The Postcolonial Gramsci 9780415874816, 9780203128916

The importance of Antonio Gramsci’s work for postcolonial studies can hardly be exaggerated, and in this volume, contrib

223 67 5MB

English Pages [267] Year 2012

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Table of contents :
Cover
The Postcolonial Gramsci
Copyright
Contents
List of Figures
List of Abbreviations
Acknowledgments
Introduction: The Postcolonial Gramsci
Part I: Gramsci and Postcolonial Studies
1. Il Gramsci meridionale
2. Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci
3. The Travels of the Organic Intellectual: The Black Colonized Intellectual in George Padmore and Frantz Fanon
4. The Secular Alliance: Gramsci, Said and the Postcolonial Question
Part II: Gramsci and the Global Present
5. The “Unseen Order”: Religion, Secularism and Hegemony
6. Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century
7. Entering the World from an Oblique Angle: On Jia Zhangke as an Organic Intellectual
8. Questioning Intellectuals: Reading Caste with Gramsci in Two Indian Literary Texts
9. Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America: Between Revolution and Decoloniality
Part III: Epilogue
Interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak
List of Contributors
Works Cited
Index
Recommend Papers

The Postcolonial Gramsci
 9780415874816, 9780203128916

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

The Postcolonial Gramsci

ROUTLEDGE RESEARCH IN POSTCOLONIAL LITERATURES Edited in collaboration with the Centre for Colonial and Postcolonial Studies, University of Kent at Canterbury, this series presents a wide range of research into postcolonial literatures by specialists in the field. Volumes will concentrate on writers and writing originating in previously (or presently) colonized areas, and will include material from non-anglophone as well as anglophone colonies and literatures. Series editors: Donna Landry and Caroline Rooney. 1. Magical Realism in West African Fiction: Seeing with a Third Eye by Brenda Cooper 2. The Postcolonial Jane Austen edited by You-Me Park and Rajeswari Sunder Rajan 3. Contemporary Caribbean Women’s Poetry: Making Style by Denisede Caires Narain 4. African Literature, Animism and Politics by Caroline Rooney 5. Caribbean–English Passages: Intertextuality in a Postcolonial Tradition by Tobias Döring 6. Islands in History and Representation edited by Rod Edmond and Vanessa Smith 7. Civility and Empire: Literature and Culture in British India, 1822–1922 by Anindyo Roy 8. Women Writing the West Indies, 1804–1939: ‘A Hot Place, Belonging To Us’ by Evelyn O’Callaghan 9. Postcolonial Pacific Writing: Representations of the body by Michelle Keown 10. Writing Woman, Writing Place: Contemporary Australian and South African Fiction by Sue Kossew 11. Literary Radicalism in India: Gender, Nation and the Transition to Independence by Priyamvada Gopal 12. Postcolonial Conrad: Paradoxes of Empire by Terry Collits 13. American Pacificism: Oceania in the U.S. Imagination by Paul Lyons 14. Decolonizing Culture in the Pacific: Reading History and Trauma in Contemporary Fiction by Susan Y. Najita 15. Writing Sri Lanka: Literature, Resistance and the Politics of Place by Minoli Salgado 16. Literature of the Indian Diaspora: Theorizing the Diasporic Imaginary by Vijay Mishra 17. Secularism in the Postcolonial Indian Novel: National and Cosmopolitan Narratives in English by Neelam Srivastava 18. English Writing and India, 1600–1920: Colonizing Aesthetics by Pramod K. Nayar 19. Decolonising Gender: Literature, Enlightenment and the Feminine Real by Caroline Rooney 20. Postcolonial Theory and Autobiography by David Huddart 21. Contemporary Arab Women Writers by Anastasia Valassopoulos 22. Postcolonialism, Psychoanalysis and Burton: Power Play of Empire by Ben Grant 24 Land and Nationalism in Fictions from Southern Africa by James Graham 25. Paradise Discourse, Imperialism, and Globalization: Exploiting Eden by Sharae Deckard 26. The Idea of the Antipodes: Place, People, and Voices by Matthew Boyd Goldie 27. Feminism, Literature and Rape Narratives: Violence and Violation edited by Sorcha Gunne and Zoë Brigley Thompson 28. Locating Transnational Ideals edited by Walter Goebel and Saskia Schabio 29. Transnational Negotiations in Caribbean Diasporic Literature: Remitting the Text by Kezia Page 30. Representing Mixed Race in Jamaica and England from the Abolition Era to the Present by Sara Salih 31. Postcolonial Nostalgias: Writing, Representation and Memory by Dennis Walder 32. Publishing the Postcolonial: Anglophone West African and Caribbean Writing in the UK 1948– 1968 by Gail Low 33. Postcolonial Tourism: Literature, Culture, and Environment by Anthony Carrigan 34. The Postcolonial City and its Subjects: London, Nairobi, Bombay by Rashmi Varma 35. Terrorism and Insurgency in Indian-English Literature: Writing Violence and Empire by Alex Tickell 36. The Postcolonial Gramsci edited by Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya Related Titles: Postcolonial Life-Writing: Culture, Politics, and Self-Representation by Bart Moore-Gilbert

The Postcolonial Gramsci

Edited by Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya

NEW YORK AND LONDON

First published 2012 by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Simultaneously published in the UK by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN

Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business

© 2012 Taylor & Francis The right of Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya to be identified as the authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual chapters, has been asserted by them in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. Typeset in Baskerville by IBT Global. Printed and bound in the United States of America on acid-free paper by IBT Global. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data The postcolonial Gramsci / edited by Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya. p. cm. — (Routledge research in postcolonial literatures ; 36) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Gramsci, Antonio, 1891–1937—Criticism and interpretation. 2. Postcolonialism in literature. 3. Criticism—Italy—History—20th century. I. Srivastava, Neelam Francesca Rashmi, 1972– II. Bhattacharya, Baidik, 1975– PC1064.G7P67 2011 195—dc23 ISBN13: 978-0-415-87481-6 (hbk) ISBN13: 978-0-203-12891-6 (ebk)

Contents

List of Figures List of Abbreviations Acknowledgments Introduction: The Postcolonial Gramsci

vii xi ix 1

NEELAM SRIVASTAVA AND BAIDIK BHATTACHARYA

PART I Gramsci and Postcolonial Studies 1

Il Gramsci meridionale

17

ROBERT J. C. YOUNG

2

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

34

PAOLO CAPUZZO AND SANDRO MEZZADRA

3

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual: The Black Colonized Intellectual in George Padmore and Frantz Fanon

55

NEELAM SRIVASTAVA

4

The Secular Alliance: Gramsci, Said and the Postcolonial Question

80

BAIDIK BHATTACHARYA

PART II Gramsci and the Global Present 5

The “Unseen Order”: Religion, Secularism and Hegemony IAIN CHAMBERS

101

vi 6

Contents Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century

119

PARTHA CHATTERJEE

7

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle: On Jia Zhangke as an Organic Intellectual

137

PHENG CHEAH

8

Questioning Intellectuals: Reading Caste with Gramsci in Two Indian Literary Texts

165

RAJESWARI SUNDER RAJAN

9

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America: Between Revolution and Decoloniality

191

WALTER D. MIGNOLO

PART III Epilogue Interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak

221

List of Contributors Works Cited Index

233 237 251

Figures

7.1

“You can travel around the world without leaving Beijing,” with fictitious web path of the park’s website, from title sequence.

152

Old peasant man walking past with replica of Eiffel tower in the background, from title sequence.

153

7.3

Tao dressed as a fl ight attendant.

155

7.4

Animation of Tao flying past Tiananmen Square.

156

7.2

Abbreviations

SPNB = Selections from the Prison Notebooks. Ed. Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell Smith. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1971. SPW 1 = Antonio Gramsci, Selections from Political Writings, 1910–1920. Ed. Quintin Hoare. Trans. John Mathews. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1977. SPW 2 = Antonio Gramsci, Selections from Political Writings, 1921–1926. Ed. and trans. Quintin Hoare. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1978.

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Michelle Houston for her splendid editorial work in preparing this manuscript for publication. We would not have been able to complete this book without her. Neelam Srivastava would also like to thank the people who read drafts of this work and offered helpful and constructive feedback, especially Jim House, Carolyn Pedwell, Eleanor Spaventa, Rajeswari Sunder Rajan, and Robert Young. Many thanks also to Claudia Baldoli for her helpful advice on Italian historiography. Baidik Bhattacharya would like to thank Rajeswari Sunder Rajan, Udaya Kumar, and Mallarika Sinha Roy for their help and encouragement at various stages of the project. He would also like to thank Renish Abraham, Loiya Leima Oinam, and Yamini Sahista for their editorial help. And fi nally, we would like to thank all our contributors for their generosity with time and resources—without which this volume would not have been possible.

Introduction The Postcolonial Gramsci

1

Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya

This volume presents a series of essays that engage with the oeuvre of Antonio Gramsci in relationship to the field of postcolonial studies. The importance of Gramsci for the development of this school of critical thought can hardly be exaggerated, and this book is the fi rst to offer a comprehensive overview of how a number of leading postcolonial scholars have engaged with his work. At the same time, the essays contained here draw on his thought to understand the present moment of history that we inhabit, and suggest future possibilities for research on Gramsci as a postcolonial thinker. Over the past few years, there has been renewed academic interest in Gramsci in the Anglophone world, which testifies to the continuing importance of his work for a variety of different disciplines, including politics, international relations, globalization studies, and literary and cultural studies.2 Marcus E. Green, for example, in his wide-ranging edited collection Rethinking Gramsci (2011), offers an overall reassessment of Gramsci for the contemporary era within the context of a broader reevaluation of Marxist thought today. In part, the recent emergence of this rich body of Anglophone scholarship on the Italian thinker may have been prompted by the publication of the fi rst three volumes of the complete English translation of The Prison Notebooks by Joseph A. Buttigieg. The focus of our book, however, differs from these recent studies. While many of the essays included here fully engage with this new translation of the Notebooks, our aim is to examine Gramsci’s legacy for postcolonial studies, and to revisit sites and ideas that have been central to this exchange. As a Sardinian intellectual located in the South of Europe, Gramsci’s “meridionalismo,” and his understanding of subalternity as a concept that intersects nation, class, and race, continue to offer productive lines of enquiry for postcolonial scholars. As the essays in this collection testify, we are not aiming at an overall reassessment of Gramsci’s work, and at the same time we are not restricting him to certain available traditions of Marxist thinking that, quite contrary to the spirit of Gramsci’s own writing, steadfastly offer a constrained framework as the true context of his political writing. Our insistence on the postcolonial is an attempt to mark our distance from such readings of Gramsci, and also

2

Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya

to stretch the possibilities of his texts beyond any restrictive geographical boundaries. Our contributors offer new interpretations of Gramsci in specific postcolonial contexts, informed by an interdisciplinary thrust. Some essays examine Gramsci’s relevance in the diverse geopolitical contexts of South America, China, and India. Others revisit his legacy for the development of anti-colonial and postcolonial theories, as we discuss in the plan of the book. We have also strived to present a comparativist approach that links Gramsci’s position in the complex debate on the role of the left in Italy, to his uses by scholars in wider geographical and historical contexts. Timothy Brennan, in his 2006 book Wars of Position, warns of the perils of “decontextualizing” Gramsci from his Italian location and argues for a philological scholarship that maintains an attentiveness to the textual detail of the Quaderni del carcere [The Prison Notebooks] and the pre-prison writings. While our essays demonstrate a sustained attention to the philological detail of his texts, often drawing both on the Italian original and on the available English translations, they also reiterate the importance of a non-dogmatic approach in the interpretation of the Italian thinker’s work, insisting that there is no “single” reading of his oeuvre. This may be to do partly with the unfi nished and ongoing nature of the Quaderni, which can be seen as a sort of work in progress that Gramsci was frequently revising and redrafting; and partly, of course, with the enormous variety and complexity of the topics he covers. Gramsci, as Iain Chambers has argued recently, was instrumental in helping scholars rethink the understanding of historical, political, and cultural struggle by substituting the relationship between tradition and modernity with that of subaltern versus hegemonic parts of the world (Esercizi di potere 8). A fundamental legacy of Gramsci, as Chambers remarks, is his insistence on the primacy of culture in the elaboration of power, “and thus of the power of culture in the realization of a historical-social bloc” (8, emphasis in the original). In the spirit of thinkers such as Frantz Fanon and Edward Said, the essays in our book aim to reconsider the role of culture and its inherent relationship to political directiveness, in the formation of a genuinely anticolonial way of thinking. This introduction attempts to provide a map of reading Gramsci from a postcolonial perspective for readers who may not be overly familiar with his work. In the fi rst section, “Gramsci and the Colonial Question,” we give a brief overview of Gramsci’s quite original engagement with imperialism, which has received little discussion in the Anglophone postcolonial theorization of modern empires and their legacies.3 It also demonstrates that his relevance to the study of contemporary empires and neo-colonial formations goes beyond the indirect influence of his political concepts. This helps us lay the ground for our claim that Gramsci can be considered a postcolonial thinker. In the second section, “Gramsci and the Postcolonial,” we further develop this claim, by briefly tracing the genealogy of Gramsci in

Introduction

3

foundational moments of postcolonial thought. In this last section, we also lay out the plan of the book, and examine how each contributor has engaged with his work. Gramsci and the Colonial Question Gramsci’s own reflections on colonialism and empire were sophisticated and forward-looking, more progressive than most Marxist and socialist thinkers of his generation, though they retain an undeniably Eurocentric approach. In this section, we identify three key moments of his engagement with these issues in the Prison Notebooks. He developed these reflections over a period of time, beginning in the late 1920s, through to the mid-1930s. First, we discuss how he elaborates his idea of the “war of position” and “war of manoeuvre” in relationship to anti-colonial struggle in India against British imperialism. Second, we examine how he draws analogies between Italy and the colonial context. Third, we look at Gramsci’s theory of Italian colonialism, and its connections to the Southern Question and to economic policy after Italian Unification. We also discuss his critique of the civilizing mission, where he indicates that anti-colonial wars of national liberation are the sign of an achieved political maturity on the part of colonized peoples, as thinkers such as Fanon would subsequently do. Gramsci on Gandhi Writing in the late 1920s, and elaborating on the parallels and divergences between political struggle and military war, Antonio Gramsci introduces a curious detour in his Notebooks and talks about the Indian nationalist struggle, especially under the leadership of Gandhi, against British colonial occupation. The connection between politics and war is one of the central rubrics through which Gramsci explores the much larger architecture of the state and the civil society, and, being the astute philosopher of praxis that he is, he stretches the connection beyond figurative analogies. The complexity of political struggle, he suggests, can be grasped through a comparison with “colonial wars” or “old wars of conquest” where military conquest is followed by a prolonged resistance that may assume different forms and modalities. The political struggle in India against the English (and he is quick to signal other parallels: “Germany against France,” “Hungary against the Little Entente”) is a paradigmatic case in one’s understanding of the political struggle as it simultaneously assumes three different forms of war: “war of movement, war of position, and underground warfare.” Gandhi’s “passive resistance” in movements like Non-cooperation that includes strategies like boycotting of British merchandise and colonial bureaucracy, constitutes a war of position; it often becomes a war of movement through strategies like “strike” and at other times underground warfare through the “secret

4

Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya

preparation of weapons and combat troops” (Gramsci, SPNB 229). Gramsci’s elliptical passage on Indian nationalist struggle cannot be dismissed as a mere marginal entry into an otherwise Eurocentric text because of the importance he assigns to the colonial paradigm in thinking the contours of political struggle in his contemporary world.4 What is more, this passage, and several other similar passages across the Prison Notebooks, constitutes a testimony not only to the international and connected histories he had in mind while talking about contemporary political praxis, but also of a certain version of history he privileged in his writing. It is the version of history that takes sudden turns to explode national boundaries, in order to accommodate and elaborate on unexpected locations and peoples, and to think of historical narrative not as a tribute to monologic orthodoxy but as a plural and heterodoxic enterprise. The passage previously quoted does not offer the colonial location as an additive element to larger historical narratives, but uses it as a paradigmatic case to think of certain key concepts in Gramsci’s oeuvre. In the pages that follow this passage, he proposes an increasing overlap between the military and the political, and argues for a political model that must use war as a “stimulus” and not simply as a “model” that must be emulated. Through a series of historical examples, he outlines the way the war produces stimuli for both the state and the civil society, and, with particular focus, delineates the vicissitudes of organized politics that assumes different modes of war. The colonial locations—whether India or Ireland—remain quite central to this formulation (SPNB 230–3). Gramsci on the Southern Question A second point of engagement with the colonial issue is Gramsci’s treatment of the Southern Question. He analyzes Italy as a country that presents some intriguing analogies with colonial situations; independence and unification came late, in 1861. Previously, Italy had been territorially fragmented, divided up among various hereditary realms, European powers such as the AustroHungarian Empire, long-standing dynasties such as the Bourbon Kingdom of the Two Sicilies, and of course the ever-powerful Catholic Church. After unification the country was characterized by an ever-increasing gap between the more industrialized and wealthy North and the more rural, poverty-stricken South, with a tendency of the North to exploit the resources of the South for its own economic development. 5 The South was reduced to a “semi-colonial market” (Quaderni del carcere 2038).6 Gramsci argues that while the common perception was that the North was “supporting” the South, in actual fact wealth from the South, coming from rich landowners and feudal landlords who exploited agricultural labor, was being diverted to the North. Thus Italy presents itself as a case study for understanding the colonial relationship, both in international terms—as having been both subject to external powers

Introduction

5

and a colonizing power itself—and in domestic terms—as the dominance of the North over the South. Gramsci argues that after 1861 there was a situation of “internal colonialism,” with the North exercising political and economic hegemony over the South. Indeed, the forms of racialist discourse that the North projected onto the South of Italy were eerily reminiscent of colonial racisms practiced in the British and French colonies. Gramsci links Northern racism toward the South to the increasing exploitation of Southern material resources on the part of the North, after Unification. The “poverty” of the South was inexplicable to the popular masses of the North; they did not understand that Unification had not happened on an egalitarian basis, but as the hegemony of the North over the Mezzogiorno, as a territorial relationship between city and countryside. In other words, the North, in concrete terms, was a “tentacular parasite” that became rich at the expense of the South. (Quaderni 2021) The common man of the North could not understand why the South had not managed to modernize after being liberated from the ancien régime, and after becoming part of unified Italy. The only explanation available, then, was that people from the South were biologically inferior and barbaric (Quaderni 2022). Recent scholarship has developed these reflections on the Southern Question to demonstrate how racism in Italy was internalized within its own borders. Jane Schneider has identified the contemporary persistence of the Southern Question discourse in modern Italy as a series of racialized binary oppositions between the “civic,” industrialized North and the backward, “clientelistic” South, which helped to produce a “neo-Orientalist discourse within Italy itself” (“Introduction” 8). In Italy “race was used to . . . explain persistent differences within the nation, especially divergences between the North and the South” (Gibson 100). Lenin’s Theses on the National and Colonial Questions of 1920 also influenced the way Gramsci perceived the close analogies between colonizer/colonized and what he called “the semi-colonial relationship” between Northern and Southern Italy (Rosengarten 140). Gramsci on Italian Imperialism and the Civilizing Mission A third moment of engagement with colonialism in the Notebooks is represented by Gramsci’s theory of Italian imperialism and his reflections on the civilizing mission. Gramsci argued that the imperial aspirations of the new nation-state were linked to the Southern Question and Italian economic policy after 1861. Gramsci notes how Italy’s need for agricultural land and space for demographic expansion fuelled the desire for colonies among Italian statesmen at the end of the nineteenth century, especially the Prime Minister Francesco Crispi, who was in office from 1887 to 1896, with one interruption

6

Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya

(Quaderni 2019). Gramsci observes that, in classic “imperial” fashion, Crispi presented the “mirage” of African colonies to the Southern Italian peasant as a diversionary tactic to avoid having to effect a more equitable redistribution of land in Italy itself (Quaderni 2018), and to consolidate the hegemony of the political ruling class over the rural masses of the South. Colonization follows the flow of capital invested in different countries, and is never due purely to the need to “place” its excess population (Quaderni 986; 1991). For Gramsci, Italian imperialism was “passionate and rhetorical,” without any real economic basis, since it lacked capital to invest in overseas markets. Unlike other European empires, it followed a purely political logic, that of bolstering up national unity (Liguori and Voza 143).7 Thus Gramsci sees a close link between the Southern question and the question of colonialism. His theory of Italian colonialism is linked to his interpretation of the Risorgimento as a failed socialist, or even social, revolution, a thesis that would have a profound and lasting influence on debates in Italian historiography, as exemplified in the work of Rosario Romeo, and picked up by historians such as John Davis.8 Gramsci’s views on colonialism differed sharply from those of other Italian socialists and Marxists. The poet Giovanni Pascoli, who had socialist leanings, and the early Italian Marxist Antonio Labriola both supported Italy’s invasion of Libya in 1912. Gramsci develops his critique of the civilizing mission by analyzing a comment made by Labriola on the idea of pedagogy for “primitive” peoples. Labriola was asked how he would morally educate someone from Papua New Guinea (i.e., a “native”). Labriola replied that provisionally, he would enslave him, but he might then consider more modern forms of pedagogy for future generations. Gramsci denounces Labriola’s remark as a form of third-rate historicism, an inadequate answer to the question of whether “a nation or social group that has reached a superior level of civilization can (and therefore must) ‘accelerate’ the process of education of more backward peoples and social groups, universalizing and translating in an adequate way their own new experience” (Quaderni 1366–7). He thus likens the colonial question to the question of whether the ruling classes have the “right” to dominate, both politically and morally, the lower classes. But he emphatically disagrees with Labriola’s simplistic equation of the natives or the people as “children.” He says that the enslavement of indigenous peoples as a form of colonial pedagogy is in itself politically retrograde; “it is in fact necessary that there be a struggle about this [slavery], and that this struggle is precisely the condition through which the grand-children of the native from Papua New Guinea will be liberated from slavery and educated to modern Pedagogy” (1367). It is through anti-colonial/class struggle that men are educated into political maturity, argues Gramsci, not through the assimilation of “superior” cultural and moral values of the colonizer (a point that is particularly resonant in Frantz Fanon’s thinking). Further on in the passage, Gramsci suggests that the endorsement of slavery is the expression of a “universally

Introduction

7

immature condition” (1368). In a brilliant reversal, Gramsci demonstrates how, far from slavery being a “necessary” condition for the entry of primitive peoples into civilization, it is in itself uncivilized and uncivilizing. Gramsci’s penetrating analysis of imperialism in its various guises shows his sophisticated awareness of its role in shaping global politics between the end of the nineteenth century and the interwar period. As Timothy Brennan remarks, “Gramsci embodies his era’s anti-colonial energies” (Wars of Position 233). In the next section, we will briefly examine some of the ways in which postcolonial scholarship has drawn on Gramsci’s thought, and end by presenting the structure of the book. Gramsci and the Postcolonial As is well known, postcolonial theory has in many ways appropriated and made its own certain Gramscian terms such as the subaltern, hegemony, the national-popular, the intellectual, and the idea of civil society versus political society, all concepts our authors deploy in their varied takes on the “postcolonial” Gramsci. These essays represent a new contribution to the ways in which postcolonial theoretical debates have often constructed their own raison d’être around these very concepts. It is precisely Gramsci’s dynamic use and application of these concepts that has made their postcolonial reincarnation so productive and indeed possible. The influence of Gramsci in postcolonial theory can be clearly mapped across two lines—the fi rst one starts with Edward W. Said’s Orientalism (1978) and the second one begins with the Subaltern Studies collective in the early 1980s under the leadership of Ranajit Guha. These two moments are important for postcolonial studies for a number of reasons, but here we wish to highlight the various ways in which both these projects were shaped by Gramsci’s works. Said and Gramsci Said describes his debt to Gramsci as a twofold one—it allowed him to think through the puzzling question of Orientalism’s durability through history despite its problems and shortcomings, and it also enabled him to place his own self within the same history as a displaced Arab intellectual. In the fi rst instance he develops the idea of hegemony to understand the efficacy of Orientalist discourses. As Raymond Williams shows, the Gramscian notion of “hegemony” allows one to think of culture as both “tradition” and “practice” and thus to conceptualize it as much more than a superstructure. Culture does not simply reflect an organized social structure, but in important ways allows one to go beyond the abstractions of social and economic realities and to relate to the world (111). When one uses hegemony to explain the strength of Orientalist discourses, practices, and institutions, it is important to keep

8

Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya

in mind the distinction Gramsci makes between hegemony (egemonia) and leadership (direzione): a class is dominant in two ways, i.e. “leading” and “dominant.” It leads the classes which are its allies, and dominates those which are its enemies. Therefore, even before attaining power a class can (and must) “lead”; when it is in power it becomes dominant, but continues to “lead” as well . . . there can and must be a “political hegemony” even before the attainment of governmental power, and one should not count solely on the power and material force which such a position gives in order to exercise political leadership or hegemony. (SPNB 57) The theoretical presupposition behind Gramsci’s argument here is a distinction between civil and political societies: while the consent-generating function is part of the civil society—and here the importance of cultural production is paramount—the other domain is reserved for the coercive apparatuses of the political society or the state to “enforce discipline on those groups who do not consent” (SPNB 12). Said’s reading of Gramsci broadly follows this argument; he argues that culture is part of the civil society and is directly involved in the way dominant ideas and discourses are generated, circulated, and maintained in any society that is not totalitarian. That Orientalism as a discourse functions so well despite its contradictions and forms a key part of the Western domination through imperialism can be explained if one conceptualizes it as a result of cultural hegemony. Indeed, through the cultural hegemony of the west Orientalism achieves its durability, strength, and functional consistency. Such a notion of cultural hegemony functions by identifying a collective European self and its opposite as an equally collective non-European other; Said even argues that the “major component in European culture is precisely what made that culture hegemonic both in and outside Europe: the idea of European identity as a superior one in comparison with all the non-European peoples and cultures” (Orientalism 7). The positional superiority that Europe enjoys vis-à-vis the Orient, which is derived from cultural hegemony and which dictates a range of relationships with the Orient, has been most prominent since the late eighteenth century, during the period of Europe’s direct political domination over the vast imperial geography, and it is during this period in history that one witnesses the emergence of a “complex Orient suitable for study in the academy, for display in the museum, for reconstruction in the colonial office, for theoretical illustration in anthropological, biological, linguistic, racial, and historical theses about mankind and the universe” (Orientalism 7). This orchestrated effort to construct a manageable and governable Orient shapes what can and cannot be said about it; it enforces a representational regime, so to speak, that shapes the contours of Orientalist discourses over the centuries. Said,

Introduction

9

however, makes it clear again through Gramsci that such “internal constraints” of the imperial culture “were productive, and not unilaterally inhibiting” (Orientalism 14); such a move is essential in Said’s theory because it allows him to think of individual authors and texts within a larger cultural milieu without making the author or the text always already subservient to the political demands of imperial ideology. The point is also important because it explains how the discourses and practices could continue through history in the fi rst place. Having said that, one also needs to account for the project of Orientalism itself and needs further to explain the condition that made it possible. If Orientalist discourses are indeed productive, and if they shape every form of enunciation on the subject, how can one possibly resist the protocols of such discourses and how does one write a critical history of their workings? Said’s answer is that the possibility of critiques lies inside the discourses, and not in any rarefied and innocent exteriority; it is his awareness of being constituted as an “Oriental,” he suggests, which makes the critical evaluation of Orientalism possible. Here again he invokes Gramsci to argue that the “starting-point of critical elaboration is the consciousness of what one really is, and is ‘knowing thyself’ as a product of the historical process to date, which has deposited in you an infi nity of traces, without leaving an inventory.” Said observes that the fi rst English translation inexplicably stops here while the original Italian adds another sentence— “therefore it is imperative at the outset to compile such an inventory” (Orientalism 25). Orientalism for him is such an inventory, it allows him to record those “infi nity of traces” that hegemonic Western culture has deposited on hi subjecthood as an “Oriental”; it is a critical engagement with historical processes at once personal and public, and an attempt to narrate them across Said’s own self. If Said’s account of Gramsci somewhat underplays the latter’s emphasis on class, the next project of the Subaltern historians, on the other hand, makes it one of their central concerns. Subaltern Studies and Gramsci The Subaltern Studies collective of historians, founded by Ranajit Guha, is perhaps Gramsci’s most visible legacy in the panorama of interdisciplinary postcolonial studies today. Guha has offered a recent reassessment of Gramsci’s importance for the collective, emphasizing the unpredictable fact that the influence of his thought on the Indian left took root in an academic project such as Subaltern Studies, rather than in the two official communist parties of India (“Gramsci in India” 289). The historians of Subaltern Studies, in their radical positioning to the left of these official parties, found in Gramsci a privileged interlocutor for their political sympathies: like him, they opposed dogmatic forms of Marxism, while supporting more militant

10

Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya

versions of leftist politics like the Naxalite movement (289). Guha reminds us that the Subaltern Studies project was profoundly political, “an organic part of its life and times,” and not just a “detached academic observation post” (290). As such, it revolutionized “the academic establishment that had been the custodian of South Asian studies both in England and India since the nineteenth century” (291). At the outset the Subaltern Studies project was designed to critique the elitism of both liberal and nationalist versions of South Asian historiography. In the fi rst volume of Subaltern Studies Ranajit Guha identifies the “six-point project envisaged by Antonio Gramsci in his ‘Notes on Italian History’” as the inspiration behind this revisionist history of South Asia (“Preface” vii). In his contribution to the same volume, “On Some Aspects of the Historiography of Colonial India,” Guha elaborates on the aspiration of the collective and defi nes the Gramscian notion of the subaltern as the autonomous domain of the people that neither originated in elite nationalist politics nor depended on it: Far from being destroyed or rendered virtually ineffective, as was elite politics of the traditional type by the intrusion of colonialism, it [politics of the subaltern classes] continued to operate vigorously in spite of the latter, adjusting itself to the conditions prevailing under the Raj and in many respects developing entirely new strains in both form and content. As modern as indigenous elite politics, it was distinguished by its relatively greater depth in time as well as in structure. (“On Some Aspects of the Historiography of Colonial India” 4) Guha also identifies several salient features of the ideology operative in the subaltern domain of politics that are derived from his central theoretical concern with subordination; the new historiography he proposes is designed to recuperate this subaltern domain of politics, a subaltern consciousness so to speak that remains vitally important for South Asian history and society and yet receives little attention in available historiographies. The result of the new historiography is to take stock of the historic failure of the nation to develop this subaltern domain to achieve national liberation; Guha’s description here is strikingly similar to Gramsci’s account of the failure of the Italian nation-state: It is the study of this historic failure of the nation to come to its own, a failure due to the inadequacy of the bourgeoisie as well as of the working class to lead it into a decisive victory over colonialism and a bourgeois-democratic revolution of either the classic nineteenth-century type under the hegemony of the bourgeoisie or a more modern type under the hegemony of workers and peasants, that is, a ‘new democracy’—it is the study of this failure which constitutes the central problematic of the historiography

Introduction

11

of colonial India. (“On Some Aspects of the Historiography of Colonial India” 7; emphasis original) The early volumes of Subaltern Studies broadly followed this structure and remained engaged in reevaluating the failure of the nation from a pure and positive description of the subaltern consciousness. Guha’s own work elaborated on the related themes and issues. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak mounted a critique of the project in two related arguments—the problematic nature of the subaltern consciousness in the project since what the collective is really interested in is a class consciousness but more like the poststructuralist concept of the “subject-effect”; and second, the problematic of representation as a strategic intervention in historiography that remains somewhat undertheorized in the early volumes (Spivak, “Subaltern Studies: Deconstructing Historiography”). Spivak also transformed subaltern historiography through two fundamental shifts in the project—fi rst, she introduced the idea of the singularity of the subaltern, that is to say, she shifted the emphasis from a largely class-oriented category to individual subjects who would be recognized as subaltern subjects. As Young remarks in his essay for this book, “In a sense, it was Spivak, not Gramsci, who invented ‘the subaltern’” (31). Her second intervention was in the form of gendered subalternity that exposes not only the limits of subalternity itself but also allows one to engage with the fundamental question of representation in history. In her influential essay “Can the Subaltern Speak?” Spivak rearranged not only the Subaltern Studies project but also much of what is known now as postcolonial studies. As she commented recently her essay was inspired by Gramsci’s “Some Aspects of the Southern Question,” and that is partly why it argues the impossibility of liberation by class alone. Indeed she points out that the importance of Gramsci’s formulation of hegemony is precisely that it is a “condition into which the subaltern graduates as a result of a larger share of persuasion and, inevitably, some coercion from the organic intellectuals as well as the state” (“In Response: Looking Back Looking Forward” 232). The story of Bhubaneswari Bhaduri in her essay testifies to such concerns—her suicide alerts one to the ethical limits of the radical politics of subalternity. Such early engagements with Gramsci’s work were instrumental in giving postcolonial theory a radical edge. Plan of the Book The chapters in this book offer interdisciplinary and original readings of Gramsci that are not restricted to the early moments of postcolonial consolidation but extend to the global structures and cultures that we inhabit now. They concentrate on different geographical locations, and are informed by various disciplinary concerns, in order to think of Gramsci’s insights for the globalized postcolony. The book, likewise, is divided in three parts. The

12

Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya

fi rst part is designed to think through the intersection between Gramsci’s work and postcolonial studies. As Robert Young’s chapter shows, there is something innately postcolonial about Gramsci—be it his Sardinian origin, or his analysis of the Southern Question in Italy, or his engagement with contemporary imperial issues, Gramsci was always a trenchant critic of imperial occupation and exploitation. The connection between Gramsci’s work and postcolonial theory becomes much more compelling if one situates him in his immediate Italian context. This Italian context comes back in Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra’s essay, but they want interrogate the historical context after the Second World War that shaped Gramsci’s reception. It is not the familiar argument about the misrepresentation of Gramsci; rather Capuzzo and Mezzadra follow diverse historical leads to show the political stakes of reading Gramsci in the Italian context and to argue that Gramsci’s posthumous career in his own country has been as eventful as was his life under the fascist regime. The Italian context is also present in the two other chapters in this section, but here the connection between Gramsci and postcolonial politics is much more pronounced. Neelam Srivastava’s chapter discusses the connections between Gramsci’s concept of the “organic intellectual” and George Padmore’s and Frantz Fanon’s notion of the “colonized” or native intellectual to argue that while both distanced themselves from Communism for its failure to support black liberation movements, they remain in constant dialogue with Gramsci’s text. Through an examination of their reflections on Pan-Africanism, Srivastava argues that Gramsci, Fanon, and Padmore can be discussed together because of the centrality they assign to the connection between the intellectuals and the masses in the construction of a truly emancipatory movement for national liberation, which depends on the development of a strong national-popular culture. Baidik Bhattacharya’s chapter, the last one in this section, offers parallel readings of Gramsci and Edward Said to demonstrate a different genealogy of Said’s “secular criticism” in Gramsci’s “secular humanism.” The connection is important since it allows a non-national mode of critical thinking and even enables one to think of the globalized postcolony in different ways. The second section of the book extends Gramsci across geographical locations. Iain Chambers offers an innovative reading of Gramsci to think through the fraught question of postcolonial secularism and its polyvalent relationship with religious practices and institutions. The return of religion as both a critique of modernity and as a “pre-modern” phenomenon that modernity fails to deal with adequately has given rise to various debates in our contemporary time. Chambers argues that a critical rethinking of Gramsci can provide fresh insights in this ongoing discussion. Partha Chatterjee reviews current debates in India about land acquisition and the neo-liberal agenda of development, and suggests that Gramsci’s writing still provides important analytical insights in such debates. Chatterjee, one of the founding members of the Subaltern Studies Collectives, argues that the new trends

Introduction

13

in the development of postcolonial capitalism warrant new conceptual categories, which are fundamentally different from those employed to analyze earlier stages of capitalist development, and using some of Gramsci’s seminal concepts he offers a re-reading of the contemporary capitalist strategies. If Chatterjee’s attempt to evaluate Gramsci draws its empirical material from India, Pheng Cheah’s similar attempt concentrates on China. Cheah revisits Gramsci to think of contemporary Chinese fi lmmaker Jia Zhangke as an “organic intellectual” and through a nuanced reading of Jia’s fi lms, he interrogates the limits of Gramsci’s concept in a socialist context. The Chinese context is particularly important since it is often viewed as an alternative possibility to the neo-liberal and market-driven world order, and hence the plausibility or otherwise of an organic intellectual within the ambit of socialist structures holds tremendous potential for rethinking some of the key political concepts in our contemporary times. The next chapter in this section is by Rajeswari Sunder Rajan, who uses Gramsci’s writing on the leadership role of the intellectual in order to question the caste politics in contemporary India. She uses literary texts to argue that postcolonial narratives of social struggle are typically located in the space between subalternity and citizenship, and the role of the intellectual becomes important within this space. And it is within this context, and more specifically for her purpose, within the caste politics in India, that the Gramscian notion of the intellectual leading the society becomes problematic. Through close reading of texts she interrogates the postcolonial trajectory of a key concept in Gramsci’s thinking. In the fi nal chapter of this section Walter D. Mignolo takes us to the South American context, and offers a thoughtful parallel reading of Gramsci and the Peruvian intellectual-activist José Carlos Mariátegui. Through this reading Mignolo elaborates on Gramsci’s influence on radical thinkers in South America, and also redefi nes some of the key concepts of postcolonial studies. His intervention is a much-needed re-theorization of the field away from its familiar Anglophone context, and also a reminder that Gramsci’s writing had unexpected reception in unusual locations. The fi nal section of this book, an epilogue, is an interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. In this interview Spivak revisits her essay “Can the Subaltern Speak” and reflects on the trajectory of the subaltern in her intellectual career. Quite characteristically, she connects her interest in the work of Gramsci with larger histories of the postcolonial world, arguing how one can re-read Gramsci in politically enabling ways. This volume is not intended to be an exhaustive survey of all the themes that merit future research in relationship to Gramsci and the postcolonial. For example, studies of gender and of education in Gramsci are both fertile areas of future enquiry. However, we feel that the essays contained here offer the fi rst opportunity for a more sustained and in-depth conversation with Gramsci within the field of postcolonial studies.

14

Neelam Srivastava and Baidik Bhattacharya

Notes 1. Many thanks to Jim House, Eleanor Spaventa, and Rajeswari Sunder Rajan for their very helpful comments on earlier drafts of this introduction. 2. Recent work includes the 2011 special issue of Journal of Modern Italian Studies dedicated to Gramsci and the memory of John Cammett; Mark McNally and John Schwarzmantel’s Gramsci and Global Politics (2009); Joseph Francese’s Perspectives on Gramsci: Politics, Culture and Social Theory (2009); San Juan, “Antonio Gramsci’s Theory of the National-Popular and Socialist Revolution in the Philippines” (2009); Peter Thomas’s The Gramscian Moment: Philosophy, Hegemony and Marxism (2009). Within the enormous bibliography on Gramsci, it is also worth mentioning Jane Schneider’s Italy’s “Southern Question”: Orientalism in One Country (1998), for its relevance to the themes of our book. 3. Giuseppe Vacca, Paolo Capuzzo and Giancarlo Schirru explore the impact of Gramsci on cultural studies and on postcolonial studies in their book Studi gramsciani nel mondo: gli studi culturali (2008). See also Iain Chambers (ed.), Esercizi di potere. Gramsci, Said e il postcoloniale (2006). Among the critics who have examined the ways in which Gramsci writes on imperialism, see V.G. Kiernan, “Antonio Gramsci and the Other Continents,” in Imperialism and Its Contradictions (1995), and Frank Rosengarten, “The Contemporary Relevance of Gramsci’s Views on the ‘Southern Question’” (2009). 4. For an illuminating elaboration on Gramsci’s insights into Gandhian politics, see Partha Chatterjee, The Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse?, 50. 5. See John Davis, Gramsci and Italy’s Passive Revolution (1979). 6. English translations of Gramsci’s work have been used where possible. All other translations of Gramsci in the introduction are by Neelam Srivastava. 7. Historians such as Angelo Del Boca confi rm Gramsci’s view that for Italian political leaders, imperialism was much more a matter of prestige than of economic gain (Del Boca 2002). 8. See Romeo 1950 (cited in Riall 71); and John Davis, Gramsci and Italy’s Passive Revolution (1979).

Part I

Gramsci and Postcolonial Studies

1

Il Gramsci meridionale Robert J. C. Young

Lo stato italiano . . . è stato una dittatura feroce che ha messo a ferro e a fuoco l’Italia meridionale e le isole, crocifiggendo, squartando, fucilando, seppellendo vivi i contadini poveri che scrittori salariati tentarono di infamare col marchio di “briganti.”

The Italian state . . . was a cruel dictatorship that massacred and burned Southern Italy and the islands, crucifying, quartering, shooting and burying alive the poor peasants that mercenary writers tried to shame by branding them “bandits.” —Antonio Gramsci1

There has always been something postcolonial about Gramsci. In his lifetime, Gramsci had minimal effect on colonial struggle: his influence has been felt almost entirely in the postcolonial era. Even José Carlos Mariátegui, who left Turin in 1922 inspired by Gramsci, L’Ordine nuovo, and the Turin 1920 factory occupations, was technically a postcolonial activist-intellectual (Young, Postcolonialism: An Historical Introduction 197–99). When Gramsci was fi rst translated into English in 1957, the introductory blurb on the back cover described him as a Marxist philosopher “little known in the West,” as if he was an obscure East European communist or third-world revolutionary (Gramsci, The Modern Prince).2 Of course Gramsci was neither of those things. Yet in a sense, he did come from a “Third World” country. It is difficult now to imagine how poor rural Italy used to be, even as late as the 1960s, when Tuscan peasants still ploughed the soil with oxen, their bells jangling as they heaved and weaved in between the olive trees, when dusty villages in the South lay half-abandoned by their inhabitants who had left for the United States or Argentina in search of a better life than the grinding poverty of the Mezzogiorno. How much more so in 1891 when Gramsci was born, not into the milieu of the relatively prosperous Italian North, but in the South, in malaria-infested Sardinia, then a far cry from the summer playground culture of tourism and dissolute Berlusconi parties and even today still poor in the rural regions that lie away from the coast. Sardinia had been a former colony of a whole series of imperial dynasties—the Catalan kingdom of the Crown of Aragon, then Spain, then

18

Robert J. C. Young

Austria-Hungary under the Hapsburgs, before becoming the Kingdom of Sardinia in 1814, prior to spearheading Italian unification under Cavour. Sparsely populated, with three-quarters of a million inhabitants and a feudal infrastructure still partly intact, the five major dialects of the Sard language (a dialect of Catalan is also spoken in Alghero) were so diverse that a version of Italian was used as a lingua franca of communication. 3 Gramsci would always maintain an interest in minority languages as forms of popular culture, of subaltern knowledge and resistance.4 In Gramsci’s day Sardinia had the highest crime rate in Italy; the reputation of Sardinians was such that in 1855 the American consul at Genoa raised the question of “objectionable” emigrants from Sardinia coming to the United States in a letter to the New York Times. 5 Migration from Sardinia increased in the 1890s, with emigrants moving to the Italian mainland, the US, Argentina or, after 1912, to Tunisia. The situation of Italy in this period came closest to that of Ireland: between 1876 and 1970, an estimated 25 million Italians left Italy in search of work. The bulk of these came from the islands and the South (Favero and Tassello). Gramsci’s father worked as a registrar, or petty bourgeois official; in 1898, when Gramsci was seven, he was accused of embezzlement and jailed, with the result that the family was thrown into abject poverty. Gramsci, who had had to leave school, eventually won a scholarship to study in Turin on the Italian mainland in 1911. His background as an immigrant from an impoverished peripheral island with its own alien language would always mark his work with a perspective that made it in some sense at odds with the Marxism that had been developed on the European mainland by intellectuals who were often, like Marx or Lenin, countercultural bourgeoisie.6 It is for this reason therefore that in a certain sense Gramsci came from outside “the West.”7 A native of the islands, Gramsci was an intellectual from the peripheries, and in every sense “Southern.” He was a poor emigrant, an immigrant, and someone physically disabled by accidental circumstance. Although in his day, emigration was primarily a first-world issue (and immigration a problem for non-Western peoples), the questions of minority existence—“assimilation, emancipation, separatism, conversion, the language of state protection and minority rights, uprooting, exile, and homelessness” (Mufti, Enlightenment in the Colony 2–3)—are those of Gramsci himself. This was especially reinforced by his father’s immigrant status in Sardinia, and his origins in the Italian colony (or variously semicolony) of Albania,8 a link that helps to account for Gramsci’s evident interest in Albania and in Islam (between 40% and 70% of Albanians are Muslims).9 I In Orientalism, Edward W. Said remarks in a footnote that the (then current Gramsci 1971) English translation of Gramsci’s Prison Notebooks inexplicably leaves out the fi nal sentence in the fi rst note to the “Preliminary Points on the

Il Gramsci meridionale

19

Study of Philosophy and the History of Culture”: “Occorre fare inizialmente un tale inventario” (Gramsci, Quaderni 1376).10 The extraordinary inventory of the textual fabric of European hegemony that Said made in Orientalism was one product of Said’s reading of Gramsci, never before a reference in his books. What was remarkable though was not that he had been reading Gramsci, but that in a book concerned with the Orientalizing of the reality of the East, he had spotted what got left out of Gramsci too. The early English translations of Gramsci tended to Europeanize his work. The various selections leave the reader with little sense that Gramsci had any interest in the world outside Europe, a perspective that reflects and illustrates the Eurocentrism of European Marxism itself in the 1970s and 80s. Although not one of the major themes sketched out for the Notebooks, Gramsci’s internationalism is certainly apparent in the pre-prison writings and in the twenty-nine prison notebooks that he wrote from 1929 until his death in 1937. It is true that Gramsci makes no direct response to the major episodes in Italian colonialism before his incarceration, for example, the invasions of Libya in 1911, Albania in 1915, or Turkey from 1919 to 1923, though he did offer a revolutionary perspective on the future of the colonies in general (revolt and emancipation—“Alla guerra europea non potrà molto tardare la guerra delle colonie”) during the First World War (Gramsci, Cronache torinesi 255–58).11 Nevertheless, the non-Western world is visible, and evidently a point of interest. Gramsci’s publications in L’Ordine Nuovo, for example, written towards the end of the anti-imperial revolutionary ferment of 1914–1920, provide a typical Leninist perspective on the revolt of the colonial populations against their imperial-capitalist masters seen as a dialectic of oppressor and oppressed nations (Gramsci, L’Ordine Nuovo 68–70, 396; Gramsci, Selections from Political Writings, 1910–1920 155; Young, Postcolonialism 132).12 In “The Colonial Populations,” the widespread resistance that Gramsci describes as “the uprising of the Moslem world against the European states” (L’Ordine Nuovo 563; SPW 1: 303) is linked to the ongoing resistance of the Albanians to the Italian occupation of 1915: the article was published at the beginning of the Vlora War ( June–August 1920), at the end of which Italy withdrew and ceded sovereignty (though Albania would be reoccupied by Italy during the Second World War). Gramsci argues that there is a “hierarchy of exploitation”: capitalism exploits the European working class, while imperialism enforces a secondary level of exploitation of the colonial populations who provide the raw materials and foodstuffs for Europe. In this way the colonial populations become the foundation on which the whole edifice of capitalist exploitation is erected. These populations are required to donate the whole of their lives to the development of industrial civilization. For this they can expect no benefit in return; indeed they see their own countries systematically despoiled of their natural resources. (L’Ordine Nuovo 562; SPW 1: 302)

20

Robert J. C. Young

This chain of exploitation, it might be remarked, has not substantially changed in contemporary arrangements of capitalism. Gramsci’s argument here, which was made by Zinoviev and others in September of the same year in the First Congress of the Peoples of the East held at Baku (Riddell, To See the Dawn 77), is that far from being peripheral to revolutionary action, the overthrow of capitalism should logically begin in the colonies: “By freeing themselves of foreign capitalist exploitation, the colonial populations would deprive the European industrial bourgeoisies of raw materials and foodstuffs, and bring down the centres of civilization that have lasted from the fall of the Roman empire till today” (Gramsci, SPW 1: 303). This, however, was not an argument to which he would seriously return, even with respect to Italy’s own internal “colony”—the Mezzogiorno. Very shortly after Gramsci published his article on colonial populations, the Second Congress of the Third International would convene in Moscow in July 1920, the Italian delegation deeply divided in their different political ideologies (Riddell, Workers of the World 1: 34–35). At the Second Congress, Lenin’s “Theses on the National and Colonial Questions” would produce a different position on the colonies from that expressed in Gramsci’s article, advocating guarded alliance with bourgeois-progressive liberation movements, and affi rming the leading role of the party and European proletariat in organizing the peasantry in colonial countries in order jointly to overthrow capitalism and imperialism (Riddell, Workers of the World 1: 283–90). Notwithstanding Gramsci’s pamphlet advocating that the radical left should stay within the PSI that was circulated at the Second Congress and that won praise from Lenin, in January 1921 Gramsci allied with Amadeo Bordiga who led the split from the PSI to found the Communist Party of Italy (CPI), as it was originally called. Bordiga’s subsequent refusal of Lenin’s directive to form an alliance or common front with the PSI resulted in Gramsci himself being nominated as the Italian delegate to the Comintern from 1922 to 1924. This meant that Gramsci was in Moscow during the period of Mussolini’s March on Rome and the fascist accession to power, a development which increased the urgency with which, at the Fourth Congress, the need for a common front between communists and socialists was advocated. Bordiga’s continuing resistance to the Third International’s demand would eventually lead to the International nominating Gramsci as the new leader of the CPI. Living through the Russian Revolution, Gramsci in certain respects also can be seen as affi liated to the situation of anti-colonial revolutionaries of that time, in particular, in negotiating the relation of the PCI to the policies being developed for international revolution by the Comintern. As the Italian delegate to the Comintern, Gramsci was in a comparable position to a range of anti-colonial activists, and faced with similar choices—namely, trying to negotiate a position with regard to the Comintern, on the one hand, and with his own party, on the other. Unlike M. N. Roy, Gramsci had a fully constituted party back home to deal with, though in his case he disagreed

Il Gramsci meridionale

21

with the policies of the CPI leadership. After Bordiga’s arrest, the Comintern effectively took over the organization of the party and nominated Gramsci as its leader; Gramsci made strenuous efforts to persuade the PCI to come into line with the orders for fusion with the socialists made by the Comintern, as well as orientating the party more closely to general Comintern policy. Although in his earlier writing, Gramsci was prepared to bend orthodoxy in order to correlate with the specific local and national situation, as in his essay “The Revolution Against ‘Capital’” (Scritti politici 1: 130 –33; SPW 1: 34–37), after his return from Moscow he would follow the broad lines of Comintern orthodoxy, albeit later developed in an original way with respect to his writings on Italian history and culture. As one would expect from a member of the Comintern, serving on the Latin American Secretariat of the Comintern under Trotsky (a connection still visible in his interest in Latin America in the Prison Notebooks) Gramsci was seriously concerned with questions of imperialism and colonialism, a preoccupation that remains evident in the Prison Notebooks. We fi nd him analyzing Italian colonialism from the perspective of the former colony of Albania, and commenting on British and American imperialism, the history of Italian-English involvement in Ethiopia and Somalia, the Yemen, Egypt, China, India, Palestine etc. (Quaderni 76, 68–70, 175–79, 186–88, 218–19, 582–84, 620–21, 635). Many of these entries take the form of discussions of books or articles that Gramsci had been reading, rather than developing independent arguments in the mode, for example, of his “History of the Subaltern Classes: Methodological Criteria.” But like the form of the Notebooks themselves, they represent an important part of both his methodology and his intellectual ambitions. For the most striking thing about the Notebooks, when compared for example to other famous Notebook writers—such as Gide, Gauguin, Leonardo da Vinci, Rilke’s The Notebooks of Malte Laurids Brigge or Césaire’s Notebook of a Return to the Native Land—is their remorselessly detached, impersonal nature, their lack of self-doubt and self-reflection. The Notebooks were, of course, intended to provide the basis for disinterested, für ewig book projects. Nevertheless, they also deliberately take on in their own way the form of the notebook genre. Gramsci did not plan one book after the next, as he might have done if writing in the freedom of his own study, the normal form of book production. In certain respects, his ambitious plan for the notebooks was far more ill suited to the conditions of his incarceration. He began from the fi rst to plan sixteen or so interrelated topics (the one that he soon dropped was the only personal one, “Experiences of Prison Life”), reduced in 1931 to ten. In this way, the twenty-nine notebooks represented a deliberately fractured, multidisciplinary enterprise, moving at will from history to literature to folklore to Fordism—an early practical example of the broad perspective of what would become known as Cultural Studies. While Gramsci was researching and writing his vast array of topics, he was at the same time deliberately producing knowledge in a new way. The entries were

22

Robert J. C. Young

not merely a group of essays—they were constructed against each other, in what might be termed a rough cut fashion, with Gramsci’s headings which order the material by repeating certain phrases and categories nevertheless preserving and in certain respects augmenting the montage effect. The jumps and moves enabled a formal heterogeneity that would otherwise have been impossible with the result that, ever since their publication, scholars have been arguing over the ways that they have been edited and translated. At the same time, this has enabled Gramsci’s work to be used as a conceptual resource in a manner comparable to few other left intellectuals: while the drive was not to produce a totalizing theory, at the same time, the analysis reaches out to the historical and political formations of society at an extraordinary range of levels. Why did Gramsci begin his prison writing on so many multiple fronts, rather than simply think of writing one or more books in serial fashion, as is the norm for most writers? The notebooks were planned as a kind of total project, embodying Gramsci’s idea that, on the model of the French Revolution, the revolution should be the product not simply of a vanguardist party coup but of intellectual and cultural preparation: “[E]very revolution has been preceded by a long process of intense critical activity, of new cultural insight and the spread of ideas through groups of men initially resistant to them” (Pre-Prison Writings 10). In this “intense critical activity,” we can see here a link to his “postcolonial” profi le. Until the Russian Revolution, the nationalist unification of Italy was regarded in colonial countries as offering one of the few contemporary examples of a successful anti-colonial revolution. Mazzini figures prominently in the pantheon of anti-colonial activists; on the model of Mazzini’s Young Italy, we fi nd Young Sardinia (discussed in Gramsci’s “The Southern Question”), Young India, Young Ireland and many other comparable organizations. The Italian nationalists were indeed engaging against empire—the AustroHungarian run by the Hapsburgs, together with the various kingdoms and Papal States, which made up the rest of the Italian peninsula—and for this reason Mazzini’s nationalism continued to be a major inspiration for anticolonial struggle. From this perspective, Gramsci was, in a technical sense, a postcolonial political activist and intellectual. His experience of living in a fragile democracy that was quickly turned into a right-wing dictatorship in which leftist intellectuals and politicians were jailed for sedition closely resembles in many ways the all too common postcolonial situation of many former colonies. It was common for anti-colonial intellectuals to combine practical political work with more reflective writing composed or developed in jail, and so too Gramsci’s active political involvement, organizing and developing practical strategies, strategic tactics, was combined with reflective critical cultural analysis in the Prison Notebooks. By investigating historical formations in the past, Gramsci builds on the possibilities of how to develop counter-hegemonic strategies that will provide the basis for an

Il Gramsci meridionale

23

alternative subaltern state. But what profound question was the untotalized project of the Prison Notebooks supposed to answer? II Gramsci’s interest in colonialism was derived directly from his early life in Sardinia, from his personal experience of the Italian dialectic of colonization and emigration, but was mediated intellectually by his membership of the Comintern and the PCI. His major discussion of these questions from an Italian perspective comes in his 1926 essay “Alcuni temi sulla questione meridionale,” “Some Aspects of the Southern Question” (in Lo Stato operaio 9–26). Among postcolonial critics, Gramsci is sometimes praised for raising the issue of the Southern Question, as if his choosing to consider North– South relations represented an original intervention and an advanced, preemptively postcolonial understanding for someone on the left in his period. Certainly it looks unusual within the general paradigm of European Marxism, but far less so for any Italian Marxist when one considers the role of the Southern Question in the history of Italian politics. The “questione meridionale” was a perennial question after unification, and one broached by a wide variety of thinkers from left and right—such as Eugenio Aziomonti, Guido Dorso, Giustino Fortunato, Arturo Labriola, Enrico Leone, Ernest Cesare Longobardi, Sidney Sonnino, Leopoldo Franchetti, Francesco Saverio Nitti, Gaetano Salvemini as well as Gramsci himself.13 Coming from Sardinia, in the Italian “South,” Gramsci had in a sense been writing about the Southern Question all his life —indeed the hardships and injustices produced by the Southern question were what had directly precipitated him into politics in the fi rst place. Symptomatically it was the Southern Question that remained an open question at the moment of Gramsci’s arrest. The inadvertently fragmented sentence highlighted by Edward Said mimics a more famous and striking fragment in Gramsci’s writings—the last sentence of the unfi nished manuscript left behind on his arrest: This [work] is gigantic and difficult, but precisely worthy of every sacrifice . . . on the part of those intellectuals (and there are many of them, more than is believed) from North and South—who have understood that only two social forces are essentially national and bearers of the future: the proletariat and the peasants. (Scritti politici 3: 265; SPW 1: 462) The three coordinates of this sentence—the intellectuals of the North and South, the proletariat and the peasants, whose union forms the difficult and gigantic political work that Gramsci envisages as the future of the Italian nation—form the very center of the political nexus around which Gramsci’s work revolved. It was not by chance that he had been writing on the

24

Robert J. C. Young

Southern Question when he was arrested at his home on the Via G. Battista Morgagni in Rome on November 8, 1926. The essay, as Giuseppe Fiore observes, “marks a transition from the journalism of [Gramsci’s] early years of political struggle to the more meditative style of the prison writings” (Fiore 208). According to the editorial note when the essay was fi rst published in 1930, the essay was being written for a new party journal for a series in which current key ideological and political issues would be broached (Gramsci, “Alcuni temi sulla questione meridionale” 9). The reason for that new tone of reflection in the deteriorating political situation of the autumn of 1926 is clear: as Mariátegui had pointed out the year before, in some respects, it was the Italian Socialist and Communist parties’ failure to provide an adequate formulation of how to solve the problem of the Southern Question that enabled the political developments of the ascent of fascism, the very process that would result in Gramsci’s arrest. The gigantic and difficult task of the Prison Notebooks was essentially designed to solve the problem with which Gramsci was preoccupied in “The Southern Question”: how to produce a new form of cultural hegemony that would bring together the workers of the North with the peasants of the South in a socialist political formation. The Southern Question, and the uneven development of the Italian economy, had been at the center of Italian politics since reunification in 1861, and a central preoccupation for all Italian politicians, including the socialists and revolutionary syndicalists, some of whom went on to support the fascist party after 1919. As early as 1902 Arturo Labriola had created a splinter group within the Italian Socialist Party (PSI), to be known as the revolutionary syndicalists, challenging the PSI on the grounds that fi rst, socialist revolution could only come through the organization of the working class into syndicates that could take over the process of production, and second that the socialists had focused exclusively on, and drew their support from, the industrial proletariat of the North at the expense of majority of the population, particularly the Southern peasantry who were being forced by economic deprivation, as Gramsci put it, “to emigrate in order to survive” (SPW 1: 57). The revolutionary syndicalists, who fi nally split with the reformist and parliamentary PSI in 1907, drew support from Southern intellectuals based in Naples, particularly Enrico Leone and Ernest Cesare Longobardi. The importance of including the peasantry meant that Labriola and Leone began to revise Marx for the fi rst time on what would now be called a third-world basis—anticipating Mao’s relocation of the revolutionary subject to the peasantry—although in their case, what they sought was rather the synthesis of the Northern industrial proletariat with the Southern peasantry—exactly what Gramsci was still trying to do in 1926. Syndicalist organization of strikes in Italy achieved some success, but they were trumped in political terms by the creation of Enrico Corradini’s nationalist party, the Associazione Nazionale Italiana (ANI) in 1910 which advocated war as the solution to the alleged sickness of an Italy saddled with the system of

Il Gramsci meridionale

25

liberal parliamentary democracy (the left and right alike in Italy, including Gramsci’s later formed CPI, shared this aversion to “bourgeois” democracy). The nationalists focused their attention on the land closest to Italy across the Mediterranean that was part of the Ottoman Empire. The expansion of Italy into a colony further south would, Corradini argued, at once reinvigorate the nation through war, and solve the problem of peasant poverty by giving them new lands to which to migrate: as Gramsci described it in terms which bring out the discursive complexity of the era, “the Libyan war appeared to a whole layer of intellectuals as the beginning of the ‘great proletariat’s’ offensive against the capitalist and plutocratic world” (Scritti politici 3: 253; SPW 2: 450). In the Prison Notebooks Gramsci offered what was in effect a critique of the nationalist rationale of the Libyan and later colonial wars to facilitate emigration. He argued that there was no necessary link between a colony and emigrants from the associated metropole. With respect to colonization the economic factor was always primary: it was not the export of people that produced colonies, it was the export of capital (Gramsci, Quaderni 986; Gramsci, Prison Notebooks 3: 279; Liguori and Voza 145). Certainly the fascist Italian government invested a large amount of capital in Libya, but this was largely in support of its role as a settler colony. Over the period 1912 to 1943 about 100,000 Italians emigrated to Libya, which by 1939 was officially designated as simply a part of Italy, its “fourth shore” (Quarta Sponda). Today, of course, the flow has been reversed, but the boastful claims that Libya was part of “Greater Italy” have been long forgotten in Italy, even if in certain respects they still remain part of the Libyan imaginary. The syndicalists, strongly influenced by the antimilitarism of Georges Sorel, for the most part supported the general resistance on the left to the Libyan war which began in 1911, and in the course of which Italy appropriated three North African provinces from the Ottoman Empire. The most vociferous of these was a socialist leader who rose to prominence on account of his vociferous opposition to colonial warfare: Benito Mussolini. The Libyan war, though popular in the South, did not transform Italy as a nation: it was the Great War which Italy joined in 1915 on the Allied side, in the face of sustained opposition from socialists and communists, that succeeded in transforming the Italian political climate so as to produce a political and ideological coalition of “national socialism” between the nationalists, who were advocating a “proletarian nationalism,” and some of the revolutionary syndicalists, led by Mussolini (Sternhell). In 1915 Mussolini had abandoned his earlier position and began to advocate Italian participation in the war (as a result of which he was fi rst, expelled from the Italian Socialist party, and second, generously funded by the British MI5 [Kington]); by 1919 he had founded the Italian fascist party, the Fasci di Combattimento. In the postwar environment, the fusion of nationalism and syndicalism in fascism offered a rival, and politically much more successful, response to the increasingly chaotic political situation in Italy that began with the Biennio Rosso years of

26

Robert J. C. Young

1919–1920. For fascism succeeded in appearing to be at once elitist and popular, pro-capitalism and pro-workers and peasantry, modern and traditional, totalitarian and anti-collectivist (Roberts). By 1926, with Mussolini effectively dictator, and initiating agricultural reforms, new model agricultural communities in Sardinia and Sicily, and other measures such as government subsidies designed to increase agricultural production and improve the lot of the peasantry, Gramsci’s political and intellectual problem was fi rst that attempted solutions to the problems of the economic and political disparities between North and South had been a central focus in Italian politics for decades—his own analysis begins in 1894—and second that solutions offered by nationalists, and former socialist syndicalists who had become national socialists, had been politically successful in so far as they were now in power. Gramsci’s analysis of the Southern Question is somewhat skewed by his discussion of Syndicalism and his claim that it was supported by the Southern peasantry. Gramsci tends to conflate all syndicalists from different generations, often of very different tendencies, together, a habit facilitated by the fact that in Italian sindacato and its derivatives can be used “for both trade union, trade unionism and trade unionist and syndicalism and syndicalist” (Gramsci, Pre-Prison Writings xl). He claims that the revolutionary Syndicalist leaders were all drawn from the South: Syndicalism was born: the instinctive, elemental, primitive but healthy expression of working-class reaction against the bloc with the bourgeoisie and in favour of a bloc with the peasants, and first and foremost with the Southern peasants. Precisely that. Indeed, in a certain sense, syndicalism is a weak attempt on the part of the Southern peasants, represented by their most advanced intellectuals, to lead the proletariat. (Scritti politici 3: 253; SPW 2: 450) This is true for some (the Leone and Longobardi circle in Naples), but it does not take into account the role of the anarcho-syndicalism of the Unione Sindacale Italiana (USI), which in many ways was to the left of the PCI (Levy, Gramsci and the Anarchists). Gramsci describes the “essential ideology” of syndicalism as a “new liberalism,” but syndicalism was really too diverse to have an essential ideology. In fact the USI itself did not consider that the peasantry of the South constituted its support base, and Gramsci was mistaken in supposing that this was the case (Roberts 53–54). Carl Levy observes, It is misleading for Gramsci to reduce syndicalist intellectuals to mere spokespersons for the interests of southern peasants. Indeed southern syndicalist intellectuals of the ‘fi rst generation’ uncritically embraced the modernity of the industrial north and their fi rst base was Milan. For

Il Gramsci meridionale

27

them the salvation of Italy lay in the modernization process pioneered in the North. (Levy, “Currents of Italian Syndicalism Before 1926” 228) This position is in many respects similar to Gramsci’s own. There is not space here to go into a detailed discussion of the complex question of Gramsci’s views on the USI and Italian syndicalism. For our purposes, the important issues are in the fi rst place the questions that arose from the fact that Gramsci considered the North–South relation to be a colonial one (though he was by no means the fi rst to suggest that it constituted a form of internal colonialism),14 and second, the extent to which this can be considered productive from a postcolonial perspective. III The Southern Question is at once anti-colonial and colonial—about the colonial submission of the South to the North, and associated emigration from the peripheral parts of the metropole to another colony. The irony with respect to Gramsci’s observation that the relation between the “nordici” and the “sudici” was essentially a colonial relation was that this was a perverse state of affairs considering that the South had formerly been part of the independent Kingdom of the two Sicilies. Until unification and the industrialization of the North, the South was by far the richest of the Italian states. In the two Sicilies there was extensive resistance to unification, with revolts (beginning in the 1860s) and brigandage—brigantaggio postunitario—being heavily suppressed by the new Italian state and continuing up to the time of Mussolini. Many in the South certainly saw unification as a form of colonial occupation by the northern Piedmontese, that is, by the Kingdom of Sardinia (“Regno Sabaudo” or “Regno di Sardegna”). If the South was in a colonial relation to the North, then that North included the “Southern” island of Sardinia that was nominally its center. At this point, the degree to which Gramsci was not dealing with a simple colonial relation vis-à-vis the Italian North and South becomes clear: if the South had been an actual colony, the obvious solution would have been independent sovereignty, and an attempt to develop national and economic autonomy—freedom—from the exploiting power. This would be the case for the two Sicilies, which had formerly been a sovereign autonomous state. Unification having been driven by the Kingdom of Sardinia, which formed the basis for the subsequent Italian state, meant on the other hand that technically Sardinia was the colonial not the colonized power—it was in the name of the Kingdom of Sardinia that Garibaldi had led “the thousand” to conquer the Kingdom of the Two Sicilies in 1860. On the other hand, within the Kingdom of Sardinia it was also the case that since the incorporation of the Republic of Genova in 1814, and with the capital in Torino, Piedmont had become the centre of political and economic power, with the result that the island of Sardinia became increasingly peripheral, particularly after unification and the industrialization

28

Robert J. C. Young

of the North. At this point, a Sardinian nationalism developed seeking autonomy for the island—from the very united Italy that had originated in the Kingdom of Sardinia itself.15 For both Sardinia and the Mezzogiorno (formerly the Kingdom of Two Sicilies), therefore, this new “colonial” relation with the North was the result of the complex processes of Italian unification. Paradoxically “colonial” oppression was instituted not by colonialism but by the creation of the independent Italian state. Although early in his life, Gramsci had in fact supported the nationalist movement in Sardinia, he rejects this explicitly in “The Southern Question” on the grounds that it would perpetuate the current structure of ruling-class exploitation. The only alternative solution therefore was not autonomy but more integration with the North. On this, at least, all Italian political parties, whether of the Left or the Right, were agreed. The claimed “solutions” to the Southern Question that had already been instituted—the invasion of Libya and its creation as a settler colony, the development of nationalist war—were both, as Gramsci points out in his essay, supported by some intellectuals and even the peasantry of the South. His work, therefore, was to develop an alternative socialist model in which the Southerners could be led by the more politically progressive communist intellectuals and proletariat of the North. The struggle was to produce a strategy that would produce a counter-hegemony to that which had already been established by Mussolini. The formation of that programme was essentially the task Gramsci undertook in the huge—“gigantic and difficult”— project of The Prison Notebooks. As we have seen, Gramsci’s own position on the Southern Question had changed and developed over the years. By the time of his 1916 essay, “Il Mezzogiorno e la guerra” (in Cronache torinesi 228–31) Sardinian nationalism had been rejected in favor of the abolition of unfair trade tariffs (a widely favored solution to the colonial market arrangements then in place), and a general socialist transformation of Italian society as a whole. By 1920, in L’Ordine Nuovo, Gramsci had developed the basis for his mature position that would be nuanced, but not radically transformed in the 1926 essay: The Northern bourgeoisie has subjugated the South of Italy and the Islands, and reduced them to exploitable colonies; by emancipating itself from capitalist slavery, the Northern proletariat will emancipate the Southern peasant masses enslaved to the banks and the parasitic industry of the North. The economic and political regeneration of the peasants should not be sought in the division of uncultivated or poorly cultivated lands, but in the solidarity of the industrial proletariat. That in turn needs the solidarity of the peasantry. (L’Ordine Nuovo 377; SPW 1: 148) While in 1920 Gramsci still considered the proletariat the only political power which could oppose the bourgeois state (L’Ordine Nuovo 473), here the major question of how to effect a double solidarity, between proletariat and peasantry,

Il Gramsci meridionale

29

is already raised but characteristically left unanswered. In true internationalist spirit, Gramsci seeks an alliance between the working class of the North and the peasantry of the South, with the former the vanguard of the latter, a position essentially compatible with the Comintern’s policy to be developed for the colonies—while the Comintern supported their liberation, they were always to be led by the working class of the North. The strategic difference from the colonial scenario was that, since they all lived in the same country, the value of the peasantry as pre-revolutionary agents lay in their sheer weight of numbers which made it conceivable that they would be able to destroy the military might of the bourgeois state and so facilitate the revolution of the workers in the city (L’Ordine Nuovo 474; SPW 1: 180). In the situation of 1926, Gramsci’s strategy was to re-imagine the possibility of a productive solidarity, intellectual and material, between proletariat and peasant, and to envisage a change in the intellectual leadership of the South from conservative Southern to revolutionary Northern intellectuals. In the “Southern Question” essay, so far as it goes, Gramsci’s position, whereby the leadership would be delivered by a Northern working class via the mediation of the intellectuals was, however, in its way somewhat colonial, since the peasantry is ostensibly offered little agency or activity beyond political re-education that would help them to abandon their folkloric beliefs—senso comune—for a properly scientific outlook— senso buono. It is in this context that the development of the idea in the Prison Notebooks of resistant “subaltern classes” beyond the narrow definition of the (Northern) proletariat and the apathetic lawlessness of Southern sovversivismo (Levy, “‘Sovversivismo’”)—marks a major move in Gramsci’s thinking. Much broader than the peasantry, the idea of subaltern or subversive groups allows Gramsci the possibility of thinking through how the necessary North–South alliance could be formed beyond the narrow concept of a leadership of the latter by the former. Having established the solidarity of different subaltern groups, Gramsci’s increasing emphasis on the role of the intellectual was the result of an increasing conviction that the radical hegemonic alliance of North and South could only be produced through the mediation of “organic” intellectuals. Gramsci speaks of solidarity, not of unity or homogeneity. He never sought to resolve the differences between North and South other than the economic ones. His emphasis on the importance of the continuing regional fragmentation of Italy can be compared to the situation of many postcolonial nations. For what was widely regarded as the central political problem for Italy was that it had unified as a state, but remained disparate as a nation and as a people, full of cultural and economic imbalances. As a communist, Gramsci does not follow the nationalist idea of arguing for cultural or linguistic homogenization, but rather sees the economic disparity as the key and that imbalance as a threat to the cultural autonomy of different regions whose differences, beginning with his interest in Sard dialectics, he continues to support (Ives). There is no mention of subalternity in Gramsci’s “Southern Question” essay, only of different social strata. The concept of subalternity was

30

Robert J. C. Young

invented in the Prison Notebooks as a way of describing the operation of different social strata or groups that had historically produced hegemonic political formations (Gramsci continues to refer to the proletariat [“classe operaia”]). Aside from Notebook 25, “Ai margini della storia (Storia dei gruppi sociali subalterni)” (Quaderni 2279–94), there are only eight other references to subaltern classes in the Prison Notebooks (Quaderni 328–32, 897, 1320, 1349, 1387–88, 1607, 1663–64, 1696).16 In Notebook 25, Gramsci uses the term to describe the lower classes in pre-capitalist societies, and all classes that struggle against the state, including even the bourgeoisie; elsewhere, at one point, “subaltern classes” includes all lower classes including the working class as well as the “most marginal and peripheral elements,” groups who have not yet come to class consciousness (Quaderni 328–32; Prison Notebooks 2: 48–52); once Gramsci uses the term as a description of the “humble” struggling against the “powerful” (Quaderni 897; Prison Notebooks 3: 197); at one point in general terms of dominant versus subaltern classes (Quaderni 1320); once to describe the popular masses in general (1664); and once as a description of those classes “who have no history” (1696). In a significant difference from the later Subaltern Studies historians, Gramsci never uses the term in direct connection to, or as a specific description of, the peasantry, who are always characterized simply as “contadini.” Of course the peasantry would form part of the account of the humble classes, but they are not foregrounded in any way in that account, even if they are privileged in Gramsci’s own analysis of the contemporary political situation of Italy still caught up in the imbalances of the Southern Question. Gramsci’s idea of an alliance of the intellectuals and the peasantry, led by the dirigente working class, brings home just how far the later Subaltern Studies historians shifted Gramsci’s formulations. Whereas Gramsci sought to bring the proletariat together with the peasantry to educate the peasantry out of the dominant ideology of nationalist narratives, Subaltern Studies was written not only against dominant nationalist accounts but also Marxist narratives of the role of the proletariat in Indian history. With their Maoist/Naxalite genealogy, the Subaltern Studies historians sought to establish not unity with the working class but a relative autonomy for the peasantry—an autonomy that Gramsci by contrast never allows the subaltern classes (Quaderni 2286). For Gramsci’s project was in a sense the very opposite of that of the Subaltern Studies historians—his aim, made very clear in “The Southern Question,” was precisely to bring the peasantry together with the proletariat into a mutual coalition for a Marxist historical narrative that would effect social and political transformation in the future, rather than to celebrate their independent political spontaneity or singular forms of resistance. Gramsci’s larger political aim mapped out in “The Southern Question” forms the testimony of a man who envisaged the intellectuals, proletariat and peasantry working together to bring

Il Gramsci meridionale

31

about a fundamental political emancipation for the country as a whole. There is something very “Southern” about that too. Coda: Spivak and “the Subaltern” We might also note here a further significant postcolonial transformation. In her well-known critique of the Subaltern Studies methodology (Spivak, “Subaltern Studies: Deconstructing Historiography”), Gayatri C. Spivak not only deconstructs the Subaltern Studies pursuit of a collective peasant class consciousness, but at the same time shifts Gramsci himself still further than the Subaltern Studies group had already done. In a sense, it was Spivak, not Gramsci, who invented “the subaltern.” The subaltern appears only once as a singular figure (“il subalterno”) in the Prison Notebooks, where the term describes someone who in historical terms was once an object but has become a historical subject, a protagonist (Quaderni 1388).17 As an in many ways fairly orthodox Marxist trained by the Comintern, Gramsci refers otherwise to “classi subalterne” or “gruppi sociali subalterni,” subaltern classes and subaltern social groups. In Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency, Ranajit Guha does use the term subaltern in the singular a couple of times when he discusses ideas that apply to the peasant generically, but as Spivak points out, the drive is not to retrieve individual consciousness but that of the class, the peasantry as such. Spivak’s innovative move that created the singular figure of the subaltern as an individual consciousness as well as being part of a group, was allied to her other critique of the Subaltern Studies collective, namely, the absence of consideration of “the figure of woman” or “the subaltern as sexed-subject” (Spivak, ”Subaltern Studies” 365, 357). While in Marxism, it remains mandatory to analyze the class rather than the individual, Spivak’s whole intervention with respect to feminism was that, when put in an international frame, there is no such thing as women’s or woman’s consciousness in general on the model of class consciousness; women are politically heterogeneous and hierarchized across class, race, ethnic lines. Gramsci does in fact consider explicitly whether women constitute a subaltern class, but though he acknowledges the similarity, he concludes that “‘masculinity’ can be compared to class domination only in a certain sense; it therefore has greater importance for the history of customs than for political and social history” (Quaderni 302, 2286; Prison Notebooks 2: 24). By contrast, in “Can the Subaltern Speak?” (1985), Spivak defi nitively introduces the singular figure of the subaltern woman. While the discussion of sati is always generic, nevertheless the very theatre of immolation means that the focus will always remain on the consciousness of the individual woman—we cannot expect to fi nd a generic class consciousness among satis here. Yet Spivak’s point is that in terms of her being impossibly placed between nationalist and liberal colonial discourses, here it is the singular “figure of woman” who disappears. The incarnation of the subaltern as a woman who individually

32

Robert J. C. Young

makes a choice—a choice of course enforced by her being a woman as such—is then defi nitively engendered with the concluding story of the suicide of Bhuvaneswari Bhaduri. With the haunting narration of Bhuvaneswari’s death, the subaltern—the “historically muted subject of the non-elite (‘subaltern’) woman in the imperialist theater”—was produced for the fi rst time as an historical agent (Spivak, “Can the Subaltern Speak?” 120). At this point it becomes clear that Spivak’s account in fact in a certain sense remains close to the spirit of Gramsci’s single use of the term “subaltern” in the singular— someone who in historical terms was once an object but has become a historical subject, a protagonist—even if this singular figure has now begun to eclipse the idea of the subaltern as a class. Since Spivak’s intervention, the subaltern has been transformed into a new and powerful paradigm for our class-wary times, showing how subaltern singularity can enact a disjunctive politics of belonging through its acts of insubordination and insurrection. This contemporary emphasis on the subaltern has nevertheless come a long way from Gramsci himself, who remains fi rmly anchored to the political possibilities offered by the construction of hegemony through the articulation of the subaltern classes. Notes 1. Gramsci, L’Ordine Nuovo 422, my translation. Citations to Gramsci’s works are fi rst to the Italian edition, followed by the English translation, where available. 2. Gramsci’s The Modern Prince (1957) was the fi rst book by Gramsci to be published in English. The fi rst translation into English was the single essay, “Benedetto Croce and His Concept of Liberty. Notes on Croce’s History of Europe (Storia d’Europa) taken from Prison Letters,” Science & Society 10.3 (1946), 283–92. 3. The Sardinian language was only officially recognized in 1999. 4. On Gramsci and the Sardinian language(s), see Ives 2004. 5. http://query.nytimes.com/mem/archive-free/pdf?res=F70B16FF3B59157493CB A9178DD85F418584F9 [accessed March 23, 2011] 6. In his class background, and in his interests in the role of dialects and minor languages in his own region, Gramsci had more in common with Joseph Stalin, both of them marked by small physical stature and disabilities. 7. At the same time, it is clear that his knowledge of the world outside Europe is sometimes limited. For example, he criticizes Aldous Huxley’s critique of British educational policy in India where Huxley suggests that it was a mistake to put all the effort into education addressed to Brahmin and Chattrya castes rather than primary school teachers. Gramsci responds by saying that this intellectual elite needed to be trained fi rst precisely so that primary schools could be developed with suitable teachers. This would work as an idea for Italy, but Gramsci evidently has little sense that few Brahmins would consider becoming primary school teachers in India, especially public schools that would be populated by the lower castes (Gramsci, Quaderni 709). 8. Gramsci, Lettere dal carcere 506. 9. E.g., Gramsci Scritti politici 3, 261; SPW 2: 458. On Islam, see Gramsci, Quaderni 246–48, 621–23.

Il Gramsci meridionale

33

10. Said, Orientalism 25, 329–30. Said does not point out that the sentence, however, was already present in the fi rst 1957 US translation of Gramsci, The Modern Prince 59. 11. Translation, “The European war must soon be followed by the war of the colonies.” 12. The two volumes of Gramsci’s Selections from Political Writings will hereafter be referred to as SPW 1 and SPW 2. 13. This is not the place for a full discussion of the history of the Southern question in Italy. For an extensive selection of writings on the topic, see Villari. 14. Compare, for example, Antonio de Viti de Marco, La questione meridionale (1903) in Villari 343–53. 15. The current independence party in Sardinia is the Indipendèntzia Repùbrica de Sardigna (IRS). 16. This count does not allow for sections repeated across different notebooks. 17. Gramsci also uses the term in the singular in a somewhat problematic way in a letter to his wife Julia ( Julca) written 8 August 1933, where he worries about their son reading Uncle Tom’s Cabin without someone situating for him the book’s religiosity and emotions in their historical context. He does not consider Julia as the person who is able to do this, remarking that: “In general, however, it seems to me that you put yourself (and not only in this connection) in the position of the subaltern rather than that of the leader [nella posizione del subalterno e non del dirigente], that is, of one who is not in a position of historically criticizing ideologies by dominating them, explaining and justifying them as a historical necessity of the past, but of one who, brought into contact with a specific world of emotions, feels attracted or repulsed by it, remaining always within the sphere of emotion and immediate passion” (translation modified; Letters, ed. Rosengarten, vol. 2, 318). Although there is no intrinsic reference to gender in this remark, the inference remains that as a woman she remains in the passive subaltern realm of being dominated by emotion and passion rather than operating as an agent or intellectual who can explain the ideological function of such emotions in art. Gramsci himself, it is implied, has by contrast made the transition from a subaltern dominated by the passions to the position of a leading critical intellectual.

2

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra

The “Italian reading of Gramsci” this chapter seeks to provincialize is deeply rooted in the political and intellectual history of the country after the Second World War. The reading of Gramsci was never a neutral scholarly exercise in Italy. His thought was always part of the stakes in the elaboration and discussion of the peculiar politics of the Communist Party. Gramsci was “appropriated” by the Party (particularly by its leadership gathered around its secretary Palmiro Togliatti) soon after the end of the war, and his reading (as well as the editorial work around his unpublished works) became a cornerstone in the building of an “imagined continuity” of the history and politics of the party since its foundation in 1921. For long time, dealing with Gramsci meant dealing with this political stake in Italy. And it should not be surprising that in the early 1960s, while Gramsci began to “travel” and to nurture creative and heterodox intellectual and political projects in different parts of the world, the break with Communist orthodoxy in Italy often expressed itself in the form of a break with Gramsci. Mario Tronti was actually referring to this point when he wrote in 1959 that the author of the Prison Notebooks had to be considered a “typically Italian thinker”;1 he was also setting the agenda for the years to come. This chapter aims at reconstructing (and deconstructing) the history of the “Italian reading of Gramsci” since the end of the Second World War (first section). The second section discusses the ways in which one of the most significant Marxist heresies in Italy, “workerism,” dealt with this Gramsci reading tradition. The third section examines the ways in which, with the political defeat of the Italian Communist Party at the end of the 1970s and then its dissolution in 1991, Gramsci “came back home” and a new season of Gramsci studies in Italy began. The discovery of the world relevance of his thought and the very relation of Gramsci to the Italian context began to be investigated in new ways. The fourth and last section discusses some of the issues at stake in recent developments of Italian Gramsci studies and outlines a research agenda for the near future. In the Shadow of Togliatti In March 1944, after eighteen years in exile, Togliatti came back to Italy and gave a boost to a new course in the history of the Italian Communist

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

35

Party (PCI), the so-called svolta di Salerno, “the turning point of Salerno.” The new strategy gave priority to the anti-fascist battle rather than to the proletarian revolution and delayed the solution of the institutional settlement of Italy, which meant the acceptance of the monarchy, at least temporarily. Moreover, Togliatti introduced two major novelties in the long term strategy of the Communist Party: he abandoned the Leninist model of a revolutionary cadre party for a modern mass party (the so-called partito nuovo, “new party”); the communists accepted the constitutional ground of democratic pluralism and parliamentary democracy, actively participating in drafting and approving the new constitution which came into force in 1948. This was a significant change compared to the cultural and political roots of communism in the 1920s, a change that reflected the political experience of Togliatti in the 1930s and 1940s. Togliatti’s conception of the “new party,” gained through his experiences in the popular fronts in the Spanish Civil War and through the analysis of fascism as a modern political mass phenomenon, 2 also responded to the need to fi nd an area of autonomy from the Soviet policy, despite a clear commitment to the Eastern bloc in terms of major international choices. The emphasis on the national character of the Party (which changed its name from PCd’I, Partito Comunista d’Italia, “Communist Party of Italy,” to PCI, Partito Comunista Italiano, “Italian Communist Party”), and the “progressive democracy” as the pivot of the PCI strategy were far removed from the revolutionary internationalism of the early 1920s and paralleled the Stalinist doctrine of the national character of popular movements. These features constituted the peculiar history of Italian communism after the war. This new politics was accompanied by a vigorous cultural policy and by a historiography that relied on two defi ning elements: the history of the PCI was read, against any reasonable analysis, as a continuous development—without contradictions— since its founding in Livorno in 1921; the pillar that sustained this tradition was the figure of Antonio Gramsci. In the cultural policy promoted by Togliatti, Gramsci became the figure around which to build the history and tradition of the Italian Communist Party. This move proved to be particularly suitable in order to attract young antifascist intellectuals who had not yet joined the Communist Party. This operation—which did not hesitate to make use of omissions and outright falsification of Gramsci’s work— made Gramsci into a figure of the national culture that went beyond his militancy in the Party of which he had been leader and founder. The image of Gramsci in the works of Piero Gobetti and Guido Dorso, representatives of Italian radical-democratic liberalism, appreciated Gramsci despite different political affi liations, and even a famous sentence by Benedetto Croce, who wrote of Gramsci “as a man of thought he was one of ours,” helped to make of the work of Gramsci a national heritage and represented a crucial trait of union between national history and that of the Party (Croce 86). The fi rst Italian edition of Lettere dal carcere [Letters from Prison] published in 1947, 3 which won a prestigious literary prize, already shows all

36

Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra

the characteristics of the editorial policy through which the Communist Party made Gramsci’s work known in the following years. These letters highlighted the human side of Gramsci and they assumed a paradigmatic meaning of the violence suffered by all those who had the courage to vigorously oppose the Fascist regime. Thus, the most private and personal work of Gramsci was the fi rst to see the light after the war and become a monument to antifascism. These letters, which touched the whole country, were censored by the Party, for all references to the “heretics” of international communism in the 1920s, Bordiga, Trotsky, and even Rosa Luxemburg as well as the entire Left opposition within the PCd’I, were removed from them.4 In a book of 1951, coordinated by Togliatti, 5 which sketched a history of the Italian Communist Party on the thirtieth anniversary of its birth, all the “dissidents,” both Right and Left, who punctuated the history of the Communist Party of Italy were concealed, removed, or attacked with violence, so that an enduring standard of the history of the Party, centered on the figures of Gramsci and Togliatti, was established.6 In the work plan prepared by Togliatti, the manipulative and propagandistic intent was clear. Togliatti wrote, among other things, “Make sure, of course, not to present objectively the infamous doctrines of Bordiga.7 Do that in a critical and destructive way” (qtd. in Liguori 271). The fi rst publication of the Prison Notebooks, the thematic edition published between 1948 and 1951, falls within the framework described so far and its composition, which did not follow any philological criteria, responded to cultural policy pursued by the party.8 The identification of the Crocian tradition as the strong tradition of Italian intellectual history, 9 which the Communist Party had to undermine, promoted the reading of Gramsci’s work on specific aspects, such as the interpretation of national history and the literary and artistic Italian tradition. This reading of Gramsci became mainstream in the postwar decades. It paradoxically led to the acceptance of the battlefield chosen by the opponent, that is, by the intellectuals inspired by Croce. Thus, texts crucial for understanding Italian society, which in the 1950s and 1960s experienced tumultuous processes of urbanization and industrialization, remained at the edge of the Gramscian reception. The notebook “Americanism and Fordism,” for example, which contained some of the sharpest pages written in prison by Gramsci, received marginal attention until the 1970s.10 The thematic edition of the Notebooks was also intended to partially defuse the subversive potential of Gramscian thought in relation to the Soviet doctrine. Togliatti had immediately realized this question as he began to read the Notebooks, so much so that he wrote to Dimitrov in 1941: Gramsci’s notebooks, which I have studied almost entirely, contain materials that can be used only after careful preparation. Without this treatment the material cannot be used and even some parts, if they were used in their current form, may not be useful to the party. For this I think it

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

37

is necessary that this material remain in our fi les to be developed here. (qtd. in Vacca, “Togliatti” 144–45) The key elements of the partito nuovo of Togliatti, namely the acceptance of a pluralist democratic system and the mass party, can be hardly brought back to Gramsci’s thought or, at the very least, this requires a historicization of his work on those subjects which have undergone significant shifts in time. Gramsci had a Leninist view of the party and when he spoke of democracy he did not refer to parliamentary democracy. But this same relationship between Gramsci and Togliatti, presented as harmonious and inspired by a continuity of common purposes, actually knew moments of heavy contrast just in a fatal moment in the history of world communism. On October 14, 1926, Gramsci, on behalf of the Political Bureau of the Communist Party of Italy, intervened on the issue of the confl ict between Stalin and Bukharin, on the one hand, and the unified opposition of Trotsky, Zinoviev and Kamenev, on the other. Gramsci was on the side of the majority in the heart of the matter, however he expressed a clear criticism of the Stalinist method with a reminder of the need to maintain the party unity and enhance the legacy of Lenin, an issue he deemed critical for the advancement of the international communist movement: It seems to us that the violent passion of the Russian questions causes you to lose sight of the international aspects of the Russian questions themselves, causes you to forget that your duties as Russian militants can and must be fulfi lled only within the context of the interests of the international proletariat.11 (qtd. in Daniele 408) Togliatti was in Moscow and there he received the letter from Gramsci who asked him to forward it to the Bolshevik party. But Togliatti did not share the content of the letter; he personally spoke to some leaders of the Soviet Communist Party and of the Third International, and decided to hold the letter without making it public. He asked to review the whole matter at a meeting of the Central Committee of the Italian Communist Party, where Jules Humbert-Droz was sent as a delegate of the Third International. On October 18, Togliatti wrote to Gramsci informing him that he did not forward the letter because it was not appropriate in the phase of heavy confrontation within the Russian party and was not sufficiently clear in the approval of the line of the party majority (Stalin-Bukharin) and in the criticism toward the opposition. The answer of Gramsci, on October 26, was very hard. He wrote, among other things, “This mode of reasoning of yours has made a very distressing impression on me” (qtd. in Daniele 437).12 Gramsci complained of the superficiality of Togliatti’s analysis and considered the outcome of the confl ict within the Bolshevik Party crucial for the fate of international communism. He claimed that the unity of the communists was of vital importance and

38

Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra

criticized the attitude of the majority, which seemed to want to crush the opposition. However, following the failed murder attempt of Mussolini on October 31, fascist violence broke out, leading to several arrests and forcing many leaders to go underground. Gramsci failed to reach that party meeting in Valpolcevera (close to Genoa).13 There it was decided to accept Togliatti’s proposal to suspend the forwarding of Gramsci’s letter, with the only opposition coming from Vernagoni, who belonged to the left current of the party led by Bordiga. The evening of November 8, Gramsci was arrested. Gramsci and Togliatti would never meet again and their last direct correspondence is related to the clash of 1926. It is easy to understand that in order to build the legend of a Communist Party whose specificity rested on the solid intellectual and political association of Gramsci and Togliatti, the party leadership carefully refrained from publishing these letters until after the war. Thus, the last direct relationship between Gramsci and Togliatti was a tough battle on an issue of primary importance: the year after, with the expulsion of Trotsky and other opponents from the party, the historical importance of the confl ict in 1926 would become very clear. This clash between Gramsci and Togliatti has been written on extensively and has created some confusion. Some scholars see the episode as emblematic of the different characters and moral statures of Gramsci and Togliatti, the first sensitive to the unity of the movement and respectful of dissent, the second who cynically adapted to the new Stalinist course. This interpretation accords well with a hagiographic image of Gramsci built by the same Communist Party after the war through an instrumental use of witnesses who had known him in jail and who described him as a man of good character, well disposed toward “simple people,” and who never failed to have a good word for everybody.14 What we want to reiterate here, however, is the political substance of their disagreement. Togliatti was in Moscow and certainly had a clearer perception of the confl ict within the Bolshevik party. In short, he was aware that the clash had already concluded and had been won by the Stalinist majority so that the Italian party had no other option than to support—without any ifs, ands, or buts—the majority. Gramsci’s analysis, however, was more far-seeing because he understood that the laceration in the party was a consequence of bureaucratic and sectarian drifts that threatened the very credibility of international communism. From that confl ict followed the national-bureaucratic drift of the Bolshevik party, the rupture in international communism and the institutionalization of violence in the management of the party that escalated in the 1930s. Thus, in the crucial moment that required an evaluation of this historic turning point, the positions of Gramsci and Togliatti were radically opposed. This was the real ground of the confl ict, while the idea that Gramsci defended the opposition against Stalin is totally groundless. Gramsci shared the line of the majority; what separated him from Togliatti was the reading of the overall strategy of the international communist movement in the mid-1920s.

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

39

But all these fi les were revealed only between the 1960s and 1970s, so that the ideological construction of the continuous history of the party could establish itself in the postwar decades. Even the publication of Gramsci’s writings in L’ordine nuovo (Torino 1954), namely, the writings of Gramsci in the years of the councils movement in the “two red years,” the “Biennio Rosso” (1919–1920), did not open a critical debate on the reappraisal of his work. Only the young intellectuals of the journal, Ragionamenti,15 used Gramsci’s thoughts of 1919 and 1921 in order to criticize the pattern of the party promoted by Togliatti within a perspective of research on the institutions of workers’ power.16 In this perspective, the councils’ democracy was reappraised as a fundamental experience of management of the production process by the working class that would take it to direct the whole society, not through the instrument of the proletarian dictatorship, but by building its own hegemony. Togliatti himself was about to intervene in a speech in 1957, “Attualità del pensiero e dell’azione di Gramsci” [“The relevance of Gramsci’s thought and action today”]17 to prevent the recovery of Gramsci’s thought on worker councils casting a shadow on the clear continuity of the history of the Party. The events in Hungary in 1956 had shifted many intellectuals from the PCI to the PSI (Partito Socialista Italiano), the “Italian Socialist Party,” although they were positioned on the radical left within the party. The renovation of the political culture of the Italian Left was starting to rest on an original reinterpretation of Marx and on a fruitful confrontation with social sciences, particularly critical sociology that the PCI had openly opposed, preferring to concentrate on the cultural opposition to the liberal tradition of Benedetto Croce in terms that were completely outdated with respect to the recent transformations of Italian society. The interpretation suggested by Togliatti in 1957 was perhaps a little less schematic than the one advanced some years before, but he maintained the thesis of the continuity in the Party history, and saw in the failure of L’Ordine Nuovo the limits of a vanguard experience which did not have a political organization able to sustain it. The PCd’I founded in Livorno after the failure of L’Ordine Nuovo was an evolution of the council experience according to the Leninist doctrine. During the 1970s, the analysis of Gramsci’s thought became more complex; contradictory aspects were highlighted as well as a shift in his orientation and his difficulties within the Party; the letters of 1926 were published in the Party press and the critical edition of the Prison Notebooks was eventually published by Valentino Gerratana in 1975. However, Gramsci, because of his reception in the 1950s and his strong historical identification with the Communist Party of Togliatti, was not an author of the new left,18 which developed new theoretical tools starting with a rereading of Marx. Some authors recovered Gramsci’s thought on worker councils, which could help to read the Italy of the 1960s and to mobilize and express the radical class confl icts that crossed it.19

40

Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra

For this exclusion of Gramsci from the theoretical references of the new left the book by Alberto Asor Rosa, Scrittori e popolo [“Writers and the People”], was decisive. Asor Rosa, literary critic and member of the workerist left, blamed the cultural policy of the Italian Left in the postwar period, its provincial populism, and the petty bourgeois character of its culture that referred to a tradition created in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries that had its pillars in Gioberti, De Sanctis, Croce and Gramsci. Much Italian literature of the twentieth century was consistent with this tradition, the principles of which had already been formulated in the Risorgimento, and went on unaffected through the Fascist period and was then re-launched by Neorealism and the PCI. The national and democratic strategy of Togliatti rested on that tradition and with the reception of the Zhdanovian Socialist Realism would have encouraged a moderate, passive, national and nostalgic portrait of the “poor people” who lived in the Italian province and had no class connotations. In this way, Togliatti developed a cultural policy consistent with the populist political mythology he had placed at the base of the Party’s strategy in the 1940s. Essential terms of this literary culture were its sentimental realism and the research on social subjects often detached from specific sociohistorical contexts, who were peasants rather than blue collar workers and were generally located in the South, paradigmatic site of a populist rhetoric that in the 1950s was enriched by the works of Carlo Levi and Danilo Dolci. The insistence on the national character of this tradition meant distance, if not open hostility, to the great twentieth-century tradition of European literary research. Gramsci, according to Asor Rosa, was a crucial element of mediation between the moderate tradition of populism and the strategy of the Italian Communist Party. Thus Asor Rosa shared in Togliatti’s reading of Gramsci, although in order to reverse its sign. Asor Rosa, against the sentimental evocation of the people, argued for the political centrality of the working class and against the national and provincial neorealism for the avant-garde and its open European horizons. Asor Rosa took on theoretical innovation at the historical-literary level where workerism was introduced in the Italian political thought of the 1960s. In this sense it represented a major break and a radical critique of the strategy of the postwar Communist Party. To reread them today, Asor Rosa’s pages on Gramsci appear to be ungenerous and substantially off-centered, but it is clear that Asor Rosa was not interested in a close analysis of Gramsci’s texts, but rather to draw criticism to a tradition that had been founded through Gramsci after the Second World War. Not by chance Asor Rosa spoke more of “Gramscianesimo” [Gramscianism] rather than of Gramsci. Asor Rosa was able to address a sharp critique to decades of cultural backwardness of the Communist Party with its distrust of the international avant-garde culture, ignorance of the social sciences, and the inability to grasp the contradictions of an advanced industrial society. For many young intellectuals this vehement complaint against the national populist culture was certainly perceived as the shedding

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

41

of an ideological cloak that compressed political energies rather than organize and mobilize them. However, this reading came to put a tombstone on any possible alternative use of Gramsci’s work. There are many criticisms that can be made of Asor Rosa’s reading of Gramsci. Gramsci’s attention to the local and national level is constantly placed in an international and global dimension. This is the framework in which Gramsci’s thought makes sense, although he was nevertheless well aware of the importance of nation building as a constitutive element of social processes of modernity, such as wars and revolutions.20 The national dimension had to be carefully analyzed in order to avoid an abstract and schematic interpretation of social processes, and in this sense, Gramsci developed the research on nation and nationalism which had become crucial in the international Marxist debate at the beginning of the century. But there are at least three other aspects of Gramsci’s thought that Asor Rosa surprisingly failed to appreciate. First, Gramsci’s analysis of culture proved to be very keen, precisely in the direction which Asor Rosa hoped for, i.e., the battle against idealism and a materialistic view of cultural processes.21 Second, the analysis of the culture of the subaltern in the Prison Notebooks is far from any apologia; indeed, it denounced its more reactionary and regressive aspects, however imagining it as the only possible starting point for a political struggle that aimed at mobilizing subalterns who inevitably defi ne themselves through the lens of the dominant culture. According to Gramsci, peasant and subaltern cultures22 do not in themselves automatically carry any antagonistic and progressive meaning, contrary to the opinion of some scholars of the “history from below,” which was so successful even in Italy in the 1960s and 1970s. Finally, what is surprising is Asor Rosa’s separation of Gramsci as literary critic from Gramsci as political thinker, because the unification of these two figures prevents locking him into a national tradition that he confronts in order to overthrow its hegemony. Gramsci was the leader of an internationalist party that in the 1920s and 1930s was just coming to terms with the difficult terrain of articulating the local and national level with the international dimension in which to fight against global capitalism. This keen perception of the global dimension of capitalism was openly discussed in “Notebook 22,” “Americanismo e fordismo,” “Americanism and Fordism,” and the already mentioned confl ict with Togliatti in 1926 bears tragic witness to the international dimension of Gramsci’s thought. In the famous letter of 1926, Gramsci was talking of the difficult relationship between local and international levels in the history of communism, and although he joined the majority’s argument against the unified opposition, his call for unity of the Leninists was not a simple tribute to orthodoxy but the prophetic intuition that a split of an international movement on a national confl ict was a harbinger of doom for the history of international communism. At any rate, the text of Asor Rosa, despite the limited relevance of his critique of Gramsci, was central in the critique of the cultural tradition of the

42

Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra

PCI that had been based on a certain reception of Gramsci. In the 1960s, Italy became an advanced industrial society and the intellectual apparatus built by the Italian Communist Party after the war proved to be increasingly obsolete. The most innovative categories of social analysis and political intervention in social struggles were put forward from outside of the PCI and of its surrounding intellectual influence. From the intellectual and political environment of workerism came some of the most interesting hints toward a new political culture able to interpret the powerful social confl icts of those years. “Our Near Past”: Marx v. Gramsci in the Experience of Workerism Also known as “autonomist Marxism,” “workerism” was surely the most important and original theoretical and political development within Italian Marxism in the 1960s. 23 It played a crucial role both in the interpretation of the powerful workers’ struggles that shook the country during that decade and in the formation of the revolutionary groups that shaped the “long” Italian 1968 movement—from 1968 to 1977. English-speaking readers may be familiar with what is today called “post-workerism,” associated with Antonio Negri whose theories have deeply influenced international debates on globalization and within cultural and postcolonial studies since the publication of Empire. “Workerism” was, of course, not the only relevant development within Italian critical theory in the 1960s. As far as the legacy of Gramsci is concerned, it is worth mentioning the influence of the great anthropologist Ernesto De Martino, and the emergence of vast grassroots movements engaged in the south of the country in the project of developing what has been recently called an “ethnography of Italian subalterns.” Poor Southern peasants and rural day laborers were considered by these researchers and activists as the “internal others” par excellence, as the subjects who were to play a seminal role in the re-politicization of the “Southern Question” and in the renewal of the Gramscian project of an alliance between Northern industrial workers and Southern peasants. 24 These experiences were often shaped by an original reading of Gramsci’s reflections on “subaltern groups” and “folklore” in the Prison Notebooks (especially “Notebook 25” and “27”). They nurtured a kind of underground Gramscian stream that in the following years deeply influenced the development of ethnology, anthropology and museography in Italy. Nevertheless, the importance of “workerism” cannot be underestimated. In the 1960s the workerist intellectuals, researchers and militants seemed able to provide the most effective interpretations of what was called at the beginning of the decade “neo-capitalism,” the spectacular economic development as a result of “Fordist” mass industrialization that dramatically changed the

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

43

productive, social and cultural landscape of the country. In a book published in 1972, which remains the most important workerist statement on the issue, Luciano Ferrari Bravo and Alessandro Serafi ni noted that the very “Southern Question” changed its profi le through the mass emigration toward the North and the contradictory take off of industrialization processes in several Southern areas between the end of the 1950s and the early 1960s. The reality of the Fordist factory was the research object and the political stake for the development of workerism in the 1960s. Such journals as Quaderni rossi and Classe operaia brought together intellectuals, researchers, militant workers and union organizers who, in the majority, had no previous political experience or came from the left of the Italian Socialist Party, such as the founder of Quaderni rossi, Raniero Panzieri, as well as Antonio Negri. The Roman group around Mario Tronti and the already mentioned Alberto Asor Rosa were an exception in this regard, since they were part of the University section of the Italian Communist Party. But in general the relation between “workerism” and the PCI was from the beginning very tense and confl ict-ridden, and this is easy to understand since workerism as a whole developed a radical critique of the national hegemony project that had been elaborated by Togliatti in the previous years. It is nevertheless worth recalling that both Mario Tronti and Alberto Asor Rosa, as well as the younger student of Negri’s, Massimo Cacciari (who was to become a well-known philosopher and later, the mayor of Venice), decided to continue their political militancy in the Communist Party after 1968, further elaborating the legacy of workerism in peculiar ways that were quite influential for the cultural politics of the party in the 1970s and in the 1980s. The birth of workerism in the early 1960s is a turning point not only for the political culture of the left and for the development of critical theory in Italy, it is also a crucial moment in order to understand the destiny of Gramsci in his home country in the following decades. For instance, if one looks at the history of the British New Left, at South America or India, it is easy to see that Gramsci’s thought provided crucial tools that helped to break with Marxist orthodoxy as represented by official Communist parties. This rupture must be recognized as the point of inception of some of the most important and creative developments of contemporary critical theory, in which the reference to Gramsci continues to be a defining theoretical element—from cultural to postcolonial and the Subaltern Studies project. In order to understand the different situation in Italy, one has to realize that the break with Marxist and communist orthodoxy was indeed a break with Gramsci, meaning a break with the image of Gramsci that took shape through the interpretation of his work within the Italian Communist Party in the 1940s and 1950s and that we have tried to reconstruct. And while for example, in Great Britain the basic critical move was to disentangle the element of “workers’ consciousness” from an “objectivist” reading of capitalist development, in Italy the workerist engagement with the reality of the Fordist factory immediately raised the problem of subjectivity.

44

Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra

Inhabited by what Tronti memorably termed the rude razza pagana, “the rough pagan race” (that is, the new “mass worker,” young, and mostly Southern migrant workers), the factory, as represented for instance by the huge FIAT plants in Turin, or by the emerging chemical industrial complex of Porto Marghera (Venice) was, in the eyes of the workerists, eventually opening up modernity in Italy. What Asor Rosa criticized, as we saw above, from the point of view of literature, the sentimental and nostalgic longing for the “people” of the province, became a kind of general cipher of an Italian provincialism that the struggles of the working class were getting rid of. The workerists were deeply convinced that Italy was becoming a very advanced revolutionary laboratory, and this meant that there was a need for a “philosophy”—or better for a “science”—capable of interpreting such advanced struggles. Needless to say, this could not be a “provincial” philosophy. From this point of view, in order to understand the relation of the workerists with Gramsci it is particularly important to read an essay published in 1959 by Mario Tronti, “Tra materialismo dialettico e filosofia della prassi. Gramsci e Labriola” [“Between dialectical materialism and philosophy of praxis. Gramsci and Labriola”]. The importance of Gramsci is recognized from the first lines by Tronti, who states that “the whole cultural world of his age is interpreted and ‘translated’ in his thought.” But this is precisely the key to an interpretation of Gramsci that aims at locating his work within a history and a cultural constellation that are “immediately behind us” and that build our “near past” (in Caracciolo and Scalia 141). Even more relevant for our present discussion is Tronti’s argument that Gramsci “is a typically, I would even say fundamentally Italian thinker,” and that it would be a mistake to give him “a European range” (“Tra materialismo dialettico e filosofia della prassi” 156). Revisiting through Gramsci the history of the debates on Marx and Marxism in Italy since the late 1890s, Tronti argues that Gramsci himself remained caught within an interpretation of Marx shaped by idealism and historicism—that means by the philosophical interpretations provided by Giovanni Gentile and Benedetto Croce (“Tra materialismo dialettico e filosofia della prassi” 156–61). One could say that the basic aim of Tronti and of most workerist theorists in the following decade was to disentangle Marx from idealism and historicism, and this meant to also disentangle him from Gramsci. Back to Marx became the slogan of workerism, which led to a tight engagement fi rst of all with Capital, volume 1 (especially with the chapters on “The Working Day” and on “Machinery and Large-Scale Industry” 25 ), and soon afterwards with the Grundrisse.26 And while Gramsci was a point of entry to understand the past, Marx was to be read in the present: he must be confronted “not with his age, but with ours. Capital has to be evaluated on the basis of contemporary capitalism” (Tronti, Operai e capitale 31). In 1966, Mario Tronti summed up the results of his engagement with Marx, publishing Operai e capitale, a book that was to become famous for the thesis of the priority of workers’ struggles with respect to capitalist development. 27

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

45

At the same time, one has to keep in mind that the criticism of idealism and historicism opened up the possibility of a direct engagement with sociology, and especially labor and industrial sociology, that were in a way banned in the 1950s (of course with some relevant exceptions) with a reference to the authority of Gramsci and Croce, both from Marxist and from “liberal” culture. Some of the most important Italian labor and industrial sociologists of the following decades—from Aris Accornero to Giovanni Mottura—had their training in such journals as Quaderni rossi and Classe operaia. These journals started to produce an accurate cartography of workers’ conditions and struggles under the conditions of neo-capitalism, stressing the importance of seemingly “un-political” workers’ behaviors such as absenteeism and small (even individual) gestures of sabotage, and initiated “militant investigations” (or “co-researches”) in many factories, directly involving workers in the production of knowledge on their living and work conditions and experimenting with the transformation of this knowledge into a condition for struggle.28 “Militant investigation” and “co-research” became the tools through which the cartography of workers’ conditions and struggles turned into a cartography of subjectivity (we could even say, with contemporary terms, of the production of subjectivity). As we were anticipating previously, Italian workerists did not use the concept of “class consciousness” in their researches and in their political theory. It is easy to see that this happened because of the “idealist” imprinting of the very concept of consciousness. Instead of an emphasis on class consciousness, the way out of any possible kind of “objectivism” was sought, on the one hand, through the already mentioned thesis of the priority of workers’ struggles with respect to capitalist development, and, on the other hand, through the forging of the category of class composition and through a focus on the tension between its “technical” and its “political” dimensions. The concept of “technical class composition” was worked out as a kind of reverse side of what Marx had termed the “organic composition of capital,” and was meant to grasp from the workers’ point of view the structure of the capitalist organization of labor. To this, the concept of a “political class composition” was added in order to take the subjective behaviors, the needs, and the traditions of struggle into account when defi ning class. The subjective figure of the “mass worker” (operaio massa) corresponding to neo-capitalism was interpreted as the partial subject that carried the whole weight of mass production and that had the potential to blow up the discipline and order of the “factory-society” with its correlate ideologies of social integration and welfare. It is precisely the emphasis on the partiality of this subject that leads Tronti to produce a radical rupture with the ideology and the project of the Communist party, which through a specific and, as we saw, very selective interpretation of Gramsci, did not center upon the working class but rather upon the “people”: “when the working class politically refuses to become people,” writes Tronti in 1963, “this does not mean that the straight way toward socialist revolution is being closed: the opposite

46

Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra

is true, it is rather the opening up of that way” (Operai e capitale 79). Tronti’s criticism applies not only to the concept of the people, but also to the concept of “general will” and to the political language of universalism in general, deconstructing the whole strategy of “progressive democracy” envisioned by Palmiro Togliatti. The name of Gramsci was so deeply associated with this strategy that he was not even mentioned in Operai e capitale. And while the concept of culture was playing a crucial role in the UK, for example, in an attempt to innovate the working class’s history and politics that shared at least some concerns with Italian workerism, Tronti was in a hurry to get rid of it as a legacy of the “near past” to which he relegated Gramsci. The very concept of culture, he wrote in 1965, does not mean anything more, or it takes up a totally alien meaning for the working class as a partial subject. Culture in fact, like the concept of Right, of which Marx speaks, is always bourgeois. In other words, it is always a relation between intellectuals and society, between intellectuals and the people, between intellectuals and class; in this way it is always a mediation of confl icts and their resolution in something else. If culture is the reconstruction of the totality of man, the search for his humanity in the world, a vocation to keep united that which is divided—then it is something which is by nature reactionary and should be treated as such. (Operai e capitale 245) “Culture” appeared to Tronti closely associated with the concept of the “people,” which he was criticizing as the cornerstone of what appeared to him as a populist strategy of the Communist party.29 More precisely it was considered by him as the crystallization of a specific hegemonic constellation that the Communist Party was indeed contributing to enforce and reproduce (both through its “intellectuals” and through its action in “society”), while the insurgence of the working class as a partial subject was radically challenging it. This is perhaps the point in which the development of workerism was furthest away from the Communist Party reading of Gramsci in the 1960s. Back Home After the great rupture produced by the 1968 movement and by the dramatic workers’ struggles during the fall of 1969, Gramsci was of course circulating among the revolutionary groups of the Italian new left: the group of il Manifesto gathered around such important political and intellectual former leaders of the Communist Party as Rossana Rossanda, Luigi Pintor, and Valentino Parlato (they were expelled from the party after openly criticizing the USSR intervention in Czechoslovakia), and took Gramsci’s writings on the workers’ councils as an important point of reference in the development of its reading of the Italian situation in the early 1970s. Also to be mentioned here is the

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

47

activity of the “Gruppo Gramsci” in Milan, in which important intellectuals and political cadres such as Romano Madera, Luisa Passerini, and Giovanni Arrighi were active. This experience—“a rarity in the extra-parliamentary left,” as Arrighi himself retrospectively recognized—was meant in Gramscian terms to forge “organic intellectuals of the working class in struggle,” whose function was to help the class to develop its own “autonomy” (61–94, 66f). 30 Nevertheless, Gramsci did not play an important role in the debates of the “new left” in the 1970s, while he continued to be at the core of the intellectual discussion within the Communist party. Independently of an extraordinary production of specialized scholarly works of heterogeneous quality, 31 at stake from a political point of view was a new reading of the concept of hegemony. This new reading stressed the “organicistic” elements of Gramsci’s thought, making him available for a legitimization of the new strategy of the so-called “historical compromise.” The “historical compromise” meant the alliance with the Christian Democratic Party in the perspective of a revival of the founding spirit of the Republic after 1945, which the general secretary of the party, Enrico Berlinguer, started to develop in the wake of his interpretation of the 1973 coup in Chile and of the ongoing radicalization of social struggles and movements in Italy. From this point of view, a lively discussion developed around the thesis presented by Norberto Bobbio, who emphasized the “super-structural” elements of Gramsci’s concept of civil society and made this concept itself an important political battlefield. 32 Bobbio’s reading was rooted in the liberal reading of Gramsci that had its antecedents in Benedetto Croce and Piero Gobetti. But it resulted, on the one hand, in making Gramsci even more distant from the intellectual references of the diverse spectrum of the radical left, and, on the other, it attracted severe criticism from intellectuals tied to the Communist Party. One could even say that Bobbio’s insistence on the cultural fabric of civil society anticipated some terms of later Gramscian revivals. After the electoral successes of the Communist Party in the mid-1970s, it entered a phase of decline and the strategy itself of the “historical compromise” was a failure in the turbulent years that closed one of the most important and confl ict-ridden decades in the history of the Italian Republic. The 1980s were shaped by a confused search for new models and perspectives within the Communist Party. In this search, Gramsci was progressively marginalized from the intellectual debate, and one can say that the end of the Communist Party after 1989 also marked the vanishing of a “cultural industry” revolving around the name of Gramsci, an industry which flourished for four decades, monopolizing the interpretation of his thought, surely producing some important scholarly achievements but also radically limiting the potentiality and reducing the openness of his work. At the same time, an awareness of the existence of a different debate on Gramsci beyond the borders of his native land started to spread in Italy.33 It was no coincidence that one of the fi rst points of crystallization of a new

48

Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra

interest for Gramsci (one which was nevertheless bound to remain quite marginal in the Italian academic and intellectual life) was “Notebook 22,” “Americanism and Fordism.” Giorgio Baratta, who would emerge as a central figure in this new season of Italian Gramscian studies, organized a conference on Gramsci’s critique of Americanism in 1987. It was an important landmark in the process of “provincializing” the Italian discussion on Gramsci and recovering the global perspective inherent in his thought. 34 “Notebook 22” presented moreover an analysis of the complex relations between “culture” and production that were emerging as crucial, precisely in the crisis of Fordism, as had already been stressed by the so-called French regulation school and would lie at the core of Stuart Hall’s controversial reading of the New Times inaugurated by Thatcherism in the UK. 35 In the following years, Baratta, who was also the founder of the Italian section of the International Gramsci Society, contributed to the reception of the most stimulating readings of Gramsci developed especially in the Latin American experience (especially Carlos Nelson Coutinho) and within cultural and postcolonial studies (especially Edward Said and Stuart Hall).36 A conference organized in 2007 in Rome titled “Gramsci, Cultures and the World” was a kind of concluding step in this direction: after many travels around the world, Gramsci was coming back to Italy in a quite different shape than the one that had dominated the postwar era. 37 Outlining a Research Agenda In the last decade, the Italian debate and scholarly research on Gramsci has been particularly intense, producing important philosophical and political general interpretations of his thought as well as bibliographical and even encyclopedic reference works. 38 But independently of individual achievements, what characterizes the new season of Italian Gramsci studies that started in the 1990s is the recovery of the global dimension of Gramscian thought and concepts that, as we have seen, had been previously inscribed within a rather parochial intellectual and historical experience. In what follows we would like to outline a kind of research agenda, indicating some of the basic topics and insights that are already developed in the Italian discussion and could be even more elaborated in the near future. As Edward Said, in particular, has emphasized, the importance of space in Gramsci’s thought (his “geographical materialism”) opens up the possibility of using his concepts in order to reconstruct the historical and contemporary dynamics of global capitalism in its multi-scalar hierarchies, relations, and confl icts. 39 This seems to us one of the most promising research perspectives to be developed in the near future. The interpenetration and increasing overlap between the local, the national, and the global would have been a topic of great interest for Gramsci himself, who was particularly sensitive to the mobility and elusiveness of spatial coordinates. Writing to his brother Carlo

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

49

on September 28, 1931, Gramsci commented on H. G. Wells’ Short History of the World, It is interesting because it tends to break with the prevailing habit of thinking that history only existed in Europe, particularly in ancient times; Wells discusses the ancient history of China, India, and the medieval history of the Mongols with the same tone he adopts in speaking of European history. He shows that from a world standpoint Europe should not be regarded as anything more than a province that considers itself the depository of all world civilization. (Gramsci, Letters from Prison, ed. Rosengarten 2:80) In this perspective, the nation itself becomes a specific historical actor, which played a fundamental role in European modernity, but not the exclusive semantic horizon within which Gramscian concepts are located. As Gramsci wrote on August 8, 1927 in a kind of postcolonial mood to his friend Berti commenting on Henri Massis’ Défence de l’Occident, What makes me laugh is the fact that this eminent Massis, who is dreadfully afraid that Tagore’s and Gandhi’s Asiatic ideology might destroy French Catholic rationalism, does not realise that Paris has already become a semicolony of Senegalese intellectualism and that in France the number of half-breeds is increasing by leaps and bounds. One might, just for a laugh, maintain that, if Germany is the extreme outcrop of ideological Asianism, France is the beginning of darkest Africa and the jazz band is the fi rst molecule of a new Euro-African civilization! (Gramsci, Letters from Prison, ed. Rosengarten 1:128) Crucial from the point of view of the formulation of his “geographical materialism” has been, of course, Gramsci’s work on the Southern Question. We do think that rereading these writings is particularly telling not only for the topic discussed but also more generally in terms of method. We fi nd here a topological model of analysis of the peculiarities of Italian capitalism, of the social forces that shape it, of the political alliances, and confl icts among these diverse social segments, but above all of the multifarious ways in which power relations between them are continuously arranged and rearranged, establishing mobile forms of cultural hegemony. It is in this framework that the figure of the “subaltern” becomes a subject of history, with a specific gaze on the cultural forms of expression that were particularly analyzed by Gramsci in “Notebook 25” and “Notebook 27,” where he speaks of “folklore” not as something “picturesque” but as a “conception of the world and of life of certain defi ned social strata (defi ned in time and in space)” (2311). Entering history, subalterns do not enter a kind of teleological process, and their “spontaneous philosophy,” as Gramsci also writes, is not necessarily

50

Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra

“progressive.” Nevertheless, it is the inescapable point of reference for political mobilization of subalterns themselves as well as for a materialist writing of history. In the field of tension between the two concepts of hegemony and subaltern, a whole series of problems, dynamics, and confl icts can be relocated and investigated anew: from the question of ideology to investigation of the social pressures that limit and shape individual behaviors (what Gramsci analyzes through such keywords as conformismo, “conformism,” and uomomassa, “man-as-mass” (Prison Notebooks 3:164–66). The field of “culture,” sharply criticized and radically dismissed in the 1960s by Mario Tronti, presents itself now as a privileged field on which the crucial issue of the production of subjectivity under the conditions of contemporary capitalism can be critically analyzed. This critical analysis can fi nd in Gramsci’s answer to the question “What is Man?” a surprisingly useful tool. It is worth rereading it after the whole discussion on the crisis of humanism and post-structuralist deconstruction of the subject: “[M]an must be conceived of as a historical complex made up of purely individual and subjective elements on the one hand, and on the other, of mass, objective or material elements, with which the individual has an active relationship” (Quaderni 1338). Another topic worth developing is Gramsci’s thought and his reflection on language in general, and specifically on translation and translatability.40 “Notebook 29,” “Note sullo studio della grammatica” (“Notes on the study of grammar”), the last “Notebook,” demonstrates this reflection. The distinction formulated by Gramsci between “normative grammar,” on the one hand, and “spontaneous and immanent grammars,” on the other hand, seems to be particularly promising, especially if we connect it with the defi nition of “man” quoted previously. In a way, the “normative grammar” discussed by Gramsci seems to be one of those “mass and objective elements” that make up “man,” while “spontaneous and immanent grammars” (whose number is “incalculable and theoretically one can say that everybody has his or her grammar”) surely correspond to the “purely individual and subjective elements” (Quaderni 2343). More generally, Gramsci seems once more particularly sensitive here to the mobility of languages and to the reality of power relations that crisscross the processes of their formation and that shape their relations—in other words, he was sensitive to an issue that is widely recognized as crucial in our postcolonial world. A very rich reflection on the issue of translation relates to this conception of language in the Notebooks. It is worth emphasizing that the very root of the problem for Gramsci is political, and he was already aware of that in the wake of the Russian revolution. One of the most intense paragraphs on the problem of translation in the Notebooks is introduced by a quote from Lenin, who said in 1921 that “we haven’t managed to translate our language,” meaning the revolutionary politics of the Bolsheviks themselves, “into the European languages” (Quaderni 1468). Starting from this very peculiar problem of “translation,”

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

51

Gramsci developed a multi-scalar theory of translation (linguistic, scientific, philosophical, popular, cultural, and so on) that although fragmentary, seems to be particularly topical. In a way, it allows to combine and articulate, as a kind of mobile and flexible platform, the interplay of the three previous points that we briefly discussed: Gramsci’s “geographical materialism,” his “topological” reflection on the cultural dynamics of hegemony, and his approach to the issue of subjectivation. It is working from within this mobile and flexible platform that we hope new Italian studies and scholars will be able to contribute in an innovative and creative way to the ongoing transnational and transcontinental conversation on Gramsci’s thought. Notes 1. See Tronti, “Tra materialismo dialettico e fi losofia della prassi,” 141–62. We discuss Tronti’s essay subsequently (second section). 2. The analysis of the fascist movement as a “regime reazionario di massa” (reactionary regime with mass support) was outlined by Togliatti in 1935 in a series of lectures held in Moscow, but published in Italy only in 1970. These lectures represented a very stimulating analysis of fascism and the awareness of the mass character of fascist organizations influenced Togliatti’s project of the “partito nuovo”; see Togliatti, Lezioni sul fascismo. 3. This book won the Premio Viareggio, a major Italian literary prize. In 1950 the Fondazione Istituto Gramsci was founded, whose aim was to promote research on Gramsci’s work and the communist movement. In the 1960s the Istituto Gramsci acquired the letters and the notebooks of Gramsci. 4. This censorship was denounced by the socialist historian Salvatore Sechi already in 1965; see Sechi, “Le ‘lettere dal carcere’ e la politica culturale del Pci” (1965), now in Movimento operaio e storiografia marxista, Bari, De Donato, 1974. The fact that Gramsci’s reception after the war was based on a heavy manipulation and sometimes falsification of his writings is nowadays recognized by scholars with different orientations in the interpretation of Gramsci; see Vacca, “Togliatti editore delle Lettere e dei Quaderni del carcere,” in Vacca, Togliatti sconosciuto 123–69; Bermani 2007. 5. Palmiro Togliatti, Trenta anni di vita e lotte del Pci. 6. A substantial change in the historiography on the Italian Communist Party was introduced by the huge work of Paolo Spriano, whose fi rst volume was published in 1967; see Spriano 1967–1975. 7. Amadeo Bordiga was the leading founder of the PCd’I in 1921, his left-wing positions within the communist movement had been attacked by Lenin already in 1920 in Left-Wing Communism: An Infantile Disorder. In the following years Bordiga maintained a critical position toward the development of the Bolschevik Party in Russia and its leading role in the Third International, and he was a prominent representative of the so-called left-wing communism so that he was marginalized both in the Italian and international communist movement. Bordiga was expelled by the Communist Party in 1930 and he never went back. After the second World War he founded his own small revolutionary party which did not have any significant role in Italian politics; on Bordiga see De Clementi.

52

Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra

8. The fi rst edition of the Prison Notebooks was published by Einaudi (Torino) in six thematic volumes between 1948 and 1951, edited by Felice Platone under the supervision of Togliatti. The Selections from the Prison Notebooks, edited and translated by Hoare and Smith, which shaped the discussion of Gramsci’s work in the Anglophone world, was based on this edition. 9. Croce has been the most influential intellectual of Italian idealism in the twentieth century. His work constituted the basis of the education of the liberal ruling class in Italy. The Italian Communist Party aimed at refuting Croce, stressing the role of the “common people” in nation building and in the development of Italian modernity, but it shared with Croce a similar historicist-progressive vision of history. 10. In the 1970s, just in the phase of Fordism’s crisis, some scholars began to pay more attention to “Notebook 22,” on “Americanism and Fordism”; see the special edition of the Notebook edited by F. De Felice in 1978. Some papers presented at the Gramsci conference of 1977 have a focus on “americanismo e fordismo,” in particular Bodei, Battini, Salvadori, Paggi, F. de Felice; see Ferri 1977. Within the workerist debate, Sergio Bologna recovered Gramsci’s thought. In the following years, interest grew in “Notebook 22,” and the analysis of it signaled the engagement with Gramsci of Giorgio Baratta, one of the most distinguished scholars of the Gramsci renaissance of the last twenty years. See Baratta and Catone (eds.), Modern Times. A brilliant reading of the influence of “Notebook 22” in postwar Italian debates on the left, “through and beyond workerism,” has been recently provided by Boni 79–88. 11. “[C]i pare che la passione violenta delle quistioni russe vi faccia perdere di vista gli aspetti internazionali delle quistioni russe stesse, vi faccia dimenticare che i vostri doveri di militanti russi possono e debbono essere adempiuti solo nel quadro degli interessi del proletariato internazionale,” Gramsci, letter of October 14. The correspondence of 1926 is now entirely published in Chiara Daniele (ed.), Gramsci a Roma, Togliatti a Mosca. Il carteggio del 1926. In an essay within this book, Vacca reads these letters within the internal debate of the Italian Communist Party in those years, focusing on the confl icts between the political strategies of Gramsci and Togliatti. The text of the fi rst letter had been already published by Tasca in 1938; the answer of Togliatti was published in Rinascita in 1964; the above objection of Gramsci was published only in 1970. It was certainly not by chance that Togliatti published a part of the correspondence just three months before his death at a moment in which, faced with the confl ict between the Soviet Union and China, he was outlining a critical perspective on the history of international communism. 12. An English translation of this letter can be found in http://www.marxists.org/ archive/gramsci/1926/10/letter-togliatti.htm. 13. Gramsci was stopped in Milan and sent back to Rome by the police. What occurred in those days has been clarified by a letter of Tatiana Schucht discovered only in 2008 and published in L’Unità on November 7, 2008. 14. Emblematic of this hagiography is the fi rst biography of Gramsci, by Lucio Lombardo Radice and Giuseppe Carbone, Vita di Antonio Gramsci (1952). This book contributed to consolidating the historiographical tradition discussed above, i.e. a direct line which linked Ordine Nuovo, PCd’I (Partito Comunista d’Italia), and the “partito nuovo” (the “new party”) bound by the relationship

Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci

15.

16.

17. 18.

19. 20. 21. 22.

23.

24. 25. 26.

27. 28. 29.

30.

53

between Gramsci and Togliatti. This orthodox tradition eliminated every other voice which had contributed to the history of the Italian communist movement, labeling them as sectarians and heretics. Ragionamenti was an innovative journal animated by young intellectuals closest to the socialist party and was fi nanced by Gian Giacomo Feltrinelli; see Colummi 31–56. This rereading of Gramsci’s thought in the early 1920s was encouraged also by Antonio Giolitti in the VIII congress (1956) of the PCI, which was the last before his exit from the party. See Giolitti 1957. Republished in Togliatti, Gramsci 193–212. An exception was represented by scholars who considered Gramsci a man betrayed by the party, according to an interpretation that was already claimed by the Italian Trotskyists (see Corvisieri 1969). Meaningful is an essay written just on the eve of the 1968 events; see Merli 1967. On this point see Baratta, “Popolo, nazione, masse nel pensiero di Gramsci,” in Baratta and Catone 9–41. See Forgacs, “National-Popular: Genealogy of a Concept.” On the Gramscian defi nition of “gruppi sociali subalterni” (subaltern social groups), see Baratta, “Gramsci e i subalterni,” in Adamo 83–99; and Buttigieg, “Sulla categoria gramsciana di ‘subalterno’,” in Baratta e Liguori (eds.), Gramsci da un secolo all’altro, 27–38. For a good introduction in English, see Wright. In Italian see Asor Rosa, 1649ff; Trotta and Milana, L’operaismo degli anni Sessanta. Da “Quaderni rossi” a “classe operaia.” Cf. Rivera in Adamo 111–32. See Marx, Capital, Chapter 10 (“The Working Day”) and Chapter 15 (“Machinery and Large-Scale Industry”). See for instance Marx, Scritti and above all the fi rst translation (by Renato Solmi) of the so-called “Fragment on the machines” from the Grundrisse in Quaderni rossi, 4 (1964), 289–300. The fi rst Italian edition of the Grundrisse was also translated and edited by a workerist intellectual, Enzo Grillo; cf. Marx, Lineamenti fondamentali della critica dell’economia politica. See also Negri, Marx Beyond Marx: Lessons on the Grundrisse. On the continuing importance of Tronti’s “Copernican revolution,” see Hardt and Negri, Commonwealth 290–95. See for instance the work of the “inventor” of the methodology of “militant investigation” or “co-research,” Alquati. One could recall here the recent interpretation of Togliatti’s “new party” in terms of populism provided by Laclau, On Populist Reason. Needless to say, while Laclau uses the concept of populism in positive terms, Tronti was radically criticizing the centrality of the “people” (and not of the working class) in the political strategy and discourse of the Communist party in the 1950s and 1960s. Arrighi also mentions in this important interview that in the postscript to the second edition of The Geometry of Imperialism (1983) he argued “that the Gramscian concept of hegemony could be more useful than imperialism in analyzing contemporary dynamics of the inter-state system” (70): his experience in the

54

31. 32. 33.

34. 35. 36. 37.

38.

39.

40.

Paolo Capuzzo and Sandro Mezzadra “Gruppo Gramsci” was thus an important step in the formulation of a theory of the world system of historical capitalism that has played a crucial role in the international debate of the last two decades. For one of the most important works on Gramsci in these years, see Paggi. Bobbio’s pamphlet developed the text of a paper presented by him in 1967 at a conference for the thirtieth anniversary of Gramsci’s death. An important event in this regard was the conference organized by the “Fondazione Istituto Gramsci” in 1989 in Formia: see the proceedings, Righi (ed), Gramsci nel mondo. See also Santucci. Baratta and Catone (eds.), Tempi moderni. See for instance Aglietta, and Hall and Jacques. See for instance Baratta, Le rose e i Quaderni. Il pensiero dialogico di Antonio Gramsci. See the proceedings in Schirru (ed.), Gramsci, le culture, il mondo. A collection of landmark essays in cultural studies on Gramsci has been edited by Vacca, Capuzzo, and Schirru, Studi gramsciani nel mondo: gli studi culturali. See for instance Burgio, Gramsci storico. Una lettura dei Quaderni del carcere; Frosini, Da Gramsci a Marx. Ideologia, verità, politica; Liguori, Sentieri gramsciani; and Guido Liguori and Pasquale Voza (eds.), Dizionario gramsciano. Particularly important in this regard is the work done in Naples by Lidia Curti and Iain Chambers: see for instance Chambers (ed.), Esercizi di potere. Gramsci, Said e il postcoloniale. There is of course a wide literature especially on the issue of translation and translatability in Gramsci’s thought. Particularly important in the Italian debate has been the work on Gramsci and language by Lo Piparo, Lingua, intellettuali, egemonia. See also his recent essay, “Gramsci and Wittgenstein. An Intriguing Connection,” in Capone (ed.), Perspectives on Language Use and Pragmatic: A Volume in Memory of Sorin Stati.

3

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual The Black Colonized Intellectual in George Padmore and Frantz Fanon

1

Neelam Srivastava

Ross Posnock, in a magisterial essay on the black (male) intellectual, defi nes the fundamental aporia that marks his condition. In the emergence of the black intellectual as a social category, he appears to white society as a “threatening oxymoron” (330). But the political and epistemological problems surrounding this figure are not limited to his confrontation with whites. They extend to the difficult negotiation between élite and popular strata of black and colonized cultures in the context of liberation struggles. Posnock notes how Frantz Fanon refused the ideology of authenticity that characterized Négritude and its elaboration of a black cultural identity, and opted instead for an ex novo creation of the self in the wake of racism and colonialism. Posnock’s essay focuses mainly on the figures of W. E. B. Du Bois and Fanon, arguing that “neither man regarded nationalism or Négritude as an endpoint or a fi xed identity, rather they were moments, critical stages, to be worked through to reach a telos of the universal. This perspective sponsors a raceless society without erasing the historical experience of racism that unites all black and colonized people” (329). 2 Thus Posnock examines their efforts to negotiate the “racial particular” and the “unraced universal,” a tension that seems to run through many writings on the black intellectual. This chapter starts from Posnock’s very helpful reflections on the aporia of the black intellectual in order to examine the difficult relationship between the black and anti-colonial intelligentsia, on the one hand, and the colonized popular culture, on the other. These problems of negotiation are well represented in the writing of the Trinidadian George Padmore and in the Martinican (and subsequently Algerian) Frantz Fanon. Both writers dedicated much of their lives to anti-colonial activism, and both were acutely aware of the need for connection, and of the frequent communication problems, between the élite and popular strata of liberation movements. 3 To cite Posnock again, Fanon strips black “authenticity” of its foundations, and he tries to demystify the concept of blackness. But in doing so, he unwittingly creates another problem: he reanimates “the crisis of origins

56

Neelam Srivastava

that perennially attends the figure of the intellectual” (330). In other words, the intellectual is always seen as déraciné (rootless). Thus the problem of the black intellectual is a more intensified version of the problem of the progressive/left intellectual, an issue to which Antonio Gramsci dedicated some of his most salient pages in his Quaderni del carcere [Prison Notebooks]. In this chapter, I examine the points of contact between the Gramscian notion of the organic intellectual and Padmore’s and Fanon’s notion of the “colonized” or native intellectual (in Fanon’s terms, “l’intellectuel colonisé”). I explore the increasing identification between political struggle and national cultural identity that defi nes Fanon’s later work, and read this as a parallel project to Gramsci’s rethinking of the Italian intellectual’s role in postunification Italy and in the fascist era. The 1950s and 1960s witnessed a transition in conceptions around the role of the black intellectual, while “the postwar anticolonial conjuncture” inspired a whole generation of black intellectuals including George Lamming, Richard Wright and E. Franklin Frazier, who observed with admiration the way in which “colonial subjects were becoming new historical subjects” (Gaines 526). Padmore and Fanon can be said to represent two different positions on the changing role of the black intellectual. Their differing stances were connected to the shift in attitudes to Pan-Africanism and Négritude, both foundational concepts of black nationalism in the earlier decades of the twentieth century. It is very likely that Padmore and Fanon actually met in Accra in 1958, at the fi rst All-African People’s Conference organized by Padmore and Kwame Nkrumah, the president of the newly independent Ghana. This conference was an important event in Pan-Africanist politics, and it was attended by more than three hundred delegates from all over Africa, including Patrice Lumumba, representatives from the African National Congress, and of course Fanon (Young, “Fanon and the Turn to Armed Struggle in Africa” 35). Fanon’s statements in favor of armed struggle in Algeria at the conference would present a direct challenge to the nonviolent principles of Pan-Africanism.4 On other occasions, Fanon was also highly critical of Négritude. Fanon’s critique of Négritude was partially informed by his insistence that the black intellectual understand and make his the culture of the colonized masses, much in the way Gramsci insisted that Italian intellectuals discard their internationalist, cosmopolitan tendencies, and instead focus on absorbing the true culture of the Italian subaltern classes. Fanon was responding to intense cultural debates on Négritude that were taking place among black intellectuals of that period. But he was also engaging with the political dimensions of Pan-Africanism, which had been supported by the earlier generation of black activists such as Padmore, and he was attacking the quietist attitude that many newly decolonized African states had towards neo-colonialism and the continuing economic presence of ex-colonial powers in these regions. At the same

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

57

time, it should be stressed that Fanon was profoundly invested in the idea of Pan-Africanism, as his essays in Towards the African Revolution demonstrate. Indeed, as Robert Young argues, Fanon “found no incompatibility between his nationalism and Pan-Africanism” (“Fanon and the Turn to Armed Struggle in Africa” 38). In what follows, I look at Padmore’s most important oeuvre, Pan-Africanism or Communism? (1956) and at Fanon’s Les damnés de la terre (1961) [The Wretched of the Earth], examples of what Cedric Robinson problematically defi nes as “Black Marxist” texts. Fanon and Padmore both distanced themselves from orthodox Marxism, though Padmore was much more explicit about his rejection of Eurocommunism than Fanon was. Both writers, while acknowledging the profound epistemological and political influence of Marxism on their elaboration of anti-colonial thought and history, also recognized that Marxism had frequently let down black liberation movements and had attempted to co-opt their struggles. It might seem counterintuitive, then, to map out parallels between one of Europe’s most important Marxist thinkers, one of the founders of the Italian Communist Party, and Fanon and Padmore. But arguably Gramsci’s emphasis on the role of the intellectual both in history and in organizing political activity valorizes the importance of culture in class struggle. This emphasis resonates interestingly with the centrality placed on culture in much anti-colonial writing, especially that of Fanon, and is an aspect which was generally overlooked in orthodox Communist assessments of the strength of anti-colonial movements. 5 What brings together Gramsci, Padmore and Fanon in this particular conjuncture of leftist thought is the attention paid to the popular culture of the colonized subalterns as the authentic expression of a national consciousness and as the essential cornerstone of a successful program of political emancipation and liberation. In other words, we need to examine the place of the black colonized intellectual in relation to this situation, and see how the two thinkers attempt to organize and think through the “common, if dispersed and contradictory experience of both African and diaspora responses to the taking away, repression and denial of collective experience” (Idahosa 393).6 Of course, the word “authenticity” in the context of anti-colonial thought is fraught with dangers and contradictions. We will examine its use more carefully in Fanon’s essay “On National Culture,” and we will explore its complex articulation as a position which owes little to folklore, ethnic nativism, or racial essentialism. It will be argued that Fanon’s emphasis on culture, together with his and Padmore’s interrogation of the role of the black intellectual, represent important conceptual links with Gramsci’s organic intellectual as he laid it out in his Notebooks, fi rst published in their entirety in 1975. It might be useful to start with Gramsci’s defi nition of the organic intellectual, in order to proceed with the startling similarities between his, Fanon’s and Padmore’s thinking.

58

Neelam Srivastava

Gramsci’s New Intellectual Gramsci’s long-standing interest in writing a history of intellectuals was to become a central one in the Notebooks, indissolubly linked to his elaboration of hegemony, national-popular culture and the political party. Every social group, coming into existence on the original terrain of an essential function in the world of economic production, creates together with itself, organically, one or more strata of intellectuals which give it homogeneity and an awareness of its own function not only in the economic but also in the social and political fields. (SPNB 5) Gramsci thus immediately links the emergence of social class with the need to establish functionaries who will articulate and propagate its position in society and politics. In other words, the role of the intellectual is to help establish the hegemony of that particular social class. Gramsci notes that the role of the intellectual is a mediated role, because it is not directly concerned with the means of production, but rather with the super-structure. Intellectuals have “organizing” and “connective” roles, both in civil society (roughly corresponding to the private sphere), where hegemony is exercised as a form of social control, and in political society (roughly corresponding to the state or public sphere), where “direct domination” is exercised through the state and government. Gramsci sees the intellectuals as “deputies” of the dominant group, “exercising the subaltern functions of social hegemony and political government” (SPNB 12). Here, as is often the case in the Notebooks, Gramsci means “subaltern” in the military sense of “subordinate.” The deputy, that is, the intellectual, functions as a subordinate “official” who carries out the “orders” of the chief economic producer of his own social class, for example the capitalist entrepreneur (Quaderni del carcere 1513).7 Dominant groups tend to produce their own organic intellectuals who propagate their ideas and worldview at a social and cultural level. However, certain oppressed social groups, for example, the peasants, do not produce organic intellectuals (Quaderni 1518). Gramsci saw the problem of the intellectuals as a specifically Italian problem, which was linked to the uneven economic development of the country. His new conception of the intellectual as “organic” meant that this person stayed faithful to the interests of the class he belonged to and was integrated into its specific cultural-political vision, and indeed helped to establish it as hegemonic. The organic intellectual did not work to build the hegemony of a superior social class, as was the case of what he calls “traditional intellectuals,” who tended to live in rural areas (Quaderni 1520–21). These often came from the petty bourgeoisie or even the peasantry, but served the interests of the landowners, and the cultural and social outlook of the traditional intellectual was heavily influenced by the Catholic Church. With this formulation of intellectual, Gramsci essentially redefi nes this figure, and expands its remit far beyond the conventional understanding of

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

59

someone who is dedicated to cultural, literary and philosophical pursuits. The intellectual, in Gramsci’s formulation, has an inherently political function. However, he never divorces the intellectual’s political function from the cultural function, in fact the two are always seen to be indissolubly linked in his thinking. In a parenthetical note to his section on the intellectuals, Gramsci remarks that his research “will not be of a ‘sociological’ nature, but it will produce a series of essays on the ‘history of culture’ (Kulturgeschichte) and on the history of political science” (Quaderni 1515). In so doing, Gramsci democratizes the notion of intellectual, by seeing it as a function, rather than as a figure: “non-intellectuals do not exist” (SPNB 9). Homo faber cannot be separated from homo sapiens. Education figures prominently in this section of Gramsci’s Notebooks. His history of intellectuals was essentially geared towards the formulation of a new intellectual, who could “bring into being new modes of thought.” But this is only possible if people are educated into it. The traditional distinction between intellectual labor and physical labor must no longer obtain if we wish to create a new class of intellectuals: these two activities must be connected and linked into one, creating a “new equilibrium.” Indeed, the “muscular-nervous effort itself, in so far as it is an element of a general practical activity, which is perpetually innovating the physical and social world, becomes the foundation of a new and integral conception of the world” (SPNB 9). It is clear then that for Gramsci, “organic” means precisely this complete integration between the physical and the intellectual side of human nature. He concludes his section on the intellectuals by delineating clearly the type of education that should form the basis of the new intellectual: technical-industrial education (Quaderni 1551). However—and he arrives at this statement through his lengthy discussion of the merits of the Italian educational system based on the “liceo classico,” somewhat similar to a grammar school— humanism and historicism also need to form the basis of this new intellectual: The mode of being of the new intellectual can no longer consist in eloquence, which is an exterior and momentary mover of feelings and passions, but in active participation in practical life, as constructer, organizer, “permanent persuader” and not as a simple orator (but superior at the same time to the abstract mathematical spirit); from technique-aswork one proceeds to technique-as-science and to the humanistic conception of history, without which one remains “specialised” and does not become “directive” (specialised and political). (SPNB 10) Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell Smith rightly note that this is a very dense passage in Gramsci, one that contains in nuce a number of key concepts. First, Gramsci is criticizing the notion of the Italian intellectual, who in his opinion is still anchored to a belle-lettristic, rhetorical and sentimental

60

Neelam Srivastava

understanding of his role, and one that is completely divorced from the culture of the people. At the same time, however, Gramsci recognizes the fundamental importance of the historicist and humanistic approach in Italian education in forming the “truly” directive intellectual. What we see here, then, is a clear identification of the political with the cultural function of the intellectual. Italian intellectuals have historically been “cosmopolitan” in a negative sense; they have embraced an internationalist cultural dimension to the detriment of their connection with Italian indigenous cultural traditions and expressions, and have thus fatally impeded the development and consolidation of this popular-national culture. Fanon similarly remarks on the “deeply cosmopolitan mentality” of the national bourgeoisie after decolonization, linking it to its apathy and mediocrity (Wretched of The Earth 98). There is a conceptual link between Fanon’s critique of the postcolonial bourgeois intellectual and Gramsci’s critique of the traditional intellectual. Fanon sees the post-independence middle class in the newly decolonized country as an underdeveloped bourgeoisie that simply substitutes its erstwhile colonial masters. It is underdeveloped, he argues, because it is not willing to take risks and invest in the progress, industrialization and betterment of the nation the way the European bourgeoisies did in their heyday (Wretched 100–01). The passivity of this indigenous middle class recalls the ways in which Gramsci critiques the laziness and conservatism of the Italian bourgeoisie and ruling class after the Italian unification in 1861. Gramsci’s verdict on the historic role of the Italian middle class is damning. He considers it to be timid, conservative and neither capable nor willing to support the demands of the peasantry for the redistribution of land and wealth, or to oppose the stifl ing hegemony of the Catholic Church (Liguori and Voza 77). By contrast, the organic intellectual that Gramsci envisaged—one who would stay faithful to the cultural and political mandates of his social class, and who would attempt to channel national-popular culture—relates to Fanon’s understanding of the postcolonial bourgeois intellectual, as someone who leads the economic development of the country, “and fi nally pave[s] the way for a genuine national culture” (Wretched 119).8 Hegemony and the Debates on Marxism Gramsci’s emphasis on the importance of culture in the construction of a healthy and functioning political system, and of a successful nation-state, cannot be overstated enough. Closely linked to his extended and detailed concern with national culture and literature, is his notion of hegemony, which at one point he defi nes as “direzione culturale” [cultural directiveness]. A reading of the relevant sections in the Notebooks suggests that the focus on culture, and its link with hegemony may have been influenced by his debate with the Italian philosopher Benedetto Croce on the status of Marxism as a philosophical current. Croce, a great interlocutor of Gramsci and a constant

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

61

addressee of the Notebooks, had accused the “philosophy of praxis” (aka Marxism) of lacking the ethico-political dimension, and of merely consisting in a form of economic determinism. In a letter to Tatiana Schucht of 1932 (a discussion he further develops in Notebook 10), Gramsci notes how Croce’s historical-political work stresses only what in politics is known as the moment of “hegemony”, of consensus and cultural leadership, as distinct from the phase of coercion, whether exercised by legislative or executive powers, or expressed through police intervention. (Letters from Prison 235) Here Gramsci defi nes hegemony as “cultural leadership” (“direzione culturale”), foreshadowing the element of “directiveness” that marks the organic intellectual, in his discussion of the history of intellectuals in Notebook 12 quoted earlier. However, Gramsci disagrees with Croce over the supposed lack of the ethico-political dimension in Marxism. On the contrary, he argues, contemporary developments in Marxism, and specifically the thought of Lenin, have made a significant contribution in reevaluating the moment of hegemony as essential to Marxist conceptions of the State and in the “valorization” of cultural activity and of a cultural front as a necessary accompaniment to the merely political and merely economic ones (Quaderni 1224). In the Notebooks, Gramsci develops the notion of hegemony as it had emerged in classical Marxism and in the writings by Lenin. 9 Jonathan Joseph explains that for Lenin “maintaining a concept of hegemonic struggle is necessary if a mechanical materialism is to be avoided” (2). Gramsci further confi rms this, arguing that the greatest modern theorist of the philosophy of praxis [i.e. Lenin], in the field of political struggle and organization, has, in opposition to the various “economistic” tendencies, re-valorized the cultural front of struggle and has constructed the doctrine of hegemony as a complement of the history of the State as force, and as the contemporary form of the 1848 doctrine of the permanent revolution. (Quaderni 1235) Hegemony is crucial for restoring the importance of human agency in political struggle, and “for returning the active political element to history” ( Joseph). For Gramsci, then, hegemony represents Lenin’s single most important contribution to Marxism, thus helping it to evolve not only in political history and economics, but also in philosophy (SPNB 465). He goes so far as to describe Lenin’s innovation as a great “metaphysical event” (SPNB 357). Gramsci applies the notion of hegemony to many different contexts: economics, culture, religion, anthropology, psychology and linguistics. However, these distinctions are methodological rather than organic, namely, hegemony in Gramsci has a stable, core meaning that fi nds different applications in these different fields (Liguori and Voza 266ff). The bottom line of his

62

Neelam Srivastava

thinking is that cultural hegemony is not separable from political hegemony. His basic thesis is that “the philosophy of praxis conceives of the reality of human relations of knowledge as an element of political ‘hegemony’” (Quaderni 1245), using the inverted commas around the term almost as if to signify its status as a conceptual neologism. Hegemony as agency and as cultural leadership were to be the most important understandings of the term for anticolonial struggles. Culture becomes the means of connection to the people, as well as to the political party (often in exile) that champions anti-colonial nationalism. It is worth remembering that both Fanon and Padmore wrote many of their anti-colonial works from exilic locations: Fanon in Tunis, and Padmore in London. Anti-Colonial Hegemony and Colonial Domination Hegemony is often given a negative meaning in critiques of political power and inequalities. John Chalcraft, following on from Raymond Williams, remarks that “hegemony is often seen as something imposed on inert masses from above, whereas Gramsci was ‘above all else . . . a revolutionary strategist . . . [and] championed a political and ideological struggle for hegemony’ in the name of socialism” (9). In what follows, I will use hegemony in its more positive meaning, as a joint cultural and political operation that seeks to reconstruct an autonomous popular culture for the colonized that could counteract its complete negation under colonialism. Similar to Gramsci, hegemony, for both Fanon and Padmore, was a goal to be achieved by the leaders and intellectuals of black liberation movements, working together with the people. Numerous questions arise in relationship to this. First, can we consider Fanon and Padmore themselves as organic intellectuals in the Gramscian sense? Is this concept useful for making sense of their autobiography as postcolonial intellectuals? Padmore, in his history of the development of Pan-Africanism as a political movement, identified Marcus Garvey, with his populist racial rhetoric, and W. E. B. Du Bois, with his much more sophisticated thinking around race, as the twin pole stars of Pan-Africanism. Padmore, while clearly much more sympathetic to Du Bois than to Garvey, recognizes that Du Bois never saw himself as a popular leader and never had the gigantic following that Garvey enjoyed (140). The issue of connection with the grassroots was very much on Padmore’s mind, and his own career as publicist and journalist testified to his ongoing attempts to popularize and disseminate Pan-Africanism as an “accessible” and alternative ideology for black colonized peoples.10 Second, my discussion explores whether Padmore and Fanon theorized the black/colonized intellectual in a similar way to Gramsci, and to what extent they departed from him. This question opens up a larger debate on the relationship between Third World Marxism and Pan-Africanism, on the one hand, and Western Marxism on the other.

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

63

Third, I wish to ask whether Fanon was consciously influenced by Gramsci, or whether he develops his observations independently and in relationship to the colonial context. I also explore the ways in which he develops and expands on Gramsci’s embryonic conceptions regarding the colonized peoples and their leadership. Here it may be relevant to trace the history of Gramsci’s translations in French in order to gauge to what extent his work circulated among Francophone anti-colonial intellectuals. Translations of Gramsci’s writings did not appear in France until 1953 and 1955. 1955 was the year in which a selection of his writings appeared in the French journal Europe, under the title “L’organisation de l’école et de la culture” (Lussana 1058). This was an excerpt of Gramsci’s longer work, “Gli intellettuali e l’organizzazione della cultura” [Intellectuals and the organization of culture], and focused on the role of the intellectual in political and cultural organization. Thus it is possible that Fanon could have read these texts, and he may have had them in mind when he prepared his talk “On National Culture,” presented in 1959 at the Second International Congress of Black Writers and Artists, in Rome. To my mind, this essay displays the strongest similarities and links with the Gramscian understanding of popular-national culture. What emerges is also a striking parallel between Gramsci’s theorizations of postunification Italy and Fanon’s reflections on the postcolonial nations in the wake of decolonization. Gramsci is not very explicit about the nature of the relationship between hegemony and domination that is so crucial in a colonial context; at times, he juxtaposes hegemony, understood as intellectual and moral directiveness, with “direct domination” (Quaderni 2010). In this passage, he also argues that hegemonic activity must take place before the gaining of power on the part of a political movement or party. It is not enough to count on “the material force that power bestows” in order to exert an effective leadership (2011). The “brilliant resolution” of this achievement of hegemonic power on the part of the Italian Moderate Party at the head of the struggle for Italian unification, meant that the Risorgimento was a revolution without a revolution, in other words, a “passive revolution” (Quaderni 2011).11 At other times, however, Gramsci identifies hegemony as a combination of force and consensus, which constitutes the “normal” exercise of hegemony in classic parliamentary regimes. It is a combination of force and consensus that balance each other out in various ways, without letting force have the upper hand over consensus, but on the contrary trying to make it appear as if force is supported by the consensus of the majority, expressed by the so-called medium of public opinion—newspapers and associations—which therefore, in certain situations, are artificially multiplied. (Quaderni 1638)

64

Neelam Srivastava

This passage obviously contains the more negative connotations of hegemony. Interestingly, hegemony in the capitalist countries is described by Fanon, though not in so many words, as juxtaposed to the direct domination of colonial rule. The “language of pure violence” of the settler is a form of domination without hegemony, as opposed to the creation of consensus, through education, “the teaching of moral reflexes,” “aesthetic forms of respect for the status quo,” in the colonizing country. “In capitalist countries a multitude of sermonizers, counselors and ‘confusion-mongerers’ intervene between the exploited and the authorities” (Wretched 4). On the other hand, in the colony, the policeman and the soldier act as go-betweens. “The agent does not alleviate oppression or mask domination. He displays and demonstrates them with the clear conscience of the law-enforcer, and brings violence into the homes and minds of the colonized subject” (4). As Ato Sekyi-Otu comments, “There is here no mediation of opposition by an appeal to a shared community and a common humanity. If hegemony is precisely such a mediation, then the colonial regime is indeed the order of immediacy, one in which ‘the language of pure violence’ is conspicuous by its ‘immediate presence’” (86). Padmore and Fanon through their work and thought can be seen as activists of an anti-colonial counter-hegemony, or in other words, of a positive Gramscian notion of hegemony as establishing the dominance of the subaltern classes against the dominant forces of that particular society. But as already mentioned, they were both acutely aware of the problems in communication between the intellectuals and the masses in anti-colonial struggle, and they sought to bridge that gap in various ways. The central question, therefore, was for the native intellectual to create a form of hegemony that tied him organically to the colonized masses, expressing their political interests and socio-economic needs. This is also the fundamental question that Gramsci asks of intellectuals: whether they have a “paternalistic” attitude toward the proletariat, or whether they believe themselves to be an “organic expression” of them. “Do they have a ‘servile’ attitude towards the ruling classes, or do they believe themselves to be directive, an integral part of the directive classes?” (Quaderni 2041). We could say that this question opens up the debate around the role of the black intellectual in liberation movements of the twentieth century, and in particular the reflections of George Padmore and Frantz Fanon. The Pan-Africanism of George Padmore While both men saw mass political emancipation as their common goal, arguably Padmore belongs to an earlier generation of anti-colonial and black radicals, a generation that Fanon savagely critiques in The Wretched of the Earth, for being too removed from the people whose interests they were supposed to represent. As I will argue later, Fanon’s book was as much

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

65

an attack on the pacifi st Pan-Africanism of Senghor and Nkrumah as it was on European colonialism.12 Thus Fanon’s particular elaboration of the notion of hegemony and the native intellectual must be understood against the backdrop of Pan-Africanism and its history. For this reason, I will fi rst proceed to analyze Padmore’s seminal work, Pan-Africanism or Communism?, fi rst published in 1956. I focus mainly on this text as a form of “subalternist history,” which places the black subject fi rmly at the center of his own historical development. In this text, Padmore provides a masterful account of black nationalism and anti-colonial movements, beginning with the “Back to Africa” movements of the early nineteenth century through to the most recent events of Pan-Africanism. The book was the culmination of Padmore’s decades-long polemic with, and aversion to, Communism. He had been expelled from the Comintern in 1934, but in reality it was a case of mutual disgust; Padmore was thoroughly disillusioned with the way in which the Communist Party had let down burgeoning anti-colonial movements in Africa and elsewhere, and this book constituted his attempt to showcase Pan-Africanism as a political theory and praxis that was distinct and autonomous from Western political thought. His position on Communism was echoed by Aimé Césaire’s “Letter to M. Thorez,” also published in 1956, in which he explained his reasons for leaving the French Communist Party. As Césaire says in his letter, “What I want is for Marxism and communism to be placed at the service of the Negro peoples, and not the Negro peoples at the service of Marxism and communism” (156). In part, the problem of tackling a study of the growth of Pan-Africanism was where to start. Padmore began by focusing on the birth of Liberia and Sierra Leone, both founded to host emancipated American slaves. Pan-Africanism, which Padmore also calls “African nationalism,” emerges from Padmore’s account as a unique hybrid of nationalism and race consciousness. One detects a certain slippage in the ways in which Padmore uses this term. The ambiguities surrounding its meaning are partly due to the fact that the African diaspora did not have the possibility to make territorial claims on any physical region of Africa, with the possible exception of Ethiopia, and of course the extant states of Liberia and Sierra Leone. Thus the hybridity of Pan-Africanism as a political concept derives from its birth in the forced diaspora of slavery and in land dispossession. Padmore also sets Pan-Africanism up as an oppositional political idea to both capitalism and communism. Obviously, his was very much a Cold War book in the sense that it sought to affi rm the position of non-alignment, which many recently decolonized states embraced. “At the moment,” he says writing in 1956, none of the African independence movements is influenced by Communism. Indeed this book will show that the struggles of Africans and peoples of African descent began with their endeavours to establish a

66

Neelam Srivastava “National Home” on the West African coast nearly a century before Communist Russia emerged as a power in world politics. (xiii)

Padmore’s construction of an autonomous political subjectivity for Africans (whether diasporic or native) is not only anti-colonial; by identifying a second ideological enemy, “Communism,” he further develops this subjectivity as non-aligned, and contributes to an emerging discourse of “Third-Worldism” (also known as Tiers-mondisme in French, or Terzomondismo in Italian), which originated precisely in the years of decolonization.13 In the course of the book, Padmore offers a very rich account of major players in the foundation of Pan-Africanism, and illuminates the theoretical debates and dissent that took place among the most well-known representatives of the movement. Throughout, we get the sense that Padmore assigns value to the role of race as a tool of mass political mobilization, but that it exists ultimately in order to be superseded. While recognizing the enormous popular appeal of Marcus Garvey (apparently his organization, the Universal Negro Improvement Association, boasted 6 million members by 1923), he also pinpoints the causes of his eventual downfall: his excessive racialism. Coming as he did from Jamaica, where the degree of racial mixture with white blood determined a black person’s position in society (as it did in Martinique), Garvey took a radical stance by rejecting any alliances with mixed-race activists and intellectuals in the US, seeing them as sellouts and middle-class yes-men. Garvey thus alienated the sympathies of many black leaders, and problematically allied himself with members of the Ku Klux Klan who supported his “Back to Africa Movement” and his idea of racial purity (67). Garvey was also a passionate advocate of capitalism: “Why should not Africa give to the world its black Rockefeller, Rothschild and Henry Ford?” (Garvey quoted in Padmore, 83). Padmore ultimately recognizes, however, that Garvey “was one of the greatest Negroes since Emancipation, a visionary who inspired his race” (82). Gramsci himself might have had Marcus Garvey and W. E. B. Du Bois in mind when he commented on “the formation of a surprising number of negro intellectuals who absorb American culture and technology” (SPNB 21). In this very interesting passage, Gramsci relates the role of the intellectual not only to his nation (as he tends to do in this section of the Notebooks), but to his race, hypothesizing a future leading role for African American intellectuals at the head of a cultural and political revolution in Africa. Gramsci, speaking of Africa in frankly racist terms that perhaps derived from the extant colonialist mindset of the time, felt that these African American intellectuals could exert an indirect, or even a direct influence on the “backward masses in Africa” (SPNB 21). But he also mentions Garvey’s “Back to Africa” movement as a second possibility for the influence black American intellectuals could have on Africans:

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

67

That the struggle for the unification of the American people should intensify in such a way as to provoke a negro exodus and the return to Africa of the most independent and energetic intellectual elements, the ones, in other words, who would be least inclined to submit to some possible future legislation that was even more humiliating than are the present widespread social customs. (SPNB 21) For him, this development would lead to two fundamental questions on the consequences of this movement. The fi rst would be a question of a linguistic nature: would English be the lingua franca of emancipated Africans, thanks to the leadership role undertaken by African American intellectuals? The second question, more far-reaching and interesting for the study of Pan-Africanism as a movement that could foster its own organic intellectuals, concerned the possibility of African nationalism. He asked whether “this intellectual stratum could have sufficient assimilating and organizing capacity to give a ‘national’ character to the present primitive sentiment of being a despised race, thus giving the African continent a mythic function as the common fatherland of all the negro peoples?” (SPNB 21). This question aligns Gramsci’s thought with that of other PanAfricanists such as Padmore who advocated African nationalism as a unifying framework for black liberation struggles, and echoed widely held beliefs about Africa as an imaginary homeland for black diasporic peoples. Gramsci’s question also links this nationalism to concrete territorial claims on Africa that began to be made in the second and third decades of the twentieth century. But the most fascinating reflections come at the end of this passage. Gramsci fi nds that the national and racial spirit of “American negroes” is negative rather than positive, “one which is a product of the struggle carried on by the whites in order to isolate and depress them” (SPNB 21). He then links black nationalism to Zionism: “Liberia, already Americanized and with English as its official language, could become the Zion of American negroes, with a tendency to set itself up as an African Piedmont” (21). There are two observations to be made about this passage. First, Gramsci’s obvious referent here is Marcus Garvey and his “Black Zionist” movement. Second, he reads black nationalist struggles in terms of Italian history; he sees the potential role of Liberia as the leader of Africa in analogy to the role played by the state of Piedmont in leading Italy to independence and unification during the Risorgimento. It is clear then that Gramsci conceived of these prominent black intellectuals as organic; but not so much to class or nation, as to race. But Padmore, writing in 1956, could draw more long-sighted historical conclusions on the failures of Garveyism. His great hero is W. E. B. Du Bois, who was the fi rst to conceive of African nationalism as a form of self-determination, individual liberty and democratic socialism (84). Throughout the book, Padmore envisaged anti-colonial struggle along constitutional and

68

Neelam Srivastava

nonviolent agitation, using the role of the free press and initiating talks with government officials. Padmore thus belongs to a different generation of black radicals from Fanon. He had a great belief in the British parliamentary system; the problem for him lay with the fact that British colonial administrations were loath to speed up the process of self-government that so many African colonies aspired to. He concludes then, “As the British never laid down a time limit for the working out of this process, the realization of independence depends on the colonial peoples themselves” (170). This political position, tending towards accommodation and dialogue with the colonial powers, can be seen to align Padmore with a more elitist understanding of black politics, and begs the question to what extent he really was an organic intellectual. Toward the end of his life, he became Personal Advisor to Nkrumah in the newly formed state of Ghana (Hooker 132ff). Azinna Nwafor, in an even-handed preface to Pan-Africanism or Communism?, argues that Pan-Africanism strived to preserve the status quo of the black political elites and did not serve the interests of the African colonized masses. On the contrary, Pan-Africanists had chosen a cooperationist, nonviolent form of anti-colonial action that would ensure the extension of British interests in Africa, without direct colonial domination. Nwafor’s words recall the savage attacks of Fanon on the nonviolent methods of Pan-African socialism in his most famous essay “Concerning Violence.”14 But the Fifth Pan-African Congress held in Manchester in 1945 represented a turning point, in many ways, for the movement. Padmore indicates that it seemed to signal a shift in policy from elite to more inclusive forms of Pan-Africanism, with representation drawn from trade unions and grassroots political organizations: A new militant leadership was reflected, closely linked with the popular movements in the home lands. Earlier Congresses had centred around a small intellectual élite. Now there was expression of a mass movement intimately identified with the under-privileged sections of the coloured colonial populations. (Padmore 139) By emphasizing the more popular forms of political participation in the Fifth Congress, Padmore may have been responding to critics who accused PanAfricanism of elitism. Padmore was acutely aware of the need to involve the wider popular movements in political participation and representation. He called this the “new phase” of Pan-Africanism, which coincided with concrete political action on the ground and a closer connection to grassroots anti-colonial activists. In words that parallel Gramsci’s emphasis on organization, Padmore observed that the effectiveness of this new phase of Positive Action “depended on the degree to which the African people were organized. Without the active support of the common people, the intellectuals remain isolated and ineffectual” (149). The spirit of the Fifth Congress of

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

69

Pan-Africanism was embodied in its “Declaration to the Colonial People,” “which stressed the importance of forming a united front between the intellectuals, workers and farmers in the struggle against Colonialism” (149). These resolutions were actively taken up by radical and workers’ grassroots movements in Africa, such as the All-African Trade Union Federation.15 Padmore was part of a generation of black radicals, including T. Ras Makonnen, C. L. R. James, Harold Moody and Henry Sylvester Williams, who had fi rst embraced Marxism while in Britain, but had subsequently distanced themselves from it. Robinson argues that their period of “initiation” in the metropole was necessary for their anti-imperialist project to come to political maturation. Confronted by the duality of “the two Englands—the England of the colonies and that of the metropolis”—they developed their own autonomous brand of anti-colonial politics (Robinson 261). Padmore and others also greatly appreciated the freedom of association and possibilities for dissemination of anti-colonial material in Britain; “despite [his] vigorous opposition to British imperialism, he shared Makonnen’s enthusiasm for the metropole” (Robinson 263). Padmore’s radicalism reflected the comparative gaze of the colonized intellectual, whose knowledge of the differences between colony and metropole made him see more clearly how double standards were applied to British and native subjects. Nwafor’s preface to Pan-Africanism or Communism? seems to imply that Padmore was less “advanced” than Fanon, who had a more acute sense of the failures of the black political intelligentsia towards the colonized masses of Africa. This suggests that this black intelligentsia didn’t have such a strong hegemonic presence among the masses, and perhaps failed to develop and cultivate its own influence sufficiently. However, we should not forget that Padmore’s magisterial oeuvre produced one of the most authoritative histories of black political and liberationist movements available at the time; he was an erudite and committed scholar of this history. Carol Polsgrove reminds us that Padmore’s successful publication of his extensive writings was an achievement in and of itself. He and other anti-colonial writers of the time “did not control the discursive machinery that defi ned them as powerless and undeserving of power. Thus, in producing a book at all with the expectation of publication, they challenged the status quo and their low place in it” (7). “On National Culture” Pan-Africanism or Communism? does for Pan-Africanism what Jawaharlal Nehru’s The Discovery of India (1946) did for Indian historiography in the period of decolonization: it challenged the colonial monopoly on the historical narrative of the colonized subject, and placed this subject at the centre of his own history. Moreover, Padmore’s critique of Communism was very farreaching and very necessary; he foreshadowed Robinson’s statement that we

70

Neelam Srivastava

cannot understand black radicalism as a mere variant of Western radicalism whose proponents happen to be black. However, what we notice is Padmore’s almost exclusive preoccupation with the political aspects of Pan-Africanism. We know that his disgust with Communism stemmed from his realization that its support for anti-colonial movements was far from disinterested, and that racial solidarity was a key factor in creating Pan-Africanism as an autonomous movement. But as we turn to Fanon, we see that among the black radicalists, he was the one who most extensively theorized the role of culture in anti-colonial movements. In the Gramscian spirit, the focus on culture cannot be divorced from that of political engagement. Fanon’s “black Marxism” in The Wretched of the Earth, by incorporating a materialist focus on culture as part of its anti-colonial project, can also be said to have constituted the real future of Marxism in the postwar years. The great innovation of black/Third Worldist Marxism was the insight that black, colonized, African revolutionary culture “implied . . . that bourgeois culture and thought and ideology were irrelevant to the development of revolutionary consciousness among Black and other Third World peoples. It broke with the evolutionist chain in, the closed dialectic of, historical materialism” (Robinson 275). Quite clearly, then, what Padmore’s brand of Pan-Africanism may not have achieved was the establishment of a successful counter-hegemony that combined political leadership with cultural decolonization. If establishing hegemony meant affi rming the agency of the political subject over the forces of history, then we can see how later theorists of Third-Worldism, such as Amilcar Cabral and Frantz Fanon, pinpointed much more clearly the necessary nexus between hegemony, political leadership and an organic connection with the culture of the colonized. Cabral, like Padmore, took exception to Marxism for its doctrinal inflexibility in analyzing Third World struggles. The African peasants and nomadic communities were not outside history, as orthodox Marxism would imply, simply because they did not correspond to the Marxist notion of the “proletariat.” On the contrary, these two thinkers were more than able to bring about revolution, and take agency for their own history (Cabral 77ff). Fanon and Cabral were critical of Pan-Africanism as kowtowing too heavily to colonial interests and to the neo-colonial elites. At the same time, they continued the innovative and creative take on Marxism begun by Padmore, C. L. R. James, and others, and sought to infuse it with their own experience of Third World anti-colonial struggles. But most importantly, Fanon developed an analogous project to Gramsci in his reworking of MarxismLeninism, assigning a central role to the revalorization of native culture on the part of the colonized/native intellectual. We shall explore below the links between Fanon’s passionate attack on the colonized intellectual’s lingering cultural ties with Europe, on the one hand, and Gramsci’s indictment of the Italian cosmopolitan intellectual, and his lack of connection with nationalpopular culture of the Italian masses, on the other. Both identify this lack of

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

71

organicity as a fundamental political weakness that poses a real risk to the success of the socialist revolution. Gramsci’s cosmopolitan intellectual, as we have seen, was unable to or uninterested in building a popular-national culture for Italy that drew on the lived experience of the people, and was deracinated from the social class that he was meant to represent. Fanon’s “colonized” intellectual, with his ties to Europe, was deracinated from his race. For both, then, identity emerges as a problem. But both Fanon and Gramsci were concerned with the formation of a new intellectual. Fanon in particular develops his ideas about the native intellectual in relationship to his idea of a new humanism. Fanon and Gramsci’s writing displays some striking stylistic similarities: like Gramsci, Fanon mixed political analysis with literary and cultural criticism. This multidisciplinary form of writing suggests an emphasis on culture and politics together. Fanon dedicates the central part of the book to an analysis of the “intellectuel colonisé.” Constance Farrington’s translation of The Wretched of the Earth seems to have overlooked the wider meaning of Fanon’s choice of term here, by rendering it as the “native intellectual.” But it is surely more accurate to speak here of “colonized intellectual” (in line with Richard Philcox’s more recent translation), where the defi ning condition is not so much race or ethnicity, but colonialism. A translation of Fanon’s phrase as “colonized intellectual” renders much more clearly the transformation that this figure must undergo in order to become an organic intellectual, and also gestures towards the possibility of transcending race. Indeed, the “intellectuel colonisé” is someone who must abandon his Europeanized education, but also any attachment to a racialist, essentialist identity (à la Négritude). Constructing a real, authentic and vital national culture means eliminating colonialism from one’s mental and psychological makeup through the war of liberation: “After the struggle is over, there is not only the demise of colonialism, but also the demise of the colonized” (Wretched 178). The colonized intellectual will no longer exist in a postcolonial future in which the political and psychological effects of oppression no longer exist, and will be replaced by a “new humanity” (Wretched 178). In order for this new humanity to be free of the “cultural indecisiveness” that plagues many newly independent countries, it must be entirely supported by the will and concerted efforts of the people. Fanon emphasizes inventiveness, not a return to tradition, as constitutive of a truly decolonized national culture (179). For Fanon, as for Gramsci, “authenticity” does not consist of tradition. Négritude’s essentialist conception of blackness “fi nds its fi rst limitation” in the fact that racial identity is historically constructed (Wretched 154), as Fanon had already stated in Black Skin, White Masks. The problems that Richard Wright or Langston Hughes had to face were very different from those of Léopold Senghor and Jomo Kenyatta. Here Fanon was referring to the debate between Wright and Senghor, which took place

72

Neelam Srivastava

at the First World Congress of Black Writers and Artists in 1956. Wright felt Négritude represented an exclusionary cultural approach that didn’t take into consideration Black Americans’ economic and social conditions (Macey 286). Interestingly, Gramsci was more prescient than Senghor in recognizing the impact that the advanced industrialization of America would have in shaping the responses of African American intellectuals, as I have discussed earlier. At the same time, however, the colonized intellectual must immerse himself in the native culture in order not to become deracinated. If this tearing away from colonial culture is not accomplished, the result will be “individuals without an anchorage, without borders, colorless, stateless, rootless—a body of angels” (Fanon, Wretched 155). This last figure resembles Gramsci’s cosmopolitan intellectual and his responsibility in failing to create an organic form of literature for the nation. In a note entitled “The non popular-national character of Italian literature,” he speaks of a historically determined separation between intellectuals and nation . . . a fragmentation that is a consequence of their separation from the people-nation and of the fact that the emotive “content” of art, the cultural world, is disconnected from the deep currents of national-popular life, which itself remains fragmented and without expression. Every intellectual movement becomes or returns to being national if a “going to the people” has taken place . . . Even if one has to begin by writing “serial novels” and sentimental poetry, without a period of going to the people there can be no Renaissance and no national literature. (Prison Notebooks 3: 319; my translation in italics) This passage by Gramsci emphasizes the importance of “going to the people” (“andata al popolo”) in order to recuperate the lost ties to native culture, a sentiment echoed in Fanon’s account of the “colonized literature,” or littérature colonisée (Wretched 150). Gramsci also indicates that there are stages in this approach to native culture, and that one might have to begin by writing avowedly popular novels and “versi da melodramma,” melodramatic, sentimental verse. This “stagist” idea of a return to, and recuperation of, native literature is also present in Fanon’s outline of the three phases (“un panorama en trois temps”) in the evolution of the colonized writer of fiction (écrivain colonisé). His emphasis on culture and literature in this essay was due to the fact that Fanon delivered part of it at the Second Congress of Black Writers and Artists in Rome in 1959. Richard Wright’s perception of the limits of Négritude at the First Congress prepared the ground for Fanon’s impassioned attack in “On National Culture.” Fanon also suggested that the nativist celebration of African culture went hand in hand with the political quietism and compromise of African bourgeois nationalists towards the excolonial powers. The priorities of the Second Congress were also different

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

73

from the fi rst one; rather than Négritude, the focus was now on the responsibility of the black intellectual. For Fanon, the fi rst phase in the evolution of the colonized intellectual is the period of assimilation, in which the colonized writer adheres entirely to the literature of the metropole in terms of style and trends, and produces derivative models from the West. The second phase, which Fanon defi nes as the “period of remembrance,” is a result of the colonized plunging back into his own culture, and attempting to remember the folklore and traditions that he had cast aside in his period of Westernization. But all he can do, at this stage, is remember, because he is not integrated into his own people and has only external relations to them (Les damnés de la terre, 268). This detached and sentimental memorialization is profoundly reminiscent of Gramsci’s Italian cosmopolitan intellectual, who unconsciously adopts a paternalistic attitude towards national-popular culture. But then the third period begins, and here Fanon connects a revolutionary approach to culture with national struggle. He defi nes the literary production of this period as a “combat literature,” a revolutionary literature, which for him becomes synonymous with national literature (Wretched 159). It is here, however, that Fanon issues a warning to the colonized intellectual: he must be wary of the methods he uses in his cultural operation. Fanon uses terms that are strikingly similar to Gramsci’s: the “going to the people” that Gramsci saw as key to the construction of a national-popular literature, is rendered as the intellectual “returning to his people” (Wretched 160, “qui revient à son peuple” in the original French, 269). The colonized intellectual must be wary of the literary techniques and language that he uses for writing a new national literature, as he runs the risk of exoticizing the very culture and society he wishes to represent most faithfully and passionately. At all costs, he must avoid acting like a foreigner, and he must go beyond a mere superficial relationship to the constantly changing cultural parameters of the people in the revolution. The most innovative aspect of Fanon’s thought in these passages is his understanding of the way in which national liberation struggles utterly transform the culture of the colonized. Just like Gramsci, Fanon realized that national culture is not merely a recuperative operation. There is no hidden, ancient essence of the people that the intellectual must tap in order to produce national culture. On the contrary, Fanon stresses how the revolution is transforming the culture of the people in its very making. To echo Cabral, the people make their own history, but they also, constantly make their own culture: “a dense, subterranean life in perpetual renewal” (Wretched 160). Fanon here makes an absolutely fundamental juxtaposition: culture versus custom. “Culture has never the translucency of custom. In its essence, it is the very opposite of custom, which is always the deterioration of culture” (Wretched 160). Fanon’s stark rejoinder to the proponents of Négritude (and by extension, Pan-Africanism) is never more evident than in this passage. Brilliantly,

74

Neelam Srivastava

Fanon rejects this cultural movement as containing all the perils associated with nativism, including conservative forms of cultural revivalism and the stolid defense of “native customs” against a true liberation of the indigenous people from both colonial and pre-colonial oppression. The colonized intellectual must avoid being hypnotized by the “mummified fragments” of native culture, which are static and outworn. Fanon identifies true national culture as being forged in the smithy of the revolution: “When a people support an armed or even political struggle against a merciless colonialism, tradition changes meaning . . . Traditions in an underdeveloped country undergoing armed struggle are fundamentally unstable and crisscrossed by centrifugal forces” (Wretched 160). The foundations of popular national culture are to be found in the lived experience of anti-colonial revolution. Fanon underlines that the people’s culture has not remained static, thanks to modern techniques of information, language and dress that have dialectically reorganized the “mind of the people” and that the traditions which remained intact during the colonial period are now undergoing extremely radical changes (Wretched 160). Though Fanon is arguing that narratives of radical social and cultural change do not have to be narratives of “progress” in the Western sense, unconsciously he may be bringing a “modernizing” perspective to his discussion here, at least in part. The colonized intellectual must avoid folklore, custom, outmoded examples of native culture; rather, he must realize that “national truth is fi rst and foremost the national reality” (Wretched 161). Fanon advocates an almost telepathic, alchemistic connection between the intellectual and the popular culture of the nation in flux: “It is not enough to be reunited with the people in a past where they no longer exist. We must rather reunite with them in their recent counter move which will suddenly call everything into question”; it is in this “zone of hidden fluctuation where the people can be found” (Wretched 163) (the French original has “ce lieu de déséquilibre occulte,” 273). Here again we fi nd a parallel with Gramsci’s dynamic “andata al popolo,” the intellectual going to the people, in enhanced and poeticized form, set against the backdrop of the anti-colonial struggle. It is not clear whether the intellectual would then “fuse” with the people or remain in some senses distinct from it. But it seems like Fanon had the former in mind. He uses the verb “revenir” to indicate the intellectual’s reconnection with his own culture, that of the people. His organic relationship to the people can be linked to Gramsci’s idea that we must understand the role of intellectuals as merely a specialization of a quality inherent to all mankind: “Non-intellectuals do not exist” (SPNB 9). The intellectual embodies in an intensified form what all the people possess and know already. Fanon’s rejection of custom and celebration of national culture as inherently dynamic and shifting reveals the intellectual’s return to the “people” as a careful balancing act. Fanon’s very choice of lexicon here is also eerily reminiscent of Gramsci’s complex treatment of “folklore” in the Notebooks. He

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

75

also outlines two different types of folklore, or “popular religion” as he also calls it, or rather he identifies different strata that constitute it: The fossilized strata that reflect past conditions of life, and thus [are] conservative and reactionary, and those that consist of a series of innovations, often creative and progressive, spontaneously determined by forms and conditions of life in the process of developing, and which contradict, or are merely different from, the morality of the leading groups. (Quaderni 2313) Gramsci rejects the received notion of folklore as picturesque and quaint, and instead emphasizes the active popular spirit inherent in it, which is clearly distinct from that of the traditional intellectuals. Giovanni Mimmo Boninelli comments that folklore in Gramsci has these two sides to it: on the one hand, it has the negative connotations of being regressive, conservative and passive. On the other hand, however, it “spontaneously produces positive, progressive, innovative fragments, which are active among those sectors of the population which are able to express their own ‘organic intellectuals’” (322). Boninelli thus identifies in Gramsci a link between the producers of an active and innovative folklore, and the creation of organic intellectuals, a position that is echoed by Fanon’s insistence that the colonized intellectual gain access to that “zone of hidden fluctuation” that is the true repository of national culture: a dynamic, rather than passive understanding of this culture. It is only through an active revalorization of folklore that the organic intellectual can act in order to counter-act the social hegemony and consensus that govern that particular society (Boninelli 322). For Fanon, as for Gramsci then, the intellectual’s true comprehension of the “people’s culture” consists in demystifying it. Demystification is necessary in the case of folklore, which is otherwise seen in a rather Orientalist light, a form of self-exoticization and self-distancing. The real point of connection here between Gramsci and Fanon is that both thinkers are addressing the intellectuals of the same nation to which the people belong. In other words, the process of reconnection and demystification must begin at home, a very difficult operation that must discard most, if not all, of the previous intellectual and cultural education received at the hands of the metropole. As Fanon says, “A national culture is no folklore where an abstract populism is convinced it has uncovered the popular truth” (Wretched 168). Moreover, the birth of a true national literature signifies a change in readership: whereas before the colonized writer produced work for the European oppressor, now he “gradually switches over to addressing himself to his own people. It is only from this point onward that one can speak of a national literature” (Wretched 173). Gramsci also argued that the preference of Italian readers for foreign popular fiction, rather than homegrown middlebrow authors, was the most evident proof of a disconnect between the writers and the public in

76

Neelam Srivastava

Italy. Italians considered foreign literature more relevant and interesting to them than their own national literature. This fact leads Gramsci to another conclusion: that the literature of a people can come from a different national context, in other words, a people can be subject to the intellectual and moral hegemony of other peoples. Thus the very taste of a national readership is intimately linked to issues of cultural, and thus political hegemony (Letteratura e vita nazionale 98). Fanon gives some examples in the text of what he means by an authentic national literature, though he is remarkably vague as to which national context he is referring to. His only example of “combat literature” is from the Guinean poet Keita Fodeba, and he also briefly mentions the evolution of jazz. However Macey, in his excellent discussion of Fanon’s essay, offers some suggestions of what Fanon may have had in mind. Kateb Yacine, Mouloud Feraoun and Assia Djebar are some of the Algerian writers who began to represent the Algerian war in fiction and poetry in new and experimental ways (Macey 382ff). The use of vernacular languages or popular theatre may also have been a way for colonized writers to reach a wider audience, as colonialism had tended to defi ne the potential linguistic audience for culture through its exclusive focus on literature in French, often consigning Algerian production to “folklore.” Fanon, throughout the essay, constantly insists that only the fight for nationhood can “unlock” culture; it is the “material matrix on the basis of which culture becomes possible” (my own translation, 280 in the French original). National Algerian culture, for example, gains consistency in the course of the struggle, in the myriad sites of resistance: in front of the guillotine, in prison, in every French outpost that is captured and destroyed. Thus it is the fight for national liberation that opens to national culture “the doors of creation” (Wretched 197). In short, the war of liberation itself is an expression of culture. “We believe the conscious, organized struggle by a colonized people in order to restore national sovereignty constitutes the greatest cultural manifestation that exists” (178). As in Gramsci, the struggle for political leadership is identified with a struggle for cultural hegemony. Fanon, like Gramsci, assigns a wide semantic field to the intellectual that extends from political activist to writer and man of culture. But his achieved fusion with the subaltern group he wishes to represent is essential for the success of the revolution. Fanon is careful to distinguish his idea of national culture from that of Négritude: “To believe one can create a black culture is to forget oddly enough that ‘Negroes’ are disappearing, since those who created them are witnessing the demise of their economic and cultural supremacy” (Wretched 169). Fanon’s dismissal of Négritude may have been linked to the fact that this movement was largely irrelevant to the Algerian situation (Macey 378). In fact, “Arab culture,” identified with that of the invading nomadic tribes from the north, was regarded as suspect by Sub-Saharan cultural theorists. Négritude is seen as static and essentialist, whereas Fanon makes it clear that

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

77

the condition of colonization is temporary, both for the colonizer and for the colonized, and it does not establish immoveable racial identities. On the contrary, the struggle for national freedom results in a tabula rasa regarding previous culture and customs; “this struggle, which aims at a fundamental redistribution of relations between men, cannot leave intact either form or substance of the people’s culture” (Wretched 178). Thus, in a typically utopian vein Fanon returns to the notion of a new humanity, which will be the end result of the anti-colonial liberation struggle. This position also signals an evolution from Black Skin, White Masks, in which Fanon had been so critical of Sartre’s defi nition of Négritude as a “racist anti-racism.” In 1953, while recognizing that black racial identity was historically constructed by the white gaze, he also felt that it was nevertheless here to stay, at least until racism existed (Bernasconi 107). In The Wretched of the Earth he is much more optimistic. The disappearance of colonialism—understood as a psycho-cultural hegemony as much as a political one—will mean the end of the colonized man, and thus possibly the end of racial difference. Where for Gramsci the new society of socialism meant the end of social classes, for Fanon it meant the end of race, and its replacement by the nation, presumably in non-ethnically exclusive terms. More realistically, Macey reminds us that after Algerian independence in 1962, the FLN established Algerian nationality on the basis of ethnicity and adherence to the Muslim religion (389). That Gramsci and Fanon’s leanings toward utopianism were born out of their conditions of exile and imprisonment is very possible. Gramsci developed his notion of the organic intellectual and his role in the creation of a national culture, in the context of fascism, imagining the rebirth of an Italian nation that would overcome the failed revolution of the Risorgimento. Fanon, on the other hand, and to a lesser extent Padmore, develop their notion of the black/colonized intellectual and his role in anti-colonial movements, in the context of colonialism, and they link it to the need to re-think colonized culture as distinct from that of the colonizer. My discussion of the intellectual in Fanon’s and Padmore’s writings has left open the question as to whether they could be considered as organic intellectuals themselves. In a way, that might lead us to ask whether Gramsci saw himself as an organic intellectual. He discussed at length the type of cultural and political work an intellectual must undertake in order to become “organic”; but did he recognize his own work and life in this set of prescriptions? Perhaps we may perceive all three thinkers along the lines of how Gramsci spoke of Niccolò Machiavelli. Gramsci found that Machiavelli combined both the pragmatic and the philosophical aspects of politics: he wasn’t only a political scientist, but a “partisan, a man of powerful passions, an active politician, who wishes to create a new balance of forces and therefore cannot help concerning himself with what ‘ought to be’” (SPNB 172). One gets the impression that Gramsci may be thinking of himself here, as someone who engages with effective reality, understood as a constantly

78

Neelam Srivastava

shifting, dynamic relation of forces, rather than something fi xed and static. Machiavelli (and possibly Gramsci, Fanon and Padmore) could be described then as “realistic” individuals— realistic even if it did not in fact become direct reality, since one cannot expect an individual to change reality but only to interpret it and to indicate the possible lines of action . . . Machiavelli never says that he has any thought or intention of himself changing reality—only of showing concretely how the historical forces ought to have acted in order to be effective. (SPNB 173) Notes 1. I would like to thank Jim House, Carolyn Pedwell, and Robert Young for their helpful and constructive comments on previous drafts of this chapter. 2. Relevant to this discussion is the way Fanon took exception to Sartre’s critique of Négritude as an “anti-racist racism,” in Black Skin, White Masks (132). Fanon strongly contested Sartre’s easy dismissal of a cultural and psychological position that “asks Blacks unilaterally to renounce the pride of their colour” (Bernasconi 108). 3. See especially Fanon’s essay “The Trials and Tribulations of National Consciousness” in The Wretched of the Earth, where he examines the betrayal of the newly liberated African masses on the part of élite middle-class nationalists, in the wake of decolonization (97–98). Paul Idahosa also discusses how Fanon and C. L. R. James tackled the difficult issue of how the black intelligentsia could effectively channel the collective experience of racism, marginalization and economic exploitation of blacks in the colonies and elsewhere. 4. Indeed, “moved by the words of the future author of The Wretched of the Earth, the conferees passed a resolution justifying violence by nationalists when violence was thrust upon them” (Polsgrove 160). 5. Generally, the Communist Party had little comprehension for the strength of cultural nationalisms in anti-colonial struggles. The CP tended to condemn these nationalist parties as expressions of petty bourgeois and landed interests. M. Thorez and Velio Spano, two Communist Party members who operated in colonial Tunisia (Thorez would eventually go on to become the leader of the French Communist Party), were scathing of the Tunisian nationalist party, Destour, which refused any alliances with the CP, and accused it of privileging their ethnic and nationalist particularisms over an alliance with the French proletariat (Mattone 58). 6. As is obvious from this discussion, the debate on the black colonized intellectual in the work of Gramsci, Padmore, and Fanon is entirely gendered. There is almost no explicit acknowledgement of the fact that the intellectual is always male in their discussions. 7. When possible, I use available English translations of the Notebooks. All other translations from Gramsci are my own. 8. In what follows, I will be using Richard Philcox’s 2004 translation of The Wretched of the Earth.

The Travels of the Organic Intellectual

79

9. See Perry Anderson’s “The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci” for a thorough discussion of the origin of the term in Russian Communism and its influence on Gramsci’s elaboration of it. As Anderson remarks, hegemony “was one of the most widely-used and familiar notions in the debates of the Russian labor movement before the October Revolution,” and lived on in the documents of the Communist International, which Gramsci was familiar with (17–18). Derek Boothman also discusses the sources of the concept of hegemony in Gramsci (2011). 10. Carol Polsgrove has an excellent discussion of Padmore’s career as a journalist in her book Ending British Rule in Africa: Writers in a Common Cause (2009). 11. The applicability of the “passive revolution” to postcolonial transfers of power has been remarked upon most famously by Partha Chatterjee in his analysis of Indian nationalist thought, Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse? 12. See Robert Young’s discussion of Fanon’s essay “On Violence” as a riposte to the compromising strategy of certain Pan-Africanists, in Postcolonialism: An Historical Introduction, and in “Fanon and the Turn to Armed Struggle in Africa,” Wasafiri 44 (Spring 2005): 33–41. 13. The French demographer and historian Alfred Sauvy is credited with coining the phrase “Tiers monde” [Third World] in an article of August 14, 1952 for L’Observateur. Sauvy locates the conceptual space of the Third World as equally oppressed by capitalism and communism, echoing Padmore’s position. 14. Unsurprisingly, Nwafor’s preface to Padmore’s book was written in 1971, when the relative failure of Pan-Africanism in decolonized African states had become very evident. 15. Opoku Agyeman traces the history of this important association, and its ultimate failure to establish a popular Pan-Africanism, in The Failure of Grassroots Pan-Africanism: The Case of the All-African Trade Union Federation (2003).

4

The Secular Alliance Gramsci, Said and the Postcolonial Question 1

Baidik Bhattacharya

The crisis of “postcolonialism” or “postcolonial theory” is well known (Loomba; Yaeger; Miguel). The curious point about this crisis is that it is never conceptualized as a singular event and is frequently understood as the corollary of a new mastercode—globalization—that supposedly subsumes the possibilities opened up by postcolonial politics in the second half of the last century (Robertson; Appadurai; Hardt and Negri; Mbembe). In a rather heuristic schematization, these descriptions can be divided into two clusters—the fi rst one argues that postcolonial politics loses its topicality because its contradictions (which were the legacies of the age of empire) are resolved through a metapolitical assemblage called globalization; and the second one proposes that postcolonial politics is no longer relevant since its possibilities have been transformed, for better or worse, under the aegis of globalization as it converts every sectoral political claim into a planetary one. Irrespective of the overall orientation of such arguments—celebratory or elegiac—there emerges a fundamental agreement across the board on the peripheral nature and inconsequence of postcolonial politics in the globalized world of today. This line of argument often synthesizes various theoretical schools and political agendas, and more often than not positions itself within a critical crevice that is designed to attend to the new and the as-yet unthought. A case in point is Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri’s prognosis of the subordination and eventual demise of the postcolonial nation-state and the rise of a new global order they call “empire”: The final link that explains the necessary subordination of the postcolonial nation-state, however, is the global order of capital. The global capitalist hierarchy that subordinates the formally sovereign nation-states within its order is fundamentally different from the colonialist and imperialist circuits of international domination. The end of colonialism is also the end of the modern world and modern regimes of rule. (Empire 134) It follows from their argument that this new form of domination demands new sociological description and political orientation. The vistas offered by

The Secular Alliance

81

postcolonial theory are not simply inadequate to address the newness of empire/globalization, but are woefully outdated. What is even more dangerous, Hardt and Negri suggest, the mutated postmodern power—“imperial sovereignty” in their words—actually thrives on the cherished ideals of postcolonial (and postmodernist) theory: “[M]odern forms of sovereignty would no longer be at issue, and the postmodernist and postcolonialist strategies that appear to be liberatory would not challenge but in fact coincide with and even unwittingly reinforce the new strategies of rule” (Empire 138). The undemanding equation between postcoloniality and the postcolonial nation-state in Hardt and Negri’s formulation is easy to detect; and this erroneous equivalence between a philosophical position and a political structure animates most accounts of the death of postcolonialism or postcolonial theory. What is much more difficult to identify, and hence much more insidious in their theorization of the contemporary, is the model of collusion they set up between such accounts of death that offer no way out from a landscape of political sterility of the contemporary world and the theoretical narratives that allegedly flourish on and celebrate such an impasse; the model is erected only to exploit the fissures of the latter, only to suggest that within the misleading will to theorize the false enemy resides the correct understanding of contemporary political order. This is most prominent in the way they theorize the new political subject of global democracy, that is, “multitude,” toward the end of their treatise. It is only through a strategic erasure of the nation-state (postcolonial and otherwise) that they can insert a further category of multitude below and behind the people; the association here, unlike other forms of associational life, is subterranean, rhizomic and unregulated. Whether in its demand for global citizenship and social wage, or whether in its aspiration for a proletarian telos and the singularity of “posse,” the global multitude can only assert itself in a space that exists beyond the territorial sovereignty of the nation-state. This space below and behind the people, as an exterior to it, enables the multitude to avoid the networks of the nation-state and further to strategize with the global structures of domination and exploitation. The esteemed principles of postcolonial theory like ambiguity, hybridity, marginalization, fragmentation, and so on, are unable to track this new form of social life; they are rather the tools through which the empire functions and tries to trap the radical potential of the multitude. It is not that Hardt and Negri do not recognize the considerable critical energy that went into the questioning of the nation-state in postcolonial scholarship, it is not even the case that they are blind to the fruits of non-nationalist political struggles all over the postcolonial world in the second half of the twentieth century; rather, they insist that such scholarship and political program offer limited insights into the contemporary order of things, and, as a curious afterthought, they unproblematically reduce the politics of postcoloniality to anti-colonial nationalism. In their schematic reading, the only outcome of decolonization is the state that unfailingly traps the nation within its Manichean apparatuses—“the state

82

Baidik Bhattacharya

is the poisoned gift of national liberation” (Empire 134)—and postcolonialist theorization is a rubber stamp that unimaginatively endorses this history. The empire as a global system and multitude as a possible antithesis, in other words, remain beyond the purview of postcoloniality; the initial promises of decolonization petered out rather easily. I begin with Hardt and Negri not because they are the only ones to voice such discomfort with postcolonialism, not even to suggest that theirs is the most attractive of all the available accounts, but because in many ways their critique captures and concludes a long series of attacks (e.g., Appiah; Ahmad; Dirlik; Brennan’s Wars of Position), and brings into sharp focus some of the major charges against postcolonial theory over the years. I also open this essay with their account since it gives me the perfect opportunity to revisit the influence of Antonio Gramsci on postcolonial critical thinking. The way they formulate the multitude, and the way they set it beyond the pale of the modern nation-state as a necessary precondition, one would have hoped that they would at least acknowledge similar moves in the two branches of critical thinking heavily influenced by Gramsci—cultural studies and postcolonial theory—not so much as guiding templates but as cognate theoretical maneuverings. It is indeed a curious elision given the enormous scholarship in both disciplines on the Gramscian notions of “nation-people,” “hegemony,” the “subaltern,” and “passive revolution” that has been preoccupied with the release of the “popular” from the strict conscription of the nation, and that has been relentless in probing the coercive mechanism of the modern nation-state. The suggestive split within the nation-people in Gramsci’s work, and its re-appropriation within specific postcolonial locations, indeed can be reworked to theorize an alternative genealogy of postcolonial critical thinking and its relationship with the contemporary phase of globalization. In this chapter I offer a set of postcolonial speculations through the works of Edward W. Said and Gramsci to break free of weary terms of the debate, and also to suggest that postcolonial theory at its foundation and genealogy offers alternative ways to think about the philosophical questions raised by the contemporary phase of globalization. The arguments here are speculative in nature not because they lack conviction, rather because they take globalization as an unfolding saga and engage with it from a position of contingency. This location of my arguments—that is, postcolonial and inglobalization—I hope would lend them the spirit of, to quote one of Gramsci’s favorite phrases from Marx, theory as “material force” (SPNB 333) as they engage with an unfi nished structure and become part of a continuous and oppositional critique of it.2 The speculative theories I propose here are based on Said and Gramsci; the link between the two is obvious. Said has repeatedly cited Gramsci as one of the chief intellectual influences on his work, so much so that Mustapha Marrouchi describes Gramsci as Said’s maître à penser (39). My own reading here avoids the obvious connections between the two, or the popular concepts on which they have been discussed together.

The Secular Alliance

83

Rather, in this chapter I follow two non-national and secular possibilities in their respective works, and I try to show how at unexpected junctures they often come together to think of a critical tradition whose vocation is worldly as well as global. The point is worth repeating since despite their repeated critique of the nation-form, the political discussion of Gramsci and Said have often been reduced to two failures of the national project—Italy and Palestine, respectively—and they have been portrayed as apostles of failed nationalities. In the following pages I do not try to summarize the globalization debate through these two authors; rather I try to present possibilities in their writing that may open up new horizons for the debate. Trajectories of the Secular The influence of Gramsci has been felt most conspicuously in two disciplines—literary studies and history—and with good reason. I am not simply referring to the institutionalization of postcolonial theory in the Anglo-American academia in the 1980s primarily through these two departments; rather I am much more concerned here about the way postcolonial theory engaged with the constitutive principles of such disciplines. The complicity between these two disciplines, on the one hand, and the course of nation formation in eighteenth- and nineteenth-century Europe, on the other, is a well-known story. Implicit in this co-production was the principle of their mutual corroboration—the textual and the territorial did not simply coincide but they were meant to stand in for each other. The result is that literatures and histories since the nineteenth century have most prominently been closed off by national boundaries and territorial protocols. Postcolonial theory made two important inroads in this edifice and challenged the economy of this construction—fi rst, Edward Said’s Orientalism (1978) and the works of the Subaltern Studies historians in the 1980s exposed a further layer of collusion between such developments in Europe and its imperial expansion, especially the way the power–knowledge nexus as well as the material forces of this European venture shaped the lifeworlds and livelihoods in the overseas colonies. A third voice was soon added to this ensemble in the 1980s—that of Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak—who renovated the project of the Subaltern historiography (Chatterjee) and also transformed the ways scholars engaged with the questions of coloniality/postcoloniality. And second, postcolonial theory, which was largely inspired by these early interventions, also turned its gaze to the colonial and postcolonial locations to reinterpret them within a counter-narrative to European modes of knowledge production. In the 1980s and 1990s these revisionist readings considerably reconfigured the various disciplines of knowledge and gave rise to an ethico-political field known as postcolonial studies or simply as postcolonial theory. The result of this dual intervention has been quite dramatic at a global scale; as Susie O’Brien and Imre Szeman summarize it,

84

Baidik Bhattacharya Though there is no shortage of criticism of postcolonial studies—even or especially from within its own ranks—no other critical practice has foregrounded the links between cultural forms and geopolitics to the degree that postcolonial studies has over the past four decades. No other materialist practice has considered the modalities of race, nation, gender, and ethnicity, in relationship to the global activity of hegemonic cultural, political, and economic forces, with the degrees of complexity and sophistication that have come to be associated with the best work in the field. Before postcolonial studies, Western scholarship was an embarrassment. (606)

History and literature played vital roles in such postcolonial and revisionist projects, and Gramsci’s insights featured prominently. Let me begin with Said’s elaboration on Gramsci in Orientalism, and how this can be used as a thread through his critical oeuvre, most notably in his formulation of “secular criticism” in the introduction to The World, the Text, and the Critic.3 It is important to note that Said invokes Gramsci at two crucial junctures in Orientalism—fi rst to explain the stability of Orientalism (where he also names Michel Foucault and Raymond Williams as possible theoretical allies) and second to point out his own personal stakes in the project. Said’s debt in the fi rst case is quite specific, as he invokes the familiar Gramscian concept of “hegemony” to account for the “durability and strength” of Orientalism. He also acknowledges that hegemony is “an indispensable concept for any understanding of cultural life in the industrial West” (Said, Orientalism 7). Alongside this quite impersonal working of cultural hegemony Said proposes his own investment in the project through Gramsci by echoing the latter’s point that the “starting-point of critical elaboration is the consciousness of what one really is, and is ‘knowing thyself’ as a product of the historical process to date, which has deposited in you an infi nity of traces, without leaving an inventory”; the critical project for him is, as also was with Gramsci, “to compile such an inventory.” Orientalism, Said suggests, is such an inventory of his own history as a displaced “Oriental” subject: Much of the personal investment in this study derives from my awareness of being an “Oriental” as a child growing up in two British colonies . . . In many ways my study of Orientalism has been an attempt to inventory the traces upon me, the Oriental subject, of the culture whose domination has been so powerful a factor in the life of all Orientals. (Said, Orientalism 25) His insistence on the “cultural reality of [and] the personal involvement in having been constituted as ‘an Oriental,’” the “disheartening” life of an Arab Palestinian in the West and his resultant invisibility in the social field (Said, Orientalism 26–27), all lead to the notion of cultural domination that sustained

The Secular Alliance

85

Orientalism for the better part of its history and that remains a defi ning force for the displaced critic even in the late twentieth century. To get the full measure of Said’s formulation of cultural domination, and the way he calls upon Gramsci, let me introduce here his defi nition of culture from the introduction to The World, the Text, and the Critic; he claims that culture entails “an environment, process, and hegemony in which individuals (in their private circumstances) and their works are embedded, as well as overseen at the top by a superstructure and at the base by a whole series of methodological attitudes.” To drive his point home he further suggests that “[i]t is in culture that we can seek out the range of meanings and ideas conveyed by the phrases belonging to or in a place, being at home in a place” (8; emphasis original). Hegemony, then, is no longer an effect of cultural domination but a dimension built into cultural practices and forms; one’s relationship to cultural forms is also negotiated through the hegemonic forces that defi ne a given culture, and that further dictates the modes of belonging or otherwise. Said’s theory of “secular criticism” needs to be understood against this formulation of culture.4 Bruce Robbins has suggested that “secular” in Said’s critical vocabulary is not the antinomy to institutional religion but is an “opposing term . . . to nationalism” (26). Aamir Mufti, while retaining this lead, has also argued that one needs to be careful about such displacement of terminologies; his own view is that Said’s formulation of the “secular” has vital implications for postcolonial secularism since it is rooted in the “concern with minority culture and existence” so much so that that the condition of minority functions as “a fundamental and constitutive concern, a condition of possibility of the critical practice itself” (96). 5 While both these readings are important for my argument, and I will return to them later, here I want to pursue a somewhat different lead provided by Said’s texts, and argue that both these interpretations restrict the project of secular criticism within a frame focused solely on the nation. Whether seen as rebuttal of nationalism as belief system or as elaboration on the minority within a (postcolonial) nation-state, the secular in Said’s imagination loses its edge through its exclusive association with the nation. My suggestion is that rather than prioritizing the territorial codes of the nation, it would be much more productive if we conceptualize the operative principle in his argument as a series that comprises of concepts like place, displacement and criticism and their complex interplay in constituting modern conditions of belonging. Indeed Said makes it abundantly clear that the intimate connection between the idea of place and the protocols of a given culture must not be framed vis-à-vis the nation. Though the “readiest account of place might defi ne it as the nation,” and “in the exaggerated boundary drawn between Europe and the Orient . . . the idea of the nation, a national-cultural community as a sovereign entity and place set against other places, has its fullest realization” (Said, The World, the Text, and the Critic 8), he suggests, their assumed identity is counterproductive. Neither the everyday conception of place nor this ready qualification of

86

Baidik Bhattacharya

place-as-nation can capture the full semantic content of phrases like “at home in place;” on the contrary, if one foregrounds the primacy of the nation in understanding the workings of modern culture, one runs the risk of reproducing the “exaggerated boundaries” that marked the imperial political order. However, Said should not be taken as suggesting an unproblematic association between cultural belonging and place; I think his primary point is that culture—as highly determined “environment, process, and hegemony”— delimits the circulation of time, space and representation and thus regulates a complex system of inclusion and exclusion within a given structure loosely defi ned as place. This hegemonic process is responsible for the way cultural value is produced and distributed across the social field (leading to cultural hierarchies), and also for the way individuals are placed within the social field made of hierarchical structures. Said clearly wants to release this description from the codes mandated by nation-states and further attempts to articulate it at a global level for two reasons. First, secular criticism is aimed at specific forms of cultural domination like Orientalism that stretches across nations, and its critique, likewise, has to be rooted in non-national spaces. In his introduction to Orientalism, he clearly signposts this: For the general reader, this study deals with matters that always compel attention, all of them connected not only with Western conceptions and treatments of the Other but also with the singularly important role played by Western culture in what Vico called the world of nations. Lastly, for readers in the so-called Third World, this study proposes itself as a step towards an understanding not so much of Western politics and of the non-Western world in those politics as, of the strength of Western cultural discourse, a strength too often mistaken as merely decorative or “superstructural.” My hope is to illustrate the formidable structure of cultural domination and, specifically for formerly colonized peoples, the dangers and temptations of employing this structure upon themselves or upon others. (Said 24–25) The “dangers and temptations” of Orientalism is the cultural domination of the “world of nations,” or a world that reveres national identity and distributes it through the grids of imperial structures; Orientalism, in other words, may function in the “world of nations” but its cultural formations are not necessarily reducible to the nation. The danger for the postcolonial world—itself a supra-national territory—is precisely that it may, along with the derivative nationalist ideals, repeat this imperial formation. Mufti’s suggestion that this danger is palpable in the majority–minority relationship in postcolonial nations is a partial reading of Said (Mufti, “Auerbach in Istanbul” 109–10). The thrust of the argument clearly shows that cultural domination is not necessarily restricted within national structures and institutions and secularism in this instance must be supra-national and opposed to global

The Secular Alliance

87

cultural formations. The globality of such formations is not accidental, but guaranteed by modern imperialism. The influence of Gramsci on Said is once more palpable in the second case where he again tries to avoid the national frame. Toward the end of his introduction to The World, the Text, and the Critic he approvingly quotes Raymond Williams’ commentary with prominent Gramscian overtones that no dominant social formation can exhaust all “social experience” and thus there are always possible “space for alternative acts and alternative intentions which are not yet articulated as a social institution or even project”; once we agree with this, Said argues, then “criticism belongs in that potential space inside civil society, acting on behalf of those alternative acts and alternative intentions whose advancement is a fundamental human and intellectual obligations” (Said, The World, the Text, and the Critic 29 –30).6 If in the earlier case he advocates a move beyond the nation-state, here he revisits the Gramscian distinction between civil and political societies to situate both dominant cultural formations and its critical opposition in the former.7 This duality of criticism, that it is pitted against cultural formations that are simultaneously larger and smaller than any given national culture, produces its radical appeal—the radicalism lies in its “suspicion of totalizing concepts . . . its discontent with reified objects . . . its impatience with guilds, special interests, imperialized fiefdoms, and orthodox habits of mind” (Said, The World, the Text, and the Critic 29). In short, criticism is most effective when it is in displacement, when it is in opposition to various territorial categories and thus rendered nomadic. The exteriority of criticism indeed is the global dimension of postcolonial theory. The fi nal gloss Said provides on secular criticism, about criticism vis-à-vis what he calls “fi lial” and “affi liative” relationships, makes the point clear.8 Cultural domination, he suggests, becomes effective with the passage from the fi rst to the second, with the naturalization of affi liative bonds. Though the affi liative is initially conceived as an alternative to the fi lial—and this is a point Said charts through some of the stalwarts of modernism—the relationship, under rigorous inspection, turns out to be collusive and hegemonic. The role of the critic is not to endorse the passage between two forms of cultural association but to expose the way affi liative cultural forms become legitimized by reproducing the frame of the fi lial. The critic, in other words, is not simply a product of history, but is also a “historical and social actor”; her position is prompted not by “conformity and belonging” but by “circumstance and distinction” that produces distance and the possibility of criticism (Said, The World, the Text, and the Critic 15–24). The critic is equally situated at the cusp of the two—between the “culture to which critics are bound fi liatively” and “a method or system acquired affi liatively” (Said, The World, the Text, and the Critic 25). The displacement of criticism is a measure of the oppositional relationship that the critic can maintain with the universalist and naturalized claims of both fi lial and affi liative codes of a given culture.

88

Baidik Bhattacharya

The point is not a naive return to possibilities opened up by Enlightenment or the liberal ideals of critique, but an endeavor to expose the mechanism of cultural and systematic claims that are increasingly global. The nomadic secularism of Said is indeed a contrapuntal point to the increasing homogenization of global cultural productions. Humanism as Praxis Said’s formulation of secular criticism as a non-national and indeed global phenomenon, however, must not be taken as blind endorsement of elite cosmopolitanism. In important ways it revisits and modifies some of the key concepts in Gramsci’s Prison Notebooks in an effort to redeploy them for the postcolonial condition. The secularism he advocates is postcolonial because it is rooted in the history of displacement occasioned by quasi-religious authorities of imperialism; it is also part of a history Gramsci describes as the emergence of a modern secular “humanism.” Gramsci’s own elaboration on the possibilities of such a position is rooted in his careful reading of Italian history, and hence all the more apposite for my purpose because of the similarities between Italy and much of the colonial/postcolonial world; his starting point is the split between the national and the popular in the Italian context: One should note that in many languages, “national” and “popular” are either synonymous or nearly so (they are in Russian, in German, where völkisch has an even more intimate meaning of race, and in the Slavonic languages in general; in France the meaning of “national” already includes a more politically elaborated notion of “popular” because it is related to the concept of “sovereignty”: national sovereignty and popular sovereignty have, or had, the same value). In Italy the term “national” has an ideologically very restricted meaning, and does not in any case coincide with “popular” because in Italy the intellectuals are distant from the people, i.e. from the “nation.” They are tied instead to a caste tradition that has never been broken by a strong popular or national political movement from below. (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 208) Gramsci makes it clear that this relationship is not a natural one but the product of history—that is, in both cases where there is a perfect match between the two (as in France) and where there isn’t any (as in Italy), the phenomenon should be seen as the result of concrete historical events. In Italy the national was segregated and restricted, as its intelligentsia historically could not develop a national-popular consciousness/collective will since the Renaissance (SPNB 113, 131), and eventually failed even to unite the popular with the state. 9 In “Notes on Italian History” he observes that the chief failure of the Italian national movement in the nineteenth century was its inability to

The Secular Alliance

89

transform itself into a popular one. Whereas France in the nineteenth century could forge a genuine national-popular through both bourgeois revolution and cultural alliance, the national movement in Italy failed to extend its sphere of influence beyond a select few (SPNB 52–54). The promises of Risorgimento quickly faded into passivity (a “revolution without revolution” or “passive revolution”) because of the central failure to bring the people in its fold, and because of its inability to conceive of the national as coterminous with the popular. Gramsci identifies two reasons for this historic failure: fi rst, he points out that the “Italian bourgeoisie was incapable of uniting the people around itself, and this was the cause of its defeats and the interruptions in its development” (SPNB 53). This was most notable in the Action Party’s failure to effect a dialectical mobilization through rural classes, on the one hand, and through the intellectuals from the “middle and lower strata,” on the other (SPNB 54). In his opinion, such a dialectical move would have been critical as a safeguard against the growing influence of the Moderates, and also as a way of forging a national alliance across Italy. Along with this, the Action Party also lacked a certain Jacobinism which Gramsci describes as the “inflexible will to become the “leading” [dirigente] party” (SPNB 80); in the absence of such a will to lead, the Action Party not only failed to give birth to a Jacobin spirit (described as “audacious, dauntless” that would have resulted in something like the French revolution, but also lost control over the vast majority of the rural classes especially in the impoverished South (SPNB 84). The problem manifests itself at different moments in modern Italian history: in the “immaturity and intrinsic weakness” of the educated class in their historic failure to lead the “popular masses and develop their progressive elements” (SPNB 90); in the aftermath of the Risorgimento, especially through the rightists who “made the people-nation into an instrument, into an object” and thus “degraded it” (SPNB 90); in the complex and unequal relationship between the “countryside” and the “city” which not only reinforced the North–South divide in various combinations but even nullified the vitally important “agrarian question” under the virtual domination of the industrial North (SPNB 100–2). For my purpose here the important point is Gramsci’s tracking of this complex history through cultural artifacts, most notably narrative fiction. His point of reference is a perplexing question, that despite the huge demand for popular literature “why does the Italian public read foreign literature, popular and non-popular, instead of reading its own?” (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 209). Newspapers catered to popular taste by regularly serializing foreign and mostly French popular novels, the people seemed to enjoy old novels like Count of Monte-Cristo instead of any modern Italian novel, and the public literary discussions were imbued with foreign values and norms. The result was that the Italian people became interested in a “past that is more French than Italian”: “[T]hey know the popular figure of Henry IV better than that of Garibaldi, the Revolution of 1789 better than

90

Baidik Bhattacharya

the Risorgimento and the invectives of Victor Hugo against Napoleon III better than the invectives of Italian patriots against Metternich” (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 216). To put it another way, barring a few minor exceptions, Italian authors failed to connect with the lived worlds of the people, to fictionalize their intellectual and emotional aspirations. It is this gap between the national intelligentsia—whom Gramsci describes as “something detached, without foundation, a caste and not an articulation with organic functions of the people themselves” (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 209)—and the people that was responsible for the absence of popular literature of a national kind, something that would have been able to unite popular sentiments with artistic ingenuity. This failure, as we have seen already, is historic in nature for Gramsci and certainly not an isolated event; what is interesting to note here is that he gives it a further twist by describing the failure as the intelligentsia’s inability to develop a modern and secular “humanism”: The lay forces have failed in their historical task as educators and elaborators of the intellect and the moral awareness of the people-nation. They have been incapable of satisfying the intellectual needs of the people precisely because they have failed to represent a lay culture, because they have not known how to elaborate a modern “humanism” able to reach right to the simplest and most uneducated classes, as was necessary from the national point of view, and because they have been tied to an antiquated world, narrow, abstract, too individualistic or caste-like. French popular literature, on the other hand, which is the most widespread in Italy, does represent this modern humanism, this in its own way modern secularism, to a greater or lesser degree, and in a more or less attractive way. (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 211; emphasis added)10 There are two vital points in this quote that I wish to highlight at this point. First, Gramsci’s formulation that “modern ‘humanism’” must be secular in nature is made within a specific historical context, and thus it invites us to think about the meaning of history in the creation of such a spirit. He of course makes the point that if the lay intellectuals failed to connect with the masses the Catholics had hardly fared better. But the secular humanism he proposes has larger historical milieu, and a more complex trajectory, than this simple comparison with the church. I shall discuss some of the major features of this history further and shall also suggest that this remains the closest approximation to Said’s secular criticism. The second point I want to underscore is the connection that Gramsci makes between this secular humanism and popular culture. The gap between the intellectuals and the masses is not caused by the absence of popular literature; neither is the secular humanism missing from popular culture altogether. The point rather is that the “intellectual needs” of the people are being satisfied by non-national

The Secular Alliance

91

cultural artifacts like French novels that had served their purpose in their own nations and now were playing a surrogate role in Italy.11 The real failure of the Italian intelligentsia was their inability to dress the secular humanism within a national garb, to unite the national-popular collective will with the state; popular culture (or its absence) was the measure of that failure. Modern and secular humanism, then, is part of popular cultural formations and is not necessarily restricted by national boundaries. Gramsci’s rejection of the transcendent metaphysics of German philosophy in favor of historicism or humanism is a topic of much debate. It is worth noting, however, that in his discussion of Marxism Gramsci describes the “philosophy of praxis” as “absolute historicism or absolute humanism”; historicism is derived from “Hegelian immanentism,” but it becomes absolute only when combined with the philosophy of praxis, and the product of this fusion is humanism (SPNB 417). As Gramsci makes it clear here and elsewhere in Prison Notebooks, humanism for him primarily means an understanding of history (and hence the equivalence with historicism), that history is the product of human labor and not a divinely ordained sequence of events. Even human consciousness is part of this historical narrative and not anterior to it. But when he qualifies it as secular, he has very specific historical sequencing in mind. Secular humanism becomes important when there is a need to create a “new intellectual and moral order” or a “new type of society,” typically in a post-revolution society when the subaltern class becomes both autonomous and hegemonic. The task indeed is threefold: to “develop more universal concepts and more refi ned and decisive ideological weapons,” to “open the struggle for an autonomous and superior culture,” and to give a “modern and contemporary form to the traditional secular humanism which must be the ethical basis of the new type of State” (SPNB 388).12 The tripartite task is also the mechanism through which the intellectual (the critic in Said’s account) can surpass her separation from the masses. Within the specific context of Italian history Gramsci locates the origins of humanism in the history of the Renaissance. In a characteristic way, he distinguishes between two meanings of Renaissance—“the Renaissance is a very significant movement which begins after 1000, of which Humanism and the Renaissance (in the strict sense) are two conclusive moments, which have Italy as their principal seat, while the more general historical process is European and not just Italian” (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 221). The Renaissance then is both a periodization and, along with humanism, a product of that period. Indeed, Gramsci imagines a more intimate connection between humanism and the Renaissance since the origin of the former can be found in the latter—in other words, the basic unit of humanism, that is, man “was not ‘discovered’, rather a new form of culture was initiated [during the Renaissance], a new effort to create a new type of man in the dominant classes” (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 217). This new form of culture had very different trajectories in Italy and the rest of Europe—while

92

Baidik Bhattacharya

in other countries the combined forces of humanism and the Renaissance led to the formation of national states, in Italy, in spite of its vital contribution through communes that decisively challenged the feudal order, the general movement degenerated. Instead of national states, Italy was overtaken by “papacy as an absolute state” that destroyed the spirit of the Renaissance and “broke up the rest of Italy” (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 222). Gramsci reads Machiavelli as proposing the theory that without a national state the Renaissance remains incomplete and offers Italian history as empirical corroboration. There are two interesting outcomes of this rather schematic reading of history: Gramsci acknowledges that though the culmination of the Renaissance was the national state, in large parts of Europe—Spain, France, England and Portugal—the history continued through their imperial expansion. In contrast, because of the imperfect nature of the Italian state, the Renaissance was able to give birth to two kinds of intellectuals, one that colluded with the papacy and was “reactionary in nature,” and the other which “was formed abroad by political and religious exiles and had a progressive function in the various countries in which it took up residence” (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 220). A number of key concerns in Gramsci’s thinking are at play here: the failure of the Italian state, the ascendency of papacy that stifled the nationalpopular, the regressive nature of the traditional intellectual, and so on. The failure of humanism in Italy is instructive because it offers a new theoretical framework to conceptualize these concerns—it offers a non-national framing within which these concerns can be articulated. The secular humanism he champions—“human spirit as the creator of life and history” (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 234)—is not a philosophical position that can be formulated or worked out within a national framework; even though he recognizes the contribution of this philosophy in the making of modern European nation-states, the result of such national containment only leads to imperial expansion. It seems to me much more interesting to follow the lead that the philosophical position is the key to understanding the popular, the way it shapes up within a given social structure, and the way it negotiates with hegemonic structures. Secular humanism, in other words, is a critical tool that allows one to think of the popular without necessarily subsuming it to the fi nal framing of the national or without making it an abstract category that remains locked in the pedagogical realm of national culture. In the context of Italy the failure of the intelligentsia to nationalize this secular philosophy—a fact that Gramsci laments—paradoxically opens up the space for this new theorization in his own work. Gramsci’s work, in other words, sets a global paradigm for critical thinking beyond the nation or national culture. The analogy between Said’s secular criticism and Gramsci’s secular humanism practically suggests itself not only because of the former’s expressed debt to the latter, but more so because of the way both try to develop a theoretical paradigm that would be responsive to the

The Secular Alliance

93

cultural hegemonies with supra-national structures, and a philosophical underpinning for radical thinking. The Terrain Ahead As would be evident by now, I chart two accounts of criticism through Gramsci and Said in order to make fresh inroads into the globalization–postcoloniality debate, and I want to suggest that whether one looks at the foundational moments of postcolonial theory or the genealogies of such thinking, there are interesting and provocative leads that can take us beyond the national question. The common thread that runs through these two accounts of Said and Gramsci is of course their emphasis on the possibility of non-national critical thinking; but it should not be taken as a purely negative position, that is, it should not be taken only as negation of the nation-state. In both cases the philosophical position reformulates criticism itself as a social and secular vocation. In Culture and Imperialism Said revisits Gramsci to make this point. He reiterates the fundamental point I have mapped in Gramsci, that in spite of an “irreducible subjective core to human experience” such experiences are also “historical and secular”; the relationship between human experience and history is that of mutual influence and not of exclusion. The historical and secular aspect of this interaction cannot be “marked and limited by doctrinal or national lines” and cannot be permanently restricted within “analytical constructs.” Indeed the legacy of Gramsci is precisely to expose the absurdity of such attempts to essentialize human experience and history according to doctrinal or quasi-religious authorities, or narrowly defi ned dogmas or credos. If one believes with Gramsci, Said argues, that an “intellectual vocation is socially possible as well as desirable,” then it is important to recognize at the same time that such a vocation cannot be constructed on “historical experience around exclusions” of any kind. Every doctrinal or national claim, or every form of essentialization functions on exclusions—social, political, cultural, and so on—and the task of the secular critic is to think beyond such strategies of exclusion, to make possible a form of thinking that does not correspond to such strategies (Said, Culture and Imperialism 35). Let me illustrate my point with an example from Culture and Imperialism. The central point about modern imperialism according to Said is a very Gramscian one: “[H]ow the national British, French, American cultures maintained hegemony over the peripheries. How within them was consent gained and continuously consolidated for the distant rule of native peoples and territories?” To understand this imperial conundrum, he suggests, there are two critical strategies—either one can read European cultural forms against their supposed autonomy, and place them against the larger history of European imperialism where they will show traces of their global genealogy. And second, a related theme that Said describes as a “contrapuntal” reading strategy with a “simultaneous awareness both of the metropolitan history that is narrated and of

94

Baidik Bhattacharya

those other histories against which (and together with which) the dominating discourse acts” (Said, Culture and Imperialism 59). Both these strategies are of course examples of secular criticism; the central aim in both cases is a secular unraveling of power and its ability to generate consent across territories. But the secularism of these practices, especially the way I have elaborated it above, needs some further clarification. In Culture and Imperialism in general, and especially here, Said’s argument takes a notably spatial turn as he translates imperial culture into a “cultural topography” that spans across the imperial divide, across metropolitan and peripheral territories, and allows the secular practice of contrapuntal reading.13 Modern empires are marked by territorial expansion and control; modern imperial cultures are similarly territorial in their orientation. Though cultural productions are not always marked by any singular territorial ideology of the empire, and though modern empires lack any such one official ideology in the first place, cultural texts are often marked by this central principle of representing cultural topography. Said’s preferred example is a series of canonical English authors like Spenser, Shakespeare, Defoe and Austen who consistently represent far-flung territories that are connected with the British empire in various ways; the consistency does not stop at mere representation, it is extends in the mode of such representation of such distant lands as “desirable but subordinate.” The point is not that all these writers were convinced about the greatness of British empire, or that they participated in nefarious conspiracy to embolden the overwhelming imperial project, but rather that their texts are “bound up with the development of Britain’s cultural identity, as that identity imagines itself in a geographically conceived world” (Said, Culture and Imperialism 61). This is by no means is unique to British imagination either, as innumerable similar examples from French and American cultures testify. What is unique in this mode of representation across modern imperial cultures is the “way in which structures of location and geographical reference appear in the cultural languages of literature, history, or ethnography” that are not always orchestrated as part of larger imperial designs (Said, Culture and Imperialism 61). Contrapuntal reading strategies can unearth the vast imperial archive across genres to show how the hegemonic metropolitan cultures are actually shaped by such cultural topographies. The point I wish to highlight about the description of cultural topography is its inspiration. In the pages immediately preceding this vital formulation of contrapuntal reading Said tells us that Gramsci provides an “explicitly geographical model” to think about imperial culture; he is particularly suitable for this since, unlike Lukacs, his focus is resolutely on the “territorial, spatial, geographical foundations of social life” and that his oeuvre testifies to his interest in conceptualizing “social history and actuality” in overtly “geographical terms” (Said, Culture and Imperialism 57).14 The piece Said chooses to discuss is “Some Aspects of the Southern Question” where Gramsci considers the vast discrepancies between the industrial North and the agrarian South, and how in

The Secular Alliance

95

spite of its degeneration the South holds a key to understanding the problems of the North. The text is situated between Gramsci’s journalistic writing and Prison Notebooks, and as such can be seen as prelude to his extended reflection on the failure of the Italian national project in the latter. I have already indicated some of these concerns in the section on Gramsci; but what Said wishes to highlight is the territorial underpinning of Gramsci’s argument. He points out Gramsci’s remarkable detailing of the peculiar topography of the South, and his fastidious attempt to relate this topography to the larger question of national integration. Though Said does not say this explicitly, he almost wants to recast Italian history after the model of imperial territorial domination, where the advanced Northern metropolitan centre controls the vast Southern countryside teeming with poor peasants and cheap laborers, and at the same time in important ways depends on it. Said’s reading of Gramsci’s text presents it not only as an instance of secular criticism but as an exercise in contrapuntal reading itself, displaying in this process how questions of culture and imperialism necessarily cross borders. The next move in Said’s reading is also closely related to our concern here— that is, the role of the critic and the functioning of secular criticism. He brings out the importance Gramsci accords to Piero Gobetti and his work in connecting the North and the South and in working out an exceptional model for this purpose. Gobetti recognized the need to connect the two parts of Italy but did not conceive such a connection through cultural homogenization or forced national assimilation. Rather, Gramsci argues, his proposal was two-pronged—on the one hand, he introduced the Northern proletariat to the Southern peasantry, and on the other, he emphasized the importance of cultural organization in bringing about such an alliance. In this radical rethinking of history Gobetti was indeed a break in the Italian intellectual tradition—a decisive contrast to say Croce or Fortunato—and a secular intellectual who understood the importance of intellectual labor in its secular and worldly dispensation. Said, however, also points out that Gramsci is particularly sensitive to the temporal structure of such intellectual labor; he, along with Gobetti, recognizes the importance of the break the latter provides and the cultural projects that need to be built on such a crucial break, but also admits that, in Said’s words, intellectual work is slower, works according to more extended calendars than that of any other social group. Culture cannot be looked at as an immediate fact but has to be seen (as he was to say in the Quaderni) sub specie aeternitatis. Much time elapses before new cultural formations emerge, and intellectuals, who depend on long years of perception, action, and tradition, are necessary to this process. (Said, Culture and Imperialism 57–58) The longue durée of cultural practices are part of the secular vision I have been charting through Said and Gramsci, and the very structure makes it

96

Baidik Bhattacharya

imperative that secular intellectual labor be part of it in at least two ways—in the fi rst instance, in terms of political commitment, and in the second by being itself the “link between disparate, apparently autonomous regions of human history” (Said, Culture and Imperialism 58). At this stage we may return to the debates with which I open this chapter— the crisis of postcolonial theory and the rhetoric of globalization. The debate has been concerned for too long with the question of the nation-state—that is, whether postcolonial theory in its global ambition valorizes national culture (since the outcome of decolonization was the nation-state) or whether it already marks the advent of a global culture based on hybridity and difference. A classic case in point is Simon Gikandi’s essay “Globalization and the Claims of Postcoloniality.” Published in a special issue on postcolonial literature and globalization, it starts with quite a few bold claims about the problematic at hand; one of the most interesting arguments he puts forward is that there is a natural link between the vocabularies of contemporary globalization and postcolonial theory, making the latter particularly adept at discussing issues of global cultural production. He makes a distinction between the earlier phase of globalization that was dominated by the rhetoric of colonization and modernization and the latter one that is built around postcolonial terms like hybridity and difference. The result, Gikandi argues, is that a new grammar of globalization is at hand that heavily borrows from critical terms made available by postcolonial theory. After this elaboration, however, Gikandi surprisingly goes back to the history of nationalism and its role in the making of postcolonial cultures; the claims of the nation, he suggests, are still strong and it would be foolish to discard the history of the nation in the production of modern cultural forms. This more or less summarizes the central thrust in most accounts of the debate—the participants have only relativized the question (how important is the nation after all) or have sounded cautionary notes against various theoretical assumptions. One of the central challenges for critical thinking I think is to move beyond such exhausted paradigms of the debate, and to produce an organic break in the intellectual tradition that both Gramsci and Said see as vital for intellectual labor. The lead provided by both is a stepping-stone toward such a goal; the rest remains to be worked out. Notes 1. I would like to thank Neelam Srivastava and Rajeswari Sunder Rajan for their comments on an earlier draft of this essay. 2. The reference is to Marx’s 1844 text “Towards a Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right: Introduction”; the passage runs like this: “The weapon of criticism obviously cannot replace the criticism of weapons. Material force must be overthrown by material force. But theory also becomes a material force once it has gripped the masses. Theory is capable of gripping the masses when it demonstrates ad hominem, and it demonstrates ad hominem when it becomes radical” (34).

The Secular Alliance

97

3. Much of what Said says about “secular criticism” in his introduction to The World, the Text, and the Critic, especially about its “oppositional” nature, Jonathan Arac reminds us, can be traced back to his early works like Beginnings (56); this is partly why I treat it as a theme running through his oeuvre. 4. “Secular criticism” is often a misunderstood concept in Said’s oeuvre and hence needs careful elaboration (See Mufti 1998). Even an otherwise sympathetic commentator like Abdirahman A. Hussein, for example, completely misconstrues Said’s concept by describing it as one of the “age-old imperatives” that Said merely wishes to re-introduce with a contemporary critical edge (Hussein 11–12). 5. This preoccupation with the question of minority also allows Mufti to develop the notion of what he calls “critical secularism” or “a secularist critique of modern secularism” (Mufti, Enlightenment in the Colony 13–14). 6. The reference here is to Williams, Politics and Letters 252; he elaborates this at greater length in Marxism and Literature 125. 7. In Orientalism he argues, “Culture, of course, is to be found operating within civil society, where the influence of ideas, of institutions, and of other persons works not through domination but by what Gramsci calls consent. In any society not totalitarian, then, certain cultural forms predominate over others, just as certain ideas are more influential than others; the form of this cultural leadership is what Gramsci has identified as hegemony” (Said 7). 8. In Said’s formulation fi lial bonds are based on “natural forms of authority” that involves “obedience, fear, love, respect and instinctual confl ict,” and the affi liative relationships are predicated on “transpersonal forms” like “guild consciousness, consensus, collegiality, professional respect, class, and the hegemony of a dominant culture” (Said, The World, the Text, and the Critic 20). 9. As Gramsci argues elsewhere, “It must be observed that in Italy, unlike other countries, not even religion acted as an element of cohesion between people and intellectuals, and that for this very reason the philosophical crisis of the intellectuals did not extend to the people, because it did not originate from the people and there did not exist a ‘national-popular bloc’ in the religious field” (quoted in SPNB 394). 10. Gramsci of course acknowledges that a few Italian authors like Guerrazzi and Mastriani represented the spirit of this modern humanism but by and large it remained a peripheral force in modern Italian culture. 11. Gramsci notes, “Now the absence of a national-popular literature . . . has left the literary ‘market’ open to the influence of intellectuals from other countries. ‘National-popular’ writers at home, they become national-popular in Italy too because the needs which they satisfy are the same in this country” (Gramsci, Selections from Cultural Writings 215). 12. Secular here, however, must not be confused with atheism, since in Gramsci’s formulation the latter is a “purely negative and sterile form, unless it is to be conceived as a period of pure popular literary polemic” (SPNB 418). 13. For a different reading of this spatial turn in Said’s work, and its connection with Gramscian humanism, see Brennan, “Places of Mind.” 14. Elsewhere Said talks about a “spatial tradition” of thinkers, which is based on Italian materialism and can be traced back to Lucretius; this tradition includes, among others, Gramsci (Mitchell 43).

Part II

Gramsci and the Global Present

5

The “Unseen Order” Religion, Secularism and Hegemony Iain Chambers

El Jadida. It is the hour that milk is delivered. The hour that I love the most in my city, peopled still only for an instance by those who have to rise early: street cleaners, fi sherman, donut vendors, the devout, vegetable sellers, the custodians of the public ovens. One after another they wish me a “luminous day” while I wander the streets and alleys. Come with me into the old Portuguese town where the past has been restored in the smallest detail. In this space, the size of a public square, there, flanking each other, is a mosque, a church and a synagogue. What is this Islamism? This word does not appear in our dictionaries. I learnt of its existence in the Western media. —Driss Chraibi, “Extreme West”1

[A]ll of history is testimony to the present. —Antonio Gramsci, Quaderni del carcere2

Christianity invented the distinction between religious and secular, and thus it made religion. It made religion the problem—rather than itself. —Gil Anidjar, Semites. Race, Religion, Literature3

Power seeks a language of authorization. Such a language is neither invented ex novo nor simply borrowed. It is assembled, elaborated and practiced wherever possible and via whatever means. The making of such a language, that is the articulation of power to name, hence direct and defi ne, necessarily draws upon available sense. In order to convince and convey, even when there is the desire to promote a radical announcement, language cannot stray too far from an already established semantics. It can only shift, extend and push the existing langue; that is why language is essentially about hegemony. The struggle for sense—both for meaning and direction—requires language. And if language is not invented but rather constructed and configured, then existing senses—social, cultural, political, historical, religious, and so on—coalesce and combine in its making.

102

Iain Chambers

Or rather, they take form and fl ight there, in the very stuff and texture of the parole. It is also here, in its performative exercise and consensual recognition, that power is transformed from mere force to a disseminating pedagogy and the potential counter-site of possible replies. Among the lexicons that have seemingly returned to invest the powers of modernity is that of religion. Once assumed to have been superseded by modern, secular society, we discover that religion has become the name of a struggle for authority within modernity: both in London and Cairo; both in cultural configurations correlated by Christianity as in those of Islam, Judaism and Hinduism. Religion, as a modality of modern power, directly and indirectly seeks to provide the narrative authority able to domesticate the world and command the horizon of contemporary sense.4 This suggests that in religion today we encounter far more than the institutional force of consecrated texts and their custody in religious authorities, even more than the creation of communities of believers and the attraction of the sacred. There emerges here, as Foucault might have suggested, a discursive power that penetrates the textures of our lives and regulates the bio-politics of our very being and becoming. The “natural sacredness” of reality which sustains the poetical piety pursued in Pier Paolo Pasolini’s fi lm, The Gospel according to Saint Matthew (1964), as in all of his cinema, promotes a humble mission to endow the world with social justice: an act of faith that is simultaneously a critique of religious authority and the institutional powers of the Catholic Church for their subsequent betrayal of Christ. 5 A similar perspective was pursued in those very same years by the Italian anthropologist Ernesto De Martino in his ethnographic work among the peasantry of Southern Italy. There is a subversive idea here. Language, as it were, is turned against itself to reveal a further possibility. If religion exercised the symbolic power essential to the production and reproduction of hegemony and insuring the status quo, it also provided the immediate language, creolized by local custom and tradition, for a popularly practiced, often heterodox, “common sense.” Such an unsystematic, fragmented language can potentially provoke the communication of that critical self-awareness which Antonio Gramsci nominated “good sense.” From rural Catholicism in Southern Italy to Rastafarianism in the Caribbean and Islam in the Algerian qasba, these mixtures of conservatism and local knowledge are also sites of power. Similarly, in a significant essay titled “Said, Religion, and Secular Criticism,” Gauri Viswanathan examines Edward Said’s attempt to elaborate a secular criticism while attentive to the heterogeneous complexities of Islam as a reasoning, dissenting tradition, opposed to the stereotypical understanding of a homogeneous consensus. What emerges at this point is perhaps less the argument that dissenting traditions are the precursors of modern secularism, but rather like religion itself, that they are deeply embedded and disseminated within modernity. This, as Viswanathan

The “Unseen Order”

103

notes, raises questions about secularism’s presumed autonomy “as a postreligious development” (171). Friends, Foes and Faith The daily deployment of the lexical index of us and them, notoriously elaborated in the Schmittian distinction between friend and foe, has more recently been distilled into the numbing binarism and violent insistence of Huntingdon’s The Clash of Civilizations. Accompanied by rising xenophobia and the unfolding lexicon of anti-immigration legislation, we today increasingly register the violence of the political, juridical and cultural schemata that seeks to reduce the world into neat, easily identifiable opposites. The problem is that there does not exist a unique and homogeneous West or East; there is no such thing as Islam, or Christianity. Over forty years ago, in his Islam Observed, the anthropologist Clifford Geertz underlined, in their respective crossing by local currents and conditions, the complex communality in difference of Islam in then contemporary Morocco and Indonesia. In the Westernization of the world, the tendency, on the contrary, is toward what Serge Latouche refers to as the “standardisation of the imaginary” in the context of a “generalised mimesis.” At this point, the hegemony of the media has apparently become the immediate measure of truth. The media seems to surrender to every temptation of reducing reality and condensing it into a symbol, thrusting the whole issue into discursive disrepair . . . In cinematographic language this fi xed spatial determination is simply called “a shot”, suggesting that the real is no longer represented but targeted. In the staccato of television news shots, this particular shot becomes the symbol that encapsulates the meaning of the entire drama. It is evident that complex social relations are not negotiated in this frantic manner. (Biemann 45) To insist on Islam as a thing, invariably condensed in the figure of armed terrorists and veiled women—that is, an image to be confronted, contested and eventually converted to our way of life—is precisely, as both Edward Said and Gil Anidjar have argued, to reveal the centrality of religious discourse to the West. As a category for a distinct sense of understanding—like “race” and “ethnicity”—“religion” is very much an invention of occidental modernity and its planetary pedagogy (Anidjar 27). Rey Chow has frequently pointed out that the separation of the world into distinct histories and cultures, via area, religious and geo-political studies, is a form of intellectual and historical management that holds out the promise of disciplinary certitude. It leads to an enormous exercise, along the lines of divide and rule, in cultural and political power. This is to neatly side-step the crushing verdict delivered more than seventy years ago from a Fascist prison by Antonio Gramsci:

104

Iain Chambers The question of religion is to be intended not in terms of a confessional faith but rather in the secular terms of the unity of belief between a vision of the world and rules of conduct; but why call this unity of belief “religion” rather than “ideology”, or more simply “politics”? (Quaderni 1378)

With this we arrive, with Gil Anidjar and the Catholic historian and scholar of Arab philosophy, Rémi Brague, at the disquieting conclusion that Christianity is in fact the name, acknowledged or not, of Occidental modernity and globalization.6 Secularism is sustained by a disposition of belief: in the teleological redemption of time as “progress,” in the calling to redeem the planet in a unique image and impose a humanist mastery on the cosmos, in the “mission” to establish the exceptional state, or “city on a hill.” As Gramsci sharply reminds us, the relationship between religion, the state and political formations in the West is indissoluble. “The principal elements of common sense are provided by religion and therefore the relationship between common sense and religion is much more intimate than that between common sense and the philosophical systems of the intellectuals” (Quaderni 1396–97). In the immediacy of inherited beliefs, popular sayings, superstitions, everyday practices and local custom, that is, in commonsensical understandings deposited in the textures of everyday life, the subaltern both recognizes herself while finding there the ambivalent resources of her speech. For what comes to be said may both confirm and modify, both sustain and subvert, the status quo. Conjunctural forces, social crises and individual assessment can interrupt the continuum of common sense, exposing its constructed and contradictory nature. So, we need to ask ourselves, where do these popular beliefs come from? How do they acquire coherence? As we have seen, Gramsci attributes to religion the principal sources of common sense. Those whose conceptions of the world are largely inscribed in the parameters of an everyday consensus, for whom a critical education is socially and economically excluded, inevitably tend to reproduce acritical meanings that sustain a narrative endorsed by religious finality. Here the Catholic Church reveals its syncretic mastery: combining religious dogma and peasant, stretching back to pagan, community rites in a potent synthesis. It is precisely for this reason, as Gramsci argues, that intellectual dissent and critical philosophies are invariably resisted. The tendential disruption of the everyday world is considered the work of an external and negative hegemony, seeking to limit the freedom of popular thought and render it subordinate and marginal. This, of course, is a profoundly political problem. How is the slippery coherence of common sense, secured in sedimented understandings of the religiosity of the universe, to be transformed? This takes us into a further set of questions, but simply to consider the weight of the religious underwriting of contemporary politics, in particular in modern occidental society, is to register the disturbing heart of the question. The secular West is sustained by the “unseen order” of religious belief ( James 53). In historical terms this argument would rarely be contested; just

The “Unseen Order”

105

think of the centrality of Christianity in its Protestant variants to the making of English and British modernity as so meticulously traced by historians, Catherine Hall and Carolyn Steedman. Yet, to insist on the contemporary impact of this formation is usually to encounter an uncomfortable silence. Surely in our modernity, religion is now elsewhere, back there and elsewhere: the property and problem of someone else? As Leila Ahmed pointed out some years ago, in their centuries-long struggle for greater freedom and rights, no one ever suggested that Occidental women should abandon Christianity, yet it is precisely this option—the abandonment of Islam in order to embrace modernity—that the West today desires of Muslim women (244). This, of course, is also to assume that Islam and modernity are separate entities, and not profoundly entwined and multiplied in both a European and a planetary formation. Religion lived as an unseen Occidental order today increasingly reveals itself, for example, in the moment that Turkish membership of the European Union is considered. In the end, the objections to Turkey come down to: religion and the fear of Islam—kebab shops are acceptable, but the idea of pinnacled mosques punctuating the skyline of European cities is another matter. The fact is that secularism, spawned by the Occidental category of religion, is also the means whereby inequality and hierarchies of racial, ethnic and gender discrimination are sustained on a global scale. For it is a “discourse of power that legitimates itself and presents itself as secular as if indifferent to religion yet producing religion as a (generic) problem” (Anidjar 51). This brings us to confront the racializing pedagogy of reason and religion: between those who know and those cast out in ignorance, excluded and rendered inferior in their religious bigotry and fundamentalism. This, as Gil Anidjar argues, is to insist on recognizing (and resisting) the interlaced disciplinary procedures and protocols of religion and race (17). Again, religion in its Christian variants has been a part of the recent political landscape in Europe for decades— for example, in the near hegemony of the Christian Democrat parties in Germany and Italy—but any mention of politicized Islam, for example, in modern Turkey, actually gripped in the military enforcement of secularism, is considered an alien threat rather than part of a clearly differentiated but shared modernity. Prizing open the intricate interrelationship between occidental secularism and religion might also allow us to begin to unpack the unexamined faith that democracy and capitalism somehow coexist in a harmony, sustained by the laws of the market and the theology of individual freedom. What if, on the contrary, they are actually deeply antagonistic? But more on this in a minute. Blinded by the Image Of course, one might initially object that many of these observations, in this case largely inspired by Antonio Gramsci’s observations in the 1930s, have

106

Iain Chambers

been overtaken by events. In the West, the simple, rural peasantry and unruly working class no longer exist as distinct cultural blocs in any obvious position of cultural subalternity. Today, the ignorant, rural pastor who repeats platitudes to his illiterate flock is sometimes replaced by the independent, urban priest who provides a focus in the struggle against crime and corruption. In the Scampia quarter of Naples, as in the region around Caserta, such figures have become outspoken leaders against the Camorra, sometime paying for their opinions with their life. As organic figures of the local community, these priests provide a cultural, political and moral direction in the absence of leadership from the state and official cultural agencies. If secular, intellectual culture continues to remain “external” to the sense of street life and its moral economy, and the rhetoric of the Catholic hierarchy remains largely unaltered, conditions have nevertheless changed. The worldly languages of the mass media and metropolitan culture have truncated the ancient alliances of popular superstition, clerical obscurantism, and the public authority of the Church. At the same time, however, the legislative power registered in the ubiquitous lexicons of Christianity and the television screen actually betray far deeper currents, illustrating how the Church has adapted in molecular ways to the media of contemporary culture, and the fact that Occidental culture is itself thoroughly Christianized. On this point, Gramsci quotes Croce, “after Christ we are all christians” (Quaderni 1307). The news shot, the image and the icon, the television screen and the figure of the Madonna, are deeply embedded in each other’s agendas. If to see is to believe, and the image is considered to be “factual” testimony to the event, then the Occidental vision sustained in Christian iconography— the whole history of Western art from the late classical period through to the Baroque and beyond—has hardly been displaced or disrupted by secular modernity. On the contrary, the faith in the immediate visualization of truth—from the Crucifix, the image of the Madonna, and the subsequent plunge downwards through TV reality shows to the digital framing of the aerial bombardment of the not-yet-modern world—is firmly unshaken (Chow, “The Age of the World Target”). Edward Said suggestively noted that this realism reaffirms Europe’s historical trajectory; a realism that is sustained in a precise conceptual unity: [T]he Church and the Holy Roman Empire guarantee the integrity of the core European literatures. At a still deeper level, it is from the Christian Incarnation that Western realistic literature as we know it emerges. This tenaciously advanced thesis explained Dante’s supreme importance to Auerbach, Curtius, Vossler, and Spitzer. (Culture and Imperialism 45) If today the aura of the unique artwork fades into the multiplying flux of the copy, the aura of a seemingly tangible and immediate reality, even if mediated and manipulated (after all, it is an image, an inscription, a cultural construction, a pixel configuration), remains undisturbed. “Nature,” the

The “Unseen Order”

107

“human” and “faith” are immediately present and simultaneously removed from critical concern: they simply are. As Gramsci once suggested, only a polemical relationship to such an inheritance and hegemony is possible. Only a critical undoing and overcoming of common sense can lead to a “new philosophy: this explains the necessity of a polemic with traditional philosophies in the exposition of the philosophy of praxis” (Quaderni 1397). What emerges clearly from this discussion is the primacy that Gramsci gives to the generative role of culture in the critical understanding of the political powers of a historical formation. Power is exercised—that is, it is not merely applied as a direct force, but is practiced, performed, and extended in the immediacy of everyday perceptions and languages. Power does not simply subject; it seeks to convince and hence is both a subjecting and subjective force (Butler). The centrality and originality of Gramsci’s thought lies precisely here in the key idea that cultural hegemony has to be achieved prior to the realization of political power. This evokes a pedagogical undertaking that seeks in education (understood in the widest sense of the term) the means able to consistently challenge the status quo, leading to knowledge that is not an object to be attained and possessed as information, but rather a disposition that sustains a critical pedagogy in constant engagement. Not by chance does the increasing configuration of education in terms of market criteria, privatization and religious belonging, signal, in the most blatant of terms, this ongoing struggle for hegemony within the heartlands of occidental education. Perhaps the central, if largely unnamed, force of cultural consensus and conservation in the West is that represented by religion—that is, by Christianity. The continuing silence of intellectuals in the face of the religious elaboration of occidental hegemony, both at home (schooling, public morality, family values) and abroad (colonialism, imperialism, globalization, liberalism and their combination in civilizing missions) suggests Christianity’s implicit organicity to that formation. This very silence betrays complicity, an embarrassment. Religion, like the school and the family, are among those apparatuses that the French Algerian philosopher, Louis Althusser, incisively referred to as ideological state apparatuses. ISAs interpellate our individual and collective formation to the degree that we (mis)recognize ourselves within them (127–86). Christian values are taken for granted, rendered commonsensical, by both by those in power and by those subordinate and seemingly in opposition. Perhaps such values require an altogether more Nietzschean and Foucauldian style of critical revaluation: the Church, and its violent custody of ontological truth and belief, has played a formidable role in the formation of modern, secular society and its global reach and imposition; certainly as significant as that played by the prison, the clinic, and the invention of sexuality. Perhaps, secularism is another one of those inventions? This suggests something more than merely an intellectual critique of occidental religion— whether by classically influenced and pagan-tinged Renaissance humanists,

108

Iain Chambers

or skeptical Enlightenment thinkers. It suggests the need for an altogether more radical exposition of the archive or archaeology of religion in the West. In the end, it comes down to a radical revaluation of the Occidental archive; that is, the critical exposure, undoing and reworking of the powers of a precise historical and cultural formation. Here is Antonio Gramsci once again: It seems to me that the problem is much simpler than it is made to appear by those who implicitly consider “Christianity” as being inherent to modern civilization, or lack the courage to raise the question of the relations between Christianity and modern civilization. . . . the people of the Orient perceive the hostility which is invisible in our countries because Christianity has adapted itself molecularly and has become Jesuitism, that is, a great social hypocrisy. (Prison Notebooks 1: 333) The Colonization of Democracy The very closure of the West faced with migratory movements, the “asymmetrical” relationship between the “internal principles” of liberal political theory, those evoked in the treatment of “citizens”, and its “external principles”, can justly be considered as the postcolonial fall-out of the logic of “spatial” domination that has historically accompanied the construction of liberalism as the hegemonic thought of modernity. (Mezzadra 83) While there is much talk these days of the relationship between democracy and Islam, or of the problems facing Muslim women, we are completely unaccustomed to posing those questions to Christianity. No one would presume to talk of women in metropolitan Europe as Christian women, or ask of Christianity to account for itself in terms of democracy and gender equality, although in both historical and contemporary terms this is clearly a very pertinent question (Lazreg 7). It is simply as though Christianity, democracy and modernity are all one. To adopt for a moment a Durkheimian perspective, if religion is a symbolic system in which society becomes collectively conscious of itself, then secular Europe is historically and culturally soaked in Christian values and their associated belief system. Here it is also worth recalling the sharp pertinence of Talal Asad’s criticism of Clifford Geertz’s understanding of religion as a complex cultural system for overlooking the dimension of power as being decisive for its affi rmation (Genealogies of Religion). Rather than insist on its historically hybridized realization, at this point perhaps it might be intellectually and politically more significant to accept the idea that Europe is fundamentally Christian in its formation; after all, that is what it tends to believe. Then we can perhaps begin to think about how to undo this formation. From this threshold it becomes possible to think the

The “Unseen Order”

109

limits of Europe and its religious infrastructure in a critical space that neither has authorized. To seek to change the languages of comprehension and (common) sense is to disrupt an existing consensus and its accompanying order. It means to rework an existing structural logic. In an altogether more fluid scenario, a historical bloc cannot appeal to an autonomy unsullied by the forces and currents that precede and exceed its attempts to grasp and transform the world, but neither can it simply be construed as an abstract counter-power located in the anonymous multitude that sustains First World desires for radicalism. To seek in the external what is most profoundly internal—the imperious faith in material and metaphysical progress that sustains, however critically, the liberal and occidental appropriation of the planet in terms of its economic, political, cultural and religious lexicons—is to avoid the big chill that accompanies the discomfort of a profound critical interruption. The occidental institution of philosophy rarely recognizes the full significance of this critical challenge. When there is seemingly a direct response—Foucault, Deleuze, Negri and Hardt—it tends to remain locked within the confi rmation of its own discursive horizon. As Gayatri Spivak rightly points out, the other, as subaltern, multitude, immigrant, sustains rather than shatters, the authority of the critical paradigm. It is precisely here that the deconstructive turn within occidental reasoning becomes most suggestive and subversive: as the internal outside, as the voice that speaks the West without being fully reducible to the law of its logos—thinking on the threshold of its metaphysical certainties. Displacing the logic of its language, disseminating an interrogative cut in what Derrida called “globalatinization” and thereby insisting that not all roads lead to Rome, promotes the undoing and dispersal of such white mythologies.7 Returning us to a postcolonial insistence, and to the Gramscian perspective of thinking in a worldly fashion, we are invited to register the spatialization and geography of power, and the fact that the Gramscian Southern Question, in all its diverse peculiarities, today extends itself on a planetary scale (The Southern Question). As we are well aware, alongside “the march of liberal democracy in the twentieth century there has been a gross increase in inequalities of power and wealth, both locally and globally” (Vázquez-Arroyo 127). Liberal democracy is full of promises of freedom and equality that it is incapable of delivering; for it seeks, as Étienne Balibar points out, not equality but equivalence in the liberal world market (“Debating with Alain Badiou on Universalism”). This ultimately explains why the liberal-democratic consensus makes so few demands in terms of democratic participation. Politics is increasingly mediated through the channels (and concentrated powers) of mass communications that call upon citizen-spectators to verify the truth of the image and then mandate a government that expects them to remain mute. The very nature of this state of affairs, in which the interests of the First World are so intertwined with the direction of the global economy, is far from consonant

110

Iain Chambers

with the “egalitarian and participatory aspirations of democracy” (Balibar). Liberalism as the motor of such a development is hardly in the position to transcend this problem except in a vacuous rhetoric where terms like freedom stand in for the defense of the status quo and the existing distribution of riches, resources, and power. Crisis and contingency are continually disciplined by this premise, and democracy is increasingly denuded of all critical import, reduced to the disembodied language of tolerance and pluralism. The question on whose terms participation is permitted brings us back to Gramsci’s considerations on the margins of history and the exclusion of subaltern and popular forces from its defi nition. The vicious state repression of sporadic and spontaneous peasant revolts seeking rural reform, invariably nurtured with a sense of justice drawn from popular religious sentiments, betrays precisely the dark side of a modern secularism intent on sustaining the separation of religion and the state. Gramsci himself draws from the case of Davide Lazzaretti, leader of a peasant revolt in the Monte Amiata region of southern Tuscany, and the priests and peasants involved around the same period in the mountains of Benevento and Matese, north of Naples, this potent, popular mixture and its challenge to both lay and religious authority. Under a left-wing national government, the revolt was squashed and Lazzaretti summarily executed by a military fi ring squad in 1878. A radical religiosity crossed with republican sentiments—on the red flag of Lazzaretti’s movement was written “The Republic and the kingdom of God”—dramatically exposed institutional power to the limits of its hypocritical rhetoric: just whose rights and religion were being defended here? (Quaderni 2279–83). An existing order is privileged over the potential instability of multiple participation and the practices of egalitarianism. Meaningful involvement in political power is blocked precisely in the instance that power itself grows in increasingly undemocratic and unaccountable concentration. As the cultural, historical and political product of occidental modernity, liberalism is simultaneously Christian and in confl ict with the full reaches of democracy when voiced in the moral languages of republicanism and religion seeking a justice yet to come. When structural and institutional questions of power are reduced to debates over policy decisions and generic intent, then questions of justice and freedom—for whom, where, when and how—are diverted into appeals to an abstract humanity by which the whole world is colonized and its heterogeneous challenge sequestered and subsequently silenced. This logic can take many forms and degrees of sophistication, but in the end it is reduced to the bluntness of “You’re either with us—the West and its ‘democracy,’ ‘progress,’ ‘civilization’ (and implicitly its Christianity)—or against us.” Just as in the hierarchical order of racialized colors where whiteness goes unannounced, so in the sphere of religion the hegemonic formation does not need to be nominated. Non-Christians can only be considered trespassers in (Occidental) modernity, for they are structurally excluded. We are all

The “Unseen Order”

111

expected to respect the economical, juridical, and cultural laws of such a perspective, and those of us in difficulty are expected to work harder in order to enter the frame, certainly not to question, disrupt, or rearticulate its premises. In this sense, liberalism has fully colonized democracy, reducing it to a smiling mask and public masque, and its language to an infi nite and ineffectual ventriloquism. The Violence of Secularism The liberal violence to which I refer (as opposed to the violence of illiberal regimes) is translucent. It is the violence of universalizing reason itself. (Asad, Formations of the Secular 59) Tied deeply into the largely unrecognized nexus between religion and secularism as a historical and cultural formation is the question of tradition. This is not to suggest the seemingly obvious idea of tradition as the source of religious rites, customs and beliefs that survive and live on in the complex currents of modernity, but rather to insist that in the narratives of continuity, in the faith in the uniqueness of Occidental progress, in the narration of the nation as the privileged locus of identificatory practices, a metaphysics of belief, formed and disciplined by Christianity, remains unchallenged. Here, of course, we are conversing with Friedrich Nietzsche and his acerbic critique of the “slave mentality” of modernity, but we are also joined by Gramsci and his insistence on the political function of Christianity in the manufacture of common sense and a world outlook whose secular affi rmation is inextricably bound to centuries of religious incubation. As an uncanny insistence, taken, transformed and translated into secular visions, the continuing dissemination of a transcendental authority—from baptism to the cemetery—is undeniably still fi rmly in place.8 As an integrating force, as a form of social glue and cultural cohesion, the atemporal values of Christianity seemingly legitimate a tradition (transformed, rendered modern) that is ours. Once again, in a Durkheimian sense, this may well be its function. However, we also need to critically prize open that seemingly neutral factor, and insist on the more uncomfortable perspective that as a disseminated form of power, as a molecularization of transcendental authority, Christianity continues to provide and legitimate the largely unquestioned and unseen order of the West. To argue that people in the West feel the need for Christianity in order to domesticate and make sense of the world may well be true, but it may also be the case that such a need blocks other horizons of sense, obscures other, less provincial and more beneficial, structures of belief. In this sense, Christianity becomes the name of the pathology of the West. If, these days, public leaders are increasingly arguing that Christianity should be formally acknowledged in the founding discourse and identitarian touchstone of Europe and the Occident (thereby excising the creolizing prospects of the pagan Greeks and

112

Iain Chambers

Romans, along with the heretical monotheisms of Judaism and Islam), then Western modernity loses its exceptional secular state. It becomes coeval, crossed, divided and contested by the very same forces—religion—that it seeks to expel into the backward and underdeveloped margins of its empire. To prize open this Occidental archive, and to dirty its shelves with these heretical and unauthorized matters—paganism, Judaism and Islam—is to propose an altogether more unruly study of modern secularism. Restored to its inconclusive becoming, as a complex and often indeterminate series of cultural and historical processes that are currently underway, this heritage incisively impacts on any critical understanding of the modern languages of the law, the state, and governmentality. Secularization, as the seemingly progressive disinvestment in the institutions and rites of religious certainties, turns out to be a homeopathic force. It does not cancel Christianity: the theology of individual redemption and teleological progress rather doubles and disseminates the belief system of modernity’s historical winners. Monuments to wars fought, territories conquered and the world converted to its beliefs—European cities are brimming with these signs and symbols—propose a moral economy that considers itself the judge of mankind. God may well have abandoned his long hair and flowing robes for a sharp haircut, a business suit, or a military uniform, but he has certainly not forsaken the transcendental power of the West. 9 The assumption is that whereas “the West” is greater than and has surpassed the stage of Christianity, its principal religion, the world of Islam—its varied societies, histories, and languages notwithstanding—is still mired in religion, primitivity and backwardness. Therefore, the West is modern, greater than the sum of its parts, full of enriching contradictions and yet always “Western” in its cultural identity; the world of Islam, on the other hand, is no more than “Islam”, reducible to a small number of unchanging characteristics. (Said, Covering Islam 10 –11) Thinking the relationship between the presumptions of an internal secularism (Europe, the West and its modernity) and an externalized religious world (Islam, the South of the planet and its underdevelopment), an altogether more complex picture emerges. Conjoined with the state, secularism becomes the name of a governmentality and the management of faith, belief and religion through modern technologies of power, and certainly not, as we are usually taught, the realization of a post-religious society. Exploring what Tasal Asad refers to as the epistemological assumptions of the secular, and its imbrications in the practices and technologies of modern power, we register that secularism is not really about personal choice, or the identification of an individual or collective state isolated from religion (Genealogies of Religion 25). It is rather a discursive formation that is among the necessary conditions of a historical and cultural matrix,

The “Unseen Order”

113

addressing the mediation and management of beliefs and convictions in the formation and direction of modern power and politics. Stripping away the secular does not so much reveal the religious infrastructure of our faith in modernity as expose the conjunctural constellation that is simultaneously sustained and sutured by religion, secularism and the institutional and everyday powers they exercise in shaping the horizons of sense.10 In this sense, both public and private spheres as sites of the dispositions of power are already and simultaneously “christianized” and secularized. The secular and the sacred are in fact entwined in the French Revolution and the political birth of modern mass politics where “the sacralisation of individual citizen and collective people expresses a form of naturalized power” (Asad, Genealogies of Religion 32). Concepts such as freedom and the individual, essential to the grammar of the modern state, become sacred and a redeeming force for the world; secularism, as Talal Asad insists, is a political doctrine (56). Learning from Islam What has occurred? To refer to the intertwining of liberalism and religion in the Europe of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries is, as we noted, quite acceptable in historical and cultural terms. It is understood in both sociological and philosophical perspectives to be central to the making of occidental modernity. Yet when we turn to the present there is a silence, as though that argument and, in particular, that formation that is also and always a formation of power, has somehow fallen into disuse. Of course, political and cultural configurations shift and change, they are contingent; however, there has been no epistemological rupture, no radical revaluation of values. We are right to suspect that this previous order, even if displaced and unacknowledged, continues to discipline the core of the European public and private sphere, its technologies of power, and its bio-politics. Talk of Turkey’s entrance into the European Union in Germany, or of headscarves in France, and that inherited corpus of thought and practices immediately springs into life to sound the chord of the “lasting trauma” of Islam for Christianity (Said, Orientalism 59). In a seemingly secularized modernity we continue to grapple with the ghosts of a formation that refuses to pass away. At this point, the apparently sharp separation, and subsequent opposition, between secularism and religion falls, dissolved into an altogether more ambivalent fluidity. Secularism itself becomes problematic. As a social and cultural practice it, too, is caught, suspended and sustained in a constellation—occidental modernity—in which Christianity and its variants was, and is, essential to its hegemony. This is clearly, both in historical and philosophical terms, a complicated argument that requires a careful unwinding in order to identify its multiple modalities and affects. What—and thinking of Gramsci’s many meditations

114

Iain Chambers

on the question of religion, popular culture, the institutional powers of Catholicism, and the realization of hegemony—becomes clear is that liberalism, secularism, and religion are not distinct categories to be contrasted, but rather provide the critical triangulation of a specific historical formation and its subsequent political and cultural configurations. Perhaps, and referring to the provocative title of this section, it might be instructive to look elsewhere for a moment. This is not in order to fi nd a better realization of the role of religion in social and political life, but rather, in considering other forms and formulations, it helps us to register the limits of a specific constellation peculiar to the West that considers its perspectives universal and its solutions inevitably the most civilized and morally superior. Christianity, at this point, is the moral adjudicator of modern (Occidental) civilization. Gramsci succinctly acknowledged such presumptions in his short comparative analysis in the Quaderni del carcere of Islam and Christianity and their relationship to modernity. In both, he notes that it is not religion per se that is unable to molecularly adapt itself to modernity, but social and historical structures— such as feudalism and cultural isolation—that create obstacles to that process. Gramsci goes even further. He suggests that the absence of a massive religious hierarchy and the institutional powers of a Church makes Islam potentially even more susceptible to eventual transformation and modernization. He concludes: “Christianity has taken nine centuries to evolve and adapt, and it has done so in small steps, etc.; Islam is forced into a headlong rush” (Prison Notebooks 1: 333). In an important, pathbreaking essay that opens up the critically intercultural space within modernity, Armando Salvatore and Mark LeVine have carefully examined the question of the public sphere and technologies of power in modern Muslim majority countries. Considering the centrality of the Islamic concept and legal method of Istislah for seeking the social good through mediation, compromise and consensus as being central to a Muslim understanding of the public sphere, they contrast this practice with the abstract, universal categories of law and justice that sustain the conceptual violence and frequently punishing modalities of reason in the West. Their argument is that the public sphere, in its singular occidental abstractness, excludes other kinds of reason, and cancels the understanding of its own particular historical formation. They then extend their analysis through a Gramscian reading, attentive to the historical textures and cultural sentiments and formation of Islamic notions of custom, ‘urf, and habits or ‘adat, where ideas such as the public sphere and justice are certainly not absent, but neither are they simply poor copies of their Occidental counterparts. The very sense of the public, for historical and cultural reasons, is figured differently. It is neither transparent nor readily translatable to Western reasoning.11 As such it marks not simply a difference but proposes a profound critical challenge. What emerges most clearly from Salvatore’s and LeVine’s analysis is the Occidental lynchpin of the private citizen who, after all, “is just one—albeit

The “Unseen Order”

115

historically powerful and largely hegemonic—practiced and theorized approach to the public sphere” (7). In the manner in which the public sphere is embedded in the dynamics of the modern Muslim world, “secularly oriented rationality” is exposed to be not the only normative language for public life (Salvatore and LeVine 7). All of this stretches and reformulates the Gramscian understanding of civil society to include multiple social and cultural articulations on which “alternative hegemonic configurations of publicness in the Muslim majority world and elsewhere base their forces and sometimes legitimacy” (Salvatore and LeVine 7). In this altogether more complex conceptual mix, everyday practices and spaces receive and rework religion and tradition as forms of ongoing negotiation, mediation, refusal and resistance to an order that may be simultaneously local, national and international. This is close to Gramsci’s understanding of the hold of the counter-hegemonic prospects of popular religion and its implicit desire for social justice among the peasants of Southern Italy. Remaining on the edge of this critical fault-line, where European categories do not readily transmute into other historical heritages, and recognizing that religion itself continues to haunt the very heart of the West, we are confronted with the task, already elaborated in different ways by Talal Asad and Gil Anidjar, of “provincializing” secular modernity. In particular, as Salvatore and LeVine rightly insist, the myth of liberal politics secured in the figure of free, autonomous subjects and their associated decisional power, is rendered altogether more problematic. The complexity of forces that render accessibility to public recognition difficult, unequal and frequently unjust, transforms the abstract concept of the individual into an altogether less reassuring figure, certainly decentered and depotentialized with respect to the autonomous powers assumed and assured by the modern myth of citizenship (Asad, Formations of the Secular 5). If in Occidental liberalism the state is premised on the apparently sharp distinction and subsequent contracts between the public and the private spheres, Salvatore and LeVine argue that other forms of public participation emerge when public reason is based on “a practical reason sanctified by religious tradition, however variably interpreted. Such a perspective provides these discourses with a level of fluidity and adaptability that account in large measure for their success in mobilizing large numbers of people in their cause” (29). While the authors justly underline that this fluid ambivalence cannot be automatically labeled subaltern or counter-hegemonic, they argue that ideas of public welfare and social justice are entwined in a complex sociopolitical matrix. Here in an historical formation in which change is in custody to local coordinates and conditions, tradition—those popular forms of cultural life and religious customs that Gramsci analyzed—also provides and provokes sites of transformation. This is to think with Gramsci where the practice of reasoning occurs, inaugurating a potential passage from common to good sense: in the traditions of the religious lexicon of southern Italian

116

Iain Chambers

Catholicism, in the multiple and differentiated localities of modern Muslim communities. This is not to praise Islam (or Catholicism), or to extract from modern Muslim society an improved prospect of the common good. Rather, in contrasting the fluidity and embedded response to the forces of modernity with the abstract rigidity of occidental categorization, an intercultural critique is rendered possible: sense is not a category but, evoking a lineage that runs from Ibn Khaldûn through Giambattista Vico to Marx and Gramsci, an historical and cultural practice. This suggests that modern ideas of social justice and public welfare have a complex history in diverse cultural formations. These cannot be reduced to an Occidental version whose abstraction pretends universal validity. Outside and beyond the liberal repertoire of tolerance, integration, and assimilation in which Occidental categories are secured as the norm, largely immune from criticism, it becomes altogether more pressing to elaborate the idea of a new public sphere that will challenge hegemonic power formations whose authority may be predominantly considered religious or secular. What was once considered to be the property and privilege of the West— the knowledges, practices and institutions that inform justice, well-being and freedom—will come, as Edward Said and Gayatri Spivak might put it, to be “worlded” in a manner that confronts its “widespread social hyprocrisy,” and pose a challenge to its particular authority. There exist other ways of being in the world, of being in modernity. Returning religion to secular Europe, the fundamental point here is that Islam is not simply in Europe, but also profoundly of Europe. Today, this is not only the case among its immigrant populations from Asia, but has been so for well over a thousand years (that is, for a longer period than Christianity has existed around much of the Baltic Sea): medieval Islamic Spain, Sicily and Malta, the Ottoman Empire, and the medieval and modern Balkans. In other words, Islam refers to an internal component in the making of modern Europe and not simply the externalized other that mirrors European fears and self-fashioning. “Muslims are clearly present in a secular Europe and yet in an important sense absent from it. The problem of understanding Islam in Europe is primarily, so I claim, a matter of understanding how ‘Europe’ is conceptualized by Europeans” (Asad, Formations of the Secular 159). Historically, Islamic culture represented not simply the transmission of classical learning to medieval Europe, but was the site of a fundamental transformation and translation of that knowledge into modern concepts and concerns: from philosophy to agriculture, from poetry to medicine. Like today’s unwelcomed immigrant, this externalized and expelled body decenters and dispels the unquestioned referent of an autochthonous Europe and its elaboration in autonomous national components. The presumed homogeneity of a European space, temporality and identity is challenged by an altogether more complex, unstable geography, home to multiple rhythms, accents and compositions. Here, the assumed autonomy of the individual,

The “Unseen Order”

117

the presumed secularism of the state, the triumph of reason and the progressive universalism of its culture is interceded and interrupted by ongoing practices and possibilities in which traditions, translations and other modes of reasoning exceed the liberal coordinates of Occidental hegemony. Modernity is transformed from an existing state into a potential, folded into diverse “worldings” of the world whose dynamic and unpredictable outcome, as Gramsci always warned us, is ultimately unknown (Heidegger 170). It is precisely in this expanded world that we are confronted with the paradoxical fulfi llment of religion as a secular power. The fi nal point here, and returning to Gramsci’s insistence on the intricate interrelationship of Christianity and modernity, is that Occidental religious belief is not, as Max Weber taught us, simply transferred into the seemingly secular imperative of individual self-realization in the modern capitalist order and a boundless faith in rationalism. This understanding of secular conduct and salvation is itself essential to the formation and realization of today’s planetary bio-power and politics. We are not simply referring to observable rites and customs, and Europe, for example, is saturated in these, but to the ongoing practices that reveal the religious infrastructure of the West’s belief in itself. Through the racialization of the world in hierarchies of cultural value that mirror the historically sanctified ethnic superiority of the West, Occidental humanism, as the assumed epistemological and moral origin of knowledge, continues to propose its mission of worldly redemption in terms that are simultaneously racist and religious. In the persistence of race and religion as discriminatory categories, which continue to distinguish and subordinate both the nonOccidental world and its internal populations, past sentiments sedimented in the mishmash familiarity of common sense, invariably rush in to offer explanation for the existing bio-political order.12 Attentive to the intricate weave of cultural textures, to their historical formation and conjunctural power, Gramsci’s acute understanding of his present and our modernity, permits us to begin to excavate this archeology. It is there that we can uncover the unacknowledged faith and belief of modern secularism—that is, as Gramsci pointed out, its politics: the power to defi ne and decide. In the seemingly secular reach of Occidental empire, in its presumed ethical and ethnical preeminence, we come to discover the ancient rhythms of a theological heartbeat. Notes 1. 2. 3. 4. 5.

Chraibi 23; my translation. Gramsci, Quaderni del carcere. All the translations from the Quaderni are mine. Anidjar, Semites: Race, Religion, Literature 47. See Jedlowski. Here is Gilles Deleuze describing Pasolini’s cinema: “[W]hat characterises Pasolini’s cinema is a poetic consciousness, which is not strictly aestheticist or technicist, but rather mystical or ‘sacred.’ This allows Pasolini to bring the

118

6. 7. 8.

9. 10. 11.

12.

Iain Chambers perception-image, or the neurosis of his characters, on to a level of vulgarity and bestiality in the lowest subject-matter, while reflecting them in a pure, poetic consciousness, animated by the mythical or sacralising element” (77). Anidjar 40; Brague’s thesis is well explored in Salvatore 29–56. Jacques Derrida, Rogues: Two Essays on Reason; Robert Young, White Mythologies: Writing History and the West. The presence of Christianity in everyday life in the West—from the news of the pope every evening on all channels of Italian television, the ubiquity of the cross in public schools and hospitals, to being a fashion accessory around people’s necks accompanied by the public expression of faith by major political leaders—is often in striking contrast to the altogether more discreet civic presence of Islam in many Muslim countries. This is an ironic reference to Durkheim’s idea of religion as the transcendental power of society itself. For further discussion on the intertwining of religion and secularism in the formation of modernity, see Taylor. For example, the Habermasian conception of the “public sphere,” and its rigid dependency upon the liberal category of the “private citizen” (Salvatore and LeVine 5–7). See Ash Amin, “The Remainders of Race.”

6

Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century Partha Chatterjee

Peasant Society Today The fi rst volume of Subaltern Studies was published in 1982, twenty-five years ago. I was part of the editorial group that launched, under the leadership of Ranajit Guha, this critical engagement with postcolonial modernity from the standpoint of the subaltern classes, especially the peasantry. In the quarter of a century since then, there has been, I believe, a fundamental change in the historical situation of postcoloniality. The new conditions under which global flows of capital, commodities, information, and people are now regulated—a complex set of phenomena generally clubbed under the category of globalization—have created both new opportunities and new obstacles for postcolonial countries. The old idea of a Third World sharing a common history of colonial oppression and backwardness is no longer as persuasive as it was in the 1960s. The trajectory of economic growth taken by the countries of Asia has diverged radically from that of most African countries. The phenomenal growth of China and India in recent years has set in motion a process of social change that, in its scale and speed, is unprecedented in human history. It is now well known that Subaltern Studies was inspired by the prison writings of Antonio Gramsci in which he sketched a methodological outline for a “history of the subaltern classes.” In these writings, Gramsci used the word subalterno (subaltern) in at least two senses. In one, he used it as a code for the industrial proletariat. But against the thrust of orthodox Marxist thinking, he emphasized that in its rise to power, the bourgeoisie did not simply impose a domination through the coercive apparatus of the state, but transformed the cultural and ideological institutions of civil society to construct a hegemony over society as a whole, even eliciting in the process the acquiescence of the subaltern classes. In Gramsci’s analysis of capitalist society, the central place is occupied by questions such as the relation of state and civil society, the connections between the nation, the people, the bourgeoisie and other ruling classes, the role of intellectuals in creating the social hegemony of the bourgeoisie, strategies for building a counter-hegemonic alliance, and so on. In the second sense, Gramsci talked of the subaltern classes in pre-capitalist

120

Partha Chatterjee

social formations. Here he was referring to the more general relationship of domination and subordination in class-divided societies. But specifically in the context of Southern Italy, he wrote about the subordination of the peasantry. Gramsci was very critical of the negative and dismissive attitude of European Marxists toward the culture, beliefs, practices, and political potential of the peasantry. Positioning himself against this attitude, he wrote about the distinct characteristics of peasants, the religious beliefs and practices, language and cultural products, the everyday lives and struggles, and of the need for revolutionary intellectuals to study and understand them. But he also highlighted the limits of peasant consciousness, which was fragmented, passive and dependent, contrasted with the comprehensiveness, originality and active historical dynamism of the ruling classes. Even at moments of resistance, peasant consciousness remained enveloped by the dominant ideologies of the ruling classes. These discussions by Gramsci were turned to productive use by historians of South Asia writing in the 1980s. Twenty-five years later, I believe it is important for scholars of Asia to revisit the question of the peasantry in postcolonial societies. This is not because I think the advance of capitalist industrial growth is inevitably breaking down peasant communities and turning peasants into proletarian workers, as predicted innumerable times in the last century and a half. On the contrary, I will argue that the forms of capitalist industrial growth in the twenty-fi rst century may, in large agrarian countries like China, India and the countries of Southeast Asia, make room for the preservation of peasant production and peasant cultures, but under completely altered conditions. The analysis of these emergent forms of postcolonial capitalism requires new conceptual work in which, I will now argue, the writings of Gramsci continue to be of great analytical value. Let me begin by referring to a series of recent incidents of violent agitations in different regions of India against the acquisition of agricultural land for industry. The most talked-about incidents occurred in a place called Nandigram in West Bengal where there was a proposal to acquire 14,000 acres of agricultural land to set up a special economic zone for chemical industries. In January 2008, when news spread of the possible acquisition of land, armed villagers chased out all government officials, policemen and supporters of the ruling Communist Party; dug up roads, destroyed bridges and sealed off the entire area to outsiders. After a standoff lasting two months, when the police and government supporters tried to enter the area by force, fourteen villagers were killed in police shootings. Even after the government announced that the chemical industry zone would be located elsewhere, the area continues to be disturbed. If these incidents had taken place twenty-five years ago, we would have seen in them the classic signs of peasant insurgency. Here were the longfamiliar features of a peasantry, tied to the land, and small-scale agriculture, united by the cultural and moral bonds of a local rural community, resisting

Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century

121

the agents of an external state and city-based commercial institutions by using both peaceful and violent means. Our analysis could have drawn on a long tradition of anthropological studies of peasant societies, focusing on the characteristic forms of dependence of peasant economies on external institutions such as the state and dominant classes, including landlords, moneylenders and traders, but also of the forms of autonomy in peasant cultures based on the solidarity of a local moral community. We could have also linked our discussion to a long tradition of political debates over the historical role of the peasantry under conditions of capitalist growth, beginning with the Marxist analysis in Western Europe of the inevitable dissolution of the peasantry as a result of the process of primitive accumulation of capital, Lenin’s debates in Russia with the Narodniks, Mao Zedong’s analysis in the Chinese Revolution, and the continuing debates over Gandhi’s vision of a free India where a mobilized peasantry in the villages would successfully resist the spread of industrial capitalism and the violence of the modern state. Moreover, using the insights drawn from Antonio Gramsci’s writings, we could have talked about the contradictory consciousness of the peasantry in which it was both dominated by the forms of the elite culture of the ruling classes and, at the same time, resistant to them. Twenty-five years ago, we would have seen these rural agitations in terms of the analysis provided by Ranajit Guha in his classic work Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency in Colonial India. I believe that analysis would be inappropriate today. The reasons are the following. First, the spread of governmental technologies in the postcolonial world in the last three decades, as a result of the deepening reach of the developmental state, has meant that the state is no longer an external entity to the peasant community. Governmental agencies distributing education, health services, food, roadways, water, electricity, agricultural technology, emergency relief and dozens of other welfare services have penetrated deep into the interior of everyday peasant life. Not only are peasants dependent on state agencies for these services, but they have also acquired considerable skill, albeit to a different degree in different areas, in manipulating and pressurizing these agencies to deliver benefits. Institutions of the state, or at least governmental agencies (whether state or non-state), have become internal aspects of the peasant community. Second, the spate of reforms in the structure of agrarian property, whether revolutionary as in China or gradual as in most parts of India and the other countries of Southeast Asia, has meant that except in isolated pockets, for the fi rst time in centuries, peasants no longer directly confront an exploiting class within the village, as in feudal or semi-feudal conditions. This has had consequences that are completely new for the range of strategies of peasant politics. Third, since the tax on land or agricultural produce is no longer a significant source of revenue for modern governments, the relation of the state to the peasantry is no longer directly extractive, as it often was in the past. Fourth, with the

122

Partha Chatterjee

rapid growth of cities and industrial regions, the possibility of peasants making a shift to urban and non-agricultural occupations is no longer a function of their pauperization and forcible separation from the land, but is often a voluntary choice, shaped by the perception of new opportunities and new desires. Fifth, with the spread of school education and widespread exposure to modern communications media such as the cinema, television and advertising, there is a strong and widespread desire among younger members of peasant families, both male and female, not to live as peasants in the village, but to move to the town or the city despite the hardships and uncertainties because of its lure of anonymity and upward mobility. This is particularly significant for countries like India, where the life of poor peasants in rural society is marked not only by the disadvantage of class but also by the discriminations of caste, compared to which the sheer anonymity of life in the city is often seen as liberating. A New Conceptual Framework I may have emphasized the novelty of the present situation too sharply; in actual fact, the changes have undoubtedly come more gradually over time. But I do believe that the novelty needs to be stressed at this time in order to ask, how do these new features of peasant life affect our received theories of the place of the peasantry in postcolonial countries? Kalyan Sanyal, an economist teaching in Kolkata, has attempted a fundamental revision of these theories in his recent book Rethinking Capitalist Development.1 This work, I think, well represents a new phase of using Gramsci to understand economic and political changes in postcolonial societies of the twenty-fi rst century. The key concept in Sanyal’s analysis is the primitive accumulation of capital—sometimes called primary or original accumulation of capital. Like Sanyal, I too prefer to use this term in Marx’s sense to mean the dissociation of the laborer from the means of labor. There is no doubt that this is the key historical process that brings peasant societies into crisis with the rise of capitalist production. Marx’s analysis in the last chapters of Volume 1 of Capital shows that the emergence of modern capitalist industrial production is invariably associated with the parallel process of the loss of the means of production on the part of primary producers such as peasants and artisans. The unity of labor with the means of labor, which is the basis of most precapitalist modes of production, is destroyed and a mass of laborers emerge who no longer possess the means of production. Needless to say, the unity of labor with the means of labor is the conceptual counterpart in political economy of the organic unity of most pre-capitalist rural societies by virtue of which peasants and rural artisans are said to live in close bonds of solidarity in a local rural community. This is the familiar anthropological description of peasant societies as well as the source of inspiration for many romantic writers and artists portraying rural life. This is also the unity that

Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century

123

is destroyed in the process of primitive accumulation of capital, throwing peasant societies into crisis. The analysis of this crisis has produced, as I have already indicated, a variety of historical narratives ranging from the inevitable dissolution of peasant societies to slogans of worker–peasant unity in the building of a future socialist society. Despite their differences, the common feature in all these narratives is the idea of transition. Peasants and peasant societies under conditions of capitalist development are always in a state of transition–whether from feudalism to capitalism or from pre-capitalist backwardness to socialist modernity. A central argument made by Sanyal in his book is that under present conditions of postcolonial development within a globalized economy, the narrative of transition is no longer valid. That is to say, although capitalist growth in a postcolonial society such as India is inevitably accompanied by the primitive accumulation of capital, the social changes that are brought about cannot be understood as a transition. How is that possible? The explanation has to do with the transformations in the last two decades in the globally dispersed understanding about the minimum functions as well as the available technologies of government. There is a growing sense now that certain basic conditions of life must be provided to people everywhere and that if the national or local governments do not provide them, someone else must, whether it is other states, international agencies, or nongovernmental organizations. Thus, while there is a dominant discourse about the importance of growth, which in recent times has come to mean almost exclusively capitalist growth, it is, at the same time, considered unacceptable that those who are dispossessed of their means of labor because of the primitive accumulation of capital should have no means of subsistence. This produces, says Sanyal, a curious process in which, on the one side, primary producers such as peasants, craftspeople and petty manufacturers lose their land and other means of production, but, on the other, are also provided by governmental agencies with the conditions for meeting their basic needs of livelihood. There is, says Sanyal, primitive accumulation as well as a parallel process of the reversal of the effects of primitive accumulation. It would be useful to illustrate this process with some examples. Historically, the process of industrialization in all agrarian countries has meant the eviction of peasants from the land, either because the land was taken over for urban or industrial development or because the peasant no longer had the resources to cultivate the land. Market forces were usually strong enough to force peasants to give up the land, but oftentimes, direct coercion was used by means of the legal and fi scal powers of the state. From colonial times, government authorities in India have used the right of eminent domain to acquire lands to be used for “public purposes,” offering only a token compensation, if any. The idea that peasants losing land must be resettled somewhere else and rehabilitated into a new livelihood was

124

Partha Chatterjee

rarely acknowledged. Historically, it has been said that the opportunities of migration of the surplus population from Europe to the settler colonies in the Americas and elsewhere made it possible to politically manage the consequences of primitive accumulation in Europe in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. No such opportunities exist today for India or China. More importantly, the technological conditions of early industrialization that created the demand for a substantial mass of industrial labor have long passed. Capitalist growth today is far more capital-intensive and technology-dependent than it was even some decades ago. Today, large sections of peasants who are victims of the primitive accumulation of capital are completely unlikely to be absorbed into the new capitalist sectors of growth. Therefore, without a specific government policy of resettlement, the peasants losing their land face the possibility of the complete loss of their means of livelihood. Under present globally prevailing normative ideas, this is considered unacceptable. Hence, the old-fashioned methods of putting down peasant resistance by armed repression have little chance of gaining legitimacy. The result is the widespread demand today for the rehabilitation of displaced people who lose their means of subsistence because of industrial and urban development. It is not, says Sanyal, as though primitive accumulation is halted or even slowed down, for primitive accumulation is the inevitable companion to capitalist growth. Rather, governmental agencies have to fi nd the resources to, as it were, reverse the consequences of primitive accumulation by providing alternative means of livelihood to those who have lost them. We know that it is not uncommon for developmental states to protect certain sectors of production that are currently the domain of peasants, artisans and small manufacturers against competition from large corporate fi rms. But this may be interpreted as an attempt to forestall primitive accumulation itself by preventing corporate capital from entering into areas such as food crop or vegetable production or handicraft manufacture. However, there are many examples in many countries, including India, of governments and nongovernment agencies offering easy loans to enable those without the means of sustenance to fi nd gainful employment. Such loans are often advanced without serious concern for profitability or the prospect of the loan being repaid, since the money advanced here is not driven by the motive of further accumulation of capital, but rather by that of providing the livelihood needs of the debtors—that is to say, by the motive of reversal of the effects of primitive accumulation. In recent years, these efforts have acquired the status of a globally circulating technology of poverty management: a notable instance is the micro-credit movement initiated by the Grameen Bank in Bangladesh and its founder, the Nobel Prize–winner Mohammed Yunus. Most of us are familiar now with stories of peasant women in rural Bangladesh forming groups to take loans from Grameen Bank to undertake small activities to supplement their livelihood and putting pressure on one another to repay the

Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century

125

loan so that they can qualify for another round of credit. Similar activities have been introduced quite extensively in India in recent years. Finally, as in other countries, government agencies in India provide some direct benefits to people who, because of poverty or other reasons, are unable to meet their basic consumption needs. This could be in the form of special poverty-removal programs, or schemes of guaranteed employment in public works, or even direct delivery of subsidized or free food. Thus, there are programs of supplying subsidized food grains to those designated as “below the poverty line,” guaranteed employment for up to a hundred days in the year, and free meals to children in primary schools. All of these may be regarded, in terms of our analysis, as direct interventions to reverse the effects of primitive accumulation. It is important to point out that except for the last example of direct provision of consumption needs, the other mechanisms of reversing the effects of primitive accumulation involve the intervention of the market. This is the other significant difference in the present conditions of peasant life from the traditional models we have known. Except in certain marginal pockets, peasant and craft production in India today is fully integrated into a market economy. Unlike a few decades ago, there is almost no sector of household production that can be described as intended wholly for self-consumption or non-monetized exchange within a local community. Virtually all peasant and artisan production is for sale in the market and all consumption needs are purchased from the market. This, as we shall see, has an important bearing on recent changes in the conditions of peasant politics. Transformed Structures of Political Power To place these changes within a structural frame that describes how political power is held and exercised in postcolonial India, I also need to provide an outline of the transformation that, I believe, has taken place in that structure in recent years. Here, once again, Indian scholars have sought help from Antonio Gramsci. Twenty-five years ago, the structure of state power in India was usually described by scholars in terms of a coalition of dominant classes—namely, the capitalists, the rich farmers and the bureaucracy—competing and aligning with one another within a political space supervised by a relatively autonomous state.2 The dominant class coalition model was given a robust theoretical shape in a classic essay by Sudipta Kaviraj in which, by using Antonio Gramsci’s idea of the “passive revolution” as a blocked dialectic, he was able to ascribe to the process of class domination in postcolonial India its own dynamic.3 Power had to be shared between the dominant classes because no one class had the ability to exercise hegemony on its own. But “sharing” was a process of ceaseless push and pull, with one class gaining a relative ascendancy at one point, only to lose it at another. Kaviraj provided us with a synoptic political history of the relative dominance and decline of

126

Partha Chatterjee

the industrial capitalists, the rural elites and the bureaucratic-managerial elite within the framework of the passive revolution of capital. The characteristic features of the passive revolution in India as described twenty years ago were the relative autonomy of the state as a whole from the bourgeoisie and the landed elites; the supervision of the state by an elected political leadership, a permanent bureaucracy, and an independent judiciary; the negotiation of class interests through a multi-party electoral system; a protectionist regime discouraging the entry of foreign capital and promoting import substitution; the leading role of the state sector in heavy industry, infrastructure, transport, telecommunications; banking, and so on; state control over the private manufacturing sector through a regime of licensing; and the relatively greater influence of industrial capitalists over the central government and that of the landed elites on the state governments. Passive revolution was a form that was marked by its difference from classical bourgeois democracy. But to the extent that capitalist democracy as established in Western Europe or North America served as the normative standard of bourgeois revolution, discussions of passive revolution in India carried with them the sense of a transitional system—from pre-colonial and colonial regimes to some yet-to-be-defi ned authentic modernity. The changes introduced since the 1990s, I believe, transformed this framework of class dominance. The crucial difference now is the dismantling of the license regime, greater entry of foreign capital and foreign consumer goods; and the opening up of sectors such as telecommunications, transport, infrastructure, mining, banking, insurance, and so forth, to private capital. This has led to a change in the very composition of the capitalist class. Instead of the earlier dominance of a few “monopoly” houses drawn from traditional merchant backgrounds and protected by the license and import substitution regime, there are now many more entrants into the capitalist class at all levels and much greater mobility within its formation. Unlike the earlier fear of foreign competition, there appears to be much greater confidence among Indian capitalists to make use of the opportunities opened up by global flows of capital, goods and services, including in recent times, significant exports of capital. The most dramatic event has been the rise of the Indian information technologies industry. But domestic manufacturing and services have also received a major spurt, leading to annual growth rates of 8% or 9% for the economy as a whole in the last few years. There have been several political changes as a result. Let me list a few that are relevant for our present discussion. First, there is a distinct ascendancy in the relative power of the corporate capitalist class as compared to the landed elites. The political means by which this recent dominance has been achieved needs to be investigated more carefully because it was not achieved through the mechanism of electoral mobilization (which used to be the source of the political power of the landed elites). Second, the dismantling of the license regime has opened up a new field of competition between state governments

Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century

127

to woo capitalist investment, both domestic and foreign. This has resulted in the involvement of state-level political parties and leaders with the interests of national and international corporate capital in unprecedented ways. Third, although the state continues to be the most important mediating apparatus in negotiating between confl icting class interests, the autonomy of the state in relation to the dominant classes appears to have been redefi ned. Crucially, the earlier role of the bureaucratic-managerial class, or more generally of the urban middle classes, in leading and operating, both socially and ideologically, the autonomous interventionist activities of the developmental state has significantly weakened. There is a strong ideological tendency among the urban middle classes today to view the state apparatus as ridden with corruption, inefficiency and populist political venality and a much greater social acceptance of the professionalism and commitment to growth and efficiency of the corporate capitalist sector. The urban middle class, which once played such a crucial role in producing and running the autonomous developmental state of the passive revolution, appears now to have largely come under the moral-political sway of the bourgeoisie. It would be a mistake, however, to think that the result is a convergence of the Indian political system with the classical models of capitalist democracy. The critical difference, as I have pointed out elsewhere, has been produced by a split in the field of the political between a domain of properly constituted civil society and a more ill-defi ned and contingently activated domain of political society (Chatterjee, The Politics of the Governed 53–78). Civil society in India today, peopled largely by the urban middle classes, is the sphere that seeks to be congruent with the normative models of bourgeois civil society and represents the domain of capitalist hegemony. If this were the only relevant political domain, then India today would probably be indistinguishable from other Western capitalist democracies. But there is the other domain of what I have called political society that includes large sections of the rural population and the urban poor. These people do, of course, have the formal status of citizens and can exercise their franchise as an instrument of political bargaining. But they do not relate to the organs of the state in the same way that the middle classes do, nor do governmental agencies treat them as proper citizens belonging to civil society. Those in political society make their claims on government, and in turn are governed, not within the framework of stable constitutionally defi ned rights and laws, but rather through temporary, contextual and unstable arrangements arrived at through direct political negotiations. The latter domain, which represents the vast bulk of democratic politics in India, is not under the moral-political leadership of the capitalist class. Hence, my argument is that the framework of passive revolution is still valid for India. But its structure and dynamic have undergone a change. The capitalist class has come to acquire a position of moral-political hegemony over civil society, consisting principally of the urban middle classes. It exercises its

128

Partha Chatterjee

considerable influence over both the central and the state governments, not through electoral mobilization of political parties and movements but largely through the bureaucratic-managerial class, the increasingly influential print and visual media, and the judiciary and other independent regulatory bodies. The dominance of the capitalist class within the state structure as a whole can be inferred from the virtual consensus among all major political parties about the priorities of rapid economic growth led by private investment, both domestic and foreign. It is striking that even the Communist parties have, in practice if not in theory, joined this consensus. This means that as far as the party system is concerned, it does not matter which particular combination of parties comes to power in the central government, or even in most of the states: support for rapid capitalist growth is guaranteed to continue. This is evidence of the current success of the passive revolution. However, the practices of the state also include the large range of governmental activities in political society. Here there are locally dominant interests, such as those of landed elites, small producers and local traders who are able to exercise political influence through their powers of electoral mobilization. In the old understanding of the passive revolution, these interests would have been seen as potentially opposed to those of the industrial bourgeoisie; the confl icts would have been temporarily resolved through a compromise worked out within the party system and the autonomous apparatus of the state. Now, I believe, there is a new dynamic logic that ties the operations of political society with the hegemonic role of the bourgeoisie in civil society and its dominance over the state structure as a whole. This logic is supplied by the requirement, explained earlier, of reversing the effects of primitive accumulation of capital. To describe how this logic serves to integrate civil and political society into a new structure of the passive revolution, let me return to the subject of the peasantry. Political Society and the Management of Non-Corporate Capital The integration with the market means that large sections of what was called the subsistence economy, once the classic description of small peasant agriculture, have now come fully under the sway of capital. This is a key development that must crucially affect our understanding of peasant society in India today. There is now a degree of connectedness between peasant cultivation, trade and credit networks in agricultural commodities, transport networks and petty manufacturing, and services in rural markets, small towns, and so forth, that makes it necessary for us to categorize all of them as part of a single complex. A common description of this is the unorganized or informal sector. Usually, a unit belonging to the informal sector is identified in terms of the small size of the enterprise, the small number of laborers employed, or the relatively unregulated nature of the business. In terms of the analytical

Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century

129

framework I have presented here, I will propose a distinction between the formal and the informal sectors of today’s economy in terms of a difference between corporate and non-corporate forms of capital. My argument is that the characteristics I have described of peasant societies today are best understood as the marks of non-corporate capital. To the extent that peasant production is deeply embedded within market structures, investments and returns are conditioned by forces emanating from the operations of capital. In this sense, peasant production shares many connections with informal units in manufacturing, trade and services operating in rural markets, small towns and even, large cities. We can draw many refi ned distinctions between corporate and non-corporate forms of capital. But the key distinction I wish to emphasize is the following. The fundamental logic that underlies the operations of corporate capital is further accumulation of capital, usually signified by the maximization of profit. For non-corporate organizations of capital, while profit is not irrelevant, it is dominated by another logic—that of providing the livelihood needs of those working in the units. This difference is crucial for the understanding of the so-called informal economy and, by extension, as I will argue, of peasant society. Let me illustrate with a couple of familiar examples from the non-agricultural informal sector and then return to the subject of peasants. Most of us are familiar with the phenomenon of street vendors in Indian cities—they occupy street space, usually violating municipal laws, they erect permanent stalls, use municipal services such as water and electricity, and do not pay taxes. To carry on their trade under these conditions, they usually organize themselves into associations to deal with the municipal authorities, the police and credit agencies such as banks and corporate fi rms that manufacture and distribute the commodities they sell on the streets. These associations are often large and the volume of business they encompass can be quite considerable. Obviously, operating within a public and anonymous market situation, the vendors are subject to the standard conditions of profitability of their businesses. But to ensure that everyone is able to meet their livelihood needs, the association will usually try to limit the number of vendors who can operate in a given area and prevent the entry of newcomers. On the other hand, there are many examples where, if the businesses are doing particularly well, the vendors do not, like corporate capitalists, continue to accumulate on an expanded scale, but rather agree to extend their membership and allow new entrants. To cite another example, in most cities and towns of India, the transport system depends heavily on private operators who run buses and auto-rickshaws. There is the frequent violation of regulations such as licenses, safety standards, and pollution norms. Although most operators own only one or two vehicles each, they form associations to negotiate with transport authorities and the police over fares and routes, and control the frequency of services and entry of new operators to ensure that a minimum income, and not much more than a minimum income, is guaranteed to all.

130

Partha Chatterjee

In my book The Politics of the Governed, I have described the form of governmental regulation of population groups such as street vendors, illegal squatters and others, whose habitation or livelihood verge on the margins of legality, as political society. In political society, I have argued, people are not regarded by the state as proper citizens possessing rights and belonging to the properly constituted civil society. Rather, they are seen to belong to particular population groups, with specific empirically established and statistically described characteristics, which are targets of particular governmental policies. Since dealing with many of these groups implies the tacit acknowledgement of various illegal practices, governmental agencies will often treat such cases as exceptions, justified by very specific and special circumstances, so that the structure of general rules and principles is not compromised. Thus, illegal squatters may be given water supply or electricity connections but on exceptional grounds so as not to club them with regular customers having secure legal title to their property, or street vendors may be allowed to trade under specific conditions that distinguish them from regular shops and businesses who comply with the laws and pay taxes. All of this makes the claims of people in political society a matter of constant political negotiation and the results are never secure or permanent. Their entitlements, even when recognized, never quite become rights. To connect the question of political society with my earlier discussion on the process of primitive accumulation of capital, I now wish to advance the following proposition. Civil society is where corporate capital is hegemonic, whereas political society is the space of management of non-corporate capital. I have argued that since the 1990s, corporate capital, and along with it the class of corporate capitalists, have achieved a hegemonic position over civil society in India. This means that the logic of accumulation, expressed at this time in the demand that national economic growth be maintained at a very high rate and that the requirements of corporate capital be given priority, holds sway over civil society—that is to say, over the urban middle classes. It also means that the educational, professional, and social aspirations of the middle classes have become tied with the fortunes of corporate capital. There is now a powerful tendency to insist on the legal rights of proper citizens, to impose civic order in public places and institutions and to treat the messy world of the informal sector and political society with a degree of intolerance. A vague but powerful feeling seems to prevail among the urban middle classes that rapid growth will solve all problems of poverty and unequal opportunities. The informal sector, which does not have a corporate structure and does not function principally according to the logic of accumulation, does not, however, lack organization. As I have indicated in my examples, those who function in the informal sector often have large, and in many cases quite powerful and effective, organizations. They need to organize precisely to function in the modern market and governmental spaces. Traditional organizations

Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century

131

of peasant and artisan societies are not adequate for the task. I believe this organization is as much of a political activity as it is an economic one. Given the logic of non-corporate capital that I have described, the function of these organizations is to successfully operate within the rules of the market and of governmental regulations in order to ensure the livelihood needs of its members. Most of those who provide leadership in organizing people, both owners and workers, operating in the informal sector are actually or potentially political leaders. Thus, it is not incorrect to say that the management of noncorporate capital under such conditions is a political function that is carried out by political leaders. The existence and survival of the vast assemblage of so-called informal units of production in India today, including peasant production, is directly dependent on the successful operation of certain political functions. That is what is facilitated by the process of democracy. The organizations that can carry out these political functions have to be innovative—neither the history of the cooperative movement nor that of socialist collective organization provides any model that can be copied by these non-corporate organizations of capital in India. What is noticeable here is a strong sense of attachment to small-scale private property and, at the same time, a willingness to organize and cooperate in order to protect the fragile basis of livelihood that is constantly under threat from the advancing forces of corporate capital. However, it appears that these organizations of non-corporate capital are stronger, at least at this time, in the non-agricultural informal sectors in cities and towns and less so among the rural peasantry. This means that while the organization of non-corporate capital in urban areas has developed relatively stable and effective forms and is able, by mobilizing governmental support through the activities of political society, to sustain the livelihood needs of the urban poor in the informal sector, the rural poor, consisting of small peasants and rural laborers, are still dependent on direct governmental support for their basic needs and are less able to make effective organized use of the market in agricultural commodities. This challenge lies at the heart of the recent controversies over “farmer suicides” as well as the ongoing debates over acquisition of agricultural land for industry. It is clear that the sector of agricultural production will face rapid changes in the near future and Indian democracy will have to invent new forms of organization to ensure the survival of a vast rural population. Peasant Culture and Politics I have mentioned before that state agencies, or governmental agencies generally, including NGOs that carry out governmental functions, are no longer an external entity in relation to peasant society. This has had several implications. First, because various welfare and developmental functions are now widely recognized to be necessary tasks for government in relation to the poor, which includes large sections of peasants, these fields of health,

132

Partha Chatterjee

education, basic inputs for agricultural production and the provision of basic necessities of life are now demanded from governmental agencies as a matter of legitimate claims by peasants. This means that government officials and political representatives in rural areas are constantly besieged by demands for various welfare and developmental benefits. It also means that peasants learn to operate the levers of the governmental system, to apply pressure at the right places or negotiate for better terms. This is where the everyday operations of democratic politics, organization, and leadership come into play. Second, the response of governmental agencies to such demands is usually flexible, based on calculations of costs and returns. In most cases, the strategy is to break up the benefit-seekers into smaller groups, defi ned by specific demographic or social characteristics, so that there can be a flexible policy that does not regard the entire rural population as a single homogeneous mass. The intention is precisely to fragment the benefit seekers and hence divide the potential opposition to the state. One of the most remarkable features of the recent agitations in India over the acquisition of land for industry is that despite the continued use of the old rhetoric of peasant solidarity, there are clearly significant sections of people in these villages that do not join these agitations because they feel they stand to gain from the government policy. Third, this field of negotiations opened up by flexible policies of seeking and delivering benefits creates a new competitive spirit among benefit-seekers. Since peasants now confront, not landlords or traders as direct exploiters, but rather governmental agencies from whom they expect benefits, the state is blamed for perceived inequalities in the distribution of benefits. Thus, peasants will accuse officials and political representatives of favoring cities at the cost of the countryside. Sections of peasants will complain of being deprived while those from other regions, ethnic groups, or political loyalties are allegedly favored. The charge against state agencies is not one of exploitation but discrimination. This gives a completely new quality to peasant politics, one that is completely missing in the classical understandings of peasant society. Fourth, unlike the old forms of peasant insurgency that characterized much of the history of peasant society for centuries, there is, I believe, a quite different quality in the role of violence in contemporary peasant politics. While subaltern peasant revolts of the old kind had their own notions of strategy and tactics, they were characterized, as Ranajit Guha showed in his classic work, by strong community solidarity on the one side and negative opposition to the perceived exploiters on the other. Today, the use of violence in peasant agitations seems to have a far more calculative, almost utilitarian logic, designed to draw attention to specific grievances with a view to seeking appropriate governmental benefits. A range of deliberate tactics is followed to elicit the right responses from officials, political leaders, and especially the media. This is probably the most significant change in the nature of peasant politics in the last two or three decades.

Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century

133

As far as peasant agriculture is concerned, however, things are much less clearly developed. Small peasant agriculture, even though it is thoroughly enmeshed in market connections, also feels threatened by the market. There is, in particular, an unfamiliarity with, and deep suspicion of, corporate organizations. Peasants appear to be far less able to deal with the uncertainties of the market than they are able to secure governmental benefits. In the last few years, there have been hundreds of reported suicides of peasants who suddenly fell into huge debts because they were unable to realize the expected price from their agricultural products, such as tobacco and cotton. Peasants feel that the markets for these commercial crops are manipulated by large mysterious forces that are entirely beyond their control. Unlike many organizations in the informal non-agricultural sector in urban areas that can effectively deal with corporate fi rms for the supply of inputs or the sale of their products, peasants have been unable thus far to build similar organizations. This is the large area of the management of peasant agriculture, not as subsistence production for self-consumption, but as the field of non-corporate capital, that remains a challenge. It is important to emphasize that contrary to what is suggested by the depoliticized idea of governmentality, the quality of politics in the domain of political society is by no means a mechanical transaction of benefits and services. Even as state agencies try by constantly adjusting their flexible policies to break up large combinations of claimants, the organization of demands in political society can adopt highly emotive resources of solidarity and militant action. Democratic politics in India is daily marked by passionate and often violent agitations to protest discrimination and to secure claims. The fact that the objectives of such agitations are framed by the conditions of governmentality is no reason to think that they cannot arouse considerable passion and affective energy. Collective actions in political society cannot be depoliticized by framing them within the grid of governmentality because the activities of governmentality affect the very conditions of livelihood and social existence of the groups they target. Interestingly, even though the claims made by different groups in political society are for governmental benefits, these cannot often be met by the standard application of rules and frequently require the declaration of an exception. Thus, when a group of people living or cultivating on illegally occupied land, or selling goods on the street claim the right to continue with their activities, or demand compensation for moving somewhere else, they are in fact inviting the state to declare their case as an exception to the universally applicable rule. They do not demand that the right to private property in land be abolished or that the regulations on trade licenses and sales taxes be set aside. When the state acknowledges these demands, it too must do so not by the simple application of administrative rules but rather by a political decision to declare an exception. The governmental response

134

Partha Chatterjee

to demands in political society is also, therefore, irreducibly political rather than merely administrative. I must point out one other significant characteristic of the modalities of democratic practice in political society. This has to do with the relevance of numbers. Ever since Tocqueville in the early nineteenth century, it is a common argument that electoral democracies foster the tyranny of the majority. However, mobilizations in political society are often premised on the strategic manipulation of relative electoral strengths rather than on the expectation of commanding a majority. Indeed, the frequently spectacular quality of actions in political society, including the resort to violence, is a sign of the ability of relatively small groups of people to make their voices heard and to register their claims with governmental agencies. As a matter of fact, it could even be said that the activities of political society represent a continuing critique of the paradoxical reality in all capitalist democracies of equal citizenship and majority rule, on the one hand, and the dominance of property and privilege, on the other. But the underside of political society is the utter marginalization of those groups who do not even have the strategic leverage of electoral mobilization. In every region of India, there exist marginal groups of people who are unable to gain access to the mechanisms of political society. They are often marked by their exclusion from peasant society, such as low-caste groups who do not participate in agriculture or tribal peoples who depend more on forest products or pastoral occupations than on agriculture. Political society and electoral democracy have not given these groups the means to make effective claims on governmentality. In this sense, these marginalized groups represent an outside beyond the boundaries of political society. The important difference represented by activities in political society when compared to the movements of democratic mobilization familiar to us from the twentieth century is its lack of a perspective of transition. While there is much passion aroused over ending the discriminations of caste or ethnicity or asserting the rightful claims of marginal groups, there is little conscious effort to view these agitations as directed toward a fundamental transformation of the structures of political power, as they were in the days of nationalist and socialist mobilizations. On the contrary, if anything, it is the bourgeoisie, hegemonic in civil society and dominant within the state structure as a whole, which appears to have a narrative of transition—from stagnation to rapid growth, from backwardness and poverty to modernity and prosperity, from Third World insignificance to major world-power status. Perhaps this is not surprising if one remembers the class formation of the passive revolution: with the landed elites pushed to a subordinate position and the bureaucratic-managerial class won over by the bourgeoisie, it is the capitalist class that has now acquired a position to set the terms to which other political formations can only respond.

Gramsci in the Twenty-First Century

135

The unity of the state system as a whole is now maintained by relating civil society to political society through the logic of reversal of the effects of primitive accumulation. Once this logic is recognized by the bourgeoisie as a necessary political condition for the continued rapid growth of corporate capital, the state, with its mechanisms of electoral democracy, becomes the field for the political negotiation of demands for the transfer of resources, through fiscal and other means, from the accumulation economy to governmental programs aimed at providing the livelihood needs of the poor and the marginalized. The autonomy of the state, and that of the bureaucracy, now lies in their power to adjudicate the quantum and form of transfer of resources to the so-called “social sector of expenditure.” Ideological differences, such as those between the right and the left, for instance, are largely about the amount and modalities of social sector expenditure, such as poverty removal programs. These differences do not question the dynamic logic that binds civil society to political society under the dominance of capital. Let me conclude by pointing out once more that this analysis of postcolonial capitalist development in the twenty-fi rst century has been greatly enabled by the analytical insights given to us by Antonio Gramsci, writing against the historical background of backward capitalism in Italy in the early twentieth century. It is a measure of the power of his thought that it still provides the resources for scholars in the postcolonial world today to understand their rapidly transforming world. Perhaps it is also significant that these scholars have taken seriously Gramsci’s advice that there is no merit in blindly asserting an “optimism of the will” without fi rst coming to grips with the lessons offered by a pessimistic intellect. The present dynamics of the passive revolution make it extremely difficult to propose credible counter-hegemonic strategies. Yet, even if a perspective of transition is unavailable, our analysis using Gramscian concepts makes us aware of the many spaces within postcolonial capitalist democracy that have not come under the hegemony of corporate capital and, given the present form of the passive revolution, are unlikely to do so. Those are the spaces that remain open for bold and innovative counter-hegemonic strategies. I also suggest that the distinction between corporate and non-corporate capital appears to be coinciding with the divide between civil society and political society. Once again following Gramsci, who himself experienced and fought against the rise of fascism, we can anticipate some ominous consequences. We have seen in several Asian countries what may be called a revolt of “proper citizens” against the unruliness and corruption of systems of popular political representation. In Thailand in 2006, there was an armyled coup that ousted a popularly elected government. The action seemed to draw support from the urban middle classes who expressed their disapproval of what they considered wasteful and corrupt populist expenditure aimed at gaining the support of the rural population. The following year, there was a similar army-backed coup in Bangladesh where plans for parliamentary

136

Partha Chatterjee

elections were indefi nitely postponed while an interim government took emergency measures to clean the system of supposedly “corrupt” politicians. Reports suggest that that move was initially welcomed by the urban middle classes. In India, a significant feature in recent years has been the withdrawal of the urban middle classes from political activities altogether: there is widespread resentment in the cities of the populism and corruption of all political parties that, it is said, are driven principally by the motive of gaining votes at the cost of ensuring the conditions of rapid economic growth. There is no doubt that this reflects the hegemony of the logic of corporate capital among the urban middle classes. The fact, however, is that the bulk of the population in India lives outside the orderly zones of proper civil society. It is in political society that they have to be fed and clothed and given work, if only to ensure the long-term and relatively peaceful well-being of civil society. That is the dilemma of political management on which the future of the passive revolution under conditions of democracy depends. We hope we have better intellectual and political resources today to fight the forces of reaction than we did during the life of Antonio Gramsci. Notes 1. See Sanyal. 2. See Bardhan. 3. See Kaviraj, “A Critique of Passive Revolution” 2429–44.

7

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle On Jia Zhangke as an Organic Intellectual Pheng Cheah

Antonio Gramsci’s concept of the organic intellectual is an important analytical category for understanding the political vocation of revolutionary thinkers and writers from the colonial and postcolonial peripheries since the period of decolonization to the present. As a member of that stratum of a social group that expresses and gives it homogeneity and self-consciousness about its own vocation, the organic intellectual of a revolutionary social group has a fundamental role in reaching out to the mass members of the group to aid them in articulating and organizing their feelings and experiences with the aim of cultivating a revolutionary consciousness. Gramsci’s concept communicates directly with the thought of postcolonial intellectuals and cultural workers such as Ayi Kwei Armah (Ghana), Ngugi wa Thiong’o (Kenya), Frantz Fanon (Martinique/Algeria) and Amilcar Cabral (GuineaBissau). The following comment by Armah is representative. The question of any individual African, Afro-American, Afro-Caribbean or any other kind of African-related intellectual is whether to decide to go along with this useless and destructive parasitical bourgeois élite or to rack our brains to fi nd a way to be useful not to the system that oppresses our people but to our people themselves . . . To Fanon, culture meant only one thing, an environment shaped to help us and our children grow—shaped by ourselves in action against the system that enslaves us. (Armah 41–42)1 However, the continuing pertinence of the concept of the organic intellectual for analyzing progressive political struggles in the peripheries of the contemporary world system can be questioned on two grounds. First, the organic intellectual’s task of organizing his or her social group within the specific context of the historical development of its cultural resources and values indicates that this organizational function is geographically limited, exercised over a territorially bound social space, the civil society of a nationstate. Yet, the borders of this social space are gradually being undermined

138

Pheng Cheah

by globalization. Second, the emphasis on counter-hegemonic struggle for radical social change presupposes the telos of a socialist revolution that may no longer be plausible in today’s post-socialist world. This chapter attempts a critical examination of the limits of Gramsci’s concept by considering the case of Jia Zhangke (賈樟柯), the renowned fi lmmaker from the People’s Republic of China (PRC). Throughout his career, Jia has been concerned with portraying the negative impact of capitalist globalization on local populations in China. In their focus on the material transformations of China’s urban and provincial landscape as a result of its accelerated integration into the global capitalist system, Jia’s recent fi lms are celluloid interpretations of the ruined landscape of rapidly globalizing China and the plight of its masses in the same way that Charles Dickens’ Hard Times or Elizabeth Gaskell’s novels are novels of the English Industrial Revolution. Jia is an especially interesting test case for evaluating the concept of the organic intellectual because the PRC, one of the few remaining socialist states in the world, is often considered by world systems theorists as a critical site for examining whether there are alternatives to the social formations of capitalist market economies.2 An organic intellectual of the masses would attempt to arrest the slide of Chinese society into a post-socialist market system, to divert China from being transformed in the image of neoliberal capitalism by returning Chinese society back to critical elements from its socialist past so that its political economy and society remains that of market socialism. But if this critical task turns out to be implausible or even impossible, then the vocation and function of the radical organic intellectual is no longer viable in the contemporary world, which is thereby inevitably post-socialist. The Organic Intellectual: Organization, the Vitality of the Social Organism and the Circle of Organic Form The important function that Gramsci accords to the organic intellectual in counter-hegemonic struggles can only be adequately understood through the semantic, conceptual and metaphorical connections between the adjective, “organic,” the activity of organization, and the modern philosophical understanding of the organism as an organized and self-organizing system of means and ends. Gramsci’s definition of the organic intellectual begins as follows: Every social group, coming into existence on the original terrain of an essential function in the world of economic production, creates together with itself, organically, one or more strata of intellectuals which give it homogeneity and an awareness of its own function not only in the economic but also in the social and political fields. (SPNB 5) The genesis of organic intellectuals occurs according to laws of functional development. In the first place, a social group comes into being in correspondence

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

139

with a function of economic production. Second, that social group’s genesis requires an almost equiprimordial generation of intellectuals who fulfill the specific function of thematizing and presenting the function of that social group to itself, thereby enabling the group to recognize itself and its function in different fields. The word, organic, has two related meanings. It refers to the fact that the genesis of the intellectual strata in question is autochthonous, that is, grows out of or is generated by the social group from within itself. But it also points to the fact that such intellectuals are able to give to the social group its proper organic form, or more precisely, to complete this form. This organic form is both a final and a formal cause.3 It gives to the social group an awareness of its ends or aims, the “for-the-sake-of-which” the social group came into being in the first place. But such ends are also ideational forms that arrange the masses into relations with each other such that they are members of a social group, thereby shaping the social group by giving it its form. Hence, the organic form is also a technical power of organization, which Gramsci regards as synonymous with human intellectual activity.4 This power of organization is not the unique preserve of those who have the socially designated function of intellectuals. 5 It is already operative in the economic sphere in the person of the capitalist entrepreneur, who himself represents a higher level of social elaboration, already characterised by a certain directive [dirigente] and technical (i.e. intellectual) capacity: he must have a certain technical capacity, not only in the limited sphere of his activity and initiative but in other spheres as well, at least in those which are closest to economic production. He must be an organizer of masses of men; he must be an organizer of the “confidence” of investors in his business, of the customers for his product, etc. (SPNB 5) Gramsci’s emphasis on organization radically modifies the conventional economic determinism of Marxist theory on two related levels. At the systemic level, the development of social forms is no longer understood in terms of a rigid base-superstructure model. At the level of individual human behavior, the fundamental human activity of work is now expanded to include intellectual processes. With regard to the development of social forms, Gramsci emphasizes the importance of organization in the economic sphere and all other adjacent spheres. The process of organization concerns the sum total of technical or means–ends causal relations that concern society. To organize is to establish and regulate relations between various social classes, what Marx called the “reproduction” of social relations. Gramsci emphasizes the link between organization and the social and political organism. If not all entrepreneurs, at least an élite amongst them must have the capacity to be an organiser of society in general, including all its complex

140

Pheng Cheah organism of services, right up to the state organism, because of the need to create the conditions most favourable to the expansion of their own class; or at least they must possess the capacity to choose the deputies (specialised employees) to whom to entrust this activity of organising the general system of relationships external to the business itself. (SPNB 5–6)

The elaboration of organic intellectuals is a second-order process that follows on the elaboration of the new social class that is assuming hegemony. On the one hand, then, the various organic intellectuals of the capitalist bourgeoisie—Gramsci mentions “the industrial technician, the specialist in political economy, the organisers of a new culture, of a new legal system” (SPNB 5)—are epiphenomena or reflections of the entrepreneur, his deputies, or delegates. On the other hand, however, precisely because the organic intellectual is a specialization of activities of the new social type that were only previously present in an unelaborated, embryonic form, he is also a crystallization of these fundamental activities and brings out their defi ning character in the sharpest relief. This means that culturalintellectual work is not a mere reflection of the economic infrastructure from which it is elaborated. It has a causal capacity to change society precisely because like economic activity, it is also a form of organization. Indeed, insofar as it is the crystallization of the capacity for organization into specialized functions, intellectual work is even a necessary condition for maintaining economic activity. The organizational connections between organic intellectuals, their social class and economic production are therefore organic in a third sense: they are functions of society conceived in analogy with the causality of an organism or a self-organized being.6 It may initially have seemed that the entrepreneur qua representative of the capitalist class is the agent of organizational activity. But it becomes clear that the social organism is also an “agent.” The entrepreneur has the capacity to be an organizer only because he is an elaboration of the social organism and, hence, part of society’s process of epigenesis. The same reasoning applies to the organic intellectual. He is also an agent at the same time that he is an elaboration of larger social forces. Hence, far from characterizing a form of existence that is static, pre-given or innate, the “organic” refers instead to a dynamic process of the inner-directed development of a bounded whole, one that is connected to its members in relations of complete reciprocity and mutual feedback such that both the members and the social whole are means and ends of each other, where members and whole are equally active and possess agency. Such a whole would be an integrated totality. Herein resides the organic intellectual’s fundamental causal power in the development of society: society requires and, indeed, is nothing other than the process of organization. The intellectual is the organizer in its purest shape, the meta-organizer who completes the organic form of a society at a

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

141

given historical conjuncture because he articulates the ends of the hegemonic social class as ideal and formal causes. Put another way, organization is the constitutive process of social elaboration and one of the products of this elaboration is the organic intellectual who personifies the organizational activity of a given social class. The organic intellectual is of paramount importance in creating the web of relations that makes society functional according to the ends of his social group. More specifically, organic intellectuals of the hegemonic social class consciously complete the self-organization of society by creating and maintaining social relations in the image of their class. Gramsci’s distinction between traditional and organic intellectuals should also be understood according to this organismic schema. Traditional intellectuals refer to intellectuals that seem to transcend the historical development of social and political forms. They do not subsist in an organismic feedback relation with social groups because they are professional intellectuals who predate the emergence of the hegemonic social group and present themselves as independent of the latter.7 However, this autonomy from political struggles is false because all traditional intellectual strata were elaborated from hegemonic social groups in prior historical periods and their self-understanding as transcending political struggles can have important political consequences. I have been discussing the important role given to organic intellectuals at the systemic level of the development of society. Since their function involves giving direction to their social group at the level of collective consciousness through the thematization of ends in intelligible forms, the elaboration of organic intellectuals from within their social group requires the cultivation and transformation of their consciousnesses at the individual level. Gramsci’s philosophical anthropology is informed by a similar organismic schema. His expansion of intellectual activity to include all socially related technical relations follows directly from his philosophical account of human nature where the conventional distinction between thought or intellection and material labor is rejected. For Gramsci, all human practical activity entails both intellectual and muscular-nervous effort because it involves a creative relation between the self and the world and thus requires an intellectual conception of the world even if this conception is not explicitly thematized (SPNB 9). Although practical activity continually changes the physical and social world, it can only bring about a long-lasting transformation of the world if it is combined with a carefully articulated conception of the world. This is Gramsci’s version of the unity of theory and practice envisioned by the early Marx when he wrote in his Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right that [T]heory also becomes a material force [Gewalt] once it has gripped [ergreift] the masses. Theory is capable of gripping the masses when it demonstrates ad hominem, and it demonstrates ad hominem as soon as it becomes radical. To be radical is to grasp [ fassen] things by the root. But for man the root is man himself. (Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right. Introduction, 251) 8

142

Pheng Cheah

Marx is alluding to the derivation of the verb, begreifen, to grasp or to comprehend, and the noun, Begriff (concept), from the physical action of grabbing or seizing something (greifen). Concepts are both the means by which we handle things but they can take hold of us and move (ergreifen) and change us. One uses a concept as a tool or mediating term to get a grasp on a thing but to understand something through concepts is also to be taken hold of by them, to let them guide one in one’s relation to things. Gramsci’s reinscription of Marx emphasizes that the power of intellectual concepts to grasp us is also physiological. The world picture that concepts articulate can physically change the bodies of individuals by stimulating the intellectual activity already present in everyone so as to bring about a new equilibrium in the relation between intellectual activity and muscular activity (SPNB 9). This gripping of everyone by intellectual conceptions does not involve subordinating material activity to ideas. 9 Conceptions of the world need to be actualized and must therefore be rooted in or united with material action. An actualizable conception is one that acknowledges the primacy of material processes. It is a matter of incorporating or incarnating the new conception of the world in the efforts and activities, both intellectual and physical, of the masses. This process has two moments. First, the new stratum of intellectuals is produced or created by an elaboration in which intellectual activity found in everyday life is focused and specialized. Second, the new intellectual stratum then attempts to bring about changes in society as a whole. Now, it is unclear whether the power of the new intellectual stratum consists merely in organizing the efforts of the masses to create a new world by giving them direction or whether the change is more radical and occurs at the physiological level—that is, altering the equilibrium between material and intellectual activity. This lack of clear distinction between the different levels of social change (giving direction to the masses and changing their bodies) is due to the fact that the processes that constitute any organism always bleed into each other in a relation of feedback. An aesthetically pleasing analogy between organization at the levels of the society and the individual body lies at the heart of Gramsci’s account of the organic intellectual. Just as the individual in daily practical activity organizes his muscular-nervous effort through the positing of ends, the actions of masses are organized by the intellectual stratum through conceptions of the world that give mass activity direction. But since organic intellectuals are themselves elaborated from social forces and must be rooted in the political struggles of their class, they cannot be said to impose extraneous ideas onto practical activity. This is because practical activity that seeks to create a world involves organization and the organic intellectual is merely the personification of organizational activity. In his relation to the general members of his class, the organic intellectual personifies the unity of theory and practice because he embodies the organizational power of intellectual activity that is united with practical activity. In Gramsci’s words,

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

143

[T]he mode of being of the new intellectual . . . [consists] in active participation in practical life, as constructor, organizer, “permanent persuader” and not just a simple orator . . . from technique-as-work one proceeds to technique-as-science and to the humanistic conception of history, without which one remains “specialised” and does not become “directive” (specialized and political). (SPNB 10) The organic intellectual is the completion of the social organism. The social organism is a fluid whole that maintains an internal fluidity in its constituent processes despite the determinateness of its proper contours. The organic intellectual enables the social organism to be a whole in its very fluidity because he facilitates the organism’s return to itself, thereby completing the form of the social organism as a self-organizing being. This power of completion is vested in an intelligible form, the conception of the world the intellectual articulates, where technical knowledge (techne) directs practical activity and becomes political. The geometrical figure, or concept-metaphor, for this completion of the social organism qua power of self-return is the closure of a circle. This figure governs all of Gramsci’s analyses and concrete prescriptions concerning the health, vigor, and power of a social class seeking dominance and the generation of organic intellectuals as the stratum that completes the dominance of its class through the securing of social hegemony. For reasons of economy, I only mention four of the more important examples of this figure of the circle. First, Gramsci argues that a social group seeking dominance must assimilate traditional intellectuals by winning them over at the level of ideology. But this appropriation, a process of ingestion that pulls what is external or foreign into the circle—that is, an act of organization that remakes the foreign in the image of the organism’s proper form—“is made quicker and more efficacious the more the group in question succeeds in simultaneously elaborating its own organic intellectuals” (SPNB 10). Second, the organic quality of intellectuals is figured in terms of the role they play in completing the circle of their social group’s exercise of power. This power is exercised through two main superstructures, the state and civil society, which correspond to the functions of domination and hegemony respectively. These functions are, Gramsci emphasizes, “precisely organisational and connective” (SPNB 12; emphasis added). Intellectuals are functionaries in the complex mediations between these superstructures and the world of production. In performing this connecting task, they “are the dominant group’s ‘deputies’ exercising the subaltern functions of social hegemony and political government” (SPNB 12). Third, the function of the political party in elaborating various types of organic intellectuals such as political intellectuals and leaders in both civil society and political life is another process of maintaining the circle through the establishment of connections within civil society. This is seen most clearly in the political party’s secondary function of “welding together the organic intellectuals of a given group—the dominant one—and the traditional

144

Pheng Cheah

intellectuals” (SPNB 15; emphasis added). Fourth, the analytical distinction between organic and traditional intellectuals is essentially one between a selfcompleting circle and a broken circle where the capacity for self-return has been obstructed because of the traditional intellectual’s lack of connection to the masses. This is the most important circle in Gramsci’s writings because it concerns the unity of theory and practice, now refigured as the need for a more elementary unity between knowing and feeling, attitudes that Gramsci initially attributes to the intellectual strata and the masses, respectively. The popular element “feels” but does not always know or understand; the intellectual element “knows” but does not always understand and in particular does not always feel . . . The intellectual can be an intellectual (and not a pure pedant) if distinct and separate from the people-nation, that is, without feeling the elementary passions of the people, understanding them and therefore explaining and justifying them in the particular historical situation and connecting them dialectically to the laws of history and to a superior conception of the world, scientifically and coherently elaborated . . . One cannot make politics-history . . . without this sentimental connection between intellectuals and people-nation. In the absence of such a nexus the relations between the intellectual and the people-nation . . . are reduced to relationships of a purely bureaucratic and formal order; the intellectuals become a caste, or a priesthood (so-called organic centralism). (SPNB 418) Elsewhere, Gramsci defi nes the organic centralism of traditional intellectuals as a form of fetishization of the collective organism in which the social organism becomes autonomized from the decisions, actions and lives of its individual members and gains a (phantasmatic) life of its own in relation to which individuals are passive and helpless (SPNB 187 fn 83). In contradistinction, the unity of feeling and knowledge achieved by the contact between the organic intellectual and the masses will generate true social organic life that constitutes a revolutionary social force (SPNB 418). While Gramsci acknowledges that it is inevitable that “a gap” can develop between intellectuals and masses since the self-organization of a mass requires that there be intellectuals (organizers and leaders) who specialize in the conceptual and philosophical elaboration of ideas, this gap can always be bridged through a dialectical reciprocity between the intellectuals and the masses (SPNB 334–35). This give and take (“exchange”) completes the circle of the social organism and gives it the vigor of a social force with world-historical power. Globalization and the Breaching of the Circle: Jia Zhangke’s Dilemmas The immediate attractiveness of Gramsci’s account of the organic intellectual for understanding the struggles of colonized peoples as well as popular

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

145

struggles for freedom and justice in postcolonial space lies in his extension of intellectual activity to include the technical organization and direction of material practical activity, his focus on the need to establish reciprocal connections between the masses and intellectuals for an economically and politically ascendant class, and his study of the relationship between the peasant masses and intellectual organization in the Italian case. Of special significance here is the fact that Gramsci also describes the masses—the material basis of the revolutionary historical subject—as “the people-nation.” This implies that the organic intellectual who seeks to connect with the masses becomes rooted in the proper body of the people-nation and that the social organism he completes is national. In contradistinction, traditional intellectuals are characterized as rootless and cosmopolitan, not least because they appear separated from the dominant class.10 The national character of Gramsci’s political thought is consonant with the general trend of political organicism in modern European philosophy, especially German idealism, which, as I have argued elsewhere, characterized the political body as the incarnation of freedom, understood in analogy with a living organic totality because the organism’s causality was seen as analogous with the causality of freedom, in terms of the bounded community of a people defi ned in terms of language (Fichte) or of the constitutionally organized territorial state (Hegel; see Cheah, Spectral Nationality Chs. 3–4). As a result of Marxist theoretical influences, political organicism is the unspoken philosophical basis of revolutionary decolonization. Accordingly, there are strong resonances between Gramsci’s thought and the situation of decolonizing nations with large peasant populations and an emerging indigenous bourgeoisie seeking to wrest political power from the colonial state. This explains why the fi rst generation of the subaltern studies historians of South Asia have taken Gramsci’s ideas about the passive revolution and the relation between dominance and hegemony as points of departure in their studies of the limits of Indian bourgeois nationalist politics in the colonial era and the failings of the postcolonial state.11 The issue I want to address is whether the organic intellectual in our era of globalization can successfully fulfi ll his function of completing the circle of the social organism. And if he cannot, what implications does this have for accounts of the power of intellectual form in struggles for freedom, of which Gramsci’s theory of the organic intellectual is exemplary? Gramsci’s account of the organic intellectual is deeply marked by a mesmeric fascination with the capacity of technological mediation in the modern capitalist era. He endowed technical knowledge with the power to complete the circle of the social organism because for Gramsci as it was for the Marx of the Grundrisse and thereafter, technology promised to be the basis of the unity of theory and practice since in it, scientific knowledge had become a direct efficient cause and a material force. The power of intellectual form qua conception of the world to organize and give direction to the masses is merely an elaboration of technique-as-science. Hence, “in the modern world, technical education, closely bound to industrial labor even at the most primitive

146

Pheng Cheah

and unqualified level, must form the basis of the new type of intellectual” (SPNB 9). In this regard, the fi lmic image is an exemplary intellectual form both because it gives a visual image of the world and also because this image is the product of ongoing technological innovations. I approach Jia Zhangke’s fi lms from this perspective. But fi rst, a few words to frame this displacement of Gramsci in postcolonial space to Gramsci in post-socialist China. Gramsci’s account of hegemony is of great interest to the leading New Left Chinese intellectual, Wang Hui, in his attempt to formulate a new socialist vision for China in the wake of the marketization of the PRC economy as a result of its entry into the global capitalist world system (Wang Hui 683 –700).12 In this context, the organic intellectual’s task is to contest the hegemony of a bureaucratized communist state that has become increasingly depoliticized as a result of its amenability to global capitalist market imperatives. Such depoliticization, Wang suggests, has transformed the PRC into a heteronomous body. To counteract this depoliticization, a radically politicized popular vision of civil society that retains socialist ideals is required. Insofar as Gramsci’s thought is premised on the horizon of the realization of a communist society, the task of the organic intellectual would now need to be re-conceptualized in terms of a selective and critical inheritance and reincarnation of socialist ideals that are viable in a post-socialist age instead of a dogmatic return to orthodox forms of state socialism as exemplified by the PRC state. Rather than a revival of already achieved forms of communism that have been rendered effete in contemporary globalization, what needs to be envisioned is a form of socialism that is a viable social, political and economic alternative today for those sections of the Chinese population that have been marginalized by post-socialist market economic development and its political administration. These sections of the population are largely rural or provincial, including a large floating population of migrant workers who moved to large cities in search of work and economic prosperity. Hence, what needs to be envisioned is a neo-socialism in a post-socialist world, so to speak, that can take root in this part of the Chinese population. Furthermore, as Wang rightly observes, in an age of globalization where the legitimacy of the PRC state is secured by its acquiescence to and active accommodation of global or transnational capitalist market relations, counter-hegemonic struggles cannot remain merely national or international in scope but must also have a global focus to match the capitalist market system. The articulation of a conception of the world through which the masses of the PRC can map the PRC’s place in the global capitalist system and recognize the impact of these global market forces on the culture and social life of the urban and rural population and on their daily existence is a crucial aspect of counter-hegemonic work. This project of articulation is consonant with the task of forging and developing a national-popular collective will through culture that Gramsci attributed to the Jacobin forces in the case of

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

147

the French Revolution, although it cannot carry the same radical revolutionary charge of overthrowing a political regime. In Gramsci’s words, The positive conditions are to be sought in the existence of urban social groups which have attained an adequate development in the field of industrial production and a certain level of historico-political culture. Any formation of a national-popular collective will is impossible, unless the great mass of peasant farmers bursts simultaneously into political life. (SPNB 131–32) Jia Zhangke intends his fi lms to be a medium for a similar mode of selfrecognition for the masses that we may characterize as organic. If we are to give credence to his comments about the subject-matter and documentaryrealist style of his fi lms, they are meant to be celluloid archives of popular Chinese consciousness and its historical memories in the period of massive social upheaval from the beginning of the economic modernization of China to the post-socialist present. Commenting on his focus on the lives of young people from provincial China (Fengyang, Shanxi province, where Jia was born) as his subject matter in his Fengyang trilogy (Xiao Wu 小武, 1997), Platform (站台, 2000), and Unknown Pleasures (任逍遙, 2002), he has said that “the country scene is the background of China and of the Chinese people . . . I am ready to admit my origins. I am proud of where I am from but I don’t want to glorify it with lyricism. I just don’t want to break my link with the earth” (“Director Jia Zhangke. True to Life”). In his earlier films, the portrayal of grassroots Chinese life is facilitated by a realist style, the main features of which are a quasi-documentary use of a handheld camera, a use of long shots, and amateur actors with strong local or provincial dialect accents and lots of background noise.13 Handheld camera work conveys the sense of the immediate experience of an involved first person observer, someone who witnesses the portrayed events on the spot in the manner of a participant, because there is a rapport and even an organic unity between the camera and the events that are captured as they unfold in living time.14 The long shot likewise captures real time, but in a different, more formalistic, aestheticized manner. The camera observes the characters from a distance, thereby foregrounding the gulf between the human characters in their daily experience of monotonous, meaningless time and the progress of historically significant time marked by the narrative.15 The desire to portray people “in a very natural realistic state” also motivates Jia’s use of non-professional actors from rural parts of China with strong local accents. Because of their training, professional actors find it hard to “adapt their methods of movement and speech to the kind of documentaryesque type of narrative film” and to fit in naturally with the surrounding environment whereas amateur actors have “speech and movements that are extremely natural” and understand what he is trying to express with his script because they grew up in a similar atmosphere

148

Pheng Cheah

and they believe in the script and the characters and the world it evokes. They have “a natural confidence and ‘at home’ feeling that professional actors can’t compare with” ( Jia, “Capturing a Transforming Reality” 198).16 The thematic thread that runs through these comments is the connection between the fi lmic image, the various components and processes that produce this image, and the Chinese people in an authentic state or original condition of living reality (the referent or subject matter of the image). The relation between the fi lmic image and the referent is that of truth and accuracy of representation. This authenticity must be present at every stage of the production of the fi lmic image. Non-professional actors, by virtue of their lack of training and their personal experiences of rural and provincial life similar to the social setting portrayed by the fi lm, have a closer connection to the real life of the Chinese masses. The rapport and unity between the camera work, the actors performing their scenes, and the referent of those scenes indicates an authenticity in the aesthetic techniques. This is precisely the circle of organic self-return articulated in Gramsci’s idea of the organic intellectual, a fact made more patent by Jia’s repeated use of imagery of organic unity and being at home in and having a natural connection to the surroundings. Jia’s fi lms not only portray and express this natural connection to the real life of the Chinese masses, but also (re)enable and (re)activate this connection. They are organic and organicizing for they complete the circle of organic self-return of the Chinese masses. This ethical, vocational aspect of Jia’s films is most clearly evidenced in his emphasis on the creative dimension of his films as narrative films. For him, the cinematic image has two different origins: the referent and the director. The image’s original vocation is to have a firsthand, unmediated or direct relation to the masses through these two origins. The filmic image’s authenticity lies not only in the accurate portrayal of the life of the Chinese masses but also in the creative human life force unleashed within the director and expressed in his films, a force that has been stifled by professional filming techniques and commodity-market demands (Jia Xiang: Jia Zhangke 33).17 In his well-known short essay “The Age of Amateur Cinema Is about to Return” (业余电影时代即将再次 到来), Jia characterized this creative life force in terms of the moral values of conscience (良知, liangzhi) and sincerity (真诚, zhencheng) (in Jia Xiang: Jia Zhangke 33).18 This is the subjective aspect of a film’s authenticity. Jia associates the earnest and responsible filmmaker’s attitude with “the conscience of the intellectual (知识分子的良心, zhishifenzi de liangxin)” (34). Its aim is not merely to accurately portray the life experiences of the Chinese masses. It is also transformative. It seeks to strengthen the will of the masses to live: to stimulate collective self-awareness in the intended audience and a sense of fortitude and hope as a result of the knowledge of the human communality of suffering, that my suffering is common to all human beings. People are the same all over the world; they go through the same motions. They face the same spring, summer, fall and winter; the same

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

149

birth, ageing, illness and death. I don’t know what this revelation does to me exactly, but it seems to make me stronger. This personal experience strengthens me to endure the heavy stress in life. I feel that I’m not alone. My humble experiences are not unique . . . By watching this imperfect world, we can become stronger and more optimistic of change . . . It’s not by shooting a luxurious and happy world that we can affect the audience. It’s important to keep criticising culture and our society; it provides a vivid description of human difficulties. I’m going to carry on making this kind of fi lm, in the hope that audiences will be strengthened to face daily life. ( Jia in Shih 53–58) Jia’s humble social background and the fact that he was initially an underground fi lmmaker further strengthens the popular organic-intellectual dimension of his fi lms, so much so that he has been characterized as a “fi lm industry migrant worker” (电影民工, dianying mingong) who has a special connection to the socially marginal characters he portrays, people whose living conditions and experiences were not seen on the silver screen although they make up a large part of the Chinese population (“Jia Zhangke” 362).19 Indeed, Jia intends his fi lms to be counter-hegemonic because they bring to view the life-experiences and memories of the masses that have been occluded from sight by the official state picture of China. Film reviewers and academic fi lm scholars have largely concurred on the organic character of his fi lms. Jia’s credentials as an organic intellectual have remained intact despite the fact that he is now no longer an underground director but is actively courted by the state-run National Film Bureau. 20 As one fi lm scholar puts it, Jia’s frequent and unashamed public references to his own relatively humble geographic and social origins, have made him a veritable poster boy for the still pending democratization of Chinese fi lmmaking . . . [M]edia reports on Jia’s work consistently impute to him personal moral qualities that relate implicitly to the quality and concerns of his fi lms: “sincerity,” “determination,” and the like. ( Jaffee, “Bringing the World to the Nation”) What we see here is an elaborate series of countersignatures that confi rm the organic character of Jia’s fi lms by attesting to their authenticity and their provenance. His fi lms originate from two authentic sources: their referent or subject matter (the Chinese masses) and the creative life force of a popular intellectual who is himself from the masses. The techniques deployed in the crafting of the fi lmic image are themselves authentic because they maintain as close a rapport as possible with their referent. And this chain of authenticity is further affi rmed through the recognition of the international art fi lm festival and world cinema circuit and the critics and reviewers who preside at and attend such events. But the fact that this authentication process needs to

150

Pheng Cheah

make a detour through the international stage of critical recognition should give us some pause about the applicability of Gramsci’s concept, and more generally, in an era of globalization. In the fi rst instance, the hegemonic order that Jia is trying to challenge is not a bourgeois state and its form of society but a rapidly modernizing socialist state in collaboration with global capital. Second, insofar as the development of counter-hegemonic conceptions of the world draws on cultures and traditions from local communities as resources, we must reckon with the fact that the masses are themselves displaced by internal and transnational migration and cannot be considered members of an organic community in an unqualified manner. Third, as Jia himself has gained international acclaim through the fi lm festival circuit, his fi lms have received international funding and are also made for a global audience.21 As I will show via an examination of Jia’s 2004 fi lm, The World (世界), these global processes radically compromise the processes of organic development because they disarticulate the social organism as a bounded whole that is the autonomous subject of its own development. But since these global processes also enable and constitute the process of the self-return of the Chinese masses as facilitated by Jia’s fi lms, they indicate that the organism’s life-process is irreducibly marked by a certain auto-immunity in which the very self of the organism is contaminated without return. Jia makes the destabilizing force of globalization the explicit theme of the two narrative fi lms immediately after the Fengyang trilogy. The World depicts the destruction of the existing built landscape and the degradation of lived social place and their replacement by simulacral models characteristic of industrial and postindustrial capitalist society and its culture of consumption. It contrasts the miserable and aimless lives of the migrant workers who staff the Beijing World Park with the glitzy images they project as performers and the replicas of international architectural icons such as the Eiffel Tower that fi ll the theme park. Still Life (三峡好人, 2006) chronicles the destruction of old villages and communities by the Three Gorges Dam project and the ensuing anomie of the displaced poor and migrant workers. This erosion of organic communal ties may be typical of the violent upheaval of capitalist modernization. Jia regards this destabilization as a force that is imposed on the Chinese masses by the collaboration of the Chinese state with global capitalism in a post-socialist era. But global capitalist culture is also something that the masses desired as an alternative to the deprivation of the Communist years. What is important, however, is that although the masses may also be implicated in their own alienation by global capitalist consumerism, Jia regards his fi lms as celluloid records of this upheaval that observe it critically from an external vantage point rather than being constitutively implicated in these global processes. In this way, the organic character of his work can be preserved so that it can stimulate the Chinese masses to think critically about and change their current conditions, not by returning to a Communist or traditional past, but by building a future that draws on the positive

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

151

resources from these pasts as well as resources from contemporary social situations and technological innovations that can be organically assimilated by the masses. Accordingly, Jia’s comments about The World’s thematic content are part ambivalence, part lament and part nostalgia. Because global culture, mass media and information flows in general inculcate in the masses a sense of individuality and make them aware of the existence of a larger world beyond their immediate surroundings and the conception of the world promulgated by the Chinese state, they stimulate an inchoate personal longing for a global reality that is larger than the state’s official conception of China. However, and this seems unique to the Chinese situation where extremely rapid marketization and economic hyper-development abruptly follow a long period of isolation from the larger world (with the deprivation and repression of desire this entails) and now coexists with state control, the Chinese masses have a flawed and self-alienating conception of the world where they see themselves as already modern and worldly people because of the intense social climate created by hyper-development. 22 They seek to satisfy their longing for the world through the materialistic consumption of transnational commodities and its ersatz social forms (exemplified by the fake landscape of the World Park) because in their conception of the world, being modern and being worldly is precisely to be a savvy consumer of foreign objects. But such materialistic pursuit for illusory things does not lead to a genuinely fulfi lling life. It is even a form of escapism from social problems because such pursuit inevitably confl icts with the “traditional” values of provincial organic communities that still exert a hold over the masses even if they are being eroded by rapid modernization, labor migration, and consumer culture. In Jia’s view, this is the predicament specific to the Chinese people’s “longing for the world.” In Chinese society today there are a lot of moments where what’s going on could be called a show. . . The economy’s doing very well, and everywhere you look you have these “shows,” sort of like economic bubbles, fi lling up every sector of our lives . . . I think those sorts of environments, those artificial landscapes, are very significant. The landscape in the World Park includes famous sights from all over the world. They are not real, but they still can satisfy people’s longing for the world. They reflect the very strong curiosity of people in this country, and the interest they have in becoming a part of international culture. At the same time, this is a very strange way to fulfi ll these demands . . . [I]t makes for a very sorrowful scene . . . Every time I went to one of the parks for the shooting, I saw all the tourists and how overjoyed they were to be there, and for me it was all very sad . . . This is what Chinese reality is like. And so, in the fi lm, a lot of action takes place under the “Arc de Triomphe.” Or in front of the “Taj Mahal,” or in “London,” or in “Manhattan.” Of course all of these landscapes are fake. But the problems our

152

Pheng Cheah society faces are very much Chinese issues, and I think all of this is not unrelated to that. We’re living in a globalised age, in a world saturated by mass media, in an international city, as it were. But despite all that, the problems we’re facing are our own problems. ( Jaffee, “An Interview with Jia Zhangke)

Hence, alongside the lamentation of the suffering caused by globalization, there is also a certain nostalgia for the disappearing solidarities of organic communal values. This predicament is neatly captured in a striking image in the fi lm’s title sequence. What seems like an advertisement slogan for the World Park (“You can travel around the world without leaving Beijing”) fl ashes across the screen accompanied by the web path for the park’s fictitious website, with the replicas of the Pyramids and the Sphinx of Giza in the background (see Figure 7.1). The next shot is of the replica of the Eiffel Tower in the background. An old peasant man, his back bent by a heavy sack probably fi lled with recyclable garbage slowly walks past. He turns to face the camera and stares before turning away and making his way across the screen as the fi lm’s title appears (see Figure 7.2). This sequence juxtaposes globalization’s promise of illusory mobility with the real time of provincial life and its hardship. The image of the old man roots the fi lm organically. His quizzical stare summons and draws the viewer to follow him on his path across this simulated landscape that allegorizes China’s entry into the global capitalist system.

Figure 7.1 “You can travel around the world without leaving Beijing,” with fictitious web path of the park’s website, from title sequence. The World (2004).

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

153

Figure 7.2 Old peasant man walking past with replica of Eiffel tower in the background, from title sequence. The World (2004).

The World portrays the state-sanctioned entry of China into the world from the oblique angle of how the rapid opening up to flows of transnational capital impacts the daily lives of the Chinese masses. The fi lm thus gives a certain look of China to the world. It exposes to the phenomenality of a wider gaze the lives of those Chinese people who are literally barred from the world: the masses that desire globality but can only passively suffer its consequences because they have no self-determined access to it. This thematic contrast between the real lives of the masses and the glittering façades of globalizing post-socialist China runs throughout the entire fi lm. Its central characters are migrant workers from the provinces who have come to Beijing and fi nd themselves working in “The World,” a Las Vegas or Epcot® World Showcase–style theme park.23 The gritty realism used to portray the workers in their dressing rooms and their private lives is contrasted with the glitzy costumes they put on as they assume the personae of people from other cultures and the spectacle of simulated tourist landmarks from around the globe built to scale with materials similar to those of the originals. As rightly noted, this frontstage/backstage structure sets up a contrast between reality and spectacle, truth and illusion that the fi lm proceeds to complicate (McGrath 221–22). 24 The park is clearly a synecdoche for the world globalization is making in the PRC. One of the segments of the fi lm is wittily titled, “A (New) World Each Day” (Yitian yige shijie, Everchanging world), and a poster in the dressing room reads in Chinese, “I give you a world” (Wo gei ni yige shijie). The World cogently captures the speed and intensity of the flow of global capital through images and sounds of media connectivity

154

Pheng Cheah

and travel: cell phones, instant messaging, and fl ash animation graphics, trains, planes, and cars, highways and rail tracks that connect Beijing to the provinces, bringing in migrant workers, even as China is connected to the rest of the globe and serves both as the source and destination of clandestine transnational labor. This world has a surreal quality to it: we see people whizzing around or passing through this global landscape in a skytrain and other modes of transportation. Indeed, the fi lm broaches the issue of the digitalization of their lives by interspersing fl ash animation graphics that show them as cartoons in cyberspace when they use their cellular phones. The repeated contrast between this speed and the relative immobility of the park’s workers in their private lives indicates a complex layering of different worlds onto each other. The viewer gets a sense of the corrosive alienation and existential solitude that globalization causes by uprooting and driving people to fi nd jobs in places without any sense of social belonging. The world globalization creates is not a world in any genuine sense, a community of intersubjective relations in which one can have a meaningful life and death. Globalization has made the characters of The World worldless, or as Heidegger or Arendt would say, weltlos, without world. Here, and even more so in Still Life, Jia portrays the integration of China into the global capitalist system as the destructive creation of a ruined world, a world that has been denuded by demolition, mass displacement, and environmental pollution as a result of rabid construction in the service of hyper-industrialization. The contrast between the real lives of the workers and the simulated world of the park is, however, not a simple opposition between truth and illusion. The notion of true reality that underwrites The World far exceeds any notion of veridical truth, truth as the faithful adequation of fi lmic representation to the objective world, the principal axiom of cinéma vérité. The mundane reality of the park workers’ lives faithfully represented by the fi lm is not a true reality, a reality that has any truth in the ontological sense. It is already a degraded reality, an alienated reality in the strict Marxian sense of the word, where the workers have already been corrupted by the consumer desires of capitalist commodification. Unlike the old man in the title sequence whom globalization has left behind, the two main characters whose tragic romantic relationship drives the plot, Tao and Taisheng, are swept up in globalization’s path. They are incorporated as migrant workers who help to build the new Chinese global dream of market socialism. If the park is a synecdoche for the world for local Chinese visitors, Beijing, like other major Chinese cities such as Shanghai and Shenzhen, are portals to and enclaves of globality for workers from the provinces. Tao and Taisheng have their own Beijing dreams. In a scene in Taisheng’s

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

155

hot and fi lthy lodgings next to the train tracks, typical of the places where migrant workers live, he tells her that on his fi rst night in Beijing, he vowed to make a name for himself in this city so that he can give her a good life. But although they both pay lip service to the park’s promise of a cosmopolitan experience, unlike the Chinese visitors to the park, they sense its hollowness because the illusion they are fabricating contradicts their private lives. This contradiction between their private and work lives is not a splitting into true private and false public selves. They are no more real in their private lives than the personae they project because they also yearn for a fuller version of the global dream represented by the park, which they think can be achieved beyond the park’s boundaries, in the aspiring global city of Beijing. In one of the visual set pieces of the fi lm, Tao and Taisheng meet during a work break in the cockpit of an old plane that has been turned into a theme park experience. Dressed in the costume of a fl ight attendant, she tells him to take her outside the park because she will soon turn into a ghost if she is stuck there all day (see Figure 7.3). But the world outside the park is initially also a simulation: Tao imagines herself as an animation fi gure who levitates in the air and fl ies past Tiananmen Square with posters of Deng Xiaoping and Jiang Zemin (the key political architects of the marketization of the Chinese economy) before ending up in an outlying district as a real life person (see Figure 7.4). The park’s replicas are thus not false. They have as much truth as the alienated reality of Tao’s and Taisheng’s lives. Even if Tao leaves the World Park, in what more truthful reality will she end up? As the PRC state attempts to

Figure 7.3

Tao dressed as a flight attendant. The World (2004).

156

Pheng Cheah

Figure 7.4

Animation of Tao flying past Tiananmen Square. The World (2004).

make China attractive to global capital, many theme park-like global structures have sprung up in Beijing. They include highly visible public buildings designed by rock-star architects such as the Bird’s Nest, the Water Cube, the CCTV tower, and the National Center for the Performing Arts as well as private residential villas replicating Versailles and the Louvre in the eighty-two acre Palais de Fortune compound for China’s wealthiest CEOs and foreign businessmen.25 A similar habit of consuming replica objects is found at the lower levels of society. Qun, the woman with whom Taisheng cheats, owns a tailoring workroom that makes knockoff designer clothes copied from foreign fashion magazines. Imposter designer bags with fake logos are prominently visible in her workshop. Throughout the fi lm, there are numerous instances of the training of park workers, especially women, into modern consumers who become service providers for the leisure consumption of others in order to support their own consumption. The path of capitalist consumption is, however, less salutary for the lower classes. One of the fi lm’s segment titles is “Paris in a Beijing suburb.” Qun’s husband is an illegal migrant worker who has lived in Paris for the past decade and she is applying for a visa to visit him. When Taisheng asks her to visit the park to familiarize herself with Paris before her trip, she grimly replies that the park does not have the neighborhood where he lives, Belleville, which is Chinatown in a Paris suburb. The inner truth or telos of “Paris in a Beijing suburb” is to become an illegal worker in Belleville. 26 Tao has even less freedom of mobility. Not only has she never been on a plane, she has never even seen a passport and can only imagine traveling in her fl ights of escapist fantasy in the virtual world of flash animation. As we have seen, Jia critically denounces the equation of worldliness with the consumption of foreign commodities as a hollow capitalist

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

157

ideology. In a similar vein, although these virtual fl ights in Tao’s imagination provide her with temporary emotional excitement and comfort, they are in the fi nal analysis symptoms of a false consciousness, or at least, the masses’ ignorance and lack of awareness of the truth about their degraded reality. Indeed, Tao herself seems to be naïve or dense about the oppressiveness of the working conditions in the park. She initially cannot or does not want to acknowledge that Anna, one of the dancers brought from Russia to work in the park, has been forced into prostitution. The more fundamental sense of reality that underwrites Jia’s aesthetic—and what makes The World an organic intellectual product—is that it points to different resources from which a truer, non-alienated reality can be created and, moreover, attempts to be a causal factor in the making of this reality. For it can be said that instead of merely portraying their conditions accurately (realism as a mode of representation), The World brings the masses into the real world in a second, transformative sense. It presents their plight in the global forum of world cinema while also presenting the masses to themselves in a manner that is aimed to stimulate self-awareness so that they can emerge as something new; that is, transform themselves by learning to direct their participation in the ever-changing world while maintaining their integrity as a people, whatever that may be. It is exactly in this sense that Gramsci saw intellectual/cultural work as completing the circle of the people’s self-return as an organism. Jia’s fi lms point to cultural resources in the existing world for this transformative reality. Despite her ignorance, Tao has her own sense of moral conduct. Unlike some of the other women workers in the park, she refuses to sell her sexuality for material benefit. Her empathy and friendship with Anna, the Russian dancer, and her solidarity with other female colleagues in the park are instances of building a shared space, community or a web of interpersonal relationships, a world, through acts of kindness that do not involve self-interest. Taisheng may be a heartless philandering cad, but he shows a deep sense of responsibility and loyalty to his hometown kin and friends such as Little Sister, a construction worker who is killed in an accident. Popular folk religious rituals have a role in world building. Taisheng and Little Sister’s parents perform a ritual ceremony to appease his spirit at the construction site where he is killed. But although these different resources for world formation are immanent to existing reality, they are only activated either in chance encounters or in moments of crisis and suffering and are not amenable to permanent institutionalization. The only plausible openings of other worlds seem to take place beyond the frame of the hollow world of commodified spectacles for the characters who managed to leave the world of the fi lm by going elsewhere. Yet, even here, it is suggested that the world beyond the frame of the fi lm is just as likely to be another world of commodification. Tao’s former boyfriend leaves to fi nd work in Mongolia. Qun leaves to join her husband, probably to become an underprivileged illegal migrant

158

Pheng Cheah

in Belleville. We see Anna aboard an Aeroflot fl ight from Beijing to visit her sister in Ulan Bator, but we are unsure whether she will return to her job as a sex worker in Beijing. The only permanent escape is to leave this world by dying. Despite having lived in Beijing for several years, Tao has remained traditional in her values. She values her chastity so much that when she finally gives herself to Taisheng, she tells him that she will kill him if he is unfaithful to her. We can sense that this will end tragically. She discovers that he cheated on her with Qun and the film’s final scene shows them as corpses, victims of an accident with a leaking gas pipe. But it is strongly suggested that she is responsible. The film ends with an aporia, literally, an impasse, no passage, a road that cannot be crossed: the screen is pitch black. Taisheng’s voice over says, “Are we dead?” and Tao replies, “No, we are just beginning.” It remains undecidable for the viewer whether they have been rescued in enough time to be resuscitated, and so have to remain in this world, or whether they have crossed into a better world on the other side of death. Globalization creates a world they cannot tolerate and that literally kills them and makes them worldless. Or better yet, the only way for them to be part of a genuine world is to cast aside this one. But although Jia’s fi lm cannot show us characters who have become genuinely real by overcoming the power of consumer desires that have thoroughly made them over at the level of consciousness and even bodily habits and needs (the reification of consciousness is the Marxist-savvy word, biopower the Foucauldian one), the fi lm can promise a true world in the future through a double gesture: fi rst, it can demystify its Chinese viewers of the myths of the contemporary Chinese state and global capitalism so that they can recognize the degree to which their existing reality has been degraded and second, it can stimulate a counter-hegemonic consciousness that will strive to create a truly meaningful world. However, the fi lm encounters a series of blockages that threaten to undermine the viability of Jia Zhangke’s function as an organic intellectual. Despite his trenchant critique of globality, The World is a globally produced object. It is a synecdoche of globality and an example of worldliness par excellence. The transnational character of the production of cultural and aesthetic objects can be understood in various ways: in terms of transnational funding sources and corporate involvement; in terms of the diverse origins of the collaborators in the creative process; or in terms of the fact that the cultural object is made with the purpose of being disseminated to markets and audiences beyond the borders of its production that will lead it to be “consumed” beyond its (national) site of production. The theoretical debate about the effects of this transnationalization has predictably wavered between three diagnoses: cultural homogenization in which the local is reprocessed and repackaged under the stamp of the global culture industry, banal cultural hybridization, and the manufacturing of cultural authenticity; that is, sanctioned cultural difference in a global market. Jia’s

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

159

situation is more complex and aporetic. The global nature of the fi lm’s own production and distribution means that the fi lm’s formal structure of address is necessarily split. It portrays the ways in which the various characters desire an imagined world of consumer fantasies, for two audiences. On the one hand, if we are outside China, we look at the characters as they desire a world that lies beyond the frames of the fi lm where we, the global audience, are located, the telos of the characters’ desire. On the other hand, a PRC audience gazes at a celluloid version of its own desire for globality so that it can critically question this desire and, by extension, the PRC state’s collusion with this desire in its ideology of market socialism. In the scenario of strict state control and censorship of cultural production, the interface of these two different structures of address and reception must be at an optimum to cultivate a counter-hegemonic consciousness. This is, in essence, the conceptual basis of the debate concerning the “underground” or “independent” status of Sixth Generation Chinese narrative and documentary fi lm: can these fi lms escape the regulatory grip of the PRC state without succumbing to the pressures and commercializing influence of the Hollywood culture industry model? Jia is cognizant of the fact that the global character of his fi lms can be a mixed blessing. Transnational funding (via Hong Kong as a production base) is a way of escaping bureaucratic censorship by the PRC state. In the case of his earlier fi lms, although the state did not prohibit him from shooting in China, it prohibited the public screening of his fi lms, thereby making it difficult for Jia to obtain fi nancing for his fi lms within China. Transnational funding and success in the world fi lm festival circuit, however, exacts a price. In the fi rst place, although it enables Jia to make fi lms, the organic connection between the fi lms and the Chinese mass audience is severed. Despite the international acclaim for his fi lms, Jia is essentially unknown among the Chinese masses. His earlier fi lms were seen in China in fi lm fan clubs, minor fi lm festivals, or pirated DVDs. International acclaim has led to his acceptance by the PRC state, which gave official approval to the fi lming of The World. But as Jia notes, such approval occurs because the state no longer views fi lms as a propaganda tool but as a tool for making money: “Films are now considered to be national properties, and to be treated as an economic tool” (Shih). In this changed world where the PRC state has opened up to market imperatives, the influence of transnational flows of information and popular culture that had been, in the years of the Cultural Revolution, resources for individual expression and creative freedom because of their inaccessibility have now become part of a larger process of opening up China to the capitalist world system that is community- and world-destroying. The solution cannot be to go in the direction of international art fi lm for at least two reasons. First, the international art fi lm circuit is also a prestigious niche market in which Jia’s brand of realist cinema will have

160

Pheng Cheah

to compete as a commodity with other types of art fi lm. 27 But more important, unless they can cultivate and transform popular taste in China, such art fi lms are unlikely to appeal to a domestic mass audience that has been educated to fi nd pleasure in Hollywood-style Chinese commercial cinema. 28 Thus, even though The World and Still Life were released through officially recognized studios and screened to mass Chinese audiences, they fared poorly at the box office. Here, then, is the aporia: to be relevant to and to touch a popular Chinese audience, the fi lms need to be viewed in China. Cooperation with the PRC state to facilitate distribution involves compromise, but this can be mitigated through a partnership with transnational capital. However, this in turn entails participation in the circuits of commodification whose negative effects Jia’s fi lms attempt to document. Jia has tried to resolve this aporia by championing the importance of Hong Kong as an organizational center for producing his fi lms because it is a Chinese space with some independence. As Jia puts it, [M]y activity cannot be guaranteed inside of China. I need an open space and international one, because I’ve got to fi nd some investors. I’ve chosen Hong Kong, since it still keeps free spaces and plus it’s a Chinese place and this help my communication. So we have come to a decision: to establish our seat in Hong Kong. This to me sounds like an optimum compromise, since it’s difficult to count on international collaborations in Beijing. (Damiani, “A Conversation”) But given Hong Kong’s historical position as a gateway of trade between the West and mainland China and its current attempt to reinvent itself as a global integrator or center for the organization of global production chains in East Asia, Jia’s claim about the autonomy of Hong Kong is disingenuous. What is especially striking is that Jia’s dilemma parallels that of the characters of The World. Contemporary mass media, old and new, and the consumer culture they disseminate enable the concomitant rise of individualism and the alienation that accompanies the erosion of communal solidarity. Elsewhere, Jia describes the inherently alienating character of mass media as a form of cultural oppression. The power of the collective was extremely strong [when I was growing up], and culturally speaking, we always had a lot of confidence. But the younger generation are faced with a new kind of cultural oppression. This is in part due to the lifestyles they hear and learn about through the media—especially the Internet and cable television—which exist on a completely different plane from their everyday reality. It is this radical contrast between the reality of their environment and the picture of the

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

161

world they get through the media that creates an enormous pressure in their lives. (“Capturing a Transforming Reality” 193) Tao’s digital fl ights of fantasy are illusory panacea to this loss of a world. Jia’s attempt to fi nd a transnational space for creation beyond China puts him in exactly the same position of the characters who leave the frame of The World. But like them, it is highly doubtful that Jia can transcend the circuit of commodification. This is the aporia faced by the organic intellectual today and why I think Gramsci’s concept needs to be radically rethought within the context of contemporary globalization. Opening up to transnational flows is crucial to counter-hegemonic struggles against the territorial state. But this presentation of the picture of the masses to themselves and an alternative conception of the world through the detour of transnational space to enable the masses to return back to themselves may very well be an opening without the possibility of return. The organic intellectual can no longer complete the circle of self-return of the social organism because he also encounters, at the level of aesthetic production, something similar to the erosion of the potentiality of the masses to be an autonomous self-organizing being by the power of commodification. What we have here is not the self-returning movement of an organism, its ability to remain at home with itself in its other in its metabolic relations with the outside, but something that is closer to what Derrida has called “auto-immunity,” a structure of radical contamination in which what enables the self to constitute its proper self is precisely what undoes this self.29 Autoimmunization is a perversion of the process of immunity. In immunization, a body protects itself by producing antibodies to combat foreign antigens. In autoimmunization, however, the organism protects “itself against its self-protection by destroying its own immune system” (Derrida, “Faith and Knowledge” 73 n27). Autoimmunization is therefore a radical form of suicide because the organism immunizes itself against its own immunity (Borradori 94).30 The auto-immunity at the level of symbolic production that structures Jia Zhangke’s film is a synecdoche for the auto-immunity that necessarily follows at the level of global political economy when the delinking, full or relative, of socialist countries from the global capitalism is implausible. I have argued elsewhere that autoimmunity is the condition of financial globalization, where the constitution of the nation-state’s very selfhood requires the exposure of the self to the alterity and heteronomy of capital flows (Cheah, “Crises of Money” 189–219). This radical contamination is the true meaning of “organic,” the technical function of organization taken to its logical extreme: techne as what is artificial and not amenable to human control even as it is the constitutive feature of humanity and all its capabilities and powers. Its implications for counterhegemonic struggles at the level of culture have to be attended to through the careful study of concrete cases in the postcolonial world.

162

Pheng Cheah

Notes 1. See also Ngugi Wa Thiong’o, Moving the Centre: The Struggle for Cultural Freedoms. 2. For an elaborate argument about why the PRC can be seen as a world-historical experiment in the socialization of a global market economy, see Arrighi, Adam Smith in Beijing: Lineages of the Twenty-First Century. 3. I am using “formal” and “fi nal” cause in the Aristotelian meaning of the form and the end of a thing. 4. Addressing the issue of whether members of a political party are intellectuals, Gramsci notes that one is an intellectual if one’s function is “directive and organizational, i.e., educative, i.e. intellectual” (SPNB 16). 5. Hence, Gramsci’s famous claim that “all men are intellectuals. . .but not all men have in society the function of intellectuals” (SPNB 9). 6. For a fuller elaboration of the basic principles of the modern philosophical understanding of organism and its influence on social and political thought, see Cheah, Spectral Nationality: Passages of Freedom from Kant to Postcolonial Literatures of Liberation, esp. Chapters 1–2. 7. The paradigmatic example of the autonomous traditional intellectual is the German idealist philosopher, who thinks of himself “as ‘independent’, autonomous, endowed with a character of their own” (SPNB 8). 8. Marx, Zur Kritik der Hegel’schen Rechts-Philosophie. Einleitung, in Marx, Werke, Artikel, Entwürfe, März 1843 bis August 1844, Karl Marx-Friedrich Engels Gesamtausgabe. 9. Note, however, that this does not mean that in historical cases, the masses are not subordinated to intellectuals. This is certainly the case with the peasant masses, who, according to Gramsci, do not have their own intellectuals (see SPNB 14–15). However, the subordination must be overturned by assimilating the intellectuals into the peasantry, thereby forming a revolutionary group. 10. See Gramsci’s discussion of the formation of traditional intellectuals from freed slaves of Greek and Oriental origin in the Roman Empire, and later, from people of Romanized origin after the fall of the Roman Empire. In the case of Italy, intellectuals have a cosmopolitan function because the peninsular lacked cohesion (SPNB 17–18). 11. See, for instance, Chatterjee, Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World—A Derivative Discourse? and Guha, Dominance without Hegemony: History and Power in India. 12. The rest of this paragraph draws on Wang’s argument. 13. In a perceptive study, Jason McGrath distinguishes between two kinds of realism in Jia’s fi lms, “an ‘on-the-spot’ cinéma vérité realism that draws on a wider documentary impulse among Chinese artists and fi lmmakers of the 1990s and a comparatively aestheticized long-shot/long-take realism that draws more upon a contemporary international art-cinema style” (160). 14. Commenting on Xiao Wu, Jia notes: “I wanted a sensation of being on the spot. Therefore, I had a lot of hand-held camera work, and there were many imprints of the auteur. I always say to my cinematographer that we should be bystanders. When an event happens, we are behind there looking, and we are participating

Entering the World from an Oblique Angle

15. 16.

17.

18. 19.

20.

21.

22.

163

. . . The starting point is that the camera exists, it is at one with the event that occurs and it is present at the scene” (Teo, “Cinema with an Accent: Interview with Jia Zhangke, director of Platform”). This is the approach of Platform (Teo, “Cinema with an Accent”). Cf. Jia’s comment that non-professional actors “really attained a state of naturalism, and I wanted also to fi lm that state of naturalism, and they captured that” (Teo, “Cinema with an Accent”). “When I made Xiao Wu, I wanted to capture that sense of primitive creativity and to return to that stage of cinematic primevalism . . . That’s the kind of movie I want to make. Pouring your life force into the movie, not conforming to a cold industrial standard. That’s why I rejected the use of certain supplementary fi lm techniques such as steadicam or even the track . . . I don’t want my cameramen to use these supplementary techniques. Because I want my camera to come into direct contact with the subject” (Teo, “Cinema with an Accent”). This was fi rst published in Nanfang zhoumo (The Southern Weekly), 1999. “I feel that I have the same character as migrant workers, the same sense of reality. I also feel that the movie screen at that time was not really concerned for this kind of person, was completely without any concern. I think that I fi lmed Xiaowu because I felt that I had a kind of dissatisfaction, a kind of life-experience, the life conditions of many people were hidden from view” (“Jia Zhangke” 362). Jia’s repeated celebration of the emergence of digital video and the availability of cheap cameras as leading to a democratization of Chinese fi lm-making because more people can become amateur fi lmmakers as a result of greater access to the means of fi lmmaking is important in this regard. See “Now that we have VCDs and Digital Video Cameras” (有了 VCD和数码摄像机以后, Youle VCD he shuma shexiangji yihou) in Jia Xiang, 36–39. For a discussion of Chinese DV documentary, see Yiman Wang, “The Amateur’s Lightning Rod: DV Documentary in Postsocialist China.” For a comprehensive account of Chinese independent fi lm and video, see Zhang 23–45. On Jia’s becoming a mainstream or “above ground” director, see Joey Liu, “Welcome to the Reel World,” South China Morning Post, November 2, 2004, 5. For a fuller discussion of the distinctions between “underground” and “independent” and their implications that also touches on Jia Zhangke’s case, see Pickowicz 1–21. The World was nominated for the Golden Lion Award at the 2004 Venice Film Festival and Still Life, a fi lm on the The Three Gorges Dam project, won the Golden Lion Award in 2006. There was a March 2010 retrospective of his work at the Museum of Modern Art, New York. Richard James Havis, “Clarity Begins at Home,” South China Morning Post, April 1, 2005, 5: “Under the surface, China is not as modern as everyone—even the Chinese themselves—think it is. With The World, I want to show the confl icts between the superficial idea of modernization and the deeper reality of a much deeper backwardness . . . A lot of Chinese people . . . believe that China has really become a part of the international community. But that’s not really a true reflection of the lives of everyday people in China. A family may be able to visit the world in the park. But foreign travel is just a dream . . . Most of the individuals in China are living in an illusory world . . . They don’t really understand what the modern world is like.”

164

Pheng Cheah

23. “The World Park” is a real park in the Fengtai District of Beijing, a suburb sixteen kilometers from the city. The park’s real website is http://www.beijingworldpark.com.cn. The website of the 2008 Beijing Olympics describes it as “featur[ing] 106 of the most famous sites from 14 countries and regions the world over . . . The tourist can take an electric train and a motorboat through the park to simulate a trip around the world.” The Epcot World Showcase is a collection of pavilions in the Walt Disney World Resort, Florida. 24. My interpretation of how the reality/spectacle and truth/illusion oppositions are undone in The World is different from McGrath’s. 25. On the theme-park atmosphere of luxury villa estates in Beijing, see Fowler. 26. In the Chinese version of the DVD, Belleville is another segment title. Hence, what was initially an invagination (the outside turned inward—Paris in Beijing) is turned back outward. 27. On this point, see McGrath 156. 28. Cf. Zhang, “My Camera Doesn’t Lie?” 38–39, who questions the authenticity of Jia’s fi lms. 29. See Derrida, Rogues: Two Essays on Reason, trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas. 30. The pharmakon is an older name for autoimmunization (Borradori 124).

8

Questioning Intellectuals Reading Caste with Gramsci in Two Indian Literary Texts Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

Antonio Gramsci’s writings on the leadership role of intellectuals frame the reading of the two literary works that I focus on in this essay, U. R. Anantha Murthy’s novel in Kannada, Bharathipura (1974), and Indira Parthasarathy’s Tamil play The Legend of Nandan (1978).1 My interest in these texts is directed at the caste politics they represent, from a shared authorial perspective broadly identifiable as upper caste but “progressive.” Their resonance with each other as near-contemporary texts from the same region, southern India, makes it productive to read them together, while at the same time, the different languages in which they are written, their different genres, the different literary histories of which they are products, and the distinctive caste politics of the states they represent, Karnataka and Tamilnadu, respectively, require attention to their contrasting literary and political contexts. Written in the 1970s, a decade of considerable political turbulence in post-Independence Indian history, 2 both texts reflect caste struggle as a key site of political transformation. Literature in the Indian vernaculars (bhashas) written in this decade, like much of the cinema, theater and the other arts, was marked by the newfound political engagement that intellectuals were propelled into by the Emergency. Both Bharathipura and Legend of Nandan build on the recognition of powerful Brahmin hegemony in their respective societies. Both writers are convinced that it is only lower-caste mobilization that can effectively challenge it, but that this revolution will require the initiative and organizational leadership skills of the Gramscian “organic intellectual” to transform both the passivity as well as the intransigence of the untouchables into political discontent. Both works are therefore framed by the problematic of the “collective will.” The test case in both literary works is structured around the untouchables’ entry into the upper-caste temple, which in Bharathipura is coded as an ostensibly iconoclastic act, and in The Legend of Nandan as an ostensibly devotional one. The movements end in failure, represented as such in an uneasily mixed comic-tragic register. The implications of “failure” are, however, open-ended. Bharathipura poses the dilemma of the crypto-authoritarian leadership assumed by the upper-caste, English-educated landlord, and

166

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

explores the legitimacy, efficacy and historical necessity of such a situation. The Legend of Nandan poses the equally fraught question of the exceptional intellectual who develops from within the group but at odds with it, whose religio-aesthetic sensibility, aspirational desires and ambivalence toward his own caste occupation and culture are seemingly both historically necessary and profoundly flawed. The subjective-psychic operation of desire, which is also social-instrumental in its dynamics, is central to caste politics as these works envisage it. But whereas Jagannatha in Bharathipura invokes desire as the means of raising untouchable consciousness, the Brahmins in The Legend of Nandan incite the selfsame desire as a way to trap the untouchable Nandan. I shall leave implicit the intriguing parallels and differences between the two texts—much more can be said obviously about the generic differences between novel and play, and the contemporary versus historical settings of each text—but their relevance for certain kinds of Gramscian analysis should be obvious from this sketch of the arguments they propose. Postcolonial narratives of social struggle are inevitably located within the tension, if not actual contradiction, between subalternity and citizenship, 3 and it is in this context that the role of intellectuals comes to be of central significance. In the case of India, the implicit slogan “society must be led” became the postcolonial bourgeoisie’s rationale for claiming a continuing centrality for itself in the newly independent nation, constitutionally mandated to be a democratic republic. Historically, it was the educated, urban, Hindu uppercaste (and invariably male) leader who emerged from his involvement in the anti-colonial nationalist struggles as the “voice” of the people. In literary texts he becomes the focal point of consciousness.4 The Nehruvian state established major developmental and modernizing agendas for the nation with which educated (and especially bureaucratic) elites, in the decades immediately following independence, were closely associated. Post-Nehru, the belief increasingly spread that the state had ceased to be the primary agent of social change. The question of a civil society in India on the model of Western liberal democracies—its constitution, its autonomy from the state, its conditions of possibility, and the extent of its hegemony—has been widely debated since then. Political analysts like Rajni Kothari have forcefully argued the need for “grass-roots movements and non-party political formations” that will constitute an “autonomous force of civil society,” in opposition to a state that came to be perceived as “repressive and increasingly unrepresentative” (Chatterjee, State and Politics in India 43–44). 5 In her major book about the new social movements in western India, Gail Omvedt celebrated the emergence of new actors on the “stage of history” in the 1970s and 1980s. “For many of India’s oppressed and low-caste poor,” she writes, “the aspiration and reality of becoming historical actors was something new in their lives.” But at the same time she identifies the limits of these new roles. Agency had to be mediated and was sometimes usurped by their representatives (Reinventing Revolution, 250–51). In particular, wherever or whenever “people’s movements”

Questioning Intellectuals

167

failed—either to materialize “spontaneously” or to sustain themselves at the grassroots—they have been taken over by well-meaning elite “volunteers”6 acting in the belief that the people must be “mildly forced to be free.” Their “evangelical impatience,” to borrow Sudipta Kaviraj’s ironic description of middle-class leaders, is embodied perfectly in the character of Jagannatha, the protagonist of Anantha Murthy’s Bharathipura (Kaviraj, “In Search of Civil Society” 287–323, esp. 322). Modern political democracy in India came into direct confrontation with the institution of caste. It is not of course the case that constitutional equality would, or indeed could, demolish caste-based hierarchy in a single stroke. What the confrontation meant was that the problematic was newly structured by caste perceived as injured identity, pitted against the potential and limits of political rights to address that condition (Rao). Opposed and diverse interpretations of caste as the ideological product of religious doctrine, ritual or belief, on the one hand, and as a socioeconomic material condition of poverty, disprivilege, discrimination and occupational marginalization, on the other, have generated multiple modes of caste struggle, led by both uppercaste reformers and untouchable leaders with different emphases. Caste, with its close parallels to race and ethnicity as a discriminatory social system, its overlaps with class as an hierarchical division of labor, and its inextricability from gender and sexuality, has been a potent field of hegemony’s operations in India in the past as well as the present, allowing us to invoke Gramsci’s understanding of power, confl ict and counter-hegemonic struggle productively in reading its narratives. Hegemony is a concept that has considerable explanatory power for understanding the otherwise inexplicable millennial reign of upper-caste (specifically Brahmin) domination that based itself on hereditary authority, cultural superiority, monopoly over learning, economic power and rights of governance—an arrangement that could not have been maintained without the consent of the subordinated. (One of the few direct references that Gramsci makes to India is an allusion to the caste system when he observes, “In both India and China the enormous gap separating intellectuals and people is manifested also in the religious field” [SPNB 23]). The hegemony of Brahmins has survived into postcolonial modernity, thanks to a combination of factors: support from colonial administration, the mobilization of the Hindu religious establishment, upper castes’ opportunistic alliances with upwardly mobile lower castes, and Brahmins’ selective appropriation of and successful adaptation to aspects of modernity. Of course, it is not the case that it is only by consent and moral suasion that caste hierarchy is maintained. Violence and coercion are all too often resorted to as a means of controlling lower caste challenges to the caste order. The narrative Gramsci offers of Jacobinism’s fortunes in France following the Revolution into the “parliamentary regime” is applicable with very few modifications to the narrative of caste struggles in India from the colonial into the postcolonial period:

168

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan The entire society was in a continuous process of formation and dissolution, followed by more complex formations with richer potentialities . . . In this process, attempts at insurrection alternated with pitiless repression, enlargements of political suffrage with restrictions, freedom of association with restriction or annulment of that freedom . . . The “normal” exercise of hegemony on the now classical terrain of the parliamentary regime is characterised by the combination of force and consent, which balance each other reciprocally, without force predominating excessively over consent. (SPNB 80 fn49)

The relatively effortless portability of Gramsci into Third World contexts is most commonly explained with reference to Eric Hobsbawm’s argument in support of a wider applicability of the Italian Marxist’s theorization of world capitalism: Italy was, as it were, a microcosm of world capitalism inasmuch as it contained in a single country both metropolis and colonies, advanced and backward regions . . . [A]n intelligent Italian marxist was in an unusually good position to grasp the nature both of the developed capitalist world and the “Third World” and their interactions, unlike marxists from countries belonging entirely to one or the other. Gramsci therefore was not exclusively “a theorist of ‘western communism.” His thought was neither designed exclusively for industrially advanced countries, nor is it exclusively applicable to them. (“Gramsci and Political Theory” 205–12, esp. 206) I have taken this as license to “apply” hegemony to the Indian context of caste, and have deployed caste subalternity as homologous with subalternity in conventional class terms, that is, the untouchable as continuous with Gramscian “peasant” or “worker.” This subsumption largely reflects the social reality of India. That outcasts/untouchables occupy the economic margins as oppressed class and gendered subjects, are subject to forms of racialized discrimination, and collectively lack the “political organization and representation” of the typical proletariat, are facts that make them the paradigmatic subalterns in a specifically Indian context. Gramsci is useful as well for the questions of representation I foreground in the caste context—that is, questions of subjectivity and leadership—because of the cultural component of caste identity which derives from the caste’s “primordial” connection to religion. Since Gramsci’s ideas of hegemony draw heavily from the significance he attaches to the influence of the Catholic Church in Italy, they serve in my view as a resource for reading caste. On the one hand, Gramsci viewed religion with the familiar skepticism of the secular, left intellectual; his personal knowledge and experience of the Catholic Church in Italy inclined him to view it as supremely hegemonic.

Questioning Intellectuals

169

But keenly aware of the ideological “strength” that the Catholic Church possessed, Gramsci located it primarily in the “doctrinal unity of the whole mass of the faithful,” a unity achieved by the Church ensuring that “the higher intellectual stratum does not get separated from the lower” (SPNB 328). (As noted earlier, Gramsci did not believe this was the case in religion in India or the East Asian countries.) Gramsci therefore found a model in the Church for Marxism. As a “philosophy of praxis,” the latter must remain close to the experience of the people and their “common sense,” in emulation of the former (SPNB 332).7 Although not exclusively or wholly grounded in religion, and more generally tending to follow the variable and shifting dynamics of custom, caste derives considerable sanction from divine ordination. This explains caste hegemony as we saw. On the other hand, religion, in its heterodox aspects, held the potential for radicalism. Gramsci’s interest in the Reformation in Europe was prompted by the historical evidence that religious beliefs could also be critically negotiated to produce an alternative and oppositional consciousness, given the right circumstances.8 Buddhism in India, doctrinally caste-free and gender-equal, arose as a challenge to Brahminism in the sixth century BC, followed by the Reformation-like bhakti movement from the twelfth to the fi fteenth centuries. In the present day, many dalits have refused to be counted as “Hindu” and either resort to converting to another religion, or insist on the separation and distinctiveness of their own religious culture. 9 In the two texts that I discuss in this chapter, caste struggle is located in the historical example of lower castes’ attempts to enter the forbidden territory of the upper-caste Hindu temple. The complex politics of this movement, coded as simultaneously religious/iconoclastic and political/secular, raises questions about caste’s relation to religion that are examined in more detail in the discussion of the texts’ representation of temple entry. Caste was given little prominence in the political schema of newly independent India in Nehru’s regime. It was refused consideration even as a social determinant of poverty, let alone as political identity. The caste dynamics represented in these two texts from southern India reflect a significant shift in the politics of caste that occurred in the 1970s, moving it toward a more identity-based social movement. (There is a general pan-Indian dimension to caste politics, although regional specificities are of significance as well.) The Dalit Panthers movement in Maharashtra was the most significant indication of this change. The radical dalit youth who constituted the movement drew inspiration from the militant race struggles in the United States. Gopal Guru and Anuradha Chakravarty describe their politics as representing a “Gramscian brand of Marxism” insofar as they focused their efforts in the cultural sphere, contesting the “ideological, moral, and cultural superstructure of the political-economic system.” “They missed, however, a key insight of Gramscian Marxism,” they regret. What was needed was a “degree of political organization, the strength of political alliances, and the relations of force

170

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

within a particular historical bloc of contention,” which they were not able to muster (146–47). In particular, the Dalit Panthers, an urban working- class movement, failed to mobilize untouchables in the rural areas, a failure that is notably Gramscian in its diagnosis. In Tamilnadu since the 1970s, dalits have adopted heterogeneous modes of activism; forming NGOs that focus on promoting dalit education, employment opportunities, and human rights; resorting to Communist militancy (primarily over agricultural land issues); following the path of Christian liberation theology; and allying with political parties to capture power at local and regional levels. Jean-Luc and Josiane Racine emphasize the centrality that questions of culture came to have in dalit struggles in Tamilnadu, even though the revolutionary Communist party (Marxist-Leninist) took the lead in agricultural areas by organizing dalit laborers in land struggles (5–19). A key event in the history of the dalit movement in Tamilnadu was the tragedy in Kilvenmani, a village in the Thanjavur district of Tamilnadu in which more than forty dalit farm laborers were burned alive by landlords for demanding higher wages (an event represented by Indira Parthasarathy in a powerful and controversial novel, Kuruthippunal (River of Blood) in 1975). The controversy over whether these laborers were punished because of their caste identity as dalits or as class-subjects continues to this day. That violence against dalits is a continuing reality in the face of both state-led initiatives such as rights and reservations, as well as dalit-led movements for emancipation and political influence, marks caste as a primary site of social confl ict in the state. It is into this volatile situation of caste hegemony, growing dalit mobilization and empowerment, and upper-caste retaliatory violence in the state of Tamilnadu in the 1960s to the 1970s that Indira Parthasarathy’s play, like his earlier novel, made its intervention. In Karnataka, a more specifically literary revolution was initiated in the 1970s, following what came to be known as the “busa controversy” when the dalit politician B. Basavalingappa dismissed all Kannada (upper-caste) literature, classical as well as modern, as useless (busa, meaning husk). This provoked caste ire, but at the same time, led dalit and shudra (other backward caste) intellectuals to reject the dominant literatures of the past including the modernist movement (navya) (to which the writer U. R. Anantha Murthy belonged). The Dalit-Bandaya (rebel) movement engaged in serious debates about cultural issues especially as they related to dalit “cultural memory.” The well-known Kannada critic D. R. Nagaraj is a product of this phase of the cultural politics of the region. Anantha Murthy, sympathetic to but not always in agreement with the dalit movement, took the position that literary criticism would need to be equally attentive to questions of form and aesthetics, while he was clearly also deeply engaged by caste and the role literature played in effecting social change that the dalit cultural movement brought to the fore.10

Questioning Intellectuals

171

This is by way of setting the stage for “questioning” intellectuals, the Gramsci-aided interrogation of the major thematic preoccupation of these works, to which I now turn. Bharathipura Bharathipura is a work of searing brilliance by one of contemporary Kannada literature’s major figures. Asking how caste critique can be articulated by a man belonging to the upper caste, and whether dalit revolution in the form of temple entry can be led by a Brahmin, it engages these questions in a profoundly experimental mode. That Anantha Murthy envisages such critique and praxis in opposition to the expected Gandhian forms is of further extraordinary interest. The book opens with Jagannatha, a wealthy young Brahmin landlord, returning from his studies in England to his native Bharathipura, a small temple town in the district of Shimoga in northern Karnataka. The temple of Manjunatha dominates the town, making it a famous pilgrim location. Jagannatha’s family has been for many generations a patron of the temple. Jagannatha feels he is an unreal and inauthentic person until he loosens the hold of caste-based religion over the untouchables. He begins to build a movement for their entry into the temple where they are ritually forbidden. Jagannatha’s decision to rouse the untouchables to defy the hegemony of the temple and the Brahmins in the town is attended by long and intense discussions with a whole range of friends and opponents. Above all, the decision is accompanied by Jagannatha’s profound musings—political, ethical and existential—as confided to his private journal. The climax of the novel is reached with the temple entry. Before the climatic event, Jagannatha stages a sort of dress rehearsal by making the untouchables go through a test. The “shaligrama test” in Bharatipura is a wellknown, often-cited literary episode. In a passage of unbearable intensity and tense drama, Jagannatha picks up a shaligrama, a sacred fossilized stone that has been worshipped in the puja-room of his home for centuries, and brings it outside the house as an object to be touched—and thereby desacralized—by the untouchables. He encounters opposition from everyone around him, high caste and low, though the opposition is limited to silent resistance. Here is the extract from the novel, some of it in the form of a stream of consciousness: The words that Jagannatha wanted to say stuck in his throat. In a sense, he told himself, “This is fi rst matter, a mere stone. Touch this. I hold my life in my hand in offering this to you. Touch this. The deepest part of my inner being is invested here. Touch this. This is the propitious hour of the evening prayers. Touch this. The eternal lamp is burning in vain in the puja room. Touch this. My people at my back are pulling at me, reminding me of a thousand obligations. What are you waiting

172

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan for? Touch this. Understand what is happening here. By offering this as a mere stone, I turn it into a shaligrama. The minute you touch this, it turns into a mere stone for all these people. My anguish will then become a shaligrama. Because I offer this to you, because you touch it and because these people will witness this on this darkening evening, let stone turn into shaligrama and let shaligrama turn into stone. You Pilla . . . touch this and turn it into stone. After that, in a single step, crossing the threshhold of the temple, centuries will be shaken. Touch this. Touch it now. Touch, touch . . . See how easy it is! Touch!” (148)

But the pariahs recoil in horror. Jagannatha tries persuasion, then great rage overpowers him, and he “turned cruel.” “They appeared to him like disgusting worms.” As he shouts at them, “Touch this, touch this, touch!” they respond with fear, “the untouchables came forward mechanically, touched with no feeling whatsoever what Jagannatha had extended to them and withdraw swiftly.” The rest is anticlimactic. Jagannatha, weakened by cruelty and grief, threw away the shaligrama. His moral anguish had been thoroughly twisted and distorted. He had even lost for a moment the very human feeling Chiki had for the untouchables. He had seen them as meaningless things. Jagannatha stood, hanging his head. He did not realize that the untouchables had left. When he found out that there was no one around him, it was already dark. Loathing himself, he paced around for a while. How he and they had died, losing their humanity, when they touched the stone! The reason for it—was it inside him, or outside in society? (Bharathipura 148 –50) The episode is a “parable” in Anantha Murthy’s own words, accruing deposits of meaning and susceptible to a variety of interpretations by those reading it for their own ends.11 D. R. Nagaraj highlights an aspect that is relevant to my interest here in exploring the implications of the distance and difference between Jagannatha and the untouchables. Nagaraj describes Jagannatha’s rebellion as stemming from “ontological” rather than “organic” necessity since he, Jagannatha, is not himself a “direct victim” of “the structures of humiliation and deprivation that he is fighting” but is instead “driven by a deeper desire to establish a more humane and meaningful relationship with the world” (Introduction to Bharathipura, ix).12 The novel’s interest, Nagaraj goes on to point out, lies in the tragic drama of Jagannatha’s “martyrdom and despair.” There is no denying that the novel’s finest success is to mark through this struggle a growth in the political consciousness of Jagannatha, as revealed in the novel’s conclusion: in his startlingly feminist acceptance of his mother’s sexual infidelity, his renunciation of his lands, his entry into politics as vocation, and his announcement of the “birth of a new man within” (Bharatipura 203). Anantha Murthy himself would no doubt grant this intention.

Questioning Intellectuals

173

Nagaraj acutely notes that the cruel consequence of the rebel’s “grandeur, misery and sentimental attachment to his cause” is that, “in a moment of crisis it transforms itself into pure hatred of the subjects of his cause” (Introduction to Bharathipura x). In the face of Jagannatha’s bullying tactics the untouchables, as we saw, are reduced to passivity, silence and sullen resistance. Along with this failure of humanity, Jagannatha fails strategically also, his intended “act of negation ironically leading to an affi rmation of the same” (Introduction x). Anantha Murthy—and Jagannatha himself—include these critiques of his failure in the episode’s narration and analysis. The self-critique is not simply a rhetorical move intended to pre-empt outside criticism, but the intellectual’s spontaneous, introspective analysis of the limits and costs of ideological struggles led by people like himself. Where, however, would this critique leave Jagannatha’s and the novel’s diagnosis of caste oppression? True, Jagannatha’s strategy is misplaced, not only in the initial shaligrama episode, but also in the climactic temple entry scene. The untouchables arrive at the temple drunk and frightened, dissolving into confusion at the crucial point of entering the temple, and fi nally have to be dragged into the temple by one of the organizers. The idol has meanwhile been taken away and hidden in a genuine act of iconoclasm by the priest’s son, Ganesha. In an ironic reversal of meaning, this act is instead publicized as a devotional one of “rescue”; the temple is not polluted thanks to the idol’s absence at the time. The temple entry collapses into fiasco. All is as it was, and Brahmin hegemony is seemingly restored. How does the failure impact upon the revolutionary enterprise? I wish to read Jagannatha’s anti-caste mission against the grain of its ending in failure in what might seem an inapposite way. Despite his culpable violence and self-centeredness, Jagannatha’s actions are impelled by faith in the transformability of dalit consciousness, accompanied by a commitment to exploring the modalities of such transformation. In what follows, I shall trace his train of thought and actions in some detail. He operates with the logic of touch, appropriately since touch is the ground of untouchables’ oppression (“touch has become one of my themes”) (Anantha Murthy, “Five Decades of My Writing”). When Sripathi Rao admonishes him, “It’s not a question of whether you touch them. What’s important is whether they touch you or want to,” he agrees enthusiastically: “Yes, you’re right, Rao. The day the untouchables want to touch me will be the day of my triumph. I am trying to make it possible for them to have this explosion in their consciousness. The day they make bold to take this one step” (Bharatipura 84). Jagannatha comes to the determination to provoke the untouchables—to “jealousy and greed” if need be—via Engels, “Doesn’t Engels say the reason for history’s march is the evil passion of men?” As he plans the shaligrama test of touching, he dreams, “The untouchables too should desire what we want. An untouchable young man should be able to desire a Brahmin girl. A Brahmin girl should want to sleep with an untouchable. Without desire,

174

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

they will not learn to read and write. From desire, pain. From pain, consciousness” (Bharathipura 138). Fanon is relevant here. “The look that the native turns on the settler’s town is a look of lust, a look of envy, it expresses his dream of possession—all manner of possession—to sit at the settler’s table, to sleep in the settler’s bed, with his wife if possible. The colonized man is an envious man” (The Wretched of the Earth, trans. Constance Farrington 39). That which Fanon sees as the spontaneous, existing consciousness of the native leading to anti-colonial violence (violence as a “cleansing force” that “frees the native from his inferiority complex and from his despair and inaction, [and] restores his self-respect”)—this consciousness is what Jagannatha will first have to provoke in the untouchable whom centuries of religious belief have cowed into submission (94). Jagannatha’s is a preposterous project and projection of desire, the desiring of another’s desire. We are not meant to be blind to the contradictions inherent in his stating “they should desire.” And the fraternity forged from universal male sexual desire is undeniably problematic, “they too should desire what we want,” what the men want being the Brahmin woman (but note, she should desire the untouchable back). The metonymic series of cause-andconsequences that Jagannatha envisages—desire-pain-consciousness—is the inexorable path to be followed by the untouchable, without exception. And sure enough, following the disastrous encounter with the shaligram, Pilla, the untouchable approaches a naked upper-caste woman, Kaveri, when the opportunity offers itself. When Pilla sees her naked with an upper-caste man he rushes to the scene, it might be with rescue in mind. Rightly or wrongly, Jagannatha links Pilla’s awakening of desire for the woman to his experience of having touched the shaligrama. As might be expected, Pilla is framed and arrested, beaten up by the police, and jailed until he is rescued by Jagannatha. This experience of gratuitous violence, by Jagannatha’s logic, will act as the spur to Pilla’s future rebellion. Jagannatha’s earlier failure of humanity in the shaligrama episode is redeemed at this point with his realization that “both he and Pilla had desired the same girl. The strong black body facing him under the gas light was like his own, carnal and fully alive. Jagannatha thought that he could really touch this untouchable” (55). Desire may be shared between the men, but what of the pain? It is, after all, Pilla who is beaten up, and it is the untouchables whose houses are burnt down in upper-caste retaliation for their defiance. Jagannatha may bail Pilla out and build new houses for the untouchable tenants and fi nd them new jobs; but the ethical issue of responsibility remains. Fanon’s invocation of violence, like Jagannatha’s of pain, is susceptible to the accusation of glibness, of a too easy resort to the argument of historical necessity. As Nagaraj says, “The obsession with the historical hardly respects the existential and the quotidian” (Introduction to Bharathipura x). I must leave this as a question with a resonance beyond this context. Would a gradualist pace of reform be necessarily painless? Would a dalit-led

Questioning Intellectuals

175

revolution be able to avoid pain, sacrifice and retaliatory violence? Would not the preservation of the status quo (based on a functionalist argument for caste) guarantee the most painless existence after all? Further, in what sense can Jagannatha be said to oppose the will of the untouchable peasants? It is not as if they have a defi nite alternative agenda, unless it be to continue as they are, not exactly a matter of decisive existential choice. And surely we are allowed to argue “if the modern iconoclast is dehumanizing the Dalits by his actions . . . the established power structures also dehumanize the dalits” (Mallavarapu and Prasad 194). I turn now to a question I posed at the outset about Jagannatha envisaging his project in implicit opposition to the Gandhian forms of caste critique and praxis (I have suggested that it is instead Fanonian in spirit). Gandhi’s ethical address to the caste issue was an appeal to upper castes to transcend caste consciousness; Jagannatha’s, as we saw, is an incitement of the “evil passions of [dalit] men.” Congress-led temple entry had been prominently practiced in the 1920s and 1930s in the Gandhian mode of satyagraha; Jagannatha instead envisages it in the independent India of his time as a storming of the Bastille. Temple satyagraha had been attempted by dalits in large numbers under the leadership of the dalit leader, Dr. B. R. Ambedkar, but with different ends in view than Gandhi’s. Ambedkar was at pains to provide a correct understanding of this symbolic struggle under his leadership. Entry into temples (as also taking water from temple tanks) staked dalits’ claim for equal access to public spaces. It was emphatically not an expression of Hindu devotion, but rather an expression of their claim to modern political rights. As Ambedkar put it succinctly in a speech, “The issue is not entry but equality” (qtd. in Rao 85). Dalit demands were coded in the language of universal civic rights, and Hindu temples were re-designated by them as (secular) public spaces. This was an idiom very different from Gandhi’s argument for untouchable entry into temples that was targeted primarily at the reform of caste Hinduism, to be achieved entirely by upper castes’ voluntary change of heart. Gandhi castigated the independent initiative of dalits in starting the temple satyagrahas since he held that they were incapable of conducting it in the disciplined spirit of non-violence that he advocated (Rao 93–94). Although Jagannatha, as a Brahmin himself, might be expected to subscribe to the Gandhian credo, the emphasis on upper-caste reform and non-violence that such an allegiance would require is conspicuously absent from his arguments. The novel in fact gently satirizes a minor character (Ananthakrishna, a Sarvodaya activist) for the Gandhian language he bandies, even though he does support Jagannatha’s temple entry project. He is shown to be more concerned about “the need for non-violence” while staging the temple entry, and about the benefit a caste-reformed Hinduism would gain from it (“the glory of Manjunatha would be enhanced by the entry of the untouchables into the temple”) (Anantha Murthy, Omnibus 231).

176

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

But Jagannatha neither takes recourse to the more advanced language of rights nor challenges the so-called “private” terrain of the Hindu temple, as Ambedkarite activists did. His reasoning most closely resembles instead Ambedkar’s as expressed in the following letter he wrote: I did not launch the temple entry movement because I wanted the Depressed Classes to become worshippers of idols . . . or because I believed that temple entry would make them equal members in and an integral part of Hindu society . . . [but] only because I felt that was the best way of energizing the Depressed Classes and making them conscious of their position. (qtd in Omvedt, Ambedkar 57) These multiple positions around temple entry—Fanon’s putative violence, Gandhi’s non-violent satyagraha, Ambedkar’s strategic consciousness-raising—reveal its multi-dimensionality as a political and ethical crux of the caste struggle. The space of the novel allows the author to explore the limits and possibilities of temple entry as political experiment, even if somewhat anachronistically. It is this openness that makes Bharathipura, to my mind, a work of such profound engagement. It is interesting and surely significant that in Bharathipura, Anantha Murthy combines a Gramscian-Ambedkarite interest in the strategic aspects of subaltern mobilization of this kind, with more specific ethical issues surrounding subaltern representation. Like most other critics of the novel, it is the latter that I have focused on until now. Such ethical issues have been of particular concern to the Subaltern Studies school in their engagement with the peasant and tribal in colonial history. In the novel, the focus on the upper-caste protagonist’s subjectivity at the expense of the untouchables, and the rendering of Jagannatha’s behavior as coercively modernizing, dehumanizing, and arrogantly knowing in both thought and praxis, highlight the kind of ethical dilemma that Dipesh Chakrabarty, for instance, has found intellectually paralyzing. Chakrabarty has expressed acute angst about what he sees as the non-democratic nature of the subaltern historian’s “dialogue” with the object of his study. Subaltern Studies itself, he feels, in its foundational allegiance to Gramsci, was guilty of such a “pedagogic” address to the subaltern, one that foreclosed on the possibility of the historian’s being able to learn from the other. Chakrabarty deplores Gramsci’s view of subalternity as a political position that, “by itself, was incapable of thinking the state” and his conviction that “this was a thought to be brought to that position by the revolutionary intellectual” (34). Gramsci, on the other hand, as Timothy Brennan has explained, viewed the subaltern primarily as “the target of organizational overcoming” rather than as “an already complete ‘resistant presence’” (“Antonio Gramsci and Postcolonial Theory” 143–87, esp. 170; emphasis added). I shall return to this less-discussed Gramscian dimension of the caste politics of the novel after

Questioning Intellectuals

177

fi rst clarifying a couple of points relating to the debate on the ethical issues at stake. The fi rst relates to the controversial question of subaltern representation. Gramsci’s understanding of peasant consciousness (especially in “backward” countries, as he explains) is lacking in the kind of political correctness we have come to expect in representations of the subaltern.13 In several of the articles he wrote for the party journal the subaltern is at best regarded as a “pre-political” “primitive rebel” (Hobsbawm, Primitive Rebels). Hobsbawm and Gramsci share the view that the subaltern was capable of sporadic violent revolts but not of a sustained campaign. The peasant, Gramsci notes, may “erupt in violent revolt against the ‘gentry’ every now and then, but he is incapable of seeing himself as a member of a collectivity (the nation for the land-holders, the class for the proletarians), nor can he wage a systematic and permanent campaign designed to alter the economic and political relations of society” (in Forgacs, The Antonio Gramsci Reader 114). At the same time Gramsci also took seriously as we know the “common sense” of the peasant, gave credit to the “necessity” of his religion, and pursued an interest in folklore. His suggestive observations about the role of culture in shaping the revolutionary consciousness anticipate Fanon’s memorable injunction to intellectuals participating in decolonizing movements: “It is not enough to get back to the people in that past out of which they have already emerged; rather we must join them in that fluctuating movement which they are just giving shape to . . . It is to this zone of occult instability where the people dwell that we must come” (The Wretched of the Earth 227). Like Fanon, Gramsci was convinced of the need to involve the peasantry in the revolutionary project and believed in their political potential.14 Note that the passage cited above does not propose a reified peasant consciousness. On the contrary it is a prelude to Gramsci’s optimistic observation that participation in the war of 1914 “radically changed the peasant psychology” (emphasis added). The war opened up to the subaltern class a knowledge of the larger world, forged solidarities among the soldiers, and fashioned a “common, united spirit,” so much so that “a spiritual world emerged that was avid to form itself into permanent and dynamic social structures and institutions” (in Forgacs, Gramsci Reader 115). It is this kind of understanding of subaltern consciousness, based on a closely observed knowledge of the “totality of subaltern existence” that Bharathipura also expresses—and being novelistic fiction is particularly fitted to express.15 As in Gramsci’s writings, the emphasis in the novel is on dalit potentiality, change and growth of political consciousness rather than on the “autonomy” and “spontaneity” that invests subalterns with a spurious “agency,” or the kind of “respect” that would preserve them in their immutable difference. Here for instance is a passage that expresses Gramsci’s faith in subaltern will and its capacity for transformation that resonates closely with Jagannatha’s hopes for untouchable emancipation: “[B]asically

178

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

if yesterday the subaltern element was a thing, today it is no longer a thing but an historical person, a protagonist.” This quickly leads to the insight, “But even yesterday was it ever mere ‘resistance,’ a mere ‘thing,’ mere ‘nonresponsibility?’ Certainly not.” Gramsci attributes the earlier condition to “fatalism,” which is “nothing other than the clothing worn by real and active will when in a weak position.” Intellectuals who subscribe to a philosophy of such “mechanical determinism” end by making it a “cause of passivity, of idiotic self-sufficiency” (SPNB 337). Gramsci’s warning is useful to bear in mind when we turn to certain popular misconceptions about Jagannatha’s pedagogy. Like many other readers, Latour makes the assumption that the shaligrama experiment is intended to vanquish the untouchables’ superstitious faith. Not so: it is the Brahmins’ fetish—and to a considerable extent the unacknowledged hold that it has on his own psyche as well—that Jagannatha wishes to de-fetishize. There is nothing to suggest that the shaligrama means anything to the untouchables other than an object that belongs to the Brahmins and hence is forbidden to their touch. It is the prohibition they respect, not the stone. It is this taboo (to invoke another Freudian term) that Jagannatha wishes to break by the empirical challenge of touch: “See? Nothing happened.”16 (And at the same time that he sets out to prove the inconsequentiality of touch, he also, let us note, seeks to fi ll it with the charge of sexuality.) The distinction between fetish and faith is the distinction between the traditional and the organic intellectual’s respective responses to a stone. And it is the former that stands in need of correction, not the latter. To regard Jagannatha as a modernizing, secular force is therefore correct but insufficient. Certainly he is armed with his reading of Russell and Marx, and it is true that he wishes to force the pace of change. But he is only too aware that the millennial power of religion will not be defeated by theatrical flourishes. The narrative reversals with which the book concludes have something of inevitability about them. That the attacks on the mystique of deities and sacred objects should rebound, and that the desecrated shaligrama should be purified and reinstalled, the idol recovered, and the temple the untouchables entered be cleansed and made fit for upper-caste worship again: none of this should surprise us. The hold of caste goes beyond religion as we saw, and therefore the secularizing or iconoclastic response has only limited impact. The sociality of caste relations is built on tradition (history, culture) and derives its meaning from the force of material conditions, both economic and political. It requires a revolutionary praxis for which ideology critique is a necessary fi rst step, even if only the fi rst step. In summing up the ethical import of Jagannatha’s movement, I would be inclined to argue that even where the novel shows the troubling aspects of elite-led reform, it redeems it by identifying the democratizing impulse that lies at its heart. In Bharathipura, this impulse is envisaged as the incipience of brotherhood between would-be reformer and the putative subject of his

Questioning Intellectuals

179

reform, even if seemingly it has to be forged on the problematic grounds of shared male sexual desire for the upper-caste woman. Jagannatha sees the untouchables as people to be educated and converted to be like himself, in both outward form and inner compulsion.17 Anantha Murthy’s understanding of caste as an intimate form of social relationship within the ambience of a southern agrarian small town, perhaps also his location within a Kannada literary tradition which, as Nagaraj points out, has long been interested in exploring the tension between a revolutionary vanguard and the masses, allows him to frame the question of caste relations in more complex ways than many other left radical (and similarly Brahmin-authored), or liberal-humanist texts.18 He does this mainly by stressing the affect-laden dimensions of the relationship in actual situations of social crises. In general, the novel form tends to reduce politics to the liberal contours of interpersonal relations. Anantha Murthy’s interest in the dynamics of social transformation in this novel is therefore exceptional. The position taken in Bharathipura is that an elite-led modern, rational, secular impetus for change that stems from the belief that everyone wants the same thing, is—therefore—democratic. In conclusion, I turn to the strategic aspects of caste mobilization as envisaged in Bharathipura. These must be viewed in both continuation of and contrast to the predominantly ethical issues that Jagannatha’s leadership has brought to the discussion so far. The distinction between the “strategic” and the “ethical” is an admittedly imprecise one that I take recourse to here as a heuristic in order to understand specific historical conjunctures. Where solidarities are forged across social division—as in times of revolutionary class struggle, during anti-colonial liberation struggles, or in contemporary civil society “new” social movements—it is common to fi nd that leadership is taken over by a “vanguard,” either in the form of the Party or in the person of an individual of the traditional ruling class. Such leadership can be “strategic” only if it is provisional and coalitional in nature. Gramsci’s understanding of the necessary alliance of intellectuals and masses (the people-nation) has been expressed in The Prison Notebooks as the complementarity of the “knowledge” that the one possesses to the “feeling” that characterizes the other: One cannot make politics-history without . . . this sentimental connection between intellectuals and people-nation . . . If the relationship between intellectuals and people-nation, between the leaders and the led, the rulers and the ruled, is provided by an organic cohesion in which feeling-passion becomes understanding and thence knowledge (not mechanically but in a way that is alive), then and only then is the relationship one of representation. (SPNB 418) While Gramsci sees the leadership of intellectuals as essential for the success of a subaltern revolutionary movement, it is important not to conflate these intellectuals with the middle class as such, as is the case in Fanon’s

180

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

analysis. The “intellectuals” Gramsci has in mind are not, or are not in the fi rst place, “traditional” intellectuals or intellectuals of the ruling class, but rather those who emerge “organically” from within the group itself. Gramsci is more interested in the formation of “homogeneous, compact social blocs, which will give birth to their own intellectuals, their own commandos, their own vanguard” (SPNB 205; emphasis added).19 His position is developed through historical analysis and is primarily related to considerations of the organization of the Communist party in Italy, not formulated as an abstract ethical issue for the academic to ponder (SPNB 202–05, 310). Therefore for Gramsci the key distinction would be between “intellectual elites separated from the masses” and those “conscious of being linked organically to a national-popular mass” (SPNB 204). Only the latter counts as the organic intellectual. The question if applied to Bharathipura would be whether Jagannatha succeeds in “shedding the false heroisms and pseudo-aristocracies” that for Gramsci characterizes the déclassé or nomadic (in other words, dilettantish) intellectual who enters the political fray (SPNB 204).20 Jagannatha’s caste identity as a Brahmin marks him as intellectual by tradition, an identity further reinforced by his modern education. His voluntary, existentially mandated entry into social activism in his native Bharathipura is by itself of course no guarantee of Gramscian organicity (or “authenticity” as it is termed in the novel). What matters is that despite his long stay abroad in England and the modernity toward which he ideologically leans, Jagannatha is no outsider to the region, nor is he alienated from its people and politics. Instead he cultivates a unique double perspective, which is also a source of confl ict (the mark of the postcolonial intellectual). In his introduction to Bharathipura Nagaraj has made it a point to draw attention to Anantha Murthy’s own familiarity with locality, his intimate connection to place, and his political activism and commitment, which are similar to Jagannatha’s in the novel. Gayatri Spivak’s clarification that “organic intellectual is not a concept of identity but a . . . function,” can help us to understand how the move into organicity is made from both sides, the subaltern’s as well as the intellectual’s. She reminds us that “the word ‘class’ loses its lineaments” in Gramsci’s defi nition of organic intellectuals in terms of a formation that is to be found in every class (“Translator’s Preface” 209). The leadership of intellectuals, we noted, would have to be provisional and coalitional. Obviously there is a sense of temporality operative in judging the legitimacy and effectiveness of the role played by the “voluntary” leader in subaltern movements: just as there is a period when particular groups will need the support of leaders, the time will also come when the latter’s uses will cease and their presence will become irksome. A Brahmin-led caste movement today would not only be highly unlikely but also far more politically problematic than in the rural Karnataka of the 1960s in which Bharathipura is set. To recognize and acknowledge subaltern autonomy—and announce its own demise at the precise point of its attainment—is the Gramscian task of the historical vanguard.

Questioning Intellectuals

181

Indira Parthasarathy’s Legend of Nandan, to which I shall now turn, presents us with a different phenomenon: the emergence of the organic intellectual from within his own social group. While sidestepping questions about “authenticity,” the play reveals how his leadership is nevertheless fraught with contradictions and existential pain. And the specter of failure haunts both works, a matter for the concluding discussion. The Legend of Nandan Published not long after Bharathipura, The Legend of Nandan (Nandan Kathai in Tamil, 1978) is a more overtly polemical text about caste politics in southern India.21 In this play Indira Parthasarathy, an established Delhi-based Tamil scholar, dramatist and novelist associated with a broad left radical political activism, rewrites the seventh-century figure of an untouchable field laborer, Nandan, who has been transformed into a saint and is celebrated in the legend and myth of the Tamil country for his bhakti (religious devotion). Parthasarathy seeks to expose in this sharp, swift-paced, explosive drama the ploy of the upper castes to halt Nandan’s rise as a caste leader by plotting his death.22 This version of the legend has wide currency to this day and Nandanar, as he is known, is a venerated saint in the canon of Tamil bhakti figures. In the nineteenth century the story was revised by the poet Gopala Krishna Bharati, and made to serve as a pointed critique of Brahminism, which Indira Parthasarathy further sharpens in his own revisionary work. Parthasarathy makes clear at the outset in an Author’s note, that he will refer to his hero as plain “Nandan,” forswearing the widespread form “Nandanaar” because the “‘—aar’ is not an honorific but a cross to bear” (2). He thereby makes clear his refusal of the ideological and instrumental elevation of the untouchable into sainthood. The play exposes the Brahmin conspiracy to destroy Nandan and quell the untouchables under his leadership. More ambitiously, Indira Parthasarathy’s robust Marxist demystification of the meaning of Nandan’s life is meant to contest the upper-castes’ historical victory in establishing the “legend” of Nandan in their own chosen terms, that is in terms of his transcendent religious devotion alone, an emphasis which ignores his tragic death and their own role in bringing it about. Parthasarathy’s interest in the play is divided between showing the singular development of Nandan’s consciousness as a lover of Beauty and the devious cunning of Brahmins and other upper-castes (merchants, landlords) who plot his downfall. Nandan worships the beauty of God (who is a Brahmin God), the arts, music and dance through which this God’s greatness is celebrated, and the beauty of (a) woman, the temple dancer, who represents all of these. His desire is invested with the kind of political force that Jagannatha had intuited was necessary for the awakening of dalit consciousness in Bharatipura. His constant reiteration of what constitutes the

182

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

“human”—significantly, in terms of the experience of the aesthetics of pleasure, desire and transcendence—leads Nandan to criticize the untouchables’ life-world and propels him into a romantic and ideological alliance with the dancer, Abhirami. Not content with self-reformation, in the characteristic way of the organic intellectual he seeks to persuade his fellow-pulaiyars (the untouchable caste of field-laborers) to follow him into the new way of life he envisages as their salvation.23 (Note that this detail about pulaiyar mobilization under Nandan’s leadership is Parthasarathy’s own contribution to the historical account.) At this point the upper castes step in to manipulate both Nandan’s newly enlarged sphere of consciousness and his growing constituency. It is they who bring him into proximity with Abhirami so as to arouse envy among his fellow pulaiyars; they who divide him from his community and its norms; who convince him of dreams, voices, and visions purportedly coming from God himself; deceive him with manufactured miracles; and endow him with dubious religious powers. And fi nally it is they who persuade him to walk into the purificatory ritual fi re with Abhirami as a way of cleansing himself of the dross of his caste-being and achieve rebirth. The play ends with the sound of the victims’ “non-human wails” as they burn. Even as the Vediyar exclaims on the “wonder” of their martyrdom, the Udaiyar asks the watching crowd, “Are there any more paraiyans who desire to become paarpaans? . . . come, come! If you take a dip in the fi re . . .” (ellipses in original). The concluding stage directions: “Exit the paraiyans running for their dear lives” (49). Parthasarathy admittedly uses exposé as the blunt weapon of demystification. The play is not without its contradictions and ambivalences, however: it conveys as well more profound complexities about the nature of individual and collective social resistance. Critics of the play were quick to note, for instance, the writer’s uncertainty about how to develop Nandan’s character. C.T. Indra cites the Tamil critic Uthirapathi who observed that “while in the beginning he [Nandan] is seen as governed by the reason and thinking that marks any ideologue, he later rather naively succumbs to the ploy of the upper castes and accepts the commands of an allegedly astral voice which is heard by some of the characters” (xix). There is a suggestion all the same that Nandan is never entirely taken in by the status transformation he undergoes, but is instead overwhelmed and overpowered by the public image he has to live up to—which of course, only makes him even more the puppet of the Brahmins who fi rst created and then exploited the image. An extension of the characterological question leads to the central and unresolved dilemma of the play: how to expose the Brahmins without simultaneously reducing Nandan’s status to that of a simpleton and dupe. The division in the representation of Nandan between autonomous, even subversive intellectual development and leadership, on the one hand, and his victimhood and defeat at the hands of his caste enemies, on the other, is symptom of this deeper aporia. Nandan is the celebrated untouchable subject of bhakti

Questioning Intellectuals

183

in the medieval literary tradition. When he is rescued from that apotheosized representation it is only to be revealed as dupe and victim—the mere object—of Brahmin conspiracy. The mainspring of Nandan’s agency lies in his caste-transcendent bhakti. By making Brahmin manipulation rather than this autonomous devotion the cause of his death, Parthasarathy undermines Nandan’s agential motivation and initiative. The untouchable devotee becomes primarily a bone of contention between opposed literary-political interpretations. Whether the point that Parathasarathy is attempting to make is that religion itself—all religion—is a delusion, or whether he means to suggest that Nandan’s coming under its sway as an untouchable intellectual, is a political error: in either case he cannot allow Nandan’s death to be meaningful. In attempting to re-code religious martyrdom as secular tragedy, he reduces it to near-farce. The representation of hegemony’s operations (representation functioning here as literal disclosure) is not sufficient to strip it of its potency. On the contrary, it ends by reproducing and reinforcing it. Unable to deny that it is Nandan’s religious aspirations which are as much transgressive as they are conservative, that constitute his exceptional character and his organicity, Indira Parthasarathy arrives at a creative solution: he resorts to the aestheticization of Brahmin ritual as a way of sidestepping a direct address to the question of Nandan’s religiosity. 24 Nandan is thus able to identify himself as simply “a slave of beauty.” When Abhirami presses him to explain “whose beauty,” he replies, “You, your dance, and the deity you worship” (Parthasarathy 8). It is in effect his appreciation of beauty, sensuous rather than spiritual in nature, that is displaced on to religion. Nor is this necessarily only an ideological maneuver on the writer’s part. The arts, architecture, music and dance of the medieval period were so comprehensively performed in the service of the temple that it would have been impossible to separate the aesthetic from the religious in any clear-cut way (arguably this is still true of much traditional Indian culture). Nandan’s religious fervor and his aesthetic passion are fused. It is his fervent expressions of religio-aesthetic sensibility that give us access to his interiority, where his poignant love of beauty and aspiration for a better life is revealed. The religio-aesthetic domain to which Nandan turns is, however, inexorably caste-marked, dominated as it is by a monopolistic Brahmin high culture. The playwright himself succumbs to the lure of Brahminical culture by copiously reproducing it in the play in the songs Nandan sings, the dances Abhirami performs, and the images of the dancing Nataraja that are reproduced in the sets on stage. Not that the author is oblivious to the reality that culture is a contested political terrain in caste struggles, so much so that he includes a (somewhat gratuitous) scene in which the Brahmins propose and stage a contest between “our” dance, Bharatanatyam (the highly evolved temple dance performed by Abhirami) and “their” dance, koothu (the vigorous folk dance of the paraiyans). The contest ends by reinforcing the superiority of Brahmin culture (for the audience in the theatre we can’t help noting, as much as the

184

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

audience on stage); while at the same time it also demonstrates Nandan’s alienation from his own people. Moving on to another aspect of the organic intellectual—whose “mode of being” as famously described by Gramsci would consist in “active participation in practical life, as constructor, organiser, ‘permanent persuader’ and not just a simple orator,” and who thereby becomes “‘directive’ (specialized and political)”— Parthasarathy’s reading of the legend highlights the social disturbance that Nandan’s aspirations provoke (SPNB 10). Therefore the play shows not only Nandan’s individual hubris that the Brahmins set out to check, but also the beginnings of collective unrest. His mobilization of the puliyars is not limited to being a cultural movement. It has its material aspects as reflected in agricultural labor and class relations. The landlord and merchant upper castes in the play are profoundly worried about the neglect of the harvest and other menial tasks that the pulaiyars and paraiyars are exclusively assigned to do, according to a permanently entrenched division of labor. Equally, the untouchables opposed to Nandan fear the loss of their wages and punishment by the masters. While caste is not reducible to class, the class aspect of caste formation cannot be long overlooked. 25 At the play’s opening, the four vediyars (brahminical Vedic scholars, priests) assemble to discuss Nandan’s threat in a series of quick exchanges: Nandan is carrying on a “campaign” among the pulaiyars; he is “trying to turn the paraccheri (untouchable neighborhood) into an agraharam (Brahmin neighborhood)”; he advises the people “to give up the paraiya God” and embrace “the paarpaara God” (6). What does Nandan’s campaign entail? “I am bringing around the folks of my cheri to my way of thinking. I shall bring a few of them [to the temple] . . . those who wallow in squalor worshipping the palla deity should know what a paarpaara deity is like,” he tells Abhirami (10). He is angry with his people for indulging in mere drinking, dancing and eating, and for the mindless labor they perform. In argument with them, he denies that caste is “a loss which one suffers at birth.” “No, it’s a law made by the rich.” It is a thing of the mind, “Half of it is just what the upper castes say. The rest of it is what we think ourselves.” He speaks to them of “Beauty,” which consists of “being human”: “we’re beasts, we must become human” (12). The play consequently shows untouchable life as brutal and bestial. Nevertheless, even in the face of such a representation, the paraiyas are able to defend their way of life with arguments built on a powerful sense of autonomy, coupled with a critique of Brahminical life. Nandan’s own repudiation of his stigmatized culture, origins and people, and his desire for the “other,” remain unalterable. It is seemingly the tragic price the untouchable intellectual pays for his caste-consciousness. D. R. Nagaraj observes how frequently “the birth of the modern individual in the humiliated communities is not only accompanied by a painful severing of ties with the community, but also a conscious effort to alter one’s past is an integral part of it” (7–8).26 Here

Questioning Intellectuals

185

Indira Parthasarathy stages one of the central debates relating to modern dalit cultural politics. Nandan is one in a long line of caste leaders, dalit as well as savarna (upper caste), who have propagated the reform of untouchable customs and manners so total as to threaten to undermine dalit identity itself.27 That there are serious and long-lasting implications to this reformist pedagogy has since come to be recognized.28 Interestingly however, the possibility of such self-alienation is not an eventuality that Gramsci takes cognizance of in urging the emergence of the organic intellectual into leadership. In the teleology of history we do often fi nd that in the liberatory movements of stigmatized groups self-transformation and radical reform precede self-acceptance and the demand for recognition. It is to this earlier stage of untouchable politics that Nandan belongs. It is an approach not unlike that of dalit leaders, like Ambedkar, whose emphasis on organizational strategy and social transformation we may plausibly describe as Gramscian, in marked divergence from the kind of respect for dalit “difference” that is recommended by Indian subaltern historians like Dipesh Chakrabarty in an avowedly Heideggerian mode, and different also from the “recognition” that is demanded by contemporary dalit intellectuals. Timothy Brennan insists vehemently on the need to mark Gramsci’s political agenda as distinct from the Heideggerian ontology subscribed to by the subalternists, as follows: Having no desire to “give voice” to the essential wisdom of the subaltern, or glorify subalternity as such, Gramsci repeatedly made clear in his writing the need for the training and discipline provided by education, “national-popular” literature, and other practices that would, in essence, eradicate subalternity. (“Antonio Gramsci and Postcolonial Theory” 166, 170; emphasis added). Nandan’s failure as leader, beyond strategic considerations, is typically attributed to the ideological abjectness of his upward caste mobility that, when it takes the form of imitating upper-caste customs and manners and is attended by repudiation of indigenous practices, has been described in Indian caste sociology as “Sanskritization.”29 The Sanskritization theory is not innocent of “perpetuating the hierarchy it purports to reduce,” as Andrew Parker observes of Bourdieu’s sociology of class-distinction (xvi). But is Nandan’s passion for the Brahmin God even adequately captured by the Sanskritization thesis? The literary text’s formal insistence on singularity as much as Indira Parthasarathy’s own investment in endowing Nandan with a complex psychic interiority, makes his behavior seem both less and more than the collective social impetus that inspires so-called Sanskritization: less, because its aesthetic fervor is seen as unique to him rather than typical of his class; more, because it is directed at a radically egalitarian end, not at conservative adaptation. We might come closer to understanding Parthasarathy’s Nandan as a Gramscian organic intellectual if we were to understand his thirst

186

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

for forbidden education as somewhat analogous to that of Kumud Pawde, a mahar by caste who became a Sanskrit scholar against all the odds, rather than as one succumbing to Sanskritization, the sociological process (Pawde 96–106). Needless to say the distance between Sanskritization and the dalit acquisition of Sanskrit is a vast one. Parthasarathy’s endowment of Nandan with the attributes of a poet manqué heightens this more radical characterization.30 By breaking out of caste-based occupation into an inappropriate aestheticism and religious devotion Nandan, however limited by the models of idealized upper-caste life available to him, not only functions as an overt (if containable) threat to the social order of his times but also unsettles an influential explanation of the sociology of caste. We are left, nevertheless, with the indisputable reality that The Legend of Nandan explicitly marks the historical defeat of the untouchable intellectual by the successful workings of upper-caste hegemony. How then should we read subaltern failure—or read this particular reading of subaltern failure—in political and historical terms? Gramsci for instance concludes from his reading of the Risorgimento that “the history of subaltern groups is necessarily fragmented and episodic” since their attempts at “unification” are thwarted by the ruling groups (emphasis added). “Subaltern groups are always subject to the activity of ruling groups, even when they rebel and rise up: only ‘permanent’ victory breaks their subordination, and that not immediately.” This is what makes it all the more important to record “every trace of independent initiative on the part of subaltern groups” (SPNB 54–55). Gayatri Spivak was quick to note that the historical writings of the Subaltern Studies collective too are invariably “accounts of failures.” It would be a mistake however, she warns, to correlate subaltern failure to the “level of consciousness” of the class. The theoretical innovation of subaltern historiography is that the distinction between success and failure is itself deconstructed (made “indeterminate”) in the work of the collective. The “possibility of failure cannot be derived from any criterion of success unless the latter is a theoretical fiction” (“Subaltern Studies” 3–34, especially 5–7). The seesaw of interpretations of Nandan’s subjectivity and actions within the play itself—between hubris and humiliation, autonomy and false consciousness, resistance and subjection, agency and victimization—is therefore due in part at least to the difficulties of deciding subaltern success and failure by established criteria. From the conventional Marxist point of view that is attributable to the author himself, the subaltern cast of the play, that is, Nandan, Abhirami, and the pulaiyars, suffer a defeat that is coded in the traditional language of class struggle. Historically the conditions of possibility for the emergence of caste mobilization led by an untouchable cannot be expected to be present in the eighth century feudal past in which the events take place, a period marked by increasing Brahmin dominance following the defeat of Buddhist influence in the Tamil country. And as an allegory of the present, the play’s profound pessimism about organized (agrarian) resistance can

Questioning Intellectuals

187

be attributed to the likelihood that Parthasarathy linked his reading of the fate of the historical Nandan to the brutal retaliation that was carried out against dalit peasants in Velmani village, and the blatant miscarriage of justice that had resulted in the acquittal of the landlords responsible for the killings, only a few years before. In a return to Gramsci, however, we can read the dominant groups’ resort to violence against the subaltern/dalit—in both the play and its present-day context—in symptomatic terms, as an indication of a “crisis of authority.” “If the ruling class has lost its consensus, i.e. is no longer ‘leading’ but only ‘dominant’, exercising coercive force alone, this means precisely that the great masses have become detached from their traditional ideologies, and no longer believe what they used to believe previously etc,” writes Gramsci. This moment then is an “interregnum,” harboring revolutionary potential (SPNB 276). Like Gramsci, the two writers I have discussed in this chapter also read history as a process rather than in terms of a single, defi nitive and conclusive event. While as literary texts these imaginative reconstructions of subaltern insurgency may not be able to entirely avoid narrative telos, their formal open-endedness allows us to glimpse a future beyond the closing verdict of failure. The reading of these texts as representation of an “interregnum” fi lled with uncertainty and potential is made possible, in my view, by Gramsci’s analysis of subaltern history. Notes 1. Anantha Murthy, Bharathipura (1974) translated from Kannada by P. Sreenivasa Rao (New Delhi: Macmillan India, 1996); Indira Parthasarathy, Nandan Kathai (1978), in English The Legend of Nandan, translated from Tamil by C. T. Indra (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2000). All page references to the Introduction and the English translation are to these editions and are given in parentheses within the text. 2. The 1970s in India witnessed India Gandhi’s promulgation of a state of national emergency, a two-year period (1975–1977) when the democratic state experienced a profound crisis. 3. Pandey offers a perceptive theoretical discussion of this development. 4. Salman Rushdie’s Midnight’s Children (1981) is the locus classicus here. It is of course the timing of Saleem Sinai’s birth and not his participation in the freedom struggle that entitles him to national centrality. 5. Chatterjee is referring to later works of Rajni Kothari such as Politics and the People: In Search of a Humane Idea. 6. Gramsci gives the name of “volunteers” to those individuals who “have detached themselves from the mass [i.e., their own class] by arbitrary individual initiative, and who often stand in opposition to that mass or are neutral with respect to it” (SPNB 203). 7. But Marxism must also be the “antithesis” of the Church in that a Marxist organization, unlike the Catholic Church, cannot leave the masses content in their

188

8.

9.

10.

11.

12.

13.

14.

15.

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan common sense but will seek to lead them instead towards a “higher conception of life” (SPNB 332). On the Lutheran Reformation and Calvinism constituting a “vast nationalpopular movement” in Europe, especially in Germany (but not in Italy), see SPNB 394ff. The religious politics of caste is summed up in Ambedkar’s forceful anti-Hindu argument in favor of conversion: “I had the misfortune of being born with the stigma of an untouchable but will not die a Hindu for this is in my power” (B. R. Ambedkar, Bombay Chronicle, October 16, 1935; cited in Rao 118). I have drawn on Prithvi Datta Chandra Shobhi’s Introduction to D. R. Nagaraj, The Flaming Feet and Other Essays: The Dalit Movement in India for this abbreviated account of the Kannada cultural scene in the 1970s. Anantha Murthy in his Samvatsar lecture at the Sahitya Akademi, “Five Decades of My Writing.” Bruno Latour has used Jagannatha to serve as an example of the kind of iconoclast whose action he reads as reductively secular and impoverishing: “The fetish gains strength in the hands of anti-fetishists . . . Neither the aunt nor the priest considered the saligram as anything but a mere stone. Never.” See Latour 270–71, cited in Srikanth Mallavarapu and Amit Prasad, “Facts, Fetishes and the Parliament of Things.” In a fine critique of Latour’s reading of the episode, Mallavarapu and Prasad have deplored Latour’s failure to contextualize the episode within the book, as also his ignorance of the “position the stone occupies (and has occupied for centuries) in a network of caste hierarchies that the priest and the aunt operate in” (194), and his larger disregard of the complex career of modernity’s “mediations and translations” in the non-West (192). The influence of European existentialist philosophy on Anantha Murthy’s fiction of the 1960s and 1970s has been remarked upon frequently, criticized as both derivative and unsuited to his “Indian” subject matter. In Bharathipura, however, Jagannatha appears to invoke the philosophical language of existentialism deliberately, in the conviction that his search for “authenticity” constitutes a stronger ethical motive than liberalism. His “experiment” would involve “some cruelty,” he realizes; the untouchables must be “assaulted.” “But could he, a polite liberal, mount this assault?” (Bharathipura 137). Ultimately Jagannatha can be convicted of many things, but not of inauthenticity—or liberalism. Gramsci is indebted to Marx’s analysis of the psychology of small peasant proprietors in The Eighteenth Brumaire where the diagnosis of the division between their class identity and their class consciousness/interest leads to the famous pronouncement that “they cannot represent themselves; they must be represented.” “Antonio Gramsci’s work on the ‘subaltern classes’ extends the class-position/ class-consciousness argument isolated in The Eighteenth Brumaire,” observes Spivak (“Can the Subaltern Speak?’” 271–313, especially 283). “The proletariat can become the leading [dirigente] and the dominant class to the extent that it creates a system of class alliances which allows it to mobilize the majority of the working population against capitalism and the bourgeois state” (‘Some Aspects of the Southern Question,’ in Forgacs, Gramsci Reader, 173). In “Southern Question,” as is well known, Gramsci urges the alliance of the northern proletarian factory-worker with the peasant in the South. The phrase is Marcus Green’s, “Gramsci Cannot Speak” (88). Gramsci, Green elaborates, was interested in “the integral relationship between their [subalterns’]

Questioning Intellectuals

16.

17.

18.

19. 20.

21.

22. 23.

24.

25.

26. 27.

28.

189

economic, political, and social positions; the stages of their development in history; their significance in cultural forms; how they are represented in literature; and so forth.” Anantha Murthy writes in an essay, “Haven’t I become what I am by demythifying, even desecrating, the world of my childhood? As a boy growing up in my village, didn’t I urinate stealthily and secretly on sacred stones under trees to prove to myself that they have no power over me?” in “Why not Worship in the Nude?” (Omnibus 332). Dress, for example, is an important marker of untouchable difference which Jagannatha tries to remove by giving the men clothes (and soap). “They were just like the clothes he wore. They had to look like members of his own class— pockets, collars, half-sleeves, dhotis with borders” (Omnibus 230). He instructs them on how to wear the dhotis, whole, to reach the feet. “You should walk like me in the market place, without fear or shame” (232). Examples of the fi rst kind would be Indira Parthasarathy’s Legend of Nandan, which I discuss next, and of the second, Arundhati Roy’s God of Small Things (1997). Gramsci mocks the “rhetorical heroism” of the language of “vanguards” and “commandos” when these entities are isolated from the political party (204). Note the anxiety about “heroism” expressed by both Gramsci and Fanon, which anticipates the “intense mistrust of super-revolutionaries” (alongside a “subtle endorsement of the political wisdom of the masses”) that Nagaraj identifies in the tradition of the Kannada novel to which Bharathipura belongs (viii). C.T. Indra’s English translation bearing the title The Legend of Nandan appeared in 2003 (Oxford University Press), together with an introduction, a critical essay and elaborate textual apparatus all provided by her. I am greatly indebted to the information provided in this scholarly edition. All upper castes are here referred to as “paarpaan” (meaning “seer”) in the play, a term more commonly used to signify Brahmins alone. On this see Gramsci: “[A]ny cultural movement which aimed to replace common sense and old conceptions of the world in general’ would require the leadership of ‘intellectuals of a new type which arise directly out of the masses, but remain in contact with them to become, as it were, the whalebone in the corset” (SPNB 340). C. T. Indra considers this equation of Nandan’s religious sense with his aesthetic sense a “self-imposed limitation in the playwright’s conception of Nandan” (xviii). Note that Parthasarathy gives specific occupational caste names to identify different groups of the untouchable community as is customary in actual practice. Cited in Pandian 16. For example, Narayana Guru, Gandhi, Ambedkar. As we saw this emphasis on untouchable dress and comportment is stressed by Jagannatha also in Bharathipura. In The Flaming Feet D. R. Nagaraj rehearses some of the debates among dalit intellectuals on the question of preserving or abandoning their culture and customs in a chapter titled “The Problem of Cultural Memory.” See also U. R. Anantha Murthy’s essay, “Why Not Worship in the Nude?” for a similar debate.

190

Rajeswari Sunder Rajan

29. M. N. Srinivas is credited with the term and the theory of “Sanskritization” in Social Change in Modern India. 30. Writing about the French working-class poor of the 1830s, Jacques Ranciere is struck by their “transgressive will to appropriate the ‘night’ of poets and thinkers, to appropriate the language and culture of the other, to act as if intellectual equality were indeed real and effectual” (219).

I am grateful to all those who read various drafts of this essay and offered their comments and suggestions, especially the editors of this volume, and Toral Gajarawala, You-me Park, and Kaushik Sunder Rajan.

9

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America Between Revolution and Decoloniality

1

Walter D. Mignolo

Introduction For this volume I was asked for a contribution on Antonio Gramsci in Latin America. To focus on Gramsci without examining the intellectual and political environment in which he was translated, read, used and discussed would be a sort of anti-Gramscian endeavor. As I understand it, Gramsci would have not written about Lenin in Italy without examining the situation in Italy that may have or have not made Lenin relevant. In that regard, and for reasons that will be clarified in the following pages, it is necessary to start by examining in parallel and in contrast both Peruvian José Carlos Mariátegui (1894–1930) and Sardinian Antonio Gramsci (1891–1937). The two great thinkers have been placed in relation several times. The general tendency is to underline the influences of Gramsci on Mariátegui. There are a few who have doubts about it, although they do not radically contest the idea. The assumption here is that Gramsci could have influenced Mariátegui; never that Mariátegui could have influenced Gramsci. And the underlying presupposition under the assumptions is that “influence” goes from the center to the periphery of the modern/ colonial world, never the other way around. I will come back to this issue. In the meantime, I invite you to think about it: they were almost the same age, three years difference. When Mariátegui was in Italy, he was about twenty-four and Gramsci was twenty-seven. Gramsci was very influential in Argentina and Brazil (particularly since 1960).2 The young Marxist generation found in Gramsci’s writing a breath of fresh air and the opportunity to break away from the institutional Marxism-Leninism that emanated from Moscow. Later on we found Gramsci in México (because of the Argentine émigrés in the mid-1970s) and his impact can be traced today in several places and disciplines. But it is obvious and necessary to remember, Gramsci was influential within Marxism mainly. For the contemporary debates in Latin America of the 1960s, like dependency theory, philosophy of liberation and Indianism (as voiced by Bolivian Fausto Reinaga), Gramsci was not a necessary reference.

192

Walter D. Mignolo

At the beginning of the 1970s in Argentina the military dictatorship ended and the path toward democracy opened up; in the mid-1980s, the émigrés to México returned to the country—and with them Gramsci. The historical situation has changed radically in relation to the conditions that in the 1960s and the 1970s made Gramsci necessary for certain sectors of the left. This volume focuses also on Gramsci and the postcolonial. And Gramsci and the postcolonial in “Latin” America is an empty category. Consequently, I will slightly deviate from the topic and address instead “Gramsci and the decolonial,” and will be putting Gramsci in conversation with the decolonial in South/Central America and the Caribbean, a sphere of political and epistemic debate in which Gramsci was not influential. “Colonialism” is common to both projects, post- and decolonial. But while decolonial thinking originated under colonial rule in Indias Occidentales and the Caribbean, for postcolonial scholars the Enlightenment is a point of reference of colonialism and modernity and the independence of Asian and African countries after the Second World War is the marker of postcoloniality.3 Understandably so, because the experience upon which postcolonial studies and theory emerged was that of the second wave of Western expansion (England and France in Asia and Africa), while “decolonial” goes back to the historical foundation of “coloniality” (the logic underlying different historical and special imperial/colonial formations) during the formation of the Atlantic commercial circuits in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries (Spain and Portugal in America and the Caribbean). Gramsci was introduced by the “Latin” American left in the early 1960s. He was not a key figure either for Afro-Caribbean and Afro-Continental intellectuals or for Indigenous intellectuals. In that context, Gramsci was not related at all with any issues regarding “colonialism.” He was fi rst a helpful thinker for local Argentinian and Brazilian left-wing intellectuals to detach themselves from the bureaucracy of the Communist Party and, later on, to enter in the debate about the “State” when the failed project of “modernization and development” (addressed by dependency theory) mutated into “transition to democracy” and the State became the main actor of a new melodrama. In fact, at the beginning of the 1970s, theories on democracy in Latin America began to emerge and they become dominant in the 1980s. “Transition to democracy” was the key expression. The Gramscian left coexisted with the rehearsal of liberal discourses in the ex- colonies, with dependency theory and with theology of liberation.4 The failed project of modernity and development collapsed between the “global 68” (from Beijing to Mexico, Paris and Prague) and the fi rst oil crisis of the early 1970s. The fi rst attempt of the neo-liberal project was Chile right after the fall of Salvador Allende and that initiated the dictatorship of Augusto Pinochet in 1973. Shortly after that, economic dependency theory went out of business: Milton Friedman was the new intellectual leader, dictatorship ruled

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

193

Chile and Argentina. The “transition to democracy” became the main topic of debates for liberal and Marxist thinkers in the mid-1980s and early 1990s. Gramsci’s influence began to recede in the political arena, but remained in the libraries of progressive intellectuals. Before the 1980s and the displacement of the debate to the “transition to democracy” the left in Argentina and Mexico5 was divided between the supporters of Louis Pierre Althusser and Nicos Poulantzas, on the one hand, and the followers of Gramsci, on the other. In Bolivia, it was the period in which Zavaleta Mercado was still relying on Gramsci but at the same time heavily focused on the colonial history of Bolivia that, a few years later, led him to abandon Gramsci and concentrate on theorizing from the history of Bolivia rather than from the debates in the Communist Party. In all of these debates, colonialism in Argentina and Brazil was out of the question. The idea that colonialism ended mostly in the fi rst half of the nineteenth century with the independence from Spain (and later on Portugal) was taken for granted. During the years (early 1970s) that Gramsci was occupying certain quarters, in another country, in México, two influential sociologists—Pablo González Casanova and Rodolfo Stavenhagen—introduced the concept of “internal colonialism.” It was a departure from strictly Marxist debates where Gramsci had entered in Latin America. One could say that the Southern Question was a situation explained through the concept of internal colonialism. The concept did not come from Gramsci. It originated in México. But the Latin Marxist left was oblivious to this concept. Internal colonialism was already a forerunner of coloniality: the independences (and the revolution in the US, and decolonization in Africa by the 1970s) did not end coloniality. It was a restructuring: the “native” elites managed the newborn countries and the “imperial” elites continue to manage international law and relations and the capitalist market. Coloniality (without being named as such yet, but the imperial/colonial logic being already unveiled) was alive and well in Bolivia through the work of Aymara intellectual Fausto Reinaga and very present in the work of the brilliant non-indigenous intellectual René Zavaleta Mercado (1935–1984). Not surprisingly and judging by their works, there was no communication between them. Scholars who explored Zavaleta Mercado’s work distinguished three periods in his influential production: the first period devoted to the national question (shortly after the Bolivian revolution of 1952); the period of Marxist orthodoxy, that included his reading of Gramsci’s work (the period in which Gramsci was being read in South America), and the final period in which the history and present of Bolivia become central to his thought and he found the limit of Marxist thinking. It was in this period that the concept of “motley society” emerged. In this period Zavaleta Mercado approaches the attitude and the faith of José Carlos Mariátegui. Not by influence but by the sheer courage of thinking on their own and not from concepts that had been forged in England to account for the condition of the Industrial Revolution that Marx was witnessing or under

194

Walter D. Mignolo

the conditions in Italy during the 1920s, in which Gramsci was immersed.6 The geopolitics of knowledge and the biographic epistemic foundations emerge here in full, debunking the pretense of a universal epistemology that dominates the world from the top of the hill, even if that hill is the South of Italy being appropriated by the postcolonial market. Revisiting Mariátegui and Gramsci The most obvious beginning to deal with Sardinian Gramsci in relation to the decolonial is to look at him in tandem with Peruvian José Carlos Mariátegui. Gramsci and Mariátegui run parallel lives. Although “influences” of the former on the latter have been suggested, as I just mentioned, it is quite unlikely, unless the precocity of Gramsci’s writing met the precocity and voracity of Mariátegui’s reading habits. Mariátegui was well acquainted with Marxists of Eastern Europe (Rosa Luxembourg [1871–1919], George Luckàcs [1885–1991] and with Antonio Labriola [1843–1904]), but Gramsci seems to have been as unknown to Mariátegui as Mariátegui to Gramsci. Or they probably met when Mariátegui was in Italy, but there is no correspondence that will tell us that the meeting was the flashing light for Mariátegui or that Gramsci noticed the similar concerns in this young Peruvian intellectual. The influence of Gramsci in Mariátegui seems to be more the wishful thinking of Mariátegui’s followers than a historically documented event. What is undeniably true is that both Gramsci and Mariátegui were facing and living in a similar “colonial” situation: the internal colonialism in the history of Southern Italy and the external colonialism in the history of the Andean region (Perú, Bolivia, Ecuador). Gramsci presented the dilemma of the “Southern Question” in free indirect style and faced the Southern subaltern with two options: either be with the local elite or with the workers of the mainland. The “colonial question” was connected to the “industrial question” Gramsci reports addressing an audience in these terms: The dilemma: Are you, poor Sardinian devils, are you for a bloc with the gentry of Sardegna, who have ruined you and who are the local overseers of capitalist exploitation? Or are you for a bloc with the revolutionary workers on the mainland, who stand for the abolition of exploitation and emancipation of all who are oppressed? This dilemma was rammed into the head of those present. (The Southern Question 38) For Mariátegui, the dilemma was the long-lasting colonial legacies in South America and the peculiarity of not having a bourgeoisie and, therefore, a proper working class in the sense Gramsci was talking about: The agrarian problem is first and foremost the problem of eliminating feudalism in Peru, which should have been done by the democratic-bourgeois

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

195

regime that followed the War of Independence. But in its one hundred years as a republic, Peru has not had a genuine bourgeois class, a true capitalist class. The old feudal class—camouflaged or disguised as a republican bourgeoisie—has kept its position. The policy of disentitlement, initiated by the War of Independence as a logical consequence of its ideology, did not lead to the development of small property. The old landholding class had not lost its supremacy. The survival of the latifundistas, in practice, preserved the latifundium. Disentailment struck at the Indian community. During a century of Republican rule, great agricultural property actually has grown stronger and expanded, despite the theoretical liberalism of our constitution and the practical necessities of the development of our capitalist economy. (Seven Interpretative Essays 41) In sum, the colonial conditions of the rural South and of the industrial North are quite different from the colonial conditions of the ex-colonies in South America, where there is no equivalent to the Italian industrial North. Once in a lecture I mentioned this topic, I was asked during the Q&A period what I thought about the fact that Gramsci may have suffered more in prison under fascism than Mariátegui under internal colonialism. I politely responded that it was a moot point from a political perspective. It may be important in a discussion about Christian institutional morality (not even for Theology of Liberation). The problem is of course not who suffered more (for indigenous and enslaved Africans and their descendants in the New World suffered more than Gramsci and Mariàtegui together), but that Gramsci was in prison because of Fascism and Mariàtegui because of internal colonialism and his confrontation with the dictatorship of Augusto B. Leguía. The problem is that you cannot expect to solve Peruvian problems based on Gramsci suffering more under Fascism than Mariátegui under internal colonialism and Leguía´s dictatorship during his early years of critical journalism. The problem of the question was the presupposition of one single story. Let’s take two paragraphs to illuminate the point I am trying to make. The fi rst deals with the Southern Question and the other with the indigenous problem. For Gramsci, “The question in Italy is historically determined,” it is not the “peasant and agrarian question in general.” In Italy, the peasant question has, given its specific Italian tradition, assumed two particular typical and peculiar forms, the Southern question and the Vatican question (Gramsci, The Southern Question 32). For Mariátegui, instead, the assumption that the Indian problem is ethnic is sustained by the most outmoded repertory of imperialist ideas. The concept of inferior races was useful to the white man’s West for purposes of expansion and conquest. To expect that the Indian will be emancipated through a steady crossing of the aboriginal race with white immigrants is an anti-sociological naiveté that could only occur to the

196

Walter D. Mignolo primitive mentality of an importer of merino sheep . . . The degeneration of the Peruvian Indian is a cheap invention of the sophists who serve feudal interests (Mariátegui, Seven Interpretative Essays 25).

Mariátegui has laid out in his treatment of the “Indian Question” the epistemic and political foundation of the project modernity/(de)coloniality, which is the perspective that nourished these pages. I am not just reporting on Gramsci in “Latin” America from a neutral disciplinary perspective, but in dialogue with the adaptation. The point is not Gramsci’s work but its uses in the Southern Cone. So I am not saying that Gramsci is Eurocentric. He is just Italian. His adaptation in South and Central America was a manifestation of the Eurocentered left that, at that point, found in Gramsci a support for their need to detach from the Communist Party. And about that, I have obviously no objection. I am just being careful not to make Gramsci the last postcolonial gadget in outre-mer. Gramsci of course was not Eurocentrist, he was European; Eurocentrics were rather the Latin American left that introduced Gramsci in Latin America and turned their back to the emergent movement of a parallel critical left that was doing what Gramsci did in Italy: thinking from their own histories and experiences. As you can see Gramsci’s local history and Mariátegui’s local history are quite far apart and although they are both walking in the same direction, they have a necessity to walk parallel roads. To expect that Gramsci would solve the problems in Peru (or South and Central America and the Caribbean) would be like expecting Mariátegui to solve the problem of the Southern Question in Italy. Of course, Mariátegui could have learned from Gramsci and Gramsci from Mariátegui. But to put one over the other would be to reproduce coloniality of knowledge from the left. The reason that Gramsci is better known than Mariátegui is due to the imperial/colonial history of Western knowledge of which the left has not been exempt. And of course, this was not Gramsci’s problem for he did what he had to do. It is a problem of the “uses” of Gramsci, either by the “Latin” American left or by the postcolonial market today. In any event, what counts is that Mariátegui and Gramsci were radical critics grounded in their own geo-historical and bio-graphic formation, confronting the limits of Marxism. Mariátegui was facing the lasting legacy of Spanish colonialism, plus the more recent colonialism without colonies (which is just a mutation of coloniality), under British and US economic management. Here is one of the many paragraphs and pages Mariátegui devoted to the issue: There is a chapter in the evolution of the Peruvian economy that opens with the discovery of guano and nitrates and closes with the loss of

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

197

this wealth . . . These materials, on a remote coast in the South Pacific, were essential to the development of European or Western industrialism. In addition, unlike other Peruvian products they were not hampered by the rudimentary and primitive state of land transport. Whereas gold, silver, copper, and coal mined from the Andes had to be conveyed great distances over rugged mountain ranges, guano and nitrate deposits lay on the coast within easy reach of the cargo ships. (Seven Interpretative Essays 33) Both also were facing the quarrel between colonial legacies and nation building (Italy united in 1861 after being torn apart by Spanish, Austrian, and French colonial expansion in Europe; Peru began the process of nation building in 1821). Mariátegui lived through the second presidency of extreme right-winger Augusto B. Leguía (1919–1930) and Gramsci through Benito Mussolini (1925–1943). Both, in their singular local histories, traced parallel trajectories of epistemic disobedience, independent thoughts and decolonial freedom. Although the term “colonialism” is frequently used in Gramsci’s Notebooks it is not one of his keywords. Gramsci has been seldom quoted for giving the term “colonialism” a theoretical meaning, as he is quoted for his concept of “hegemony” and “subalternity.” “Colonialism” instead is one of Mariátegui’s key concepts. As a matter of fact, Mariátegui’s use of colonialism is the forerunner of “coloniality.” “Colonialism” was an historical concern for Gramsci, as it is clear when he addresses the Southern Question. But Gramsci’s colonial experience was very different from Mariátegui’s. However, an important consideration for both of them is that they are thinkers who developed their thought from their historical and personal experiences rather than from previous theories. Both Mariátegui and Gramsci were voracious readers; they knew and pondered coexisting theories. Because they grounded their theorizing in their geo- and body-political location they remain exemplary intellectual guides and they are irreducible to one another. As original thinkers, they confront theories with phenomena to be accounted for and confronted existing theories that were derailed in relation to what they were perceiving. Both, in their own local histories and from them, confronted the limits of Marxist theories of their time as well as many others one can fi nd in both thinkers. Thus, while Gramsci provided a wealth of concepts and insights to the renovation of the “Latin” American left of Marxist persuasion, Mariátegui provided the conditions for the advent of the concept of coloniality (and hence, decoloniality) introduced by Peruvian sociologist Aníbal Quijano at the end of the 1980s.7 Decoloniality since that moment meant “epistemic decolonization” and delinking from Eurocentrism. 8

198

Walter D. Mignolo

In a related issue, one of the evaluators of this article noted that Gramsci in several opportunities commented on the situation in South America and on the question of “Latinity.” But in the same fashion, Mariátegui has countless comments on Europe, on Italy, on the Communist Party, and so on. However, this article is not about what both authors said about the other author’s history and location but the uses of Gramsci in South America mainly. For it would be unfair and totally colonial to only consider what Gramsci has to say about South America without paying attention to what Mariátegui has to say about Italy and Europe. It will mean to follow the same self-colonized logic of the South American and Caribbean intellectuals who put Gramsci fi rst and Mariátegui second. This article is an effort to shift this colonial geography of reasoning and to decolonize the epistemic racism implied in such hierarchy. 9 In his critique to Lamberti Sorrentino’s book Latinitá dell´America, Gramsci opens the paragraph by asking, “Are Central and South America Latin?”; he is asking the question to prepare the Italian reader to his critique of Sorrentino (Prison Notebooks 3: 11ff). He is not addressing South and Central Americans for whom the question is not asked because they knew that they were not Anglo or Slavic or Chinese or Indians from South Asia. Intellectuals certainly knew that the population of European descent in South and Central America did not come from Germany (although there were a few) or England (although there were a few) but that their ancestors came from Spain, Italy or Portugal. In the second paragraph of the same entry, Gramsci observes, Characteristics of South and Central America [1] a considerable number of Indians who, albeit passively, exercise an influence on the state: it would be useful to have information on the social status of these Indians, on their economic importance, on their role in land ownership and industrial production. (Prison Notebooks 3: 11) Gramsci is telling this to the Italian reader. Leaving aside the question of the passivity of the Indians (which was the landowner mythology in South and Central America), we cannot assume that he was telling this to Peruvians and other South and Central American countries. Mariátegui, who died the same year as Gramsci, wrote the preceding observations in 1930 when he published Seven Interpretive Essays along with many articles that were overwhelmingly answering the questions Gramsci was asking and correcting the mistakes he had made. This is not a critique of Gramsci. This is a critique of those who expect that because Gramsci wrote about South America, what he wrote was relevant for South Americans who were living the experience he was describing from Italy.

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

199

Now, regarding Gramsci’s assessment of South and Central America as well as his assessment of the intellectuals in these locations, his views are certainly very limited. He seems to have in mind the “organic intellectuals” and completely ignores some of his contemporaries, like Mariátegui himself or the Cuban José Martí (1853 –1895), who died when Mariátegui was still a child. I do not have time here to explore the dissident thoughts that include not only Creole and Mestizos, but also Indians and Africans in South America. In this regard, Gramsci’s views are limited to the European perspective, while Mariátegui offers a corrective to this type of comment that prevails today in Le Monde Diplomatique, for instance. I am sure that Italian and European critical intellectuals today question Mariátegui’s assessment of Italy and Europe. The bottom line however is not what Mariátegui and Gramsci said about the histories and societies of the other, but why they say it. In both cases, what they said, the enoncé was implicated in their own unapologetically original conceptual and political framework (their own enunciation). A second reader of this article pointed out that Gramsci’s interest in South America emerged out of an “internationalization of the Southern Question.” True. Based on what I just said about the enunciation, it could be surmised that Mariátegui’s interest in Europe, Asia, Russia and Africa was based on his interest on the “internationalization of the Indian Question.” And both were right: there are Souths all over the globe as we know today with the popular expression “the global south” and also there is indigeneity all over the world for “global indigeneity” is meaningful beyond the fi rst encounter between Indigenous Europeans and Indigenous people outside of Europe that happened in the Americas. The same is true for Mariátegui. He has several writings on Europe and even reflections on the Italian Communist Party. Obviously, Mariátegui’s writings on Europe, on Communism, on the international situation are not coming from the internationalization of the Southern Question but out of the internationalization of the Andean Question. I admire Gramsci, but I am not ready to sacrifice the contribution of South American thinkers and fall into an imperialism of the left using Gramsci as a banner. On the other hand, the fact that Gramsci wrote on South America and Mariátegui on Europe shall not make us forget that it is the loci of enunciation rather than the object they talk about that give its full meaning to what they have to say about South America and Europe, respectively. Furthermore, my argument is about the uses of Gramsci in South America rather than on Gramsci’s interest on South America. But all of this, prompted by the question of one of the evaluators of this article, is a moot point. I was asked to write about the uses of Gramsci in South America and not about what he wrote and or why he could have written what he wrote about South America.

200

Walter D. Mignolo

Geopolitics of Knowledge: Mariátegui’s “Colonial Question” and Gramsci’s “Southern Question” Where Mariátegui and Gramsci run at the same speed and in the same direction is on the colonial and the Southern Question, respectively. However, the emphasis varies. In Mariátegui’s work, the colonial legacies in the Andes are as central as is hegemony for Gramsci. If the future for Gramsci was how to build socialist hegemony, for Mariátegui it was how to decolonize and delink from colonial legacies. If at that point Mariátegui was still thinking within a socialist future horizon, he was walking toward it on a road parallel to Gramsci’s. Each of them were facing “similar” historical processes in “different” historical trajectories, but both within the colonial matrix of power: the Southern Question comes out of the emerging Italian bourgeoisie, liberating itself from the Bourbon monarchy and unifying Italy and starting the process of nation-state building facing the heavy burden of the clergy that Gramsci constantly reminds the reader of. That was not a major problem for Mariátegui. Peru did not have the Pope but other institutions guiding the structuring of society and of history. For Mariátegui the question of the nation-state (whose process started about a century before his active intellectual and political life), was strictly connected to Spanish colonial legacies, on the one hand, and England and the US imperial management since the second half of the nineteenth century. If Gramsci fl ags the role of the clergy in South America it is not that it doesn’t exist, but it is that it is a major problem for Gramsci rather than for Mariátegui. Mariátegui has other enemies: the Spanish colonial legacies and the secularized Creoles and Mestizos land and mine owner elites who implanted internal colonialism in confl ictive relations with the church. That of course was not a problem for Gramsci. It is not that Mariátegui was oblivious of religions. It is that for him religion had priority over the institutional clergy. He devoted a chapter of his Seven Interpretive Essays to “The Religious Factor.” The Andean region, and in particular Peru where Mariátegui dwelled, was not Italy. Italy had Rome and the papacy behind its religious history. Peru has Tawantinsuyu and the Spanish colonization. And it is precisely here that Mariátegui begins his chapter on religion, “the religion of Tawantinsuyu.” Cuzco, in the Incanate (the parallel equivalent to a Roman Empire), was the center of the world as it was Rome. But the religions were different: Rome was the center of enunciation of Christian theology. The Incanate, and Cuzco, was a place that Spanish Christians declared without religions and managed by the Devil. That is indeed a heavy past to deal with. But what interests us here is what happened with Catholicism and Christianity during and after the independence. According to Flores Galindo’s interpretation of Mariátegui,

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

201

Perú had a liberal and patriotic clergy from the first day of its revolution. In a few isolated cases, civil liberalism was inflexibly Jacobin, and, in even fewer cases, anti-religious. Most of our liberals came from the Masonic lodges that were so active in preparing the independence, so they almost all professed the deism that made Freemasonry in these Latin countries a kind of spiritual and political substitute for the Reformation. (146) To speculate about the clergy and the intellectuals in Latin America from the background of the clergy in Italy may have been significant in Italy, but not in Latin America. There is of course much more to say about the question of the clergy, the intellectuals, and the local histories of Italy and Peru. I hope these few indications help to understand that we are facing crossing gazes when Gramsci talks about Latin America and Mariátegui about Italy and Europe. They were both concerned with and theorizing from the irreducible difference of their local history. However, they were located at different points of the colonial matrix of power: Gramsci in the South of Europe, a degraded part of Europe since Kant and Hegel’s writing, while Mariátegui was located in the Andes and South America, a degraded part of the world in Hegel’s philosophy of history. Located at different points of the colonial matrix, Gramsci and Mariátegui were responding from their own locations to the imperial universality of liberalism, Marxism, and Christianity. If we now turn the table around and attempt to understand the Southern Question and Gramsci’s take on it from the history of Peru, we would fi nd out that Italy and Peru in the twenties were going through similar situations at two different ends of the colonial matrix spectrum: two different manifestations of internal colonialism, one in the very history of Europe and the other in the history of European colonial expansion and domination. Looked at from the standard perspective of Western universal history to which local histories are appended, Italy and Peru have nothing to do with each other. But if we look at them from the perspective of the colonial matrix of power that emerged in the sixteenth century and is still alive and well, then Italy and Peru are at the time two clear cases of re-articulation of the internal and external colonial differences. The colonial matrix is, in a nutshell, a structure of management and control upon which the modern/colonial world and, in the last analysis, Western civilization rests (Gramsci, Southern Question 171–85). It was put in place by actors and institutions on a set of assumptions and categories of thought and knowledge that made it possible to build and maintain the interrelations between four basic spheres—authority (politics), economy (including land as private property and natural resources), gender and sexuality, knowledge and subjectivity—as a single, although transformed

202

Walter D. Mignolo

through the century, matrix. It is the enunciation, in other words, that made and makes possible to maintain the consistency and coherence of the colonial matrix. The point I am driving at is that the matrix was built, on the one hand, by delimiting a series of domains (just mentioned) and, on the other, by securing the locus of enunciation for the management and control of those domains. Thus in the process of building and managing the colonial matrix, it was necessary to create a series of “differences,” colonial and imperial, of which I would only here refer to the “colonial differences.”10 Colonial differences were established vis-à-vis the non-European population (e.g., Indians and blacks in the sixteenth century) and vis-à-vis the European population (e.g., Jews and Roma in the same period). In the eighteenth century, when the control of knowledge, and consequently the management of authority and the economy moved to the North of Europe (Germany, France, England), a new dimension of the difference appeared: this time, the imperial difference in the history of Europe itself. To control knowledge means to control the enunciation and by so doing to be able to classify without being classified, to be able to degrade other forms of knowledge, to demonize what is not sustainable according to the dominant locus of enunciation. To control knowledge is not to control content (the enunciated) but to control the logic that organizes the content (the enunciation).11 The idea of “the South of Europe” was put in place with all its transformations, internal structuring and consequences. Gramsci, as a Southerner himself, lived in different places but his dwelling was Southern memories, while Mariátegui was experiencing the legacy of the external colonial difference that put him in the very notable situation of being neither European nor Indian, but feeling the consequences of the colonial difference.12 Gramsci in “Latin” America: How Coloniality of Knowledge Works I hope this sweeping contextualization would make understandable the following question: who introduced Gramsci in “Latin America,” when and why, since we know almost for sure that it was not Mariátegui who initiated the process? And we know also through the previous narrative that Mariátegui and Gramsci were foundational thinkers whose legacies transcended their time and context. Gramsci’s influence has been wider than Mariátegui’s. But that is understandable if we know how the colonial matrix of power works and understand what colonial epistemic differences mean. For this reason, when Gramsci entered “Latin” America in the 1960s, those who introduced Gramsci respected Mariátegui but the Andean situation in “Latin” America (of which they themselves were part) was less meaningful than what was happening in Italy.13 But it is still

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

203

unthinkable that Mariátegui would have entered Italy in the same way: peripheral thinkers are invisible in the European hegemony of thoughts (right and left). That is why Sartre prefaced Fanon, but it is unthinkable to imagine one of Sartre’s books introduced by Fanon. This line of argument is decolonial rather than postcolonial. For one, Sartre wrote it during the struggle for decolonization and, secondly, central to Sartre’s argument addressing his European fellows, was to underscore that Fanon was no longer writing to the Europeans: he was addressing the non-European world, he was decolonizing knowledge rather than proposing a new postmodern or postcolonial argument. Sartre was aware that Fanon was moving in a different direction. The shifting of the geography of reasoning is one of the basic principles of decolonial thinking. Fanon, in the last analysis, was a decolonial thinker and Sartre understood it. When Sartre is addressing his European audience, or better yet, French audience, he is telling them that Fanon is not talking to you but he is addressing a Third World audience. During my fi rst and second years at the University of Córdoba, Argentina in 1963, I learned quickly (since I enrolled in an MA program in philosophy and literature) that there was a new publication in Córdoba steered by the young generation of Marxist intellectuals, with considerable clout already at the University and in the intellectual milieu of Córdoba (by then a city of around 600,000 people and close to a million today). The journal they published was named Pasado y Presente. Soon, after the fi rst issues, I found myself and other students reading Antonio Gramsci. It all started with the young intellectual dissidents that broke up with the Communist Party shortly after the fall of Juan Domingo Perón in 1955. Curiously and interestingly enough, Gramsci entered Argentina through Córdoba (the second largest city, very continental, and not through the Atlantic port of Buenos Aires). In Brazil, Gramsci arrived later but under similar circumstances: it was after the fall of Getulio Vargas in 1964 that there was a reading and breathing room for the young generation that felt not only cornered by Getulio Vargas but also by the Communist Party.14 Gramsci, in other words, was invited in an environment of strong nationalist revival in the early years of the Cold War and the early years of the US’s plans for development and modernization of Latin America (in this case, without quotation mark and without parenthesis). It was also in the late 1960s, that what is known today as “dependency theory” (a theory that originated in Argentina and was developed in Brazil, Chile and Mexico, which confronted the rhetoric of development advanced by the US in its project of development and modernization, after the Second World War) began to be formulated. As is well known, dependency theory was based on the CEPAL (Comisión Económica Para Amérida Latina) report written under the guidance of Argentinian liberal economist Raúl Prebisch, according to which it was stated (in the second half

204

Walter D. Mignolo

of the 1950s) that under current economic dependency conditions, Latin American countries couldn’t develop according to the expectations of the US program of modernization and development. The US program of modernization and development was initiated after Harry Truman’s presidential address (1949) in which he declared that many countries of the world were underdeveloped. Those countries that, after 1955, will be classified as “Third World.” But Gramsci was not used (and I do not know if read) in the debate on dependency theory. One may surmise that the question of underdevelopment and development was not an issue for Southern Italy, in the terms that were announced by President Truman and implemented by the US in the 1950s. If anything, “dependentistas” were closer to Fanon and the struggle for decolonization in Africa than to Gramsci, in spite of the differing points of view between Fanon and the dependentistas when it came to the role of the State (Smith 247–88). Dependency was obviously not, and did not have to be, one of Gramsci’s concerns. Dependency was not a problem of the internal colonial differences in Europe (the Jewish question) or of the internal imperial difference (the South of Europe). The internal colonial difference was created in Europe in reference to their internal others (e.g., Jews, Roma) while the internal imperial difference was created by Northern Anglo monarchies (from Elizabeth I of England) downgrade the Latin Catholic monarchies (Phillip II and Phillip III in Spain), well known as the “Black Legend.”15 Basically, the imperial external difference was traced between Europe and similar civilizations, that Europe considered inferior (like the Ottoman). The internal imperial difference was constructed inside Europe itself (e.g., Kant and Hegel constructing the South of Europe, the Latin Catholic countries). The external colonial difference was created to classify Indians and Blacks fi rst, and then the people colonized by England and France during the nineteenth century. And if you look around, all of this confi guration is alive and well. Italy was placed in the South but still it was one of Europe’s industrial countries, while Brazil, Argentina, Chile, and Peru, were not. All these countries were enduring the consequences of being cast as and treated through the colonial external difference. But that was not all. The young Marxist Argentinian dissidents ( José Aricó, Juan Carlos Portantiero, Oscar del Barco, Héctor Smuckler) from the CP introduced a new and important dimension in the political and intellectual debate, while many other debates were going on concurrently. Chiefly, in Argentina, the previous generation was also dissident and their inspiration to delink from the CP was an amalgam of Marxism at large and Perónism. They were brilliant analysts of the global economy and imperial rearticulations. For them, like for Mariátegui, history was a key factor to understand Argentinian history from the colony to the republic and from the republic to Juan Domingo Perón. They were also nationalists, and their school of thought

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

205

became known as “the nationalist left.”16 Gramsci thus entered Argentina and “Latin” America by the doors opened by young intellectuals who in the 1960s were in their thirties. Intellectuals of the same generation were being introduced in Argentina as well as in other countries of South America, parallel to Gramsci, to French structuralism and post-structuralism. Gramsci, in other words, was part of a significant renewal absorbing intellectuals’ debate in Europe (e.g., Althusserians v. Gramscians). This debate was reproduced in South America where Althusserians and Gramscians debated with each other and it coexisted with the origination in “Latin” America of dependency theories, liberation theology and, in some way, the forgetting of Mariátegui. Now, the point is that in countries with colonial legacies, the intellectual tradition rooted in the history of the region has to coexist with the importation of the last ideas being debated in Europe. Coloniality of knowledge works in the entire spectrum and impinges on the right, the left and the center. Gramsci, and European intellectuals in general, do not have to worry about the debates going on in the colonies. The differential of epistemic power is engrained in the colonial difference in all its facets and faces. José Aricó, in his classic book on Gramsci in Latin America—a book that is the product of his research, of course, but also of his engagement with Gramsci and as an activist and political analyst—devoted a chapter to the following question: “Why Gramsci in Latin América?” (34ff). What were the circumstances and the needs that led to the incorporation of Gramsci’s thoughts? For Aricó, Gramsci entered at the junction of two key moments: the illusions awakened by the Cuban Revolution in 1959 and, by 1970, the moment of crisis of the Cuban Revolution coincided with the repercussion, in Latin America, of the world crisis, the end of the welfare state and the initial moment of a series of dictatorial regimes (Pinochet in Chile, Videla in Argentina, the infamous “Operación Condor,” etc).17 In the 1970s and 1980s the attention devoted to Gramsci by the Latin American intelligentsia was increasing. In the context that Aricó is describing, the concept of “hegemony” was the most helpful. As the debates in the late 1970s were moving from dependency to transition to democracy, the question of the State, central for Gramsci in his struggle with fascism, was paralleled in Argentina and in “Latin” America. On the question of the State, Gramsci offered an outlet to the indifference of Marxist international thinking. His distinction between civil and political society, next to that of hegemony, provided a concept of the state that was alien to the orthodox Marxist thinking which saw in the State a bourgeois institution to be superseded by the dictatorship of the proletariat and the internationalization of the revolution. In South and Central America the question of the State became central during the period of dictatorships in Argentina, Chile and Brazil, and so Gramsci provided basic tools. However, in Bolivia, René Zavaleta Mercado was moving away from Gramsci and rethinking the State in relation to the national-popular.18

206

Walter D. Mignolo

From a decolonial perspective one of the most interesting aspects of Gramsci’s reception was his distinction between the “Occident” and “Orient.” For decolonially, decolonially, the main problem was not so much class struggle or the State but the West (Occident) in which both class struggle and the (modern) State originated. The issues were already framed in indigenous thinking to which of course the Gramscian left was blind. Political thinking scould only come from Europe; no original thinking could exist beyond the Western tradition. José Aricó reflects on this point as follows. In the distinction between Orient and Occident that Gramsci introduced in his Notebooks, Aricó concludes that “Latin” America belongs in Gramsci’s term to Occident. Reflecting also on Juan Carlos Portantiero’s seminal book on Gramsci, Aricó accepts that the concept of Occident is wide enough to include both European countries beyond the core of Europe. He described as estados periféricos (or peripheral states) countries like Italy, Poland and Portugal. The reason Portantiero located these countries in the periphery was due to his reading of Gramsci’s perception that the articulation between the State and the society was through the intermediary social classes. Such intermediary classes to a certain extent, attempt and succeed in advancing a politics of their own interest while in other cases, they attract the proletarian class, and are also but above all influential among the peasants.19 Portantiero was reflecting on societies where industrialization was more “advanced” and compared them with Latin American countries: Comparable by their type of development and differing in their irreproducible historical formation, those countries are comparable to Latin America. Latin America is not the “Orient” for it is clear that it has common features with the peripheral West, late in its development. In Latin America we can see more clearly this “second West” that was formed in Europe toward the end of the nineteenth Century. In Latin America it is the State and politics that model society. But it is a type of State—and here we go into one of the aspects of dependent States—that while attempting to shape a national community cannot achieve the degrees of autonomy and sovereignty of the “Bismarckian” and “Bonapartian” models. In Latin America all the struggles during the nineteenth century were struggles among economically similar groups that fought among themselves for the control of the State. The aim was to control the State to develop the economy in order to promote a more complex structure of social classes. (Portantiero 93) The quote is interesting for several reasons. First, it ends up on the question of the State, but without taking into account the differentials

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

207

between the modern European State and the colonial states in “Latin” America. That is, the colonial difference that was clearly seen by scholars in the Subaltern Studies project, chiefl y by Partha Chatterjee (The Nation and Its Fragments) was invisible to the “Latin” American Gramscian. But the colonial difference was not invisible to Bolivian intellectual Zavaleta Mercado. The period of his intellectual work (roughly from 1960 to 1984) was precisely the moment that, without naming it as such, he realized that Marxist categories and Gramsci in particular whom he had endorsed in previous years, fell short of explaining a “motley society” or “sociedad abigarrada.” Second, for Gramsci the two categories (Orient and Occident) are a way to describe the relations between the State and the Civil Society—racism, in America is as pervasive as classism in Europe. Curiously enough, the uses of Gramsci in South America not only displaced Mariátegui from the intellectual scene, but also Zavaleta Mercado and Fausto Reinaga. Motley society is a crucial concept to understand the layers and interlayers of social formations in colonial societies. We can fi nd nothing like that in Gramsci, and the Latin American left ignored the concept until the books by Luis Antezama and Luis Tapia, in the past twenty years when the colonial question awakened the left, was put again in circulation. This is not a critique of Gramsci, of course. He did what he had to do. It is a critique of the colonial mentality of the left in South and Central America. So, if the question is to understand the uses of Gramsci in South and Central America, we have to be aware that his work served, unintentionally, to displace the local production of knowledge. Gramsci indeed was also local production of knowledge, but why does Zavaleta remain only as local while the Gramscians pretend that Gramsci is universal (or at least global)? The West or “Occidente” was not a central problem for Gramsci. But of course it is for all those who do not belong to the six dominant European languages. Now, there are indeed at least three Occidents: Hegel’s heart of Europe, Gramsci’s peripheral Europe, and the “colonial Occident” (America except the US) that was self-described by an Argentine intellectual as “the confi ne of Occident.” 20 There is the Occident in which the interconnections between the economy, class structure, and state appear in a more balanced organization and the Occident in which such relations are still in less articulated conditions. Those were, for Gramsci, the frontier or peripheral states (Poland, Italy, Spain and Portugal). For the Argentinian left it was important that Gramsci’s thought emerged from his living and observing peripheral occidental societies. For that reason, they concluded, certain Latin American societies, like Argentina, Brazil and Mexico where industrialization was advanced, were similar to the European peripheral societies. The historical blindness was remarkable—both for Argentinian and Brazilian followers of Gramsci—for Spain and Portugal are deeply rooted in the colonial memories. Gramsci’s analogy was

208

Walter D. Mignolo

possible for the Argentinian and Brazilian left, because their own colonial past was suppressed. That memory was very present in the entire work of José Carlos Mariátegui. From a decolonial perspective Italy, Spain and Portugal are the roots of European self-proclaimed (imperial) modernity. Portugal-Brazil will need further and specific consideration, which is not the place to go into here. Poland is perhaps the closest parallel to “Latin” America in the sense that since the sixteenth century it went through a series of violent colonizations and partitions by the Russian Tzarate, the Kingdom of Prussia, and the Hapsburg Monarchy. For the new left (the Gramscian) the legacies of the colonial past and the distinction between countries with imperial legacies (Italy, Spain, Portugal) and countries with colonial legacies (Poland, Argentina, Brazil, Mexico) was not as important as it was for the “national left” whose arguments were based both in the history of the nation and the history of imperialism (from Spain and Portugal, to England and France, and to the US). The new left had two foci: to liberate themselves from the Communist Party and to reflect on the State during the era of dictatorship. The national left was also formed in contradistinction with the Communist Party, but it focused on the crossing between national and imperial histories in the history of particular countries as well as in the history of South and Central America. Gramsci entered “Latin” America perhaps a decade before he made his way into the South Asian Subaltern Studies historiographical project, and the emphasis was different. “Subalternity” was seldom, if ever, an issue for South American Gramscians. What caught their attention were the concepts of “hegemony” (chiefly Ernesto Laclau) and “historical block.” 21 This difference is telling of what Gramsci took to India and what Gramsci took to Argentina. South Asian Subaltern Studies scholars and intellectuals were quick to mutate “subalternity” and make it work in the colonial history of India. The colonial context made it necessary to clarify the distinction between hegemony and domination. 22 “Subaltern subjects” are formed—as is well known—not only by the larger class of deprived, politically marginalized, economically exploited, and subjectively undermined individuals, as Gramsci taught us to see. Next to subaltern subjects are the “colonial subjects,” and colonial subjects are a different species of subaltern. Colonial subjects are crossed by racism and, therefore, by the colonial and imperial differences. Colonial subjects are specifically those marked by the double-crossing of racism and patriarchy, enduring the colonial wound. These are not central concerns in Gramsci, but they are in Fanon and Mariátegui. In this regard, subalternity in India is very close to Fanon’s damnés, and one could wonder why it was Gramsci and not Fanon who became the point of reference for Asian Subaltern Studies. 23 A quick answer would be that Fanon was, like Mariátegui, a respected but second-class thinker; a thinker from the colonies. Beyond Gramsci’s brilliancy, there was also the clout of being a European thinker. Italy has

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

209

a huge peasant population, but not as huge as India’s. Furthermore, Italy belonged in the nineteenth century, to the “peripheral” modern, capitalist countries of Europe while India was colonized by the leading European imperial country, Britain. What is at stake here is the internal colonial difference (or internal colonialism) in which Gramsci is thinking and the external colonial difference that lay at the historical foundation of Gandhi, Nehru, and the South Asian Subaltern Studies. That was where progressive intellectuals from the ex-colonies looked for their own salvation. They were not looking much into their own past. That is why Mahatma Gandhi is somewhat despised by Guha. 24 Thus, the generation who introduced Gramsci and created Pasado y Presente could have named their publication Amauta—that was the journal started by Mariátegui. Amauta in Quechua-Aymara languages means “philosopher, man of wisdom.” But that would have been taken as traditional. Instead, Gramsci was a song “for the young generation” of modernity. In fact, it was the same ideology of modernity that the US was using to promote their own projects of “development and modernization;” the project that provoked the critical responses of dependency theory and theology of liberation. Now the fact that Gramsci entered Argentina through Córdoba and not through Buenos Aires was not by chance. There is a long history that gave Córdoba its place in Argentina. In 1575, the University of Córdoba was inaugurated. That was a few decades after the creation of the University of Santo Domingo, the University of Mexico, and the University of San Marcos in Lima and about sixty years before the foundation of Harvard University in 1636. During the nineteenth century Córdoba was a focus of the civil war and the national re-organization since 1862. In 1918, Córdoba was the focus of Reforma Universitaria (University Reformation) that had an impact all over Spanish America. By the 1960s, Córdoba became a center of industrial modernization and development. The car industry was responsible for the miracle: FIAT, Kayser, and Renault found their home in Córdoba. And because of that, in 1969 the city witnessed “El Cordobazo:” the workers of Kayser industry, with the support of the student population, literally took the city. The uprising, that came about a year and a half after the “global 1968” (Beijing, Czechoslovakia, Paris, Mexico), was led not by the Marxist avant-garde but by workers and students in the long tradition of Córdoba University and the shorter tradition of university reformation. The fact then that it was in Córdoba where Gramsci found his fi rst shelter in Argentina is indeed quite relevant. And it explains also why Mariátegui was less relevant in this context: the history of Argentina that Perón was able to mobilize. That is, the people from the countryside and the Bolivian workers that migrated to Buenos Aires were shattered by the shining path of industrialization, modernization, and development that transformed Córdoba from a provincial and colonial city into a modern city—the center, nothing less, of the car

210

Walter D. Mignolo

industry. And we all know the meaning the car industries had in the Third World—they carried the promises of entering the route toward the First World. Thus, Gramsci in Córdoba did not come with the “Southern Question,” but with the “Northern Question.” Gramsci arrived at Córdoba, Argentina, at the moment the city was becoming the hub of the automobile industry: Kayser, Renault and Fiat set their plants and office in the outskirts of the city. They developed a large body of workers. The industrial environment of Cordoba, where Gramsci found his home in Argentina, was like the Milano of Luchino Visconti’s Rocco e i suoi fratelli (1960): the Southern Question in the Industrial North. The Garden of Forking Paths I have already mentioned the national left (la izquierda nacional, sometimes also referred to as Marxismo nacional) that made a mark on the political and intellectual debate in Argentina; a debate with projection mainly in Spanish America, since Brazil belongs to a different colonial trajectory.25 For the national left that preceded the arrival of Gramsci, history was of the essence. And that history was the Spanish colonial history followed by the liberal orientation, after independences, in the foundation of colonial nation-states.26 The national left emerged, indeed, in 1945 when Juan Domingo Perón was rescued from military captivity and became president of Argentina. At that time a significant number of intellectuals in their forties (they were born in the first decade of the twentieth century), turned the page and reclaimed Marx independently from Moscow. But, at the same time, they reclaimed the national history narrated from a Marxist perspective and introduced a superb analysis of the history of British and US imperialism in America and in Argentina.27 Contrary to what happened in India, where Marxist narratives where disqualified and superseded in the South Asian Subaltern Studies project,28 the national left in Argentina was not superseded by the Gramscian left that emerged in the early 1960s. They both followed parallel and different paths: the splendor of the national left was to absorb Marx and integrate his work in the historical task of building “national consciousness” and to make Marxism work from inside, from the history of previous colonialism and current imperial forces.29 Its misery was to create the conditions for national fundamentalism. But there were other paths unfolding at the time Gramsci entered in Argentina and Latin America in the 1960s. One was the decolonial path opened up (and obviously marginalized) by the Argentine philosopher of German descent, Rodolfo Kusch (1920–1979). In the twenty-seven years that elapsed between his fi rst book Seduction de la Barbarie (1952), and his last book, Geocultura del Hombre Americano (1979), a critical and relentless line of demarcation was traced between the right and the left. The right was mainly characterized by the urban middle class (wanting to be European) of Buenos Aires and by the imperial theories of modernization

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

211

and development; the left by general tendencies of the time. Kusch is not personalizing, but is confronting the general principles and assumptions of the Marxist left. Thus, if you are engaged in a double critique of the left and the right in their Euro-American point of origination and their route of dispersion in the Americas, and you think from the histories and experiences of the popular (not the subaltern) and the Indigenous, then chances are that among the available options you engage in decolonial thinking. 30 A parallel story was that of Aymara intellectual and activist, Fausto Reinaga in Bolivia.During the years between the late 1950s (when he returned from France) and his death in 1994, Fausto Reinaga was also engaged in a parallel trajectory of decolonial thinking based on the memories, categories of thoughts, and sensibilities of Quechua-Aymara histories in the Andean regions. Scholars generally agreed that Gramsci’s Prison Notebooks marks one of the nodal points of Western Marxism’s break with Leninism and the breed of Marxism born of the Bolshevik Revolution. Vice-president of Bolivia, Alvaro García Linera, assessing the situation of the country in 2007, did worry about making such a distinction: Any state crisis, then, may be reversible, or it may continue. If the crisis continues, a subsequent stage is the catastrophic equilibrium. Lenin spoke of a revolutionary situation, Gramsci of catastrophic equilibrium, both referring to the same phenomenon albeit in distinct languages. (“Catastrophic Equilibrium and Point of Bifurcation”) The point is not of course about scholarly debates. The question gestures toward the correlation between Marxism and ethnicity/racism in America and the Caribbean. Garcia Linera is facing in Bolivia a situation that neither Lenin nor Gramsci could have imagined: a country in which 60% of the population are the aboriginals of the land and Marxism being a way of thinking and being that suits people of European descent but not so much Indians and people of African descent. Or course I’m not referring to the fact that there were no aboriginals, but to the fact that colonial legacies in America (and the US—as well as in Africa) present problems and issues alien to those the Russian Lenin confronted and the Italian Gramsci was dealing with. I am suggesting that in spite of the conceptual differences between Lenin and Gramsci, there were more commonalities between Russia and Southern Italy at the margin of Europe than with the Andes of South America: the land, territory, history, memory and living experience Indians have endured through fi ve hundred years of European colonialism, including, of course, Marxism. The issues confronted by Indo and Afro intellectuals, scholars and activists are not the same as those affl icting Euro-descendent activists,

212

Walter D. Mignolo

scholars and intellectuals. We are all living in the same world, but we inhabit different corners of the colonial matrix of power. Marxist views cannot be universal, neither for that matter, Liberal, Christian or Islamic views. The decolonial fi nds its place right there, on the cracks produced in the clash of abstract universal in their struggle to obtain a universal hegemony. If we are to still use the Gramscian concepts, it is necessary to extricate them from the modern political theoretical frame in which it emerges and to bring it to the decolonial horizon. In that horizon, decolonial hegemony would look like pluriversality as a universal project rather than the hegemony of one abstract universal. When I say that in America Gramsci has been used mainly by the population of European descent, but not so much by indigenous and Black radical thinkers, I have two scenarios in mind; one is Fausto Reinaga, Aymara intellectual and activist. In his book The Indian Revolution he stated, The manifesto of the Partido Indio de Bolivia (PIB) does not have to be subjected to any model, rule or logic, formal or intellectual, that rules the political parties of the White-mestizo “cholaje” [cfr. People of Indian ancestry mixed with other ethnicities, mixed in blood but ¨white¨ in mind] of Bolivia and Indoamérica. 31 This is not a manifesto of the social class. It is a manifesto of a race, of a people, of a Nation: the manifesto of an entire culture oppressed and silenced. It is not possible to compare with Marx´s Communist Manifesto. It is not possible to compare because the genial “Moor” did not confront the West (Occident). He confronted the proletarian with the bourgeois class and proposed, within the same Western Civilization, the “intangida” [cfr. incapable of being thought out or realized] communist revolution. (Reinaga 382; my own translation) Reinaga assumed his Aymara identity. As such he perceived that a communist revolution within Western civilization could not really be a revolution. Some say he is mestizo. He may have been mestizo in blood, but he was Indian in mind, while mestizos in blood are generally white in mind. Mestizos of white mind couldn’t take it and accused him of being mestizo and pretending to be Indian. The point is this: in the preface to his The Indian Revolution, which we just read in the previous quotation, he is saying that for him the problem is not the struggle between proletariat and bourgeoisie, but that the problem is Western civilization in its entirety, including the proletarian and bourgeois classes. In other words, proletariat and bourgeoisie are not universal concepts. And whether universal history is determined by class struggle is an open question. For Reinaga, as for any decolonial thinker (not only in America but in the

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

213

Middle East [or better yet, West Asia] and Africa, and Central, East and South East Asia) the problem is not just capitalism but the West of which both capitalism and Marxism are two important aspects. The problem is coloniality of power, of which the type of economy described by Liberals and Marxists as capitalism is a component, a fundamental one nowadays, but only a component and not the full story. The second scenario comes from Afro-Caribbean intellectuals and scholars, some of them residing in the US. All are “Fanonians” rather than “Gramscian.” You see the point. Lewis Gordon—philosopher from Jamaica—made an insightful observation tracing the distinctions between Europe and America (in general, from pole to pole) and is very important for my argument. Gordon suggested that Europe smells like class while the Americas smell like race. What did he mean by that? The Europe of the Industrial Revolution and of Marxism is basically “white” Europe. 32 The South, where mixing bloods and religions could be found, was fi rst “purified” with the expulsion of Jews and Moors since the end of the fi fteenth century. Furthermore, by the end of the eighteenth century, Enlightenment philosophers were effective in downgrading the South/Latin region of Europe. In such a way that when the question of class began to be formulated, it was formulated in the heart of Europe (England, Germany and France) where ethno-racial confl icts were invisible since the majority of the population was white and Christian. On the other hand, Paget Henry published a landmark book in 2003 that was awarded the fi rst annual Fanon Prize by the Caribbean Philosophical Association in 2004. The title of the book is Caliban’s Reason: Introducing Afro-Caribbean Philosophy.33 The chapter before last is devoted to “Caribbean Marxism: After the Neoliberal and Linguistic Turn.” There is not one single quote from Gramsci. Certainly, the chapter focuses on the period “after the neo-liberal and linguistic turn” and Gramsci strongly entered in Latin America in the 1960s, but apparently not so strongly in the Caribbean. But the time period should be a factor since Henry devotes a chapter to C. L. R. James, and James adhered to a certain extent to Marxism, until he was disenchanted and wrote Beyond a Boundary (1963), a personal and critical narrative of cricket in Jamaica. The year of the publication of James’s book was the year in which Gramsci was being received by young generations of Marxists, in Argentina and Brazil, disenchanted with the Communist Party. As we can imagine, not quoting Gramsci was not Henry’s oversight of careless scholarship. It is just that for Caribbean black intellectuals, Gramsci was not addressing issues relevant to them. Certainly, radical Black thinkers of the twentieth century have been all critics of capitalism, like Gramsci. However, as you can imagine, Marxism doesn’t have the monopoly of that kind of criticism and visions toward the future. As Fanon said in The Wretched of the Earth, “Marxist analysis should always be slightly stretched every time we have to deal with the colonial problem” (xx). 34

214

Walter D. Mignolo

Last but not least, Anthony Bogues—Jamaican political theorist—wrote a book about Black radical intellectuals. His line of reasoning is parallel to that of Fanon. Bogues writes, Regimes of domination do not rest solely upon economic, political, social and cultural power. They also exist and conduct politics within a field of political and social knowledge, of ideas that form part of the selfconsciousness of all members of society. Given the nature of anti-black racism and the racialized object (who is human), the black radical intellectual as critic is fi rst of all engaged with challenging the knowledge regime of the dominant power. (70) Here, Bogues refers to the knowledge regime that made the intellectual an object and less human. For Gramsci this was not a problem. Gramsci was put in prison because of his ideas not because the color of his skin, and the meaning of “blackness” in Western white modernity. I am not saying that one form of violence (because of ideas or because of skin color or religious belief) deserves more attention or has an epistemic privilege over the other. I am saying that for the “Latin” American left that introduced Gramsci, racism was not a problem. And Bogues further on observes, [W]e have already noticed that the radical black intellectual is, to use Gramsci’s term, an “organic” intellectual. But he or she is organic with a difference. While in the Gramscian mode radical organic intellectuals provide the missing inventory of the spontaneous philosophy of ordinary people, they do so within a framework and discursive practice that do not call into question their own ontological natures. (71) The “difference” in question is the colonial epistemic and ontological difference. The awareness of this difference brings to the scholar and intellectual, the unavoidable need to engage in border thinking, in bringing out his or her double consciousness. And when you enter this path you are going in a different direction to the one opened up by Gramsci. They could complement each other, but they are irreducible to one another. Gramsci opened new vistas toward socialist projects and future. Indigenous and Black radical thinkers opened up vistas of decolonial trajectories and futures. “Decolonization” means something other than emancipation (a common term used by liberals and Marxists) and liberation (the preferred concept in the struggle of political decolonization during the Third World and also of theology of liberation). “Decolonization” takes us to a step beyond emancipation and liberation. And that is Fanon’s great contribution. Therefore, if you are in the struggle for decolonization and you are an Afro-Caribbean intellectual (man or woman), the problems you face are significantly different from the problems you face if you are a “Latin” American intellectual, man or woman for whom

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

215

Gramsci was and may very well continue to be a guiding light of your thoughts and actions. But remember, there are other equally valid options. Notes 1. The title implicitly invokes its missing counterpart: “Gramsci and Mariatégui in Europe.” Coloniality of knowledge (and Eurocentrism) implies that intellectual influences are centrifugal, never centripetal. Many of the ideas advanced here, were rehearsed in a seminar co-taught, at Duke, with Roberto Dainotto in the Fall of 2009 titled “The left, the right and the decolonial.” The two pillars of the seminar were Gramsci and Mariátegui. I am thankful to Roberto for his generosity in sharing his substantial knowledge and understanding of Gramsci’s work as well as the students in the seminar. 2. For the “arrival” of Gramsci to Brazil in the 1960s, see Lincoln Secco; in Argentina, see Portantiero. 3. For further explanation see Mignolo, The Idea of Latin America. 4. See O’Donnell. For a summary, see the superb report by one of the actors involved in the debate, the sociologist Nun 375–93. Nun distinguished “liberal democracy” from “democratic liberalism” to avoid the imperial bent associated with the former expression. 5. By 1990, Nicos Poulantzas’s Las clases sociales en el capitalismo actual was running its tenth edition. It was published by Siglo Veintiuno, a publishing house with a strong leaning to the left with wide distribution in Spanish American countries. 6. Institute of Philosophy at the ZRC SAZU (Scientific and Research Center of the Slovenian Academy of Science and Art). 7. Quijano, “Colonialidad y Modernidad/Racionalidad” 11–20. Although the concept was already circulating at the end of the 1980s, the fi rst printed version was in 1991. 8. Quijano, Anibal. “Coloniality and Modernity/Rationality.” 168–78. 9. I have explored in several places the question of “Latinity,” notably in The Idea of Latin America. It was very well known and debated among intellectuals from the right and from the left that “Latinity” was mainly a French imperial export and a right wing South American elite’s import. 10. For a more detailed explanation, see Grzinic’s interview with Walter Mignolo. 11. I have elaborated on geopolitics of knowledge in several places. See for instance, Chapter 2 of Local Histories/Global Designs. See also, “Geopolitics of Knowledge and the Colonial Difference” 57–96. 12. I have dealt with the distinction between ¨living¨ and ¨dwelling¨ in several occasions. The most recent is in “I Am Where I Think.” 13. Gramsci’s translation appeared in Argentina toward the end of the 1950s and beginning of the1960s: Gramsci, El Materialismo, Introducción a la filosofía de la praxis, Los Intelectuales y la Organización de la Cultura, and Notas sobre Maquiavelo, sobre Política y sobre el Estado Moderno. 14. See Secco. 15. See Greer, Mignolo, and Quilligan. 16. One of the most prolific writers of the national left (delinking from the Communist Party) was José Hernández Arregui. Among his most relevant books, Imperialismo y cultura (1964); La formación de la conciencia nacional (1961); Nacionalismo

216

17. 18.

19. 20. 21. 22.

23. 24.

25.

26.

Walter D. Mignolo y liberación (1969). Notice that the national left was active during the years that Gramsci was being translated and incorporated into the Gramscian left. Two different lefts, indeed. For “Operación Condor” see The National Security Archive. On the work of Zavaleta Mercado, see Antezama and Tapia. In reality, Tapia’s book is mostly, and rightly so, about “the local production of knowledge” than about “the production of local knowledge.” That is precisely the point I am underlying here on Gramsci and Mariátegui; they are engaged in the local production of knowledge rather than in the production of local knowledge. Gramsci, “Un exámen del a situación italiana” 286. See Canal Feijoo. The concern of being Peripherals was very pronounced in the 1950s. Laclau and Mouffe. Laclau left Argentina during the years that Gramsci was introduced and returned Gramsci to Europe, so to speak. See Guha, Dominance without Hegemony. The uses of Gramsci by Guha and the South Asian Subaltern Studies collective are radically different from the uses of Gramsci by the New Left in Latin America. The contention for dominance, between the two groups studied by Guha (the British colonial elite and the local Indian elite), was no longer comparable with the situation in South and Central America whose countries obtained “independence” in the fi rst half of the nineteenth century. Mignolo, “On Subaltern and Other Agencies” 381–407. Interestingly enough, Guha critiqued Gandhi for his shortcoming in front of the masses, while Partha Chatterjee and Ashis Nandy highly praise Gandhi for his overall decolonial (my word, not theirs) project and his confrontation with Western civilization. For Gramsci, Western Civilization was not a concern (neither for Marx): they were living and thinking within it. For Reinaga and Gandhi, and for Mariátegui Western civilization was a problem because it is part capitalism. For Marx and Gramsci, capitalism was a problem, not Western Civilization. For Guha, see the section on Gandhi in his Dominance without Hegemony. See the interviews with Partha Chatterjee and Ashis Nandy in Jahanbegloo. On the Argentine national left, see the useful summary written by Chumbita in El pensamiento alternativo en la argentina del siglo XX. See also the monographic volume edited by Zulma Palermo with a preface by Walter Mignolo. I said “colonial nation-states” for the simple reason that their historical foundations in America, Africa and Asia (after the Second World War) differ from the historical foundation of “modern nation-states” in Europe after the French Revolution, because the French was not a revolution against imperial domination but, on the contrary, it opened the ways to new forms of imperialism. Italy although in a minor scale, was in the same path. Italy’s colonies were not of the same scale as France’s and England’s, but the colonial mentality (and frustrations) were there. We should remember that Fascism, Nazism and Francoism materialized in countries that remain in the margins of “the core of Europe”: Spain lost all its colonies in 1898, and Italy’s and Germany’s colonial possessions were of a minor scale. Gramsci was living and thinking in that tradition and memories; Mariátegui and the national-left in the colonial history of Spanish America. And of course, the Subaltern Studies South Asia group were still thinking within a colonial situation that not only was different from South

Mariátegui and Gramsci in “Latin” America

27.

28.

29. 30. 31.

32. 33. 34.

217

America, but was radically different from that of Italy. The introduction of Gramsci in Spanish America (and in Brazil), allowed its followers to cut the strings with the “populism” of the national left and focus, instead, on the theoretical aspects of class struggles within the capitalist logic: capitalist bourgeoisie against the working class. The nationalist-left was fully aware of the racial aspects of colonial histories; the Gramscians were not. Among the many books published on these issues, see, José Hernández Arregui, (1913–1974), Imperialismo y Cultura (1957), La formación de la conciencia nacional (1960), Jorge Abelardo Ramos (1921–1994), Socialismo y ejército en la semicolonia (1968), El marxismo de Indias (1972). Arturo Jauretche (1901–1974), Ejército y política (1958), Política y economía (1977), Los profetas del odio y la yapa. La colonización pedagógica (1975). For a recent re-evaluation of the national left from a decolonial perspective, see Zulma Palermo, Pensamiento Argentino y opción descolonial. Of note here is the book by Hernández Arregui, Imperialismo y Cultura (1957). See the classical debate between Gyan Prakash, on the one hand, and O’Hanlon and Washbrook, on the other, in Prakash, “Can the ‘Subaltern’ Ride? A Reply to O’Hanlon and Washbrook.” For a recent reevaluation of this trajectory, see Palermo (with a preface by Walter Mignolo). See Kusch. Notice that for Reinaga there is no “Latin” America—the America of European descent belongs, but “Indo” America, the America of the Indians; my addition. See Gordon 65. See Henry. See Fanon, Les damnés de la terre xx.

Part III

Epilogue

Interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak

Baidik Bhattacharya: We want to begin with the connection between Antonio Gramsci’s work and “postcolonial studies.” One of the central concerns in this dialogue across boundaries has been the notion of the “subaltern.” Writing in 1995 you observed, “Although I read it [i.e., subaltern] fi rst in Gramsci, I encountered it in its current usage fi rst in the work of the Subaltern Studies group. As a result of the publication of Selected Subaltern Studies, in the US, the word has now lost some of its defi nitive power” (The Spivak Reader 280–81). Could you please tell us a bit more about this history of a word with restricted “defi nitive power” in the intervening years? And taking this as an example could you tell us your assessment of the impact of Gramsci’s work on the postcolonial project? Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak: It is a difficult but important question, isn’t it? By defi nitive power I mean the power to give us defi nitions that are also rules of thumb, so we can progress rather than simply produce knowledge as power. This was somewhat undermined to begin with by the effect of what Edward W. Said called “travelling theory.” The US is a place where intellectual commodification is extreme—and I don’t think one should really today, in globalization, speak only about the US, but let’s use that as shorthand—so, what I would say is that a good desire on my part, in the mid1980s, to make the work of Subaltern Studies more easily accessible to those of us who taught in the US, did inevitably cause a certain dilution of the word, what Raymond Williams would describe as the dominant, appropriating opposition as alternative, and Herbert Marcuse and Robert Paul Wolff would call “repressive tolerance.” (I should add here that the subalternists themselves were not particularly keen to embrace international popularity. They had sufficient popularity among specialists in the field.) As a result of this dilution, the claim to native informantship on the part of the upwardly mobile, or desiring to be upwardly mobile, new immigrant population after 1965 began to fi nd a new word with which to describe itself; not just native informant—it was never a word for them, it was for me. But, subaltern became a claim to a certain kind of undifferentiated victimage. I quote always Fredric

222

The Postcolonial Gramsci

Jameson’s surprising axiom that “subaltern is anybody who feels inferior.” This is the fi rst part of my answer, the easier part. As for the trajectory of Gramsci, Giorgio Baratta has recently observed in an article that I read through the International Gramsci Newsletter but apparently it had its fi rst publication somewhere else, an Italian journal published in English, that Gramsci seems to be almost the only older Communist theorist who has emerged unstained from the fate of actual International Communism, and he warns us that Gramsci is increasingly read as a liberal democrat, whereas what both he and I think is that Gramsci is a democratic Communist. Sitting in West Bengal today, after the collapse of the left, this is a difficult project to restore because the local presentation of an international way of thinking has made the left here clueless and corrupt and electorally expendable. But I get ahead of myself. When in the early 1980s the Subaltern Studies folks got inspired by Gramsci, I think, what they looked at was that Gramsci was locating a subject outside of capital logic, the study of which could not be performed through the regular historiographies of modern India. (As a result of the publication of Selected Subaltern Studies, Latin American subaltern studies groups got started. There the effect of Gramsci is not particularly noticeable.) But Ranajit Guha and his collective went to Gramsci because of this place outside of capital logic. Dipesh Chakrabarty’s fi rst book is resonant with this. Even at that early stage, Barun De noted that this was not exactly true to Gramsci. For me, this is a good thing, intellectual activism that re-territorializes a powerful original. Yet we must also note the difference from Gramsci. In notes on “History of the Subaltern Classes: Methodological Criteria” Gramsci gives a powerful defi nition in the second paragraph, which will boil down in my language as the following: the subaltern classes do not achieve the state. This is slightly upstream from the circuit of citizenship although that is what is implied. But, Gramsci is still talking there about how to write history. And so he suggests that you cannot fi nd records, and therefore, that famous metaphor, “inventory without traces.” Now, this is not the case of the South Asian subalterns. Because nobody achieved the state in colonialism—no natives, not even the ICSs, the Deputy Magistrates and so on—they do not precisely achieve the state, number one. Number two, there is, if anything, an excess of record; so, therefore, the task became immediately different. In other words, teasing out the consciousness of the subaltern or the subaltern consciousness from the texts of the elite—that wasn’t Gramsci. But for me, it is not problematic. It is the historical stamp on the South Asian subaltern studies work. Let us go back to Gramsci. As you know, Palmiro Togliatti was Gramsci’s literary executor. Togliatti and Gramsci had serious political differences, although they were friends and associates, over relationships with Moscow and various things which may not concern us here. And it was Togliatti who chopped up Gramsci in the way in which Europe and Britain received him. In the process, what got lost was Gramsci’s (after all, these notes on the

Interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak

223

subaltern are precisely that) articulation of what I have called a methodicomethodological difference under the auspices of the subaltern. I am revising in Kunming, China, far from my personal library. So let me simply say that if one reads Gramsci’s many notes on the subaltern raw, one fi nds this difference indicated between method and methodology which the reader must elaborate (work at). It is only now that with Joseph A. Buttigieg’s excellent translation—annotated critical translation of the Notebooks—we are beginning to realize that Gramsci, on the occasion of the subaltern, began to talk about the need to acknowledge that in order to devise a methodology for the study of the subaltern, one had to realize that the intellectual’s method was produced in a different class-space and that there would always be a difference between the method and the methodology; and that difference pretty much defi nes the status of historiography itself as the ontico-ontological difference defi nes the status of fundamental ontology. That is necessarily ignored by later English-reading groups influenced by Gramsci, so that the subaltern remained an object of study rather than a subject to learn from in a mediated way because the subaltern classes cannot be—unless you have a Christian theory of suffering, keeping consciousness intact—unmediated teachers. Gramsci, therefore, said in the Notebooks that the intellectuals must be instrumentalized in order to produce the subaltern intellectual, in order to produce a proletarian intellectual who is unmarked by a prejudice against the subaltern. And the instrumentalization of the intellectual has to be in the format of a master-disciple dialectic following Hegel, of course, where the disciple is the intellectual and the master is not the subaltern, but what has been translated as the cultural environment. I fear that the word “cultural” is not the best word to be used and that would lead us into a much longer discussion of the hopeless culturalization of Gramsci. But I am not going to go there. I think I want to move on to the next question. However, one more thing and this is in a piece that is recently out in the Columbia Press Collection edited by Rosalind Morris. Since you talk about a trajectory and I am influenced by Gramsci, let me repeat that “Can the Subaltern Speak?” was given as a lecture before I had actually read Subaltern Studies, and then that got covered over because of the powerful influence of the Subaltern Studies people on me. But in that essay, I was moving more under the influence of the notion of the necessity of class consciousness in order for subaltern resistance to be recognized as such that we fi nd in Marx’s Eighteenth Brumaire. BB: Your essay “Can the Subaltern Speak?” is one of the most important texts for the field “postcolonial studies.” In this essay you proposed a radical re-imagination of the subaltern—on the one hand you argued that Gramsci’s “work on the ‘subaltern classes’ extends the class-position/class-consciousness argument isolated in The Eighteenth Brumaire.” And on the other you also emphasized the “singular” position of the gendered subaltern subject. We were wondering if you would like to revisit the essay in light of this

224

The Postcolonial Gramsci

productive tension, and if you could tell us about the way you look at that essay after almost two decades of its publication. GCS: That essay is not really post-colonial as such. I was looking at female subalternity as singular, rather than necessarily at a subaltern class. And subalternity is not in the state, so post- or anti-colonialism is incidental there. (Recently, Ursula Apitzsch has pointed at Gramsci’s correspondence with Giulia and Tatiana Schucht where he speaks of individual if not singular subalternity.) Also, the essay is concerned with pre-colonial determinations of gendered subaltern psychobiography. Sumit Sarkar has been kind enough to say that this is almost the only subalternist work that looks at pre-colonial material. It is much more a critique of the Hindu orthodoxy around sati, and then the middle class displacement of that ideology into a world where sati itself had no reality—that world of Bhubaneswari Bhaduri—than anything about the British as such. And I have remained in that position, Baidik, because I fi nd it without any intellectual or political effort at all. I fi nd it much more didactically alive for me in my everyday. To think of the fact that I belong to a ferocious majority with a terrible history of both cultural production and criminal social tradition, grandeur built on cruelty, and therefore, the entire trajectory of knowledge as property and power, which is millennial—I fi nd that to be a much greater didactic corrective than the few hundred years of colonization, which I was smart enough to recognize early on that if it is not recognized as enabling violation, we are in bad faith. So therefore, it is really not a postcolonial essay in the sense of focusing on a critique of colonization. What I am trying to say there, if anything, is that two groups in such a contrast—the Hindu orthodoxy as well as the Indo-British reformers and legalists (there is a difference between the two segments of the portmanteau designations)—that both of them, in fact, had no interest in accessing the protocols of gendered agency. That is what my basic position was then, which may be revised when I read Ranajit Guha’s recent book Daya. Now I have subsequently tried to place it within my own intellectual autobiography, my stereotype of myself. And I have noted that I went to my own class. It is now well known that the woman in the case was my grandmother’s sister. So, because I wanted access I went into the family. I do not particularly admire this, although I understand this, and it warns me against identitarianism because it was basically an identitarian move. I was smart enough to know that identitarianism was intellectually harmful. So, at least, I kept her identity—her kinship inscription—a secret. And I moved from that fi rst move. I moved from studying the subaltern to learning from, which is the hardest possible task, especially because given the complete lack of interest of the State or National Civil Service in terms of training primary school teachers, and the domestic and international civil society’s unexamined patronizing of it, my attempt to learn from the subaltern how to produce subaltern intellectuals, has to remain in a sector which I disapprove of—classic description

Interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak

225

of a double bind -- private sector voluntarism. It was in that situation that I went to Gramsci’s thoughts on this in the Prison Notebooks— I did not know that I was doing precisely that, I discovered the deep affi nity teaching Gramsci in New York. When I taught Gramsci before, all the way from Texas in the late 1970s, my own subalternist educational work had not matured enough for me to make this connection. Also some specific Gramsci people in Italy, especially women, Sergia Adamo and Giorgio Baratta saying that in recognizing the need for the production of the subaltern intellectual I had taken Gramsci somewhere, which I think was very kind and affectionate of them. But nonetheless, that is what made me look again at Gramsci, and beginning to teach him carefully I realized what I was doing. You cannot do this kind of thing— if you think to yourself, oops! I am teaching Gramsci or I am doing Freire or I am doing Dewey or I am doing Montessori. No. You are going there because you are trying to not learn from a Gramsci or a Freire who is continuous with you as a university academic but as I said, in a mediated way from people who cannot, in fact, “teach” in a way that you can recognize. You have to know, quite unsentimentally, that whatever they may say themselves, they are deeply affected by the history of which you are both agent and victim, as are they, in a different way. The gender argument of subalternity is different yet. In the old dispensation the subaltern allowed us to stop outside of capital logic. In the thinking that I am now describing, gender allows us to think outside of the abstract logic of citizenship alone. So that it is in thinking of gendered subalternity that we step—at risk—we step from the abstract structures of citizenship, the circuits of hegemony, in other words, agency talk—very important—into subjection. From agent to subject. Gendered subalternity is not easy to track. The new gendered subaltern I have defi ned in a conversation with Vinayak Chaturvedi in terms of TRIPS and TRIMS and global super-exploitation. Citizenship and the civil rights of the subaltern are still in the realm of agency even when gender sensitive. It is necessarily somewhat gender blind because it cannot step back from the realm of rights and agency. Even when we are most self-consciously gendered, in terms of citizenship within which we take gendered oppression and make a case, we are somewhat genderblind because gendering is upstream from the State. The State has a history, the history of gendering is as we are constituted in sexual difference and fall into a so-called “cultural” field of negotiations abstracted in terms of that difference. Reproductive heteronormativity is our oldest institution of validation and we are in a double bind with it. It cannot be corrected, it can only be approached. And so, the gendered subaltern lives in another space and Gramsci’s argument about “inventory without traces” is taken into that arena because psychoanalysis is also aligned with reproductive heteronormativity. Its corrections too are within that alignment. Reproductive heteronormativity contains psychoanalysis. Both Irigaray and Judith Butler are aware of this. Gramsci, necessarily not thinking of this, says that sociology might now have

226

The Postcolonial Gramsci

to produce shorter essay-like things which are more literary because of this methodico-methodological difference. Perhaps Shahid Amin is the one who has an intuition of this in the way he writes. That is the Gramscian risk. BB: In a talk titled “The Trajectory of the Subaltern in My Work” (2004) you have pointed out two configurations of the subaltern in your work: through your engagement with Ranajit Guha’s work and your “loose bonding” with the Subaltern Studies group that leads to the project of “learning to learn from below”; and your engagement with the “new subaltern” that allows the “homoeopathy of self abstraction” in the public sphere in order to connect with the state. We were wondering if you could tell us how these two moments extend the legacies of Gramsci in your recent project—which you describe in the talk as critical negotiation with the “abstract understanding of secularism and the state”—and, if we can extend this insight, how you see the relevance of Gramsci (if any) in this age of globalization/post-globalization. GCS: Post-globalization is not a word I would use because in spite of people trying to locate globalization in the earliest attempts to think a world and systematize it, we must also, à la Lenin’s work on imperialism, where he so clearly pointed out that capitalism was in a moment of Aufhebung into commercial capital, realize that globalization is an Aufhebung of the self-determination of capital. When Lenin is writing about the defi nition of fi nance capital is still authorized by our view of commercial capital. When the commercial banks and the investment banks were collapsed in the US . . . that was the beginning of an upheaval which showed the interconnectedness of globalized capitalism. In this respect, post-globalization is the articulation of an unexamined desire, it needs a reality check. It is for the future to defi ne us as post-something. As a claim, it is useless. What has happened to the Gramscian project within globalization? Can one talk about it? Yes, I think we can talk about it because the subaltern is a position without identity. Remnants of identity must claim to each of the forms of appearance of this position because there is no position that stands by itself. All class positions are always contradicted by identitarian rags hanging from their abstract structure so that the position is also different. And I took it to the gendered subaltern in terms of crossing what may be called the agency-subject barrier. What we can see in globalization is the creation of new forms of subalternization. Globalization imposes an uneven economic simultaneity upon varieties of political formation. The unevenness of the economic—seemingly simultaneous and therefore unredressable can only be controlled by secularist absolutisms—from benevolent to malevolent. Religion goes from social justice to terrorism as opposition to absolutism. Islamism in Central Asia after communism is a rich example. If you want to see new forms of subalternization here according to Gramsci’s classic description—no access to the hegemonic

Interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak

227

structures of the state, Kathleen Collins’s book Clan Politics and Regime Transition in Central Asia will give you a lead. This calls for a re-thinking of secularism that exceeds the boundaries of our conversation. Despite the vigorous argument of Indian secularists, I don’t think India is a model for secularism. On the one side are the socialist absolutisms declining into Central Asian corruption and, on the other side, the great historical model of China. I am just coming from a theatre of new subalternizations in China, and it doesn’t have much to do with religion. Another kind of subalternization today lodges in the so-called illegal immigrant groups, they may use religion as redress, again, but I don’t think the remedy there is secularism. To the extent that religion oppresses gender in these groups, we can have local struggles, but the issue of secularism as such is not the fi nal solution in Gramscian terms. Where I deal with secularism is in terms of the unexamined class-specific privatization of the intuition of the transcendental, and that is not through Gramsci. BB: If we can go back to my earlier question once again, the point you make about the “metonymization” of the self. GCS: Oh, the Santa Barbara talk, which has been so YouTubed? Everybody has seen it. I feel very embarrassed. But, yes, the metonymization, I don’t want to call it code-switching because if you call it code-switching that is a rational choice reduction—an existential impoverishment. By metonymization, what I was trying to describe is the part of the practice of those who have the leisure and class position to be morally outraged for the sake of the world at large rather than self-interested because of the need for freedom from oppression. This seems clear, doesn’t it? Now, if we think about the way in which people like that whole generation, not just Georges Sorel or Walter Benjamin but people like Rosa Luxemburg—thought about the importance of the general strike because the agent of the general strike is— not the ideologue. But what does the ideologue do? That is what I am talking about here. Those of us who become “activist ideologues”—whatever that word activism means—inhabit, the methodico-methodological difference as best as we can. In that situation we inevitably enter engaged collectivities by emphasizing— this is the synecdoche part—one part of our stereotype, of our agential selves. This has to do with tremendous intuition of the production of the subaltern intellectual. When I try minimally to engage in that Gramscian model of work my self-metonymization reduces itself of a claiming of equality through the formula: you have one vote and I have one vote. The arithmeticization of democracy—it is nonsense if taken as essence. Nonetheless, I metonymize myself as such. This is a declaration of figuration; it is not a rational choice. The project is to restore to the subaltern, through infrastructural engagements, the possibility of a broader spectrum of selfmetonymization without criminal violence against them. In that interest the

228

The Postcolonial Gramsci

specific metonym is part of a war of maneuver. This is by way of a contrast with the protective and benevolent ex-zamindar types who join hands with the World Social Forum—very far indeed from the Gramscian project—I call it a feudality without feudalism. Their alter-globalization European associates play with them as if they themselves are the ethnicized subaltern without realizing that there is a representational problem here, democratic structures hardly exist in the situation of the benevolent feudal, conscientized feudal, superficially lefticized feudal, Chomskianized feudal class, without actually existing feudalism, but with affective feudalism still in place. This is exactly opposed to the Gramscian imperative. That particular possibility of broader self-metonymization, which is extra-moral in the Nietzschean terms, is quenched in the benevolence of an unacknowledged feudality. It is not without interest that my schools after twenty years of work in the fi rst state were closed because one of the young boys showed a modicum of judgment about good and bad education. Armed struggle is okay, there is goon-politics on both sides. To distract them with radical phraseology is okay, I suppose, when they are fighting. To describe the phenomenon through Euro-US radical phraseology is as foolish as it is wrong, but it’s okay. This other thing—the possibility of much broader self-metonymization on the part of the subaltern, remotely indicated by this boy’s transformed consciousness —this intangible thing, a minimal representation, perhaps, of what Gramsci wanted to arouse in the subaltern, seemed altogether threatening to the canny old ex-zamindar, the benevolent despot. To produce this requires so much involvement that you can’t do collective world-saving under these auspices. Nobody seems particularly interested in what Gramsci calls a disciple-relationship with the subaltern environment and I call learning to learn from below. Right from the fi rst day, the fi rst encounter, the bourgeois activist knows how to solve the problem. And I know immediately, they will never learn from below. The least that can happen is that they will perhaps submit to me and go my way. This is the most difficult part of my intellectual project—supplementing vanguardism by expanding the possibility of self-metonymization. BB: You have often talked about your “field work” in your school in the Adivasi areas of West Bengal as an integral part of your intellectual life. Does this experience allow you to rethink the Gramscian notion of the organic intellectual? GCS: When I wrote “Righting Wrongs” I didn’t realize that the power of the feudal personalities keep the adivasi as close to anthropological “purity” as possible. What I was looking at was a simulacrum. I was looking at a removal from the stream of history, not by history as such, but by the desire of the feudals without feudalism to remain benevolent by way of an earlier semiotic field: fighting the police, fighting the party on behalf of the “serfs”—public interest litigation—imposing upon them absurd agricultural projects thought

Interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak

229

up by retired, old codgers from agricultural schools, completely unmindful of chemical fertilizers, I could go on. This was the version of benevolent feudal intervention from above that I mistook for the “nature” of tribal “culture.” God knows the benevolent despots took me in! Those tribals were in the hyper-real. They were not acting out cultural conformity. They were obliged to remain faithful to the idea of their masters. This is why the UNstyle feminists dislike the fact that I don’t dress ethnic and talk global. BB: Does your experience allow you to rethink the Gramscian notion of the “organic intellectual?” GCS: Sorry! I forgot that completely! What is there to rethink? Gramsci does not think that the organic intellectual is necessarily a good guy. What he thinks is that every mode of production throws up an organic intellectual who supports that mode of production. His only example is the organic intellectual of capitalism. Organic for Gramsci does not mean Coleridge. It is more like organon, organization—a system. The contrast between traditional and organic intellectual does not really hold as he goes on writing. I am sure if he had had the time and health to come out of jail and write a book, there would have been negotiation between these two worlds. It would not have been a binary opposition. We take these notes to himself, by a very smart and sick man in jail, as defi nitions. Hegemony, war of maneuver, war of position, organic intellectuals, intellectual—everything is what I call medicine and poison in Gramsci, because he is thinking, he is thinking. Pharmakon is more complicated because in Derrida’s discussion, Socrates is the pharmakeus. Mine—and to an extent Gramsci’s—is a vulgarization of the Socratic position. There is, however, one important distinction to keep in mind: we are speaking of medicine and poison, not cure and poison. Medicine can be poisonously used or can become poison because of your organic connection with a specific mode of production, in the Gramscian sense. The traditional organic contrast, if it holds in Gramsci, holds only in terms of modes of production, pre-capitalistic, generally Catholic (catholic is not a mode of production, of course, so Gramsci sees its ideological force as capital determines itself). Remember, Marx also talks about the clergy in terms of ideological production. If you want to keep that moving—intellectuals organic to Catholicism and intellectuals organic to capitalism—that is the traditional organic divide as commonly understood, as far as I am concerned. Then the new intellectual, who has been transferred by the postTogliatti English translators from the end—the fi nal paragraph of the speculation about education—in that particular notebook to an insignificant position in the middle. Why and how? There is no critical apparatus to explain. It has been transferred into a kind of hodgepodge middle space. Page 10, upper left hand corner of the paperback of the Selections from the Prison Notebooks.

230

The Postcolonial Gramsci

The New Intellectual is a different thing. She or he (Gramsci knew female intellectuals, though his mode is benevolent patriarchal) is, if you like, an organic intellectual of democratic socialism. I write about this in the Introduction to my book Aesthetic Education in the Age of Globalization. I believe the argument is tested right in front of us and that to me is a more interesting thing. The sentimental academic-populist version of the organic intellectual takes the counter-intuitive in Gramsci and turns it into something that is no more than commonsensical. BB: This brings us to our next question . . . GCS: It seems to me that you have really linked these questions very well because I seem to be answering always the next one or beginning to answer the next one. BB: Do you see Gramsci’s influence on your ideas about education? GCS: Yes. Yes. That is a very good question. Gramsci had two forays into education. First, the Factory Council days before his imprisonment. And then, in jail he had the time to consider why the Turin strike failed and put his mind to the problem of producing the subaltern intellectual. Gramsci is careful from the start not to base epistemological authority in the unions. This is the one place where he stands with Rosa Luxemburg. Unlike Luxemburg, though, Gramsci insists on taking the epistemological task (long run) away from the unions (short run) and makes epistemological transformation the task of the new intellectual. This he begins to think about more in terms of the available class mobile system of education rather than an alternative project in the factories. And I myself would say that that was right on target because no alternative proposed as an alternative ever remains an alternative. The only thing that you lose is the weight of amoral history concerned with nothing but itself. That is a great advantage to have. For example, one of my former “advisors” whom I used to take into the villages and who could only ever stay there for two or three days would say: if you make them make up diagrams themselves they will learn much better. But the part of our mind that can connect the abstract and the concrete in terms not of art-practice (that, funnily enough gets damaged less, is tougher), but in terms of cognitive performance, has been destroyed by centuries of prohibition of intellectual labor. Could my “advisor” step out of his own upper middle-class production? Not for a minute. This is why Gramsci says that the subaltern environment must be the intellectual’s teacher. It is a sabotaging argument, as it were. Gramsci obviously is not perfect. He is not an educationist tying up things. The entire business of taking Latin away from the Latinitas of Mussolini, nonetheless, has a pretty old-fashioned argument behind it, but the important

Interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak

231

thing is to sabotage it to a different end, the old-fashioned tools have lasted. I am not a Gramscian fundamentalist. But on the other hand, the idea that you insert these folks into a good way of teaching the national and state curriculum fi nds resonance in that intuition of Gramsci’s: the instrumentalization of the intellectual, the new intellectual is in the master–disciple position, in the disciple position—all of that is the methodical part. The methodological part is to use the established system because, if you simplify de-subalternization into mere class mobility, the subaltern does not have a chance in hell with a non-formal education. One of my associates in Hong Kong, she is a young woman who was good enough to say she was influenced by my thought, ran a wonderful NGO. She said at one point: How can this be? Where there is so much education and has been for long, so the students are getting to the electoral age. How is it that they voted BJP? And I said: what does learning Maths have to do with thinking democratically? Du Bois also, not only Gramsci, says this. Just after Emancipation, says Du Bois, the Negro needs food and shelter but they must at once learn to communicate with the stars. What does that mean? It is that engagement with that historical system of education which the bourgeois intellectuals, who are themselves very well educated within that system, dismiss as producing traditional intellectuals (does not have to if the teaching has changed). So it is an activity- intensive rather than curriculum-intensive project and there I am with Gramsci without being a Gramscian fundamentalist. I think there are areas where . . . I mean Gramsci himself changes his mind about the relationship between national languages and dialects in the wonderful last Notebook printed. But that is too “thick” a topic for now. BB: And my last question, how do you revisit “Can the Subaltern Speak?” now? GCS: Okay! First of all, the original version needed another round of editing that my editors did not provide. People fi x on that “White Man Saving Brown Women from Brown Men” sentence as if it is the central message. But the rhetorical moment there is that I say I do not know anything about South Asia, so, I take Freud as my monitory model. If I can construct it as a sentence then I can go forth to construct an object. Just as Freud wrote the sentence “a child is being beaten,” so can I write this sentence. Tada, right? And recently I saw that what I was doing was taking a white man (Freud) and using him to save brown women, namely the satis, from brown men, namely, Hindu orthodoxy. So, in a deep sense, I was myself implicated. No one else has noticed it because if they had, they would have killed me. But I looked at it and I also realized that that is the one thing that Bhubaneswari is not doing. Her charge was to kill a white man. So, that’s where the double bind between ethics and politics came in. I think the one thing that I do think about that incident is that it taught me to get beyond knowledge as power.

232

The Postcolonial Gramsci

By looking at foremothers—the essay “Foremothers” is on the web and is now being published by Susan Gubar. To learn this lesson of extreme politics, suicide politics, body-as-inscription politics, to inhabit the cusp of ethics and politics, and the impossibility of being ethical and the impossibility of being political and producing oneself as response—this is what today, I really take away from that event. I had a huge writer’s block when I fi rst wrote it in the eighties; it was not written easily. And so, then, the recent discovery through Nayanika Mukherjee with whom in a kind of casual conversation, I revealed that I have photographs of the Birangonas—the rape victims of the Bangladesh war—as she reminded me they were called. I had forgotten that mother and I were there at that time and mother was really the much greater figure and activist at that stage. BB: Do you still have those photographs? GCS: Photographs? Indeed I have them. So, Nayanika came to me and she took the photos. There were eighteen photos. They were just in my album. They were not part of any archive. In 1973, okay? So, she took them and she organized them. She gave credit due to the University Press and interviewed me, which I have just edited. At any rate in talking to Nayanika, I said no, Bhubaneswari is not the origin of the turn to the subaltern. This is the secret that I never unearthed, until the casual conversation with Nayanika. It is the scene of being with mother, where I owe, as a daughter, no activist responsibility. My father, who died in 1955, had destroyed his extremely brilliant career as a Civil Surgeon in Dhaka in 1940—in about two seconds. He had been asked to give false evidence at a rape trial. So, there was a whole itinerary of heteronormative familial connections drawing me there in terms of a much bigger scene which was non-productive, which was precisely not fieldwork. This is very unusual. And talking to Nayanika, I realized my stereotype of my autobiography, that it started with a foremother, was the second take. The Birangonas will remain the open secret, the agential articulation of which became “Can the Subaltern Speak?” and, then, turning away from family to other people’s children—an accessible democratic signature—to the hard work of learning from below the production of the subaltern intellectual. ©Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak Columbia University

Contributors

Baidik Bhattacharya is assistant professor of English at the University of Delhi, India. His essays on colonial and postcolonial theory and literature have appeared in journals like Postcolonial Studies, Novel, and Interventions. He is currently completing a book manuscript tentatively titled Postcolonial Writing in the Era of Globalization. Paolo Capuzzo is associate professor of contemporary history at the University of Bologna. He has been researcher at the universities of Vienna, TU-Berlin, Université Libre in Brussels, University of Leicester and professor at the universities of Barcelona and Tour. Among his recent publications are Culture del consumo (Bologna, Il Mulino, 2006), and Studi gramsciani nel mondo. Gli studi culturali coedited with G. Vacca and G. Schirru (Bologna, Il Mulino, 2009). Iain Chambers presently teaches cultural, postcolonial, and Mediterranean studies at the Oriental University in Naples, Italy. His most recent book is Mediterranean Crossings: The Politics of an Interrupted Modernity (2008). He is also editor (with Lidia Curti) of The Post-colonial Question. Common Skies, Divided Horizons (1996) and the volume Esercizi di Potere. Gramsci, Said e il postcoloniale (2006), and is presently preparing a work on the musical “mappings” of the Mediterranean. Partha Chatterjee is professor of anthropology at Columbia University, New York, and honorary professor, Centre for Studies in Social Sciences, Calcutta. He is a founding member of the Subaltern Studies editorial group. His books include Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World (1986), The Nation and Its Fragments (1993), The Politics of the Governed (2004), and Lineages of Political Society (2010). Pheng Cheah is professor of rhetoric at the University of California at Berkeley. He is the author of Inhuman Conditions: On Cosmopolitanism and Human Rights (Harvard University Press, 2006) and Spectral Nationality:

234

The Postcolonial Gramsci

Passages of Freedom from Kant to Postcolonial Literatures of Liberation (Columbia University Press, 2003), and the co-editor of several book collections, including Derrida and the Time of the Political (Duke University Press, 2009), Grounds of Comparison: Around the Work of Benedict Anderson (Routledge, 2003), and Cosmopolitics—Thinking and Feeling Beyond the Nation (University of Minnesota Press, 1998). He is currently completing a book on theories of the world and world literature from the postcolonial South in an era of global fi nancialization. Also in progress is a book on globalization and world cinema from the three Chinas, focusing on the fi lms of Jia Zhangke, Tsai Ming-liang, and Fruit Chan. Sandro Mezzadra works as an associate professor of political theory in the Department of Politics, Institutions, History at the University of Bologna. He has been research fellow at the Humboldt Universität, Berlin; in the Centre for Cultural Research at the University of Western Sydney; at the Fondation Maison des sciences de l’homme, Paris; and at Duke University. His research work has focused on the classical modern European political philosophy as well as on the history of political, social, and legal sciences in Germany between the nineteenth and the twentieth centuries. In the last decade his work has particularly centered on the relations between globalization, migration and citizenship, as well as on postcolonial theory and criticism. He is an active participant in the discussion within the tradition of Italian autonomist Marxism and (post)operaismo and one of the founders of the UniNomade network (http://uninomade.org/). Walter D. Mignolo is William H. Wannamaker Professor of Literature and Romance Studies, Professor of Cultural Anthropology, Spanish and Latin American Studies, at Duke University. In 2010 he was appointed International Board Member for the six-year project “Time, Memory and Representation,” Sorderton University, Sweden. He also serves on the Advisory Board of The Hong Kong Advanced Institute for Cross Disciplinary Studies (College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences), at the City University of Hong-Kong, China. In October 2010, he lectured at the Bruno Kreisky Foundation in Vienna and he delivered the Annual Norbert Lerner’s Lecture Series at the Universidad Diego Portales, Chile. Additionally, he was the 2010–2011 Visiting Fellow at the Institute of Advanced Studies at Warwick University, England. He also curated the exhibit “Esteticas descoloniales,” which opened in Bogota, Colombia, on November 10, 2010, and at Duke University in May 2011. His next book, The Darker Side of Western Modernity: Global Futures, Decolonial Options will be released in October 2011. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, university professor at Columbia University, has been profoundly influenced by the work of Antonio Gramsci

Interview with Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak

235

in the area of the epistemological performance of Marxism and the production of the subaltern intellectual. His influence will be felt again in her forthcoming book An Aesthetic Education in the Era of Globalization (Harvard University Press). Neelam Srivastava is senior lecturer in postcolonial literature at Newcastle University (UK). She is the author of Secularism in the Postcolonial Indian Novel: National and Cosmopolitan Narratives in English (Routledge, 2007). She has published essays on South Asian literature in English, the fi lmmaker Gillo Pontecorvo, and the cultural history of Italian colonialism. She is currently the coordinator of an International Research Network, “Postcolonial Translation: The Case of South Asia,” funded by the Leverhulme Trust. Rajeswari Sunder Rajan is Global Distinguished Professor in the Department of English at New York University. She has been a Senior Fellow at the Nehru Memorial Museum and Library, New Delhi, and taught in the English faculty at the University of Oxford where she was Professorial Fellow of Wolfson College. Her publications include Real and Imagined Women: Gender, Culture and Postcolonialism (1993), The Scandal of the State: Women, Law and Citizenship in Postcolonial India (2003), and the co-edited volume The Crisis of Secularism in India (2007). Robert J. C. Young is Julius Silver Professor of English and Comparative Literature at New York University. His White Mythologies: Writing History and the West (1990), Colonial Desire: Hybridity in Culture, Theory and Race (Routledge, 1995), and Postcolonialism: An Historical Introduction (Blackwell, 2001), have been some of the most influential books in the field of postcolonial studies. He has also written Postcolonialism: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford, 2003), The Idea of English Ethnicity (Blackwell, 2008), and is currently writing a book on translation. Prior to moving to New York, Robert Young was professor of English and critical theory and a fellow of Wadham College, Oxford University. He is general editor of the quarterly Interventions: International Journal of Postcolonial Studies. His work has been translated into twenty languages.

Works Cited

Adamo, Sergia, ed. Culture planetarie? Prospettive e limiti della teoria e della critica culturale. Roma: Meltemi, 2007. Print. Aglietta, Michel. Regulation et crise du capitalisme. L’experience des États-Unis. Paris: Calmann-Levy, 1976. Print. Agyeman, Opoku. The Failure of Grassroots Pan-Africanism: The Case of the All-African Trade Union Federation. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2003. Print. Ahmad, Aijaz. In Theory: Classes, Nations, Literatures. London: Verso, 1992. Print. Ahmed, Leila. Women and Gender in Islam. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1992. Print. “Alfred Sauvy.” Bibliomonde. Web. 4 June 2011. Alquati, Romano. Sulla Fiat e altri scritti. Milano: Feltrinelli, 1975. Print. Althusser, Louis. “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses (Notes Towards an Investigation).” Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays. New York: Monthly Review Press, 2001. 127–186. Print. Amin, Ash. “The Remainders of Race.” Theory, Culture, Society 27.1 ( January 2010): 1–23. Print. Anantha Murthy, U. R. Bharathipura. [1974]. Trans. P. Sreenivasa Rao. New Delhi: Macmillan India, 1996. Print. . “Five Decades of My Writing.” Samvatsar Lecture. Sahitya Akademi, 21 February 2007. Web. . Omnibus. Ed. N. Manu Chakravarthy. Gurgaon: Arvind Kumar, 2008. Print. . “Why Not Worship in the Nude?” Omnibus. Ed. N. Manu Chakravarthy. Gurgaon: Arvind Kumar, 2008. 323 –340. Print. Anderson, Perry. “The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci.” New Left Review 100 (1977): 5–80. Print. Anidjar, Gil. Semites. Race, Religion, Literature. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2008. Print. Antezana, Luis H. J. La diversidad social en Zavaleta Mercado. La Paz: Centro Boliviano de Estudios Multidisciplinarios, 1991. Print. Appiah, Kwame Anthony. “Is the Post- in Postmodernism the Post- in Postcolonial?” Critical Inquiry 17.2 (1991): 336–357. Print. Arac, Jonathan. “Criticism between Opposition and Counterpoint.” Boundary 2, 25.2 (1998): 55–69. Print. Arrighi, Giovanni. Adam Smith in Beijing: Lineages of the Twenty-First Century London: Verso, 2007. Print. . Interview with D. Harvey. “The Winding Paths of Capital.” New Left Review 56 (March–April 2009): 61–94. Print.

238

Works Cited

Aricó, José. La cola del diablo. Itinerario de Gramsci en América Latina. Caracas: Editorial Nueva Sociedad, 1988. Print. Armah, Ayi Kwei. “Frantz Fanon: The Awakener.” Negro Digest 18.12 (October 1969): 4–42. Print. Asad, Talal. Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons of Power in Christianism and Islam. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University, 1993. Print. . Formations of the Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003. Asor Rosa, Alberto. Storia d’Italia. Vol. 4, Part 2. Dall’Unità a oggi, La cultura. Ed. Ruggero Romano and Corrado Vivanti. Einaudi: Torino, 1975. Print. . Scrittori e popolo. Roma: Savelli, 1965. Print. Balibar, Étienne. “Debating with Alain Badiou on Universalism.” Centre International D’Étude de la Philosophie Française Contemporaine. December 2008. Web. 7 July 2011. Baratta, Giorgio. Le rose e i Quaderni. Il pensiero dialogico di Antonio Gramsci. Roma: Carocci, 2003. Print. Baratta, Giorgio and Andrea Catone, eds. Tempi moderni. Atti del Convegno Internazionale organizzato dal Centro di Iniziativa Politica e Culturale di Roma. Roma: Edizioni Associate, 1989. Print. Baratta, Giorgio and Guido Liguori, eds. Gramsci da un secolo all’altro. Roma: Editori Riuniti, 1999. Print. Bardhan, Pranab. The Political Economy of Development in India. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1984. Print. Bermani, Cesare. Gramsci, gli intellettuali e la cultura proletaria. Milano: Colibrì, 2007. Print. Bernasconi, Robert. “The European Knows and Does Not Know: Fanon’s Response to Sartre.” Frantz Fanon’s Black Skin, White Masks: New Interdisciplinary Essays. Ed. Max Silverman. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press, 2005. 100–111. Print. Biemann, Ursula. “Agadez Chronicle. Post-colonial Politics of Space and Mobility in the Sahara.” The Maghreb Connection. Movements of Life Across North Africa. Ed. Ursula Biemann and Brian Holmes. Barcelona: Acta, 2006. 43–67. Print. Bobbio, Norberto. Gramsci e la concezione della società civile. Milano: Feltrinelli, 1976. Print. Bogues, Anthony. Black Prophets, Black Heretics: Radical Political Intellectuals. New York: Routledge, 2003. Print. Bologna Sergio. “Il rapporto società-fabbrica come categoria storica.” Primo Maggio 2 (1974): 3–8. Print. Boni, Livio. “Un Gramsci minore. Il ‘Quaderno 22’ attraverso e al di là delle letture operaiste.” Critica Marxista 3–4 (2010): 79–88. Print. Boothman, Derek. “The Sources for Gramsci’s Concept of Hegemony.” Rethinking Gramsci. Ed. Marcus E. Green. London: Routledge, 2011. 55–67. Print. Borio, Guido, Francesca Pozzi, and Gigi Roggero. Futuro anteriore: dai Quaderni rossi ai movimenti globali: ricchezze e limiti dell’operaismo italiano. Roma: DeriveApprodi, 2002. Print. Boninelli, Giovanni Mimmo. “Folklore.” Dizionario gramsciano: 1926–1937. Ed. Guido Liguori and Pasquale Voza. Rome: Carocci, 2009. 319–322. Print. Brague, Rémi, Eccentric Culture: A Theory of Western Civilization. Trans. Samuel Lester. South Bend: St Augustine’s Press, 2009. Print. Brennan, Timothy. “Antonio Gramsci and Postcolonial Theory.” Diaspora 10.2 (Fall 2001):143–187. Print. . “Places of Mind, Occupied Lands: Edward Said and Philology.” The Arab World Geographer 7.1–2 (2004): 47–64. Print.

Works Cited

239

. Wars of Position: The Cultural Politics of Left and Right. New York: Columbia University Press, 2006. Print. Burgio, Alberto. Gramsci storico. Una lettura dei Quaderni del carcere. Roma: Laterza, 2003. Print. Butler, Judith. The Psychic Life of Power: Theories in Subjection. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1997. Print. Cabral, Amilcar. “The Weapon of Theory.” Revolution in Guinea: An African People’s Struggle. London: Stage 1, 1974. 73–90. Print. Canal Feijoo, Bernardo. Los confines de occidente. Buenos Aires: Editorial Sur, 1954. Print. Césaire, Aimé. “A Distinguished Martinican Leaves the Communists.” The Crisis. 64.3 (March 1957): 154–156. Print. Chakrabarty, Dipesh. “Subaltern Histories and Post-Enlightenment Rationalism.” Habitations of Modernity: Essays in the Wake of Subaltern Studies. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002. 20–37. Print. Chalcraft, John. “Introduction.” Counterhegemony in the Colony and Postcolony. Ed. John Chalcraft and Yaseen Noorani. London: Palgrave, 2007. 1–19. Print. Chambers, Iain. Esercizi di potere. Gramsci, Said e il postcoloniale. Rome: Meltemi, 2006. Print. Chatterjee, Partha. Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse? London: Zed Books, 1986. Print. . The Nation and its Fragments: Colonial and Postcolonial Histories. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993. Print. . State and Politics in India. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1997. Print. . The Politics of the Governed: Reflections on Political Society in Most of the World. New York: Columbia University Press, 2004. Print. . “Conversation with Ramin Jahanbegloo.” India Revisited: Conversations on Continuity and Change. Ed. R Jahanbegloo. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008. 45–58. Print. . “Reflections on ‘Can the Subaltern Speak?’: Subaltern Studies after Spivak.” Can the Subaltern Speak? Reflections on the History of an Idea. Ed. Rosalind C. Morris. New York: Columbia University Press, 2010. 81–86. Print. Cheah, Pheng. Spectral Nationality: Passages of Freedom from Kant to Postcolonial Literatures of Liberation. New York: Columbia University Press, 2003. . “Crises of Money.” Positions: East Asia Culture Critique. 16.1 (Spring 2008): 189–219. Print. Chow, Rey. Ethics after Idealism: Theory, Culture, Ethnicity, Reading. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1998. Print. . The Age of the World Target: Self-Referentiality in War, Theory, and Comparative Work. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2006. Print. Chraibi, Driss. “Occidente estremo.” Voci dal Mediterraneo. Ed. Micaela Arcidiacona and Erminio Risso. Naples: Edizioni Magma, 1996. Print. Chumbita, Hugo. “Patria y revolución: la corriente nacionalista de izquierda.” El pensamiento alternativo en la argentina del siglo XX. Tomo II: Obrerismo, vanguardia, justicia social (1930–1960). Buenos Aires: Biblos, 2006. 77–100. Print. Colummi Cristiana. “Le riviste del disgelo: ‘Ragionamenti’ e ‘Opinione’ (1955–57).” Classe 17 (1980): 31–56. Print. Corvisieri, Silverio. Trotskij e il comunismo italiano. Roma: Samonà e Savelli, 1969. Print. Coutinho, Carlos Nelson. “A Presenca de Gramsci no Brazil.” Pauta 22 (2008): 37–44. Print. Croce, Benedetto. Review of Gramsci’s Lettere dal carcere. Quaderni della critica 3.8 ( July 1947): 86–88. Print.

240

Works Cited

Damiani, Matteo. “A Conversation with Jia Zhangke.” http://blog.sina.com.cn/s/ blog_444dd391010007ml.html. 6 December 2006. Web. 16 July 2010. Daniele, Chiara. Gramsci a Roma, Togliatti a Mosca. Il carteggio del 1926. Torino: Einaudi, 1999. Print. Davis, John A., ed. Gramsci and Italy’s Passive Revolution. London: Croom Helm, 1979. Print. De Clementi, Andreina. Amadeo Bordiga. Torino: Einaudi, 1971. Print. Deleuze, Gilles. Cinema 1. The Movement-Image. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam. London: Continuum, 1986. Print. Derrida, Jacques. “Faith and Knowledge: The Two Sources of ‘Religion’ at the Limits of Reason Alone.” Religion. Ed. Jacques Derrida and Gianni Vattimo. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1998. 1–78. Print. . “Autoimmunity: Real and Symbolic Suicides—a Dialogue with Jacques Derrida.” Giovanna Borradori, Philosophy in a Time of Terror: Dialogues with Jürgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2003. 85–136. Print. . Rogues: Two Essays on Reason. Trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press, 2005. Print. “Director Jia Zhangke. True to Life.” China.org.cn. 5 December 2003. Web. 10 July 2010. Dirlik, Arif. The Postcolonial Aura: Third World Criticism in the Age of Global Capitalism. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1997. Durkheim, Émile. Suicide. London: Routledge, 2002. Print. Fanon, Frantz. Black Skin, White Masks. [1952]. Trans. Charles Lam Markmann. London: Pluto Press, 1986. Print. . Les damnés de la terre. [1961]. With a Preface by Jean-Paul Sartre. Paris: Gallimard, 1991. Print. . The Wretched of the Earth. [1961]. Trans. Constance Farrington. London: Penguin, 2001. Print. . The Wretched of the Earth. [1961]. Trans. Richard Philcox. New York: Grove Press, 2004. Print. . Toward the African Revolution. Trans. Haakon Chevalier. London: Pelican, 1970. Print. Favero, Luigi and Graziano Tassello. Cent’anni di emigrazione italiana (1876–1976). Roma: Cser, 1978. Print. Fernández-Díaz, Osvaldo. “Gramsci y Mariátegui: frente a la ortodoxia.” Nueva Sociedad 115 (1991): 135–144. Print. Ferrari Bravo, Luciano and Alessandro Serafi ni. Stato e sottosviluppo. Il caso del mezzogiorno italiano. Milano: Feltrinelli, 1972. Print. Ferri, Franco, ed. Politica e storia in Gramsci: atti del Convegno internazionale di studi gramsciani: Firenze, 9–11 dicembre 1977. Roma: Editori Riuniti, Istituto Gramsci, 1977. Print. Fiore, Giuseppe. Antonio Gramsci: Life of a Revolutionary. Trans. Tom Nairne. London: New Left Books, 1970. Print. Flores, Galindo Alberto. “La agonía de Mariátegui.” Obras Completas II. Lima: Editorial Sur, 2005. 367–602. Print. Forgacs, David. “National-popular: Genealogy of a Concept.” The Cultural Studies Reader. Ed. Simon During. 2nd ed. London: Routledge, 1993. 209–219. Print. , ed. The Antonio Gramsci Reader: Selected Writings 1916–1935. New York: New York University Press, 2000. Print. Fowler, Geoffrey A. “In China, the Wealthy Show Off Wealth with Lavish Homes.” Wall Street Journal. 22 October 2007. Web. 14 July 2010. Francese, Joseph, ed. Perspectives on Gramsci: Politics, Culture and Social Theory. New York: Routledge, 2009. Print.

Works Cited

241

Frosini, Fabio. Da Gramsci a Marx. Ideologia, verità, politica. Roma: DeriveApprodi, 2009. Print. Gaines, Kevin. “E. Franklin Frazier’s Revenge: Anticolonialism, Non-Alignment, and Black Intellectuals’ Critiques of Western Culture.” American Literary History 17.3 (Fall 2005): 506–529. Print. Garcia Linera, Alvaro. “Catastrophic Equilibrium and Point of Bifurcation.” Bolivia Rising. December 2007. Web. November 11, 2011. Geertz, Clifford. Islam Observed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1968. Print. Gibson, Mary. “Before the Southern Question: ‘Native’ Ideas of Backwardness and Remedies in the Kingdom of Two Sicilies, 1815–1859.” Italy’s “Southern Question”: Orientalism in One Country. Ed. Jane Schneider. Oxford: Berg, 1998. 27–50. Print. Gikandi, Simon. “Globalizations and the Claims of Postcoloniality.” South Atlantic Quarterly 100.3 (2001): 627–658. Print. Giolitti Antonio. Riforme e rivoluzione. Torino: Einaudi, 1957. Print. Gordon, Lewis. Existentia Africana. Understanding African Existential Thought. London: Routledge, 2000. Print. Gramsci, Antonio. “Workers and Peasants.” Selections from Political Writings 1910– 1920. Ed. Quintin Hoare. Trans. John Mathews. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1977. 83–87. Print. . “Some Aspects of the Southern Question” (1926). The Antonio Gramsci Reader: Selected Writings 1916–1935. Ed. David Forgacs. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1999. 171–185. Print. . “Some Aspects of the Southern Question.” Selections from Political Writings, 1921–1926. Ed. and Trans. Quintin Hoare. London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1978. . “Alcuni temi sulla questione meridionale.” Lo Stato operaio, Rassegna di politica proletaria. Anno IV.1. Paris: Bureau d’Editions (1930): 9–26. Print. . “Benedetto Croce and His Concept of Liberty: Notes on Croce’s History of Europe (Storia d’Europa) taken from Prison Letters.” Science & Society 10.3 (1946), 283–292. . Lettere dal carcere. Torino: Einaudi, 1947. Print. . “Brief Notes on Machiavelli’s Politics” [“Note sul Machiavelli, sulla politica e sullo Stato moderno (1949)].” The Modern Prince, in Selections from the Prison Notebooks. . The Modern Prince and Other Writings. Trans. Louis Marks. New York: International Publishers, 1957. Print. . Lettere dal carcere. Eds. Sergio Caprioglio and Elsa Fubini. Torino: Einaudi, 1965. Print. . Selections from the Prison Notebooks. Ed. and trans. Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell Smith. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1971. . Letters from Prison. Selected, translated and introduced by Lynne Lawner. London: Cape, 1973. Print. . Scritti politici. 3 vols. Ed. Paolo Spriano. Roma: Editori riuniti, 1973. Print. . Quaderni del carcere. 4 Vols. Ed. Valentino Gerratana. Turin: Einaudi, 1975. Reprinted 2007. Print. . Selections from Political Writings, 1910–1920. Ed. Quintin Hoare. Trans. John Mathews. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1977. Print. . Selections from Political Writings, 1921–1926. Ed. and Trans. Quintin Hoare. London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1978. Print. . Cronache torinesi, 1913–1917. Ed. Sergio Caprioglio. Torino: Giulio Einaudi, 1980. Print. . “Un exámen del a situación italiana.” Escritos Políticos 1917–1933. Cuadernos de Pasado y Presente 54 (1981): 278–287. http://www.scribd.com/doc/27809452/ Gramsci-Escritos-politicos-1917–1933. Web. 16 July 2011.

242

Works Cited

. Selections from Cultural Writings. Eds David Forgacs and Geoffrey Nowell Smith. London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1985. . L’Ordine Nuovo 1919–20. Ed. Valentino Gerratana and Antonio A. Santucci. Torino: Einaudi, 1987. Print. . Letteratura e vita nazionale. Rome: Editori Riuniti, 1991. . Prison Notebooks. Ed. and trans. Joseph A. Buttigieg. 3 vols. New York: Columbia University Press, 1992; 1996; 2007. Print. . Letters from Prison. 2 vols. Ed. Frank Rosengarten. Trans. Raymond Rosenthal. New York: Columbia University Press, 1994. Print. . Pre-Prison Writings. Ed. Richard Bellamy. Trans. Virginia Cox. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. Print. . The Southern Question. Trans. Pasquale Verdicchio. Montreal: Guernica Editions, 2006. Print. Green, Marcus E. “Gramsci Cannot Speak: Presentations and Interpretations of Gramsci’s Concept of the Subaltern.” Rethinking Gramsci. Ed. Marcus E. Green. New York: Routledge, 2011. 68–89. Print. . “Introduction: Rethinking Marxism and Rethinking Gramsci.” Rethinking Gramsci. Ed. Marcus E. Green. New York: Routledge, 2011. 1–8. Print. , ed. Rethinking Gramsci. New York: Routledge, 2011. Print. Greer, Margaret, Walter Mignolo, and Maureen Quilligan, eds. Rereading the Black Legend: The Discourses of Religious and Racial Differences in the Renaissance Empires. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2007. Print. Grzinic, Marina. “Interview with Walter Mignolo: Delinking Epistemology from Capital and Pluriversality. A Conversation with Walter Mignolo.” Reartikulacija. Web. Guha, Ranajit. “Preface.” Subaltern Studies: Writings on South Asian History and Society. Ed. Ranajit Guha. Vol. 1. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1982. vii–viii. Print. . “On Some Aspects of the Historiography of Colonial India.” Subaltern Studies: Writings on South Asian History and Society. Vol. 1. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1982. 1–8. Print. , ed. Subaltern Studies: Writings on South Asian History and Society. Vol. 1. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1982. Print. . Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency in Colonial India . New Delhi, Oxford University Press, 1983. Print. . Dominance without Hegemony: History and Power in Colonial India. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998. Print. . “Gramsci in India: Homage to a Teacher.” Journal of Modern Italian Studies. 16.2 (2011): 288–295. Print. Guru, Gopal and Anuradha Chakravarty. “Who Are the Country’s Poor? Social Movement Politics and Dalit Poverty.” Social Movements in India: Poverty, Power and Politics. Ed. Raka Ray and Mary F. Katzenstein. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2005. 135–160. Print. Hall, Catherine, Civilizing Subjects: Metropole and Colony in the English Imagination 1830–1867. Oxford: Polity, 2002. Print. Hall, Stuart and Jacques Martin, eds. New Times. London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1991. Print. Hardt, Michael and Antonio Negri. Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000. Print. . Commonwealth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009. Print. Havis, Richard James. “Clarity Begins at Home.” South China Morning Post. 1 April 2005. 5. Print. Heidegger, Martin. “The Origin of the Work of Art.” Basic Writings. Ed. David Farrell Krell. New York: Harper & Row, 1976. 139–212. Print.

Works Cited

243

Henry, Paget. Caliban´s Reason: Introducing Caribbean Philosophy. London: Routledge, 2000. Print. Hernández Arregui, José. La formación de la conciencia nacional [1961]. Buenos Aires: Ediciones del Continente, 2004. Print. . Imperialismo y cultura [1964]. Buenos Aires: Ediciones del Continente, 2005. Print. . Nacionalismo y liberación [1969]. Buenos Aires: Ediciones del Continente, 2004. Print. Hobsbawm, E. J. Primitive Rebels: Studies in Archaic Forms of Social Movement in the 19th and 20th Centuries. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press, 1959. Print. . “Gramsci and Political Theory,” Marxism Today ( July 1977): 205–213. Print. Hooker, James R. Black Revolutionary: George Padmore’s Path from Communism to PanAfricanism. London: Pall Mall Press, 1967. Print. Hui, Wang. “Depoliticized Politics, Multiple Components of Hegemony, and the Eclipse of the Sixties.” Trans. Chris Connery. Inter-Asia Cultural Studies 7.4 (2006): 683–700. Print. Huntingdon, Samuel P. The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order. New York: Free Press, 2002. Print. Hussein, Abdirahman A. Edward Said: Criticism and Society. London: Verso, 2004. Print. Idahosa, Paul. “James and Fanon and the Problem of the Intelligentsia in Popular Organizations.” C. L. R. James: His Intellectual Legacies. Ed. Selwyn R. Cudjoe and William E. Cain. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1995. 388– 404. Print. Indra, C.T. “Introduction.” The Legend of Nandan. Trans. C.T. Indra. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2000. Print. Ives, Peter. Language and Hegemony in Gramsci. London: Pluto Press, 2004. Print. Jaffee, Valerie. “Bringing the World to the Nation: Jia Zhangke and the Legitimation of Chinese Underground Film.” Senses of Cinema (May 2004). http://archive. sensesofcinema.com/contents/04/32/chinese_underground_fi lm.html. 2 February 2010. . “An Interview with Jia Zhangke.” Senses of Cinema ( June 2004). http:// archive.sensesofcinema.com/contents/04/32/jia_zhangke.html. 5 February 2010. James, C. L. R. Beyond a Boundary. [1963]. London: Serpent’s Tail. 2000. Print. James, William. The Varieties of Religious Experience, Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin, 1983. Print. Jedlowski, Paolo. Il Racconto come Dimora. Turin: Bollati Boringhieri, 2009. Print. Jia, Zhangke. Jia Xiang: Jia Zhangke Dianying Shouji 1996–2008 [Jia’s thoughts: Jia Zhangke’s Film Notes 1996–2008]. Beijing: Peking University Press, 2009. . “Jia Zhangke: Zai ‘Zhantai’ shang dengdai” [贾樟柯:在“站台”上等待, “Jia Zhangke: Waiting at the ‘Platform’: A Dialogue with Cheng Qingsong and Huang Ou”]. Wo de sheyingji bu sahuang: Xianfeng dianying ren dang’an, shenyu 1961–1970 [My Camera Doesn’t Lie: Files of Avant-garde Chinese Filmmakers, Born Between 1961 and 1970]. Ed. Cheng Qingsong and Huang Ou. Beijing: China Friendship Press, 2002. 335–379. Print. , director. The World. Celluloid Dreams. 2004. Film. . “Capturing a Transforming Reality.” Speaking in Images: Interviews with Contemporary Chinese Filmmakers. Ed. Michael Berry. New York: Columbia University Press, 2005. 182–206. Print. , director. Still Life. Xstream Pictures, 2006. Film. Joseph, Jonathan. “Lenin’s Concept of Hegemony.” What Next Journal. 1997. Web. 3 May 2011.

244

Works Cited

Kaviraj, Sudipta,. “A Critique of the Passive Revolution.” Economic and Political Weekly 23.45–7 (1988): 2429–2444. Print. Kaviraj, Sudipta. “In Search of Civil Society.” Civil Society: History and Possibilities. Ed. Sudipta Kaviraj and Sunil Khilnani. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001: 287–323. Print. Kiernan, V. G. “Antonio Gramsci and the Other Continents.” Imperialism and Its Contradictions. Ed. and intro. Harvey J. Kaye. New York: Routledge, 1995. 171–190. Print. Kington, Tom. “Recruited by MI5: The Name’s Mussolini. Benito Mussolini.” The Guardian 13 October 2009. Web. 15 May 2011. Kothari, Rajni. Politics and the People: In Search of a Humane Idea. 2 Vols. Delhi: Ajanta, 1989. Print. Kusch, Rodolfo. Indigenous and Popular Thinking in America. 1970. Trans. María Lugones and Joshua Price. Intro. Walter Mignolo. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2010. Print. Laclau, Ernesto. On Populist Reason. London: Verso, 2005. Print. Latouche, Serge. The Westernisation of the World: Significance, Scope and Limits of the Drive towards Global Uniformity. Oxford: Polity, 1996. Print. Latour, Bruno. Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies. Trans. Catherine Porter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999. Print. Lazreg, Marnia. The Eloquence of Silence: Algerian Women in Question. London: Routledge, 1994. Print. LeVine, Mark and Armando Salvatore. “Socio-Religious and the Transformation of ‘Common Sense’ into the Politics of ‘Common Good.’” Religion, Social Practice, and Contested Hegemonies. Reconstructing the Public Sphere in Muslim Majority Societies. Ed. Armando Salvatore and Mark LeVine. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005. 29–56. Print. Levy, Carl. Gramsci and the Anarchists. Oxford: Berg, 1999. Print. . “Currents of Italian Syndicalism Before 1926.” International Review of Social History 45.2 (2000): 209–250. Print. . “‘Sovversivismo’: The Radical Political Culture of Otherness in Liberal Italy.” Journal of Political Ideologies 12.2 (2007): 147–161. Print. Liguori, Guido. Gramsci conteso. Storia di un dibattito 1922–1996. Roma: Editori Riuniti, 1996. Print. . Sentieri gramsciani. Roma: Carocci, 2006. Print. Liguori, Guido and Voza, Pasquale, eds. Dizionario gramsciano. 1926–1937. Roma: Carocci, 2009. Print. Liu, Joey. “Welcome to the Reel World.” South China Morning Post. 2 November 2004. 5. Print. Lo Piparo, Franco. “Gramsci and Wittgenstein. An Intriguing Connection.” Perspectives on Language Use and Pragmatic: A Volume in Memory of Sorin Stati. Ed. A. Capone. München: Lincom Europa, 2010. 285–319. Print. Lo Piparo, Franco. Lingua, intellettuali, egemonia. Bari—Roma: Laterza, 1979. Print. Lombardo Radice, Lucio and Carbone Giuseppe. Vita di Antonio Gramsci. Roma: Edizioni di cultura sociale, 1952. Print. Loomba, Ania et al., eds. Postcolonial Studies and Beyond. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2005. Print. Lussana, Fiamma. “L’edizione critica, le traduzioni e la diffusione di Gramsci nel mondo.” Studi storici: rivista trimestrale dell’Istituto Gramsci 4 (1997): 1051–1086. Print. Macey, David. Frantz Fanon: A Life. New York: Picador, 2000. Print. Maldonado-Torres, Nelson. “On the Coloniality of Being: Contributions to the Development of a Concept.” Cultural Studies 21.2–3 (March–May 2007): 240–270. Print.

Works Cited

245

Mallavarapu, Srikanth and Amit Prasad. “Facts, Fetishes, and the Parliament of Things: Is there Any Space for Critique?” Social Epistemology 20.2 (April–June 2006): 185–199. Print. Mariátegui, José Carlos, La escena contemporánea. 1925. Lima: Amanta, 1985. Print. . Seven Interpretive Essays on Peruvian Reality. Trans. Jorge Basadre. Austin: The University of Texas Press, 1971. Print. Marrouchi, Mustapha. Edward Said at the Limits. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2004. Print. Marx, Karl. Scritti inediti di economia politica. Roma: Editori Riuniti, 1963. Print. . Lineamenti fondamentali della critica dell’economia politica. 2 vols. Firenze: La Nuova Italia, 1968–1970. Print. . Capital. Vol. 1. Trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling. Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1968. Print. . Capital. A Critique of Political Economy. Vol 1. Trans. Ben Fowkes. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1976. Print. . Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right. Introduction. Early Writings. Trans. Rodney Livingstone and Gregor Benton. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1975. 245–255. Print. . “Zur Kritik der Hegel’schen Rechts-Philosophie. Einleitung. Werke, Artikel, Entwürfe, März 1843 bis August 1844, Karl Marx-Friedrich Engels Gesamtausgabe. Ed. Institut für Marxismus-Leninismus, Erste Abteilung. Band 2. Berlin: Dietz, 1982. Print. . “Towards a Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right: Introduction.” Selected Writings. Ed. Lawrence H. Simon. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1994. 27–39. Print. Mattone, Antonello. Velio Spano: vita di un rivoluzionario di professione. Cagliari: Edizioni Della Torre, 1978. Print. Mbembe, Achille. “At the Edge of the World: Boundaries, Territory, and Sovereignty in Africa.” Globalization. Ed. Arjun Appaduari. Durham, NC: Duke University Press 2001. 22–51. Print. McGrath, Jason. Postsocialist Modernity: Chinese Cinema, Literature, and Criticism in the Market Age. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press, 2008. Print. McNally, Mark and John Schwarzmantel, eds. Gramsci and Global Politics: Hegemony and Resistance. New York: Routledge, 2009. Print. Merli, Stefano. “I nostri conti con la teoria della ‘rivoluzione senza rivoluzione’ di Gramsci.” Giovane Critica 17 (1967). Print. Mezzadra, Sandro. Diritto di fuga, migranti, cittadinanza, globalizzazione. Verona: Ombre corte, 2006. Print. Menon, Dilip. Caste, Nationalism, and Communism in South India: Malabar 1900–1948. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. Print. Mignolo, Walter D. Local Histories/Global Designs. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000. Print. . “Geopolitics of Knowledge and the Colonial Difference.” South Atlantic Quarterly 101.1 (2002): 57–96. Print. . The Idea of Latin America. London: Blackwell, 2005. Print. . “On Subaltern and Other Agencies.” Postcolonial Studies 8.4 (2005): 381–407. Print. . “I Am Where I Think.” The Creolization of Theory. Ed. Shu-mei Shi and Francoise Lionnet. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2011. 159–192. Print. Miguel, Yolanda Martínez-San. “Postcolonialism.” Social Text 27.3 (2009): 188– 193. Print. Mitchell, W. J. T. “The Panic of the Visual: A Conversation with Edward Said.” Edward Said and the Work of the Critic: Speaking truth to Power. Ed. Paul A. Bové. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2000. 31–50. Print.

246

Works Cited

Mufti, Aamir R. “Auerbach in Istanbul: Edward Said, Secular Criticism, and the Question of Minority Culture.” Critical Inquiry 25.1 (1998): 95–125. Print. . Enlightenment in the Colony: The Jewish Question and the Crisis of Postcolonial Culture. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007. Print. Nagaraj, D. R. The Flaming Feet: A Study of the Dalit Movement. Bangalore, India: South Forum Press, 1993. Print. . Introduction to U. R. Anantha Murthy, Bharathipura. New Delhi: Macmillan India, 1996. Print. Nandy, Ashis. “Conversation with Ramin Jahanbegloo: Gandhi and the Indian Identity.” India Revisited. Conversations on Continuity and Change. Ed. R. Jahanbegloo. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008. 51–58. Print. Negri Antonio. Marx Beyond Marx. Lessons on the Grundrisse [1978]. London: Pluto Press, 1991. Print. Ngugi Wa Thiong’o. Moving the Centre: The Struggle for Cultural Freedoms. Portsmouth, NH: Heinemann, 1993. Print. Nwafor, Azinna. “Introduction.” George Padmore. Pan-Africanism or Communism. New York: Doubleday, 1971. xxv–xlii. Print. O’Brien, Susie and Imre Szeman. “Introduction: The Globalization of Fiction/the Fiction of Globalization.” South Atlantic Quarterly 100.3 (2001): 603–626. Print. Omvedt, Gail. Reinventing Revolution: New Social Movements and the Socialist Tradition in India. New York: M. E. Sharpe, 1993. Print. . Ambedkar: Towards an Enlightened India. New Delhi: Penguin/Viking, 2004. Print. Osorio, Carlos and Mariana Enamoneta, eds. Operación Condor. The National Security Archive. 21 December 2007. Web. 16 July 2011. Padmore, George. Pan-Africanism or Communism. New York: Doubleday, 1971. Print. Paggi, Leonardo. Gramsci e il moderno principe: nella crisi del socialismo italiano. Roma: Editori Riuniti, 1970. Print. Palermo, Zulma. Pensamiento Argentino y opción descolonial, with a preface by Walter Mignolo. Buenos Aires: Editorial del Signo y Duke University Globalization and the Humanities Project, 2010. Print. Pandey, Gyanendra. “Introduction: The Subaltern as Subaltern Citizen.” Subaltern Citizens and their Histories. Ed. Gyanendra Pandey. New York: Routledge, 2009. 1–12. Print. Pandian, M. S. S. Council for the Development of Social Science Research in Africa. “One Step Outside Modernity: Caste, Identity Politics and Public Sphere.” Sephis-Codesria, Amsterdam/Dakar, 2002. Lecture. Parker, Andrew. “Mimesis and the Division of Labor: Editor’s Introduction.” Jacques Ranciere, The Philosopher and His Poor. Ed. and trans. Andrew Parker. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2004. ix–xxiii. Print. Parthasarathy, Indira. The Legend of Nandan. 1978. Trans. C. T. Indra. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2000. Print. Pasolini, Pierpaolo, director. The Gospel According to Saint Matthew. Titanus Distribuzione Spa, 1964. Film. Pawde, Kumud. “The Story of my Sanskrit.” Poisoned Bread: Translations from Modern Marathi Literature . Ed. and trans. Priya Adarkar and Arjun Dangle. Hyderabad: Orient Longman, 1993: 96–106. Print. Pickowicz, Paul G. “Social and Political Dynamics of Underground Filmmaking in China.” From Underground to Independent: Alternative Film Culture in Contemporary China. Ed. Paul G. Pickowicz and Yingjin Zhang. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2006.1–22. Print. Polsgrove, Carol. Ending British Rule in Africa: Writers in a Common Cause. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press, 2009. Print.

Works Cited

247

Portantiero, Juan Carlos. Los usos de Gramsci. Buenos Aires: Folios Ediciones, 1983. Print. Posnock, Ross. “How It Feels to Be a Problem: Du Bois, Fanon, and the ‘Impossible Life’ of the Black Intellectual.” Critical Inquiry 23 (Winter 1997): 323–349. Print. Prakash, Gyan. “Can the ‘Subaltern’ Ride? A Reply to O’Hanlon and Washbrook.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 34 (1992): 168–184. Print. Quijano, Anibal. Prólogo to Siete ensayos de interpretación de la realidad Peruana. Caracas: Biblioteca Ayacucho, 1979. Print. . “Colonialidad y Modernidad/Racionalidad.”Heraclio Bonilla (comp.). Los Conquistados. 1492 y la población indígena de las Américas. Bogotá: FLACSO-Tercer Mundo. 1992. Print. . “Coloniality of Power, Eurocentrism, and Latin America”. Nepantla: Views from South 1.3 (2000): 533–580. Print. .“Coloniality and Modernity/Rationality.” Cultural Studies 21.2 (2007): 168–178. Print. Racine, Jean-Luc and Josiane Racine. “Dalit Identities and the Dialectics of Oppression and Emancipation in a Changing India: The Tamil Case and Beyond.” Comparative Studies of South Asia, Africa and the Middle East 18.1 (1998): 5–19. Print. Ranciere, Jacques. The Philosopher and his Poor. Trans., ed., and intro. Andrew Parker. Durham NC: Duke University Press, 2004. Print. Rao, Anupama. The Caste Question: Dalits and the Politics of Modern India. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2009. Print. Reinaga, Fausto. La revolución India. La Paz: Ediciones Partido Indio de Bolivia, 1969. Print. . La revolución India y Occidente. Bolivia: Editorial Renovación, 1974. Print. Riall, Lucy. “The Nation and the South in the Work of Rosario Romeo: A Debate Between John Dickie, Lucy Riall and Giuseppe Galasso.” Modern Italy 7.1 (2002): 59–84. Print. Riddell, John, ed. The Communist International in Lenin’s Time. To See the Dawn. Baku, 1920—First Congress of the Peoples of the East. New York: Pathfi nder Press, 1993. Print. . The Communist International in Lenin’s Time. Workers of the World and Oppressed Peoples, Unite! Proceedings and Documents of the Second Congress, 1920. 2 vols. New York: Pathfi nder Press, 1991. Print. Righi, Maria Luisa, ed. Gramsci nel mondo. Atti del convegno internazionale di studi gramsciani. Roma: Fondazione Istituto Gramsci, 1995. Print. Robbins, Bruce. “Secularism, Elitism, Progress, and Other Transgressions: On. Edward Said’s ‘Voyage In.’” Social Text 40 (1994): 25–37. Print. Roberts, David D. The Syndicalist Tradition and Italian Fascism. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1979. Print. Robertson, Roland. Globalization: Social Theory and Global Culture. London: Sage, 1992. Print. Robinson, Cedric. Black Marxism: The Making of the Black Radical Tradition [1983]. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 2000. Print. Rosengarten, Frank. “The Contemporary Relevance of Gramsci’s Views on the ‘Southern Question.’” Perspectives on Gramsci: Politics, Culture and Social Theory. Ed. Joseph Francese. New York: Routledge, 2009. 134–144. Print. Rushdie, Salman. Midnight’s Children [1981]. London: Penguin, 1991. Print. Said, Edward. Orientalism: Western Representations of the Orient [1978]. London: Penguin, 2003. Print. . The World, the Text, and the Critic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1983. Print. . Culture and Imperialism. London: Vintage, 1994. Print.

248

Works Cited

. Covering Islam. How the Media and the Experts Determine How We See the Rest of the World. London: Vintage, 1997. Print. Salvatore, Armando. “Europa e mondo islamico: un dialogo mediterraneo?” L’alternativa mediterranea. Ed. Franco Cassano and Danilo Zolo. Milan: Feltrinelli, 2007. Print. Salvatore, Armando and Mark LeVine. “Introduction. Reconstructing the Public Sphere in Muslim Majority Societies.” Religion, Social Practice, and Contested Hegemonies. Reconstructing the Public Sphere in Muslim Majority Societies. Ed. Armando Salvatore and Mark LeVine, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005. 1–25. Print. San Juan, Jr., Epifanio. “Antonio Gramsci’s Theory of the National-Popular and Socialist Revolution in the Philippines.” Perspectives on Gramsci: Politics, Culture and Social Theory. Ed. Joseph Francese. New York: Routledge, 2009. 163–185. Print. Santana, Joaquin. “Gramsci y Mariátegui.” Archivo Chile. http://www.archivochile. com/Ideas_Autores/gramscia/s/gramscisobre0005.pdf. 16 July 2011. Web. Santucci Antonio, ed. Gramsci in Europa e in America. Roma—Bari: Laterza, 1995. Print. Sanyal, Kalyan. Rethinking Capitalist Development: Primitive Accumulation, Governmentality and Post-Colonial Capitalism. New Delhi: Routledge, 2007. Print. Schirru, Giancarlo, ed. Gramsci, le culture, il mondo. Roma: Viella, 2009. Print. Schneider, Jane, ed. Italy’s “Southern Question:” Orientalism in One Country. Oxford: Berg, 1998. Print. Schneider, Jane. “Introduction: The Dynamics of Neo-Orientalism in Italy (1848– 1995)”. Italy’s “Southern Question”: Orientalism in One Country. Ed. Jane Schneider. Oxford: Berg, 1998. 1–23. Print. Secco, Lincoln. Gramsci e o Brasil. Recepção e difusão de suas idria. Cortez: São Paulo, 2002. Print. Sechi, Salvatore, “Le ‘lettere dal carcere’ e la politica culturale del Pci (1965).” Movimento operaio e storiografia marxista. Bari: De Donato, 1974. Print. Sekyi-Otu, Ato. Fanon’s Dialectic of Experience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996.Print. Shih, Alice. “Interview. Jia Zhangke: Life and Times Beyond the World.” Cineaction 68 (Winter 2006): 53–58. Print. Shobhi, Prithvi Datta Chandra. “Introduction: Khadgavagali Kavya (Let Poetry Become [a] Sword).” In D. R. Nagaraj, The Flaming Feet and Other Essays: the Dalit Movement in India. Delhi: Permanent Black, 2010. 1–18. Print. Smith, Tony. “The Underdevelopment of Development Literature: The Case of Dependency Theory.” World Politics 31–32 (1979): 247–288. Print. Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty. “Can the Subaltern Speak? Speculations on Widow Sacrifice.” Wedge 7–8 (1985): 120–130. Print. . “Subaltern Studies: Deconstructing Historiography.” Subaltern Studies: Writings on South Asian History and Society. Vol. 4. Ed. Ranajit Guha. New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1985. 330–363. Print. . “Can the Subaltern Speak?” Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture. Ed. Cary Nelson and Lawrence Grossberg. Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 1988. 271–313. Print. . “Subaltern Studies: Deconstructing Historiography.” Selected Subaltern Studies. Ed. Ranajit Guha and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. New York: Oxford University Press, 1988. 3–34. Print. . Translator’s Preface. Mahasweta Devi, Imaginary Maps. Trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. London: Routledge, 1995. xxiii–xxx. Print. . Afterword. Mahasweta Devi, Imaginary Maps. Trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. London: Routledge, 1995. 197–205. . A Critique of Postcolonial Reason: Towards a History of the Vanishing Present, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999. Print.

Works Cited

249

. “In Response: Looking Back Looking Forward.” Can the Subaltern Speak? Reflections on the History of an Idea. Ed. Rosalind C. Morris. New York: Columbia University Press, 2010. 227–236. Print. Spriano Paolo. Storia del partito comunista italiano. 5 vols. Torino: Einaudi, 1967–1975. Print. Srinivas, M. N. Social Change in Modern India. New Delhi: Orient Longman, 1972. Print. Steedman, Carolyn, Master and Slave: Love and Labour in the English Industrial Age. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007. Print. Sternhell, Zeev, Mario Sznajder, and Maia Asheri. The Birth of Fascist Ideology: From Cultural Rebellion to Political Revolution. Trans. David Maisel. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994. Print. Tapia, Luis. La producción del conocimiento local. Historia y política en la obra de Zavaleta Mercado. La Paz: Muela del Diablo, 2002. Print. Taylor, Charles. A Secular Age. Cambridge, MA: Belknap, 2007. Teo, Stephen. “Cinema with an Accent: Interview with Jia Zhangke, director of Platform.” Senses of Cinema. June 2001. Web. 5 February 2010. Thomas, Peter. The Gramscian Moment: Philosophy, Hegemony and Marxism. Leiden: Brill, 2009. Print. Togliatti, Palmiro. Trenta anni di vita e lotte del Pci. Roma: Quaderni di Rinascita, 1952. Print. . Gramsci. Roma: Editori Riuniti, 1967. Print. . Lezioni sul fascismo. Roma: Editori Riuniti, 1970. Print. Tronti, Mario. Operai e capitale. 1966. Torino: Einaudi, 1971. Print. . “Tra materialismo dialettico e fi losofia della prassi. Gramsci e Labriola.” La città futura. Saggi sulla figura e il pensiero di Antonio Gramsci. Ed. Alberto Caracciolo and Gianni Scalia. Milano: Feltrinelli, 1959. 141–162. Print. Trotta, Giuseppe and Fabio Milana. L’operaismo degli anni Sessanta. Da ‘Quaderni rossi’ a ‘Classe operaia’. Intro. M. Tronti. Roma: DeriveApprodi, 2008. Print. Vacca, Giuseppe. Togliatti sconosciuto. Roma: L’Unità, 1994. Print. Vacca, Giuseppe, Paolo Capuzzo, and Giancarlo, Schirru. Studi gramsciani nel mondo: gli studi culturali. Bologna: Il Mulino, 2008. Print. Vázquez-Arroyo, Antonio Y. “Agonized Liberalism: The Liberal Theory of William E. Connolly.” Radical Philosophy 127 (September–October 2004): 8–20. Villari, Rosario, ed. Il sud nella storia d’Italia: antologia della questione meridionale. Bari: Laterza, 1961. Print. Viswanathan, Gauri. “Said, Religion, and Secular Criticism.” Waiting for the Barbarians: A Tribute to Edward Said. Ed. Müge Gürsoy Sökmen and Basak Ertür, London: Verso, 2008. Print. Wang, Yiman. “The Amateur’s Lightning Rod: DV Documentary in Postsocialist China.” Film Quarterly 58.4 (Summer 2005): 16–26. Print. Williams, Raymond. Marxism and Literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977. Print. . Politics and Letters: Interviews with New Left Review. London: New Left Books, 1979. Print. “The World Park.” Beijing World Park. Web. 14 July 2010. Wright, Steve. Storming Heaven. Class Composition and Struggle in Italian Autonomist Marxism. London: Pluto Press, 2002. Print. Yaeger, Patricia. “Editor’s Column: The End of Postcolonial Theory?” PMLA 122.3 (2007): 633–651. Print. Young, Robert. Postcolonialism: An Historical Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell, 2001. Print. . White Mythologies: Writing History and the West. London: Routledge, 2004. Print.

250

Works Cited

. “Fanon and the Turn to Armed Struggle in Africa.” Wasafiri 44 (Spring 2005): 33–41. Print. Yingjin, Zhang. “My Camera Doesn’t Lie? Truth, Subjectivity, and Audience in Chinese Independent Film and Video.” From Underground to Independent: Alternative Film Culture in Contemporary China. Ed. Paul G. Pickowicz and Yingjin Zhang. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2006. 23–45. Print.

Index

A agency 29, 61, 70, 166, 177, 183, 186, 224, 225 Algeria 56, 76–7, 102 Althusser, Louis 107, 193, 205 Ambedkar, B.R. 175–76, 185, 188n9, 189n27 Anantha Murthy, U.R. 165, 167, 17073, 175, 176, 179, 180, 188n11, 188n12, 189n16 Anidjar, Gil 103–104, 105, 115, Appadurai, Arjun 80 Arac, Jonathan 97n3 Arendt, Hannah 154 Aricó, José 204, 205, 206 Asad, Talal 108, 111, 112, 113, 115, 116

citizen/citizenship 13, 81, 108, 109, 113, 114, 115, 118n11, 127, 130, 135, 166, 222, 225 civil society 3, 4, 7, 8, 47, 58, 87, 97n7, 115, 119, 127–128, 130, 134, 135–137, 143, 146, 166, 179, 207, 224 Croce, Benedetto 35, 36, 39, 40, 44, 45, 47, 52n9, 60–61, 95, 106

D decoloniality 191, 197 Deleuze, Gilles 109, 117n5 Derrida, Jacques 109, 161, 229 Du Bois, W.E.B. 55, 62, 66, 67, 231, exile 18, 34, 62, 77, 92,

F

bhakti 169, 181, 182–183 “black Marxism” 70 Bolshevik 37, 38, 50, 211 Bordiga, Amadeo 20–21, 36, 38, 51n7 Brennan, Timothy 2, 7, 82, 97n13, 176, 185

Fanon, Franz 2, 3, 6, 12, 55–7, 60, 62, 63–64, 68, 70, 71–74, 75, 76, 77, 78, 78n2, 78n3, 78n6, 79n12, 137, 174, 175, 176, 177, 178, 189n20, 203, 204, 208–209, 213, 214, 215 Fascist/Fascism 12, 20, 24, 25, 36, 38, 40, 51n2, 56, 103, Foucault, Michel 84, 102, 109

C

G

Cabral, Amilcar 70, 73, 137 “Can the Subaltern Speak?” 11, 13, 31, 32, 188n13, 223, 231, 232 caste 13, 32n7, 90, 122, 134, 165–171, 173–176, 178, 179–186, 188n9, 188n11, 189n22, 189n25 Catholic Church 4, 58, 60, 102, 104, 168–169, 187n7 Chakrabarty, Dipesh 176, 185, 222 Chatterjee, Partha 12, 14n4, 79n11, 83, 166, 187n5, 207, 216n24

Gandhi, M. K. 3–4, 14n4, 49, 121, 171, 175, 176, 187n2, 189n27, 209, 216n25 Geertz, Clifford 103, 108 Gobetti, Piero 35, 47, 95 Guha, Ranajit 7, 9–11, 31, 119, 121, 132, 209, 216n23, 216n25, 222, 224, 226

B

H Hegel, G.W.F. 91, 141, 145, 201, 204, 207, 223

252

Index

hegemony 5, 6, 7–8, 10, 11, 19, 24, 28, 32, 39, 41, 43, 47, 49, 50, 51, 53n30, 58, 60–62, 63–64, 70, 75, 76, 77, 79n9, 82, 84, 85, 86, 93, 97n7, 97n8, 101, 102, 103, 104, 105, 107, 113, 117, 119, 125, 127, 135, 136, 140, 143, 145, 146, 165, 166, 167, 168, 170, 171, 183, 186, 197, 200, 203, 205, 208, 212, 225, 229 Heidegger, Martin 117, 154, 185 Hobsbawm, Eric 168, 177

nationalism 19, 22, 25, 28, 41, 55, 56, 57, 62, 65, 67, 78n5, 81, 85, 96 national-popular 7, 12, 58, 60, 72, 73, 88, 89, 91, 97n9, 97n11, 146, 147, 180, 185, 206 Naxalite 10, 30 Negri, Antonio 42, 43, 80, 81–82, 109 Négritude 55–56, 71–73, 76, 77, 78n2, Nehru, Jawaharlal 69, 166, 169, 209 Nietzsche, Friedrich 107, 111, 228

I

organic/organicity 10, 45, 58, 59, 64, 70, 72, 74, 90, 106, 107, 122, 140, 145, 148, 150, 152, 172, 179, 180, 183, 229 definition of 139 organic intellectual 11, 12, 13, 29, 47, 56, 57, 58, 60, 61, 62, 67, 68, 71, 75, 77, 137, 138, 145, 146, 149, 151, 158, 161, 165, 178, 180, 181, 182, 184, 185, 199, 214, 228–230; definition and types of 140–144

Italian Communist Party 34, 35, 36, 37, 40, 42, 43, 51n6, 52n9, 52n11, 57, 199

J James, C.L.R. 69, 70, 78n3, 213

K Kant, Immanuel 201, 204 Kaviraj, Sudipta 125, 167

L Latour, Bruno 178, 188n11 Lenin, V.I. 5, 18, 20, 37, 50, 51n7, 61, 70, 121, 191, 211, 226 Luxemburg, Rosa 36, 227, 230

M Mariátegui, José Carlos 17, 24, 191, 194–202, 205, 208, 209, 215n1, 216n18, 216n24, 216n26 Marx, Karl 24, 39, 44, 45, 46, 53n26, 57, 82, 96n2, 116, 119, 120, 121, 122, 139, 141–142, 145, 154, 169, 170, 178, 188n13, 191, 210, 212, 216n25, 223, 229 Marxism 1, 9, 18, 19, 23, 31, 42, 44, 60–61, 62, 65, 69, 70, 91, 211–12, 213, 214 Mazzini, Giuseppe 22 modernity 2, 12, 26, 41, 44, 49, 52n9, 102, 103, 104, 105, 108, 110, 111, 112–113, 114, 115, 116, 117, 118n10, 119, 123, 126, 134, 167, 180, 188n11, 192, 196, 208, 209, 214 Mussolini, Benito 20, 25, 26, 27, 28, 38, 197, 230

N Nandy, Ashis 216n25

O

P Padmore, George 12, 55–57, 62, 64, 70, 77, 78, 79n13 Parthasarathy, Indira 165, 170, 181–187, 189n18, 189n25 passive revolution 63, 79n11, 82, 89, 125, 126, 127, 128, 134, 135, 136, 145 political society 58, 127, 128, 130–131, 133–136, 205

R religion 12, 61, 75, 77, 85, 97n9, 101, 102–105, 107–108, 110–114, 117, 118n10, 168–69, 171, 178, 181, 183, 200, 213, 226, 227 Risorgimento 6, 40, 63, 67, 77, 89, 90, 186 Rosa, Asor 40–41, 43, 44, 53n23, Russian Revolution 20, 22, 50

S Said, Edward W. 2, 7–9, 12, 18–19, 23, 33n10, 48, 82–83, 84–87, 90, 91, 92, 93–96, 97n3, 97n4, 97n8, 97n13, 97n14, 102, 103, 106, 112, 113, 116, 221 Sanyal, Kalyan 122–24 Sardinia 1, 12, 17–18, 22, 23, 26, 27–28, 32n3, 33n15, 191, 194

Index secularism 12, 85, 86, 88, 90, 94, 97n5, 102, 103, 104, 105, 107, 110, 111–114, 117, 118n10, 226, 227 “Southern Question, the” 4–6, 11, 12, 22, 23–24, 26, 28–30, 42, 43, 49, 94, 109, 188n14, 193, 194, 195–197, 199, 200–201, 210 Stalin, Joseph 32n6, 35, 37, 38 subaltern/subalternity 1, 2, 7, 9–12, 13, 18, 21, 23, 29–32, 33n17, 41, 42, 49–50, 53n22, 56, 57, 58, 64, 65, 76, 82, 91, 104, 106, 109, 110, 115, 119, 132, 143, 145, 166, 168, 176–180, 185, 186–87, 188n13, 188n15, 194, 197, 208, 211, 221–228, 230, 232 Subaltern Studies 7, 9–11, 12, 30, 31, 43, 83, 119, 145, 176, 186, 207, 208–209, 210, 216n23, 217n27, 221, 222, 223, 226

T Tamilnadu 165, 170

253

Togliatti, Palmiro. 34–40, 51n1, 52n8, 52n11, 52n14, 53n29, 222, 229 untouchable 165, 166–168, 170, 171–176, 178, 179, 181–186, 188n9, 188n12, 189n17, 189n25, 189n27

V Viswanathan, Gauri, 102–03

W Weber, Max 117 West Bengal 120, 222, 228, Williams, Raymond 7, 62, 84, 87, 97n6, 221

X Xiaoping, Deng 155

Z Zedong, Mao 24, 30, 121 Zhangke, Jia 13, 138, 144, 146–149, 150–152, 158, 161, 163n19, 163n20