ordinarily incorporates possibilities such as touching it, picking it up, and drinking from it. These possibilities are inextricable from a range of felt, bodily dispositions, such as the inclination to reach out towards something or retreat from it. Both Husserl and Merleau-Ponty add that localized experiences of possibility presuppose a more enveloping orientation, a sense of belonging to the world. When I see or think about something, 251
Matthew Ratcliffe
when I am afraid of something, and when I am in a bad mood about a wider situation, I already find myself in the world, in a way that differs in kind from intentional experiences in one or another modality (e.g., imagining, perceiving, or remembering something). This ‘world’ is presupposed by intentional states of whatever kind with whatever content. We can think of it in terms of a possibility space, a receptivity to types of possibility. Different existential feelings, I suggest, involve differences in the types of possibility to which one is receptive, differences that are integral to experience rather than consisting of non-experiential dispositions. Things are experienced as significant to us, as mattering to us, in different ways, something that involves a sense of the possibilities they offer. For instance, something might appear threatening in one or another manner, or immediately useful in the context of a project. Alternatively, it might offer the possibility of hope or disappointment, security or insecurity. The interpersonal realm includes a host of further possibilities, such as communion, rejection, admiration, and shame. We can specify a type of possibility independently of any contingent experiential content. A hammer may appear practically significant in a certain way in relation to a particular project, such as assembling a bookcase. However, the type of practical significance it has can be considered without reference to a specific tool, project, or capacity of the tool (e.g., hitting nails). All manner of things can be experienced as immediately relevant to furthering one’s aims in the context of one or another goal-directed project. Types of possibility can be further differentiated in terms of (a) whether they involve encountering something as certain, possible, likely, or doubtful; (b) whether something appears significant to me, to us, to her, or to them; and (c) whether they concern something to be brought about through one’s actions, the actions of others, or by others’ means. There is also a broad distinction to be drawn between a sense of being able to do something and a sense of its mattering. Something can appear pressing but unachievable or, alternatively, achievable with ease but of little consequence. These possibilities hang together as a cohesive whole, involving various relationships of implication and mutual implication. Even so, types of possibility are to some extent dissociable from each other. We can understand all-enveloping changes in the sense of reality and belonging as changes in the types of possibility one is open to. A world in which everything appeared bereft of its usual tangibility would be a world where everything appeared distant, ‘not quite there’. A world bereft of possibilities for communion with others would involve a different kind of disconnectedness and unreality, a sense that I am not ‘there’, not part of a consensus realm. The question of exactly which types of possibility our experience incorporates and how they interrelate remains open. My proposal is that we seek to chart the possibility space and distinguish the types of change it is susceptible by interpreting various ‘existential changes’ that people describe, rather than first getting our house fully in order and only then applying the analysis. In the process, we can also further explore how various bodily feelings contribute to one or another variant of existential feeling (Ratcliffe 2015).
2. Applications The concept of existential feeling can serve to cast light on experiences that are otherwise elusive. For instance, people with psychiatric diagnoses such as ‘major depression’ and ‘schizophrenia’ often report profound experiential changes, which are sometimes described in terms of ‘inhabiting a different world’ or having lost something fundamental to life. Some add that their inability to adequately express these experiences, along with an inability or unwillingness on the part of others to understand, can exacerbate feelings of distress, isolation, and helplessness that are central to the experiences in question. 252
Existential feelings
Time and time again, those with diagnoses of severe psychiatric illness either explicitly refer to a loss of possibility or offer descriptions that are plausibly interpreted in these terms. For instance, those who write about their experiences of ‘depression’ often state that it seemed inconceivable to them that they would ever recover, that the world of depression was experienced as inescapable, eternal. This can be understood in terms of erosion or loss of the ability to experience and contemplate certain types of possibility. In the most extreme case, the world is bereft of the possibility of ‘anything changing for the better’. It is not simply that one ceases to hope for p or for q but that the world appears devoid of the possibility of hope. As the prospect of positive change is altogether absent, one cannot contemplate the more specific possibility of recovering from depression. So, what might look like a propositional belief of the form ‘I do not believe that p’ is actually the expression of a more encompassing existential predicament (Ratcliffe 2015).2 One could thus say that an appeal to existential feeling contributes towards the explanation of various types of experience. Accounting for an experience in terms of existential feeling does not amount to a causal explanation, but it does involve identifying relationships of phenomenological dependence and implication, which can be understood as ‘explanatory’ in a more permissive sense of the term (Sass 2010). This approach also facilitates more fine-grained and discriminating analyses, which accommodate forms of experience described in terms of the body, time, the interpersonal realm, and the ability to act (Ratcliffe 2015). So it can contribute to the task of providing more principled classifications for one or another purpose, thus informing research and treatment. For instance, suppose one seeks to investigate the neural correlates of experience x. One will not get very far if the initial sample of x includes a range of quite different experiences, x, y, and z, which one has failed to distinguish from one another. Likewise, the efficacy of one or another pharmacological treatment cannot be adequately gauged if one is unable to distinguish its effects on different populations. In addition, recognizing the possibility of ‘existential differences’ between people can aid empathy, in the clinic and more widely. In assuming that the world of another person is fundamentally like one’s own and that any differences concern experiences that arise within a common world, one will remain oblivious to profoundly different forms of experience. An initial openness to potential existential differences can facilitate a better understanding of someone else’s experience, an understanding that may be recognized as such by that person (Ratcliffe 2012b, 2015). Therapeutic responses can also be informed by an appreciation of how existential feelings constrain self-regulation and self-interpretation, and of when and how those constraints might be circumvented. The ‘prison’ of depression is a case in point; asking someone to entertain a future scenario involving positive change will be unhelpful if that person is incapable of doing so. To complicate matters, what a person experiences as impossible need not be impossible for him, even at the time. For instance, while he might be unable to entertain the possibility of self-transformative interpersonal interactions, of a kind that could rekindle the possible and restore feelings of connectedness, he might remain capable of such interactions, at least with some individuals in some environments. The study of existential feeling can thus be combined with that of self-regulation and its interpersonal context, in a way that has potential implications for practice (Stephan 2012a, 2012b; Varga and Krueger 2013; Ratcliffe 2018). Employing the concept of ‘existential feeling’ to understand anomalous experiences can serve not only to illuminate the experiences in question but also to corroborate, elaborate, and refine our analysis of existential feeling, by (a) drawing attention to a substantial and diverse body of testimony, which consistently points to the conclusion that experience incorporates a sense of the possible, and (b) indicating how this sense of the possible is malleable, 253
Matthew Ratcliffe
enabling us to further explore the diversity of existential feelings and to make more precise distinctions between them. One does not simply apply phenomenological research; one also does original phenomenological research in the process. Psychiatric illness is not the only circumstance in which existential feelings undergo marked change. Similar points apply to illness and healthcare more generally (Carel 2013). The concept of existential feeling has also been put to work in other contexts. Various authors have discussed how it can be integrated into a broader account of affective phenomena (see, e.g., Slaby et al. 2011; Fingerhut and Marienberg 2012).3 There is also the question of how existential feeling might feature within a wider social and cultural perspective on affectivity (Slaby 2012, 2019). Other areas where the concept has been used to illuminate otherwise elusive forms of experience include art and aesthetics (Saarinen 2014) and cinema (Eder 2016). There is even a discussion of how existential feelings are conveyed by children’s picture books (Mallan 2017). The concept may prove especially fruitful in the study of religious experience and belief. For instance, it has been proposed that religious conversion be understood in terms of changed existential feeling. Along with this, it has been suggested that ‘belief in God’ sometimes consists not in endorsement of the proposition that a specific entity exists but in the expression of a type of existential feeling, a way of inhabiting the world that lends itself to religious interpretation (Wynn 2012, 2013).4 The concept of existential feeling is not something that we first have to accept and only subsequently apply in one or another of these domains. It is something that we can come to better appreciate and further explore by using it as a lens through which to interpret various experiences.
3. Interpretations So far, I have focused on my own understanding of ‘existential feeling’. However, the term is not always used in quite the same way. For example, McLaughlin (2009) takes existential feelings to be experiences with intentional contents that can be veridical or otherwise. He further suggests that they operate as evidence in some instances of delusional belief, via an “acceptance” route from feeling to belief. We are, he says, poorly equipped to handle “affective illusions” and the force of a feeling often overrides other relevant factors. McLaughlin notes that our uses of the term are “very close” (2009, 152). However, there is also an important difference. According to my account, existential feelings comprise a possibility space within which McLaughlin’s ‘existential feelings’ arise. For example, one might have an overriding intentional feeling that is expressed propositionally as the feeling that recovery is impossible. At the same time, this feeling is symptomatic of a wider background of existential feeling, of a world bereft of certain possibilities. So the difference between us is a terminological one. Even so, some of McLaughlin’s points apply equally to existential feeling in my sense of the term. For instance, I accept that existential feelings of ‘control’ and ‘safety’ can be appropriate or inappropriate to a given situation, revealing or deceptive. However, if we think of existential feeling as a changeable possibility space, it is often difficult to determine whether or why an existential feeling is situation-appropriate or otherwise, especially when it comes to the question of whether it is ‘world-appropriate’. It is plausible, I have suggested, that certain recalcitrant philosophical disagreements have their source in subtly different and often unacknowledged ‘ways of finding oneself in the world’, something that is repeatedly emphasized by William James (Ratcliffe 2008, chap. 9; 2017, chap. 10). Here, it is far from clear how to arbitrate between conflicting feelings, as one’s intuitions concerning what is and is not an appropriate or adequate philosophical engagement with the world are partly symptomatic of those same feelings. 254
Existential feelings
There are also different approaches to the individuation and classification of existential feeling. Slaby and Stephan (2008) endorse a conception of existential feeling that is consistent with my own. Nevertheless, we part company when it comes to classification. They distinguish different “levels” of existential feeling, involving varying degrees of “situational specificity” and “conceptual impregnation” (510). There is a basic level of “pure” existential feeling, which includes being alive, having a body, a sense of the world’s existence, and a sense of being situated within a world. At the next level, there are feelings of familiarity, unfamiliarity, homeliness, and security. Then come feelings of anxiety, control, and vulnerability, or lack thereof. Finally, there are feelings of being watched, unloved, abandoned, and the like. One concern I have here is that different ‘levels’ of feeling sometimes look more like different ways of describing the same feeling. A pervasive feeling of abandonment can add up to a sense of lacking control and, with this, of facing a strangely unfamiliar world. Furthermore, a combination of abandonment, passivity, and unfamiliarity can amount to an experience of being dislodged from the world, of inhabiting a realm where nothing seems quite real. We can better see how these aspects of experience interrelate once we analyze them in terms of a possibility space. However, it is plausible to suppose that different feelings incorporate different degrees and kinds of ‘conceptual impregnation’. I regard existential feeling as an inextricable constituent of our wider experience, rather than a separable component. It is something we can fruitfully think of in isolation from conceptualization and self-narrative. But, in practice, existential feelings (at least when they are phenomenologically salient) are indeed conceptualized in one or another way and often bound up with more elaborate self-interpretations. In addition, how one interprets an existential feeling can play a role in regulating and altering that feeling. Nevertheless, if we want to distinguish and classify existential feelings, I think it is more fruitful to restrict ourselves to the structure of the possibility space, to a single phenomenological ‘level’. When we talk of more or less deep or profound existential feelings, what we are actually referring to is the profundity of a shift from one existential feeling to another, the extent to which the possibility space is altered (Ratcliffe 2015, chap. 5). To include conceptual content as a criterion for individuation would be to risk an endless proliferation of feeling-types. Suppose we admit, say, “the feeling of ‘belonging to the elite’” (Slaby and Stephan 2008, 510). This opens the floodgates to all manners of conceptually enriched feelings, such as a ‘post-Brexit feeling of estrangement and helplessness’ or a ‘feeling of being lost in the electronic age’. Having said that, I acknowledge that more fine-grained classifications are useful for some purposes. For instance, references to Brexit or to a political elite can serve to identify a more specific focus of concern that is relevant to the causation, self-interpretation, and regulation of the feeling in question. So, to some extent, the classificatory choice here is a pragmatic one, with one or another degree of specificity being better suited to a given area of inquiry or practice.5 There is also the wider issue of how existential feelings relate to various other affective phenomena that do not feature in standard lists of emotions and moods. For example, Stern (2010) discusses the experience of “vitality”, something that is usually “hidden in plain view”, permeating experience and activity without being explicitly acknowledged or remarked upon. His emphasis is slightly different from mine, as he is interested in the “dynamic qualities of the experience” in contrast to “background feelings”. However, there is clearly overlap, given Stern’s emphasis on the “feel” of “being alive”, something I would not want to regard as separate from existential feeling (Stern 2010, 45–46).6 As I will make clear in the final section, existential feelings are also inseparable from what we might call an overarching ‘dynamic quality’ of experience. 255
Matthew Ratcliffe
Other close relatives of existential feeling include what Gendlin (1978) calls the “felt sense” of a problem or situation, and the “background feeling” described by Colombetti (2014, chap. 5), which she regards as “very close” to my “existential feeling”. We could seek to get our shared terminological house in order. On the other hand, it would be a lot easier to endorse pluralism, not only about the range of affective phenomena but also about how they should be classified for one or another purpose. Even if we settle for this, it is important that terminological differences are acknowledged by all parties concerned and—where a lack of clarity remains over whether we are talking about the same thing—further clarified. Otherwise, there is the risk of confusing terminological differences with substantive disagreements. To illustrate how this can happen, consider the relationship between Heidegger’s discussion of ‘mood’ in Being and Time and my account of existential feeling, which is strongly influenced by Heidegger. Fernandez (2014) argues that if we are to understand phenomenological changes in psychiatric illness, we should draw on Heidegger in a different way. He proposes that experiences of ‘depression’ sometimes involve disturbances of ‘situatedness’ that are more profound than alterations of existential feeling. To make his case, he distinguishes between ‘structure’ and ‘mode’. While Heidegger’s ‘moodedness’ (Befindlichkeit) refers to an invariant structure of human existence, moods (Stimmungen) of whatever kind are its contingent modes. Depression, according to Fernandez, can involve a diminution of structure, rather than a mere shift in the moods that depend upon it. He maintains that Heidegger’s own analysis fails to capture this, given that it does not acknowledge the possibility of structural changes. As my ‘existential feeling’ corresponds roughly to Heidegger’s ‘mood’, I am guilty by association; I likewise assume that “everyone must have the same basic structure of human existence” (Fernandez 2014, 601–602). At first, I took this to be a substantive disagreement and, given this, the criticism struck me as misplaced. I explicitly state that changes in existential feeling are changes in the types of possibility to which one is receptive. In so doing, I emphasize how the sense of being situated in a world can be profoundly diminished. The main difference between my approach and that of Fernandez is that I seek to discern a range of qualitatively different disturbances, and reject a simple diminution-loss model as too crude. It is not enough to postulate a “wholesale leveling-down of sense and meaning” (Fernandez 2014, 606); the sense of being situated in a world can be eroded in all sorts of different ways. So, if an appeal to existential feeling does not accommodate ‘structural changes’, it is unclear what a ‘structural change’ actually amounts to. However, I now suspect that the disagreement is terminological in origin. I doubt that Heidegger has a consistent account of what changes in and differences between ‘moods’ consist of. His various remarks strongly indicate that at least some ‘moods’ correspond to changes in the types of significant possibility to which one is receptive. But his discussion of ‘fear’, for instance, suggests that others involve more superficial changes in the salience of one or another possibility-type. When one becomes afraid, threat is a more conspicuous feature of one’s experience. Even so, one’s world already incorporated that type of possibility (Kusch and Ratcliffe 2018). The relationship between Befindlichkeit and Stimmung is no less murky. If we accept that different ‘moods’ can involve being open to different types of possibility, it is not clear how we can sustain a conception of Befindlichkeit as an unchanging, underlying structure. Rather, we might say, certain ‘moods’ involve different configurations of that structure, quite different ways and degrees of being situated in the world (which can be more or less recalcitrant to change). As Heidegger’s use of terms is open to different interpretations, it is easy to slip into a practice of ‘Heidegger-laundering’, where you take something inspired by 256
Existential feelings
Heidegger, put it back through Heidegger, and pull out something different at the end. This confuses matters, and ‘existential feeling’ should be evaluated on its own terms rather than annexed to one or another interpretation of Heidegger.
4. Outstanding issues Setting aside terminological quagmires, I acknowledge that the concept of existential feeling requires further clarification and elaboration. To conclude, I will briefly consider some open questions and sketch how one might start to respond. I will focus on several concerns raised by Saarinen (2018), in a detailed, specifically focused critique of my work. Saarinen questions the manner in which existential feelings are ‘felt’. More specifically, he argues that my account is phenomenologically problematic in suggesting that a generalized existential feeling and a localized emotion can both be felt at the same time: How does the body simultaneously generate two distinct types of feeling? Along with this, there is the question of how a bodily feeling of whatever kind could add up to a complex possibility space. And how, exactly, is the possibility space as a whole experienced, given that not all of it is salient on a given occasion? In response, I think it is helpful to emphasize that existential feeling consists not in an abstract, static sense of the possible but in an anticipatory structure, something Merleau-Ponty (1945) refers to as an overarching “style” of experience. In essence, this structure is fairly simple. But this is easily obscured by the complexity of the language needed to make it explicit and describe it. Consider the analogy of losing confidence in a particular domain. Suppose that, after a few weeks of mishaps, one starts to doubt one’s competence as a lecturer. What one experiences upon entering the classroom could be described in terms of a number of localized experiences, occurring simultaneously or in succession. But we can also discern an overarching structure, a pervasive sense of unease in the context of which these more localized experiences arise. This unease amounts to what we might call a style of anticipation and fulfillment, a cohesive, dynamic way in which events are anticipated and in which they unfold. In place of a more usually confident style of anticipation, there is unpleasant uncertainty, which is not felt in any particular part of one’s body or at any particular moment but manifests itself more widely in one’s engagement with the environment. This style of anticipation has a degree of consistency and coherence that warrants our calling it a distinctive kind of ‘feeling’. We can think of existential feelings in much the same way: They are styles of anticipation that permeate one’s engagement with the world as a whole, which can open up or shut down types of possibility. A world where everything is anticipated in the guise of dread and where other people fail to offer the prospect of communion or support is a world in which goaldirected projects are unsustainable and where things are no longer experienced as practically significant in the ways they once were. Thus, a pervasive, dynamic style of engagement with the social world can also be described in terms of a possibility space. To inhabit this space is not to grasp the relevant types of possibility in an abstract way, but to be immersed in an all-encompassing pattern of anticipation and fulfillment, which is susceptible to various kinds of alteration (Ratcliffe 2017a, chap. 5 and 6). Thus, at any given time, it is not that one simultaneously experiences a vast inventory of different types of possibility, including the possibility of, however, many variants of hope, fear, joy, and so forth. Rather, one’s dynamic experience of the possible allows for certain kinds of emotional response and not others. This is distinct from the stronger claim that a sense of what, exactly, it allows for must be a constant ingredient of existential feeling. To put it in another way, one can be open to possibilities of type p without having an additional, continuous experience of being open to possibilities of type p. 257
Matthew Ratcliffe
Given this perspective, the relationship between localized feelings and temporally co-incident existential feelings is not so mysterious. To return to the analogy of losing confidence, one might experience a specific incident as especially troubling in some way and, in so doing, have a localized, intentional feeling. However, this arises against the backdrop of a more enveloping feeling, a way of engaging with one’s surroundings that disposes one towards such feelings and upon which their possibility depends. Were exactly the same feeling to arise without warning in the context of previously effortless, confident engagement with one’s surroundings, it would be experienced as odd, discrepant, puzzling. In fact, it would not be quite the same feeling, given that the nature of the relevant experience is inseparable from its relationship to a wider style of anticipation. We can thus come to better appreciate the relationship between existential feelings, intentional feelings, and possibilities by emphasizing the dynamic nature of feeling, the role played by patterns of anticipation, and the fact that these feelings are not localized, freeze-framed qualia that an introspective gaze can lock onto (Ratcliffe 2017a).7 One might also wonder, with Saarinen, about the manner in which existential feelings are felt. In some cases, the feeling operates as pre-reflective background to experience, while in others, such as pronounced, generalized anxiety and unsettling feelings of unfamiliarity, the feeling itself is salient. Such contrasts need not imply that the relevant feelings are fundamentally different in kind. For example, cases where everything unfolds as habitually anticipated and where everything appears utterly surprising can both be understood in terms of an overarching anticipation-fulfillment dynamic, even though one is phenomenologically salient and the other not. Even so, I am inclined to concede that existential feelings can involve different kinds of phenomenological access. Along with this, there are varying degrees of insight into their nature. Again, this becomes easier to accept once it is acknowledged that the feeling amounts to a kind of ‘style’ that is manifested in one’s experiences, thoughts, and activities (or lack of activities), rather than a singular psychological entity that reveals itself in one or another way. Given this, there is no clear line to be drawn between accessing the feeling itself, recognizing it through its pervasive effects, and somehow inferring its presence. I further acknowledge that more work is needed to clarify what ‘phenomenological access’ consists of and what qualifies something as ‘phenomenologically accessible’. However, this concern is not exclusive to my own account and applies much more widely. Another outstanding issue concerns the relationships between existential feelings and conceptual thought. I regard existential feeling as a phenomenologically distinctive aspect of experience, which can be analyzed independently of any conceptual ‘overlay’. However, as Saarinen points out, this seems questionable in cases such as ‘existential guilt’ (Ratcliffe 2015). Can we really extricate an existential feeling of guilt from its further conceptualization in terms of reprehensible deeds or personal characteristics? My position is that certain existential feelings lend themselves to interpretation in terms of guilt, worthlessness, or selfhate (Ratcliffe 2015, chap. 5). Furthermore, they are frequently experienced in these terms, at least in certain cultures. However, as Saarinen observes, guilt has an essentially evaluative dimension to it; it involves recognition of wrong-doing. If this is not intrinsic to the existential feeling, then surely that feeling is far-removed from an actual experience of ‘guilt’. And, if the feeling does incorporate normativity, this seems to imply an additional evaluative ingredient. But an existential feeling can, I think, include a sense of what we might call ‘wrongness’, ‘lack’, or ‘failure’. The world as a whole can appear somehow lacking, missing something, ‘not quite how it was or how it ought to be’. There can also be a sense of one’s being unable to actualize certain possibilities, however pressing they might appear, and thus a pervasive sense of ‘I can’t do what this situation, or this world, demands of me’. Indeed, the 258
Existential feelings
whole possibility space can appear in the guise of one’s failing to achieve anything, to effect change, to realize possibilities that present themselves as in one or another way as salient, important. So it is plausible that existential feelings can themselves include some form of ‘normativity’. This does not add up to a fully rich grasp of moral norms and some conceptual input is needed for an existential feeling to crystallize into a specifically ‘guilty’ feeling. But this may involve taking a small step, rather than a giant leap. To summarize, the theory of existential feeling requires refinement in several respects, and some of the outstanding issues apply to the study of human experience more generally. Among other things, there is still a need for (i) a comprehensive account of the various types of mood, emotion, and feeling, and of the relations between them; (ii) a synchronic and diachronic analysis of the relationships between feelings and conceptual thought; and (iii) a clear statement of what it is for something to be phenomenologically accessible, one that distinguishes between different degrees and types of access.
Acknowledgments Thanks to Hilge Landweer, Jussi Saarinen, and Thomas Szanto for their helpful comments on an earlier version of this chapter.
Notes 1 Adopting a slightly different approach, Slaby (2008) also emphasizes that bodily feelings are not just bodily, focusing on diffuse bodily dispositions that admit considerable variety. For complementary claims concerning bodily feeling and emotional intentionality, see, for example, Colombetti (2014) and Deonna and Teroni (2015). 2 See also Jacobs et al. (2014) for a lengthy discussion of existential feeling in depression. 3 See also several of the essays in a recent special issue of the journal Philosophia, on ‘The Meaning of Moods’ (Volume 45, Issue 4, 2017). 4 See also Andrejč (2012) for an account of how the concept of existential feeling might apply to certain religious feelings, helping us to appreciate how they dispose one toward religious belief. 5 Stephan (2012a, 2012b) proposes a simpler classification scheme, consisting of elementary, nonelementary, and atmospheric existential feelings. My concerns apply equally to the elementary/ non-elementary distinction. However, I agree that certain ‘atmospheric’ experiences are distinct from existential feelings. When we speak of the atmosphere of a place or situation, we refer to something that is experienced as specific, contingent, and potentially escapable, rather than to a space of possibility within which such atmospheres are anticipated and experienced. On emotional atmospheres, see also Chapter 23 in this volume. 6 See also Fingerhut and Marienberg (2012) for discussions of the ‘feeling of being alive’. 7 Even so, a clean phenomenological distinction between intentionally directed emotions and existential feelings seems doubtful in some instances. For example, profound grief involves both specifically directed emotions and all-enveloping changes in one’s relationship with the world. Furthermore, it is implausible to conceive of the two as separate. The recognition that a particular person is gone from one’s world is at the same time a disturbance of the world that one previously took for granted, given the many ways in which that person was implicated in one’s habitual concerns. I discuss such experiences in detail elsewhere (Ratcliffe 2017b).
References Andrejč, Gorazd (2012). Bridging the Gap between Social and Existential-Mystical Interpretations of Schleiermacher’s ‘Feeling’. Religious Studies 48(3), 377–401. Carel, Havi (2013). Bodily Doubt. Journal of Consciousness Studies 20(7–8), 178–197. Colombetti, Giovanna (2014). The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
259
Matthew Ratcliffe Deonna, Julien A., and Teroni, Fabrice (2015). Emotions as Attitudes. Dialectica 69, 293–311. Eder, Jens (2016). Films and Existential Feelings. Projections 10(2), 75–103. Fernandez, Anthony V. (2014). Depression as Existential Feeling of De-Situatedness? Distinguishing Structure from Mode in Psychopathology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13(4), 595–612. Fingerhut, Jörg, and Marienberg, Sabine (Eds.) (2012). Feelings of Being Alive. Berlin: De Gruyter. Gendlin, Eugene T. (2003[1978]). Focusing: How to Gain Direct Access to Your Body’s Knowledge. London: Rider Books. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2009). Getting Feeling into Emotional Experience in the Right Way. Emotion Review 1, 232–239. Heidegger, Martin (1962[1927]). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell. Husserl, Edmund (1973[1938]). Experience and Judgment. Transl. by J. S. Churchill and K. Ameriks. London, New York: Routledge. ——— (1989[1952]). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy: Second Book. Transl. by R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (2001). Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis: Lectures on Transcendental Logic. Transl. by A. J. Steinbock. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Jacobs, Kerrin, Stephan, Achim, Paskaleva-Yankova, Asena, and Wilutzky, Wendy. (2014). Existential and Atmospheric Feelings in Depressive Comportment. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 21(2), 89–110. James, William (1902). The Varieties of Religious Experience. New York: Longmans, Green & Co. ——— (1912). Absolutism and Empiricism. In: W. James: Essays in Radical Empiricism. New York: Longmans, Green & Co, 266–279. Kusch, Martin, and Ratcliffe, Matthew (2018). The World of Chronic Pain: A Dialogue. In: K. Aho (Ed.). Existential Medicine. London: Rowman and Littlefield, 61–80. Mallan, Kerry (2017). Spatialities of Emotion: Place and Non-Place in Children’s Picture Books. In: K. Moruzi, M. J. Smith, and E. Bullen (Eds.). Affect, Emotion and Children’s Literature: Representation and Socialisation in Texts for Children and Young Adults. London, New York: Routledge, 129–145. McLaughlin, Brian P. (2009). Monothematic Delusions and Existential Feelings. In: J. Bayne and J. Fernández (Eds.). Delusion and Self-Deception. London: Psychology Press, 139–164. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (2012[1945]). Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by D. Landes. London, New York: Routledge. Ratcliffe, Matthew (2005). The Feeling of Being. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12(8–10), 43–60. ——— (2008). Feelings of Being: Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2012a). The Phenomenology of Existential Feeling. In: J. Fingerhut and S. Marienberg (Eds.). Feelings of Being Alive. Berlin: De Gruyter, 23–54. ——— (2012b). Phenomenology as a Form of Empathy. Inquiry 55, 473–495. ——— (2015). Experiences of Depression: A Study in Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2017a). Real Hallucinations: Psychiatric Illness, Intentionality, and the Interpersonal World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ——— (2017b). Grief and the Unity of Emotion. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 41, 154–174. ——— (2018). Depression, Self-Regulation, and Intersubjectivity. Discipline Filosofiche 28(2), 21–41. Rzesnitzek, Lara (2014). Narrative or Self-Feeling? A Historical Note on the Biological Foundation of the ‘Depressive Situation’. Frontiers in Psychology 5, 1–3. Saarinen, Jussi (2014). The Oceanic Feeling in Painterly Creativity. Contemporary Aesthetics 12, 1–12. ——— (2018). A Critical Examination of Existential Feeling. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17(2), 363–374. Sass, Louis A. (2010). Phenomenology as Description and as Explanation. In: S. Gallagher, and D. Schmicking (Eds.). Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Dordrecht: Springer, 575–590. Slaby, Jan (2008). Affective Intentionality and the Feeling Body. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7, 429–444. ——— (2012). Matthew Ratcliffes phänomenologische Theorie existenzieller Gefühle. In: A. Schnabel, and R. Schwitzeichel (Eds.). Emotionen, Sozialstruktur und Moderne. Heidelberg: Springer, 75–92.
260
Existential feelings ——— (2019). Existenzielle Gefühle und In-der-Welt-sein. In: H. Kappelhoff, J.-H. Bakels, C. Schmitt, and H. Lehmann (Eds.). Emotionen. Ein interdisziplinäres Handbuch. Stuttgart: Metzler, 326–339. Slaby, Jan, and Stephan, Achim (2008). Affective Intentionality and Self-Consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 17, 506–513. Slaby, Jan, Stephan, Achim, Walter, Henrik and Walter, Sven (Eds.) (2011). Affektive Intentionalität: Beiträge zur welterschließenden Funktion der menschlichen Gefühle. Paderborn: Mentis. Stephan, Achim (2012a). Existentielle Gefühle und Emotionen: Intentionalität und Regulierbarkeit. In: J. Fingerhut, and S. Marienberg (Eds.). Feelings of Being Alive. Berlin: De Gruyter, 101–121. ——— (2012b). Emotions, Existential Feelings, and Their Regulation. Emotion Review 4(2), 157–162. Stern, Daniel N. (2010). Forms of Vitality: Exploring Dynamic Experience in Psychology, the Arts, Psychotherapy, and Development. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Varga, Somogy, and Krueger, Joel (2013). Background Emotions, Proximity and Distributed Emotion Regulation. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 4(2), 271–292. Wynn, Mark (2012). Renewing the Senses: Conversion Experience and the Phenomenology of the Spiritual Life. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 72(3), 211–226. ——— (2013). Renewing the Senses: A Study of the Philosophy and Theology of the Spiritual Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
261
23 EMOTIONAL ATMOSPHERES Tonino Griffero
1. Introduction An atmospheric feeling is almost omnipresent, even though at times unnoticed and ephemeral. One speaks of atmospheres continuously, describes them and calls them into question every time that some invisible effects seem to be out of proportion with respect to their visible causes and not fully perceivable through standard sense organs. When a person speaks, for example, of a political wind blowing in the country or of the mood specifically suggested by a certain weather, etc., they are referring to a social or natural atmospherisation. One has always known what “there is something in the air” means (tension or relaxation, for example). Western culture has been feeling for at least a century the increasing need for atmospheric concepts (such as aura, ambiance, Stimmung, etc.), and even marketing has been understanding for at least half a century that “in some cases, the place, more specifically the atmosphere of the place, is more influential than the product itself in the purchase decision” (Kotler 1973–1974, 48). But it is only for about 20 years that the notion of atmosphere has become a philosophical theme (cf. Thibaud 2015, 13–43; Runkel 2016; Griffero 2018) precisely since the New Phenomenology, founded by Hermann Schmitz, uses atmospheric feeling as a leverage to wipe away that dualism, both Christian-Platonist and Cartesian, that makes it impossible to explain how the subject is then able to get outside and acquire a reliable knowledge of the external world.1 One could welcome this situation as a real atmospheric turn (Soentgen 1998, 72–73)2 based on a stance that borders the Deleuzian-metaphysical affect theory (affects as ubiquitous and anonymous intensities) as well as the more detailed and applicable affect studies (affects as bodily relational relationships with the world). This turn is, however, ontologically much more ambitious than today’s widespread cognitive rehabilitation of feelings in functional, narrative and even evolutionary-adaptive terms, as such however obliged to choose between the devil (the subpersonal-neuronal dimension) and the deep blue see (the highly personal-cultural side). By stating that “feelings are the most important thing in life, because only they bring power and delicacy, brightness and opacity into the world; the only thing that, generally, makes something important to men” (Schmitz 1969, XII; own transl.), the new phenomenologist paves the way for a philosophical approach to reality based on a radical de-psychologisation of emotional life. 262
Emotional atmospheres
But what does “atmosphere” precisely mean? The term derives from the Greek (ἀτμός=vapour and σφαῖρα=sphere) and denotes in meteorology the gaseous envelope surrounding our planet. It relies on a metaphorical use since the 18th century, but it has boomed only recently in areas of humanities that, bypassing positivist conventions and strictly functional parameters, pay attention to the vague and qualitative “something-more” (Tellenbach 1968, 47), more to expressive qualia and phenomenal nuances of appearing reality (the pathic “how”) than to detailed material reality (the cognitive “what” and the aetiological “why”) (Straus 1963). As a colloquial term, however, “atmosphere” is largely dependent on the context. Without the usual addition of qualifying adjectives,3 it works as a neutral title (the atmosphere of London, for example, does not mean anything precisely per se) or refers to an only decorative background (“there is an atmosphere, but…”); sometimes, it means an ipso facto favourable feeling (“what an atmosphere!”) and even defines, as inferential psychology well knows, the persuasive effect of syllogisms (Woodworth and Sells 1935) based on particular and affirmative premises. Being philosophically interesting not despite but precisely because of its (de re) vagueness, an atmospheric perception never has to exit from its vagueness, but it must learn to stay in it in the right way, first of all by acquiring that specific competence which is able to partially immunise from the media-emotional manipulation which the aestheticisation of politics and social life in the late capitalistic “scenic” economy results in (see, from last, Böhme 2017c). Generally speaking, today atmosphere means a feeling, more or less distinguished from emotion, affect and mood, that is not private and internal but objectively diffuses in the space and works as a qualitative-sentimental prius of every sensible (and later differentiated) encounter with the world. Regardless of whether it is tense, relaxed, gloomy, etc., an atmosphere tonalises the situation in which perceivers find themselves and sometimes involves them to the point that they are unable to escape from it. And if one does not say “I feel sadness around me”, it is only because of the extreme proximity of that gloomy atmosphere and the introjectionist prejudice emphasising the possessive (and not adverbial) sense of the personal pronoun.4
2. Atmosphere makes a career In its new (theoretical) sense, the notion is introduced independently of each other by both the psychiatrist Hubertus Tellenbach (1968) and the philosopher Hermann Schmitz (1969, 1998, 2007, 2014; see also Chapter 19 in this volume). Tellenbach makes of atmosphere an elusive but essential quality of intersubjectivity, generated especially through oral sense as sense of proximity (olfaction and taste) and in particular through smell as a favoured medium of the atmosphere defined as what is eternal of the past.5 A positive neonatal atmospherisation would ensure the newborns the trust which is required for a correct development of their personality, and would provide the psychiatrist an effective diagnostic tool for psychic diseases whose symptom is some atmospheric aberration of oral sense. Schmitz develops a wide antireductionist (new) phenomenology of the felt body (Leib) aiming at reformulating the concept of philosophy in terms of a self-reflection of persons regarding the way in which they feel and orientate within their environment. Hence, he conceives feelings as atmospheres in a revolutionary way, partially restoring, in line with Ludwig Klages’ science of elementary souls,6 the Ancient Greek concept of feelings as powers (demons) poured out into a non-localisable space. Schmitz goes against the dominance of the psychologist–introjectionist–reductionist paradigm from the 5th century BC onwards, consisting of a reduction of the world to single quantifiable entities without any affective 263
Tonino Griffero
character and of the decision, in order to emancipate human beings from the diktat of involuntary impulses, and that all feelings one feels coming from outside are nothing but inner states (psychic introjection) thereafter projected onto the outside (projection). Because of this paradigm, the very idea of the atmospheric, subject-independent nature of feelings disappeared: a “repression” that also involves both the felt body as irreducible to the physical one and the perception as ubiquitous felt-bodily communication with the world. From the neo-phenomenological point of view, therefore, atmospheres are no longer subjective psychic states projected outside but affective powers that authoritatively fill and qualify a surfaceless spatial situation and whose qualitative expressions (through suggestions of movement and synaesthetic qualities) one can experience through one’s own similar felt-bodily qualities. This anti-introjectionist and therefore also anti-projectivist conception of atmospheric feelings, however, reaches its maturity only within Gernot Böhme’s New Aesthetics (Aisthetics), understood as a general theory of perception, i.e., as an affective and involving experience.7 He departs from the intellectualism of classical aesthetics and its exclusive focus on art and, while incorporating some of the neo-phenomenological key points (externality and felt-bodily action of atmospheres), conceives of the production of atmospheres as the tacit core of the “aesthetic work” (art in a strict sense, but also cosmetics, advertising, design, scenography, interior decoration, acoustic furnishing, etc.); the latter’s best paradigm is, according to Böhme’s purely descriptive approach, stage design, especially in a late capitalist aesthetic economy increasingly interested in stage-values rather than more traditional use- and exchange-values. As a primary object of perception, the atmosphere is responsible for our emotional well-being in a certain environment and, as an “in between” mediating subject (bodily feeling) and object (environment) and attesting their co-presence, it is a quasi-objective being, intersubjectively present in the space. Even if, strictly speaking, it is nothing without a subject feeling it, it is something you can enter into and be caught by, a sensuous experience of things and ecstatic qualities they radiate (cf. Böhme 2017b, 37–54). Understanding the different generators of atmosphere (movement impressions, synaesthesia, scenes, social characters, etc.) and their potentially manipulative power might then give rise to a real atmospheric “competence”, conceived of as a critical theory of aestheticisation. By emphasising the skills through which aesthetic workers know well, although often tacitly, how and what “making” atmospheres means, Böhme obviously makes the successful career of atmospheres in humanities possible. “Atmospheres are involved wherever something is being staged, wherever design is a factor—and that now means: almost everywhere” (Böhme 2017a, 29). But this “making” atmospheres is somewhat also for Böhme “confined to setting the conditions in which the atmosphere appears” (Böhme 2017a, 31), in other words to just establishing the generators through which atmospheric phenomena “could” possibly emerge.
3. Can atmospheres be produced? The mother of all problems Despite Böhme’s caution, the idea that one is able to intentionally generate atmospheres has led to a dispute with Hermann Schmitz, whose anti-intentionalistic warning may be summarised as follows (cf. 1998; 2003, 243–261). First of all, by “making” atmospheres, our societies manipulate those “actual impressive situations” through which they try to escape from solipsism. Furthermore, by developing an impression engineering (Eindruckstechnik), they mimic the golden season of European art and stabilise atmospheres for propagandistic or advertising superficial purposes (Plakatsituation). Finally, accepting that atmospheres are 264
Emotional atmospheres
the result of ecstasies of things means accepting two false assumptions: Both that situations are radiated primarily by single objects (singularism) and not by a chaotic-multiple significance, and that an atmospheric perception can be explained through a dualistic sender–receiver model. This ontological contrast between Böhme’s and Schmitz’s accounts also refers to a different assessment of everyday life’s aestheticisation: It is stigmatised by Schmitz as a misleading propaganda, while it is analysed by Böhme as the unavoidable reflection of a more general “theatricalization of our life” (Böhme 2017a, 33). Although Schmitz’s criticism should be taken seriously, it may be argued that it conflicts with his own assumption that it would be possible to cultivate atmospheric feelings in a closed space (dwelling and church, garden and Japanese tea house) in a non-manipulative way; it wrongly downgrades the rhetorical coté of aesthetics to something superficial and anti-educational, and, finally, by assuming that impression engineering generates only fake atmospheres, it relies on an external-normative axiology clearly conflicting with his descriptive phenomenological approach. In order to really do justice to atmospheres’ ubiquity, I suggest to use a distinction among three kinds of atmospheres and consequently of spatiality. On the basis of their decreasing objectivity (and typically their intensity, too) and their increasing objectual focalisation,8 they can be prototypic (objective, external, unintentional, sometimes lacking a precise name and space and related to vastness),9 derivative (objective, external, intentionally produced and related to directional space) and even quite spurious in their relatedness (subjective, projective and related even to local space) (cf. Griffero 2014, 144). To give some examples: The groundless and unfocused boredom felt all around us is a prototypic atmosphere, whereas the fact of becoming bored by something is a derivative one and getting bored (for strictly personal reasons) during a party when others are enjoying it as a spurious-idiosyncratic one. This makes it possible to accept both Schmitz’s idea of freely floating atmospheric feelings (that I understand as the prototypical ones) and Böhme’s effort to mitigate their overly random nature and to bind them as tightly as possible to objectual poles (that I understand as the derivative ones). If there were only prototypical atmospheres, partly overlapping with Stimmungen, it would be hard to understand how aesthetic works could successfully produce an atmosphere and why the humanities successfully apply this concept.
4. A modest atmospherological proposal My atmospherological approach, that highlights affective appearance qua talis over both the genetic question (“in what series of events does this feeling occur?”) and the causal one (“what is the cause of this feeling?”), defines atmospheric feeling as the “first impression” of what surrounds us and acts on us as quasi-things (see espec. Griffero 2017a). As an example of an (also Husserlian) intersubjective and holistic passive synthesis, that precedes analysis and influences from the outset the emotional situation of the perceiver, resisting moreover any conscious attempt at projective adaptation, an atmosphere constitutes an influential and (in exemplary cases) numinous “presence”.10 Inextricably linked to the felt body (Leib) and characterised by a qualitative microgranularity, which is opaque to a third-person epistemic perspective, it is more a “spatial” state (in a non-metaphorical sense) of the world than a private psychic state, a feeling that is not circumscribed to specific senses but that is almost always synaesthetic.11 The atmospheric “coldness” of a room, for example, is due to the furniture type or sound quality, the colour of the walls or the temperature, the unlived order, lights, the sound of the voice of those who are there, etc. 265
Tonino Griffero
While sometimes an atmosphere unites and allows for a productive tuning, it sometimes divides, generating “numerous invisible, yet selective and efficacious, frontiers” (Tellenbach 1968, 56; own transl.), and may even be responsible of brutal social exclusions. It gives thus life to a natural-cultural segmentation, which also provides an intersubjectively communicable repertory of different atmospheric situations.12 Through their pervasive quality, they act as situational constraints accessible not to a representative–ocular–distal perception, but only to an ambulatory one, to that first-person felt-bodily involvement in chaotic-multiple situations that is more a being-perceived than an active perception. They are phenomena beyond whose appearance it is meaningless to proceed and whose excessive (semiotic, hermeneutic) focalisation would represent a flat rationalisation ex post or even a reifying pathology betraying the Goethian principle of the immanence of theory in phenomena themselves. Perceiving atmospheres neo-phenomenologically means felt-bodily communicating with meaningful impressions, suggested by animate and inanimate forms. Unlike the physical body (stable, extended, divisible, etc.), the felt body is surfaceless and occupies an “absolute” and non-geometrical space. It is capable of self-auscultation without organic mediations and exceeds the skin contour, being articulated not into discrete parts but into “corporeal isles” of variable duration and configuration (see Schmitz 1965 onwards; Griffero 2016a; 2017a, 53–77; 2017b, 2017c). Thanks to its polarised rhythm (contraction or narrowness/expansion or vastness), it acts as a real sounding board for atmospheres, thus reacting to their felt-bodily qualities (motor suggestions and synaesthetic qualities) in a way that is the more perfect the less one thinks about it. Hence, there is a wide, yet not well investigated range, of possible states (positive or negative) according to the shape of the intertwining between the mentioned poles of the whole vital dynamics. Far from being an exceptional event, atmospheric perception is thus a variant of ordinary perception of environmental affordances, of affectively rich ecological invites, which are not restricted to the visual and pragmatic-behavioural dimension.13 Like climate conditions preceding the subject/object distinction, they authoritatively modulate the lived and predimensional space whose presence we feel and as a consequence also our personal mood. They are, moreover, extraneous to any (epistemic) criterion of truth or falsity, because aesthetic workers may clumsily generate unwanted atmospheres, but one cannot properly make mistakes in perceiving them, since there is no difference between feeling fake (or apparent) and real atmospheres.
5. Ontologically heterodox suggestions Developing to some extent a neo-phenomenological ontology, it could be said, in summary, that atmospheres as quasi-things, unlike things, (a) are not edged, discrete, cohesive, solid, perduring in time, normally inactive, without concealed sides, and for this reason, they coincide with their appearance. (b) Not having inherent real tendencies, they have no history (they do not get old), are radically event-like in character and not merely a trace of something other. (c) Without being the property of something or universally predictable genera, they coincide with their own phenomenal and “actual” “character”. (d) More immediate, intrusive and demanding than things, they arouse incorporations and excorporations by virtue of an authority that is sometimes so absolute as to be irreducible to culturally emotional norms14 and to win any critical distance.15 (e) They have an intermittent life, in the sense that they come and go, without there being any point in asking what they did in the meantime. (f ) But along with transient atmospheric qualities, there are also more persistent atmospheric qualities: The sublime atmosphere of an alpine landscape, for example, is relatively stable 266
Emotional atmospheres
despite changing weather conditions. (g) They do not act as the separate causes of the influence but are the influence itself, exactly like the wind, that does not exist prior to and beyond its blowing. (h) Although they do not properly have a whence or a where, they “occupy” surfaceless lived spaces characterised by blurred boundaries.16 (i) They are relatively (perceptually) amendable, if only on the level of common sense. ( j) They must have yet some kind of identity, as is well shown by the fact that one can be mistaken in producing them, for example trying and arousing an atmosphere of euphoria in a dreary day, or rightly imagine the (even counterfactual) conditions under which it could be produced. (k) They never properly exist as purely potential (thinkable) states. Nevertheless, an atmosphere, especially the prototypical one, cannot be completely reduced to its subjective perception. (l) There are things and situations that stably arouse certain atmospheres, and others that occasionally take charge of them, as it happens when a wild atmosphere, for example, ceases to be such, sensorially perceived components being equal, when its origin is ascertained to be artificial. (m) They are mostly an “in between” made possible by the (felt-bodily but also social and symbolic) co-presence of subject and object. The last point should now be specified: The inter-corporeal “in between” must not be reified to the point of counting as “a third element which, as a membrane, is interposed between the two margins” (Schmitz 2002, 71), because this would lead to the dualism that atmospherology actually tries to avoid. A joyful atmosphere, for example, is not the mere outcome of isolable parts (me and the situation) but rather a holistic relationship17 that is prior to its relata18 and hard to understand because of the dualistic tendency inherent to our ordinary way of thinking.
6. Atmospheric interplay The relationship between the perceiver and the already mentioned three types of atmospheres (cf. Section 3) may result in many different emotional interactions. Roughly put, (a) an atmosphere can overwhelm a perceiver (ingressive-antagonistic encounter), completely reorient their emotional situation and be refractory, as a real antagonist, to a more or less conscious attempt at a projective, reflective and amending interpretation. (b) It can find perceivers attuned with it (syntonic encounter), to the point that whereas others may even remain upset, they do not realise they actually entered it. This apparent absence of atmosphere can be explained by a (gestaltic) insufficient contrast between figure and background, thus causing in them an embarrassing affective and social inadequacy, but also by a felt-bodily disposition so compact as to prevent them from abandoning themselves to the situation. The most powerful atmospheres, however, are exactly those which lie in the background and provide the tacit and non-thetical contextual conditions of transitive perceptions.19 (c) Sometimes, one clearly recognises an atmosphere in its “objective” roots (mere contemplation), but without being really felt-bodily involved. This emotionless recognition, while showing the failure of the projectivist thesis again, also raises the controversial question (that cannot be addressed here) of how exactly emotion and cognition overlap or interact. (d) An atmosphere can also elicit a resistance (mood protest) and the very intensity of this emotional reaction is indeed the best proof of the objective effectiveness of the atmosphere one reacts to. (e) An atmosphere, which as such is supervenient on its (material and immaterial) generators, may sometimes be aroused by elements normally expressing completely different moods, such as when our self-disdain is strengthened by the (however suggested) beauty of a landscape. (f ) Although the prototypical atmosphere is that suggested by the first impression,20 the subsequent ones may give rise to relatively different atmospherisations (however influenced by the very first 267
Tonino Griffero
one). There are various reasons for this: perceptual and climatic changes, end of sensory illusions, change in the perceiver’s physiological conditions, contrast between the atmosphere and its unwanted sub-atmospheres, additional and divergent cognitions, purely idiosyncratic experiences, focusing over time on misleading fields of condensation (thus also involving or even, so to speak, infecting objects that are not directly responsible for that feeling, such as when the fear of the dentist also spreads a negative atmosphere on every visible object in their waiting room, etc.). Even if the non-prototypical atmosphere can, therefore, change over time and be filtered through new evaluations of the perceiver, this does not mean that projectivistic relativism must be embraced. And pour cause: If persons always perceive something as merely subjective, no atmosphere could ever overwhelm and affect them. (g) An atmosphere, finally, might elicit an active feedback loop to the extent that perceivers, for example, the spectators of a performance, coordinate themselves with it such that they reinforce the staged atmosphere.
7. To be continued These ontological and phenomenological classifications are surely not exhaustive and yet too abstract, but they should at least provide the necessary framework for some controversial problems that can only be mentioned here. That an atmospherisation could be generated by language does not reductionistically mean that it is nothing but the result of an illegitimate (metaphoric) use of language if only because the very condition of a metaphorisation, i.e., the distinction between the proper (literal) and the improper (figurative), is totally missing here. Although my comprehensive definition of atmospheres allows including a stronger subjective component in some of them, the quasi-objective externalisation of the prototypical ones cannot be condemned as a dangerous reification, if only because their space is not the metrical but the pre-dimensional one and they do not belong to things but to quasi-things (cf. above §5). Stressing that “usually (…) the perceiving subject is not struck by a feeling, rather his getting struck is the feeling itself ” (Hauskeller 1995, 26) implies an excessive fear of ontology, which I understand simply as the catalogue of all existing “entities”. Also the risk that “all the feelings should be constantly present in the given space” (Fuchs 2000, 227; own transl.) should not be overestimated if it is true that atmospheres are only intermittently present in a certain space. The fact that a certain atmosphere ceases to exist, however, as soon as one leaves a certain situation proves how a particular situation is clearly responsible for that atmospheric feeling, while the subject is only its sounding board. One must not, moreover, confuse evaluation differences with the subjectivity of atmospheres: The atmospheric narrowness, for example, is quasi-objectively felt by everyone, regardless of whether it is annoying or attractive (children, for instance, prefer closed spaces like nests or caves). In other terms, the diversity of moods in two different perceivers does not prove the subjectivity and privacy of the atmosphere at all. Usually, different moods result from a different “filtering” process—which, according to New Phenomenology, is based on different felt-bodily dispositions and degrees of personal emancipation—of the “same” atmospheric quality. One must also avoid the misleading tendency to attribute to an “atmosphere” (without specifications) an automatically positive value. As seemingly non-atmospheric situations turn out to be simply impersonal and anonymous atmospheres, so, too, bad situations are not less atmospheric only because they do not arouse a positive attunement. Regarding atmospheric “competence”, it should involve the ability of feeling atmospheres (having a sense for them), of staging them, but also of not being seriously manipulated 268
Emotional atmospheres
by them. Now, the problem is that one’s responsiveness to external atmospheric impressions, usually helped by a certain passivity (tiredness, half-focalisation, crepuscular state, etc.), surely conflicts with the reflective distancing required by a more critical approach. What matters for me is to abandon the illusion of subjects’ full autonomy in favour of their sovereignty, understood as “a certain willingness to expose oneself, so that human beings may be trained to accept the fact that they are hetero-determined” (Böhme 2008, 197; own transl.). Adults, in short, are those who do not neurotically remove the passivity to which atmospheres force them but are able to both pathically immerge themselves into, and to rationally re-emerge from them later.
8. Interdisciplinary dissemination It is beyond the scope of this chapter to give a reasonable account of the various interdisciplinary areas of application of atmospherology.21 Suffice to highlight that philosophy enhances the intriguing vagueness of this approach and makes it the kernel of a pathic aesthetics, which puts into question aesthetics understood as a philosophy of art and its categories (beauty, sublime, etc.) (see Griffero 2014, 2016b) or of a theory focusing both on the sensory-affective engagement with the world (see Hauskeller 1995; Hasse 2005) and on the specific intertwining of environment and feeling (cf. Rauh 2012). Moreover, various humanistic fields must also be mentioned 22: First of all, architecture (see at least Zumthor 2006; Böhme 2006, 2017b; Hahn 2012) and urban studies, whose aim is to clarify how cities, buildings, streets, traffic, etc., experienced through “parcours commenté”23 a “peripheral unfocused vision” (Pallasmaa 2005) and first-person lifewordly micrologies (e.g., Hasse 2016), pathically modulate the felt-bodily space, offering, in the best cases, a possibility of attunement for people’s actions and habits (Pérez-Gòmez 2016).24 As regards arts, atmosphere has been applied especially to theatre (see Rodatz 2010; Schouten 20112), photography, literature and poetry, film and media,25 discussing both the limits of its intentional production and its greater or lesser discontinuity with everyday life. While intercultural and classical studies focus on ancient or Eastern atmospheric concepts (like the Japanese ki) (Rappe 1995; Hisayama 2014; Rouquet 2016), pedagogy questions to what extent atmospheres can be more educative than methodological solutions,26 musicology, psychopathology,27 organisation and marketing studies (see Julmi 2015, 2017; Julmi and Rappe 2018), sociology,28 ecological anthropology,29 etc. investigate the pervasive (and possibly therapeutic) quality of social situations and structures. Finally, Sloterdijk has aimed to (onto-)atmospherologically explain chaotic foams as the current form of immunity after the collapse of metaphysical all-encompassing monospheres (bubbles and globes) (1998–2004).
9. Conclusion In order to legitimately speak of atmospheric feelings rather than generically of emotions and feelings, one must refer to feelings that are poured out into a certain space30 and that one experiences as coming from the environment, thus overturning our culture’s dominant introjectionism. This neo-phenomenological “campaign” of de-psychologisation (externalisation) of the emotional sphere31 is undeniably provocative and counterintuitive if summarised by saying that atmospheres are “no more subjective than highways (…), only less easy to fixate” (Schmitz 1969, 87; own transl.).32 Yet, it has the great merit of updating (cum grano salis) the archaic view of the emotional as a “demonic” extra-personal sphere (thymos) against the dominant post-Cartesian dualism; it also has the merit of questioning a purely 269
Tonino Griffero
projective-empathetic (or worse, associationist and conventionalist) explanation of external affective qualities, based on the hydraulic model of psychic filling of the extra-psychic world, as such unable to explain why a fully subjective projection is projected exactly into that specific space. However, the aim is certainly not a regression to a pre-introjectionist way of life, but simply a re-balancing of the predominant psychic and dualistic ontology. In conclusion, one may submit that any strategy excluding atmospheres from the ontological catalogue seems doomed to failure. Atmospheres resist all kinds of reductionist and reistic strategies: for example, the eliminativistic tendency to downgrade them to collective deceits, the inclination to make them mere dispositional elements, and the need to declass them to qualities of objectual poles rather than quasi-things. Like other elusive qualitative entities (holes, shadows, clouds, etc.), atmospheres must be taken seriously, both aesthetically and ontologically, regardless of their more or less precise location.33 Atmospherology is not deterministic, but it puts precisely to good use the fact that one is not entirely the master in one’s own house.
Notes
270
Emotional atmospheres
271
Tonino Griffero Brunner, Philipp, Schweinitz, Jörg, and Tröhler, Margrit (Eds.) (2011). Filmische Atmosphären. Marburg: Schüren. Bulka, Thomas (2015). Stimmung, Emotion, Atmosphäre. Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Struktur der menschlichen Affektivität. Münster: mentis. Debus, Stephan, and Posner, Roland (Eds.) (2007). Atmosphären im Alltag. Über ihre Erzeugung und Wirkung. Bonn: Psychiatrie-Verlag. Diaconu, Madalina (2006). Patina—Atmosphere—Aroma. Towards an Aesthetics of Fine Differences. Analecta Husserliana 42, 131–148. Diaconu, Madalina, and Copoeru, Ion (Eds.) (2014). Place, Environment, Atmosphere. Studia Phaenomenologica 14, 11–16. Düttmann, Susanne (2000). Ästhetische Lernprozesse. Annäherungen an atmosphärische Wahrnehmungen von LernRäumen. Marburg: Tectum-Verlag. Francesetti, Gianni, and Griffero, Tonino (Eds.) (2019). Neither Inside nor Outside. Psychopathology and Atmospheres. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholar. Fuchs, Thomas (2000). Leib, Raum, Person. Entwurf einer phänomenologischen Anthropologie. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta. Gibson, James J. (1986). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. London: Routledge. Goetz, Rainer, and Graupner, Stefan (Eds.) (2007–2012). Atmosphäre(n). Interdisziplinäre Annäherungen an einen unscharfen Begriff. 2 voll. München: kopaed. Graupner, Stefan, Herbold, Kathrin, and Rauh, Andreas (Eds.) (2010). Gretchenfragen: Kunstpädagogik, Ästhetisches Interesse, Atmosphären. München: kopaed. Griffero, Tonino (2014). Atmospheres. Aesthetics of Emotional Spaces. London, New York: Routledge. ——— (2016a). Atmospheres and Felt-Bodily Resonances. Studi di estetica 44(1), 1–41. ——— (2016b). Il pensiero dei sensi. Atmosfere ed estetica patica. Milano: Guerini & Associati. ——— (2016c). Urbilder o atmosfere? Ludwig Klages e la Nuova Fenomenologia. Annuario Filosofico 32, 326–348. ——— (2017a). Quasi-Things. The Paradigm of Atmospheres. New York: Suny Press. ——— (2017b). Felt-Bodily Communication: A Neophenomenological Approach to Embodied Affects. Studi di estetica 45(2), 71–86. ——— (2017c). Felt-Bodily Resonances. Towards a Pathic Aesthetics. Yearbook for Eastern and Western Philosophy 2, 149–164. ——— (2018). Atmospheres. International Lexicon of Aesthetics. https://lexicon.mimesisjournals.com/ international_lexicon_of_aesthetics_item_detail.php?item_id=16. Griffero, Tonino, and Moretti, Giampiero (Eds.) (2018). Atmosphere/Atmospheres. Milan: Mimesis International. Griffero, Tonino, and Somaini, Antonio (Eds.) (2006). Atmosfere. Rivista di estetica 46(33). Grossheim, Michael (1994). Ludwig Klages und die Phänomenologie. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Grossheim, Michael, Kluck, Steffen, and Nörenberg, Henning (2014). Kollektive Lebensgefühle. Zur Phänomenologie von Gemeinschaften. Rostocker Phänomenologische Manuskripte 20. Gugutzer, Robert (2012). Verkörperungen des Sozialen. Neophänomenologische Grundlagen und soziologische Analysen. Bielefeld: transcript. Hahn, Achim (Ed.) (2012). Erlebnislandschaft—Erlebnis Landschaft? Atmosphären im architektonischen Entwurf. Bielefeld: transcript. Hasse, Jürgen (2005). Fundsachen der Sinne. Eine phänomenologische Revision alltäglichen Erlebens. Freiburg, München: Alber. ——— (2016). Die Aura des Einfachen. Mikrologien räumlichen Erlebens. Vol. 1. Freiburg, München: Alber. Hasse, Jürgen (Ed.) (2008). Stadt und Atmosphäre. Die Alte Stadt 35(2). Hauskeller, Michael (1995). Atmosphären erleben. Philosophische Untersuchungen zur Sinneswahrnehmung. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Hauskeller, Michael (Ed.) (2003). Die Kunst der Wahrnehmung. Beiträge zu einer Philosophie der sinnlichen Erkenntnis. Kunsterdingen: Die Graue Edition. Havik, Klaske, Teerds, Hans, and Tielens, Gus (Eds.) (2013). Building Atmospheres. Oase. Journal of Architecture 91, 3–12. Heibach, Christiane (Ed.) (2012). Atmosphären. Dimensionen eines diffusen Phänomens. München: Fink. Hisayama, Yuho (2014). Erfahrungen des ki-Leibessphäre, Atmosphäre, Pansphäre. Freiburg, München: Alber. Ingold, Tim (2015). The Life of Lines. London, New York: Routledge.
272
Emotional atmospheres Institut für Immersive Medien (Ed.) (2013). Atmosphären: Gestimmte Räume und sinnliche Wahrnehmung. Jahrbuch immersiver Medien. Julmi, Christian (2015). Atmosphären in Organisationen. Wie Gefühle das Zusammenleben in Organisationen beherrschen. Bochum, Freiburg: projektverlag. ——— (2017). Situations and Atmospheres in Organisations. A (new) Phenomenology of Being-in-theOrganisation. Milan: Mimesis International. Julmi, Christian, and Rappe, Guido (2018). Atmosphärische Führung. Stimmungen wahrnehmen und gezielt beeinflussen. München: Hanser. Klages, Ludwig (1976). Charakterkunde I. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1979). Charakterkunde II. Bonn: Bouvier. Knodt, Reinhard (2017). Der Atemkreis der Dinge. Freiburg, München: Alber. Kotler, Philip (1973–1974). Atmospherics as a Marketing Tool. Journal of Retailing 49(4), 48–64. Landweer, Hilge (1999). Scham und Macht: phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Sozialität eines Gefühls. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. Landweer, Hilge (Ed.) (2007). Gefühle: Struktur und Funktion. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Latour, Bruno, and Gagliardi, Pasquale (Ed.) (2006). Les atmosphères de la politique. Dialogue pour un monde commun. Paris: Le Seuil. Lüdtke, Ulrike (1998). Die Pädagogische Atmosphäre—Analyse—Störungen—Transformation—Bedeutsamkeit. Eine anthropologische Grundlegung der Sprachheilpädagogik, Frankfurt a. M.: Lang. Mahayni, Ziad (Ed.) (2002). Neue Ästhetik. Das Atmosphärische und die Kunst. München: Fink. Mc Cormack, Derek P. (2013). Refrains for Moving Bodies: Experience and Experiment in Affective Spaces. London: Duke University Press. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (2005). Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by C. Smith. London, New York: Routledge. Meyer-Sickendiek, Burkhard (2012). Lyrisches Gespür. Vom geheimen Sensorium moderner Poesie. München: Fink. Otto, Rudolf (1936). The Idea of the Holy: An Inquiry into the Non-Rational Factor in the Idea of the Divine and Its Relation to the Rational, revised with additions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pallasmaa, Yuhani (2005). The Eyes of the Skin. Architecture and the Senses. Chichester: Wiley & Sons. Pérez-Gòmez, Alberto (2016). Attunement. Architectural Meaning after the Crisis of Modern Science. Cambridge, MA, London: MIT Press. Pfaller, Larissa Pfaller, and Wiesse, Basil (Eds.) (2018). Stimmungen und Atmosphären. Wiesbaden: Springer. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, Andreas (2014). Spatial Justice: Body, Lawscape, Atmosphere. Abingdon: Routledge. Rappe, Guido (1995). Archaische Leiberfahrung. Der Leib in der frühgriechischen Philosophie und in außereuropäischen Kulturen. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Rauh, Andres (2012). Die besondere Atmosphäre. Ästhetische Feldforschungen. Bielefeld: transcript. Rémy, Nicolas, and Tixier, Nicolas (Eds.) (2016). Ambiances, Tomorrow. Proceedings of the 3rd International Congress on Ambiances. 2 vols. International Ambiances Network & University of Thessaly. Rodatz, Christoph (2010). Der Schnitt durch den Raum. Atmosphärische Wahrnehmung in und außerhalb von Theaterräumen. Bielefeld: transcript. Rouquet, Paul (2016). Ambient Media-Japanese Atmospheres of Self. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Runkel, Simon (2016). Zur Genealogie des Atmosphären-Begriffs. Eine kritische Würdigung der Ansätze von Hermann Schmitz und Gernot Böhme. In: Ulrich Wünsch (Ed.). Atmosphären des Populären II. Perspektiven, Projekte, Protokolle, Performances, Personen, Posen. Berlin: Uni-Edition, 20–39. Schmitz, Hermann (1965). System der Philosophie, II: 1. Teil: Der Leib. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1969). System der Philosophie, III.2, Der Gefühlsraum, Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1998). Situationen und Atmosphären. Zur Ästhetik und Ontologie bei Gernot Böhme. In: M. Hauskeller, C. Rehmann-Sutter, and G. Schiemann (Eds.). Naturerkenntnis und Natursein. Für Gernot Böhme. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp, 176–190. ——— (2002). Begriffene Erfahrung. Beiträge zur antireduktionistischen Phänomenologie, with G. Marx and A. Moldzio. Rostock: Koch Verlag. ——— (2003). Was ist Neue Phänomenologie? Rostock: Koch Verlag. ——— (2005). Situationen und Konstellationen. Wider die Ideologie totaler Vernetzung. Freiburg, München: Alber.
273
Tonino Griffero ——— (2007). Der Leib, der Raum und die Gefühle. Bielefeld, Locarno: Sirius. ——— (2014). Atmosphären. Freiburg, München: Alber. Schouten, Sabine (20112). Sinnliches Spüren. Wahrnehmung und Erzeugung von Atmosphären im Theater. Berlin: Theater der Zeit. Schroer, Sara Asu, and Schmitt, Susanne B. (Eds.) (2017). Exploring Atmospheres Ethnographically. London, New York: Routledge. Schultheis, Klaudia (1998). Leiblichkeit—Kultur—Erziehung. Zur Theorie der elementaren Erziehung. Weinheim: Deutscher Studien Verlag. Sloterdijk, Peter (1998–2004). Sphären. 3 vols. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Soentgen, Jens (1998). Die verdeckte Wirklichkeit. Einführung in die Neue Phänomenologie von Hermann Schmitz. Bonn: Bouvier. Sonntag, Jan (2013). Demenz und Atmosphäre. Musiktherapie als ästhetische Arbeit. Frankfurt a.M.: Mabuse Verlag. Stenslund, Anette (2015). A Whiff of Nothing: The Atmospheric Absence of Smell. The Senses and Society 10(3), 341–360. Straus, Erwin (1963). The Primary World of Senses: A Vindication of Sensory Experience. New York: The Free Press. Tedeschini, Marco (Ed.) (2014). Focus Atmosfere. Lebenswelt 4 (2014). Tellenbach, Hubertus (1968). Geschmack und Atmosphäre. Salzburg: Müller. Thibaud, Jean-Paul (2015). En quête d’ambiances. Éprouver la ville en passant. Genève: MētisPresses. Thibaud, Jean-Paul, and Siret, Daniel (Eds.) (2012). Ambiances in Action/Ambiances en acte(s). Grenoble: International Ambiances Network. Tidwell, Philip (Ed.) (2014). Architecture and Atmosphere. Espoo: Tapio Wirkkala-Rut Bryk Foundation. Ulber, Marie (2017). Landschaft und Atmosphäre—Künstlerische Übersetzungen. Bielefeld: transcript. Ulrich, Sebastian (2008). Stadionatmosphäre als verhaltenswissenschaftliches Konstrukt in Sportmarketing. Wiesbaden: Springer. Weidinger, Jürgen (Ed.) (2014). Atmosphären Entwerfen. Berlin: Technische Universitätsverlag. Wolf, Barbara (2012). Bildung, Erziehung und Sozialisation in der frühen Kindheit. Eine qualitative Studie unter Einbeziehung von Richard Sennetts Flexibilitätskonzept und Hermann Schmitz’ Neuer Phänomenologie. Freiburg, München: Alber. ——— (2015). Atmosphären des Aufwachsens. Rostocker Phänomenologische Manuskripte. Band 22. Rostock: Universitätstverlag. Woodworth, Robert Session, and Sells, S. B. (1935). An Atmosphere Effect in Formal Syllogistic Reasoning. Journal of Experimental Psychology 18, 451–460. Zumthor, Peter (2006). Atmosphären. Architektonische Umgebungen. Die Dinge um mich herum. Basel, Boston, Berlin: Birkhäuser.
274
24 VALUES, NORMS, JUSTIFICATION AND THE APPROPRIATENESS OF EMOTIONS Roberta De Monticelli I find myself in an immeasurably vast world of sensible and spiritual objects which set my heart and passions in constant motion. I know that the objects I can recognize through perception and thought, as well as all that I will, choose, do, perform, and accomplish, depend on the play of this movement of my heart. It follows that any sort of rightness or falseness and perversity in my life and activity are determined by whether there is an objectively correct order of these stirrings of my love and hate, my inclination and disinclination, my many-sided interest in the things of this world. (Scheler 1973a, 98)
These opening lines from Max Scheler’s essay “Ordo Amoris” bring the subject matter of this contribution nicely into focus, namely, the relation between emotion and reason. They also raise the main question addressed here: Do right and wrong in matters of emotion exist? The quotation begins by noting the primacy of emotional experience. Thought and action “depend” somehow on emotion. The study of emotional life, which has been curiously neglected by most modern philosophers, is introduced as a crucial domain of philosophical research. This is one of the merits of classical phenomenology, whose founders very early recognized not only the role played by the body in shaping the mind and cognition (Gallagher 2006), but also the role played by emotional life in shaping agency and personhood. The continent of emotional experience—as a mode of consciousness endowed with its own intentionality and internal lawfulness—was opened up and explored by many within the first generation of phenomenologists, long before the recent anti-Cartesian turn in cognitive science or the emergence of embodied approaches to cognition. Nowadays, emotions are indeed privileged objects of research for phenomenology, particularly of the “4e”-variety, where it is assumed that no satisfactory account of the mind can be offered without considering the mind’s embodiment, the environment in which it is embedded, the way in which life is enacted within that environment, and the extra-bodily extensions of mind which make up the cultural layer of a human, and indeed social, life-world. Yet, strangely enough, the question of the sources of normativity within the realm of emotional sensibility has yet to receive the attention it deserves.
275
Roberta De Monticelli
As is suggested by our initial quote, a phenomenological approach to human emotional life promotes a redefinition of reason and rational agency, questioning the traditional oppositions between emotion and reason while integrating emotional sensibility as a part, and even a fundamental part, of rationality. This contribution attempts to show how this can be done. By rational agent, I mean an agent capable of performing as well as responding to intentional actions. Responsibility in this sense, though, does not imply a disposition to act on good, let alone moral, reasons. A rational agent is capable of highly irrational and harmful actions, including those inspired by politically charged forms of hatred or racism. Only rational agents—that is, persons—act based on value judgments. These are often motivated by underlying emotions that, of course, are fallible. Only persons can become criminals. Only persons, moreover, can go mad in the psychiatric sense. This is why the questions about the appropriateness of emotions, their standards of correctness, and their susceptibility to correction and self-correction are so vital for contemporary philosophy, especially practical philosophy, including ethics, legal, and political theory and the foundations of education. Last but not least, if emotions are among our most common reasons for action, emotional sensibility is bound to shape not only practical rationality but the agent’s personality as well. Hence, the ultimate ambition of this chapter is to highlight the crucial contribution of emotional life to the constitution of our personhood and individual personality. The traditional, poorly grounded opposition between reason and emotion was questioned by classic phenomenology much earlier than by analytic philosophy and the contemporary philosophy of mind, where it became a more and more popular target for critics (de Sousa 1987; Greenspan 1988; Helm 2001). The appropriateness/inappropriateness of emotions— an opposition familiar from everyday language—seems to bring the affective life under the jurisdiction of reason, revealing the issue of normativity of emotions. Appropriateness itself has been further analyzed in terms of fittingness (correct presentation of a value-laden state of affairs) and rightness/wrongness (e.g. envy can be fitting without being right, cf. D’Arms and Jacobson 2000).
1. Methodology: a bottom-up approach A recent introduction to the philosophy of emotions points out three fundamental features of emotions that any account should address: their phenomenology (experiential, felt qualitative character), intentionality (directedness toward objects), and epistemology (the standard of appropriateness to which they are answerable) (Deonna and Teroni 2012, 1). While accepting this tripartition as a useful set of desiderata for theories of emotional experience, we should further insist on the inseparability of these aspects in any given emotional experience. In terms borrowed from Husserl’s theory of wholes and parts (Husserl 1900/1901, vol. II, 1–46), these three aspects (or “moments”) “hold together” through a relation of “unitary foundation”. The best way to grasp this unity is by “going back to the things themselves”. Phenomenological philosophy is ruled by the principle of the priority of the given over conceptual construction, as expressed in the familiar motto just quoted. This motto invites us to adopt a bottom-up approach to the philosophical problems, which can be made more explicit through the following methodological rule: (M) No theoretical problem about a type of thing S should be addressed without recourse to the intuitive presence of some token or instance, s, of S.
276
Values, norms, justification
To illustrate, imagine you have been assigned an important contribution for an important handbook, such as the present one. While trying to carry out your task, you might well find yourself having an episode of discouragement. Discouragement is an especially trying emotional state. It is usually task-related, whether the task is assigned or self-imposed, and is felt as overwhelming. This feeling of being overwhelmed does not “cause” discouragement; it is its very core. I could not “perceive” a task as overwhelming without (i) feeling that the task is somehow required of me as something I “ought to do”, and (ii) feeling myself inadequate to the task. A feeling of inadequacy in the absence of a commitment of some sort, whether privately to yourself or in some social setting, would not be (or cause) discouragement. It would be only an emotionally indifferent sense of extraneousness concerning relevant sphere of activity. I am doubtless unable to write a treatise in economics, and awareness of my incompetence would “discourage” any temptation to get involved in such an undertaking. Yet, “being discouraged to do so” would simply amount to lacking any reason and indeed any motivation to do so. I would certainly not feel discouraged. My self-confidence wouldn’t be reduced in the least. There wouldn’t be that oppressive feeling of an unbearable burden on my heart, taking my breath away and reducing me to a state of inertia, an oppression that turns to depression and a sense of failure if I give up the task, giving up a part of my hope, lowering my self-esteem. Discouragement is a challenge to one’s very self hood and future. The first observation we can make based on this (hopefully accurate) description is that the existence of a lived experience of discouragement is beyond doubt. This emotion has a feel; there is something that being discouraged is like. The second observation is that this feeling has an intentional object, which may be a task or, perhaps, a contractual obligation, and hence a social object. And the object is given in a mode of presence, for example, as overwhelmingly hard or oppressive. Third, this mode of presence is a felt quality of a very specific sort: It is a value quality. The discouraging task is arduous, which is a peculiar kind of hardship or difficulty, intuitively related to what is “highest” among the values that bear on your ambitions. But even the mode of presence of the subject is a value quality: inadequacy. This description highlights the intertwining in emotion of those three moments we called phenomenology, intentionality, and epistemology. How are we to conceptualize the “unitary foundation” that binds them into one typical emotion? Let’s start from the last feature. Discouragement, recall, may or may not be appropriate and proportionate. It could not be either without an intentional object—in this case, a well-defined and genuinely exciting project— and no committed subject. More specifically, discouragement cannot be inappropriate unless it makes the task feel more arduous than it actually is, given the subject’s abilities, and, thus, if there were nothing correctible in the way the object is presented to the subject (as too arduous) or in the way the subject is presented to herself (as inadequate). But these modes of presence are in both cases value qualities. In short, discouragement involves the subject’s experience of not living up to the required value standards. To generalize, every emotion is an experience of (some) value (or disvalue) that encompasses both poles of the intentional relation. Value experience is the unitary foundation of the subjective and objective poles of any emotion. In other words, emotions have an intrinsically evaluative, twofold intentionality. Is this generalization plausible? Although the relation between emotion and value is much discussed in contemporary philosophy, what still seems missing is a general theory of feeling as (fallible and correctible) value experience, and one aiming, moreover, to provide a unitary foundation for the dazzling variety of human emotional experiences, as well as for the countless forms experienced values take on. Outlining such a theory is our next task.
277
Roberta De Monticelli
2. The perceptual model of emotions: a false start? Are emotions like sensory perceptions, with values—instead of, say, colors or other secondary qualities—as their intentional objects? Our everyday language encourages that view, insofar as value qualities are labeled with adjectives such as “fearful”, “disgusting”, “admirable”, or “amusing”. What else would feeling fear, disgust, admiration, or amusement be, if not “perceiving” a positive or negative value quality of something? (Deonna and Teroni 2012, 67) A version of this “perceptual theory of emotions”, presenting Wertfühlen (value feeling) as an “epistemic contact” with value (Mulligan 2009, 154), has been attributed to classical phenomenologists (Husserl 1900/1901; Hildebrand 1916, 1922; Hartmann 1932; Reiner 1932; Scheler 1973a; Geiger 1986; Stein 1989, to cite but a few of them). Versions of it have more recently become popular among analytical philosophers as well (McDowell 1985; D’Arms and Jacobson 2000; Goldie 2000, 2004; Tappolet 2000, 2015; Mulligan 2009). For a sustained— but sympathetic—criticism of the perceptual theory, see Brady (2009), who distinguishes literal (such as in Prinz 2004) from non-literal variants of it (such as in de Sousa 1987). Now, the idea that classical works of phenomenology contain a perceptual theory of emotions oversimplifies things to the point of getting them wrong. Consider the following claim (E): (E) Emotions are essentially perceptions of things’ value-qualities, whether positive or negative. I will explain why this thesis has no place in classical phenomenology in the next section. Prima facie, (E) seems a promising way to cash out the idea of an intrinsically evaluative intentionality of the emotions, and this would explain its relative popularity in recent times. Several critics have raised objections against more recent incarnations of the idea (Deonna and Teroni 2012; Bagnoli 2013; Dokič and Leymarie 2013). Emotions, the objection runs, are not to value qualities what visual perceptions are to colors or auditory perceptions are to sounds. Admittedly, the analogy is supported by an analysis of the intentional contents of perceptions and emotions and of their common properties. So, perceptions and emotions have the same mind-to-world direction of fit. They are like cognitive states such as beliefs, and do not exhibit the typical world-to-mind direction of fit of desires and intentions. This difference in direction of fit explains the difference in satisfaction conditions enjoyed by cognitive and conative states. There is a further experiential feature distinguishing direct or immediate cognition. Perceptions and emotions share causal self-reference, i.e., they are about what is (experienced as) causing them (redness, danger). On the side of phenomenal consciousness, the analogy can be spelled out in terms of the lived “affection”—for example, in sweating or trembling—of suffering as it were the impact of reality, through the bodily feeling in which the emotion is lived, much as seeing can be felt in dazzlement or hearing in near-deafening loudness. On both sides, however, fleshing out the analogies immediately reveals important differences, which lead us directly to the critical objections against the perceptual model. From the standpoint of psychology, objects are only envisaged as stimuli. By stimuli, I mean whatever triggers experiences, whether the latter are taken to be qualia, mental representations, images, or otherwise—in short, whatever transpires in the theater of consciousness. The trigger-experience model of perception (Noë 2015, 97) accounts for the experience of colors and shapes only on the basis of the retinal input, thereby leaving the 278
Values, norms, justification
“felt” sweetness—the value quality—and the “feeling” itself without a specific organ. This is the first dissimilarity between perception and emotion. Perception is associated with certain sensory modalities and their specific organs and emotion is not. So, if the red tomato is not there to cause my visual experience of it, I only seem to see a red tomato (i.e., the experience is an illusion). On the contrary, not being appropriate does not make the emotion “illusory”: I may genuinely feel afraid of a barking dog, even if it is not, in fact, dangerous. All subsequent objections of this sort emphasize the relative objectivity (i.e., the more or less universal accessibility) of (stimulus-based) perceptual information in contrast to the subjectivity of emotional responses. 1 2
3
Intersubjectivity/Idiosyncrasy: Unlike perceptions, emotions are highly dependent on the subject’s motivations, beliefs, and character traits. You fear the barking dog, I don’t. Transparency/Self-affection: Unlike perceptions, emotions are not “transparent”. They seem more to induce qualitative states in the experiencing subject, than to reveal qualities (e.g., color, shape) of their object. Cognitive Grounding: Emotions stand in need of justification (“Why are you indignant?” “What are you afraid of?”), unlike perception, which serves as a source of justification for judgments (“Why do you say he is a thief?” “I saw him steal your necklace”). Emotions always seem to need a cognitive basis (perceptions, memories, beliefs, imagined situations), whereas perception provides such a basis for other states.
To conclude, the analogy doesn’t withstand scrutiny. Emotion and perception are significantly dissimilar.
3. Feeling as the unitary foundation of the emotional life Can anything be salvaged from the perceptual theory, notwithstanding these objections? In this section, I respond in the affirmative, drawing on and further developing a view found in some classical phenomenologists. We must first see how that view squares with the perceptual model of emotion. To see that it can, let’s consider the vagueness and ambiguity of the notion of emotions in the context of (E). In current literature on emotion, the concept of emotion is used sometimes in a very broad and comprehensive way as synonymous with “affective state” (Goldie 2000, 51), thus including affective sensations, bodily feelings and moods, or even affective dispositions, like character traits. It is also used in a narrower way that distinguishes emotions from other affective states like (some) moods and bodily feelings. Yet, the criteria of application for the narrower use are not clear. Peter Goldie, contrasting emotions with “brute feelings like toothache, which we cannot make sense of ” (Goldie 2000, 20), seems to propose meaningfulness or intelligibility, a criterion that would be both too inclusive (is esteem not meaningful, without being an emotion?) and too exclusive (as a way of becoming aware of part of one’s body, or of one’s fragility or poor health, even a toothache can make sense, and likewise for physical pleasures, bodily feelings, moods). More recent treatments seem to land in the same predicament. “Considering how emotions contrast with other affective phenomena and, more generally, other psychological states” (Deonna and Teroni 2012, 1) would require a general theory of the feeling core of any affective phenomenon, “bracketing” any aspect of it exceeding that core. What does in a way resemble perception is the core of emotions as well as of any affective state, namely, feeling. Let’s take this as a claim that does not concern emotions only but rather any affective 279
Roberta De Monticelli
phenomenon, including emotions, thus highlighting the unitary foundation of the entire affective life of the person: (F) Feeling is essentially a perception of the value-qualities, whether positive or negative, of things. Exploring the essentially evaluative twofold intentionality of feeling is indeed necessary for a theory of the emotional life of a person in all its richness and complexity, as it is conceived in some classical texts (Pfänder 1913/1916; Scheler 1973a; Stein 2000). In fact, we need a rationale for distinguishing, ordering, and connecting such distinct yet related phenomena as those lumped together in the conceptual hodgepodge one finds in the literature, where one can find toothaches and the pleasures of the flesh, so to speak, along with, say, the sin of pride or the passion for truth. A taxonomy is needed for such a broad range of emotional phenomena. Indeed, included under that heading are local sensory feelings, like pleasure and pain in every sensory modality; global bodily feelings, like feeling ill or well, being tired, hungry, sleepy; moods and states of mind, like anxiety, depression, euphoria; emotions of different kinds and levels (basic, like fear, anger, disgust; non-basic, like shame, regret, guilt, indignation; and, more generally, social, moral, aesthetic, political, religious); personal sentiments (such as love and hate, esteem, respect or contempt, devotion); affective dispositions charged with definite conative habits (which are often called “passions” (like gambling addiction, passion for truth); habitual but changeable dispositions/attitudes (e.g., trust or mistrust, sympathy, reliance on others); attitudes of personality (self-esteem, confidence, humility, curiosity); and existential feelings (feeling at home, feeling lost, at one with nature, helpless) (Ratcliffe 2008). Such a general theory, though, requires a full-fledged phenomenology of the emotional life, which the classical phenomenological works on the topic at least partly provide. By a “full-fledged phenomenology”, I mean something more than what is often understood by “phenomenology” in contemporary philosophy of mind, where this term is commonly taken to refer to the analysis of “phenomenal consciousness”, leaving intentionality for separate treatment. A full-fledged phenomenology of feeling is supposed to highlight the way feeling presents the world. It turns out that the felt world is the world under the aspect of value and disvalue, as a world of goods and ills/evils. Only if feeling is a kind of direct cognition, fallible but capable of self-correction, like perceptual experience, can value judgments be justified. The ultimate foundation of practical rationality, prudential and moral—contra skepticism and naturalistic or postmodern disenchantment (Dworkin 2011)—depends on the question of whether we can take the experience of feeling seriously as a cognitive experience. Is there a place for values in a world of facts? (Köhler 1966) At this point, a terminological remark may be helpful. The word “experience” can be used in two senses. Quite broadly, it designates what-it’s-like-ness, roughly equivalent to the German Erlebnis (often translated “lived experience”). More narrowly, it designates a mode of immediate presence of reality as a boundless source of information, roughly equivalent to the German Erfahrung. Only on this second understanding does it make sense to say that we “learn” from experience, i.e., we can always further explore the given and correct illusions and errors. That is, in experience so understood, we may get reality right or wrong. No such immediate hold on reality figures in remembering or thinking, let alone daydreaming. Granted, daydreaming or remembering and even propositional thinking do have a what-it’slike-ness of their own, after all, as a number of authors have recently maintained (Baine and Montague 2011), and thus count as Erlebnisse, but that is not sufficient for them to also count as Erfahrungen as not every lived experience is an encounter with reality. 280
Values, norms, justification
4. Outline of a general theory of feeling as value experience Feeling, like perception and unlike daydreaming, is a way of encountering reality under its axiological aspect, or so I argue. This section offers a defense of (F) based on a full-fledged phenomenology of feeling. A full-fledged phenomenology of feeling is an analysis of feeling experience in the narrow sense, as a type of direct presence of objects to a subject. Such a mode of presence is what Husserl used to call an “originally giving” consciousness (Husserl 1983, § 67, 154), a type of experience best exemplified by (external) perception. Yet, external perception is hardly the only instance of originally giving consciousness. Further instances include indeed feeling as well as that direct mode of social cognition that phenomenologists usually call empathy. As in classical phenomenology, (F) should be shown to apply to the feeling core of any emotional experience, while “bracketing” whatever aspect of it exceeds pure feeling. We shall hence embed claim (F), expressing the intrinsically evaluative intentionality of feeling, into the framework of a full-fledged phenomenological approach. (F) will then figure as the first of three basic claims or principles that, I argue, constitute the foundation of a phenomenologically acceptable theory of feeling: (F1) Feeling is essentially a perception of things’ value-qualities, whether positive or negative. (F2) All affective phenomena are founded on, but not reducible to, feeling. (F3) The disposition of feeling, or affective sensibility, has a layered structure (“stratification”) corresponding to both a hierarchy of value spheres and a matching hierarchy of levels of self-experience as the two are encountered in occurrent feeling experiences.
4.1 Bracketing motivational components Claims F2 and F3 go against the grain of the current literature, though I contend they alone do justice to the complexity of emotional phenomena and their essential relation to values and norms. More specifically, F2 clarifies the relation that holds among all affective states and dispositions in the taxonomy outlined above and identifies their common feeling core, which, in Husserlian terms, is the unitary foundation of all emotional experience. F2 articulates two “moments” characteristic of most emotional phenomena: a
b
Being affected by: This denotes their receptivity, “passivity”, as when being “struck” by or having an “impression” of something; in short, it names the receptive component of an emotional episode, marking it as a kind of perception. Being inclined to: This refers to their quality of being “moved”, as impulses or desires, highlighting, in short, their conative or action-motivating component.
The founding relation is a relation of ontological dependence. That the receptive component provides the foundation for the conative means, first, that the latter cannot exist without the former, while the former can exist without the latter. There are many examples that illustrate the idea. Think of aesthetic experience, for example, listening to music and discriminating its aesthetic and expressive qualities, or think of the way a mother lovingly contemplates her sleeping child, or, again, of states like blissfulness, calm, despair, surprise, or amazement. Conversely, we can hardly conceive of a conative urge lacking any feeling. So, far from being reducible to excitability, emotional experience is based upon sensitivity (“being affected by”), 281
Roberta De Monticelli
and excitability (“being inclined to”), when the former is in effect, tends to be conditioned by it and not directly by the “stimulus”. This claim goes against a prominent tradition, according to which what is essential and ineliminable in affectivity is its conative component. This tradition is exemplified by theorists like Freud, but can be traced back to Plato, Aristotle, Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, Descartes, and Hume, among others. Even Franz Brentano remains completely faithful to this tradition. Hence, F2 represents a revolutionary innovation in philosophy of mind and personhood as well as a genuine discovery on the part of phenomenology and justification for its cognitivism in axiology (Mulligan 2009, 154). According to this theory, emotions are not mere feelings, i.e., perceptions of value. They are personal responses and re-actions to such perceptions. F2 allows one to “bracket” the motivation-component of affectivity as distinct but dependent on the latter and thus making possible a thorough analysis of “pure feeling”, that is, of its peculiar intentionality. Further, F1 and F3 shed light, respectively, on the objective and subjective poles of the intentional relation, explaining what is essential to any mode of consciousness involving feeling.
4.2 Originally giving consciousness and positionality: the foundations of normativity Recall Husserl’s technical term for our “epistemic contact” with a perceptual object. He calls it an “originally giving” consciousness, or a presence of the object “in flesh and bones”. This involves a mode of presence requiring further experience on the “noematic” side, i.e., on the side of the object. In the paradigmatic case, an object of perception is given as further explorable, indeed, as an infinite source of further experience. There is much more than intuitive presence to “original” presence. If you doubt it, try to count the pillars of the Parthenon just by recalling it in memory. Unless you already knew the number of the temple’s pillars, you won’t be able to count them on your imagined temple. One might think that this difference is captured by a standard (Searlian) analysis of the mental state’s content in terms of direction of fit plus causal self-referentiality (enjoyed by perception, but not by imagination). But how could causal self-referentiality alone account for the possibility of illusion and correction, “learning from experience”, which is constitutive of perception? Illusion and correction would be impossible if experience were only a causal impact of reality on sensory organs. There is a tacit claim of validity (veridicality) to any genuine perception that no sheer causal impact of things on organs can produce. What “bears” the implicit claim of validity is a feature of perception, which makes an act out of it—rather than a state (De Monticelli 2000, 88; 2018). We “take notice” of the (apparent) existence of the perceived object, or “take a position” concerning it. Doxic positionality, independent of any propositional attitude, thought, or conceptually articulated belief, is the noetic correlate of the perceived object’s original givenness and further explorability (Husserl 1983, §103, 250). It is a recognition of something being there or happening, and this is not at all subject to the will. That’s why radical doubt is impossible when it comes to actual perceiving. This taking a stance, in which the embodied subject “lives” while experiencing, is subject to the “jurisdiction of reason”, though. That is, it can turn out to be wrong, and may be “cancelled” in favor of a new position or suspended in hesitation, uncertainty, or further exploring, all of which take place at a pre-linguistic level (the level of the “pre-reflective cogito”, as Merleau-Ponty would have it).
282
Values, norms, justification
Positionality involves a claim of validity, which may be right or wrong, that is, subject to epistemic evaluation within the “jurisdiction of reason”. Perception thus contrasts with imagination, in which, because veridicality is not an issue and positionality is “neutral”, there is no claim of “validity”. I’m perfectly free, for instance, to imagine flying donkeys. This two-sided “noematic-noetic” analysis of perceptual intentionality is the background against which an analysis of feeling intentionality can be now outlined.
4.3 Values in the flesh. Feeling as self-revealing experience of the world In a footnote to a manuscript on emotional life, Husserl quotes William Hamilton, who “says that in feeling we are in a peculiar way one and the same with its content” (Husserl 2005, 165). This observation is the cornerstone for a phenomenology of feeling. It highlights a key point of contrast between feeling and “pure” perceiving. The intentionality of feeling is both a valued presence of objects to a subject and a valued presence of the subject to herself. Just as you can hardly separate your vision of the golden glare of the Pisan Hills from your sentiment of their beauty, so also any measure of proprioception involved in ordinary perception includes a sense of how you are faring bodily. The two poles of feeling are, as noted above, the targets of F1 and F3, respectively.
The feeling dimension of breadth: the plurality of values Noematic description highlights our receptivity to an infinite variety of value qualities belonging to things, capturing how things are experienced as, in a way, good or bad. Receptivity is the phenomenon of “being struck”, grounding emotional responses which are more or less appropriate and in principle correctible. Axiological positionality, which may be positive, negative, or neutral, is as much “under the jurisdiction of reason” as doxic positionality. So far, the analogy with perception is fitting and at least to an extent the “perceptual model” of feeling is justified. I may feel the unpleasantness of a sting, the bodily or psychological discomfort associated with a state of illness or weariness, or the agreeable nature of an arrangement of colors. But I may also sense the nobility of a gesture, the vulgarity of an attitude, the wickedness of an act, or the beauty of a masterpiece. The harmonious way a tool or a piece of furniture fits one’s body, the placid shape of a teapot—these and many other examples illustrate how we also characterize objects in terms of their “affordances” (Gibson 1986). Feeling is similarly essential in the “perception” of these qualities. It is, as the German language has it, a Wertnehmen. To summarize, feeling reveals a neglected yet pervasive feature of the life-world, namely, the richness and variety of positive and negative value qualities that “color” things, events, states of affairs, and situations in the surrounding world. Indeed, it is hard to find descriptive terms, adjectives, that do not refer to some value quality. Axiology is in a sense the ontology of adjectival language.
The depth dimension of feeling: exploring the self “Noetic” description takes into account another feature of feeling, the one noticed by Hamilton and explored by many classic phenomenologists (Hildebrand 1971; Scheler 1973a;
283
Roberta De Monticelli
Stein 2000). Phenomenologically, experience is always also experience of oneself at least as a “minimal self ” of agency and ownership (Zahavi 2010). Theoreticians of the minimal self, though, may have overlooked the extent to which feeling, however intensely directed toward other objects, is always self-revealing. The scope of self-experience far exceeds the limits of minimal self hood but is not subject to the vagaries of a “narrative” self either, as exemplified by a captivating view of narrative self-constitution, not so clearly distinguishable from self-deception (Goldie 2004). The emotionally experienced self sets limits to “creative” self-narrative. Noetic analysis reveals a further dimension of feeling’s intentionality, which we can call its depth. Value experience is always self-experience as well, to the extent that it concerns us. Doubtless, not all feeling experiences are on a par. There are differences in importance or weight, or, we might say, in rank of value, as well as differences in motivating power (i.e., the felt goods and bads). It is as if the experience of different values belonged to different layers of sensibility (Scheler 1973a, 330). Intuitively, we realize that a feeling can touch a person more or less “deeply”, depending on the degree of personal involvement. For instance, the pleasure of a good massage can be felt by most of us as much less involving than the joy of discovering Shakespeare. This joy will likely have a greater degree of motivational power than the pleasure of the massage, and it might even motivate a choice to study English literature rather than something else, a turn of events with significant consequences for the rest of my professional life. Is it possible to give, if not a way to measure depth, at least a rationale for the putative ordering of layers of sensibility concerned, respectively, with the pleasure of a massage and the joy of reading Shakespeare? Scheler suggests that a feeling’s “depth” is proportionate to the importance of the values concerned (Scheler 1973a, 331). Feelings are modes of presence of values at different levels of an axiological hierarchy. Many are dubious of the sort of objective value hierarchy that Scheler offers in his Formalism, with its four spheres of value, i.e., the sensory, the vital, the personal, and the divine. But to fully appreciate it, one must understand its phenomenological grounding, which is intimately bound up with our self hood, as experienced through all the different states of feeling. By “self hood”, I mean the being of a person as she is given to herself, in that quite peculiar and irreducible way in which she is not given to anybody else, that is, from a first-person perspective (Baker 2013). Any value experience is at the same time an experience of self hood, though in varying degrees of centrality, or of wholeness, so to speak. This seems phenomenologically undisputable. The relatively localized pleasure of a massage is an experience of those parts of the body, the ones being touched, as parts of my (bodily) self. The pain I feel when you step on my foot teaches me the boundaries of my bodily being. Similarly, any global, the so-called “vital” (Scheler) comfort or discomfort—hunger, drowsiness, fatigue— informs me of how I am, what condition I am in, as well as what I need insofar as I am in a constant state of vital self-regulation. They inform me, too, of my finitude, my dependence on the material and social environment. I am always in some global felt state, which is exactly what basic emotions alter, by flagging threats and advantageous opportunities in the surrounding world. Moods are also indicative, both for myself and others, of how I am. They can reveal what I lack or need, often without realizing it. But only encounters with what kindles sentiments in me—whether of admiration and contempt, love and hate, political passions, religious or artistic devotion will, over time, tell me who I am. By sentiments, I mean those relatively abiding dispositions to assent to or dissent from the very being and value of someone or something. The peculiarity of sentiments is to present their objects to us as domains of axiological discovery. They instigate a kind of 284
Values, norms, justification
search as exciting and fallible as any search for truth. They motivate higher-level emotions that would not arise in their absence; in addition to motivating choices, actions, and behaviors. Throughout our personal growth—and humans in some respects never cease to grow as persons—our sentimental dispositions lead us to discover, wonder about, change, establish, or disrupt our individual scales of value priorities. Sentimental life, as a ground for our long-term desires, passions, intentions, choices, and actions, is what first awakens what we may call the personal layer of our sensibility, an individual style of feeling and acting, over and above the relatively typical or uniform ways of feeling rooted in more basic sensory and vital layers. A person’s sentiment is always indicative of the state of the growing core of their self hood or personal identity: “In many ways the heart is more the real self of a person than his intellect or will” (Hildebrand 1971). Recall the list of affective phenomena given above, a sampling out of the hodgepodge of familiar emotional experiences. We can now discern a clear order to them, the rationale for this order being their place and role in the self-experience we have in exploring the axiological aspect of reality, from sensory pleasures and pains to global bodily feelings and moods, and on to basic emotions, sentiments structuring our axiological scales, and nourishing higher emotions, will-shaping passions, and even personal vocations. It should thus be apparent now that (F3) is the organizing principle grounding all of the preceding analysis.
References Bagnoli, Carla (Ed.) (2013). Constructivism in Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Baine, Tim, and Montague, Michelle (2011). Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Baker, Lynne R. (2013). Naturalism and the First-Person Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brady, Michael S. (2009). Emotional Insight. The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press. De Monticelli, Roberta (2000). L’avenir de la phénoménologie – Méditations sur la connaissance personnelle. Paris: Aubier Flammarion. ——— (2018). Sensibility, Values and Self hood. For a Phenomenology of the Emotional Life. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 16 195–211. D’Arms, Justine, and Jacobson, Daniel (2000). Sentiment and Value. Ethics 110(4), 722–748. De Sousa, Ronald (1987). The Rationality of Emotions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Deonna, Julien A., and Teroni, Fabrice (2012). The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction. London, New York: Routledge. Dokič, Jerôme, and Lemaire, Stephan (2013). Are Emotions Perceptions of Value? Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43(2), 227–247. Dworkin, Ronald (2011). Justice for Hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Gallagher, Shaun (2006). How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Geiger, Moritz (1986). The Significance of Art. Ed. and transl. by K. Berger. Washington, D.C.: Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology and University Press of America. Gibson, James J. (1986). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2004). Emotion, Feeling, and Knowledge. In: R. C. Solomon (Ed.). Thinking about Feeling. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 91–106. Greenspan, Patricia S. (1988). Emotions and Reasons. An Enquiry into Emotional Justification London, New York: Routledge. Hartmann, Nikolai (1932). Ethics. Transl. by S. Coit. London: George Allen & Unwin. Helm, Bennett W. (2001). Emotional Reason: Deliberation, Motivation and the Nature of Value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hildebrand, Dietrich von (1916). Die Idee der sittlichen Handlung. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 3, 126–252. ——— (1922). Sittlichkeit und ethische Werterkenntnis. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 5, 462–602.
285
Roberta De Monticelli ——— (1971). Das Wesen der Liebe. Regensburg: Josef Habbel. Husserl, Edmund (2001[1900/1901]). Logical Investigations. Transl. by J. N. Findlay. London, New York: Routledge. ——— (1983). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. First Book: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology. Transl. by F. Kersten. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (2005). Wahrnehmung und Aufmerksamkeit, Texte aus dem Nachlass (1893–1912). (=Husserliana 37). Ed. by T. Vongehr, and R. Giuliani. Dordrecht: Springer. Köhler, Wolfgang (1966). The Place of Values in a World of Facts. London: Mentor Books. McDowell, John (1985). Values and Secondary Qualities. Reprinted in J. McDowell (1998), Mind, Value and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 131–150. Mulligan, Kevin (2009). On Being Struck by Value: Exclamations, Motivations and Vocations. In: B. Merker (Ed.). Leben mit Gefühlen – Emotionen, Werte und ihrer Kritik. Paderborn: Mentis, 141–162. Noë, Alva (2015). Strange Tools: Art and Human Nature. New York: Hill and Wang. Pfänder, Alexander (1913/1916). Zur Psychologie der Gesinnungen. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 1, 325–404 and 3, 1–125. Prinz, Jesse J. (2004). Gut Reactions. A Perceptual Theory of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ratcliffe Matthew (2008). Feelings of Being. Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. Scheler, Max (1973a). Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values. Transl. by M. Frings and R. L. Funk. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. ——— (1973b). Ordo Amoris. In: D. R. Lachterman (Ed.). Selected Philosophical Essays. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 98–135. Stein, Edith (1989). On the Problem of Empathy. Transl. by W. Stein. Washington, D.C.: ICS Publications. ——— (2000). Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities. Transl. by M. C. Baseheart and M. Sawicki, Washington, D.C.: ICS Publications. Tappolet, Christine (2000). Émotions et valeurs. Paris: PUF. ——— (2015). Value and Emotions. In: I Hirose, and J. Olson (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 80–95. Zahavi, Dan (2010). Minimal Self and Narrative Self. A Distinction in Need of Refinement. In: T. Fuchs, H. Sattel, and P. Henningsen (Eds.). The Embodied Self: Dimensions, Coherence, and Disorders. Stuttgart: Schattauer, 3–11. Further reading 1. More classics of phenomenology Hildebrand, Dietrich von (1977). Ästhetik. 1. Teil. Gesammelte Werke, Band V. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer. ——— (1984). Ästhetik. 2. Teil. Gesammelte Werke, Band VI. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer. Husserl, Edmund (1973[1907]). Ding und Raum: Vorlesungen 1907. Ed. by U. Claesges (=Husserliana 16). Den Haag: Nijhoff. Kolnai, Aurel (1977). Ethics, Value and Reality, Selected Papers (1957–1972). Worcester, MA, London: Trinity Press. ——— (1998). The Standard Modes of Aversion: Fear, Disgust and Hatred. Mind 107(427), 581–595. ——— (2004). On Disgust. Ed. by B. Smith and C. Korsmeyer. Chicago: Open Court. Reinach, Adolf (1989). Sämtliche Werke. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Ed. by K. Schuhmann and B. Smith. München: Philosophia. Reiner, Hans (1932). Der Grund der sittlichen Bindung und das sittliche Gute. Halle: Niemeyer. Scheler, Max (1954[1913]). The Nature of Sympathy. Transl. by P. Heath. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. 2. Further contemporary debates Bagnoli, Carla (Ed.) (2011). Morality and the Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. D’Arms, Justin, and Jacobson, Daniel (2000). The Moralistic Fallacy: On the “Appropriateness” of Emotions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51(1), 65–90. Goldie, Peter (2004). On Personality. London, New York: Routledge. Johnston, Mark (2001). The Authority of Affect. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63(1), 181–214.
286
Values, norms, justification Mulligan, Kevin (2010). Emotions and Values. In: P. Goldie (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 475–500. Roberts, Robert (2003). Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tappolet, Christine (2011). Values and Emotions: Neo-Sentimentalist’s Prospect. In: C. Bagnoli (Ed.). Moral Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 117–134.
287
25 MORALITY AND THE EMOTIONS John J. Drummond and Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl
The relation between the emotions and morality is complex and varied, and phenomenological reflection thereupon—we shall call it “moral phenomenology”1—is equally complex and varied. Moral phenomenology seeks to clarify the intentional structures at work in (1) our experiences of valuing, choosing, planning, and acting in ways that have moral significance; (2) our experiences of persons, actions, situations, and events as good or bad, right or wrong, and obligatory, permissible, or impermissible; and (3) our experiences of institutions and social structures as beneficial or harmful or as liberating or imprisoning. This chapter will discuss (i) the emotions in the disclosure of moral value, (ii) the emotions and moral obligation, and (iii) a well-ordered and -balanced emotional life as a constituent of a flourishing life (see, e.g., Drummond 2010a; Ozar 2010; Hermberg and Gyllenhammer 2013; Steinbock 2014, 2016; Drummond and Rinofner-Kreidl 2017).
1. Emotions and the disclosure of value Moral phenomenology, as we understand it, is situated within the axiological discussions prevalent among the early phenomenologists—those working (roughly) in the first third of the 20th century, such as Edmund Husserl (1988, 2004), Adolf Reinach (1989), Edith Stein (1989, 2007), Max Scheler (1973), Nicolai Hartmann (1963), and Dietrich von Hildebrand (1916, 1922, 1953). These phenomenologists agree (1) that the disclosure of values depends on subjects capable of feelings and emotions, (2) that a thing being valuable is not reducible to it being felt valuable, (3) that the emotions have moral relevance,2 and (4) that our choices are rooted in the emotions’ disclosure of the value of both the ends at which the agent aims and the actions conducive to those ends. Though (1) through (4) attribute crucial importance to emotions as basic human experiences, phenomenologists reject attempts to naturalize the emotions and morality when those attempts extend beyond understanding emotions and morality as proper to human nature and as anchored in natural properties of things (cf. Rinofner-Kreidl 2011, 2015). In particular, the above theses deny the alleged opposition between the emotions and rational thinking, that has been used to advance a debunking argument from the irrationality of moral emotions (Campbell 2015, §4.3). Notwithstanding their shared commitment to (1) through (4), there is disagreement among phenomenologists about the nature of value, a disagreement best exemplified in the 288
Morality and the emotions
difference between Husserl and Scheler. Husserl characterizes the experience of value as a type of perceiving; he uses the term wertnehmen (1989a, 12; 2004, 120, 283, 292)—a modification of wahrnehmen, to perceive or take as true—to denote the taking of “objects, things, qualities, and states of affairs that stand there in the valuing as valuable (im Werten als werte)” (Husserl 2014a, 190). For Husserl, to experience a value is to have an intentional feeling or emotion grasp its object as valued. The value of the object is grounded in the object’s nonaxiological properties that, relative to the physiological constitution, experiential history, interests, concerns, and commitments of the subject, make the object valuable. The value attribute is understood as a dyadic attribute dependent both upon features of the object and upon subjective structures at work in the subject’s evaluatively intending the object. In the moral sphere, examples of such Wertnehmungen include seeing a student gratuitously punch a classmate as morally wrong or hearing someone making a rude remark to a colleague as morally wrong (see also Audi 2013). Value-perceptions underlie both value-judgments and the identification of the a priori (universal) “values as objects themselves” (Wertgegenstände or Wertobjektitäten) (Husserl 2014a, 190–191). Disclosure of the latter, however, requires reflecting upon the intentional contents of the underlying value-perceptions and abstracting the value-content of similarly valued objects. Husserl’s axiological theory has, therefore, been characterized as a two-tiered theory of the constitution of value (Rinofner-Kreidl 2016c). Scheler (1973), by contrast, claims that an intentional feeling directly and originally apprehends an a priori value. The experience of value in an intentional feeling is epistemologically (although not temporally) prior to the experience of an entity as bearing that value. The value-perception, in other words, apprehends the instantiated value as the good-making characteristic of the object valued as good, but, contra Husserl, the a priori value itself does not depend on any non-axiological properties of the bearer or any psychological features of the subject experiencing it, although experiencing an entity with particular non-axiological properties is an occasion for the subject’s feeling the value and attributing it to the bearer. For Scheler, valued objects (goods) are empirical, variable, and subjective objects of desire, but the values themselves are a priori, immutable, and objective ideals that are ontologically prior to goods. Whereas, for Husserl, values are a priori in the sense of being necessary and universal features of objects possessing that value but are not epistemologically prior to goods, they are, for Scheler, both ontologically and epistemologically prior to goods. And whereas for Husserl value attributes are dyadic, value-objects are for Scheler monadic. Scheler further believes that there is an a priori hierarchy of values. In ascending order, they are (1) the values of the pleasant and unpleasant; (2) vital values, such as the fine and the vulgar; (3) spiritual values, such as the beautiful and the ugly, correctness and incorrectness; and (4) the values of the holy and unholy. Although the list does not include any moral values, the hierarchy has moral significance. Scheler distinguishes the purely ideal oughtto-be (the value) from the moral ought-to-do (Scheler 1973, 203ff.) and claims that insight into the ideal ought-to-be grounds the willing and realizing the moral ought-to-do. Moral value, then, is found in the actions realizing the values in the hierarchy. There is, however, no clear account in Scheler of the transition from the insight into ideal value-possibilities to the experience of moral imperatives. What is clear is that in the order of experience, the movement is from the lower to higher values and that the higher a value, the more difficult it is for a subject to realize it. Husserl’s early ethics is a form of ideal consequentialism, and he argues that the laws governing our axiological and practical reasoning are a priori laws. Husserl’s consequentialism, however, explicitly recognizes that the reasoned determination of the highest good must take account of what is attainable in the circumstances in which the particular agent acts. 289
John J. Drummond and Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl
The practical domain, in other words, is circumscribed in reference to both the agent’s capabilities and the agent’s circumstances. Husserl later modified his view, bringing to the fore this idea of the particularity of the agent and her practical domain. Central to the later view is the recognition that the same objective value can become an “individual, subjective value of love,” that is, that “the same value can be infinitely more ‘significant’ for one person than another” (Husserl 2012, 146). Hence, Husserl came to favor the view that “absolute loves” (commitments) generate “absolute oughts” (Husserl 2012, 146; 2014b, 391–392). The idea is that a subject with certain loves or commitments unconditionally values those things to which the love or commitment binds the subject (Husserl 2014b, 391–392). Such absolute loves motivate an agent to adopt an ethical life-project and to undertake those actions necessary to realize that project, a project that is “the deepest ground of [her] personal identity and individuality” (Melle 1991, 131; see also 2002, 243–244). The dyadic character of Husserl’s notion of value comes to the fore even more clearly in these later views. This does not, however, mean that values for Husserl are subjective or viciously relativistic. Values are more significant for different persons having different experiential histories, different cultural traditions, and different commitments, but they are no less objective (cf. Drummond 2010b; Rinofner-Kreidl 2016b). Nicolai Hartmann, like Scheler, maintains that feelings and emotions access a priori values. On Hartmann’s view, ideal values are experienced as universal demands, but they can conflict with personal values in ways that can never be fully resolved. To do what everyone should do in the same circumstances is, in effect, to say that an agent is replaceable by anyone, and, for Hartman, this is to deny the agent’s individuality as a person (Hartmann 1963, 357). Moreover, appeals to universal values and principles depend upon a similarity among the situations in which we act, but any action is necessarily tied to both a particular situation and a particular agent in that situation. Hence, the universality of a principle undercuts its own applicability to particular situations that, owing to the uniqueness of persons, their interests, and commitments, is itself unique (Hartmann 1963, 358–360). For Hartmann, universal values and principles—just insofar as they fail to heed the individual personalities of agents—in a paradoxical way do not, and cannot, offer moral guidance. Systematically viewed, any phenomenological critique of a strong commitment to the universality of values will acknowledge the more or less extensive context-dependence of morally relevant emotions. Context-dependence refers to the specific ways in which or the specific aspects according to which different emotions function as reason-responsive, and it is relevant to assessing their moral significance and moral impact. It is impossible to determine the latter once and for all by considering only abstract types of emotional experiences. For example, it is not universally true that showing gratitude is the morally correct response to every situation in which one receives a gift as when a gift is intended to humiliate a less fortunate person. The moral significance of gratitude cannot be stated in advance, once and for all. It displays considerable variation according to the different circumstances in which it is realized and the different kinds of behavior and social interaction involved. Given that it is nonetheless feasible to determine non-arbitrary and invariant relations holding between specific types of emotion, types (or patterns) of behavior or interaction, and types of situation, we need not overinterpret examples of historical and cultural variation. The latter do not without further ado warrant a strong moral relativism. We may characterize the relevant differences in how various emotions are reasonresponsive in terms of varying requirements and demands of appropriateness. For some emotions, responding appropriately to an object lies exclusively or predominantly in accurately grasping its nature. This is true, for example, with regard to the (unarmed) hiker’s 290
Morality and the emotions
fear in the face of a horde of howling wolves. For other emotions, appropriate responses depend more extensively and more determinatively on the motives underlying a person’s intentions and modes of behavior or expressions. Humility, hate, and indignation provide suitable examples. In yet other cases, judging whether an emotion is an appropriate response requires accounting for the manner in which the person addresses an object or another person. Generosity and gratitude are instructive examples of an emotional engagement whose moral character and moral achievement are complex in terms of combining the elements listed above: picking out of suitable objects, entertaining proper motives, and referring not only to suitable objects but also doing so in a suitable manner. Determining how precisely these combined requirements play out in different emotions is part of the micro-ethical descriptive-analytic work done by a moral phenomenology (see, e.g., Chapter 43 in this volume). The above considerations support the view that for phenomenologists, it is far more important to delve into the moral phenomenology of particular emotions than to begin by distinguishing moral emotions from non-moral ones. To give priority to fine-grained bottom-up descriptions of particular emotions may result in blurring apparently clear-cut distinctions, but it could turn out to be both more sensible and more faithful to the phenomena to consider varying degrees or different spheres of moral significance as well as the different evaluative power particular emotions might manifest in typical situations.
2. Emotions and moral obligation Values are often experienced as confronting us, as prescriptions, norms, imperatives, obligations, demands, and so forth. The problem of making the transition from the experience of value to the experience of obligation provides the context for understanding those phenomenologists who emphasize the deontological aspect of morality. Emmanuel Levinas, for example, claims that the experience of obligation is prior to all acts of evaluation, all choices, all projects, and all dictates of reason. Obligation arises for Levinas, as it does for Kant, from beyond all “inclinations.” Unlike Kant, however, Levinas turns his attention to a primordial sociality to find the ground of obligation. Ethics begins when another addresses me, summons me, and commands me, and this awakens in me a sense of responsibility (Levinas 1969, 43, 50–51; cf. Darwall 2006). Only insofar as I acknowledge this command do I live in a world with the other and become a person myself. The experience of the other is from the start an experience of obligation. The question raised by this account concerns the motivation of moral action. I can encounter moral obligation as my obligation only insofar as what I encounter is referred back to my moral concerns. As Hartmann recognizes, obedience to the moral imperative apart from any reference to inclinations or desires depersonalizes the action insofar as the action is divorced even from the agent’s will to flourish as a human agent. More recently, although on entirely different theoretical grounds, Mackie (1977, chap. 1) has argued that invoking universal principles and abstract value-entities renders moral motivation mysterious. In either case, we are led back to the sphere of social interaction in which all moral action occurs. If it is correct (1) that emotions are indispensable for each and every instance of Wertnehmung and (2) that in undergoing emotional experiences, human beings find themselves entangled in particular social relations and situations, these relations and situation are the natural starting-points for a phenomenological investigation of moral motivation. Within this domain, moral motivation presents itself as an ongoing attempt to establish a proper balance between self-interest and other-directedness. 291
John J. Drummond and Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl
The moral significance for the agent of various emotions and the moral obligations entailed in undergoing and expressing emotions depend on how these emotional experiences establish a balance between self-interest and other-directedness. It is often the case that this balance is not only subtle but also involves both the extended experience of undergoing an emotional process (rather than a fleeting state) and a far-reaching social dynamic (rather than an inner mental “reality”). This is obvious, for instance, with regard to feelings of grief (cf. Rinofner-Kreidl 2016a, 2017). Generally, a specific emotion’s balancing achievement can unfold only if the emotion is realized in a concrete situation. Nor can we become aware of this achievement or assess it from various points of view (e.g., moral, social, or psychological) unless we are acquainted with the peculiar circumstances in which the emotion becomes manifest. Let us assume that I receive a gift I dislike. Yet, I know that the benefactor has made a great effort to obtain it and expected it to make me happy. If, on these conditions, I failed to show any gratitude or, even worse, declared how ugly and disgusting the gift was, this certainly would be insensitive and unfair. Such behavior could hardly count as a morally decent response. Yet, failing to show gratitude in the face of a “generous” gift from someone who deliberately hands it over with a disrespectful and humiliating gesture that makes me feel ashamed is entirely justified. In this case, failing to be grateful is a morally suitable response (cf. Chapter 43 in this volume). Analogous considerations and cases can be found for anger, guilt, forgiveness, and other emotions. Everyday motivations are typically mixed and involve elements of self-concern and other-directedness. This kind of motivation reflects a moral agent’s communality whose selfunderstanding is replete with references to social relations and experiences. It is, however, necessary to note that dwelling on moral motivation according to the above lines of reasoning is not meant to be a phenomenological inquiry into the ultimate sources of normativity. Talk of (mixed) moral motivation in the above sense presupposes the social constitution of the moral self (or agent). By contrast, inquiring into the ultimate sources of normativity entails an account of the social constitution of the self (cf. Crowell 2013; Zahavi 2014). If this is done on phenomenological grounds, that is, in a descriptive-analytic manner, it is crucial to give due attention to and to accurately expose the radical otherness of the other. One of us has suggested that an axiological approach can ground obligation by appealing to the phenomenological notion of empathy (Drummond 2006). Empathy is the experience in which one experiences a “subject-object,” an embodied, experiential agent who shares a world with me (Husserl 1973, 427). To this extent, the other is, like me, a subject in the world who is aware of the world and, unlike me, a subject who radically transcends me and my perceptual capacities. I can never directly experience the other’s experiences, and this paradox of sameness and radical difference in the experience of the other is a universal and mutual feature of our encounter of other persons. Both respect and sympathy for other persons are rooted in empathy. Respect is rooted in the radical otherness of the other, while sympathy for other persons is rooted in the sameness and communalization of persons (Drummond 2006, 2017b). A subject moves beyond mere empathy in the encounter with the other when she encounters a being who is not merely a conscious agent but one who is capable of (i) articulating the goods they pursue and the choices she makes; (ii) reflecting on her ends and choices; and (iii) expressing her moral judgments and reasoning in words as well as actions. When we encounter another in whose actions we can note a firm and habitual commitment to overarching goals that give meaning to and order that person’s life, our affective response is appraisal respect.3 When we recognize that the ground of appraisal respect lies in the rational capacities necessary for and presupposed by an agent’s acting in 292
Morality and the emotions
ways that elicit appraisal respect, we recognize that the possession of these rational capacities constitutes the dignity of rational agents. Recognition respect, which is phenomenologically posterior but morally prior to appraisal respect, grasps any being possessing these capacities, whether or not they are well exercised, as having the dignity proper to a free, rational agent (see also Chapter 43 in this volume). The mutuality in empathy introduces a communalization that is essential to objective knowledge (Mertens 2000, 10–14), including moral knowledge. Respect and sympathy are two affective responses to the empathically perceived other that complement our understanding of the other by introducing value and motivations into our shared experience. I experience—or should experience—the other both as having dignity and as a person with whose well-being and flourishing I am—or should be—concerned. I recognize—or should recognize—that, like all understanding, my understanding of emotion, value, and moral concepts is an intersubjectively achieved understanding that responds both to the way things are and to the histories, concerns, and commitments of both individuals and communities. In brief, in recognition respecting another, I am focused on the other precisely and exclusively as an alternate center of rational, conscious agency, as a person having dignity. The particular characteristics of that person’s experiences are irrelevant to the nature of recognition respect. However, the person I experience has particular experiences that I empathically recognize. In encountering the other as both like me and irreducibly different, it is necessarily the case that, along with respect, what Nancy Sherman (1997, 175–181; 1998, 134–139) calls “attractive” responses also occur. Chief among these is sympathy, which includes a care for the other (cf. Scheler 1954, 8; Darwall 1998, 261; Husserl 2004, 194; Zahavi 2008, 516) and motivates us to help them realize their chosen goods. We should not collapse sympathy into pity or commiseration (see also Chapter 37 in this volume). In empathically perceiving another’s joy, for example, I can sympathetically savor, relish, or rejoice in her joy (Scheler 1954, 42). A cultivated sympathy inclines us toward caring for and aiding the other person that recognition respect discloses as a moral agent worthy of and demanding our own moral attention. Just as we need sympathy in relation to recognition respect, we need recognition respect in relation to sympathy. The irreducible difference between self and other cannot be lost from view. The other is always irreducibly other, and recognition respect of the irreducibility of the other—a conscious, free being in her own right—creates the moral space in which sympathy can work. Sympathy, conversely, fills the moral space bounded by respect. Respect and properly cultivated sympathy jointly preserve the “sameness and communalization in irreducible difference” characteristic of the empathy grounding them.
3. Emotions and human flourishing The respect-sympathy structure at the basis of morality has further implications for ethics. First and foremost, the recognition of the communalizing nature of empathically grounded respect and sympathy has further implications for thinking about the flourishing of free, rational beings. Husserl understands that telos in terms of the achievement of evidenced truth in all the spheres of reason (Husserl 1989a, 33), in terms, that is, of “deciding” for oneself what to avow as true (Husserl 1989b, 281–282; see also Drummond 2010a). Granted that an agent’s understanding of emotion-, value-, and moral concepts is an intersubjectively achieved understanding, that agent depends upon other subjects in her striving for the telos for rational agents. To achieve it, an individual agent must (i) grasp truthfully the way things are, (ii) have appropriate affective responses and evaluations of things, and (iii) act rightly in the light of these evaluations. In deciding for herself what to avow, she executes 293
John J. Drummond and Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl
her reflected upon and evidenced intersubjective understanding, and yet she must remain capable of taking a critical distance from it. In encountering other persons and challenging my own view with theirs, I recognize another subject who is irreducibly different from me. She is the subject of her own cognitions, emotions, and actions. In this recognition, I experience an obligation out of respect for the other not to interfere with her pursuit of the goods of agency, that is, an obligation not to interfere with her autonomous cognitive, emotional, and volitional responses to things and persons in the world. Moreover, in acknowledging that my flourishing depends as well on the other’s flourishing, I adopt a sympathetic care for the other; I experience the desire to do what I can to promote the other’s realizing the goods of agency for herself as conducing to human flourishing for both of us. This encourages the development of virtues such as humility, charity, generosity, a balance between open-mindedness and firm-mindedness. Phenomenological approaches to ethics are not of mere historical interest. There has recently been an explosion of interdisciplinary research into the emotions, including by phenomenologists. For example, Íngrid Vendrell Ferran has explored the work on the emotions by early, realist phenomenologists (2008), and she has explored the implications of their work for contemporary metaethics and theory of value (2013) and for the analysis of individual moral emotions (see, e.g., 2017). Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl, developing ideas found in Husserl and Scheler, has explored the ethical significance of a number of emotions (2014a, 2014b, 2016a, 2017). Sophie Loidolt (2010, 2011, 2018) has developed ethical ideas from both Husserl and Arendt. Sara Heinämaa (2014, 2017), Anne Ozar (2009, 2010, 2017), and Michael Kelly (2016a, 2016b, 2016c) have analyzed morally relevant emotions, and Paul Gyllenhammer (2010, 2017) has tied his analyses of emotions to the virtues (see also Reynolds 2013). John Drummond (2006, 2010a, 2010b, 2013, 2015, 2017a) has modified Husserl’s account of the emotions within a eudaimonistic context. Janet Donohoe (2004) and James Hart (1992, 1997) have explored Husserl’s later ethical thought, and Anthony Steinbock (e.g., 2014, 2016) has developed a view of moral emotions grounded in Scheler’s views. William Smith (2012), Irene McMullin (2019), and Steven Crowell (2007a, 2007b, 2013, 2015) have addressed the question of moral normativity—and the place of the emotions therein—from a Heideggerian perspective. The rise of logical positivism and scientific naturalism pushed aside the study of emotions as supposedly irrational and of ethics as outside the scope of a positivistic philosophy. Since the publication of John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice in 1961, however, the study of ethics has returned to a central position in philosophy. Moreover, important publications by Elizabeth Anscombe (1958), Peter Geach (1977), Philippa Foot (1978), and Alasdair MacIntyre (1981) have re-energized the Aristotelian tradition in ethics with its emphasis on the role of the emotions in morality. These events have served to re-ignite the phenomenological tradition’s investigation of these questions, as evidenced by the just mentioned researchers. The debates have, in a sense, begun anew. There can be no doubt that these studies will continue to enrich our understanding of the emotions and our sense of the varied role they play in morality and in flourishing human lives.
Notes
294
Morality and the emotions
References Anscombe, Elizabeth (1997[1958]). Modern Moral Philosophy. In: R. Crisp, and M. Slote (Eds.). Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 26–44. Audi, Robert (2013). Moral Perception. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Campbell, Richmond (2015). Moral Epistemology. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-epistemology/. Crowell, Steven G. (2007a). Sorge or Selbstbewußtsein? Heidegger and Korsgaard on the Sources of Normativity. European Journal of Philosophy 15(3), 315–333. ——— (2007b). Conscience and Reason: Heidegger and the Grounds of Intentionality. In: S. Crowell and J. Malpas (Eds.). Transcendental Heidegger. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 43–62. ——— (2013). Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. New York: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2015). Why Is Ethics First Philosophy? Levinas in Phenomenological Context. European Journal of Philosophy 23, 564–588. Darwall, Stephen (1977). Two Concepts of Respect. Ethics 88, 36–49. ——— (1998). Empathy, Sympathy, Care. Philosophical Studies 89, 261–282. ——— (2006). The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Donohoe, Janet (2004). Husserl on Ethics and Intersubjectivity: From Static to Genetic Phenomenology. Amherst: Humanity Books. Drummond, John J. (2006). Respect as a Moral Emotion: A Phenomenological Approach. Husserl Studies 22, 1–27. ——— (2007). Moral Phenomenology and Moral Intentionality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7, 35–49. ——— (2010a). Self-Responsibility and Eudaimonia. In: C. Ierna, H. Jacobs, and F. Mattens (Eds.). Philosophy, Phenomenology, Sciences 441–460. Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (2010b). Universal Goods, Cultural Specificity. In: K. Lau, C. Cheung, and T. Kwan (Eds.). Identity and Alterity. Phenomenology and Cultural Traditions. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 247–258. ——— (2013). The Intentional Structure of Emotions. Logical Analysis and the History of Philosophy/ Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse 16, 244–263.
295
John J. Drummond and Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl ——— (2015). Neo-Aristotelian Ethics: Naturalistic or Phenomenological. In: J. Bloechl, and N. de Warren (Eds.). Phenomenology in a New Key: Between Analysis and History. Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (2017a). Having the Right Attitudes. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 15, 142–163. ——— (2017b). “Empathy and the Foundations of Morality.” Lecture at Conference Empathy, Recognition, Morality, University of Copenhagen, Copenhagen, September 21. Drummond, John J., and Rinofner-Kreidl, Sonja (Eds.) (2017). Emotional Experiences: Ethical and Social Significance. London: Rowman & Littlefield International. Foot, Philippa (1978). Virtues and Vices. In: Ph. Foot (Ed.). Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1–18. Geach, Peter (1977). The Virtues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gyllenhammer, Paul (2010). Sartre on Shame: From Ontology to Social Critique. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 41, 48–63. ——— (2017). Shame and Virtue. In: J. J. Drummond, and S. Rinofner-Kreidl (Eds.). Emotional Experiences: Ethical and Social Significance. London: Rowman & Littlefield International, 73–90. Hart, James G. (1992). The Person and the Common Life: Studies in a Husserlian Social Ethics. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (1997). The Summum Bonum and Value-Wholes: Aspects of a Husserlian Axiology and Theology. In: J. Hart, and L. Embree (Eds.). Phenomenology of Value and Valuing. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Hartmann, Nicolai (1963). Ethics. Transl. by S. Coit. New York: Humanities Press. Heinämaa, Sara (2014). Husserl’s Ethics of Renewal: A Personalistic Approach. In: M. Tuominen, S. Heinämaa, and V. Mäkinen (Eds.). New Perspectives to Aristotelianism and Its Critics. Leiden: Brill, 196–212. ——— (2017). Love and Admiration (Wonder): Fundaments of the Self–Other Relations. In: J. J. Drummond, and S. Rinofner-Kreidl (Eds.). Emotional Experiences: Ethical and Social Significance. London: Rowman & Littlefield, 155–174. Helm, Bennett W. (2017). Communities of Respect: Grounding Responsibility, Authority, and Dignity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hermberg, Kevin, and Gyllenhammer, Paul (Eds.) (2013). Phenomenology and Virtue Ethics. London: Bloomsbury. Husserl, Edmund (1973). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität: Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil: 1929–1935. Ed. by I. Kern. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. ——— (1988). Vorlesungen über Ethik und Wertlehre 1908–1914. Ed. by U. Melle. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (1989a). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. Transl. by R. Rojcewicz, and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (1989b). Aufsätze und Vorträge (1922–1937). Ed. by T. Nenon and H. R. Sepp. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (2004). Einleitung in die Ethik: Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1920/1924. Ed. by H. Peucker. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (2012). Einleitung in der Philosophie. Vorlesungen 1916–1920. Ed. by H. Jacobs. Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (2014a). Ideas for a Pure Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy. First Book: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Transl. by D. Dahlstrom. Indianapolis: Hackett. ——— (2014b). Grenzprobleme der Phänomenologie: Analysen des Unbewusstseins und der Instinkte. Metaphysik. Späte Ethik. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1908–1937). Ed. by T. Sowa, and T. Vongehr. Dordrecht: Springer. Kelly, Michael R. (2016a). Grief: Putting the Past before Us. Quaestiones Disputatae 7, 156–177. ——— (2016b). Envy and Ressentiment, a Difference in Kind: A Critique and Renewal of Scheler’s Phenomenological Account. In: B. Harding, and M. Kelly (Eds.). Early Phenomenology: Metaphysics, Ethics, and the Philosophy of Religion. London: Bloomsbury 49–66, ——— (2016c). Phenomenological Distinctions: Two Types of Envy and Their Difference from Covetousness. In: J. A. Simmons and J. E. Hackett (Eds.). Phenomenology for the Twenty-First Century. London: Palgrave-Macmillan, 157–177 Levinas, Emmanuel (1969). Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Transl. by A. Lingis. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
296
Morality and the emotions Loidolt, Sophie (2010). Husserl und das Faktum der praktischen Vernunft: Anstoß und Herausforderung einer phänomenologischen Ethik der Person. In: C. Ierna, H. Jacobs, and F. Mattens (Eds.). Philosophy Phenomenology Sciences. Dordrecht: Springer, 483–503. ——— (2011). Fünf Fragen an Husserls Ethik aus gegenwärtiger Perspektive. In: V. Mayer, C. Erhard, and M. Scherini (Eds.). Die Aktualität Husserls. Freiburg, München: Alber, 299–334. ——— (2018). Phenomenology of Plurality: Hannah Arendt on Political Intersubjectivity. London, New York: Routledge. MacIntyre, Alasdair (1981). After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Mackie, John L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. New York: Penguin. McMullin, Irene (2019). Existential Flourishing: A Phenomenology of the Virtues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Melle, Ullrich (1991). The Development of Husserl’s Ethics. Études phénoménologiques 7, 115–135. ——— (2002). Edmund Husserl: From Reason to Love. In: J. J. Drummond, and L. Embree (Eds.). Phenomenological Approaches to Moral Philosophy: A Handbook. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 229–248. Mertens, Karl (2000). Husserls Phänomenologie der Monade: Bemerkungen zu Husserls Auseinandersetzung mit Leibniz. Husserl Studies 17, 1–20. Mulligan, Kevin (2014). Moral Emotions. In: D. Sandner, and K. Scherer (Eds.). Oxford Companion to Emotion and the Affective Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 262–265. Ozar, Anne (2009). The Moral Significance of Sincerity. PhD Dissertation, Fordham University: ETD Collection for Fordham University. https://fordham.bepress.com/dissertations/AAI3353775. ——— (2010). The Value of a Phenomenology of the Emotions for Cultivating One’s Own Character. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 10, 303–317. ——— (2017). Trust as a Moral Emotion. In: J. J. Drummond, and S. Rinofner-Kreidl (Eds.). Emotional Experiences: Ethical and Social Significance. London: Rowman & Littlefield International. Rawls, John (1961). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Reinach, Adolf (1989). Die Überlegung: ihre ethische und rechtliche Bedeutung. In: K. Schuhmann, and B. Smith (Eds.). Sämtliche Werke. Textkritische Ausgabe. München: Philosophia Verlag. Reynolds, Jack (2013). Phenomenology and Virtue Ethics: Complementary Antitheoretical Methodological and Ethical Trajectories? In: K. Hermberg, and P. Gyllenhammer (Eds.). Phenomenology and Virtue Ethics. London: Bloomsbury, 113–131. Rinofner-Kreidl, Sonja (2011). Motive, Gründe und Entscheidungen in Husserls intentionaler Handlungstheorie. In: V. Mayer, C. Erhard, and M. Scherini (Eds.). Die Aktualität Husserls. Freiburg/München: Alber, 232–277. ——— (2014a). Neid und Ressentiment: Zur Phänomenologie negativer sozialer Gefühle. In: J. Müller, and K. Mertens (Eds.), Die Dimension des Sozialen: Neue Philosophische Zugänge zu Fühlen, Wollen und Handeln. Berlin: De Gruyter, 103–126. ——— (2014b). Neid. Zur moralischen Relevanz einer “Outlaw Emotion”. In: I. Römer (Ed.). Affektivität und Ethik bei Kant und in der Phänomenologie. Berlin: De Gruyter, 173–204. ——— (2015). Mereological Foundation vs. Supervenience? A Husserlian Proposal to Re-Think Moral Supervenience in Robert Audi’s Ethical Intuitionism. Metodo 3, 81–124. ——— (2016a). On Grief ’s Ambiguous Nature: Persisting vs. Transforming, Concealed vs. Expressed. Quaestiones Disputata 7, 178–207. ——— (2016b). Moral Perception: On What It Requires and How It Benefits from Reading Fictional Texts. In: B. Centi (Ed.). Ethical Reflections on the Mind/Body Problem. Firenze: Le Lettere. ——— (2016c). Disenchanting the Fact/Value Dichotomy: A Critique of Felix Kaufmann’s Views on Value and Social Reality. In: A. Salice, and H. B. Schmid (Eds.). The Phenomenological Approach to Social Reality: History, Concepts, Problems. Cham: Springer, 317–348. ——— (2017). Grief: Loss and Self-Loss. In: J. J. Drummond, and S. Rinofner-Kreidl (Eds.). Emotional Experiences: Ethical and Social Significance. London: Rowman & Littlefield. Scheler, Max (1954). The Nature of Sympathy. Transl. by P. Heath. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. ——— (1973). Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values: A New Attempt toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism. Transl. by M. Frings, and R. Funk. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Sherman, Nancy (1997). Making a Necessity of Virtue: Aristotle and Kant on Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
297
John J. Drummond and Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl ——— (1998). Concrete Kantian Respect. Social Philosophy and Policy 15, 119–148. Smith, William H. (2012). The Phenomenology of Moral Normativity. New York: Routledge. Stein, Edith (1989). On the Problem of Empathy. Transl. by W. Stein. Washington, DC: ICS Publications. ——— (2007). An Investigation Concerning the State. Transl. by M. Sawicki. Washington, DC: ICS Publications. Steinbock, Anthony (2014). Moral Emotions: Reclaiming the Evidence of the Heart. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. ——— (2016). The Role of the Moral Emotions in Our Social and Political Practices. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 24(5), 600–614. Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (2008). Die Emotionen: Gefühle in der realistischen Phänomenologie. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. ——— (2013). Moralphänomenologie und gegenwärtige Wertphilosophie. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 61, 73–89. ——— (2017). Contempt: The Experience and Intersubjective Dynamics of a Nasty Emotion. In: J. J. Drummond and S. Rinofner-Kreidl (Eds.). Emotional Experiences: Ethical and Social Significance. London: Rowman & Littlefield International. von Hildebrand, Dietrich (1953). Ethics. Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press. ——— (1916). Die Idee der sittlichen Handlung. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 3, 126–251. ——— (1922). Sittlichkeit und ethische Werterkenntnis. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 5, 463–602. Zahavi, Dan (2008). Simulation, Projection, and Empathy. Consciousness and Cognition 17, 514–522. ——— (2014). Self and Other. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Further reading Ahmed, Sara (2015). The Cultural Politics of Emotion (2nd ed.). London, New York: Routledge. Greenspan, Patricia S. (1988). Emotions and Reasons: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification. London, New York: Routledge. Nussbaum, Martha C. (2013). Political Emotions: Why Love Matters for Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ——— (2016). Anger and Forgiveness: Resentment, Generosity, Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Oakley, Justin (1992). Morality and the Emotions. London, New York: Routledge. Roberts, Robert C. (2003). Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2013). Emotions in the Moral Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Roeser, Sabine, and Todd, Cain (Eds.) (2014). Emotion and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Solomon, Robert C. (2003). Not Passion’s Slave: Emotions and Choice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2007). True to Our Feelings: What Our Emotions Are Really Telling Us. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
298
26 SITUATED AFFECTIVITY Achim Stephan and Sven Walter
“You can’t do much carpentry with your bare hands and you can’t do much thinking with your bare brain.” Dennett’s (2000, 17) insightful adage reminds us that just as we do well to use a hammer, a saw and clamps when building a log cabin, we are well advised not to bank on our internal neuronal machinery when dealing with the obstacles we encounter day after day. Rather, we ought to exploit ‘tools for thinking’ whenever possible. The philosophical literature on the so-called ‘situated’ (e.g., Walter 2014) or ‘4E’ approaches to cognition (e.g., Newen et al. 2018) that has proliferated over the past decade or two has detailed many ways in which the integration of neuronal resources with extracranial ‘tools’—including the morphological and physiological characteristics of our body as well as our embodied interaction with our appropriately structured natural, technological or social environment—can simplify our cognitive life. Recently, the ensuing debate has spilled over into the affective sciences and the philosophy of emotions, with some daring pioneers arguing that the same holds for our affective life. As they see it, ‘tools for feeling’ are just as characteristic of the human condition as tools for carpentry or thinking (Griffiths and Scarantino 2009; Colombetti 2014; Krueger 2014; Slaby 2014; Stephan et al. 2014; Colombetti and Krueger 2015; Colombetti and Roberts 2015; Wilutzky 2015; Carter et al. 2016; Krueger and Szanto 2016). On the surface, the claim that human affectivity is not ‘brainbound,’ but a matter of our specific bodily constitution and environment, ties in nicely not only with the mundane fact that affective episodes typically occur in social contexts and are mostly reactions to, expressed towards and regulated by our relations with others; it is equally supported by recent work in psychology that deals with the function of individual affective comportments with respect to social practices, group processes or culture at large (e.g., Parkinson et al. 2005; Fischer and Manstead 2008). It also reflects the dominant consensus in most of philosophy, ranging all the way from Aristotle’s remark that anger is as much a matter of the boiling of the blood around the heart as it is a matter of the striving for revenge (De Anima 403a/b), over William James’ famous quip that “a purely disembodied human emotion is a nonentity” (1890, II, 452), to Heidegger’s view that moods and emotions are core structures of our being-in-the-world (see Chapter 7 in this volume), Sartre’s contention that emotions are not simply passive reactions to but an active “transformation of the world” (1994[1938], 58; see Chapter 13 in this volume) and Merleau-Ponty’s argument in “The Child’s Relations with Others” (1968[1951]) that certain early experiences are jointly owned by both infant and 299
Achim Stephan and Sven Walter
caregiver or his claim that we “perceive the grief or anger of the other in his conduct, in his face or his hands (…) because grief and anger are variations of belonging to the world” (1962[1945], 318–319; see Chapter 17 in this volume). One need not dig far below the surface, though, to be struck by the fact that the recent debate about situated affectivity seems somewhat odd in that it either appears to reinvent the wheel or else indulge in metaphysical intricacies that will hardly resonate with those familiar with the topic, in particular from a more phenomenological point of view. Putting these seemingly odd excesses into perspective is the goal of Sections 1 and 2. In Section 1, we briefly show why it seemed promising to carry over some of the key terms from the philosophy of cognitive science to the affective domain. In Section 2, we sketch the roots of these terms in their original context and argue that taking them either not seriously enough or too seriously blocks the view for what is really at issue. Having cleared up some of the mess we ourselves have contributed to causing in the first place (Stephan et al. 2014), we then discuss some intriguing situated aspects of human affectivity in Sections 3 and 4.
1. From situated cognition to situated affectivity The idea of situated affectivity took root in the philosophy of emotions because of the concern that both the philosophical discussion and the empirical investigation of affective phenomena were too strongly biased toward cognitivist and individualist accounts. In their legitimate pursuit of an alternative to pure feeling theories à la James (1884), which conceived of emotions as feelings of bodily changes, cognitivists had come to regard them as fleshless cognitive states or processes. They thereby veered too far in the other direction. The reduction of our fear of a spider to our belief that the spider is dangerous together with our desire that it go away (e.g., Marks 1982), or the reduction of our anger to our judgment that we have been wronged (e.g., Solomon 1976; Nussbaum 2001), downright ignored the essential role of the body in emotional experience. At the same time, efforts to operationalize affective phenomena and investigate them under lab conditions had led to an almost exclusive focus on emotions that could be analyzed as inner snapshot responses to external triggers, such as fear- or disgustreactions. This ignored that affective phenomena also include dynamic engagements with the world and dynamically unfolding interactions between two or more social agents and thus the essential role that the interaction with the environment plays in emotional experience. Dissatisfied by this denigration of body and environment, early advocates of the idea of situated affectivity saw a striking parallel to recent developments in cognitive science. Up until the end of the 20th century, cognitive scientists had conceived of cognition as an abstract process of computation consisting in the syntactically driven manipulation of internal representations in a central processing unit like the brain. As such, cognition was regarded as an entirely intracranial affair. This changed with the advent of situated approaches to cognition, according to which cognition is essentially also a matter of the agent’s body and her embodied interaction with her environment. By providing indispensable ‘tools for thinking,’ body and environment function as important cognitive resources. It is thus little wonder that those who were concerned that philosophical and empirical emotion research had come to focus too narrowly on cognitivist and individualist aspects of affective phenomena and deemed it important to (re-)honor the essential role of the body and the interaction with the environment sought support in situated approaches to cognition. This was a laudable endeavor. Alas, in retrospect, one has to admit that it backfired. For along with some helpful, innovative and fertile ideas, it also brought in conceptual confusion, ontological promiscuity and a penchant for metaphysical aberrations that have blocked the view for what really matters. 300
Situated affectivity
In Section 2, we explain our rather pessimistically sounding assessment before we turn to the decidedly more positive side of the story in Sections 3 and 4.
2. Situated affectivity: trials and tribulations When cognition is said to be situated, this is a placeholder for a family of approaches according to which cognitive processes are (potentially) Embodied, Embedded, Extended, and Enacted. Each of these ‘4Es’ is supposed to highlight a different—and allegedly unique—way in which cognition is a matter of the specific morphological and physiological characteristics of the agent’s body and her embodied interaction with her appropriately structured natural, technological or social environment. This is not the place to go into the details of all the ideas discussed under this conceptual behemoth (see Walter 2014; Newen et al. 2018). Here are some pithy clarifications, just enough to later illustrate some pitfalls these notions harbor. According to embodied approaches, cognitive processing exploits our specific bodily make-up, in particular the fact that we have the kind of body that functions in our environment as it does. On one popular—although quite weak—reading, this means that cognitive processes are not just a matter of abstract (potentially symbolic) processes, but reuse action-specific bodily format representations. For instance, there is no abstract ‘meaning center’ in the brain. Rather, words retain their sensorimotor origins: Semantic processing of action verbs ‘lick,’ ‘pick’ and ‘kick’ activates areas that are also activated by actual movements of the tongue, fingers, or feet (Pulvermüller 2005). According to a stronger—and significantly more interesting—reading, cognitive processes are in part constituted by the extracranial body in the sense that they make use not (only) of bodily format representations in the brain but of certain features of the agent’s (extracranial) body in such a way that the overall computational load is reduced. For instance, the density and placement of the facets in the compound eye of the housefly structure visual information in such a way that motion identification becomes less computationally demanding (e.g., Pfeifer and Bongard 2007). According to embedded approaches, human and non-human animals sometimes use an appropriately structured environment as an external ‘scaffold’ that makes neuronal representations (be they modality-specific or not) dispensable because it replaces or augments the intracranial transformation of passively received representations by the active manipulation of the corresponding external structures. To take the standard example: Expert bar tenders associate drinks with different glassware and decorations and memorize long lists of orders by arranging the corresponding items on the counter rather than literally remembering the orders in their head. According to extended approaches, interactions with the environment sometimes become so intricate that it no longer seems appropriate to distinguish an organism-bound cognitive system—the agent—on the one hand and the external ‘tool’ on the other. Rather, a hybrid ‘extended’ system spanning brain, body and environment seems to emerge, with cognitive processing constantly ‘looping out’ into the world. In the standard example of Otto, who suffers from Alzheimer’s disease and relies on a notebook to record information he thinks he will later need to remember (Clark and Chalmers 1998), the notebook entries are supposed to literally be an extended constituent of Otto’s memories. According to enacted approaches to cognition, cognition is an active, essentially relational and temporally extended process of ‘sense-making’ through which autonomous and adaptive cognitive systems bring about (‘enact’) a meaningful environment (e.g., Thompson 2007). The continuous struggle for self-preservation in the face of decay under precarious circumstances defines a norm of survival for the system. Thereby, things in its surroundings 301
Achim Stephan and Sven Walter
acquire a meaning as something which is good or bad for it. This sort of meaning generation is the primordial progenitor of the kind of cognition found in complex systems such as human beings. Human beings also enact cognition as the relational result of a sense-making process in which they come to view the world as having a value with regard to their basic goal of self-preservation inherent in them qua living organisms. Importantly, this renders it senseless to ask whether cognition is confined to the brain or loops out into the body, the environment or any combination thereof; cognition is an essentially relational phenomenon that is brought about by the agents having a concerned perspective on the world and as such simply has no location. As indicated in Section 1, early proponents of a situated approach to affectivity turned to these notions in reaction to a cognitivist and individualist climate. They wanted to reiterate what once would have been little more than a truism, viz., that many interesting affective phenomena do not lend themselves to overly simplistic analyses as fleshless, one-shot sense-appraise-act cycles by individual emoters. Judging by the renewed (and seemingly still increasing) interest in the idea of emotions beyond the brain, both from a philosophical (e.g., Colombetti 2017; León et al. 2019; Slaby et al. 2019; Varga 2019) and an empirical (e.g., Carr et al. 2018) perspective, they achieved their goal. But they paid a heavy price for it. For while the ‘4E’-terminology is by now well entrenched, its sloppy and sometimes outright inconsistent use and the metaphysical aberrations that have followed suit have often led to less, not more, clarity, opening up irrelevant secondary battlefields and obscuring the view for what really matters. Let us highlight three examples of what we have in mind. Embodied emotions? When advocates of an embodied approach first suggested that cognition is essentially a matter of the agent’s particular bodily features, this was truly revolutionary. The computational approaches prevailing at the time worked with a rather bold functionalist conception of the mind according to which mental processes are a matter of their functional role, not their material implementation. What they overlooked, and what advocates of an embodied approach pointed out, is that functional roles are causal roles and that not just anything can implement any causal role, and in particular not equally efficiently. In contrast, if it had not been for the short period of radical cognitivism, it would not have been necessary (let alone revolutionary) to point out that affectivity is essentially a matter of the agent’s bodily features. Affective phenomena have always been regarded as hybrid phenomena including the body—from Aristotle to recent psychological theories of emotions such as Scherer’s (2005) component process model in which three of the five components are essentially bodily. Given that the whole idea of disembodied emotions is pretty much a red herring in the first place, it is hardly surprising that much research on embodied emotions is actually not concerned with the question whether emotions are embodied. Most take this for granted and then argue that embodied emotional processes strongly (though not indispensably) influence various cognitive and motivational tasks (Wilutzky et al. 2011, 287–298; Stephan 2018, 609–610). The result is a pompous, but annoying, change of topic. Some studies regularly associated with embodied emotions are concerned with the way in which the cognitive processing of affective stimuli is facilitated or impeded by either using or not using parts of one’s (extracranial) body. For instance, using one’s own facial muscles facilitates both the recognition of emotions and the linguistic understanding of affective content (e.g., Effron et al. 2006; Niedenthal et al. 2009). The key idea is something like ‘affective mimicry,’ i.e., affective stimuli are more easily recognized, categorized, comprehended, etc., by using the extracranial morphological and physiological structures involved in the corresponding affective phenomena themselves. This is undeniably interesting. But it has little to do with the embodiment of emotions. What such studies investigate is not the way in which 302
Situated affectivity
affectivity is grounded in our bodily nature, but the way in which the latter affects the cognitive processing of affective stimuli. Other studies regularly associated with embodied emotions are concerned with the way in which cognitively processing affective stimuli activates sensorimotor representations. For instance, anger is frequently conceptualized in heat-related terms (e.g., hot-headed) because the representation of anger is systematically related to sensorimotor representations of heat, so that perceptions of heat facilitate the use of anger-related conceptual knowledge and a priming with anger-related thoughts leads participants to judge the room temperature as hotter than it actually is (Wilkowski et al. 2009). Again, this is undeniably interesting. But again, it has little to do with the embodiment of emotions. What such studies investigate is not the way in which affectivity is grounded in our bodily nature, but the way in which cognitively processing affective stimuli relies on something like an ‘affective mirror neuron system,’ i.e., activates sensorimotor brain regions also involved in actually experiencing the corresponding affective phenomenon. Such studies not only work with too weak a notion of embodiment as is particularly apparent in the case of emotions: When James (1884) took the body to be a ‘resonance body,’ a most sensitive ‘sounding board,’ he did not have in mind bodily format representations in the brain, but the extracranial body—the sweaty hands in which our fear resonates, the deep-red face in which our shame resonates, etc. They also investigate the (embodied) mechanisms of the cognitive processing of affective stimuli only, not the embodiment of emotions. Much recent empirical research regularly associated with embodied emotions is thus either not about the body or not about emotions (or, in the worst case, not about either). Importantly, this is not just a terminological quarrel. The point is not that these studies work with a different conception of embodiment than the one established in the debate about embodied cognition. The point is that they are either not about emotions or not about the body and thus a fortiori not about embodied emotions in any intelligible sense. Those are cases in which our view for what matters is obscured by paying not enough allegiance to the conceptual roots of one of the famous ‘4Es.’ Research on embodied emotions ought to investigate whether and in what way the body, and in particular the extracranial body, is constitutive of our affective states or processes. For instance, affective processes are associated with characteristic bodily changes, such as when depressed or sad individuals walk slower, show less movements of their arms, adopt a less erect posture, etc., and some take this to provide “strong support for the notion that sadness and depression are embodied in the way people walk” (Michalak et al. 2009, 586). The problem with such studies is to substantiate the claim that movement patterns and body posture are indeed constitutive of and not merely causal consequences of sadness or depression. This problem of distinguishing between causation and constitution is at the heart of our second exemplary worry to which we turn next. But aside from that, it is studies like this one that investigate the embodiment of emotions and the embodiment of emotions. Recent studies claim that some extracranial parts of the body, namely the gastrointestinal tract and gut microbiota together with the Hypothalamic-Pituitary-Adrenal (HPA) axis modulate various brain processes, with which they are reciprocally connected; and jointly play a role in depression, anxiety and the susceptibility to stressors (Dinan and Cryan 2013; Foster et al. 2017). If correct, these studies show that the brain alone neither realizes nor is the single control unit of an important subset of affective processes. Embedded or extended emotions? The distinction between causation and constitution just mentioned is at the heart of the distinction between embedded and extended approaches to cognition or affectivity. Conceptually, this distinction is easy to draw. Causation is a diachronic relation between two ontologically unrelated entities, whereas constitution is a synchronic 303
Achim Stephan and Sven Walter
relation between two entities standing to each other in the part–whole relationship. With regard to concrete examples, however, it is hard, if not outright impossible, to make a principled case for, say, the extendedness thesis over the embeddedness thesis. In particular, as the debate about the so-called ‘coupling-constitution fallacy’ has made amply clear (e.g., Adams and Aizawa 2008), the mere fact that an environmental structure or process causally contributes to a cognitive process, no matter how critically, does not render it constitutive of it. The mere fact that, say, we could not see without light should not render the light rays radiating from the sun constitutive of our visual perception, at least not if one does not want to water down the notion of a constituent beyond recognition. As a result, there have been seemingly endless—and equally fruitless—metaphysical skirmishes between those who believe that cognition is extended and those who insist that it is merely embedded. By picking up on the 4E-terminology, the debate about situated affectivity has inherited that futile metaphysical dispute and along with it all the unwary ontological promiscuity it invites. Slaby, for instance, takes the fact that in some cases, “a part of the world is what sets up, drives, and energizes our emotional experience” (2014, 35) to show that the environment provides “‘tools for feeling’ (…) in something like the way there are ‘tools for thinking’ in EM [extended mind] theorizing” (ibid., 36). This is an instance of Adams and Aizawa’s (2008) couplingconstitution fallacy. The mere fact that a part of the world sets up, drives, and energizes our affective life neither entails nor justifies the claim that that part of the world is constitutive of our affective life. The same holds for other alleged cases of extended emotions that have come to be championed by advocates of the idea of emotions beyond the brain: A diary, say, in which a person notes things her parents do that make her angry, which is supposed to be an extended constituent of her resentment toward her parents (Colombetti and Roberts 2015, 1253), or a wedding ring which is supposed to be a proper part of the vehicles that instantiate one’s love towards one’s deceased spouse (ibid., 1254). Taking such ideas seriously leads to what one could call affective inflation, viz., to seeing (the partial constituents of ) affective episodes virtually everywhere. As we see it, this is a case in which what matters is obscured by paying too much allegiance to the conceptual roots of one of the ‘4Es.’ Again, this is not just terminological nitpicking. If the claim is supposed to be that emotions are extended sensu stricto, then one would like to hear a justification for such a prima facie surprising ontological promiscuity: What exactly is gained by conceiving of affectivity along such lines that could not equally well be gained by an ontologically much more conservative causation-claim? If, however, the causation-constitution distinction is supposed to be secondary, so that the claim that emotions are extended is to be read without any real metaphysical punch, then calling them such is at best hardly helpful and at worst misleading. Talk about extended emotions in the absence of any sound argument for the ontological promiscuity this entails is particularly onerous in the light of two facts. First, we will never be able to decide on empirical grounds whether a process is embedded or extended because there is no way to generate unequivocal experimental evidence for constitution, given that constitution-claims are inherently underdetermined by evidence (Baumgartner and Casini 2017). Instead, we should follow Baumgartner and Wilutzky (2017) and admit that the “inference to the extension of cognition [i.e., constitution; A. S. and S. W.] is of inherently pragmatic nature” (ibid., 1122). Second, this admission is innocuous, given that as far as any practical issues are concerned, it does not matter whether affective processes are extended or just embedded—as (we hope) will become clearer in light of the affective phenomena discussed in Sections 3 and 4. Extended or enacted emotions? Lastly, let us briefly turn to the idea of enacted emotions. Harking back to the notion of enactivism, Colombetti (2014, 2018) has recently emphasized the inherently affective character of the mind. Claiming that a mind deprived of affectivity would 304
Situated affectivity
not be a mind at all, she argues that we should give up on the distinction between cognition and affectivity. While enactivism is usually confined to the claim that cognitive processes are acts of sense-making, Colombetti takes enactivism to be inherently committed to a primordial form of affectivity as well (2014, 2). Accordingly, sense-making is always both a cognitive and an affective phenomenon. Even human cognition thus remains an essentially affective affair, being a matter of our human capacity to ‘give a damn.’ We happily concur. As one of us has argued, a system with original intentionality must care, i.e., give a damn, about getting things right, and this is a sui generis kind of affective intentionality that is irreducible to other ways of relating to the world (Slaby and Stephan 2008). But we find it unfortunate that the waters are muddied— superfluously—by combining this enactive approach to affectivity with the claim that the process of sense-making is extended. For one of the key claims of enactivism has always been that cognition—and thus, if Colombetti is right, affectivity—is a relational phenomenon and as such no more and no less in the brain than in the body, in the environment or somewhere else. It might, of course, be that what Colombetti has in mind with extended sense-making is significantly weaker than what, say, Clark and Chalmers (1998) had in mind. But then, again, it is at best hardly helpful and at worst misleading to call it such. It fosters confusion and opens up irrelevant secondary battlefields regarding the very issue it was supposed to illuminate and clarify. Now that we have a sense for what quagmire we have gotten into and what has gotten us into it, let’s try to see how to get out of it.
3. Environmentally scaffolded emotions 1: user–resource interactions Let us leave the coupling-constitution debate with its futile metaphysical quarrels behind. Let us also take it for granted that affectivity is (in ways yet to be detailed) embodied. Let us instead take a fresh look at the varieties of human affectivity beyond brain and body. We will elaborate on two different, albeit interconnected, ways in which our affective life is essentially a matter of more or less intimate dependencies and interdependencies between us and our natural, technological, and social environment. In this section, we focus on interactions which originate with the individual and from there stretch out into the environment through a (mostly intentional) process of resource usage. In the next section, we focus on influences which (mostly) originate with structures in the environment and from there reach inward into the individual through a process of intentional or unintentional mind invasion. Sterelny (2010) rightly observed that what early proponents of the extended mind thesis targeted was, in fact, just a special case of what should be characterized quite generally as niche construction by the use of environmental scaffolds. The extended mind thesis, he claimed, is true at best of “highly trusted, individualized and entrenched, single-user resources” (Sterelny 2010, 480; see also 476) which occupy just “one corner in a 3D space of environmental scaffolds” (ibid.). Most environmental resources, in contrast, do not fall under this category, as they fail to be entrenched or individualized, for example when we jointly work with others on complex tasks, or when babies interact with their caregivers. To capture such phenomena that are overlooked if one focuses too narrowly on the extended mind thesis proper, Sterelny suggested to take the hypothesis of a scaffolded mind, in its more comprehensive form, to simply be the thesis “that human cognitive capacities both depend on and have been transformed by environmental resources” (ibid., 472). Let us thus have a look at various ways in which human affectivity can be transformed by user–resource interactions. Unidirectional material tools for emoting. A mundane and ubiquitous kind of user–resource interaction is familiar from situations in which we exploit environmental resources in order 305
Achim Stephan and Sven Walter
to regulate our affective life. For instance, we (a) visit places that promise to steer our moods and emotions into an intended direction (e.g., scenic places for easing our mood, a silent old roman chapel for calming down, etc.), (b) listen to music that supports certain moods, or (c) furnish our apartment in a way to feel at home, or remove everything that reminds us of our ex-partner to avoid feelings of loneliness, loss and jealousy. In the (a)- and (b)-cases, we regulate our moods and emotions by interacting with already existing natural resources or artifacts. In contrast, in the (c)-case, we actively and deliberately structure or restructure our environment in order to regulate our moods and emotions by the preemptive selection of appropriate experiential frames. In all three cases, however, we initiate and establish more or less intentionally a predominantly unidirectional influence of the world onto us, specifically tailored to concrete emotional needs. Barring any good philosophical account of what exactly is gained from a pragmatic point of view (see Section 2) by taking human affectivity to literally extend into natural beauties, the way we furnish our rooms or to the music we listen to, such cases are arguably best regarded as instances of what using the traditional terminology one would have called ‘embedded’ affectivity—pace recent attempts to argue that even listening to music can be seen as an instance of a dynamical coupling with a “functionally integrated, gainful system” (Krueger and Szanto 2016, 867). Strongly coupled and integrated material tools for emoting. Stronger types of user–resource interactions have been discussed by Colombetti and Roberts (2015). In particular, they consider cases in which a coupled system, consisting of an emoter and an environmental item, enacts some kind of self-stimulating activity, which has been set in place and maintained over time in order to move into a certain emotional process, resulting in the formation of a new whole which allows novel forms of steering and expressing affectivity inaccessible to the uncoupled individual. A repeatedly mentioned example for an occurrent affective process of that type is (d) a deeply mourning jazz musician whose playing sets up a mutually constraining cycle of affective responding and expression: the qualities of the music performed, and of the actions and gestures initiated, feed back into the character of the musician’s emotional experience, which in turn governs what he plays next. (ibid., 2015, 1258; see also Colombetti 2018, 583–584) Another case in point might be (e) an agent who (in explicit analogy to the extended mind veteran Otto) uses a diary as a tool for constantly and reliably refueling the (dispositional) feelings of resentment toward her parents (Colombetti and Roberts 2015, 1253). Transiently coupled social tools for emoting. It took a while until it was acknowledged how strongly we also connect to other people as ‘tools for emoting.’ Think (f ) of someone who seeks to act out his bursting aggression and, therefore, goes out to find others to couple to ‘in the right way’—elbows out, just waiting for someone to bump into him and drag the other into an argument which can develop into a fight. In such cases, the aggressor treats the other as a tool for acting out aggression. But compared to the deep and integrated coupling a musician can develop with her instrument, the coupling between the aggressor and the victim seems to be rather transient. Yet, the aggressor obviously involves and manipulates the victim with the deliberate goal of emotion regulation. Similar cases include going to (g) techno parties in order to ‘dance out’ one’s emotions, or (h) confession in order to relieve one’s pain about one’s failures. In both cases, the individual—again intentionally—uses resources which are already out there. As in case (f ), however, the causal path is multi- or bi-directional. In case (g), the individual herself contributes in one way or another to the atmosphere of the party 306
Situated affectivity
through the way she interacts with others. Case (h) is also a mutual affair between priest and confessor. Furthermore, the confessor must already be familiar with the catholic practice of penance, that is, she must understand and believe in the ritual a confession offers—a point to which we will return in Section 4 in connection with mind invasions. Affectivity instantiated by strongly coupled social systems. There are cases in which the coupling between two or more individuals is much stronger, though. Old couples sometimes have developed (i) rituals regarding how to interact and enact certain types of emotional dynamics over and over again. These can be cycles of mutual soothing and loving, but also cycles of one partner sulking and refusing to speak, while the other tries to put things right. In other couples, the affective cycles can involve one partner responding to seemingly flirting affairs of the other with mistrust and jealousy in such a way that they mutually goad each other. In these (i)-cases, it is the existence and the particular nature of a long developed, strong coupling that allows the individuals involved to enact some sort of affectivity in the first place. Compared to the transient social tools for emotions in cases (g) and (h), though, the ‘other’ in such couplings can hardly be thought of as a ‘tool’ for sulking or putting things right, since these processes are arguably not consciously intended or endorsed. Coupled social tools for changing the emotional mind-set. There are, however, also cases where ( j) someone is indeed intentionally looking for another person as a ‘tool’ for modifying her life and mood, and not just with regard to concrete emotional needs, but in order to transform her affective response repertoire in general. Consider, for instance, someone who seeks a psychotherapist to work with. Depending on the professional orientation of the psychotherapist, her work can comprise the re-enactment of painful re-occurring interactions with others while transforming the capacities of the client to act and emote differently in similar encounters in the future. Both seeking a psychotherapist and the confession in case (h) go beyond mere user– resource interactions, albeit in different ways. They both involve some sort of mind invasion whereby structures in the environment reach inward into the individual (deliberately or not), rather than stretching out from the individual into the environment. But while the client explicitly intends that his mind set-up will be transformed by working with the psychotherapist, the confessor has (typically) been enculturated in the catholic tradition without having explicitly asked for it. Such cases of world-to-mind extension that are typically ignored in the literature on allegedly ‘extended’ emotions are the topic of Section 4.
4. Environmentally scaffolded emotions 2: mind-invasions Slaby (2016) coined the term ‘mind invasion’ to refer to cases in which what is at issue is exactly not our “individual decision to employ a mind tool in the pursuit of (…) self-avowed goals, but rather forms of pervasive framing and molding effected by aspects of technical infrastructure and institutional realities” (ibid., 6). We will use this notion more broadly to cover in toto transformational processes of the mind in enculturation—starting from early childhood to all later stages in life. Human beings have the unique privilege—and sometimes burden—that the structures offered during ontogenesis by other members of the society—be it family, peers, schools, companies, organizations, parties, and social media—can function as emotional scaffolds. Sometimes, for instance in the ( j)-case of someone seeking a psychotherapist, a scaffold for mind invasion is deliberately chosen. But as we will see below, often it is not and instead imposed on us, without us being consciously aware of it. On the side of those who provide the scaffolds, some act unintentionally, while others intentionally prepare a certain scaffold for a particular audience. In this case, the external world uses a ‘tool,’ so to 307
Achim Stephan and Sven Walter
speak, to manipulate and transform the mind-set of the individual, regardless of whether the individual wants to be affected or not. Affective enculturation through strongly coupled social systems. In their attempts to find convincing examples of extended affectivity, Krueger (2014) and Varga (2016) have addressed (k) developmental aspects in early dyadic relationships. Krueger takes infant–caregiver interactions that establish shared emotions and provide mutual affect regulation to be exemplars of collectively extended emotions (2014, 545–548). Likewise, Varga emphasizes the essential role of successful synchronic interactions between infant and caregiver for both the regulation of the infant’s current emotions and the maturation of her emotional self-regulatory abilities in an evolving diachronic process (2016, 2475–2476). In her comprehensive study of the affective and cognitive development in early childhood, Greenwood examines both synchronic and diachronic scaffolds provided by caregivers in specific sociocultural settings and explores in depth the synchronous interactions of infant and caregiver that diachronically shape and enhance the infant’s behavioral repertoire by transforming the neural structure of the child’s brain (2015, 8–9, chaps. 4–6). If we put the phase of early childhood aside and consider that (l) all human beings get enculturated in particular family styles, group norms and emotion regimes, we must appreciate that during these processes, we learn to participate in life forms with a specific repertoire of ‘feeling rules’ (Hochschild 1983) which find bodily sediments in what we may call our ‘affective biographies’ (von Maur 2017, chap. 4). Becoming familiar with, for instance, the rituals of the catholic church is but one small aspect of a larger set of diachronic enculturation processes that allow the synchronic tool use of confession in a particular situation. Special cases of (l) are particular adaptations to specific institutions and organizations that Slaby discusses under the heading of ‘mind invasion’ or ‘life hack’: the working atmosphere in a company, or the atmosphere in a study program (Haken (1996) treated such working atmospheres as order parameters that ‘enslave’ new members of the corresponding group; see Stephan 1998, 650–652). For the most part, (l)-cases are not explicitly intended, neither by caretakers, working groups, companies, etc. nor by the greater society. They are not for a special purpose, although we know of mobbing or exclusion if someone does not obey, for example, the emotion regimes established within a group, but also of various corporate manipulations of emotion regulation and ‘emotional management’ (cf. Hochschild 1983). Affective transformation through social media. A different set of structures that strongly contribute to the transformation of our (affective) mind-set are provided by (m) social media. Facebook, Twitter, Snapchat, and Instagram have a strong influence on the affective life of digital natives and non-natives. On the one hand, they allow one to participate in and share precious moments with others, even over long distances. On the other hand, they create a feeling of permanent availability and the need to communicate; they contribute to an increase of feelings of exclusion, and an increase in anonymously spread hate speech with all its consequences. In most cases though, the affective significance in such cases is merely an unintended and unsought side-effect of social media. Mind invasion as a tool for manipulating emoters. In contrast, other scaffolds are (n) deliberately launched as tools for mind invasion in order to diachronically modify the attitudes and the emotional set up of a target group. We see this in advertising, but also in political campaigns and in the recruitment policies of radical groups. The German Af D, for example, was eager to create an emotional bond with Russian-Germans by translating the party program into Russian and being present on social media platforms (e.g., Odnoklassniki.ru), which RussianGermans use to connect (positively) with relatives and friends. Another case in point is the intense and specialized social media use of extremist groups to recruit and keep followers. 308
Situated affectivity
If nothing else, it is the personal, moral and societal importance of being aware of these scaffoldings that are set up to modulate our emotional life and to intrude our minds that reinvigorate our point from Section 2: From a practical point of view, it simply does not matter whether our affectivity is properly extended or merely embedded, and we run the risk of losing track of the truly important things in life if we allow ourselves to indulge in too much quixotic metaphysics.
5. Conclusion The phenomena we have described—from very mundane and unostentatious user–resource interactions like listening to music to momentous and vital mind invasions like unwanted political agitation and other, milder, forms of brainwashing—emphasize, just with less metaphysical ballast, what advocates of enacted approaches to affectivity have continuously underlined: Namely, that there is no pre-formed, independently existing individual that comes into a pre-formed, independently existing world which it has then to make affective sense of. Rather, it is the environment and the individual which together determine who and what they are in continuous, reciprocal, dynamical interactions.
Acknowledgments The research presented in this chapter has been carried out in collaboration with the bilocal DFG-Research Training Group ‘Situated Cognition,’ GRK-2185/1, hosted by the Ruhr-University Bochum and Osnabrück University.
References Adams, Fred, and Aizawa, Kenneth (2008). The Bounds of Cognition. Malden: Blackwell. Baumgartner, Michael, and Casini, Lorenzo (2017). An Abductive Theory of Constitution. Philosophy of Science 84(2), 214–233. Baumgartner, Michael, and Wilutzky, Wendy (2017). Is it Possible to Experimentally Determine the Extension of Cognition? Philosophical Psychology 30(8), 1104–1125. Carr, Evan W., Kever, Anne, and Winkielman, Piotr (2018). Embodiment of Emotion and Its Situated Nature. In: A. Newen, de Bruin, L., and S. Gallagher (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of 4E-Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 529–551. Carter, J. Adam, Gordon, Emma. C., and Palermos, S. Orestis (2016). Extended Emotion. Philosophical Psychology 29(2), 198–217. Clark, Andy, and Chalmers, David (1998). The Extended Mind. Analysis 58(1), 7–19. Colombetti, Giovanna (2014). The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ——— (2017). The Embodied and Situated Nature of Moods. Philosophia 45(4), 1–15. ——— (2018). Enacting Affectivity. In: A. Newen, and L. S. Gallagher (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of 4E-Cognition. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 571–587. Colombetti, Giovanna, and Krueger, Joel (2015). Scaffoldings of the Affective Mind. Philosophical Psychology 28(8), 1157–1176. Colombetti, Giovanna, and Roberts, Tom (2015). Extending the Extended Mind: The Case for Extended Affectivity. Philosophical Studies 172(5), 1243–1263. Dennett, Daniel C. (2000). Making Tools for Thinking. In: D. Sperber (Ed.). Metarepresentations. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 17–30. Dinan, Ted G., and Cryan, John F., (2013). Melancholic Microbes: A Link between Gut Microbiota and Depression? Neurogastroenterology & Motility 25, 713–719. Effron, Daniel, Niedenthal, Paula, Gil, Sandrine, and Droit-Volet, Sylvie (2006). Embodied Temporal Perception of Emotion. Emotion 6(1), 1–9.
309
Achim Stephan and Sven Walter Fischer, Agneta H., and Manstead, Antony S. R. (2008). Social Functions of Emotion. In: M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones, and L. Feldman-Barrett (Eds.). Handbook of Emotions. New York: Guilford Press, 456–469. Foster, Jane A., Rinaman, Linda, and Cryan, John F. (2017). Stress & the Gut-Brain Axis: Regulation by the Microbiome. Neurobiology of Stress 7, 124–136. Greenwood, Jennifer (2015). Becoming Human: The Ontogenesis, Metaphysics, and Expression of Human Emotionality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Griffiths, Paul E., and Scarantino, Andrea (2009). Emotions in the Wild. In: P. Robbins and M. Aydede (Eds.). The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 437–453. Haken, Hermann (1996). Synergetik und Sozialwissenschaften. Ethik und Sozialwissenschaften 7, 587–594. Hochschild, Arlie R. (1983). The Managed Heart. Commercialization of Human Feeling. Berkley: University of California Press. James, William (1884). What Is an Emotion? Mind 9(34), 188–205. ——— (1890). The Principles of Psychology (2 vols.). New York: Hold. Krueger, Joel (2014). Varieties of Extended Emotions. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13(4), 533–555. Krueger, Joel, and Szanto, Thomas (2016). Extended Emotions. Philosophy Compass 11(12), 863–878. León, Felipe, Szanto, Thomas, and Zahavi, Dan (2019). Emotional Sharing and the Extended Mind. Synthese 196(12), 4847–4867. Marks, Joel (1982). A Theory of Emotion. Philosophical Studies 42(1), 227–242. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1962[1945]). Phenomenology of Perception. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. ——— (1968[1951]). The Child’s Relations with Others. In: J. E. Edie (Ed.). The Primacy of Perception and Other Essays. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 96–155. Michalak, Johannes, Troje, Nikolaus F., Fischer, Julia, Vollmar, Patrick, Heidenreich, Thomas, and Schulte, Dietmar (2009). Embodiment of Sadness and Depression—Gait Patterns Associated with Dysphoric Mood. Psychosomatic Medicine 71(5), 580–587. Newen, Albert, de Bruin, Leon, and Gallagher, Shaun (Eds.) (2018). The Oxford Handbook of 4E-Cognition. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. Niedenthal, Paula, Winkielman, Piotr, Mondillon, Laurie, and Vermeulen, Nicolas (2009). Embodiment of Emotion Concepts. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 96(6), 1120–1136. Nussbaum, Martha (2001). Upheavals of Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Parkinson, Brian, Fischer, Agneta H., and Manstead, Antony S. R. (2005). Emotions in Social Relations: Cultural, Group and Interpersonal Processes. New York: Psychology Press. Pfeifer, Rolf, and Bongard, Josh C. (2007). How the Body Shapes the Way We Think: A New View of Intelligence. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Pulvermüller, Friedemann (2005). Brain Mechanisms Linking Language and Action. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 6(7), 576–582. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1994[1938]). The Emotions. Outline of a Theory. Transl. by B. Frechtman. New York: Philosophical Library. Scherer, Klaus (2005). What Are Emotions? Social Science Information 44(4), 695–729. Slaby, Jan (2014). Emotions and the Extended Mind. In: M. Salmela, and C. von Scheve (Eds.). Collective Emotions. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 32–46. ——— (2016). Mind Invasion: Situated Affectivity and the Corporate Life Hack. Frontiers in Psychology 7, 266. Slaby, Jan, Mühlhoff, Rainer, and Wüschner, Philipp (2019). Affective Arrangements. Emotion Review 11(1), 3–12. Slaby, Jan, and Stephan, Achim (2008). Affective Intentionality and Self-Consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 17(2), 506–513. Solomon, Robert C. (1976). The Passions: Emotions and the Meaning of Life. New York: Anchor Press. Stephan, Achim (1998). Varieties of Emergence in Artificial and Natural Systems. Zeitschrift für Naturforschung 53c, 639–656. ——— (2018). 3 E’s Are Sufficient, but Don’t Forget the D. In: A. Newen, de Bruin, L., and S. Gallagher (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of 4E-Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 607–619.
310
Situated affectivity Stephan, Achim, Walter, Sven, and Wilutzky, Wendy (2014). Emotions beyond Brain and Body. Philosophical Psychology 27(1), 65–81. Sterelny, Kim (2010). Minds: Extended or Scaffolded? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 9(4), 465–481. Thompson, Evan (2007). Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Varga, Somogy (2016). Interaction and Extended Cognition. Synthese 193(8), 2469–2496. ——— (2019). Scaffolded Minds: Integration and Disintegration. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. von Maur, Imke (2017). Die epistemische Relevanz des Fühlens – Habitualisierte affektive Intentionalität im Verstehensprozess. https://repositorium.ub.uni-osnabrueck.de/handle/urn:nbn:de:gbv:700-20180807502 Walter, Sven (2014). Situated Cognition: A Field Guide to some Open Conceptual and Ontological Issues. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 5(2), 241–263. Wilkowski, Benjamin, Robinson, Brian, Meier, Michael, Carter, Margaret, and Feltman, Roger (2009). ‘Hot-Headed’ Is More than an Expression. Emotion 9(4), 464–477. Wilutzky, Wendy (2015). Emotions as Pragmatic and Epistemic Actions. Frontiers in Psychology 6, 1593. Wilutzky, Wendy, Stephan, Achim, and Walter, Sven (2011). Situierte Affektivität. In: J. Slaby, A. Stephan, H. Walter, and S. Walter (Eds.). Affektive Intentionalität. Paderborn: mentis, 283–320.
311
27 FEMINISM, EMBODIMENT AND EMOTIONS Luna Dolezal
1. Introduction There has been substantial reflection within feminist scholarship on the role that emotion plays when considering the subordination of women within patriarchal structures and power relations. In fact, in recent decades, an “affective turn” has taken place in feminist philosophy (Clough and Halley 2007), where considering how social, political and institutional forces impact on the affective and emotional lives of embodied subjects has become a central focus of scholarship (e.g., Ahmed 2004; Brennan 2004; Gorton 2007). In an era where gender equality is ostensibly guaranteed through legislation along with equality and diversity initiatives in many liberal democracies, it is argued that certain gendered inequalities persist as a result of affective, rather than material, conditions.1 Examining how negative and positive affects are embedded and operationalized within social, political and institutional structures is a means to demonstrate not only how the personal is political, but also how the political registers within the personal (Gorton 2007, 336). Feminist phenomenology has become an important theoretical frame for feminist scholarship on emotion (e.g., Bartky 1990; Dolezal 2015; McMahon 2016). Feminist phenomenology is an approach that combines insights regarding embodied experience, through phenomenological investigation, with reflections about the discursive structures which frame that experience, through feminist theory. As embodied emotional experiences are always shaped by a broad range of factors, which have political and social significance, such as age, gender, race, sexuality, ability, ethnicity, among others, feminist phenomenology attempts to reveal not only the taken for granted structures of lived experience but also the sedimented or ‘hidden’ assumptions that inform our experience with respect to these categories (e.g., Fisher and Embree 2000; Landweer and Marcinski 2016). Considering a feminist phenomenology of emotion is important as it is paramount to investigate how the structures of one’s emotional experience can affect the expression, attitude and atmosphere of one’s embodied life along with the textures of one’s experiences of intercorporeality, and furthermore the repercussions this has in familial, social and political life. Sandra L. Bartky, writing on the phenomenology of emotion in her influential collection of essays Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression, argues that women “are situated differently than men within the ensemble of social relations” (Bartky 1990, 83). 312
Feminism, embodiment and emotions
She identifies that certain “patterns of mood or feeling (…) tend to characterize” women’s experience (Bartky 1990, 84). The differences in women’s social position—as a result of the material and psychic legacies of patriarchy along with the enduring embodied realities of pregnancy and motherhood—mean that, in general rather than universal terms, women find themselves living within social structures in such a way that certain emotional responses become more predominant, especially when compared to their male counterparts.2 While there are an array of emotions and experiences that might be identified to be characteristic of women’s experience, Bartky identifies negative self-conscious emotions as particularly central (Bartky 1990, 84). More specifically, she argues that shame is the most ubiquitous and significant emotion to the experience of female subjectivity. As a result of their subordinated position, she writes, women “more often than men, are made to feel shame in the major sites of social life” (Bartky 1990, 93). For women, Bartky argues, shame forms a “pervasive affective attunement to the social environment” (Bartky 1990, 85). In making this claim, Bartky identifies shame not merely as a discrete emotional event occurring as a result of a breach of social norms (as described, in part, by Chapter 30 in this volume), but rather, she argues that shame, for women, is a chronic and persistent backdrop colouring all aspects of ordinary day-to-day life: “women’s shame is more than merely an effect of subordination but, within the larger universe of patriarchal social relations, a profound mode of disclosure both of self and situation” (Bartky 1990, 85). My aim in this chapter is to take up Bartky’s claim that shame, particularly in its chronic form, is characteristic of female embodied experience, or a profound mode of disclosure both of self and situation, to use her words, and to explore some of the particularities that substantiate this claim. Through exploring chronic shame in relation to female embodied experience, the mechanisms through which certain gendered power relations are sustained and reproduced will be elucidated.3 Furthermore, the challenges inherent in providing a phenomenology of chronic shame will be considered.
2. Shame, embodiment and female experience Bartky is, by no means, the only feminist scholar to identify shame, particularly in its chronic form, as a characteristic of female experience and social oppression (e.g., Bouson 2009; Johnson and Moran 2013). There exists a long association historically, theologically, sociologically and philosophically between women, shame and the body. As the psychologist Paul Gilbert notes: “Control of female sexuality (and the female body) has been institutionalized in social and religious forms for hundreds of years and more (…) often involving the shaming/stigmatizing of female sexuality and appearance” (Gilbert 2002, 35). In The Second Sex, Simone de Beauvoir, drawing on insights from biology, social and economic history and sociology, gives a philosophical account of the process of becoming a woman, essentially characterizing this process as “an extended lesson in shame” (Guenther 2011, 11). Beauvoir discusses how many ordinary female anatomical differences, such as the onset of menstruation, sexual maturation and breast development, have long been occasions for shame, especially recurring shame about embodiment, for young girls (Beauvoir 2010, 336–341). These bodily changes, deviating from an imagined norm of male bodily stasis, are seen as shameful and of needing concealment, and this has a long history in many cultures and traditions. As Beauvoir writes, “[The young girl’s] metamorphosis into a woman takes place not only in shame but in remorse for suffering that shame” (Beauvoir 2010, 347). The experience of becoming and being a woman, as Beauvoir and other feminist thinkers 313
Luna Dolezal
argue (e.g., Manion 2003; Locke 2007; Fischer 2018), historically involves a process of learning to interpret the body as a site of shame (on Beauvoir, see also Chapter 16 in this volume). The strong relation and association, historically and culturally, between women’s bodies, women’s sexuality and shame, both personally and politically, is far from trivial. The male body has set the standard for the ‘normal’ or ‘neutral’ body in philosophical accounts of experience and subjectivity—and there is a long tradition of feminist writing critiquing phenomenologists such as Husserl, Merleau-Ponty and Sartre for this implicit bias in their work (e.g., Young 1980; Murphy 1999; Fisher and Embree 2000; Olkowski and Weiss 2006). As a result, women’s bodies and female experience are positioned as essentially deviant from this (male) norm or, in some cases, even pathological. Inevitable events in female embodiment such as pregnancy, childbirth, menstruation and menopause are positioned as anomalies of ‘normal’ experience, which are not only stigmatized, but also pathologized, requiring professional medical attention. Furthermore, a significant site for shame for women is in the realm of the seemingly ‘trivial’ concerns of appearance and physical attractiveness. The control of women’s bodies through oppressive beauty norms has been an explicit focus of the feminist critique of the patriarchal framework of consumer capitalism and neoliberalism for several decades. It is widely acknowledged by feminist thinkers that appearances cannot be considered a trivial concern for women and that body dissatisfaction is part of a systematic (and oppressive) social phenomenon. Appearances are intimately linked to how one values and sees oneself, and, furthermore, to one’s social worth and position within a social group. Increasingly, beauty ideals have become ethical ideals (Widdows 2018, 30). Failing to achieve certain standards of attractiveness through the physical body has repercussions for one’s sense of self. One is not just failing to achieve a discrete social norm, but instead this embodied failure is viewed as global, and, as a result, it is an occasion for shame (Widdows 2018, 31–35). This is especially the case for women, as how they look and present themselves affects how they are treated and their chances for success in various aspects of their lives. That which is considered a ‘normal’ and allegedly attainable standard of attractiveness is, in fact, an ever-shifting and unattainable body ideal. As a result, women, as Susan Bordo notes, are often “obsessed” with their bodies and are “hardly accepting of them” (Bordo 1993, 14–15). The continuous comparisons a woman may make between her actual body and versions of the socially constructed ‘ideal’ body represented in media images are a potent source of shame. Women’s bodies, already shame-prone as a result of their cultural inheritance, are continuously positioned as inadequate or inferior when compared to these elusive body ideals; shame, and body shame in particular, becomes a permanent possibility. Jane Northrop notes that the “potential for women to feel shame is ubiquitous and potentially overwhelming” (Northrop 2012, 179). In short, ubiquitous and oppressive social structures position the appearance of women’s bodies as a constant opportunity for the experience of shame. As physical and personal ‘inadequacies’ are recurrent, difficult to alleviate and ever-shifting, shame can become permanently anticipated, part of a ‘normal’ landscape of experience, or an “affective attunement” to use Bartky’s formulation (Bartky 1990, 85).
3. Understanding shame Shame is commonly understood to be an emotion that arises when we are concerned about how we are seen and judged by others. It is what is called a self-conscious emotion, in that the object of shame is oneself and, furthermore, it involves an awareness of how 314
Feminism, embodiment and emotions
other people view the self.4 As such, shame is an emotion that involves both self-awareness and social interaction (even if this interaction is just anticipated or imagined). We feel ashamed when we are seen by others (whether they are present, imagined or internalized) to be flawed in some crucial way, or when some part of our core self is perceived to be inadequate, inappropriate, or immoral. Distinguished from guilt, where we feel bad about an action or something that we have done, shame is about the person that one is. In a moment of shame, we feel deeply and often irreparably flawed, or that we are unworthy and unlovable. Shame has both acute and chronic forms. When struck by a moment of acute shame, we can understand shame to be a discrete experience that arises, has a certain duration, and then passes away. During the moments of the shame experience, it is characteristic that one is overwhelmed physically, and common physical responses to shame include a sense of intense physical exposure, coupled with a sense of wanting to hide or withdraw. In moments of shame, the body folds in on itself. Often, our posture is stooped, the gaze is downward, and the head is bowed; we want to shrink or get smaller, or to just disappear. There are many other physical signs of shame, such as blushing, stuttering, sweating, blanching, hesitating, cowering, covering the face, and a sinking feeling. Accompanying these physical and physiological responses is an intense feeling of emotional anguish or pain. There is a sinking feeling of dread, coupled with an acute anxiety. An acute episode of shame is experienced as an overwhelming feeling of self-consciousness that is focused on some negative evaluation of the self and a concern with how the self is or will be perceived by others. The extreme negative self-consciousness that comes with shame, coupled with its intense physical response, gives shame its most recognizable feature: the feeling that one is completely, and uncontrollably, exposed. This exposure leads to a physic, along with a sense of physical, paralysis or, what Kaufman terms “binding.” Kaufman writes: “Exposure can interrupt movement, bind speech and make eye contact intolerable. Shame paralyzes the self ” (Kaufman 1993, 5, 18). One feels isolated, singled out and intensely conspicuous, as though paralysed in a spotlight. There is a strong feeling of vulnerability that comes with this sense of exposure. It feels as though everyone can see your flaws or misdeeds and that they may scorn, judge and then ultimately reject you. As a result, acute shame is alienating, isolating and deeply disturbing. It can provoke powerful feelings of despair, inferiority, powerlessness, defectiveness and self-contempt, to name a few. As a result of acute shame’s deeply painful and disturbing nature, it is widely acknowledged that we go to great lengths to avoid and circumvent shame experiences. In fact, anticipated shame is a powerful force within in social interaction, where individuals in social situations make continuous efforts to avoid shame, embarrassment and other negative self-conscious experiences that might arise because of social transgressions. We unremittingly design and adjust our behaviour and appearance to avoid shame in order to avoid the pain of social rejection and the threat of severing our social bonds. In this way, anticipated shame acts as an invisible and often unacknowledged boundary in social interaction, delineating the contours of what is permissible or acceptable, and the standards for ‘normal’ behaviour, appearance, speech and so on. Anticipating acute shame experiences, and making efforts to avoid them, is an ordinary part of social interaction and human lived experience. However, when the anticipation of shame becomes overwhelming and a constant feature of every interaction and experience, then we can start to see how shame can become chronic in nature, or form an “affective attunement,” as Bartky postulates (Bartky 1990, 85). 315
Luna Dolezal
4. A phenomenology of chronic shame? Living with chronic shame, one might experience a pervasive and enduring sense of shame that colours many aspects of life and social interaction. Shame, instead of being an acute and fleeting episode, becomes global and diffuse, causing a continuous sense of social anxiety, personal inadequacy and relational disconnection. Chronic shame can be linked to an enduring feature of the self, for instance, one’s appearance, weight, skin colour or social status. However, research suggests that susceptibility to chronic shame in adult experience can be caused by a variety of factors, including childhood abuse or highly dysfunctional shamebased family dynamics, as well as being a feature of certain psychopathologies such as PTSD or social anxiety disorder (Dolezal and Lyons 2017, 3). As the theologian and philosopher Stephen Pattison, who has theorized extensively about shame, writes: There is an enormous difference between acute, reactive shame and the chronic shame that shapes a whole personality and may last a lifetime. When individuals appear to experience the whole of life as actually or potentially shame-productive and manifest such symptoms as withdrawal, self-contempt, inferiority and gaze aversion as a matter of course throughout their everyday lives, shame has become pathological and chronic. (Pattison 2000, 83) Chronic shame, in contrast to experiences of acute shame, has a very different phenomenology. While chronic shame would share many of the painful features of acute shame, such as emotional pain, self-consciousness and a heightened sense of visibility, chronic shame is not experienced as an acute incident of emotional torment and hyper-self-consciousness, but rather as a background of pain and self-consciousness, perhaps becoming more acute in moments of exposure or self-awareness. In fact, it is widely acknowledged that chronic shame is less about discrete shame experiences, but instead is an affective atmosphere—or attunement—that colours many, if not all, aspects of one’s life. Living with chronic shame may not mean that shame is continuously experienced, but instead that the threat of shame is more predominant and persistent. Chronic shame, hence, is not a state of perpetually feeling ashamed, but rather, a state of persistent “shame anxiety,” where there is an “anticipatory anxiety about the imminent threat of being exposed, humiliated, belittled or rejected” (Pattison 2000, 85). Anticipated shame comes to be an enduring part of experience. What is most challenging when attempting to articulate a phenomenology of chronic shame is that it is frequently silent, repressed or unavailable to reflective consciousness. Shame is an experience that is so painful and intolerable that it is often forced outside the realm of conscious lived experience: It is forced “underground” (Scheff 2004, 231), and as a result, chronic shame often “disappears” or is “bypassed” (DeYoung 2015, 24). Rather than the searingly painful self-consciousness that accompanies episodes of acute shame, chronic shame can be invisible, both to the self, who is experiencing it, and to others around them. As a result, there are challenges to identifying, diagnosing and describing the experience of chronic shame, and, concomitantly, attempting to describe its phenomenology. In her recent book Understanding and Treating Chronic Shame, the relational psychotherapist Patricia DeYoung discusses how many of her clients who suffer from chronic shame do not even know that they are experiencing shame (and related strategies to circumvent the threat of shame) with debilitating frequency. DeYoung writes: “Clients come for help with troubled emotions and difficult relationships. They say they have problems with stress, anxiety, 316
Feminism, embodiment and emotions
depression, or self-esteem. But they don’t name shame as a problem” (DeYoung 2015, 3). She describes chronic shame as “silent,” shadowing her clients’ experiences in the world: Clients who struggle with the disintegrating power of chronic shame may not daily or consciously expect to be annihilated by shame. However, the threat is always around somewhere, just out of awareness, kept at bay. What they live with daily is what it costs them to keep from falling into shame. (DeYoung 2015, 19) Stephen Pattison echoes these insights: “few people may describe themselves as chronically shamed, many exhibit behaviour and attitudes such as consistently blaming others, being passive, deprecating themselves and their achievements, or ridiculing self and others” (Pattison 2000, 120). As a result, what seems to characterize the experience of chronic shame is not enduring or repetitive experiences of shame but rather an atmosphere of anticipated shame that leads to compensatory behaviours or experiences. Instead of shame, what often enters reflective consciousness and the landscapes of lived experience are powerful “defensive scripts,” or rules and habits of interaction, which make it possible for an individual to avoid the constant pain of shame (Kaufman 1993, 113). Shame anxiety activates a variety of “reactive scripts and actions,” Pattison writes, drawing on the work of the shame theorists Donald Nathanson and Gershan Kaufman (Pattison 2000, 120). “These scripts are ‘performed’ or activated when shame threatens” (Pattison 2000, 111). While some of these scripts allow the shame experience to manifest, others use denial or bypassing as coping mechanisms. Nathanson describes four basic shame scripts: shameful withdrawal, masochistic submission, narcissistic avoidance of shame and the rage of wounded pride (Nathanson 1992). Through this schema of reaction patterns, a wide range of behavioural forms emerge that help one cope with the perceived threats to one’s social bonds and one’s identity that shame experiences provoke, no matter how mild or intense. Defensive scripts commonly lead to a wide range of experiences or states of being such as narcissism, depression, perfectionism, aggression, violence, anxiety, addiction and social withdrawal, among others (Pattison 2000, 110–130). In other words, chronic shame is frequently cloaked by other experiences, and as a result, its presence and impact on lived experience are often underestimated or remain unacknowledged in phenomenological accounts of affect and embodiment.
5. Living with shame as an ‘affective attunement’ When considering the experience of living with chronic shame, and how this may take on a decidedly gendered nature, it is important to keep in mind that shame is not experienced in the same manner by all subjects. In fact, the propensity to shame, and its consequences, is very much dependent on one’s position within a social group. Shame, as Northrop remarks, is “most often experienced by those who occupy positions lacking social authority, those who find themselves in social situations where the parameters of shame are determined, not by themselves, but by a more powerful other” (Northrop 2012, 128). Shame experienced by members of subordinated groups is, in fact, different in nature from, and, in addition, more pernicious than, the shame experienced by socially privileged or dominant individuals. Those wielding higher levels of social power are not only less likely to be susceptible to shame, both acute and chronic, but are in a better position to inflict it on others. Cheshire Calhoun notes, “the power to shame is likely to be concentrated in the hands of those whose interpretations are socially authoritative” (Calhoun 2004, 143). 317
Luna Dolezal
Those with social power, who constitute and ratify the normative values which carve out the parameters for shame within a social group, are certainly not immune to shame; however, they are more likely to experience shame as an minor, and fleeting, disturbance. For these socially powerful individuals, shame is more often acute, rather than chronic. Shame is a “blip across the face of an otherwise undisturbed consciousness,” to use Bartky’s formulation (Bartky 1990, 97). Ullaliina Lehtinen, commenting on Bartky’s account, calls this shame of the “aristocrat’s kind”; she writes, “white European or North American, middle-class, academically trained men. The only shame they themselves knew, had experienced, was (…) a painful episode, a sudden unexpected change in the state of things, an occasion for moral reaffirmation” (Lehtinen 1998, 63). Acute shame of this sort has didactic potential: One is able to learn from one’s transgression and then adjust or regulate their behaviour accordingly. As Bartky comments, the “experience of shame can be salutary for such a person because he is not systematically impoverished by the moral economy he is compelled to inhabit” (Bartky 1990, 97). A typically socially privileged subject (usually characterized as white, Western, educated, male in feminist accounts) does not experience the same affective landscape from which hierarchies of race, class, sexuality and gender, for example, arise and are sustained. The continuous recurrence of shame for women (along with other subordinated or marginalized groups) arises because of, but also perpetuates, their subordination. Jean-Paul Sartre’s existential reflections on the role of emotions can be helpful here. Sartre reflects on how emotions are not merely cognitive events, but instead are embodied experiences that create a context or situation in which meaning, sense and one’s lived experience are shaped (see also Chapter 13 in this volume). As such, an emotion is an active and embodied response to a situation and discloses not only the self, but, in addition, the quality of one’s life-world. An emotion, such as anger, guilt, jealousy or shame, can evoke, as Sartre argues, a “total alteration of the world” (Sartre 2002, 47). Consider, for example, the jealousy experienced by the voyeur kneeling at the keyhole spying on his lover, in Sartre’s well-known vignette from Being and Nothingness. Jealousy organizes his world, shaping his actions, responses and experience within a particular situation. When the voyeur hears footsteps in the hallway behind him, he is overcome with shame, as he feels he has been caught transgressing a social norm—that it is wrong to spy on strangers. While this vignette is illustrative of an episode of acute shame, it also reveals the worldorganizing nature of emotion or affect. Jealousy, in this example, is not merely a cognitive event that can be contemplated; instead, Sartre writes, “I am this jealousy; I do not know it” (Sartre 2003, 283). The world constituted by jealousy is one of suspicion and anger. The door and the keyhole that the voyeur encounters are not merely objective objects in a neutral space, but a landscape of betrayal, obstacle and embittered curiosity. Jealousy not only colours his intentional relation to the physical realm, but also shrinks his world and its concerns. The voyeur’s preoccupations, attentions and desires spiral in a tight circle around his jealousy. Sartre’s insights on the world-organizing nature of emotions provide a useful framework through which we can articulate the affects and consequences of chronic shame, especially when considering chronic shame’s link to social and political subordination, as Bartky postulates in the case of women’s experience. Shame becomes a “form of cultural politics” that is “world making,” to quote Sara Ahmed (Ahmed 2004, 9, 12). Instead of a discrete disturbance of an otherwise untroubled consciousness, living with chronic shame has profound and on-going consequences for one’s subjectivity, both personally and politically. In addition to shaping the contours of one’s world, shame becomes characteristic of one’s way of being in the world. As the shame theorist and counsellor John Bradshaw writes, “When internalized an emotion stops functioning in the manner of an emotion and becomes a 318
Feminism, embodiment and emotions
characterological style … The person doesn’t have anger or melancholy, she is anger and melancholy” (Bradshaw 1988, 10–11). Living with chronic shame means that shame comes to colour most, if not all, situations, interactions and actions. In these cases, even when shame is not felt directly, it is permanently anticipated as one’s identity is spoiled in the first instance. Individuals who experience chronic shame are described as “shame-bound,” “shame-prone” (Pattison 2000, 83), a “shame subjectivity” (Berlant et al. 2008), and often experience “shame as a state of being” (Bradshaw 1988, vii). Crucially, this frequently occurs as a result of a set of structural social relations that create hierarchies of social worth, such as the gender inequalities that persist within traditionally patriarchal societies. Living with chronic shame can mean that one’s experience is characterized by “experiences that induce a sense of persistent inferiority, worthlessness, (…) stigmatisation, unloveablility and social exclusion” (Pattison 2000, 108). In short, the consequences of living with chronic shame are far from trivial. As Lehtinen points out, the experiences arising from the chronic shame of a socially subordinated individual “often breed a stagnant self-obsession, they are unconstructive and self-destructive; and they function as confirmations of what the agent knew all along—that he or she was a person of lesser worth” (Lehtinen 1998, 62). Chronic shame can be profoundly disempowering and damaging affecting one’s global sense of self and, as a result, the expression of one’s intentionality and agency in the world and with others. Living as a shame, subjectivity does not entail merely having internalized ideas about one’s inferior social status. Instead, this inferiority is literally embodied. The hesitation and withdrawal that characterize acute shame experiences become an enduring feature of one’s body schema and this may result in a “(psychophysical) inferiority complex” (Weiss 1999, 27–28).5 One’s posture may become stooped, one’s motor actions subdued, one’s gestures hesitant or faltering. Perpetually feeling oneself to be a person of lesser worth has concrete consequences in terms of how one comports oneself and this, of course, has consequences for one’s life chances. In general, the effect of chronic shame is negative, and sometimes even “toxic” (Bradshaw 1988, 10–11). As a result, chronic shame is closely correlated with depression, low self-esteem, suicide, anxiety, poor health, sexual assault, violence, bullying, addiction and eating disorders. Furthermore, it has been posited that chronic shame has been linked to a variety of mood disorders and pathologies such as alcoholism, anti-social personality disorder, borderline personality, pathological narcissism, psychoanalytic neuroses and social anxiety disorder (Bradshaw 1988). Even if chronic shame doesn’t result in pathological states as serious as mood disorders or in behaviours as damaging as addiction, in its on-going landscape of self-reference and self-consciousness, chronic shame can lead to a psychic ‘binding’ which is not only emotional but cognitive as well, and this is profoundly disempowering. Empirical research has demonstrated that performance in cognitive tasks, such as mathematics, diminishes when one is made to feel self-conscious or ashamed, especially when these experiences are centred on the body and attention is directed to appearance management and fear of social judgement (Fredrickson et al. 1998). Beyond its significance for individual health and well-being, chronic shame has significant social and political consequences. In fact, the sort of subjectivity that is constituted in light of the experience of chronic shame is one that is politically and socially compromised, leading to a state of profound disempowerment. It does not lead to the sort of “lucid” agent of moral philosophy, who can supposedly clearly discern between right and wrong, and exert agency in ethical and political contexts (Woodward 2000, 225). There is an extensive 319
Luna Dolezal
literature which links the systematic shaming of certain individuals to political strategies of exclusion and marginalization, arguing that chronic forms of shame, which are induced by certain societal power relations, play a key role in the establishment and sustaining of social inequalities.6 Thus, also when considered as an aspect of social and political relations, chronic shame can have serious consequences. The continuous binding effects of chronic shame hinder empathy, responsibility and active political engagement, while encouraging a toxic self-centredness and self-interest (cf. Locke 2016; Probyn 2005). As Pattison and his colleagues write: Shame (…) is a curiously premoral or amoral state in which the self is inwardly engaged and preoccupied, paralysed either temporarily or permanently, and unable to engage in taking responsibility and judgement for its own actions; a failed, defiled, unwanted self cannot act as a responsive and responsible agent. Perhaps it is not surprising that a shamed person often feels speechless—they fall out of the community of human discourse and responsibility. (Sanders et al. 2011, 85) In short, chronic has a largely negative and destructive potential, personally, socially and politically. Chronic shame seems to lack the positive potential for moral edification and social development that it is often discussed with relation to acute shame.
6. Conclusion The attunement to body shame that women experience is so pervasive and indeterminate that it is often beyond the reach of reflective consciousness. Women may not even realize that they are experiencing shame, or the threat of shame, and that they are exerting inordinate efforts to avoid shameful exposure. Instead, they become preoccupied with cultivating pride which hinges on the other side of the emotional dialectic which accompanies the narcissistic concern of the body as spectacle (Bartky 1990, 84). Or, if shame does, in fact, enter conscious awareness, it is seen as a result of one’s own inadequacies and, in particular, as one’s own fault. Personal efforts must be made in order to eliminate it. For women, chronic shame, particularly shame that is centred on embodiment, can shrink one’s world, disrupting ongoing activities and life projects as the self turns attention inward on itself. This may resu lt in compromising one’s confidence and ability to fully engage with others and with projects in the world. Or perhaps it evokes an inhibited style of bodily movement, rendering one fragile, insecure, timid and emotionally vulnerable. Or it may inhibit empathy or ethical concern for others, as Pattison and his colleagues suggest. However, as shame is such an integrated part of female identity and preying on this shame such a central part of our cultural discourse and the machinations of neoliberal consumerism (e.g., Jansen and Wehrle 2018), it is easily overlooked or ignored. There is an abiding cultural reluctance to confront the pernicious and ubiquitous shame that infects women’s day-today lived experience. It has become so thoroughly integrated into our social, cultural and political landscape as to be rendered invisible. It is precisely for this reason that any account of women’s shame must look not only at its phenomenology, or how it is experienced by the subject, but also at the structures of shame that result in the fact it is often not experienced. In its chronic form, shame is frequently anticipated but often not realized. In other words, a subjectivity can be structured by shame, and the ongoing strategies to avoid shame, without shame necessarily entering into conscious awareness or being an explicit part of the way 320
Feminism, embodiment and emotions
one self-identifies one’s experience. When considering women and their embodiment, it is evident that shame has the power to subtend all one’s experience and to form one’s world and the consequences of this can be far-reaching.
Notes
References Ahmed, Sara (2004). The Cultural Politics of Emotion. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Bartky, Sandra Lee (1990). Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression. London: Routledge. Beauvoir, Simone de (2010). The Second Sex. London: Vintage. Berlant, Lauren, Najafi, Sina, and Serlin, David (2008). The Broken Circuit: An Interview with Lauren Berlant. Cabinet Magazine (Fall 2008). Bordo, Susan (1993). Unbearable Weight: Feminism, Western Culture and the Body. Berkeley: University of California Press. Bouson, J. Brooks (2009). Embodied Shame: Uncovering Female Shame in Contemporary Women’s Writing. Albany: State University of New York Press. Bradshaw, John (1988). Healing the Shame that Binds You. Deerfield Beach: Health Communications. Brennan, Teresa (2004). The Transmission of Affect. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Calhoun, Cheshire (2004). An Apology for Moral Shame. The Journal of Political Philosophy 12, 127–146. Clough, Patricia T., and Halley, Jean (Eds.) (2007). The Affective Turn: Theorizing the Social. Durham: Duke University Press. Deyoung, Patricia A. (2015). Understanding and Treating Chronic Shame: A Relational/Neurobiological Approach. London, New York: Routledge. Dolezal, Luna (2015). The Body and Shame: Phenomenology, Feminism and the Socially Shaped Body. Lanham: Lexington. Dolezal, Luna, and Lyons, Barry (2017). Health-Related Shame: An Affective Determinant of Health? Medical Humanities 43(4), 257–263. Fischer, Clara (2018). Gender and the Politics of Shame: A Twenty-First-Century Feminist Shame Theory. Hypatia 33, 371–383. Fisher, Linda, and Embree, Lester (2000). Feminist Phenomenology. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Fredrickson, Barbara L., et al. (1998). That Swimsuit Becomes You: Sex Differences in Self-Objectification, Restrained Eating, and Math Performance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 75, 269–284.
321
Luna Dolezal Gilbert, Paul (2002). Body Shame: A Biopsychological Conceptualisation and Overview, with Treatment Implications. In: P. Gilbert, and J. Miles (Eds.). Body Shame: Conceptualisation, Research and Treatment. New York: Brunner-Routledge. Gorton, Kristyn (2007). Theorizing Emotion and Affect: Feminist Engagements. Feminist Theory 8(3), 333–348. Guenther, Lisa (2011). Shame and the Temporality of Social Life. Continental Philosophy Review 44, 23–39. Harris-Perry, Melissa V. (2011). Sister Citizen: Shame, Stereotypes and Black Women in America. New Haven, London: Yale University Press. Hatzenbuehler, Mark L., and Pachankis, John E. (2016). Stigma and Minority Stress as Social Determinants of Health Among Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, and Transgender Youth. Pediatric Clinics of North America 63, 985–997. Jansen, Julia, and Wehrle, Maren (2018). The Normal Body: Female Bodies in Changing Contexts of Normalization and Optimization. In: C. Fischer, and L. Dolezal (Eds.). New Feminist Perspectives on Embodiment. London, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 37–55. Johnson, Erica L., and Moran, Patricia (Eds.) (2013). The Female Face of Shame. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Kaufman, Gershen (1993). The Psychology of Shame: Theory and Treatment of Shame Based Syndromes. London, New York: Routledge. Landweer, Hilge, and Marcinski, Isabella (Eds.) (2016). Dem Erleben auf der Spur: Feminismus und die Philosophie des Leibes. Bielefeld: Transcript. Lehtinen, Ullaliina (1998). How Does One Know What Shame Is? Epistemology, Emotions and Forms of Life in Juxtaposition. Hypatia 13, 56–77. Locke, Jill (2007). Shame and the Future of Feminism. Hypatia 22, 146–162. ——— (2016). Democracy and the Death of Shame: Political Equality and Social Disturbance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Manion, Jennifer C. (2003). Girls Blush, Sometimes: Gender, Moral Agency and the Problem of Shame. Hypatia 18, 21–41. McMahon, John (2016). Emotional Orientations: Simone de Beauvoir and Sara Ahmed on Subjectivity and the Emotional Phenomenology of Gender. philoSOPHIA 6(2), 215–240. Murphy, Julien (Ed.) (1999). Feminist Interpretations of Jean-Paul Sartre. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press. Nathanson, Donald L. 1992. Shame and Pride: Affect, Sex and the Birth of the Self. New York: Norton. Northrop, Jane M. (2012). Reflecting on Cosmetic Surgery: Body Image, Shame and Narcissism. London, New York: Routledge. Olkowski, Dorothea, and Weiss, Gail (eds.) (2006). Feminist Interpretations of Maurice Merleau-Ponty. University Park: They Pennsylvania State University Press. Pattison, Stephen (2000). Shame: Theory, Therapy, Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Probyn, Elspeth (2005). Blush: Faces of Shame. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Sanders, Karen, Pattison, Stephen, and Hurwitz, Brian (2011). Tracking Shame and Humiliation in Accident and Emergency. Nursing Philosophy 12, 83–93. Sartre, Jean-Paul (2002). Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. London: Routledge. ——— (2003). Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology. London: Routledge. Scheff, Thomas J. (2004). Elias, Freud and Goffman: Shame as the Master Emotion. In: S. Loyal and S. Quilley (Eds.). The Sociology of Norbert Elias. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Weiss, Gail (1999). Body Images: Embodiment as Intercorporeality. New York, London: Routledge. Widdows, Heather (2018). Perfect Me: Beauty as an Ethical Ideal. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Woodward, Kathleen (2000). Traumatic Shame: Toni Morrison, Televisual Culture, and the Cultural Politics of Emotions. Cultural Critique 46, 210–240. Young, Iris Marion (1980). Throwing Like a Girl: A Phenomenology of Feminine Bodily Comportment, Motility and Spatiality. Human Studies 3(2), 137–156. Further reading Heinämaa, Sara (2012). Sex, Gender and Embodiment. In: D. Zahavi (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook in Contemporary Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 216–242.
322
28 EMBODIED INTERAFFECTIVITY AND PSYCHOPATHOLOGY Thomas Fuchs
1. Introduction The question of how interpersonal empathy and mutual understanding may be achieved on a preverbal level has dominated the debates in social cognition, social neuroscience and social philosophy for over two decades. The prevailing view still rests on the assumption that other minds are, in principle, hidden to us; hence, possible routes towards understanding can only take the detour of relying on internal cognitive mechanisms such as a ‘theory of mind’, ‘mentalizing’ or ‘mindreading’, which allow to infer others’ states of mind. Regardless of whether these mechanisms are described as akin to a scientific ‘theory’ or rather as a mental ‘simulation’ routine (Stich and Nichols 1992; Baron-Cohen 1995; Carruthers and Smith 1996), the general framework has mostly remained true to its origins in classical cognitivism and representationalism. Empathy is considered either as mind-reading or as simulating others’ mental states inside oneself. This paradigm is typically applied to emotions in general: They are not regarded as embodied responses to meaningful situations, thus being perceivable in the bodily expression and conduct of another person, but rather as internal cognitive appraisals of environmental stimuli. The phenomenological critique of the cognitivist position has rejected the internalist idea that our emotional and intentional states are hidden to others, and that empathy or sympathy may be conceived in analogy to a theory (Gallagher 2008; Zahavi 2008). Two alternative concepts of social understanding have been put forward, the one on a phenomenological, the other on an enactivist basis: a
b
According to the concept of direct perception, we are well able to immediately perceive others’ intentions and emotions to a certain extent, on the one hand in their expressive behaviour, and on the other hand in their visible intentions-in-action as being related to a meaningful context (Gallagher 2008; Krueger 2018). Seeing another person cry, one sees part of her sadness; seeing her running after a train, one sees her intention to reach it, without a need for inference. According to interaction theory, social cognition is mainly based on social interactions which induce, on a prereflective and preverbal level, a mutual bodily resonance and corresponding modification of emotional states. These felt changes brought about by the 323
Thomas Fuchs
mutual engagement should enable a primary form of empathy without requiring any representations (De Jaegher and Di Paolo 2007; Fuchs and De Jaegher 2009). Accordingly, phenomenological and enactive approaches to sociality do not start from isolated individuals and their respective inner states, but from the overarching phenomena of intercorporeality and interaffectivity (Gallagher 2001; Fuchs and De Jaegher 2009; Froese and Fuchs 2012; De Jaegher 2015). In particular, the concept of inter-bodily resonance implies the idea that the emergent dynamics of interaction creates a shared affective experience rather than transmitting internal states between individuals. On the other hand, such concepts raise the difficult question of how it is possible to experience the shared feeling or atmosphere arising from the interaction, while at the same time empathically perceiving the other’s specific emotional state. In other words, emphasizing the interaffective component of social encounters may risk losing the difference between empathic understanding and emotional contagion or even fusion. To avoid this risk, I propose that bodily and affective resonance should be conceived as a polarity of consonance and dissonance, which despite affective attunement maintains the otherness of the other. To elaborate the concept of embodied interaffectivity, in the following, I will introduce (1) a general concept of embodied affectivity: It conceives emotions not as inner mental states, but as encompassing spatial phenomena that connect the embodied subject and the situation with its affective affordances in a dynamic interaction. (2) This leads to a concept of embodied interaffectivity: In every face-to-face encounter, the partners’ lived bodies are intertwined in a process of inter-bodily resonance which provides the basis for a primary, intuitive empathic understanding. According to this concept, emotions in social encounters may not be localized within the individual (let alone his or her brain), but should rather be conceived as phenomena of a shared intercorporeal space in which the interaction partners are involved. (3) The proposed concept will then be illustrated and deepened by an analysis of disturbances of social resonance and empathy in psychopathology.
2. Embodied affectivity The concept of embodied affectivity rejects the idea that emotions are only mental phenomena, and that the world is bare of affective qualities. In fact, we do not live in a merely physical world; the experienced space is always charged with affective and expressive qualities. We feel, for example, the hilarity of a party, the sadness of a funeral march, the icy climate of a meeting or the uncanniness of a sombre wood at night. Emotions also emerge from situations, persons and objects with their expressive, attractive or repulsive qualities. The peculiar intentionality of emotions relates to what is particularly valuable and relevant for the subject (see Solomon 1976; Frijda 1994; Scarantino and De Sousa 2018). In a sense, emotions are ways of perceiving, namely attending to salient features of a situation, lending them a significance and weight they would not have without the emotion. Referring to Gibson’s (1979) concept of affordance, we may also speak of affective affordances: Objects or situations appear to us as ‘important’, ‘worthwhile’, ‘attractive’, ‘unpleasant’, ‘disgusting’ and so on. The way emotions disclose the affective qualities or affordances of a given situation is by bodily resonance. This includes, on the one hand, all kinds of bodily sensations: feelings of warmth or coldness, tickling or shivering, pain, tension or relaxation, constriction or expansion, sinking, tumbling or lifting, etc. On the other hand, emotions involve bodily action tendencies which are felt kinaesthetically, such as bowing, rising, receding, advancing, etc. There is no emotion without at least slightest bodily sensations and movement tendencies. 324
Embodied interaffectivity and psychopathology
Being afraid, for instance, is not possible without feeling a bodily tension or trembling, a beating of the heart or a shortness of breath, and a tendency to withdraw.1 It is through these sensations that one is anxiously directed towards a frightening situation. Therefore, bodily feelings and action tendencies should not be conceived as a mere by-product or add-on to the emotion, but as the very medium of affective intentionality. As William James already pointed out, the body is a “resonance body”, in which every emotion reverberates ( James 1884).2 This leads to an embodied and extended conception of emotions (see also Fuchs 2013a and Chapter 26 in this volume): Emotions emerge as specific forms of a subject’s bodily directedness towards the values and affective affordances of a given situation. They encompass subject and situation and may not be localized in the interior of persons (be it their psyche or their brain). Rather, the affected subject is engaged with an environment that has itself affective qualities. For example, in shame, an embarrassing situation and the dismissive gazes of others are experienced as a painful bodily affection, which is the way the subject feels the sudden devaluation in others’ eyes. The emotion of shame is thus extended over the feeling person and his body as well as the situation as a whole. Emotions further imply two components of bodily resonance: (1) a centripetal or affective component, i.e. being affected, ‘moved’ or ‘touched’ by an event through various forms of bodily sensations (e.g., the blushing and burning of shame); and (2) a centrifugal or ‘emotive’ component, implying specific movement tendencies (e.g., hiding, avoiding the other’s gaze, ‘sinking into the floor’ from shame). Other tendencies are approach (desire, anger), avoidance (fear), being-with (enjoyment, confidence), rejection (disgust), dominance (pride) or submission (humility, resignation) (cf. Frijda 1986). In emotions, “we are moved to move toward or against or away” (Sheets-Johnstone 1999, 267). Taken together, emotions may be regarded as circular interactions or feedback cycles between the embodied subject and the current situation (cf. Figure 28.1): Being affected by the emotional affordances or qualities of the situation (affection, impression) triggers a specific bodily resonance which, in turn, influences the emotional perception of the situation and implies a corresponding action readiness (e-motion, expression). Embodied affectivity consists in the whole interactive cycle, which is crucially mediated by the resonance of the feeling body. Bodily resonance thus acts as the medium of our affective engagement in a given situation. It imbues, taints and permeates the perception of this situation without necessarily
Figure 28.1
Embodied affectivity (adapted from Fuchs 2013a, 623)
325
Thomas Fuchs
stepping into the foreground. In Polanyi’s terms, bodily resonance is the proximal, and the perceived situation is the distal component of affective intentionality, with the proximal or tacit component usually receding from awareness in favour of the distal (Polanyi 1967). The bodily resonance of the emotion becomes conscious only at a certain level of intensity.
3. Embodied interaffectivity If we now turn to the social sphere, in particular to face-to-face encounters, then the cycle of affection and emotion, or impression and expression, involves another person as a specific affective affordance. Emotions thus become interactive phenomena which are not only felt from the inside, but also displayed and visible in expression and behaviour, often as bodily tokens or rudiments of action (Darwin 1872). The facial, gestural, vocal and postural expression of an emotion is part of the bodily resonance that feeds back into the emotion itself, but also induces processes of interaffectivity: One’s body is affected by the other’s expression, and one experiences the kinetics and intensity of his emotions through one’s own bodily kinaesthesia and sensation. Both partners’ body schemas and bodily feelings expand and incorporate the other’s body. This creates a dynamic interplay which forms the basis of social understanding and empathy, and which may also be described as “mutual incorporation” (Schmitz 1989; Fuchs and De Jaegher 2009). Here, two cycles of embodied affectivity become intertwined, thus continuously modifying each partner’s affective affordances and bodily resonance, as illustrated in Figure 28.2. Let us assume that A is a person whose emotion, e.g., anger, manifests itself in typical bodily (facial, gestural, interoceptive, adrenergic, circulatory, etc.) changes. His body thus functions as a felt ‘resonance board’ for his emotion: A feels the anger as the tension in his face, as the sharpness of his voice, the arousal in his body, etc. These proprio- and interoceptive feelings may be termed intra-bodily resonance. This resonance is an expression of the emotion at the same time; that means, the anger becomes visible and is perceived as such by A’s partner B. Moreover, the expression will also produce an impression, namely by triggering corresponding or complementary bodily feelings in B. A’s sinister gaze, the sharpness of his voice or expansive bodily movements might induce in B an unpleasant tension or even a jerk, a tendency to withdraw, etc. Thus, B not only sees the anger immediately in A’s face and gesture, but also senses it through his own intra-bodily resonance. However, it does not stop here, for the impression and bodily reaction caused in B, in turn, becomes an expression for A; it will immediately affect his bodily reaction, change his expression, however slightly, and so forth. This creates a circular interplay of expressions, impressions and reactions running in split seconds and constantly modifying each partner’s bodily state, in a process that becomes highly autonomous and is not controlled by
Figure 28.2
Inter-bodily resonance (Froese and Fuchs 2012)
326
Embodied interaffectivity and psychopathology
the partners. They have become parts of a dynamic sensorimotor and interaffective system that connects both bodies by reciprocal movements and reactions, that means, in inter-bodily resonance. Of course, the signals and reactions involved proceed far too quickly to stand out discretely and become conscious. Instead, both partners will experience a specific feeling of being bodily connected with the other: Based on its sensorimotor body schema, each lived body reaches out, as it were, to be extended by the other in a mutual incorporation. This is accompanied by a specific impression of the interaction partner and, at the same time, by a holistic feeling for the encompassing atmosphere of the shared situation.3 Importantly, as the example shows, this inter-bodily resonance and the resulting atmosphere are, by no means, restricted to ‘harmonious’ social situations—interpersonal conflicts may create most intense forms of mutual resonance and atmospheric tensions. In other words, resonance takes place on a range between consonance and dissonance. The resulting interpersonal atmosphere (e.g., ‘pleasant’ versus ‘tense’) mirrors the different interaction dynamics. This leads to a further clarification: The neurobiological support of simulation theory through the discovery of the mirror neuron system (Gallese and Goldman 1998; Gallese 2005) has often led to the assumption that empathic understanding is only based on mimetic bodily tendencies, such as subliminally imitating another’s smile or his painfully distorted facial expression. However, in order to recognize and feel the anger in another’s face, we certainly do not have to experience or simulate anger ourselves. Our primary reaction would be rather oppositional than concordant; that means, we would feel tense, frightened and tend to withdraw. Hence, inter-bodily resonance may include both mimetic and complementary or antagonistic dynamics. This offers a serious objection to concepts of embodied simulation (Gallese 2005; Gallese and Sinigaglia 2011). Moreover, even in consonant or harmonious interactions, there is never a complete attunement or in-phase mutual behaviour. Apart from situations of emotional fusion (as in joint mass emotions such as panic or enthusiasm), the other’s body always offers at least some resistance to perfect attunement, usually resulting in sequences of ‘matching’ and ‘mismatching’ episodes. This has also been shown by infant research: Even in harmonious playing interactions, infants and mothers match their affects only 30% of the time; the typical micro-interaction patterns consist in repeated sequences of matches, mismatches and ‘repairs’ (Tronick and Cohn 1989; Beebe et al. 1992). Similarly, in adult interactions, the observable coordination of movements and reactions never reaches a state of perfect synchronization (Tschacher et al. 2014). Even in a well-trained dancing couple, the other’s body offers a minute resistance and unpredictability, which ensures that the dance still remains an interaction. This lack of complete congruence in interaffectivity is crucial for the distinction of self and other, which is maintained despite mutual incorporation. Out-of-phase movements, slight misunderstandings and irritations are necessary as the dialectical counterparts of mutual empathy, should it not turn into a fusion where the other is no longer perceived as other. Thus, the behaviours and experiences of two interactants, by no means, always resemble or match each other completely. Nevertheless, their resonant dynamics is jointly created and cannot be broken down to individual behaviour. Each of them behaves and experiences differently from how they would do outside of the process, which thus gains an emergent autonomy (De Jaegher and Di Paolo 2007; Mühlhoff 2015). No mental representation of other minds is necessary for this process. There is no dualistic separation between the inner and the outer at all, as if a hidden mental state in A produced certain external signs, which B would have to decipher. A’s anger may not be separated from its bodily resonance and expression; conversely, B does not perceive A as a mere object but as a living and expressive body that he is in contact with. Instead of a hidden inside, there 327
Thomas Fuchs
is an ongoing mutual transition between expression and impression, or between centrifugal emotion and centripetal affection. The other shows himself to me through his bodily appearance and conduct. This expressivity is concentrated in the gaze: The other is for me not somewhere ‘behind’ his gaze, but he is visible in it. What is more, I experience his gaze as being seen by him, or in other words, I see him seeing me (as seeing him). There is a circularity or reflexivity involved which does not allow to clearly separate inside and outside; the gaze itself is perceived as intentional or ‘minded’. Nor is an inner or bodily simulation required for the process of mutual empathic understanding—all the more since it often happens, as we have seen, without mimetic resonance at all. Bodily sensations, tensions and movement tendencies, which arise in the interaction, do not serve as a separate simulation of the other person, but are fed into the holistic perception of the other. Using Polanyi’s terms once more, one’s own bodily resonance may be regarded as the proximal component of empathic perception, which recedes from awareness in favour of the distal, namely the other’s perceived body. Bodily resonance does not simulate, but mediate the perception of the other. Hence, direct perception in interpersonal encounters is a “mediated immediacy” (to use Hegel’s term), based on the lived body. A frequent objection to such an embodied account refers to the fact that humans are able to control their emotional expressions, that means, to withhold, suppress or feign emotions to a certain extent (for example, when lying, cheating, playacting, in poker games, etc.). This seems to show that the expression of an emotion is different from the emotion itself. However, while the phenomena themselves are undeniable, the conclusion that emotions are actually inner, disembodied states is not justified, for at least two reasons: First, the control of one’s emotional bodily resonance is restricted to the movement of the voluntary muscles, whereas the reaction of the autonomous nervous system and the kinaesthetic tendencies of the body remain largely outside of control. This may be demonstrated by measuring heart rate, skin conductance (as with a lie detector), muscle tonus, etc., during concealed emotional states. Moreover, the suppression of an emerging emotion is enabled through increased muscle tension (hardening one’s face, jaw clenching, stiff posture, etc.), which demonstrates that the emotion in question already leads to kinaesthetic tendencies that are suppressed. Hence, emotions are always embodied states, even though we can restrict their expression to a certain extent. Secondly, even artificial or pretended emotional expressions have a tendency to evoke the corresponding emotion in the individual, as embodiment research has repeatedly demonstrated (Niedenthal et al. 2005; Niedenthal 2007). Moreover, the effect of playacting on the audience depends precisely on primary interaffectivity: If we would not normally perceive others’ expressions as their emotional states, we couldn’t be easily deceived either. Hence, even though we cannot be sure that a perceived emotion is actually what the other person feels, spontaneous bodily resonance remains the default mode of non-verbal understanding. Our analysis thus confirms Merleau-Ponty’s notion of a primary intercorporeality: “It is through my body that I understand other people, just as it is through my body that I perceive ‘things’” (Merleau-Ponty 1945, 216).
4. Psychopathology of interaffectivity The concept of embodied interaffectivity may be usefully applied to several psychopathological phenomena, where the described structure of intercorporeality and empathy is disturbed. This refers mainly to a lack or loss of bodily resonance and emotional perception, as it is found, for instance, in depression, autism, schizophrenia or certain neurological disorders. 328
Embodied interaffectivity and psychopathology
4.1 Neurological disorders Individuals whose facial expression is disturbed, whether congenital as in Möbius Syndrome, by an acquired facial paralysis or by Parkinson’s disease, often report diminished emotional experience (Krueger and Michael 2012). They may complain, for example, about an impaired sense of joy or humour, since their smiling is inhibited, and about an embarrassing lack of emotional communication with others. This points to the crucial importance of facial sensorimotor feedback for the full experience of an emotion as well as for interaffective resonance: If the external expressive profile of emotions is missing, this frequently leads to experiences of social rejection or exclusion (Bogart 2015).
4.2 Depression A more encompassing loss of bodily resonance is characteristic for severe depression. Here, the lived body loses the lightness, fluidity and mobility of a medium and turns into a heavy, solid body, which puts up resistance to all intentions and impulses directed towards the world (Fuchs 2013b). This may also be characterized by a general constriction and rigidity of the body, leading not only to felt oppression and anxiety but, more subtly, to a loss of the inter-bodily resonance in social encounters. The depressive body lacks expression and offers only minimal clues for the other’s empathic perception. The continuous synchronization of bodily gestures and gazes which normally accompany interaction (Tschacher et al. 2014) breaks down. Moreover, the patients’ own mimetic perception and resonance with the other’s body is lacking (Persad and Polivy 1993; Csukly et al. 2009; Bourke et al. 2010). Thus, they feel unable to emotionally communicate their experience and try in vain to compensate for the loss of resonance by stereotyped repetition of their complaints. The deeper the depression, the more the affective qualities and atmospheres of the environment fade. The patients are no longer capable of being moved and affected by things, situations or other persons. They complain of a painful apathy, a ‘feeling of not feeling’ and of not being able to sympathize with their relatives any more. In his autobiographical account, Solomon describes his depression as “a loss of feeling, a numbness, [which] had infected all my human relations. I didn’t care about love; about my work; about family; about friends” (Solomon 2001, 45). This emotional numbing may finally lead to affective depersonalization: The patients feel disconnected from the world; they lose their participation in the interaffective space that we normally share with others (Fuchs 2005; 2013b, Ratcliffe 2014, 218ff.).
4.3 Autism Until recently, social difficulties in autism or autistic spectrum disorders (ASD) were mainly thought to arise from a dysfunctional theory of mind, rendering the individual unable to attribute mental states to others in order to interpret their behaviour (Frith 1989; Baron-Cohen 1995). However, this cognitivist approach is increasingly questioned. In contrast, phenomenological accounts locate the main problem in a fundamental disturbance of embodied interaffectivity, namely in a lack of perceiving others’ expressions, gestures and voicings in terms of affective affordances (De Jaegher 2013; Fuchs 2015). From early childhood onwards, affected individuals fail to spontaneously perceive a smile as a smile, an angry expression as anger, or a sad face as showing sadness. They are blind or non-sensitive to what infant researcher Daniel Stern (1985) has termed “vitality affects”, i.e., the intermodal qualities and dynamics of facial, gestural and vocal expressions, which their caregivers exhibit, and which 329
Thomas Fuchs
for neurotypical children convey a sense of the other’s emotion. This account is supported by the fact that many autistic symptoms such as lack of emotional contact, anxiety or agitation are already present in the first years of life, i.e. long before the supposed age of 4–5 years to acquire a theory of mind. Furthermore, while imitation and co-movement serve as a major instrument for early affect attunement and primary empathy, several studies have found that children with ASD do not readily imitate the actions of others (Smith and Bryson 1994; Hobson and Lee 1999). As a result, there is a lack of the kinaesthetic empathy that normally mediates the affective perception of the other. The feedback cycles of mutual incorporation are not achieved; instead, for children with autism, the others remain rather mysterious, detached objects whose behaviour is troublesome to predict. They prefer to attend to inanimate objects over other humans, tend to avoid direct gaze and withdraw from emotionally overburdening contacts (Klin et al. 2003; Jones et al. 2008). Correspondingly, eye tracking studies have shown that children with autism focus on inanimate and irrelevant details of interactive situations while missing the relevant social cues, e.g., neglecting the eyes and mouths of protagonists (Klin et al. 2002). In other words, the salience of social stimuli is reduced, because these are particularly bound to the resonant perception of expressive gestures which is lacking in autism. It is the disturbance of primary empathy which also compromises the later development of higher-order capacities such as perspective-taking and language acquisition. For these are based on a primary sense of ‘being-like-others’ that is subsequently extended by relating to a shared context, such as in social referencing or joint attention, and finally, by understanding others as mental agents like oneself. However, if the ‘like-me’ experience is already missing in primary bodily encounters, the development of more abstract mentalizing capacities will be seriously retarded or even remain impossible. Hence, what these children primarily lack is not a theoretical concept of other minds, but the direct perception enabled by bodily resonance (Klin et al. 2003; Gallagher 2004; De Jaegher 2013). Strategies of explicit mentalizing and inferring from social cues are rather employed by high-functioning autistic individuals as a compensation for the lacking capacities of primary intersubjectivity. Thus, Temple Grandin, a woman with ASD, described her problems with interpersonal relations to Oliver Sacks as follows: It has to do, she has inferred, with an implicit knowledge of social conventions and codes, of cultural presuppositions of every sort. This implicit knowledge, which every normal person accumulates and generates throughout life on the basis of experience and encounters with others, Temple seems to be largely devoid of. Lacking it, she has instead to “compute” others’ intentions and states of mind, to try to make algorithmic, explicit, what for the rest of us is second nature. (Sacks 1995, 270) These compensatory strategies enable functional interactions with others to a certain degree, but fail to establish the primary sense of being-with-others which is normally provided implicitly by intercorporeality, as a kind of “magical communication”: She is now aware of the existence of these social signals. She can infer them, she says, but she herself cannot perceive them, cannot participate in this magical communication directly, or conceive the many-levelled kaleidoscopic states of mind behind it. Knowing this intellectually, she does her best to compensate, bringing immense intellectual effort 330
Embodied interaffectivity and psychopathology
and computational power to bear on matters that others understand with unthinking ease. This is why she often feels excluded, an alien. (ibid., 272) As we can see from Grandin’s report, a lacking social sense as normally conveyed by bodily resonance cannot be substituted by explicit inference or rule-based knowledge about others’ behaviour.
4.4 Schizophrenia A severe disturbance of interaffectivity is also found in schizophrenia spectrum disorders, which, from a phenomenological point of view, may be regarded as fundamental disturbances of the embodied self, or as a disembodiment. This includes a weakening of the basic sense of self, a disruption of implicit bodily functioning, and a disconnection from the intercorporeality with others (Parnas 2003; Sass and Parnas 2003; Fuchs 2005; Fuchs and Röhricht 2017). If the embodied engagement in the world is disturbed, it will result in a fundamental alienation of intersubjectivity: The basic sense of being-with-others is replaced by a sense of detachment. Hence, schizophrenic patients have been found to lack primary or bodily empathy: They have problems with understanding facial and gestural expressions of others (Kington et al. 2000; Edwards et al. 2002; Amminger et al. 2012). Like individuals with ASD, they tend to experience other’s bodies as less animated and rather like objects. Moreover, patients often show a lack of implicit understanding of social situations, manifesting itself in a subtle “loss of natural self-evidence”, as Blankenburg (1971) has described it; they are unable to grasp the natural, everyday meanings of the shared life world. This alienation may sometimes even date back to the patient’s childhood: When a child, I used to watch my little cousin in order to understand when it was the right moment to laugh or how they managed to act without thinking of it before (…) It is since I was a child that I try to understand how the others function, and I am therefore forced to play the little anthropologist. (Stanghellini 2004, 115) I don’t really grasp what others are up to (…) I constantly observe myself while I am together with people, trying to find out what I should say or do. It’s easier when I am alone or watching TV. (Quote from one of my own patients) Thus, the behaviour of others comes to be observed from a distant or third-person point of view, instead of entering second-person embodied interactions. Interpersonal relationships have then to be managed by deliberate efforts, leading to constant stress in complex social situations and finally to autistic withdrawal. This alienation can also be felt when interacting with the patient, leading to what has been termed praecox feeling by the Dutch psychiatrist Rümke (1941) (derived from the former term dementia praecox for schizophrenia). It means an interpersonal atmosphere of unnaturalness, characterized by a lack of mutuality, responsivity, or attunement: Often the praecox feeling is felt even before one has spoken to the patient; the condition is recognized by mere observation of body-posture, facial expression, motor 331
Thomas Fuchs
behaviour—the whole of the patient’s expressivity. It is intuitively felt that all these are disturbed, i.e., changed with respect to the norm. Motor behaviour is stiff, bizarre, ceremonious; there are tic-like movements and the queerness of the smile is beyond description—the famous empty smile. (Rümke 1941, 337) In the encounter, the patient’s bodily movements and expressions seem stiff, often bizarre or ceremonious; they are not integrated to form a harmonious whole. Moreover, the emotional expressions and verbal utterances do not seem to correspond to each other or to the context—a feature termed parathymia. When Rümke speaks of the “queerness” of the smile, he means not only unusual kinematic features such as stiffness and rigidity, but also a lack of appropriateness to the social context. The patients’ psychomotor movements are not geared towards the establishment of human contact; we miss the contact-directed expressions found in normal people, and, at the same time, we are struck by the desperate attempts undertaken by the schizophrenic to re-establish contact. (ibid., 338) Rümke’s description has been confirmed in recent studies on the diagnostic significance and reliability of the praecox feeling (Grube 2006; Pallagrosi and Fonzi 2018). It may be regarded as a further illustration of the concept of embodied interaffectivity: The psychiatrist’s impression corresponds not only to the patient’s expression, but also to the experiential disembodiment of persons with schizophrenia.
5. Conclusion I have outlined a concept of primary intersubjectivity that is based on embodied affectivity and interaffectivity. It conceives emotions not as inner mental states, which have to be deciphered or inferred from external cues, but as expressive, dynamic forces, which affect individuals through bodily resonance and connect them with each other in circular interactions. In face-to-face encounters, each partner’s lived body reaches towards the other to form an overarching system of inter-bodily resonance and mutual incorporation. According to this concept, social understanding is primarily based on intercorporeality; it emerges from the interactive practice and coordination of embodied agents. We do not need to form internal models or representations of others in order to understand and communicate with them; as bodily subjects, we are always already involved in a shared affective and expressive space. Psychopathological conditions in which bodily resonance is disturbed in various ways can illustrate ex negativo the intercorporeal basis of normal encounters. To be sure, this embodied and enactive concept does not exhaust the possibilities of empathic understanding. On the basis of primary bodily empathy, we are also able to explicitly represent or to imagine the other’s situation. This happens in particular when their behaviour seems ambiguous or when an irritation or misunderstanding occurs. Through additional information and inference, we can then try to enhance our understanding, infer possible hidden intentions and in this way often deepen our empathy (Fuchs 2017). A further possibility is to transpose oneself into the other’s situation, take his perspective and imagine how one would feel or react in his place. Such higher-level capacities of understanding others complement the spontaneous interaffectivity of bodily resonance and direct perception. Though they correspond to the 332
Embodied interaffectivity and psychopathology
notions of ‘theory of mind’ or ‘mind-reading’ to a certain extent, these terms presuppose an inferential approach to others’ supposedly hidden minds as the standard mode of intersubjectivity. Yet, the need for such an approach arises mainly in situations in which intercorporeal communication becomes ambiguous or restricted, such as in poker games, or when it is missing completely, as in written exchange. In most cases, sophisticated or even detective-like cognitive capacities are neither necessary nor sufficient to enable empathic intersubjective relations. Despite those options for extended understanding, our everyday social encounters remain based on embodied intersubjectivity.
Notes
References Amminger, G. Paul, Schäfer, Miriam R., Papageorgiou, Konstantinos, Klier, Claudia M., Schlögelhofer, Monika, Mossaheb, Nilufar, Werneck-Rohrer, Sonja, Nelson, Barnaby, and McGorry, Patrick D. (2012). Emotion Recognition in Individuals at Clinical High-risk for Schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin 38(5), 1030–1039. Baron-Cohen, Simon (1995). Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Beebe, Beatrice, Jaffe, Joseph, and Lachmann, Frank (1992). A Dyadic Systems View of Communication. In: N. Skolnick and S. Warshaw (Eds.). Relational Perspectives in Psychoanalysis. Hillsdale, NJ: The Analytic Press, 61–81. Blankenburg, Wolfgang (1971). Der Verlust der natürlichen Selbstverständlichkeit. Berlin: Springer. Bogart, Kathleen R. (2015). “People Are All About Appearances”: A Focus Group of Teenagers with Moebius Syndrome. Journal of Health Psychology 20(12), 1579–1588. Bourke, Cecilia, Douglas, Katie, and Porter, Richard (2010). Processing of Facial Emotion Expression in Major Depression: A Review. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 44(8), 681–696. Carruthers, Peter, and Smith, Peter K. (Eds.) (1996). Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Csukly, Gábor, Szobor, Pál, Szily, Erika, Takács, Barnabás, and Simon, Lajos (2009). Facial Expression Recognition in Depressed Subjects: The Impact of Intensity Level and Arousal Dimension. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 197(2), 98–103. Darwin, Charles (1904[1872]). The Expression of Emotions in Man and Animals. London: Murray. De Jaegher, Hanne (2013). Embodiment and Sense-making in Autism. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 7, 15.
333
Thomas Fuchs ——— (2015). How We Affect Each Other: Michel Henry’s “Pathos-with” and the Enactive Approach to Intersubjectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies 22(1–2), 112–132. De Jaegher, Hanne, and Di Paolo, Ezequiel A. (2007). Participatory Sense-making: An Enactive Approach to Social Cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6(4), 485–507. Edwards, Jane, Jackson, Henry J., and Pattison, Philippa E. (2002). Emotion Recognition via Facial Expression and Affective Prosody in Schizophrenia: A Methodological Review. Clinical Psychology Review 22(6), 789–832. Frijda, Nico H. (1986). The Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frith, Uta (1989). Autism: Explaining the Enigma. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Froese, Tom, and Fuchs, Thomas (2012). The Extended Body: A Case Study in the Neurophenomenology of Social Interaction. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 11(2), 205–236. Fuchs, Thomas (2005). Corporealized and Disembodied Minds. A Phenomenological View of the Body in Melancholia and Schizophrenia. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology 12(2), 95–107. ——— (2013a). The Phenomenology of Affectivity. In: B. Fulford, M. Davies, G. Graham, J. Sadler, and G. Stanghellini (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 612–631. ——— (2013b). Depression, Intercorporeality and Interaffectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies 20(7–8), 219–238. ——— (2015). Pathologies of Intersubjectivity in Autism and Schizophrenia. Journal of Consciousness Studies 22(1–2), 191–214. ——— (2017). Levels of Empathy. In: V. Lux and S. Weigel (Eds.). Empathy. Epistemic Problems and Cultural-historical Perspectives of a Cross-disciplinary Concept. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 27–48. Fuchs, Thomas, and De Jaegher, Hanne (2009). Enactive Intersubjectivity: Participatory Sensemaking and Mutual Incorporation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8(4), 465–486. Fuchs, Thomas, and Röhricht, Frank (2017). Schizophrenia and Intersubjectivity. An Embodied and Enactive Approach to Psychopathology. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology 24(2), 127–142. Gallagher, Shaun (2001). The Practice of Mind: Theory, Simulation or Primary Interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7), 83–108. ——— (2004). Understanding Interpersonal Problems in Autism: Interaction Theory as an Alternative to Theory of Mind. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology 11(3), 199–217. ——— (2008). Direct Perception in the Intersubjective Context. Consciousness and Cognition 17(2), 535–543. Gallese, Vittorio (2005). Embodied Simulation: From Neurons to Phenomenal Experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4(1), 23–48. Gallese, Vittorio, and Goldman, Alvin (1998). Mirror Neurons and the Simulation Theory of Mind-reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2(12), 493–501. Gallese, Vittorio, and Sinigaglia, Corrado (2011). What Is so Special about Embodied Simulation? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15(11), 512–519. Gibson, James J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Grube, Michael (2006). Towards an Empirically Based Validation of Intuitive Diagnostic: Rümke’s ‘Praecox Feeling’ across the Schizophrenia Spectrum: Preliminary Results. Psychopathology 39(5), 209–217. Hatfield, Elaine, Cacioppo, John T., and Rapson, Richard L. (1993). Emotional Contagion. Current Directions in Psychological Science 2(3), 96–99. Hobson, R. Peter, and Lee, Anthony (1999). Imitation and Identification in Autism. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 40(4), 649–659. James, William (1884). What is an Emotion? Mind 9(34), 188–205. Jones, Warren H., Carr, Katelin, and Klin, Ami J. (2008). Absence of Preferential Looking to the Eyes of Approaching Adults Predicts Level of Social Disability in 2-year-old Toddlers with Autism Spectrum Disorder. Archives of General Psychiatry 65(8), 946–954. Kington, Justin M., Jones, Lisa A., Watt, Andrew A., Hopkin, Elizabeth J., and Williams, Julie (2000). Impaired Eye Expression Recognition in Schizophrenia. Journal of Psychiatric Research 34(4–5), 341–347.
334
Embodied interaffectivity and psychopathology Klin, Ami, Jones, Warren, Schultz, Robert, and Volkmar, Fred (2003). The Enactive Mind, or from Actions to Cognition: Lessons from Autism. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society London B: Biological Sciences 358(1430), 345–360. Klin, Ami, Jones, Warren, Schultz, Robert, Volkmar, Fred R., and Cohen, Donald J. (2002). Visual Fixation Patterns during Viewing of Naturalistic Social Situations as Predictors of Social Competence in Individuals with Autism. Archives of General Psychiatry 59(9), 809–816. Krueger, Joel (2018). Direct Social Perception. In: A. Newen, L. de Bruin, and S. Gallagher (Eds.). Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 301–320. Krueger, Joel, and Michael, John (2012). Gestural Coupling and Social Cognition: Möbius Syndrome as a Case Study. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 6, 81. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1962[1945]). The Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by C. Smith. New York: Humanities Press. Mühlhoff, Rainer (2015). Affective Resonance and Social Interaction. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 14(4), 1001–1019. Niedenthal, Paula M. (2007). Embodying Emotion. Science 316(5827), 1002–1005. Niedenthal, Paula M., Barsalou, Lawrence W., Winkielman, Piotr, Krauth-Gruber, Silvia, and Ric, François (2005). Embodiment in Attitudes, Social Perception, and Emotion. Personality and Social Psychology Review 9(3), 184–211. Pallagrosi, Mauro, and Fonzi, Laura (2018). On the Concept of Praecox Feeling. Psychopathology 51(6), 353–361. Parnas, Josef (2003). Self and Schizophrenia: A Phenomenological Perspective. In: T. Kircher, and A. David (Eds.). The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 217–241. Persad, Schrine M., and Polivy, Janet (1993). Differences between Depressed and Non-depressed Individuals in the Recognition of and Response to Facial Emotional Cues. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 102(3), 358–368. Polanyi, Michael (1967). The Tacit Dimension. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books. Ratcliffe, Matthew (2014). Experiences of Depression: A Study in Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rümke, Henricus C. (1990[1941]). The Nuclear Symptoms of Schizophrenia and the Praecox Feeling. Transl. by J. Neeleman. History of Psychiatry 1(3), 331–341. Sacks, Oliver (1995). An Anthropologist on Mars. Seven Paradoxical Tales. New York: Knopf. Sass, Louis A., and Parnas, Josef (2003). Schizophrenia, Consciousness, and the Self. Schizophrenia Bulletin 29(3), 427–444. Scarantino, Andrea, and de Sousa, Ronald (2018). Emotion. In: E. Zalta (Ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/emotion/ [10.03.2019] Scheler, Max (1954[1923]). The Nature of Sympathy. Transl. by P. Heath. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Schmitz, Hermann (1989). Über leibliche Kommunikation. In: Hermann Schmitz: Leib und Gefühl. Materialien zu einer philosophischen Therapeutik. Paderborn: Junfermann, 175–218. Sheets-Johnstone, Maxine (1999). Emotion and Movement. A Beginning Empirical-phenomenological Analysis of Their Relationship. Journal of Consciousness Studies 6(11–12), 259–277. Smith, Isabel M., and Bryson, Susan E. (1994). Imitation and Action in Autism: A Critical Review. Psychological Bulletin 116(2), 259–273. Solomon, Andrew (2001). The Noonday Demon: An Atlas of Depression. London: Vintage. Solomon, Robert C. (1976). The Passions. New York: Anchor/Doubleday. Stanghellini, Giovanni (2004). Disembodied Spirits and Deanimatied Bodies: The Psychopathology of Common Sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stein, Edith (1989[1917]). On the Problem of Empathy. Transl. by W. Stein. Washington, D.C.: ICS Publication. Stern, Daniel N. (1985). The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis and Developmental Psychology. New York: Basic Books. Stich, Stephen, and Nichols, Shaun (1992). Folk Psychology: Simulation versus Tacit Theory. Mind and Language 7(1–2), 29–65.
335
Thomas Fuchs Tronick, Edward Z., and Cohn, Jeffery F. (1989). Infant-mother Face-to-face Interaction: Age and Gender Differences in Coordination and the Occurrences of Miscoordination. Child Development 60(1), 85–92. Tschacher, Wolfgang, Rees, Georg M., and Ramseyer, Fabian (2014). Nonverbal Synchrony and Affect in Dyadic Interactions. Frontiers in Psychology 5, 1323. Zahavi, Dan (2008). Simulation, Projection and Empathy. Consciousness and Cognition 17(2), 514–522.
336
29 ART AND EMOTION Noël Carroll
The arts have been associated with the emotions for millennia. In the 5th century BCE, the Greek philosopher Plato linked poetry to the arousal of emotion, while in the Hindu tradition, Bharata in his Natya Shastra (Bharata 1987) made comparable claims for theater between the 3rd century BCE and the 3rd century CE. Nor is the association only an ancient one. In the 18th century, the philosopher Jean-Baptiste Dubos argued that the function of art was to elicit the emotions as a means of warding boredom (Dubos 1748). Although the relation of art to the emotions is often discussed in terms of the arousal of the emotions in audiences, the relation of emotion to the artist is also a subject of philosophical attention, often in terms of the notion of expression. Thus, in this essay, we will examine the relation of art to the emotions first in terms of the arousal of the emotions and then in terms of the expression of emotion. We will further subdivide the section on the arousal of emotion into two parts: the arousal of the everyday or common or “garden variety” emotions, like anger and sadness, and the arousal of art-specific emotions. Likewise, the topic of the expression of the emotions will be divided into two parts: the expression of emotion proper and the projection of expressive or emotively charged properties.
1. The arousal of common emotions Artworks engender a wide variety of emotions that are also common in everyday life. We are angered by the injustice suffered by fictional characters in stories as we are by the tribulations of actual oppressed peoples. We feel joy viewing pictures of people triumphing over the odds just as we do when witnessing it in the flesh. One of the earliest, if not the earliest, philosophical discussion of this phenomena in the Western tradition can be found in Books 2 and 3 of Plato’s Republic (Plato 1961). At that point in his discussion of the ideal state, Plato is concerned with the education of the future rulers of that state whom he called Guardians. Plato was especially concerned with the way in which literature, like the poetry of Homer, would influence the emotions of these impressionable youths. To this end, Plato developed the first theory of the impact of the arts on the emotions. It was a theory, based on the idea of emotional identification, that continues to live on today in views about the relation of art, especially popular art, to the emotions.
337
Noël Carroll
Greek students learned to read by reading aloud from classic texts such as those of Homer, who was called “the educator of the Greeks.” In reading his epics aloud, they would recite the dialogue spoken by the characters in the stories. This is what Plato meant by mimesis. Plato disapproved of mimesis because he feared that in voicing the feelings of Homer’s characters, the prospective Guardians would become infected by various undesirable emotions. For example, in the Iliad, Achilles laments to Odysseus that he is dead and doomed for eternity to dwell in Hades. Plato does not want the Guardians to speak Achilles’ self-pitying lines. For among their future roles, Plato’s Guardians are to be warriors. Consequently, Plato does not want them to become accustomed to self-pitying declarations especially with respect to death for that, Plato worries, would undermine their martial ardor. Plato fears that in reciting speeches that express the fear of death, the Guardians will think that the fear of death is an appropriate emotion and that this will compromise their commitment to dying for their country. Likewise, Plato did not want the Guardians to recite speeches in which the gods express their envy for each other and engage in angry disputes because Plato thought that this would abet in internecine conflict, rivalry, and civil war among the Guardians when they matured and took on their civic responsibilities. Plato feared that if his students spoke the lies of the gods and heroes, like wily Odysseus, they would become liars themselves to the detriment of the commonwealth. In short, Plato felt that the Guardians would identify with the unsavory emotions they encountered in their readers and for that reason he maintained that the poets should be censored. Undoubtedly, Plato’s sentiments continue to influence contemporary thinking about the arts in the form of demands for the regulation and even censorship of violent media. Ironically, however, where contemporary censors worry that the media will encourage aggressive tendencies, Plato feared that certain literature would inhibit the warlike temperament of his Guardians. Nevertheless, despite their different aims, Plato and present-day censors presuppose that the same mechanism is in operation in the process of molding the dispositions of audiences. That mechanism is identification, understood as the taking on by audiences of the self-same emotions as the characters in the stories that they read, hear, or watch because that is what the characters feel. Achilles feels anger toward Agamemnon; we too feel anger. The lovers feel joy when they are reunited in A Midsummer Night’s Dream; and we feel joy because they feel joy. For Plato, identification took place as a result of reading certain emotively charged lines aloud; however, the notion of audience identification still holds sway in the era of silent reading. Indeed, identification is probably the most popular view of our emotional engagement with art today, held by experts and lay folk alike. But, despite its popularity, there are a number of empirical problems with the notion of identification as a general account of our emotional engagement with art and there are also certain logical or conceptual problems with its putative intelligibility. The first empirical problem can be called the emotional asymmetry problem. Quite frequently, our emotions are not the same as those of the characters with whom we are allegedly identifying. As calamity befalls Oedipus in the play of the same name, we feel pity toward him, but he is feeling remorse for killing his father and guilt for having slept with his mother. Similarly, the character in a thriller movie may be heedlessly on her way home, while we are gripped by suspense because we know that kidnappers are lying in wait there to ambush her. So, often our response to the characters in stories diverges from their emotional states because we know more than they do. However, it can also be the case that we know less than
338
Art and emotion
they do and that this too results in our suffering asymmetric emotions. Sherlock Holmes, knowing more than we do, is calm, while we excitedly wonder who has done it. In any event, it should be clear that very often the audience’s emotional state does not match the emotional states of the characters in the stories we consume. Therefore, identification cannot offer a general account of our emotional engagement with narratives or even of pictures of events and states of affairs. Of course, sometimes the character and the audience may be in roughly the same emotional state. As the giant shark crashes into the hero’s boat, the hero is terrified and so am I. Nevertheless, I submit that this is not best explained by means of identification because my state of terror is not the result of my identifying with the emotional state of the hero, but, instead, of my being moved coincidentally by attending to the same frightening stimulus to which the hero is attending. The hero is staring into the shark’s maw and is scared; I too attend to the rows of razor sharp teeth and recoil. But I am not frightened because the hero is frightened. I am frightened because of my own apprehension of the danger in the fictional situation as I consider it imaginatively. There is no need, so to speak, to route my fear through the mental state of the hero. I am frightened as a result of my own attention to the fictional situation. Consequently, even in cases where the character and the audience appear to be in the same emotional state, identification may not be the right explanation. Indeed, it may add an extra step to the process. Thus, once again we see that identification is not a general account of our emotional engagement with art. Call this the problem of coincident emotions. Added to these empirical problems with the notion of identification, there are also conceptual problems. Very often—if not most often—the objects of the emotional states of the characters in fictions are different from the objects of the emotional states of the audience. Emotions have intentionality; they are directed at particular objects, such as fictional characters. We feel pity for Anna Karenina because her husband has forbidden her to visit her son. The object of Anna’s sadness is her separation from her son. Her sadness is directed at her son. But our pity is not directed toward either her son or our own sons. It is directed toward Anna, a woman who has been exiled from her child. The object of the audience’s emotion and the object of the character’s emotional state differ ontologically and, since they are not identical, what is going on in this case cannot be described as identification, even though cases like this are often proposed as evidence of identification. Of course, our pity for Anna’s plight and her sadness have, in a manner of speaking, a similar affective tone. They are both dysphoric emotional states. But they are different dysphoric emotional states. The notion of identification also involves logical problems insofar as it can lead to anomalies. For instance, characters in fictions are often in love. Romeo loves Juliet. If we are identifying with Romeo, then, I suppose, we should also love Juliet. But if that were so, wouldn’t we be jealous of Romeo since Juliet loves him and not me? Yet, does this ever occur and, if it did, wouldn’t we regard any audience member who was jealous of Romeo to be deranged? Surely, what we feel toward Romeo is a species of affectively charged alliance, a pro-attitude which disposes us to desire that Romeo’s desire be fulfilled. When they are not, we feel distress on Romeo’s behalf. But distress is not love, which is what the theory of identification should predict. One last problem with identification is perhaps the most obvious. Identification cannot provide us with a comprehensive account of our emotional involvement with art because a great deal of our emotional involvement with art is aroused by factors that have nothing to do with characters. We are aroused in response to art by such things as depictions of the
339
Noël Carroll
landscape, the atmosphere, the climate, the architecture, the clothing, the flora and fauna of the environment, including the soundscape, and, needless to say, by the artist’s style whether it be her vocabulary and prosody with respect to literature or her orchestration with respect to music. Given the various problems that challenge the theory of identification, an alternative account of the arousal of audience emotion in response to art needs to be explored. The most developed alternative in this regard can be called “the theory of criterial prefocusing” (Carroll 2001). The theory of criterial prefocusing presupposes that the emotions are processes that involve mental states that cause internal bodily states of the sorts that typically predispose certain behavioral inclinations to act. In particular, the emotions comprise evaluative mental states that appraise our circumstances in light of whether those circumstances are likely to advance or imperil our vital interests. Fear assesses a present situation as dangerous, that alerts us in a bodily fashion by quickening our pulse physiologically and/or sending a chill down our spine phenomenologically. And once this bodily alarm is sounded, we ready ourselves to flee, freeze, or fight. The emotions are psychophysical mechanisms that we use to assimilate our environment. They are fast mechanisms for sizing up the situation—fast, that is, in comparison with deliberation and reasoning. In the current psychological and philosophical literatures, there is some debate about whether our emotive appraisals are cognitive (Lyons 1980) versus thoroughly affective (Robinson 2005). This is sometimes framed as a matter of whether the emotions can be initiated in the frontal cortex or whether they are primarily an affair of the amygdala. I believe that the emotions can be caused cognitively even if usually they are more often than not more perception-like, immediate non-cognitive reactions. With regard to the arts, some emotional responses are more cognitively laden as in the case of literature, which must not only be read, but which must be processed imaginatively and understood. On the other hand, being comically amused by a grotesque caricature may involve a much more perception-like, immediate response. However, with respect to the theory of criterial prefocusing, the debate over whether emotive appraisals are primarily cognitive or affective is less important than the fact that they are appraisals—appraisals of the environment in light of our vital interests. An offer of food when we are hungry is appraised as a contribution to our well-being and is greeted with a feeling of gratitude. The approach of an angry, large dog is assessed as dangerous and engenders fear. The emotions are selective—they organize the environment in light of what will help or hinder us. They appraise our surroundings or elements thereof either positively or negatively. Moreover, insofar as they are evaluative, they are governed by criteria. They size up situations against certain standards of evaluation. Anger appraises circumstances as unjust; fear assesses situations as dangerous. In other words, the emotions have criteria of appropriateness (see also Chapter 24 in this volume). To be the particular object of an emotional state, the object must meet the criterion of that state. To be the object of my envy, for example, another person must be perceived to possess something that I lack—for example, a bigger bank account. In everyday life, the emotions function like searchlights, scanning the surround in order to select features of the situation that will advance or setback our interests and when the emotions appraise items one way or the other, they rivet our attention on the relevant features of our circumstances. The emotions focus our attention, directing us to what we are to attend to in our environment and to how we are to evaluate it. And once the emotions 340
Art and emotion
fix our attention on the particular object that has excited our affective state, the presiding emotion surveys the scene for other elements that may be pertinent to that state. Awakened by a loud noise downstairs, our fear encourages us to search for further possible signs of the presence of intruders. However, our emotions are engaged very differently when it comes to the arts. With respect to the arts, the artwork itself has already been structured in such a way that pertinent emotional features in the scene have already been foregrounded or made salient. For example, in a novel, certain emotional themes—such as danger or injustice—have been made to stand out. Or, in a painting, the poverty of its subjects is emphasized in order to elicit sympathy. With representational artworks, the artist literally controls our attention insofar as we can only attend to what she chooses to describe, or depict, or imply, and furthermore, we can only attend to that in light of how she has described or depicted them. So, whereas in our everyday experiences, our emotions filter situations for us, in art, scenes and sequences have been pre-digested or pre-filtered for us by the work of the artist. The artist structures the artwork in such a way that it guides our attention almost irresistibly to the elements of the scene that call for the emotional response that the artist has already cued by selecting and making prominent an object appropriate to the emotional response the artist intends to elicit. Imagine that you are making a horror film about rampaging zombies. You will design the zombies’ make-up with an eye toward provoking certain preordained affective responses by bringing to the viewer’s attention features of the relevant characters that are criterially appropriate to the desired emotional state. Where the characters are zombies, you will depict their suppurating bodies in terms of decay and incompleteness in order to arouse disgust in the viewers by focusing their attention unavoidably upon these features, thereby securing a central component of the emotion of horror, namely disgust. The process just outlined is criterial prefocusing. It is a process of prefocusing, since the relevant characters have been artfully articulated by prominently emphasizing certain aspects of the characters that are pertinent to the emotion the moviemaker intends to arouse. This prefocusing, in turn, is criterial because the objects, events, and characters and their properties that have been selected and made salient for attention are those that are appropriate to the intended emotion. That is, the features foregrounded satisfy the criteria of appraisal appropriate to that emotion-type. In our example of the zombie movie, the themes of impurity and incompleteness meet the criteria for assessing a human body as disgusting. Thus, in order to arouse the feeling of disgust in the viewer, the film director will depict the sequences of relentlessly encroaching zombie bodies as impure and incomplete in a way that viewers cannot avoid seeing save by closing their eyes or leaving the theater. Likewise, suspense is an emotion that involves presenting a situation in which an unwanted outcome seems likely to obtain—for example, that a progressively lowering, axpendulum seems destined slice its bound victim below in half. In order to arouse suspense, an author must criterially prefocus the helplessness of the victim and the implacability of the descending mechanism. With respect to painting, if the artist wishes to arouse the feeling of sublimity in the spectator, she should criterially prefocus aspects of immense scale and limitlessness in the pictorial array. Much music is accompanied by songs where the lyrics criterially prefocus the elements pertinent to the presiding emotion. Absolute or pure music—pure orchestral music—raises some theoretical problems for theories of the arousal of the common emotions in the arts since music without words or a 341
Noël Carroll
program does not appear to refer to the kinds of persons, events, states of affairs, and places that arouse to the common emotions. This is an issue to which we will return in the last section of this article on the projection of expressive properties. Nevertheless, with the exception of the controversial case of music without words or program, the theory of criterial prefocusing provides a serviceable general theory for the discussion of the arousal of the common, everyday, or “garden variety” emotions in (most) of the arts.
2. The arousal of art-specific emotions So far, we have been discussing the arousal of common emotions—such as sorrow, pity, fear, joy, etc.—by artworks. However, some philosophers of art have denied the relevance of such emotions to the proper appreciation of art and have instead maintained that there is a specific emotion, an aesthetic emotion, that all authentic art aims to arouse. Perhaps the most influential proponent of this view was Clive Bell in his book Art (1914). In Art, Bell explicitly associates the arousal of the aesthetic emotion with the essence of art, properly so called. Bell’s avowed purpose in Art is to define art. He identifies the defining characteristic of art as a significant form. Here, it is important to emphasize that Bell is talking specifically about fine art—pictorial and sculptural art. With respect to the visual arts, he characterizes significant form as an arrangement of lines, colors, spaces, and vectors. Of course, these seem to be features of visual form simpliciter. The question is: What makes these formal properties “significant?” For, without that, any visual array, including a monkey’s finger painting, would count as art, properly so called. This is where Bell’s notion of the aesthetic emotion enters the discussion. Significant form, he contends, is precisely that which arouses the aesthetic emotion in everyone who knows about art, that is, in suitably prepared and informed subjects. What exactly does this putative emotion involve? Aesthetic exaltation. It is an experience of being transported from the world of practical activity and human concerns where the expectations and worries of our mundane existence are suspended and we transcend the stream of everyday life. We are, so to speak, lifted above it. Thus, aesthetic emotion is, by definition, distinct from the common emotions since the common emotions are those that shape everyday life, the very thing from which aesthetic emotion is said to afford escape. Moreover, for the same reason, aesthetic emotion can distinguish the artwork from mere ordinary objects since mere ordinary objects are intended to serve the purposes of everyday life. So, form is significant if it arouses aesthetic emotion and, therefore, aesthetic emotion singles out art, properly so called. Of course, Bell is aware that much art, in virtue of being representational, has been known to arouse the common emotions. Pietas arouse feelings of sorrow among the faithful as they gaze upon their dying savior in the lap of his loving mother. However, Bell argues that it is not the right sort of response that the suitably prepared spectator should mobilize. Why not? A representational artwork involves form and content. A painting of a crucifixion, for example, may portray the execution of Christ on the cross with various onlookers assembled around it. The content of the painting is the dying Jesus and his family and followers, gathered at the foot of the cross. The visual form of the painting, in contrast, comprises a vertical division running down the center of the painting with shapes of contrasting masses of color balanced to either side of the cross. The cast of the painting refers to something outside the painting itself—to Jesus, his family, his friends, and followers on the promontory Golgotha. These are things in the world—or, at least, the historical world. They are not inside the painting. Shapes, colors, masses, lines, and so on are what is literally in the painting. 342
Art and emotion
Emotions, as we’ve seen, are directed. When we feel sad standing before the picture of the crucifixion, our emotional response is directed to something outside the painting—to the historical event of the death of Jesus. Bell regards all of the common emotions aroused by the representational content of the painting as directed to events and states of affairs outside the painting to be merely suggested emotions. Moreover, to indulge in the emotions suggested by the painting is to direct your attention inappropriately. Why? Isn’t it obvious that to appreciate the painting, our attention should be directed at the painting itself—at what is inside it and not at something outside it, like events represented by the picture? But what is inside it? Lines, colors, spaces, spaces, masses, perceptual vectors, and so forth. How will you know if those forms are significant forms? If they arouse the aesthetic emotion—if they lift you out of the flow of life which is dominated by the common (also known as suggested) emotions. To appreciate a painting as a painting—as a work of art—you should attend to the painting, not to the events and states of affairs outside the painting that the painting represents. Attend to the painting itself, which is literally an affair of visual forms. If those forms are arranged significantly, they will arouse the aesthetic emotion where the appropriate object of the aesthetic emotion is the form of the painting. Given his emphasis on form, it should come as no surprise that Bell’s view is called “formalism.” Although he committed himself to this view with emphasis on the visual arts, it has been extended to other arts in directions sometimes suggested by Bell himself. In many ways, Bell’s approach seems very empirical. If you want to discover whether or not a particular painting is a work of art, properly so called, see if it possesses significant form. And if you want to see if it possesses significant form, expose suitably informed and prepared spectators to it. If they suffer aesthetic emotion, the painting is a work of art; if they do not, it is not an artwork. Not all paintings are works of art. Presumably, Hitler’s weren’t. Bell can explain to us why they are not for what appear to be empirical reasons. There are many problems with Bell’s theory of art. One especially glaring is that it makes no provision for bad art insofar everything that is art, by definition, possesses some measure of significant form, which is, one assumes a good-bestowing property. Therefore, every work of art, properly so called, possesses some good. This, of course, is stupendously improbable, since we have all experienced bad art—indeed, lots of it. Another problem with Bell’s account concerns his supposed method. It appears very scientific. He gives the impression that he is doing something like discovering what causes sweetness. With sweetness, we start with certain responses in subjects—that such and such tastes sweet—and then we go on to isolate the molecular structure common to all the things that arouse the sensations of sweetness in our subjects. Putatively, we do the same thing with regard to art. We expose suitably informed and prepared subjects to an array of visual designs and discover which ones cause the aesthetic emotion. Then, we investigate those, searching for what feature or features they all share. And voilà—significant form. But is this analogy convincing? We can characterize the molecular structure of sweetness independently of referring to the sensation of sweetness. And we can use that way of identifying the pertinent molecular structure to test our hypothesis about that which gives rise to the sensation of sweetness by exposing people to that very molecular structure and seeing whether our subjects say that it’s sweet. But you can’t do the same thing with significant form. Why not? Because significant form, unlike the molecular structure that gives rise to sweetness, is not independently specifiable apart from the so-called aesthetic emotion. About all we know of significant form is that it arouses the aesthetic emotion, or, correlatively, that it is the object of the aesthetic emotion. 343
Noël Carroll
Thus, we have no way of running a test to determine whether significant form systemically arouses the aesthetic emotion, since we have no way of independently identifying significant form apart from the provocation of the aesthetic emotion. Put technically, we have no independent variable to manipulate. Likewise, we confront a comparable problem with the aesthetic emotion. We have no way to identify the aesthetic emotion except to say that it is aroused by significant form. But this is tantamount to saying that the aesthetic emotion is caused by the aesthetic emotion, which is both uninformative and circular. Bell might object that he has told us something about the nature of the aesthetic emotion, viz., that it is a form of exaltation or ecstasy. But this is not sufficient to differentiate aesthetic emotions from other forms of exaltation and ecstasy. There are also religious forms of exaltation and ecstasy, which are also said to release us from everyday earthly concerns. Suppose I am standing before a painting of the Madonna and Child and I feel ecstasy, a sensation of freedom from the quotidian and an intimation of the transcendental. How will Bell discriminate that experience of deeply reverential emotion from an experience of the aesthetic emotion? Undoubtedly, he will say that it is not directed at significant form. But that puts it back on the circle again. Moreover, Bell’s argument presupposes that what is “inside” an artwork is just its formal elements. He never argues for this claim, but simply presumes it. Surely, the image of the Madonna is in the painting and, furthermore, it would appear to be an appropriate prompt for the emotion of reverence. Can Bell show this is an inadmissible way of speaking without begging the question again? Bell’s is probably the most influential defense of the idea that there is an art-specific emotion—a distinctive emotion that art and only art proper arouses. However, the problems with this view are pressing enough that the more frequent position—that art arouses a multitude of common emotions—seems much more attractive.
3. Art as the expression of the emotions So far, we have been discussing the arousal of emotion by works of art which has led us to focus on the effect of artworks upon their audiences. But what of the relation of the emotional states of the artists to the artworks that they create? Here, the relevant idea is not arousal but expression. That is, the artist is said to express her feelings, emotions, moods, and other affective states by means of her artwork. For some philosophers of art, like R. G. Collingwood (1938), expression is the essential defining characteristic of art. Indeed, for Collingwood, the arousal of emotion in an audience is the mark of craft, not art. Collingwood maintains that insofar as emotions can be aroused by means of certain techniques, as we have seen in terms of criterial prefocusing (a notion Collingwood does not use), it is more like pharmacology than art. It is a matter of finding the most efficient means to the designated end (such as arousing pity and fear). Expression, on the other hand, is not aimed at securing a preordained emotional end by means of tried-and-true techniques. It is involved with the artist’s exploration of her feelings for the purpose of clarifying them. Typically, an artist begins a work—a poem, a song, or a painting—with an insistent, but nevertheless vague feeling. She tries to bring this feeling into sharp relief. She works on it, bringing it into sharper focus. Partly, she does this by eternalizing it—by experimenting with different ways of expressing it. A dancer will combine several steps and phrases; a painter by trying several brushstrokes, erasing some, expanding upon others; a composer by playing with alternative notes and chords. At various points, the artist stands back from her work and surveys it, inquiring whether her choices are “right”—where “right” means “do they 344
Art and emotion
feel right?” or “do they get the emotion right?” This process clarifies the emotion for the artist at the same time that the initially vague feeling inspires and informs the artist’s choices. The artist does not start out with an agenda—to arouse fear. The artist aspires to discover precisely what she is feeling in the process of producing her artwork. She does not know what she feels until she is satisfied that she has captured it. And the feeling she articulates may not be one that we antecedently have a name for. In this way, artworks can give us a handle on heretofore unrecognized feelings as the label “Kaf kaesque” gives a symbol or marker with which to recognize many of our affective experiences when dealing with modern bureaucracies. In making an artwork, the artist is working through an emotion by striving to articulate it in her medium. The artist is doing what we all do when we ask ourselves what we really feel about something. The first few sentences that we utter may be vague and fragmentary. But we keep revising them, striving to be more accurate and exact. Similarly, a painter is working through the same process, only she is using lines, shapes, colors, and images rather than words. What color is my emotion? Is it jagged or smooth? She tries one line and then shortens it. The painting is under the controlled guidance of the emotion, but as the picture acquires more detail and definition, so does the emotion. The painting as a process of successive choices is a way of clarifying the emotion—a way of clarifying what the artist is feeling. Undoubtedly, Collingwood’s account of expression accurately describes the process of many artists. But it is overly ambitious in several respects. It does not characterize all art since some art is not devoted to expression but may be predominantly cognitive, plumbing the very nature of art itself, while other acknowledged artistic masterpieces, such as the Greek tragedies, may be dedicated to the arousal of emotions, and yet other artworks may not traffic in expression, truth, or the arousal of emotion, but in formal invention. Furthermore, Collingwood’s conception of expression presupposes that the artist must actually be undergoing some affective state, whereas it seems eminently possible that a composer may write a requiem expressive of sadness without being sad herself. That is, she may be projecting the expressive property of sadness without being in that state, the sadness instead being a property of the music.
4. The projection of expressive properties Artworks have expressive properties. That is, they may have various affective, anthropomorphic properties attributed to them. But these attributions need not presuppose that the creator was in the affective state signaled by the property in question. For example, one can imagine a thoroughgoing atheist composer being commissioned to write a religious hymn that is highly reverential in tone without the composer feeling reverential. Rather, she may know how to combine musical structures in a way that projects reverence. Similarly, a motion picture cinematographer knows how to light a scene so that it appears menacing, without having to feel menaced herself. In other words, we often discern properties in artworks where we are not tempted to connect them to an underlying psychological state attributable to either the artist or to the work itself. Yet, this should not seem strange. After all, we do it with objects in nature frequently. Certain willow trees are said to weep, but we do not believe that the willow trees are sad. Instead, we call the willow trees sad because in virtue of its configuration, it reminds us of the prototypical aspects of sad people who in their misery are bent over, and their shoulders hunched. Likewise, the tumultuous background of an expressionist painting may suggest to us configurationally the unsettled thought and chaotic movement of an anxious person. 345
Noël Carroll
How artists’ configurations manage to project expressive properties not necessarily connected to the psychological states of their creators is an important question to which various answers have been offered. Nelson Goodman (1968) proposes that it is accomplished by means of complex systems of analogy and homology resulting in metaphorical exemplification; Peter Kivy thinks that it is a matter the imitation of (human) behavioral configurations (sad music is slow because sad people typically move slowly); others cite cultural and linguistic associations and conventions; and some say: all of the above (Carroll 1999). Although the projection of expressive properties occurs across the arts, it provides an especially useful clue for solving the problem of the relation of the emotions to pure orchestral music. That is, since pure orchestral music lacks reference to characters, actions, and events, it would appear incapable of arousing common emotions like anger and grief. Nevertheless, pure orchestral music clearly seems to have a relation to such emotions. What could it be? Perhaps that is projects’ expressive properties (Kivy 1984). Of course, the projection of expressive properties figures in all of the arts. The enveloping columns fronting St. Peter’s Basilica in Rome are inviting; the towers of Gothic churches are aspiring; the French horns in Handel’s Water Music are jaunty; the plot structures of many comedies are antic; and so on. Through the projection of expressive qualities, artworks of all sorts are suffused with emotion.
References Bell, Clive (1958[1914]). Art. New York: Capricorn Books. Bharata (1987). The Natya Shastra of Bharata Muni. Delhi: Sri Satguru. Carroll, Noël (1999). Philosophy of Art: A Contemporary Introduction. London, New York: Routledge. ——— (2001). Art, Narrative and Emotion. In: N. Carroll: Beyond Aesthetics. Philosophical Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Collingwood, R. G. (1938). Principles of Art. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dubos, Jean-Baptiste (1748). Critical Reflections on Poetry, Painting and Music. Transl. by T. Nugent. 3 vols. London: John Nourse. Goodman, Nelson (1968). Languages of Art. An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company. Kivy, Peter (1984). Sound Sentiment. An Essay on the Musical Emotions. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Lyons, William (1980). Emotion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Plato (1961). The Collected Works of Plato. Ed. by E. Hamilton and H. Cairns. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Robinson, Jenefer (2005). Deeper than Reason. Emotion and Its Role in Literature, Music, and Art. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
346
PART 3
Self-directed and individual emotions
.
(
Taylor & Francis Taylor & Francis Group
http://taylorandfrancis.com
30 SHAME Dan Zahavi
It is not by chance that shame has received quite some attention from phenomenological philosophers over the years. As an analysis of the emotion reveals, shame involves and affects several dimensions of enduring interest to phenomenologists, including embodiment, temporality, sociality, and self-consciousness. Sartre’s L’Être et le Néant from 1943 contains the most well-known phenomenological treatment of shame, but other important analyses can be found in a long essay by Scheler entitled Über Scham und Schamgefühl from 1913, in a short but suggestive text by Straus from 1933 entitled “Die Scham als historiologisches Problem”, and in several texts by Levinas including De L’Évasion from 1935 and Totalité et Infini from 1961. In the following, I will not discuss the contribution of each of these authors one by one, but rather reference them in the course of a more systematically oriented discussion.1
1. Shame and related emotions What is shame? One initial challenge is to clarify how shame differs from other related emotions. As Miller rightly points out, it would be a mistake to approach shame as if it is a clearly demarcated and well-bounded type of experience. The distinction between shame and embarrassment is not as neat as the difference between a lamp and a table (Miller 1985, 28). Shame belongs to a family of interrelated emotion, and it is not difficult to come up with scenarios where the demarcations get fuzzy, and where different individuals might react differently. Consider, however, the following four cases:
349
Dan Zahavi
350
Shame
The moment the humiliated person will start to blame himself for his humiliation, shame will follow. To sum up, shame is a distressing emotion, where we feel faulty and unworthy, defective, exposed, and vulnerable. Whereas we in guilt are concerned with our actions or omissions, with having breached a norm or inflicted harm upon another, the focus of shame is on our very being, on who we are. Although one can be ashamed of moral infractions, one can certainly also be ashamed of things that have nothing to do with the moral domain. Indeed, shame does not have to be brought about by something one wilfully does. One can feel ashamed of a physical disability, of one’s parentage, or of skin colour, etc. To be sure, my interpretation of these cases is open to dispute. Some might claim that the scene with the bullies is more likely to result in shame, or that the scene with the friend will only give rise to embarrassment. I think this is quite correct. Different people can indeed react to the same event with humiliation, shame, or embarrassment. To that extent, there is no clear correlation between specific scenarios or events and the occurrence of specific emotions, and one cannot define the latter in terms of the former. However, the purpose of the four examples was simply to single out some distinctive features of shame, features that makes it different from embarrassment, humiliation, and guilt. Let me in the following explore these features further, and examine how a variety of experiential dimensions is affected in shame.
2. Shame and self-consciousness As we have seen, shame is generally considered a self-involving and self-directed emotion. I am ashamed of who and what I am. Obviously, the trigger might be a specific property or trait of mine, I might feel ashamed because of my weight, my speech defect, my lack of courage, my salary level, my dishonesty, etc., but importantly when feeling ashamed, I am never simply ashamed of that specific property. Rather, the property in question is taken to reveal something more fundamental about who I am, is taken to disclose a central flaw in my very being. The experience of shame is consequently an experience of self. It is somewhat more controversial what kind of self-experience shame is. Is it a reflective form of self-consciousness? Is shame primarily a question of reflectively sitting in judgment on oneself, is it a critical self-evaluation? For Sartre, shame is not primarily and originally a phenomenon of reflection. I can reflect upon my failings and feel shame as a result, just as I might reflect upon my feeling of shame, but I can also feel shame prior to engaging in any kind of reflection. Shame is initially, as he puts it, “an immediate shudder which runs through me from head to foot without any discursive preparation” (Sartre 1943, 246). Shame is not something we control, but something that overwhelms us. As Sartre is quick to point out, however, there is something special about shame. It does not simply amount to an ordinary form of pre-reflective self-consciousness. Rather, in addition to reflective and pre-reflective self-consciousness, we ought to recognize the existence of a third type of self-consciousness that is intersubjectively mediated, i.e., one that has the other as its condition of possibility. Sartre consequently argues that shame in its primary form is a feeling that I cannot elicit on my own, but that shame is shame of oneself before the other: [A]lthough certain complex forms derived from shame can appear on the reflective plane, shame is not originally a phenomenon of reflection. In fact no matter what results one can obtain in solitude by the religious practice of shame, it is in its primary structure shame before somebody. (Sartre 1943, 245) 351
Dan Zahavi
Thus, although shame exemplifies a self-relation, we are on Sartre’s account dealing with an essentially mediated form of self-relation, one where the other is the mediator between me and myself. Shame presupposes the intervention of the other, and not simply because the other is the one before whom I feel ashamed, but also and more significantly because that of which I am ashamed is only constituted in and through my encounter with the other (Sartre 1943, 246). To put it differently, rather than primarily being a self-reflective emotion involving negative self-evaluation, shame is for Sartre an emotion that reveals our being-for-others. Shame is relational. It reveals to me that I am (partially) constituted by others, that I depend upon others, and that I have my foundation outside myself. For Sartre, shame is consequently both a self-conscious emotion and a social emotion. To use a term coined by Reddy, one might talk of shame as a self-other-conscious emotion, since it makes us aware of our relational being, it concerns the self-in-relation-to-the-other (Reddy 2008). This is one of the areas where Sartre’s and Scheler’s analyses diverge. Scheler accepts the idea that shame is an emotion that essentially involves the self, but he explicitly rejects the claim that shame is essentially a social emotion, one that by necessity involves others. For Scheler, there are self-directed forms of shame that are just as fundamental as the shame one can feel in the presence of others, and, more generally speaking, Scheler argues that shame is an emotional response to the uncovering and display of our weaknesses, defects, and imperfections. In its core, shame concerns the tension between our aspirations and ideals on the one hand and our awareness of our finitude, vulnerability, and bodily needs on the other (Scheler 1913, 5, 15). This is also why Scheler claims that shame is a distinctly human emotion, one that neither God nor animals could have (Scheler 1913, 3, 28).
3. Shame and the body The behavioural manifestations of shame typically include averted gaze, slumped posture, and downward head movement. The fact that shame is also characterized by a heightened feeling of exposure and vulnerability, by a wish to hide, to become invisible, and to sink into the ground, should alert us to the fact that the body plays a significant role in the emotion. This is highlighted in Sartre’s analysis, since he speaks of how shame reveals to me that I am visible to others. Rather than simply existing bodily, rather than simply being absorbed in various projects, rather than simply interacting confidently with the environment, shame makes me painfully aware of my bodily facticity and exposure, and effects something akin to a bodily paralysis. Sartre speaks of the existential alienation occasioned by my encounter with the gaze of the other. To apprehend myself from the perspective of the other is to apprehend myself as seen in the midst of the world, as a thing among things with properties and determinations that I am without having chosen them. The gaze of the other confers a truth upon me that I do not master, and over which I am—in that moment—powerless (Sartre 1943, 260). For Sartre, the body symbolizes our defenceless state as objects and he claims that the fear of being surprised in a state of nakedness is a symbolic manifestation of original shame. To put on clothes is to attempt to hide one’s object-state; it is to claim the right of seeing without being seen; that is, to be a pure subject (Sartre 1943, 312). Scheler, as well, comments on the fact that nakedness has traditionally been associated with shame. For him, however, the reason why we seek to cover our body is precisely because it reminds us of our animality, mortality, and neediness (Scheler 1913, 11). Consider how the loss of control over one’s bodily functions, as in sickness or old age, might be felt as shameful, just as it might be shame-inducing to realize that one is being observed while vomiting or defecating. 352
Shame
4. Shame and time We have seen that guilt is typically accompanied by a wish to repent, to repair the harm, and to make it up to the other. In all these cases, there is a future-directed dimension to guilt. In the case of humiliation, as well, the desire for revenge will make the emotion future-oriented. What about shame? Some further distinctions are in order. Sometimes people distinguish what is called prospective shame from retrospective shame. As an instance of the former, consider the case of a teenager who spends hours on end trying out different clothes in preparation for the school party. The one thing he desires is the approval of others, the one thing he fears is their ridicule. Prospective shame is clearly forward-looking, but rather than being a case of shame proper, it might be better characterized as a fear of shameful situations. Prospective shame can consequently function as significant restrictive force. If I do not do anything—if I stay away from the party—I do not risk potential shameful exposure. Retrospective shame, by contrast, can either take the form of a repeated return to and rumination over a past shame or as the subsequent realization that a past situation or action was indeed shameful. In either case, the retrospective shame is past-oriented and might well be accompanied by a feeling of remorse. In both cases, however, and more so in the former than in the latter, one will have the benefit of a temporal distance to the actual event; a temporal distance that everything else being equal will lessen the force of the emotion. Prospective and retrospective shame must consequently be distinguished from the acute shame best characterized in terms of what Karlsson and Sjöberg have called a “frozen now” (2009, 353). When caught in the spotlight of the other’s unsparing glance, it is not only as if the moment seems to drag on and on, but that experience of shame also disrupts the normal temporal flow. As Sartre writes, in shame I experience myself as trapped in facticity, as being irremediably what I am (rather than as someone with future possibilities, as someone who can become otherwise) (Sartre 1943, 286, 312). The shamed subject is fixed in the present to such an extent that an open future is lost. When shame overwhelms you, you are reduced to your flaw and there is no room for the exploration of future possibilities of redemption.
5. Shame and others What is the role of others? Despite their differences, both Sartre and Scheler agree that one can feel ashamed when one is de facto alone. However, they interpret this possibility differently. For Sartre, this fact, in and of itself, does not prove that the relation to others is inessential for shame, and that one can simply ignore the social dimension when analysing the emotion. The evaluating perspective of others might play a role in the structure of the emotion even when they are not factually present. On his account, there are certain preconditions that must be met if reflective shame is to be possible. It is a latecomer, and a more paradigmatic and more fundamental form of shame is the one we feel when confronted with the objectifying gaze of others. It is only because of a subsequent internalization of the other’s perspective that the kind of critical self-evaluation that we find in intrapersonal reflective shame becomes possible. And the latter will never have the same force as the former. In his analysis, Sartre highlights the impact of the gaze. However, the nature of the look can vary enormously. As Straus observes, the look of the voyeur is as different from the looks exchanged by lovers as the medical palpation is from the gentle caress (Straus 1966, 219). More importantly, however, shame can be triggered not only by the look of others but also by their wilful overlooking. The fact that we can feel ashamed because we are overlooked and ignored by others is revealing. In psychoanalytic theorizing, it has been proposed that 353
Dan Zahavi
shame is an emotional reaction to the absence of approval (Ikonen and Rechardt 1993, 100). If this were correct, it would situate shame right at the core of our interpersonal life. In its most fundamental form, it would not be connected to a breach of specific cultural norms or standards, but rather concern our fundamental need for recognition. When the latter is being withheld, we might feel shame. If so, this would also suggest a possible remedy for more enduring forms of shame, namely love.2 But why is the contempt of the other, her disrespect, met with shame? If one found the assessment of the other completely unwarranted, it would not result in shame, but more likely in indignation or indifference. To react with shame when confronted with the other’s evaluation is consequently, as Sartre points out, to accept that evaluation (Sartre 1943, 246, 287, 290). That which is revealed in shame, although highly undesirable, is precisely experienced as disclosing the truth about oneself (Karlsson and Sjöberg 2009, 350). Perhaps more distinctions are in order, however. Does the identity of the other not make a difference? Aristotle once observed that the people we feel shame before are those whose opinion of us matters to us (Aristotle 1984, 1384a25). To have one’s frailties exposed to one’s beloved is quite different from having them exposed to people in whose presence one does not feel secure or loved. Not only might it make a difference whether the witness is a close family member, somebody who is part of your social network, or a total stranger (especially if the person in question does not know who you are either), but hierarchy and social status can also play a role (Landweer 1999). A sub-par performance in public will be experienced as more shameful if noticed by somebody with more rather than less status and authority than you. Compare, for instance, the situation where a flutist makes mistakes when practicing a piece alone, with the situation where she makes mistakes at a public recital with the composer in attendance. An account of shame should be able to explain why mistakes that are tolerated in privacy as minor shortcomings might be felt as shameful the moment they are publicly exposed. The case of vicarious shame provides further reason to question the proposal that others are accidental to shame, and play no significant role in its structure. It is no coincidence that the Oxford English Dictionary in its definition of shame includes a reference to situations, where shame arises from the consciousness of something dishonouring, ridiculous, or indecorous in the conduct of those whose honour or disgrace one regards as one’s own. Consider the two following examples:
In both cases, you are unlikely to remain emotionally unaffected. Again, people might react differently, but in some cases, I would venture, shame would occur.3 The interesting question, though, is why? If shame is a self-conscious emotion, if shame concerns your own identity, 354
Shame
why then feel ashamed in situations like these. The key, I believe, lies in the relationship between yourself and the one who is behaving indecorous or who is subjected to a denigrating criticism. Had the latter been a stranger, it is unlikely that you would have felt ashamed. For us to react with shame in the two situations described above presupposes that processes of group-identification are in place, and that we consider, say, our relationship to our parents (partially) constitutive of our own identity, constitutive of who we are (see Salice and Montes Sánchez 2016; see also Chapter 39 in this volume). Obviously, such identifications are not restricted to family members alone, which is also why, when travelling abroad, some might feel ashamed when witnessing the misbehaviour of compatriots. We are not only individuals, possessors of singular identities, but also group members, shareholders in collective identities.
6. The moral value of shame How should one assess the role of shame? Is it, as Tangney and Dearing have argued “an extremely painful and ugly feeling that has a negative impact on interpersonal behaviour” (2002, 3)? Is it a destructive and repressive emotion, one we should aim to remove from our lives? One line of thinking taken to support such a view is the following. When you feel guilty, you wish to undo the deed and you seek to redress the harm. You seek the forgiveness of the other and attempt to repair and re-establish the social bond. To that extent, the feeling of guilt serves a pro-social purpose. Shame by contrast is isolating. You withdraw from others and are consumed by a self-loathing with no obvious social benefits that can ultimately lead to suicide (see Lester 1997). One indication that this depiction is highly incomplete, however, can be found if we for a moment return to the Oxford English Dictionary (OED). Among the various meanings of the term, the OED distinguishes the painful emotion arising from the consciousness of something dishonouring or disgraceful in one’s own conduct from the sense of shame, i.e., the perception of what is improper or disgraceful. Why should the latter be something we would want to eliminate? Indeed, as the notion of shamelessness suggests, it is not the presence, but the absence of shame that is shameful. The incapacity to be ashamed of anything is not a moral virtue, but a moral flaw, a sign of degradation. Similar considerations can be found in the writings of the phenomenologists. Scheler explicitly considers a capacity for shame ethically valuable and links it to the emergence of conscience—it is, as he points out, no coincidence that Genesis explicitly relates shame to knowledge of good and evil (Scheler 1913, 79). Scheler also emphasizes the extent to which our feeling of shame, even if it involves a decrease of self-esteem, testifies to the continuing presence of a certain amount of self-respect; it is only because one expects oneself to have worth that this expectation can be disappointed and give rise to shame (Scheler 1913, 79). Indeed, as Scheler points out, the shame reaction must be seen in the light of a persisting normative commitment (Scheler 1913, 37). The feeling of shame occurs precisely because of a discrepancy between values one continues to endorse and the actual situation. Some have also claimed that shame, rather than being inherently debilitating, might play a constructive role in moral development. In Totalité et infini Levinas argues that shame is a response to the ethical encounter with the other who interrupts and disrupts my tranquillity by putting me and my unjustified and arbitrary freedom into question (1979, 83–84). More generally speaking, the experience of shame might function as a wake-up call. It can disrupt my self-complacency, modify my self-understanding, and in the end, motivate me to reorient my way of living (Steinbock 2014). For a concrete example, consider a case reported by Hutchinson. It concerns Léopard, who committed atrocities during the Rwanda genocide. Several years later, Léopard is interviewed while in prison, and he recounts how he has 355
Dan Zahavi
subsequently come to feel deep shame and how this has resulted in him being ostracized by his former comrades (Hutchinson 2008, 141–143). It is, however, again important not to overlook differences. There is more than one type of shame. In his work, Straus discusses a kind of protective shame, which involves sensitivity to and respect for boundaries of intimacy (Straus 1966, 220), and which manifests our need to protect the most private and intimate aspects of our existence from public exposure and scrutiny. Likewise, in the literature, one can find distinctions between disgrace-shame and discretion-shame, natural shame and moral shame, and bodily shame and spiritual shame, to mention just a few of the available candidates (Ausubel 1955, 382; Smith et al. 2002, 157; Gilbert 2003, 1215; Bollnow 2009, 55–57). Even if there is something valuable in the type of shame discussed by Straus, it is hard to see anything positive in the so-called chronic and toxic shame felt by some sexually abused children (Zupancic and Kreidler 1999; see also Chapter 27 in this volume).
7. Conclusion As I have suggested above, shame testifies to our exposure, vulnerability, and visibility and is importantly linked to such issues as concealment and disclosure, sociality and alienation, and difference and connectedness. Shame is a self-involving emotion, one that points to the embodied and normatively embedded nature of the self. Shame is a more complex emotion than say anger, fear, or joy, and there are limits to how far a purely philosophical analysis can progress. A more comprehensive understanding of shame would also require extensive analyses of, for instance, its developmental trajectory (how early does it emerge, how much does infantile shame—if it exists—resemble adult shame, what role does it play in adolescence, and so on), and cultural specificity (to what extent do the shame-inducing situations, the very experience of shame and the available coping strategies vary from culture to culture) (see Cole et al. 2006). Shame can be a very painful experience, but it is by no means obvious that we should regret being able to feel it and strive to remove it from our lives. As Scheler wrote, shame is a fundamental human emotion, one characterizing conditio humana (Scheler 1913, 3, 28).4
Notes
References Aristotle (1984[c.340 BCE]). Rhetoric. In: The Complete Works of Aristotle II. Ed. by J. Barnes. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Ausubel, David P. (1955). Relationships between Shame and Guilt in the Socializing Process. Psychological Review 62(5), 378–390.
356
Shame Bollnow, Otto F. (2009[1947]). Die Ehrfurcht: Wesen und Wandel der Tugenden. Würzburg: Königshausen und Neumann. Cole, Pamela M., Tamang, Babu L., and Shrestha, Srijana. (2006). Cultural Variations in the Socialization of Young Children’s Anger and Shame. Child Development 77(5), 1237–1251. Darwall, Stephen L. (1977). Two Kinds of Respect. Ethics 88(1), 36–49. Gilbert, Paul (2003). Evolution, Social Roles, and the Differences in Shame and Guilt. Social Research 70(4), 1205–1230. Honneth, Axel (1995). The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts, Transl. by J. Anderson. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hutchinson, Phil (2008). Shame and Philosophy: An Investigation in the Philosophy of Emotions and Ethics. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Ikonen, Pentti, and Rechardt, Eero. (1993). The Origin of Shame and its Vicissitudes. Scandinavian Psychoanalytic Review 16(2), 100–124. Karlsson, Gunnar, and Sjöberg, Lennart G. (2009). The Experiences of Guilt and Shame: A Phenomenological–Psychological Study. Human Studies 32(3), 335–355. Landweer, Hilge (1999). Scham und Macht: Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Sozialität eines Gefühls. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. Lester, David (1997). The Role of Shame in Suicide. Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior 27(4), 352–361. Levinas, Emmanuel (2003[1935]). On Escape. Transl. by B. Bergo. Stanford: Stanford University Press. ——— (1979[1961]). Totality and Infinity. Transl. by A. Lingis. The Hague: Nijhoff. Miller, Susan (1985). The Shame Experience. London: Analytic Press. Reddy, Vasudevi (2008). How Infants Know Minds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Salice, Alessandro, and Montes Sánchez, Alba (2016). Pride, Shame, and Group Identification. Frontiers in Psychology 7(557), 1–13. Sartre, Jean-Paul (2003[1943]). Being and Nothingness: An Essay in Phenomenological Ontology, Transl. by H. E. Barnes. London, New York: Routledge. Scheler, Max (1987[1913]). Shame and Feelings of Modesty. In: Max Scheler: Person and Self-Value: Three Essays. Dordrecht: Springer. Smith, Richard H., Webster, Matthew J., Parrott, Gerrod W., and Eyre, Heidi L. (2002). The Role of Public Exposure in Moral and Nonmoral Shame and Guilt. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83(1), 138–159. Steinbock, Anthony J. (2014). Moral Emotions: Reclaiming the Evidence of the Heart. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Straus, Erwin W. (1966[1933]). Shame as a Historiological Problem. In: Erwin W. Straus: Phenomenological Psychology: Selected Papers. New York: Basic Books. Tangney, June P., and Dearing, Ronda L. (2002). Shame and Guilt. New York: Guilford Press. Zahavi, Dan (2014). Self and Other: Exploring Subjectivity, Empathy, and Shame. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Zupancic, Melissa K., and Kreidler, Maryhelen C. (1999). Shame and the Fear of Feeling. Perspectives in Psychiatric Care 35(2), 29–34.
357
31 SELF-ESTEEM, PRIDE, EMBARRASSMENT AND SHYNESS Anna Bortolan
1. Introduction Extensively investigated across disciplines such as psychology, psychiatry, education, and social policy, self-esteem has been comparatively under-researched in philosophy.1 However, a number of theories and notions relevant to the understanding of self-esteem and related experiences have been put forward in both classical and contemporary phenomenology of emotion. Drawing upon this body of research, in this chapter, I will present a phenomenological account of self-esteem. First, I will suggest that this is best understood as a particular kind of background affective orientation, and, more specifically, as a narratively shaped “existential feeling”. I will then move to explore the relevance of such an account for the philosophical understanding of pride, embarrassment, and shyness, thus providing an example of the influence exerted by self-esteem on other self-related affects and traits.
2. Self-esteem 2.1 A background affective orientation In the psychological literature, self-esteem is generally characterised as a positive, evaluative attitude towards the self (Baumeister et al. 1989). Self-esteem, it is claimed, consists in conceiving of oneself as valuable because of the possession of certain features and particular achievements. For example, the APA Dictionary of Psychology defines self-esteem as follows: [T]he degree to which the qualities and characteristics contained in one’s self-concept are perceived to be positive. It reflects a person’s physical self-image, view of his or her accomplishments and capabilities, and values and perceived success in living up to them, as well as the ways in which others view and respond to that person. The more positive the cumulative perception of these qualities and characteristics, the higher one’s self-esteem. (VandenBos 2015, 955) The idea that positive self-evaluation is at the core of self-esteem emerges also from philosophical accounts. Gabriele Taylor (1985), for instance, claims that “[t]he person who has 358
Self-esteem, pride, embarrassment, shyness
self-esteem takes a favourable view of himself, while he who lacks it, will think of himself in unfavourable terms: he is not worth much” (1985, 77–78). In both philosophy and psychology, self-esteem is thus often associated with a conception of the self as worthy, and cognition is attributed a central role in such self-evaluation. Self-esteem is indeed seen as an evaluative response to the conception one has of oneself, thus requiring both reflective awareness and a degree of self-knowledge. In this context, it is recognised that feelings and self-assessment are related (e.g., Campbell and Lavalle 1993), but the self-attitude with which self-esteem is identified is not generally attributed a distinct phenomenal character or a primarily affective nature. A connection is also often established between self-esteem and various dimensions of our mental and practical life. It is acknowledged that self-esteem has a strong motivational character (Dillon 2013), inclining us to think and act in certain ways. However, despite the recognition of these dynamics, self-esteem itself has been seen as an “intrapsychic attitude” (Baumeister et al. 1989), a discrete mental state—or set of mental states—which are structurally distinct from one’s bodily experience of self, others, and the world. The idea that self-esteem is first and foremost a matter of cognitive self-evaluation, potentially accompanied by a set of self-focused feelings, and that it is just one possible manner of relating to oneself, can be challenged by providing a more fine-grained account of the ways in which it influences our experience. This account will show that a particular form of affectivity is cardinal to the structure of self-esteem, and that this is not a circumscribed self-attitude, but rather an experiential orientation that radically shapes our emotions, actions, and cognition itself. In order to bring the phenomenological features of self-esteem to the fore, it will be helpful to start by examining an example of how one’s experience may be impacted by fluctuations of self-esteem. Consider, for instance, the case of someone who has been in a precarious employment situation for a while and, despite strenuous attempts to secure a more stable position, still has to move from one temporary job to another in the uttermost uncertainty regarding their future. While people may react in very different ways to such circumstances, some may experience a weakening of self-esteem when faced with this kind of adversity. Due to the repeated failed attempts to reach the professional position that she is seeking, the person may lose confidence in her abilities and start to conceive of herself as not good enough to reach the goals that she is striving towards. This loss, however, will not amount to an isolated change which will leave unaltered the other dimensions of her experience. On the contrary, the weakening of self-esteem will be marked by a series of modifications in various aspects of the individual’s personal and interpersonal life. For example, upon hearing about new job opportunities she may no longer react with excitement and hope, taking this as a possibility to finally reach her goals and a professional position in alignment with her competences and capacities. Rather, hearing about job openings may trigger feelings of hopelessness, as the person predicts that this will be yet another situation in which she will fail to achieve what she wants. Rather than being enlivening, getting to know about these opportunities will be disheartening, as she has lost confidence in her ability to change her position. The fluctuation of self-esteem thus goes hand in hand with a modification of one’s attitude towards the future, as this comes to be seen as something that one does not have the power to control or influence. The loss of confidence in one’s ability to improve one’s standing, may also lead to the feeling of being “stuck” or “trapped” in the present. What before appeared to be annoying and painful, but bearable because of its temporary nature, now may become intolerable due to its seemingly unavoidable character. The dissatisfaction, despondency, and profound irritability that may ensue will unlikely be 359
Anna Bortolan
confined to the professional domain, but will rather tend to spread to other dimensions of the person’s life. In particular, feelings of low self-worth may have a strong impact on the way in which she relates to others, both at work and in the interaction with family and friends. Judging herself as unable to reach her goals and fulfil her ambitions may trigger feelings of shame, and the willingness to withdraw from social interaction, so as to avoid her alleged failures being exposed to and potentially further criticised by others. This may be the case also when others have a non-judgemental attitude and offer support and encouragement, as the person who is experiencing low self-esteem may struggle to believe other people when they praise her and when they show optimism towards the future, and can rather come to think that they are doing so just to make her feel better. She may also doubt that colleagues, friends, and significant others who act in this way fully appreciate the seriousness of her situation, and this could lead to feelings of resentment or loss of trust. Self-esteem thus appears to have a distinct phenomenal character: it is something that we feel, and that significantly impacts upon how we perceive both our position in the world, and others more broadly. As I argued elsewhere (Bortolan 2018), however, it is difficult to provide an account of self-esteem through the framework of existing affective taxonomies, as neither the concept of “emotion” nor that of “disposition”, which are central to these classifications can do justice to the features of self-esteem. Rather, I claimed that in order to account for the structure of this experience we need to refer to a different form of affect, suggesting that the phenomenological notion of “mood” (Heidegger 1927) or “existential feeling” (Ratcliffe 2005, 2008; see also Chapter 22 in this volume) is the most relevant in this context. In phenomenology of emotion attention has often been drawn to the fact that every intentional state—be it cognitive, affective, or volitional—is grounded in particular forms of affective experience, which enable us to encounter the world and objects in it as meaningful in certain ways. These affects are not themselves intentional, but are considered to be the ground from which mental states directed at particular things, people, or states of affairs stem. Heidegger refers to experiences of this kind through the concept of “moods” which— contrary to the characterisation often provided in the psychological literature—he conceives of not as inner mental states, but rather as ways of being in the world, which make it possible for things to matter to us in particular manners (Elpidorou and Freeman 2015; Ratcliffe 2013) (see also Chapter 7 in this volume). This idea has been further developed by Ratcliffe who conceives of “existential feelings” as sets of bodily feelings, which are fundamental in shaping our “sense of possibility” (Ratcliffe 2012, 2015). According to him, these feelings have a “pre-intentional” character, that is not only they do not have specific intentional objects but rather determine “what kinds of intentional state it is possible to have” (2010, 604). Self-esteem appears to share its fundamental features with the background affects discussed by Heidegger and Ratcliffe. As shown above, it is an occurrent, felt state, but one that is not directed to particular objects as emotions, for example, are. Self-esteem cannot be “about something”: it may be nurtured by the positive assessment of particular traits and features, but in itself, it is a global form of self-experience, which is devoid of such directionality (cf. Bortolan 2018). However, self-esteem is not merely non-intentional either, a feeling which only occasionally comes to colour our experiential field. Degrees of self-esteem can fluctuate, and so can the degree of reflective awareness that we have of these dynamics, but a sense of one’s own worth is always present: it is an ineliminable feature of our self-awareness, which, as highlighted previously, modulates other dimensions of experience too. Our level of self-esteem determines the possible ways in which we can think and feel about ourselves, and the range of possibilities of action and interaction that the world appears to harbour. As such, self-esteem too can be considered to be “pre-intentional”. 360
Self-esteem, pride, embarrassment, shyness
The idea that self-esteem can be accounted for in these terms is consonant with various insights into the connection between existential feelings and self-experience put forward by Ratcliffe and other contemporary phenomenologists. For instance, the suggestion that affects closely related to self-esteem may be integral to the “background orientations” (Ratcliffe 2008), which structure our experience seems to emerge from Ratcliffe’s account of trust (Ratcliffe et al. 2014; Ratcliffe 2015). Through the examination of the multiple manners in which one’s way of being in the world may be altered after having undergone traumatic events, Ratcliffe identifies interpersonal trust as one of the experiential structures upon which our perception of the world and everyday interactions with others fundamentally impinge. Trust, and the loss of it which may be triggered as a response to trauma, in other terms, are background orientations, which modulate our sense of possibility, and are explicitly described by Ratcliffe as being “integral to existential feeling” (2015, 123). While focused predominantly on the trust we experience towards other people, this account, however, also draws attention to the existence of a close connection between interpersonal trust and self-trust. As Ratcliffe and colleagues (2014) suggest, disruptions of interpersonal trust have an impact upon the attitudes we hold towards ourselves too. Moreover, they highlight that one of the ways in which the trust that underlies our ordinary dealings with the world can be disrupted involves the loss of confidence in oneself (2014, 5). It is thus suggested that self-trust not only can be influenced by alterations of interpersonal trust, but also that it is one of the experiential structures that modulate the way in which we find ourselves in the world. A view that is deeply consonant with Ratcliffe’s position and the insights presented in this chapter is developed by Slaby in his account of affective self-consciousness and the sense of ability (2012; Slaby and Wüschner 2014), a form of experience which he explicitly connects to self-esteem (2012, 153). According to Slaby, affective states have a “self-disclosive” character, they enable us to experience not only certain aspects of the world but also various features of the self. More specifically, Slaby suggests that intrinsic to any affective experience is a particular “affective self-construal”, a feeling of oneself as possessing certain abilities and agentive capacities in the context in which one finds oneself. This form of self-feeling is considered to be essentially connected to a sense of one’s bodily potentialities, and it is indeed defined by Slaby as an “embodied sense of capability” (2012, 152), which deeply shapes one’s self- and world-experience. Because of its pervasiveness and the role it plays in structuring our personal and interpersonal experience, the sense of ability is considered by Slaby to be akin to the notion of “existential feeling” (2012, 153).2 What emerges from Slaby’s and Ratcliffe’s accounts is thus the idea that a particular sense of oneself as more of less able to deal with and act in the particular circumstances that have to be faced is integral to any form of experience and structures the way in which we find ourselves in the world.
2.2 Ability, achievement, and narrative structure Phenomenological accounts of affectivity thus point towards the possibility of conceiving of trust and confidence in oneself—or what in the psychological literature has been described through the notion of “self-efficacy” (e.g., Branden 1994; Bandura 1997), namely a sense of being able to cope with the demands and challenges of one’s life—as a background affective orientation akin to “moods” or “existential feelings”. This is highly relevant to the attempt to provide an account of self-esteem, because the experiences described through the notions of self-trust, sense of ability, or self-efficacy appear to be a core aspect of its phenomenology. 361
Anna Bortolan
Confidence in one’s capacities and potentialities—a felt sense of one’s cognitive, affective, and practical possibilities—seems to be key to experiencing self-esteem. However, as remarked in the definition given by the American Psychological Association, self-esteem does not have to do only with abilities and potential; rather, it is also dependent on how we use those capabilities, and what we manage to realise through their exercise. In other terms, self-esteem is both a matter of possibility and reality, and it is anchored to both our perceived ability and our actual “accomplishments”. The positive self-evaluation with which self-esteem is identified concerns both one’s capacity to achieve and the successes that one has already achieved, an idea that the psychologist Nathaniel Branden has defended by claiming that not only self-efficacy, but also “self-respect” is to be considered a key component of self-esteem (1994). In the philosophical literature, the notion of “self-respect” has received multiple characterisations (Cf. Dillon 1995), and engaging in a comparison and critical assessment of these views would exceed the scope of this study. For the purpose of my analysis, and in line with Branden’s characterisation, I will be using “self-respect” to refer to the positive form of self-evaluation, which has one’s achievements, rather than one’s ability, as its focus. Experiences of self-efficacy and self-respect are both causally and phenomenologically entangled. A good level of confidence in one’s own abilities can have a positive effect on one’s performance, facilitating the achievement of one’s goals and success in a variety of domains. On the other hand, trust in one’s capacities is nurtured by the awareness of one’s previous accomplishments. As far as the phenomenology of these experiences is concerned, while it is possible to distinguish between feelings of ability and possibility on the one hand, and a felt sense of achievement on the other, what we usually experience is rather a broader sense of ourselves as being more or less worthy, a global feeling of our value in which assessments concerning capability and actual success are inextricable. Self-esteem is to be identified with this general experience of the self as valuable to various degrees, and although there are different constitutive elements to it, this is still a unitary phenomenon.3 Can a phenomenological account of self-esteem do justice to the complex nature of the self-evaluations involved in the experience of self-esteem? And, more specifically, is the account of self-esteem as an existential feeling compatible with the acknowledgement that there are various aspects or components to the experience of self-esteem? I believe that both questions can be given a positive answer, and, in the following, I will argue that the various features of self-esteem discussed so far can be coherently accounted for through the notion of “narrative structure” as developed by Peter Goldie in his account of emotions. Goldie’s account moves from the acknowledgement that the theories that conceive of emotions as single mental states or events do not do justice to some fundamental intuitions we have about the nature of affective experience (Goldie 2011). By identifying emotions with individual affective, cognitive, or volitional states, these theories would provide a static characterisation of emotions, which ignores their intrinsically “dynamic” and “complex” nature (Goldie 2000, 12). An example that Goldie uses to clarify his view is the emotion of grief (2011). He observes that while grieving certainly involves a specific feeling, this is not all there is to this experience. Grief, he suggests, involves a plurality of other elements unfolding over time and thus should be seen as a complex and temporally extended experience. According to Goldie, emotions involve the recognition of something as possessing a particular evaluative property, and a number of responses including characteristic expressions, bodily changes, motivational elements, and actions (2000). For instance, the fear experienced when facing a ferocious animal would be characterised by the acknowledgement of the animal
362
Self-esteem, pride, embarrassment, shyness
as dangerous and by a number of reactions to that danger, such as the feeling of fear, a specific profile of bodily activation, and action tendencies such as the impulse to run away. Goldie claims that the various components of the emotion are meaningfully connected, as they are various aspects of the process through which we recognise and respond to something as valuable in a certain respect—what he calls the “recognition-response tie” (2000, 28–37). The fact that the emotion has different constituents which are so connected is in his view what makes it possible to attribute to it a “narrative structure”. The notion of narrative structure appears to be useful to account for the complex nature of self-esteem. As previously observed, this predicament is indeed best understood as a background feeling of the self as worthy, an experience to which both a sense of ability and a sense of actual achievement are integral. Self-esteem is, from a phenomenological point of view, a unitary experience, but, as it is the case for the emotions discussed by Goldie, its structure comprises different components, namely, as discussed above, self-efficacy (or sense of ability or self-trust) and self-respect. Conceiving of self-esteem as a narratively structured existential feeling also makes it possible to account for the fact that the role played by the different components of self-esteem in its constitution and phenomenology can be different at different points in time. For example, there may be situations in which the felt sense of achievement at the core of self-respect is diminished, but our sense of ability and possibility remains intact, allowing for self-esteem to be preserved. In other circumstances the situation may be reversed, and a diminished sense of ability may co-exist with a positive level of self-respect, to which our sense of self-worth remains anchored. Therefore, the weakening of one of the components of self-esteem does not always bring about a diminishment of self-esteem, and this is the case because other components in the narrative structure of this affect may remain unaffected, making it possible to maintain one’s positive self-evaluation. However, if an alteration of self-efficacy or self-respect persists over time, also one’s general level of self-esteem may be affected. As it is the case with the emotions discussed by Goldie (2000, 37), occasional failures to experience one of the constituents of the narrative structure of self-esteem will not change the self-evaluation with which it is identified. Nevertheless, persisting modifications of one’s sense of ability or achievement will result in a different narrative structure and level of self-esteem.4
3. Pride, embarrassment, and shyness So far I have defended the idea that self-esteem is best understood as a complex background affective orientation. I have argued that this is a specific way of experiencing oneself, which deeply modulates the range of cognitive, affective, and volitional states that we can entertain. As such, self-esteem plays a fundamental role in our mental and practical life. In the following, I will investigate this further by examining the connection between self-esteem and other self-focused affects, namely pride, embarrassment, and shyness.
3.1 Pride In the philosophical and psychological literature, pride is often characterised as a “selfconscious emotion” (Tracy and Robins 2004), namely as an emotion that is essentially connected to the way in which we conceive of ourselves.5 To be more specific, pride is frequently identified with a self-evaluation, and, in particular, with an evaluation of the self as
363
Anna Bortolan
praiseworthy (Solomon 2007, 99). We are proud of ourselves in virtue of being connected to something that we deem positive (Ben-Ze’ev 2000, 491), and philosophers have advanced various proposals as how this relationship should be characterised. Gabriele Taylor (1985), for example, claims that there needs to be a relationship of “belonging” between what we are proud of and ourselves, where “belonging” may involve “ownership”, but can just be a shared condition (e.g., belonging to the same family etc.) (30–32). Pride is often related to the possession of certain features—for example certain physical or psychological traits— particular achievements, relationships, or the ownership of particular goods. When we feel pride, we experience ourselves as deserving praise in virtue of having certain properties or being closely associated with something or someone that does have these properties. Pride is thus closely connected to one’s self-conception, and it is to be expected that experiences of pride will influence and be influenced by feelings and judgements regarding one’s worth. This has been noted by Taylor (1985), who claims that our level of self-confidence and the related expectations we have with regard to what is possible for us to achieve determine the frequency with which we are likely to experience pride. In particular, she suggests that a low degree of self-confidence will lead to not expect much of oneself, and that this in turn will provide us with more opportunities to experience pride. As she explains: Where expectations are pitched low the occasions for thinking of oneself as having achieved something are particularly numerous. If I think of myself as the sort of person who cannot make machines work for them or whose flowers die on them, then any successful operation of the machine and any flourishing of my plants will be seen as an achievement and so as something to be proud of. (1985, 39–40) This view, however, does not consider that such an evaluation can only take place if one’s general experience of oneself and the world allows for a positive form of self-assessment. I can only be proud of a particular achievement if, to start with, I experience myself as someone for whom achieving something of value is a possibility. Taylor recognises that the experience of pride is dependent on one’s self-conception and the expectations which are rooted in it, but she does not consider the impact that extremely low levels of self-esteem can have on the capability to recognise one’s achievements as such, and thus to feel pride. If, due to little trust in my abilities, I do not expect much of myself—that is, I do not expect myself to be capable of doing anything of particular value—it is likely that, when I manage to do something good, I will struggle to see it as such. As my successes will not appear to be coherent with the negative view of myself, I may rather be inclined to belittle them, or to deny that they are successes at all, for example by downplaying the efforts or skills necessary to their obtainment, or by refusing to take credit for them.6 Therefore, contrary to what is suggested by Taylor’s account, the person who has a low consideration of herself will have fewer opportunities to experience pride than the one who has a positive self-conception. This dynamic provides an illustration of the way in which self-esteem can restrict (or extend) the range of affective and other mental states we are capable of experiencing. The background sense of one’s ability and achievements with which this affect has been identified disposes us to feel emotions and entertain thoughts, which are congruent with it, and these in turn can reenforce the negative (or positive) evaluations at the core of self-esteem. On this basis, it is also possible to conceive of pride—and arguably other self-conscious emotions like guilt and shame—as an integral part of the narrative structure of self-esteem, as they can be characterised as some of the responses through which the evaluation of one’s worthiness is realised over time.7 364
Self-esteem, pride, embarrassment, shyness
3.2 Embarrassment Embarrassment is a social emotion, which we experience when we find ourselves in a particular relationship to other people. While it is generally agreed that embarrassment is experienced in interpersonal contexts (Taylor 1985; Ben-Ze’ev 2000; Purshouse 2001), different accounts have been given of the dynamics in which it originates. For example, Purshouse has argued that embarrassment stems from an unwanted experience of “exposure” to which either the self or someone she is interacting with are subjected. The nature of what can be so exposed and thus generate embarrassment is diverse: according to Purshouse, this can be one’s “physical body, mental states, dispositions of character, and actions”, where also cases in which someone acquires knowledge about someone else can count as “exposure” (2001, 530–531). A compatible, but more restrictive account of the conditions that must be in place in order for embarrassment to occur is put forward by Taylor (1985). In her view, embarrassment stems from a particular demand posed directly or indirectly by others to which the individual is unable to respond appropriately. Not knowing what to do when a pipe bursts, she observes, may lead to feelings of embarrassment if I am in the presence of someone who can efficiently deal with this type of situation (69–70). In this case, the emotion would be triggered by perceiving the need to respond to the situation while not having the possibility or the knowledge necessary to do so. As it is the case with pride, embarrassment is thus a self-conscious emotion, and one that may entail a negative self-evaluation.8 When feeling embarrassed, we see ourselves as being in a situation in which we deem inappropriate to be, or as failing to behave in a way adequate to the circumstances. These shortcomings are relative to specific contexts (Taylor 1985, 75; Ben-Ze’ev 2000, 503) and may not concern domains which are central to one’s self-conception, but they still show the self as falling short in a certain way. Whether embarrassment is conceived simply as a form of unwanted or unforeseen exposure, or whether a more demanding account of the type of dynamic in which it is rooted is embraced, it is important to acknowledge that, in virtue of its structure as a background feeling of one’s worth, self-esteem can be closely connected to the experience of this emotion too. For example, the range of situations that we conceive as involving “unwanted exposure” will at least in part depend on how confident and good we feel about ourselves. Low selfesteem may indeed be associated with the tendency to withdraw or refrain from social interactions, as the person who keeps herself in low regard will expect others to share her negative views of herself. In addition, lack of self-trust and/or self-respect may make us feel “on the spot”, making us more inclined to think that we are responsible for solving the socially problematic situations we are facing. This may be the case because, due to low self-esteem, the person may be more prone to consider herself as the cause of negative events—although in many circumstances, such a causal attribution would likely give rise to shame rather than embarrassment (see also Chapter 30 in this volume). Alternatively, her feelings of inadequacy may make her feel as if she always owed something to others, so that any demand for action which arises in a social context may be taken as having to be fulfilled by her. This does not mean that embarrassment is only experienced when self-esteem is low, but rather that the evaluation of oneself as failing to adequately deal with the demands of a particular situation may be fostered by prior feelings of worthlessness. Unlike pride, which is connected to one’s achievements and thus to the evaluation of one’s worthiness, embarrassment—even when it involves a negative self-assessment—does not appear to immediately reflect on our value as persons. However, it is arguable that repeated, intense experiences of embarrassment may weaken one’s confidence, generate shame (Taylor 1985, 76), and ultimately pose a danger to the integrity of one’s self-esteem. 365
Anna Bortolan
3.3 Shyness Shyness can be conceived of as a character or personality trait (Ben-Ze’ev 2000)—i.e., being a shy person. However, as it is the case with pride, shyness can also refer to an episodic affective state—i.e., feeling shy in a particular situation. Here, I will predominantly consider shyness in its occurrent, emotional form, but my observations will also be relevant to our understanding of dispositional shyness, as arguably the shy person is inclined, among other things, to experience feelings of shyness when certain circumstances occur. Like embarrassment, shyness requires the presence of a real or imagined audience and is thus to be considered a social emotion. We feel shy when we are in front of other people or directly interacting with them, but we can also experience shyness when foreseeing or imagining a possible interaction, so the physical presence of an interlocutor is not a necessary condition. Shyness is defined by the reluctance to be seen, heard, or to interact with others. We typically feel shy in situations in which we may be at the centre of attention—for example when asking a question at an academic event, or when someone wants to take a picture of us—and at the core of the experience is a felt hesitance to be the object of such attention. Intrinsic to shyness is a disinclination to engage in particular forms of interpersonal exchange, but this does not necessarily entail a firm resolution to avoid the relevant situation. At least in some cases, it seems that uncertainty, rather than the resolve to avoid interaction, is what the shy person is experiencing. In an analogous way to pride and embarrassment, due to its focus on the self, shyness is also likely to be modulated by self-esteem. As previously discussed, the way in which we feel about ourselves shapes our expectations and perceptions regarding the encounter with others, so that different levels of self-esteem may be associated with different patterns of social emotions and behaviours in interpersonal contexts. For example, as remarked above, the feelings of unworthiness that mark low self-esteem may affect the decisiveness with which we approach social interactions, as we may expect others to share the negative view we have of ourselves, potentially exacerbating our painful feelings of inadequacy. On the other hand, high selfesteem may dispose us towards a more optimistic attitude with regard to social encounters, as confidence in our value inclines us to expect that others may find enjoyable interacting with us, thus providing opportunities to confirm or enhance our sense of self-worth. Both dynamics can therefore also have a self-perpetuating effect, as others may respond with diffidence or disappointment to the hesitation of the person who is being shy, while resonating more easily with the openness of those who are forthcoming in social interactions.
4. Conclusions In this chapter, I have outlined a phenomenological exploration of self-esteem, and of some of the experiences to which this is closely related. I claimed that self-esteem is to be understood as a particular form of “existential feeling”, an affective, background experience of one’s worth, which deeply modulates our way of being in the world. In so doing, I have also shown that intrinsic to the structure of self-esteem is a sense of both one’s abilities and achievements, and—drawing on Goldie’s account of the narrative structure of emotions—I suggested that these are intertwined components of a unitary phenomenological experience. I then moved to show how self-esteem can impact on the experience of pride, embarrassment, and shyness. In particular, I suggested that the ability to experience pride, the frequency with which we feel embarrassed, and the tendency to be more or less shy, are all shaped by the implicit sense we have of our own value. More broadly, due to its structure as a background 366
Self-esteem, pride, embarrassment, shyness
affective orientation, it is to be expected that different degrees of self-esteem will be associated with distinct patterns of self-focused emotions and attitudes, influencing whether and how we can experience feelings such as guilt, shame, self-compassion, and self-love.
Acknowledgments This chapter was developed during my appointment at University College Dublin as a Government of Ireland Postdoctoral Fellow (project “The Phenomenology of Self-Esteem” – GOIPD/2016/555) and I thank the Irish Research Council for their support.
Notes
References Baumeister, Roy F., Tice, Dianne M., and Hutton, Debra G. (1989). Self-Presentational Motivations and Personality Differences in Self-Esteem. Journal of Personality 57(3), 547–579. Bandura, Albert (1997). Self-Efficacy: The Exercise of Control. New York: W.H. Freeman. Ben-Ze’ev, Aaron (2000). The Subtlety of Emotions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bortolan, Anna (2018). Self-Esteem and Ethics: A Phenomenological View. Hypatia 33(1), 56–72. Branden, Nathaniel (1994). The Six Pillars of Self-Esteem. New York: Bantam. Campbell, Jennifer D., and Lavallee, Loraine F. (1993). Who Am I? The Role of Self-Concept Confusion in Understanding the Behavior of People with Low Self-Esteem. In: R.F. Baumeister (Ed.). Self-Esteem: The Puzzle of Low Self-Regard. New York: Plenum Press, 3–20. Deigh, John (1983). Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique. Ethics 93(2), 225–245.
367
Anna Bortolan Dillon, Robin (2013). Self-Respect and Self-Esteem. In: H. LaFollette (Ed.). The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. New York: Wiley-Blackwell, 4772–4782. Dillon, Robin (Ed.) (1995). Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect. New York, London: Routledge. Elpidorou, Andreas, and Freeman, Lauren (2015). Affectivity in Heidegger I: Moods and Emotions in Being and Time. Philosophy Compass 10(10), 661-671. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ——— (2011). Grief: A Narrative Account. Ratio 24(2), 119–137. Govier, Trudy (1993). Self-Trust, Autonomy, and Self-Esteem. Hypatia 8(1), 99–120. ——— (1998). Dilemmas of Trust. Montreal, Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press. Heidegger, Martin (1962[1927]]). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell. Helm, Bennett W. (2009). Love, Identification, and the Emotions. American Philosophical Quarterly 46(1), 39–59. Honneth, Axel. (1995). The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts. Transl. by J. Anderson. Cambridge: Polity Press. Keshen, Richard (2017). Reasonable Self-Esteem. A Life of Meaning. (2nd ed.). Montreal, Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press. Leary, Mark R., Tambor, Ellen S., Terdal, Sonja K., and Downs, Deborah L. (1995). Self-Esteem as an Interpersonal Monitor: The Sociometer Hypothesis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 68(3), 518–530. Purshouse, Luke (2001). Embarrassment: A Philosophical Analysis. Philosophy 76(4), 515–540. Ratcliffe, Matthew (2005). The Feeling of Being. Journal of Consciousness Studies 12(8-10), 43-60. ——— (2008). Feelings of Being: Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2010). Depression, Guilt and Emotional Depth. Inquiry 53(6), 602–626. ——— (2012). The Phenomenology of Existential Feeling. In: S. Marienberg, and J. Fingerhut (Eds.). The Feeling of Being Alive. Berlin: de Gruyter, 23–54. ——— (2013). Why Mood Matters. In: M. Wrathall (Ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger’s Being and Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 157–176. ——— (2015). Experiences of Depression: A Study in Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ratcliffe, Matthew, Ruddell, Mark, and Smith, Benedict (2014). What Is a “Sense of Foreshortened Future?” A Phenomenological Study of Trauma, Trust, and Time. Frontiers in Psychology 5, 1–11. Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Schmid, Hans Bernhard (2011). Feeling Up to It – The Sense of Ability in the Phenomenology of Action. In: A. Konzelmann Ziv, K. Lehrer, and H. B. Schmid (Eds.). Self-Evaluation. Affective and Social Grounds of Intentionality. Dordrecht: Springer, 215–236. Slaby, Jan (2012). Affective Self-Construal and the Sense of Ability. Emotion Review 4(2), 151–156. Slaby, Jan, and Wüschner, Philipp (2014). Emotion and Agency. In: C. Todd, and S. Roeser (Eds.). Emotion and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 212–228. Solomon, Robert C. (2007). True to Our Feelings. What Our Emotions Are Really Telling Us. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Taylor, Gabriele (1985). Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Tracy, Jessica L., and Robins, Richard W. (2004). Putting the Self into Self-Conscious Emotions: A Theoretical Model. Psychological Inquiry 15(2), 103–125. VandenBos, Gary R. (2015). APA Dictionary of Psychology (2nd ed.). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Yanal, Robert J. (1987). Self-Esteem. Noûs 21(3), 363–379. Further reading Baumeister, Roy F., (Ed.) (1993). Self-Esteem: The Puzzle of Low Self-Regard. New York: Plenum Press. Brennan, Geoffrey, and Pettit, Philip. (2004). The Economy of Esteem. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lehrer, Keith. (1997). Self-Trust. A Study of Reason, Knowledge and Autonomy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Tangney, June P., and Fischer, Kurt W. (1995). Self-Conscious Emotions. The Psychology of Shame, Guilt, Embarrassment, and Pride. New York: The Guildford Press. Tracy, Jessica L., Robins, Richard W., and Tangney, June P. (Eds.) (2007). The Self-Conscious Emotions. Theory and Research. New York: The Guildford Press.
368
32 HUMILITY, HUMILIATION AND AFFLICTION Anthony J. Steinbock
Loving and humility are intimately related, and I understand their difference in terms of experiential emphases. I take loving as an immediate and direct opening to another as bearer of value—any other—in the integrity of what it is and toward the fullest realization of what it is with respect to its own sphere. Here the focus is on the other, and is characterized as a movement originating from the beloved as invitational (in one respect), and toward the other as an initiatory movement of the lover (in another). Humility is this openness and dynamic movement, but where the experiential resonance is on how I spontaneously receive myself as what I call “Myself,” that is, as who I am from another and as not self-grounding. Both loving and humility are equally radical, but humility is a spontaneous actualization where the experience is lived in its emphasis on the reception of “Myself,” most fundamentally as beloved (Steinbock 2014).1 I treat humility as a moral emotion because of the way in which it is inherently connected to loving, namely, as the way I receive myself in loving. Although humility is how I receive Myself, humility is a moral emotion of otherness, and describing its structure helps to elucidate the meaning of person. In this chapter, I address the question of self-givenness in humility especially in relation to pride. This is followed by a differentiation between being humbled, humbling myself, and modesty. I then distinguish between humiliation, affliction, and humility.
1. The question of self-givenness in humility If we examine emotions of self-givenness such as pride, shame, and guilt, we can find an unequivocal self-givenness (which some investigators take as forms of self-assessment or self-judgment) in the experiences of them. These emotions of self-givenness are conducive to a phenomenological analysis, not only because “I” am given to myself in these very experiences as first-person experiences but also because I can reflect on this self-givenness and describe it as it is taking place. Here, I become an explicit theme of the experience, even if— as in the case of pride—such an experience amounts to a self-dissimulation (Steinbock 2014, 31–66). Humility is usually treated alongside pride, shame, and guilt because it is seen either as marking a point of contrast with pride or as residing on a continuum with shame and guilt (Taylor 1985; Tangney and Fischer 1995). How are we to understand the experience of 369
Anthony J. Steinbock
self-givenness in relation to humility? In this section, I examine the sense in which humility clearly is not a self-givenness like we find in the cases of pride, shame, and guilt. But I also describe the distinctive way humility is a unique kind of self-givenness. Thus, humility occupies a peculiar place in relation to the individual person (self-givenness) and otherness. Let’s begin with an example. If I were to present a group design project as my own work, it could make sense to reflect on it and think, “Wow, I am really being prideful right now” (and disdain it or embrace it). If I look at the way that the other team members and the judges look at me for grandstanding, it might make sense to feel shame and to describe it as such in that very experience. Further, if I take all the credit and the prize money for the winning design, I could experience guilt and describe this experience as it is taking place. But when for example describing the communal effort that went into the design, where the focus is on the design and the cooperation—and not myself as ego—it does not seem possible at that very moment, reflectively, to describe myself as experiencing humility. “I” in some sense disappear as a focal point in the very experience of humility, which is one reason why humility evades the same kind of first-person-present description that we find in the other emotions of self-givenness, e.g., pride, shame, and guilt. Nevertheless, the difficulty of describing humility as I experience it in a first-person-present experience is also a clue to the very experience of humility. It is a clue insofar as this difficulty corresponds to what can be loosely described as a “loss” or “forgetfulness” of self. Because humility is given as I am disposed toward an “other” (i.e., loving) I do not find myself as humble in the first-person experience, now. Yet, as in the case of shamelessness, humility can be given from a first-person plural perspective, a “we,” or from an I–you perspective (e.g., perceiving humility in someone) (Steinbock 2014, 67–99). In this way, another can become exemplary of humility for me. Or humility can be given in a memorial experience with regard to myself as the person of my own past, whereby I am able to identify some act or attitude as humble. Let me now examine the way in which humility is a kind of self-givenness. Phenomenologically speaking, what is known as the phenomenological “reduction” is not method of finding a remainder, something left over after putting my prejudices out of play, but a process of disposing oneself to what something is in the manner that it gives itself. It thus liberates the phenomena, as it were. The style of “liberation” of the reduction is operative in the epistemic as well as in the moral sphere, though in different ways. In the “moral reduction” of humility, I am “reduced”—to Myself. That is, I am reduced to the core of who “I” am—not as independent, fully self-originating, or self-grounding, but as essentially relational and not self-grounding, ultimately, interpersonal from the very start. Humility is a being revealed to myself as Myself: as related to another, as accepting from another, as accepting the givenness from another and contributions from others—precisely the opposite of pride. Accordingly, the eclipse of self-givenness where I am an explicit theme (like we find in pride, shame, and guilt) does not mean that there is no self-givenness in humility. It is possible, for instance, to receive myself as a recovery of Myself as relational, since humility is the way I am self-given in the process of accepting or receiving without merit or “just deserts.” I understand by pride an interpersonal movement that presupposes an implicit movement toward others, one that includes others only by resisting their contributions to who I am and the meaning of the world through them in the constitution of who I am through the vaulting self-valuation. Thus, pride is a twofold movement. It is both (1) a subjective self-movement, as (2) a resistance to others. This is why pride is actually a self-dissimulation; it dissimulates the self as interpersonal, as receiving myself/Myself. Pride belongs to a moral dimension of experience, because it is a resistance to others and to their contributions to shared meaning 370
Humility, humiliation and affliction
in and through asserting myself as the only or the highest source of meaning. I am given to myself in pride as self-grounding. In distinction to pride, humility is a recovery and realization of myself, precisely as Myself in the dynamic sense described above. But as foundational for pride, humility does not reach its deepest sense first as a “recovery” of the interpersonal from pride. I mean by this that humility does not presuppose pride; it is just the reverse in terms of its very structure. As foundation, “I” can in principle experience of Myself as interpersonal without having to have been a recovery of a sovereign self in pride. Rather, humility is a reception of myself in the presence of things, a reception of myself as Myself—outside of my expectation or what I would anticipate as a return. As humble, I receive Myself, accepting in openness Myself as self-given ( Jankélévitch 1986, 363). Not only am I not the “object” of the experience, I am not the motivation of the movement—even though it is none other than “I” who am humble. I am not the object of the experience of humility in the sense that I am not the thematic terminus a quo and terminus ad quem. And I am not the motivation of the movement of humility in the sense that this movement is initiated from the outside, from the other, and not from myself. For example, I am drawn toward this profession; I devote myself to understanding this text; I am engaged in pursuing that idea which “I” am trying to realize; I am caught up in a conversation with this student. Because humility is the way in which I am “self-given,” e.g., in loving, the humble person is completely absorbed in the attentiveness to others, to the tea, to the process, the music, etc. In this respect, the non-reflection on myself in the experience is a by-product of humility, but not the goal. This is also why I cannot try to be humble and achieve humility; the very “attempt” as the exercise of my focus on myself would eclipse the very process. It is not that the case that the humble person is pathetic or feeble. Quite the contrary; there is an integrity, “force,” and strength in humility; but the point of the integrity, force, and strength arises through the spontaneous acceptance of Myself in its movement toward and reception from others. Humility should not be confused with abasement. I do not focus on myself in order to be humble. It is quite the opposite. I am too engaged in the reception of what is given to be concerned with myself. It is a question of overabundance in an affirming or accepting, not negating. In comparison to pride, therefore, the humble person accepts the contribution of others to the meaning constitution of the world, and to Myself. We see this spontaneous acceptance in humility that qualifies the person as humble. Certainly, given the whole person, we live through manifold layers and dimensions of temporality. But by honing in on the experience of temporality in humility, there are unique modes of temporal givenness. They include a presence-at, which is the temporal “how” of openness and acceptance, as a being thankful for, an ante-memorial reception, or how I receive myself as given to Myself, as not self-grounding, and accepting-ahead and as accepting-ahead, reflected in devotion toward—all of which may go on at the same time as a presentation, retention, and protention—or with the temporal modes of other emotional experiences—but are essentially distinct from them. To sum up, then, I have characterized humility as a mode of self-givenness as who I am in loving or being oriented toward another. As a way of clarifying this, I have examined the limits of this self-givenness in humility. Unlike pride, humility is the experience of the non-self-grounding character of who I am. Further, unlike other emotions of self-givenness, namely, pride, shame, and guilt, however, I am not self-given in a thematic way in humility. And unlike shame and guilt, I am not given to myself in a diremptive experience. Nevertheless, I am given as having received Myself. 371
Anthony J. Steinbock
However, because humility—viewed from the perspective of pride—calls pride into question, humility can be understood as a recovery of Myself as not-self-grounding, as interrelated, and as interpersonal, and only thereby a forgetfulness of the self in which “I” am not an issue in humility. From this viewpoint, it is possible to distinguish humility from experiences that seem to be similar to humility, but that are essentially distinct, precisely where “I” am an issue. To this end, I describe below the experiences of being humbled, humbling myself, and modesty, all of which are distinct from humility. This set of issues relates to the problem of self-givenness because in these cases it is precisely an issue of how I am given in them.
2. Being humbled, humbling myself, and modesty In order to discern stricter contours of humility, and to avoid common ambiguities associated with this emotion, I describe the experience of being humbled, of humbling myself, and of modesty. In each of these cases, “I” come into a certain prominence in the experience, something that is not the case in humility. Being Humbled: The experience of being humbled presupposes the constitution of something like an “emotional level,” akin to what Merleau-Ponty (1945) has called the constitution of a “spatial level.” That is, being humbled presupposes something in relationship to which I now experience myself as lowered. For example, I may think of myself as an accomplished rock climber, but when I climb with others, and I see how good they are, I could feel humbled. This need not take place before a personal other. For instance, I could try to climb an apparently easy path up a rock face, but struggle making the climb; I may even give up. In this case, I could realize that my efforts to overpower the rock face did not work, that I do not know how to read the rock cliff, or that I am no match for the rock face (as if I were in a competition with it). In these ways, I might experience myself as humbled by the rock face without having to impute any intention to it or of it wanting to humble me. In all instances of being humbled, the experience is accompanied by a negative valence. Certainly, this is not the strong negative valence that is encountered in shame, but it is negative nonetheless because the discrepancy from one emotional level to the next is an abasing one. Even if we might feel positive about being humbled, this is not an original positive valence unique to the experience, but a positivity as a reaction to the negative valence. For example, I may take pleasure in being humbled by the rock face (it may disclose my place in the universe), or in being humbled by another person for some reason, but then we are witnessing two levels peculiar to the experience. First, there is a spontaneity in this being humbled (which is given with a negative valence), and then there is a positivity associated with the negativity such that I may even delight in being humbled. This is why being humbled cannot be equated with masochism. Masochism wants to will being lowered, and in this sense, it insidiously wills to be or to remain in control in the submission. Being humbled, experienced originally, is something by which I am caught off-guard and is not willed; I experience myself immediately as not in control or as having to release my control or mastery. Certainly, being humbled may lead to new insights that I have gained into myself; however, it could just as well motivate other responses; for example, it could just make me angry, prideful, or reactionary. Humbling Myself: Humbling myself relates to my egoic activity, and as such it is expressive of my will. In humbling myself, I freely submit myself to another in a relation to whom I am given to myself. Humbling myself is something distinctive from humility in and through which I serve another, because in humbling myself, I posit myself as in relation to another, 372
Humility, humiliation and affliction
in and through the process of serving another. This can be seen in the case of perceiving someone as superior to me and perhaps more poignantly, with respect to someone perceived as “inferior” to me in some regard. For example, as a car mechanic, I can devote myself to the repair of cars, or I can aid the head mechanic in her task. This could be simply a matter of service—independently of whether or not I am getting paid for this service. Further, no matter how I may have considered myself in relation to others or to this task, I undertake it, say, without complaint, though I may have had my own ideas of how to do things; or I could undertake my duties without any consideration of the merits of the head mechanic, but do this only with the awareness that she is in charge. In this spirit, I carry out my task as servicing cars. Such an example can be seen as humbling myself in relation to the “master” because the very positions of the relation demand “lowering” myself in relation to her. It is also possible that I humble myself in relation to another because I perceive that she is in a position of power; from here I can recognize myself as inferior in relation to someone who is superior, and I could do it out of self-preservation (I want to keep my job). We might consider other examples in which the relation of “humbling myself ” is intensified, for instance, when as a car mechanic I still serve the head mechanic in the same spirit, but I think my ideas, methods, or techniques are superior to hers. This is likewise the case when I, as the head mechanic, inversely work for the new hire—in the spirit of serving—e.g., by assisting the new mechanic in her own way. If I do humble myself in these ways, however, I do not do so in a condescending or patronizing manner. I may do this as a courtesy, in an effort to encourage dialogue rather than shut it down, or in order to make another feel comfortable. In terms of bodily comportment, humbling myself can be expressed as bowing down lower than another; or by letting another go first, as when entering a building. If it is a matter of humbling myself, then it is more than merely following custom, manners, or mores. I mean by this that humbling myself is irreducible to following rules of behavior or codes of conduct, because whereas the latter might be compulsory, here I am “freely” engaged in the process of humbling myself before another—even if objectively humbling myself and just doing things by social rote might look the same. I cite these examples of being humbled and humbling myself because they are essentially distinct from humility; and though they may seem to be quite similar, they show by contrast how distinctive the movement of humility is from them. In humility, the humble person does not compare his position with another; the humble person does not position herself in relation to another. She thinks neither highly nor lowly of herself, because I am not the issue.2 Likewise, when one receives in humility, what is received is not taken as one’s “just deserts,” but rather as gift; only post facto is it “humbling”; only after the fact do I feel myself as “undeserving”—which for humility, would find no end. In fact, humility admits of no intention, no fulfillment, no disappointment. Accordingly, Scheler writes that in humility one accepts all things with thanks, from the most subtle pleasure to the grandest bliss; we do this without ever imagining that we deserve even the smallest part (Scheler 1955, 17–26). The humble person does not give thought to the proper order of things, but accepts what comes with gratitude and without the thought of merit. Accordingly, Jankélévitch writes that the humble person does not have rights, but only duties ( Jankélévitch 1986, 398). I find it telling that the process of humbling myself is susceptible to a patronizing attitude, whereas humility is not. There is a danger where humbling myself is concerned insofar as this process of humbling myself could slip into being manipulative (for example, I lower 373
Anthony J. Steinbock
myself in order to gain control). Moreover, because it is possible to sense my superiority in humbling myself (and therefore put myself above another by placing myself below another— and also having a positive valence accompany this experience), humbling myself reveals the possibility of superiority in relation to which the earlier being humbled had a negative valence. Thus, being humbled and humbling myself are distinctive experiences from humility. Let me now compare these two experiences (which in their own ways bring the self into relief at least in terms of a comparative relation) with modesty, which also bears on me in a peculiar way. Modesty. In distinction to being humbled or humbling myself, modesty requires neither lowering nor raising myself. It is also a style of comportment that operates or attempts to operate without pretension, illusion, or self-deception. Not only does modesty presuppose an exposure of myself, but it is simultaneously a refraining from the exposure of myself, a process of not being “showy,” where precisely a refraining from myself is brought into relief. In this regard, modesty is more aligned with pride than with shame, since the self-salience in a positive respect emerges and is covered up. Unlike humility, in modesty, I am still an issue because I am oriented toward the non-salience of the self (Dōgen 2007, 961).3 Thus, modesty emerges in the context of exposing myself or being exposed in a brazen way and resisting this kind of exposure; modesty holds back from asserting myself in this way. Further, modesty is impersonal in the sense that it is not oriented toward anyone in particular or toward the personal core of the individual. The reserved character of modesty as a holding myself back makes a gesture both toward a hiding or veiling of insufficiencies, or delicately showing talents, and in this way gestures toward anonymity. Its movement is more a self-retraction than putting myself in my rightful place. But if the latter were the case, then it would always be subordinated to the movement of non-prominence, and hence the former gesture. Even though there is this gesture toward impersonality and anonymity, there is nonetheless a givenness of myself. In modesty, writes Jankélévitch, it is not a matter of the others; or as I would say in this context, it is not a question of a comparison in being humbled or humbling myself before another. It is “only me,” but it is still (a matter of ) me ( Jankélévitch, 1986, 333). The individual is not a big deal, but what he is, is something, however minimally. Moderation or the appearance of equilibrium might be a consequence of modesty, but if moderation or equilibrium were the intended outcome, we would only be describing something like propriety. This is because modesty is still a practice related to myself, as a recognition and a suppression of the self-salience.
3. Humiliation and affliction Because humiliation is often treated alongside the experience of humility (perhaps because of an etymological relatedness), often—misleadingly I think—in terms of a genetic relation of humiliation to humility, I treat the experience of humiliation in the context of humility. I also treat the phenomenon of affliction here. I do this because from the outside, affliction and humiliation appear to be the same; experientially, however, they are quite distinct. Furthermore, it is affliction, not humiliation that can lead to humility. Further, the discussion of humiliation belongs in the context of shame and debilitating shame. In a different work (Steinbock 2014), I have shown how shame is lived in a distinctive manner as a diremptive experience, and how shame as self-revelation (which can provoke a positive self-critique), can also issue in (but is irreducible to) a debilitating shame. In fact, the former presupposes the latter such that this kind of self-revelation and self-critique become 374
Humility, humiliation and affliction
distorted precisely through a disordered heart, and such that I am given to myself through distortions of value, either on the part of others or myself. We see this in the cases of emotional or physical abuse and cultural forms of domination (like racism) that support and elicit deformative and alienating economic, political, corporeal value ideals such as we get in advertising and in certain forms of commoditization.4 These result from a disordered heart (Scheler 1957). Humiliation and Debilitating Shame: By humiliation, I understand a destructive force that is abusive, such as being exposed to mockery, being subject to ridicule, or being reduced to powerlessness before the power of another. It includes being stripped down before others, physically and emotionally—before others who remain in power, where this power is a power over the humiliated one. It targets the basic sense and integrity of the person for all to see. This gives us a clue to the interpersonal status of humiliation. Humiliation is at heart interpersonal; it cannot occur within a solus ipse, but it is not expressive of positive interpersonal relations. The interpersonal nexus that we would find in experiences like love or trust are disoriented. If I am humiliated, I am humiliated by another and before another; I am both presupposed as person, yet actively de-personified. This is what makes the process so powerful. I can only be subject to humiliation because there is (at least) an implicit sense of my personal integrity to be humiliated. It is a de-personalization on the basis of an interpersonal nexus. In this regard, humiliation can also be understood as a diremptive experience, namely, I am given to myself in a way that is in tension with a more basic orientation, or in this case, personal self-presence. There is a diremption in humiliation because I am being reduced to this object, which I as person am not, though I am made to appear (=violence) in this light. Humiliation sustains this active tension. I cannot humiliate a person who does not have a sense of him or herself as a person. However, as opposed to embarrassment or shame, there is nothing “corrective” that can come out of humiliation. Shame, for example, keeps the personal sense of the individual intact—I am thrown back on myself as being revealed to myself as who I “am” in the dynamic sense of becoming. Humiliation, on the other hand, targets me as destroying the personal integrity in question; it is not open to positive critique or to a re-orientation of who I am, but only holds me as dis-oriented from who I am before others and as subject to others. Whereas it is courage that might be evoked as a resistance to humiliation, it is rather arrogance that might arise as a resistance to shame (provided, again, that it is not debilitating shame—i.e., akin to humiliation). We can see the difference between shame and humiliation in the following example. I can scold a child in public, saying: “you should be ashamed of yourself ” from the perspective of our shared homeworld. But this is much different from humiliating a child—opening him or her to the derision of others and in a manner that does not allow the child to recover from it. This could include bringing out the child’s faults in front of friends or strangers, with no other purpose than bringing attention to the faults and so ridicule the child; for example, it could entail drawing attention to someone who stammers simply to draw attention to it such that the other person just goes deeper and deeper into stammering. When I am humiliated, I am made to feel less than who I am, and only that. Whereas invoking shameful behavior in a scold could still take place in a loving attitude that wants to draw the child back to his or her “true” self, humiliation only wants to disparage, ridicule, and to reduce the other person to an object in order to exert control, but hold the experience at the disorientation, as it were, without futural recovery. Its internal sense is interpersonal since it is realized as violence directed toward a person. But it is not a positive return to my “true” self—which could in a different context lead to repentance 375
Anthony J. Steinbock
(Steinbock 2014, 137–159). Its internal sense is not humility, as the recovery or reception of myself as Myself. Rather, the sense of humiliation is for this other person to become that de-personified object that I or others could master (e.g., out of anger or hate), where the humiliated person remains a witness to this de-personalization. In this respect, its meaning is not the positive interpersonal relation. Thus, shame, guilt, embarrassment, and humiliation are all diremptive experiences. But whereas shame can point toward the future in the sense of a recovery or a return to Myself, humiliation sustains the point of “disorientation” or “diremption” and holds it there, withholding the dimension of recovery or return to the presence of personhood. The devastating quality of humiliation is due in part to closing down the future, holding the individual in the obstinate and abstract “now,” making it all the more difficult to recover. Further, while I can be embarrassed before others because of something I do, in humiliation, it is others (real or imagined) who make me appear in this way before others. Finally, humiliation is distinct from insult in the way that embarrassment is distinguished from shame. Insult is an incidental rupture against a basic self or personal experience. Humiliation bears on the core of the personal orientation. Let’s compare this characterization of humiliation with debilitating shame (MacKendrick 2008, 145–163). Debilitating shame appropriates a “false” self-image such that the individual internalizes it, producing or appropriating the same dis-ordered heart. Unlike shame, which is rooted in a genuine self-love, debilitating shame works from self-love that is transformed into self-hate. Humiliation is an active operation toward another who is acted upon as an object—but where the individual has not yet internalized what I would want to call this disordered sense of self. Hence, we can say that debilitating shame can result from an internalized humiliation (though this is not the only source), and why the experience of humiliation belongs properly alongside the thematic of debilitating shame, and not humility. Paradoxically, in order to humiliate another, in order to execute or sustain a depersonification of him, I have to posit him as “person.” And in order for humiliation to work, I have to keep it in process or in an active tension. I have to recognize his personhood in order to destroy it before his eyes, which is to say, before others’ eyes—without completely reducing him to the status of an object while attempting to reduce him to the status of an object—so that he can actively witness his own de-personalization against the background of a perceived personhood. Similarly, as the one humiliated, I have to maintain my own personal sense or dignity, while I am being made to appear differently, and I must remain held there at this disequilibrium without the futural movement of return. However, for humiliation to arise, while I may presuppose the other’s personhood, it is also essential that the personhood of the other not be acknowledged explicitly or be made the theme of the actions. If so, this process might instead result in torture without humiliation, for example, physical or psychological abuse (e.g., only to get information, or to do to another what she did to me, etc.) without the diremptive experience of a denigrated integrity before others, thwarting a futural recovery. Thus, there has to be a co-givenness of personhood, but a personhood that is both being denied by the one humiliating and experienced as such by the one humiliated. For example, if someone tries to humiliate me by shaving my head and exposing me to public ridicule, this will only work if I, too, see a positivity in a full head of hair and a simultaneous denigration in a shaved head.5 But if it is only a matter of the shaved head, and if in fact, a shaved head is actually part of my usual self-comportment, say, as a monk, I will not be humiliated by this singular activity. Thus, the sense of integrity (the person—person relation) on both sides of humiliating and humiliated must be presupposed in order for humiliation to arise, but it must remain in the background of and resist an active de-personalization. There is thus a double gesture of both 376
Humility, humiliation and affliction
ascribing and denying the dignity of the other in humiliation where a diremption is posited, but held there without the possibility of the individual’s return to his or her personal integrity. Humiliation and Affliction: Let me draw a further distinction between humiliation and affliction. Affliction is not only lived as beyond my own power, or as beyond any “worldly” measures to initiate it or alleviate it, but ultimately because affliction is a religious relation and for those who undergo it, has a redemptive quality. The fact that there is no “worldly” cause to affliction is an initial clue that affliction has a “religious” sense. Hence, Simone Weil will distinguish between the “I” that is “destroyed” in a mundane manner, which is what I have called humiliation, and the “I” that is “destroyed” from within an interpersonal relation (a relation with God), which only within this very movement is viewed as redemptive (Weil 1988, 35, 2002, 26).6 Affliction is experienced in terms of a presence that should be there, but is not. It is therefore important to note that we cannot simultaneously experience affliction and experience affliction as the process of redemption. It is only after the fact, that is, from the perspective of redemption, and for whom on the other side of the experience, that it may constitute the removal of obstacles, like the attachment to myself in pride, etc. These experiences have a different tenor depending upon how they are lived and are not differentiated by virtue of their objective circumstances. For example, it is not the event itself that qualifies it for me as suffering, humiliation, or affliction. Social degradation, poverty, separation from a loved one, torture, could be lived as either suffering, humiliation, and/or affliction. But in affliction, writes Weil, God is made to appear absent for a time, more absent than a dead man, more absent than light in the utter darkness of a cell. “A kind of horror submerges the whole soul. During this absence there is nothing to love” (Weil 1963, 84, 2001, 70). This suggests an essential difference between humiliation and affliction, namely, “I” can try to resist humiliation, but there is no point to trying to resist affliction in the same way. For example, I can assert in humiliation (at least to myself ) that “I have my pride, you know.” But “I” am powerless to resist affliction. From the outside, of course, extreme suffering, humiliation, and affliction can appear indistinguishable. They all essentially occur against my will. Is it others with a political agenda who make me a pariah; is it economic conditions that make me a social outcast; is it God who makes me stand alone or removes my dignity? Within a merely secular experience, humiliation would be limited to something like exerting power over another, on the one hand, and experiencing abuse and destruction of integrity, on the other. Affliction is ultimately a religious experience. Only to the extent that there is an experience of some other as a center of loving, could there be an experience of affliction. This is to say two things. First, the context in which affliction arises cannot be “secular” because the otherwise secular would have a religious meaning, even if we did not actively impute to it a religious significance. Second, affliction tears down the attitude that gives absolute weight to some relative good, on infinite weight to some finite value. This goes even to the finite absoluteness of myself in pride. Thus affliction, properly speaking, belongs to the religious sphere of experiencing. Accordingly, it is affliction, which is ultimately rooted in loving, and not at all humiliation, that has a genetic connection to humility.
4. Conclusion Allow me to conclude these reflections on humility by providing a brief summary. To describe humility, I related it to the experience of loving as movement toward another as bearer in the fullness of its becoming-being. Humility is who I “am” as how I am given to myself 377
Anthony J. Steinbock
in as Myself. It is a unique kind of self-givenness that is unlike the self-givenness of pride, shame, or guilt. Further, humility is distinctive from my being humbled, from humbling myself insofar as I am not placed or do not place myself in comparison with another; unlike modesty, there is no attempt in humility to suppress myself. Despite the fact that humiliation seems to be tied to humility, humiliation really belongs to the problematic of shame, and in particular, to the dynamic of debilitating shame. Distinguishing between humiliation and affliction, it is possible to assert that the latter appears within a religious or interpersonal context, and that it is this experience, namely, affliction, and not humiliation that can have a genetic relation to humility.
Notes
References Dōgen (2007). Sh ōb ōgenzō: The Treasure House of the Eye of the True Teaching (A Trainee’s Translation of Great Master Dōgen’s Spiritual Masterpiece). Transl. by Rev. Hubert Nearman, O. B. C. Mount Shasta: Shasta Abbey Press. Hagerty, Barbara Bradley (October 14, 2003). Papers Show Mother Teresa Felt Abandoned. National Public Radio. https://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyId=1464889. Jankélévitch, Vladimir (1986). Les vertus et l’amour. Ed. by Françoise Schwab. Paris: Flammarion. MacKendrick, Karmen (2008). Humiliated Subjects. In: L. Armand, J. Lewty, and A. Mitchell (Eds.). Pornotopia: Image, Apocalypse, Desire. Prague: Univerzita Karlova v Praze, 145–163. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1945). Phénoménologie de la perception. Paris: Gallimard. [Engl. Transl.: Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by D. Landes. London, New York: Routledge 2014.] Scheler, Max (1955). Die Demut. In: Maria Scheler (Ed.). Vom Umsturz der Werte. Gesammelte Werke, Vol. 3. Bern: Francke, 17–26. ––––– (1957). Ordo Amoris [=Schriften aus dem Nachlaß, Vol 1./ Gesammelte Werke, Vol. 10.]. Ed. by M. Scheler. Bern: Francke, 345–376.
378
Humility, humiliation and affliction Steinbock, Anthony J. (2014). Moral Emotions: Reclaiming the Evidence of the Heart. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Tangney, June Price, and Fischer, Kurt W. (Eds.) (1995). Self-Conscious Emotions: The Psychology of Shame, Guilt, Embarrassment, and Pride. New York: Guilford Press. Taylor, Gabriele (1985). Pride, Shame and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Theresa, Mother (1995). A Simple Path. Ed. by Lucinda Vardey. New York: Ballantine Books. Weil, Simone (1963). Attente de Dieu. Paris: La Colombe. [Engl. Transl.: Waiting for God. Transl. by E. Craufurd. New York: Perennial Classics 2001.] ––––– (1988). Le pesanteur et la grâce. Paris: Librairie Plon. [Engl. Transl.: Gravity and Grace. Transl. by E. Crawford, and M. von der Ruhr. New York, London: Routledge 2002.]
379
33 DISGUST Sara Heinämaa
1. Introduction Disgust is usually characterized as a strong negative emotion, more concretely as an aversion accompanied by intense, even violent, bodily reactions. The bodily aspects of disgust are taken to include nose wrinkling, retraction of the upper lip, gaping, convulsions, gagging and nausea. Many theorists contend that such bodily tendencies are universally shared by all humans (or primates more generally) (cf. Demmerling and Landweer 2007, 93–95). The putative fact is explained ontogenetically by early child-development and phylogenetically by the mechanisms of species evolution (e.g., Darwin 1872; Rozin and Fallon 1987; Rozin et al. 1993, 757). This does not entail that all human beings in all cultures and at all times would reject the same objects as disgusting, but merely that when humans reject something as disgusting, they do so by the same or very similar facial gestures and bodily movements.1 The intentional content of disgust involves a disturbing or threatening focal object given either perceptually or imaginatively to the experiencing subject. The experienced threat is specific in depending on the vivid presence of the object (cf. Kolnai 1929, 40ff., 78–80; Demmerling and Landweer 2007, 95). When we hear that a callous criminal has broken loose from the city prison, we tend to be alarmed and feel fear even when we have no visual or auditory evidence of the vicinity of the person. In contrast, slimy substances and obsequious behaviors elicit disgust only when actually detected, directly perceived or vividly imagined. Disregarding such a difference, disgust resembles fear in that its focal object menaces the subject in a thorough and comprehensive way, bodily and mentally. Moreover, both emotions easily transfer from one object to another. Having been attacked by a bull, a person may dread all cattle; and a person disgusted by spiders may also be alarmed by other arthropods. The center of attention of the two emotions differs, however: whereas the frightened is concerned about the very being of the object (actual or possible, present or future), the disgusted is more troubled by the object’s manner of being. Moreover, the experiencing subject is given in different ways in fear and disgust: fear brings the subject, her well-being and survival into focus, but disgust is fixed on an external object and involves only a marginal awareness of the subject (cf. Korsmeyer and Smith 2004, 8–9; Korsmeyer 2008). These differences in the intentional content of the two emotions manifest in characteristic behaviors: a person struck 380
Disgust
by fear tends to look for escape routes or hiding places, or, when petrified by the emotion, tends to cower; the revolted, in contrast, cannot but stare at the disturbing thing. Disgust differs from other negative emotions also in having a great variety of intentional objects. On the one hand, human beings tend to be disgusted by many different sorts of material substances and things. This category involves various objects characterized by brute materiality: feces, waste, sewage, corpses, carrions, wounds and bodily fluids (pus, clot, snot, spittle, urine, vomit). Also many sorts of animals belong in this category: rats, snakes, maggots, spiders and a mixed group of insects, including cockroaches and grasshoppers. On the other hand, disgust may also be inflicted by human behaviors and actions. The objects of this category involve both manners of behavior and types of agency: compromise, treachery and betrayal; laziness, idleness and obsessions of different kinds; weaklings, traitors and devious criminals. This duality of disgust elicitors is often conceptualized by the distinction between ‘physical disgust’ directed at natural substances, matters, things and processes, and ‘moral disgust’ directed at human behaviors and actions. However, the terms ‘physical’ (or ‘visceral’) and ‘moral’ are also used to distinguish between forms of aversion accompanied by strong bodily reactions and merely verbal reproach without visceral convulsions.2 Several contemporary philosophers discuss the role of disgust in racism, sexism and homophobia and other forms of social and political discrimination.3 Martha Nussbaum argues in Hiding from Humanity (2006) that disgust is a dehumanizing emotion that tends to strip its human targets from their capacities and aspirations and from their individuality and reduces them to lower forms of life. Nussbaum criticizes disgust-ridden behavior by arguing that disgust depends on projective psychological mechanisms that prompt us to attribute to others those aspects of our own existence that we experience as most disturbing: dependency on others, vulnerability and mortality. Furthering this line of thought, Nussbaum argues that disgust is a seriously detrimental emotion since its projective mechanisms allow us to disregard or belittle our factual condition and reject it as a weakness in others, but also, and more viciously, since its mechanisms serve attacks against marginalized and powerless groups of individuals (e.g., Nussbaum 2006, 14–16, 89, 114, cf. Nussbaum 2010, 2013). Many theorists agree with Nussbaum in criticizing disgust as a profoundly harmful emotion. Whereas shame and guilt are taken to have potentially constructive social implications, disgust is seen as an essentially destructive feeling. The analytical concepts and the critical methods used in putting forward such arguments, however, greatly vary. In her Cultural Politics of Emotion (2004), Sara Ahmed argues that human bodies and human behaviors become disgust elicitors on the basis of the social-historical processes of stigma-creation that operate by circulation, repetition and accumulation of affective signs. In The Anatomy of Prejudices (1996), Elisabeth Young-Bruehl resorts to the Freudian theory of libidinal economies and distinguishes between different personality types disposed to different forms of emotive bigotry and fanaticism. More recent studies have drawn attention to the fact that disgust is not just operative in the segregation, marginalization and exclusion of groups but that it also has an intensifying or amplifying role in collective acts of persecution, mass perpetration and genocide (e.g., Munch-Jurisic 2015, 2018; cf. Cavarero 2018). However, some theorists have argued that disgust has a constructive role of in the evaluation and ranking of socially or morally offensive or unacceptable forms of behavior and types of action (e.g., Kahan 1998; Miller 1998). Nussbaum rejects these proposals by arguing that the strong tendency of disgust to transfer from harmful things and actions to persons and groups of persons is more detrimental than any minor advantage that the emotion may have in intensifying proper moral sentiments, such as indignation or anger (e.g., Nussbaum 2006). 381
Sara Heinämaa
2. Theorizing disgust The main difficulty in providing a philosophical account of disgust lies in the fact that the emotion is highly various and ambiguous, both in its motivations and functions and in its intentional content. One general strategy in the theorization of disgust has been to identify a set of core objects—substances, elements, materials, things or processes—that paradigmatically inflict disgust, and then argue that other disgust elicitors are extensions of this class of “core elicitors.” Theorists have introduced various psychological, social-cultural, historical and symbolic processes and mechanisms to explain how such extensions become possible and are motivated and realized. These processes include association, analogy, condensation, displacement, symbolization and projection.4 One dominant strategy is to argue that all disgust experiences originate, in one way or another, from rejection of spoiled food and/or viral substances (e.g., Rozin and Fallon 1987; Rozin et al. 1993; cf. Oaten et al. 2009; Curtis et al. 2011). The other explanatory strategy is to contend that disgust originally guards our bodily boundaries and is thus paradigmatically focused on bodily orifices and their secretions and excrements (e.g., Freud 1910–1905; Jones 1912; Angyal 1941; Kristeva 1980). Third, it has been suggested that disgust is paradigmatically elicited by animals that spread diseases or threaten the cultivation of crops, such as rats, pigeons, cockroaches and grasshoppers. In this account, the core elicitors of disgust would be pests and parasites. The cognitive psychologist Paul Rozin has developed a highly influential explanatory paradigm centering on the concepts of contamination and magical thinking (cf. Rozin and Fallon 1987; Rozin et al. 1993, 757). Rozin and his colleagues argue that disgust has a species-specific core form in the rejection of potentially contaminating nourishment but, in addition to this, also culture-specific variants in which specific foods and other substances, but also human behaviors, are rejected as potentially contaminating. Rozin’s account is cognitivist in suggesting that disgust essentially involves a magical belief in the viral powers of its object. Several theorists and critics of disgust build on this contamination-theoretical corner-stone (cf. Nussbaum 2006, 2010, 2013; Kelly 2011). The problem with such explanatory accounts and hypotheses is that they tend to be experientially selective. Whereas some cases of felt disgust are handled in detailed analyses and cogent explanations, other cases are omitted as insignificant, and without proper arguments. Rozin, for example, dismisses a prominent class of disgust elicitors consisting of spiders and harmless insects and characterizes them as “anomalous animals” (Rozin et al. 1993, 760). Such approaches can be said to be experientially inadequate in so far as they sacrifice phenomena for the unity of explanation (cf. McGinn 2015). Phenomenological accounts of disgust differ from explanatory approaches—both causal and functional—in aiming primarily at a comprehensive description that covers all prominent experiences of the emotion as well as their various intentional objects. Such accounts look for common structural features shared by all cases of disgust, both at their subjective (noetic) and objective (noematic) sides. Rather than offering an account in terms of common origins or root forms, phenomenologists put forward claims about the common structures and modes of organization of experiences, that is, isomorphisms. Another characteristic factor of phenomenological approaches is that many of them entail the idea that disgust is directly founded on perception and does not entail acts of believing or judging. If this holds, then disgust would not involve any beliefs about its object, its viral powers or role as a contaminant. On the basis of such analyses, phenomenologists tend to question both contamination theories of disgust and cognitivist approaches to emotions. 382
Disgust
3. Kristeva’s concept of abject and Sartre’s discourse on the slimy Many contemporary discussions of disgust build on Julia Kristeva’s theory of abjection as developed in Powers of Horror (1980) and related works. The emotional reactions and attitudes that Kristeva describes by her concept of abjection are not distinguished by their strength or intensity. What defines this category of the affective and emotive responses is their intentional structure and experiential genesis, not their force. Kristeva argues that abjection and emotional reactions to abject things and processes are experientially not motivated by prospects of infection, sickness or death. What is at issue is not death and mortality as such but the unstable borderline between life and lifeless matter and our task of maintaining this border, necessary for our existence as bodily subjects (1980, 3; cf. Demmerling and Landweer 2007, 95–96; Cavarero 2018, 131–133). In phenomenological terms, we can say that in instances of abjection something in the world—a thing, a process, a behavior—is presented in a way that undermines or endangers the division between life and the non-living. This can happen when something traverses between these two experiential fields, when something undergoes a transformation from one mode of being to another, or when something combines features from both realms in an unexpected way. Thus, the category of the abject is broad and includes many different kinds of material entities and processes, from bodily fluids and waste products to parasites and vermin. Moreover, we may also reject in abjection human behaviors and modes of agency that are socially or morally questionable. In Powers of Horror, Kristeva summarizes: “The inbetween, the ambiguous, the composite. The traitor, the liar, the criminal with a good conscience, the shameless rapist, the killer who claims he is a savior” (Kristeva 1980, 4, cf. 69). On psychoanalytical and semiotic grounds, Kristeva argues that abjection is always ambivalent, including opposite values or valences. The main experiential component is a clear rejection or refusal of the abject thing or process, but this is always accompanied by a peculiar fascination which is foreign to other negative emotions, for example, anxiety, fear and anger. We turn away from and take distance from the abject, but at the same time it draws and attracts us; we rebuff it, but we also feel an alluring force that resides in it. Thus, we do not distance ourselves from the abject in order to simply leave it behind, but in order to establish a proper boundary between ourselves and it. In Kristeva’s account, this ambivalence bears traces of our pre-verbal struggle for identity and differentiation, more concretely, for separation from our bodily contact with our caretakers, paradigmatically from the maternal body. Kristeva argues that human infants must make considerable efforts to break the vital strings and contours that sustain their early existence, already long before any verbal tools are available to them, and already before entering any social roles or positions. Thus understood, abjection involves a non-conceptual bodily “memory” or “trace” of the primary struggle for separation and identity (Kristeva 1980, 13). One of Kristeva philosophical sources in the theorization and explanation of the a mbivalent character of abject phenomena is Sartre’s Being and Nothingness (1943). Kristeva does not draw directly from Sartre’s account, but she inherits Sartrean insights through one of her central sources. This is Mary Douglas’ anthropological classic, Purity and Danger: An Analysis of the Concepts of Pollution and Taboo (1966), that deals with the cultural boundaries between purity and impurity, from the dirty and polluted to the defiled, the mixed and the tabooed. In Chapter 2, titled “Secular defilement,” Douglas resorts to Sartre’s analysis of the slimy (viscous) when theorizing the ambivalent character of tabooed phenomena: “The viscous is a state half-way between solid and liquid. It is like a cross-section in a process of change. There is no gliding on its surface. Its stickiness is a trap, it clings like a leech” (Douglas 1966, 39). 383
Sara Heinämaa
Douglas’ reference here is to the very last sections of Being and Nothingness, in which Sartre outlines a new philosophical approach that he calls “psychoanalysis of things” (psychanalyse des choses). Sartre is not concerned with psychological images, memories or phantasies of individual persons nor with social-cultural distinctions but aims at capturing modes of being that belong to things themselves as they are given in experience.5 His analysis is existential-phenomenological and concerns the givenness of things (Sartre 1943, 645–647/764–766; cf. Dalí 1932).6 To concretize his new type of philosophical-experiential inquiry, Sartre develops an exemplary inquiry into the quality of the slimy. The inquiry confronts us with a type of repulsion directed at various objects, including concrete items and abstract entities, material things and mental states and attitudes. Sartre’s examples accentuate the variety of the phenomenon: pitch, tar, honey, syrup, melted sugar, oysters, raw eggs, snails, leaches, fungi, mollusks, bogholes, quick sand, liars, weaklings and deceivers (Sartre 1943, 650–652/770– 773; cf. Kolnai 1929, 48, 55). As conceptualized by Sartre, slime is “a substance between two states,” an intermediate mode of being between solidity and fluidity (Sartre 1943, 654/774; cf. Kolnai 1929, 49–51). Thus characterized, slime is exemplified by the movements of coagulating liquids that have started to solidify, have lost their quickness and freely flowing character, but have not yet reached the firmness and rigidity of solid objects. As such, slime is a thickening, dense and viscous fluid, yielding but deceptive. Sartre, like Kristeva, stresses that the aversion elicited by abject slime must not be assimilated with the fear of death or with the anguish inflicted by our own mortality. Rather, what is at issue for Sartre is the horror (horreur) of the possibility that consciousness (beingfor-itself ) could be arrested by materiality (being-in-itself ) and could lose the projective openness of its temporality. Thus, whereas Kristeva’s analysis suggests that the emotion of disgust is evoked by any kind of transgression of the cultural and symbolic border between the living and the dead, inside and outside, Sartre argues that all slimy phenomena involve the specific mode of being that looms between self-governed free activity and inert matter (cf. Demmerling and Landweer 2007, 97). Sartre’s discussion of slime is influenced by the French literary tradition, but it is also significantly indebted to earlier phenomenological inquiries. The most important source here is Aurel Kolnai’s treatise On Disgust (Der Ekel) from 1929.7 Sartre did not study Kolnai directly, but he was exposed to Kolnaiean themes and conceptualizations through the works of Salvador Dalí, Louis Buñuel and Georges Bataille, who all were readers of Kolnai and applied his descriptive and analytical results in their own essayistic and artistic projects (Margat 2000; Radford 2004; Menninghaus 2012, 363; cf. Dalí 1930, 1932; Buñuel 1982). My aim here is not to focus on the historical connections of influence between these thinkers. Rather, I want to argue that with the help of Kolnai’s analyses we can further illuminate the intentionality of disgust and sharpen the phenomenological description of the emotion.
4. Kolnai’s phenomenological analysis of disgust The main analytical outcome of Kolnai’s essay concerns the peculiar intertwining of life and death that characterizes experiences of disgust. What disgusts us ultimately, Kolnai argues, is the disintegration of purposeful life into extravagant proliferation or excessive growth. The intentional object of the experience is “surplus of life (...) [not] structured by purpose” (Kolnai 1929, 72, cf. 57–62). The phenomenon has two faces, so to say: on the one hand,
384
Disgust
boundless regeneration and, on the other hand, the inner tendency of life to collapse in superfluity (Kolnai 1929, 53–65; cf. Kosmeyer and Smith 2004; Knapp 2007; Korsmeyer 2008; Šinkūnas 2017a, 2017b). The paradigm here is the rotting, putrefying corpse, but Kolnai’s account emphasizes that the focus of disgust experiences is not on the dead body as such but on the extravagant life that feeds on the body and multiplies without boundaries or directions. Pullulating maggots and swarming flies are thus central to the imagery of disgust. They signal superfluous fertility, excessive vitality and unbounded energy (Kolnai 1929, 50–56, 62–63, 72–74). The core structure here is not just the interconnection of two dynamic processes— directionless life feeding on death and death endlessly lurking in life—but rather the flip from one process to the other, the verge or the peak past which one course turns into another (Šinkūnas 2017a, 238ff., 2017b, 10). Thus conceived, disgust is a dynamic double phenomenon that in a disturbing way combines two modalities of living and a transformation from one to the other: on the one hand, purposeful human existence organized by goals and means, and on the other hand, extravagantly flourishing life that mushrooms without boundaries (cf. McGinn 2011). Separately, neither of these two phenomena is able to elicit feelings of disgust, but when juxtaposed and connected in a particular manner they are bound to evoke the type of repulsion-attraction characteristic of disgusted aversion. Thus, rapidly dividing and replicating mitotic cells observed through a microscope or viral growth simulated on a computer screen are not experienced as disgusting, since they lack this dual structure. In contrast, a cadaver coated by pullulating maggots, a corner of a room infested by harvestmen and even an isolated light source surrounded by swarming moths would all be disgust elicitors in Kolnai’s analysis since they display the dual pattern of purposefulness, on the one hand, and directionless energy of life, on the other. Moreover, what is equally crucial to disgust as this juxtaposition is the dynamic temporal structure of the phenomenon. In the paradigmatic case, extravagant growth first spurts and with such vigor that it seems to be prolonged endlessly; but then suddenly, as fast as it first appeared, the growing mass disintegrates and vanishes, displaying an emptiness. This Kolnaiean analysis of the intentionality of disgust further illuminates the crucial factor that both Kristeva and Sartre stress: disgust is not about fear of death or about abhorrence of corpses; nor should it be assimilated with anxiety about human mortality or vulnerability. It is a more complex aversion that concerns disproportional intertwinements of life and death (Kolnai 1929, 53ff., 1998, 102; cf. Cavarero 2018, 132–133). But even more specifically, and in contrast to Kristeva and Sartre, Kolnai’s analysis demonstrates that disgust is not just about any kind of imbalance but about a specific type of disproportion: extravagant, profligate or wasteful expenditure of life forces, behaviors in which the goals and the means, the what and the how, get out of proportion. Kolnai’s essay also clarifies the complexity of the subjective side of disgust. We have seen that on the objective side of the experienced phenomenon, life and death penetrate one another in disturbing proportions. On the subjective side, the experience is correspondingly characterized by an ambivalence: disgust alternates between repulsion and attraction and is able to combine instantaneous, even violent rejection with persisting fascination. Kolnai calls “macabre allure” the force by which disgusting things and processes draw us while at the same time provoking our revulsion. On the one hand, disgust-elicitors command us to eject, expel and distance, but concurrently they captivate our interest and order us fix our gaze upon them. We are drawn to inspect their details and scrutinize their sensible qualities
385
Sara Heinämaa
(Kolnai 1929, 39–43; cf. Knapp 2007, 524). As such, the disgust experience resembles desire or, better, it betrays “a shadow of desire for intimacy,” as Kolnai himself formulates (1929, 46). Alluringly, the object suggests that the subject could “lay hold of [it] whether by touching, consuming or embracing” (Kolnai 1929, 43).
5. From “anomalous animals” to shameless criminals In this last section of this chapter, I will develop Kolnai’s analysis of disgust by adding two new insights with the aim of finding deeper unity in the experimental field of disgust elicitors. The first insight comes from my own work in phenomenology of embodiment. It concerns the group of disgust elicitors which Rozin calls “anomalous” on the basis that they do not fit neatly in any explanatory paradigm. My argument is that in order to find a unity in the phenomenal field of disgust elicitors we need to pay attention not merely to the entities at issue or their powers but more importantly to their manners of movement and behavior. I will suggest that the intentional content of disgust has a dynamic perceptual gestalt. On the basis of this insight, I want to argue that moral disgust is an emotive reaction directed at manners of behaving and acting rather than action types or motivations of actions. Thus, I will ultimately argue that moral disgust is an adverbial emotion, and structurally similar to physical disgust since both concern manners and modes of discernible behaviors or activities. Let us start with the case of the “anomalous animals,” that is, with the mixed group of spiders, harvestmen and insects, that do not seem to fit in any explanatory and theoretical paradigm of contemporary disgust studies. It seems to me that if we are able to spell out how the givenness of these beings resembles those of slimy substances and decomposing bodies, then we get a new grip on the intentional content of the emotion of disgust. I will build on Kolnai’s idea of disproportional and extravagant life but will add insights from my earlier work in phenomenology of embodiment that clarify the role of movement in the constitution of the sense of alien life (Heinämaa 2014, 2018). I will argue that what is crucial to disgust is the manner of the movement or behavior witnessed (cf. Kolnai 1998, 102). In other words, disgust is not focused on what the animal does or what results from its behavior but on how it behaves and moves. Accordingly, the object of disgust is not grasped in cognition or belief, and it is not rejected on the basis of everyday or magical reasoning about causes and effects. Rather, the object is immediately grasped in perception (or imagination), as it appears in the proximate perceived environment. This does not imply that the object of disgust would be simple. Rather, it has an intricate and dynamic gestalt structure, a characteristic organization with a focal center and non-thematic margins, as well as internal and external horizons, and it is associated with other percepts by isomorphism (cf. Kolnai 1929, 29–30, 47, 80).8 On this account, the trouble with insects and spiders is not, as the contamination-theorists and many cognitivists suggest, that they would be considered polluting or contaminating or associated with such processes. In Kolnai’s analysis, repulsion characteristic of disgust is fundamentally not triggered by any beliefs or cognitions about the harmfulness of these entities or about their causal role in the spreading of diseases and death—real or imagined, verifiable or magical (Kolnai 1929, 31, 39–40, 48–49, 1998, 100–101; Johnston 2001, 84ff.; Charles 2004). In order to be repulsed or disgusted by swarming flies, by pullulating maggots or by wobbly masses of spiders one does not have to have any biological, physiological or medical beliefs about these invertebrates or their powers. Disgust may immediately be inflicted by the
386
Disgust
movements of the creatures, given to us in straightforward perception (or imagination), free from magical notions about influence at a distance and everyday beliefs about viral powers. The notion that disgust is directly founded on perception and not on any type of judgment, cognition or belief, is one of the main results of Kolnai’s analysis. I agree with Kolnai on this basic point but wish to develop it further by adding two arguments: first, that disgust-eliciting percepts have a dynamic gestalt form, and second, that the focus of perception in disgust is not on any particular behavior or type of behavior but on the manner of behaving or being (So-being, Sosein) (Kolnai 1929, 34, 44–47, 74–77, 1998, 99–100). So, what in the movements of invertebrates is disturbing in the particular manner that involves attraction? Ordinary language offers clues that help us focus on experientially crucial aspects. We have already used some verbs to characterize these beings, pointing out that they “swarm” and “pullulate.” When we add more terms—such as “wriggling,” “buzzing,” “quivering,” “scrambling,” “fluttering,” “throbbing” and “pulsating”—we can detect a perceptual pattern. Two aspects stand out. First, when we observe insects, for example bees or ants in their ‘daily business’—collecting honey, dragging food crumbles, cutting leaves or carrying their larvae from one place to another—we are usually able to detect aims and goals in their movements. But when we see the same creatures gathering in great quantities or swarming around a covered thing, their movements do not present any evident goals or purposes (cf. Kolnai 1929, 56–58). Such a structureless aggregate is at the nucleus of the ant scene of Dalí and Buñuel’s The Andalusian Dog, but the same emotive content also informs the very last clip of Hitchcock’s Birds (1963) in which the main characters cautiously get in a car at dawn and slowly drive away, crossing a bird-infested landscape. The gestalt is specific in having a center around which the energetic animal movement revolves and cruises in unexpected ways and from which it seems to spread. Moreover, the moving mass of animal bodies covers this center or source and hides it from sight. Finally, when the mass dissolves, an emptiness is disclosed. Thus, the gestalt is spatial but also dynamic, with progress and duration. Second, when we study such living creatures collectively as a mass, their combined movements resemble those of glutinous liquids. The animal mass spreads slowly, like spilled gore or syrup, but it may also vanish unexpectedly in the ground and reappear without warning. It is plastic like resin and sticky like glue. Being able to split and divide, it can invade solids; it is capable of percolating through porous surfaces, membranes and pellicles, and entering insides protected by integumentary systems. Most critically, such movements threaten the orifices and openings of the human body (cf. Kolnai 1998, 101–102). On this Kolnai-inspired analysis, the connection between masses of insects (and masses of animals in general) and viscous liquids, crucial to the understanding of the feeling of disgust, is in their ways of moving and in the disturbing potencies that their movements indicate, and so in the dynamism of their movements. The relevant movement gives itself as purposeless or as merely aiming at (self-)proliferation, but at the same time also as exceptionally vigorous, cohesive and unexpectedly morphing. Such movements are displayed by rotting bodies, bodily fluids, saprophytes, colonies of insects and loathed forms of obsessed and addictive behaviors (cf. Kolnai 1929, 52–58). What is emotionally disturbing is unrestricted autotelic growth and extravagant behavior that uses life force for no other end than that of maintaining itself. I want to conclude by specifying the category of moral disgust on the basis of this preparatory analysis of physical disgust. For this end, I resort to a crucial distinction that Robert
387
Sara Heinämaa
Audi makes in his analysis of moral action. In his Means, Ends, and Persons: The Meaning and Psychological Dimensions of Kant’s Humanity Formula from 2016, Audi argues that for moral-theoretical and ethical purposes it is crucial to distinguish between three aspects of human conduct: (i) the action type, (ii) the motivations of the action, and (iii) the manner of performing the action (Audi 2004, 391–398, 2016, 55–56, 64, 151–152). Audi argues that all these aspects can be morally assessed or evaluated, and independently of one another. My hypothesis here is that moral disgust concerns not action types nor motivations of actions, but the manners in which actions are performed (cf. Kolnai 1929, 82–83). In order to clarify this idea, I want to return to Sartre’s and Kristeva’s formulations. We saw above that, in Sartre’s account, both innocent actions or types of actions and moral offences can be rejected as slimy: a handshake, a smile, a deception and a lie. Kristeva’s formulations concretize the idea further by specifying the kinds of actions and agents at issue: “The traitor, the liar, the criminal with a good conscience, the shameless rapist, the killer who claims he is a savior” (Kristeva 1980, 4; italics added). Both Sartre and Kristeva argue that disgust has social or socio-moral functions that are not all negative or destructive, as many contemporary authors argue. Moreover, Kristeva’s formulations give us an analytical clue by specifying the types of offences and offenders that typically inflict disgust. It is not just any criminals or wrongdoers who are rejected as abject but the ones who “act in good conscience,” the ones who proceed shamelessly and the ones who portray themselves as saviors. The attributive adjectives and adverbs are crucial here: Moral disgust is not focused on episodic actions, action types or agents. Rather, disgust is directed at actions that are performed in specific ways and agents who operate in particular manners. This highlights the fact that moral disgust is an adverbial emotion, and not a material one, being focused on the manner in which an action is performed rather than on the intentions, goals or motivations of the action (cf. Audi 2004, 292, 2016, 64).9 To give a concrete example: all lies are reprehended; ‘white lies’ may be tolerated with sympathy or with mixed feelings; ‘black lies’ are rejected in anger; it is only heartless lies that elicit disgust, such as the lies of Tom Ripley.10 Correspondingly, what is disgustingly disturbing in Hannibal Lecter’s case is not merely the amount of his victims or his ritualistic repetition of the crime, but Lecter’s culinary, elegant and artistic attitudes toward his targets. Similarly, what is disgusting in Charles Manson’s destructive actions and chaos-oriented projects is not the goals of destruction and chaos as such. Such goals may elicit horror or fear and many other negative emotions, but not disgust. What elicits disgust is the quasi-political and quasi-religious tone that Manson gives to his projects and actions. The crucial aspect is not quantitative but qualitative, or adverbial in Audi’s terms. My point here is not to belittle the quantitative dimensions of mass murders or genocides, but to draw attention to the fact that human sentiments as well as the concepts describing them are specific in their functions: whereas some distinguish between types of actions and others between motivations of actions, still others focus on the manners in which actions are performed. More precisely, moral disgust is directed at the manner of behaving or way of acting, and can thus be characterized as an emotive response to the adverbial aspects of human behavior and action. As such, disgust would be a response to the experiential fact that the manner of behavior or action is not appropriate, but disproportional in respect to the action or action type at issue.11
388
Disgust
Notes
References Ahmed, Sarah (2004). Cultural Politics of Emotion. Edinburg: Edinburgh University Press. Angyal, Andras (1941). Disgust and Related Aversions. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 36(3), 393–412. Audi, Robert (2004). The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ——— (2016). Means, Ends and Persons: The Meaning and Psychological Dimensions of Kant’s Humanity Formula. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Buñuel, Louis (2013[1982]). My Last Sigh. Transl. by A. Israel. New York: Vintage. [Orig.: Mon dernier soupir. Paris: Robert Laffont.] Cavarero, Adriana (2018). “Destroy Your Sight with a New Gorgon”: Mass Atrocity and the Phenomenon of Horror. In: T. Brudholm, and J. Lang (Eds.). Emotions and Mass Atrocity: Philosophical and Theoretical Explorations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 123–141.
389
Sara Heinämaa Charles, David (2004). Emotion, Cognition and Action. In: J. Hyman, and H. Steward (Eds.). Agency and Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 105–136. Curtis, Valerie, Michaél De Barra, and Robert Aunger (2011). Disgust as an Adaptive System for Disease Avoidance Behaviour. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 366(1563), 389–401. Dalí, Salvador (1932). The Object as Revealed in Surrealist Experiments. This Quarter VIII(1), 197–207. ——— (1979[1939]). L’âne pourri. In: Dalí: Retrospective, 1920–1980, exhibition catalogue. Paris: Centre Georges Pompidou. Darwin, Charles (1872). The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. London: Murray. de Beauvoir, Simone (1949[1987]). The Second Sex. Transl. and ed. by H. M. Parshley. Harmondsworth: Penguin. [Orig.: Le deuxième sexe I–II, Paris: Gallimard.] Demmerling, Christoph, and Landweer, Hilge (20w07). Philosophie der Gefühle: Von Achtung bis Zorn. Stuttgart: Metzler. Douglas, Mary (2003[1966]). Purity and Danger: An Analysis of the Concepts of Pollution and Taboo. Collected Works, Volume II. London, New York: Routledge. Fanon, Franz (2008[1952]). Black Skin, White Masks. Transl. by R. Philcox. New York: Grove Press. [Orig.: Peau noire, masques blancs. Paris: Seuil.]. Freud, Sigmund (1953[1901–1905]). Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality. In: J. Strachey (in collaboration with A. Freud) (Ed.): The Standard Edition of Collected Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 7. Transl. by J. Strachey. London: The Hogarth Press, 125–246. [Orig.: Drei Abhandlungen zur Sexualtheorie. Leipzig und Wien: Franz Deuticke 1905.] Heinämaa, Sara (2014). The Animal and the Infant: From Embodiment and Empathy to Generativity. In: S. Heinämaa, M. Hartimo, and T. Miettinen (Eds.). Phenomenology and the Transcendental. London, New York: Routledge, 129–146. ——— (2018). Embodiment and Bodily Becoming. In: D. Zahavi (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 533–557. Johnston, Mark (2001). The Authority of Affect. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63(1), 181–214. Jones, Ernest (1948[1912]). Anal-Erotic Character Traits. In: Papers on Psychoanalysis. Boston: Beacon Press, 413–437. Kahan, Dan M. (1998). The Anatomy of Disgust in Criminal Law. Michigan Law Review 96(6), 1621–1657. Kelly, Daniel (2011). Yuck! The Nature and Moral Significance of Disgust. Cambridge, MA, London: MIT Press. Kim, David Haekwon (2001). Mortal Feelings: A Theory of Revulsion and the Intimacy of Agency. Doctoral Dissertation. Syracuse University. Knapp, Christopher (2007). Aurel Kolnai: On Disgust. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74(2), 523–526. Kolnai, Aurel (2004[1929]). Disgust. In: Aurel Kolnai: On Disgust. Transl. and ed. by B. Smith, and C. Korsmeyer. Chicago and LaSalle: MIT Press, III, Open Court, 27–92. [Orig.: Der Ekel. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, X, 515–569, 1929]. ——— (2004[1998]). Standard Modes of Aversion: Fear, Hate, and Disgust. In: Aurel Kolnai: On Disgust. Transl. and ed. by B. Smith, and C. Korsmeyer. Chicago and LaSalle: Open Court, 93–109. [Orig.: Mind 107(427), 581–596, 1998]. Korsmeyer, Carolyn (2008). Fear and Disgust: The Sublime and the Sublate. Revue internationale de philosophie 246(4), 367–379. Korsmeyer, Carolyn, and Smith, Barry (2004). Visceral Values: Aurel Kolnai on Disgust. In: Aurel Kolnai: On Disgust. Ed. by B. Smith, and C. Korsmeyer. Chicago and LaSalle: III, Open Court, 1–25. Kristeva, Julia (1982[1980]). Powers of Horror: An Essay on Abjection. Transl. by L. S. Roudiez. New York: Columbia University Press. [Orig.: Pouvoirs de l’horreur: Essai sur l’abjection. Paris: Seuil]. Margat, Claire (2000). Bataille et Sartre face au dégôt. Linges 1(1), 197–205. McGinn, Colin (2011). The Meaning of Disgust. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2015). Disgust and Disease. Emotion Review 7(4), 381–382. Menninghaus, Winfried (1999[2012]). Disgust: Theory and History of a Strong Emotion. Transl. by H. Eiland and J. Golb. Albany. New York: SUNY Press. [Orig.: Ekel: Theorie und Geschichte einer starken Empfindung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp 1999.] Miller, William Jan (1998). The Anatomy of Disgust. Harvard: Harvard University Press.
390
Disgust Mizrahi, Vivian (2018). Stench and Olfactory Disgust. In: C. Tappolet, F. Teroni, and A. Konzelmann (Eds.). Shadows of the Soul: Philosophical Perspectives on Negative Emotions. London, New York: Routledge, 86–94. Munch-Jurisic, Ditte Marie (2015). Perpetrator Disgust: An Inquiry into the Relationship between Body, Emotion and Mortality. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Copenhagen. ——— (2018). Perpetrator Disgust: A Morally Destructive Emotion. In: T. Brudholm and J. Lang (Eds.). Emotions and Mass Atrocity: Philosophical and Theoretical Explanations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 142–161. Nussbaum, Martha (2006). Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ——— (2010). From Disgust to Humanity: Sexual Orientation and Constitutional Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2013). Political Emotions: Why Love Matters for Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Oaten, Megan, Stevenson, Richard J., and Case, Trevor I. (2009). Disgust as a Disease-Avoidance Mechanism. Psychological Bulletin 135(2), 303–321. Prinz, Jesse J. (2010): The Moral Emotions. In: P. Goldie (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 519–538. Radford, Robert (2004). Aurel Kolnai’s “Disgust”: A Source in the Art and Writing of Salvador Dalí. In: Z. Balázs, and F. Dunlop (Eds.). Exploring the World of Human Practice: Readings in and about the Philosophy of Aurel Kolnai. Budapest, New York: Central European University Press, 327–333. Rozin, Paul, and Fallon, April E. (1987). A Perspective on Disgust. Psychological Review 94(1), 23–41. Rozin, Paul, Haidt, Jonathan, and McCauley, Clark R. (1993[2008]): Disgust. In: M. Lewis and J. Haviland (Eds.). Handbook of Emotions. New York: Guilford, 757–776. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1956[1943]). Being and Nothingness: A Phenomenological Essay on Ontology. Transl. by H. E. Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press. [Orig.: L’être et le néant: Essai d’ontologie phénoménologique. Paris: Gallimard]. ——— (1948[1946]). Anti-Semite and Jew: An Exploration of the Etiology of Hate. Transl. by G. J. Becker. New York: Schocken Books. [Orig.: Réflexions sur la question juive. Paris: Paul Morihien]. Šink ū nas, Tomas (2017a). Hidden Foundations of Disgust: Reevaluating the Existential Nature of Disgust. Horizon 6(2), 226–249. ——— (2017b). Making Sense of the Confused Defence Mechanism of Disgust: Reinterpreting Aurel Kolnai’s Essay Disgust (1929). Unpublished research manuscript, KU Leuven. Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (2008). Die Emotionen: Gefühle in der realistischen Phänomenologie. Stuttgart: Akademie Verlag. Young-Bruehl, Elisabeth (1996). The Anatomy of Prejudices. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Further reading Sartre, Jean-Paul (1964[1938]). Nausea. Transl. by L. Alexander. New York: New Directions. [Orig.: La nausée. Paris: Gallimard]. Tedeschini, Marco (2018) Disgust. In: International Lexicon of Aesthetics. Spring 2018 Edition, URL= https://lexicon.mimesisjournals.com/archive/2018/spring/Disgust.pdf, doi:10.7413/18258630010.
391
34 FEAR, ANXIETY AND BOREDOM Lauren Freeman and Andreas Elpidorou
Phenomenology’s central insight is that affectivity is not an inconsequential or contingent characteristic of human existence. Emotions, moods, sentiments, and feelings are not accidents of human existence. They do not happen to us. Rather, we exist the way we do because of and through our affective experiences. Phenomenology thus acknowledges the centrality and ubiquity of affectivity by noting the multitude of ways in which our existence is permeated by our various affective experiences. Yet, it also insists that such experiences are both revealing and constitutive of human nature. It is precisely this last point that marks an important distinction between a phenomenological study of affectivity and perhaps all others. For phenomenology, one cannot understand the nature of human existence without coming to terms with the character of affectivity, and at the same time, one cannot come to terms with the character of affectivity without understanding the nature of human existence. Practical and social engagements, scientific endeavors, familial and political interactions are all predicted on the fact that we are beings who are capable of being affectively attuned to ourselves, to the world, and to others. In this entry, we discuss Martin Heidegger’s and Jean-Paul Sartre’s respective accounts of affectivity. In the first section, we present Heidegger’s understanding of affective existence. In this context, we discuss the significance of moods and offer an analysis of the affective phenomena of fear, anxiety, and boredom. In the second section, we present an overview of Sartre’s account of emotions and advance a Sartrean interpretation of fear and boredom. We conclude by raising some brief concerns with both accounts.
1. Heidegger and affectivity Heidegger’s phenomenological account of affect is both novel and important.1 Moreover, it can be instructive both within the phenomenological tradition and also more generally within the context of conceptual and empirically informed studies of emotion (see, e.g., Ratcliffe 2008; Elpidorou 2013; Freeman 2014; see also Chapter 7 in this volume). This is because for Heidegger, affective experiences are far more robust than we typically think; contrary to many folk psychological conceptions of emotion, they are not just discrete states that we happen to occupy that are caused by our surrounding environment; rather, they are basic to and constitutive of human existence. According to Heidegger, what makes us human 392
Fear, anxiety and boredom
(or, Dasein) is not just that we are rational, social, or practical beings. In addition to being these things, we are also affective, specifically, ‘mooded’ beings. Moods shape the fabric of our being insofar as they are the condition for the possibility of experiencing a world of values and concerns (Elpidorou and Freeman 2015). Additionally, affective experiences are disclosive. On account of their disclosive nature, they make accessible to us the valence of situations thereby highlighting what is important for us. For Heidegger, it is through moods that the world is disclosed to us and that we find ourselves amidst worldly projects and social situations that matter to and that affect us emotionally. In what follows, we first situate Heidegger’s account of mood within the context of his project of fundamental ontology in Being and Time (BT).2 In order to do so, we briefly outline the role of Befindlichkeit (“attunement” or “disposition”) and Stimmung (“mood”) in Heidegger’s general account of human existence, discuss the relationship between the two, and consider how the former discloses the world. We then focus on the fundamental moods (Grundstimmungen) of anxiety and profound boredom; discuss why, for Heidegger, they are important; and try to make sense of the relationship between anxiety and fear, two “kindred phenomena” (BT 230/185).3
1.1. Befindlichkeit and Stimmung Heidegger’s account of mood unfolds systematically within the context of his project of fundamental ontology in BT, the aim of which is to ask the question of the meaning of Being. Heidegger answers this question with an analysis of the only kind of being for whom such a question arises, namely, human beings, or Dasein. Dasein is a unique kind of being insofar as its Being is disclosed (erschlossen) to it in various ways. Much of BT is an existentialontological analysis of how Dasein exists in the world, how its existence in the world is disclosed to it, and how it makes sense of the meaning of this disclosedness. Ontologically, Dasein is constituted by four basic structures of existence, or existentials— Befindlichkeit,4 understanding (Verstehen), fallenness (Verfallensein), and talk (Rede).5 These existentials are equiprimordially united in Dasein’s ontological structure, care (Sorge), which unifies and discloses Dasein’s being-in-the-world as temporal (BT 375/327, 293/249, 277/234). Each ontological structure manifests ontically through the ways in which Dasein finds itself (sich befinden) in the world. Dasein’s ontic and ontological dimensions are two different, yet related ways of understanding and articulating its existence: whereas the former refers to the necessary structures of its existence, the latter refers to the concrete aspects of its comportment to the world and to others. Befindlichkeit is a basic ontological structure of human existence that makes it possible for human beings to find themselves in the world in a way that holds meaning for and thus matters to them. It is one of the ways in which Dasein’s existence in the world is disclosed to it. Heidegger uses the term “Befindlichkeit” to denote the ontological character of a phenomenon, mood (Stimmung), that is ontically (i.e., in an ordinary manner) most familiar to us (BT 172/134). Thus, the terms “Befindlichkeit” and “Stimmung” name the same phenomenon, understood from different perspectives: the former, an ontological structure of Dasein’s existence, refers to a basic mode of existence in, and openness to, the world; the latter, the ontic manifestation of Befindlichkeit, refers to the various and specific ways in which Dasein can relate to and disclose the world. For Heidegger, Befindlichkeit is always manifested through mood and Dasein is always in some mood. As modes of a fundamental ontological structure, moods are both constitutive and disclosive of the way one exists or finds oneself (sich befinden) attuned to the world and of how one is faring in the world with others. Moods have an important, 393
Lauren Freeman and Andreas Elpidorou
underlying revelatory dimension in that they affect and to an extent, even determine, how things appear to us. Moods disclose three key features of Dasein’s existence to it: (a) its thrownness (Geworfenheit), (b) being-in-the-world as a whole, and (c) what matters to it.6
1.2 Fear, anxiety, and boredom For Heidegger, not all affective states are metaphysically on par; some have more primary disclosive powers than others. Those that do are called “fundamental moods” (Grundstimmungen) or “fundamental attunements” (Grundbefindlichkeiten) and constitute the most farreaching and primordial possibilities of disclosure in which Dasein is revealed to itself in some exceptional way (BT 226/182). Heidegger’s point in outlining such fundamental modes of existence is that they bring us closer to an understanding of both the meaning of Being as such and also of Dasein’s existence. In what follows, we begin by briefly discussing fear, an important, yet for Heidegger, ultimately inauthentic mood or affective state.7 We then focus on what Heidegger takes to be two fundamental affective experiences: anxiety (Angst), fear’s authentic relative, and profound boredom (tiefe Langeweile).8 We highlight some of the similarities between them and discuss how they both enable Dasein’s authentic existence. For Heidegger, fear (Furcht) is an affective experience that arises when one encounters something in the world that is fearsome or threatening: something that has as its kind of being either readiness-to-hand (Zuhandenes), presence-at-hand (Vorhandenes), or Dasein-with (Mitdasein). According to Heidegger, fear compels Dasein to turn away from itself, thereby preventing Dasein from being able to face its own existence (BT 229–230/184–185). Thus, in fear, Dasein fails to notice its thrownness and insofar as this is the case, it cannot take over its ground (in other words, it cannot authentically take over its possibilities as its own). Thrownness is a central feature of Dasein’s existence and as long as Dasein exists, it is always thrown (BT 223/179, 321/276, 344/297)—that is, it finds itself always in a specific material, embodied, social, political, historical, and ancestral situation that it did not choose, that is beyond its control, and that both grounds and delimits Dasein’s actions and possibilities. Dasein’s thrownness is revealed to it through moods, but in a peculiar way: moods disclose Dasein’s thrownness “in the manner of an evasive turning-away” (BT 175/136; cf. 230/185). That is, moods do not reveal our thrownness as a fact that can be apprehended or perceived. Instead, through moods, our thrownness is disclosed in our very tendency to turn away from it. In fear, this turning away is understood by Heidegger as both a fleeing and a falling (BT 230/185): we flee from our thrownness by evading our true self (who we were, are, and can be) and by falling into the “world” of concern we can, temporarily at least, ignore the weight of our existence (BT 233–234/189). Fear precludes one from becoming one’s authentic self (BT 373–374/325–326) and precisely because it does so, it is considered to be an inauthentic affective experience. In contrast to fear, anxiety carries for Heidegger greater existential and ontological significance and consequently, plays a much more important role in Dasein’s existential-analytic. A key difference between fear and anxiety is this: whereas that in the face of which Da sein fears is a determinate entity within-the-world (BT 230/185), that in the face of which Dasein has anxiety is not. What is threatening in anxiety does not have the character of a “definite detrimentality” (BT 231/186)—anxiety neither has a specific intentional object nor a determine cause. Moreover, it comes unannounced. That in the face of which one is anxious is “completely indefinite” (ibid.). In anxiety, the world of our everyday concern loses all significance, but not in the sense that it falls away from us as an absence (ibid.); rather, in anxiety significance is lost insofar as familiar entities appear foreign, disconnected from their 394
Fear, anxiety and boredom
ordinary uses and meanings (BT 393/343). As a result, one ceases to feel at home, one is unable to understand oneself, and one is thrown into a profound and uncanny crisis of meaning. From the fact that anxiety renders everything insignificant, one ought not to conclude that anxiety itself is a passive state of meaninglessness or insignificance: quite the opposite. The profound crisis of meaning that Dasein experiences in anxiety is not the end; rather, it initiates a transformation in Dasein’s existence. Anxiety throws Dasein back upon that which it is anxious about, namely, its own authentic potentiality-for-being-in-the-world (BT 232/187). More specifically, in anxiety, Dasein is brought to see itself for who it really is (BT 235/190–191): a thrown, fallen, finite being who is ever projecting its future possibilities and whose existence is oriented toward and also individuated by, its own death. Unlike fear, during anxiety, one does not flee from one’s thrownness. Even though anxiety, like fear, involves a turning-away, in anxiety one turns away from everydayness and turns toward one’s existence. In doing so, one finds oneself face-to-face with one’s “ownmost potentiality-for-Being” (BT 321/276). Heidegger writes: Anxiety makes manifest Dasein in its being towards its ownmost potentiality-for-Being, namely, its Being-free for the freedom of choosing itself and taking hold of itself. Anxiety brings Dasein face to face with its Being-free for the authenticity of its Being and for this authenticity as a possibility which it always is. (BT 232/188; see also BT 321/276) Moreover, and crucially, anxiety individualizes Dasein for its ownmost being-in-the-world, which projects itself authentically upon its possibilities. This individualization brings Dasein back from its falling, and makes manifest to it that authenticity and inauthenticity are possibilities of its Being. These basic possibilities of Dasein (…) show themselves in anxiety as they are in themselves—undisguised by entities in the world, to which, proximally and for the most part, Dasein clings. (BT 235/191) Though unannounced and unanticipated, Dasein’s authenticity is disclosed in this primordial sense in anxiety (BT 190/234–235). The capricious features of anxiety render it profound and ominous, particularly since it is unpredictable and inescapable. In the first half of his 1929–1930 lecture course The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude (FCM), Heidegger discusses profound boredom (in addition to two other forms of boredom), thereby broadening his account of Grundstimmungen in his oeuvre. Up until that point, Grundstimmungen had only been discussed in terms of anxiety, which played a key role in both BT and also in his lecture, “What is Metaphysics?” (1929). One of Heidegger’s aims in FCM is to delineate his conception of philosophy and metaphysics, already departing from the one presented in BT. Another aim is to develop his account of the fundamental mood (Grundstimmung) of boredom in terms of grasping the fundamental meaning of our being. Heidegger delineates three forms of boredom in this lecture. The first is becoming bored by something (Gelangweiltwerden von etwas), for example, an object, person, or state of affairs (FCM §§19–23); the second is being bored with something (Sichlangweilen bei etwas), where it is not immediately clear to Dasein precisely what is boring, but only that one is bored (FCM §§24–28). In what follows, we limit our discussion to the third type of boredom (FCM §§29–41), profound boredom (tiefe Langeweile), since it is both the most fundamental kind and also the one 395
Lauren Freeman and Andreas Elpidorou
that is central to Heidegger’s aim in the course. Unlike the first two forms of boredom, in profound boredom, nothing in particular is boring, nor is there any determinate cause of boredom or reason for being bored.9 And yet, everything bores us, even ourselves. The very construction that Heidegger uses to describe profound boredom—the impersonal, “it is boring for one,” where “it” (es) is the same subject found in expressions such as “it is snowing” or “it is cold”—expresses the depersonalized omnipresence of profound boredom (see, e.g., FCM §30). Neither I nor you experience this form of boredom; rather, in it, Dasein becomes an “undifferentiated no one” (FCM 135/203). Not only does Dasein lose all concerns and interests, but all identifying characteristics, histories, and projects fall away. Like anxiety, profound boredom is unbidden, overpowering, and all-encompassing. Moreover, in profound boredom, the passing of time is absent in that all three temporal dimensions (past, present, future) merge into a unified temporality. The experience of profound boredom reflects that of anxiety. During profound boredom, one experiences the complete withdrawal of beings. This loss of significance is ontologically important insofar as everything around and alongside us loses meaning, nothing carries any future prospects, and nothing relates to or gives meaning to our past (having-been). Thus, in profound boredom, Dasein becomes indifferent to who and what one was, is, and to who and what one will be. And yet, as with anxiety, what might appear to be a nadir of Dasein’s existence by leading to complete meaninglessness, is anything but. Profound boredom leaves Dasein empty and holds it in limbo, yet it also brings the potential for “an exceptional understanding” of the kind of being that Dasein is (FCM 136/205). This is because entrancement—the loss of all meaning and significance—results not only in the withdrawal of significance but also in the revealing of possibilities proper to Dasein. What is revealed to Dasein in this peculiar refusal is its freedom, and this revealing acts as a call for action (FCM 148–152/222–228). That is, in profound boredom, Dasein is called to resolutely disclose and appropriate itself, namely, to take action in the moment of vision (Augenblick), to choose what is properly its own, and to become the author of its own existential meaning (FCM 149/224) (for more detailed discussions of Heidegger and boredom, see De Beistegui 2003; Slaby 2014; Elpidorou and Freeman 2019). We can see then that there are important similarities between the Grundstimmungen of anxiety and profound boredom: first, both have distinctive revelatory functions, and second, both compel Dasein to face its own existence and to become authentic.
2. Sartre and affectivity Sartre addresses the topic of affectivity explicitly and in most detail in his Sketch for a Theory of Emotions. The Sketch might be the locus classicus of Sartre’s treatment of affectivity, yet it is not the only place in his work in which affectivity is discussed. In addition to a presentation of the notions of unreflective consciousness and pre-reflective self-awareness—both of which are necessary for understanding Sartre’s position on the emotions—The Transcendence of the Ego includes brief discussions of the nature of states (e.g., hate) and dispositions. The Imaginary enriches and extends Sartre’s account of the Sketch. It contains, among other things, a careful analysis of feelings and an exploration into the relationship between emotions and imagination. Being and Nothingness adds layers to Sartre’s earlier account of emotions by painting a vivid picture of human existence in its various concrete and interpersonal manifestations. Saint Genet, Critique of Dialectical Reason, and The Family Idiot provide indispensable insights into Sartre’s more mature views about the power of circumstances to shape human existence. And Sartre’s literary writings supply texture, specificity, and urgency to his philosophical approach to affectivity. 396
Fear, anxiety and boredom
It is not possible to offer a comprehensive account of Sartre’s views on affectivity in this entry (for a more detailed account, see Chapter 13 in this volume). Our aim is not completeness but rather accessibility and clarity. By focusing primarily on the Sketch, we explicate the most central themes of Sartre’s view on emotions and put them to use by offering a Sartrean interpretation of the negative emotions of fear and boredom.
2.1 Emotions as lived transformations For Sartre, emotions are embodied, enactive ways in which we exist in the world and engage with worldly objects, situations, others, and with ourselves. While experiencing an emotional episode, we could react to it by making the emotion the focal point of our consciousness or by becoming aware of ourselves as emoting subjects (STE 34).10 We could do that, and sometimes we do just that. Yet, for Sartre, emotions are not primarily nor most fundamentally reflective experiences. During emotional experiences, it is the world that is our primary concern, not our consciousness of it. And although we continue to be conscious of ourselves during emotional experiences, the form of awareness that characterizes emotions is pre-reflective (STE 35–37, 52, 61). Emotions are thus, first and foremost, ways of relating to and experiencing the world— “[e]motion is a specific manner of apprehending the world” (STE 35). But by apprehending the world emotionally, the world is transformed: “The onset of emotion is a complete modification of the ‘being-in-the-world’” (STE 63; cf. STE 54).11 Emotions thus mark an existential transition: through them our engagement with the world is modified. Before the onset of an emotion, our experience of the world is characterized by means-ends relationships. In this mode of existence, the “world around us […] appears to be all furrowed with straight and narrow paths leading to such and such determinate ends” (STE 39). Entities within it are perceived as calls for action. We find ourselves within a nexus of concerns, obligations, and possibilities. Such a world is both instrumental and deterministic. It is instrumental because, to attain the ends that one desires, one must first procure the means that lead to those ends. It is deterministic because there is a presumed order in the world; there are rules—physical, social, or otherwise—that one must obey. Due to its instrumental and deterministic character, our everyday concernful world can be inflexible. There will be occasions during which we will be unable to achieve the necessary means and consequently, our desired ends will remain out of reach. It is precisely when we find ourselves in such unyielding situations— situations in which our desires remain frustrated and our practical actions cannot resolve the difficulties that we face—that emotions arise. And they arise as a way of mitigating or even resolving the experienced difficulties (STE 39–40). Emotions are capable of offering a solution to the difficulties that we face only because the world that they usher in is unlike the one encountered in our concernful existence. During our emotional experiences, we “live it [the world] as though the relations between things and their potentialities were not governed by deterministic processes but by magic” (STE 40). Emotions modify our world, and do so profoundly. They confer onto situations and encountered entities new qualities. Importantly, they also alter the way in which the world itself is experienced—the world is no longer governed by instrumental rules and means-ends relationships. Precisely because emotions do not reveal a world that is deterministic and governed by instrumental rules, they are capable (at least, most of the time) of providing escapes from the difficulties that gave rise to them. A fit of anger is an escape from an argument not because it deals with the issue at hand but because one no longer needs to offer a response to the argument. One can yell and silence one’s interlocutor, or one can 397
Lauren Freeman and Andreas Elpidorou
just walk away. Anger magically absolves one of the responsibility of dealing with a difficult situation. Crying during sadness does something similar. It can offer us a respite from a difficult situation. It affords us a break and thus an escape because, at least temporally, it suspends the need to deal with the world. But the world of emotions is magical not only because emotions change the way in which we experience and relate to the world; it is also magical because of the peculiar manner in which they do so. The change that emotional consciousness brings about is not material: emotional conduct “is not effectual” (STE 41). Emotions change the world magically insofar as they change our consciousness of the world.12
2.2 Fear and boredom Emotions are embodied, enactive, and unreflective attempts to resolve insurmountable difficulties by changing the ways in which we relate to the world. By offering us a world in which deterministic means no longer hold, they strive to make the difficulties that we previously encountered disappear. A Sartrean characterization of any type of emotion requires the explication of at least two features of emotions: (i) the difficulty that gives rise to the type of emotion, and (ii) the manner in which the onset of the emotion attempts to resolve the difficulty. Consider fear. Sartre discusses fear in the Sketch (STE 42–43) and distinguishes between passive and active fear, both of which arise on account of the experience of a threat. Thus, what gives rise to the emotion of fear is the perception of a situation that is threatening to one’s well-being. Passive and active fear are both fear not only because they arise due to the perception of a threat, but also because they share a common aim: they both attempt to take care of the perceived threat when deterministic means fail us. If fear arises on account of the perception of a threat and if its aim is to negate that threat, then how does it attempt to fulfill its aim? In other words, what exactly is the magical transformation brought about by the onset of fear that carries the potential to resolve the experienced difficulty? Here is where the distinction between passive and active fear becomes pertinent. The two subtypes of fear are differentiated in terms of the manner in which they offer an escape from the perceived threat. In the case of passive fear, we cannot outrun the threat, nor can we escape it using ordinary means. So, we use the only means available to us: we negate it by negating our consciousness of it. We faint, thereby we make the threat disappear. I see a ferocious beast coming towards me: my legs give way under me, my heart beats more feebly, I turn pale, full down and faint away. No conduct could seem worse adapted to the danger than this, which leaves me defenseless. And nevertheless it is a behaviour of escape; the fainting away is a refuge. (STE 42) The transformation that passive fear brings about is the same as that which all emotions bring out: it is, according to Sartre, magical. Consequently, its power is limited. We negate the threat without materially changing the world. And that means that we do not really make the beast disappear. The beast is there; we simply do not perceive it. Whereas in the case of passive fear, we negate our consciousness in order to negate the threat; in active fear, we flee. Yet, in essence, the two are different manifestations of the same phenomenon. “Flight is fainting away in play,” Sartre writes (STE 43). And he adds that “it is magical behaviour which negates the dangerous object with one’s whole body, by reversing the vectorial structure of the space we live in and suddenly creating a potential direction on 398
Fear, anxiety and boredom
the other side” (ibid.). While fleeing, we have magically transformed our world so that it does not contain the threat. But of course, the threat still exists. By running away, we have at least temporarily forgotten about it. Out of sight, out of mind. It is tempting to think of fleeing as some kind of prudential or calculative action. We flee in order to escape. But as Sartre warns us, this would be a misunderstanding of the character of emotional consciousness. Fear is unreflective behavior. It is not a tool that we calculatedly employ; rather, we live the world through it. As a type of emotional consciousness, fear “is primarily consciousness of the world” (STE 34).13 Though boredom is not discussed in the Sketch, Sartre’s account could indeed be applied to it—in fact, given that Sartre’s account is a general account of affect, it ought to apply to boredom. A Sartrean explication of boredom would need to specify the difficulty that gives rise to boredom and the solution that boredom attempts to offer. The problem that gives rise to boredom is not difficult to discern. Boredom arises on account of the perception of a situation that is not meaningful, interesting, or captivating to us. The problem of boredom is, in other words, a perceived meaninglessness, lack of interest, or challenge. We wish to do something other than what is available to us. And when we find ourselves in such a difficult situation, we experience boredom. Being stuck in a meaningless or unengaging situation is the problem that gives rise to boredom, but what solution does it offers? Boredom is characterized by a feeling of dissatisfaction and involves a strong desire to engage in something else. During boredom, we cannot maintain our attention to the situation at hand; we mind-wander and alternative goals and situations, which we could pursue become salient to us. Time appears to be moving slowly and we undergo various physiological changes (see, e.g., Eastwood et al. 2013; Elpidorou 2018a). Ultimately, and because of the manner in which boredom is experienced, boredom modifies our situation: our situation loses its grip on us and is no longer meaningful or worth pursing. But unlike apathy, boredom is not a state in which we merely remain unengaged with our situation; instead, it repels us from our meaningless or unengaging situation. In sum, boredom transforms our world magically (Elpidorou 2015). It creates zones of interests and dullness. It delineates the meaningful and the fulfilling from that which is not. And it sets us in motion by pushing us out of our unsatisfactory situation. A Sartrean take on boredom safeguards one from assuming an overly negative take on boredom. Although boredom is potentially problematic and can be associated with a number of harms, it is not necessarily negative. Depending on the context and the manner in which one responds to it, boredom could serve as the means out of a difficult situation and into a better (i.e., more fulfilling) life (Elpidorou 2018b). By transforming our bodies and our consciousness of the world, the onset of boredom motivates the pursuit of an alternative situation when our current situation ceases to be meaningful, engaging, fulfilling to us. Sartre’s view on boredom, however, comes with a price: it appears to turn boredom into something more radical than what it is. Often, when we experience boredom, we are aware of it. We know that we are bored and we even think of ways to alleviate it. It is on account of our realization that we are bored that we fight off boredom. We go for walks, check our phone, and turn on (or off ) the television, all of which are means of making it disappear. If boredom involves a magical transformation, it is not one that strips our world of its means-ends relationships. The worry generalizes. It would appear that Sartre’s account of the emotions renders them disruptive: they do not permit us to relate to the world in instrumental ways. But is it always the case that we “lose our heads” in the midst of our emotions? For instance, couldn’t we be afraid and still act calculatedly? One might worry that Sartre’s account of emotions is too inflexible (we either exist in our concernful world or in the magical world of emotions) 399
Lauren Freeman and Andreas Elpidorou
or too radical (there are no “weak” emotions). It is often objected that the main weakness of Sartre’s account is that it does not apply to positive emotions—such emotions, critics point out, do not seem to be solutions to experienced difficulties (see, e.g., Fell 1965; Weberman 1996). But given our foregoing discussion, it appears that his views on negative emotions are also susceptible to criticism, for not all instances of negative emotions need to mark an existential transition. Perhaps Sartre’s account could be amended in a way that avoids these and other difficulties. Whether such a restorative project can ultimately succeed remains to be seen.
3. Conclusion Though Heidegger and Sartre adopt importantly different perspectives on affectivity, they both insist that it is a constitutive part of human existence. Furthermore, through their respective accounts, they highlight phenomenology’s ability to bring into clear view the significance of our affective experiences. But can the two accounts be rendered consistent with each other? Are Sartrean emotions compatible with Heidegger’s ontological claims? And do Heideggerian moods have a place in Sartre’s system? Although we cannot take up these issues in great detail here, we wish to conclude by raising a conciliatory suggestion: Sartre’s account appears to already utilize many of the philosophical resources that Heidegger derives from Befindlichkeit (and Stimmungen). The grounds of our emotions, according to Sartre, are experienced difficulties that we cannot overcome with pragmatic means. Such experiences are difficult precisely because they arise in situations that matter to us. Thus, emotions already presuppose that the world is meaningful to us; they are predicated on the fact that our existence matters to us. Seen in this light, Sartrean emotions appear to require something like Heidegger’s Befindlichkeit. The two philosophers are similar, however, in another, more problematic, respect: their accounts portray human existence as overly and almost exclusively negative. If, as Sartre maintains, all emotions (both negative and positive) are solutions to experienced difficulties, then emotions arise only when things go wrong for us. And if we accept Heidegger’s account of anxiety and profound boredom, then affectivity can lead to authentic existence primarily by bringing about a profound crisis of meaning, but cannot do so in extreme instances of joy, love, awe, hope, etc. Both philosophers, it seems, have neglected to investigate into the distinctive nature of positive affective experiences and to explore the transformative power and character of the various subtle shades of affectivity that define our existence. Even if neither one has taken up those important tasks in any detail, we can. In the case of affectivity, the phenomenological project must carry on.
Notes
400
Fear, anxiety and boredom
4 5 6 7
8
9 10 11 12 13
anxiety, or profound boredom without understanding how each is related to Dasein’s temporality. For our expanded discussion of the temporality of fundamental affective states, see Freeman and Elpidorou (2015). We leave Befindlichkeit un translated because no English term fully and adequately captures its meaning. For a lengthy discussion of this issue, see Elpidorou and Freeman (2015), note 4; see also Thonhauser’s discussion in his Chapter 7 on Heidegger in this volume. In several instances in BT, Heidegger excludes talk from the list of existentials (BT 235ff./191ff., 263ff./221ff., 401/350); in others, he replaces fallenness with talk (BT 172/133, 203/161, 342/296). In BT 384/335, however, he mentions all four. For an extended discussion of each of these three features, see Elpidorou and Freeman (2015). Though in BT §30, Heidegger claims that fear is a mood (Stimmung), we hesitate in following his lead. This is because a close reading of this section yields the conclusion that, despite what Heidegger writes, fear more closely resembles what we would consider to be an emotion (an occurrent, intentional state experienced by an agent). Heidegger himself even confirms that fear is more emotion-like than mood-like (BT 230/185). For a more complete argument, see Freeman (2014, 250–252). It ought to be underscored that Heidegger is not consistent with the use of his own terminology. He refers to anxiety as both “Grundstimmung” (BT 358/310; see also “What is Metaphysics?” in GA 9) and as “Grundbefindlichkeit” (for example, see BT 179/140, 227/182, 228/184, 233–235/ 188–190, 321/276, 393/342). Taking some interpretive liberty in the name of clarity and consistency, we will refer to anxiety as “Grundstimmung.” This is because the way that Heidegger describes it—namely, as a profound experience that brings us closer to authentic existence—it only makes sense for it to be a Stimmung (or experience of mood) and not a Befindlichkeit (structure of existence). This is because we cannot directly experience structures of existence. Moreover, there are a number of parallels between anxiety and profound boredom and the latter, according to Heidegger, is also a Grundstimmung and not a Grundbefindlichkeit. For a more robust consideration of profound boredom, in addition to the other two forms of boredom, see Elpidorou and Freeman (2019). All references to Sartre’s Esquisse d’une théorie des emotions will be indicated by STE followed by the pagination of the English translation. Sartre draws a distinction between two types of emotions on the basis of whether the transformation happens on account of our own doing or not (STE 57). The issue is discussed in detail in Elpidorou (2016). A more detailed presentation of Sartre’s account of emotions can be found in Elpidorou (2017). Sartre considers only one possible expression of passive fear (i.e., fainting), thereby neglecting to consider other expressions of this emotion. In fact, the most prominent expression of passive fear is freezing. To use Sartre’s own example, upon encountering the predator or ferocious beast, one would very likely and at least initially freeze: one would remain motionless and orient oneself with respect to the threat. Although it is easy to see how fainting could solve the difficulty that gives rise to fear—indeed, fainting appears to be a solution to every conceivable difficulty that one may experience—it is not obvious how freezing could offer us a solution. What exactly is the magical transformation that such behavior brings about? And how does it negate the perceived threat? Given that Sartre does not discuss this issue, the onus of explication falls on commentators (see Elpidorou 2016).
References De Beistegui, Miguel (2003). Thinking with Heidegger: Displacements. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Eastwood, John D., Frischen, Alexandra, Fenske, Mark J., and Smilek, Daniel (2012). The Unengaged Mind: Defining Boredom in Terms of Attention. Perspectives on Psychological Science 7(5), 482–495. Elpidorou, Andreas (2013). Moods and Appraisals: How the Phenomenology and Science of Emotions Can Come Together. Human Studies 36(4), 565–591. ——— (2015). The Significance of Boredom: A Sartrean Reading. In: D. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou, and W. Hopp (Eds.). Philosophy of Mind and Phenomenology: Conceptual and Empirical Approaches. London, New York: Routledge, 268–283.
401
Lauren Freeman and Andreas Elpidorou ——— (2016). Horror, Fear, and the Sartrean Account of Emotions. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 54(2), 209–225. ——— (2017). Emotions in Early Sartre. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 41(1), 241–259. ——— (2018a). The Bored Mind Is a Guiding Mind: Toward a Regulatory Theory of Boredom. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17(3), 455–484. ——— (2018b). The Good of Boredom. Philosophical Psychology 31(3), 323–351. Elpidorou, Andreas, and Freeman, Lauren (2015). Affectivity in Heidegger I: Moods and Emotions in Being and Time. Philosophy Compass 10(10), 661–671. ——— (2019). Is Fundamental Boredom Boredom? In: C. Hadjioannou (Ed.). Heidegger on Affect. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan, 177–203. Fell, Joseph P. (1965). Emotion in the Thought of Sartre. New York: Columbia University Press. Freeman, Lauren (2014). Toward a Phenomenology of Mood. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 52(4), 445–476. Freeman, Lauren, and Elpidorou, Andreas (2015). Affectivity in Heidegger II: Temporality, Boredom, and Beyond. Philosophy Compass 10(10), 672–684. Heidegger, Martin (1927). [=GA 2]. Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer [Engl. Transl.: Being and Time. Transl. by Macquarrie and Robinson. New York: Harper & Row 1962.] ——— (1983). [=GA 29/30]. Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik. Welt, Endlichkeit, Einsamkeit. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann. [Engl. Transl.: Basic Concepts of Metaphysics: World—Finitude— Solitude. Transl. by W. McNeill and N. Walker. Bloomington: Indiana University Press 1995.] ——— (1997). [=GA 9]. Wegmarken. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann. [Engl. Transl.: Pathmarks. Ed. by William McNeill, multiple translators. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1998.] Ratcliffe, Matthew (2008). Feelings of Being: Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the Sense of Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1939). Esquisse d’une théorie des emotions. Paris: Hermann. [Engl. Transl.: Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions. Transl. by P. Mairet. London, New York: Routledge 2004.] Slaby, Jan (2014). The Other Side of Existence: Heidegger on Boredom. In: S. Flach and J. Söffner (Eds.). Habitus in Habitat II: Other Sides of Cognition. Frankfurt: Peter Lang. Weberman, David (1996) Sartre, Emotions, and Wallowing. American Philosophical Quarterly 33(4), 393–407. Further reading Neuber, Simone (2017). Latent Moods in Heidegger and Sartre: From Being Assailed by Moods to Not Conceding to (Some) Moods that Assail Us. Philosophia 45(4), 1563–1574.
402
35 GRIEF Line Ryberg Ingerslev
What has taken refuge Your future in me becomes my purity through life, which I shall not touch – (Mallarmé, A Tomb for Anatole)
1. Introduction In many accounts of grief, the struggle to handle reality after losing a loved one is to be reconciled in a form of internalization of the deceased. As a way in which we attempt to keep our lost ones, we carry them with us in our narratives, in our vivid memories, in our rituals, and in our attempts to make sense beyond the lack of sense that is exposed to us by death. In his “Mourning and Melancholia”, Freud (1917) describes how we enter a twilight zone of reality-testing when we mourn the loss of a loved one. No longer finding our lost other, our whole conception of reality is distorted and disrupted. Reality testing is a process of coming to term with no longer finding the other, and consists of what Freud called Trauerarbeit, grief work. Thus, Freud and with him many others describe mourning and the result of a process of mourning as an internalization of the relation with the deceased: “Mourning is one way we recreate our past by making it present—sometimes as memory, sometimes as psychic structure” (Lear 2017, 196). In the psychoanalytic tradition, Lear here quotes Loewald, internalization refers to “processes of transformation by which relationships and interactions between the individual psychic apparatus and its environment are changed into inner relationships and interaction within the psychic apparatus” (ibid.). The idea of internalizing the deceased other as part of the self-transformation taking place in grief can be found in reports on how continuing bonds are kept with the deceased (Silvermann and Klass 1996; Higgins 2008; Attig 2011; Fuchs 2018) as well as in autobiographical reports (Lewis 1961; Didion 2005; Barthes 2009; Riley 2012). What we often find here are descriptions of how we hold on to our deceased loved one by integrating and incorporating them in our routines; we turn to them as guardians of a moral code we try to live by; we keep them in our narratives and remain in inner dialogue with them; we keep
403
Line Ryberg Ingerslev
saluting their existence by ways of honoring them in our doings (Nussbaum 2001; Solomon 2004; Kierkegaard 2009a; de Warren 2017; Ruin 2018). What does it mean philosophically to keep a bond with one’s ancestors and to incorporate a relation with a deceased? In order to reflect on these question, we must look at what kind of memory is at stake in grief and at what kind of psychic structure we experience, as we experience the death of the other. Do we in fact get to keep our dead ones in this way, that is, by incorporating them and by preserving an inner relation with them? One such account is offered by Thomas Fuchs (2018). Fuchs argues that incorporation and identification are ways in which we respond to grief; and at the same time, these are ways that allow us to lead an afterlife with the deceased other. This view provides an occasion for asking a more general question that is at the root of any grief: in responding to grief, how do we preserve the otherness of the other? That is, in keeping a bond with our deceased how do we avoid reducing them to fiction of our own imagination? What does a phenomenology of grief tell about relating to the dead?
2. Incorporation in the case of grief In his grief diary, C.S. Lewis (1961) writes that in his insistence on remembering exactly how his late wife was, he tends to forget her the most. He describes how already a month after her death, he has turned her into an imaginary woman, a phantom. Only when he tries not to mourn her, does he see her most vividly: “And suddenly, at the very moment when, so far, I mourned H. the least, I remembered her best. Indeed it was something (almost) better than memory; an instantaneous, unanswerable impression” (1961, 39). Although this problem is not restricted to deceased persons, it allows us to ask how we are to remember the dead. Fuchs describes the structure of grief as an experience of a “partial loss of oneself ” (see also Murray Parkes 2009; Ratcliffe 2017, 2019), since in grief I can no longer share the habituated and embodied world with the deceased other. The bench we used to sit on, the stories we used to laugh at can no longer be shared. The person who has lost a loved one is expressive of an embodied form of ‘being-with’ the other that results from the work of shared habits and life forms: despite the loss of the other and the loss of the meaning of our shared world, I keep expressing what can no longer be shared: our world. In this way, grief “like hardly any other psychic phenomenon” reveals how we are “fundamentally related to, and in need of, other” (Fuchs 2018, 48). According to Fuchs, the being-with that we experience differently when the other dies is constituted by two interdependent moments, namely self-expansion and identification. Self-expansion is defined by the way in which the other enables aspects of my self-realization, which I would not have had without her. Identification is defined as a way in which I adapt to the other by taking on his or her feelings such that they affect me as well as him (2018, 48–49). This model of an interfused self-other organism, described by Fuchs, leads us to the following question: if interdependent, what happens when a part of the intrapsychic organism dies? As Fuchs puts it: The question is “who am I now that my loved one is gone?” (…) Grief offers the chance to ultimately gain a new relation to the deceased and to resolve the ambiguity [of searching and not finding the other] in two complementary ways: the one means taking the lost person inward, namely through incorporation and identification, the other proceeds by way of representation, be it by recollection or by symbolization. (Fuchs 2018, 57)
404
Grief
Grief offers the survivor the “chance to ultimately gain a new relation to the deceased”. The new relationship consists in a twofold process: on the one hand, the survivor incorporates and identifies with the deceased; on the one hand, she represents the deceased other differently. The idea of gaining a new relation to the deceased is common place as part of the self-transformation that takes place in grief, as argued for instance by Freud, but also recently by Attig (2011), as a way in which we come to “relearn” our world. But Fuchs argues for something stronger. Taking the lost person inward, what would that mean? Apart from being a metaphor, the movement inwards is described as follows: When I identify with the deceased “the loved one is gradually incorporated, as it were, instead of being searched in vain outside” (Fuchs 2018, 57). The deceased becomes incorporated due to mimic appropriation and is granted an inner presence in me. It might be in my laughter, my gait or my daily routines that I mimic my lost friend or partner. As Fuchs describes it, the purpose of internalization is to stop the searching behavior that conflicts with reality; the other cannot be found in the outside world, but if we internalize the deceased within as an “inner comforting presence”, there will be no conflict any more: In the later stages of grief, the mimetic incorporation proceeds more subtly. One can frequently observe the appearance of traits of the deceased in the behavior of the bereaved. They may be observed or find themselves gesturing or walking in the same manner, or they may take over the loved one’s former habits, interests and activities by an often unconscious identification. (…) However, instead of the detachment or cutting the bonds of which Freud considered the purpose of grief work, it may rather lead to a new inner presence of the deceased which does not get in conflict with external reality any longer. The loved one is now “in me”, within my own field of emotional experience; still present, but as an inner, comforting presence, without having to be searched for or “found outside”. (Fuchs 2018, 57–58) The loved one is ‘in me’, the conflict is resolved, and my habits have enabled the transition; by identifying, taking over, repeating, and mimicking patterns, I have come to incorporate my deceased other. As for the second moment, that of representation and recollection, Fuchs holds that we can think of it as a way recollecting the past as past and no longer as an ambiguous presence of the other. Once representation is possible, say in the form of clear memories, rather than felt ambiguous presence, as might be the case very close to the actual death of the other, “the past may retain a consolatory indelibility: what we have shared and experienced together remains and cannot be extinguished” (2018, 58). In symbolic recollection, representation provides the deceased a place, be it in memorial space, in rituals, or in combination of these like in narratives about the deceased. The central forces at stake in this process are habit and memory. Through identification, we transform uncertainty into patterns of meaning where the deceased other can be kept as a form of inner presence. Meanwhile, memory allows us to narratively hold on to our deceased, while externalizing what is irreducibly something we have shared. In this way, it seems, we do keep our dead ‘alive’. With the death of a loved one, a joint sense-making has been disrupted; however, by practice of internalization, the joint aspect is artificially kept alive. But what is meant by the process of internalization, and how do habit and memory in narratives and repeated rituals allow us to capture and eventually control what we have lost.
405
Line Ryberg Ingerslev
In what follows, I will focus on two sets of problems. First, the term internalization has a psychoanalytic heritage, that Fuchs translates as incorporation and intersubjective bodily resonance (2018; see also Fuchs 2012, 2017). This translation, however, does away with the terminological ambiguity related to the technical term. I suggest to question the term on its own grounds in order to better understand how ‘incorporation’ is to be imagined. Second, the idea of representation in narratives, habits, and rituals seem to somehow affect the memory of the dead, namely turning it into an unchanging memory, into an invariable, timeless picture and thereby into sort of icon. While an icon is one way to preserve value, the problem consists in turning the icon into a ghost; the holiness of the picture ignores the horror of facing and accepting the death of the other. As a result, we might be stuck in obsessive rituals that allow the dead to ‘haunt’ us. As Lewis describes: All reality is iconoclastic. The earthly beloved, even in this life, incessantly triumphs over your mere idea of her. And you want her to; you want her with all her resistances, all her faults, all her unexpectedness. That is in her foursquare and independent reality. And this, not any image or memory, is what we are to love still, after she is dead. (Lewis 1961, 56) Can we keep the otherness of the other without turning her into an icon or a ghost, but rather into an ancestor, that is, a source of sense?
3. Abraham and Torok on incorporation A first set of problems announces itself simply by the term incorporation. As Abraham and Torok explain, the psychoanalytic term is ambiguous and referred to in different ways (1994, 110–116). As the authors describe it, incorporation has the following meaning in psychoanalysis: Introducing all or a part of a love object or a thing into one’s own body, possessing, expelling or alternately acquiring, keeping, losing it—here are varieties of fantasy indicating, in the typical forms of possession or feigned dispossession, a basic intrapsychic situation: the situation created by the reality of a loss sustained by the psyche. If accepted and worked through, the loss would require major readjustment. But the fantasy of incorporation merely simulates profound psychic transformation through magic; it does so by implementing literally something that has only figurative meaning. So in order to “swallow” a loss, we fantasize swallowing (or having swallowed) that which has been lost, as if it were some kind of thing. (Abraham and Torok 1994, 126) As a consequence of de-metaphorization, that is, of taking the figurative term literally, and of objectifying the loved object, “the magical cure by way of incorporation exempts the subject from the painful process of recognizing the loss” (Abraham and Torok 1994, 126–127). According to Abraham and Torok “[w]hen, in the form of imaginary or real nourishment, we ingest the love-object we miss, this means that we refuse to mourn and that we shun the consequences of mourning even though our psyche is fully bereaved” (1994, 127). What is important here is the idea that part of the incorporation consists in refusing to mourn. Identifying and incorporating the other can prevent us from realizing the loss we are suffering (1994, 130). That is, taking the deceased loved one inwards, be it by carrying on an inner dialogue, 406
Grief
be it in habitual patterns, invented rituals, or be it as a moral code to be consulted; some aspects of incorporation can prevent us from realizing the loss, and it can eventually cancel out the death of the other, as it were. What I will suggest is that we think of two possible ways of coming to terms with the absence that grief leaves us to face and with the idea of preserving a relationship with the deceased. As Fuchs suggests, internalization can be understood as an embodied practice of keeping the dead by affectively identifying with her, reproducing the habitual patterns that constituted our shared world, as we saw above. Here, the other is swallowed in the sense that he or she is made into a comforting presence, a being-with the other that cancels out the actual painful absence; we keep the other by repeating his or her gestures, expressions, stories, and values. By contrast, internalization could be understood in terms of being responsible for the other by way of surviving his or her absence. In this case, survival is something only I do; I remain alone, and surviving means carrying back into the world something that has no place in the world any more. In what follows, I will try to spell out how we can understand survival as a form of responsibility for carrying on the world (see also Derrida 2004, 8), not by taking the other inwards as a comforting presence, but by carrying outwards the meaninglessness that we experience in grief and thus by recommitting to the world.
4. Levinas and the pure question mark What is, for us, the mode of being of the dead other? How do we preserve the alterity of the other after her death? Put differently, how does absence actively modify our relation to the dead other. And what is the object of modification in the first place? As C.S. Lewis describes, he fears that his memories will inevitably change his picture of his beloved wife; due to the modification made by our way of recollecting, he fears that “the real shape will be quite hidden in the end” (Lewis 1961, 18). Our relation to the other is modified, not simply because the other is dead but also because memory keeps changing it: Ten minutes—ten seconds—of the real H. would correct all of this. And yet, even if those ten seconds were allowed me, one second later the little flakes would begin to fall again. The rough, sharp, cleansing tang of her otherness is gone. (Ibid.) The experience of absence questions our mode of survival and at the same time something or someone survives the absence. Survival calls us into question, and the modified relation is articulated as an experience of concern that has no place. The experience of the death of the other is tied to a disruption of responsiveness that leaves us only with the experience of a pure question mark, that is, with us having to relate to what Levinas calls “the unknown” (Levinas 2000, 18). Something is modified and modifies us; and the concern we are left with is articulated as a pure question mark. Let me unfold this idea. For Levinas, the other is “someone who expresses himself in his nudity—the face—is one to the point of appealing to me, of placing himself under my responsibility: Henceforth, I have to respond for him” (Levinas 2000, 12). First of all, this means that all the gestures of the other, conceived of in this way, are signs addressed to me. Address comes with being entrusted. I am never free of an infinite debt that comes with being entrusted in this way (ibid.). Being addressed by the other in his gestures is a way in which we exist responsively for-each-other. Before I directly perceive expressive gestures as meaningful, I am already addressed by the other. Being addressed is not a contingent happening; it is the structure 407
Line Ryberg Ingerslev
of my subjectivity. This can be understood as follows: The appeal, within the expressive gestures of the other, affects and calls me before they are perceived as meaningful in this or that way. My experience of your expressions is not first and foremost a matter of how you appear in my experience, structured in its for-me-ness, intentionality, and mineness; it is not a matter of which opportune self-realization you might enable; rather, the expressive body of the other interrupts a joint sense-making in addressing me first and foremost as a subject. Therefore, in the experience of bodily expressions, I do not identify with you, nor do we overlap in undifferentiated, bodily resonating interaffectivity (cf. Chapter 28 in this volume). Rather, as responsive subjects we exist as exposed and on the outside of ourselves, sensing ourselves by being sensed and subjected by others. To put it differently, we can say with Nancy that the body is the unity of a being outside itself. The unity of the coming to self as a “self-sensing” a “self-touching” that necessarily passes through the outside—which is why I can’t sense myself without sensing otherness and without being sensed by the other. It involves thinking the unity (…) as form, which is inevitably an articulation. (Nancy 2008, 133) What Nancy describes here is an articulation that goes through the other, and by being separate from the other, it constitutes the responsive unity of my subjectivity. It is only by being in-touch with others that I sense myself. The important point is that my articulation is experienced and mediated by the other. I will return to the role of articulation later. For now, consider that it is through the other that I come to conceive of sense, namely as the sense that has been articulated through outsidedness and exposure to the other. Now, if as responsive subjects we articulate sense, then this kind of sense is disrupted with the death of the other. “Death is an immobilization of the mobility of the face that denies death in advance; it is a struggle between discourse and its negation” (Levinas 2000, 14). We must ask how this struggle is experienced, the struggle between the wanting-to-beresponded-to and the denial of being-called-again. How is wanting-be-responded-to related to the impossible continuation of discourse with a deceased? The experience, according to Levinas, is that of a pure question mark which is pure in the following sense: Instead of letting itself be described in its own event, death concerns us by its nonsense. The point that death seems to mark in our time (i.e., our relation to the infinite) is a pure question mark: the opening onto that which provides no possibility of a response. (2000, 21) For Levinas, the pure question mark is a point of concern that is experienced as responsibility. Let’s hold on to the idea that surviving the absence of the other is tied to an experience of responsibility and that the concern at the root of this experience is still tied to having no place and to the experience of no-response. Levinas expands on how this concern is experienced: The other concerns me as a neighbor. In every death is shown the nearness of the neighbor, and the responsibility of the survivor, in the form of a responsibility that the approach of proximity moves or agitates. A disquietude that is not thematization, not intentionality (…) This is a disquietude that therefore resists all appearing, all phenomenal 408
Grief
aspects, as though emotions passed by way of the question, without encountering the slightest quiddity, toward that acuity of death, and instituted an unknown that is not purely negative but rather in nearness without knowledge. (Levinas 2000, 18) For present purposes, let me focus on the idea that survival is tied to a concern that is instituted by a relation to the unknown. The unknown that Levinas describes and that is initiated by disquietude is not the unknown that is tied to answers we will never get, the purely negative; rather, it consists in a nearness without knowledge and it is experienced as responsibility for the other. When Levinas emphasizes the purity of the question mark as beyond thematization and intentionality it means that our attempts to represent the other will all fail. The otherness of the other is beyond intentionality in the sense that we cannot come to grasp it; rather, we come to experience it as concern and responsibility. Thus, the mode of survival does not allow for an experience of undifferentiated affective sameness. Rather, it keeps us suspended in relation to the unknown, that is, to what cannot be an object of consciousness, namely the absent other. While doing so, the experience of surviving establishes an opening towards what doesn’t provide a response, and yet keeps addressing us in terms of disquietude, searching and desiring a response from the deceased other (2000, 107). The idea of the pure question mark that keeps addressing us as responsible for the dead in the unknown, a pure question mark that resists thematization and all appearing, seems to resist any form of internalization or incorporation along the lines that Fuchs describes it. According to Levinas, there can be no reduction of dead other to the realm of sameness, of understanding-as, or of appearing-as. I do not keep the dead reduced to a form of comforting sameness within. The experience of the death of the other leaves us with a no-response. I myself am no longer responded to by you, and this experience is one of disquietude. I am eager to respond to the plaguing questions your absence leave me with; at the same time, I cannot reduce your absence to my lack of getting any answers. Rather, I experience your absence as a nearness without knowledge and a kind of responsibility for the other in the unknown. The structure I am interested in is how preservation of the otherness of the other is possible without reducing her to my own narrative, my own memory, my own set of commemorative rituals, that is, how is preservation possible without internalization? How can we preserve the dead other without reducing him to imaginary sameness, that is, to a fiction of our own imagination?
5. The taboo of wanting to be responded to Let me illustrate the anticipated grief by way of an example that illustrates the struggle between wanting-to-be-responded-to and the inescapable silence of the (soon to be) deceased other. The example also provides grounds for a discussion of incorporation as a form of reconciliation. Simone de Beauvoir describes a scene with her dying mother in her book A Very Easy Death (1965): The physiotherapist came to Maman’s bed, turned down the sheet and took hold of her leg: Maman had an open hospital nightdress on and she did not mind that her wrinkled belly, criss-crossed with tiny lines, and her bald pubis showed. “I no longer have any sort of shame”, she observed in a surprised voice. “You are perfectly right not to have any”, I said. But I turned away and gazed fixedly into the garden. The sight of my mother’s nakedness had jarred me. No body existed less for me: none existed more. As a child I 409
Line Ryberg Ingerslev
had loved it dearly; as an adolescent it had filled me with an uneasy repulsion: all this was perfectly in the ordinary course of things and it seemed reasonable to me that her body should retain its dual nature, that it should be both repugnant and holy—a taboo. (Beauvoir 1965, 19–20) In witnessing her mother’s insensitivity to shame, Beauvoir herself feels ashamed, while granting that there is nothing to be ashamed of. This moment reveals how the responsive dynamic tied to exposure is disrupted in grief. It is not because we can see the mother now naked and dying that we feel ashamed on her behalf, and it is not because she no longer makes herself shown or presents herself that we feel ashamed on her behalf. Rather, it is because her body now lacks an address that an essential for-you-ness is already dying. Death makes itself appear as a lack of address, a no-longer-responding, thereby turning the body into a being-for-no-one; the moment of no-shame reveals a sliding into non-responsive anonymity. This process reveals itself in the mother’s witnessing of her own letting go. “Death is the disappearance in beings of those expressive movements that made them appear as living, those movements that are always responses. Death will touch above all, that autonomy or that expressiveness of movement (…) Death is the no-response” (Levinas 2000, 9). The experience of shame in front of her dying mother can be understood as what A nthony Steinbock calls a diremptive experience (Steinbock 2014, 72–37, 98): two modes of orientation that are otherwise unified come apart and the one experiencing the diremption is itself called into question. Beauvoir’s experience of shame can be understood as a call for orientation, being lost as she is in front of her mother, wanting her response, and realizing she shall not receive it any longer. The conflict experienced as two different modes of orientation falling apart is articulated in the feeling of a taboo tied to desiring a response from a body that, in turning into a corpse, can no longer express itself in proximity, can no longer address or respond anymore. To witness this silencing of the body, as it appears as a saying-for-the-other, fills Beauvoir with shame. Not only because her mother’s body is now naked, aging and dying, but because the body now appears for-no-one. Shame in Beauvoir’s case is a response to being left alone with seeking, demanding, and desiring responses from the flesh that cannot and will not respond. Beauvoir’s sense of herself is interrupted, distorted by the fact that the mother will no longer respond. The shame does not concern the nakedness of the mother’s body, but the inappropriateness of her own (Simone’s) embodied wanting-to-be-responded-to. We can say that the mother is letting go of hosting the other’s desire, letting go of inviting to the fine risk of approach qua approach, to the exposure of one to the other, to the exposure of this exposedness, the expression of exposure, saying. In the approach of a face the flesh becomes word, the caress a saying. (Levinas 1998, 94) What Beauvoir’s story reveals is the structural responsiveness tied to the body: Constitutively, I am not at one with myself, but I am exposed to otherness and alterity, coming to myself from the outside (Nancy 2008, 33). My sense of myself, we might say, is a form of anticipated wholeness that is bound to fall apart, since we can capture neither the recognition nor the response from the other. We might say that my sense of myself consists in an expectation of sense that structurally depends on otherness: Rather (…) I promise, I anticipate a sense that is not yet there and will, in fact never be there as something completed and presentable, a sense that is always in and according to 410
Grief
the other, making sense only by being exposed to the other, to the risk of not m aking sense, to the always certain risk of changing the sense of the other and so of always being other, always being altered, always being outside, being by itself, as sense, a being-infinitely-for-the-other. (Nancy 2003, 295) Being situated next to her dying mother, we can say that Beauvoir’s self-conception is disrupted since she can no longer call or demand anything from the (m)other, and thus, her self-image cannot continue to be imagined—it becomes unimaginable. The exposure and suffering tied to being-for-the-other is articulated in my self-image shaped as a being-foryou. Exposure to silence in this case breaks the anticipated wholeness and reveals that my sense of myself was always deferred, incapable of receiving the response that shaped it as a saying: The disclosing of a face is nudity, non-form, abandon of self, ageing, dying more naked than nudity. It is poverty, skin with wrinkles, which are a trace of itself [sic!]. My reaction misses a present which is already the past of itself. This past is not in the present, but is as a phase retained, the past of this present, a lapse already lost which marks ageing, escaping all retention, altering my contemporaneousness with the other. It reclaimed me before I came. The delay is irrecuperable. (…) The common hour marked by the clock is the hour in which the neighbor reveals himself and delivers himself in his image, but it is precisely in his image that he is no longer near. (Levinas 2000, 88–89) Confronted with her nakedness as the incarnation of a non-responsive body, Beauvoir is overwhelmed of the motherly body as she has loved and hated it, as it represents what is at one and the same time holy and repugnant: a taboo. What is sacred and forbidden in relation to the body is not merely its nakedness or sexuality, but its falling out of time, its timelessness. The enigma of time captured in the body is exposed in the face of death: “No body existed less for me: none existed more”. Irreducible to identification in Fuchs’ sense, the taboo that confronts Beauvoir tells of her desire to be responded to what death confronts her with. In this sense, we might say that my own self-understanding reflects a displacement in time; I am constitutively delayed, and in the face of death, the responsive moments come apart; I can no longer make claims on you; it becomes clear that your response was always unimaginable and as such part of my deferred sense of myself. Importantly, the diachronicity that Levinas describes in terms of responsibility cannot be reduced to my way of incorporating the image of the other and fixating him or her in time, in an image, in a narrative or a ritual or a new set of animated habits. The deferral that articulates the sense for which I am responsible consists in the irreducibility of the other to becoming that image.
6. Survival as responsibility for sense This example provides us with an important antidote to the idea of a possible reconciliation with the dead through our memory and our continuation or re-enactment of shared habits. Fuchs suggested that we can incorporate the other and gain a new relationship with her in the form of an inner comforting presence. Beauvoir’s story however could be understood as testifying to the impossibility of keeping the dead exactly because we ourselves embody the insatiable desire to be responded to that cannot be fulfilled. Therefore, any form of internalization 411
Line Ryberg Ingerslev
and identification would only attest to wishful thinking or indeed self- deception. For, as we would ourselves fill in that lacking response by way of restoring an imaginary sameness, namely the sameness of tying together two incommensurable orders, the order of death and the order of our own survival, we would in that self-fabricated response come to answer to our own desires by way of our powerful monitoring of our fantasies. Now, as Kierkegaard (2009b) writes, the dead man is a silent man. By placing himself, imaginatively, at a graveside, looking into the grave, speaking at the grave, Kierkegaard insists that there is a struggle to be recognized at the graveside, namely the struggle of what is known and certain (that we will survive some of our loved ones, we might say) and what is unknown and uncertain (that we don’t know what survival means, that survival is unimaginable, we might say). We must experience this struggle practically, in order to fully grasp it, despite the knowledge we already have of it. What presents itself differently when death cuts into our lives with certainty is the future. While this factually happens after the death of the other, the struggle between certainty and uncertainty serves as an existential fundament for being placed and for us taking place in the world. Survival is at stake at every moment as praxis of sense, whereas death factually reveals the fundamental dynamic of survival in time. The earnestful praxis described by Kierkegaard consists in a form of re-engagement, as it were. In grief and at the graveside, I have to re-settle the struggle between the known (that you have died) and the unknown (that I survived but I don’t know what that means without you to give sense to our world) by way of re-committing myself to the world. As Kelly suggests, we can capture grief by accounting for its temporal meaning or significance on analogy with a thrown projection. As throwness denotes a full awareness of those uncontrollable and limiting conditions into which we have been born, we might consider grief a second thrownness in which we once again enter the world anew—and wailing. (Kelly 2017, 176–177) The important point here is that we have to recommit to the world in which we already are; we have to relearn the world (Attig 2011) and we do so in the form of recommitting to sense in the face of no-response and the non-sense of death, almost as an ethical practice of hope (Mattingly 2010). The promise of sense is made not to the absent other, but consist in the praxis of articulating that absence back into the world over and over again, as a reengaging movement in time that constitutes the world. Absence and separation are what enable an articulation of the world, and this articulation is carried out as responsibility for sense. Grief reveals this struggling articulation as a mode in which we survive absence. What Kelly describes as thrownness, a second birth, brings us back to the difference emphasized by Abraham and Torok, namely between incorporation and Sándor Ferenczi’s original term “introjection” (Ferenczi 1912, 316–317). According to the authors, incorporation denotes a fantasy, a psychic structure, whereas introjection should be understood as a process; a process by which experiences of the dead is indeed projected inwards, but at the same time these experiences involve an opening to the external world. Therefore, the notion of introjection, offered by Abraham and Torok, might be helpful to correct some of the tendencies in approaches that speak of taking the deceased inwards in order to keep her as a kind of comforting presence by proxy. The originary experience of absence, viewed psychoanalytically, is tied to the absence or separation from the care-taking other (see also Winnicot 1958, 2005), which gives rise to articulation. The infant learns separation as articulation out of absence of the caregiving 412
Grief
(m)other/milk; the empty mouth is the experience of and articulation of absence, and in the transformation of articulating absence a world is gained: The absence of objects and the empty mouth are transformed into words. So the wants of the original oral vacancy are remedied by being turned into verbal relationships with the speaking community at large. Introjecting a desire, a pain, a situation means channeling them through language into a communion of empty mouths… Since language acts and makes up for absence by representing, by giving figurative shape to presence, it can only be comprehended or shared in a ‘community of empty mouths’. (Abraham and Torok 1994, 128) Importantly, absence here is something we learn to experience, and this absence is tied to an experience of sense as world-building. Relating to the other through identification or affective overlapping, as described by Fuchs, does to some extent prevent an open worlddirectedness. By contrast, it is through the experienced separation from—and absence of— the other that we gain access to a shared world, a world for which we are at the same time responsible. It is the lived articulation of the experience of absence that commits us to the world. The contrast between introjection and incorporation is respectively tied to the articulation of a wanting-to-mourn or to refusing-to-mourn by taking the other inward. We might say that survival in the case of incorporation turns the survivor into a cemetery guard, whereas survival in the case of introjection is tied to a constant confrontation with being committed, worldly, at the graveside, thrown a second time and ongoingly into giving sense otherwise (see also Ingerslev 2018). We might think of refusing to mourn in collective terms as well. In Jonathan Lear’s interpretation (2017) of Coetze’s Waiting for the Barbarians, he describes how melancholia can become a life form; waiting is what we do, melancholically, when we hold on to a certain life form, a certain set of norms, a certain way of seeing each other. Collectively, we can wait for the climate to get worse, we can wait for justice, we can accept injustice, but with mourning comes a creative recommitment to sense. Melancholia is the condition of being stuck in repetition. For the melancholic, everything is always already the same again—stretching back into the past, and on into the future. Mourning, by contrast, is imaginative recreation. That is, it is the occasion for taking up the past way and using it as an occasion to break out of repetition and create a new future. Though it is often painful process, it is also fertile. In mourning, the past nourishes the present and future; and the mourner ultimately says yes to life by saying no to the depressing confines of “same again forever”. (Lear 2017, 98) Lear describes the shift from melancholic waiting to a creative commitment to sense understood as mourning as a shift that grants ghosts the status of being ancestors. We are no longer just haunted, we commit to non-sense being part of us as a way in which we respond responsibly to existence. It is not the world that is new in the experience of grief, we remain embedded in cultural structures of sense, but the sense we re-commit to is a kind of sense that creatively and re-creatively commit us to the world. Our deceased keep haunting us as a demand for meaning, as a pure question mark, and we keep hearing this demand, we keep sending our ghosts away as we turn them into ancestors (see also Butler 2006), into sources of sense for how we responsibly carry on surviving. 413
Line Ryberg Ingerslev
7. Concluding remarks In asking how we preserve the alterity of the other who is dead, we looked at two ways of memorizing the dead other; either as an attempt of carrying the other inwards while creating a comforting presence, or as a world-directed practice of sense that I keep being concerned by. These two modes of internalization entail either a form of incorporation of the other or a way of keeping a promise of sense. Importantly, the promise of sense is not a promise to the dead; rather, it is a way of re-engaging in time and over time with the memories of the deceased, by continuously turning him into an ancestor. On this latter model, what we might get to keep is a relation of sense carried back into the world. Preserving otherness is thus a way of practicing memory. In Kierkegaard’s terms, the praxis of remembering one’s dead is a work of love (2009a, 317–329). Our grief work should in fact be understood as a work of love. We are relearning the world by practicing memory as a work of love over and over again, each time differently, each time anew; by recommitting to the world, by turning our ghosts into ancestors, by keeping a promise of sense yet to come. This kind of memory cannot be purified, kept untouched by time or sterilized into fixed meaning; rather, is a practice that we rehearse world-building, over and over again.
References Abraham, Nicolas and Torok, Maria (1994). The Shell and the Kerknel. Transl. by N. T. Rand. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Attig, Thomas (2011). How We Grieve. Relearning the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Barthes, Roland (2009). A Mourning Diary. Transl. by R. Howard. New York: Hill and Wang. Beauvoir, Simone de (1965). A Very Easy Death. Transl. by P. O’Brian. New York: Pantheon. Butler, Judith (2006). Precarious Life. The Powers of Mourning and Violence. London: Verso. Derrida, Jacques (2004). Uninterrupted Dialogue. Between Two Infinities, The Poem. Transl. by T. Dutoit and P. Romanski. Research in Phenomenology 34, 2–19. Didion, Joan (2005). The Year of Magical Thinking. London: Harper Perennial. Ferenczi, Sándor (2018[1912]). On the Definition of Introjection. In: Ferenczi Sándor: Final Contributions to the Problems and Methods of Psycho-Analysis. Ed. by M. Balint, transl. by E. Mosbacher et al. London, New York: Routledge, 316–318. Freud, Sigmund (1917). Mourning and Melancholia. The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works. Transl. by J. Strachey. Vol. 14. London: The Hogarth Press. Fuchs, Thomas (2012). The Phenomenology of Body Memory. In: S. Koch, T. Fuchs, M. Summa, and C. Müller (Eds.). Body Memory, Metaphor and Movement. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 9–22. ——— (2017). Collective Body Memory. In: C. Durt, T. Fuchs, and C. Tewes (Eds.). Embodiment, Enaction and Culture. Investigating the Constitution of the Shared World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 333–352. ——— (2018). Presence in Absence. The Ambiguous Phenomenology of Grief. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17(1), 43–64. Higgins, Kathleen (2008). Love and Death. In: J. Deigh (Ed.). On Emotions. Philosophical Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 159–178. Ingerslev, Line Ryberg (2018). Ongoing: On Grief ’s Open-ended Rehearsal. Continental Philosophy Review 51(3), 343–360. Kelly, Michael R. (2017). Grief: Putting the Past before Us. Quaestiones Disputatae 7(1), 156–177. Kierkegaard, Søren (2009a). At a Graveside. Three Discourses on Imagined Occasions. Transl. by H. and E. Hong. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ——— (2009b). Works of Love. Transl. by H. and E. Hong. New York: Harper-Collins. Lear, Jonathan (2017). Wisdom Won from Illness. Essays in Philosophy and Psychoanalysis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Levinas, Emmanuel (1998). Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence. Transl. by A. Lingis. Pittsburg: Duquesne University Press. ——— (2000). God, Death, and Time. Transl. by B. Bergo. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
414
Grief ——— (2006). Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence. Transl. by A. Lingis. Pittsburg: Duquesne University Press. Lewis, Clive Staples (1961). A Grief Observed. London: Faber and Faber. Mattingly, Cheryl (2010). The Paradox of Hope. Journeys through a Clinical Borderland. Berkeley: University of California Press. Murray Parkes, Colin (2009). Love and Loss. The Roots of Grief and Its Complications. London, New York: Routledge. Nancy, Jean-Luc (2003). Responding to Existence. A Finite Thinking. Transl. by S. Guyer. Stanford: Stanford University Press. ——— (2008). Corpus. Transl. by R. A. Rand. New York: Fordham University Press. Nussbaum, Martha (2001). Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ratcliffe, Matthew (2017). Real Hallucinations. Psychiatric Illness, Intentionality and the Interpersonal World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ——— (2019). Grief and Phantom Limbs: A Phenomenological Comparison. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 17, 75–96. Riley, Denise (2012). Time Lived, Without Its Flow. London: Capsule. Ruin, Hans (2018). Being with the Dead. Burial, Ancestral Politics, and the Roots of Historical Consciousness. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Silverman, Phyllis R., and Klass, Dennis. (1996). Introduction: What’s the Problem. In: D. Klass, P. R. Silverman, and S. Nickman (Eds.). Continuing Bonds. New Understandings of Grief. London, New York: Routledge. Solomon, Robert (2004). In Defense of Sentimentality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Steinbock, Anthony (2014). Moral Emotions. Reclaiming the Evidence of the Heart. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Warren, Nicolas de (2017). The Souls of the Departed. Towards a Phenomenology of the After-Life. Metodo 5(1), 205–237. Winnicott, Donald (1958). The Capacity to Be Alone. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis 39, 416–420. ——— (2005). Playing and Reality. London, New York: Routledge. Further reading Goldie, Peter (2012). The Mess Inside. Narrative, Emotion, and the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ratcliffe, Matthew (2016). Relating to the Dead: Social Cognition and the Phenomenology of Grief. In: T. Szanto and D. Moran (Eds.). Phenomenology of Sociality: Discovering the ‘We’. London, New York: Routledge, 202–215. ——— (2017). The Phenomenological Clarification of Grief and Its Relevance for Psychiatry. In: G. Stanghellini et al. (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Phenomenological Psychopathology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198803157.013.58. Rinofner-Kreidl, Sonja (2018). Grief: Loss and Self-Loss. In: J. J. Drummond, and S. Rinofner-Kreidl (Eds.). Emotional Experiences: Ethical and Social Significance. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 91–120. Varga, Somogy, and Gallagher, Shaun (2020). Anticipatory-Vicarious Grief: The Anatomy of a Moral Emotion. The Monist 103(2), 176–189.
415
36 JOY AND HAPPINESS Michela Summa
Within the constellation of the positive emotional responses related to the sense of accomplishment and/or fulfillment—a constellation that also includes feelings like pleasure and enjoyment as well as positive emotions like gladness, cheerfulness, hilariousness, serenity, etc.—joy and happiness stand out as two related, and yet different, experiences. Considering recent work, the discrepancy between the large amount of research on happiness and the comparatively little one on joy is remarkable (cf. Demmerling and Landweer 2007, 111–125; Potkay 2007, 1–29). Interdisciplinary research on happiness have flourished in the last decades, and research fields called “happiness studies” or “the science of happiness” have developed (Ahmed 2010, 2–20; Haybron 2011). Several attempts have been made to establish more or less standardized criteria for the evaluation of individual and social happiness. This interest for happiness and happiness standards not only concerns scientific research but also social discourses: we read articles about the happiest country in Europe, about how to keep a happy relationship, about being happy with what you are, etc. There seems to be nothing similar concerning joy. The reason for this discrepancy is at least partly bound to the cultural tradition in Western civilization and to the history of concepts. First, the concepts of joy and happiness are often used interchangeably, so that discourses about happiness should sometimes be better understood as discourses about joy and vice versa. Moreover, both concepts, ‘joy’ and ‘happiness’, harbor some ambiguities. On the one hand, experiencing joy may be either understood as ‘enjoying something’ or as ‘rejoicing about something’ and the two have rather different characteristics. On the other hand, ‘happiness’ is alternatively used to designate an emotional state—feeling happy about something essentially means feeling satisfied—or a judgmental stance we take about our life, or a period thereof—we are or were happy with what we are, with what we have reached, which means that a happy life is a life that “goes well for the person leading it” (Haybron 2011). I will assume that the former sense of ‘happiness’ comes rather close to joy, whereas the latter is a distinctive experience. ‘Happiness’ in this narrower sense has historically gained stronger ethical/moral connotations (cf. Annas 1993), which are not associated with our current understanding of ‘joy’ (Potkay 2007, 1–28). This is particularly remarkable if one considers how important figures in the philosophical, literary, and religious tradition have emphasized the social, ethical and even political impact of joy (cf. Potkay 2007). Finally, and relatedly, our understanding of happiness has requirements 416
Joy and happiness
that do not seem to applicable in the same sense to joy. According to a tradition that has its roots in Aristotle’s account of eudaimonia, for rational beings, happiness is and should be the ultimate aim. In this sense, we are somehow accountable and responsible for the way in which we realize our happiness (Ahmed 2010). In what follows, I will tackle these issues from a phenomenological perspective. I will emphasize what is distinctive for joy and happiness, particularly in relation to temporality and to processes of self-realization. Section 1 expands on the ambiguity in the use of and on some relevant distinctions between the concepts of joy and happiness; Section 2 focuses on joy, and in particular on what I will call ‘deep joy’; Section 3 addresses the specificity of happiness as based on an evaluative/judgmental stance on one’s own life as a good life.
1. Joy and happiness: some preliminary distinctions That expressions of joy and happiness are often used interchangeably has notably been observed, in two different argumentative contexts, by Nozick and Foot. Focusing on what we mean by saying that we are happy to x or that we are happy that x is the case, Nozick (2006, 108 f.) distinguishes: (i) being happy that something or other is the case, (ii) feeling that one’s own life is good as it is right now, and (iii) being satisfied with one’s own life as a whole. Discussing these three meanings, he observes that the former two describe joy rather than happiness: they respectively refer (i) to the ordinary experience of rejoicing about something and (ii) to the experience of deep joy. Happiness in the strict sense is what is meant in case (iii), which differs from both previous ones because, on the one hand, it does not refer to one specific episode and, on the other hand, it entails a judgmental stance that the two others do not have. Foot’s (2010, 81f.) remarks converge with these in emphasizing how, besides being used in order to characterize dispositions or moods, expressions of happiness often refer to two rather different phenomena: rejoicing and being happy about one’s own life as a good life. Whereas the former designates an episodic state of mind, the latter implies a judgmental stance on the goodness of one’s life, thus coming close to the understanding of eudaimonia in Aristotle and the ethical tradition that followed. Nozick and Foot thus agree on the two following claims: first, joy has an episodic character, whereas happiness refers to larger segments of one’s own life or even to one’s life as a whole; second, different from joy, which is an immediate response, happiness entails an evaluative and judgmental stance. Yet, a further aspect, which is more explicitly thematized by Strasser in the phenomenological tradition, is implicit in both Nozick’s and Foot’s observations. Considering both joy and happiness as experiences of accomplishment, Strasser (1956, 238f.) emphasizes that joy is felt while we experience the accomplishment of a process, whereas happiness, as an emotional experience based on evaluation, only comes at the end of a process. Accordingly, joy should be considered as the feeling of “affirmation” in “taking possess”, which occurs after previous uncertainty (ibid., 233f.) and accompanies processes of accomplishment through and through (ibid., 239). A similar view can be found in some of Husserl’s manuscripts collected as Studien zur Struktur des Bewusstseins (Husserl forthcoming). Here, Husserl often associates joy with the fulfilment of the intentional tendency, with the satisfaction of instincts and drives—whereby joy arises in the process of satisfaction and culminates at its end—and with the dynamics of accomplishment of activities that are considered to be aims in themselves, like playful activities (cf. Bernet 2006, 2013, 223–332, Summa 2014, 224f.). Conversely, Strasser (1956, 238f., 244f.) observes that happiness only occurs at the end of processes of accomplishment, or at the moment of achievement: we are not happy at the 417
Michela Summa
beginning of a process, nor during its unfolding, but rather only at its successful conclusion,1 as we reflectively turn to the process and its ending. These remarks indicate that joy and happiness have a different temporal structure and are differently related to experiences of accomplishment, realization, and self-realization. In the following two sections, I will explore these aspects more closely.
2. Joy and deep joy Let us begin with some semantic and grammatical distinctions in the expressions of joy. In English, the two main verbs that have ‘joy’ as their root are ‘enjoying’2 and ‘rejoicing’. The distinction between these two verbs at least partially coincides with the distinction between Freude an etwas and Freude über etwas in German. In his work on aesthetic enjoyment, Geiger devotes much effort to this distinction, contending that only in the latter case—i.e., only in rejoicing about something (Freude über)—can we properly speak about joy. Despite the etymological connection in English and the use of the same word with a different preposition in German, the experience of enjoyment (Freude an, Genuss) is, in other words, to be distinguished from joy as rejoicing (Freude über). We should particularly retain three aspects of Geiger’s phenomenological analysis. First, Geiger (1913, 587f.) observes that while joy is motivated by inner experiences, enjoyment can be said to be grounded, but not properly motivated. Motivational relations concern the reasons why the given state of affairs is something I rejoice about: we cannot universalize any claim concerning the content of joy, but we can (formally) claim that something can be the source of joy for someone only if it is meaningful for him/her. Enjoyment, and aesthetic enjoyment in particular, does not have the same motivational structure. We can typically mention the aspects that make something enjoyable, and thus also raise general and quasi-normative claims concerning aesthetic enjoyment, but we are not always able to say why something is enjoyable for us. Second, Geiger (1913, 616–617, 587 f.) emphasizes that joy is always an act in the strict sense. Joy describes a centrifugal movement. We are certainly first of all affected by what we rejoice about, but the proper experience of joy expresses an active movement toward the object, and the affirmation of the experience. Enjoyment is instead centripetal, since what its central feature is the passivity of the affection (ibid., 616–617). Although he does not explicitly refer to Geiger’s work, this view on the primacy of affection—and of hetero-affection in particular—in enjoyment is something we also find in Levinas’ (1979, 109f.) discussion of enjoyment ( jouissance). Although Levinas understands enjoyment as a much more encompassing and multifaceted phenomenon, the reference to the primacy of affection may also be taken to justify his understanding of enjoyment as an experience of separation—an interpretation that is not appropriate to the traditional understanding of joy, which rather emphasizes unification, and joining (cf. Potkay 2007). Third, whereas enjoyment can occur only on the basis of the mere presentation of its object, or on the basis of imagistic representations, joy requires the position of existence, or of the actual occurrence of that about which we rejoice (Geiger 1913, 598). Joy, in other words, presupposes a twofold affirmation: of the intentional correlate and of its existence.3 In his attempt to trace all complex emotions back to joy, sadness, and conatus and their composition, Spinoza already hints at this. Complex affects like hope and fear are inconstant, since they respectively entail joy and sadness related to the content (or the idea) of something uncertain (Spinoza 1985, III, P. 18, schol. 2). Yet, these affects are complementary—there is no hope without fear and no fear without hope. Thus, the uncertainty concerning the outcome—the 418
Joy and happiness
future effective existence—implies sadness even when the content or the idea is the source of joy (in hope), and joy even when the content is the source of sadness (in fear) (ibid., III, def. XII–XIII, exp.). Similarly, longing is for Spinoza sadness concerning the absence of something we love (ibid., III, P. 36, schol.), i.e., concerning the cause of our joy (ibid., III, P. 13, schol.). Given these distinctions, what interests us here is rejoicing, which, following Foot’s and Nozick’s remarks, should be specified either as ordinary joy or as deep joy. An ordinary experience of joy is something like a positive emotional response to an event or state of affairs—a response which, however, remains confined to the present and does not impinge on how we relate to ourselves and the world we experience in a more encompassing way. Precisely this bigger impact in terms of meaningfulness of the event or state of affairs about which we rejoice is characteristic of the experience of deep joy, on which I will concentrate in the following. Admittedly, the metaphorical reference to depth may sound somehow vague and is certainly difficult to define (Foot 2010, 86f.). Such a difficulty can be interpreted as mysteriousness: the depth of an emotional experience, and particularly the depth of rejoicing, is something we would not be able to grasp in rational terms. In the history of the concept of joy, such a view on the ineffability of the depth of joy is widely spread, particularly in religious discourses, and can similarly be found in literary and poetic traditions (Potkay 2007, esp. 17f., 30f.). Yet, the remark on the metaphorical character of the concept of deep joy, as well as the reference to the tradition that emphasizes the ineffability of deep joy (or the incapacity to capture and render the experience by means of rational inquiry), should not prevent us from trying to shed some light on what is characteristic of this phenomenon. The touch of mysteriousness, in other words, might certainly point to the limits of strictly philosophical and rationalizing inquiries; but it should not be taken as a mystification of the experience itself. In order to address some of the aspects that characterize deep joy, let us consider one passage from Nozick’s discussion at length: Recall those particular moments when you thought and felt, blissfully, that there was nothing else you wanted, your life was good then. Perhaps this occurred while walking alone in nature, or being with someone you loved. What marks these times is their completeness. There is something you have that you want, and no other wants come crowding in; there is nothing else that you think of wanting right then. I do not mean that if someone came up to you right then with a magic lamp, you would be at a loss to come up with a wish. But in the moments I am describing, these other desires—for more money or another job or another chocolate bar—simply are not operating. They are not felt, they are not lurking at the margins to enter. There is no additional thing you want right then, nothing feels lacking, your satisfaction is complete. The feeling that accompanies this is intense joy. These moments are wonderful, and they are rare. (Nozick 2006, 108–109) There are two aspects in this description that allow us to better characterize the experience of deep joy. First, the difference between ordinary cases of rejoicing and deep joy does not rely merely on the intensity of the feeling.4 Second, deep joy is not related to some specific content, to something we already know to be valuable, or to something we assume to be equally valuable for everyone. We can thus say that joy is not based on a previous and detached evaluation of the object, but rather that the evaluation of the object depends on the fact that it generates a response of deep joy for us in the present situation. Watching a sunrise, 419
Michela Summa
for instance, may produce for someone an experience of deep joy because it yields a sense of completeness and participation in what this particular person is doing or experiencing. Yet, deep joy is not simply independent from the qualities of the object, nor shall it be understood internalistically. Instead, depth relies on some kind of attunement between oneself and what one experiences. As Pugmire (2005, 30f.) observes, emotional depth in general depends on both content and personal susceptibility, and it essentially reflects the embeddedness of the emotion in one’s own larger concerns, or in what matters for a person’s life. These rather general remarks should now be further explicated in relation to the temporality of deep joy and its impact on how we experience ourselves in the situation. With respect to temporality, we can observe that deep joy is characterized by both a sense of the uniqueness of the episode and by a sense of abidingness, which somehow lets the feeling irradiate into the past and the future.5 Deep joy is related to moments of fullness and expresses a feeling of self-sufficient unity with what one is experiencing.6 The feeling of completeness, of unification with what one experiences, and of integration of the present moment within one’s own life are certainly among the most characterizing aspects of joy. As Nozick’s emphasizes, they seem to blend all further desires and expectations, and they entail some sort of appeasement and tranquility, so that we can somehow experience that present moment as eternal. Although one might interpret this in terms of a liberation from the passions—something that we can find in different terms in the understanding of both joy and happiness in the Stoic and the Epicurean tradition (McMahon 2006, 50f.)—what Nozick emphasizes is rather that there is some inevitable contingency in these moments, which is also part of their inner value. Also, these moments are not only contingent, they are also extremely rare, fragile, and transient: they leave in their wake the nostalgic wish to re-live them. Such fugacity of joyful experiences is probably what justifies the traditional conception of an eschatology of eternal joy. As Potkay shows, eschatological descriptions about the joyful sense of unity and about the empowerment that results from this sense of unity can be found in religious and literary texts (Potkay 2007, 31f., 50f.). They refer to an eternal and fully lived-through presence as something we long for, and as operating in terms of a salvation to be reached in another world, also thanks to the mediation of worldly joy. Yet, the experience of joy one longs for is that of an anticipated deep joy, mostly coinciding with the moment in which the oneness with God and the universe or with the beloved one is reached. Joy is still considered to be fully realized only in the moment of full presence and realization; yet, the perspective from which such joy is experienced always implies some divergence, or perhaps even the hope for an enduring oneness that is always there to come. And this, paraphrasing Spinoza, would actually be a complex affect in which moments of joy also contain moments of sadness. The previous remarks also impinge on the relation between joy and self-realization. The self-realization that occurs in joy is related to a sense of achievement, which also entails a sense of unity and sharing. Joy is something that accompanies the process of achievement through and through. Authors like Spinoza (1985), Bergson (1929), Nietzsche (1987, 1974), and Deleuze (1988) strongly emphasize this aspect of joy as an affect that is intrinsically connected with the expression and the increasing of our power to act, as well as with creativity. Self-realization, in this sense, occurs in the expression of the activity itself. Joy fulfills us by expressing who we are, and this also has social and even political reverberations. Commenting on Spinoza and Nietzsche, Deleuze brings this to the fore by contrasting the increment of the power to act (puissance d’agir), which is something that unites and promotes self-realization, to power (pouvoir), which is instead based on separation and on maintaining 420
Joy and happiness
those upon whom power is exercised in the state of ignorance, thus promoting sadness instead of joy through the inhibition of expressiveness (Deleuze 1988, 17f.).7 These remarks should clarify what I previously called the centripetal character of joy as an act. Rejoicing means affirming and such affirmation is not only relevant for the evaluation of specific contents (which actually have their value precisely because they are the source of joy for someone), but also because it says something about who we are, and in this sense, it can be characterized as a form of self-realization. This kind of self-realization differs from what we consider to be the self-realization occurring in happiness. Particularly, the self-realization in moments of joy does not seem to have the same implications in terms of responsibility and accountability or the same claim to truthfulness as the self-realization occurring in a happy life.
3. Happiness and the good life The main differences between joy and happiness, both considered as emotional responses to processes of accomplishment, can be reassessed on the basis of the following two factors. First, joy accompanies the process through and through, whereas happiness seems to be more strictly tied to the moment of achievement of the process. Second, joy is not only a direct emotional response to an event that is embedded in our life-concerns but is also tightly bound to the present moment, whereas happiness presupposes an evaluative stance concerning one period of one’s life or one’s own life as a whole.8 This is also what underlies the traditionally stronger relation between happiness and ethics/morality (Annas 1993)—mostly based on the relation between happiness and the good life.9 Different from deep joy, happiness is not an experience of completeness and lack of further desires; it rather derives from a balanced evaluation of what one has or has achieved. In his later ethics, and notably in his later manuscripts collected as Grenzprobleme der Phänomenologie (cf. Husserl 2014, 297f., 379f., 502f.), Husserl also commits to this view (cf. Drummond 2010; Peucker 2008, 2010).10 He understands happiness as closely related to virtue ethics, in which self-satisfaction is combined with virtue and corresponds to the best possible accomplishment of one’s life, as an ideal state of happiness. In his later approach to ethics, Husserl contends that goodness in general, and the goodness of ethical principles in particular, do not only refer to singular acts of will, but rather to the significance of these acts for one’s own personal life, which is always embedded in the life of a community. Furthermore, he argues that happiness arises from a retrospective overview (Überschau) that should in principle embrace one’s own life as a whole (e.g., Husserl 2014, 502f.). Accordingly, happiness is an emotion that derives from an evaluative, judgmental, and reflective stance taken on one’s own life as a whole. The ethical value of a happy life, as well as its reflective character, become evident if one considers how Husserl ‘tests’ happiness in relation to regret (Reue): a happy life is a life I can appraise and affirm without regret. What Husserl has in mind here is a “radical and universal regret” (Husserl 2014, 492) concerning the whole of one’s life, or those important choices and volitions that impinge on one’s life as a whole. This has implications concerning the temporality of happiness. On the one hand, as we have seen, happiness arises at the end of a process, and therefore, it seems to rule out the moments of uncertainty that accompany an unfolding activity. On the other hand, happiness implies a certain tension between the three temporal dimensions of experience. Although not episodically tied to the present moment, happiness is nonetheless a present experience. Yet, this is the presence of an instant (Augenblick), which has its meaningfulness only in relation to the openness toward the past and the future (cf. Bollnow 2009, 123 f.). Moreover, while the fullness and completeness of joyful experiences is strictly tied to a present moment 421
Michela Summa
that we may somehow wish to be eternal just as it is, the experience of happiness has some overarching temporal implications. Yet, as Nozick (2006, 99f.) observes, it would be wrong to consider happiness as exclusively bound to the temporality of the present. This has to do with his critique to a merely quantitative understanding of a happy life: intuitively, we would not wish ourselves or someone we care about to experience a short period of happiness to be followed by misery and unhappiness. Assuming that happiness can be experienced without hope for future happiness seems to entail something like an experienced contradiction.11 This also shows that happiness does not have the same (aspiration at) fullness as joy: in the experience of deep and fully actualized joy there is—or there would/will be, if we follow the eschatological tradition—no space for hope and further desires. Thus, there is an interplay between different temporal dimensions in happiness. The presence of a happy moment is the presence of a balanced reflection about what one has and what one can still wish. It entails a self-evaluative reference to the past and the still open future possibilities. Moreover, it is the presence of a reflection on how what one has or has done is related to what is good and valuable, whereby both are not related to the experience of completeness, but rather to the feeling that one has made the right choices, even if this implies that one had to give up others, including moments of deep joy. Also, the openness to the future implied in happiness is not intended in eschatological terms as a salvific unification, but rather as something we are and can be (ethically) responsible of. This latter remark brings us to the relation between happiness and self-realization, which differs from self-realization occurring in joy. Regarding this, Foot (2010, 81f.) emphasizes that happiness even more than joy presupposes the concept of goodness, so that one cannot be authentically happy and desire or choose the evil, and this already indicates that there is some form of responsibility for one’s own happiness, which extends beyond one’s own individual experience. The idea that happiness is connected to the assumption of responsibility for one’s own present and future within social experience can also be interpreted in performative and social terms of a reciprocal promise between individuals and the society in which they are embedded. With respect to this, the implications of happiness in terms of commitment and responsibility even more explicitly come to the fore. Ahmed (2010) develops a reading of happiness in terms of promise, the uptake of which seems to imply a double-bind situation. On the one hand, we find ourselves in a social and cultural environment that promises us happiness, in terms of ethical self-realization, i.e., in terms of an appropriation of one’s own life as a good life. On the other hand, however, this very promise implicitly made to the modern individual implies not only the conformity to what one believes to be good, but more importantly to what is ethically, socially, intersubjectively recognized as good. And this eventually implies that one is also called to take responsibility for one’s own happiness, and for what makes him/her happy. For Ahmed, the fact that criteria for happiness are often criteria of social acceptability and recognition results in the risk of some explicitly or implicitly imposed assimilation to models or discursive practices. These often require individuals to be happy, and to be happy in a certain way, i.e., precisely according to those standards of acceptability that are often confused with social and ethical goodness. From this social embedment of the evaluation of one’s life as a happy life, two other aspects follow, which I wish to mention in conclusion. First, being strictly bound to the responsibility of self-realization as self-conscious determination, happiness makes an even stronger claim concerning the reality of its object than joy. As we have seen above, different from aesthetic enjoyment, joy also entails the position of real existence of its object. We would not 422
Joy and happiness
properly rejoice about a merely imagined experience of unification, if our actual experience is in fact that of a deep separation or inner laceration. Yet, this does not exclude that we can experience genuine joy only about what we believe to be the case, and that we might not be interested in checking whether such an experience of joyful unification is real or deceptive (or that we may even more or less consciously avoid to check whether our joy was fully justified in terms of a reality-check or not). In other words, precisely because joy is not based on a detached self-evaluative stance, there seem to be no reasons to question the authenticity or genuineness of joy. This does not hold for happiness, as Nozick (2006, 110f.) aptly illustrates with his imaginary example of a happiness machine. In such a machine, we would live an entire happy life, without, however, ever being able to check whether our happiness passes the test of Nozick’s own reformulation of the “reality principle”, i.e., without being able to say whether our happiness is actually “fitting”. Second, an etymological characteristic of the concept of happiness, which should not be overlooked if one believes that the history of concepts is also revelatory for their meaning, is often underestimated, if not explicitly bracketed, in current understandings of happiness emphasizing the moment of responsibility. This etymological characteristic, which can be found in several languages, binds happiness to contingency and the arbitrariness of luck. For instance, in English, this is expressed by the root ‘hap’ in happiness, which signifies ‘luck’, ‘fortune’, ‘chance’. In ancient Greek, ‘eudaimonia’ signifies ‘good-spiritedness’ and, while certainly remaining secondary if confronted with what is attributed to rational deliberation and evaluation in the achievement of happiness, the reference to the contingent aspects that may facilitate or obstacle such achievement is present in Aristotle’s philosophy of happiness.12 In German, the relation is even more salient since ‘Glück’ ordinarily means both ‘happiness’ and ‘fortune’ or ‘luck’ (McMahon 2006, 10f.). Authors believing that ethical responsibility and commitment to make of one’s own life happy should ideally rule out the contingency or outer conditions, or that one should focus on the ideality of what is good—isolating it from contingency—either tend to overlook or to explicitly neglect the ‘hap’ of happiness, even claiming that “one of the basic tasks of the phenomenology of happiness is to take as much of the hap out of happiness as possible” (Heffernan 2014, 251). Authors who are keen not to oppose contingency in phenomenological descriptions, instead, would precisely make the ‘hap’ of happiness stronger, and rather insist on the need to appropriate this ‘hap’, to make it a virtue, rather than a hindrance, to the understanding of happiness. Ahmed’s (2010) discussion of cases of resistance to the mere acceptance of established and socially normalized models of happiness precisely goes in this direction.
4. Concluding remarks Despite the overlapping in the ordinary and, occasionally, also in the philosophical use of the concepts of joy and happiness, in this chapter, I have shown that they not only have assumed a different meaning throughout the (Western) history of ideas, but also that there are various reasons for this distinction that can be phenomenologically investigated. The differences between joy and happiness are, in particular, tied to their respective temporality, to their relation to different forms of self-realization and accomplishment, and to a different ethical and social relevance. A task still to be accomplished is to clarify whether there are, besides the distinctions, also some necessary relations between the two. What we can certainly say on the basis of our discussion, is that happiness is neither reducible nor exclusively dependent on the joyful experiences one has had throughout one’s life. Even a life that has been confronted with several sad episodes and obstacles, to which one has however 423
Michela Summa
responded in a way that corresponds to what one takes to be a valuable accomplishment or self-realization, could possibly be experienced as ‘happy’ in self-evaluation. Yet, it seems plausible that at least in the moment when one realizes that one’s life was a happy life, even if only under a certain description, one should also experience deep joy, as a sense of unification with what one is and as expression of a power to act.
Notes
References Ahmed, Sara (2010). The Promise of Happiness. Durham, London: Duke University Press. Annas, Julia (1993). The Morality of Happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Anscombe, Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret (1967). On the Grammar of ‘Enjoy’. The Journal of Philosophy 64(19), 607–614. Bergson, Henri (1929). Life and Consciousness. In: Henri Bergson: Mind-Energy. Lectures and Essays. New York: Holt, 3–36.
424
Joy and happiness Bernet, Rudolf (2006). Zur Phänomenologie von Trieb und Lust bei Husserl. In: D. Lohmar and D. Fonfara (Eds.). Interdisziplinäre Perspektiven der Phänomenologie. Neue Felder der Kooperation: Cognitive Science, Neurowissenschaften, Psychologie, Soziologie, Politikwissenschaft und Religionswissenschaft. Dordrecht: Springer, 39–53. ——— (2013). Force—Pulsion—Désir. Une autre philosophie de la psychanalyse. Paris: Vrin. Bollnow, Otto Friedrich (2009). Das Wesen der Stimmungen. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann. Brudzi ń ska, Jagna (2017). In Sachen Glück. Ein genetisch-phänomenologischer Ansatz. Gestalt Theory 39(2/3), 281–302. Deleuze, Gilles (1988). Spinoza: Practical Philosophy. Transl. by R. Hurley. San Francisco: City Lights Book. Demmerling, Christoph, and Hilge Landweer (2007). Philosophie der Gefühle. Von Achtung bis Zorn. Stuttgart: Metzler. Drummond, John J. (2010). Self-Responsibility and Eudaimonia. In: C. Ierna, H. Jacobs, and F. Mattens (Eds.). Philosophy, Phenomenology, Sciences: Essays in Commemoration of Edmund Husserl. Dordrecht: Springer, 411–430. Foot, Philippa (2010). Natural Goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Geiger, Moritz (1913). Beiträge zur Phänomenologie des ästhetischen Genusses. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 1(2), 567–684. Haybron, Dan (2011). Happiness. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/ entries/happiness/ [06.07.2011] Heffernan, George (2014). The Phenomenon Happiness: Prolegomena to a Phenomenological Description. The Humanistic Psychologist 42(3), 249–267. Husserl, Edmund (2014). Grenzprobleme der Phänomenologie: Analysen des Unbewusstseins und der Instinkte, Metaphysik, Späte Ethik—Texte aus dem Nachlass (1908–1937). [=Husserliana 42]. Ed. by Rochus Sowa and Thomas Vongehr. Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (forthcoming). Studien zur Struktur des Bewusstseins. Ed. by Ullrich Melle and Thomas Vongehr. Dordrecht. Springer. Levinas, Emmanuel (1979). Totality and Infinity. An Essay on Exteriority. Transl. by A. Lingis. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff. McMahon, Darrin M. (2006). Happiness. A History. New York: Grove Press. Nietzsche, Friedrich (1974). The Gay Science. Transl. by W. Kaufmann. New York: Vintage. ——— (1987). The Birth of Tragedy and The Case of Wagner. Transl. by W. Kaufmann. New York: Vintage. Nozick, Robert (2006). The Examined Life. Philosophical Meditations. New York: Simon & Schuster. Peucker, Henning (2008). From Logic to the Person: An Introduction to Edmund Husserl’s Ethics. The Review of Metaphysics 62(2), 307–325. ——— (2010). Aristotelische Elemente in der Ethik von Edmund Husserl. Philosophisches Jahrbuch 117, 54–68. Potkay, Adam (2007). The Story of Joy. From the Bible to Late Romanticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pugmire, David (2005). Sound Sentiments. Integrity in the Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Spinoza, Baruch (1985). Ethics. Ed. and transl. by E. Curley. The Collected Works of Spinoza Vol. I. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Strasser, Stephan (1956). Das Gemüt. Grundgedanken zu einer phänomenologischen Philosophie und Theorie des menschlichen Gefühlslebens. Freiburg: Herder. [Engl. Transl.: Phenomenology of Feeling: An Essay on the Phenomena of the Heart. With a foreword by P. Ricoeur. Transl. by R. E. Wood. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press 1977.] Summa, Michela (2014). Spatio-Temporal Intertwining. Husserl’s Transcendental Aesthetic. Dordrecht: Springer. Tatarkiewicz, Wladyslaw (1976). Analysis of Happiness. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.
425
.
(
Taylor & Francis Taylor & Francis Group
http://taylorandfrancis.com
PART 4
Other-directed and collective emotions
.
(
Taylor & Francis Taylor & Francis Group
http://taylorandfrancis.com
37 EMPATHY, SYMPATHY AND COMPASSION Thiemo Breyer
Introduction In everyday language, according to the Oxford English Dictionary (OED), “people often confuse the words empathy and sympathy.” As is clarified promptly, “empathy means ‘the ability to understand and share the feelings of another’ (as in both authors have the skill to make you feel empathy with their heroines), whereas sympathy means ‘feelings of pity and sorrow for someone else’s misfortune’ (as in they had great sympathy for the flood victims).” In the case of “compassion,” the usage is presented as rather straightforward. Compassion is understood as “sympathetic pity and concern for the sufferings or misfortunes of others: the victims should be treated with compassion.” The formulation “should be treated” already implies an otherdirected awareness that is aimed at a helping behaviour—even if no action proper is taken, compassion demands one to adopt a certain respectful attitude towards the suffering person. These definitions demonstrate that the three terms pick out different aspects of intersubjective experience. Whereas empathy and sympathy seem to refer mainly to the experience of the empathiser, compassion seems to be more geared towards the target. Having empathy, according to the linguistic approach, means being able to cognitively make sense of another subject’s psychological life, or to share an affective state with them. However, these seem like entirely different capacities with different degrees of interpersonal involvement. Having sympathy, on the other hand, moves the focus of attention towards the target, for whom we feel pity, i.e., it is not so much a matter of what we understand or what we feel; rather, it is more about being concerned for the other. Having compassion goes even further in the direction of the other, since we not only witness somebody’s suffering and feel concerned but also wish to do something about it. Interestingly, to conclude this introductory glimpse at the OED, unlike “empathy” and “compassion,” which are approximated swiftly with singular definitions, the lexeme “sympathy” displays many facets. Its meanings range from having sympathies as an “agreement with or approval of an opinion or aim,” to one’s sympathies as a “formal expression of pity or sorrow for someone else’s misfortune,” to common feeling as a special kind of “understanding between people,” and to being in sympathy as “relating harmoniously to something else.” The latter two connotations are especially revealing because they point to the deep semantic and philosophical history of the concept, namely to the anthropologically founded fellow-feeling, 429
Thiemo Breyer
postulated by thinkers such as David Hume and Adam Smith in the 18th century, and further to the notion of a cosmological harmony in ancient natural philosophy. In the following, I will briefly sketch the historical roots of each key concept and then describe how they have been elaborated in the phenomenological tradition.
Empathy Empathy is clearly the youngest of our three concepts (for a philosophical history, cf. Pinotti 2011). Even though the word, “empathy,” is rooted in ancient Greek, was not really used as term in philosophy at that time. Composed of the prefix em- (which can have the spatial meaning “(with)in,” the temporal meaning “during,” and the figurative meaning “(together) with” and the root path- (as in the noun pathos, meaning “suffering” or “passion”), empathy denotes a pathos that is experienced with another. (Side note: in modern Greek, empatheia has curiously taken a very different meaning, namely spite.) To better understand what such an intersubjective pathos might mean, it is helpful to elucidate the different meanings of “pathos” in Greek. As Bernhard Waldenfels (2006, 3) explains, pathos means first of all an experience (in the sense of the German Widerfahrnis), something that happens to us—not without our doing, but going beyond it. Second, pathos means something adversarial, which is connected with suffering or enduring, but which also allows for a certain kind of learning through it (pathei mathos). Third, pathos is a passion that pulls us out of the ordinary and makes us transcend what we are commonly immersed in. These semantic dimensions are interpreted by Waldenfels in such a way that they bring out the aspect of being challenged by experience and afforded certain options to react that is key to his responsive phenomenology (cf., e.g., Waldenfels 1994). Pathos, in this sense, is something that always precedes my subjective intentions and that calls for my response. Empathy would then be something that I experience as a response to another, whose appearance, expressions, and actions catch my attention or impose themselves upon me. It is something that has a unique intersubjective quality insofar as the other is the source and reference point of my experience, but also in a second sense that it can be a shared suffering the other and I endure together, and in a third sense, that the other provokes a passionate reaction in me. After this short interpretation of the important element of pathos, which is of course also relevant for the second key concept, “sympathy,” let us return to the history of the notion of “empathy.” As mentioned before, it is of recent origin: for academic purposes, it was introduced as a technical term only at the beginning of the 20th century. Edward Titchener (1909) used it as a translation of the German Einfühlung (literally meaning “feeling into”), which had been common in aesthetics (Vischer 1872) and hermeneutics (Dilthey 1910). In this tradition, empathy was not conceived as an intersubjective process unfolding in the concrete interaction between persons, but as a mode of relating to artefacts or expressive displays—for example inspecting a work of art or interpreting a historical source in order to grasp their meaning. In psychology, especially in the work of Theodor Lipps (1907), empathy was determined as the primary source of understanding other minds, which functions on the basis of motorically co-performing a movement of expression observed in another. This simultaneous imitation leads to a recollection of one’s own prior emotions that are associated with the perceived expression. The emotion thus experienced is then attributed projectively to the other as their supposed internal state. This mechanism is, however, not restricted to the observation of other people, but extends to objects, for example, geometrical figures with anthropomorphic qualities. 430
Empathy, sympathy and compassion
In early phenomenology, contemporary theories of empathy were much discussed and criticised. Being generally interested in the “experience of the minded life of others” (Zahavi and Overgaard 2011, 5)—the most general definition of empathy as intersubjective awareness— phenomenologists tried to work out the fundamental structures of empathy and to differentiate various forms of alterity. As the mind expresses itself in many ways, the experience of empathy also takes many forms—from the bodily, to the affective-emotional, to the cognitive dimension. In the following, I briefly sketch some ideas by classic thinkers in the phenomenological tradition (for an overview, cf. also Jardine and Szanto 2017), to then point to some ongoing debates about social cognition and the interventions made by current phenomenological authors. Edmund Husserl (1990) and his pupil Edith Stein (1989) agree with Lipps’s account by emphasizing that empathy is an experience sui generis, which allows direct access to another person’s subjectivity. However, they disagree that this access is accomplished by perceptive, mnemonic, and projective sub-processes taken together. They rather believe that empathy is a sui generis mode of intentional directedness. Given as the noematic correlate of the empathic noesis, the other appears as a minded being with all kinds of expressive qualities. As an experience and understanding of the other mind (Fremderfahrung, Fremdverstehen), empathy consists in expression-perception (Ausdruckswahrnehmung). When seeing another person’s bodily display of anger or sadness, for instance, one does not need to first remember how one has experienced those emotions, but grasps their meaning in the expression itself. The phenomenological criticism rests on the observation that one’s own feeling in the face of another’s expression is not usually the same feeling the other has. For example, one perceives the other as angry, but this does not in itself make one angry, since that would amount to emotional contagion, which is not considered by Husserl and Stein as a form of empathy. Furthermore, one needs to understand the other’s emotion at least in type before one can recall from memory how it felt like for oneself to have such an emotion. This goes against Lipps’s claim that the recourse to one’s own previous emotional experiences allows the access to the other’s emotions in the first place. What is generally opposed by phenomenologists at this point is the dualism of mind and body, which underlies not only much of traditional Western ontology and epistemology, but also Lipps’s psychological approach. According to Max Scheler (1923), as will be discussed below under the rubric of sympathy, bodily expressions are the locus where understanding of other minds in the form of direct social perception finds its anchor. Expressions are neutral to the differentiation between physical outer appearance and psychological inner experience. In them, the emotions find their proper articulation and display. Not only in the perception of expressions does the body play a central role for a phenomenological understanding of empathy but also in interbodily encounter. According to the approach taken by Maurice Merleau-Ponty, empathy is possible on the basis of a transcendental structure of embodied subjectivity, namely the double-aspectivity of body-as-subject (Leib, to use the original German term) and body-as-object (Körper). This ambivalence that is inherent in bodily self-experience also allows for an immediate grasp of another’s body, which operates “neither [by] comparison, nor analogy, nor projection or ‘introjection’” (Merleau-Ponty 1964, 168). Rather, the structure of “compresence” of both aspects within oneself and of the other and the self in intersubjective space grants an understanding of the other as co-constituting what empathy can then refer to in various ways. As Merleau-Ponty explains: “The reason why I have evidence of the other man’s being-there when I shake his hand is that his hand is substituted for my left hand, and my body annexes the body of another person in that ‘sort of reflection’ it is paradoxically the seat of. My two hands ‘coexist’ or are ‘compresent’ because they are one single body’s hands. The other person appears through an extension of that compresence; he and I are like organs of one single intercorporeality” (ibid.). 431
Thiemo Breyer
In contemporary phenomenology, the concept of empathy is also widely discussed and used in the context of embodied (Gallagher 2005) and social cognition research (Zahavi 2014), psychopathology (Henriksen 2018), social ontology and collective intentionality (Salice and Taipale 2015; Szanto 2015; Szanto and Moran 2015; Szanto and Krueger 2019), virtuality (Fuchs 2014), and aesthetics (Hagener and Vendrell Ferran 2017), as well as in interdisciplinary cooperation with psychology and anthropology (Breyer 2015). Concerning a broader theory of intersubjective experience, phenomenological approaches intervene in mainstream definitions of empathy in elucidating ways as can be exemplified by the confrontation with theory theory and simulation theory approaches to social cognition. Theory theory claims that our understanding of other minds is based on knowledge that has the form of a theory and on computational mechanisms that run as algorithms. Nativistic varieties postulate evolutionarily developed modules in the brain, which are selected for processing socially relevant information (Baron-Cohen 1995; Carruthers 1996). Acquisitive theories, on the other hand, propose that the theory of mind according to which individuals make sense of other’s actions and psychological states results from continuous learning and experimentation (Gopnik 1993; Wellman et al. 2001). Understanding the other empathically, then, means that either neural algorithms run subconsciously and produce an attributable result, or that folk psychological knowledge and general intuitive rules are consciously applied to a situation. Simulation theory, on the other hand, takes empathy to be a simulation process that happens in one’s mind when observing another person. Neuroscientific approaches commonly refer to the activity of mirror neurons, which are supposed to enable empathy. Research has revealed that similar activity patterns in this part of the brain occur when a subject performs a specific movement and when it observes another subject do the same (Gallese and Goldman 1998; Rizzolatti and Sinigaglia 2008). This subpersonal mimetic mechanism is believed to be the root of empathy. Other accounts understand simulation as the conscious mental activity of imaginative perspective-taking. Empathy, according to this view, is the process by which somebody tries to put herself in the position of somebody else to figure out what they are experiencing (Goldman 2006; Heal 1998). Phenomenological accounts criticise these approaches for taking the dualism of self and other for granted and for viewing empathy as a process that goes on in the detached observer’s mind alone, thereby radicalising the third-person perspective. Contrary to this, they insist on the interactional negotiation (Gallagher 2001) of the contents of the empathic relation and the “participatory sense-making” (De Jaegher and Di Paolo 2007) in an empathiser-target-situation, as well as the intertwinement of self and other in embodied intersubjectivity. The constitutive role of the body for empathy can be emphasised in two ways (see above). First, the body is regarded as the primary medium of our contact with the world and with others; therefore, empathy is taken to unfold as an interactive process in the sphere of intercorporeality (Fuchs 2013; Tanaka 2015). Second, the body also displays all kinds of expressions (mimic and gestural), which provide information about the experience of the expressing subject. Empathic understanding, then, consists primarily in the perceptual grasp of another’s bodily expression (Gallagher 2008), an idea taken from early phenomenology and developed further under the rubric of “direct social perception” (Zahavi 2011).
Sympathy Sympathy (from Greek sym-, meaning “(together) with,” and again path-) can literally mean the same as empathy, namely experiencing a pathos with another (for philosophical differentiations cf. Chismar 1988 and Darwall 1998). If there is a semantic difference, it is perhaps that 432
Empathy, sympathy and compassion
the prefix sym- accentuates the togetherness even stronger than the prefix em-. The concept of sympathy has been widely used in the philosophical tradition since antiquity in various domains, from natural philosophy and cosmology to moral philosophy and ethics. In ancient philosophy, sympathy served as an explanatory concept for the most diverse phenomena, which are based on the observation that the same thing happens to two entities in an overarching whole without any visible direct influence. What this connection in each case is based on was interpreted differently, for example physically by Aristotle, atomistic by Epicurus, cosmologically by the Stoics or by a world-soul as by the Neoplatonists. In Plato and Aristotle, sympathy is construed as a physiological process, exemplified by the bodily resonance that is experienced when yawning because somebody else is yawning (Plato, Critias (1989)) or shuddering when hearing an unpleasant sound (Aristotle, Problems (2011)). Sympathy in this understanding always has an involuntary or compulsive element. There is a transfer of energy that is physically mediated and that contagiously overwhelms one. The Stoics understood sympathy as a principle that permeated and regulated the entire universe. It was not primarily a process of interpersonal encounter and communication, but a characteristic of the world. Nevertheless, there were also reflections that led from cosmic sympathy to interpersonal sympathy as a sense of community, not unlike how the concept is used in modern times. In particular, the postulate of a feeling of community through rationality stands out. When their anthropologically founded rationality is perfected to a certain degree, a person will experience their belonging to a humanity of likewise rational beings, and this is called sympathy. Though the word, sympathy, is not originally used for interpersonal affection but primarily describes the “coaffectibility” (Schliesser 2015, 9) of different entities—physical, biological, or psychological—it is increasingly applied to social, moral, and socio-political relations from the 16th century onwards. It then denotes the attraction between people or the correspondence of their feelings. In the 18th century, the term sympathy, and especially the adjective sympathetic, was progressively used in literature in which it meant having a direct affinity for something or an affection for someone, i.e., a resonance that could stand for friendship and human love. In philosophy, this meaning then became relevant in moral sense philosophy in England, which is based on the assumption that morality is rooted in natural human tendencies, for example, virtues stemming from an inherent altruism (e.g., Shaftesbury, Characteristics (2001); Hutcheson, A System of Moral Philosophy (2006)). Two prominent positions developing these ideas shall be briefly mentioned since they elaborate important motifs that inform the later debates on sympathy and empathy up to the present: David Hume and Adam Smith. For Hume, in his Treatise on Human Nature (2007), sympathy means the social practice of exchanging feelings and opinions on the basis of a universal principle of human nature. The mechanism behind it is based on the similarity and contiguity between self and other. When one sees the expressions of another, one tries to infer their causes and realises a certain affection or passion. This will then activate an idea of that passion in one’s own mind. Everybody has a vivid impression of their own feelings and other psychological states. Through sympathy, the idea of another person’s affections is associated with the impressions of one’s own affections, so that one can eventually experience the same passion as the other. For Smith, in his Theory of Moral Sentiments (2002), the basic process by which sympathy works is not inference and association, but imaginatively putting oneself into the other’s position to figure out what it would be like for oneself to be in that situation. This can result in the matching of one’s own psychological state with that of the other, but there are also limitations. For instance, it is difficult to imagine what it is like to experience something the 433
Thiemo Breyer
other is going through if one has never made an experience of the same kind. Today, this would usually be called perspective-taking or simulation (see above). What Hume and Smith in their different approaches have in mind when they speak of sympathy, namely sharing or understanding what another experiences and feels, is usually called empathy today. In phenomenology, it is Max Scheler—in his groundbreaking work Wesen und Formen der Sympathie (“Nature and Forms of Sympathy”) from 1923—who elaborates the various forms of intersubjective affectivity most extensively under the label of sympathy (see also Chapter 4 and Chapter 49 in this volume). Also for his approach, it is true that most people today would subsume some of the phenomena he discusses in terms of sympathy under the concept of empathy. It should be noted, however, that Scheler uses the term feeling-after (Nachfühlen) instead of empathy (Einfühlung), because he opposes basic assumptions of the theories of Einfühlung of his time. The most fundamental critique concerns the idea that to share emotions and understand other minds, one has to “feel oneself into” the other. This would imply that what is to be grasped empathically (the psychological experiences of the other) is not directly accessible and that the attempt to access it amounts to an active conscious procedure. For Scheler, this is a misconception. He emphasises that feelings are directly perceivable and understandable in the embodied expressions of a subject. Moreover, what the other is experiencing is often co-experienced by us involuntarily, as a passive co-affection, not as an imaginative or otherwise cognitive effort to understand the other. Among the many ways intersubjective affectivity manifests itself in experience, the following basic types of sympathy should be distinguished: (1) feeling-together (Mit-einander-fühlen), (2) feeling-after (Nachfühlen), (3) feeling-with (Mitgefühl), emotional contagion (Gefühlsansteckung), and (5) feeling-one or emotional unification (Einsfühlung). (1) The first form consists in feeling the same feeling as another subject by way of participating in it. The famous case Scheler evokes is that of two parents mourning over their deceased child. Each of them has their individual feelings of pain and sadness, but when standing next to the dead body of the child, they experience the suffering together as one and the same feeling. In this case, the sadness of the mother is not objectified in the consciousness of the father and vice versa. Rather, they co-subjectively experience the same. (2) Feeling-after is a mode of intentional relatedness to the other by which an understanding of their feelings emerges that does not involve sharing the same feeling. One retains a certain emotional distance and grasps what the other is experiencing without having analogous affective qualities in one’s own experience to the same extent as in feeling-together. Scheler nonetheless points out that the understanding of the other through feeling-after is not purely cognitive and affectively neutral. It is best understood as an understanding-by-feeling, in which we realise the type of the other’s feeling without it being transferred and made into a concrete vivid feeling of our own. It is this form of sympathy that today would regularly be conceptualised as empathy. (3) In feeling-with, on the other hand, one develops the same feeling in oneself on the basis of a previous feeling-after. One can share in the other’s joy in co-joy (Mitfreude) or in their suffering in co-suffering (Mitleid) with the corresponding affective characteristics. Hereby, one not only understands what the other is going through but also feels with them and potentially for them (as in the case of compassion or pity discussed below). (4) Emotional contagion is different from feeling-with because one is not intentionally directed towards the other but rather overtakes an emotion passively and involuntarily from them up to the point where one seems to loose oneself in the emotion of the other. Essentially, through contagion one is compelled to perform the same expressive movement as the other. It can happen in a dyadic form, as for instance when one feels the urge to giggle standing next to somebody who is giggling, but also in more collective forms, 434
Empathy, sympathy and compassion
as when entering a party and catching the joyful atmosphere in the room (for a contemporary social-psychological account, see Hatfield et al. 1993). (5) Feeling-one can be conceived as a limit case of contagion because here the ego perspective gets lost, and the subject merges with the other. For this mode of sympathy, Scheler gives a number of examples: the identification of a child with a toy or figure; the identification of spiritual practitioners with a totem animal in certain cultures, or with gods in ancient mystical traditions; the adoption of the will and contents of consciousness of the hypnotist when undergoing hypnosis; the reciprocal merging of partners during sexual intercourse; the mass-dynamic phenomenon of identification with a charismatic leader and with the other members of the collective; or the love of a mother for her child, where the impulses and drives of the child are experienced by the mother as if they were her own.
Compassion Compassion (from Latin compassio) is a literal translation of Greek sympatheia, which makes it difficult on a linguistic level to differentiate between compassion and sympathy; thus, we have to look for the historical developments of their respective usages as well as the philosophical meanings that have been bestowed upon them. Throughout history, there have been diverging opinions not so much on the basic psychological process of compassion, but concerning the ethical and moral value of compassion as an instinct, drive, motivation, feeling, or attitude. Plato and the Stoics commonly regarded compassion as a human tendency working against the application of rational principles, hindering appropriate moral evaluations and the capacity to adequately help the other. In the Christian tradition, compassion is then considered as a positive virtue. Apart from the term compassio, there are also the terms misericordia and commiseratio, expressing aspects of sympathy with varying connotations (Fischl 2017). It is impossible to trace the semantic history of these concepts here, yet it suffices to allude to a general tendency towards altruistic action in the context of theology. Here, misericordia was used as a translation of eleos, which in Greek means compassion in the sense of pity, as famously defined by Aristotle: “a feeling of pain that arises on the occasion of any evil, or suffering, manifest, evident (apparent, to the eye or ear), deadly or (…) painful, when unmerited; and also of such a kind as we may expect to happen either to ourselves or to those near and dear to us, and that when it seems to be near at hand” (Aristotle 2009, 2.8.2). Misericordia is then spelled out in different ways, but an important articulation is given by Augustine, who defines it as “a kind of compassion in our hearts for the misery of others which compels us to help them if we can” (Augustine 2018, 9.5). The shift from Aristotle’s conception consists in the idea that the emotional process of misericordia as a kind of compassion goes beyond eleos and is not so much about relating the perceived suffering to oneself, but about feeling the urge to help the other and eventually doing it. This of course is at the heart of the Christian virtue of charity. The positive value of compassion is also later embraced by thinkers such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau and moral sense philosophers. For Rousseau, it is not practical reason but compassion as a natural feeling before any reflection that is considered to be a moral principle. Compassion is the revulsion to see one’s kind suffer, which allows one to identify with a suffering person and thereby grasp the fundamental connectedness of humankind, including the anthropologically founded pains and sorrows of life. For Hume and Smith, compassion is a universal feeling that is explained by sympathy (see above). According to Smith, it is “the emotion which we feel for the misery of others, when we either see it, 435
Thiemo Breyer
or are made to conceive it in a very lively manner,” a “fellow-feeling with the sorrow of others” (Smith 2002, 4ff.). Among the more critical voices concerning the ethical impact of compassion is Immanuel Kant, who characterises it as a weak and blind affect. Therefore, “it must never rule, but must be subordinated to the capacity and reasonable desire to do good” (Kant 2011, 103). However, Kant also acknowledges that compassion can have a subsidiary motivating force precisely to do what is good. Taking this into account, he demands that it be an “indirect duty to cultivate the compassionate natural (…) feelings in us” (Kant 1991, 251) because they help realise the moral principles that reason alone perhaps could not apply. Schopenhauer in his ethics of compassion then famously radicalised the idea of an anthropological foundation of a feeling of humanity by claiming that compassion alone is the only true source of moral action, which again provoked efficacious criticism by thinkers such as Nietzsche (1986). Similarly, Arendt (1963) voiced staunched criticism of compassion’s role for genuine political action (see Chapter 15 in this volume). But here is not the place to review the ramified history of moral philosophy; let us thus turn to phenomenology. In phenomenology, the interest is first and foremost not in evaluating the moral significance of compassion, but in descriptively capturing it and comparing it with other types of affective states and emotional acts. In his lectures on ethics, Husserl briefly treats compassion when discussing Hume’s moral philosophy. Compassion, for Husserl, “does not mean suffering from the same pain as another, but to feel sorry for him, pitying him, suffering from the fact that he is suffering and because he is suffering” (Husserl 2012, 194, own translation). Concerning the affective quality, such suffering on the part of the compassionate subject is “genuine suffering,” as Husserl (1973b, 188) emphasises. Concerning the intentional object of an act of compassion, Husserl makes clear that one is only directed to the cause of the other’s suffering in a mediate way. The primary object of compassion is the other and the fact that they are suffering. In other places, Husserl identifies compassion as a genuinely intersubjective act, in that we regard the other as an ego, and acknowledge their subjectivity, their embodied being with all respective sensations and their having a world (the same world) as oneself (Husserl 1973a, 92). For Scheler, as we have seen, compassion as co-suffering (Mitleid) is a subtype of feeling-with (Mitgefühl). Compassion in this sense is a suffering on the basis of the other’s suffering, while it is clear to the compassionate subject that the original suffering is on the side of the other, i.e., the feeling of co-suffering has its origin there, not in one’s own subjectivity. In compassion, one experiences the other “as the other” (Scheler 1923, 40). The other’s alterity is thematic in consciousness, which excludes any form of identification or contagion. The intentional reference point of compassion is the other as a personal subject with their unique individual pain and sorrow. In emphasising the heteropathic element of compassion, Scheler criticises the theories of French Enlightenment thinkers who would attest an egoistic tendency to compassion, as they would suppose that it operates as a mode of self-protection on the basis of an analogical comparison of the sufferer with oneself, aiming at identifying and avoiding potential harm. In contrast, authentic compassion, according to Scheler, acknowledges the other’s suffering as their suffering. In the context of the question regarding the egoistic and altruistic tendencies of intersubjective emotions, Scheler also discusses the possibility of “inauthentic compassion” (Scheler 1923, 45), which arises when one feels distressed by witnessing the suffering of another and as a consequence helps them in order to alleviate one’s own discomfort. This feeling is affected by the feeling of the other but is ultimately self-directed and egoistic.
436
Empathy, sympathy and compassion
In Emmanuel Levinas’s phenomenological approach to an asymmetrical ethics, which is based on the idea of the primacy of the other who appears as a vulnerable being, suffering is conceived as irreducible. Thus, a responsibility for the other arises from the impossibility of looking away or attending to their suffering. This responsibility is manifest first and foremost in compassion, i.e., the compassionate co-suffering in which one also experiences oneself as an essentially vulnerable and exposed being and which constitutes the “nexus of human subjectivity” and as such a “supreme ethical principle” (Levinas 1998, 94). For Levinas, suffering is in principle endured as pure passivity. It is meaningless because it cannot be embedded in a rational whole, and therefore it is essentially evil. As such, it can also never be justified—be it as a mild form of suffering for a greater good or on the basis of utilitarian principles, or universal ethical principles à la Kant. One recognises the ethical command coming from the face of the other in suffering calls for a compassionate response in which the most fundamental responsibility for the other is rendered visible. Furthermore, according to Levinas, it is only via suffering that one can build up a relationship with the other (Levinas 1987, 92). In suffering as a limit case of consciousness, one experiences radical alterity—one is overwhelmed by the merciless world and by violent others. Precisely because of this heteronomous experience one can attain access to the other’s subjectivity through witnessing their suffering. Conversely, Levinas sees the justification of the suffering of others or its neglect as the source of all cruelty and immorality (Edelglass 2006, 45). Compassion is the remedy in that it not only acknowledges the other as being exposed to suffering, but also renders oneself exposed and vulnerable to the other. In being a “suffering for the suffering (…) of someone else” (Levinas 1998, 94), compassion is a genuinely ethical response, a mode of being-forthe-other that goes beyond—or lies ontologically before—any understanding of compassion as a psychological process or feeling. Working in the French tradition of combining phenomenological and theological thought (with key figures such as Paul Ricœur or Jean-Luc Nancy), Emmanuel Housset, in his book L’intelligence de la pitié (2003) (“The Intelligence of Pity”), has recently developed a wide-ranging account of compassion. In this investigation, he proposes that compassion is the only place from which the other can be attended to, recognised as a moral person, and understood in an ethically relevant sense. The author opposes views suspecting compassion to be an irrational drive leading to blurred moral judgments and requiring the correction through universal rational principles. In favouring compassion as a fundamental or existential dimension of the human being, Housset emphasises the quality of a responsive opening-up to the other, while letting them be, as well as the possibility of developing an intelligence for love, which also comprises a duty to realise justice made possible by compassion.
Conclusion As this chapter has shown, the terms “empathy,” “sympathy,” and “compassion” each have their remarkable semantic and philosophical history—sometimes reaching far into the past and into domains like theology and literature, sometimes signalling a specific discursive constellation where philosophy and the sciences construe new guiding concepts. In the context of a handbook on emotions, we should finally ask: Are all three concepts referring to emotions proper? As there is great variability in definitions, one will easily find theories that would clearly answer the question affirmatively. However, especially when it comes to empathy, it is not so clear whether it is a purely emotional capacity, or even whether the main component of the empathic process is emotional in nature. Phenomenologists have devoted
437
Thiemo Breyer
a lot of descriptive work to capturing the essential structures of empathy. Being conceived as a perception-like process of understanding the expressions of others, empathy does not in and of itself imply a necessary emotional component. Also, the basic embodied kind of empathy that ranges from intercorporeality to synchronisations and bodily resonances does not yield specific emotional qualities, but rather precedes and enables them. Furthermore, the imaginative engagement with the other in terms of putting oneself in their position and approximating their experience need not occur while feeling in a similar way as the other. In the case of sympathy, Scheler developed the most thorough account, wherein he subsumes various forms of affective forms of intersubjective engagement under the label. However, what Scheler refers to as “sympathy” would today frequently be construed as “empathy,” namely as affective or emotional empathy, which itself would be regarded as one among several forms of empathy (including bodily and cognitive empathy). Depending on the theoretical approach, emotional sharing is taken to be or not to be an integral part of empathy. In the first case, empathy would amount to what Scheler calls Mitfühlen, in the second case, it would come close to Nachfühlen. Compassion is quite unanimously regarded as an emotional matter, combined with a motivational and volitional component that drives us to help the other who is suffering and thereby causes our co-suffering. However, we should be aware that there are also other conceptions of compassion that regard the emotional dimension of the complex process leading from passive affection to active helping as morally problematic and would rather cut it out altogether. Such proponents of a “rational compassion” (from the Stoics to contemporary psychologists, cf. Bloom 2017) would reserve the term, compassion, for a purely cognitive procedure of figuring out the best ways to support the ones in need without any emotional involvement. To conclude, one should note that in phenomenology, but also in philosophy in general, in psychology, anthropology, and neighbouring disciplines, empathy has become the most widely used term. It has become an umbrella term for phenomena that have traditionally been designated with “sympathy” or “compassion.” These concepts are in themselves complex and cover many different aspects of our conscious experience (cf. also Michael 2014). Therefore, when using the broader term, “empathy,” one needs to be particularly clear about which aspect of intersubjectivity one is referring to. I have suggested elsewhere (Breyer 2015) that a multidimensional theory of empathy—covering processes on the level of embodiment, affectivity, perception, and cognition—can help locate the various intersubjective phenomena in a conceptual matrix and prevent hasty reductions of the term, “empathy,” to narrow definitions, which isolate phenomena that are best understood in their interconnectedness.
References Arendt, Hannah (1963). On Revolution. London: Faber and Faber. Aristotle (2009). Rhetoric. Vol II. Ed. by E. M. Cope, and J. E. Sandys. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Aristotle (2011). Problems. Ed. and transl. by R. Mayhew. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Augustine (2018). De Civitate Dei – The City of God. Ed. by P. G. Walsh, Isabella Image, and C. Collard. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press. Baron-Cohen, Simon (1995). Mindblindness. An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bloom, Paul (2017). Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. New York: Random House. Breyer, Thiemo (2015). Verkörperte Intersubjektivität und Empathie: Philosophisch-Anthropologische Untersuchungen. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
438
Empathy, sympathy and compassion Carruthers, Peter (1996). Language, Thoughts, and Consciousness: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Chismar, Douglas (1988). Empathy and Sympathy: The Important Difference. The Journal of Value Inquiry 22(4), 257–266. Darwall, Stephen (1998). Empathy, Sympathy, Care. Philosophical Studies 89(2/3), 261–282. De Jaegher, Hanne, and Ezequiel Di Paolo (2007). Participatory Sense-Making: An Enactive Approach to Social Cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8(4), 465–486. Dilthey, Wilhelm (1910). Der Auf bau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschaften. Abhandlungen der Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Philosophisch- Historische Klasse 1910, 1–123. Edelglass, William (2006). Levinas on Suffering and Compassion. Sophia 45(2), 43–59. Fischl, Thomas (2017). Mitgefühl – Mitleid – Barmherzigkeit: Ansätze von Empathie im 12. Jahrhundert. München: Utz. Fuchs, Thomas (2013). Depression, Intercorporeality, and Interaffectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies 20(7/8), 219–238. ——— (2014). The Virtual Other: Empathy in the Age of Virtuality. Journal of Consciousness Studies 21(5/6), 152–173. Gallagher, Shaun (2001). The Practice of Mind: Theory, Simulation, or Interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies 5–7, 83–108. ——— (2005). How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2008). Direct Perception in the Interactive Context. Consciousness & Cognition 17(2), 535–543. Gallese, Vittorio, and Goldman, Alvin (1998). Mirror Neurons and the Simulation Theory of Mind-Reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2, 493–501. Goldman, Alvin (2006). Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gopnik, Alison (1993). How We Know Our Minds: The Illusion of First-Person Knowledge of Intentionality. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16, 1–14. Hagener, Malte, and Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (Eds.) (2017). Empathie im Film: Perspektiven der Ä sthetischen Theorie, Phänomenologie und Analytischen Philosophie. Bielefeld: Transcript. Hatfield, Elaine, Cacioppo, John T., and Rapson, Richard L. (1993). Emotional Contagion. Current Directions in Psychological Science 2(3), 96–100. Heal, Jane (1998). Co-Cognition and Off-Line Simulation: Two Ways of Understanding the Simulation Approach. Mind and Language 13(4), 477–498. Henriksen, Mads Gram (2018). Schizophrenia, Psychosis, and Empathy. In: Magnus Englander (Ed.). Phenomenology and the Social Context of Psychiatry: Social Relations, Psychopathology, and Husserl’s Philosophy. New York: Bloomsbury, 27–48. Housset, Emmanuel (2003). L’intelligence de la pitié. Paris: Cerf. Hume, David (2007). A Treatise of Human Nature. Ed. by D. F. Norton, and M. J. Norton. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Husserl, Edmund (1973a). Zur Phänomenologie Der Intersubjektivität I. Ed. by I. Kern. (=Husserliana XIII). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. ——— (1973b). Zur Phänomenologie Der Intersubjektivität III. (=Husserliana XV). Ed. by I. Kern. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. ——— (1990). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. (=Husserliana IV). Ed. by M. Biemel. Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (2012). Einleitung in die Ethik: Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1920/1924. (=Husserliana XXXVII). Ed. by H. Peucker. Dordrecht: Springer. Hutcheson, Francis (2006). A System of Moral Philosophy. London: Bloomsbury. Jardine, James, and Szanto, Thomas (2017). Empathy in the Phenomenological Tradition. In: H. Maibom (Ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Empathy. London, New York: Routledge, 86–97. Kant, Immanuel (1991). The Metaphysics of Morals. Ed. by M. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2011). Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime. Ed. by P. Frierson, and P. Guyer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Krebs, Angelika. Love. In: T. Szanto, and H. Landweer (Eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Emotions. London, New York: Routledge.
439
Thiemo Breyer Levinas, Emmanuel (1987). Time and the Other. Transl. by R. A. Cohen. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press. ——— (1998). Entre Nous: Thinking-of-the-Other. Transl. by M. Smith, and B. Harshav. New York: Columbia University Press. Lipps, Theodor (1907). Das Wissen von fremden Ichen. In: T. Lipps: Psychologische Untersuchungen, Vol. 4. Leipzig: Engelmann. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1964). Signs. Transl. by R. C McCleary. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Michael, John (2014). Towards a Consensus about the Role of Empathy in Interpersonal Understanding. Topoi 33(1), 157–172. Mohrmann, Judith. Hannah Arendt. In: T. Szanto, and H. Landweer (Eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Emotions. London, New York: Routledge. Nietzsche, Friedrich (1986). Human, All Too Human. Transl. by R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pinotti, Andrea (2011). Empatia: Storia di un’idea da Platone al postumano. Roma: Editori Laterza. Plato (1989). Timaeus. Critias. Cleitophon. Menexenus. Epistles. Transl. by R. G. Bury. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Salice, Alessandro, and Taipale, Joona (2015). Group-Directed Empathy: A Phenomenological Account. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 46(2), 163–184. Scheler, Max (1923). Wesen und Formen der Sympathie. Bonn: Cohen. [Engl. Translation: The Nature of Sympathy. Transl. by P. Heath. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul 1956.] Schliesser, Eric (Ed.) (2015). Sympathy: A History. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Shaftesbury, Anthony Ashley Cooper, Earl of (2001). Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times. Edited by Douglas den Uyl. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. Smith, Adam (2002). The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Ed. by K. Haakonsson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stein, Edith (1989). On the Problem of Empathy. Transl. by W. Stein. Washington, D.C.: ICS Publication. Szanto, Thomas (2015). Collective Emotions, Normativity, and Empathy: A Steinian Account. Human Studies 38(4), 503–527. Szanto, Thomas, and Moran, Dermot (Eds.) (2015). Empathy and Collective Intentionality: The Social Philosophy of Edith Stein. Special Issue of Human Studies 38(4). Szanto, Thomas, and Krueger, Joel (Eds.) (2019). Empathy, Shared Emotions, and Social Identity. Special Issue of Topoi 38(1). Tanaka, Shogo (2015). Intercorporeality as a Theory of Social Cognition. Theory & Psychology 25(4), 455–472. Vischer, Robert (1872). Über das optische Formgefühl: Ein Beitrag zur Ästhetik. Diss. Tübingen. Waldenfels, Bernhard (1994). Antwortregister. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. ——— (2006). Das Fremde im Eigenen. Der Ursprung der Gefühle. E-Journal Philosophie der Psychologie 6, 1–6. Wellman, Henry M., Cross, David, and Watson, Julanne (2001). Meta-Analysis of Theory-of-Mind Development: The Truth about False Belief. Child Development 72(3), 655–684. Zahavi, Dan (2011). Empathy and Direct Social Perception: A Phenomenological Proposal. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2(3), 541–558. ——— (2014). Self and Other: Exploring Subjectivity, Empathy, and Shame. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Zahavi, Dan, and Overgaard, Søren (2011). Empathy without Isomorphism: A Phenomenological Account. In: J. Decety (Ed.). Empathy: From Bench to Bedside. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 3–20.
440
38 AGGRESSIVE EMOTIONS From irritation to hatred, contempt and indignation Hilge Landweer
What do emotions like irritation, rage, envy, hatred and indignation have in common and how do they differ? Are there connections between them? There seem to be some typical overlaps, such as between hatred and contempt. How can these emotions be transformed into one another, and what role does embodiment play in this? These are the questions that I will address in the present chapter.1 At first glance, all of these emotions seem to be triggered by something that is rejected by the subject of the emotions; from her point of view, it would have been better if the occasion for the emotion had not existed in the first place. These emotions are often accompanied by the desire, which is not necessarily realizable, that the circumstance that occasioned it should disappear or even be destroyed. Thus, all these emotions have an aversive character: when they are directed against things, then it is with an urge to destroy them; when they are directed against persons, they can generally be characterized by the desire to see the other person suffer harm, or they even involve the impulse to harm them. Therefore, I want to describe them as “emotions of aggression” or “aggressive emotions,” where “aggression” should not be understood in the psychoanalytical sense of the theory of drives. What is “aggressive” about these emotions is their bodily orientation: they are all directed “outwards” against other persons or things on which they impinge like aggressive vectors. I will argue that these aversive strivings often prevail despite social condemnation. Typically, they do so by virtue of the fact that emotions like hatred are reinterpreted by their subjects into seemingly more harmless emotions like contempt.
1. Basic concepts of my phenomenological analysis In what follows, I make use of Hermann Schmitz’ phenomenological vocabulary (Schmitz 2019; Chapter 19 in this volume), which is only gradually gaining recognition in the debate on emotions. A more common approach is to differentiate Husserl’s concept of the intentional object in terms of more recent concepts in the theory of emotions such as target, focus and formal object (Helm 2001). Schmitz’s phenomenological apparatus has the advantage of offering a more precise analysis of the reinterpretations in the spectrum of the emotions of aggression based on their bodily-felt aspects and spatiality.
441
Hilge Landweer
I describe as “corporeal,” “bodily-felt” or “relating to the felt body” (leiblich)—what can be felt on or in the body from the first-person perspective (whether interoceptively or not) without relying on exteroceptive senses such as sight or touch. The “body” (Körper), on the other hand, is objectified and perceived from the third-person perspective, even when it is viewed by the person herself. “Contraction” and “expansion” are two fundamental categories for describing bodily-felt sensation. To illustrate: When I am afraid, I experience a certain bodily-felt contraction, as when someone says “I am choking with fear”; when I am happy, I may feel buoyant and elated (think of the expression “walking on air”) or feel a sense of expansion, as when we say “my heart is bursting with joy.” The structure of contraction and expansion is not specific to emotions, but is a fundamental feature of our bodily-felt experience. Our entire bodily-felt condition continually oscillates between tendencies toward contraction and toward expansion. One could say that it exhibits a dialogical structure: contraction “responds” to expansion and vice versa, whereby contraction and expansion remain closely interrelated (Schmitz 2019, 61–72).2 When inhaling, for example, you first feel an expansion until a contraction begins that is released by exhaling; this second expansion in turn reaches a limit, as it were, and thus contracts, thereby forcing you to reverse direction in renewed expansion by inhaling. This is a spatial experience. Emotions grip us at the bodily-felt (leiblich) level, that is, they intrude in the dynamics of our felt bodies and change them. This is what I call “affectedness” (Betroffenheit), the condition of being affected by an emotion, or “affective involvement.” Affectedness refers to having an emotion. There are good reasons to distinguish between an emotion and being affected by it, that is, between an emotion and actually experiencing it. Thus, we are quite capable of perceiving an emotion merely in a distanced way without at the same time being affected by it—for example, when we register the emotions of other people who are not close to us without feeling with them. The same applies to observing the emotions of film characters (see Chapter 29 in this volume) or noticing the atmospheres of landscapes, which we can also perceive without necessarily being gripped by them at a corporeal-affective level (see Chapter 23 in this volume). That emotions can be perceived from a distance without one being gripped by them indicates they possess a relative ontological independence. Like bodily-felt sensations, they are situated phenomenologically in experiential space, which is different from the familiar geometric space. In the space of emotions (Gefühlsraum), we can perceive directions such as the downward pressure exerted by the weight of grief; these directions cannot be measured, however, and their at times voluminous weight cannot be divided into dimensions. Thus, emotions are not primarily states of consciousness, but spatial phenomena that are appropriated in bodily-affective affectedness (see Landweer 2019). Since emotions are spatial, they can be described more precisely in terms of the distinction between their “anchoring point” (Verankerungspunkt) and their “condensation area” (Verdichtungsbereich). This only appears to correspond to the more standard distinction in theories of emotions between “focus” (anchoring point) and “target” (condensation area). The anchoring point can be understood as the location that triggers the emotion, while the condensation area refers to those aspects of the situation in which the emotion manifests itself vividly (Schmitz 1990, 301). This distinction enables a better understanding of the transitions and overlaps between supposedly distinct emotions in space; in all factual emotions, mixtures of different emotional states are the norm rather than the exception. How, then, can the individual emotions be delimited from each other?
442
Aggressive emotions
We can offer at least a rough sketch of the specific embodiment of the particular emotions. Our vocabulary for describing bodily-felt experience is limited and is probably insufficient to demarcate the different emotions clearly from each other through bodily-felt sensation alone. However, this becomes possible through a more precise description of the respective anchoring points and condensation areas of the emotions, or their absence, as spatial determinations. These determinations provide us with orientation, given that the vast majority of languages have a plethora of expressions for emotions of aggression, whereby not every expression refers to a distinct phenomenon and not every distinct emotion has a name in every language. Characteristic of all emotions of aggression is that they are almost universally normatively regulated, and indeed sanctioned. Consequently, there is a strong impulse on the part of their subjects to reinterpret them in terms of socially more accepted emotions, often against the background of ideological narratives. The theoretical framework of the spatiality of emotions, with anchoring point and condensation area, and their embodiment renders these reinterpretation processes more transparent (see Section 6).
2. Irritation and rage Irritation as an emotion refers to a more or less slight irritability that arises when the person concerned is disturbed in the pursuit of their intentions or in their actions (anchoring point). The condensation area of irritation is unspecific: one can become irritated about something or about someone that one blames for the disturbance. But the emotion can also become consolidated in the circumstance that was hindered or constrained, or in the hindrance itself, that is, in the state of affairs that thwarts one’s intentions. In the form of an irritated mood, irritation can dispense with an anchoring point altogether; often the individual who has the emotion is unaware of a cause of their emotional state. Irritation is characterized at the corporeal level by a tension, a disquieting restlessness and impatience that finds expression in clenched teeth, but also in one’s tone of voice, irritated utterances and little attacks against others, which the subject of the emotion herself hardly notices. The aggressive bodily-felt orientation of irritation may manifest itself in treating things roughly. Instead of “breaking out,” irritation simmers. The actions to which it can lead usually provide no relief—unlike angry and indignant actions—and they are not necessarily directed against the (actual or supposed) source of the disturbance. Rather, they are generally directed more or less aimlessly against the entire social environment, on which the subject takes out her irritation. Typically, the anchoring point and the condensation area can shift from one object or state of affairs to another over the course of a period of irritation. For example, initially the fact that the carpenter failed to appear at the appointed time and you waited in vain can be the anchoring point, eventually that the bus came too late, and finally that you forgot important documents. As a result, someone who is not involved often becomes the “victim” of the irritated mood. Here the condensation area would first be the carpenter or carpenters in general, then the appointment you have missed because of the bus delay, and finally everyone you meet, all of whom are now perceived as an annoying disturbance. This description shows that irritation often fluctuates between an emotion with a clearly recognizable anchoring point and an objectless mood. The characteristic corporeal manifestation of the emotions of aggression as a whole is one of breaking out of bodily-felt confinement. This is least pronounced in the case of irritation, but appears clearly in the case of rage, hatred, anger and indignation (contempt is an
443
Hilge Landweer
interesting exception that I will address below). “Rage” generally designates an emotion that reacts to more serious disturbances than anger—moreover, in an explosive way. Here, too, the trigger is something external that thwarts one’s intentions, but which—more so than in the case of irritation—often arises suddenly and unexpectedly (anchoring point). As with irritation, the condensation area of rage can be a person or a state of affairs, but also in a very diffuse way the situation as a whole and even something against which one is in a rage; in “blind” rage, the condensation area is lacking entirely (see Schmitz 1973, 33f.). Corporeally speaking, rage can be described in terms of centrifugal impulses that break out of the confinement of the felt body into expansiveness with directions but without an aim. The expression a “fit of rage” expresses the involuntary, violent and sudden character of rage. In its condensation area, this emotion is not as unwavering and unerring as, for example, anger over an injustice that has been committed, which can only refer to persons, specifically those who are held responsible for the injustice by the subject of the emotion (see below). Rage, on the other hand, is vented on someone or something who or which is not necessarily related to its anchoring point; rage often seeks out substitutes.3
3. Envy, jealousy, Ressentiment Envy and jealousy, emotions whose anchoring points and condensation areas are more sharply circumscribed than those of irritation and rage, undoubtedly belong to the emotions of aggression. The anchoring point of envy is a quality or the possessions of another person, which the subject of the emotion would like to possess herself. Corporeally speaking, envy is a contracting or confining, unrelenting emotion; thus, we sometimes speak of “gnawing” envy. Envy involves a certain fixation on the thing envied and also on the person who is envied; the episodic emotion of envy has a more pronounced tendency than other emotions to develop into an attitude or disposition, in the sense of an increased probability of being overcome by acute envy. The condensation area of this emotion is always clearly circumscribed, but it can either be the person envied—in which case it typically has the connotation that one begrudges the person the things for which one envies them—or more strongly the coveted quality or thing itself. In the latter case, envy can develop into competition or even into a certain admiration, and largely lose its aversive quality. Often this “productive” envy is subsequently used to make an effort to acquire the envied thing oneself, an attitude and emotional modification typical of neoliberal societies. In all cases, however, envy presupposes comparability and hence, in certain respects, also equality between the envier and the envied.4 But one can certainly also envy people with whom one is not personally acquainted, as long as one sees one’s own situation as being comparable to theirs; one can even be envious of social groups with whom one merely shares membership in a society (see Salice and Montes Sánchez 2019). Jealousy, on the other hand, seems to be an emotion that is reserved for close relationships, i.e., above all family and intimate relationships and friendships. It can be regarded as a special case and a further differentiation of envy, since it is related to persons not only in its condensation area but, like envy, also in its anchoring point. The jealous person A envies another person B for the relationship she has with someone C and sees it as a threat to her own relationship with C (anchoring point). In its condensation area can be situated either the person “of whom” one is jealous (B), less often the person for whose sake one is jealous (C), but above all also obsessive fantasies about the nature of the relationship between B and C. Thus, jealousy has an extremely complex structure bound up with a strong fixation on its condensation area: the jealous person cannot let go of the “object” of her emotion. In many 444
Aggressive emotions
cases, the feeling of jealousy is virtually immune to correction through confrontation with reality, i.e., with the question of how “justified” it is; the jealous person often seems to be almost inextricably fettered to the condensation area of her emotion. The complexity and fixedness of jealousy have to do with the fact that it is closely bound up with other emotions: most importantly, jealousy can easily turn into resentment, Ressentiment or hatred of one—generally B; C is usually “spared”—or both parties involved. The violent corporeal reactions associated with jealousy, ranging from palpitations, shortness of breath and other sudden feelings of contraction (in the sense outlined in Section 1) to violent attacks, are well documented.5 A phenomenon widely studied in philosophy and closely related to envy is Ressentiment, a mixture of emotions that originates in feelings of inferiority and envy, and often also shame.6 Ressentiment is founded on prejudices, presumed negative attributes of persons, which constitute its anchoring point. It is marked by a strong emotional aversion mostly against certain social groups, less often against individuals, as its condensation area. In French, “ressentiment” means something like “secret rancor.” The genesis of Ressentiment is rooted in an enduring feeling of powerlessness: those affected feel disadvantaged by comparison with those who are situated in the condensation area of this emotion, or feel that they have been outdone or outsmarted by them and correspondingly are inferior to them. At the same time, Ressentiment is often associated with a compensatory ideology of one’s own superiority, although this is not felt at the moment of affective involvement—in fact, the person who is developing an attitude of Ressentiment tends to feel inferior. This ambivalence can easily develop into a general attitude that one has got a raw deal. This rancor is “secret”—as suggested by the French term—insofar as the resentful person does not admit this to herself, but also because she keeps it in check, generally for reasons of conforming to social norms. The concept of Ressentiment represents a challenge for the theory of emotions because the vast majority of those affected by this emotion would not describe their own state of mind in this way; sometimes Ressentiment is deemed to be “unconscious” from an outside perspective. It then seems questionable whether Ressentiment is a distinct episodic emotion at all, or whether it is not rather a consolidated conglomerate of emotions, or even a disposition or an affective attitude toward certain others (Szanto unpubl. manus.). Even if the latter conception may capture how the word is commonly used, an attitude that is so strongly associated with aversive emotions will undoubtedly manifest itself at least occasionally in episodic emotions. In the case of Ressentiment, it is the aversion to certain others, which can assume an acute form and at any rate in most cases is likely to be noticed by those affected themselves. The term “Ressentiment” would then designate a special disposition to aversion and even hatred among the emotions of aggression.
4. Hatred and contempt This brings me to the most clearly aversive emotion in the spectrum of emotions of aggression, which is almost always associated with an impulse to violence—which, of course, does not have to be acted out—namely, hatred. A certain group or the hated person is situated in its condensation area—that is, as in the case of envy and jealousy, it can only be a personal object.7 Like jealousy, hatred is also marked by a contracting fixation on the condensation area, from which the subject can free herself only with difficulty. In the case of hatred, however, this fixation on a particular group or person is even more powerful. The occasions for hatred in individual relationships, its anchoring points, may be injuries suffered or humiliations; in the case of hatred of groups (but also of individuals), the occasions are generally real 445
Hilge Landweer
or imagined restrictions of one’s own possibilities by the reactively hated persons. Typical of hatred, however, is that the original anchoring point fades and mutates into other reasons that become the pretext for the persistence of this emotion, which is supposedly “justified” by the new state of affairs. A characteristic feature of hatred is therefore that the anchoring point often shifts, so that ultimately it is arbitrary. Although someone appears to be hateful because they have done something, such as harming the hater, or supposedly have certain odious qualities, it is ultimately almost impossible from an external perspective to distinguish whether there are in fact reasons for the hatred or the hater is just looking for pretexts for their emotions (see Szanto forthcoming). So is hatred, like love, an emotion without an anchoring point? Do people hate “for no reason,” as they love “for no reason”? That would be an overhasty inference. The question of the reason for hatred or its groundlessness does not arise in a neutral space, but is always shaped by normative ideas (see Chapter 48 in this volume). If one understands hatred as an emotion that has to be proscribed and prevented on account of its destructiveness, then one may be more inclined to describe hate as fundamentally irrational, as an emotion without any reason or “focus” (in the terminology of Helm 2001; see also Chapter 20 in this volume) or any anchoring point, as if what is “hateful” cannot be concretized in principle.8 On the other hand, one could also argue that hatred lacks an anchoring point in principle on the grounds that those who hate tend to offer pretexts for hatred precisely because they know that their hatred is not tolerated: in order to lend their emotions the appearance of being justified in their own eyes and those of others, they cite reasons that do not really apply to them or are even entirely arbitrary. From this perspective, one could go so far as to assert that the normative proscription of hatred leads to its being presented as a different emotion, such as indignation, for which there is a clear reason, but that “genuine” hatred does not have any qualifiable anchoring point (see Section 6). Even though this may actually occur, I don’t think that it is justified to infer that hatred has no anchoring point at all. The phenomenological description of hatred should not treat as paradigmatic the cases in which hatred seems especially incongruous or arbitrary; rather, as with other emotions, the analysis of hatred should be based on situations in which hatred is comprehensible, albeit not acceptable. At any rate, the normative attitude to this emotion should be methodologically separated as far as possible from its description. Let us consider the extreme case of hatred of a rapist or a torturer in a legal system that does not allow such perpetrators to be prosecuted. Here hatred seems to have a clear anchoring point. In this case, hatred even has a certain proximity to emotions of injustice such as feeling humiliated or indignation (Landweer 2016, see Section 5). In such a case, for example, the story may begin with indignation at the behavior of the person who is eventually hated; but the indignation does not find any legally or socially recognized form and remains ineffectual, because—for whatever reason—it cannot pursue its retributive impulse. As a result, the person concerned often cannot express or act out their emotions, and instead becomes completely fixated on the person who was previously situated in the condensation area of anger or indignation and is now hated. This fixation on the condensation area is typical of fully developed hatred. In some cases, then, hatred has a clear anchoring point, but in others the anchoring point seems arbitrary or is entirely absent. In all cases of hatred, however—and in contrast to anger, indignation, rage and even irritation—the anchoring point loses its salience by comparison with its condensation area: the more intense the hatred, the more its object becomes the hated person in their entirety; and this means that, regardless of what they do or fail to do, the less important their actual and past behavior, the stronger the concentration on the 446
Aggressive emotions
hated person becomes. To a certain extent, the hater is hardly able to detach herself from her fixation on the object of her hatred when she has surrendered herself to her hatred. Corporeally speaking, the hater is directed in her acute emotion directly at the hated person with aggressive vectors: if there were no inhibiting factors, her preference would be to attack the hated person head-on. The expression “If looks could kill…” expresses this aggressive concentration on the hated person. More than any other emotion, hatred is associated with an impulse to act to destroy one’s counterpart. The object of hatred is someone whose presence is unbearable to the hater; everything the hated person does seems equally repugnant; from the hater’s perspective, it would be better if they did not exist. This impulse is what constitutes the high propensity to violence of hatred. In contrast to emotions such as irritation, rage and anger, hatred very rarely occurs just once and in an exclusively acute form and then disappears again. Instead, it typically develops into a disposition of hatred toward a specific person or a group and can then become an attitude that determines long phases or even the whole life of the person affected.9 This is linked to the fact that hatred, unlike rage or anger, cannot be acted out corporeally through acute outbursts. Hatred is typically limitless; the pattern in which this emotion unfolds does not allow its fixation on its condensation area to be loosened and in many cases not even the death of the hated person puts an end to the emotion of the hater. Of course, as with all emotions, the personal attitude toward this emotion contributes to the intensity and concision or vagueness in which hatred is expressed; this attitude is always shaped by culture. Thus, everyone develops an attitude toward how they deal with corporeal-affective affectedness, for example, whether they cultivate it, endure it or deny it. In Western Europe, individual hatred is generally morally denounced and in certain frameworks also legally proscribed (think of hate speech or hate crime legislations); thus, those subject to it usually deny it, but hatred of certain social groups is at least tolerated in some milieus, and is even sometimes cultivated. Legitimizing narratives about the hated group, such as misogyny, racism and anti-Semitism, serve as indicators and justifications of hatred, especially hatred of collectives (Demmerling and Landweer 2007; Szanto forthcoming). These ideologies, stories and anecdotes contain allusions to ambivalent emotions such as feelings of superiority and inferiority, and it becomes clear that hate narratives always address a mixture comprising a variety of aggressive emotions: envy, resentment, anger and indignation, but also contempt, combine with hatred to form a toxic mixture. Here the coexistence of hatred and contempt is in need of explanation, since, aside from some commonalities, the two emotions exhibit virtually opposed strivings. At first glance, contempt seems to be an anomaly among the group of aggressive emotions, because it leads those who feel it to avoid the objects of their contempt; unlike hatred or anger, it is specifically not corporeally directed against its object. In its clear and unadulterated forms, in particular in the case of moral contempt,10 it is rarely associated with a physical impulse to annihilate its object. Nevertheless, it has a high potential for aggression, not only because social exclusion on account of ignorance can have equally destructive effects to violence, but also because the despised person is regarded and treated as someone who should not be there and is worthless. Characteristic of contempt is a corporeal impulse to shun, which is connected with a tendency to adopt an upright posture, comparable to the bodily-felt directions in pride, but also arrogance (see Kolnai 1935), and is generally associated with a feeling of superiority. This actual or merely imagined superiority can refer to supposed moral qualities, but also to any other qualities regarded as somehow “good.” The feeling of superiority corresponding to the upward bodily-felt tendency is associated with the fact that contempt tends to be felt from a socially superior position or one endowed 447
Hilge Landweer
with a greater potential for power (Kolnai 1935). Hatred, on the other hand, is more an emotion of the socially inferior,11 which is directed against those who—from the point of view of those who feel hatred—are responsible for their problematic situation. Thus, in historical and in individual or political constellations, it can often be traced back to the experience of inferiority. This connection is founded on the fact that hatred mobilizes forces for overcoming the situation that is experienced as unbearable; in hatred, the powerless experience themselves as capable of action. This is why it is those who feel powerless and helpless who are more likely to hate. Someone in a socially superior position, on the other hand, can feel confidently detached or sovereign, and hence will more likely feel contempt. Unlike hatred’s impulse to annihilate, contempt involves an impulse to social ostracism and exclusion; it aims at the “social death” of its object as opposed to their physical death, which is the ultimate goal of hatred. This does not mean that contempt is incompatible with physical violence, only that its starting point is a different one. Because the despised person is regarded as in some way inferior, inferiority can become the reason for treating those who are despised in extreme cases as things and thus dehumanize them; any kind of treatment, including brutal violence, then seems justified. The connection between hatred and violence only seems to be closer than that between contempt and violence because, in hatred, the powerless person is bent on violence to resolve the situation, whereas the socially superior person stands in a different relation to the situation, and therefore has no need to hate, and certainly does not need to become violent—they have other practical options. In any case, one or more persons are situated in the condensation area of contempt, while the anchoring point is their supposed inferiority in moral, social or some other respects. In all forms of contempt, the despisers elevate themselves above the despised; contempt stages its own superiority. Hatred, on the other hand, involves concentrated attention to the other; it binds (see also Kolnai 1935; Ahmed 2014; Szanto forthcoming). Contempt, by contrast, is expressed in the withdrawal of recognition of the other person as an equal; those who are despised are disregarded and ignored. Here, I have offered ideal-typical descriptions of the two emotions in order to differentiate the phenomena. However, since hatred and contempt are often intermingled, can mutate into each other, but can also alternate, the above attribution to power constellations will have to be differentiated further in Section 6.
5. Anger and indignation Anger and indignation are moral emotions or emotions grounded in the sense of justice. They arise when someone has committed an injustice against you or against someone else. Here, it should be noted that “anger” is used in everyday language in a wider sense and often coincides with what has been described here as “rage.” Moral emotions or justice-related emotions are not exclusively individual but are shared in a legal culture—notwithstanding differences in detail (Landweer 2016). A legal culture is mainly held together by a range of shared legal and moral emotions, even if one may feel or express, with regard to particular legal issues, very different emotions; accordingly, in this sense, different, more or less individual emotional orientations may be at play in some cases while the most important legal norms are shared. A norm applies to someone if she recognizes it in the sense that she feels bound by it. Without such (emotional) self-commitment, no norm can be valid for the respective person in the sense that she is really oriented toward it and its observance can be ensured, at best, through external coercion. Norms thus would not even be valid for us if we did not register and sanction violations of them emotionally, which means: if we did 448
Aggressive emotions
not become indignant when others violate norms and if we did not feel ashamed when we violate norms ourselves.12 The violation of binding norms—regardless of whether oneself or someone else has transgressed the norm—disturbs what can be called “legal peace” in a certain social context, namely that balance in which there is no reason for anger, indignation and shame. The emotions of indignation and shame demand that the legal peace disturbed by the violation of the norm be restored: shame by signaling that the person who is ashamed recognizes the norm in question in principle, even though they have just transgressed it; anger and indignation by indicating that someone else has transgressed a norm that applies to the angry person and by urging that action be taken against them. Anger and indignation involve an impulse to exact retribution that can assume various forms. The endeavor to restore the legal peace disturbed by an injustice is a characteristic feature of the emotions of justice, which traditionally include at least shame, guilt, anger and indignation. Anger and indignation are difficult to distinguish. Indignation has the same cause, but it can also refer to injustice that either cannot be attributed to specific persons or is based on abstract circumstances. The phrase “to be angry with someone (for something)” suggests that anger has one or more persons as a condensation area. Accordingly, if it is unclear who is responsible for the injustice, we speak instead of “indignation”; it is significant that, in the expression “to be indignant over something,” there is no personal object.13 Anger seems to require a counterpart, whereas this is not necessarily the case with indignation. As regards corporeality, however, there is no difference, and even the everyday understanding seems to regard both emotion terms as synonymous. The corporeal side of anger and indignation and its anchoring point and condensation area can be explained by contrasting it with shame, which is not, of course, counted among the emotions of aggression, but is rather opposed to them. Anger and indignation, like rage, are projected in all directions. Thus, corporeally speaking, they are directed centrifugally into expansiveness, in stark contrast to the contracting centripetal directions of shame: someone who is ashamed feels penetrated by the glances of others as if by aggressive vectors, and lowers her gaze. Typical of shame is the metaphor of wanting to sink into the ground, and in shame one does indeed feel an absolute contraction. Anger and rage, on the other hand, are often described in German using the image “aus der Haut fahren” (“to jump out of one’s skin”—i.e., “to fly off the handle”). This touches on to the centrifugal and thus expansive corporeal directions of the emotion and an eruptive element. As with shame, the anchoring point of anger is also that a norm was transgressed that holds for the subject of the emotion. However, anger and indignation refer to the transgressions of others, whereas shame (and also guilt) refers to one’s own violations; the condensation area of anger is one or more other persons, that of shame is oneself, one’s own unworthiness (but on shame on behalf of someone else, or Fremdscham, see Chapter 40 in this volume; see also Landweer 1999). Apart from persons, institutions such as “the government” or abstractions such as “capitalism” can also be located in the condensation area of indignation, provided that they are determined by human action. But how do emotions like anger indict right or wrong? Hermann Schmitz argues that anger takes the measure of the prior disruption of the sphere of justice and that it can adapt its intensity to the violation suffered. Of course, anger can also be mistaken and be too violent. The fact that we make corresponding evaluations, however, points indirectly to a margin of variation that is normally sounded out in the emotion itself. To corroborate this, Schmitz refers, among others, to the despair of the irascible when they suddenly realize that their anger has gone far beyond the appropriate retribution.14 It is not that the angry person 449
Hilge Landweer
measures the talion precisely, according to Schmitz; the measuring is normally performed by the emotion itself. In support of Schmitz, one could also cite talk of the “appropriateness” of anger and indignation, which not only refers to whether an injustice has occurred at all, but can also mean the intensity of the emotion and the measure of the action motivated by it, that is, the retribution. The expression “holy anger” also refers indirectly to a measuring internal to the emotion itself. This expression implies a certain admiration for the extent of the anger thus described, which refers to especially egregious injustice: “holy anger” is generally judged to be vehement, but morally appropriate, because it corresponds as a sanction to the scale of the injustice.
6. Transformations and reinterpretations of emotions of aggression At the outset, I raised the question of the similarities between the emotions of aggression and of typical mixtures and transformations. In this section, I would like to draw together the results and, on this basis, outline some theses on the normatively embedded character of the transformations and the corresponding reinterpretations. All aggressive emotions (with the exception of some forms of irritation and rage) share the more or less sharply circumscribed personal object in their condensation area, and they are corporeally directed against this object in irritated, explosive or fixating ways. This commonality facilitates transformations from one aggressive emotion to another, transformations that should be understood in spatial terms. If the anchoring point and condensation area are conceived as part of the experienced space of the emotion, then all that is required for a transformation into a different aggressive emotion is a slight shift of the anchoring point in directional space while the condensation area remains constant. For example, I can initially envy a colleague for the honorable post to which he has been appointed. But if I learn that he probably only got the position because he is best friends with the person who wielded the most influence in the decision-making process, then the anchoring point, the coveted post, can shift, namely to the fact that my colleague was appointed to this post unjustly—on the basis of a biased judgment. The condensation area of envy in which the colleague with the honorable post was situated does not need to be changed, but only needs to be expanded to include his friend: now my indignation is clearly consolidated in both persons as jointly illegitimate actors. What is important here is that the space involved is not geometric three-dimensional space, but experienced directional space: with the new anchoring point, the emotion intrudes from an only slightly altered direction in the dynamics of the felt body. The fact that such transitions are facilitated by the spatial structure of anchoring point and condensation area makes it easier to understand the typical mixtures in the domain of emotions of aggression mentioned in the foregoing sections: Ressentiment as involving the overlapping of envy, feelings of inferiority, aversion and rancor, the frequent mixture of hatred and contempt, but also the combination of jealousy and hatred. If the aforementioned transformations of emotions were merely phenomena of consciousness, the transitions within the “focuses” and “targets” would be less obvious and more difficult to explain than if the transmissions are understood as spatial processes involving shifts in the anchoring point and the condensation area. However, the transformations supported by the spatial structure of the emotions also provide occasions for misinterpretations and reinterpretations, which always occur within a normative framework. The norms in terms of which the aggressive emotions are judged go beyond the notions of appropriateness that also apply to all other emotions (see Chapters 24 and 41 in this volume). Since emotions such as hatred, envy and resentment can motivate 450
Aggressive emotions
aggressive, and even violent, actions, not only are these actions themselves generally socially sanctioned, but so too are the emotions by which they are motivated and prompted. To what extent and on which occasions the various emotions of aggression are tabooed, sanctioned or accepted depends, of course, on the cultural context in which they arise. The spectrum of possible normative attitudes extends from an absolute taboo, which for the most part applies to hatred, especially in virtue of its high potential for violence, to disapproval of uncontrolled outbursts of rage and approval of some forms of envy that are regarded as productive and simultaneous condemnation of other variants such as malevolence. However, these normative attitudes also include the acceptance of certain forms of jealousy, which, despite a high proclivity to violence in certain contexts, are still regarded as understandable, and sometimes even as proof of love or as being required by honor. While contempt is more or less ignored in public and private discourses, the retributive emotions of justice, anger and indignation, garner special recognition.15 What accounts for their special status? In the spectrum of the emotions of aggression discussed here, anger is certainly not only the emotion which—in appropriate expressions— enjoys the highest social esteem. It also stands in contrast to the other aggressive emotions in virtue of its particularly concise structure. Its anchoring point and condensation area are clearly circumscribed and, in addition, are connected in an unambiguous way: one is angered by a violation of a binding norm, namely by someone who has committed this violation. It is only in virtue of this interlocking but unambiguous structure that anger can function as a feeling of justice. Only envy and its special form, jealousy, have a similarly clear and at the same time complex structure. But these emotions have a close connection to the subject of the emotion herself: here it is a matter of the thing, quality or relationship that she claims for herself. Anger, on the other hand, is aimed at an injustice that need not necessarily have been suffered by the angry person herself. Any notion of “injustice,” and hence of “justice,” relativizes the limited perspective on one’s own immediate well-being and includes the views of others. What is aggressive about anger seems justified because (and when) it is not merely a matter of selfish interests, as in the case of envy and jealousy, but, moreover, the retribution to which the emotion motivates must be commensurate with the seriousness of the violation of the norm. Since anger and indignation are the only socially accepted emotions of aggression, it makes sense to reinterpret other aggressive emotions as instances of anger and indignation in order to increase their acceptance. Thus, it may happen that someone envies somebody else’s possessions, but does not accept her own envious feelings. Instead, she may deem the other’s possessions to be “unjust” and describe her emotions accordingly as “indignation” over the unequal distribution of goods. Such reinterpretations will rarely be instances of intentional deception, but more often of self-misunderstanding or self-deception. In such cases, one is not mistaken about the fact that one is affected in a corporeal-affective way, but instead about the emotion by which one is affected: one thinks that one is angry about an injustice, but “in reality” is envious. The motive for this self-misunderstanding is the normative precept that envy is not a socially acceptable emotion, while anger or indignation is. But the fact that envy is often reinterpreted as indignation also means that indignation can easily be misunderstood by others as envy or is deliberately reinterpreted as envy in order to discredit the concerns expressed in indignation. This is how the concept of “social envy” became established and used as a polarizing label. The close connection between envy and indignation can also be observed in the case of Ressentiment, which Nietzsche describes as self-poisoning through inhibited revenge.16 Here the transformation in the genesis of Ressentiment assumes a different form. Envy, 451
Hilge Landweer
shame and feelings of inferiority are the initial emotions that are suppressed, denied and then transformed into irritation, aversion and hatred. But these emotions are also inhibited in their expression. Here, it is above all the shares of envy in Ressentiment that are not acknowledged in the relation to self, because they are not approved, but also one’s own social inferiority, which as a result has to be reinterpreted. As with Ressentiment in its typical mixture, the dynamics of superiority and inferiority also play an important role in many particular emotions of aggression. This applies especially to the above-mentioned oscillation between hatred and contempt. Whereas contempt has a clear anchoring point in the supposed inferiority of those who are despised, this is, as outlined above, much less clear in the case of hatred, while the same group of persons or an individual can be located in the condensation area of both emotions.17 Even if hatred may arise out of a situation of real or supposed inferiority, how the relationship of power to those who are hated is viewed may undergo a shift, for example as a result of ideologies about their inferiority, such as misogyny. Moreover, subjectively speaking, contempt is certainly the more pleasant emotion, since it dispenses with the fixation of hatred on its condensation area and in addition involves the feeling of superiority. That is why talk about the inferiority of those who are despised is so cheap. Fantasies and projections have massive effects; even the suggestion of supposed superiority improves one’s own power position. But contempt—and here this is the most important motive for the reinterpretations of hatred into contempt—is also the more socially recognized emotion: unlike hatred, it hardly seems to lead to physical violence, since its motivating impulse is to avoid contact with the despised person. But, as we have seen in Section 4, this is to underestimate the aggressive potential of contempt, which, in virtue of its anchoring point in supposed inferiority, can lead to the presumption of superiority, and at worst to social exclusion and dehumanization. This is why the tendency to trivialize contempt18 seems highly problematic, especially since it is combined with a cultural tendency in neoliberal social media to cultivate feelings of one’s own moral or other superiority, contempt and gloating. Malicious glee at the dismantling of public personalities and of private persons through bullying has become a depressingly frequent occurrence (see also Chapter 27 in this volume). In this way, hatred and arrogance appear disguised as contempt. The transformations that the emotions of aggression undergo show that the aversive strivings also try to circumvent normative proscriptions. While the reinterpretations of envy into anger or indignation are comparatively harmless, because references to justice always have to be justified in a public discourse, the misrecognition of hatred and of the destructive effects of contempt are much more serious. The foregoing analysis points to the conclusion that it makes more sense to recognize emotions of aggression in all their diversity than to suppress them. Only then it is possible to control their aggressive tendencies effectively. But this presupposes that we understand their aggressive impact. Thus, we are in urgent need of a public discourse on the corrosive role of contempt in neoliberal cultures.
Notes
452
Aggressive emotions
References Aeschbach, Sebastian (2017). Ressentiment: An Anatomy. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Geneva. https:// www.academia.edu/35721906/Ressentiment_--_An_Anatomy. Ahmed, Sara (2014). The Cultural Politics of Emotions. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Aristotle (2007). On Rhetoric: A Theory of Civic Discourse. Transl. and ed. by George A. Kennedy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bell, Macalester (2013). Hard Feelings. The Moral Psychology of Contempt. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bollnow, Otto Friedrich (1968). Einfache Sittlichkeit (4th ed.). Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht. Demmerling, Christoph, and Landweer, Hilge (2007). Philosophie der Gefühle. Von Achtung bis Zorn. Stuttgart: Metzler. Fuchs, Thomas, and De Jaegher, Hanne (2009). Enactive Intersubjectivity: Participatory SenseMaking and Mutual Incorporation. Phenomenology and Cognitive Science 8(4), 465–486. Helm, Bennet W. (2001). Emotional Reason: Deliberation, Motivation, and the Nature of Value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
453
Hilge Landweer Kolnai, Aurel (2004[1935]). On Disgust. Transl. by E. Kolnai et al. Peru: Open Court. Landweer, Hilge (1999). Scham und Macht. Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Sozialität eines Gefühls. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. ——— (2016). Ist Sich-gedemütigt-Fühlen ein Rechtsgefühl? In: H. Landweer, and D. Koppelberg (Eds.). Recht und Emotion I. Verkannte Zusammenhänge, Freiburg: Alber, 103–135. ——— (2019). The Spatial Character of Atmospheres: Being affected and Corporeal Interaction in the Context of Collective Feeling, Studi di estetica, XLVII, IV serie, 2/2019 Sensibilia, 153–168. Mason, Michelle (2003). Contempt as a Moral Attitude. Ethics 113, 234–272. Nietzsche, Friedrich (1996[1878]). Human, All Too Human. Transl. by R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University. ——— (2007[1887]). On the Genealogy of Morals. Transl. by C. Diethe, and ed. by K. Ansell-Pearson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rinofner-Kreidl, Sonja (2014). Neid und Ressentiment: Zur Phänomenologie negativer sozialer Gefühle. In: J. Müller, and K. Mertens (Eds.). Die Dimension des Sozialen: Neue philosophische Zugänge zu Fühlen, Wollen und Handeln. Berlin: De Gruyter, 103–126. Salice, Alessandro, and Montes Sánchez, Alba (2019). Envy and Us. European Journal of Philosophy 27(1), 227–242. Scheler, Max (1994[1915]). Ressentiment. Transl. by L. B. Coser. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. Schmitz, Hermann (1982[1965]). Der Leib [= System der Philosophie Vol. II, 1]: Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1983[1973]). Der Rechtsraum. Praktische Philosophie [= System der Philosophie, Vol. III, 3]. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (1990). Der unerschöpfliche Gegenstand. Bonn: Bouvier. ——— (2011a). Der Leib. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter. ——— (2011b). Emotions Outside the Box—The New Phenomenology of Feeling and Corporeality. Transl. by R. O. Müllan, and J. Slaby. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10(2), 241–259. ——— (2019). New Phenomenology. A Brief Introduction. With an introd. by T. Griffero. Transl. by R. O. Müllan with support from M. Bastert. Milan: Mimesis International. Solomon, Robert (1978). Emotions and Anthropology: The Logic of Emotional World Views. Inquiry 21, 181–199. Szanto, Thomas (forthcoming). In Hate We Trust: The Collectivization and Habitualization of Hatred. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-018-9604-9. ——— (unpubl. ms.). The Politics of Ressentiment: From Value-Illusion to False Solidarity. Presentation at ZiF, University of Bielefeld, 2019. Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (2017). Contempt: The Experience and Intersubjective Dynamics of a Nasty Emotion. In: J. Drummond, and S. Rinofner-Kreidl (Eds.). Emotional Experiences. Ethical and Social Significance. London, New York: Rowman & Littlefield. ——— (2018). Phenomenological Approaches to Hatred: Scheler, Pfänder, and Kolnai. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 16, 158–179. Wüschner, Philipp (2017). Scham—Schuld—Strafe. Zur Frage nach der Legitimität von Schamstrafen. In: H. Landweer and F. Bernhardt (Eds.). Recht und Emotion II. Sphären der Verletzlichkeit. Freiburg, München: Alber. Further reading Brudholm, Thomas (2010). Hatred as an Attitude. Philosophical Papers 39(3), 289–313. Brudholm, Thomas, and Johansen Schepelern, Brigitte (2018). Pondering Hatred. In: T. Brudholm, and J. Lang (Eds.). Emotions and Mass Atrocity: Philosophical and Theoretical Explorations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 81–103. Caze, Marguerite L. (2001). Envy and Resentment. Philosophical Explorations 4(1), 31–45. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions. A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Meyer-Drawe, Käte (2007). Ablehnung des Leibes. Ekel und Haß. In: R. Konersmann (Ed.). Das Leben denken—die Kultur denken. Freiburg: Alber, 110–127. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1976[1944]). Anti-Semite and Jew. An Exploration of the Etiology of Hatred. Transl. by G. J. Becker. New York: Schocken.
454
39 HETERO-INDUCED SHAME AND SURVIVOR SHAME Alba Montes Sánchez
Most authors writing on shame nowadays agree in characterizing it as an emotion of selfassessment, an emotion that intentionally targets and evaluates the one who feels it (see Chapter 30 in this volume; cf. also Chapter 27 in this volume). Now, if this is true, some instances of shame seem puzzling, because the circumstances in which they typically arise don’t appear to offer the right kind of basis for a self-evaluation: hetero-induced shame1 (or shame felt about somebody else’s actions or features) and survivor shame (or shame felt about having been the victim of an abuse). Here are some examples. Consider, first, heteroinduced shame: You take a friend to a classical music concert where your son, a professional piano-player, is the main soloist. When he comes on stage, he is visibly drunk and offers a disgraceful performance. You feel ashamed. As for survivor shame, consider the testimony of two genocide survivors. This is Primo Levi on the Nazi genocide: “That many (including me) experienced ‘shame’, that is, a feeling of guilt during the imprisonment and afterward, is an ascertained fact confirmed by numerous testimonies. It may seem absurd, but it is a fact” (Levi 1989, 60). And this is Francine Niyitegeka, a survivor of the Rwandan genocide: I do not think this will ever be over for me, to be so despised for having Tutsi blood. (…) I feel a sort of shame to have to spend a lifetime feeling hunted, simply for being what I am. The very moment my eyelids close shut on all of this, I weep inside, out of grief and humiliation. (Hatzfeld 2008, 28) These phenomena are different in most respects, but they share one common feature: the ashamed individual hasn’t done anything to bring about a state of degradation onto themselves or others. Therefore, the self-evaluation might seem inappropriate. In the first case, it seems inappropriate to self-evaluate on the basis of someone else’s degradation. In the second case, it seems inappropriate to do so when one is not responsible at all, but just a victim, of the situation. In an influential paper, D’Arms and Jacobson (2000) distinguished between the moral appropriateness of an emotion, i.e., whether it is morally good to feel it, and its fittingness, whether it correctly represents and evaluates its intentional object. For example, my envy 455
Alba Montes Sánchez
may be fitting, in that it correctly represent my colleague as having gained the promotion I coveted and didn’t get, while still deserving moral condemnation. Hetero-induced shame and survivor shame raise different worries concerning appropriateness. In the case of hetero-induced shame, the suspicion is that, according to the standard view, it may never be fitting. As such, it seems either to be irrational, or to put pressure on the received view on shame. In the case of survivor shame, the puzzle primarily concerns moral appropriateness, and it puts pressure on the relatively widely held view of shame as a positive force in our moral lives, an emotion that motivates us to learn from previous inappropriate behavior and change for the better (e.g., Williams 2008; Deonna et al. 2011; Aristotle 2014). In what follows, I provide analyses of both phenomena that dispel such worries.
1. Hetero-induced shame2 If we assume that the intentional object of shame is the one feeling it, how can we explain those instances where we feel ashamed of someone else? Few philosophers have addressed this question, with Scheler among the notable exceptions. But before I tackle it, let me make it explicit that I seek to investigate an emotional experience, not to clarify language use. I do not seek an account of what competent English speakers mean when they say they are ashamed of someone else, or when speakers of other languages use expressions that refer to similar phenomena, such as Fremdscham in German or vergüenza ajena in Spanish (in fact, these expressions are used in quite different ways). What I am after is a phenomenological description: i.e., investigating the structure of an experience of “being ashamed of someone else”. It is therefore important to bear in mind that language use and phenomenological structure can and do come apart. Indeed, when German speakers say they feel Fremdscham, and when English speakers say “I am ashamed of you/him”, often they are not reporting actual experiences of shame. Instead, these expressions might be reports of indignation at shamelessness that seek to reaffirm relevant communal norms. They mean something along the lines of: “this behavior is shameless, you/he should be ashamed of your/himself, and I am shocked that you aren’t/he isn’t”. For example, imagine you are returning home from a conference abroad, and in the airport you bump into a colleague from a different country. While waiting to go through security, you witness a scene where some fellow nationals of yours try to jump the line and behave rudely to everyone. You comment to your colleague that this is terrible and you are ashamed of them. On one interpretation of this example, it is easy to see your comment not as reporting your actual feeling of shame, but simply as reporting disapproval and trying to reassure your colleague that you are not like those shameless fellows. There might be a different explanation: you might be feeling something similar to, but different from, shame, namely embarrassment. Both emotions are closely related, but they differ in important ways that in principle may make it easier to feel embarrassment when one is only a witness of a ridiculous or inappropriate situation. Embarrassment is always about public appearances, about looking foolish in front of others, while shame is characterized by a deeper feeling of degradation or inferiority. Embarrassment is shallower and much more fleeting, it disappears as soon as you remove yourself from the situation, and it always requires an audience. It typically arises when one makes a social faux-pas, for example, misremembering yet again the name of your next-door neighbor (for a full characterization, see Nussbaum 2006; Zahavi 2014; Chapter 31 this volume). But situations and our position in them are not exclusively the product of our own actions. Others can easily cause social awkwardness, in ways that leave you feeling ridiculous, out of place, or thrown into an 456
Hetero-induced shame and survivor shame
uncomfortable witness position. The above example of the airport could be one of them. So often when we feel “ashamed of others” what we actually are is embarrassed. This is a possibility, but not all cases of feeling ashamed of others can be explained away in this manner. I believe that my initial example of you feeling ashamed of your son cannot. Moreover, embarrassment and shame are so closely related that they can easily transform into each other, depending on how the subject experiences the situation. In any case, the crucial point is not whether from a third-person perspective the situation is better described as one of social awkwardness or as one of degradation. Rather, the crucial point is whether the subject undergoing the emotion frames the situation as one or the other. Issues of public presentation can have deeper implications, they can sometimes be experienced as degrading, and so transform into shame. You might experience that your tendency to forget your neighbor’s name is a sign of you being selfish, and this might cause you shame. Similarly, someone may come to feel shame in my airport example above (more on this below). Finally, someone might argue that, when I feel ashamed of someone else, what I do is putting myself in their shoes and coming to feel the emotions that are appropriate to their situation, like we do when we read an engaging novel.3 Once again, this is a possibility, but it cannot account for most cases of hetero-induced shame. Take the example of you feeling ashamed of your son at the concert. Are you feeling ashamed of him because you put yourself in his shoes and imagine the situation from his perspective? Do you feel as if you were the pianist? This doesn’t seem very plausible. As the parent, you are more likely to be keeping a clear awareness of your own position as an observer, of the strong bond that links you to the shameful subject, and of the presence of your friend looking at you both. There are clear differences between the intentionality of hetero-induced shame and that of imaginative perspective taking. These considerations show that, even if expressions such as Fremdscham or “I am ashamed of you” are sometimes employed to refer to something other than an experience of shame, there are genuine cases of shame where the characteristic evaluation of degradedness seems better ascribed to someone other than the emoter. In previous work with Alessandro Salice, we have labeled such cases ‘hetero-induced shame’ (Salice and Montes Sánchez 2016; Montes Sánchez and Salice 2017). But if these cases are genuine and relatively frequent, the question is whether the standard account of shame is adequate. Perhaps we should abandon the claim that shame intentionally targets the one that feels it. Indeed, a minority of authors thinks it doesn’t necessarily. Scheler is perhaps the most prominent example (Scheler 1987). More recently, Helm (2010, chap. 5, 2017, chap. 7) has offered a more detailed version of a similar idea. Let me briefly discuss their views in turn. For Scheler, shame is an emotion that protects our humanity and individuality, our higher spiritual values, from threats of degradation and contamination. He writes: “shame is a protective feeling of the individual and his or her value against the whole sphere of what is public and general” (Scheler 1987, 17). But in his view, since the sphere of human spiritual values and individuality is not exclusive to myself, it can be put at risk in myself or in another. This is what, in Scheler’s view, explains why he feels ashamed when another man makes an indecent comment in front of a lady. Scheler is quick to rule out emotional contagion: he feels ashamed even though nobody else present, neither the other man nor the lady, feels ashamed. His shame can therefore not be the product of his having been “infected” by someone else’s emotions, as when we join a merry party and become merry ourselves. Scheler’s example has complications I cannot address here, but the crucial point is that, in his view, it shows that the intentional object of shame is “the individual self as such (das individuelle Selbst überhaupt)” (Scheler 1987, 18, transl. modified, for the original, see 1957, 81). Anybody can 457
Alba Montes Sánchez
be in a position where their higher spiritual values are threatened with contamination, and anyone who witnesses this can respond with shame, with this protective reaction. Unfortunately, Scheler never completed his essay on shame. But as things stand, an obvious problem with his account is that most of us do not routinely feel ashamed whenever we see others in shameful situations: often we are amused or outraged instead. So the idea that shame is “about the individual self as such” seems much too wide to specify the characteristic intentional object of shame. What distinguishes those others whose behavior or features can make me feel shame from those who cannot? Some have gestured at an answer by saying this happens because one associates or identifies with others, or loves them, without explicating how such connections work to produce shame (Walsh 1970; Cavell 1995, 286; a more detailed account can be devised on the basis of Hume (1978, 277–391, 310–311); see Salice and Montes Sánchez 2016, 3–4). Helm, however, does offer a detailed account of how one can come to feel ashamed of others. Helm distinguishes between two types of shame: personal shame, which is a “personfocused emotion” (Helm 2010, chaps. 4 and 5, 2017, 49–51), and social shame, which is a “character-oriented reactive attitude” (Helm 2017, chap. 7). The difference between them is based on his distinction between ‘target’ and ‘focus’ of an emotion (Helm 2010, 58). The target of the emotion is its thematic object: if you are angry at your son for playing carelessly with a ball next to your porcelain vase, then your son is the target of your anger. The focus of the emotion is a background object that you care about, which is related to the target in such a way as to make intelligible your emotional evaluation of the target: in this example, the precious vase you treasure. Your anger at your son is intelligible because you care about the vase, which is threatened by his behavior. Applying this distinction, Helm proposes that two types of shame can be distinguished in virtue of their foci. Personal shame is focused on a person, on her identity and the kind of life she finds worth her living. Social shame is focused on a specific community that the subject belongs to, and on its norms of character, on the kind of life the community finds worthy of their members. For Helm, person-focused shame can target someone other than the emoting subject: a loved one. Paradigmatic cases of shame about oneself are focused on oneself as a person, they are made intelligible, in Helm’s view, by one’s own self-love. To love oneself is “to have a concern for oneself as this particular person with a sense of the kind of life worth one’s living” (Helm 2010, chap. 4, 2017, 49). This is the background concern that enables us to understand why I evaluate myself as degraded (why I feel ashamed) when I betray the values that make up the life worth my living. That would be the case was I the pianist that gets drunk in an attempt to fight stage fright and ends up giving a horrible performance. This is what Helm (2010, 153) calls “directly reflexive” shame.4 Personal shame can also be “indirectly reflexive”, when we feel ashamed of something that we take to be representative of qualities we value (e.g., if I take my battered old apartment to represent my low social status and I am therefore ashamed of it). Being ashamed of other people would be a subclass of indirectly reflexive shame, for example, if you were ashamed of your national soccer team’s poor performance in the World Cup. In Helm’s view, in such cases you see others as representing something else you value as a part of your identity (i.e., here, national citizenship), such that their performance reflects on who you are (Helm 2010, 153–154). However, seeing someone as representative of something you value cannot always ground shame. The shameful others have to be associated with you in a meaningful way: they have to represent a group the membership in which you value (Helm 2010, 154). I think this is a crucial point, but here Helm doesn’t develop it further. As I argue below, a link is still missing: the question is not whether the other does actually represent my values or is a 458
Hetero-induced shame and survivor shame
member of my group, but whether, in the relevant situation, I frame her as a group member with a capacity to impact my identity. Now, Helm further argues for a third class of person-focused shame—“loving” shame— that is not reflexive, because it is focused on the beloved, not on oneself (Helm 2010, 154). In his view, loving someone implies an “intimate identification” with them, where I care about them as persons, I care about the life they find worth living, and about their projects for their sake. This concern makes it intelligible for me to feel a range of person-focused emotions with a focus on my beloved, including shame. So in my example of the pianist, his parents can intelligibly feel ashamed of him because they love him, they intimately identify with him, they care about him as this particular person and about his projects for his sake. Part of Helm’s motivation to defend this view is to resist the union account of love, according to which lovers form a unity, a “we” that blurs the boundaries between self and other. While I partially agree with him in resisting this blurring, there are ways of conceiving of a “we” that don’t erase the boundary, but rather presuppose it (see, e.g., Zahavi 2015). The above taxonomy, however, seems to suggest that fusion is the only option: either the other is taken as a representative of my personal values, and therefore an extension of myself, in indirectly reflexive shame, or the other is fully recognized as an independent person whose identity doesn’t affect mine, in loving shame. I find this dichotomy, especially the lack of inter mediate cases or gradual variations, unsatisfactory. Collective intentionality is obviously more complex than this and Helm has since devoted an entire book to it (Helm 2017, see also his contribution to this volume). Here Helm introduces a second type of shame, social shame. But his analysis of it doesn’t seem to allow for being socially ashamed of others in the sense of hetero-induced shame. Social shame, for him, is shame one feels as a member of a particular community of respect before one’s fellow members, when one betrays norms of character that prescribe the kinds of life worth living for community members. The foci of social shame are the community and its norms of character. These foci don’t seem to allow for one to feel socially ashamed of someone else: our common concern for the community means that if I do something shameful before our eyes, you as a fellow member should be contemptuous (not ashamed) of me (2017, 197–198, see also 201–202, 210). If I read Helm correctly, we are left with the following picture: we have a communal identity that is not susceptible to hetero-induced shame, a personal identity that is susceptible to it through group representatives, and a kind of shame (loving shame) that leaves the emoter’s identity untouched. I am not sure to what extent personal and group identities can be disentangled in particular cases, but I will leave this point aside. What I want to take issue with is the idea that shame might be non-reflexive. I am skeptical of this proposal, since I agree with Sartre (2003), according to whom shame is the experience that I am Being-for-Others, that I am an object of the other’s perception, that I have an outside that others can observe and that escapes my control, even though it is a part of me (see Chapter 30 in this volume for details). This phenomenological structure of felt exposure is preserved in cases of feeling ashamed of others. Take my example of the pianist. You are much less likely to feel ashamed of your son if you hear his drunken playing in his rehearsal studio with no other witnesses present: you might rather feel disappointed or angry. You are more likely to feel ashamed in public, i.e., in a situation where your identity and his are associated and degraded together, where his performance might put you both on the spot. Therefore, in my view, the best way of accounting for episodes of “being ashamed of others” (both loving and indirectly reflexive in Helm’s terminology) is to retain the idea that 459
Alba Montes Sánchez
they are about oneself, but they are special cases. They do not target oneself as an individual, but oneself as a member of a group to which the shameful other also belongs, they are instances, so to speak, of being exposed by proxy, of having one’s own identity “tainted” by association (see Salice and Montes Sánchez 2016; Montes Sánchez and Salice 2017). The crucial aspect is indeed identification, but not in Helm’s sense of love, of caring about the other’s projects for their sake, nor of mere representativeness of personal values, but in the sense of social or group identification, such that some aspects of my own identity are (or can become) entangled with others, in a way that I can become exposed through them. As hyper-social creatures, many aspects of our identities are tied to our belonging to certain groups: families, friends, religious groups, professions and so on. This is what social psychologists call our social identities (e.g., Brewer 1991)—although they shouldn’t be regarded as clearly distinct from personal identity. Nevertheless, merely acknowledging that I belong to a category, say, that I have a certain nationality, does not necessarily have an impact on my social identity. For this to happen, I have to group-identify, which means living the group “from within”, experiencing myself as part of a “we”, such that my behavior and emotions are significantly impacted (Turner 1987, 50). When group identification is in place, I can easily feel ashamed of myself because of the actions or features of another member of my group, since they impact my social identity. Family members can thus feel ashamed of each other because they group-identify as members of the same family; sport fans can feel ashamed of the team’s performance because they identify as members of the same group, and so on. Social psychologists call this group-based shame (Lickel et al. 2011). Salice and I call this hetero-induced shame because we don’t think robust group membership is either strictly necessary or actually sufficient for so-called group-based shame. Again, one can formally and robustly be a member of some group without identifying with it in some situations—or ever. Perhaps, I regard my nationality as irrelevant to my identity, and thus I’m not disposed to group identifying with my fellow nationals, so in a case like the airport example above, I might feel annoyed by the noise or disapprove of the rowdy travelers’ behavior, but remain unashamed. On the other hand, perhaps I typically don’t care about nationality as a part of my identity, but the presence of my colleague (who might associate me with the troublemakers in virtue of it) assigns salience to this feature of myself and prompts me to (atypically for me) group-identify with the other travelers and feel ashamed in this occasion. Moreover, in certain situations, one can group-identify with people who are not co-members of a robust group, on the basis of very superficial features, as shown by in “minimal group” paradigm experiments (Tajfel 1970; Tajfel et al. 1971). Situational factors are crucial, they can confer salience to certain properties one shares with others, and prompt group identification even where one would not expect it. Where does this leave us on the matter of appropriateness I mentioned at the start? If one agrees that personal identity constructions are not an entirely private matter, that they have social aspects and others can impact them and constantly contribute to shape them, I can see no principled reason why it may always necessarily be unfitting to feel “exposed by proxy”. Sometimes it will be fitting, and some other times it won’t. As for moral appropriateness, the issue will partially depend on how one understands collective responsibility. These questions remain largely unexplored (but see Salmela and Sullivan 2016), and they require a careful consideration of particular examples that I cannot engage in here. However, having clarified the general mechanism underlying hetero-induced shame allows us to see that it is not necessarily inappropriate. In this sense, it does not differ from standard shame, and so the initial puzzlement is dissolved. 460
Hetero-induced shame and survivor shame
2. Survivor shame5 Survivor shame, as claimed above, is the shame that survivors of atrocities and abuse often feel about what happened to them. It is so frequent among trauma victims that it is included in psychiatry manuals as a diagnostic criterion for post-traumatic stress disorder (see American Psychiatric Association 2013). The puzzle with this type of shame precisely concerns its moral appropriateness and significance. The question here is why a victim should feel ashamed about what happened to her. It seems that, if the perpetrator is the one at fault, it is the perpetrator who should feel ashamed—and often they don’t. What we find in these cases looks like a paradox: the victims feel deeply ashamed; the perpetrators are shameless (Shapiro 2003). Explanations of this paradox often take an evolutionary route (see Budden 2009; for a philosopher who adopts this strategy, see Maibom 2010). According to Fessler (2007), there are two kinds of shame—subordinance shame and social acceptability shame. The latter is characteristically human, and it focuses on one’s peers’ good opinions, on keeping a good reputation and having smooth social relations within a group of equals. This kind of shame can be linked to moral norms. But the former, subordinance shame, is simpler, evolutionarily more primary, it can be found in non-human animals, and it is about strict hierarchies of dominance and subordination. Subordinance shame is a mechanism to prevent aggression from a hierarchical superior through a display of inferiority. Survivor shame looks paradoxical from the point of view of social acceptability shame, but it is perfectly intelligible from the point of view of subordinance shame. Indeed, if you are being attacked and subjugated by someone with power over you, according to this description, it is to be expected that you display subordinance shame (and incidentally, it would be nonsensical for the powerful one to feel it). This approach is helpful in dissolving the paradox and making shame intelligible in such cases, as well as in emphasizing how some aspects of our identities (and their degradation) can indeed be outside of our control. The problem is that survivor shame, as its name indicates, is a survivor phenomenon, i.e., an emotion that is felt by someone who has been, but is no longer being, attacked and subjugated. While the abuse is taking place, an appeasement response seems appropriate, but afterwards it seems pointless. And thus survivor shame seems to be a clearly pathological and irrational phenomenon. Furthermore, since it is disconnected from social acceptability shame, it seems to have no moral significance. This, however, doesn’t neatly match the complex descriptions of the phenomenon that one finds in survivors’ testimonies. Most survivors do feel that their shame is paradoxical and irrational, but they often also attribute it some moral significance (Levi 1989, 1996). Indeed, the first term that psychiatrist chose to refer to this phenomenon was survivor guilt. This was in part due to psychoanalytic influences, but it also reflects the fact that survivors often give some moral significance to these feelings (Leys 2009, chap. 2). The standard way of defining guilt, in counter-distinction to shame, is that, while in guilt I feel bad about an action or omission (and so guilt always entails responsibility and a moral evaluation), in shame I feel bad about my identity, about the kind of person I am (see Tangney and Dearing, 2004; Williams, 2008). Given this account, as Corbí (2012) argues, interpreting survivor shame as exclusively pathological and irrational amounts to dismissing the survivors’ experiences and their moral meaning as irrelevant, which inadvertently serves the purposes of the perpetrator by ignoring the victims’ experiences and silencing their voices. Another problem with an account of survivor shame exclusively in terms of subordinance shame is that it flattens the complexity of the phenomenon and collapses its 461
Alba Montes Sánchez
diachronic extendedness. Such an account approaches survivor shame as if it was, on the one hand, equivalent to the shame that a victim might feel while being humiliated,6 and on the other, as if it was an isolated and uniform emotional episode, a more or less short-lived mental state, like being afraid of a snake when I see one. Paradoxically, when Agamben (1999) attempted to do justice to the moral meaning of survivor shame, he ran into these problems too (see Welz 2011; Guenther 2012). Agamben (1999) builds his account of survivor shame drawing on the early Levinas, and focusing mainly on a passage where Antelme (1992, 231) describes the blush of a prisoner being singled out for execution. In On Escape, an essay originally published in French in 1935, Levinas (2003, 63–64) argued that shame is not about the exposure of a particular flaw one could fix, but about discovering that insufficiency and vulnerability are constitutive of our very being. Drawing on Levinas, Agamben described shame, as exemplified by the blush of the prisoner being singled out for execution, as a simultaneous movement of subjectification and desubjectification, as a moment when the subject bears witness to her own desubjectification. Shame would thus reveal the resistance of humanity in the face of dehumanizing attacks, and that would constitute its ethical significance (Agamben 1999, 104, 128). This account is not only problematic, as I already suggested, because it collapses the temporality of survivor shame and victim humiliation, but also because it is solipsistic and ignores the relational element of shame. After surviving the Holocaust himself, Levinas (1969) developed a new account of ethical shame that is not about me discovering my own vulnerability, but about being called into question by another, about having to respond to the call implied in the suffering of others (see Morgan 2008; Guenther 2011, 28–33). As Guenther (2012, 64) puts it, the importance of shame in this context is its emphasis on relations rather than acts: I feel shame not because of what I have done, but rather because others matter to me, and because I care what they think of me. The capacity for shame attests to a remnant, however small, of interhuman relationality—an interest, however diminished or degraded, in others. To appreciate more clearly the force of these objections, consider Levi’s testimony. In the last volume of his Auschwitz trilogy, he lists some typical sources of survivor shame and guilt (he does not clearly distinguish between them and often refers to both synonymously): (i) the state of real degradation in which the prisoners were forced to live; (ii) their passivity in the face of their oppressors, i.e., the prisoner’s failure to fight or rebel; (iii) their failures of solidarity to other prisoners; (iv) the suspicion that they might have survived in the place of another, a better or worthier person; and (v) what he calls “the shame of the world”: the shame of knowing that humanity is capable of horrors such as the Holocaust (Levi 1989, 75–85). A mere glance at Levi’s list allows us to see that, except for (i), all sources of shame imply an explicit reference to a relation to others. Furthermore, he is referring to a host of related, but different, phenomena, most prominently: memories of past shame, humiliation (i) and guilt (iii), as well as present-day shame and guilt when looking back (ii, iii, iv, v).7 Note also that this list includes emotional episodes, but also judgments, and emotions that seem to require a degree of analysis of the past events (iv, v). This is one of the reasons why in previous work, Zahavi and I (Montes Sánchez and Zahavi 2018) have suggested that we should understand survivor shame as a process, rather than a state, in line with Goldie’s narrative model of emotion. 462
Hetero-induced shame and survivor shame
Goldie (2012, 56) argues that an emotion is a kind of process; more specifically, it is a complex pattern of activity and passivity, inner and outer, that unfolds over time, and the unfolding pattern over time is explanatorily prior to what is the case at any particular time. This pattern is composed of many different elements, including judgments, dispositions, emotional episodes, expressive actions, habitual actions, etc., which take a characteristic shape that distinguishes them from other emotions (2012, 62). Understanding survivor shame as an emotional process structured in this way can help us do justice to the complexity of this phenomenon. The main idea is that survivor shame is not a unified experience, a single mental state, it involves emotional episodes of, at least, shame of both kinds discussed by Fessler, humiliation and guilt. It contains irrational and rational elements, some unjustified and some justified. This variety of elements means that questions of fittingness and moral appropriateness cannot be settled in general terms. Furthermore, from second- and thirdperson perspectives, survivor shame calls for compassion rather than contempt, and it can be so destructive (Baumeister, 1990; Budden, 2009) that considerations of prudential appropriateness (whether the emotion is practically advisable in a given situation) may often overrule all others. The puzzle of survivor shame is thus related to its multivalent complexity, but once this is recognized, it doesn’t invalidate the picture of shame as a potentially positive force in our moral lives.
3. Conclusion In this chapter, I have addressed two varieties of shame that seem puzzling: hetero-induced shame and survivor shame. Far from undermining the claim that shame involves a selfevaluation, both disclose ways in which our personal identities are social: they can become entangled with the identities of others via group identification, or they can be impacted, for better or worse, by what others do to us. Both conclusions ultimately underscore the idea that shame discloses our essential human relationality.
Notes
463
Alba Montes Sánchez 6 This is not to deny that trauma victims typically experience flashbacks, where the traumatic experience is given not as a memory, but as if it was happening in the present. Survivor shame, however, is not typically described as a flashback experience. 7 For more on the differences among these emotions, see Chapters 30 and 32, respectively, in this volume; on embodiment and shame, and in particular chronic shame, see Chapter 27 in this volume.
References Agamben, Giorgio (1999). Remnants of Auschwitz. The Witness and the Archive. Transl. by D. HellerRoazen. New York: Zone Books. American Psychiatric Association (2013). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, 5th Edition. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Publishing. Antelme, Robert (1992). The Human Race. Marlboro, Vermont: Marlboro Press. Aristotle (2014). Nicomachean Ethics. Ed. by C. D. C. Reeve. Cambridge, MA: Hackett. Baumeister, Roy F. (1990). Suicide as Escape from Self. Psychological Review 97(1), 90–113. Brewer, Marilynn B. (1991). The Social Self: On Being the Same and Different at the Same Time. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 17(5), 475–482. Budden, Ashwin (2009). The Role of Shame in Posttraumatic Stress Disorder: A Proposal for a Socio-Emotional Model for DSM-V. Social Science & Medicine 69(7), 1032–1039. Cavell, Stanley (1995). The Avoidance of Love: A Reading of King Lear. In: S. Cavell: Must We Mean What We Say. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 267–353. Corbí, Josep E. (2012). Morality, Self Knowledge, and Human Suffering, An Essay on The Loss of Confidence in the World. New York: Taylor and Francis. D’Arms, Justin, and Jacobson, Daniel (2000). The Moralistic Fallacy: On the “Appropriateness” of Emotions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61(1), 65–90. Deonna, Julien, Rodogno, Raffaele, and Teroni, Fabrice (2011). In Defense of Shame: The Faces of an Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fessler, Daniel M. T. (2007). From Appeasement to Conformity: Evolutionary and Cultural Perspectives on Shame, Competition, and Cooperation. In: J. L. Tracy, R. W. Robins, and J. P. Tangney (Eds.). The Self-Conscious Emotions: Theory and Research, 174–193. New York: Guilford Press. Goldie, Peter (2012). The Mess Inside: Narrative, Emotion, and the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Guenther, Lisa (2011). Shame and the Temporality of Social Life. Continental Philosophy Review 44(1), 23–39. ——— (2012). Resisting Agamben: The Biopolitics of Shame and Humiliation. Philosophy & Social Criticism 38(1), 59–79. Hatzfeld, Jean (2008). Into the Quick of Life: The Rwandan Genocide – The Survivors Speak. London: Serpent’s Tail. Helm, Bennett W. (2010). Love, Friendship, and the Self. Intimacy, Identification, and the Social Nature of Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2017). Communities of Respect: Grounding Responsibility, Authority, and Dignity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hume, David (1978). A Treatise of Human Nature. Ed. by L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Levi, Primo (1989). The Drowned and the Saved. Transl. by Raymond Rosenthal. London: Abacus. ——— (1996). Survival in Auschwitz. Transl. by Stuart Wolf. New York: Simon and Schuster. Levinas, Emmanuel (2003). On Escape. Transl. by B. Bergo. Stanford: Stanford University Press. ——— (1969). Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Transl. by A. Lingis. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. Leys, Ruth (2009). From Guilt to Shame: Auschwitz and After. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Lickel, Brian, Steele, Rachel R., and Schmader, Toni (2011). Group-Based Shame and Guilt: Emerging Directions in Research. Social and Personality Psychology Compass 5(3), 153–163. Maibom, Heidi L. (2010). The Descent of Shame. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80(3), 566–594.
464
Hetero-induced shame and survivor shame Montes Sánchez, Alba, and Salice, Alessandro (2017). Feeling Ashamed of Myself Because of You. In: C. Durt, T. Fuchs, and C. Tewes (Eds.). Embodiment, Enaction, and Culture—Investigating the Constitution of the Shared World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 229–244. Montes Sánchez, Alba, and Zahavi, Dan (2018). Unravelling the Meaning of Survivor Shame. In: T. Brudholm, and J. Lang (Eds.). Emotions and Mass Atrocity: Philosophical and Theoretical Explorations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 162–184. Morgan, Michael (2008). On Shame. London, New York: Routledge. Nussbaum, Martha (2006). Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Salice, Alessandro, and Montes Sánchez, Alba (2016). Pride, Shame, and Group Identification. Frontiers in Psychology 7(557), 1–13. Salmela, Mikko, and Sullivan, Gavin Brent (2016). Commentary: Pride, Shame, and Group Identification. Frontiers in Psychology 7(1946), 1–2. Sartre, Jean-Paul (2003). Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology. Transl. by H. E. Barnes. London, New York: Routledge. Scheler, Max (1957). Über Scham und Schamgefühl. In: Schriften aus dem Nachlass, Bd. 1 : Zur Ethik und Erkenntnislehre, 65–154. Bern: Francke. ——— (1987). Shame and Feelings of Modesty. In: Person and Self-Value: Three Essays, Ed. by M. S. Frings. Dordrecht: Nijhoff, 1–85. Shapiro, David (2003). The Tortured, Not the Torturers, Are Ashamed. Social Research 70(4), 1131–1148. Tajfel, Henri (1970). Experiments in Intergroup Discrimination. Scientific American 223, 96–102. Tajfel, Henri, Billig, M. G., Bundy, R. P., and Flament, C. (1971). Social Categorization and Intergroup Behaviour. European Journal of Social Psychology 1(2), 149–178. Tangney, June P., and Dearing, Ronda L. (2004). Shame and Guilt. New York: Guilford Press. Turner, John C. (1987). A Self-Categorization Theory. In: J. C. Turner (Ed.). Rediscovering the Social Group, a Self-Categorization Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, 42–67. Walsh, W. H. (1970). Pride, Shame and Responsibility. The Philosophical Quarterly 20(78), 1–13. Welz, Claudia (2011). Shame and the Hiding Self. Passions in Context: International Journal for the History and Theory of Emotions 2(1), 67–92. Williams, Bernard (2008). Shame and Necessity (2nd ed.). Berkeley: University of California Press. Zahavi, Dan (2014). Self and Other: Exploring Subjectivity, Empathy, and Shame. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2015). ‘You, Me, and We’: The Sharing of Emotional Experiences. Journal of Consciousness Studies 22(1–2), 84–101.
465
40 JOINT FEELING Héctor Andrés Sánchez Guerrero
1. Introduction There are different senses in which people might be said to share an emotion. In certain cases, talk of participation in a joint feeling may appear warranted. The minimal phenomenological condition satisfied in these cases might be articulated as follows: If I am to regard myself as someone who is sharing in a joint feeling I have to be able to experience the emotion I am feeling as a constituent of our emotional response. That we can have this sort of affective experiences seems uncontroversial. In which cases exactly they may be said to have a foundation in a state of affairs that deserves to be called a collective emotional response, however, is a matter of debate. Moreover, one could take the very idea of a response that is at the same time affective and collective to involve a metaphysical absurdity. For one thing, properly affective states centrally involve feelings, and there is widespread agreement that groups are not the kind of entities that can experience feelings. This contribution offers a phenomenological account of the core features of those emotional feelings that allow a number of individuals to respond to some event in a manner experienced by them as authentically affective and genuinely collective. In so doing, it shows that a phenomenological characterization of the relevant affective experiences delivers that which skeptics about the possibility of properly collective emotions miss: a description of the ontological requirements of a genuinely joint feeling.
2. Episodes of joint feeling We often speak and write in ways that suggest that humans can participate in what we may call episodes of joint feeling. After a crucial game, a football player may exclaim: “We feel enormously happy about the undefeated season”. A family member might assert: “This family has treated you very badly. We feel terribly guilty” (Gilbert 2002, 118). Konzelmann Ziv asks us to consider the following statement made by a journalist reporting on the funeral of Winston Churchill: “Not since the war has there been such a shared emotion” (2009, 85). When we hear someone making a statement along these lines, we normally do not feel urged to interrupt her in order to ask what she means. We seem to pre-theoretically understand what is meant by such an assertion. But, although we have an intuitive grasp of 466
Joint feeling
the meaning of these sorts of statements, there is ample room for dispute concerning what exactly it is that we have thus understood. Here are two options. Statements that refer to episodes of joint feeling may be taken to describe the “affective atmosphere” that reigns at a given moment—something that, so to say, is in the air and may be perceived by the individuals involved in the situation. Alternatively, it may be argued that such statements should be understood as economical ways of saying that most of the implicated individuals have responded in a similar emotional way to the event at issue. The problem with these two interpretations is that they do not entail the crucial idea that the participants are jointly responding to something. But if the similarity of the individuals’ responses is not sufficient, adding some component of mutual awareness concerning this match could complete the picture, one may think. To explore this intuition, imagine a number of passengers who have coincidentally taken the same train. Given that the train has left the last station with a delay of about 20 minutes, each of them has come to feel worried about the possibility of not getting her or his train connection. Assume that they become aware of this similarity and feel, for this reason, in some way closer to one another. Would this suffice? The sense in which we could in this case assert that the involved individuals are sharing an emotion is definitively not weak. But it is uncontroversial that these individuals are not sharing in a joint feeling in the same sense in which the members of a football team who exclaim to feel blissful about their undefeated season may be claimed to be doing so. The point is that there are situations—and the other three sorts of cases examined so far do not exemplify them—in which the affective responses of the participants are such that we could assert that they are feeling together, and not merely alongside each other—in a merely parallel way. These are situations in which our inclination to speak of a joint feeling may correspond to some state of affairs that deserves to be called a collective emotional response. To come closer to a characterization of such states of affairs, let us continue to specify what is special about the way in which we experience these situations. At the beginning of his book The Nature of Sympathy, the German phenomenologist Max Scheler, as it has been repeatedly pointed out in recent contributions to the debate on collective emotions (cf. Konzelmann Ziv 2009; Schmid 2009; Salmela 2012), offers a taxonomy of what we may call varieties of shared affectivity. In this context, Scheler argues that there are cases in which we could talk of a type of immediate feeling-together (unmittelbares Miteinanderfühlen). He distils this phenomenon by discussing a dramatic situation: Two parents stand beside the dead body of a beloved child. They feel in common the ‘same’ sorrow, the ‘same’ anguish. It is not that A feels this sorrow and B feels it also, and moreover that they both know they are feeling it. No, it is a feeling-in-common. A’s sorrow is in no way an ‘external’ matter for B here, as it is, e.g. for their friend C, who joins them, and commiserates ‘with them’ or ‘upon their sorrow’. On the contrary, they feel it together, in the sense that they feel and experience in common, not only the selfsame value-situation, but also the same keenness of emotion in regard to it. The sorrow, as value-content, and the grief, as characterizing the functional relation thereto, are here one and identical. (1913, 12–13) In the described situation, the participants are not simply responding in a similar way to one and the same occurrence. Furthermore, they are doing this in such a way so as to understand 467
Héctor Andrés Sánchez Guerrero
their feelings as feelings that constitute a joint experiential act. This feeling-together, Scheler argues, is not a matter of the involved individuals’ capacity to become aware, in a second move, that they have an experience of the same sort—like in the case of the train passengers who worry in a parallel way. Nor is it a matter of their capacity to have affective experiences whose intentional object is the emotion of another individual, such as in the case of someone who merely sympathetically feels the sorrow of another person. Rather, it is in virtue of their being intentionally directed toward a given event in a very particular mode that the involved individuals come to participate in a joint affective experience. This is why Scheler talks of an immediate feeling-together. Against this background, we could formulate a first characterization of the phenomenon at issue. An episode of joint feeling is a situation in which two or more individuals are emotionally responding to an event in such a way as to non-mistakenly understand their feelings as affective experiences that immediately bring them to take part in some unified emotional response. Taking this possibility for granted, some philosophers have tried to elucidate what it means to non-mistakenly understand one’s feelings as experiences that bring one to participate in a genuinely collective emotional response. In the next section, I shall reconstruct an attempt to do so that originates in primarily ontological concerns. On this basis, I shall propose requirements that any adequate phenomenological account of properly joint feeling must accommodate.
3. Feeling together that our action is morally blameworthy In the context of the current debate on collective intentionality, Margaret Gilbert (2002) has offered the most influential account of a collective affective intentional attitude. Her leading intuition could be stated as follows: if we are to make sense of the idea of a genuinely collective affective intentional attitude, we have to show that there are situations in which we could speak of an emotion had by the group itself. Gilbert sets out to show that such a view is defensible by developing an account of what she calls collective guilt feelings. Extending her previous accounts of collective action and collective belief, Gilbert proposes that a collective guilt feeling could be understood in terms of a joint commitment on which the involved individuals have, at least tacitly, agreed. She writes: “For us collectively to feel guilt over our action A is for us to be jointly committed to feeling guilt as a body over our action A” (2002, 139). Gilbert provides the following answer to the question as to what exactly the parties involved in such a joint commitment are committed to: “They are to act as would be appropriate were they to constitute a single subject of guilt feelings” (ibid.). Being aware that most philosophers do not understand social groups as entities capable of experience, Gilbert argues for the idea that such a collective response amounts to a collective emotional response and claims that there is no particular feeling that necessarily accompanies a response of guilt. She generalizes the claim by asserting that “[p]articular emotions may not require a specific phenomenology” (ibid., 119). Although certain “feeling-sensations”, Gilbert contends, could be argued to typically accompany our experiences of guilt, all that is needed for us to feel guilt is a judgment concerning the morally blameworthy character of the acts we feel guilty about (cf. ibid., 120). Her point is, of course, that this holds true for what she calls a collective guilt feeling. How compelling is such an account? Gilbert’s view has been criticized for different reasons. The most common objection leveled against Gilbert’s position concerns the inadequacy of this proposal as an account of a 468
Joint feeling
collective affective intentional state (cf. Wilkins 2002; Konzelmann Ziv 2007; Schmid 2009; Salmela 2012; Sánchez Guerrero 2016). The problem is that it is hard to see to which extent the invoked joint commitment to “feel guilt as a body” is not merely a joint commitment to judge a certain action to be morally wrong. And the issue is that such a joint commitment does not necessarily give rise to a genuinely affective experience. But there is a second—and more fundamental—problem. It concerns Gilbert’s assumption that the “specific phenomenology” of an emotion is best characterized in terms of the bodily sensations that contingently, as she correctly points out, accompany this response. One of the thoughts that have revolutionized the contemporary debate on emotions turns on the issue that although feelings are at the heart of genuinely emotional responses, to feel an emotion is not identical to feeling certain bodily sensations. To feel fear, for instance, is not necessarily to feel the hairs on the back of one’s neck going up and one’s heart beating faster. Rather, to feel fear means to feel a particular situation to be dangerous (cf. Sartre 1939; Ricœur 1950; Goldie 2000; Helm 2001; see also Chapter 20 in this volume). The point is that the intentional character of our emotional experiences may be said to be a matter of certain feelings that are not sheer sensations, since they are object directed or world construing. Peter Goldie (2000) calls them feelings towards. So, even if we granted that there are no feeling-sensations specific to particular kinds of emotions, we should be careful not to overlook a fundamental issue: being able to respond in a properly emotional way presupposes being able to feelingly understand the relevant situation as meriting a particular sort of response. By the same token, feeling guilt in a joint manner is not a matter of being jointly committed to deeming some acts of our group to be morally blameworthy and, on this basis, experiencing some bodily sensations. Rather, it is a matter of feeling together that something we did deserves some sort of repentance expressing act. If in our attempt to provide an account of collective emotions we are to take seriously this idea that object-directed feelings are central to our emotional relation to the world we have to construe the phenomenon at issue in terms of individuals feeling towards something together. In the next section, I shall formulate a phenomenologically rooted proposal concerning what it means to feel toward in a properly joint manner. Before I do so, however, I would like to stress a distinctive feature that the account reconstructed in this section captures, which is in a way not paralleled by accounts originating from the phenomenological tradition. What I am referring to is the normative dimension essential to every genuinely collective intentional act. This is a dimension that Gilbert, extending her original conception of collective actions and beliefs to the realm of the affective, captures in terms of a joint commitment. To avoid losing sight of this aspect, while trying to offer a phenomenological account of joint feeling, we could formulate at this point a condition of adequacy against which to weigh, then, the resulting view. On the basis of a crucial insight articulated by Bennett Helm (2001, 2017), we could require from every account of joint feeling that it should manage to extend to the collective level the following idea: given what we know about the things that really matter to the subject of emotion, in the relevant situation certain (and only certain) emotional responses may be taken to be warranted. My extreme anger at a car driver who ignored the zebra crossing while my daughter wanted to cross the street may appear warranted, given the extent to which my daughter’s wellbeing matters to me. But if what in this situation warrants my anger is the import my daughter’s wellbeing has to me, some contextual explanation would be required, were I, for instance, to react with disappointment to a letter that confirms that she has been accepted to the school she most wanted to attend. 469
Héctor Andrés Sánchez Guerrero
I believe that the latter thought may be accommodated in a way that respects the intuition that object-directed feelings are at the heart of collective emotional responses, too. As argued in detail elsewhere (Sánchez Guerrero 2016), this could be achieved by construing a collective emotion in terms of a joint act of felt understanding. According to this view, what this joint act of feeling discloses is the import something has to the participants as members of a certain group. And it is this idea that the participants’ emotional feelings disclose the import the relevant situation has to them (as a group) that makes their responses intelligible as constituting a properly collective and authentically emotional response.
4. Jointly feeling that it matters to us Hans Bernhard Schmid has suggested an account that allows us to begin spelling out what it is to jointly actualize our capacity to feel toward. What brings two or more individuals to feel that they are participating in a feeling-in-common, Schmid proposes, is the fact that at the relevant moment, they have come to emotionally express a shared concern (cf. Schmid 2009, 68). This idea could be worked out by appealing again to Helm’s (2001) insight that our emotions disclose and co-constitute what we care about by disclosing and co- constituting a unified (and for the most part coherent) personal evaluative perspective (see also Chapter 20 in this volume). In a paper more straightforwardly related to our discussion, Helm (2008) extends this view by arguing that some of the responses exhibited by certain collectives—he talks of plural robust agents—may also be taken to disclose a unified (and for the most part coherent) evaluative perspective; an evaluative perspective the participants share. The latter proposal allows us to provide a first answer to the question concerning what it means to jointly actualize our capacity to feel toward: it means to emotionally respond to a certain event in such a way as to disclose that we (the participants) share an evaluative view of some aspect of this occurrence. This, however, can only be a provisional answer. For, not only the sense in which we can share an emotion, but also the sense in which we can share an evaluative view of the world or a concern, can be more or less demanding (cf. Salmela 2012). Responding emotionally in a genuinely joint manner is, hence, not simply a matter of responding in a way that makes evident that we (the participants) share a concern. Furthermore, it is a matter of being able to express in an authentically emotional way our capacity to care with one another about something. Participating in an episode of joint feeling is, hence, a matter of expressing in an emotional way that we care about something in a particular mode—a mode for which I have elsewhere used the label caring-with (cf. Sánchez Guerrero 2016). The question that arises here is, of course, what it means to care with one another about something, as opposed to merely caring about something alongside each other. Appealing to a technical notion employed by Martin Heidegger in his analysis of fear (1927, §30), I would suggest that to care about something in a genuinely joint manner means for two or more individuals to care about this thing in such a way as to understand a particular group they take themselves to constitute as the for-the-sake-of-which (das Worum) of their concern, i.e., as that to which the experiential state refers back as the relevant—in this case plural—subject of care.1 In order to spell out this idea of caring about something in such a way as to understand some concrete ‘We’ as the for-the-sake-of-which of our concern-based responses, we could appeal to Heidegger’s explication of what it is to exist as a human being, i.e., in a care- defined way. Heidegger seems to suggest that this means to exist in terms of certain possibilities that one takes oneself to be able to actualize (cf. Blattner 1999). Being a Dasein is thus a matter of 470
Joint feeling
existing in such a way that in doing what one is doing, one is always already “pressing ahead into” the actualization of certain possibilities (in Möglichkeiten dringen), thereby leaving other possibilities unactualized (cf. Heidegger 1927, 184ff.). In this sense, to exist as a human means to be those concrete possibilities toward whose actualization one is pressing ahead in the different situations that constitute one’s existence. On this basis, we could conceive of those situations in which a number of individuals are actualizing their capacity to care with one another—and these are the sorts of situation in which individuals can come to participate in an episode of joint feeling—as situations in which the participants are jointly pressing ahead into the actualization of some concrete possibilities they together have as a group: possibilities they jointly are. This is the fundamental sense in which feeling together may be said to be a matter of jointly feeling that something matters to us, as a group.
5. Feeling in concert and affective synchrony Let us contrast this proposal with an alternative view of collective emotions that might seem to resonate with the phenomenological approach to emotions. Its core idea could be captured as follows: if affective intentionality is a matter of object-directed feelings, genuinely collective affective intentionality could be said to be a result of highly synchronized object-directed feelings. Recent philosophical work inspired by empirical observations may be taken to suggest that this idea of affective synchrony is the key to a proper understanding of collective emotions. Drawing on Randall Collins’ (2004) analysis of the emergence of collective emotions in interaction rituals, Mikko Salmela offers an account of shared emotions that, among other things, aims at accommodating the crucial requirements of joint feeling discussed above. Salmela observes: “[M]ere contingent similarity among people’s emotional responses does not amount to the collectivity of those responses, let alone to a phenomenological fusion of individual feelings. The individual responses must be synchronized in order to produce a shared affective experience” (Salmela 2012, 41). Here, Salmela is distinguishing between feeling in a merely parallel way and participating in a collective emotional response. His claim seems to be that the relevant difference could, at least in part, be captured in terms of the interindividual synchrony of different components of the participants’ responses. He writes: “I believe that a convergence and synchronization of both cognitive and non-cognitive elements of emotion is required for such non-reflexive absorption in shared affect that sometimes takes the form of a phenomenological fusion of feelings” (2012, 42).2 In the context of an informative classification of degrees of collectivity exhibited by different forms of shared emotions, Salmela construes the experience of affective sharedness in terms of the result of the mentioned synchronization processes. In particular, he maintains that different forms of shared emotional experience emerge when, among other things, the mechanisms of attentional deployment, emotional contagion, facial mimicry, and behavioral entrainment synchronize the group members’ emotional responses producing a (…) shared affective experience, either phenomenologically fused or aggregative, with mutual awareness that the other group members are feeling the same. (Ibid., 43; my emphasis) Based on interviews with the members of the Danish String Quartet, Salice et al. (forthcoming) discuss affective states that can arise in the course of joint musical performances. The authors 471
Héctor Andrés Sánchez Guerrero
challenge Schmid’s (2014) claim that a pre-reflective form of plural self-awareness is at the heart of properly collective actions. They do so by showing that musical interaction can also unfold without a sense of we-agency. In a vein similar to Salmela’s proposal, the authors construe the sense of we-agency that, as they contend, develops only in certain moments of joint musical performance as a result mainly of synchronization processes. They put a stronger emphasis than Salmela on the synchronization—or what they call entrainment—of corporeal aspects that, as they argue, lead to a sense of “intercorporeity”. To this effect, they appeal to Elizabeth Behnke’s (2008) notion of interkinesthetic affectivity and briefly discuss in this context the importance that shared emotions have for the emergence of the sense of we-agency. The authors maintain that interkinesthetic affectivity is unique in generating a feeling of we-agency, a ‘hive-mind’ in which one’s own perception–action loops are coupled to other bodies (in an intercorporeity that is also describable in terms of (…) joint body schemas or the experience of extended peripersonal space), and thus loop intersubjectively. (Salice et al. 2019, 206) They suggest that the possibility that a number of individuals, who are making music together, develop a sense of we-agency and that this depends on the sum of “ingredients like trust, the intensity of the collective emotion, etc. [which] come in degree[s]” (ibid.). Their claim, then, is that, the sense of we-agency, understood as something that can come in degrees, “peaks when interkinesthesia is at the forefront of the [participant’s] experience. Once [interkinesthetic affectivity] is in place, the sense of individual agency is transformed— one feels totally absorbed by the group’s activity” (ibid.). Here, too, the crucial point seems to be the achievement of high degrees of synchrony. Also alluding to emotions that emerge in the context of musical experiences, Joel Krueger argues that in certain situations—cases of collective emotion, as he calls them—“a numerically single emotion can be given to more than one subject” (2016, 263). In his discussion, Krueger also makes use of the term “entrainment” which he, referring to Will and Turrow (2011), defines as follows: “‘Entrainment’ refers to instances where two or more independent processes become synchronized with each other, gradually adjusting toward, and eventually locking into, a common phase and/or periodicity” (Krueger 2016, 267). Krueger argues that individuals interacting under certain conditions engage in mutual processes of emotion regulation (“emotional off-loading”). His point is that this gives rise to affective experiences that could not be had outside such a group context. Seeking to deliver a picture of the “mechanisms” by means of which a collective accomplishes these regulative functions, Krueger discusses the capacity of music to modulate our affective experiences: “by manipulating our behavioral responses via entrainment, music manipulates our emotions by taking over what are normally subject-centered, endogenous processes of self-regulation” (ibid., 268). Here, too, the capacity of a piece of music or a collective to modulate the emotions of individuals is understood in terms of certain forms of synchrony. One virtue of these types of accounts is that they also accommodate the phenomenologically crucial idea that feelings play a key role in collective emotions. Furthermore, these arguments may be taken to articulate more straightforwardly the above-formulated thought that feeling together is a matter of jointly feeling that a particular situation deserves a certain sort of response. For, the reconstructed proposals conceive of certain feelings that emerge in the context of interpersonal interactions as affective states able to give rise to a sense of experiential proximity apt to motivate collective acts. 472
Joint feeling
Note, however, that in these accounts the experienced fusion of feelings is construed as something that results from the synchronization of affective states that are, at least initially, experienced by each participant as her or his affective state. Indeed, a shared emotion is construed here as a state of affairs based on a web of interlocked and highly coordinated formally individual feelings: feelings whose intentional structure does not refer back to a group as the subject of the relevant act.3 According to these authors, the key to an account of properly collective emotion lies in the idea that there are some sorts of affective states that can exclusively be instantiated in certain pluripersonal contexts apt to induce high degrees of synchrony. But the problem is that this could hold true for certain merely parallel affective experiences. As far as the participants’ experience is concerned, the appeal to high degrees of synchrony cannot (on its own) explain the crucial difference between feelings the participants experience alongside each other and feelings they experience together. This is not a minor point. Indeed, this ostensible shortcoming of the examined proposals allows us to better understand what is at stake here. The claim that the intentional feelings by means of which a number of individuals participate in an episode of joint feeling have a plural for-the-sake-of-which is not an empirical claim concerning merely the probable existence of some feelings with a peculiar structure. Rather, it is a transcendental philosophical claim concerning the necessity of such a structure. The point is that we simply cannot make sense of the idea of a genuinely collective emotional response, as opposed to the idea a highly coordinated web of individual emotions, without presupposing this structure that certain affective experiences exhibit. One could allege that by alluding to a sort of second-order feeling (the emergent “hivemind” or the “phenomenological fusion of individual feelings”), the scrutinized proposals can accommodate the idea of a participation in one and the same joint feeling. But this move could do its job only if the invoked second-order feelings were to have the structural property that I have discussed above in terms of a ‘plural for-the-sake-of-which’. In fact, one could argue that the possibility of the invoked synchronization to induce, in certain cases, a sense of togetherness is grounded in the following fact: in these cases, the participants always already understand themselves as confronted with an event that has import to them qua members of one and the same group. To probe the latter intuition, imagine that the train passengers of our example above are mutually aware not merely of the coincidence between their worries of possibly not reaching their train connection but also of the perfect synchrony of their respective (formally individual) emotions. The individuals would not be able to understand the highly synchronized emotional expressions as responses that bring them to participate in one and the same joint experiential act were the feelings that are at the heart of their emotional responses not to be (tacitly) understood by them as experiences that express the import something has to them (as a group they have come to constitute, at the latest, as it were, in this situation). Moreover, it would be a mistake to think that the appeal to some observationally based cognitive processes that (in a second step) register the perfect synchrony of certain emotions could offer the basis for a justification of the participants’ belief to the effect that they are feeling in a joint manner. If, being challenged by a skeptic, they had to explain why they are convinced that they are feeling in concert (and not merely alongside each other), the participants could surely appeal to reliable cognitive processes at the core of their mutual awareness of the perfect synchrony at issue. But this reference would manage to convince the skeptical observer just in case she shared with the challenged participants the assumption that this synchrony transforms their emotional experiences in a particular way. And the required 473
Héctor Andrés Sánchez Guerrero
phenomenal transformation must, at the minimum, transform the object-directed feelings of the participants into intentional acts with a convergent plural for-the-sake-of-which. To illustrate the issue, imagine four gifted musicians who are in the last stages of their preparation for an important audition that is going to decide which of them is going to be hired by a renowned orchestra. There is only one vacant position. These four musicians can, for this reason, not be said to constitute a social group. On the contrary, they are competitors. Imagine that the conditions of preparation at this stage of the contest are extreme: they have to simultaneously and in the same room complete the preparation for their last (individual) performances. Being aware that they are going to perform the same piece of music, they begin to synchronize their individual acts just to avoid, as far as possible, disturbing each other. Assume that, being gifted musicians, they immediately achieve an extremely high degree of musical synchrony of which they become aware. Feeling proud of what she or he is able to musically achieve even under extreme conditions, each of the four musicians experiences a particular kind of joy that can certainly be said to have some foundation in this pluripersonal musical act. Being guided by the music, their emotional expressions in this peculiar situation also rapidly achieve a point of perfect synchrony of which they (in a series of further cognitive steps) also become mutually aware. Note that just the way the appeal to the mutual awareness of musical synchrony would doubtfully convince our skeptical observer—who knows the conditions under which this ‘perfect’ pluripersonal resonant structure emerged—that the participants are performing together a piece of music, and not merely alongside each other, the appeal to a mutual awareness of the perfect synchrony of their affective states would hardly convince her that they are feeling together. The problem is that the appeal to the synchrony of affective expressions offers primarily what we may call a mechanical account. But such an account would be phenomenologically relevant just in case it could explain in phenomenological terms the relevant experiential transformation: the transformation that brings the participants to understand their feelings as part of their joint feeling. To be sure, neither Salmela nor Krueger seems to take a primarily mechanical account to be apt to explain the emergence of an experience of affective sharedness. Salmela, for instance, writes: Even if it is widely agreed that the causal processes that contribute to the synchronization of emotional responses in groups are non-conscious and automatic, recent evidence suggests that these processes are nevertheless sensitive to social context. Thus, Bourgois and Hess (2008) found [that] anger and sadness were mimicked only between ingroup members. Other emotions that may be synchronized only within an ingroup might include pride, shame, and guilt. (Salmela 2012, 43) In an account of the situation described by Scheler, Krueger (2016), on the other hand, introduces an additional dimension, which he calls “diachronic narrative intimacy”. He refers in this context to Konzelmann Ziv who in her analysis of Scheler’s example points to “pre-existing relations of marital love and marital life between the sharers of the feeling, as well as the relations of biological maternity, of care giving and of parental love to the object of the shared feeling” (2009, 102). Observe that both the sensitiveness to an ingroup-status and the requirement of a diachronic narrative intimacy may be accommodated by the idea that two or more individuals can come to experience their feelings as constituents of a joint feeling just in case they, at the 474
Joint feeling
relevant moment, always already take themselves to constitute together the group at issue. This is completely independent of—and cannot be explained by—the level of affective or behavioral synchrony achieved. There is, furthermore, an important aspect that the simple image of affective synchrony is not able to accommodate, namely the normative aspect. On the contrary, the experience of an emotion self-referentially structured by a plural for-the-sake-of-which may be taken to entail the experience of a commitment to a series of intentional acts, namely those that are warranted, given the import something has to us. Imagine a football player who shares with one of his teammates the position as leading scorer of the tournament. Were the import his team has to him to be of a greater degree than the value he sees in the award as leading scorer, he ought to feel an impulse to join the rest of the team in a joyful celebration, would the mentioned teammate in the last minute score a goal that at the same time leads the team to become champion of the tournament and keeps him from becoming personally awarded. Were he to exclusively celebrate the goals he himself scores, his teammates could have reasons to think that in the cases in which he does celebrate his joy merely coincides with the joy of the other individuals involved in the situation. What is more, were this player to register in a delayed manner that his teammate has scored, thereby failing to celebrate in a synchronous way with the other players, his retarded celebration could still be felt by him and understood by others as a participation in their collective joy. Failing to adequately synchronize our emotions with the relevant other’s ones we could still participate (together with them) in an episode of joint feeling and feel compelled to respond in certain ways. One of the virtues of the recommended view is that it elucidates what it is that enables us to do so. Coming back to the above-formulated condition of adequacy, the ground for this possibility may be finally articulated here as follows: joint feeling is feeling that in virtue of an experienced normative pressure to act in conformity to the import certain things have to us discloses our joint commitment concerning a certain collective-pressing-ahead-toward—i.e., discloses our capacity to be this group.4
6. Closing remark The main reason why the view suggested in this contribution may be seen as a phenomenologically satisfactory account of collective emotion is because it explains the key conception captured by Scheler’s example: the conception of a participation in a unified feeling. As I have tried to show, competing views of collective emotion, for different reasons, ultimately fail to account for this crucial idea. I have argued that the capacity we have to affectively respond to certain events in such a way as to be able to understand our feelings as feelings that constitute a joint experiential act is grounded in our capacity to care with one another about something. I have proposed that we can conceive of those situations in which we are actualizing our capacity to care with one another as situations in which we (the participants) non-mistakenly experience ourselves as jointly pressing ahead into the actualization of some possibilities of a group that we together are. Importantly, the phenomenological characterization of the conditions met by those experiences that are at the heart of an episode of joint feeling leads to a description of a state of affairs in which talk of participation in an episode of joint feeling is warranted. To the extent to which this description captures conditions that are necessary and jointly sufficient to justify talk of participation in a joint feeling, it may be understood as a characterization of the ontological conditions of cases of genuinely collective emotions. 475
Héctor Andrés Sánchez Guerrero
Notes
References Behnke, Elisabeth (2008). Interkinaesthetic Affectivity: A Phenomenological Approach. Continental Philosophy Review 41(2), 143–161. Blattner, William (1999). Heidegger’s Temporal Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bourgois, Patrick, and Hess, Ursula (2008). The Impact of Social Context on Mimicry. Biological Psychology 77(3), 343–352. Collins, Randall. (2004). Interaction Ritual Chains. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Gilbert, Margaret (2002). Collective Guilt and Collective Guilt Feelings. The Journal of Ethics 6(2), 115–143. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Heidegger, Martin (1962[1927]). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. New York: Harper and Row. Helm, Bennett (2001). Emotional Reason. Deliberation, Motivation, and the Nature of Value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2008). Plural Agents. Noûs 42, 17–49. ——— (2017). Communities of Respect. Grounding, Responsibility, Authority, and Dignity. New York: Oxford University Press. Konzelmann Ziv, A. (2007). Collective Guilt Feeling Revisited. Dialectica 61, 467–493. ——— (2009). The Semantics of Shared Emotion. Universitas Philosophica 52, 81–106. Krueger, Joel (2016). The Affective ‘We’: Self-regulation and Shared Emotions. In: T. Szanto and D. Moran (Eds.). The Phenomenology of Sociality: Discovering the ‘We’. London, New York: Routledge, 263–280. Ricœur, Paul (2009[1950]). Philosophie de la Volonté I: Le Volontaire et l’Involontaire. Paris: Édition Points. Salice, Alessandro, Høffding, Simon, and Gallagher, Shaun (2019). Putting Plural Self-awareness into Practice: The Phenomenology of Expert Musicianship. Topoi 38(1), 197–209. Salmela, Mikko (2012). Shared Emotions. Philosophical Explorations 15(1), 33–46. Salmela, Mikko, and Nagatsu, Michiru (2016). Collective Emotions and Joint Action. Journal of Social Ontology 2(1), 33–57. Sánchez Guerrero, Héctor A. (2016). Feeling Together and Caring with One Another: A Contribution to the Debate on Collective Affective Intentionality. Cham: Springer. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1939). Esquisse d’une Théorie des Emotions. Paris: Hermann. Scheler, Max (2008[1913]). The Nature of Sympathy. Transl. by P. Heath. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers. Schmid, Hans Bernhard (2003). Can Brains in Vats Think as a Team? Philosophical Explorations 6(3), 201–218. ——— (2009). Plural Action: Essays in Philosophy and Social Science. Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (2014). Plural Self-Awareness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13(1), 7–24.
476
Joint feeling Stein, Edith (1922). Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie und der Geisteswissenschaften. Zweite Abhandlung: Individuum und Gemeinschaft. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, Vol. V. Halle: Niemeyer, 116–283. [Engl. Transl.: Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities. Transl. by M. C. Baseheart, and M. Sawicki. Washington D.C.: ICS Publications 2000.] Szanto, Thomas (2015). Collective Emotions, Normativity, and Empathy: A Steinian Account. Human Studies 38(4), 503–527. ——— (2017). Review of Feelings of Being Together and Caring with One Another: A Contribution to the Debate on Collective Affective Intentionality. Journal of Social Ontology 3(2), 267–273. Wilkins, Burleigh (2002). Joint Commitments. The Journal of Ethics 6(2)3, 145–155. Will, Udo, and Turrow, Gabe (2011). Introduction to Entrainment and Cognitive Ethnomusicology. In: J. Berger, and G. Turrow (Eds.). Music, Science, and the Rhythmic Brain: Cultural and Clinical Implications. London, New York: Routledge, 3–30. Zahavi, Dan (2018). Collective Intentionality and Plural Pre-Reflective Self-Awareness. Journal of Social Philosophy 49(1), 61–75. Further Reading Osler, Lucy (forthcoming). Feeling Togetherness Online: A Phenomenological Sketch of Online Communal Experiences. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-019-09627-4. Thonhauser, Gerhard (2018). Shared Emotions: A Steinian Proposal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17(5), 997–1015.
477
41 Political emotions Thomas Szanto and Jan Slaby
1. Introduction Philosophers, cultural, social and political scientists are increasingly recognizing affectivity as an essential dimension of the political. Affectively charged political rhetoric, political strategies, and the global rise of populist and nationalist movements have contributed to this resurging interest in political affectivity (cf. Cossarini and Vallespín 2019). Yet, when one recent political economy bestseller’s title reads Nervous States: How Feeling Took Over the World (Davies 2018), anybody who is at all familiar with the history of political philosophy from Plato and Aristotle through Hobbes, Spinoza, Rousseau, Montesquieu and, indeed, Kant, to contemporary postfoundational political theorists is likely to meet such a title with a raised eyebrow. Arguably, it is not news that the political is deeply stirred by affect and emotions. But affectivity is not just some by-product of a properly “emotion-proof ” ( Demertzis 2013) political domain based on rational judgment, deliberation and (self-)interest, as some traditional liberal political theorists have suggested (Hirschman 1977; Holmes 1995).1 Rather, the political—the realm in which we negotiate our plurality and differences with a view to freedom, power, individual autonomy, collective recognition or our forms of living- together—is essentially affective. In this respect, ‘the political’ must be distinguished from policy-making or ‘real politics’, where affectivity and emotions are typically also involved, but often just contingently so (cf. Slaby and Bens 2019). The political is affective because it fundamentally deals with what matters to us, what we value, fear or desire, or what concerns us—us as a polity. Conversely, the affective is always political, since emotions are not just subjective affairs but are governed by “feeling rules” (Hochschild 1983) and are modulated by shared or conflicting values. Hence, emotions always involve the negotiation of what, how, and with (or against) whom we ought to feel. In the wake of the ‘affective turn’, political affect and emotions have been widely investigated in various research fields. Within cultural studies, there has been a special emphasis on gender, the ‘politics of affect,’ and power (Ahmed 2004; Thrift 2008; Butler 2009; Bargetz 2015, 2020). Political theorists have focused on the ambivalent role of emotions in liberal democracies, and on ‘hostile’ emotions and sentiments such as disgust, resentment, or hatred in the context of political tensions, nationalism, genocide, or transitional 478
Political emotions
and post- conflict retributive justice processes (Brudholm and Lang 2018; Hutchinson and Bleiker 2008; Crociani-Windland and Hoggett 2012; Hoggett and Thompson 2012; Demertzis 2013; Mihai 2016). Political psychologists have targeted, for instance, the role of affects in voters’ behaviour, political judgment, campaigning, or in the context of (post-)war conflicts (Marcus 2002; Redlawsk 2006; Neuman et al. 2007; Åhäll and Gregory 2015). Sociologists addressed political emotions in activism and social and protest movements (Goodwin et al. 2001; Flam and King 2005; Van Stekelenburg and Klandermans 2013; Jasper 2018), and social psychologists have investigated different affective and political reactions to in-group and out-group members based on emotional group-identification (Clarke et al. 2006; Halperin 2016). In philosophy, some have drawn on the work of the French philosopher Deleuze and on historical resources in Spinoza and Bergson for analyzing the “socio-somatic” (Protevi 2009), dynamic and relational nature of political affect (Protevi 2014; Massumi 2015; Lordon 2016; Slaby 2017). Others have reassessed ancient Greek and further historical sources (Sokolon 2003; Hall 2005; Kingston and Ferry 2008; Koziak 2010) or aimed at bridging political philosophy or psychology with contemporary philosophy of emotions (Solomon 1995; James 2003; Nussbaum 2013; Mohrmann 2015; Romano 2018). This wide-ranging discussion can be broadly sorted into approaches that focus on emotions, and those that focus on affect. While emotions are usually construed as mental states with specific intentional contents or directed at specific affectively significant targets—for example fear, anger, shame, hatred, envy or indignation—affect is an ontologically broader and less specific category. This is especially so in the Spinoza- and Deleuze-inspired perspective prevalent in recent cultural studies and parts of continental philosophy. Within this context, affect is seen as a dynamic relationality between organic and non-organic bodies, comprising an ontological layer of reality prior to and formative of intentionally directed emotions (see Slaby and Mühlhoff 2019). Not surprisingly, these two approaches have rather little in common. In order to prevent confusion, and not least because there is a significant lacuna of philosophical discussions about the political nature of emotions, in the present chapter, we focus on the political character of just these, leaving considerations about affect aside.2 With regard to political emotions, there are several important issues that remain controversial and little understood: In what sense exactly is the political essentially tied to emotions? And what makes emotions political? Is it their public expression and recognition? Is it their reference to a political community and the sharedness of the concerns? How and by whom are political emotions felt? What is their normative function, and can they be appropriate or inappropriate? Are forms of antagonisms—along with their orientation to commonality—built into the very heart of political emotions qua political, as anti-liberal political theorists in the tradition of Carl Schmitt (1932) or post-foundational democracy theorists (Mouffe 2013; cf. Mihai 2014) claim? To address these issues, we elaborate the conceptual preconditions that must be fulfilled such that the qualifier ‘political’ can be applied to emotions in the first place (Section 2). We then sketch a multi-dimensional approach to political emotions3 and employ the concept of ‘collective affective intentionality’ as an explicative framework. We argue that political emotions in the robust sense constitute a subclass of collective emotions—collective emotions that disclose a shared concern of political import, claim public recognition and affectively and normatively modulate the emotional life of the members of a polity (Section 3). Finally, we demonstrate how political emotions essentially contain an orientation towards—often contested or ‘agonistic’—forms of communalization (Section 4).
479
Thomas Szanto and Jan Slaby
2. Emotions and the political: preliminaries In this section, we provide a provisionary sketch of the relationship between emotions and the political. In order to approach political emotions, we start out from a construal of emotions as repeatable sequences of embodied relations—relations both among actors and between actors and environment. Most generally, what qualifies social relations as emotional is their systematic relatedness to what matters—to individuals as well as to collectives. As engagements with matters of concern emotional comportments inevitably raise questions with regard to what has—or should have—significance and what might or should be done about it. This lends emotions a complex normative dimension (see Section 3.2). Against this background, it is relatively easy to see that the political is non-contingently interlinked with emotions. No matter whether the political is understood in terms of formative power relations (Saar 2013), in terms of the formation of collectives (see Section 3), in terms of human freedom (Arendt 1961) and contingency (Marchart 2007), or as antagonistic relations between collectives or social formations (Laclau and Mouffe 1985; Mouffe 2013)—emotions loom large in its affairs. Think of the aversive sentiments in an open political conflict, or of the enthusiasm accompanying political sea changes, or the fear, envy and resentment directed at powerful or wealthy factions in divided societies, hatred in intergroup and ethnic conflicts or feelings of solidarity within social movements. Likewise, consider the public outrage in response to manifest social injustice, or the “collective joy” (Ehrenreich 2007) that energizes grass-root political initiatives, or the tricks and techniques of emotional modulation employed strategically by expert politicians. But pointing to such cases is certainly not enough to see how ‘the political’ is essentially affective or how emotions can be counted as political emotions properly speaking. We cannot revisit the debate about the nature of ‘the political’ in contra-distinction to institutionalized ‘real politics’, as it has been conducted especially in French Theory informed political philosophy in recent decades (Lacoue-Labarthe and Nancy 1997; Marchart 2007). Instead, we circle in on an interrelated cluster of issues that we deem central for determining the affective nature of the political and the political nature of political emotions (regardless of whether these issues might also be manifest in concrete political practices and institutions). For a start, consider Hannah Arendt’s dictum that “freedom is the raison d’être of politics” (Arendt 1961, 146)4: Only beings who are not confined to natural necessity and thus capable of self-determination, however limited, have both the capacity and the need for politics. Accordingly, the political, for Arendt, is the dimension pertaining to the active determination of that which is not already determined for human collectives. The political is a collective engagement with contingence—a matter of shaping the world in certain ways. The partial freedom from necessity that Arendt highlights implies a further key dimension of the political: the possibility, but also the need, to form alliances—to act in concert, as Arendt (1958) puts it—and also the all-too acute possibility of conflict and antagonism resulting from free beings encountering one another. Another crucial aspect is implied by Arendt’s general characterization: political concerns are only those that make some (implicit or explicit) claim to public recognition, where these claims are typically, but pace Arendt (1958) not necessarily, explicitly raised in a public sphere. Freedom, contingency, collectivity, antagonism and publicity—these are five different yet constitutively interlinked ‘names’ of the political. Unsurprisingly, there are many rivalling accounts of the nature of the political. But the most foundational quarrel is the one between Arendt’s associative paradigm, where the political is at base a matter of commonality, collectivity or collective action, and the dissociative 480
Political emotions
paradigm forcefully articulated by Carl Schmitt (1932; cf. Marchart 2007). For Schmitt, the essence of the political lies in the possibility to draw and enact the distinction between friend and enemy—i.e., association by dissociation. Accordingly, Schmitt defines the political in terms of the instituting power of the ever-lurking possibility of, and indeed the preparedness and ability to, engage in conflict or war. Regardless of which side one takes in the debate between Arendtians and Schmittians, what matters presently is just the broad contours of an understanding of the political shared by both camps. On the level of analysis needed for studying the general structure of political emotions, alliance, antagonism, contingency and (bounded) freedom operate together as a tension-riddled constellation that is characteristic of the political, whatever its particular manifestations.
3. Political emotions: collectivity and normativity Consider the following examples for political emotions: anger of state-employees in the face of cutting paid lunch-breaks, leading to nation-wide strikes; indignation of an affluent downtown apartment owner on behalf of precarious creative industry workers and lowincome families in the neighbourhood, who are forced to move due to steeply rising rents; resentment and feelings of powerlessness or hatred on the part of minorities over failed retributive justice in the wake of ethnic cleansing they have suffered; or a still simmering but growing hope for a future when humanity would come to terms with its failings and reverse climate change. What, if anything, do these emotions and sentiments, with such saliently different affective and political impact, power-relations and political stakes, have in common? And what makes them political in the first place? In this section, we propose to answer these questions by first considering the intentional structure of political emotions, i.e., what philosophers of emotion call affective intentionality (Slaby 2008). Next, we will zero in on the distinctive and complex normative structure of political emotions.
3.1 The collective affective intentionality account of political emotions Affective intentionality refers to the evaluative world-orientation of emotions, their capacity to disclose the world in light of specific concerns. The key point of the concept is that the intentional evaluation of objects, persons and events is intrinsically linked to their affective import for the subjects of those evaluations. Intentional evaluation and affective import are not two separate components of emotions. Rather, emotions are “feelings-towards” (Goldie 2000), or “felt evaluations” (Helm 2001). Moreover, the concerns, in the light of which felt evaluations gain their affective weight so as to matter, holistically hang together. They form more or less coherent patterns that constitute the overall emotional orientations of the subjects (cf. Chapter 20 in this volume). Particularly relevant for our purpose is that some recent phenomenologically inspired work applies the concept of affective intentionality to collectives, and suggests a collective affective intentionality (CAI) account (Schmid 2009; Guerrero Sánchez 2016; Thonhauser 2018; see Chapter 40 in this volume). Now, we suggest applying the CAI account to political emotions. Applying CAI to political emotions means taking their affective phenomenology seriously: political emotions are not mere cognitive appraisals or evaluations of import in 481
Thomas Szanto and Jan Slaby
the service of political judgment. Rather, they have an experiential dimension and are felt in certain ways. CAI is the disposition of a group to jointly disclose situations or events in light of more or less unified patterns of shared concerns. Notice that this disposition is not actualized by groups as such, but by individual members’ “feeling-towards together” (Guerrero Sánchez 2016). Hence, CAI requires no emergent or supra-individual subject as the bearer of collective emotions. On the other hand, collective emotions are not reducible to some loose affective interaction between members either. Specifically, collective emotions are neither reducible to what psychologists call ‘social appraisal’, nor to communicative sharing of emotional information (Michael 2011). Similarly, collective emotions cannot be construed in terms of the “synchronous convergence” of individuals’ emotions towards the same target (von Scheve and Ismer 2013), a mere affective resonance between individuals or so-called emotional contagion (Hatfield et al. 2014). In applying the CAI account to political emotions, we argue that robustly political emotions too must be jointly felt. That is to say, they are not merely based on affective interactions between citizens either, but on affectively shared evaluations that disclose concerns of political import. According to our proposal, there are three necessary and in conjunction sufficient requirements for members of a community to affectively share political concerns in this robust sense5: 1 2 3
The members’ emotions have a double affective-intentional focus: (a) a focus on the same matter of political import and (b) a background focus on the political community itself. Members implicitly or explicitly claim public recognition of the emotions and their import for the polity. There are certain reciprocal relations between the community’s emotional outlook and that of the members: The very shared nature of political emotions must feed into the individuals’ felt experience, or their affective concern for the polity, and it must have normative impact on their emotion regulation, their political motivation and comportment and on the appropriateness of their emotions. Thus, there will be an affective and normative integration of the members’ emotions.
The initial consideration underlying (1) is that emotions cannot be properly shared unless the respective members acknowledge their sharedness. Note that this acknowledgment need not occur via any direct, let alone mutual, awareness of each other’s emotions. Members of a political community often lack direct bodily or communicative interaction, and typically, the acknowledgement involves symbolic, ritualistic or discursive forms of mediation. Moreover, the subjects of such shared political emotions must not only acknowledge the sharedness of their concerns, but also the import of those concerns for the community. The ‘double aspect’ of the affective intentionality of political emotions in sketched in (1) is meant to capture this.6 As part of their affective focus, political emotions thus involve the concern for a group and its felt evaluative outlook. The key idea, then, is that in political emotions, individuals overtly or tacitly pay “reverence” (Helm 2017) to the emotional outlook of their (actual or projected) political community. Thus, members not only reinforce this outlook but also co-constitute it as theirs—as their jointly felt evaluation. Concerning (2), we argue that it is this very sharedness that makes political emotions publicly recognizable in a way that non-political emotions are not.7 To be sure, a fan crowd at a football match vociferously cheering for their team is also readily recognizable publicly. However, there is a significant difference between a sports fan crowd and a political protest 482
Political emotions
group: As shared concerns of import for the political community, political emotions must also always involve a claim to public recognition. In addition to recognizing their manifest concerns, this is also a claim for others to recognize these concerns as being of import for the community at stake. We take this to be an ontologically foundational claim: One need not publicly express or enact this claim for recognition to transpire. As we have just seen, the community whose political concerns are at stake must figure among the emotion-constitutive concerns. Now, the community ‘at stake’ may already be constituted and united by some shared political concerns, or it may be a community ‘in the making’. In the latter case, the community’s evaluative outlook is not yet settled even if engaged individuals might emphatically endorse it. To be sure, emotions not only facilitate a sense of belonging to a putative or given community but also a community’s constitution as a community of a concern. Furthermore, political emotions shape individuals’ socioaffective relations to certain political communities, and may eventually modulate their political and social identity, even if they are not actual members of those communities. Consider a white-collar employee who, in feelings of solidarity, comes to share the concerns of working class citizens and engages in related activism. She may thus incorporate those working class concerns into her social identity without ever belonging to the working class. Now, before outlining the various affective and normative relations of reciprocity (3) in the next two subsections, we need to further specify the affective-intentional structure of political emotions. Following affective-intentional accounts of emotions, we must first distinguish the target of an emotion from its focus. The target of an emotion is the object eliciting the emotional reaction; its focus is the object of import, or the background feature of the object that makes the emotion’s evaluation of the target intelligible (Helm 2001, 2017; Slaby 2008). Say, the target of my anger is the finance minister’s decision to lower corporate taxes, while its focus is the state of the tax-dependent medical care system. The target of political emotions may involve quite different kinds of objects: political events or policies, politicians, discursive elites, majority or minority groups, individual proxies or representatives of groups, etc. Often, in certain antagonistic political emotions, the target is a diffuse or overgeneralized object: think of Ressentiment directed at ‘the establishment’, distrust borne towards ‘the media’, or hatred in the face of ‘hordes of refugees’. In such cases, the negatively evaluated properties (e.g., greed, exploitation) are transposed from individuals to groups or to some unspecified ‘Other’, or individuals are treated as stereotypical proxies of groups (cf. Szanto forthcoming). The target on its own, however, will not suffice to render an emotion political, even if it qualifies as a political object in some relevant sense.8 Our point is not only that, for instance, my repulsion of the Brazilian President Jair Bolsonaro as a despicable human being is insufficient to render my repulsion political. Moreover, even my repulsion of him as a homophobe will not suffice for it to count as a political emotion properly speaking, as long as homophobia is only of my individual concern. Instead, we suggest that for the emotion to have political import, it must also have a background focus, namely a concern for the actual, putative or imaginary political community. But above and beyond their general background focus, political emotions always have specific concerns as their focus as well. It is worth noting that target and focus do not always overlap. Political discourse often aims precisely at driving them apart. Consider the hatred of refugees. Typically, that hatred is not focused on individual refugees, but nor is its focus on heterogeneous refugee-groups. Rather, the focus tends to be on the putatively endangered ethnic or cultural homogeneity of the host country, some readily invoked ‘Judeo-Christian’ tradition, or an allegedly unambiguous Western liberal Enlightenment heritage (cf. Mishra 2017). Thus, in some cases, 483
Thomas Szanto and Jan Slaby
such as intergroup hatred, the focus of political emotions is “blurred” and the intentional object of the emotions is “overgeneralized” (Szanto forthcoming). As Scheler’s classicphenomenological study (1912/1919) demonstrates, this feature of an indeterminate focus is also distinctive of Ressentiment. According to Scheler, Ressentiment is characterized by an unfocused intentionality “radiating” in all directions (Scheler 1912/1919, 60). Instead of making the concerns of the emoter salient, the affective focus of Ressentiment is uninformative of what really matters to the emoters.9 In other cases, though, political emotions will have a clear focus. In such cases, they will also have clear epistemic functions and contribute to so-called ‘political sophistication’, or the capacity and attempts to integrate complex and often diffuse political information (Schreiber 2007; Miller 2011). Paradigmatic examples here are emotions that drive political movements, such as anger, moral outrage or indignation (e.g., the Spanish and Greek Indignants). Such emotions will alert or capture the attention of oneself, one’s peers, or third parties to the underlying political concerns at stake, and facilitate critical reappraisal of the information upon which the evaluation is based (Romano 2018; cf. Brady 2013).
3.2 Towards a multi-dimensional taxonomy We have seen that, for an emotion to count as political in the robust sense of a CAI-type political emotion, it is not enough that individuals have certain affective reactions towards political issues. Nor is it sufficient that they simply interact or group-identify with other political subjects and actors who have the same or similar emotional reactions. Rather, we have argued that what renders emotions political in the robust sense is a jointly felt evaluative outlook that involves a number of requirements: an acknowledgment of the sharedness of concern and import for the political community, a concern for the community itself, a claim for the public recognition of the former, and a reciprocal modulation and integration of individuals’ emotional experiences. To be sure, this is a demanding model. However, notice our emphasis on ‘robustness’ here. To accommodate emotions that are not shared in the robust sense of the CAI model, but which do still have a political focus, we propose a multi-dimensional account. Consider, for example, an individual’s fear of social déclassement due to certain socio-economic and political developments; that fear may modulate one’s voting behaviour without, however, resulting in any robustly shared sense of belonging to a class or political group. Contrast this to emotions jointly expressed in a political movement or with the motivational power for even existentially dangerous political action that feelings of solidarity in certain protest movements might generate. Accounting for such differences also helps clarify the flexibility of behaviour among voters who are not politically organized or who do not group-identify with any political organization or class—a phenomenon evidenced by the current erosion of established parties across Western democracies. Accordingly, we need to differentiate not just between individual and shared political emotions but also among different levels of emotional sharing and their distinct sociopsychological mechanisms (see Salmela 2014; Salmela and Nagatsu 2016; cf. Barsade and Knight 2015). At the minimum, we can distinguish the following levels: (a) Weakly shared political emotions; at this level, sharedness is based on social appraisal or on the socio-communicative sharing of information. An individual’s emotional appraisal of a political fact or event is influenced and modulated by relevant others’ appraisals (Rimé 2007; cf. Michael 2011), as for example when individuals’ xenophobic fears are reinforced by polarized peer-discussions. Incidentally, these mechanisms are partly responsible for so-called ‘emotional enclaves’ (see Section 3.3), especially if they are amplified by social or mass media. 484
Political emotions
(b) Group-based political emotions; here, political emotions are based on individuals’ self-categorization as members of a political community and their concomitant groupidentification (cf. Smith et al. 2007). In addition to their appraisal of certain political facts or events, such emotions also re-evaluate one’s relation to the (putative) group, and typically serve as “amplifier” of the emotion (Halperin 2016). Think of feeling guilt, shame, or indignation ‘in the name of ’ one’s group. (c) Finally, we have more or less diachronically robust, public, and properly speaking collective political emotions. These are precisely based on a shared and jointly felt evaluation of the target in light of the community’s concerns. Let us emphasize that only (c) requires the existence of an actual community and an actual interaction between members. Such interaction can take place either in physical co-presence or, more typically, in variously mediated (e.g., by social media), in shared public spaces, or in the so-called ‘social imaginary’ (Taylor 2004). But emotions still qualify as political as long as the individuals’ affective focus involves reference to a public space of shared concerns—even if those individuals ultimately turn out to be political Robinson Crusoes and the allegedly social imaginary nothing but an imaginary space. In contrast, we can dub emotions that only have a politically relevant focus but are otherwise in no relevant sense of (a) to (c) related to a political community as such, politically focused emotions. According to our account, however, these are not ‘political emotions’ properly speaking. Consider somebody who is angry in the face of a policy reform of employment laws that affect her working-hours, but who doesn’t have any solidary with similarly affected employees. Coming back to the reciprocity requirement above (3), notice that differences in the robustness of sharing correspond not just to the mentioned behavioural or motivational differences (voting, joining social movements, etc.) but also to certain phenomenological and normative differences in the participants’ affective and political life. Consider, for example, how the fact that I share my indignation about a political event with others modulates the very felt quality of my emotion. This different phenomenology has much to do with accompanying feelings of solidarity (cf. Chapter 45 in this volume). Such feelings of solidarity will, in turn, have certain motivational and normative functions. Most obviously, they will reinforce political identification and might motivate members to join a political movement. Mere individual group-identification will not have the same effects. Collective political emotions often also express, or indeed co-constitute, a sense of the breaching of shared values. And, as moral address, such emotions do more than simply target the disruptors of the normative order. They are also directed at one’s own community or at third parties, whom they may address as witnesses of the violation and as implicit benefactors or potential agents of restorative justice (cf. Brudholm 2008; MacLachlan 2010; Mihai 2016; Salmela and von Scheve 2018). Consider, for example, indigenous Canadians’ resentment towards the forefathers of non-indigenous citizens regarding a forced schooling policy (see MacLachlan 2010; Stockdale 2013): the resentment is not primarily directed at the forefathers themselves but at their contemporary successors or current quasi-colonial conditions, while also focusing fellow indigenous citizens’ collective memory or shared vulnerability. Thereby, these emotions (re-)establish or (re-)enforce sympathy or solidarity with, and among, say, the oppressed. But often the inverse will also happen, as when groups refuse to recognize grounds for such collective or proxy resentment and instead bear resentment towards the ‘resenters.’ Think, for instance, of overtly or covertly misogynistic anti-‘MeToo’ repercussions, or of anti-Semitic refusals of the ‘remembrance culture’. 485
Thomas Szanto and Jan Slaby
3.3 The normativity of political emotions Phenomenological differences between the above-sketched types of political emotions are intimately tied to differences regarding their normative dimensions. In particular, different types of political emotions correlate to differences in normative power and to the pressure they place upon individuals regarding what and how they ought to feel (together), and how they ought to express, voice and enact certain emotions. Concerning their normative power, collective indignation or resentment, for example, are surely more powerful emotions for restorative claims of justice than interpersonal emotions or the ‘private’ resentment of individuals towards certain groups. Concerning their different normative pressures, consider the difference between personal and collective commitment to feel something. For instance, if I sincerely share my anger with my ‘fellow-travellers’, and am thus committed to the emotion’s shared focus, it will not be quite appropriate to only half-heartedly join demonstrations, and even less appropriate to ridicule in private my fellow-travellers for their naïve behaviour. On pain of feeling excluded or being in fact excluded from the community, I will rather have to regulate, monitor, express and enact my emotions accordingly. In more general terms, there are three interrelated but distinct normative issues regarding political emotions: (i) The first has to do with their normative capacity and function vis-à-vis political concerns. Emotions clearly have not just an epistemic but also a normative function. For example, they voice or testify to moral breaches or reclaim moral or social norms. The paradigm emotions usually invoked here belong to the class of moral emotions that Strawson (1962) famously labelled ‘reactive attitudes’, and in particular, resentment, contempt, indignation, moral outrage or anger (e.g., Rawls 1971; Nussbaum 2016), and shame (Tarnopolsky 2010; Locke 2016). Moreover, many have argued that emotions help establish and maintain attachments to otherwise abstract liberal or democratic political values, such as equality, fairness or justice (Walzer 2004; Hall 2005; Kingston 2011; Nussbaum 2013). Others have claimed that they constitute a sense of justice and contribute to its cultivation (Solomon 1995). Ever since ancient Greek discussions of political emotions, and in particular Aristotle’s Rhetoric, whenever philosophers or political theorists discuss the normative dimension of political emotions, it is usually only these normative functions they have in view. However, there are two equally important normative dimensions, albeit normative in a different sense. (ii) As we have seen, collective affective intentionality puts certain normative pressures on individuals’ emotional regulation and expression, and indeed on the very way they (ought to) feel. These norms are particularly powerful in political contexts. But they do not exert their normative powers so much by individuals’ “joint commitment to feel” “as one body”. According to such a joint commitment account of collective emotions, suggested by Gilbert (2002, 2014), members retain the right to “rebuke” each other for unilateral affective deviance. But the norms at issue work more subtly and indeed more effectively: namely by means of internalized “feeling rules” (Hochschild 1983) or what Hochschild (2016) calls “deep stories”, viz. narratives that we are told and re-tell ourselves about how, given our political identifications and allegiances, we ought to feel about certain socio-cultural or political issues. And when such norms and internalized narratives sediment themselves abidingly, they constitute what has recently been described as “emotional habitus” or “emotional culture” (Illouz 2007; Barsade and Knight 2015). Habitualized emotion norms guide and police appropriateness of emotions with regard to the display, suppression, or duration, of the emotion. They also apply to the perceived 486
Political emotions
appropriateness of specific types of emotions vis-à-vis specific emotional targets, which is coded within particular political communities (‘We are not complainers like those welfare-benefit recipients’; ‘War-refugees don’t deserve compassion, they are traitors and should rather fight for their freedom, as we have’; ‘These are liberal sympathies, not ours’; cf. Hochschild 2016). As Hochschild arrestingly puts it, what often happens here is that “people are segregating themselves into different emotionally toned enclaves—anger here, hopefulness and trust there” (2016, 6). In more positive terms, such norms affectively integrate individuals’ affective concerns into the broader network of the political community’s concerns, and thus they (re-)align individuals around a shared emotional perspective. (iii) Finally, there is another central, but so far largely ignored,10 dimension to the normative appropriateness of political emotions. This dimension is best conceived of in terms of emotions’ so-called “fittingness”. As a number of analytic philosophers of emotions have convincingly argued, fittingness is orthogonal to the moral appropriateness of emotions, but also to any instrumental or prudential consideration (de Sousa 1987; Helm 2001; D’Arms and Jacobson 2010; Salmela 2014). Fittingness is not a question of which emotions are, as it were, good, or when it is right to feel or express them. Nor is the issue which emotions are conducive to certain political goals. Rather, what is at stake is whether an emotion is fitting in the sense that its intentional object actually has the evaluative features that the respective emotion discloses to the emoter. Fittingness thus does not appeal to objective evaluative properties, and it is neutral to value-realism.11 As such, the concept allows us to ask whether an emotion’s focus picks out those evaluative properties that really matter to the emoters themselves. To illustrate, consider again Ressentiment, a sentiment that has been repeatedly identified as a driving emotional mechanisms of right-wing populism (in contrast to resentment as a form of shared moral anger fuelling left-wing populism; cf. Salmela and von Scheve 2018). Ressentiment is precisely an emotional mechanism that renders certain emotions— primarily envy and shame—unfitting in the above sense. Imagine somebody who has fully internalized the values of a success-oriented individualistic society, and envies the success of others. He feels powerless, fears that he cannot keep pace, and is ashamed in the face of these insufficiencies. Facilitated by the repression mechanism characteristic of Ressentiment, he eventually comes to conceive of the desired values (success, wealth, etc.) in a self- deceptive fashion as something undesirable (‘success only corrupts’) or as based on reprehensible values (e.g., greediness). Thus, in a process of “transvaluations of values” (Nietzsche 1887), desirable values that one finds oneself powerless to attain are reassessed as non-desirable or reprehensible. This is a clear case of an inappropriate relation between an emotion and its focus, since the sentiment discloses subjectively ‘false’ values to the emoter. Accordingly, Scheler (1912/1919) views Ressentiment as an “illusion of evaluative feeling”.12 As we shall see in the next section, such subjectively unfitting or self-deceptive affective mechanisms will only be reinforced on the collective level, leading to ever-fortified emotional enclaves.
4. Collectivity, the political and the “agonistic” dialectic Our provisional result is that robustly political emotions affectively and normatively align individuals around a shared emotional perspective and, at the same time, exclude, vitiate or even aim to eliminate those not endorsing that perspective. Moreover, we have argued that the distinctive feature of political emotions is a concern for the (real or imagined) polity. This polity is part of the manifest content of the overall emotional outlook, and variously modulates individuals’ emotional experience and behaviour. Viewed thus, a certain striving for communalization as such forms a fundamental concern of political emotions. 487
Thomas Szanto and Jan Slaby
However, this needs to be immediately qualified: surely, not all types of communities are grounded in a political concern. As we have seen, concerns are only political if they recognize the possibility, as well as the need, to form alliances in the face of finite and contested resources; ultimately, they thus have individual and collective freedom in view. Moreover, recall that concerns only qualify as political in the proper sense if they make some claim for public recognition. Accordingly, a family or a circle of friends or a team at one’s workplace will not, under normal circumstances, qualify to ground an allegiance or antagonism (or both) that carries political weight. In this section, we aim to show how in the striving for communalization, there is always an element of both allegiance and antagonism involved, no matter whether communalization assumes directly associative or dissociative forms. We suggest that political emotions essentially involve a certain “agonistic” dialectic of allegiance and antagonism (Mouffe 2013). Simply put, our suggestion is that both sharedness and antagonism are built into the very heart of political emotions. Shared emotional outlooks will always involve some who do not share them: those who do not wish to partake, those who are excluded from partaking, or those who are negatively evaluated by it. But there are different aspects of this still very general claim. To determine which form of ‘agonism’ applies, one must look case by case at concrete instantiations of political emotions. We cannot provide any such contextual analysis here; instead, in accordance with our multi-dimensional model, we shall sketch a rough-and-ready taxonomy of possible manifestations of agonistic communalization, which in actual scenarios typically intermesh: (i) There are manifestations of directly associative communalization. These may come in the form of group-identification, the aspiration for group inclusion, or alliance-formation, in the sense of the CAI account. This will vary according to the level and type of affective sharing outlined above. Finally, directly associative communalization may also involve utopian hope, revolutionary ‘enthusiasm’ (Mohrmann 2015), or the anticipation of imagined political communities to come (Nancy 1991; Agamben 1993). (ii) On the other hand, the political arena is also characterized by outright affective antagonism in the form of hostile emotions, such as hatred, distrust, resentment, indignation, moral outrage or disgust, or more subtle ‘anti-pathetic’ emotions, such as envy, lack of sympathy, refusal of compassion (see Chapter 38 in this volume). Direct manifestations of such dissociative communalization will involve some element of outgroup demarcation, which may or may not eventually lead to intergroup conflict or violence (e.g., derogative or ridiculing discourse targeting minorities or power groups). What we wish to stress is that an essential characteristic of the political emerges not only in such direct forms of inclusive alliances (i) or exclusive antagonism (ii) but also in indirect forms of ‘agonism’: alliances for self-empowerment and what might be called ‘negative solidarity’ (cf. Arendt 1951, 315). This brings us to two further manifestations of contested political community. (iii) Consider instrumental, agonistic alliances of self-empowerment. Political alliances are often not so much formed on the basis of affects, emotions or values in concordance, but precisely when there is no such accord, or even in instances of outright evaluative conflict. Here, one affectively allies oneself with those one considers as fundamentally Others—i.e., those whose overall evaluative outlook is different from one’s own—if such an alliance serves or facilitates one’s own thriving or power-status. Indeed, the distinctive force of political affectivity often manifests itself precisely where it cuts across more or less superficial alliances, bridging conflicting values or interests. By doing so, political affectivity not only reinforces the respective parties’ room for manoeuvre and control over the other group or third parties but, 488
Political emotions
more importantly, what might be called their ‘affective power’. A curious example here is the alliance between environmentalist and staunchly anti-environmentalist fractions within the Tea Party movement. These two fractions do not share concrete core political interests. Yet, they do share a whole range of affectively binding and mutually empowering background sentiments, such as a deep distrust towards the government, religious devotion, or Ressentiment in the face of affirmative action (see Hochschild 2016). (iv) Finally, consider hostile emotions that manifest agonistic forms of communalization or involve a certain ‘negative dialectic’ leading to forms of ‘false solidarity’. For example, a number of phenomenologists have pointed out that racial or religious hatred not only creates outgroup demarcation but, ironically, facilitates feelings of solidarity, which indeed co-constitutes allegiance to one’s ingroup (Kolnai 1935, 1998; Sartre 1944; Ahmed 2004; Szanto forthcoming; cf. also Chapter 38 in this volume). There are two dialectically opposed affective orientations here. The first is a ‘positive’ affective binding that attaches individuals to their ingroup (the ‘community of haters’), or an “alignment” between the I and the We (Ahmed 2014, 51). Just as importantly, the second orientation entails an antagonistic affective attachment to the target: here the haters (We) negatively “attach” themselves to the hated ones (Them). In that sense, one can say that haters ‘need’ a stereotypically created Other for their very self-constitution as a community of haters (cf. above, and Sartre 1944). A somewhat similar mechanism can be seen in collective forms of Ressentiment. In order to facilitate repression of negative self-focused or social emotions (shame, feelings of powerlessness), individuals align themselves with their initially powerless ingroup and collectively transform negative emotions into ones that are ‘positive’ (e.g., national pride) or into purportedly moral or power-conducive antagonistic ones (e.g., Ressentiment, feelings of superiority, hatred). The solidarity here is ‘false’ since the concern for one’s own community is solely based on a devaluation of others (as in hatred), and more importantly, because of its (self-)deceptively invoked—and hence ‘false’—values (as in Ressentiment). This self-deceptive affective mechanism is often reinforced at the collective level, leading to a sort of “spiralling” (Szanto 2017) that eventually strengthens the formation of isolated affective enclaves. To be sure, the collaborative transformation of negatively valenced self-regarding emotions into positive ones is not restricted to cases of false solidarity, as for instance the Gay Pride movements show. To avoid any misunderstanding, none of the above agonistic orientations are meant to establish any necessary connection between ingroup solidarity and outgroup hostility (consider, for instance, differences between patriotic and nationalistic forms of allegiances; cf. Li and Brewer 2004). Rather, what this taxonomy aims to show is that different forms of agonism are generally at work on the ontologically foundational baseline of political emotions.
5. Conclusion At all its levels, the political intersects with power. We have suggested that the affective drive behind the political, however, is not so much concrete political power-dynamics themselves as contested commonality. Such contested commonality entails dialectics of antagonism, allegiance and relations of power, long before they manifest themselves in concrete institutional power-struggles. This perspective should also allow for a theory of political emotions that cuts across the reductive dichotomy between the Arendtian associative and the Schmittian dissociative traditions of conceptualizing the political. As an alternative, we have argued that what makes emotions political is their shared or jointly felt evaluative outlook. This involves an acknowledgment of the import of the focus of the emotions for the political community and claims to their public recognition. 489
Thomas Szanto and Jan Slaby
Moreover, this shared evaluative outlook variously modulates individuals’ emotional experiences. Ultimately, emotions partly constitute that politics matters, disclose what matters—and that it matters to ‘me’, to ‘us’, and to ‘them’ often differently and conflictingly. In this sense, then, political affectivity, in general, and antagonistic political emotions in particular, go directly to the onto-political heart of ‘real politics’.
Acknowledgments Thomas Szanto’s work on this paper was supported by the Academy of Finland research project MEPA: “Marginalization and Experience: Phenomenological Analyses of Normality and Abnormality” (PI: Sara Heinämaa), as well as Szanto’s research project “Antagonistic Political Emotions” (P 32392-G), from The Austrian Science Fund (FWF). Jan Slaby’s contribution was conducted within the subproject B05 of the Collaborative Research Center “Affective Societies”, funded by the German Research Foundation (DFG). We are very grateful for Tamar Blickstein’s, Lucy Osler’s, Gerhard Thonhauser’s and Ruth Rebecca Tietjen’s insightful comments on an earlier draft.
Notes 1 See critically of this tradition Okin (1989), Walzer (2004), Hall (2005); Kingston (2011), and most recently Ginsberg and Labate (2019). 2 For an analysis of ‘political affect’ in a perspective indebted to Spinoza, Deleuze and Foucault, see Slaby and Bens (2019), which is effectively a sister article to the present one. Another recent alternative that is in many respects congenial to our account is Bens et al. (2019). 3 Emotions in the sense employed here encompass both episodic (e.g., occurrent fear) and dispositional affective states, and in particular sentiments (e.g., hatred). We refrain here from discussions of the political moods, emotional climates or atmospheres; but as should become clear, they too can be integrated into our framework. 4 On Arendt’s otherwise critical and indeed deflationary account of the role of emotions for the political, esp. in Arendt (1961), see Chapter 15 in this volume. 5 For similar requirements for collective emotions, see Szanto (2015, 201) and León et al. (2019). Notice that in Section 3.2, we sketch an account that can accommodate politically focused emotions that need not fulfill all these robust—and arguably demanding—requirements. 6 This double-aspect intentionality account for shared emotions was first suggested by phenomenologists such as Scheler (1912) and Stein (1922); cf. Szanto (2018). 7 Closest to the mark is the conceptualization of “public passions” by Kingston. Kingston convincingly argues that what makes an emotion public and hence distinguishes it as a political emotion, are three features: “its quality as shared, its focus or object of concern acknowledged as something that has impact on the life of everyone in the political community, and the importance attached to that concern” (Kingston 2011, 46). She markedly distinguishes this account from construals of political emotions, according to which “emotions relevant to polities are a collection of essentially idiosyncratic responses to matters of public importance and may vary considerably within a given population” (ibid.) (a view she attributes to Hall (2005), Koziak (2010) and Sokolon (2003)). Cf. also Berezin’s (2002) notion of political “communities of feeling”, that she borrows from Scheler (1913/1926), which, however, is actually a much looser notion than Scheler’s (and also than Kingston’s “public passions”). 8 In this respect we disagree with Protevi, who “define[s] collective political emotion as collective emotion within a political context such that a political event of issue is the target, but not necessarily the focus, of the emotion. (…) Thus, a group of people could be angry about the inflation they expect to come from a particular government policy, but the focus of those fears might be individual retirement plans of the angry people” (Protevi 2014, 327). 9 Note that Ressentiment in Scheler’s (and Nietzsche’s) technical sense is altogether different from resentment; see more on both below. See also the respective sections on Ressentiment in Chapters 4, 6 and 38 in this volume.
490
Political emotions
References Agamben, Giorgio (1993). The Coming Community. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Åhäll, Linda, and Gregory, Thomas (Eds.). (2015). Emotions, Politics, and War. London, New York: Routledge. Ahmed, Sara (2014[2004]). The Cultural Politics of Emotion. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Arendt, Hannah (1973[1951]). The Origins of Totalitarianism. San Diego: Harcourt Brace. ——— (1958). The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ——— (1990[1961]). On Revolution. London: Penguin. ——— (1963). Between Past and Future: Six Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Viking. Bargetz, Brigitte (2015). The Distribution of Emotions: Affective Politics of Emancipation. Hypatia 30(3), 580–596. Barsade, Sigal G., and Knight, Andrew P. (2015). Group Affect. Annual Review of Organizational Psychology and Organizational Behavior 2(1), 21–46. Brady, Michael S. (2013). Emotional Insight. The Epistemic Role of Emotional Experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brudholm, Thomas (2008). Resentment’s Virtue: Jean Améry and the Refusal to Forgive. Philadelphia: Temple University Press 2008. Brudholm, Thomas, and Lang, Johannes (Eds.) (2018). Emotions and Mass Atrocity: Philosophical and Theoretical Explorations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Clarke, Simon, Hoggett, Paul, and Simon, Thompson (Eds.). (2006). Emotion, Politics and Society. Basingstoke: Palgrave. Cossarini, Paolo, and Fernando Vallespín (Eds.) (2019). Populism and Passions: Democratic Legitimacy after Austerity. London, New York: Routledge. Crociani-Windland, and Lita, Hoggett, Paul (2012). Politics and Affect. Subjectivity 5(2), 161–179. D’Arms, J., and Jacobson, D. (2000). The Moralistic Fallacy: On the “Appropriateness” of Emotions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 51(1), 65–90. De Sousa, Ronald (1987). The Rationality of Emotions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bens, Jonas et al. (2019). The Politics of Affective Societies: An Interdisciplinary Essay. Bielefeld: transcript. Berezin, Mabel (2002). Secure States: Towards a Political Sociology of Emotion. The Sociological Review 50(2/suppl.), 33–52. Butler, Judith (2009). Frames of War. When Is Life Grievable. London: Verso. Demertzis, Nicolas (Ed.). (2013). Emotions in Politics: The Affect Dimension in Political Tension. Basingstoke: Macmillan. Ehrenreich, Barbara (2007). Dancing in the Streets. A History of Collective Joy. London: Granta. Flam, Helena, and King, Debra (Eds.) (2005). Emotions and Social Movements. London, New York: Routledge. Gilbert, Margaret (2002). Collective Guilt and Collective Guilt Feelings. The Journal of Ethics 6(2), 115–143. ——— (2014). How We Feel: Understanding Everyday Collective Emotion Ascription. In: C. v. Scheve, and M. Salmela (Eds.). Collective Emotions. Perspectives from Psychology, Philosophy and Sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 17–31. Ginsberg, Paul, and Labate, Sergio (2019[2016]). Passions and Politics. Transl. by D. Broder. Cambridge: Polity.
491
Thomas Szanto and Jan Slaby Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions. A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Goodwin, Jeff, Jasper, James M., and Polletta, Francesca (Eds.). (2001). Passionate Politics: Emotions and Social Movements. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Guerrero Sánchez, Héctor A. (2016). Feeling Together and Caring with One Another: A Contribution to the Debate on Collective Affective Intentionality. Cham: Springer. Hall, Cheryl (2005). The Trouble with Passion: Political Theory beyond the Reign of Reason. London, New York: Routledge. Halperin, Eran (2016). Emotions in Conflict. Inhibitors and Facilitators of Peace Making. London, New York: Routledge. Hatfield, Elaine, Bensmana, Lisamarie, Thorntona, Paul D., and Rapson, Richard L. (2014). New Perspectives on Emotional Contagion: A Review of Classic and Recent Research on Facial Mimicry and Contagion. Interpersona 8(2), 159–179. Helm, Bennett W. (2001). Emotional Reason: Deliberation, Motivation, and the Nature of Value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2017). Communities of Respect. Grounding Responsibility, Authority, and Dignity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hirschman, Alberto O. (1977). The Passions and the Interests. Political Arguments for Capitalism before its Triumph. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Hochschild, Arlie R. (1983). The Managed Heart. Commercialization of Human Feeling. Berkley: University of California Press. ——— (2016). Strangers in their Own Land. Anger and Mourning on the American Right. New York: The Free Press. Hoggett, Paul, and Thompson, Simon (Eds.) (2012). Politics and the Emotions: The Affective Turn in Contemporary Political Studies. New York, London: Continuum. Holmes, Stephen (1995). Passions and Constraint: On the Theory of Liberal Democracy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hutchison, Emma, and Bleiker, Roland (2008). Emotional Reconciliation: Reconstituting Identity and Community after Trauma. European Journal of Social Theory 11(3), 385–403. Illouz, Eva (2007). Cold Intimacies. The Making of Emotional Capitalism. Cambridge: Polity. James, Susan (2003). Passion and Politics. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 52, 221–234. Jasper, James M. (2018). The Emotions of Protest. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kingston, Rebecca (2011). Public Passion: Rethinking the Grounds for Political Justice. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s Press. Kingston, Rebecca, and Ferry, Leonard (Eds.) (2008). Bringing the Passions Back in: The Emotions in Political Philosophy. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press. Kolnai, Aurel (2007[1935]). Ekel, Hochmut, Haß: Zur Phänomenologie feindlicher Gefühle. Berlin: Suhrkamp. ——— (1998). The Standard Modes of Aversion: Fear, Disgust and Hatred. Mind 107(427), 581–595. Koziak, Barbara (2010). Retrieving Political Emotion: Thumos, Aristotle, and Gender. Philadelphia: Penn State Press. Laclau, Ernesto, and Mouffe, Chantal (1985). Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics. London: Verso. Lacoue-Labarthe, Philippe, and Nancy, Jean-Luc (1997). Retreating the Political. London, New York: Routledge. León, Felipe, Szanto, Thomas, and Zahavi, Dan (2019): Emotional Sharing and the Extended Mind. Synthese 196(12), 4847–4867. Li, Qiong, and Brewer, Marilynn B. (2004). What Does It Mean to Be an American? Patriotism, Nationalism, and American Identity after 9/11. Political Psychology 25(5), 727–739. Locke, Jill (2016). Democracy and the Death of Shame: Political Equality and Social Disturbance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lordon, Frédéric (2016). Les affects de la politique. Paris: Seuil. MacLachlan, Alice (2010). Unreasonable Resentments. Journal of Social Philosophy 41(4), 422–441. Marcus, George E. (2002). The Sentimental Citizen: Emotion in Democratic Politics. University Park: Penn State Press. Marchart, Odo (2007). Post-Foundational Political Thought: Political Difference in Nancy, Lefort, Badiou and Laclau. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Massumi, Brian (2015). Politics of Affect. Cambridge: Polity.
492
Political emotions Michael, John (2011). Shared Emotions and Joint Action. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2(2), 355–373. Mihai, Mihaela (2014). Theorizing Agonistic Emotions. Parallax 20(2), 31–48. ——— (2016). Negative Emotions and Transitional Justice. New York: Columbia University Press. Miller, Patrick R. (2011). The Emotional Citizen: Emotion as a Function of Political Sophistication. Political Psychology 32(4), 575–600. Mishra, Pankaj (2017). The Age of Anger. A History of the Present. London: Penguin. Mohrmann, Judith (2015). Affekt und Revolution: Politisches Handeln nach Arendt und Kant. Frankfurt: Campus. Mouffe, Chantal (2013). Agonistics: Thinking the World Politically. London: Verso. Nancy, Jean-Luc (1991). The Inoperative Community. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Neuman, W. Russell, Marcus, George E., Crigler, Ann N., and Mackuen, Michael (Eds.) (2007). The Affect Effect: Dynamics of Emotion in Political Thinking and Behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Nietzsche, Friedrich (1997[1887]). On the Genealogy of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nussbaum, Martha (2013). Political Emotions. Why Love Matters for Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ——— (2016). Anger and Forgiveness: Resentment, Generosity, and Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Okin, Susan M. (1989). Reason and Feeling in Thinking about Justice. Ethics 99(2), 229–249. Protevi, John (2009). Political Affect: Connecting the Social and the Somatic. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. ——— (2014). Political Emotion. In: C. v. Scheve, and M. Salmela (Eds.). Collective Emotions. Perspectives from Psychology, Philosophy and Sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 326–340. Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Redlawsk, David P. (Ed.) (2006). Feeling Politics: Emotion in Political Information Processing. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. Rimé, Bernard (2007). The Social Sharing of Emotion as an Interface between Individual and Collective Processes in the Construction of Emotional Climates. Journal of Social Issues 63(2), 307–322. Romano, Benedetta (2018). The Epistemic Value of Emotions in Politics. Philosophia 46(3), 589–608. Saar, Martin (2013). Die Immanenz der Macht: Politische Theorie nach Spinoza. Berlin: Suhrkamp. Salmela, Mikko (2014). The Rational Appropriateness of Collective Emotions. In: G. Sullivan (Ed.). Emotions of Collective Pride and Group Identity: New Directions in Theory and Practice. London, New York: Routledge, 21–33. Salmela, Mikko, and Nagatsu, Michiru (2016). Collective Emotions and Joint Action. Journal of Social Ontology 2(1), 33–57. Salmela, Mikko, and Scheve, Christian v. (2017). Emotional Roots of Right-Wing Political Populism. Social Science Information 56(4), 567–595. Salmela, Mikko, and Scheve, Christian v. (2018). Emotional Dynamics of Right- and Left-Wing Political Populism. Humanity and Society 42(4), 434–454. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1976[1944]). Anti-Semite and Jew. An Exploration of the Etiology of Hatred. Transl. by G. J. Becker. New York: Schocken. Scheler, Max (1994[1912]). Ressentiment. Transl. by W. W. Holdheim. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. [Orig.: Ressentiment im Auf bau der Moralen. In: Max Scheler: Vom Umsturz der Werte: Abhandlungen und Aufsätze. Gesammelte Werke 3. Bonn: Bouvier 1955.] Scheler, M. (1954[1913/1926]). The Nature of Sympathy. Transl. by P. Heath. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. [Orig.: Wesen und Formen der Sympathie. Gesammelte Werke, Vol. 7., Bonn: Bouvier 2005.] Schmitt, Carl (2007[1932]). The Concept of the Political. Transl. by G. Schwab, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Orig.: Der Begriff des Politischen. Berlin: Duncker and Humblot 2015.] Schmid, Hans Bernhard (2009). Plural Action: Essays in Philosophy and Social Science. Dordrecht: Springer. Schreiber, Darren (2007). Political Cognition as Social Cognition: Are we All Political Sophisticates? In: W. R. Neuman, G. E. Marcus, A. N. Crigler, and M. Mackuen (Eds.). The Affect Effect: Dynamics of Emotion in Political Thinking and Behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 48–70. Slaby, Jan (2008). Affective Intentionality and the Feeling Body. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7(4), 429–444.
493
Thomas Szanto and Jan Slaby ——— (2017). Affekt und Politik: Neue Dringlichkeiten in einem alten Problemfeld. Philosophische Rundschau 64(2), 134–162. Slaby, Jan, and Bens, Jonas (2019). Political Affect. In: J. Slaby, and C. v. Scheve (Eds.). Affective Societies: Key Concepts. London, New York: Routledge, 340–351. Slaby, Jan, and Mühlhoff, Rainer (2019). Affect. In: J. Slaby, and C. v. Scheve (Eds.). Affective Societies: Key Concepts. London, New York: Routledge, 27–41. Smith, Eliot R., Seger, Charles R., and Mackie, Diane M. (2007). Can Emotions be Truly Goup Level? Evidence Regarding Four Conceptual Criteria. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 93(3), 431–446. Sokolon, Marlene K. (2003). Political Emotions: Aristotle and the Symphony of Reason and Emotion. DeKalb, Ill.: Northern Illinois University Press. Solomon, Robert C. (1995). A Passion for Justice: Emotions and the Origins of the Social Contract. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield. Stein, Edith (2000[1922]). Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities. Transl. by M. C. Baseheart, and M. Sawicki. Washington D.C.: ICS Publications. [Orig.: Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie und der Geisteswissenschaften. Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe, Vol. 6. Freiburg, Basel, Wien: Herder 2010.] Stockdale, Katie (2013). Collective Resentment. Social Theory and Practice 39(3), 501–521. Strawson, Peter F. (1962). Freedom and Resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy 48, 187–211. Szanto, Thomas (2015). Collective Emotions, Normativity and Empathy: A Steinian Account. Human Studies 38(4), 503–527. ——— (2017). Collaborative Irrationality, Akrasia and Groupthink: Social Disruptions of Emotion Regulation. Frontiers in Psychology 7(2002), 1–17. ——— (2018). The Phenomenology of Shared Emotions: Reassessing Gerda Walther. In: S. Luft, and R. Hagengruber (Eds.). Women Phenomenologists on Social Ontology. We-Experiences, Communal Life, and Joint Action. Dordrecht: Springer, 85–104. ——— (forthcoming). In Hate We Trust: On the Habitualization and Collectivization of Hatred. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-018-9604-9. Tarnopolsky, Christina H. (2010). Prudes, Perverts, and Tyrants: Plato’s Gorgias and the Politics of Shame. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Taylor, Charles (2004). Social Imaginaries. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Thonhauser, Gerhard (2018). Shared Emotions: A Steinian Proposal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17(5), 997–1015. Thrift, Nigel (2008). Non-Representational Theory: Space, Politics, Affect. London, New York: Routledge. Van Stekelenburg, Jacquelien, and Klandermans, Bert (2013). The Social Psychology of Protest. Current Sociology 61(5–6), 886–905. Voigtländer, Else (1920). Zur Psychologie der politischen Stellungnahme. Eine massenpsychologische Studie. Deutsche Psychologie 3(3), 184–206. von Scheve, Christian, and Ismer, Sven (2013). Towards a Theory of Collective Emotions. Emotion Review 5(4), 406–413. Walzer, Michael (2004). Politics and Passion: Toward a More Egalitarian Liberalism. New Haven, London: Yale University Press.
494
PART 5
Borderline cases of emotions
.
(
Taylor & Francis Taylor & Francis Group
http://taylorandfrancis.com
42 FORGIVENESS AND REVENGE Fabian Bernhardt
1. Introduction: the place of forgiveness and revenge in everyday life and in philosophy Human agency goes hand in hand with fallibility. The capability to act inevitably involves the capability for wrongdoing. People hurt each other—sometimes intentionally, often without bad faith—and treat each other in unjust ways. The intersection between agency and vulnerability—the point where one subject gets negatively affected by the unjust action of another subject—thus can be conceived of as the existential and affective ground from which both the desire for revenge and the longing for forgiveness emerge. “Who among us”, Charles Griswold asks, “has not longed to be forgiven? Nearly everyone has suffered the bitter injustice of wrongdoing. Who has not struggled to forgive? Revenge impulsively surges in response to wrong and becomes perversely delicious to those possessed by it” (2007, XIII). Forgiveness and revenge are both responses to the experience of getting wronged. As such, they play a vital role in the lives of individuals and of communities. In everyday language, we use and understand the terms forgiveness and revenge without problems. In the context of a phenomenology of emotions, it might be noteworthy that the very words revenge and forgiveness already bear an affective quality. When we hear them, we tend to think of certain episodes and instances of our lives which go along with moral sentiments like anger, indignation, resentment and grief. That forgiveness and revenge are somehow connected to affective phenomena seems obvious. However, the question which particular emotions are involved in them and how these emotions relate to each other is subject of ongoing philosophical debates (for an overview, cf. Hughes and Warmke 2017). As soon as one starts to examine revenge and forgiveness philosophically, both notions turn out to be astonishingly complex and difficult to understand. The specific reasons for this difficulty in both cases are quite different though. The difficulty in understanding forgiveness has to do with the fact that in the last decades the notion of forgiveness has disseminated into many different spheres—international politics, penal law, even economy—such that it has become increasingly difficult to identify its semantic core and conceptual limits. “In all the scenes of repentance, confession, forgiveness or apology which have multiplied on the geopolitical scene since the last war, and in an accelerated fashion within in the last few years”, Jacques Derrida stated already in 1997, “one sees not 497
Fabian Bernhardt
only individuals, but also entire communities, professional corporations, the representatives of ecclesiastical hierarchies, sovereigns, and heads of state ask for ‘forgiveness’” (2001, 28). In public discourse, the language of forgiveness has become ubiquitous. It has not only entered the political and legal sphere but has also been assimilated into the therapeutic domain, where forgiveness, or self-forgiveness, is broadly construed as a technique of individually healing oneself from the burdens of a painful past. This development—which can be characterized as a gesture of politicalizing forgiveness on the one hand and of psychologizing it on the other hand—tends to blur the lines between forgiveness and cognate concepts such as apology, regret, excuse, pardon, reconciliation, closing and healing (cf. Derrida 1997, 27–32; Griswold 2007, XVII–XX; Bandes 2009; Hughes and Warmke 2017). Yet, even when being differentiated from these cognate phenomena, conceptualizing forgiveness remains a challenging philosophical task. The difficulty in understanding revenge is quite different in nature. Contrarily to forgiveness, the problem is not that the conceptual limits of revenge have become too broad and blurry, but rather too narrow. The modern standard view of revenge can be described as follows: “Vengeance is thought to be especially dangerous and socially disruptive, typically violent, utterly unreasonable, and by its very nature opposed to law and its constraints” (Solomon 1999, 129). This prevalent understanding is also shared by many philosophers. However, it is normatively distorted and flawed by a number of Eurocentric misconceptions (cf. Bernhardt 2017, 1–34). It is true that revenge can occur in the form as described—violent, unreasonable and socially disruptive—but it is wrong to believe that it necessarily does so. In fact, revenge occurs in many different forms. In modern everyday life, for example, there are numerous instances where people get even in ways which are not violent at all (for example, if person X intentionally refuses to invite person Y to a party because some time ago Y has not invited her). According to Robert Solomon—one of the few philosophers who aim to develop a more differentiated approach to revenge—we are all “living in a tit-for-tat-world. We are all moral accountants, even if the bookkeeping varies considerably” (1999, 126). Another problem with the modern standard view of revenge is that it does not consider appropriately that the functioning and conceptualization of revenge differs drastically between different cultures and societies. The place and functioning of revenge in societies without a central political power (which are usually referred to as “segmentary” or “acephalous” societies in social and cultural anthropology; cf. Amborn 2016) can hardly be compared to its place in societies with a central political power (like modern states or ancient Greek poleis) (cf. Verdier 1980–1984; Hénaff 2002, 202–241; Paul 2005; Schlee and Turner 2008a, 2008b). Most philosophical approaches tend to ignore this fact (cf., e.g., Govier 2002). Instead, the one-sided notion of revenge as “typically violent, utterly unreasonable, and by its very nature opposed to law” is taken to be universally valid and projected onto those societies which, from the viewpoint of Western imagination, figure as cultural counterpart and epitomized “other” to modern civilization. In order to develop a more appropriate (and less Eurocentric) understanding of revenge, philosophers are therefore better off when applying an interdisciplinary framework that takes into account the findings of cultural and social anthropologists, historians and other researchers who are concerned with so-called “traditional” societies (cf. Hénaff 2002; Bernhardt 2017). In the following, I will discuss the issues that seem, against the just-sketched background, particularly pertinent when it comes to theorizing forgiveness and revenge. I will start with forgiveness (Section 2) and then focus on revenge (Section 3); in the last section, I will outline in which sense forgiveness and revenge can be considered as borderline cases of emotion (Section 4). 498
Forgiveness and revenge
2. Theorizing forgiveness What is it that we call forgiveness? To start with, it seems a lot easier to say what forgiveness is not than to determine what it is. As already mentioned, forgiveness is part of a whole cluster of concepts including pardon, excuse, mercy, apology and reconciliation. In some respects, the meaning of forgiveness and these other concepts overlap, in other respects, there are significant differences. However, among most researchers there is general agreement that forgiveness should be differentiated from ‘pardoning’ (which is a legal term), ‘condoning’ (which implies a justification of the offense), ‘excusing’ (which implies that the offender had a good reason for committing the offense), ‘forgetting’ (which implies that the memory of the offense has simply decayed or slipped out of conscious awareness), and ‘denying’ (which implies simply an unwillingness to perceive the harmful injuries that one has incurred). Most also seem to agree that forgiveness is distinct form ‘reconciliation’ (which implies the restoration of a relationship). (McCullough 2001, 8) Charles Griswold also cautions not to confound forgiveness with the notion of simply “finding a therapeutic way to ‘deal with’ injury, pain, or anger”; if it were nothing more than that, Griswold argues, “then hypnosis or amnesia or taking a pill might [also] count as forgiveness” (2007, XIV). What can be positively said about forgiveness is that it requires fault; one can only forgive where there has been an infraction of shared moral norms (cf. Ricœur 2000, 459). This basic presupposition entails another: There must be an agent who can be held accountable for the infraction that occurred. Paul Ricœur has highlighted that fault is necessarily based on imputability. He explains this relation as follows: There can (…) be forgiveness only where we can accuse someone of something, presume him to be or declare him guilty. And one can indict only those acts that are imputable to an agent who holds himself to be their genuine author. In other words, imputability is that capacity, that aptitude, by virtue of which actions can be held to someone’s account. (Ricœur 2000, 460) In its most basic sense, the term forgiveness thus refers to a relationship between two subjects, one of whom has wronged the other. Most philosophers take this interpersonal situation as a paradigm scenario (cf. Arendt 1958, 241; Derrida 1997, 42; Griswold 2007, 47) from which all other possible uses of the term forgiveness—for example political forgiveness—are derived of. Even if pinned down to this basic meaning, the notion of forgiveness still raises a number of puzzling questions since it seems to contest our established notions of responsibility and fault, the nature of human agency and the irreversibility of time (cf. Crépon and Rauen 2012). Within the last few decades, there has been a significant rise of philosophical interest in the questions surrounding the notion of forgiveness, especially in the United States.1 Accordingly, philosophical attempts to theorize forgiveness by now form a manifold and diverse landscape. By and large, the different theories of forgiveness can be separated into two groups, each of them starting from different premises and focusing on different questions. I will refer to them as (I.) the conditional approach and (II.) the unconditional approach to forgiveness. 499
Fabian Bernhardt
(I.) The conditional approach is based on the premise that forgiveness is in principle a human capability (as we shall see, this claim is not as self-evident as it might initially seem). There is nothing enigmatic or metaphysical about forgiveness; the power to forgive lies fully within the sphere of human agency. Forgiveness is here conceived of as a form of action which, as such, is governed by certain norms. Accordingly, theorists of this group focus on the question which conditions must be met by the wrongdoer and by the wronged person in order for the act of forgiveness to be morally praiseworthy. One of the most elaborated versions of the conditional approach has been developed by Charles Griswold (2007). Like Hannah Arendt, Griswold asserts that the proper target of forgiveness is the person, not the deed (cf. Arendt 1958, 241–243; Griswold 2007, 47–48). As a starting point, Griswold also takes the paradigm scenario laid out above—forgiveness as an interpersonal relation—but he adds an important detail: The two individuals must be “capable of communicating with each other” (2007, XVI). In his view, forgiveness should be seen not so much as a unilateral act (relying solely on the good will of the wronged person) but, rather, as a dyadic process in which the steps both individuals take reciprocally depend on each other. From this it follows that “each party holds the other in its power (…): the offender depends on the victim in order to be forgiven, and the victim depends on the offender in order to forgive” (Griswold 2007, 49). This interdependence is not just logical but practical: There are certain conditions both individuals must meet, certain things they must do and feel, in order to assure that the act of forgiveness does not collapse into mere condonation, forgetting, excusing or some sort of rationalization. What precisely are these conditions? Let’s begin with the conditions that must be met by the wrongdoer. Griswold identifies six of them (cf. 2007, 49–53). (1) The offender must take over accountability and thus acknowledge that she indeed was the author of the deeds in question. (2) The wrongdoer must credibly repudiate these deeds and disavow that she would do this kind of wrong again. (3) The wrongdoer must feel regret about the specific injury that she has caused and she must communicate this feeling to the particular person she injured. (4) Furthermore, she must credibly commit to changing her ways and to becoming a person who does not inflict injury to others. (5) This commitment would be incomplete without a true understanding of the suffering that was caused by the deeds in question. According to Griswold, the “offender is thus required to exercise ‘sympathy’ in the sense of putting herself in the position of the person she injured, and understanding what being in that situation meant for the injured person” (2007, 51). (6) The last condition is a kind of synthesis of the precedent. Griswold asserts that the offender is required to “offer some sort of narrative accounting for how she came to do wrong, how that wrongdoing does not express the totality of her person, and how she is becoming worthy of approbation” (2007, 51). Corresponding to the required transformation of the wrongdoer, there are also certain conditions the wronged person must meet if forgiveness is to take place. Again, Griswold lists six of them (2007, 53–59). In accordance with the Butlerian framework of his approach (cf. Butler 1896), Griswold asserts that forgiveness (1) necessarily requires the wronged person to forswear revenge.2 This entails (2) a moderation of resentment—which Griswold understands as a “reactive as well as retributive passion that instinctively seeks to exact a due measure of punishment” (2007, 26)—and (3) the commitment to let resentment go altogether. Whereas the first three conditions are situated on the affective level, the fourth condition is merely cognitive. (4) It involves a process of reframing through which the victim comes to see the offender in a new light—a light, which enables the wronged individual in particular to recognise that the wrongdoer as a whole person cannot be reduced to the self she was when committing the wrong (cf. also Ricœur who identifies the core of forgiveness in the formula 500
Forgiveness and revenge
“you are better than your actions” (2000, 493)). The reframing entails that (5) the victim comes to see herself in a new light as well. This change of perspective involves “dropping any presumption of decisive moral superiority, and recognizing instead the shared humanity of both parties” (Griswold 2007, 58) (6). The last condition is that there must be an explicit statement of forgiveness that is directly addressed to the wrongdoer. If the wrongdoer explicitly asked for forgiveness, Griswold argues, then the positive response should be explicit, too. In other words, the act of forgiving should take the form of a “communicative act that is and is taken to be an expression of forgiveness” (2007, 58). It is important to note that this set of conditions does not only involve certain steps on the level of action, but also, and even more importantly, on the level of emotions (the plea for forgiveness, for example, would become worthless if it was not supported and motivated by a true change of heart, the feeling of regret and so on). Both the offender and the victim are required to change the way they feel. This, however, gives rise to a basic problem. We cannot look inside another person’s heart. Therefore, we can never know for sure—with absolute certainty—if the two individuals have really undergone the required affective transformation. How, for example, do we verify if the wrongdoer actually feels regret or if she just pretends to do so in order to appear in a more favourable light? Due to this epistemic problem, the conditional approach to forgiveness is inevitably prone to the dangers of untrustworthiness and instrumentalisation. And, in fact, when watching the news today, one easily gets the impression that many of those scenes of self-accusation, repentance and asking for forgiveness—publicly performed by accused war criminals, politicians, managers, the representatives of churches and so on—resemble the staging of a hollow ritual, being enacted in the service of particular interests. (II.) In a way, the unconditional approach to forgiveness can be understood as a response to this basic problem. The most radical and uncompromising version of the unconditional approach was developed by Jacques Derrida (1997). Derrida directly contests the idea that forgiveness should come with certain conditions attached. According to Derrida, this idea is based on what he calls a “logic of the exchange” (1997, 34). If forgiveness was only granted on the condition that the wrongdoer asked for it, “in the course of a scene of repentance attesting at once to the consciousness of the fault, the transformation of the guilty, and the (…) obligation to do everything to avoid the return of evil”, then it would sink down to a kind of “economic transaction” (ibid.). Instead, Derrida argues for what he calls “pure” forgiveness, a forgiveness which is unconditional, and, moreover, devoid of any purpose. “I shall risk this proposition”, he states, that each time forgiveness is at the service of a finality, be it noble and spiritual (atonement or redemption, reconciliation, salvation), each time that it aims to re-establish a normality (social, national, political, psychological) by a work of mourning, by some therapy or ecology of memory, then the ‘forgiveness’ is not pure—nor is its concept. Forgiveness is not, it should not be, normal, normative, normalising. It should remain exceptional and extraordinary, in the face of the impossible: as if it interrupted the ordinary course of historical temporality. (Derrida 1997, 31–32) What are Derrida’s arguments to support this extreme claim? With his notion of pure forgiveness, Derrida explicitly calls two assumptions into question: The first is that forgiveness is in principle a “human possibility” and, thus, a human capacity; the second assumption is that the capacity to forgive is the “correlate to the possibility of punishment” (1997, 37). 501
Fabian Bernhardt
Both assumptions figure prominently in Arendt’s theory of forgiveness. In The Human Condition, Arendt states: The alternative to forgiveness (…) is punishment (…). It is (…) a structural element in the realm of human affairs, that men are unable to forgive what they cannot punish and that they are unable to punish what has turned out to be unforgivable. This is the true hallmark of those offenses which, since Kant, we call ‘radical evil’ (…). (Arendt 1958, 241) According to Arendt (and many others), the unforgivable is beyond forgiveness. If a crime is so enormous that it transcends the possibility of due punishment, then it also exceeds the power to forgive. In the face of the unforgivable, there is no place for forgiveness. Derrida does not only refuse this view, he turns it completely upside-down. According to him, the unforgivable is not where forgiveness ends, but the very source where the idea of forgiveness emerges from. “Is the unforgivable”, he asks, not, in truth, the only thing to forgive? The only thing that calls for forgiveness? If one is only prepared to forgive what appears forgivable, (…) then the very idea of forgiveness would disappear. If there is something to forgive, it would be what in religious language is called mortal sin, the worst, the unforgivable crime or harm. From which comes the aporia (…): forgiveness only forgives the unforgivable. (…) That is to say that forgiveness must announce itself as impossibility itself. It can only be possible in doing the impossible. (Derrida 1997, 32–33) In Derrida’s view, only the hyperbolic notion of “pure” forgiveness is able to ascend to the unforgivable (cf. 1997, 39). However, he makes no secret of the fact that his demand of purity makes it virtually impossible for forgiveness to actually take place in real life; it remains “a madness of the impossible” (ibid.). So, what’s the use of setting the bar so high and articulating an ideal which is impossible to meet? It is important to note that the idea of unconditional forgiveness is not an invention of Derrida, but something he derives from the “Abrahamitic” tradition (a label Derrida uses in order to refer to Judaism, Christianity and Islam altogether). However, at the heart of this religious heir, we find not only the idea of unconditional forgiveness but also its opposite. Thus, already in the historical backdrop, there is a characteristic tension between two poles: On the one side, there is the gracious idea of unconditional pure forgiveness—“granted to the guilty as guilty (…) even to those who do not repent”—and, on the other side, there is the idea of a conditional forgiveness which is “proportionate to the recognition of the fault, to repentance, to the transformation of the sinner who then explicitly asks forgiveness” (Derrida 1997, 34–35). One would misunderstand Derrida’s position, if one took it only as a radical plea for the first pole. Derrida’s intention is not to dismiss the notion of conditional forgiveness altogether; his claim is, rather, that whenever forgiveness is made a subject of discussion, whenever the question of forgiveness is at stake, either in a practical context or theoretically, one should always remain the reference to the pole, which binds forgiveness to the idea of unconditional purity. Without the reference to this pole, the whole idea of forgiveness would become meaningless. Although the two poles are completely heterogeneous, they cannot be separated from each other. Derrida explains this as follows: Sometimes, forgiveness (…) must be a gracious gift, without exchange and without condition; sometimes it requires, as its minimal condition, the repentance and 502
Forgiveness and revenge
transformation of the sinner. (…) These two poles, the unconditional and the conditional, are absolutely heterogeneous, and must remain irreducible to one another. They are nonetheless indissociable: if one wants (…) forgiveness to become effective, concrete, historic; if one wants it to arrive, to happen by changing things, it is necessary that this purity engage [sic] itself in a series of conditions of all kinds (…). It is between these two poles, irreconcilable but indissociable, that decisions and responsibilities are to be taken. (Derrida 1997, 44–45) This claim also holds true for the different philosophical attempts to theorize forgiveness. Concerning their premises and basic assumptions, the conditional approach and the unconditional approach are extremely different and in some respects even irreconcilable. However, when it comes to capturing the idea of forgiveness in its full extent, in all its depth and practical implications, the two approaches must complement each other.
3. Theorizing revenge In modern societies, revenge has a bad image. Understood as an outburst of uncontrolled individual passions, blind, dysfunctional and excessively violent, revenge seems to contradict everything modernity stands for—particularly its establishment of legal procedures based on the ideas of impartiality and dispassionate reason (cf. Maroney 2011). Philosophy played a great part in shaping this image (cf. Bernhardt 2017, 11–22). In their endeavour to provide the normative ground for the rule of state and its monopoly on the use of retributive violence, legal and political philosophers from the 18th and 19th century drew a sharp line between (private) revenge and (public) punishment (cf. Foucault 1975; Lehmann 2012). This operation was essentially driven by normative interests. The genuine motivation of these thinkers was primarily not to better understand revenge but to provide reasons for its condemnation. The legitimization of the state and the delegitimization of revenge were part of the same philosophical project (cf. Menke 2012; Bernhardt 2017). In older traditions (for example the biblical and the ancient Greek), revenge and justice were not conceived of as being necessarily opposed to one another (cf. Gehrke 1987; Burkert 1998; Beinhauer-Köhler et al. 2004). However, in modern legal and political philosophy, it is taken for granted that they are mutually exclusive: “Justice is a legitimate concept in the modern code of civilized behavior. Vengeance is not ( Jacoby 1983, 1). Only recently did philosophers begin to call this prevalent view into question, claiming that “vengeance and its satisfaction will remain durable components of any realistic theory of human nature” (Solomon 1999, 124). Despite the extensive endeavor to exclude revenge from the realm of modern existence, the emotions and affects underlying the desire for revenge have not vanished—although they often remain on the level of private imagination and are not publicly shared (cf. Frijda 1994, 264; Bernhardt 2017, 274–282). Philosophy is therefore well advised to acknowledge that revenge inevitably remains “an integral aspect of our recognition and reaction to wrong and being wronged” (Solomon 1999, 126). Instead of regarding our legal system as being directly opposed to revenge, both should be conceived of as interdependent (cf. Jacoby 1983; Frijda 1994; Solomon 1994 and 1999). As Jacoby puts it: “Laws are designed not to weed out the impulse towards revenge but to contain it in a manner consistent with the maintenance of an orderly and humane society” (1983, 5) Solomon goes even further when he claims that “the often despised and dismissed emotion of vengeance (…) may, in fact, be (both historically and psychologically) the seed from which the entire plant of justice has grown” (1994, 304). 503
Fabian Bernhardt
Based on this view, it becomes possible to analyze revenge in a less unbiased way. The impulse toward revenge emerges from the experience of being wronged: we feel a desire to injure those who have injured us. The offended person becomes the offender, and vice versa. Again, we find the intersection between agency and vulnerability here, and again, there are the basic presuppositions of fault and accountability. Accordingly, the paradigm scenario of revenge seems to be the same as in the case of forgiveness: There are two individuals, one of whom has wronged the other. However, this paradigm scenario cannot be taken for universal. In societies without a central political authority, revenge is not a relation between two individuals, but between two groups. It is collective, not individual (cf. Hénaff 2002, 216; Paul 2005, 245). Social and cultural anthropologists have clearly shown that in these societies revenge is neither uncontrolled nor excessively violent: This may be the case within political societies where vengeance is no longer coded (since it is considered illegitimate in principle). (…) But the case is entirely different in societies without a central state, in which vengeance contrarily constitutes an extremely elaborate and controlled form of the regulation of violence. This is the important point: in traditional societies, far from being an outburst of pure violence, ceremonial vengeance is a way to rigorously restrict violence. It is indeed a sophisticated exercise of justice. (Hénaff 2002, 215; emphasis mine) In these societies, the ceremonial revenge—or “vindicatory system”, as Hénaff also calls it—follows the same rules and norms as the ceremonial gift-exchange. Both are governed by a rationale of reciprocity (cf. Hénaff 2002, 215; Paul 2005, 255; Schlee and Turner 2008a, 7–9): “In the same way as a countergift must reply to a gift, a counteroffense must reply to an offense” (Hénaff 2002, 218). The system of vindicatory justice does not aim at perpetuating the violence, but at putting an end to the conflict. There are complex procedures of compensation, which allow to make up for an incurred harm without using violence. Instead, the party of the wrongdoer makes amends by offering some form of symbolic compensation. All of this is subject of negotiations. The ceremonial revenge remains within the sphere of reciprocity, which, at the same time, is the sphere of partners in alliance and horizontal gift-exchange (cf. Hénaff 2002, 218). The popular belief according to which revenge in premodern societies is necessarily violent and socially dysfunctional—a belief both shared by common sense and a great part of modern philosophy—thus turns out to be errant and empirically inaccurate. The revenge of the alleged “savages” is everything but savage. In fact, revenge only takes this form under the condition of the establishment of a central political authority. In other words, uncontrolled revenge is not what modernity has left behind, but something it gave birth to by replacing the vindicatory system through a new model, a system administered by a central power that solely is bestowed with the right to judge and punish: It is this replacement of ceremonial vengeance by arbitrational justice that opens the possibility of private revenge. But then vengeance is no longer the application of justice. It becomes the pursuit of personal compensation. It no longer constitutes a complete and instituted procedure. It releases individual violence instead of expressing the action of the group vis-à-vis another group. (Hénaff 2002, 221)
504
Forgiveness and revenge
4. Forgiveness and revenge as borderline cases of emotion In fact, forgiveness and revenge can both be regarded as genuine borderline cases of emotion. Both phenomena are intricately entwined with emotions and other affective states, but neither revenge nor forgiveness are names for a particular or discrete emotion. There is not the one emotion of forgiveness (cf. Rinofner-Kreidl 2013, 216). The same holds true for revenge. In the history of philosophy, the desire for revenge has been frequently linked to (vengeful) anger and resentment, but we have to take into account here that the meanings of these terms—like of all emotion terms—are not stable. Language is historical. And emotions are historical, too. The way we feel is shaped by various conditions which change throughout time, depending on the cultural, social and political contexts. This particularly holds true when it comes to our emotional responses to the experience of being wronged. They are shaped and channelled differently in different societies. Closely connected to the historicity of emotions is the problem of how to translate emotion terms from one language to another. Aristotle’s orge, Homer’s menis, and Seneca’s ira—all notions used in the context of revenge (cf. Homer 1961; Aristotle 1991; Seneca 2013)—can be equally translated with ‘anger’, but it would be short-sighted to believe that their respective meaning therefore is synonymous. Anger is polymorphous; it involves different forms and shades. And it is by no means the only emotion that can give rise to revenge. Most languages provide not a single term, but a whole cluster of expressions to refer to the affective side of revenge. Besides anger, in English there is also “wrath, indignation, fury, ill temper, ill humour, bitterness, irritation, irascibility, resentment, exasperation, pouting, annoyance, and, of course, vengefulness” (Griswold 2013, 81–82). Solomon refers to vengeance as an emotion, but he frankly admits that he just does so in order to avoid “the intolerable awkwardness of always referring to ‘the complex of various emotions that gives shape to and motivates the desire for revenge and the demand for its satisfaction’” (1999, 124) In short: “The set of emotions that victims might possess in response to being wronged by another agent (…) form a large and diverse landscape” (Hughes and Warmke 2017). Now, what about the affective side of forgiveness? Interestingly, in continental philosophy, emotions hardly play a role when it comes to theorizing forgiveness. Arendt and Ricœur remind us of the relationship that the Christian tradition has established between forgiveness and love (agape) (cf. Arendt 1958, 242–243; Ricœur 2000, 467–468), but the respective notion of love is very different from our modern understanding and seems to refer rather to a general trait of character than to an actual emotion. In analytic philosophy, or the Anglophone tradition, the picture is quite different; the emotional make-up of forgiveness is frequently discussed here. This might be due to the fact that continental and analytic thinkers of forgiveness tend to start from quite different theoretical (and also historical) backgrounds. The accounts of Arendt (1958), Derrida (1997), Jankélévitch (1967, 1996), Levinas (1961) and Ricœur (2000), either directly or implicitly, all refer to the crimes that have been committed throughout the first half of the 20th century, namely the Holocaust. This is probably why the notion of the unforgivable figures more prominently in their accounts than in their US-counterparts. For most Anglophone philosophers, the seminal work of Joseph Butler (1896) serves as the philosophical point of departure. (Curiously, his theory of forgiveness is not mentioned at all by Arendt, Derrida and other philosophers from the continental tradition.) For Butler, forgiveness and resentment are intimately tied to one another. This is why questions concerning the emotional nature of forgiveness are routinely discussed in the Anglophone tradition. According to Butler, to forgive means essentially to overcome
505
Fabian Bernhardt
resentment and the desire for revenge. Accordingly, the affective make-up of forgiveness can best be described in negative terms. It comes along with the forswearing and vanishing of retributive emotions like anger, resentment and hatred. Here, then, forgiveness is less about what one feels and does than about what one ceases to feel and strive for. Drawing on the etymological relationship between the German words Verzeihen (forgiveness) and Verzicht (waiver, renunciation), Thomas Macho has highlighted that forgiveness is more passive than active. According to Macho, “each act of forgiveness (Verzeihen) is originally an act of waiver (Verzicht): an omission of retribution and the form of compensation that vengefulness strives for. Forgiveness is the name of the action which abstains from acting” (Macho 1988, 139; own transl.). In this peculiar embrace of activity and inactivity, the act of forgiveness involves the acknowledgement that there are deeds and sufferings that cannot be undone. The fault is irreversible. However, forgiveness is irreversible, too. To say “I forgive you” means to do what one says. If one utters these words and comes to revoke them later, then one can be sure that the phrase has been out of place (cf. Bernhardt 2014, 116). If forgiveness takes place, it remains once and for all—thereby opening up the possibility of a new beginning.
Notes 1 The rise of philosophical interest not only in forgiveness but also in revenge broadly converges with the general renaissance of the philosophy of emotion, and, in particular, the establishment of the research field “Law and Emotion”. The authors in this field share the assumption that the strict distinction in legal theory between reason and emotion—and the dismissal of the latter—is not only empirically wrong, but also the source of much mischief. Accordingly, their common aim is “to inject emotion back into discussions of justice” (Solomon 1994, 292). 2 In this respect, Griswold’s interpretation of Butler differs from the standard reading, according to which the core of Butler’s account is not to forswear revenge, but to forswear resentment (cf. Griswold 2007, 20).
References Amborn, Hermann (2016). Das Recht als Hort der Anarchie. Gesellschaften ohne Herrschaft und Staat. Berlin: Matthes & Seitz. Arendt, Hannah (1998[1958]). The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Aristotle (1991). On Rhetoric. A Theory of Civic Discourse. Transl. by G. A. Kennedy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bandes, Susan (2009). Victims, ‘Closure’ and the Sociology of Emotion. Law and Contemporary Problems 72, 1–26. Beinhauer-Köhler, Bärbel, Zenger, Erich, and Volkmann, Stefan (2004). Rache. In: H. D. Betz, D. S. Browning, B. Janowski, and E. Jüngel (Eds.). Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart. Handwörterbuch für Theologie und Religionswissenschaft, vol. 7. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 11–13. Bernhardt, Fabian (2014). Zur Vergebung. Eine Reflexion im Ausgang von Paul Ricœur. Berlin: Neofelis. ——— (2017). Rache. Über einen blinden Fleck der Moderne. Ph.D.-thesis, Free University Berlin. Burkert, Walter (1998). Strafe [I. Teil A: Griechische und römische Antike]. In: J. Ritter and K. Gründer (Eds.). Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, vol. 10. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 208–216. Butler, Joseph (1896). Sermon VIII, IX. Upon Resentment, and Forgiveness of Injuries. In: W. E. Gladstone (Ed.). The Works of Joseph Butler, vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 136–167. Crépon, Marc, and Rauen, Verena (Eds.) (2012). Aporien des Verzeihens. Wien, Berlin: Turia + Kant. Derrida, Jacques (2001[1997]). On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness. Transl. by M. Dooley, and M. Hughes. London, New York: Routledge. Foucault, Michel (1978[1975]). Discipline and Punish. The Birth of the Prison. Transl. by A. Sheridan. New York: Pantheon. Frijda, Nico (1994). The Lex Talionis. On Vengeance. In: S. van Goozen, N. van de Poll, and J. Sergeant (Eds.). Emotions. Essays on Emotion Theory. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum, 263–289.
506
Forgiveness and revenge Gehrke, Hans-Joachim (1987). Die Griechen und die Rache. Ein Versuch in historischer Psychologie. Saeculum 38, 121–149. Govier, Trudy (2002). Forgiveness and Revenge. London, New York: Routledge. Griswold, Charles L. (2007). Forgiveness. A Philosophical Exploration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2013). The Nature and Ethics of Vengeful Anger. In: J. E. Fleming (Ed.). Passions and Emotions. New York: New York University Press, 77–124. Hénaff, Marcel (2010[2002]). The Price of Truth. Gift, Money, and Philosophy. Transl. by J.-L. Morhange with the collaboration of A.-M. Fenberg-Dibon. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Homer (1961). Iliad. Transl. by Richmond Lattimore. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hughes, Paul M., and Warmke, Brandon (2017). Forgiveness. In: Edward N. Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/ entries/forgiveness/. Jacoby, Susan (1983). Wild Justice. The Evolution of Revenge. New York: Harper & Row. Jankélévitch, Vladimir (2005[1967]). Forgiveness. Transl. by A. Kelley. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ——— (1996). L’Imprescriptible. Paris: Éditions du Seuil. Lehmann, Johannes F. (2012). Im Abgrund der Wut. Zur Kultur- und Literaturgeschichte des Zorns. Freiburg i.Br.: Rombach. Levinas, Emmanuel (1969[1961]). Totality and Infinity. An Essay on Exteriority. Transl. by Alphonso Lingis. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Macho, Thomas (1988). Fragment über die Verzeihung. Zeitmitschrift. Journal für Ästhetik 3, Düsseldorf: Bollmann, 135–145. Maroney, Terry (2011). The Persistent Cultural Script of Judicial Dispassion. California Law Review 99, 629–681. McCullough, Michael E., Pargamont, Kenneth I., and Thoresen, Carl E. (2001). The Psychology of Forgiveness. History, Conceptual Issues, and Overview. In: Michael E. McCullough, Kenneth I. Pargamont, and Carl E. Thoresen (Eds.). Forgiveness. Theory, Research, and Practice. New York: Guilford Press, 1–14. Menke, Christoph (2012). Recht und Gewalt. Berlin: August. Paul, Axel T. (2005). Die Rache und das Rätsel der Gabe. Leviathan. Berliner Zeitschrift für Sozialwissenschaft 33(4), 240–256. Ricœur, Paul (2004[2000]). Memory, History, Forgetting. Transl. by K. Blamey and D. Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Rinofner-Kreidl, Sonja (2013). Zwischen ‘cheap grace’ und Rachsucht. Zu Reichweite und ambivalenter Bewertung von (Selbst-)Vergebung. Phänomenologische Forschungen 2013(1), 197–235. Schlee, Günther, and Turner, Bertram (2008a). Einleitung: Wirkungskontexte des Vergeltungsprinzips in der Konfliktregulierung. In: G. Schlee and B. Turner (Eds.). Vergeltung. Eine interdisziplinäre Betrachtung der Rechtfertigung und Regulation von Gewalt. Frankfurt am Main: Campus, 7–47. ——— (2008b). Rache, Wiedergutmachung und Strafe: Ein Überblick. In: G. Schlee and B. Turner (Eds.). Vergeltung. Eine interdisziplinäre Betrachtung der Rechtfertigung und Regulation von Gewalt. Frankfurt am Main: Campus, 49–67. Seneca (2013). On Anger. In: Seneca: Moral and Political Essays. Ed. and transl. by J. M. Cooper and J. F. Procopé. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1–116. Solomon, Robert C. (1994). Sympathy and Vengeance: The Role of the Emotions in Justice. In: S. v. Goozen, N. v. de Poll, and J. Sergeant (Eds.). Emotions. Essays on Emotion Theory. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 291–311. ——— (1999). Justice v. Vengeance. On Law and the Satisfaction of Emotion. In: Susan A. Bandes (Ed.). The Passions of Law. New York: New York University Press, 123–148. Verdier, Raymond et al. (Eds.) (1980–1984). La vengeance. Études d’ethnologie, d’histoire et de philosophie. 4 vols. Paris: Editions Cujas. Further reading Burkert, Walter (1994). ‘Vergeltung’ zwischen Ethologie und Ethik. Reflexe und Reflexionen in Texten und Mythologien des Altertums. München: Carl Friedrich von Siemens Stiftung. Flaßpöhler, Svenja (2016). Verzeihen. Vom Umgang mit Schuld. München: Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt. French, Peter (2001). The Virtues of Vengeance. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.
507
Fabian Bernhardt Griswold, Charles L., and Konstan, David (Eds.) (2012). Ancient Forgiveness. Classical, Judaic, and Christian. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Klinger, Elmar (1987). Revenge and Retribution. In: M. Eliade (Ed.). The Encyclopedia of Religion, vol. 12. New York: Macmillan, 362–368. Probst, Peter, and Sprenger, Gerhard (1992). Rache. In: J. Ritter and K. Gründer (Ed.). Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, vol. 8. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1–6. Sloterdijk, Peter (2006). Zorn und Zeit. Politisch-psychologischer Versuch. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
508
43 GRATITUDE Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl
Gratitude is the return of good for good. Generally, it is a positive emotion someone undergoes in response to another one’s attention, love, fidelity or any other kind of material or immaterial good. Either as an independent object of concern or as associated with other phenomena, gratitude is of interest for normative ethics, moral psychology and political philosophy. It also has been discussed in non-philosophical contexts, above all by anthropologists, sociologists, and more recently psychologists, in the wake of so-called positive psychology. Gratitude is an important part of common morality. It is firmly anchored in Christianity and other religious traditions like Judaism, Islam or Buddhism. Among philosophers, it is contested what its precise meaning, range and implications are. The present chapter focuses on a phenomenology of gratitude and does so by addressing the following questions: What is gratitude? What is its object? On what conditions do people feel and show gratitude? What inhibits gratitude in situations that prima facie seem to warrant it? What is the good of gratitude? How should we assess its social and moral significance?
1. Historical and cultural relativity: shifting views of gratitude and associated clusters of emotions To a considerable extent, the social and moral significance of gratitude depends on the status and meaning of gift-giving as part of everyday life and common morality. Relating to this, far-reaching differences between different epochs and societies suggest themselves (cf. Mauss 1923; Heyd 1982, 38–48; Komter 2004). Among others, these differences concern the ( lacking) spiritual, religious or metaphysical underpinning of gift-giving or benevolence towards human and non-human creatures. They are also due to the respective functions of gratitude in terms of establishing and strengthening intergenerational bonds and collective or group identities. Querying the adaptive function of gratitude in postmodern societies should also take into account those clusters of emotions and attitudes with which gratitude is linked up (cf. Klein 1957; Emmons and Shelton 2002, 460; Solomon 2004; Algoe and Haidt 2009). Compassion, contentment, modesty, humility, kindness, forgiveness or love do not seem to be among the most cherished dispositional emotions or character traits in highly competitive achievement-orientated societies. The same holds for mindfulness, awe, wonder 509
Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl
and admiration. It also holds for empathy, which is involved in both giving and receiving of benefits. Therefore, gratitude has been placed in the class of empathic emotions (cf. Lazarus and Lazarus 1994). Historical and cultural shifts of meaning and moral assessment also come to bear on those mind-sets and (pathological) character dispositions that render feelings of gratitude unlikely or effectively prevent their occurrence (e.g., envy, narcissism, egoism, haughtiness, hate). Relevant emotions come in degrees and have to be caught in their pertaining dynamic and dialectics in order to see whether they function as reinforcers or disenablers of gratitude. Pride, for example, can very well go along with gratitude, yet tends to exclude it as soon as it intensifies and enlarges, transforming itself into an excessive proud of one’s independence (see Selbständigkeitsstolz, Kolnai 2007, 79). “We wish to be self-sustained. We do not quite forgive a giver” (Emerson 1923, 12). Humility can help to become sensitive to a plenty of reasons for being grateful (cf. Hildebrandt 1980; Schwarz 1992; Scheler 2005, 24–32; Snow 2005; Wenisch 2010; McAleer 2012; Roberts 2016). If it degenerates into self-abnegation and obsequiousness, it is, however, incompatible with authentic gratitude.
2. Elements and accounts of gratitude Typical cases of gratitude are triadic relations: someone is grateful to x for A. Apart from this basic form of personal (attribution-dependent or targeted) gratitude, which seems to prevail in everyday life, there is also a dyadic relation of gratitude. The latter is outcome-dependent, but attribution-independent and can be designated non-personal gratitude: someone is grateful for A, for instance, for enjoying physical health, the sight of a captivating landscape or the good luck that happens in one’s life. In this chapter, I restrict myself to triadic or personal gratitude, which conceives of gratitude as an essentially social emotion that goes beyond an attribution-independent feeling of appreciation (cf. McCullough et al. 2001, 256; Emmons and Shelton 2002, 460f.; Gulliford et al. 2013, 297–301; Kristjánsson 2015, 500f.). The aim is to carve out the distinctive features of gratitude as a positive emotion, which is different from other positive emotions like joy, hope, relief or admiration (cf. Roberts 2004, 65). More precisely, I focus on the core experience of personal gratitude. I do not pretend to cover the entire range of its social implications. The effects of this restriction need to be kept in mind. When specifying inhibiting conditions of gratitude, for example, I do not mention institutional factors that thwart gratitude. Such factors certainly had to be considered if one took a more encompassing perspective. What might fill the gap between the personal and the institutional aspects of gratitude is a closer investigation of the various ways in which gratitude and justice are interrelated, on the one hand (cf. Solomon 1995; Boleyn-Fitzgerald 2005), and the role of gratitude, taken as a civic virtue, in moral learning and moral education, especially in citizenship education, on the other hand (cf. Klosko 1989; White 1999; Jonas 2012). Investigating gratitude in terms of a triadic relation amounts to considering it as part of benevolence/gratitude interactions. Accordingly, talk about goods for which someone is grateful refers to goods conveyed in course of such interactions. For the present purpose, I use “good,” “gift” and “benefit” interchangeably. When designating gratitude as a positive emotion “positive” has at least one of the following meanings that prevail depending on the particular context of speech: “appropriate,” “pleasant,” “positively evaluating,” “conducive to (mental and physical) health” (cf. Kristjánsson 2013, 173f.). Moreover, it is controversial among philosophers whether the good whose conveyance calls for gratitude should be interpreted in a broad (non-standard cases) or narrow sense (standard cases). Narrowly conceived, gratitude is a response to beneficence. Broadly conceived, one should also include non-standard 510
Gratitude
cases of gratitude to the non-maleficent, that is, those who do not harm you although they could do so and might have good reasons to do so (cf. Smilansky 1997) and even, though much more controversial, gratitude to the maleficent, that is, to those who pushed you towards self-improvement by actually harming you (cf. Boleyn-Fitzgerald 2005). Gratitude can be conceived either as an occurring emotion (episode-gratitude) or as a disposition (trait-gratitude) as is the case when it is taken as a human strength or moral virtue said to increase individual well-being and social cohesion. The present chapter is mainly concerned with episode-gratitude. Without first gaining, a clear grasp on the rational structure of episode-gratitude one could not understand the meaning and working of trait-gratitude. The rational structure, however, must not be considered in isolation (see Sections 3.1 and 3.2). Any complete understanding and assessment of gratitude has to take into account the particular circumstances and modes of acting. Among the philosophical issues that come along with gratitude, especially in deontological or virtue ethical contexts (cf. Smit and Timmons 2011; Herman 2012), is whether one should conceive of benevolence and gratitude in terms of obligations, supererogation, virtues or imperfect duties (cf. Card 1988; Manela 2015; Carr 2015a). It has been argued that whether or not beneficent acts count as supererogatory depends on whether they surpass specific demands of justice. This, again, depends on the presupposed notion of justice as has been shown, among others, relating to the narrow and wider meaning of justice in A ristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (cf. Heyd 1982, 42–48). The present chapter cannot enter detailed discussion of these and other special issues although they will be touched on occasionally. The focus lies on a phenomenology of gratitude.
3. A phenomenological framework for studying gratitude The main thrust of a phenomenology of gratitude does not lie with taxonomies of various theoretical accounts of gratitude and relating classificatory issues. It rather aims at clarifying the phenomenal qualities and the intentional structure of gratitude and, within this framework, giving an account of its social and moral dimension. For phenomenologists, the feeling qualities cannot be considered separately from the intentional structure of an experience (as is nowadays usually supposed when referring to so-called “qualia”). The former rather are part and parcel of the latter. According to its focus on human experience, spelled out in terms of a variety of different forms of intentional structures, the phenomenological analysis sets in bottom-up, yet without taking an anti-universalist position. Rather, it refers to tokens of gratitude experiences, delivers intuition-based in-depth descriptions and thereby tries to unveil an essential structure, which proves valid for every particular instance of the same type of experience (cf. Rinofner-Kreidl 2018). If studying emotions proceeds bottom-up in the peculiar manner specified in Edmund Husserl’s phenomenology, one must be all the more vigilant not to base one’s investigation on too limited a range of cases (although cases here always function as exemplary cases). The idea of gratitude we advance, among others, depends on the breadth and variety of cases we take into account in the first place. For example, there are non-standard cases in which benefactors severely suffer because they give more than they can do without. Beneficiaries who learn about disproportionate sacrifices for their benefit tend to undergo mostly negative feelings of gratitude, which are mixed up with feelings of regret, shame or guilt (cf. Manela 2016). The intentionalist framework and intuitive-descriptive method distinguishes the phenomenological approach from empirical (e.g. psychological) investigations dealing with 511
Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl
statistical or experimental research on gratitude’s intensity, frequency, life-span distributions or effects on physiological functioning and physical health (cf. Peterson and Seligman 2004, 558–563). Elaborating on the intentional structure of gratitude is meant to demarcate and define the core experience of gratitude. It does not display the overall role of gratitude in human flourishing. Neither does it overrule or render unimportant the particular contexts and social dynamics gratitude experiences are part of. (For an explanation of how an intuition-based phenomenological investigation leaves room for considering varying contexts and various elements of experiences linked up with a routine practice of shifts of attitudes see Rinofner-Kreidl 2014.) Combining intuitive and attitude-related aspects in one’s investigation of specific emotions allows for reflectively shaping one’s emotions. Relating to these general features, a phenomenology of emotion, which follows Husserl’s classical brand of phenomenology, fits well with those strands of current emotion studies that embark on moderate cognitivism (see, for instance, the conception of emotions as concern-based construals, cf. Roberts 2003, 2007, 2013).
3.1 The intentional structure of gratitude Clarifying the intentional structure of gratitude requires making explicit its cognitive content. The fact that the beneficiary’s gratitude is a response to another one’s benevolent intention, which is perceived or otherwise immediately grasped, is of crucial importance to understand what gratitude is and achieves. Gratitude is not merely and not exclusively a response to the good received. This holds true even on condition that the relevant good is urgently desired or required, which marks the subject-relative and yet objectively stated value of the good. (The latter certainly is compatible with stating different degrees of a particular good’s desirability or requiredness according to persons and circumstances.) The assumption that gratitude does not only respond to the good received is corroborated if a benefactor’s serious attempt to convey a good founders. In such cases, it regularly happens that the beneficiary nonetheless feels and shows gratitude for the benefactor’s willingness and effort, however futile, to convey the good. This behaviour would be irrational and hard to understand if the only relevant factor were the value of the good (for her) as well as its immediate and successful conveyance. Indeed, the benefactor’s kind and friendly intent is part of the notion of benefit as it reflects common morality. Accordingly, nobody can do a benefit without knowing that he does. Neither can one do a benefit unwillingly (cf. Seneca 1935, 379–387). Hence, we may say that the relational (or social) aspect is crucial for gratitude to be warranted. The benefactor’s intention to convey the good, as noticed by the beneficiary, is a necessary condition of gratitude to be justified. Gratitude is an appropriate response primarily to another one’s benevolent intention, which is directed to some particular person who is perceived as needing help or support (cf. Seneca 1935, 401–403). The beneficiary becomes indebted for a good bestowed on him only on condition that she conceives herself as object of the benefactor’s goodwill intention. Gratitude therefore is part of a complex intentional structure that entails recognition of another person, of a specific relation to her and of a specific good conveyed (cf. Watkins 2014, 42–49). It is not simply a response to a benefit or good considered as such, that is, in isolation from the mutual intentionality of benevolent/ gratitude interactions. Such an isolating consideration of the good conveyed is tempting only on condition that the social interaction at issue is reduced to bargaining. Benevolent actions and grateful responses, however, do not represent exchange relations in terms of commercial transactions (cf. Simmel 1908). Warding off this misconception amounts to realizing that, 512
Gratitude
at this primary level of description, the intended object of gratitude is the good-as-valuablefor-the beneficiary-according-to-the benefactor’s-intention as the latter is conceived by the beneficiary. Less technically: it is not the good as such (i.e., the good absolutely conceived) but its meaning here and now for a particular beneficiary that is a relevant factor with regard to the appropriateness of gratitude. Benefit appraisals therefore vary from individual to individual (as is the case with benevolence and generosity too). Explaining the respective differences required going beyond episode-gratitude and investigating trait-gratitude. It also required taking into account past experiences, current social positions, the dynamics of other-perception and self-perception, political convictions and other factors in order to fully understand what fuels or thwarts the respective gratitude dispositions and their connection with episode-gratitude. Each or all these factors may well undermine the giving and receiving relation. Consider, for instance, the rule of thumb that the needier a person is the more grateful she will be for suitable benefits. The reverse often turns out to be true, however, especially when recipients believe their needs are unjust or a source of shame. In such a case, the donor may be resented, and the recipient may feel entitled to what is given. (Lazarus 1999, 245) This, again, touches upon the issue of a clustering of emotions, which can turn the positive value of gratitude into a mixed or ambiguous emotion. It can even engender an altogether different, mainly negative emotional outlook like resentment, contempt, or hate. There is no pure and stable intentionality of gratitude responses. They are always entangled in particular relations and social dynamics, which must be taken seriously in order to understand the evaluating character of the many forms of gratitude (cf. Kekes 1981, 299, 302; Blum 2000, 206, 211f., 217). In this vein, a phenomenology of gratitude delivers a thick description. It takes note of how the various elements of benevolent/gratitude interactions are related to one another and does not simplify the situation by, first, artificially disentangling and separating the moments involved and, second, trying to get rid of or objectify circumstantial aspects. Pondering possible inhibiting conditions of gratitude can pave the way for a more finegrained description of gratitude. Given that someone carries out a benevolent action and that the circumstances do not impair or annul its aim and basic character, what kind of reason could then block the beneficiary’s impulse to feel and show gratitude? A case in point is that the beneficiary cannot enjoy the gift or cannot consider it valuable at all. If we exclude the unlikely case that the benefactor erroneously conceived of the other person as standing in need of shelter, food, emotional support or whatever, reasons for denying appreciation of the gift will distribute among the following options. The beneficiary may (a) dislike the benefactor as a person, independent of her actual gift-giving, due to previous experiences and interactions. Or she may (b) dislike receiving help from this particular person because, for example, the benefactor is in love with her but she does not feel the same way. Or the benefactor who helped her getting out of an embarrassing public scenario turned out to be a racist or sexist afterwards. Also it might be the case that the beneficiary (c) dislikes the kind of help or support she is offered because, for instance, she feels forced into an improper intimate relation with or subservient position to the benefactor. Or the beneficiary (d) believes that the benefactor would like to be repaid in terms of goods she does not want to give (e.g., joining the benefactor’s religion). The beneficiary may also be inclined (e) to refute in general being the addressee of benefaction because she reduces gratitude to and does not distinguish it from indebtedness, which can be felt as extremely unpleasant and burdening 513
Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl
(cf. Schwarz 1992, 25; Lazarus and Lazarus 1994, 122; Watkins 2014, 215f.). Nowadays, the received view is that gratitude cannot be reduced to indebtedness and should be distinguished from it, although a feeling of indebtedness regularly is part of gratitude (cf. Watkins et al. 2006). A strong feeling of indebtedness can inhibit gratitude. It can also inhibit acknowledging gratitude as a virtuous emotion. An overstatement of indebtedness is probably also what motivates Aristotle to deny acknowledging gratitude as a virtue, since it would not be decent and indeed demeaning for the great-minded (megalopsychoi) to show gratitude (cf. Kristjánsson 2015). Finally, and possibly nourished or increased by (some of ) the aforementioned options (a)–(e), the beneficiary may (f ) have doubts concerning the goodwill of the benefactor. The goodwill of the benefactor can be impaired or annulled either from reasons internal to the present (inter)action or from external reasons. In the latter case, the reasons that diminish or abolish the benefactor’s (alleged) goodwill can, for example, refer to her character traits and feeling dispositions. A case in point is what Max Scheler discusses under the heading of a “pharisaic” attitude and motivation to act. Though this may characterize an agent’s general attitude and behaviour, it has a remarkable impact on particular instances of benevolence/gratitude interactions by redefining their intentional structure. Acting in a pharisaic manner means not to do benevolent acts for the sake of alleviating the beneficiary’s needs or hardship; rather carrying them out in order to publicly show up as a benevolent person. The agent of course tries to conceal this selfish motivation or downrightly denies having it (cf. Scheler 1973, 27, 179f., 182f.). It is an effective disqualifier of gratitude if the beneficiary views the donor as self-serving. Authentic benevolence and authentic gratitude are devoid of predominating pharisaic motives. It is, however, misconceived to stipulate a radical antagonism of pure pharisaism and pure altruism (cf. Hampton 1993). Self-concern, to some degree, is always involved. Real-life benevolence/gratitude interactions allow for mixed motives on both sides. Mixed motives do not necessarily hamper or annul the benevolent act and its generosity. They are compatible with the normative idea of a benevolence/ gratitude interaction as long as the self-related aspects do not take precedence. Acting pharisaically does not primarily concern the manner in which the benevolent act is carried out. It rather concerns the posture or mindset of the alleged benefactor. It therefore represents an at least semi-external inhibiting condition of gratitude. This being the case, one may argue that pharisaic benevolence hinders the occurrence of gratitude from contingent reason. The next step is to query whether there are inhibiting conditions of gratitude referring to intrinsic aspects of the benevolence/gratitude interaction. Scrutinizing possible intrinsic reasons for inhibiting gratitude helps to get a clearer grasp on the social and moral significance of gratitude. It also helps to understand the specific “sense of justice” involved in everyday benevolence/gratitude interactions.
3.2 Adverbial duties and the proper reference of “a sense of justice” Both in philosophical and psychological literature, gratitude is usually understood as a positive emotion suited to enhance social cohesion and individual well-being. Given this characteristic, it is disturbing to see how insecure and wavering actual assessments of benevolent actions and relating responses of gratitude are. Although it is generally assumed that gratitude is the proper and warranted response to benevolent actions, the reality of gift-giving shows an entire range of more or less positive or negative assessments referring to gratitude. On various occasions, it is considered inappropriate to show gratitude because it would be insincere, humiliating, obsequious or self-demeaning to do so. Whether or not gratitude is 514
Gratitude
warranted in particular cases cannot be determined in advance and in a context-independent manner. Neither can it be determined without judging upon the correlating benevolent act. This seems clear and uncontroversial given the fact that gratitude occurs as an emotional response. The propriety of the response, at least to a large extent, depends on the propriety of the originary act of benevolence. Moreover, the relational aspect has to be taken in account too. Among others, it is relevant with regard to assessing the proper intensity (magnitude) and expression of gratitude. Whether it is suitable to feel gratitude on a given occasion, however, first and foremost depends on the propriety of the benevolent act. “Propriety” here does not merely refer to the occurrence or non-occurrence of gift-giving; or, to the issue whether, from what reasons and to what extent, the benevolent action was called for at all. The extended meaning of “propriety” in the present context mirrors the idea that the moral assessment of gratitude depends on the desirability of the benefit from the beneficiary’s point of view, the goodwill of the benefactor, the effort she undergoes to give the benefit (e.g., by deviating from her social roles) and how hard it is for her to relinquish the good herself (cf. Watkins 2014, 41–51). Yet the effective assessment of gratitude—whether it is justified and decent to feel gratitude in particular instances of benevolence/gratitude interactions—also and in a weighty sense depends on what has been designated “duties of manner” or “adverbial duties” (cf. Audi 2004, 179–182). Adverbial duties go beyond the demand that some specific (type of ) action has to be realized in order to meet certain normatively required achievements. They go beyond the fulfilment of strict or perfect duties. Adverbial duties refer to the manner in which those actions are carried out whose performance is suited to meet either perfect or imperfect duties. (The latter distinction goes back to Kant who defines imperfect duties as duties of personal discretion: it is up to the individual agent when and to what extent they are fulfilled. On the contrary, there is a moral demand on every agent to completely fulfil strict or perfect duties. Cf. Kant 1964, 118–124 [§§ 27–33].) Deontologists and virtue ethicists usually agree that benevolence is an imperfect duty: the benefactor is not strictly speaking obliged to help the beneficiary. If she does so, the help is offered not on the basis of another one’s right or entitlement (which does not exist) but on the basis of a voluntary decision and within the limits of individual discretion. What sense could it make to nonetheless talk about adverbial duties on these conditions? As “duties” falling on the side of the benefactor, they refer to the right manner of giving benefits. Though the right manner of giving certainly leaves some latitude it nonetheless is subject to an invariable constraint of rationality. The respective manner of giving must not undermine or abolish the very nature of benefaction and, consequently, must not disenable the beneficiary to feel and show gratitude in a proper manner. Among Seneca’s many subtle descriptions of the dialectics involved in benevolence/gratitude interactions, we find the following: Often, I say, the benefit endures, and yet imposes no obligation. If the giver repents of his gift, if he says that he is sorry that he gave it, if he sighs, or makes a wry face when he gives it, if he thinks that he is, not bestowing, but throwing away, his gift, if he gave it to please himself, or, at any rate, not to please me, if he persists in being offensive, in boasting of his gift, in bragging of it everywhere, and in making it painful to me, the benefit endures, although it imposes no obligation (…). (Seneca 1935, 373) How do adverbial duties of gratitude bear on the issue of justice and its specific weaving into benevolence/gratitude interactions? If interactions are motivated by justice-based rights or 515
Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl
entitlements, the agents are brought together on symmetrical terms, at least as far as their formal roles as bearers and “executers” of the relevant rights-based claims are concerned. There is no debt of gratitude involved. One person is entitled to receive something, and another person is strictly obliged to give it. Both of them act in accordance with a principle of justice or a particular application thereof (indictment) which they unanimously acknowledge. In case of clear-cut justice-based interactions there is no absolute need to pay attention to the peculiar manner of giving and receiving. The object conveyed is a material thing or immaterial good. To be sure, flaws concerning the manner of giving and receiving may cause annoyance even on condition that we are dealing with justice-based claims. Yet the crucial point is that these flaws do not undermine or annul the very nature or normative character of the relevant act or interaction. Gift-giving is far more susceptible to variations with regard to the manner in which it is carried out. This goes hand in hand with other relevant differences that come to light when this kind of interaction is compared with straightforwardly justice-based interactions. First of all, gift-giving or benefaction is no strict obligation. The benefactor’s help, if she decides to offer it, is voluntary and flows from her own initiative. The beneficiary’s gratitude depends on his understanding that the benefactor acted from goodwill, without any strict obligation and in the absence of any outer influence or force that determined her to do so. (This reflects the feeling of undeserved benefit often reported.) Taking benevolence/gratitude interactions at face value, it is obvious that they rest on an asymmetrical relation: the beneficiary stands in need of some good, which is conveyed voluntarily and intentionally by the benefactor. The beneficiary depends on the attentiveness and generosity of the benefactor. The latter enjoys an opportunity to gain self-esteem as well as social appreciation because she is able to alleviate the other’s plight. While the benefactor is endowed with property, knowledge, cultural backing, professional networks or whatever appears useful and desirable, the beneficiary is seriously hampered with regard to her freedom of action. She is unable to satisfy an urgent need without the help of others, and she perceives herself unable to do so right in the moment when she is succoured. It is due to this striking asymmetry, which is more or less strongly felt by the parties involved, that benevolence/gratitude interactions gain a considerable complexity with regard to their intentional content and social as well as moral significance. Owing to this asymmetry, it is all the more important to carefully pay attention to the manner of giving and receiving. More precisely, adverbial duties are crucial with regard to benevolence/gratitude interactions because they reflect a deeper layer of meaning, which is suited to balance the prima facie asymmetry of giver and receiver by a more fundamental symmetry. How does this work? At first sight, benevolence/gratitude interactions revolve around the conveyed good and its value for both the giver and the receiver. It is therefore plausible to consider the benefit as the visible or otherwise immediately present object of concern. However, it is by focusing on the (missing) fulfilment of adverbial duties that we realize the true range of the experiences at issue. What is at stake goes far beyond the giving and receiving of a benefit. What is at stake can properly be called the “topic” of benevolence/gratitude interactions, which does not coincide with their intentional object or prima facie agential character. The topic announces itself and can be seized (at least by those who are sensitive and attentive to these qualifications) in the manner in which benefits are conveyed and received. The topic is a mutually granted, that is, symmetrically “distributed” recognition-respect between the parties involved (cf. Darwall 1977, 2006). Acknowledging the other in the light of this respect is inevitable as soon as the allocation of social roles (powerful/helpless, rich/poor, generous/ 516
Gratitude
needy) is realized as built on unstable and contingent grounds. By means of empathic understanding and imagination, it is conceivable that the roles of benefactor and beneficiary could be performed the other way round. Recognition-respect does not address the agents as equipped with their actual social roles. It rather takes them as “naked” human beings who find themselves in very different situations, striving to get along, to improve themselves, to live an honourable and worthwhile life. Recognition-respect is inevitable on condition that the donor and the receiver of a benefit both realize (and know about each other’s insight in) their shared human vulnerability. This seems to be the ultimate ground of the experience of gratitude: that the other’s existence must not be denied; that it is urged upon us. Seeing the other and oneself in the light of plain existence and human vulnerability certainly cannot be expected from young children, even if they are already able to routinely act as gift-receivers or gift-donors and are trained to say “thank you.” Becoming sensitive to the existential level of gift-giving has to be learned. Doing so is part of acquiring the virtue of gratitude. As long as we restrict ourselves to what is obvious, that is, the asymmetrical relation of giving and receiving we are inclined to merely tackle with the benefit. Yet its conveyance can occasionally be felt as a callous demonstration of social imbalance. At this level, it is, however, impossible to understand why it often is so difficult to show an authentic and pure gratitude, which evades the risk of turning into ambiguous or even clearly negative emotions like envy or hate. Taking the point of view of deep level recognition-respect, we are able to reevaluate the above-mentioned case that a beneficiary feels and shows gratitude notwithstanding the fact that the benefactor’s intention to convey a good has failed. In this case, the beneficiary’s gratitude depends on her confidence that the benefactor tried to convey the benefit ultimately because of the recognition-respect directed towards her. The latter remains untouched by his failure to convey the good. Conversely, it can be unwarranted and unacceptable to show gratitude even if the benefit is successfully conveyed, yet the benefaction is used as a means to humiliate or denigrate, manipulate or compromise the beneficiary (cf. Lazarus and Lazarus 1994, 119). Due to the deprecating manner of conveying the gift, it has ceased to be a benefit: “A gift is not a benefit if the best part of it is lacking—the fact that it was given as a mark of esteem” (Seneca 1935, 49). Morally assessing gift-giving requires assessing possible inhibiting conditions in the light of the deep level involvement of recognition-respect. The immediate starting-point for doing so is the very manner of how the giving and receiving is carried out. The sense of justice relevant here does not refer to entitlements and obligations. It addresses the right and decent manner to encounter one’s fellow humans as it is reflected in the very manner of giving and receiving benefits. This particular sense of justice usually remains unexpressed. It is primarily given in terms of an emotional awareness of the other’s presence as it is especially realized in her empathic understanding. The sense of justice involved in benevolence/gratitude interactions does not stand in need of deliberation or theoretical investigation in order to be grasped. In particular, it must not be reduced to calculations of a “debt balance” (cf. Komter 2004, 206f.). It rather reflects the deeper existential dimension of this kind of interaction and the tacitly shared willingness not to let the obvious asymmetry between giver and receiver determine their other-perception and self-esteem. There is no right that underlies this mutual willingness. Neither do the agents have any theory of human dignity in mind. Yet being engaged in gift-giving the agents can clearly feel their respective vulnerability, at least if they have reached a mature level of moral perception (cf. Rinofner-Kreidl 2013, 175–181, 186–191). The “object” of gratitude, at this level, is the experience of sharing their human vulnerability. Correspondingly, deep level ingratitude goes beyond the ordinary conception of ingratitude, that is, one’s failing to appreciate a “visible” gift conveyed. It manifests itself as the inability to gain access to the feeling of deep level symmetry 517
Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl
or existential equality. Let us assume that it is indeed a matter of the agents’ moral maturity whether they become aware of their existential community. We then need to ponder whether deep level ingratitude (fully) lies within the individual’s responsibility or whether it is due to unfavourable circumstances of life and bad moral luck. Hence, it is not only the obvious issue of charity and generosity but also the above-sketched deep level sense of justice involved in gratitude that leads us back into the more robust political struggles about unequal distributions of opportunities and favourable circumstances of life. From this point of view, gratitude ceases to be a mild and calm emotion. It rather presents itself as a burdened virtue (cf. Tessman 2005), which includes the task to discriminate excessive or misplaced thankfulness from virtuous gratitude (cf. Carr 2015a, 2015b). A so-conceived gratitude is bound within the limits of a precarious life and incessantly on the edge to turn into anger, indignation, rage or other self-protective emotions and reactive attitudes. Understanding gratitude in its full complexity also requires seeing it as part of conflicting claims and far-reaching social dynamics (cf. McConnell 2016; Smilansky 2016). Let us take stock. In the present section, I submitted that adverbial duties are crucial because (i) they bring to bear the sense of justice that is involved in benevolence/gratitude interactions; (ii) if met properly, they can counterbalance the asymmetry between benefactor and beneficiary in a way that allows the latter to authentically feel gratitude without being forced into ambiguous emotions. Adverbial duties are the main reference for defining enabling and inhibiting conditions of gratitude. (iii) They reflect and render accessible the deeper meaning layer and overall topic of benevolence/gratitude interactions, that is, mutually granted recognition-respect.
4. Concluding remarks Benevolence/gratitude interactions must not be misconceived in terms of merely conventional practices or commercial exchanges. Neither can they be reduced to straightforwardly justice-based interactions that posit rights or entitlements and corresponding obligations. Benevolence/gratitude relations hinge upon the benefactor’s voluntariness and genuine and honest goodwill. They also hinge upon the beneficiary’s capability to ungrudgingly accept being succoured, to enjoy the good and to freely express her gratitude. All of this can be hard to realize or can become an inroad for deception and self-deception. Gratitude does not only strengthen social ties on condition of asymmetrically distributed social roles, positions and powers. The formative effects of gratitude (cf. Fredrickson 2004) also include the shaping of a virtuous character whose manifestation in an agent’s emotional responses and actions goes beyond the more superficial aspects of human interaction in favour of its existential layers. In giving and receiving gifts in a proper manner the deep symmetry of mutual recognition-respect “shines through” and thereby counterbalances those destabilizing elements of the social situation that easily bring it about that the positive feeling of gratitude turns into an ambiguous or thoroughly negative emotion. As argued above, adverbial duties function as intermediaries between the conspicuously given benevolence/gratitude interactions and the deeper meaning structure of recognition-respect. As to the latter, the crucial question is how to treat fellow human beings on conditions of dependency, which cover both circumstances of life and acquired attachment styles. The deep level sense of justice involved in everyday benevolence/gratitude interactions therefore seems to be connected with an inchoate and unarticulated, yet emotionally ingrained sense of self which amounts to a sense-of-self-as-encountering-the-other or as-bound-up-withthe-other. The relevant sense of justice is a sense of being human (cf. Roberts 2007, 147). 518
Gratitude
The above-sketched phenomenology of gratitude submits a phenomenological explanation of what philosophers, psychologists, sociologists, and anthropologists often have been stating: that gratitude is a positive emotion, which is apt to strengthen social cohesion and individual well-being. Yet, it does so in a far more complicated manner than one might have expected. The accurate meaning, evaluation and effects of gratitude vary according to the personalities and types of action involved (e.g. being grateful for a good Samaritan’s help; for having been courageous enough to beat off a rapist’s attack). They also vary according to the social contexts in which benevolence/gratitude interactions occur. Resulting from its context-sensitive appearance and against the grain of a commonplace, our emotional practice does not show gratitude as an overall calm, kind and unequivocally positive emotion.
References Algoe, Sara B., and Haidt, Jonathan (2009). Witnessing Excellence in Action: The ‘Other-Praising’ Emotions of Elevation, Gratitude, and Admiration. Journal of Positive Psychology 4(2), 105–127. Audi, Robert (2004). The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Blum, Lawrence (2000). Against Deriving Particularity. In: B. Hooker, and M. O. Little (Eds.). Moral Particularism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 205–226. Boleyn-Fitzgerald, Patrick (2005). Gratitude and Justice. In: C. Williams (Ed.). Personal Virtues: Introductory Essays. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan, 48–72. Card, Claudia (1988). Gratitude and Obligation. American Philosophical Quarterly 25(2), 115–127. Carr, David (2015a). Is Gratitude a Moral Virtue? Philosophical Studies 172(6), 1475–1484. ——— (2015b). The Paradox of Gratitude. British Journal of Educational Studies 63(4), 429–446. Darwall, Stephen (1977). Two Kinds of Respect. Ethics 88(1), 36–49. ——— (2006). The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Emerson, Ralph Waldo (1923). Gifts: An Essay. Boston: The Pinkham Press. Emmons, Robert A., and Shelton, Charles M. (2002). Gratitude and the Science of Positive Psychology. In: F. R. Snyder and S. J. Lopez (Eds.). Handbook of Positive Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 459–471. Fredrickson, Barbara L. (2004). Gratitude, Like Other Positive Emotions, Broadens and Builds. In: R. A. Emmons and M. E. McCullough (Eds.). The Psychology of Gratitude, 145–165. Gulliford, Liz, Morgan, Blaire, and Kristjánsson, Kristján (2013). Recent Work on the Concept of Gratitude in Philosophy and Psychology. Journal of Value Inquiry 47(3), 285–317. Hampton, Jean (1993). Selflessness and the Loss of Self. In: E. Frankel Paul, F. D. Miller, Jr., and J. Paul (Eds.). Altruism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 135–165. Herman, Barbara (2012). Being Helped and Being Grateful: Imperfect Duties, the Ethics of Possession, and the Unity of Morality. The Journal of Philosophy 109(5/6), 391–411. Heyd, David (1982). Supererogation: Its Status in Ethical Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hildebrand, Dietrich von (1980). Über die Dankbarkeit. St. Ottilien: Eos Verlag. Jonas, Mark E. (2012). Gratitude, Ressentiment, and Citizenship Education. Studies in Philosophy and Education 31(1), 29–46. Kant, Immanuel (1964). The Doctrine of Virtue: Part II of the Metaphysics of Morals. Transl. with an Introduction and Notes by M. J. Gregor. Foreword by H. J. Paton. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Kekes, John (1981). Morality and Impartiality. American Philosophical Quarterly 18(4), 295–303. Klein, Melanie (1975[1957]). Envy and Gratitude. In: Envy and Gratitude and Other Works 1946–1963. London: Vintage, 176–235. Klosko, George (1989). Political Obligation and Gratitude. Philosophy & Public Affairs 18(4), 352–358. Kolnai, Aurel (2007). Ekel, Hochmut, Hass. Zur Phänomenologie feindlicher Gefühle. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. Komter, Aaf ke E. (2004). Gratitude and Gift Exchange. In: R. A. Emmons and M. E. McCullough (Eds.). The Psychology of Gratitude. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 195–212.
519
Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl Kristjánsson, Kristján (2013). Virtues and Vices in Positive Psychology: A Philosophical Critique. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2015). An Aristotelian Virtue of Gratitude. Topoi 34(2), 499–511. Lazarus, Richard S., and Lazarus, Bernice N. (1994). Passion and Reason: Making Sense of Our Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (1999). Stress and Emotion: A New Synthesis. London: Free Association Books. Manela, Tony (2015). Gratitude. In: Edward N. Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/gratitude/. ——— (2016). Negative Feelings of Gratitude. Journal of Value Inquiry 50(1), 129–140. Mauss, Marcel (1990[1923]). The Gift: The Form and Reason for Exchange in Archaic Societies. London, New York: Routledge. McAleer, Sean (2012). Propositional Gratitude. American Philosophical Quarterly 49(1), 55–66. McConnell, Terrance (2016). Gratitude’s Value. In: D. Carr (Ed.). Perspectives on Gratitude: An Interdisciplinary Approach. London, New York: Routledge, 13–26. McCullough, Michael E., Emmons, Robert A., Kilpatrick, Shelley D., and Larson, David B. (2001). Is Gratitude a Moral Affect? Psychological Bulletin 127(2), 249–266. Peterson, Christopher, and Seligman, Martin E. P. (2004). Character Strengths and Virtues: A Handbook and Classification. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rinofner-Kreidl, Sonja (2013). Scham und Autonomie. Phänomenologische Forschungen, 163–191. ——— (2014). Phenomenological Intuitionism and Its Psychiatric Impact. In: F. Fuchs, T. Breyer, and C. Mundt (Eds.). Karl Jaspers’ Philosophy and Psychopathology. New York: Springer, 33–60. ——— (2018). Universalistic Demands and Ordinary Virtues: Lessons from a Moral Phenomenology of Gratitude. Unpublished manuscript, in preparation. Roberts, Robert C. (2003). Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2004). The Blessings of Gratitude: A Conceptual Analysis. In: R. A. Emmons, and M. E. McCullough (Eds.). The Psychology of Gratitude. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 58–78. ——— (2007). Spiritual Emotions: A Psychology of Christian Virtues. Grand Rapids, Cambridge: William B. Eerdmans. ——— (2013). Emotions in the Moral Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ——— (2016). Gratitude and Humility. In: D. Carr (Ed.). Perspectives on Gratitude: An Interdisciplinary Approach. London, New York: Routledge, 57–69. Scheler, Max (1973). Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values. A New Attempt toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism. Transl. by M. S. Frings, and R. L. Funk. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. ——— (2005). On the Rehabilitation of Virtue. Transl. by E. Kelly. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 79(1), 21–37. Schwarz, Balduin (1992). Zur Phänomenologie und Metaphysik der Dankbarkeit: Der Dank als Gesinnung und Tat. In: J. Seifert (Ed.). Danken und Dankbarkeit: Eine universale Dimension des Menschseins. Heidelberg: Carl Winter, 15–26. Seneca (1935). Moral Essays, Volume III. With an English Transl. by J. W. Basore. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Simmel, Georg (1950[1908]). Faithfulness and Gratitude. In: K. H. Wolff (Ed.). The Sociology of Georg Simmel. New York: Free Press, 379–395. Smilansky, Saul (1997). Should I Be Grateful to You for Not Harming Me? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57(3), 585–597. ——— (2016). Gratitude: The Dark Side. In: D. Carr (Ed.). Perspectives on Gratitude: An Interdisciplinary Approach. London, New York: Routledge, 126–137. Smit, Houston, and Timmons, Mark (2011). The Moral Significance of Gratitude in Kant’s Ethics. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 49(4), 295–320. Snow, Nancy E. (2005). Humility. In: C. Williams (Ed.). Personal Virtues: Introductory Essays. Houndmills, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Solomon, Robert C. (1995). A Passion for Justice: Emotions and the Origins of the Social Contract. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. ——— (2004). On Grief and Gratitude. In: R. C. Solomon (Ed.). Defense of Sentimentalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 75–107.
520
Gratitude Tessman, Lisa (2005). Burdened Virtues: Virtue Ethics for Liberatory Struggles. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Watkins, Philipp C. (2014). Gratitude and the Good Life: Toward a Psychology of Appreciation. Dordrecht: Springer. Watkins, Philipp, Scheer, Jason, Ovnicek, Melinda, and Kolts, Russell (2006). The Debt of Gratitude: Dissociating Gratitude and Indebtedness. Cognition and Emotion 20(2), 217–241. Wenisch, Michael (2010). The Convergence of Truthfulness and Gratitude in Scheler’s and von Hildebrand’s Account of Humility. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 84(1), 85–98. White, Patricia (1999). Gratitude, Citizenship and Education. Studies in Philosophy and Education 18(1/2), 43–52.
521
44 TRUST Nicolas de Warren
Considerations of trust widely recognize trust as indispensable for human concourse, communication, and commerce. When we commonly speak of trust, we principally have in mind the trust that is given, received, and honored among individuals. Philosophical elaborations of trust likewise focus on, or give special (“paradigmatic”) status to, mutual trust between individuals. While interpersonal trust undoubtedly represents a central dimension of trust, a consideration of trust must take into view a more complex landscape to include self-trust and trust in the world.1 Any account of these dimensions of trust in isolation, and especially with the prevalent single-minded focus on interpersonal trust commanding much of the philosophical literature, must be deemed inadequate to the truism that “upon trust men live in the world.” To thus expand a consideration of trust is to broaden as well as deepen, but as significantly: to render more complex, our understanding of the varieties of trust for human life. A consideration of trust must attend to its three manifest dimensions: trust in Others (interpersonal trust), self-trust, and trust in the world. This threefold imbrication of trusts provides the threads from which the life-world is woven and torn. When we enter into relations of trust, we become not only entrusted to the Other and give the Other our trust, but to the specific relation of trust to which we have subscribed along with the Other. In being entrusted by the Other with her trust, or likewise, in entrusting the Other with my trust, I, or the Other, must trust in oneself to honor this election. Trust is not simply given and received; it must be honored, and in honoring our trusts, we must continually attest to ourselves as entrusted as well as to our trusting relationship. In its interpersonal form, trust is not simply a binding—to be bound to the Other in trust. It is also an accompanying: when we trust the Other, we are bound to her, much as she is bound (in cases of mutual trust) to us: in friendship, in love, in collegiality, etc. This bond of trust is an accompanying. I accompany the Other in trust. The Other stands as my witness. I become the Other’s keeper much as the Other becomes my keeper. We are both keepers of our trust. In this bond of trust along with the Other (to the Other as well as towards our bond of trust), I am also bound to myself in the company of the Other’s trust in me. There is no binding to and with the Other that is also not a binding to and with myself. My trustworthiness on the basis of which the Other trusts me just as much engages and requires truthfulness towards myself as well as towards the Other. Self-attestation, and hence self-trust, is inseparable from trust in Others 522
Trust
(Ricoeur 1992). The dimension of truthfulness is not only Other-regarding but just as, significantly, self-regarding. In attesting to myself as being truthful, I stand truthfully towards the Other. The formation of the self in self-truthfulness and self-attestation, as entrusted to oneself, is critical for discourse as well as for collaborative action; without this assumption of truthfulness, discourse would collapse into either blatant hypocrisy or sheer rhetorical performance. To be truthful to oneself is to be authentic to oneself in cultivating a distance within oneself that only oneself can and knows, and, in this sense, owns. Trust in others and self-trust are inseparable from trust in the world. Trust in the world can—broadly speaking—be distinguished into two basic forms: trust as determined by modal specification and general trust in the world. In its elemental form, trust is both a binding and an accompanying: when we trust the Other, we are bound to the Other and she is bound to us: in friendship, in love, in collegiality, etc. These bindings are edgings, or linings, of the self in a dual sense: a boundary of inclusion becomes circumscribed around the trusting parties, which at once internally distinguishes a schema of mutual recognition (as those in whom we trust) as well as externally forming a schema of discrimination, as those outside the bounds of our trust, towards which we are more readily, if not by default, distrustful. Bound in trust, we accompany, and, in this sense, participate in the lives of Others, much as those Others accompany, and, in this sense, participate in our lives. Trust constitutes an elemental form of participation, or involvement; in trust, we do not simply live with Others, but we live with Others in us much as we live in Others (de Warren 2017). Individuals in whom we trust line our own sense of self from within; the inner lining of myself is the Other in whom I trust. We are involved in their lives in an emotional atmosphere of assuredness from the inside; from within their own lives in the allowance of their trust. Such intimate involvement in the lives of Others (in contrast to involvement with the lives of Others) fosters an assured form of identification and emotional attachment: we identify more assuredly with those in whom we trust, both cognitively, conatively, and affectively, much as we come to identify ourselves more assuredly in our entrustments by Others. Such “trust networks” (family, community, parish, army, nation-state, etc.) reflect the social structuring and modal specification of trust that configure various institutions of trust in the life-world (Tilly 2005). Institutions of trust are bound to modal specifications: we trust a given person in her capacity as a doctor, as a professor, etc. (Misztal 1996, 129ff.; Steinbock 2014, 219ff.). By contrast, we more readily distrust Others, or simply distrust by default, according modal specifications that define those Others in terms of a distance, or exclusion, from our own self-invested trust networks. Trust networks are symbolically encoded (we spontaneously trust the stranger with the Red Sox cap rather than the stranger with the New York Yankees cap) as well as historically embedded. In terms of social groups, cultural heritage, and other institutions in the phenomenological sense of Stiftungen, trust networks are inscribed into symbolic forms, or symbolic systems, that mediate and, in this sense, enable the coupling of values, discourse, and action (Hosking 2014). Trust networks, modal specifications, and symbolic forms compose manifold structures of the life-world. As Schütz argues, “faith in the Other’s truthfulness” (Glauben an die Wahrhaftigkeit des Anderen) stands as the conditio sine qua non for intersubjective existence: the possibility of communication, participation, and experience with others assumes the truthfulness of Others, and this truthfulness, in turn, must be invested in the truthfulness of the world (Schütz 1964, 155). This faith or belief in the “truthfulness” or “creditability” (die Wahrhaftigkeit) of Others, without which we would not entrust Others (either give, receive, or honor trusts), entails not only a trust that Others speak truthfully and take responsibility for their speaking; we would not be disappointed at the individual who lies to us if 523
Nicolas de Warren
not for this basic trust that Others should speak truthfully. This assumption of the Other’s truthfulness bespeaks a general attitude of trustworthiness in Others as such. Simmel argues that money and, more broadly, economic exchange and value critically depend on such trust. More pervasively, as Simmel writes: without the general trust that people have in each other, society itself would disintegrate, for very few relationships are based entirely upon what is known with certainty about another person, and very few relationships would endure if trust were not as strong, or stronger than, rational proof or personal observation. (Simmel 1978, 178) This “general trust”—here understood as a pervasive assumption of the trustworthiness of Others as such—is both inseparable from yet irreducible to the plurality of trust networks, or institutions of trust, configuring the life-world. Is there is pervasive and grounding trustworthiness towards Others, irrespective of any differentiation between friend and foe, us and them? This general thesis of the natural attitude, not just in terms of an original positing of the world, but as an original positing, that is: faith, in the trustworthiness of Others should not be understood in the vein of instinctual human sympathy or Christian universal Love of humankind. Such notions assume a determinate image of human nature and, moreover, a specifiable emotional quality as well as specifiable object (“who” is humanity as such?). What distinguishes a general thesis of trustworthiness is precisely that it lacks any specifiable object, in so far as it bespeaks of a trustworthiness not yet configured according to modal specifications and collective trusts that bind together in-groups (we trust those whom we recognize as members of our group). In edging our identity, trust institutes a border of inclusion, edging away the stranger, who is placed outside the sphere of our trust in an atmosphere of distrust. Trust constitutes bonds as well as boundaries; the stronger our emotional investment and feelings of mutual trust, the stronger the inclusionary affective force of trust’s assuredness, and, likewise, the stronger the exclusionary repulsion of distrust’s assurances. Trust’s emotional lining, as bonding and boundary-marking, is exemplified with nation-states and religious communities. As Hosking observes, “nations create both strong solidarities and also rigid boundaries. A major component of national feeling is the sense of the Other, the certainty about who one is not, whom one tends to distrust, or certainly trusts less readily” (Hosking 2014, 110). Trust in the world is spun from social, cultural, and institutional trusts (along with their respective symbolic forms and historical sedimentations) along with the underpinning of such trust networks in the truthfulness/trustworthiness of Others as such. In its primordial form, this faith in the Other is an openness towards Others molded on an assuredness that the Other is first neither my friend nor my enemy, but the Stranger with whom communication, commerce, and concourse are possible, but not guaranteed. Openness towards the Other is trusting that there is a possible future of encounter and shared narrative with the Stranger. What distinguishes this assuredness is, on the one hand, its thinness with regard to the instituted robustness of modal specification, collective differentiation, and symbolic forms, and, on the other hand, its steadfastness in the face of innumerable betrayals, deceits, and conflicts within the specification of instituted trust. If we were deprived of any openness in trust towards Others, were we to live entirely distrustful of Others, we would become the Misanthrope in the image of the Man from the Underground, whose pervasive distrust of Others expresses itself in the heady mixture of aggression towards Others and toxic volatility within his own pride and shame, self-assuredness (egotism), and self-doubt. We cannot live with a complete 524
Trust
lack of assuredness with regard to Others; and yet, we cannot live trusting Others equally and universally, in which case we would become either the Idiot (Prince Myshkin) of Dostoevsky, who remains socially illiterate to the intrigues and machinations around him, or Voltaire’s Candide, whose unperturbed faith in humankind remains innocent, yet therefore blank and untroubled in the stare and stupor of non-comprehension, despite the patent evils of the world. With Candide, unflagging optimism in humankind is bolstered by an unassailable trust in the rationality of the world, or trust in the world in the maximized form of rational intelligibility and necessity. Pangloss’ metaphysical refrain “this is the best of all possible worlds” accompanies Candide’s faith in human beings like a mantra with its constant reassurance that optimism with regard to Others is not misplaced given this underwritten trust in the world as the best of all possible worlds. Candide’s narrative wanders across the globe of human folly, ever in search of returning to the garden from which he was first ejected. The gardens located throughout Candide’s journey each represents a different image (or mirage) of being at home in the world. Thrown into his narrative from the garden of paradise (Baron Thunder-ten-Tronckh’s keep), Candide comes across in his worldly wanderings the False Garden of Eldorado, only to end his travels in a more modest garden with the memorable counsel: il faut cultiver notre jardin. Trust in the world as structured through social, cultural, and political institutions, as well as the open-ended assuredness of human truthfulness, rests on an existential sense of being at home in the world, or trust in the world in this more fundamental sense, one that is not constituted through trust networks, but disclosed as their very condition. Loss of trust in the world in this primordial sense—when the gods fall silent—unhinges and uncouples social, cultural, and discursive symbolic systems of trust, but likewise, the withering away of trust in the world can be precipitated by the erosion and collapse of those same institutions. Gaining the Other’s trust and trusting in the Other allows the Other to enter into our lives as involved and invested participant. The Other accompanies us in our bond of trust. In granting the Other our trust, we give the Other, as Baier argues, a discretionary power of judgment over our lives, or something (or someone) we care about, in the hold of assuredness that we can rest assured in the Other’s beneficence (Baier 1995). The Other becomes our better angel, thus alleviating the burden of our lives in bolstering our own freedom insofar as bonds of trust must be freely given and accepted for our own self-realization. The Other in this manner lines our subjectivity from within; our sense of self becomes edged with the Other. Allowing the Other to stand as my witness, as critic and confidant (as well as, once I pass from the scene of the world, in remembrance), the Other is given an edge over my subjectivity. In moments of personal indecision, ambivalence, or crisis, I look to the Other’s better judgment and wise counsel. I allow the Other a wider berth within which to confront me with myself through the Other with a directness and truthfulness that I would find either too intrusive (as with my office colleagues) or too obsequious (as with the sycophant) with Others outside my bond of trust, or too suspicious (as with the Confidence Man). This edging of the self in the Other can be leveraged against me when the Other abuses or manipulates my trust to cause my ruin or gain an advantage at my expense. In allowing the trusted person to participate in our lives and exercise discretionary judgment, we have placed ourselves in their hands—hands which now move against us.
1. Affective and atmospheric trust Relations of trust must be nourished and nurtured. Through a mutual edging, or lining, of one another’s sense of self, a space and time of trust emerges between us, bonding us to each Other in the allowance of the Other’s accompaniment from within. This span of trust 525
Nicolas de Warren
is held between two extremes: blind devotion or loyalty in which our autonomy and discretion becomes entirely dissipated into the Other; paranoid vigilance and corrosive distrust by which the Other’s discretionary power of judgment and beneficence has been entirely ejected from having a place in our life. How easily the one we trusted becomes hated when we feel deeply betrayed; how easily we surrender to the Other’s trust when we feel to have betrayed our own self-trust. Between these two poles, the nourishment and nurturing of trust requires, as Baier terms it, the exercise of “functional virtues,” or, in other words, virtues appropriate for the nourishment and nurturing of trust. We are each entrusted as the keepers of our trust, and must mutually calibrate and check upon our trust without obtrusive and suspicious monitoring. Such measured monitoring of trust involves a degree of emotional intelligence and cognitive tact. We must feel our way within our trust: adjusting its contours, shaping its substance, and guiding its future. Trusting relationships operate within a tensor of different vectors: cognitive, affective, and conative. Rather than reduce trust to an emotion, a knowing and judging, or an enduring disposition of goodwill, a bond of trust is formed in the tensor of emotions, cognition, and beneficent desire. As an emotional attachment, trust rests upon cognitive assuredness in granting discretionary power of judgment to the Other. Assuredness is not merely a felt emotional quality of nearness: the Other as lined within me. It is also an assuredness that allows for a settled confidence in coupling the Other’s motivations, values, and possible courses of action. Trusting is not merely based on the cognitive or the affective. Trusting is an assured capacity of coupling the cognitive, the affective, and the conative and, through this operation of coupling, apprehending the Other as known to me, as known in me, within the arc of my own self-knowledge. This operation of coupling is intrinsic to the knowledge I form of the Other in trusting them. Trust is knowing and being-known. Trusting relationships operate within a tensor of different vectors: cognitive, affective, and conative. Rather than reduce trust to an emotion, a knowing and judging, or an enduring disposition of goodwill, a bond of trust is formed in the conglomeration of emotions, cognition, and benevolent desire within an atmosphere of assuredness. Trust is often described as “atmospheric,” and not without reason (Bok 1978; Baier 1986). It is, one the one hand, descriptively challenging to track the distinctive phenomenological features of trust. Unlike emotions such as anger and love, or attitudes such as indifference or obsequiousness, to be trusting or to be entrusted does not manifest itself according to any specific style of manifestation. This appears to be especially significant for any proposed characterization of trust as a specific kind of emotion (Hartmann 2011, 151–171). Even love, which is often identified as the emotional register of trust, proves elusive to specify in this context, other than through attributes which just as much could be taken as characteristic of an affective attitude of goodwill towards the Other ( Jones 1996). On the other hand, the emotional registers one experiences in trusting relationships—intimacy, confidence, peace-of-mind, love, etc.—are nowhere more clearly manifest as when trust becomes betrayed, disappointed, or failed. The acute sense of despair, anger, and even hatred felt with the betrayal of trust attest, as negative images, to the positive emotional registers of trusting relationships. The emotional presentness of trust is nowhere more manifest as when it becomes lost. This is especially apparent with the trans-valuation of love into hate: we come to hate the person who betrays us in an obsessive manner, as the reverse image of our intense attachment to that person in love. Much as we can speak, as does Stendhal, of the “crystallization” of love, we can speak of the “crystallization” of hate: the despised Other becomes our entire universe, and even as we seek to expel the despised Other from our lives, her presence nonetheless remains within
526
Trust
us to the degree that we remain unable to escape from our own compulsive obsession and consuming passion for the Other. We are at times never so close to the Other as in hatred. The characterization of trust as “atmosphere” need not be taken in either a metaphorical or literal sense, but in a genuinely phenomenological sense as truthful to the distinctive of presentness in trust. Hermann Schmitz argues for “atmospheric emotions” that, by virtue of their diffuse yet pervading presentness, elude any identification with determinate acts of consciousness or with a specifiable characteristic of an object (see Chapters 19 and 23 in this volume). Such atmospheric emotions are “holistic,” embracing and prior to the differentiation between acts of consciousness and objects (intentionality). Rather than consider emotions as either affective states of consciousness or “inner experiences” of a subject, emotions are understood as embodied moving atmospheres poured out spatially. On this conception, an emotional atmosphere (for example: grief or joy) “pours” or “spills” out over the sphere of the present, which, once recognized, affects the body and the person. The person is here identified neither with “consciousness,” “the soul,” or “the body,” but with the animation, or life, of what Schmitz calls “the felt body” moving within “felt space” within an original sense of spatiality (Schmitz 1969, 2014). In a comparable vein, trust manifests itself in its emotional assuredness and attachment as an atmospheric sphere of presentness much along the lines of the spatiality of emotions and the affected, moving, that is, acting person who finds themselves within the hold of trust. We come to feel at home in a strange space within the atmospheric presence of a trusted person, as with Marcel in the hotel of Balbec (in Proust’s Recherche), who can only sleep once his grandmother has placed her bed against the shared bedroom wall from the other side within her own room. We might thus speak of trust as an emotional sphere of presentness rather than as the form of an object or an act of consciousness (Sloterdijk 2011). Within such spheres of trust, conglomerations of emotions, cognitions, and desires crystallize in the hold of trust. As an emotional attachment, trust rests upon cognitive assuredness in granting discretionary power of judgment to the Other. Assuredness is not merely a felt emotional quality of nearness: the Other as lined within me. This assuredness within me allows, most critically, for an affordance of distance from the trusted Other. As argued by Erik Erikson, the formation of basic trust within the mother-child relationship during infant development hinges on the capacity of the child to let go of the immediate presence of the mother in the expectation, or trust, that the absent mother will return. Even when the child cannot call upon the mother directly, trust in the mother’s benevolence for the child and, crucially, eventual return, allows the child to overcome the anxiety of separation (Erikson 1963). This trust in the mother’s return, for Erikson, underpins all form of social trust and requires a degree of self-trust in the child’s capacity to endure, as it were, the absence of the trusted mother. More generally, the assuredness of trust allows for a settled confidence in coupling the Other’s motivations, values, and possible courses of action.
2. The coupling of trust Trusting is an assured capacity of coupling the cognitive, the affective, and the conative and, through this operation of coupling, apprehending the Other as known to me, as known in me, within the arc of my own self-knowledge. This operation of coupling is intrinsic to the knowledge I form of the Other in trusting them. Trust is knowing and being-known. In trusting the Other, I can more ably and assuredly predict their actions, reactions, and responses on the basis on more ably and assuredly coupling their possible motivations, reasons,
527
Nicolas de Warren
and values, so as to plot and understand, approve or disapprove, their chosen course of action, or lack thereof. The inscrutability of the Other becomes for me leavened with the assuredness of my coupling together who they might be in any given situation. In trusting the Other, I can rest assured that the Other shall most likely behave in such and such a manner, be motivated to do such and such an action, and to act according to such and such a value. In this assured capacity of coupling together, the Other’s possible courses of action and reasoning, I identify myself with the kind of individual who, as the Other who is not me, is nonetheless like me. I trust that the Other would do as I would do in a given situation or trust that the Other will act in a way with which I could identity and hence endorse. Even when the Other’s actions, motivations, and values remain opaque, we are more disposed to give the trusted Other the benefit of our doubt and rule out more incriminating or trust-corrosive motivations, values, actions. When our trust becomes tested, challenged, or betrayed, the assuredness of our coupling operation (imagining what the Other would do, knowing that the Other would not do this and that, etc.) becomes itself tested, challenged, or, in cases of betrayal, broken. Much as this coupling operation called trusting the Other gives us assurances in granting discretionary judgment and embedding emotional investment, this knowing of the Other can be equally used against us, for in trust, I myself become known (and in ways I may not know of myself ) to the Other. The Confidence Man’s self-assuredness (as in Melville’s novel, The Confidence Man), charisma, and rhetorical prowess insinuates himself into a member of my trust-network, or in-group, and through this perspicuous vantage-point over who I am—what I value, how I would act, etc.—deftly uses the coupling intelligence of trust against me. Addressing us in ways that speak to what we value, a shared past, and our membership community, the Confidence Man employs a strategy of mirroring, and in this mirroring, we, the marker, become captivated and captured in seeing an image of ourselves, or an image of our in-group identity. In this mirror, we see likeness and fellow-feeling without seeing our own blindness, for it is this very mirroring that makes us blind to the Confidence Man’s dissimulation and manipulation of our trust. We have been duped in having been seen through without seeing through our own blindness for having ourselves been rendered transparent. The assuredness in trust’s coupling, and hence, coming to know the Other and feeling attached to the Other, invested in the Other’s life and assured that the Other is invested in our life, is never static. Our confidence in knowing the trusted Other is always shifting, at times more or less pronounced. Relationships of trust must be nourished and nurtured so that the assuredness of coupling becomes related to the self-monitoring of the relationship. The exercise of functional virtues (those virtues appropriate to the nourishing and nurturing of trust) as well as the monitoring of trust presupposes that the intrinsic value of trusting is valued by the mutually entrusted individuals. It is not only that the individuals in trust must respectively honor their trusts towards each Other. The relationship of trust itself must be honored by each entrusted member. I am as much your keeper as we are together the keepers of our bond of trust. We feel honored in being trusted by the Other. We must honor the trust placed in our hands by the Other, and this honoring is anchored in a feeling of being recognized and valued, elected. This is an emotion of wanting to be truthful and trustworthy; we do not want to let the other person down; we want to live up to our trusts and entrustments. To value myself as entrusted, to value the Other in trust, and to value the value of our relationship of trust reflects not only that I value both my autonomy as well as the autonomy of the Other. It also reflects that I value the autonomy of the relationship of trust in which we are bound to each other in the mutual realization of our respective freedom. We must each serve as the Other’s 528
Trust
keeper but likewise each serve as the keeper of our trusting relationship. Since it remains essential for the vitality of trust to remain open towards the future of our respective and reciprocal development in interdependent freedom, relationships of trust can be understood as an implied dialogue about trust, not merely as a constant dialogue in trust between us (we confide to each other, judge each other critically, etc.), but where the meaningfulness of our bond of trust becomes itself a critical element of the dialogue itself. A relationship of trust unfolds as much as a dialogue in trust as a dialogue about the trust of which it always speaks; about how we are to trust each other, measure and expand its limits, and make adjustments, and, when betrayed, its breakages, ruptures, and aftermaths. When conceived in its dialogical form, trust between individuals is not, contra Luhmann (1979), a mechanism for the reduction of psychological complexity, but, on the contrary, an allowance and affordance for the exploration and negotiation of complexity within the hold of assurance. Exploring and determining the possibilities of trust are entrusted to the relationship of trust itself. Although much of how we trust is prescribed by the modal specification of our relationship and assessment of the Other’s trustworthiness (we trust the doctor in ways prescribed by the profession, etc.), there is intrinsically no “concept” or “set of rules” that prescribes exhaustively the ways in which trust must navigate the course of living with the Other which trust makes possible. Trust always entails a creative impetus regarding how to sustain trust and explore, in living, its meaningfulness. Trust must trust in its own capacity to prescribe for itself how best to nourish and nurture itself, even when trust is (partly) prescribed by its modal specification, cultural heritage, and symbolic forms. This self-prescribing element of trust reflects how paradigmatic cases of non-reflective trust are sui generis and essentially without specifiable genealogy or origin. Whereas we are amazed at how suddenly and knowingly trust becomes broken, the inaugural dawning and accruing of trust is much less clear and distinct in its origin and progression. Gaining and nurturing trust is akin to the slow inflation of a balloon. When trust becomes betrayed, it is akin to a violently bursting balloon, all at once. The puncture, however, does not come from the outside, but from within, given that the Other has lined my subjectivity in trust. The wounding of betrayal runs deep and catches us from behind, from where we thought our backs were covered. In trusting each Other, we must trust in the possibilities of trust’s consideration and allowance, which are not clearly and distinctly prescribed or ordained ahead of time. These possibilities of trust depend on knowing who we are to become together in trust. The possibilities of trust are entrusted to the relation of trust itself. In this regard, trust functions as dialogical relationship in Mikhail Bakhtin’s sense: a dialogue in which the meaningfulness of the dialogue becomes itself a critical element in the dialogue itself. The dialogical relationship of trust contains through three positions: me, the Other, and the self-understanding of the relationship itself, its meaningfulness for us. As Bakhtin elaborates his conception of dialogue: Understanding itself enters as a dialogic element in the dialogic system and somehow changes its total sense. The person who understands inevitably becomes a third party in the dialogue (…) but the dialogical position of this third party is a quite special one. Any utterance always has an addressee (…) whose responsive understanding the author of the speech work seeks and surpasses. This is the second party (…) But in addition to this addressee (the second party), the author of the utterance, with a greater or lesser awareness, presupposes a higher superaddressee (third), whose absolutely just responsive understanding is presumed, in some metaphysical distance or in distant historic time. (Bakhtin 1986, 126) 529
Nicolas de Warren
In the case of trust in its paradigmatic form as mutual trust between individuals, the position of the third must remain unclaimed and unoccupied by either of the parties in the bond of trust. This autonomy of the relation of trust does not mean that none of the entrusted parties can speak for and from the position of the third. We are each keepers of the trust without any one of us becoming the lord of the trust. As a dialogical relationship, this position of the third is an “extra-location,” or transcendent opening, that must remain open towards the future and as the future. This “extra-location” is the “where-in” of the trusting relationship’s meaningfulness where we can encounter each other, bound to each other, as entrusted to each other. The meaningfulness of trust cannot become instrumentalized or manipulated for the gain of one for the ruin of the Other. When trust becomes the conduit to my ruin, when I am deceived in trust, this position of the third becomes claimed by the person who deceives me; he plays at trust all the while understanding what this relation is about, which I do not see, believing that this place is edged, neither mine nor his, but open. When trust turns against me, the position of the third has been seized from within, thus producing a split-vision of the relationship of trust. The Confidence Man runs a certain narrative of our trust while I run a different narrative; both narratives fail to touch each other and communicate. The dialogue has been severed. When I realize in hindsight that my trust was geared against me, my established perception and narrative of our trust becomes voided from the inside: I was playing a part in a game that I did not perceive and understand, and trust both blinded me to and captured me within this game. The betrayal of trust often provokes pronounced incredulity on the side of the betrayed individual. That the Other would have betrayed me seems unimaginable and unfathomable. Something profound in me has been broken: I no longer know who it is in whom I trusted. I no longer know who I am to have trusted. This existential plunge of betrayal attests to the existential depth of trust in the formation of self-assuredness. Even when registering and suffering the dissimulation of trust, betrayed individuals can nonetheless cling to their trust in the Other to the point of over-trust despite revealed untrustworthiness. Compromised trust has a way of calling the trust of the betrayed person more into question than that of the betrayer, as if the accusation of unfaithfulness to the bond of trust rebounded back onto the individual betrayed. Because trust involves the assurance of benefit—achieving a goal, upholding a value, etc.—we often find ourselves still wanting to believe in the Other by virtue of still wanting to believe what our relation of trust promised us. Our wanting to believe becomes all the more intense given the sown seed of doubt which becomes transplanted into our own self-trust. We become blind to the Other’s failing of our trust and turn to accuse ourselves instead, thus allowing ourselves, in the most pathological cases, to enter even more into the spell of the Other’s machinations and duplicity. Over-trust has a way of inducing a critical blindness often coupled with the leveraging of fear. Over-trust trumps over its misplaced excess through the incitement of fear of losing what an empty trust promises but cannot in fact deliver. The fear of losing what trust promises but cannot deliver inflates trust to over-trust. We desperately want to believe and allow ourselves too much trust. The mongering of fear covers-over and motivates the misplaced trust of over-trust: in fearing the disaster said to come, we throw ourselves more willingly (and blindly) to the promise of a protection in fact never needed, and once we have given ourselves over to overtrust, we cannot let go for fear of having no where or no one else to trust. Demagogues, like the trickster, thrive from trust upon which they themselves stand at the expense of all others.
Note 1 I shall omit, not from neglect, but for reasons of prudence and space, trust in God (and deities) as well as trust in pets and domesticated animals.
530
Trust
References Baier, Annette (1986). Trust and Antitrust. Ethics 96(2), 231–260. ——— (1995). Moral Prejudices. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Bakhtin, Mikhail (1986). Speech Genres and Other Late Essays. Transl. by V. McGee. Austin: University of Texas Press. Bok, Sissela (1978). Lying. New York: Vintage. de Warren, Nicolas (2017). Souls of the Departed: Towards a Phenomenology of the after-Life. Metodo 5(1), 205–237. Erikson, Erik (1963). Childhood and Society. New York: Norton & Company. Hartmann, Martin (2011). Die Praxis des Vertrauens. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Hosking, Geoffrey (2014). Trust. A History. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Jones, Karen (1996). Trust as Affective Attitude. Ethics 107(1), 4–25. Luhmann, Niklas (1979). Trust and Power. Transl. by H. Davies. Cambridge: Polity Press. Misztal, Barbara (1996). Trust in Modern Societies. Cambridge: Polity Press. Ricoeur, Paul (1992). Oneself as Other. Transl. by K. Blamey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Schmitz, Hermann (2014). Atmosphären. Munich: Alber. ——— (1969). System der Philosophie. Vol. 3/2: Der Gefühlsraum. Bonn: Bouvier. Schütz, Alfred (1964). Collected Papers. Vol. II. Studies in Social Theory. Den Hague: Nijhof. Simmel, Georg (1978). The Philosophy of Money. London, New York: Routledge. Sloterdijk, Peter (2011). Spheres. Transl. by W. Hoban. Cambridge, MA: Semiotext(e). Steinbock, Anthony J. (2014). Moral Emotions. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press. Tilly, Charles (2005). Trust and Rule. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Further reading Hawley, Katherine (2012). Trust. A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. McGeer, Victoria (2002). Developing Trust. Philosophical Explorations 5(1), 21–38. Pettit, Philip (1995). The Cunning of Trust. Philosophy & Public Affairs 24(3), 202–225. Solomon, Robert C., and Flores, Fernando (2003). Building Trust: In Business, Politics, Relationships, and Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
531
45 FEELING SOLIDARITY Jan Müller
Solidarity concerns the social bond, the complex amalgam of emotional relations towards other persons and groups: sympathy of various forms, but also commitment to a conviction and to those people and groups (supposedly) sharing this conviction, an emotional investment in a cause or an idea. “Solidarity” denotes an attitude one holds or a stance one takes, and so a disposition to act. The attitude of solidarity is realized in solidary action, and ideas of solidarity are invoked to provide practical reasons: someone may demand assistance from another who, if this alleged affiliation holds, is obliged by her solidary attitude towards the claimant (cf. Margalit 2011, 177). These aspects characterize the word’s ordinary uses, where solidarity sometimes takes on the moral guise of a virtue or an intrinsically valuable idea; at the same time, references to solidarity are decried as merely “ideological” appeals—for instance when it is dubious whether an affiliation with a group (which might have constituted reasons for action) actually exists. In this chapter, I will proceed in three steps. First, I will address the problem that the various uses of “solidarity” (and their conceptual relatives) always take some cue from the term’s conceptual history. “Solidarity” essentially functions as a polemical term that inevitable raises issues of social membership, and does so against the backdrop of historically intertwined political and legal discourses. Second, I will argue that the phenomenal content of the attitude and experiences of solidarity is conceptually linked to concerns of emotional affiliation and group membership. Moreover, it is a shared emotion that essentially answers to reasons. Third, I shall conclude that solidarity plays a crucial role in bridging the gap between the partiality of emotional attachment and the universal claims of (moral) obligations.
1. What’s at stake: solidarity’s promise The difficulty of an unequivocal account of solidarity stems from both the idea’s and the phenomenon’s history, tracing back to Roman law and to early modern models of the constitution of society and the social bond, respectively (cf. Bayertz 1999 and esp. Wildt 1999). In Roman law, a “solidary debt” denotes a special form of loan agreement: Partners in some joint endeavor enter into a contract with a creditor that renders the partners liable, each on her own and jointly together, for the whole of their debt (cf. Bayertz 1999, 3). Solidary debts are thus constitutive of a group: The contractual relation effects that the debtors figure 532
Feeling solidarity
as a collective addressee of their creditor, or are “at one in their exposure to the creditor” only when the debtors cannot fulfil their individual, distributive obligation (Wiggins 2009, 252). The legal institution of solidary debt ensures claims to an equal relationship between partners in case that their relationship becomes, in fact, unequal, when one of the partners defaults upon their explicitly pre-arranged obligation and the other steps in. But it also serves as a paradigm case for modelling obligations between persons by reference to the social and legal connections between them: To be solidary towards another or a group is to be motivated to act (and to act accordingly) in support, or for the benefit of others because they are in peril, and in virtue of one’s particular relation to them. The institution of solidary serves as a model for the fact that other people’s needs may constitute an obligation; however, this model relies upon an already existing obligation (namely, to honor one’s agreement). Its “direction of fit” explains the meaning of solidarity by reference to the contractually constituted obligation between creditors; but the attitude of solidarity and the obligations it illustrates exist only after the partners have entered into the legal relationship. In contrast, in modern social and political thought, references to solidarity allude to the idea that a normatively viable social bond is always already in place. According to this model, solidarity pre-dates and is itself constitutive of normative social relations: Persons are conceived to be mutually obliged in virtue of their solidarity. It reacts to the demise of traditional theological and metaphysical justifications of social hierarchies by substituting them with references to “natural” relations. Pre-given mutual normative relations are no longer attributed to divine commandments, but to family relations: Members of a social group are conceived to be connected as if by kinship.1 In the wake of the bourgeois revolutions the idea of solidarity finally champions even these analogies by substituting “kinship” with the idea of a “human fraternity” (cf. Brunkhorst 2002, 76). Ever since, the idea of solidarity purports to answer a dilemma in modern political imagination: When traditional (religious, metaphysic) forms of social cohesion loose authority, it becomes unclear how the pursuit of individual ends can be reconciled with the interests and rights of others. On the one hand, models of “natural affiliation” suggest themselves; such views, however, underrate the pivotal role of individuality (and hence of conflict) in modern forms of life and thus tend to reproduce bygone social institutions, promoting tribalism instead of providing adequate means to navigate life in functionally differentiated societies. Individual interests and pursuits are not only bound to collide; the development of individuality positively requires some relative non-compliance with the similarities in judgement and conduct that constitute a form of life. Conflict stems not from an accidental malfunction of the social fabric; it is constitutive of its proper functioning (cf. Hampshire 1991).2 On the other hand, the fragility of social cohesion cannot be mended by moral reasoning alone. Social relations are typically thick, embedded in tangible interpersonal conduct and facilitated by narratives, and this thickness needs to be accounted for, not merely dismissed as a relic of traditional ways of life. Moral thought, however, by virtue of its generality strives for “thin” reasons which touch our thick interpersonal relationships in the wrong way (cf. Margalit 2001, 139; 2010, 121); they rely on “application of principle” where a “human gesture” would be needed (Williams 1965, 227). With the concomitant reasons being of the wrong kind, it seems puzzling how moral reasoning could ever motivate a “human gesture” towards strangers. The conceptual history of solidarity carries the promise that these two directions of fit can be, in practice, reconciled: that even our conflictual modern social relations may exhibit the “intrinsic value” of “thick” relations like kinship or friendship, which exemplify basic human relations (cf. Margalit 2011, 177). The task, then, is to spell out the idea of a common 533
Jan Müller
humanity not merely as an appeal to loyalty (felt on the basis of some ideology or conviction), nor to typically “thin” universal moral reasoning, but as participation in a jointly pursued and collectively felt endeavor. Hannah Arendt brings out the problematic tension such a feeling must mediate: Solidarity establishes, she writes, a community of interest with the oppressed and exploited (whose) common interest would (…) be (…) the dignity of man. (…) For solidarity, because it partakes of reason, and hence of generality, is able to comprehend a multitude conceptually, not only the multitude of a class or a nation or a people, but eventually all mankind. (Arendt 1963, 88) 3 Solidarity promises that there is, in fact, a feeling that links one to one’s fellow human beings as fellow human beings. But collective feelings are partial, oriented towards a particular group; if solidarity were to be true to its promise, then the phenomenon in question would have to be understood as a collective feeling that not only provides practical reasons, but is also directed towards “all mankind” in virtue of its receptivity to reasons. Solidarity, so understood, would be rooted in actual affective relations and figure in moral thought both as reason-providing and subject to negotiation. Is there such a feeling?
2. What is it to feel solidarity? Solidarity, observes Avishai Margalit, is connected to “a whole gamut of human emotions”, ranging from “mild” and “operative sympathy of moral support” up to “total alignment with a group” (Margalit 2011, 177). Hence, delimitating a distinct “feeling of solidarity” requires to carefully discern it from its cognates, and in particular from loyalty. Solidarity is an intentional reactive attitude4: a mode of answering to a situation emotionally and with an according disposition to act. In solidarity, we perceive a situation as demanding that we help or benefit those we feel solidarity with (the feeling’s “target”) in light of the practice(s) we share (the feeling’s “focus”, both of which—technically speaking—constitute its content) (cf. Schmid 2009, 64). David Heyd accordingly describes solidarity as a “partial”, “local” and “reflective” reactive emotion. Elaborating these characteristics will bring out the differences between solidarity and its cognates, and explain why solidarity essentially is a shared emotion.
2.1 A partial and reflective emotion Solidarity is directed “towards some restricted group of people” (Heyd 2015, 56): One feels solidarity with someone. The feeling’s content is individuated in virtue of this partiality, which entails, first, identifying with the person or group one is solidary with, and second, “being discriminate, leaning to a particular point of view or interest (rather than being impartial)” (Heyd 2015, 57). The feeling’s partiality stems from the determinacy of its formal object. It is a reaction to a particular situation: a member of one’s own peer group is (say) in need of assistance, and one finds oneself disposed to act as befits the circumstances. Many other reactive attitudes are partial, too: Sympathetic pity, for example, is restricted to particular addressees, and resolution of their pitiable circumstances typically also brings one’s feeling-with-them to an end. Affection, to give another example, is qualified by the particular person one feels affection for, so that one is provided with special practical reasons through adopting the other’s point of view. Solidarity, however, is partial in a different sense. 534
Feeling solidarity
Though it typically occurs in specific situations, its link to these situations is not merely causal, but also conceptual. Unlike simpler forms of sympathy such as pity, solidarity need not dissolve with changing circumstances, but may effect a change in the way situations are perceived and evaluated in the future. The feeling of solidarity with, say, members of the working class is partial in that it is tethered to its history. But with time, solidarity can transcend the specific type of situation it originally responded to. Like other more complex forms of feeling-with such as affection or love, feeling solidarity involves the establishment of mutual sharedness; and since solidarity issues not merely in feeling but in action, it is not simply rooted in some (type of ) local situation (though it does by its very form refer back to it), but in shared practices, which constitute, change and eventually transform the situations one reacts to. Hence, solidarity can be practiced and trained, and responsiveness to situational affordances be developed. Feeling affinity with a group constitutes the frame in which situations reveal their affordances, and this frame is not simply given but emerges from a subject’s previous engagement, from the history of its thought and conduct (cf. Wollheim 1980, 313). Thus, solidarity is “typically mediated by thought and belief ” (Heyd 2015, 59). It is reflective above and beyond the judgment form emotions in general bear.5 Solidarity is positively defined by its relation to communicative practices of reason which provides the feeling’s intentional scope, and constitutes the frame in which situations figure in practical reasoning.6 Two aspects here deserve attention. First, solidarity contains a reflexive attitude towards oneself. Feeling solidary with particular people presupposes not only having beliefs about them; it implies knowledge of one’s own attitude towards and relation with them.7 In thoughts accompanying feelings of solidarity, oneself is represented as belonging to those one reacts solidarily towards. Second, this dependence on thought implies responsiveness to reason. The framing which both facilitates and is itself reproduced by feeling solidarity is not impervious to scrutiny; for precisely because it relies on explicit and articulate beliefs, it is susceptible to doubt and in perpetual need of rational reassurance in practices of giving and receiving reasons. In feeling solidarity towards a group, one not only believes the shared project to be worthwhile but takes these beliefs to be justified. Hence, one cannot rest content with mere “ideological” convictions to support one’s feeling of solidarity. Solidarity demands justifying reasons for its partiality; the normative distinction between rational, justified solidarity, and misled or mistaken solidarity is internal to it. Consider, by contrast, how feeling loyal to one’s sibling, too, is mediated by beliefs about one’s relation to them. These beliefs, however, figure as reasons regardless of their appropriateness; they are reasons not for the partiality of one’s feeling, but in virtue of it; the reasons’ scope is restricted to the internal perspective of a presupposed group.8 Solidarity, on the other hand, relates to the group not merely from within, without questioning the group’s internal normative fabric, for in a solidary attitude one typically assumes the intrinsic good and the we-group’s internal normative fabric to also be externally justifiable. The feeling is subject to an unrestricted claim of reason which may, during the feeling’s continual development, even devaluate one’s initial emotional response in light of new reasons.9 In loyalty, the partiality of one’s views aligns with and corresponds to the feeling’s partial focus; in solidarity, however, the partial focus of one’s feeling may be challenged by the scope of reasoning, which contributes to its very form and content. Loyalty is unabashedly partisan; solidarity’s partiality is both a property and a challenge. They differ in how they relate their subjects to the group: In both feelings, the group is represented as a we-group united by a shared concern (cf. Tuomela 2013, 27). But relations of loyalty are typically asymmetric: A loyal person subordinates herself to the we-group’s internal rules and judgments; she momentarily relinquishes her autonomy by accepting the partial reasons 535
Jan Müller
her feeling of loyalty provides. Correspondingly, she relates differently to the we-group’s internal good: loyalty implies that she, if only momentarily and implicitly, simply accepts it as always already justified. In feeling solidarity, the we-group is represented not as a normative authority the subject (if only momentarily) merely submits to, but actualizes in mutual and symmetric relations between the members. Other members are represented in her attitude not merely as its objects, but as subject-objects who actively contribute to it. They are not related immediately (as in simpler forms of sympathy), but mediated by thought in a way that, potentially, demands explicit and articulate justification.
2.2 Sharing solidarity How, then, is solidarity shared? To share a feeling is neither, to merely imagine another’s feeling, nor to have a feeling whose content accidentally matches the content of another’s feeling. If A and B both feel aggrieved over the death of a friend, their parallel feelings are not shared; if A, in an empathetic imaginative re-enactment, indeed experiences B’s grief, she still does not share in it, for she lacks the appropriate emotional responses. Shared feeling, by contrast, implies that both A’s and B’s grief is not only directed at the same object, but also at each other’s grief, and hence non-accidentally aligned (cf. Krebs 2013, 190, 194f.; 2015, chap. II.1.; see also Chapters 40 and 49 in this volume). Both their feelings target the same intentional object in the same intentional mode—namely, as shared; and this intentional focus, since it includes reference to the other subject’s feeling, accounts for the nature of their bond.10 A feels what she herself feels in virtue of B’s feeling (and conversely), so that both experience a feeling “whose sense is not an aggregate of isolated individual feelings, but a unity of sense pervading the contributing individual feelings” (Krebs 2013, 185; own transl.). For all intents and purposes, both experience the same emotional reaction in light of which they experience themselves as associated members. Such feeling implies consciousness of sharing; members experience their reactions as defined by both their own and the other’s contribution. “The relationship of the communal experience to the individual experience”, writes Edith Stein, “is constitution, not summation” (Stein 2010, 122).11 Experience of such community ineluctably changes the normative relation between its members: New practical reasons for mutual engagement emerge from it, however brief the actual communal alignment of feelings; for it requires to refer to our conduct “as ours”, to ourselves as parts of a “we”.12 Our individual behavior is oriented differently now, for it also maintains and develops “us”, our shared relation. Community neither befalls us, nor is it simply pre-given; being “parasitic to” and facilitated by shared action (Krebs 2015, 221; own transl.), it is essentially a project or a task. Stein’s analysis suggests that this is a general feature of shared feeling. Consider her example of a military unit’s members mourning their leader: First, their grief is experienced collectively by being informed by the grief of all the group’s members. An individual member’s grief may be “quite a private content”, but it claims—by virtue of its sense—“to count for (…) something subsisting objectively, through which it is rationally substantiated (…) the loss of the leader”.13 In virtue of this “objective correlate”, the “sense-content” of the individual feelings is “idealiter the same” in collective feeling, “notwithstanding the private clothing it bears at any given time” (Stein 2010, 115): It is merely exemplified individually. Second, the experience of such communal feeling is not “instantaneous. It develops in a continuity of experiencing”, during which “a whole series of currents of consciousness contributes to its coalescence” (ibid.). It is as much a process, as it is realized and retained in momentary individual emotional responses. Third, the individual responses’ interconnectedness not only 536
Feeling solidarity
enables that “the sense of the grief ” can be experienced, “in principle, by any member” of the group; it is positively “required of the unit as such and of everyone that belongs to it” (ibid.). The feeling’s specific content exerts a normative force, because an individual can realize the shared collective stance more or less “appropriately”, and even fail; conversely, a collective feeling’s specific content may be realized even if only one group member reacts appropriately ‘in the name of the unit’ (…). The experiences of the others aren’t eliminated by this. They all share in the assembling of the communal experience; but that which was intended in all of them came to fulfillment in the experience of this one alone. (Ibid.) This subject’s feeling comes to fruition in her stance and her actions, which are in turn judged against the collective feeling’s content. Feeling collectively is a practice: Individuals accomplish their contributions more or less well, with the collective feeling’s content constituting their internal normative standard. But this implies that shared feeling is mediated not only by the individuals’ reactive attitudes, but also by their thought and action. For example, the soldiers’ collective grief presupposes an idea of “fulfillment”, of what it is to feel and behave appropriately in their loss,14 an idea of which individual reaction towards one’s fellow grievers and the shared grief is “rationally required” (ibid.). Such an idea makes explicit the normative fabric of the group, not least by outlining what members can claim from each other in the process of further developing and perfecting their communal relations. In solidarity, then, a subject reacts to other’s plight with the disposition to help, or to another’s actions with the desire to join in, where her apperception of other subjects and their situation is mediated by (a) her thought about a valuable relation that exists between them in virtue of being group members, (b) about the other subject’s appreciation of this relation, and (c) her own and the other subject’s feeling as beneficial to their respective happiness and to the group’s flourishing. These beliefs constitute the idea of what it is to fulfill solidarity’s intention, its “rational requirement:” What I must demand of myself in order to fulfill my feeling’s intention, what I may demand from the other members of my solidary group; and finally, what addressees of our solidarity may rationally expect from us. My solidary attitude is held and facilitated by the aligned attitudes of others, together aggregating the collective perspective which, in turn, accounts for its individual constituents’ appropriateness. In sharing solidarity, we are continually re-evaluating our reactions and actions in light of the shared feeling’s intention and in light of the relation to our solidary comrades. Again, it is tempting to confound this with feeling loyalty; but Stein’s model highlights how different the idea of community appears in each attitude. In loyalty, the we-group is presupposed as pre-given, independent of its internal normative fabric’s actual justification.15 In solidarity, however, the we-group is not simply represented as pre-given; community (and the joy of it) is intended.16 Hence, Stein’s model allows for community to evolve from assumptions of community that are later unmasked as imaginary, or manifest in only one representative who, by fulfilling the collective feeling’s intention, nonetheless made it possible for others to join in. A feeling of community may be rooted in shared feelings, while its evaluation is still a matter of bitter dispute over who owes whom what kind of assistance, and in light of which tangible end. The initial nucleus of a collective feeling may even be a mere wish, if that wish (at first accidentally) aligns with the attitudes of others, in light of which unity an individual feeling retrospectively appears as already having exemplified the evolving community: “The wish, and the action that carries it through to fulfillment”, then will have joined 537
Jan Müller
in the unity of one experiential coherence; and if they owe their origin to different subjects, then there exists between those subjects an experienced solidarity which (…) makes it possible for them to [work] together toward one achievement. Thus, motivations of different kinds can spread from one individual to the other, making it possible for super-individual experiential unities to arise. (Stein 2010, 144) Stein’s use of “solidarity” shows that it is, indeed, fitting to ascribe an aspect of solidarity to any collective feeling and action,17 for they exhibit solidarity’s mode of reference to oneself and other as members of a group. However, this mode is fully explicit only when the reactive attitude is accompanied by the appropriate thoughts. The promise associated with the notion of solidarity is always already rooted in experiences of community, but it needs explication in terms of a responsiveness to reasons whose claim is not restricted by a given group’s normative fabric. But then negotiations about how well an individual contribution fulfills the feeling’s intention, how well individual guises of solidarity align, is always open to critique and discussion. Put differently: Precisely because “the solidarity of individuals (…) is formative of community in the highest”—and the most explicit—“degree”, the subjects’ attitudes towards each other in light of their common pursuit are fragile, subject to scrutiny, and in need of rational elucidation. “Where the individuals are ‘open’ to one another, where the attitudes of one (…) penetrate him and deploy their efficacy”, writes Stein, “there the two are members of one whole” (Stein 2010, 177). Solidarity proper requires this efficacy to not unfold blindly, as a mere passive experience, but in a way that enables participants to inquire after its reasonableness (cf. Gaita 1999, 279). In feeling solidarity, a subject’s reactive attitude is not only factually a judgement about its addressee in light of their association but is typically accompanied by thoughts fit to justify her stance.18 One feels and acts solidary from reasons, which claim that this form of comradeship is, indeed, intrinsically good (and not merely taken to be so by its loyal participants).
3. Solidarity’s morality Feeling solidarity seems restricted to tangible, particular others. Hence, reasons from solidarity seem to bear only on the “morally significant relation between members of a community” (Derpmann 2014, 90). Members of a community do not feel solidarity neutrally; the experiential mode of their relations is—the feeling’s “private clothing” (Stein 2010, 115) notwithstanding—emotionally charged: I recognize my comrades not “on the basis of certain common moral characteristics” perceived as if from an impartial neutral standpoint, but from the participant’s perspective, which draws from a “significance in the commonalities themselves” (Derpmann 2014, 90), from the experienced history of our relation. Yet precisely because it entails being emotionally invested, the experience of solidary sharedness with its internal rational requirement bridges a gap between partial feelings and the general claims of morality. It contains an always already emotionally charged orientation towards such claims and duties. Such an understanding of solidarity as a “root of morality” seems to clash with its intention: Its experience exemplifies ever only partial community. We may understand how normative convictions can be motivationally effective in light of the emotional ties between us; but apparently, other people are excluded from the feeling’s reach and scope. Solidarity is, of course, “an essentially political attitude” (Heyd 2015, 58): One cannot inquire after the quality of an individual contribution to a joint feeling without negotiating the group’s identity, its common good, and its terms of membership19; and such 538
Feeling solidarity
a unifying cause is “always in some competition, or at least contrast, with other causes (…,) often involving rivalry with or a fight against other groups” (ibid.). Note how the subtle shift from “partiality” to “competition” (however understandable in light of the fact that, historically, invocations of solidarity seem indigenous to situations of political strife) results in a picture of solidarity as essentially confrontational. But there is a difference between conceiving of a joint endeavor so that it may entail actions that clash with opposing endeavors, and conceiving of the same joint endeavor as defined (primarily) by its aggressive opposition against an antagonist. In the first case, the respective attitude is directed primarily at my comrades and our joint well-being; that it may entail resistance against our adversaries is derivative. The second case emphasizes the conflict; any relation to the other group members draws from a shared enmity (or opposition, or competition). Solidarity’s partiality would be irreconcilable with morality if understood only in the second sense; then my felt solidarity towards my comrades could oblige me to deny our opponents what we morally owe them. But we should refrain from even calling this a case of (even “misled”)20 solidarity: First, such joint feeling could not rationally require us to also negotiate the ends of our joint endeavor; quite contrary, shared enmity is presupposed 21 and, strictly, not up for debate, lest the group’s existence be jeopardized. Second, such a reactive attitude would surely miss the point of feeling solidarity towards comrades, viz. that we perceive them to be in need of assistance. That assisting them often entails civilized conflict with and, in extreme cases, resistance against opposing agents is another matter entirely.22 Thus, solidarity is a partial emotion, but it is exclusive only accidentally, and, in virtue of its rational requirements, cannot but struggle with these excluding effects. The experience of its partiality is one of situatedness (cf. Schürmann 2010, 1913b): Feeling solidarity with a group as particular prompts an understanding that this partiality comes down to mere unavoidable contingent facts. These facts explain, but cannot justify our feeling’s partiality; they just put a factual restriction on an intention that rationally ought, but factually cannot reach farther. In this experience, feelings of solidarity, indeed, are a “root of the ethical”. They show how our reactive attitude towards others always already exhibit a, however partial, practical recognition of others as bearing “human form”: for “even if the solidarity of the human may appear from some angles indiscernible from the kind of fellow feeling that is special to the group, the thing that it points to is something which has always transcended the group” (Wiggins 2009, 260). This is not to say that we “as humans” (by virtue of, say, our nature) were necessarily disposed to feel solidary towards members of our species.23 It draws merely from the observation that, as a contingent matter of fact, we do share feelings in solidary groups, which may well originate, as Stein argued, in accidental alignments of individual intentions or the spark of an individual wish. But the mere fact that we have experienced sharing, and in sharing solidarity, have opened our feeling to rational critique, has irreversibly changed the landscape of our practices (cf. Strawson 1962; Wiggins 2009, 264). It has established a rational requirement against which feelings of solidarity, their partiality and their urge towards fulfillment in community, are measured. Of course, relations of solidarity, facilitated by emotional bonds, can never aspire to morality’s universal validity. But they support the sort of meaningful “thick” relations and practices which only make social realization and implementation of morality’s claims conceivable. Solidarity, writes David Wiggins, is “not itself a human pursuit (…), not a way of arriving at something else”, but “a way of being (…). The role of solidarity is to condition, to civilize and to humanize ordinary human pursuits” (Wiggins 2009, 265). This role is not presupposed in but achieved through experiences of shared solidarity. The modern idea of solidarity retrospectively spells out the intention of such experiences, not by generalizing their partial claim in the abstract (as in naïve appeals to 539
Jan Müller
“solidarity with all of mankind”), but by translating the idea’s internal tension into an ethical task. Solidary goodness demands to orient one’s contributions to collectively felt solidarity towards the maturation of local communities; keeping them as inclusive as humanly possible, as responsive to reason as practically feasible. Each experience of collective solidarity proper points, by virtue of this intention, to the conjunction and interconnection of potentially uncounted partial solidary communities (cf. Scholz 2008, 246; Derpmann 2013, 205). The idea of a universal principle of human solidarity is unintelligible. But so is the idea that any human agent be, in principle, excluded from jointly felt solidarity.24
Notes 1 Such models of natural affiliation, however, are limited not only by the fact that they notoriously fail to value neighbors or strangers just as one’s siblings; moreover, they, too, rely on metaphysical presuppositions to back up their normative claims; cf. Derrida (1994, Chap. 9). 2 Cf. Durkheim’s corresponding distinction between pre-modern “mechanical” solidarity and “organic” solidarity under conditions of the modern distribution of labor (Durkheim 1902, 101f.). 3 Arendt takes great care to distinguish solidarity from pity; cf. Chapter 15 in this volume. For the benefit of this demarcation, Arendt often talks of “solidarity” as a “deliberate” and even “dispassionate” attitude (cf. Arendt 1963, 88). This, however, is just an exaggeration to repel sentimentalist interpretations; surely it would run against Arendt’s intention to sever emotion from solidarity and take the later to be a merely cognitive attitude. 4 Cf. Strawson (1962). Such attitudes are, as all emotions proper, intentional in the sense that they are directed towards their (logical-grammatical) objects; cf. Goldie (1999, 395). 5 The precise manner in which emotions bear the form of judgements is notoriously contended; cf. Vendrell Ferran (2015, 495), and the discussion in Schmid (2014, esp. 8f.). Understanding emotions as instantaneous judging attitudes does not entail ascribing some factual, psychological act of judging to a subject; however, it is equally misleading to posit some immediate a-rational “ feeling-sensation” which is only retrospectively fitted with judgmental content. Rather, the feeling sensation irreducibly is the mode in which the judgment’s content is given (its Fregean sense, if you will; cf. Kenny 1963, 46). 6 This aspect sometimes serves to discredit the whole notion of “solidarity” as a mere ideological ploy to hijack traditional models of “thick” relationships (cf. Capaldi 1999). Such simple substitution, however, conflates solidarity with “Kitsch solidarity” (Margalit 2011, 174) or simple loyalty. 7 This distinguishes solidarity among the family of phenomena Richard Wollheim calls “moral emotion”. Moral emotions are “reflexive”: they are an attitude towards oneself as a person ( Wollheim 1999, 149); in solidarity, this attitude towards oneself includes, necessarily, the relation of oneself and other people. 8 The very fact that the group shares some common good suffices; further inquiry may even be taken as mistrust in or dissidence from the group. 9 Talk of “false” or “mistaken” loyalty, by contrast, does not concern the reactive attitude itself (or the loyalty one feels) but the accompanying beliefs and conviction; not one’s loyalty, but one’s sense of loyalty is mistaken. 10 Hence, Szanto (2015, 507) speaks of “supra-individual” intentions. 11 All citations from Stein’s work are my own translation. Stein’s model in many ways builds upon Max Scheler’s model of joint feeling; cf. Krebs’s contribution to this volume. 12 Use of the pronoun “we” here cannot be taken to refer to some mysterious “collective consciousness”, or the specter of a “collective subject”. It refers to persons in light of their relations; cf. Krebs (2011, 196); Schmid (2009, 32); Szanto (2015, 506). 13 Precision is needed here: The feeling is directed towards “the squad leader”, not “my commanding officer;” to represent her so in thought is already to conceive of her in relation to a group (whereas “my commanding officer” represented her, primarily, in relation to me). 14 Of course, such an idea in turn presupposes beliefs about military decorum, etc. There is some discussion whether such presupposition of thought ought to be modeled after explicit, “reflective” consciousness, or after a more implicit “awareness”. For present purposes, it suffices to understand that the idea of a collective feeling’s proper fulfillment implies a capacity to articulate
540
Feeling solidarity
15 16
17
18
19
20 21 22
23
24
and judge the goodness of one’s contribution to it—even if a subject’s consciousness of these presuppositions in phenomenal experience may be gradually obscured by “private clothing”; cf. Szanto (2015, 507). Consider the zombie obedience which may appear “rationally required” from the internal viewpoint of a Mafia family, or the loyalty “rationally required” from within a romantic relation— independent from the existence (or alarming lack of ) external reasons. Naturally, collective feelings never occur on some fictional “clean slate” but always already partake in a communal history. Still, solidarity is essentially directed towards some future end; it is a project as much as a process. Margalit (2011, 177) helpfully distinguishes solidarity “of fate”, arising from an accidentally shared history or situation, from a solidarity “of destiny”, directed towards the group’s development or a common endeavor, and shows the necessary interdependence of both perspectives (lest solidarity wither to reactionary, tribalist or nativist claims). That is to say, it is appropriate to ask of any shared feeling and action “what about it is solidary”, without ascribing to their subjects an explicit attitude of solidarity. Note how Stein’s model does not presuppose some pre-given solidarity which, as it were, gave rise to community; rather, solidarity and other shared feelings emerge equiprimordially. This rather special phenomenon is probably a paradigm case for Margret Gilbert’s model. Gilbert highlights the shared commitment implicit in sharing feelings (as well as joint actions) (cf. e.g., Gilbert 2002, 125), where “being committed” to do or feel A is “is to have sufficient reason to A (…). Thus, being committed is a normative rather than a psychological matter” (Gilbert 2014, 24). Solidarity is “political” because it implies reference to the group’s makeup both from within and from without, and thus situates the group—a limine—within the framework of social relations, or the body politic. But this is not to say that feelings of solidarity pertain only to the “public sphere”. There is felt solidarity “in private” as well: with friends, partners and lovers; “political” is not synonymous with “public”, if the latter is contrasted to “private”. Cf., e.g., Derpmann (2013, 204). “Misled solidarity” is mistaking, e.g., loyalty for solidarity. That their experiential quality can, at times, be nigh indistinguishable may account for mistaken self-perception, but does not touch upon their differing claims to reason. It may even require of me to subscribe to the rule that “my enemy’s enemies are my friends”. It would be quite absurd to hold that solidarity required me to extend the reach of my feeling towards someone simply by virtue of the fact we share an enemy. Consider how jointly pulling a cart from a muddy patch on the road includes “opposing the mud” and is, in this sense, “directed against the mud” which took hold of our cart. Yet the intention of our action is indifferent towards the mud as such; it plays no role of its own in it. So it is with class struggle. Simon Derpmann understands Wiggins’s talk of “human” merely descriptively; hence he believes that Wiggins’ model of solidarity “cannot accommodate (…) the moral significance of the reference to the agent and her relations to those others to whom she is morally obliged” (Derpmann 2014, 94). However, “human” is not a merely descriptive, but a normative notion: Negotiation of what counts as “human” implies reference to the agent and her affiliates; cf. Wiggins (2009, 264). For an elaboration of this thought, cf. Adamczak (2017, 270f ).
References Adamczak, Bini (2017). Beziehungsweise Revolution. 1917, 1968 und kommende. Berlin: Suhrkamp. Arendt, Hannah (1973[1963]). On Revolution. London: Penguin. Bayertz, Kurt (1999). Four Uses of “Solidarity”. In: K. Bayertz (Ed.). Solidarity. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 3–28. Brunkhorst, Hauke (2005[2002]). Solidarity. From Civic Friendship to a Global Legal Community. Transl. by J. Flynn. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press 2005. Capaldi, Nicolas (1999). What’s Wrong with Solidarity? In: K. Bayertz (Ed.). Solidarity. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 39–56. Derpmann, Simon (2013). Gründe der Solidarität. Münster: Mentis. ——— (2014). Solidarity, Moral Recognition, and Communality. In: A. Laitinen and A. B. Pessi (Eds.). Solidarity. Theory and Practice. Lanham: Lexington, 83–97. Derrida, Jacques (2005[1994]). The Politics of Friendship. Transl. by G. Collins. London: Verso.
541
Jan Müller Durkheim, Émile (2013[1902]). The Division of Labour in Society. Ed. and with a new introduction by S. Lukes. Transl. by W. D. Halls. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Gaita, Raimond (1999). A Common Humanity. Thinking about Love & Truth & Justice. Melbourne: Text. Gilbert, Margaret (2002). Collective Guilt and Collective Guilt Feelings. The Journal of Ethics 6, 11–143. ——— (2014). How We Feel: Understanding Everyday Collective Emotion Ascription. In: C. von Scheve and M. Salmela (Eds.). Collective Emotions. Perspectives from Psychology, Philosophy, and Sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 17–31. Goldie, Peter (1999). How We Think of Other’s Emotions. Mind 14(4), 394–423. Hampshire, Stuart (1991). Justice Is Strife. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 65(3), 19–27. Heyd, David (2015). Solidarity: A Local, Partial and Reflective Emotion. Diametros 43, 55–64. Kenny, Anthony K. (1963). Action, Emotion and Will. London: Routledge and Keagan Paul. Krebs, Angelika (2010). “Vater und Mutter stehen an der Leiche eines geliebten Kindes”. Max Scheler über das Miteinanderfühlen. Allgemeine Zeitschrift für Philosophie 35(1), 9–44. ——— (2013). Wie man Gefühle teilt. / Gefühlsteilung als emotionale Grundkategorie. Eine Antwort auf Jörn Müller. In: I. Günzler and K. Mertens (Eds.). Wahrnehmen, Fühlen, Handeln. Phänomenologie im Wettstreit der Methoden. Münster: Mentis, 185–200, 210–215. ——— (2015). Zwischen Ich und Du. Eine dialogische Philosophie der Liebe. Berlin: Suhrkamp. Margalit, Avishai (2001). Recognition: Recognizing the Brother and the Other. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 71(1), 127–139. ——— (2010). On Compromise and Rotten Compromises. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ——— (2011). Why Are You Betraying Your Class? European Journal of Philosophy 19(2), 171–183. Schmid, Hans Bernhard (2009). Plural Action. Essays in Philosophy and Social Sciences. Dordrecht: Springer. ——— (2014). The Feeling of Being a Group: Corporate Emotions and Collective Consciousness. In: C. von Scheve, and M. Salmela (Eds.). Collective Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3–16. Scholz, Sally (2008). Political Solidarity. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. Schürmann, Volker (2010). Parteilichkeit. In: H. J. Sandkühler (Ed.). Enzyklopädie Philosophie. 3 Vols. Hamburg: Meiner, Vol. 2, col. 1912b–1916b. Stein, Edith (2010[1922]). Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie und der Geisteswissenschaften. Freiburg: Herder. [Engl.: Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities. Transl. by M. C. Baseheart and M. Sawicki. Washington: ICS Publications 2000.] Strawson, Peter F. (1962). Freedom and Resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy 48, 187–211. Szanto, Thomas (2015). Collective Emotions, Normativity, and Empathy: A Steinian Account. Human Studies 38(5), 503–527. Tuomela, Raimo (2013). Social Ontology. Collective Intentionality and Group Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid (2015). Empathy, Emotional Sharing and Feelings in Stein’s Early Work. Human Studies 38(4), 481–502. Wiggins, David (2009). Solidarity and the Root of the Ethical. Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 71, 239–269. Wildt, Andreas (1999). Solidarity: Its History and Contemporary Definition. In: K. Bayertz (Ed.). Solidarity. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 209–221. Williams, Bernard (1973[1965]). Morality and the Emotions. In: Problems of the Self. Philosophical Papers 1956–1972. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 207–229. Wollheim, Richard (1980). On Persons and Their Lives. In: A. Oksenberg Rorty (Ed.). Explaining Emotions. Berkeley: University of California Press, 299–322. ——— (1999). On the Emotions. New Haven: Yale University Press.
542
46 PAIN Fredrik Svenaeus
1. Pain and its relation to emotions We often use the language of pain to point to other forms of suffering than the ones a ssociated with the body, for example: “Her infidelity caused me significant pain.” To avoid misunderstandings, I would like to point out that this chapter will not deal with “mental” pains and suffering but rather focus on the phenomenology of bodily pain. In standard philosophical classifications of feelings, bodily pain is not considered an emotion, since it does not contain any beliefs or judgments about the world in the way that emotions do (Goldie 2000). I am mad, sad, afraid, or happy about something (not) being the case, but when I find myself in pain this intentional structure is not present. Pain is therefore classified as a pre-intentional feeling, which makes (a part of ) the body appear in a specific (painful) way, which does not, however, have a proper meaning content. Bodily sensations can be of the negative sort—pains, itches, feelings of being too hot or cold—or of the positive sort—tickles, feelings of bodily comfort or orgasms—but they do not carry any cognitive content beyond this perceived painfulness or pleasantness of the body (parts). Phenomenology has the potential of improving upon such narrow conceptions of pain by showing how it is a peculiar and many-faced form of embodied experience. To be in pain is not only to perceive parts of one’s body in a certain way but also to feel how the perceived world changes in structure and content. Accordingly, pain can be explored and understood as an embodied mood; a way of finding oneself in the world that typically leads to certain emotions of the negative type: frustration, irritation, anger, fear, sadness, self-pity or even loss of hope and trust in others (Svenaeus 2015, 2017, chap. 2; Kusch and Ratcliffe 2018). Such emotions, that typically occur if pain is intense and long lasting, display beliefs about the situation of the pain sufferer that are nurtured by the bodily affliction. The fact that there exist some rare pathological states that split the hurting feeling from a person’s caring about the pain, and/or the body part that it concerns, does not change the fundamentals of this phenomenological analysis. Patients afflicted by pain asymbolia feel pain without finding it unpleasant, whereas patients suffering from somatoparaphrenia feel the unpleasantness of pain but experience the part of the body that it concerns as alien—that is, as not belonging to them (de Vignemont 2015). Even in such extreme cases, not to mention other rare and fascinating neurological disorders afflicting bodily feelings, the fundamental 543
Fredrik Svenaeus
pathology appears to be related to various ways of not being fully present in one’s own body. The affective space of the lived body—more about this below—is disturbed, and this prevents the patients, not only from experiencing their own embodiment in a full-fledged and non-ambivalent manner but also from experiencing moods that nurture emotions allowing the patients to flourish. Bodily pain is not necessarily a bad thing in every type of situation—it is helpful as an alarm signal that makes us take action to protect ourselves and it can in some situations even be enjoyed—but pain has a profound tendency to involve suffering when intense and/or long lasting. A phenomenological understanding of pain finds support in the official definition elaborated by The International Association for the Study of Pain as: “an unpleasant sensory and emotional experience associated with actual or potential tissue damage, or described in terms of such damage” (https://www.iasp-pain.org/Taxonomy). We will return to the medical view on pain and its causes, but already at this point, it should be underlined that most doctors and other health care professionals treating people with pain acknowledge that pain has an emotional character and that the phenomenologist is able to explain why this is so. The feeling of pain has long fascinated philosophers since it appears to present a person with an experience that it is particularly evident or even incorrigible (it is hard to doubt that one is in pain when feeling so) and at the same time inevitably private and therefore unverifiable (how can we know that a person is not faking and lying when he claims to be in pain?). The phenomenologist would not challenge the evidence of pain but she would point out that to be in pain is not primarily to hold a belief (that I am in pain) but rather to be presented with an overwhelming experience. This is also the clue to disentangling claims about the private character of pain, since human experiences are not only subjective in character, they also take place in a shared space—the everyday world—in which we express things by way of our bodies. It is not only possible to see when other persons are in (intense) pain, it is nearly impossible to doubt that they are so: we feel the pains of other persons (expressing pain) when encountering them. Such feelings are called empathic when they become emotional in the sense of containing beliefs about the other person (the belief that she is in pain). We care not only about our own pains but also about the pains of other persons and such caring may lead to emotions that express pity or sympathy for them just like one’s own pains may lead to emotions like self-pity or loss of hope.
2. Pain as inner perception The first attempts to analyse pain in the phenomenological tradition, made by Carl Stumpf, Franz Brentano and Edmund Husserl around the turn of the last century, are marked by an ambiguity that still pervades present day theories of pain within the analytical tradition of philosophy (for references, see: Geniusas 2014). Is pain a pre-intentional feeling, or is it rather a feeling, which has a content? Another way of phrasing this ambiguity, more amenable to contemporary philosophy, is to ask whether pain is a type of qualia or rather a form of perception (Aydede 2009). Arguably pain is a form of “inner perception,” but does that mean that the experience of pain can be understood in analogy with outer perception? Since this analogy has remained the main line of argument for pain theorists during the 20th century (see the references found in Aydede 2009), we need to say something about why the perceptual account has appeared so tempting, and, also, why it is ultimately doomed to fail from the phenomenological point of view. The main reason for considering pain a form of perception is that pain, at least in some standard situations, appears to have a sort of object, namely the part of my body that hurts. 544
Pain
In the same way that I see the book lying on the table in front of me I feel the pain in my left foot. My pain experience—whatever that is exactly—appears to represent the foot in the same way that the visual experience represents the book. Philosophers of perception have invested a lot of time and energy in trying to establish how this form of perceptual representation comes about (the problems are parallel to the conundrums facing correspondence theories of truth regarding language). How does my experience—understood in terms of sense data or brain states—come to mirror a state of the world such that I have an experience of the book or my foot? The phenomenological critique of such theories of perception has been stated many times, but it deserves to be repeated: there is no mirror in my mind or in my brain making me see or feel the book or foot; the object of perception is not re-presented but presented to me when I have an experience of it (Gallagher and Zahavi 2012, chapter 5). The phenomenological account of intentionality makes it possible to see why pain and other forms of “inner perception” are different from perception proper: the hurting foot is presented to me in experience, just as the book on the table is, but the way it hurts is mine whereas the geometrical form, colour, beauty or even appealing nature of the book on the table pertains to the book and not to me. The clue to understanding the feeling of pain therefore lies in spelling out the meaning of such bodily experienced mineness. We will soon return to this analysis by way of some key concepts and passages found in the philosophies of Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Jean-Paul Sartre, but first we need to introduce the natural scientific perspective on pain to understand in what way phenomenology is able to offer a complement to this dominant view on pain and its causes.
3. Neurophysiological theories of pain and other bodily feelings One important reason why philosophers have been keen to understand pain in analogy with perception is that the rapidly developing knowledge about the physiology of pain has apparently supported such a model ever since the discovery of nociceptors by Charles Scott Sherrington in 1907. Just like outer perception, pain (and other forms of sensual) perception seems to rely on a piece of representational information being formed by sensual receptors along with the way they innervate the brain. Pain was, accordingly, seen as the result of signals sent to the brain by way of sensory neurons when certain receptors (nociceptors) found in the skin and many other organs of the body were damaged by noxious stimuli. The fundamentals of the “signal and alarm” theory of pain in medicine still hold, but, importantly, it has recently been modified by knowledge about how the brain processes pain signals. Neurophysiological theories about pain—such as the gate control theory and the neuromatrix theory—stress that the brain plays a formative part in the pain experience (Moseley 2003). The brain does not only passively register incoming signals and rings the alarm bell, but it also modulates the nociceptive information by blocking and transforming the signals travelling through the spinal cord (gate control). The brain may even give rise to pain on its own without any incoming nociceptive signals, a fact that is especially relevant to some forms of chronic pain (Thernstrom 2010). The neuromatrix theory of pain developed by Ronald Melzack states that pain is a multidimensional experience produced by characteristic patterns of nerve impulses generated by a widely distributed neural network: the “body-self neuromatrix” in the brain (Melzack 1993). These neurosignature patterns are distributed over many different regions of the brain including the thalamus, hippocampus, insula, anterior singulate and primary and secondary somatosensory cortices. 545
Fredrik Svenaeus
A matrix is arguably a form of image, or, rather, a cast for the moulding of pain feelings. Pain experiences are assigned with more or less exact bodily location by way of what is known as the cortical homunculus providing a curious image of the different parts of the body by way of different zones located on the postcentral gyrus. Located directly in front of the somatosensory cortex, both extending down from the top of the brain on both sides, the primary motor cortex provides a homunculus similar to the sensory one responsible for muscle control and movement. These two areas of the brain—sensory and motor cortex—play important roles in the development and exercise of what is known as the body schema. The body schema is not an image of the body found in the brain, rather it is the preconscious, bodily form of all our experiences, depending upon brain functions constantly registering incoming information about posture and movement of the body and directing our movements by way of output motor programs (Gallagher 2005, 45). The brain-functions supporting the body-schema include the coordination of input from the different senses (mainly vision and touch, but also hearing and perhaps even smell and taste) and what is known as proprioception—the neural system that allows us to feel the location of our body parts without checking by way of other senses. The matrix and computer program metaphors are interesting in their own right in exploring pain physiology (even though they are also potentially misleading if underestimating the difference between the computer and biological tissue “hardware”), but they do not tell us very much about the lived experience of pain. It is time to return to the phenomenological attempts to understand pain as a peculiar feeling of the body.
4. Pain and the lived body In Phenomenology of Perception, immediately after presenting the famous analysis of “I touch my right hand with my left hand and vice versa,” Merleau-Ponty makes a detour into the phenomenology of being in pain (a rather rare subject in his philosophy) (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 96). The point with the touching hands example is that the body can either be located on the experiencing-constitutive or on the experienced-constituted side of perception such that “the two hands can alternate between the functions of ‘touching’ and ‘touched’” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 95). The body is first and foremost a personally experienced lived body by way of which other objects in the world can appear for me. These objects can even include parts of my own body when I touch it, look upon it, listen to it, or smell it. But how does this work in the case of pain? If I say that my foot hurts I do not simply mean that my foot is a cause of the pain in the same way as the nail piercing it, the only difference being that my foot is closer to me in the causal chain. Nor do I mean that my foot is the last object of the external world, after which pain would begin in the intimate sense, namely, a consciousness of pain by itself and without a location that would only be linked to my foot through a causal determination and in the system of experience. Rather I mean that the pain indicates its place, that it is constitutive of a “pain space.” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 96) In his characteristic style, Merleau-Ponty here pits empiricism against idealism to show how neither can give a complete account of pain and how both are misleading if not supplemented by a phenomenological analysis. Empiricism (medical pain research) fails because it does not take into account the subjective aspect of pain. Idealism (dualism) fails because it does not 546
Pain
take into account the bodily nature of this very subjectivity. The lived body, operated by way of the body schema functions surveyed above, opens up an affective space—in the case of pain, a pain space—in which different parts of my body may reveal themselves to me. The hurting body parts do not show up to me in the manner other things in the experienced world do— including the self-referring experiences of touching, looking at, listening to and smelling one’s own body—but the pain is nevertheless experienced as having a more or less distinct bodily location and volume. As Merleau-Ponty shows by way of the examples of phantom limb pains (which come in many forms) and prosthetic devices (the feather in a woman’s hat or a blind man’s cane) lived bodily space is created by way of our inhabiting the world rather than being a biologically given (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 84, 144). But even if the furthest point of the blind man’s cane has been “transformed into a sensitive zone” whereby it “increases the scope and the radius of the act of touching and has become analogous to gaze” he would probably not experience pain if the stick broke, the way the phantom limb sufferer experiences exactly this. Or would he? To explore the phenomenology of pain experience in tool use we will now turn to Sartre and Being and Nothingness in which we find a more detailed continuation of the analysis of pain space: My eyes are hurting but I should finish reading a philosophical work this evening. I am reading. The object of my consciousness is the book and across the book the truths which it points out. The body is in no way apprehended for itself; it is a point of view and a point of departure. (…) Yet at the very moment that I am reading my eyes hurt. Let us note first that this pain can itself be indicated by objects of the world; i.e., by the book which I read. It is with more difficulty that the words are detached from the undifferentiated ground which they constitute; they may tremble, quiver, their meaning may be derived only with effort, the sentences which I have just read twice, three times may be given as “not understood,” as “to be re-read.” But these same indications can be lacking—for example, in the case when my reading “absorbs me” and when I “forget” my pain (which does not mean that it has disappeared since if I happen to gain knowledge of it in a later reflective act, it will be given as having always been there). (Sartre 1956, 436–437) As Sartre notes, the pain is not only in the eyes (or in the head if we suppose this to be the case of a headache) but also in the book insofar as my focus when reading is on the words and their meaning. Perhaps the best phenomenological account of this situation is to say that the pain is in the activity and process of reading (Svenaeus 2015). As Sartre notes, pain as lived experience is a bodily influenced mood that is not primarily reflected upon, but rather lived in and through various projects dealing with things in the world (Sartre 1956, 436–445). In these projects, such as reading a book, the pain mood penetrates the activity and shows itself in and through the things in the world that occupy my focus—the words “may tremble and quiver,” as we saw in the quote above. But in doing so the words—or other things in the world that I am painfully busy with—not only appear as full of pain, they also “bounce back” in revealing parts of my lived body as painful—the eyes and head as painful if I am reading, my index finger as painful if it is broken and I use it to turn the pages (Sartre 1956, 440). Such situations in which parts of the lived body turn up as painful are similar to the workshop situations Martin Heidegger describes in Being and Time. He illustrates how the breakdown of various tools being used in activities reveal the phenomenological structure of a situation to the person involved (Heidegger 1996, 68–69). When the hammer is no 547
Fredrik Svenaeus
longer used for striking nails it becomes obtrusive, obstinate and conspicuous, and as such it stands out precisely as a tool that is meaningfully linked to other things that are used to pursue human projects—such as building a house. However, the way the hammer becomes conspicuous if its handle breaks is different from the way my finger becomes conspicuous if I accidently hit it when striking nails (Svenaeus 2000, 108–109). Being confronted with a broken hammer is different from being confronted with a broken finger exactly because the latter is an experience of pain. If I continue the project of house building, I may be able to cope with the pain by using other fingers than the broken one (or perhaps even my toes) to hold the nails, but the pain will tend to infuse and attune the activity and reveal itself when my broken finger is involuntarily moved. With the help of tools glued to the lived body in more permanent manners than hammers— the blind man’s cane referred to by Merleau-Ponty or even a bionic hand containing electrodes, which are connected to nerve endings at the point of amputation—a person may expand her sensory field and feel the contours of things in the world in a direct manner (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 144; www.livescience.com/43125-man-gets-first-bionic-hand-thatfeels.html). Yet, even in such cases, the embodied feeling of breaking the cane or a finger of the bionic hand is not a feeling of pain, but rather a feeling of absence and confusion; perhaps different than the obtrusion and obstinacy of the broken hammer because of the prosthetic glue but still not a feeling of pain. This might change in the future if medical researchers are able to find electronic substitutes for nociceptors or neuron connections that activate centres of the brain involved in pain processing, but presently prostheses merely expand the affective space of sensory experience in action, not the experience of pain.
5. Pain and the concept of suffering The most detailed and compelling phenomenological analyses of pain to date we find in the works of Drew Leder (1984–85, 1990, chapter 3; 2016, chapter 2), who, in turn, takes his starting points not only in Merleau-Ponty and Sartre, but also in less known phenomenologists, such as F. J. J. Buytendijk (1962), Herbert Plügge (1962), and Erwin Straus (1963). Leder picks up on Merleau-Ponty’s and Sartre’s understanding of pain as an embodied mood and emphasizes the way the lived body may appear to us in lived experience (Leder 1990, chapter 3). The lived body, as a rule, disappears in perception and through this very withdrawal it creates a focus in which it becomes possible for things in the world to show up to us in different meaningful ways (like when I read the book or strike nails with the hammer in the examples above) (see also Gallagher 2005). Leder adds to this analysis that parallel to the disappearing tendency the lived body may also resist and hinder our attempts to engage in worldly projects. In such situations, the body demands our attention through “dys-appearing” and the main example of such dys-appearance is exactly to be in pain (Leder 1990, chapter 3; 2016, chapter 2). Our attuned ways of making ourselves at home in the world, constituted in and through centrifugal movements (we are directed from ourselves towards various things in the world), are brought to a halt and turned inward in a centripetal fashion: We no longer see, hear, feel the world through our bodies; instead the body itself becomes what we feel, the center or axis of thematic attention. As often as we turn outward we are pulled back by the insistent call of pain, back to the crampy stomach, the headache, the throbbing foot. Our spatiality constricts, not just to our body, but to a body-part as small and therefore as trivial as a toe. (Leder 1984–85, 255) 548
Pain
Leder goes on to argue that this centripetal force literally shrinks the worldly and temporal horizon of the person in pain. Intense pain confines us to a bodily present that cuts itself lose from past and future. Nothing matters and nothing can be remembered or imagined beyond the all-experience-consuming pain. Leder adds that we engage in centrifugal escape behaviours in order to get away from our pains (a hypothesis which is also explored by Grüni 2004). We scream and moan, twist and turn, try to find distraction by looking around and enter into absorbing activities such as watching a movie or listening to music. We may even inflict pain on ourselves to distract from other pains (like when we pinch ourselves in the arm in the dentist chair to escape the pain in the tooth when she is drilling). The example of the dentist makes another important aspect of pain obvious, namely that it is an experience of passivity, being harmed by the pain in question. When persons attempt to give descriptions of their pains—a difficult task, especially when the pain is intense and/ or long lasting—they often resort to images of being hurt by something—like the dentist drill—also in situations when there is no such outer-initiated action going on (Svenaeus 2015). The headache feels like being hit by a sledge hammer, the pain in the toe feels like someone is squeezing it in a door and the pain in the stomach feels like something is burning deep inside. Experiences of severe pain bring to mind images of being tortured, also in cases when no torturer or torture equipment is present (Scarry 1985). The reason why I am pinching myself in the dentist chair is probably not only to distract from, but also to take control of the pain by becoming the self-initiator replacing the torturer in inflicting pain. There are other situations in which pain is willingly inflicted upon oneself despite its apparent unpleasantness. The masochist seemingly enjoys bodily pain and the athlete or ascetic tolerates (or, perhaps, even enjoys) it for the sake of other goals that demand pain (see also the examples of pain asymbolia and somatoparaphrenia above). Such examples invite a more comprehensive picture of pain by addressing the temporal dimension and relating pain to the concept of suffering. Physician and medical ethicist Eric Cassell defines suffering as follows: Suffering occurs when an impending destruction of the person is perceived; it continues until the threat of disintegration has passed or until the integrity of the person can be restored in some manner. It follows, then, that although it often occurs in the presence of acute pain, shortness of breath, or other bodily symptoms, suffering extends beyond the physical. Most generally, suffering can be defined as the state of severe distress associated with events that threaten the intactness of the person. (Cassell 2004, 32) According to such an understanding, pains that are invested in life goals that do not threaten the intactness (Cassell also uses the term “integrity”) of the person, but rather form part of her flourishing, are not examples of suffering. When the masochist asks for and enjoys pain he does so because he (sexually) enjoys being dominated by the other person. When the athlete and ascetic welcome pain they do so because they enjoy the experiences of becoming bodily or spiritually more perfected persons. In most cases, however, bodily pains are not experienced as part of such personal enjoyment and flourishing projects. The pain is rather something that alienates the person from her life projects, since it inflicts (or, rather, is identical with) moods that make it hard to experience and act upon things that were previously of importance for her (Svenaeus 2017, chap. 2). This is especially so when the pain is intensive and/or chronic in character (Frank 1995; Carel 2008). Cassell states that the pains that are hardest to deal with are the ones that are overwhelming and impossible to control as well as 549
Fredrik Svenaeus
of unknown cause and non-yielding (Cassell 2004, 35). Such pains give rise to emotions like frustration, irritation, anger, fear, sadness, self-pity or even loss of hope and trust in others (Thernstrom 2010; Svenaeus 2015; Leder 2016, chapter 2; Kusch and Ratcliffe 2018).
6. Feeling the pain of others Pain is a private feeling in so far that no person can feel the pain of another person in the sense of taking residence in her bodily experienced pain mood. And yet we are affected by and feel related to the pains of other persons precisely because their lived bodily spaces proceed beyond the borders of their physical bodies to a world in which we experience things together. The togetherness of human experiences has two sides. First, we experience things as belonging to a world shared with others (phenomenologically speaking, there are no private worlds). We even experience our own physical bodies as things belonging to this shared world, but, importantly, pain is experienced as a part of my lived bodily space, which cannot be shared with others because it belongs to the constitutive rather than to the constituted side of experience. Second, we may share experiences in the sense that we experience things together with one or more other living (human) being(s) (Szanto and Moran 2016). Such sharing does not mean that the lived bodily spaces of the persons fully fuse. Even in activities shared by others in sophisticated and/or deeply felt bodily interaction, such as dancing or kissing, the affective spaces of the parties are tied together rather than collapsing into one another (Fuchs and De Jaegher 2009). Human (and other living) bodies express pain through cries, postures, movements, and facial expressions, which we experience as full of pain without developing any theories about why these bodies behave as they do. Nor do we need to mirror and then consciously project the feeling of the other person to see that he is in pain. There is no reflection or simulation going on when we feel the pain of others, we directly feel that they are so-feeling (Gallagher and Zahavi 2012, chapter 9; Colombetti 2014, chapter 7). The phenomenologist Edith Stein analysed the processes and ways of such “sensual empathy” in her doctoral dissertation, published in 1917: On the Problem of Empathy (Stein 1989, 58ff.). Sensual empathy, according to Stein, depends on what she refers to as life-bound feelings pouring out of bodily expressions to be picked up and followed through by other living bodies (1989, 49, 98). In sensual empathy, I become aware that a lived body is there in front of me, and, also, that this creature has a certain type of feeling, like pain. When I see a hand resting on a table I see immediately that it is part of a lived body that is more or less tense or relaxed and that presses itself against the table, in contrast to the book that lies beside it (1989, 58). But not only that, being a lived body myself, I then spontaneously follow the tenseness and pressing tendency of the foreign hand through with my own hand: and in this manner of co-comprehension my hand moves itself (not in reality but “as if ”) into the place of the foreign one, into it, occupying its position and tendencies, and, now, feels its sensual feelings, not in an original way and not as being its own, but “with” the foreign hand precisely in the manner of the empathy process that we have earlier differentiated from our own experiences and every other kind of making present. (Stein 1989, 58, transl. modified) When I feel the pain of the other as present in her face, I therefore, according to Stein, not only feel the pain to be there in a first step but also spontaneously proceed to a second step of the empathy process in which I follow the other’s pain through in a sort of bodily imagined 550
Pain
manner. I then return to an experience of the other’s pain, which has been enliven and enlightened by the second step of feeling-in-her-footsteps (Stein 1989, 10–11). Empathic feeling alongside the other in empathy step two is not a sharing of the other person’s experience in the same way as when we do something together with her. The person expressing pain may be totally unaware of my empathic feelings when I follow her pain through. Rather than sharing, empathy is a way of spontaneously connecting to the feelings expressed by other persons, a feeling that can give rise to sympathy (feeling for the other) and attempts to help her (for a detailed analysis of Stein’s theory of empathy, see Svenaeus 2018). It is in fact very hard to remain unaffected and pitiless in the face of others when they express intense pain. The empathic and caring tendencies may become blocked by mental disorders, such as autism or social personality disorder, or by desensitization caused by repeated confrontations with suffering persons and/or conscious efforts to harden oneself (Baron-Cohen 2011). Another way of becoming less empathic is to take drugs. Antidepressants have long been considered to make people less empathic: when the drugs flatten the emotional life of the patient they also makes him less receptive to the anxiety and sadness of others (Kramer 1993). Recently, researchers have found that off prescription pain killers, like paracetamol, have similar effects on empathy in cases of witnessing or imagining others in pain (Mischkowski et al. 2016). Such an effect would be well in line with a phenomenological account of empathy à la Stein, assuming that step two empathy is necessary to gain a more profound understanding of the pain of others. When “following through” the pains of others, we thus seem to feel something that, if not being pain, is at least pain-like, possibly engaging the same neural circuits as when we feel pain. Pain joins us together just as much as it splits us apart.
References Aydede, Murat (2009). Is Feeling Pain a Perception of Something? The Journal of Philosophy 106(10), 531–567. Baron-Cohen, Simon (2011). The Science of Evil: On Empathy and the Origins of Cruelty. New York: Basic Books. Buytendijk, Frederik J. J. (1962). Pain: Its Modes and Functions. Transl. by E. O’Shiel. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Carel, Havi (2008). Illness: The Cry of the Flesh. London: Acumen Publishing. Cassell, Eric J. (2004). The Nature of Suffering and the Goals of Medicine. (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Colombetti, Giovanna (2014). The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. de Vignemont, Frederique (2015). Pain and Bodily Care: Whose Body Matters? Australian Journal of Philosophy 93(3), 542–560. Frank, Arthur W. (1995). The Wounded Story Teller: Body, Illness, and Ethics. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Fuchs, Thomas, and De Jaegher, Hanne (2009). Enactive Intersubjectivity: Participatory SenseMaking and Mutual Incorporation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8(4), 465–486. Gallagher, Shaun (2005). How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gallagher, Shaun, and Zahavi, Dan (2012). The Phenomenological Mind. (2nd ed.). London, New York: Routledge. Geniusas, Saulius (2014). The Origins of the Phenomenology of Pain: Brentano, Stumpf and Husserl. Continental Philosophy Review 47, 1–17. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Grüni, Christian (2004). Zerstörte Erfahrung: Eine Phänomenologie des Schmerzes. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann. Heidegger, Martin (1996). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Stambaugh. New York: SUNY.
551
Fredrik Svenaeus Kramer, Peter (1993). Listening to Prozac: A Psychiatrist Explores Antidepressant Drugs and the Remaking of the Self. London: Fourth Estate. Kusch, Martin, and Ratcliffe, Matthew (2018). The World of Chronic Pain: A Dialogue. In: K. Aho (Ed.). Existential Medicine: Essays on Health and Illness. London: Rowman and Littlefield, 61–80. Leder, Drew (1984–85). Toward a Phenomenology of Pain. Review of Existential Psychology and Psychiatry 19, 255–266. ——— (1990). The Absent Body. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ——— (2016). The Distressed Body: Rethinking Illness, Imprisonment, and Healing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Melzack, Ronald (1993). Pain: Past, Present and Future. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology 47, 615–629. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (2012). Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by D. A. Landes. London, New York: Routledge. Mischkowski, Dominik, Crocker, Jennifer, and Way, Baldwin M. (2016). From Painkiller to Empathy Killer: Acetaminophen (Paracetamol) Reduces Empathy for Pain. Social, Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 11(9), 1354–1353. Moseley, G. Lorimer (2003). A Pain Neuromatrix Approach to Patients with Chronic Pain. Manual Therapy 8, 130–140. Plügge, Herbert (1962). Wohlbefinden und Missbefinden. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer. Sartre, Jean-Paul (1956). Being and Nothingness. Transl. by H. E. Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press. Scarry, Elain (1985). The Body in Pain: The Making and Unmaking of the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stein, Edith (1989). On the Problem of Empathy. Transl. by W. Stein. Washington DC.: ICS Publications. Straus, Erwin (1963). The Primary World of Senses. Transl. by J. Needleman. Glencoe: The Free Press. Svenaeus, Fredrik (2000). The Hermeneutics of Medicine and the Phenomenology of Health: Steps towards a Philosophy of Medical Practice. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ——— (2015). The Phenomenology of Chronic Pain: Embodiment and Alienation. Continental Philosophy Review 48(2), 107–122. ——— (2017). Phenomenological Bioethics: Medical Technologies, Human Suffering, and the Meaning of Being Alive. London, New York: Routledge. ——— (2018). Edith Stein’s Phenomenology of Sensual and Emotional Empathy. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17(4), 741–760. Szanto, Thomas, and Moran, Dermot (Eds.) (2016). Phenomenology of Sociality: Discovering the “We”. London, New York: Routledge. Thernstrom, Melanie (2010). The Pain Chronicles: Cures, Myths, Mysteries, Prayers, Diaries, Brain Scans, Healing, and the Science of Suffering. New York: Picador.
552
47 THE UNCANNY Dylan Trigg
1. Introduction “I got so scared,” so Clarice Lispector writes in The Passion According to G.H., “when I realize I lost my human form for several hours. I don’t know if I’ll have another form to replace the one I lost” (Lispector 2012, 6). Losing our human form may not be an experience that many of us have had, but in the course of everyday life, there are moments in which we can feel ourselves slipping away from a sense of the world as a locus of familiarity. During such moments, we might feel alienated not only from our surroundings, as though the same surroundings were synthetic, but also from ourselves. For a brief moment, we might catch sight of ourselves as strangers, as though our identity were a flimsy construct deployed to ward off unfamiliarity. In such moments, it might be that we have had a feeling of the uncanny. The concept of the uncanny has a rich history, indebted as much to psychoanalysis as philosophy. After a lengthy latency period, the concept has flourished in the last 20 years. This growth of interest in the uncanny is evident in a range of disciplines and thematic areas, including Heideggerian scholarship (Withy 2015), memory studies (Trigg 2009, 2012), medical humanities (Zaner 1981; Leder 1990; Svenaeus 2000a, 2000b, 2013), philosophy of mind (Burwood 2008; Rochat and Zahavi 2011), aesthetics (Trigg 2014), deconstructionism (Derrida 1994), architectural theory (Vidler 1992; Trigg 2006), gothic studies (Spadoni 2007), cultural studies (Collins and Jervis 2008), literature (Danielewski 2000), psychoanalysis (Masschelein 2011), and the humanities more broadly (Royle 2003). This chapter will trace the conceptual and affective significance of the concept. The plan of action is as follows. We will begin this chapter by tracing the origins of the uncanny through a critical—indeed, decisive—essay by Freud. Following this origin, we will see how phenomenology receives the uncanny, both explicitly in the work of Heidegger, but also in a more diffused sense in Merleau-Ponty. With this foundation established, we will then plot some of the “applications” of the uncanny in contemporary phenomenology, especially in the field of the medical humanities where the concept of the “uncanny body” has proved pivotal.
2. Freud and the uncanny Although the modern notion of the uncanny formally begins with the work of German psychiatrist, Ernst Jentsch, the term itself is associated with an essay by Freud, and it is 553
Dylan Trigg
Freud who is largely responsible for the genesis of the uncanny in the 20th century (Freud 2003). Prior to Freud, there had been almost no conceptual reflection on the status of the uncanny, save for Jentsch and also Friedrich Schelling (cf. Masschelein 2011). Freud’s essay is itself a response to Jentsch’s 1906 paper “Über die Psychologie des Unheimlichen” (“On the Psychology of the Uncanny”), which Freud deems “rich in content [yet] not exhaustive” (Freud 2003, 123). In the year of Jentsch’s death in 1919, Freud wrote a paper that would assume an unexpected significance not only within the corpus of his work but also within the humanities more broadly. This significance is all the more striking given that Freud introduces the topic of the uncanny in an off-handed and ironic fashion, claiming that “the present writer must plead guilty to exceptional obtuseness in [the study of the uncanny], when great delicacy of feeling would be more appropriate” (ibid., 124). Freud’s dismissal is, of course, unmerited. Far from inept, his examination of the uncanny is both astute and incisive. In part, this gift for unmasking the structural and phenomenological aspects of the uncanny should come as no surprise. After all, the topic of the uncanny dovetails with several recurring motifs in Freud’s works, not least anxiety, of which the uncanny is a special kind of variant. Indeed, the formulation of the uncanny within his essay gravitates around the idea of something long since repressed coming to the surface in another guise. This was an idea that Freud had already developed in his 1899 paper on the topic of screen memories, where screen memories perform the function of substituting one image for another. In “The Uncanny”, the idea of an image being displaced from one source to an apparently unrelated other source will itself reappear in a series of different appearances, not least that of the home. Freud’s definition of the concept remains exemplary: “That species of the frightening that goes back to what was once well known and had long been familiar” (ibid., 124). Whereas Jentsch thinks of the uncanny as involving a strong degree of intellectual uncertainty, Freud introduces a novel reading of the uncanny as entailing an aesthetic dimension, where aesthetics is employed as “relating to the quality of feeling” rather than an evaluative concern with beauty, tragedy, sublimity, and so forth (ibid., 123). If the uncanny were merely a case of intellectual uncertainty, as Jentsch has it, then the gain of intellectual certainty would domesticate the feeling, such that “the better oriented [one] was in the world around [one], the less likely [one] would be to find the objects and occurrences in it uncanny” (ibid., 125). Manifestly this is not the case; the intellectual procurement of certainty does nothing to assuage the feeling of uncanniness that is largely resistant to rationality. It is for this reason that Freud frames access to the uncanny in terms of aesthetic sensibility, the understanding of which depends less on the presentation of deductive assertions and more on a sensitivity to the phenomena. Freud comes to this thesis through a lengthy etymological analysis of the term “uncanny” itself. He begins by noting that “Unheimlich is clearly the opposite of heimlich” insofar as heimlich derives from heim, home (ibid., 124–125). There are two problems with this distinction, however. The first is that the contrast between familiar and the unfamiliar does not capture the specificity of the uncanny in distinction to, say, horror or fear. This is the limit Freud thinks Jentsch reached in his analysis, whose accent is largely on unfamiliarity and that alone. The second problem is that heimlich has multiple meanings. The first sense of heimlich refers to home in a domestic and familiar sense. But in addition to this usage, the term also refers to that which is secretive and clandestine, as he writes: “Starting from the homely and the domestic, there is a further development towards the notion of something removed from the eyes of strangers, hidden, secret” (ibid., 133). There is, then, an ambiguity between the heimlich and the unheimlich, or the homely and the unhomely, such that neither can be considered in isolation from the other; that which is the most familiar—the domesticity of the everyday—is precisely that which is the most strange. 554
The uncanny
At the end of this etymological foray, Freud makes recourse to a formulation of the uncanny posited by Schelling: “Uncanny is what one calls everything that has meant to remain secret and hidden and has come into the open” (Schelling 1842, 649). Freud’s endorsement of Schelling’s formulation is perhaps due in no small part to its alignment with the model of repression and screen memory Freud had already developed in 1899. What is frightening is not the object, as such, but instead the fact that the presentation of the uncanny is stipulated on a return of what has hitherto been repressed. As evidence of this, Freud generates a taxonomy of uncanny objects, inspired in part by Jentsch but also through a reading of E.T.A. Hoffman’s story “The Sand-Man.” For Freud, waxwork figures, dolls, automatons, the evil eye, dismembered limbs, being buried alive, encountering the same number time and again in any given day, getting lost in a small Italian town and finding oneself in the red-light district, and even epileptic fits—all of these inspire a feeling of the uncanny “because they arouse in the onlooker vague—mechanical—process that may be lie hidden behind the familiar image of a living person” (Freud 2003, 135). What is important to Freud’s analysis of such phenomena is that the surface presentation of a familiar thing—in the case of Hoffmann’s story, the eye—belies another level, in which a more occult meaning resides. Where “The Sand-Man” is concerned, this hidden level of meaning derives from a logic of repression whereby one figure—a father, a scientist, a lover—assumes the place of another, in turn producing a series of doubles. As Freud interprets it, the surface presentation of a given narrative is shrouded in a mist of anxiety-laden ambivalence, such that the reader herself is never entirely clear where they stand in relation to the real or fictitious aspects of the narrative. For Freud, it is this ambivalence of meaning that supersedes and undercuts Jentsch’s appeal to “intellectual uncertainty,” which fails to capture the irrational—indeed, unconscious—genesis at the heart of the uncanny. That Freud will end up situating the function of the eye in Hofmann’s story within the scheme of his psychosexual framework is of less importance than the broader insights gleamed from the essay. Indeed, the fact that Freud situates the anxiety concerning the loss of eye in relation to his notion of the castration complex is only a contingent dimension in the structure of the uncanny. What matters is not the specificity of a given theoretical framework, with its conceptual and cultural inheritance. Rather, what is of critical importance in the logic of the uncanny is the notion of a thought that ought to be either consigned to the archive or otherwise domesticated by reason, but which through some elaborate procedure has managed to outlast these mechanisms. Nowhere is this clearer than in Freud’s analysis of the doppelgänger, a theme that Freud inherits from the work of Otto Rank. The figure of the doppelgänger is open to a multiplicity of interpretations, including a symbol of “insurance against the extinction of the self,” a motif of “boundless self-love,” and a “primordial narcissism that dominates the mental life of both the child and the primitive man” (ibid., 142). Throughout this genesis of meanings, themes of uncanniness such as the doppelgänger are not left behind in a primitive phase of development but are instead reformed in a series of new guises, and it is precisely the re-encounter of material that ought to remain buried—either to a phylogenetic past or to infancy—that gives rise to a sense of the uncanny in adult life. As Freud sees it, the primary affective tonality of the uncanny is one of an anxiety spurred by ambivalence. But why does such ambivalence lead to anxiety? One possible answer—and one that has proved influential within a generation of thinkers after Freud—hinges on the idea that the uncanny introduces us to a dimension of subjectivity that undermines the idea of the self as rational and sovereign. In and through the experience of the uncanny, something belonging to a different order of life and thought, hitherto assumed to be relegated to 555
Dylan Trigg
the past, comes to the foreground, not as a contingent accident, but as something belonging to the structure of subjectivity itself. Indeed, the motif of the uncanny within aesthetics tends to play precisely on how the uncanny, in a Nietzschean sense, renders us strangers to ourselves. “It appears,” so Freud writes, “that we have all (…) been through a phase corresponding to the animistic phase in the development of primitive peoples, that this phase did not pass without leaving behind in us residual traces that can still make themselves felt” (ibid., 147). Here, we might think of the films of David Lynch, David Cronenberg, and Stanley Kubrick, the literature of Edgar Allan Poe, W.G. Sebald, and H.P. Lovecraft, the music of Alfred Schnittke and Valentin Silvestrov, the paintings of Léon Spilliaert, and the installations of Gregor Schneider. What bridges diverse works of art such as these is the presentation of an ostensibly familiar everyday world that is offset and undercut by a subtle atmosphere of disquiet (cf. Trigg 2006, 2011, 2012, 2014, 2016, 2019). It is because works of art of this variation begin from the point of departure of a habitual taken-for-granted world, in which the self is identifiable with the self, that the anxiety peculiar to the uncanny is rendered affectively compelling. It is on this point that phenomenology has a special relevance to the uncanny.
3. Heidegger and the uncanny Phenomenology’s relation to the uncanny is evident on a number of levels, both thematically but also methodologically. Most obviously, the uncanny has a rich heritage in the work of Heidegger, especially in his venerated treatment of anxiety in §40 of Being and Time (Heidegger 2008). Whereas Freud identifies the uncanny with respect to specific discernible things—an eye, a body part, a place, etc.—one of Heidegger’s main contributions to this research is to render the unheimlich a generalised and constitutive structure of our being-inthe-world. To understand this, it is necessary to say a brief word about his account of anxiety (see also Chapter 34 in this volume). Alongside Freud and Kierkegaard, Heidegger privileges anxiety as a mood that has the potential to disrupt our habitual, everyday being-in-the-world. As Heidegger understands it, anxiety is a privileged mood for at least two reasons. First, anxiety plays a methodological role in terms of allowing us to gain an understanding of the “totality of the structural whole” that is Being (Heidegger 2008, 229). How is it, so Heidegger asks, that Being can become an issue for beings? How, furthermore, can we grasp Being as a whole and not just the being, which takes up that existence as a series of parts? So long as we are tied up in the world, as though the world just existed in an unambiguous sense, then such questions are for the most part lost on us. It is anxiety, Heidegger suggests, that “might (…) perform some such function” of disclosing Being as a whole (ibid., 230). Anxiety does this through fragmenting the relational meaning embedded in things, in turn obligating Dasein to call into question the grounds of being-in-the-world. The implication of this rupture of everyday being-in-theworld leads to the second reason why anxiety is privileged in Heidegger; namely, it generates the possibility for a renewed understanding of the everyday. One way it does this is through the very thematic orientation of anxiety itself, which is that of uncanniness. Heidegger uses the term unheimlich to describe the state of being uncanny, though he stresses that uncanniness also means “not-being-at-home” (ibid., 233). Phenomenologically, our taken-for-granted existence consists of several key dimensions that enable us to proceed through the world without having to reflect in abstraction on how things work and assume the meaning they do. Think here of any given moment. For the most part, we are at-home in the world insofar as the world presents itself to us as a nexus of familiar pathways and 556
The uncanny
pregiven meanings. When I move through the world, then I do so with a tacit trust that the world will unfold to me in a familiar and constant sense. The world as a homeworld is given to me as a relational whole and is structured at all times in an intersubjective manner. Within this world, specific things have their place—the table lends itself to be sat at, the mug to be drunk from, and the body appears for me as a unified set of processes that enable me to get placed in the first instance. In a word, an atmosphere of familiarity envelops this world, seldom drawing attention to itself except for when it dissents from my expectations. Together, these structures of familiarity forge the homeliness of everyday existence. Anxiety, Heidegger suggests, pierces through this veil of familiarity, disrupting our taken-for-granted attitude and in the process drawing attention to “the world as world” (ibid., 232). In such moments, no matter how brief, the world no longer performs in the way we expect it to. “Everyday familiarity,” so Heidegger writes, “collapses” (ibid., 233). What this means is not that the world suddenly dissolves, as though it were made of slime; but instead that the roles one assumes and the meaning, action, and purpose one finds in things appear now as contingent constructs. In the face of this loss of familiarity and intrinsic meaning, we flee back into the state of being “at-home” of established patterns within a public sphere, such that “complete assurance” can coexist alongside the “threat” of uncanniness that haunts Dasein from the outset (ibid., 234). Heidegger’s anxiety, then, is not marked by a paroxysm of panic; he even goes so far as to dismiss “physiological” anxiety as being the same as the rarer “real” anxiety (ibid.). Nor is this anxiety an object-directed anxiety about this or that. Rather, anxiety concerns itself,” and manifests itself thematically in a mode of being “not-at“Being-in-the-world home,” which “pursues Dasein constantly” (ibid., 232–234). “Anxiety,” he goes on to say, “can arise in the most innocuous Situations. Nor does it have any need for darkness, in which it is commonly easier for one to feel uncanny” (ibid., 234). The point is that while anxiety may be an exemplary figuration of the uncanny, the uncanny nonetheless forms a subtle atmosphere of disquiet in our everyday existence, from time to time flaring up as an ecstatic realisation that leads to action and at other times paralysing us into inaction. The vital lesson to be taken from this analysis is the idea that uncanniness is not a subjective state produced by intra-psychic conflict, as we would find in Freud. Such a reading would render the uncanny a contingent dimension of subjectivity reducible to a predefined theoretical construct (be it the castration complex, the Oedipus complex, or any other Freudian conception). Heidegger’s formulation of the uncanny is more pervasive in scope, forming a primordial and “always latent” undercurrent of everyday existence, which is the very condition of there being a sense of at-homeness in the first instance (ibid.). Such a concept is, as we will see, pivotal in terms of providing an account of how being at-home is subject at all times to disintegration. *** To what extent is there a relation between Heidegger and Freud on the uncanny? The question is an area of contested research (cf. Krell 1992, 1997; Withy 2015). David Farrell Krell maintains that, while it is unlikely that Heidegger would have read Freud, there is nonetheless a strong connection between the role Freud assigns to the motifs of return and repression to those of Heidegger’s notions of concealment and unconcealment (Krell 1997). In this respect, Krell posits that “Heidegger’s thought of self-concealing being as enigma, mystery, and secret needs the thought of repression” (Krell 1997, 116). Krell’s interpretation is informed by a specific sort of reading of the relation between Heidegger and Freud, which is 557
Dylan Trigg
largely Derridean in spirit. Indeed, Derrida himself, with his influential concept of hauntology, insists on a close pairing of Freud and Heidegger, writing that they do not know each other, but according to me they form a couple, and in fact just because of that, this singular anachrony. They are bound to each other without reading each other, and without corresponding (…) two thinkers whose glances never crossed and who, without ever receiving a word from another, say the same. (Derrida 1987, 191) For both Derrida and Krell, it is the unheimlich that draws Freud and Heidegger onto the same stage, assuming—to use language of emblematic of this sort of reading—a spectral trace that haunts each figure in turn (cf. Royle 2003).
4. Merleau-Ponty and the uncanny As we have seen in Heidegger, subjective states such as anxiety render the world uncanny, transforming everyday experience into a site of estrangement. Viewed in this respect, Heidegger’s employment of anxiety is methodological in orientation insofar as it seeks to bring the uncanniness of the world into relief. Yet thematising the uncanniness of the world is not peculiar to moments of rupture; rather, it is tacit within the phenomenological methodology from the outset. Consider here one of the basic tenets of the phenomenological approach; namely, the epoché. In whatever variation it assumes, phenomenology proceeds from the broad point of departure that we put to one side our taken-for-granted presuppositions concerning our perception of the world. From a phenomenological perspective, the world is not something I construct in abstraction in order for me to get situated within it; rather, the world emerges as a unitary field of meaning long before it has become an object of theoretical reflection. Moreover, the world is given to me in and through a level of affective intentionality that shapes how I experience and interpret the world in the first instance. Through habitual experience, a level of familiarity is founded that engenders an implicit trust in the world. While anxiety and other related affective states can undermine this tacit trust, thermalising the uncanny structure of being-in-the-world need not be pathological in orientation. One such non-pathological rupture is the phenomenological method itself, which involves a gesture of attending to the natural world in an unnatural manner. Nowhere is this attention to the uncanny singularity of things clearer than in the phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty. From his early essays on Cézanne’s aesthetics to his late work on the archaeology of the body, Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology is marked by a commitment to suspending “habits of thought” in order to “reveal the base of inhuman nature upon which man has installed himself ” (cited in Johnson 1993, 66). It is for this reason, that he will conduct a phenomenological study of the world, “as if viewed by a creature of another species” (ibid.). One consequence of this mode of phenomenology is that Merleau-Ponty’s work is attuned to the ways in which meaning is fundamentally ambiguous, revealing and concealing itself in a plurality of ways, and always exceeding the horizon of human experience. Such a task is one that runs the risk of defamiliarising the familiar patterns of thought and experience that all too often lead to a sedimented perception of the world. Thus, in Phenomenology of Perception, Merleau-Ponty will ask that we consider objects in the world in separation from human perception. Under such conditions, the familiar way in which we apprehend objects gives way to a “non-human element which lies hidden” in things, and which is “unaware of us” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 336). Far from affectively neutral, this 558
The uncanny
movement of defamiliarising the everyday world carries with it a recognition of how things are no longer receptive to human habit, but instead “hostile and alien, no longer an interlocutor, but a resolutely silent Other” (ibid.). Likewise, in the case of attending to the paintings of Cézanne, for whom Merleau-Ponty regards as embodying a “feeling of strangeness,” we are presented with a world that is “unfamiliar [and] in which one is uncomfortable and which forbids all human effusiveness” (Merleau-Ponty 1964, 16). This theme of estrangement from the familiar world is one that runs throughout Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy. But it is especially, as we will see in the following section, in his elaborations on the body that this theme becomes most expressive, and, moreover, which has proved highly influential within contemporary research.
5. Uncanny bodies Whereas Freud gives much attention to how the dead body can produce the sensation of the uncanny, both he and Heidegger have very little to say on the relation between the living body and the uncanny. Perhaps the most fertile area of research where this oversight has been addressed is in applied phenomenology, especially in the area of research covered under the medical humanities framework (cf. Zaner 1981; Leder 1990; Svenaeus 2000a, 2000b; Burwood 2008; Trigg 2016). Much of the contemporary research on the phenomenology of the uncanny body takes its cue from Freud’s account of the relation between repression and the uncanny, together with Heidegger’s focus on uncanniness as a variant of anxiety, and, above all, Merleau-Ponty’s rich elaborations of the ambiguity of the body in its order and disordered state. Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy of the body takes as its point of departure the view that the body is not one thing among many, but instead a special sort of entity, which is not just an irreducible site of subjective meaning but also a discernible object in the world. This ambiguous structure is not exhausted in the distinction between the subjective and objective dimensions of the body. More than this, Merleau-Ponty will also speak of the body in terms of a thing that transcends me, and to this extent, remains resistant to any such attempt at “personalizing” it. His language is telling, speaking of an “impersonal existence [that] appears around our personal existence” (Merleau-Ponty 2012, 86) and likewise noting that if “I wanted to express perceptual experience with precision, I would have to say that one perceives in me, and not that I perceive” (ibid., 223). There is much more to say here on how Merleau-Ponty’s concept of the prepersonal or impersonal body raises questions over to what extent we “own” our bodies and whether this question of ownership reframes the integrity of identity, but for now let us simply note that with this anonymous level of bodily existence, we depart from the notion of the body as strictly “one’s own.” The body that forms a subtheme in Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology is irreducible to one’s own lived experience (“I never have an absolute possession of myself by myself ” [250]) and also non-identical with myself (“He who sees and touches is not exactly myself ” [224]). While Merleau-Ponty locates with precision the divergent structures of bodily existence, his philosophy is marked from the outset by an implicit confidence that these levels converge into a unified arc. The implication of this is that very little attention is given to our affective relationship to the impersonal dimensions of the body, a blindspot that I responded to elsewhere (cf. Trigg 2014, 2016). For the most part, our bodily existence unfolds in the world in a seamless fashion, affording us a continuity that is both spatial and temporal in structure. The same is also true of our intersubjective relations. Other people’s bodies are not chunks of matter populating space in 559
Dylan Trigg
the way plant pots are; rather, in and through our own bodily existence, we enter into a tacit pact with other people stipulated on the expressivity of the body. Yet in certain moments, this pregiven arc of meaning is called into question. In episodes of illness, fatigue, pain, disease, injury, ageing, anxiety, the body can appear for us as something distant and “thinglike,” betraying the identity we have constructed around the idea of the body as being irreducibly mine. Under such conditions, we can have an experience of the body as separated from our sense of self. Think here of how illness affords us the sense of a body that is running away from us, now assuming a course of life that is in some sense opposed to the “I” that is now left to make sense of a new world. For that matter, think also of heightened forms of anxiety, where the body generates the impression of acting of its own accord, displaying a series of symptoms that have no rational place within a given context. Think, finally, of how our relationship with other people is never neutral, but always laden with an affective structure, such that other people can render us “at home” with ourselves, or otherwise put us ill-at-ease through being subject to an objectifying gaze (cf. Trigg 2013). It is for this reason that in such moments we can speak of the body as an “it,” which has its own nature and rhythms, each of which must be accommodated in turn. It is visible to others, in such a way that it can be treated as piece of flesh, animate or otherwise. It lives, and importantly, it does so in spite of me. It is impersonal, and may at times contest the life I give it through my own history, memories, and experiences. It is the bearer of a past—whether traumatic or nostalgic in scope—that is not immediately accessible to me even though that past may play a formative part in my identity. It remains the same for each of us, a set of discrete organs, which predates personal existence and will proceed to outlive that existence. Other generations will be born into a body that belongs as much to a prehistory as it does the contingent circumstances of their personal existence. To phrase the body as an “it” that is separate from the “I” seems to suggest a form of dualism that is contrary to the orientation of phenomenology. After all, if the body resists my possession, declaring its autonomy in moments of vulnerability, then to what extent am I truly identifiable with my body? Do the experiences described above attest to a form of substance dualism? The answer is clearly no. What is at stake is not the ontological separation of body and self, but instead the experience of division, as Merleau-Ponty remarks, “[in] the cases of disintegration, the soul and the body are apparently distinct; and this is the truth of dualism” (Merleau-Ponty 1965, 209). Indeed, it is precisely because we begin with the sense of the body as inextricably mine—ostensibly, the most homely of all things—that its departure from us leads to a feeling of uncanniness (cf. Burwood 2008; Trigg 2016). In a word, if we remain strangers to ourselves, then it is only because we are fused with a bodily existence that is non-possessable while also being the source of self-identification. In the field of medical humanities, Merleau-Ponty’s account of the ambiguity of the body has been reconfigured under the term “body uncanny” (Zaner 1981; Leder 1990; Svenaeus 2000b; Burwood 2008). Historically, the notion of the “body uncanny” has its roots in the work of Richard Zaner. Given the pivotal—and, arguably, overlooked—status Zaner assumes in this field, it is worth providing a brief overview of his contribution to current debates in the phenomenology of the body and medical humanities, especially in his The Context of Self (Zaner 1981). Zaner highlights a series of modalities structuring the body uncanny. The first dimension is that of the body’s inescapability (Zaner 1981, 50). As Merleau-Ponty posited, being a subject means being limited and delimited by our bodies. What does this mean? It means that our existence as subjects is always already given to the world in a corporeal form. To transcend the body would mean to divest ourselves of what it is to be human. Being a subject means being bodily, and, more specifically, rendering the impersonality of the body “one’s own” (ibid., 51). 560
The uncanny
This inescapable dimension has an important implication: namely, as much as my sense of self is tied up with my body, there is a joint sense in which the body “implicates” me, as Zaner writes, “If there is a sense in which my own-body is ‘intimately mine,’ there is, furthermore, an equally decisive sense in which I belong to it—in which I am at its disposal or mercy, if you will” (ibid., 52). This double-sided structure of being inextricably bound to the body while at the same time being at the mercy of it generates an affective structure, which Zaner frames as “the chill” (ibid.). By this, Zaner suggests an affective recognition centred on the dissonance between being unable to escape my body while simultaneously being implicated by its materiality, Zaner reflects, “Inescapable, my embodiment is as well dreadfully and chillingly implicative” (ibid., 53). Zaner’s reflections articulate the tensions within the uncanny. Far from becoming wholly alien or remote, the body that appears for us in the uncanny is such only insofar as it draws together a constellation of divergent elements—personal and impersonal, possessable and non-possessable, contemporary and immemorial—inhabiting a body that is both mine and not mine concurrently (cf. Trigg 2014, 2016, 2017). In this respect, my affective relationship to the body as uncanny is predicated on an ambiguous interplay, in which the body is both irreducibly familiar—an expressive centre of personal gestures, memories, habits, skills, etc.—while simultaneously being that which is the most unfamiliar to me, a nexus of anonymous processes and impersonal structures over which I have no control. This joint sense of the body as familiar and unfamiliar, homely and unhomely generates an affective register that reinstates both Heidegger and Freud’s claim that anxiety is central to the uncanny. But what is at stake in this anxiety? As Freud noted, not every anxiety is uncanny. What is peculiar to uncanny anxiety—as opposed to, say, generalised anxiety—is a strange confluence of familiar and unfamiliar attributes converging in the same localised space; namely, the body. In well-being and health, this disquiet is largely absent. Integrated and unified, the everyday body not only puts us at-home in the world through allowing us to get directionally and existentially placed in the world, but also serves as a fulcrum of familiarity, such that, to paraphrase Bachelard, we carry home with us (Bachelard 2014). In turn, the fundamental role the body plays in generating a sense of well-being, familiarity, identity, and, above all, home is also why its dislocations and ruptures can just as easily render us not-at-home. To think in this respect of the articulations of bodily uncanniness—illness, anxiety, ageing—is to conceive of a body that returns to us reformed, or rather de-formed, from how we ostensibly take the body to be. It is for this reason that the affective register of the uncanny is not horror or panic, but an eerie sense that the integrity of self hood—insofar as self hood is stipulated on the concept of the body as one’s own—is vulnerable at all times to disintegration.
6. Conclusion Contemporary research on the uncanny body has gone in several directions, informed not only by phenomenology but also by feminist theory (Kokoli 2016), critical theory (Macey 2001), and race theory (Ricatti 2013). While philosophers such as Drew Leder (Leder 1990) have drawn upon Merleau-Ponty and Zaner to develop an enriched understanding of the body in its plenitude, other thinkers such as Fredrik Svenaeus, also influenced by Merleau-Ponty and Zaner, have employed the notion of the uncanny to understand specific modes of bodily existence, not least illness (Svenaeus 2000b) and anorexia (Svenaeus 2013). For my own part, the concept of the uncanny has been instrumental in developing a richer account of pathological states such as agoraphobia (Trigg 2016), but also aesthetic experiences 561
Dylan Trigg
(Trigg 2014), in addition to more ambiguous states such as nostalgia (Trigg 2012). In each case, the concept of the uncanny is helpful in delineating the fundamental ways in which our being-in-the-world is underpinned at all times by a homelessness that, far from contingent, provides the grounds upon which a sense of being at-home is founded, finding thematic expression, above all, in the lived and living body.
References Bachelard, Gaston (2014): The Poetics of Space. Transl. by M. Jolas. London: Penguin. Burwood, Stephen (2008). The Apparent Truth of Dualism and the Uncanny Body. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7, 263–278. Collins, Jo, and Jervis, John (2008). Uncanny Modernity: Cultural Theories, Modern Anxieties. Basingstoke: Palgrave. Danielewski, Mark (2000). House of Leaves. New York: Pantheon. Derrida, Jacques (1987). The Post-Card: From Socrates to Freud and Beyond. Transl. by Alan Bass. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ——— (1994). Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the New International. Transl. by P. Kamuf. London, New York: Routledge. Freud, Sigmund (2003). The Uncanny. Transl. by D. McLintock. Harmondsorth: Penguin. Heidegger, Martin (2008). Being and Time. Transl. by J. Macquarrie, and E. Robinson. New York: Harper Collins. Johnson, Galen (1993). The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader: Philosophy and Painting. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Kokoli, Alexandra (2016). The Feminist Uncanny in Theory and Art Practice. London: Bloomsbury. Krell, David (1992). “Das Unheimliche”: Architectural Sections of Heidegger and Freud. Research in Phenomenology 22, 43–61. ——— (1997). Archeticture [sic]: Ecstasies of Space, Time, and the Human Body. New York: State University of New York Press. Leder, Drew (1990). The Absent Body. Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press. Lispector, Clarice (2012). The Passion According to G.H. New York: New Directions. Macey, David (2001). Uncanny. Dictionary of Critical Theory. London: Penguin. Masschelein, Anneleen (2011). The Unconcept: The Freudian Uncanny in Late-Twentieth-Century Theory. New York: State University of New York Press. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1964). Cézanne’s Doubt. In: Maurice Merleau-Ponty: Sense and Non-Sense. Transl. by H. L. Dreyfus, and P. A. Dreyfus. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 9–25. ——— (1965). The Structure of Behaviour. Transl. by A.L. Fischer. London: Methuen. ——— (2012). Phenomenology of Perception. Transl. by D. Landes. London, New York: Routledge. Ricatti, Francesco (2013). The Emotion of Truth and the Racial Uncanny. Cultural Studies Review 19(2), 125–149. Rochat, Philippe, and Zahavi, Dan (2011). The Uncanny Mirror: A Re-Framing of Mirror SelfExperience. Consciousness and Cognition 20(2), 204–213. Royle, Nicholas (2003). The Uncanny: An Introduction. Manchester: Manchester University Press. Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph (1842). Philosophie der Mythologie. (Vol. 2). Sämtliche Werke. Stuttgart: Cotta. Spadoni, Robert (2007). Uncanny Bodies: The Coming of Sound Film and the Origins of the Horror Genre. Berkeley: University of California Press. Svenaeus, Fredrik (2000a). Das Unheimliche—Towards a Phenomenology of Illness. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3, 3–16. ——— (2000b). The Body Uncanny: Further Steps toward a Phenomenology of Illness. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 3, 125–137. ——— (2013). Anorexia Nervosa and the Body Uncanny: A Phenomenological Approach. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 20(1), 81–91. Trigg, Dylan (2006). The Aesthetics of Decay: Nothingness, Nostalgia, and the Absence of Reason. New York: Peter Lang. ——— (2009). The Place of Trauma: Memory, Hauntings, and the Temporality of Ruins. Memory Studies 2(1), 87–101.
562
The uncanny ——— (2011). The Return of the New Flesh: Body Memory in David Cronenberg’s the Fly. FilmPhilosophy 15, 82–99. ——— (2012). The Memory of Place: A Phenomenology of the Uncanny. Athens: Ohio University Press. ——— (2013). The Body of the Other: Intercorporeality and the Phenomenology of Agoraphobia. Continental Philosophy Review 46(3), 413–429. ——— (2014). The Thing: A Phenomenology of Horror. Winchester: Zero Books. ——— (2016). Topophobia: A Phenomenology of Anxiety. London: Bloomsbury. ——— (2017). Agoraphobia, Sartre, and the Spatiality of the Other’s Look. In L. Dolezal, and D. Petherbridge (Eds.). Body/Self/Other: Phenomenology of Social Encounters. New York: SUNY Press. ——— (2019). The Dream of Anxiety in David Lynch’s Mulholland Drive. In: D. P. Nicholas (Ed.). Transcendence and Film: Cinematic Encounters with the Real. London: Lexington. Vidler, Anthony (1992). The Architectural Uncanny: Essays in the Modern Unhomely. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Withy, Katherine (2015). Heidegger on Being Uncanny. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Zaner, Richard (1981). Contexts of Self: Phenomenological Inquiry. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press. Further reading Carroll, Noël (2003). The Philosophy of Horror. Or: Paradoxes of the Heart. London, New York: Routledge.
563
48 HATE OF EVIL Hans Bernhard Schmid
“Hate of evil”, some translations have Aristotle saying in his Virtues and Vices, “belongs to righteousness” (VV 1250b, 20f.)—an idea that is echoed in Thomas Aquinas’ Summa Theologiae as “odire malum est laudabile”—“hating evil is praiseworthy” (ST I-II, q. 29, a. 1, 2). This does not seem to sit particularly well with standard modern moral sensitivities. Hatred does not strike us as a particularly ethical attitude. Though it seems righteous and praiseworthy to stand firmly against moral wrongs, “hating evil” takes the idea of moral sternness over the top. Moral condemnation of wrong is very different from hatred of evil. Moral condemnation may involve anger and indignation, but this is not hatred. In anger and indignation, we find ourselves pushed to punish and to compensate, which is o.k. and perhaps even required if it is done for the right cause and to the right degree. Hatred, by contrast, is not satisfied with that. It pushes towards annihilation and eradication. Hatred is absolute enmity—an enmity that does not open up a perspective of living together with the “evildoers” it targets. It is thus not a way of seeing the wrong we do and that is done to us “in the right way”. It is not part of the inventory of ethical attitudes. Hate does not recognize moral wrong as the evil it is. Rather, hatred makes evil. It is prominently claimed in modern moral theory that the very concept of “evil” and the inimical discourse thereof is an excrescence of hatred, where pure hatred ideologically distorts our concepts of true righteousness and justice and poisons our moral outlook with Ressentiment. In the phenomenological tradition, it is Max Scheler who followed this influential Nietzschean line most closely (Scheler 1912). Hatred not only tends to single out ever worse features in its target, but it also contributes to making it worse (Scheler 1913). In this view, hatred is not seen as the right answer to evil. Rather, it is argued that moral condemnation should ultimately be guided by love.
1. It is along these lines that the concept of evil had vanished from mainstream moral philosophy, when the situation changed rather dramatically towards the end of the past century. A number of authors have come to think that there really is evil after all, and that in modern times we have come to live in a “denial of evil” (Card 2002). This, it is claimed, has led us to going too soft on the worst of the moral wrongs. The view seems to be that especially 564
Hate of evil
after what we have learned about the worst in human nature in the 20th century, we can no longer remain in denial of evil. The roots of recent “evil-revivalism” (Russell 2006) go back to Hannah Arendt’s thought about the Holocaust. “The problem of evil will be the fundamental question of post-war intellectual life in Europe”, Arendt declared in 1945 (Arendt 1994, 134). Somewhat ironically, it was not the conception of “radical evil” developed in her Elements of Totalitarianism (Arendt 1951), but rather her conception of the “banality of evil” in her reports on the Eichmann trials in Jerusalem (Arendt 1963) that spurred the new discourse of evil. Unspeakable harm, the general view among evil-revivalists seems to be, calls for the strongest concepts of condemnation, and we cannot deprive our moral vocabulary from its strongest item—“Evil!”— without turning a blind eye to the darkest realities of social life. “Evil” may be brutishly harsh, but so are some of the facts. Many philosophers have come to think that there is more than one occasion in which other discourses of moral disapproval simply will not do, and to which only a discourse of evil is adequate. Here are some selected early voices from the rapidly growing chorus of advocates of a new discourse of evil in moral philosophy. The contributors to María Pía Lara’s 2001 volume engage in the project of Rethinking Evil; as one contributor argues, “modernist common sense” has “not given evil its due”; it has ignored that “evil is a powerful sui generis social force” that “has been deprived of the intellectual attention it deserves” (Alexander 2001, 153). Claudia Card, in her admirable Theory of Evil (2002), deplores the earlier “denial of evil” that makes us, according to her, blind for important moral differences in particularly sensitive areas. The denial of evil, Card argues, prevents us from seeing atrocities for what they really are. John Kekes claims that “evil must be recognized as a moral phenomenon of primary importance” (1990, 49) because it is “the most serious obstacle to human well-being”, to which “only the strongest one-word condemnation of our moral vocabulary” is adequate (Kekes 2009, 139). And Charles T. Mathewes argues that “the whole intellectual history of modernity can be written as the story of our growing incomprehension of evil, of our inability adequately to understand both the evils we mean to oppose, and those in which we find ourselves implicated” (Mathewes 2001, 3). Mathewes’ aim is to “recover and rehabilitate” evil (2001, 240). In the meantime, it has become impossible to give even a rough overview over the relevant contributions. Starting at the fringes of contemporary moral philosophy, the discourse of evil has truly found its way into mainstream contemporary philosophy. This is not to say that the reservations against the discourse of evil have been forgotten. The reaction to the Bush administration’s attempt to introduce “evil” as a core term in international politics in the aftermath of 9/11 has met with a critical response in the global intellectual discourse in general, and from the side of moral and political philosophers in particular. The new discourse of evil in current moral philosophy claims to have learned the lesson that “evil” easily expresses demonizing bigotry. The current evil-revivalists do not advocate witch-hunts and torture of “evildoers”. Evil-revivalism aspires to be enlightened and open-minded, free of the sulfuric fumes and indeed the hatred of the old discourse. The new discourse of evil is a discourse of moral reprobation to fit the moral sensitivities of modern times. This, however, leads to the question: can “evil” be whitewashed without ceasing to be evil? How many teeth can you pull from “evil” without depriving it of its conceptual bite? How far can a discourse of evil accommodate the moral sensitivities that motivated the “denial of evil” (Card 2002)—and still be of evil rather than just of any other conception of moral wrong, such as “bad”, “mean”, or “unfair”? 565
Hans Bernhard Schmid
Much of the bigotry and demonization of old discourses of evil might easily be avoided, but any discourse that is truly of evil rather than of some other form of moral condemnation cannot avoid to be a discourse of hate. A discourse of evil may easily avoid the devil and the demonic by means of secularization and metaphysical parsimony. The devil may be cut out of the discourse of evil, but not the idea of a suitable target of hate. No renewal, revision, and revival of the discourse of evil, insofar as it is really of evil, can ignore one central feature: the correlation of evil and hate. To call something or somebody “evil” and really mean it is to take an attitude of hate towards it—hate in terms of an affectively felt commitment to annihilation. Any discourse of evil, old or new, will have to bite the bullet on this: it justifies hate. If there really is evil, there is something towards which it is righteous and laudable to take the attitude of hate—because hate is the “fitting attitude” to the kind of disvalue that evil is, it is the attitude in which evil is seen as the kind of disvalue it really is. Or, to put it in a term that proved influential in the phenomenology of the emotions: evil is the formal object of hatred. It is a remarkable observation concerning the recent evil-revivalist literature that the more loudly the loss of our sensitivity for “real evil” is deplored, the less is said about hate. Here are just three examples: John Kekes’ book Facing Evil lists in its index such related terms as “malevolence”, “destructivity”, and “moral monsters”, but it does not even mention the words “hate” or “hatred”. Charles T. Mathewes’ book-long attempt to “recover and rehabilitate” evil (2001, 240) mentions the terms “hate” or “hatred” only three times (twice in quotes). Something similar is true for Terry Eagleton’s bestselling evil-revivalist books on Holy Terror (2005) and On Evil (2010). One might ask: how can evil-revivalism aim at rehabilitate the strongest expression of moral repudiation without thereby calling for the strongest affective attitude? Claudia Card—surely one of the philosophically most powerful proponents of evilrevivalism—proves to be more circumspect in her way of dealing with the question of hate. She does not ignore Nietzsche’s lesson about the correlation between evil and hate, and she is well aware that rejecting the Nietzschean social psychological projection theory of evil does not in itself amount to rejecting any correlation between evil and hate. Yet she avoids taking a clear position in this regard, and does not oppose the “denial of evil” which she deplores with a positive account of hate. Rather, she confesses to be “ambivalent” (2002, 49) as to the question of the place of hate in ethics. She takes the first step towards an endorsement of hate: “[s]ometimes the danger seems to lie (…) in the inability to hate where hatred is earned” (Card 2002, 49). However, she takes back with one hand what she has just given with the other in suggesting that the kind of hate she has in mind is really just something like strong dislike, disgust, or some other form of repudiation. The conception of hate she seems to have in mind rids hate from its inherent destructiveness and reduces it to aversion: “Hatred distances us from what we hate. It asserts a profound rejection. To reject is not to annihilate” (2002, 49). If Card is rather unique among the recent evil-revivalists in that she preserves a sense for the correlation of evil and hate, it is a reductionist concept of hate she has in mind: Something we should better not call hate because it is just a desire for distancing oneself from the perceived “evil”, and not a commitment to annihilation. One might object, however, that this blurs important distinctions. Hate is not just any kind of distancing or rejection. It seems obviously possible to reject or to distance oneself from, to dislike, or even to be disgusted by a person or some of his or her features for the danger or harm that lies in them without hating him or her. Even in those frequent cases where hate arises from other forms of rejection, hate takes a decisive further step—or else it is, it seems, not proper hate.
566
Hate of evil
2. If a discourse of evil makes no sense without a conception of how hatred might be “justified”, Aristotle and Aquinas might be the right place to look after all. “Hate of evil” translates Aristotle’s word μισοπονηρία. This terminology features prominently in the Septuaginta that uses πονηρία (with the adjective πονηρόν) in such famous passages as “knowing good and evil” (γινώσκοντες καλὸν καὶ πονηρόν; Genesis 3, 5), and rendering πονηρία (or πονηρός) as “evil” is standard for the translation of the New Testament, such as—most famously—in the line “deliver us from evil” (ῥύσαι ἡμᾶς ἀπὸ τοῦ πονηροῦ; Matthew 6:13). Yet one might think that expressions such as “vice”, “badness” or “baseness” might perhaps serve just as well—at least in Aristotle’s case, where it is clear enough that no such idea as the devil, or devilish forces are meant. As to the component verb μισεῖν, too, it might seem far from clear that the attitude Aristotle has in mind here is of the sort of specific radical and affectively felt enmity that drives at the annihilation of its target. A more generic view of hate seems to be how Plutarch, in the short treatise On Envy and Hate in his Moralia, echoes Aristotle’s line— even though Plutarch’s version comes with the problem that he explicitly targets “righteous hate” at people rather than just their vices. Plutarch, too, says that “hatred of wickedness is among the things we praise”, but he adds that it is bad people that are “deserving of hate” and that it is therefore right that we “censure others when they fail to shun such persons and to feel loathing and disgust for them” (1959, 537 D). Plutarch uses μισεῖν in a general sense, as an umbrella term for a wide range of aversive or disapproving attitudes, including—besides the loathing and disgust directed at those who fail to hate evil—fear of and anger at evil itself. Plutarch is interested in the specifics of hate only insofar as they concern the relation to envy (the conclusion of the treatise is that hate aims to injure, whereas envy does not go quite so far). In the sense of this wider or more generic conception of hate, Plutarch lists as examples for hate such diverse aversive attitudes as the fear that elephants allegedly have of squealing pigs and the feeling of having been wronged (which is the classical definition of anger). Though Plutarch largely draws on Aristotle in his treatise, Aristotle’s own discussion of hate in the Rhetoric is much more specific about the role of hate among the “inimical” attitudes than Plutarch’s—and it explicitly involves people as target of hate. Aristotle here distinguishes hate from both anger and fear—the phenomena that we find lumped together in Plutarch’s discussion. According to Aristotle, fear is the “troubled feeling” that comes from the impression of imminent “destruction or pain”, anger is the desire to inflict pain on those who have committed acts against us, while hate is very simply the desire that the object of hate “not be” (μὴ εἶναι, sometimes translated as “perish”). If this should be the concept of hate that Aristotle advertises as “belonging to righteousness” when directed at “evil”, it seems that it is the specific sort of enmity that the discourse of evil directs at the “evildoers”. Aristotle’s discussion of hate in the Rhetoric is short but rich. Anger, Aristotle argues, is “curable by time”, hate is not. Aristotle here suggests that anger and hatred are specific forms of “enmity”, which is, in turn, the opposite of “friendship” or “friendliness”. In addition to the temporal structure, further specific differences between anger and hatred include that the former is compatible with compassion, while the latter is not. The angry person feels pain and has the intention to take action against the target of anger, and wants to see the pain he or she inflicts in return on the target; the hateful person does not feel pain (or even displeasure), and need not care about how it is the desired state comes about (R 1382a). Aristotle casts hate as an eerily cool, dispassionate and stable attitude here—in the words
567
Hans Bernhard Schmid
Leo Strauss uses, it is “a settled, quiet determination” (Strauss 1964, transcript p. 184). This last feature seems to be further fleshed out in a brief passage on the relation between anger and hate in his Politics, where Aristotle says that hatred is “more calculated” an attitude than anger, because, as opposed to hate, anger is pain, and pain makes calculation difficult (P 1312b, 25–34); Aristotle here also makes the surprising claim that anger is a “part” of hate, which poses difficulties for the understanding of anger and hate as two distinct forms of the genus “enmity” suggested in the above-mentioned passage in the Rhetoric, as well as in the Nicomachean Ethics (NE 1105b, 21–23). Strauss, in his lecture course on the Rhetoric, has difficulty imagining hate to be so utterly dispassionate, and he suspects that “Aristotle misinterprets hate” (Strauss 1964, transcript p. 184). One attempt to make sense of the apparently dispassionate and pain-free conception of hate might be to understand it as an emotional disposition rather than a specific emotion, in the sense in which many recent authors have conceived of love (cf., e.g., Naar 2013). In this dispositional view, love is not in itself a type of mental event—it has no phenomenology and hedonic quality of its own, and, just as Aristotle suggests, it has a different temporal structure. Rather than being an affective experience itself, it is a feature in virtue of which a wide array of affective experiences come about and are structured. To love in this dispositional sense is not to have a specific experience of love; rather, it is a systematic pattern of very different emotional experiences: it is to experience joy at the loved one’s thriving, to fear danger, to hope for the loved one’s good, etc. The way in which it is suggestive to read Aristotle’s “dispassionate” conception of hate along these lines is that in this view, it is not itself a passion; rather, it constitutes a pattern of passions, spelling out in different emotional experiences in different circumstances. A vivid illustration of how this might work in the case of hate is in Rosalind Hursthouse’s example of “extreme racism”: Recall, firstly, how extreme racism expresses itself in emotion, the way it generates not only (…) contempt, but fear, anger, reserve, suspicion, grief that one’s offspring is going to marry a member of the rejected race, joy when evil befalls them, pity for members of one’s own race who are bettered by them, pride when one succeeds in doing them down, amusement at their humiliation, surprise that one of them has shown signs of advanced humanity, horror or self-contempt at the discovery that one has felt fellowfeeling for one—it is hard to think of a single emotion that is immune to its corruption. It can even extend its influence to the appetites, since the rejected race’s food and drink can be found disgusting, and sexual relations with its members perversely attractive. (Hursthouse 2000, 88) It is true that such a dispositional interpretation of hate is difficult to square with many of the features highlighted by Aristotle. It does not fit to the way he draws a distinction between hate, anger, and fear, and it does not do much to explain the statement in the Politics that hate is “more calculated” than anger, to say the least. Even more obviously and importantly, the example is particularly ill-suited to make any good sense of how hate may “belong to righteousness”. Indeed, Hursthouse’s example of “extreme racism” certainly does just the opposite. Yet there is one reason why the example might nevertheless not be entirely off topic with regard to a charitable interpretation of Aristotelian hate of evil. The μισοπονηρία Aristotle commends as belonging to righteousness is of πονηρία, which is a way of acting. Looking at the discussion in his Rhetoric, however, it becomes clear that Plutarch is not entirely 568
Hate of evil
departing from Aristotle when he claims that hate is not just of “bad behavior”, as it were, but rather of people for their being bad. In his comparison between anger and hate, Aristotle says that whereas anger always targets people (for their wrongful, vicious, or base acts, we might suspect), hate targets individuals and also targets classes, or kinds (this is somewhat obscured in the popular Rackham translation that omits a decisive “and” in the original text, suggesting that hate is only of classes). This brings us back to Hursthouse’s example—though obviously, the examples Aristotle gives are not of racist stereotyping, but of other kinds of affective social classification: “everyone hates a thief or a squealer” (R 1382a). These are not classifications of agents according to non-agential features, but classifications of agents according to forms of acting, and targeting πονηρία in terms of those forms, it might not even have crossed Aristotle’s mind that classes of people might be hated for non-agential features of theirs. If it had, one would hope he would have decidedly denounced that attitude as being quite the opposite of the sort of hate that “belongs to righteousness”—indeed, with some good will, a passage in the Politics (P 1252a 35ff.) could perhaps be construed as implying that for Aristotle, misogyny is “the hallmark of barbarism” (Dobbs 1996, 77f.)—which is not to say, of course, that Aristotle himself was free of that sentiment). In his Summa Theologiae (ST I-II, q. 29), Aquinas interprets Aristotle’s view of classtargeting hatred as a transformation of “natural hatred” that “is subsequently shaped by the functionings of reason in its apprehension of the ‘universal,’ as it grasps abstract properties that give classes of objects a more or less consistent relationship over time to human desires and interests” in such a way that “beyond and out of the spontaneous aversive responses of ‘natural hatred’ arise a variety of generalized hatreds” (Green 2007, 410). Keith Green argues that according to Aquinas this works in love in the same way as it works in hate, and this is the way how we come to have generalized positive or negative evaluative attitudes—or proper conceptions of what is good and what it is bad (ibid.). Is this, now, how hate “belongs to righteousness”? Is, in other words, the problem of Hursthouse’s example just that it invokes the wrong kind of class? Does hating “thieves”—as a class rather than individually—make any good and sound ethical sense? It seems rather doubtful that it does, and it is no coincidence that the concept of hate of classes comes up in the descriptive venture of the Rhetorics rather than in the normative context of Virtues and Vices, the Politics, and the Nicomachean Ethics. It does not seem obvious at all why hate of classes of people would be needed for the right sort of attitude towards types of actions (such as thievery or treason, to use Aristotle’s examples). The opposite seems to be true. If it is right to disapprove of actions of certain types, one should not proceed to disapproving of classes of people. At the psychological level, it is difficult to imagine that “hate of classes of people” spells out as anything other than “hate of individuals for the features in virtue of which they belong to a certain class”. And normatively, it seems obvious that this is just how the logic of hate works against righteousness; hate construes an anonymous and threatening entity—“them”, “those people”—and then addresses the individual under that label. By means of classification, hate thus “produces a differentiation between ‘us’ and ‘them’, whereby ‘they’ are constituted as the cause of ‘our’ feeling of hate” (Ahmed 2014, 48). This has been studied extensively in psychology (cf., e.g., Gordon W. Allport’s illuminating analysis of the “Nature of Hatred” in his Nature of Prejudice (1979, 363ff.)) and is the ethical problem of inimical social stereotyping. Thus the generalizing move from individuals to kinds, from “natural hatred” to “rational hatred”, as hinted at in Aristotle’s sparse remarks in the Rhetoric and spelled out in Aquinas’ analysis, does not initially seem to give us an ethically defensible sort of hatred, but rather leads to an account of one of the most pressing ethical problems in culturally heterogeneous 569
Hans Bernhard Schmid
societies—if anything, this is gist for the mill of the “evil-deniers”. In the paradigmatic case of xenophobia, the additional problem is that the base of the generalizing move need not even be the experience of morally bad acts—it seems that we have the tendency of construing the unfamiliar and strange as threatening and thus bad. It may be true that the generalizing construction of the stranger as a “kind” sometimes does not seem to translate directly as hate of every single individual of that group: “I dislike them, but she is a good person”. But this is cold comfort, as this may equally be seen as a way in which generalized hatred is insulated and persists against concrete experiences of friendship. It is true that the generalizing move of hatred Aristotle and Aquinas have in mind differs from such cases as xenophobic stereotyping in that the kinds they have in mind are kinds of “wrongdoers” based on the (presumably) reprehensible acts they do—“the thieves”, “the squealers”. If it is in virtue of morally reprehensible acts, however, that membership in this class is construed, it is puzzling how hate of that “kind” should not constitute hate of the member individuals. Indeed, Aristotle illustrates hate of classes in this way by saying “everybody hates a thief ”. The only way to make this generalized hate of kinds compatible with the insight that hate of people is wrong seems to be to separate the agent from the act—hate of “the thieves” is then something like an affectively felt judgment that acts of thievery should “not be”.
3. “Hate the sin, not the sinner”, Mahatma Gandhi famously recommends in his Autobiography (1980), and this reflects a popular idea of how to give hate a morally proper place. Hate, Gandhi implies, does play a moral role, but, according to him, the room for proper ethical hate is strictly confined. Hating sins is right and perhaps the only adequate attitude towards what’s really wrong about us. Hating people, however, is a grave mistake, and indeed one of the worst of sins. “Man and his deeds are two distinct things”, Gandhi claims, and it is only when hate is directed at the wrong target that “the poison of hate spreads in the world” (Gandhi 1980, chap. 87). Here, as in so many other respects, Gandhi’s autobiography echoes Augustine’s (on which it is modelled). Sin, Augustine claims in the Confessions, should not be, and this has to be affectively felt: Sin has to be hated. Hating people, however, is wrong. A non-theological way of making the latter point is to say that as persons, people are targets of normative attitudes. To understand somebody as a person is to conceive of him or her as being susceptible to normative reasons—there is a way in which they should be. Hating people, however, is judging that they should not be. Hatred of people thus fails to conceive of people as persons. To Augustine, hatred of people is simply a sin. Where it is targeted at people, it ultimately backfires: instead of being directed at something hateworthy, it is itself hateworthy. Augustine points this out where he says of the hater of people that it is as if he should feel that there is an enemy who could be more destructive to himself than that hatred which excites him against his fellow man; or that he could destroy him whom he hates more completely than he destroys his own soul by this same hatred. (Confessions, I, xviii, 29) Hate of people, in other words, is a projection of enmity; it is itself the evil which it purports to target. Augustine puts this as clearly and succinctly as any enlightened and liberal critic of the discourse of evil and hate might wish. Ethical hate, Gandhi and Augustine argue, cannot be of the agent-targeted sort. We may be angry at people for what they do because what they do is wrong and should thus not be, 570
Hate of evil
that is, because what they do is hateworthy, but they themselves are never hateworthy. It can be granted that such “aversive” attitudes as anger and fear do involve hate. But the hate involved is not of the person, but of his act. Being angry at a person is for his doing, and the way his doing is judged to be wrong in being angry at the perpetrator involves the affectively felt commitment to the non-existence of the deed in question: being angry at a person thus is hate of the act—but it is not hate of the person. The evil that is—to use an Aquinian conception—the formal object of hate is a property of the act, not of the agent. Is “hate of sin, not of sinners” thus the answer to the question of ethical hate, and a perspective for the new discourse of evil? It might seem bold to disagree on a view that seems to be shared by Augustine and Gandhi, and that seems to receive at least some support from Aristotle and Aquinas. However, in his important essay on hate, the phenomenologist Aurel Kolnai claims that it is quite obvious that there is something fishy about the easy solution. “The distinction between act and agent”, he argues, “is never perfect” (Kolnai 1935, 139; cf. 1998 [1969/70]). It is thus not possible, Kolnai claims, to hate actions without implicating the perpetrators in that hate in some way. Kolnai does not elaborate on this in further detail, but we can put it bluntly in roughly the following way. Sometimes people act “out of character”, and the distinction between act and agent is easy in these cases. More often, however, they do not. What is a person who has a robust disposition to lying? A liar. A person who is in the habit of stealing is a thief, and a person who murders is a murderer. There is a sense in which people are what they do. If theft is worthy of hate, how could the thief not be hated—let alone be loved—without ignoring what he is? The distinction between act and agent thus leads back to the above issue of hate of evil and hate of classes addressed by Aristotle in his Rhetoric. Observing how hate works in mind and society is certainly not the same as recommending that attitude, or identifying conditions of adequacy. In fact, the way in which Aristotle’s analysis of hate in the Rhetoric is usually used in the recent literature is in a way that lends itself as a forceful criticism of the “organization of hate” in society (e.g., Ahmed 2014, 49) rather than a conception of ethical hate. It might seem that the conception of the perpetrator in the light of the perceived moral nature of his or her act is simply a mistake—and a fateful one, as it invites the step from anger at a person for his or her hateworthy act to hating the person. It deserves to be mentioned (though there is no space to show it here) that Augustine himself, who insists so vehemently on the person-act-distinction, offers ample evidence for just how slippery the slope from “hate of sin” down to “hate of sinners” really is (in the Confession, Augustine hits the bottom at C XII, xiv, 17). With his claim that the distinction between act and agent is never perfect Kolnai certainly does not mean to say that it is a common mistake for the two to be conflated. Rather, he means that there is something about targeting acts in virtue of which to some degree at least it implicates the agent in a way that is not simply misdirected. This can be approached by comparing a case of hating an agent for some of his or her bodily features or place of birth with a case of hating an agent for some of his or her practices. If it seems wrong to hate an individual for any reason, it does seem that it is “more wrong”, as it were, to hate an individual for some feature for which he or she is not responsible than to hate him or her for what expresses his or her agency. This intuition that hate of people for anything other than what they do is worse than hating them for what they do seems to find some corroboration by a comparison between hate crime, on the one hand, and support of death penalty, on the other. The perpetrators of hate crimes and their supporters hate their victims for perceived features of theirs which are typically not their actions, but rather their race, gender, origin, religion, or some such—a sort of hate that 571
Hans Bernhard Schmid
is universally recognized as despicable—even in places where the cultural politics of hate crime legislation is portrayed in a rather skeptical light (e.g., Lewis 2014). As to the hate of people for their acts, a likely place is to look at the discourse on capital punishment. After all, killing people for what they have done seems as likely a case for hate (in terms of an affectively felt commitment to the annihilation of the target) as any. There is a strand in legal theory of capital punishment that is eerily accommodating to agent-directed hatred. Denunciatory Theories assign punishment the function of “expressing the attitudes (…) that are felt by law-abiding people toward the criminal misdeed”, and clearly, where killing the perpetrator is the adequate expression, the attitude in question can only be hate—hate of the misdeed of course, but also: hate of the perpetrator for his or her act. And though denunciatory theories are often seen with some suspicion for their relation to hate, it is not the case that they are universally rejected (e.g., Kramer 2011, chap. 5). The difference between the discourse on hate crime and on death penalty as a means of denunciation clearly shows that while hating people for what they are seems out of the question, hating people for what they do is quite another thing—and is indeed an attitude that under certain circumstance seems to be met with some degree of understanding, or even accommodation. One way of making sense of this is in terms of what we may call—though perhaps in a perverted way—agent-respect. People should be seen—and judged as—subjects rather than objects. Birth, sex, bodily features, race, gender, social class are not up to an individual agent, and whoever finds him- or herself the victim of discrimination or aggression because of such features is thereby disrespected as an agent: Respecting an individual as an agent means judging that individual according to what is up to him or her. And though we might think, as argued above, that hating an agent is mistaken because wanting an individual to be killed for the sake of that person’s alleged hateworthiness seems quite incompatible with conceiving of him or her as a person, there is, it seems, more agency respect in this attitude, however contradictory it is, than in simply hating a person under the misconception as an object. It is thus perhaps not altogether surprising that quite often in the US American debate, death penalty is criticized not because it expresses agent targeted hatred and is thus a mistake, but because there is “a pattern of evidence indicating racial disparities in the charging, sentencing, and imposing of the death penalty” (U.S. General Accounting Office 1997, 271). Our result thus seems to be this: It is far from clear how “hate of evil” could be conceived in a way that fills the lacuna in current evil-revivalism. Rather than support for the project, it is critical questions that result from our investigation, especially with regards to the individual/class-distinction and the act/agent-distinction. Generalized hatred necessarily implicates individuals, and sometimes implicates them in a particularly problematic, stereotypical way. And hate of acts tends to implicate agents, and while hate of agents might be problematic in many ways, this is particularly obvious where the agents in question are persons. Perhaps there is a point that can be made with regard to some types of deficient group agents—there seems to be nothing wrong in putting out of existence corporations and institutions that are systematically geared towards the bad and are organized in a way that makes them unsuited for reform (Schmid, unpublished). It might be righteous and laudable to hate them—if the members are not implicated in hate of group agents in the way they are implicated in Aristotelian “hate of classes”. But this might seem like a fringe case. The general conclusion remains: The missing conception of ethical hatred is a reason to be skeptical of evil-revivalism. The critique of the discourse of evil marks a progress in our moral outlook whose importance is difficult to
572
Hate of evil
overestimate. The critique of the discourse of evil—polemically labeled the “denial of evil” by evil-revivalists—firmly opposes the hateful projection of absolute enmity on failing fellow human beings, and thus blocks a most destructive feature of the psychological and social dynamics of hatred.
References Ahmed, Sara (2014). The Cultural Politics of Emotion. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Alexander, Jeffrey (2001). Toward a Sociology of Evil—Getting beyond Modernist Common Sense about the Alternative to “the Good”. In: M. P. Lara (Ed.). Rethinking Evil: Contemporary Perspectives. Berkeley: University of California Press, 153–171. Allport, Gordon W. (1979). The Nature of Prejudice. New York: Perseus Books. Aquinas (ST). (2006). Summa Theologiae. Transl. by T. McDermott. New York: McGraw-Hill. [Latin quote from the Editio Leonina, vols. IV–XII, Rome 1888–1906]. Arendt, Hannah (1951). The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co. ——— (1963). Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil. New York: Viking Press. ——— (1994): Essays in Understanding, 1930–1954. Ed. by J. Kohn. New York: Harcourt. Aristotle (R). (2000[1926]). Art of Rhetoric. With a transl. by J. H. Freese. Loeb Classical Library 193. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ——— (NE). (1994[1926]). Nicomachean Ethics. With a transl. by H. Rackham. Loeb Classical Library 73. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ——— (P). (2005[1932]). Politics. With a transl. by H. Rackham. Loeb Classical Library 264. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. ——— (VV). (2004[1935]). Virtues and Vices. With a transl. by H. Rackham. Loeb Classical Library 285. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Augustinus, Aurelius (C). (1865). Confessionum Libri Tredecimi. Jacques-Paul Migne (Ed.). Patrologiae cursus completus, series Latina, vol. 32. Paris. Card, Claudia (2002). The Atrocity Paradigm. A Theory of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dobbs, Darrell (1996). Family Matters: Aristotle’s Appreciation of Women and the Plural Structure of Society. The American Political Science Review 90(1), 74–89. Eagleton, Terry (2005). Holy Terror. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ——— (2010). On Evil. New Haven: Yale University Press. Gandhi, Mohandas Karamchand (1980). An Autobiography, or the Story of My Experiments with Truth. Bombay: Gandhi Book Centre; Ahmedabad: Navajivan Publishing House. Green, Keith (2007). Aquinas on Attachment, Envy, and Hatred in the Summa Theologica. Journal of Religious Ethics 35(3), 403–428. Hursthouse, Rosalind (2000). On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kekes, John (1990). Facing Evil. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ——— (2009). The Moral Significance of Evil. In: P. A. Tabensky (Ed.). The Positive Function of Evil. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan, 139–153. Kolnai, Aurel (1935). Versuch über den Haß. Philosophisches Jahrbuch der Görres-Gesellschaft 48(2/3), 147–187. ——— (1998[1969/70]). The Standard Modes of Aversion: Fear, Disgust and Hatred. Mind 107(427), 581–596. Kramer, Matthew H. (2011). The Ethics of Capital Punishment. A Philosophical Investigation of Evil and Its Consequences. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lewis, Clara S. (2014). Tough on Hate? The Cultural Politics of Hate Crimes. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press. Mathewes, Charles T. (2001). Evil and the Augustinian Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Naar, Hichem (2013). A Dispositional Theory of Love. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94(3), 342–357. Plutarch (1959). On Envy and Hate. Plutarch’s Moralia in Fifteen Volumes, vol. VII. With a transl. by Ph. H. de Lacy and B. Einarson. Loeb’s Classical Library vol. 405, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 92–109. Russell, Luke (2006). Evil-Revivalism vs. Evil-Skepticism. The Journal of Value Inquiry 40, 89–105.
573
Hans Bernhard Schmid Scheler, Max (1994[1912]). Ressentiment. Transl. by L. A. Coser. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. ——— (1954[1913]). The Nature of Sympathy. Transl. by P. Heath. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Schmid, Hans Bernhard (unpubl. ms.). Evil in Action – The Pear Theft Paradigm: An Essay on Ethics and Hate. Strauss, Leo (1964). Aristotle’s Rhetoric. University of Chicago 1964. Transcript of a taped course of L ectures. https://cpb-us-w2.wpmucdn.com/voices.uchicago.edu/dist/f/1820/f iles/2019/05/AristotleRhetoric-1964.pdf U.S. General Accounting Office (1997). Death Penalty Sentencing: Research Indicates Pattern of Racial Disparities. In: H. A. Bedau (Ed.). The Death Penalty in America – Current Controversies. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 168–174.
574
49 LOVE Angelika Krebs
Romantic lovers share what is important in their lives, or so I will claim. In order to understand romantic love, we thus need to understand how two people can truly share feelings and actions. Max Scheler and Edith Stein offer us some valuable insights on this issue.1 In the first section, I will introduce three major models of romantic love: the fusion model, the care model, and the dialogue model. I will argue in support of the third model, which views romantic love essentially as a form of sharing. The thoughts of Max Scheler and Edith Stein about sharing are reconstructed in the second section. I will hold that Edith Stein’s perceptions, which in turn are extensions of Max Scheler’s work, constitute a convincing account of collective feeling and acting and thus of what lies at the heart of romantic love.2
1. Three models of romantic love Whether we turn to the history of ideas or look at the contemporary philosophical field, we encounter three models of love. The first sees love mainly as fusion, the second mainly as care, and the third mainly as dialogue. According to the first, the fusion model, lovers seek to merge into one. A classic version of this model is found in Plato’s Symposium. Here, Aristophanes recounts the myth of eros, according to which all human beings are halves searching for their other missing half in order to become whole and one again. The American philosopher of emotion, Robert Solomon, defends a modern version of this model in his book About Love (1988), noting however that our need to become whole and one again conflicts with our need for autonomy, so that the romantic urge for fusion can only lead to despair. And this is precisely the problem with the fusion model: fusion and autonomy don’t sit well together. The main intuition behind the second—the curative—model is that lovers want to care for each other’s flourishing. Philia, as Aristotle characterizes it in Books eight and nine of his Nicomachean Ethics, is a traditional example of this form of love. In philia you care about the other’s good in life and try to do all you can to make her flourish. The best-known recent proponent of this model is Harry Frankfurt (see The Reasons of Love 2004). Other proponents are Emmanuel Levinas (1969), David Velleman (1999), and Martha Nussbaum (2001). However, while parental love might indeed be mainly curative in kind, romantic love seems 575
Angelika Krebs
to be more demanding; it aims to achieve a dialogue with the other. Unrequited romantic love is a disaster! According to the third model, the dialogical model, lovers wish to share their lives. This model can be traced back to Aristotle too, if we take into account that his philia, in contrast to agapé, is decidedly reciprocal and consists mainly in living together and sharing your favorite pastimes. Another classic proponent of this model is Martin Buber. In I and Thou, he claims that love is between the partners; it resides in their connection: “Love does not cling to the I in such a way as to have the Thou only for its ‘content’, its object; but love is between I and Thou” (Buber 1958, 14–15). Contemporary versions of this model are to be found in Roger Scruton (1986), Robert Nozick (1989), Niko Kolodny (2003), Bennett Helm (2010), and Angelika Krebs (2015).3 The dialogical model incorporates what is most plausible in the other two models: firstly, that love aims at a kind of union (as the fusion model has it), but one that builds upon and celebrates the autonomy of the other; secondly and relatedly, that love includes care for the other’s good life (as the curative model has it), but primarily to safeguard the other’s autonomy as a prerequisite for sharing. Dialogical love is not only the most fulfilling type of romantic love; it is also the most demanding. It needs time to develop and mature. This is less the case for curative love and not at all the case for fusion love, which is usually best when it is fresh.4 Romantic lovers share activities like playing music, hiking, or traveling, and feelings such as being angry or in flow. They share them not for one hour or two, but for the longer term. Furthermore, they share them intrinsically; that is to say, for their own sake. This kind of sharing is essential to human flourishing, as human nature is social and fulfills itself by sharing (among other things). Or, as Aristotle famously puts it in his Politics, man is a political creature and one whose nature is to live with others. Like all intrinsic activities, sharing for its own sake usually goes along with pleasure. Thus, there is some truth in the saying that a shared joy is a double joy (as the pleasure of sharing is added to the original joy) and a shared sorrow halves a sorrow (as the pleasure of sharing reduces the original sorrow). To be sure, it is not only lovers who share activities and feelings. Yet in romantic love, the sharing is of a special kind. It is not only intrinsic (and pleasant, essential, and for the longer term); it is also comprehensive and personal, directed at the full individuality of the other. In contrast, think of two strangers who together carry a heavy wardrobe up the stairs; their sharing is mainly instrumental and without much regard for the particularity of the other. Sharing is to be contrasted with, first, acting and feeling in parallel; second, mutual contagion; and third, sympathy with each other. Acting and feeling in parallel is doing or experiencing the same side by side, in the I-mode. Contagion is being causally infected or swayed by what the other feels or does. Sympathy differs from contagion in being intentional; it is directed at the other, but like contagion, it is in the I-mode, even when it is reciprocal. In sharing, the participants follow practical and affective schemes that are essentially schemes for two or more people. Think of waltzing, having a philosophical discussion, or grieving together. In contributing, the participants are directed both to the schemes (of how to waltz, etc.) and to each other, constantly attuning their respective inputs. Thus, the structure of sharing is triadic. waltz
first partner
second partner
576
Love
Each participant understands her inputs as contributions to something we do or feel; accordingly, each feels responsible not only for her own inputs but also for the joint venture. Sharing is in the We-mode. Let us turn to the writings of Max Scheler and Edith Stein in order to better understand how this feeling and acting in the We-mode operates.
2. Max Scheler and Edith Stein on sharing In Scheler’s The Nature of Sympathy, written in 1913, he introduces the idea of emotional sharing (Miteinanderfühlen) with his now famous example of two parents standing beside the dead body of their child and experiencing their grief together. Scheler distinguishes this shared feeling from three other types of sympathy.
2.1 Max Scheler’s four forms of fellow-feeling The four forms of sympathy or fellow-feeling Scheler distinguishes are as follows: 1 2 3 4
shared feeling (the “dialogical” form, noted above); fellow-feeling with someone (the “caring” form, noted above); emotional infection (“contagion”, from above); emotional identification (the “fusion” form, noted above).
A fifth category that Scheler employs is that of empathy or reproduced feeling; it is not a form of fellow-feeling itself, but functions in Scheler’s typology as the basis of all true fellow-feeling. True fellow-feeling includes both shared feeling and also fellow-feeling with someone; it excludes emotional infection and emotional identification. The chart below presents, in quotation marks, the definitions of these five phenomena as given in The Nature of Sympathy as well as the examples Scheler cites for each of them. Most importantly, however, the chart notes how Scheler analyzes his five categories with the help of three criteria, namely: first, whether the respective phenomenon is directed at the feeling of the other; second, whether it recognizes the feeling of the other; and, third, whether it participates in the feeling of the other.5 Although Scheler initially strictly distinguishes between empathy and the four forms of fellow-feeling, he does see certain connections between them. Accordingly, in his opinion, emotional identification both genetically and logically underlies the reproduction of feeling in empathy, which, in turn, underlies true fellow-feeling in both of its forms. These dependence laws are also recorded in the chart, but space prevents us from exploring them here. The central passage about shared feeling is only half a page long. It starts with the example already mentioned of two parents mourning their dead child and goes on to contrast their community of feeling with feeling in parallel on the one hand and fellow-feeling with someone on the other. The assertion (quoted from Scheler 2009, 13 in the chart) that the parents feel their grief “in common” is specified, first, as the parents’ directedness at the same value-content, and, second, as the parents’ possession of the same kind of emotional keenness or functional relation. “Value-content” refers to the painful loss of the child, i.e., not only the death of the child (as a value-neutral reference) but the death in terms of its meaning for the parents’ flourishing (in an evaluative sense). “Emotional keenness” refers to the suffering caused by this loss. Scheler calls this keenness a “function”, because for him mental feelings (or emotions) such as grief are not just states of feeling, which do not refer to anything 577
- Shared parental grief: father and mother mourning over the dead body of their beloved child
1 Intentionally directed at the other’s feeling 2 Reproduced feeling (as the grasping of the quality of the other’s feeling) and fellow-feeling (as the grasping of the reality of the other’s feeling) are interwoven 3 Participation in the other’s feeling as one and the same feeling (as value-content, as functional quality, but not as function, i.e., consciousness of the different individual starting points); of utmost ethical value 1 Intentionally directed at the other’s feeling 2 Reproduced feeling precedes fellow-feeling as a separate act 3 Participation in the other’s feeling as a reaction to the other’s feeling, therefore involving two feeling facts (as value-content, functional quality, and function); in ethical value, inferior to that of shared feeling
“A’s sorrow is in no way an ‘external’ matter for B here, as it is, e.g. for their friend C, who joins them, and commiserates ‘with them’ or ‘upon their sorrow’. On the contrary, they feel it together, in the sense that they feel and experience in common, not only the self-same value-situation, but also the same keenness of emotion in regard to it.” (13)
“But here A’s suffering is first presented as A’s in an act of understanding or ‘vicarious’ feeling experienced as such, and it is to this material that B’s primary commiseration is directed. That is, my commiseration and his suffering are phenomenologically two different facts, not one fact, as in the first case [the community of feeling].” (13)
Community of feeling/shared feeling (Miteinanderfühlen)
Fellow-feeling with someone (Mitfühlen mit jemandem)
- Sympathy with grieving parents: friend C who joins the parents and commiserates with them in their sorrow
- What novelists are able to do - Our capacity to feel empathy with a dying bird
1 Intentionally directed at the other’s feeling 2 Perception of the other’s feeling directly from their expression and not through an inference or imitation; depends on emotional identification and underlies true fellow-feeling (community of feeling and feeling “about something”) 3 No participation in the other’s feeling (only its quality and not its reality is grasped; does not preclude indifference, even cruelty)
“The reproduction of feeling or experience must therefore be sharply distinguished from fellow-feeling. It is indeed a case of feeling the other’s feeling, not just knowing of it, nor judging that the other has it; but it is not the same as going through the experience itself. In reproduced feeling we sense the quality of the other’s feeling, without it being transmitted to us, or evoking a similar real emotion in us.” (9)
Directed at the feeling of the other (1) Knowledge of the feeling of the other (2) Participation in the feeling of the other (3)
Examples
Reproduced/ vicarious feeling (Nachfühlen, Einfühlen)
• • •
Criteria:
Definitions, quoted from The Nature of Sympathy (Scheler 2009)
Scheler’s four forms of fellowfeeling and reproduced feeling
1 Not intentionally directed at the other’s feeling, but unconsciously and involuntarily (with mechanical causality, but can be put in service of conscious will) 2 Does not presuppose knowledge of the other’s feeling 3 No participation in the other’s feeling, but a flow with its own laws (that sweeps everyone along and makes them do things nobody wants to do or would take the responsibility for); of negative ethical value
1 Not intentionally directed at the other’s feeling, but unconsciously and involuntarily (however, not with mechanical, but with vital causality); located in the vital I (affects, drives, passions) between body and person 2 As instinctive knowledge of others, it underlies reproduced feeling and through it true fellow-feeling 3 No participation in the other’s feeling and thus not true fellow-feeling, but an I-Thou undifferentiated flow; if not pathological (as in hysteria or obsession) or dumbing (as in a mass), of positive ethical value
“Here there is neither a directing of feeling towards the other’s joy or suffering, nor any participation in her experience. On the contrary, it is characteristic of emotional infection that it occurs only as a transference of the state of feeling, and does not presuppose any sort of knowledge of the joy which others feel.” (15)
“The true sense of emotional unity, the act of identifying one’s own self with that of another, is only a heightened form, a limiting case as it were, of infection. It represents a limit in that here it is not only the separate process of feeling in another that is unconsciously taken as one’s own, but his self (in all its basic attitudes), that is identified with one’s own self.” (18)
Emotional infection (Gefühlsansteckung)
Emotional identification (Einsfühlen)
- Primitive thinking - Mysteries of antiquity - Hypnosis - Hysteria - Child’s play with a doll - Obsession - Truly loving sexual intercourse (as gate to the life-stream) - Mass (as a bad, dumbing down substitute for it) - Unity of mother and baby - Targeted wasp sting for the purpose of paralyzing the caterpillar in order to lay eggs in it
- Gaiety at a party - Laughter of children - Lamenting tone of voice of old women - Cheeriness of a spring landscape - Dreariness of rainy weather - Plaintiveness of a room - Wanting to see cheerful faces - Fear infection in an animal herd - Folie à deux - Mass panic - Revolutionary mass
Angelika Krebs
outside of themselves, such as physical pain. Rather, Scheler understands mental feelings as “intentionally” directed at something in the world; they “mean” something in the world, as they have a value-content, and are not just caused by something in the world. According to Scheler, the parents’ suffering is of one and the same functional quality but not one and the same function; that is, there are two functions with an identical quality. Thus, we can say that there is a sense in which there are two feelings present, namely as two functions. In this sense, there is only a type-identity between the parents’ feelings, and not a token-identity. But Scheler himself emphasizes the other sense, in which there is only one feeling in shared feeling, as a shared value-content and a shared quality of emotional keenness. He makes this point more explicitly later on in his book. He writes: Even in the first-mentioned example above [shared feeling], the process of feeling in the father and the mother is given separately in each case; only what they feel—the one sorrow—and its value-content, is immediately present to them as identical. (Scheler 2009, 37) How can Scheler hold that two people react with an identical—and not only in some respects the same kind—of emotional keenness toward an identical—and not only in some respects the same—situation in the world? “Identity” is, after all, sameness in every respect. To clarify this, we need to examine Scheler’s view of personal community, as opposed to the three other forms of the social unit.
2.2 Scheler’s four forms of the social unit Three years after The Nature of Sympathy, Scheler published his opus magnum Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values. Toward the end of this volume, Scheler differentiates between four forms of the social unit: 1 2 3 4
the mass: constituted in infection and imitation; the life-community (e.g., a family, a local commune or a people): characterized by original coexperiencing; the society: comparably distanced and existing through promises and contracts; the personal community or collective person (e.g., a culture, a church or a state): constituted in shared experience of individual people.
In differentiating these four forms, Scheler explicitly builds upon the distinction of the four forms of fellow-feeling delineated in The Nature of Sympathy, while also revising some aspects of his arguments in that book (“in conformity with the detailed, but not quite sufficient, preliminary work, Zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Sympathiegefühle, especially its appendix”; Scheler 1973, 526). It is not easy to compare the two lots of four distinctions with each other, and Scheler himself is not much help. Scheler names two principles for differentiating the four forms of the social unit. The first is the “kinds of being with one another and experiencing one another” (from the Sympathy book) on the one hand, and the second is the “rank of values in whose direction the member-persons of a social unit see ‘with one another’” (Scheler 1973, 525) on the other hand. The Formalism book distinguishes the higher ranking personal values (like the being of the person and virtue values) from the lower ranking thing-values (such as, in ascending order: the useful, the pleasant, and the noble). Scheler proposes this ranking of values using 580
Love
criteria such as divisibility, durability, dependence on other values, and the depth of satisfaction (for a more detailed treatment, cf. Scheler 1973, 100–104). Scheler does not doubt, for example, that the values are higher the less divisible they are. Sharing material goods (a piece of cloth or a loaf of bread) among several people is only possible through a division of these goods, for the bodily sensations (warmth or satiation) that correspond to these are located in the body. In this way, a piece of cloth is worth approximately double than the half of the cloth is. This is entirely different with spiritual values, e.g., art works. These are intrinsically indivisible; there can be no “partial piece” of an art work. Art works can be discerned and felt and their value can be enjoyed by any number of people at the same time. Sensible values “divide” the individuals that feel them, while spiritual values “unite” them (Scheler 1973, 94). The following chart reproduces as concisely as possible Scheler’s complex system of distinguishing the four kinds of the social unit. The chart also marks the connections between the categories, as did its predecessor on the four forms of fellow-feeling. For Scheler, the life-community genetically and logically underlies society, which in turn both underlie the personal community. How do Scheler’s two sets of four distinctions relate to each other? This is relatively straightforward in the cases of mass and emotional infection. Both of these play practically no role in the dependence laws. But it makes sense to correlate life-community with emotional identification, society with reproduced feeling or fellow-feeling with someone, and personal community with shared feeling. Both dependence chains start with an original unity (the I-Thou indifferent stream of experience), followed by a distancing process that provides the precondition for the formation of a higher unity, a unity appropriate to human beings in terms of their autonomous or personal nature. A detailed analysis of Scheler’s definition of life-community confirms this reading. What is decisive here is that in the life-community, the individual I-being of each member, is not coexperienced as a starting point (cf. the long quotation in the chart from page 526). But it is precisely this coexperiencing of the individual starting points that is constitutive of shared feeling. Shared feeling is only possible because it is based upon the distance between people, which is a given in reproduced feeling. That is why—and as opposed to what is often claimed in secondary literature (e.g., Frings 1997, 101; Spader 2006, 164; Schloßberger 2016)—life-community cannot contain shared feeling. The “understanding” that Scheler emphasizes in the life-community is probably a transitional phenomenon ranging somewhere between the instinctive understanding of identification and reproduced feeling. The personal community can certainly be matched to shared feeling (although feeling is more passive than free action, which is typical of the personal community). As in his analysis of shared feeling, in his analysis of the collective person Scheler emphasizes that the communal does not result from an addition of parallel individuals, but that it represents its own reality: The collective or group person is not composed of individual persons in the sense that it derives its existence from such a composition; nor is the collective person a result of the merely reciprocal agency of individual persons or (subjectively and in cognition) a result of a synthesis of arbitrary additions. It is an experienced reality. (Scheler 1973, 522) The collective person is not a collective soul substance, which Scheler maintains would be absurd; rather, it is a unity of being of acts of different kind—like an individual person—but 581
Criteria: • Kind of being with one another: constitution (1), existence of individual (2), reality of the unity (3), and solidarity (4) • Kinds and ranks of values (5) • Spatial extension (6) • Temporality (7) 1 Constituted in infection without understanding and involuntary imitation, so it is mechanical through sense stimulation 2 With the individual not existing as an experience 3 Has its own reality and laws apart from its members 4 No solidarity whatsoever 5 No personal values, only thing-values, therefore of lower rank 6 Without a fixed location 7 Only of short duration 1 Constituted in coexperiencing (with understanding), therefore a mechanical 2 The individual I does not exist primarily as an experienced vantage point, but rather only secondarily, through an act of singularization; understanding there but without inference and does not precede coexperiencing; the other’s being is not objectified; identical content 3 Stream of experience with its own laws and with a unified striving and counter-striving (however with no real will, no ethos, just conventions and customs) 4 The reality of the community as primary focus of responsibility, with the individuals’ co-responsibility preceding self-responsibility, therefore only representable solidarity (within a position in the social structure, e.g. social standing) 5 No personal values, only thing-values (welfare and the noble), therefore of lower rank 6 Spatial extension of, e.g., marriage/family (including underage members and pets): dwelling-place, of the local commune: home, of the people: fatherland, and of humanity: Earth; overlapping of spatiality possible 7 The temporality of the life-community outlasts that of the life of individual members
Defi n it ion (quoted) f rom Fo r m a l i s m in E t h i c s a n d No n - Fo r m a l E t h i c s of Value s (Scheler 1973)
“A social unit is constituted (simultaneously) in socalled contagion and involuntary imitation devoid of understanding. Such a unit of animals is called the herd, of men, the mass.” (526)
“A social unit is constituted in that kind of coexperiencing or reliving (cofeeling, costriving, cothinking, cojudging, etc.) which reveals some ‘understanding’ of the members of this unit (distinguishing it from the mass). However, this understanding is not that which would precede this coexperiencing as a separate act, but that which occurs in coexperiencing itself. In particular, here there is no ‘understanding’ in whose acts a member coexperiences his individual egoness as the starting point of such acts; still less is the other being objectified (which distinguishes this unit from society). It is in this immediate experience and understanding, in which (as I have shown in the work mentioned) there is no division of any kind between the experience of self and that of the other or between bodily expression and experience in the comprehension of member A and that of member B, that the basic social unit which I call the life-community (in the pregnant sense) is constituted.” (526)
Scheler’s four forms of the social unit
Mass (Masse)
Lifecommunity (Lebensgemeinschaft)
“[T]he idea of a solidary realm of love of individual, independent spiritual persons in a plurality of collective persons of the same character (this unity of collective persons among themselves, as well as the unity of the individual person and the collective person, is possible in God alone).” (538)
“[T]he unity of independent, spiritual, and individual single persons ‘in’ an independent, spiritual, and individual collective person.” (533)
8
7
6
5
1 2 3 4
“We must designate as collective persons the various centers of experiencing [Er-lebens] in this endless totality of living with one another, insofar as these centers fully correspond to the definitions of the person which we gave earlier.” (520)
Personal community/ collective person (Personale Gemeinschaft/ Gesamtperson)
Constituted in shared experience Individuals are experienced, therefore dependent on society The unity has its own reality (↔ sum, synthesis, construction, interaction) Unrepresentable solidarity, single person and collective person, each self-responsible and co-responsible, no final responsibility to the collective person (like in life-community) or to the single persons (like in society); co-responsibility of the collective person also to other collective persons beside and over it (but there is responsibility to a higher instance, e.g., God) Personal values (the holy and the spiritual) and in sovereign rule over life-communities (as their collective body) and through them indirectly also over society and its thingvalues; collective person as highest form of the social unit; each real existing social unit is a mixture of all four forms, tendency for historical development from predominant existence in masses, to predominant existence in life-communities, to predominant existence in society, to predominant existence in the collective person Spatiality, e.g., of the state (as a mixed spiritual-vital, imperfect collective person; only perfect in form of nation-state): territory (overlaps not possible), of culture-nation and cultural group (as purely spiritual, imperfect collective person): culture area as a playground of influence (overlaps possible) and of church (as purely spiritual, perfect collective person): supra-spatial and intra-spatial; elevates everything Temporality, e.g., of the state: more durable than the people; of culture (nation and culture group) More durable than the state; of the church: eternal
1 Constituted in conscious acts of the mature and self-conscious individual (e.g. through promises and contracts) 2 The individual exists, understanding of others is mediated through analogical inferences (dependent on unmediated understanding of the life-community); common cognition mediated through criteria and artificial terminologies (dependent on the unmediated shared natural language of the life-community); common will mediated through promises and contracts (dependent on the unmediated common striving and solidarity of the life-community) 3 No independent reality of the unity (only artificial unity); common will only through fiction and violence (the principle of the majority) 4 Exclusive self-responsibility and no solidarity whatsoever (even baseless distrust) 5 Thing-values (the pleasant, like sociability, and the useful, like civilization) 6 No own space, or rather with the Earth as space of the life-communities, from which the elements of society come 7 No prolonged duration, only contemporaneity of the living
“The social unit of the society is basically different from the essential social unit of the life-community. First, the society, as opposed to the natural unit of the life-community, is to be defined as an artificial unit of individuals having no original ‘living-with-oneanother’ in the sense described above. Rather, all relations among individuals are established by specific conscious acts that are experienced by each as coming from his individual ego, which is experientially given first in this case, as directed to someone else as ‘another’.” (528)
Society (Gesellschaft)
Angelika Krebs
these acts are distributed among various people. Examples of such distributed acts are questions, love or orders that, in order to be complete, demand counter acts, like answers, that the love be requited or obedience. Scheler characterizes these social acts in terms of their unity of sense: (…) the ideal unity of sense of these acts as acts of the essence of love, esteem, promising, giving orders, etc., acts that require as ideal correlates responses of love, esteem, accepting, obeying, etc., in order to bring about a fact of uniform sense. (Scheler 1973, 536) 6
2.3 The unity of feeling in shared feeling In shared feeling, the participants feel “one and the same” feeling. How should we imagine such unity of feeling in shared feeling, and how does it occur? Three answers in the Schelerian spirit are possible. The first answer refers to Scheler’s idea of the I-Thou indifferent stream of experience. The second answer has the supra-individual accessibility of certain value-contents as its starting point. The third and most promising answer is oriented toward Scheler’s statements on social acts and transfers these statements out of the context of the collective person into shared feeling. According to the first answer, the participants in shared feeling fall back into the I-Thou indifferent stream of experience. It is the stream that creates the necessary unity (cf. Schmitz 1998; Schmid 2008). Yet, for Scheler, the distance that is achieved in reproduced feeling is constitutive of shared feeling. His whole Sympathy book is written as a counter to monistic metaphysical attempts to remove this distance, attempts that he identifies, e.g., in Hegel and Schopenhauer (cf. Scheler 2009, 64). As we have seen, for Scheler, reproduced feeling and with it, shared feeling, are in fact logically and genetically dependent on identification. But what is only a precondition or a basis for something else cannot at the same time be essential for it. After all, fellow-feeling with someone and reproduced feeling are also dependent on identification, without being in themselves identification or shared feeling. Shared feeling is more than reproduced feeling and is something other than fellow-feeling with someone. What is this more and this something other? The participants in shared feeling feel one and the same sorrow or joy, but not because they have forgotten that they are two people. The second answer to the question regarding the unity in shared feeling retains the separation of the Is and focuses on the supra-individual accessibility of certain value-contents. In contrast to bodily pain, which is only directly accessible to the person who experiences it, spiritual value-contents, like the death of a person or the sublimity of a piece of music, are accessible to everyone who is open to the value. The lower bodily values divide us and the higher spiritual values unite us. Those listening to a piece of music at a concert are united in this good (cf. Van Hooft 1994; Chapter 40 in this volume). The problem with this answer is that it also takes something to be essential to shared feeling that is only its precondition. For feelings to be shared, the value-content at which they are directed has to be accessible supra-individually. This is why bodily feelings cannot be shared (cf. Scheler 2009, 13). But the lonely access to something supra-individually accessible is still not a shared access. The same is true for the parallel and consciously parallel, and even the enjoyed consciously parallel accesses. If all these forms of access were shared, it would be hard to feel anything alone, apart from bodily sensations and idiosyncratic
584
Love
responses. In this second answer, shared feeling does not collapse into identification like in the first answer, but into parallel feeling. But the participants in shared feeling are not sharing one and the same sorrow or joy just because they are directed at the same value-content. According to the third answer, shared feeling is a feeling in which the participants intend their feelings as a contribution to a joint feeling and understand the feelings of the others in the same way. A shared feeling is the unity of sense of different feeling contributions. It is not the sum of separately intelligible feelings plus everybody’s knowledge about the feelings of the others. Shared feeling cannot be achieved in this summative fashion. Shared feeling is an irreducible category of feeling, like joint action is, e.g., in question and answer or in order and obedience. The participants in shared feeling feel one and the same sorrow or joy because their feelings are contributions to a single coherence of sense. This third and most fruitful way of understanding the unity of shared feelings can be further explicated by reference to the work of Edith Stein.
2.4 Edith Stein’s development of Scheler’s approach In the second part of her book Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities entitled Individual and Community, published in 1922, Edith Stein explores an example that is reminiscent of Scheler’s case of the grieving parents, namely that of a troop mourning the death of its leader. Stein distinguishes three phenomena with respect to her example: 1 2 3
personal feeling: a member of the troop mourns for the leader as a personal friend; membership feeling: a member of the troop mourns for the leader as the leader of the troop; community feeling: the troop mourns for its leader.
The third phenomenon is the one that is of interest to us and to Stein. The second phenomenon supplies the essential material for it. The first phenomenon does not play any role in it—Stein introduces it only for the sake of distinction. Stein begins her analysis with the second phenomenon, membership mourning. According to her, the member’s mourning is directed at the importance for the group of their leader’s death. The member has an intention toward the object, which can more or less do justice to the object. We know this objective intention from Scheler, who names it as directedness to a value-object. Yet Stein goes beyond Scheler and claims that, apart from this objective intention, the mourning member also has “an intention toward the communal experience” (Stein 2000, 137); his mourning is also aimed at the troop’s mourning as it is constituted by the individual members’ contributions. This intention, too, can be more or less successful. The most we find in this regard in Scheler’s exploration of parental mourning is that “All fellow-feeling involves intentional reference of the feeling of joy or sorrow to the other person’s experience” (Scheler 2009, 13). Stein explains, and here she is again in perfect agreement with Scheler, the manner in which community mourning is constituted by the individual members’ contributions. She uses biography as an analogy. The biography of an individual is more than the sum total of all that happened in the individual’s life. It is a coherence of sense in which some events are more important than others. This is true, too, in community mourning. Some individuals’ contributions are more important than others’. It is the unity or coherence of
585
Angelika Krebs
sense that holds the members’ contributions together and makes for the unity of community mourning: The relationship of the communal experience to the individual experience is constitution, not summation. If you were capable of compiling within yourself all the coalescing experiences, but you united them as a mere aggregate without inner coherence in themselves, you wouldn’t be in possession of the full communal experience, any more than you get the unity of an object by merely stringing together the sensory data. You don’t have a new whole instead of an aggregate of components until the multiple contributions, governed by the unity of one sense, have integrated themselves into a structure of a higher kind. (Stein 2000, 144) More explicitly than Scheler, Stein notes two presuppositions for community feeling. The first is that the members understand each other, that they are able to reproduce the feelings of the others. The second is that the object toward which their feelings are directed is supra-individually accessible. With regard to the second presupposition, Stein even goes so far as to call the unity of all who are united in a supra-individually accessible object but do not interact with each other a weak form of social unit. This weak form of social unit she names “the unity of structure of experience”. Stein contrasts it with mass, society, and true community, all of which she understands more or less along Schelerian lines. Stein’s two presuppositions roughly correspond to the two options of understanding the unity of feeling distinguished in the last section. By making clear that both interpersonal understanding and supra-individual accessibility are mere presuppositions of shared feeling, Stein rejects these first two options.
3. Conclusion With Edith Stein on Max Scheler’s shoulders, we finally get a convincing account of shared feeling and thus of what love is all about: The participants in shared feeling feel the same sorrow or joy because they both aim, first, at the same value object and, second, at their community with each other. That is, they both try to do justice, first, to the importance of their loss or gain and, second, to their common sorrow or joy, as it is constituted by all of their contributions.7
Notes 1 Needless to say, other phenomenologists, such as Gerda Walther, Else Voigtländer, Adolf Reinach, Alfred Schütz, Alexander Pfänder, Ludwig Binswanger, and Otto Friedrich Bollnow, also have interesting things to say about the nature of sharing. Their work is mentioned here only in passing, if at all. See more on Walther, Voigtländer, Pfänder and Bollnow in Chapters 3, 6, 7 and 10 (all in this volume). For the contribution of women phenomenologists to social ontology, cf. Luft and Hagengruber (2018). 2 For a discussion of Scheler’s metaphysical and anthropological conception of love, see Chapter 4 (in this volume). 3 Some classical articles on love are reprinted in the fourth volume of Ben-Ze’ev and Krebs (2017), together with articles on love-related emotions, such as jealousy, trust, hope, hatred, regret, and mourning. For a comprehensive collection on love alone, cf. Solomon and Higgins (1991).
586
Love 4 Cf. Krebs (2015) for a fuller presentation and critique of the three models. For the role of time in love, see Ben-Ze’ev and Krebs (2018) as well as Ben-Ze’ev (2019). 5 For a useful survey of Scheler’s distinctions, cf. Goldie (2000, chap. 7), which, however, fails to fully capture the phenomenon of shared feeling. 6 For an analysis of such social acts, see also Reinach (1913). 7 The account of shared feeling presented here is updated in Krebs (2015) on the basis of contemporary philosophy of emotion (especially Ben-Ze’ev 2000; Goldie 2000; Voss 2004) and the current debate on collective intentionality (in particular Gilbert 1989; Searle 1990; Baltzer 1999).
References Baltzer, Ulrich (1999). Gemeinschaftshandeln. Freiburg: Alber. Ben-Ze’ev, Aaron (2000). The Subtlety of Emotions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ——— (2019). The Arc of Love. How Our Romantic Lives Change with Time. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Ben-Ze’ev, Aaron, and Krebs, Angelika (Eds.) (2017). Philosophy of Emotion IV. Specific Emotions. London: Routledge. ——— (2018). Love and Time. In: C. Grau, and A. Smuts (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Love. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: https://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199395729.013.14 Buber, Martin (1958). I and Thou. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. Frankfurt, Harry (2004). The Reasons of Love. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Frings, Manfred (1997). The Mind of Max Scheler. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. Gilbert, Margaret (1989). On Social Facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Goldie, Peter (2000). The Emotions. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Helm, Bennett (2010). Love, Friendship, and the Self. New York: Oxford University Press. Kolodny, Niko (2003). Love as Valuing a Relationship. The Philosophical Review 112(2), 135–189. Krebs, Angelika (2015). Zwischen Ich und Du. Eine dialogische Philosophie der Liebe. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Levinas, Emmanuel (1969). Totality and Infinity. Transl. by A. Lingis. Duquesne: Duquesne University Press. Luft, Sebastian, and Hagengruber, Ruth (Eds.) (2018). Women Phenomenologists on Social Ontology. Berlin: Springer. Nozick, Robert (1989). The Examined Life. New York: Simon and Schuster. Nussbaum, Martha C. (2001). Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reinach, Adolf (1913). Die apriorischen Grundlagen des bürgerlichen Rechts. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 1, 685–874. Scheler, Max (1973). Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Value. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. ——— (2009). The Nature of Sympathy. London: Routledge. Schloßberger, Matthias (2016). The Varieties of Togetherness. Scheler on Collective Affective Intentionality. In: A. Salice and H. B. Schmid (Eds.). The Phenomenological Approach to Social Reality. Berlin: Springer, 173–195. Schmid, Hans Bernhard (2008). Shared Feelings: Towards a Phenomenology of Affective Intentionality. In: H. B. Schmid, K. Schulte-Ostermann, and N. Parros (Eds.). Concepts of Sharedness. Frankfurt: Ontos, 59–86. Schmitz, Hermann (1998). Der Raum, der Leib und die Gefühle. Ostfildern: Ed. Tertium. Scruton, Roger (1986). Sexual Desire. New York: The Free Press. Searle, John (1990). Collective Intentions and Actions. In: P. Cohen, J. Morgan, and M. Pollack (Eds.). Intentions in Communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 401–415. Solomon, Robert (1988). About Love. New York: Simon and Schuster. Solomon, Robert C., and Higgins, Kathleen M. (Eds.). (1991). The Philosophy of (Erotic) Love. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas. Spader, Peter (2006). Scheler’s Moral Solidarity and the Essential Nature of the Person. In: C. Bermes, W. Henckmann, and H. Leonardy (Eds.). Solidarität. Person und Soziale Welt. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 157–168.
587
Angelika Krebs Stein, Edith (1989). On the Problem of Empathy. Transl. by W. Stein. Washington, D.C.: ICS Publication. ——— (2000). Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities. Transl. by M. C. Baseheart, and M. Sawicki. Washington D.C.: ICS Publications. Van Hooft, Stan (1994). Scheler on Sharing Emotions. Philosophy Today 38, 18–28. Velleman, David J. (1999). Love as a Moral Emotion. Ethics 109(2), 338–374. Voss, Christiane (2004). Narrative Emotionen. Berlin: De Gruyter. Further reading Heinämaa, Sara (2018). Love and Admiration (Wonder): Fundaments of the Self-Other Relations. In: J. J. Drummond and S. Rinofner-Kreidl (Eds.). Emotional Experiences: Ethical and Social Significance. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 155–174.
588
INDEX
Note: Page numbers followed by “n” denote endnotes. Abraham, Nicolas 169, 406 acquisitive theory 432 action readiness 217, 222, 235 activity and passivity attunement 106, 108 actual impressive situations 264 actual-present experiences 134, 137, 139–141 actual sentiments 65, 67 “add-on” theory 6, 233 Adorno, Theodor W. 17; and Critical Theory 4, 264, 561 adverbial duties 515–516, 518 adverbial emotion 388 aesthetic emotion 342, 343 aesthetic sentiments 68 affectedness (Betroffenheit) 442, 534 affective ankylosis (ankylose affective) 211 affective apperception 58 affective colouration 58 affective experience: emotion- and valueconcepts 244–245; emotions, intentional structure of 240–244; intentional feelingact 240; multi-track dispositions 246; presentation feeling 240; retention, Husserl’s notion of 244; sentiments and moods 246–248; single-track dispositions 246 affective illusions 254 affective-intentionalist paradigm 14 affective intentionality 6, 106, 189, 194n8, 232–234, 481; see also collective affective intentionality affective motivation theory 88 affective position-takings: moral value of 119–120 affective responses 116, 119 affective self-construal feeling 361
affective sensations 54, 58, 59 affective space, pain and 547 affective style 199 affective synchrony 471–475 affective trait 240, 244–245 affective trust 526 affective turn 478 affectivity, complex theory of 215 affects (Affekte) 89 affirmation/denial act 67 affliction 374–377, 543 affordance, concept of 324 Agamben, Giorgio 462 aggressive emotions 441; affectedness 442; anger 448–450; characteristics of 443; contempt 447–448; envy 444; hatred 445–447; indignation 448–450; irritation 443; jealousy 444–445; norms 448–450; phenomenological analysis 441–443; rage 444; Ressentiment 445; transformations and reinterpretations 450–452 Ahmed, Sara 318, 381, 569, 571 Allport, Gordon W. 569 altruism, feelings of 175 ambiguity: feeling concept 73; first betrayal of 191; of freedom 188–189; second betrayal of 191 analysing attention (analysierende Beachtung) 89 analytic-continental divide 2 analytic philosophy, emotions 4–6 anchoring point (Verankerungspunkt) 442–443, 450; anger 449; contempt 448, 452; envy 444; hatred 446; irritation 443; jealousy 444 anger/angry 448–450, 453n3, 505, 567, 571 angst attunement 109–110 Anscombe, Elizabeth 92, 294
589
Index Antelme, Robert 462 anti-attitudes (anger, fear, and sadness) 45 antidepressants 551 anti-intentionalistic warning 264 anxiety (Angst) 394–396; uncanny 555–557, 561 apprehension (Erfassen) 115, 116 apprehension of value 97 Aquinas, Thomas 5, 11, 21, 23n1, 567, 570; Summa Theologiae 564, 569 Arendt, Hannah 17, 22, 436, 480, 500, 502, 505, 534, 540n3, 565; antidemocratic idea 179; compassion, analysis of 181, 183; emotion, phenomenology of 184, 185; forgiveness theory 502; French Revolution 177–178; The Human Condition 185; The Origins of Totalitarianism 182; politics and emotions 179–185; On Revolution 177; volonté générale, Rousseauian notion of 179, 180 Aristotle 2, 299, 302, 433, 435, 514, 570; aesthetic emotions 184; eudaimonia, account of 417; happiness, philosophy of 423; hate, conception of 567–570; Nicomachean Ethics 511; Politics 568, 569, 576; Rhetoric 486, 567–569, 571; Virtues and Vices 564 art: art-specific emotions 342–344; common emotions 337–342; emotions, expression of 344–345; expressive properties 345–346 atmosphere 3, 7, 8, 10, 11, 13, 18, 162, 213n3, 215, 222, 259n5, 262–70, 306, 308, 312, 316, 317, 324, 327, 331, 340, 435, 467, 442, 490n3, 523, 526–527, 556, 557 atmospheric feeling 527; anti-projectivist conception of 264; atmospheric interplay 267–268; classifications of 268–269; definition of 268; interdisciplinary dissemination 269; modest atmospherological proposal 265–266; ontologically heterodox suggestions 266–267 atmospheric trust 526–527 Attig, Thomas 405 attunements 104–106 audiences, emotions in 337 Audi, Robert 388 Augustine: compassion, kind of 435; Confessions 570; hatred of people 570 authentic love 191–193 autism 329–331 autistic spectrum disorders (ASD) 7, 329, 330 aversive emotions 101, 145, 445 Ayer, A.J. 5 background feeling 256 Baier, Annette 525–526 Bakhtin, Mikhail 529 Bartky, Sandra L. 312, 313 Barrett Feldman, Lisa 23n6 basic emotions (Ekman) 23n6 Bataille, Georges 384
Baumgartner, Michael 304 de Beauvoir, Simone 13, 17, 18, 41, 313, 409, 410; bodily existence 193; Ethics of Ambiguity 188; freedom, ambiguity of 188–189; in/ authentic love 191–193; love triangle 187–188; The Mandarins 187; Must we burn Sade 188; Pyrrhus and Cinéas 188; responsive intersubjectivity 189–191; The Second Sex 188; She Came to Stay 187; women’s condition, philosophico-political 187 Befindlichkeit, conception of 104, 105, 107 behaviorism 200 Behnke, Elizabeth 472 being affected 10–11, 14–15, 16, 27n64, 115, 175n3, 281, 325, 442 being-like-others, primary sense of 330 being struck, phenomenon of 283 Bell, Clive 342, 343 Bell, Macalester 453n18 benevolence, feelings of 175 benevolence/gratitude interactions 511, 514–516, 518 Ben-Ze’ev, Aaron 27n72, 586n3 Berezin, Mabel 490n7 Bergson, Henri 420 betrayal: of ambiguity 191, 192; of trust 530 Binswanger, Ludwig 27n75, 586n1 Blankenburg, Wolfgang 331 blind judgments 48, 49 bodily-affective style 203 bodily awareness 155, 156 bodily bound (Leibgebundenheit) 147 bodily existence 193 bodily feelings 6, 10–11, 13–14, 25n33, 26n57; bodily feelings–feeling-sensations 242 bodily-felt, 441–443, 447; sensation 442; see also: felt body bodily incorporation 201 bodily orientation (leibliche Richtung) 11, 215, 219 bodily resonance: components of 325; encompassing loss of 329; neo-Jamesian accounts of 215 bodily self-awareness 54 bodily sensations 233 body schema 546 Böhme, Gernot 264, 265 Bollnow, Otto Friedrich 3, 4, 7, 9, 13, 17, 453n3, 586n1; basic attunements 107; Das Wesen der Stimmungen 107–109, 111 Bordo, Susan 314 boredom 394–396, 398–400 bottom-up approach 276–277 Bradshaw, John 318 Branden, Nathaniel 362 Brentano, Franz 2, 3, 17, 27n75, 240, 282, 544; consciousness theory 44; descriptive psychology method 42; emotion theory
590
Index 41, 45–46; epistemology of value 46–50; evidence, method and source of 44; explicate loving and hating 45; genetic psychology method 42; mental phenomena 42–43; phenomenology, senses of 41–42; physical phenomena 42–43; psychology from empirical standpoint 42–44, 50n2; sui generis intentional phenomena 41, 45–46; The True and the Evident 47 Brentano School 2 Buber, Martin 576 “Bund,” social modal category 140–142 Buñuel, Louis 384, 387 Butler, Joseph 505, 506n2 Buytendijk, F. J. J. 548 Calhoun, Cheshire 317 Card, Claudia 565, 566 care (Sorge) 393 Cartesian intellectualism 198 Casini, Lorenzo 304 Cassell, Eric 549 center of feeling 67 centrifugal stream of feeling 65–67 Césaire, Aimé 207 Chalmers, David 305 chaotic-multiple significance 265 cheerfulness and sadness 107 children feel 80 Chisholm, Roderick 48 Clark, Andy 305 cognitive assuredness 526, 527 cognitive model 146, 305 Cohen, Hermann 2, 21 collective affective intentionality (CAI) 469, 479, 481–484, 486 collective emotional response 466, 468, 471 collective emotions theory 133, 482 collective guilt feelings 468 collective intentionality 459, 468 collective person (Gesamtperson) 583 Collingwood, R.G. 344, 345 Collins, Randall 471 Colombetti, Giovanna 155, 156, 202, 216, 304–306 colonial duration 209–212, 213n7 colonial violence 209 colonization: affective weight of 210–212; colonization process 208; violence of 210 common-sense realism 43 communal emotions 133; in broad sense 138; community feeling 139; general conditions 135; in narrow sense 137–138; paradigmatic example of 140; Walther’s concept of 138; see also joint feeling, and emotional sharing community and society emotions 139–142 community feeling 578, 585–586
community mourning 585–586 compassion: Aristotle’s conception 433; definition of 429, 435; ethical impact of 436; meaning of 429; positive value of 435 component process model 302 compromised trust 530 computational processes 198 condensation area (Verdichtungsbereich) 442–443; anger 449; contempt 448; envy 444, 450; hatred 445, 446; irritation 443; jealousy 444–445; rage 444 consciousness theory 44, 98, 160 “Conservative Revolution” 4 contempt 447–448, 452; “moral” 453n10 contractualist political theory 5 Corbí, Josep E. 461 corporeal 8, 218, 442–443, 445, 447, 449 corporeal-affective 27n64, 442, 447, 451 corporeality 442 correct emotion concept 50 correct (true) judgment 48 correctness and incorrectness possibility 47 correspondence theory of truth 47 cortical homunculus 546 coupling-constitution fallacy 304 coupling of trust 527–530 criterial prefocusing theory 340 critical phenomenology 8 Cronenberg, David 556 Crowell, Steven 294 curative model of love 575 Dalí, Salvador 384 Damasio, Antonio 23n5 D’Arms, Justin 455 Darwin, Charles: evolutionary theory 2; species evolution mechanisms 380 Dasein 104, 105, 108, 168, 247 data of consciousness 42 Daubert, Johannes 101 Davidson, Donald 5 Dearing, Ronda L. 354 death penalty 572 de Biran, Maine 26n48 deep joy, concept of 419 deep level ingratitude 517 deep stories, Hochschild’s notion of 486 Deleuze, Gilles 479 Deleuzian 23n6; metaphysical affect theory 262 Dennett, Daniel C. 299 denunciatory theories 572 Deonna, Julien 243, 246 depression 329 Derpmann, Simon 541n20, 541n23 Derrida, Jacques 497, 505, 558; pure forgiveness 501, 502 Descartes, René 42, 184
591
Index descriptive psychology method 42 De Sousa, Ronald 5, 12, 27n72 DeYoung, Patricia 316 diachronic narrative intimacy 474 dialogical model of love 576 direct perception concept 323 discouragement 277 disgust: abjection theory 383–384; anomalous animals 386–388; brute materiality 381; explanatory strategy 382; Kolnai’s analysis of 384–386; Kristeva’s concept 383–384; negative emotion 380, 381; ontogenetic account of 389n1; phenomenological analysis of 384–386; philosophical account of 382; theorization of 382 displeasure emotions 89 disposedness (Befindlichkeit) 246 dissociative communalization 488 Dōgen 374 Donohoe, Janet 294 Doppelgänger, Freud’s analysis of 555 Döring, Sabine 24 Douglas, Mary 383–384 Douglass, Frederick 208 drive-intentionality 7 Drummond, John 294 Dubos, Jean-Baptiste 337 Durkheim, Émile 540n2 Eagleton, Terry 566 ecumenical approach 114 egoism of life 172 Elpidorou, Andreas 166 Elster, Jon 5, 12 embarrassment expression 140, 141, 365, 366, 456, 457 embedded approaches 7, 65, 301, 306 embodied affectivity 324–326 embodied, embedded, extended, and enacted (4E) approach 6, 18, 275, 299, 302, 303 embodied interaffectivity: autism 329–331; concept of 324–326; depression 329; interbodily resonance 326–328; neurological disorders 329; schizophrenia 331–332 embodiment 7, 10, 14, 18, 26n48, 111, 197, 199, 201, 203–204, 208, 275, 302–303, 313, 314, 317, 320–321, 328, 349, 386, 438, 441, 443, 544, 561 emotional asymmetry problem 338 emotional contagion 482; see also emotional infection emotional culture 486 emotional depth 147 emotional disposition 568 emotional enclaves 484 emotional feelings (emotionale Gefühle) 89 emotional habitus 486
emotional identification (Einsfühlen) 577, 579; see also emotional unification emotional infection (Gefühlsansteckung) 577, 579, 581; see also emotional contagion emotional keenness 577 emotional life stratification 73–75 emotional mind-set 307 emotional sharing (Miteinanderfühlen) 79, 138, 577; see also joint feeling, collective affective intentionality, and communal emotions emotional unification 434 emotional unity 78–79 emotion regulation 472 emotions of aggression see aggressive emotions empathic perception 328 empathy theory 76, 84n5, 510, 577; acquisitive theory 432; broader theory 432; concept of 432; contemporary theories of 431; definition of 429, 431; meaning of 429, 430; neuroscientific approaches 432; pathos, meanings of 429; sensual 550; simulation theory 432 entrainment 472 environmental externalism 200, 203 envy 444, 451 episode-gratitude 511, 513 episodic sentiments 68 epistemic contact 282 epistemology of value 46–50 Erikson, Erik 527 eros, phenomenology of 172 erotic love, nature of 102 ethical hate 571 ethical theory 118 evaluative feelings 8, 46 evil: banality of 565; concept of 188; denial of 564–565, 573; discourse of 565–566; hate of 564–573; radical 565; see also hate of evil evil-revivalism 565, 566 evolutionary theory 2 existential deviation 210 existential feelings 1, 97, 106; affective illusions 254; applications 252–254; classification of 255; concept of 252; of control and safety 254; description of 250–252; interpretations 254–257; outstanding issues 257–259; psychiatric illness 254 experiential position (Erlebnisstellung) 88, 89 expression concept 56–57, 61n2 externalist approach 197, 201 external perception 44, 99 extracranial body 303 falling (Verfallen) 109 Fanon, Frantz, 13, 17, 18, 389n3; colonization, affective weight of 210–212; method of touch 209; Peau noire, masques blancs 207, 210, 213n8;
592
Index questions and reconfigures phenomenology 207; racialization, phenomenology of 207–208; touch and affective memory 209–210 far-reaching social dynamic 292 fear (Furcht) 394–396, 398–400, 567 feeling-after (Nachfühlen; Scheler), 434 feeling of being 250, 255 feelings: Ancient Greek concept of 263; breadth dimension of 283; characteristic of 64, 78; depth dimension of 283–285; feelings of reality 82–84; full-fledged phenomenology of 281; intentional and non-intentional 53–55; logical/intellectual feelings 64; mental subjects, feelings as 63–64; motivational components 281–282; normativity, foundations of 282–283; object-directed feelings, sentiments as 64–67; Pfänder’s conception of 63; pleasure feelings 57–61; of reality 82–84; reality of feelings 82–84; rhythm of feeling 59; of sympathy (Smith and Scheler) 72, 433–435; value-reception feeling 57–61 feeling-sensation 540n5 feelings of self-worth, concept 96–100 feeling rules (Hochschild) 478, 486 feeling-together 434, 467–468; see also Scheler, Max feeling towards (Goldie) 469; see also affective intentionality feeling-with-one-another 79; see also Scheler, Max fellow-feeling (Mitfühlen mit jemandem) 577–580; see also Scheler, Max felt-bodily disposition 267 felt body 3, 8, 10, 14, 25n38, 27n64, 263–266, 442, 444, 450, 527 felt evaluations 8, 227; constituting import 232; emotional commitment to import 229–232; pleasure/pain feelings 234 female education 130 female existences 191 female sexuality 313 feminine for emotion 130 feminism: affective attunement 317–320; characteristic of 313; chronic shame 316–317; feminist theory 312; self-conscious emotion 314; shame, embodiment 313–314; understanding shame 314–315 feminist phenomenology 8 feminist theory 312 Ferenczi, Sandor 412 Fernandez, Anthony V. 256 Fessler, Daniel M. T. 461, 463 floating sentiments 68 Foot, Philippa 294, 417, 419, 422 forgiveness 497–498; Arendt’s theory of 502; as borderline case of emotion
505–506; conditional approach 500–501; interdependence 500; pure 501, 502; and resentment 505; theorizing 499–503; unconditional approach 501–503 formal object 220, 228 ‘4E’ approach see embodied, embedded, extended, and enacted (4E) approach Frankfurt, Harry 575 freedom 190–191 Frege, Gottlob 2 French Revolution 177–178 Freudian theory 381 Freud, Sigmund 20, 24n13, 144, 403, 561; and uncanny 553–556 friendliness 68 friendly feelings 69 “frozen now” 353 Fuchs, Thomas 404 functional virtues 526, 528 fundamental moods 394 fusion model of love 575 Gandhi, Mahatma 570 “garden variety” emotions 337, 342 gate control theory 545 Geach, Peter 294 Geiger, Moritz 2, 4, 8, 17–18, 82; affective motivation theory 88; “The Consciousness of Emotions” 87; “Contributions to the Phenomenology of Aesthetic Pleasure” 87; emotions 88–91; ill-motivated emotions theory 93; intentionality and consciousness 88–91; joy and happiness 418; motives and emotions theory 91–94; “On the Problem of Empathy regarding Moods” 87 Gendlin, Eugene T. 256 general feelings (Gemeingefühle), 124; see also vital/common feelings, and vital feelings genetic psychology method 42 genuine sentiments 68, 69–70 George, Stefan 140 German Idealism/German Idealists 2, 23n 4 Gestalt Psychology see Leipzig School of Gibson, James J. 324 Gilbert, Margaret 157, 468, 486, 541n18 Gilbert, Paul 313 Goldie, Peter 3, 6, 9, 12, 14, 24n22, 26n53, 233, 239, 240, 251, 279, 362–363, 462–463, 469 Goodman, Nelson 346 Grandin, Temple 330, 331 gratitude 509; adverbial duties 515–516, 518; benevolence and 511, 514–516, 518; elements and accounts of 510–511; episode-gratitude 511, 513; formative effects of 518; gift-giving 516–518; historical and cultural relativity 509–510; indebtedness and 514; intentional structure of 512–514; non-personal 510;
593
Index personal 510; phenomenological framework 511–518; as positive emotion 510, 514; recognition-respect 517; sense of justice 517, 518; shifting views of 509–510; trait-gratitude 511, 513 Green, Keith 569 grief: Abraham and Torok explain 406–407; incorporation in 404–406; Levinas explain 407–409; structure of 404; survival 411–413 Griswold, Charles 497, 499–501, 506n2 grounding-attunement 111 group-based political emotions 485; see also shame: group based Guardians 337–338 Guenther, Lisa 462 Guerrero Sánchez, Héctor Andrés 476n4 guilt, collective guilt feelings 468 Gurwitsch, Aron 7, 17–18; bodily and kinesthetic moments 155; bodily awareness 155, 156; consciousness, view of 154; criticisms of 157; emotions view 153; passive impressional states 154; understanding of emotion 157 Gyllenhammer, Paul 294 Haas, Willy 2, 7, 20, 28n75, 69, 70; authentic/ inauthentic emotion 20, 99; genuine and non-genuine feelings 69, 70; Über Echtheit und Unechtheit von Gefühlen 20, 69, 99 habit-incorporation process 201 habitual unification 138 happiness studies 416 Hart, James 294 Hartmann, Martin 166 Hartmann, Nicolai 20–21, 290 Hartman, Saidiya 208 hate of evil 564–573 hateworthy 571 hatred 445–457, 564, 567; natural 569 haughtiness 149 hauntology 558 Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 23n4, 169, 237n1 Heidegger, Martin 1, 3, 4, 7–9, 11, 13–14, 17, 21, 41, 159, 470, 547, 561; account of attunement 106–107; and affectivity 392–393; angst attunement 109–110; anxiety, notion of 557; Befindlichkeit, conception of 104, 105, 107, 393; Being and Time 104–107, 556; Contributions to Philosophy 110–111; depression, experiences of 256; “everyday familiarity” 557; existential feelings 106; fundamental attunements 109–111; The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics 110, 395; philosophical anthropology 109–111; radical anti-mentalism 108; Stimmung 393–394; and uncanny 556–558
Heinämaa, Sara 294 Heller, Agnes 20, 22 Helm, Bennett W. 24n25, 457–460, 469, 470, 576 Hénaff, Marcel 504 Henry, Michel 7, 11, 20, 22, 26n48, n51 Hester, Aunt 208 Heyd, David 534 Hildebrand, Dietrich von 8, 15, 17, 21, 146; affective position-takings 116–117, 119–120; apprehension (Erfassen) 115, 116; cooperative freedom idea 119; Die Idee der sittlichen Handlung 115; ecumenical approach 114; emotion and position-taking 114–117; importance, taxonomy of 117–119; notion of (dis)value 118; Sittlichkeit und ethische Werterkenntnis 117; theoretical significance of 118 Hochschild, Arlie R. 22, 486, 487 Hoffman, E.T.A. 555 Holmes, Sherlock 339 Holocaust 462, 565 Homer 337, 338 Hosking, Geoffrey 524 human behaviors 381 human finitude 187 human, ontological structure of 393 Hume, David 3, 5, 430, 433–434 humiliation: and affliction 377; characterization of 376; and debilitating shame 375; devastating quality of 376; discussion of 374; “false” self-image 376; personal integrity 375; self-revelation and self-critique 374–375 humility: being humbled 372; humbling myself 372–374; liberation style 370; modesty 374; “Myself,” reception of 369–370; openness and dynamic movement 369; self-givenness 369–372; spatial level 372 Hursthouse, Rosalind 69, 568, 569 Husserl, Edmund 1–3, 7–8, 10–11, 13–15, 17, 21–22, 26n52, 41, 114, 116, 159, 209, 431, 436, 441, 544; affective sensations 54; Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis 211; axiological theory 289, 292; bodily self-awareness 54; drive-intentionality 7; emotion and value theory 55–57; First Logical Investigations 53–55, 125, 160; Ideas I 55–57, 160; intentional and non-intentional feelings 53–55, 189; intentionality theory 3; natural and personalistic attitudes 240; nonobjectifying awareness 54; notion of feeling 242; phenomenology 511–512; pleasure feelings 57–61; reactive emotions components 57–61; retention 244; sensation of pleasure 73; unitary impressional episode 59; valuereception feeling 57–61
594
Index I-center and self 134 identification theory 340, 460 ill-motivated emotions theory 93 Illouz, Eva 22 immediately evident emotions 42 importance (Bedeutsamkeit) 117 inactual experiences 134 inauthentic feelings 98–100 indignation 448–450, 453n13 individual emotions 135–137 infinite responsibility 174 inner concentration (Innenkonzentration) 90 inner perception 44; classification of 46; judgments of 48; pain form of 544 inner unification/division 67 intellectual position-takings 116 intellectual uncertainty 555 intentional consciousness 169 intentional direction (Gegenstandsrichtung) 90 intentional feeling 53–55, 74, 240, 243, 246, 289 intentionality of emotions 3, 6, 11–12, 14, 16, 21, 27n67, 146, 147, 191 intentionality puzzle 235 intentionality theory 3 interaction theory 323, 326 interaffectivity process 326 inter-bodily resonance 324, 326–328 intercorporeality 324, 328, 330, 332, 472 interkinesthetic affectivity 472 internalization 406 The International Association for the Study of Pain 544 interpersonal empathy 323 intersubjectivity 72, 74 intrapsychic attitude 359 introspection 91; introspection/inner observation 44 intuitive act 11 inversion of values (Umkehrung der Werte) 101 involution, movement of 172 irrational inclination 170 irritation 443 Jacobson, Daniel 455 Jacoby, Susan 503 James, William 2, 233, 251, 254, 299, 300, 303, 325 Jankélévitch, Vladimir 373, 505 Jaspers, Karl 160 jealousy 444–445 Jentsch, Ernst 553, 554 Jesus 378n2 joint act of felt understanding 470 joint feeling 466; affective synchrony 471–475; collective emotional response 466, 468, 471; collective guilt feelings 468; diachronic narrative intimacy 474; episodes of 466–468;
‘feelings towards’ 469; genuinely joint manner 470; immediate feeling-together 467–468; phenomenological account of 469; plural for-the-sake-of-which 473; plural robust agents 470; sense of we-agency 472; see also collective affective intentionality, communal emotions, and emotional sharing Jones, Warren H., 242 joy and happiness 189, 217; concepts of 416, 424n9; differences 421–423; etymological characteristic of 423; preliminary distinctions 417–418; semantic and grammatical distinctions 418–421 joy/annoyance (Ärger) 89, 100; see also irritation judgment: apodictic judgments 48; blind judgments 48, 49; Brentano’s views 47; correct (true) judgment 48; correctness and incorrectness possibility 47; objectual theory of 45; self-evident judgments 48–50 Kananow, Paul 20 Kant, Immanuel 2, 24n16, 4, 426; compassion, ethical impact of 436; The Conflict of the Faculties 186; ethical theory 118; fact of practical reason 169; nature of feelings 72; pure practical reason 76; recognition of autonomy 118 Karenina, Anna 339 Karlsson, Gunnar 353 Kaufman, Gershen 315, 317 keenness, Scheler’s notion of 577 Kekes, John 565, 566 Kelly, Michael R. 294, 412 Kenny, Anthony K. 3, 5 Kierkegaard, Soren 2, 412, 414, 556 Kingston, Rebecca 490n7 Kivy, Peter 346 Klages, Ludwig 96, 263 Kolnai, Aurel 1, 4, 10, 13, 15,17, 21, 24n14, 384–387, 453n7, 571; approach to emotions 144–147; “The Concept of Hierarchy” 147; “Der Ekel” (On Disgust) 147–149, 384–387; Der ethische Wert und die Wirklichkeit 144; “Max Schelers Kritik und Würdigung der Freudschen Libidolehre” 144; perceptual model 146; “Über den Hochmut” (On Haughty Pride) 149–150; value realism 146; “Versuch über den Hass” (Essay on Hatred) 150–151 Kolodny, Niko 576 Konzelmann Ziv, Anita 466, 474 Krebs, Angelika 576, 586n3, 587n4 Krell, David Farrell 557, 558 Kristeva, Julia 383–384 Krueger, Felix 2 Krueger, Joel 308, 472, 474 Kubrick, Stanley 556
595
Index Lange, Carl Georg 2 Lear, Jonathan 413 Leder, Drew 548, 549, 561 legal peace 449 Lehtinen, Ullaliina 318 Leipzig School of Gestalt psychologists 2 Levinas, Emmanuel 291, 408–409, 462, 505, 575; asymmetrical ethics 437; De L’Évasion 349; emotion, concept of 171; emotions and affectivity role 168–170; On Escape 462; ethics of compassion 175n3; infinite responsibility 174; intentional consciousness 169; joy and happiness 418; self, rise and rupture of 170–175; subjectivity 170, 171; Totality and Infinity 172, 173, 349, 437 Levi, Primo 462 Lewis, C.S. 404, 406, 407 libidinal economies 381 libido theory 144–145 life-community (Lebensgemeinschaft), Scheler’s definition of 581, 582 life feelings (Stein), 123–126 Lipps, Theodor 2, 68, 76, 429; aesthetic sentiments 68; emotions theory 23n7; empathic understanding 76, 430–431; feeling of self-worth 96; psychological approach 431; Selbstgefühl, notion of 94n2; self-conscious emotions (Selbstgefühle) 89, 94n2, 102n1; smoke and sadness 125 Lispector, Clarice 553 lived body, pain and 546–548 lived experiences (Erlebnisse) 55, 134, 137 live through (erleben) 88 logical/intellectual feelings 64 Loidolt, Sophie 294 love 66–67, 79–81, 246, 575; authentic love 191–193; curative model 575; dialogical model 576; fellow-feeling 577–580; fusion model 575; and hating phenomenology 45, 50; models of 575–577; and sexuality 101–102; sharing 576; and trust 526; unity in shared feeling 584–585 Lovecraft, H.P. 556 Löwenstein-Freudenberg, Karl Konstantin 20 loyalty 535–537 Luhmann, Niklas 529 Lynch, David 556 Lyons, William 5 McAllister Lopez, Linda 130 McCarthy, Mary 184 McGinn, Colin 389n4 Macho, Thomas 506 MacIntyre, Alasdair 294 Mackie, John L. 291 MacLachlan, Alice 491n12 Malebranche, Nicolas 2
McLaughlin, Brian P. 254 McMullin, Irene 294 Margalit, Avishai 534 Marxism 4 masochism 372 Mason, Michelle 453n18 mass: and emotional infection 581; Scheler’s definition of 582 material tools for emoting 305–306 Mathewes, Charles T. 565, 566 Meinong, Alexius 116 Melzack, Ronald 545 membership feeling 585 mental phenomena 42–43; fundamental classes of 63; fundamental kinds of 45; inner perception 44 mental reference 45 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice 7, 9–11, 17, 18, 7, 41, 207, 299, 545–548, 560, 561; “body uncanny” 560; Cartesian intellectualism 198; The Child’s Relations with Others 299; emotions embodied system 197–200; empathy 431; externalism 197; externalist approach 197; intercorporeality 328; Phenomenology of Perception 546, 558; scaffolded emotions 200–204; “style” of experience 257; and uncanny 558–559 Miller, Susan 349 mimesis 338 mind, concept of 144, 308 mind-independent reality 43 Minkowski, Eugene 211 mirroring 528 Möbius Syndrome 7, 329 mode of attunement 108 modes of givenness (Gegebenheitsweise) 134 Montaigne, Michel de 2, 23n1 Montes Sánchez, Alba 71n7 mood: Stein’s account of 124; and sentiments 246–248; see also fundamental moods and Stimmung moral condemnation 564 moral emotions 540n7; see also morality and emotions moral feelings 168 morality and emotions: and human flourishing 293–294; and moral obligation 291–293; value, disclosure of 288–291 moral judgment ethics 75–76 moral phenomenology 5, 294n1 moral value 289, 291 Mother Theresa 378n6 motivation theory 58, 91, 127 motive of emotion 92 Mulligan, Kevin 15, 25n35, 70n3, 84n1, 114 multi-dimensional approach 19 multi-layered experiential act 55
596
Index multi-track dispositions 246 Munich Circle of Phenomenology 2 mutual experience 137 mutual incorporation 330 Nancy, Jean-Luc 408, 437 narrative theory/model of emotions 6, 18, 26n53, 462 Nathanson, Donald 317 Natorp, Paul 2, 21 natural affiliation 533, 540n1 natural-cultural segmentation 266 Natya Shastra (Bharata) 337 Nazi Germany 4 negative emotion 380, 381 negative feelings 101 Nemo, Philippe 175 neo-Aristotelian 5 neo-Jamesian accounts, perceptual and embodied 6; bodily feeling 215 Neo-Kantians/Neo-Kantianism 2, 21, 24n10 Neu, Jerome 5 neural system 546 neurological disorders 329 neuromatrix theory 545–546 neurophysiological theories of pain 545–546 New Phenomenology 3, 8, 13–14, 28n79 Nietzsche, Friedrich 96, 100, 420, 436, 453n6 noematic-noetic analysis 283 noetic description 283–284 non-formal values theory 75 non-genuine feelings (uneigentlich) 99 non-genuine sentiments 68, 69–70 non-intentional behavior 230 non-intentional feelings 53–55 non-judgemental attitude 360 non-objectifying awareness 54 normativity: and political emotions 485–487; and emotion norms 486; see also feeling rules norms, aggressive emotions 448–450 Northrop, Jane 314 notion of emotional feelings 89 Nozick, Robert 417, 419–423, 576 neuroscientific approaches 432 Nussbaum, Martha C. 5, 46, 183, 381, 575 object-directed feelings 11, 469, 470 object-incorporation process 202 objective community 136 objectual theory of judgment 45 organism-bound cognitive system 301 Ortega y Gasset, José 20–21 Other’s trust 522, 525 Ought-Implies-Can principle 69 outer concentration (Außenkonzentration) 90 over-trust 530 Ozar, Anne 294
pain: affective space 547; bodily 543, 544; and emotions 543; empathic feelings 551; as inner perception 544–545; and lived body 546–548; neurophysiological theories of 545–546; of others 550–551; phenomenological understanding of 543–544; Phenomenology of Perception (Merleau-Ponty) 546; preintentional feeling 543; and suffering 548–550 Parkinson’s disease 329 partiality, solidarity 534–536, 539 Pascal, Blaise 2 passionate 190, 191 passions of soul 2 passive impressional states 154 pathos, meanings of 429 Pattison, Stephen 317, 320 “peace of mind” 75 perception: pain 544–545; theory of emotion 46, 278 perception theory 146, 264, 279 perceptual accounts of emotions 6, 24n25; see also philosophy of emotions personal community (Personale Gemeinschaft), Scheler’s definition of 581, 583 personal feeling 585 personality core 127–128 Pfänder, Alexander 2, 8, 17–18, 20–21, 586n1; actual sentiments stream 65; centrifugal direction 66; “deep and high” sentiments 67; Einführung in die Psychologie 63; feelings, conception of 63; genuine and non-genuine sentiments 69–70; I-center and self 134; logical/intellectual feelings 64; meaning something, discussion of 66; mental subjects, feelings as 63–64; modified sentiments varieties 67–68; object-directed feelings, sentiments as 64–67; sensory feelings 89; volitive motivation 94n4 phenomenological method 210 phenomenological puzzle 235, 236 phenomenological theories of emotions 6, 9–13; basic agreement 10; contemporary use of 41; loving and hating 45 philosophy of emotions: bottom-up approach 276–277; feeling, unitary foundation of 279–280; general theory of feeling 281–285; methodology of 276–277; perceptual model of 278–279; subjectivity of 279 physical phenomena 42–43; external perception 44 Pinscher, Doberman 241 pity 177–178, 534, 540n3 Plato 2, 337–338, 433, 575 pleasant 59, 66–67 pleasure: anticipatory configuration of 59–60; pleasure/pain feelings 57–61, 89, 234; sensation of 73
597
Index Plessner, Helmuth 20, 22, 28n79 Plügge, Herbert 548 plural pre-reflective self-awareness 138 plural robust agents 470 Plutarch 567 Poe, Edgar Allan 556 Polanyi, Michael 328 political emotions 478–479; agonistic dialectic 487–489; 490n4; collective 485, 490n8, 491n10; collective affective intentionality account of 481–484, 486; and fittingness 487; group-based 485; multi-dimensional taxonomy 484–485; normativity of 486–487; overview of 480–481; shared 484; target of 483 political sophistication 484 position-taking: intentional structure of 115–116; specific characteristics of 116–117 positive affective experiences 139, 140 positive self-evaluation 358, 362 Potkay, Adam 420 practical philosophy 5 Pradines, Maurice 153–154 praecox feeling 331 preparedness 230 presentation feeling 45, 240 pride: belonging, relationship of 364; feelings and judgements, self 364; self-confidence level 364; self-conscious emotion 363 Prinz, Jesse J. 24; see also Neo-Jamesian accounts pro-attitudes (love, joy, and worship) 45, 50 proprioception 546 Protevi, John 490n8 provisional sentiments 68 Prütting, Lenz 28n79 psychiatric illness 254 psychic depth 147 psychic feelings 74, 77 psychic realism 83 psycho-dynamic interaction 14 psychologist–introjectionist–reductionist paradigm 263 psychology: of attunements 106; Brentano’s theory of consciousness 44; subject matter and method 42 psycho-physical equipment 203 psychophysically neutral sphere 77 public passions 490n7 Pugmire, David 420 pure practical reason 76 Purshouse, Luke 365 qualia 9, 15, 263, 511 qualitative attention (qualitative Aufmerksamkeit) 88–90 qualitative feeling 9, 97 quasi-things 266, 268
quasi-transcendental approach 81 queer phenomenology 8 racialization, phenomenology of 207–208, 212 racism 211, 568 radical anti-mentalism 108 radical evil 565 rage 444, 453n3 Ratcliffe, Matthew 106, 109, 360, 361 rationality 12; and emotions 4, 5; epistemic 2; rational activity 170 Rawls, John 294 reactive attitudes 234–236, 486 reactive emotions components 57–61 reality of feelings 82–84 recalcitrant emotions 93 receptivity, case of 116 reciprocal unification 136–137 recognition-respect 517 recognition-response tie 363 Reddy, Vasudevi 352 rediscovery of emotions 2, 4–6 reductionist conception 3 Reinach, Adolf 8, 15, 21, 114, 146, 586n1; account of position-taking 116; “Zur Theorie des negativen Urteils” 115 Reiner, Hans 20–21 reproduction of feeling 80, 84n5, 577, 578 Republic (Plato) 337 respect-sympathy structure 293 responsibility 276 Ressentiment 1, 13, 18, 19, 28n80, 483–484, 487, 489, 490n9; 564; Ressentiment and negative attitudes 100–101, 445, 450–451, 453n6; see also Scheler, Max, Voigtländer, Else, and aggressive emotions retention, Husserl’s notion of 244 revenge 497–498; as borderline case of emotion 505–506; ceremonial 504; modern standard view of 498; theorizing 503–504 “rhythm of feeling” 59 Richmond, Sarah 166 Ricœur, Paul 21–22, 437, 499, 505 Rinofner-Kreidl, Sonja 294 Roberts, Robert C. 24n25, 27n72 Roberts, Tom 306 romantic love see love Rorty Oksenberg, Amelie 5 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques 1, 2, 185, 435 Rozin, Paul 382 Rumke, Henricus C. 331, 332 Rutishauser, Bruno 84n1 Ryle, Gilbert 5 Saarinen, Jussi 257, 258 Sacks, Oliver 330 Salice, Alessandro 71n7, 140, 457, 460
598
Index Salmela, Mikko 471, 472, 474, 476n2 Sartrean theory 159, 166 Sartre, Jean-Paul 1, 3, 7, 9, 10, 13, 17, 41, 318, 349, 459, 545–548; affective experience 163–164; affective phenomenon 162–163, 396–400; analysis of emotions 162–163; Being and Nothingness 383, 384, 547; conscious activity 160; consciousness, notions of 162–164; emotional transformation 166–167; emotion theory 159, 161; L’Être et le Néant 349; meaning and function 164–165; mental machinery 164–165; Nausea 160–161; prereflective consciousness 163–164; Sketch for a Theory of Emotions 396; The Transcendence of the Ego 396 scaffolded emotions: incorporation process 201–202; institutions process 202–204 Scheler, Max 1, 2, 3, 7, 8, 10, 11, 13–15, 18, 21–22, 24n17, 24n25, n51, n56, n58, n59, 27n67, n68, n75, 114, 146, 240–241, 275, 431, 434 –436, 438, 457, 458, 467, 468, 474, 475, 484, 487, 490n9, 514, 564, 575, 577; emotional life stratification 73–75; emotions theory 73; empathy theory 76; feelings of reality 82–84; Formalism in Ethics and NonFormal Ethics of Values 580; four forms of fellow-feeling 577–580; four forms of social unit 580–584; love 79–81; metaphysical system 80; moral judgment ethics 75–76; The Nature of Sympathy 84n6, 144, 467, 577, 578, 580, 584; non-formal values theory 75; quasitranscendental approach 81; reality of feelings 82–84; Ressentiment 101; shame, sense of 81–82; stratification theory 81; sympathy, forms of 76–79, 431; voluntative realism 83; Wesen und Formen der Sympathie 434 Schelling, Friedrich 554, 555 schizophrenia 331–332 Schmalenbach, Hermann 3, 17, 18; “Bund” social modal category 140; community, example of 140; conceptual tripartition 141; embarrassment, expression of 141; positive affective experiences 139; see also Walther, Gerda Schmid, Hans Bernhard 137–138, 140, 470, 472, 540n5 Schmitt, Carl 479, 481 Schmitz, Hermann 3, 7–11, 13–14, 17, 27n64, 262, 263, 264, 453n14, 527; anger 449–450; atmosphere model 218–219; bodily dimension 215; emotions move and motivate 217–218; feelings, dimension of 216–217; ontological status 221; phenomenological vocabulary 441; thematic center 219–221 Schneider, Gregor 556 Schnittke, Alfred 556 Schopenhauer, Arthur 2, 426, 436, 584
Schütz, Alfred 7, 523, 586n1 scope of life concept 211 Scottish Moralists 2 Scruton, Roger 576 Sebald, W.G. 556 second wave phenomenological rediscovery of emotions 6–8 self-affection 11, 22 self-awareness 98 self-concealing 557 self-confidence level 364 self-conscious emotions (Selbstgefühle) 89, 94n2, 314, 363, 463n1 self-deceptive mechanisms 101 self-disclosive character 361 self-esteem: ability, achievement 361–363; background affective orientation 358–361; cognitive self-evaluation 359; definition of 358; intrapsychic attitude 359; and narrative structure 361–363; non-judgemental attitude 360; phenomenal character 360; phenomenological features of 359; positive self-evaluation 358, 362 self-evident judgments 48–50, 51n10 self-givenness 369 self-other-conscious emotion 352 self-poisoning attitude 101 self-worth feeling concept 96–98 Seneca 512, 515, 517 sense-making 301 sense of justice 517, 518 sensory feelings (sinnliche Gefühle) 89, 90 sensory illusions 268 sensory pain 58 sensual empathy 550 sensual feelings 123–124 sentiments: aesthetic sentiments 68; affirmation/ denial act 67; centrifugal stream of feeling 67; deep and high structure 67; floating sentiments 68; genuine sentiments 69–70; inner unification/division 67; non-genuine sentiments 68, 69–70; as object-directed feelings 64–67; suppressed sentiments 68; unification feeling 136 Shaftesbury, Anthony Ashley Cooper 5 shame 449, 455; behavioural manifestations of 352; and body 352; chronic shame 316–317, 319; definition of 354; directly reflexive 458; group-based shame 460, 463n1; heteroinduced 456–460, 463n1; indirectly reflexive 458; loving 459; moral value of 355–356; of the world 462; and others 353–355; personal 458–459; prospective shame 353; and related emotions 349–351; retrospective shame 353; and self-consciousness 351–352; selfexperience of 351; sense of 81–82; shame, embodiment 313–314; social acceptability
599
Index 458, 461; subordinance 461; survivor 461–463; and time 353; understanding shame 314–315; vicarious shame 354, 463n1; women sexuality and 314 shared affectivity 467; see also joint feelings shared emotions 134–137, 471; see also joint feeling shared feeling 324, 577, 578, 585; solidarity 536–538; unity in 584–585; see also joint feeling Sherman, Nancy 293 Sherrington, Charles Scott 545 shyness 366 Silvestrov, Valentin 556 Simmel, Georg 96, 524 simple attention (schlichte Aufmerksamkeit) 88, 89, 90 simulation theory 432 single-track dispositions 246 situated affectivity: environmental scaffolds 305–307; mind-invasions 307–309; philosophy of emotions 300–301; trials and tribulations 301–305; user–resource interactions 305–307 Sjoberg, Lennart G. 353 Slaby, Jan 106, 108, 203, 255, 259n1, 307, 308, 361 slavery economy 208 Sloterdijk, Peter 269 Smith, Adam 430, 433–434 Smith, William 5, 294 social appraisal 482 social emotion 365 social identity 460 social imaginary 485 social media, affective transformation 308 social relations 533 social systems 307–308 social tools for emoting 306–307 social unit, Scheler’s formulation of 580–584 society (Gesellschaft), Scheler’s definition of 583 socio-diagnostic phenomenology 210 socio-moral functions 388 solidarity 541n16, 541n19; attitude of 532, 534; conceptual history of 533–534; debts 532–533; direction of fit 533; feeling 534–538; idea of 533, 539–540; misled 541n20; morality 538–540; notion of 540n6; partial and reflective emotion 534–536, 539; vs. pity 534, 540n3; promise 533–534; role of 539; sharing 536–538; Stein’s model 536–538, 540n11, 541n17; Wiggins’ model of 541n23 Solomon, Robert C. 5, 27n72, 46, 498, 503, 505, 575 spatiality of emotions 442–443; see also anchoring point; condensation area spatial level 372
species, evolution mechanisms 380 Spilliaert, Léon 556 Spinoza, Baruch 2, 23n6, 420 spiritual feelings 14 spontaneity, manifestations of 115 Steinbock, Anthony 294 Stein, Edith 3, 7–8, 10–11, 13–18, 25n45, 27n65, n69, 65, 431, 476n4, 536–539, 540n11, 541n17, 550, 575, 577; collective emotions 128–130; emotion conception 128; emotion feeling 123–128, 128–130; Essays on Woman 130; female education 130; feminine for emotion 130; Gemeinschaftserlebnis 128; and gender 130–131; joy, example of 125–126; motivation 127; personality core 127–128; Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities 125, 585; On the Problem of Empathy 550; religion and mysticism 130–131; smoke and sadness, example of 125; women, writings on 130 Stephan, Achim 106, 108, 255 Sterelny, Kim 305 Stern, Daniel N. 255, 329 Stern, William 2 Stevenson, C.L. 5 Stimmung (mood) 393–394; see also mood, Heidegger, Martin, and Bollnow, Otto Friedrich St. John of the Cross 378n6 Stoics/Neo-Stoics 2 Strasser, Stephan 3, 20–21, 417 stratification theory 81, 147 Straus, Erwin 548 Strauss, Leo 568 Strawson, Peter F. 234, 486, 540n4 Stumpf, Carl 2, 544; theories of pain 544 subconscious experiences 134, 136, 138 subject experiences motivation 93 subjective communities 136 subjectivity: dialectical genesis of 170; disintegration of 171 subordinance shame 461 sui generis intentional phenomena 41, 45–46 suppressed sentiments 68 survival, mode of 407 survivor shame 461–463 Svenaeus, Fredrik 561 sympathetic pity 534 sympathy 293, 576; concept of 433; meaning of 429 synchronic unity 70 Szanto, Thomas 71n7, 453n6, 540n10 Tangney, June P. 354 Tappolet, Christine 24n25 Taylor, Gabriele 358, 364, 365 Tellenbach, Hubertus 263 Teroni, Fabrice 243, 246
600
Index tetanisation affective 212, 213n19 theory of mind 329 things in themselves study 43 threateningness 56, 57 Titchener, Edward 429 Tönnies, Ferdinand 133, 139 Torok, Maria 406 touch and affective memory 209–210 transcendent movement 191 tried-and-true techniques 344 “troubled feeling” 567 trust: affective 526; assuredness 526–528; atmospheric 526–527; betrayal of 530; bonds 524; compromised 530; coupling of 527–530; dialogical relationship 529–530; faith in the Other’s truthfulness 523–524; loss of 525; and love 526; mutual 530; networks 523; nourishment and nurturing of 526; in others 522, 525, 527–528; over-trust 530; possibilities of 529; relationships of 526, 528, 529; self-prescribing element of 529; self-trust 522–523; trustworthiness 522, 524; in the world 523, 524 trustworthiness of others 524 truth correspondence theory 47 Turrow, Gabe 472 uncanny: anxiety 555–557, 561; bodies 559–561; concept of 553; Freud and 553–556; Heidegger and 556–558; living body and 559; MerleauPonty and 558–559; repression and 559 unification feeling 136 unity of feeling 584–585 user–resource interaction 305 value-awareness 97 value-ception 14; see also value feeling, value reception, and Wertfühlen value-complex 80 value-content 577; supra-individual accessibility of 584 value feeling 12, 278; see also value-ception, value reception, and Wertfühlen value realism 146 value-reception 57–61 values/disvalues 127 value theory 294 Varga, Somogy 308 Velleman, David 575 Vendrell Ferran, Íngrid 25n45, 71n7, 84n1, 294, 540n5 vengeance 498, 503–505 vicarious feeling 578 vigilance 230
vindicatory system 504 violence 182, 445 virtue-ethical approaches 5 vital and psychic feelings 74, 75, 77, 98 vital/common feelings 10, 14; see also general feelings vital feelings (Lebensgefühle) 107; see also general feelings Voigtländer, Else 2, 7, 11, 17, 22, 24n13, 25n45, 27n74, 94n2, 586n1; “feelings of self-worth” concept 96–98; inauthentic feelings 98–100; love and sexuality 101–102; Ressentiment and negative attitudes 100–101; self-worth feeling concept 96–98; Über die ‘Art’ eines Menschen und das Erlebnis der Maske 99; Vom Selbstgefühl 96 volitional responses 116 volonté générale, Rousseauian notion of 179, 180 Voltaire 525 voluntative realism 83 Waldenfels, Bernhard 430 Walther, Gerda 2, 3, 4, 7, 11, 13, 17–18, 70n5, 586n1; actual-present experiences 134; collective emotions theory 133; communal emotions 137–139; community and society emotions 139–142; I-center and self 134; individual emotions 136; shared emotions analysis 134–137; subconscious experiences 134; unification 136 Weber, Max 22 Weil, Simone 377 Wertfühlen (Scheler and Hildebrand), 120n12; see also value feeling, value-ception, and value reception Western philosophy 2 Wiggins, David 145, 539, 541n23 Will, Udo 472 Withy, Katherine 106 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 2, 4 Wollheim, Richard 5, 24n22, 540n7 women: condition, philosophico-political 187, 192; self-conscious emotion 314; sexuality and shame 314 World War II 5 Wüschner, Philipp 453n15 xenophobia 570 Young-Bruehl, Elisabeth 381 Zahavi, Dan 129, 140, 462 Zaner, Richard 560–561 Zulu culture 204
601