219 74 11MB
English Pages [233] Year 1987
Ins and Outs of the Predication
Functional Grammar Series This series comprises monographs and collections written in the framework of Functional Grammar. The aim is to seek explanations for a wide variety of linguistic phenomena, both language specific and cross-linguistic, in terms of the conditions under which and the purposes for which language is used. Editors:
A. Machtelt Bolkestein Simon C. Dik Casper de Groot J. Lachlan Mackenzie General address: Institute for General Linguistics Functional Grammar Spuistraat 210 NL-1012 VT Amsterdam The Netherlands
Other books in this series: 1. A.M. Bolkestein, C. de Groot and J.L. Mackenzie (eds.) Syntax and Pragmatics in Functional Grammar 2. A. M. Bolkestein, C. de Groot and J.L. Mackenzie (eds.) Predicates and Terms in Functional Grammar 3. Michael Hannay English Existentials in Functional Grammar 4. Josine A. Lalleman Dutch Language Proficiency of Turkish Children born in the Netherlands 5. Jan Nuyts and Georges de Schutter (eds.) Getting One's Words into Line
Other studies on Functional Grammar include S.C. Dik, Functional Grammar (1978), T. Hoekstra et al. (eds.), Perspectives on Functional Grammar (1981), S.C. Dik (ed.). Advances in Functional Grammar (1983). All published by FORIS PUBLICATIONS.
Ins and Outs of the Predication Johan van der Auwera Louis Goossens (eds.)
1987 FORIS PUBLICATIONS Dordrecht - Holland/Providence Rl - USA
Published
by:
Foris Publications Holland P.O. Box 509 3300 A M Dordrecht, The Netherlands Sole distributor
for the U.S.A. and
Canada:
Foris Publications USA, Inc. P.O. Box 5904 Providence Rl 02903 U.S.A. Sole distributor
for
Japan:
Sanseido Book Store, Ltd. 1-1, Kanda-jimbocho-cho Chiyoda-ku Tokyo 101, Japan
CIP-DATA
Ins Ins and Outs of the Predication / Johan van der Auwera and Louis Goossens (eds.). Dordrecht [etc.]: Foris. - (Functional Grammar Series; 6) With ref. ISBN 90-6765-348-9 SISO 805.1 UDC 801.5 Subject heading: functional grammar
ISBN 90 6765 348 9 ® 1987 Foris Publications - Dordrecht No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopy, recording, or any information storage and retrieval system, without permission from the copyright owner. Printed in the Netherlands by ICG Printing, Dordrecht.
Preface
Together with its twin volume (Getting one's words into line, eds. G. de Schutter and J. Nuyts), this collection offers a selection of papers from the Second International Conference on Functional Grammar, which was held at the University of Antwerp (UIA), from 1 to 5 September 1986. It bears witness that the framework set up under the name functional Grammar (FG) by Simon Dik (1978) continues to stimulate linguistic research on a wide range of topics and language data. While elaborating, refining, or challenging the theory of FG, these contributions, we think, will deepen our insight into the workings and organization of human language in several respects. The constitution of predications can be viewed as the central concern of FG. In a way, consequently, the title of this volume might be taken to cover about everything in the model. As it happens, the division of labour between the Word Order collection and this one excludes specific word order papers from our scope. Othe rwise, there is indeed considerable variation in the topics under discussion, which is the main reason why we have opted for an alphabetical arrangement according to the authors' second names. As will appear from the following survey, however, at least some of the contributions are concerned with issues that to some extent permit common denominators. At the same time it will emerge, we think, that there is some justification for saying that they cover some ins and certain outs of the predication. Clearly concerned with an aspect of the inside of the predication is S. Dik's Typology of Entities, which helps us to understand the 'coding' and 'behavioral' properties of terms. Entities are primarily viewed as ensembles, which at a more specific level encompass sets and masses; individuals are argued to be singleton sets. So-called classifier languages can leave ensembles undifferentiated for set/mass; the use of sortal classifiers result in set- or mass-uses. Non-classifier languages,
vi
PREFACE
on the other hand, are forced to make a choice whether the intended referent is described as a set or a Bass. build terns from
Nominalizations with
a
corpus
of
thirty
(verbal) predications. Working
languages
which
constitutes a fairly
representative sample of the languages of the world, J.L. Mackenzie shows
how
human
languages
exhibit
different
nominalization. He also demonstrates that there
degrees
is a
of
tendency for
'heavy* nominalization to correlate with Postfield ordering and for 'light' nominalization to be typical of Prefield ordering, moderate nominalization being
more equally
distributed across both classes
of language. Among the exceptions nominalization yielding
to
in
Persian,
the
tendency
organization; Hungarian, is accounted for cultural
as
pattern
of
relatively
is
terms with
to
have
degree of
is explained as a quasi-Postfield
us with a real exception,
other
metaphorizing
high
Prefield,
which provides
sharing
of
the
which
'European'
States
of
languages a
affairs (SoAs) as
ent it ies. Three authors explore relations as
the
question
predicate
whether
formation.
Serbo-Croatian treatment
of
they
Disagreeing
reflexive both
within the with
earlier
constructions,
'true'
and
predication as well
can be dealt with as instances of which
FG
treatments of
propose a unified
pseudo-reflexives
in
terms
of
predicate formation, D. KuSanda argues that true reflexives with se must be sharply distinguished from pseudo-reflexives,
because they
form highly transitive predications. On the other hand, one type of pseudo-reflexive construction passive
construction.
between the true passive admit
that
canonical
In
voice
shown to
and the passive
correlate of passivization. complex
is
order
R.
be
a
highly typical
pseudo-reflexive one, morphology Risselada
is is
not
FG should
a
necessary
concerned
with the
system of Ancient Greek, which besides an active and
a passive also has a medio-passive. as an
to
account for the similarities
instance of
The medio-passive
is regarded
valency reduction, which in FG is taken care of
by predicate formation. It is associated with a number of different interpretations, depending on the semantic function of the argument reduced. In order to capture the
so-called indirect
reflexive use
PREFACE
of
vi i
the
middle
passive,
she
distinguishes
a category of verbal
predicates implying a Beneficiary, which in spite of character
can
likewise
passive is viewed as
be
an
reduced.
instance
its satellite
The originally non-agentive
of
argument
reduction through
predicate formation which was reinterpreted as an agentive passive. W. Vandeweghe,
finally,
constructions,
discusses
Dutch
is viewed as the entity affected by the verb
and
possessive
which he relates to possessive
its
complement.
The
dative (pd)
constructions.
The pd
activity expressed
by the
relationship
between
constructions is captured by a predicate formation rule possessive
construction
as
Affect predicate;
the
semantic function
Affected.
its
the
two
taking the
input and resulting in a complex
original
possessor
The
argument
receives the
rule is limited in its synchronic
application, but the large number of
lexicalized complex
verbs in
Dutch shows that it has been very operative diachronically. Working with
examples from French, (perception verbs as well as
the verbs laisser, faire and aller), C. Vet demonstrates the use of the gramaaticalization
scale full predicate (stage one): predicate
formation (stage two): predicate operator (stage three). The second stage, in
which we get infinitive
related to Argument incorporation),
incorporation
(a feature closely
appears to
be reached
by all
the verbs considered. The third stage, which involves a clear shift in meaning and
which
exhibits
restrictions
on
the
use
of the
boundary
of the
infinitival form, is arrived at only occasionally. If
with
Vet's
paper
we
have
crossed
the
predication (at least where it deals with the creation of predicate operators),
we
predication,
are
be
it
also to
concerned varying
with
the
degrees,
in
'outs' the
of
the
remaining
contributions in this volume. Two
papers
discuss
relative
Vester concern themselves with They
argue
that
non-restrictive
other non-restrictive form part
of a
which have
clauses than
cline of
property of not being the status
clauses
the status
(RCs). M. Hannay and E. of non-restrictive
to restrictive
non-restrictive clauses
integrated
RCs.
RCs are more closely related to
into
the
core
of being either Orientation
RCs. Thus they which share the predication and or
Elaboration.
viii
PREFACE
The pragaatic functions
Orientation
and
Elaboration
subsuae the
'classical' FG functions Theme and Tail respectively. Accepting the position
that
restrictive
different constituents, clauses
explores
opposition in
the
and
non-restrictive
function
of
the
is taken
semantic Also
are totally
indicative:
subjunctive
the two types. The subjunctive in restrictive RCs is
found to be a Barker of non-specificity, RCs it
RCs
E. Vester's contribution on Latin relative
whereas in non-restrictive
to be an overt Marker of a (vague)
Circumstantial
function. Kahrel
and
understand only understood
Nuyts
deal
with
phenomena
which
we
can
if we go beyond the predication as it is currently
in
FG.
P.
Kahrel
concerns
hiaself
with
sentences
containing so-called
negative polarity itens (NPIs) and terns with
a 'zero quantifier*.
Rather
eleaents
that
require
than
the
describing
presence
Beans of a notion of pragmatic
the«
as linguistic
of Neg, he explains then by
conversion. Neg
contexts are viewed
as one possible instantiation of pragaatic conversion. Working fron a nuaber of instances of "Negative that neither
a purely
can give an
adequate
representational Functional treatnent expressing
account
level
Graiiar of
the
of
of
(PFG),
but
degrees
type
not
also of
(NR),
3. Nuyts argues
a purely pragaatic approach
thea;
the
KR-cases
various
Raising
syntactic) nor
we
need
accepted
(yet)
requires
by
recourse in
FG.
An
reference
Propositional
to a
Procedural adequate to a scale
Attitude.
Only
a
representation of this sort will trigger off a principled selection aaong various lexicalization and intonational features part in
the distinction
that play a
between raised and non-raised readings of
certain NR-cases. Modality is another phenoaenon that bursts the boundaries of the predication
stricto
Objective and
sensu.
K.
Epistenological
Hengeveld distinguishes Inherent, aodality.
Inherent
aodality types
represent SoAs and are expressed lexically by (derived) predicates; Objective
aodality
types
represent
the
speaker's
knowledge
concerning SoAs and are expressed by eabedding predicates/predicate operators; coamitnent
Epistemological with
regard
to
aodality the
concerns
the
speaker's
truth of a proposition, they are
PREFACE
ix
expressed
and
predication
operators. Using data (mainly) from Spanish, Hengeveld
by
»bedding
predicates/adverbials
demonstrates
that a FG which distinguishes these modality types, thea
as
Predication
operator,
Predicate, accounts for the
Predicate
scope
and linearizes
operator and (derived)
differences
that
hold between
then. In addition Hengeveld argues that we need a leftmost Mitigation/Reinforcement operators. L. predications
on
in FG can be refined, if we look at
Force
typology
a number
of
of data
the Bnglish modals, both in Present-day and in late
English.
Taking
exhibited by
operator
Illocutionary
Goossens' paper claims that the existing
connected with Old
operating
into
account
the predications
the
specific
which combine
well as the modality type realized by a
characteristics
with those modals as
given modal
in accordance
with those characteristics, Goossens finds evidence for a number of refinements in the present SoA-typology of FG: he makes a the distinction
of a subclass of cognizant
SoAs' situations
and events,
[controllable],
states,
as well as for
[situation-like]
case for
for the
features on
and [viewed
'hyper-
SoAs like
positively/negatively
by the deontee]. Finally, H. Weigand presents Koto, predications and
intended as
its present form it is a situations, entity Koto sentence situations
interpreted background
as
semantics
of
the
a
theory, which
model
between
system
includes
modality, aspect. A
situation,
relations
interpreted as entity information the
representation base. In
preliminary model
predicates, cardinalities,
is
with
a formal language based on FG
a knowledge
or
a
them.
elements.
couple of Terms
are
Although only
is given, it is emphasized that the
semantics must interact with a pragmatic component. Needless to say most of the here invite
further research.
Conference at the Free crystallisation May we
ideas and
investigations presented
We are looking forward to the Third
University of
Amsterdam in
1988 as
a new
point.
round off
with a
word of thanks. To the authors of this
volume for contributing, to the
editors
Georges
Nuyts, for the smooth and fruitful
de
Schutter
and
Jan
of
the
parallel
volume,
x
PREFACE
interaction, to the editors the
Publisher.
To
the
of the
Belgian
Functional Grammar National
Universitaire Instelling Antwerpen for Ann
Verschueren-Verhaert
typing/correction
for
a
Science
financial most
job.
Johan van der Auwera and Louis Goossens
kind
Series, to
Fund
and the
support. and
And to
efficient
Table of Contents
Preface
v
A typology of entities Simon
C. Dik
0. 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7.
Introduction Entities have mental status Construing and retrieving entities The insufficiency of Set Theory Typology of entities: first version Types of terms; types of nominal predicates Do we need individuals? Arguments for interpreting Individuals as singleton sets 8. Individuation of nasses 9. Sortal classifiers
Modal shifts and predication Louis
1 2 3 4 6 7 9 10 14 15
types
Goossens
0. Introduction 1. SoA-types in FG 2. Modality types and states of affairs 2.1. Situations and events 2.2. The predicate operators Prosp[ective] and Habfitual] 2.3. Controlled situations 2.4. SoA-types and aodality-types: a refined correlation 3. Data from diachrony 3.1. cunnan 3.2. magan 3.3. notan 4. Conclusion Notes Non-restrictive relatives and the representation of complex sentences Mike Hannay and Elseline Vester 0. Introduction 1. A basic functional description 2. Relative clauses within FG 3. Predication combining 4. The representation of non-restrictive clauses 5. Conclusion Notes
21 21 22 22 23 25 26 27 27 28 31 35 36
39 39 41 43 48 51 51
xii TABLE OF CONTENTS
Clause structure and modality in Functional Grammar Hengeveld
Kees
0. Introduction 1. Clause structure 2. Modality 3. Clause structure and modality 4. Illocutionary operators 5. Conclusion Notes
53 53 56 60 63 65 65
On zero terms and negative polarity Peter
Kahrel
0. Introduction 1. Zero quantification 2. Operators and conversion 3. Conclusion Notes 'True' reflexives and pseudo-reflexives with particular reference to Serbo-Croatian Dubravko Kutanda 0. Introduction 1. 'True' reflexives vs. other se constructions 2. S-C 'true' reflexives are two-place predications 3. Passive pseudo-reflexives (PPRs) 4. Conclusion Notes
67 69 71 74 75
77 79 80 83 91 91
Nominalization and basic constituent ordering J. Lachlan
Mackenzie
0. Introduction 1. Analysis of the data 2. Correlation between Postfield and nominalization 3. Towards an explanation Notes
93 94 100 102 105
A cognitive-pragmatic reconsideration of negative raising Jan
Nuyts 0. Introduction 1. A short survey of the literature 2. Against a syntactic NR-rule 3. Towards a cognitive-pragmatic account 4. The representation of the 'raised* construction 5. Conclusion Notes
107 107 108 111 117 120 121
TABLE OF CONTENTS
xiii
Voice in Ancient Greek: Reflexives and passives Rodie
Riaseiada
0. Introduction 1. Voice in Ancient Greek 2. Valency Reduction 2.1. Valency Reduction in FG 2.2. Valency Reduction in Ancient Greek 2.3. The passive 3. Conclusion Notes
123 123 127 128 128 132 135 135
The possessive dative in Dutch: syntactic reanalysis and predicate Willy
formation
Vandeueghe
0. Introduction 1. The relation between poss- and pd-construction 2. V-equivalents to expressing the Affect relation 3. Triggers for syntactic reanalysis 3.1. Object Promotion 3.2. Complex Predicate Formation 4. The reanalysis in a FG account 4.1. The rule 4.2. Productivity 4.3. Applicability 5. Conclusion Notes
137 138 141 143 144 145 146 146 146 147 150 150
A representation of Latin relative clauses Elseline
Vester
0. Introduction 1. Restrictive RCs 1.1. Definiteness and Specificity 1.2. Motivation 1.3. Conclusion 2. Non-restrictive RCs 3. Conclusion Notes
152 155 155 159 160 160 162 162
xiv
TABLE
OF
Infinitive
CONTENTS
incorporation
Co Vet 0. I n t r o d u c t i o n 1. A r g u m e n t I n c o r p o r a t i o n 2. I n f i n i t i v e s 3. P e r c e p t i o n v e r b s 4. O t h e r i n c o r p o r a t i n g v e r b s : verbs 5. F i n a l r e m a r k s Notes Functional
Hans
Granar
as
a fornai
laisser,
faire,
movement
163 163 165 168 173 176 177
language
ffeigand 0. I n t r o d u c t i o n 1. T h e K o t o l a n g u a g e 1.1. Terms 1.2. P r e d i c a t i o n s 2. S e m a n t i c s 2.1. The basic algebra 2.2. Information systems 2.3. Casts a n d scripts 2.4. Status and modality 2.5. Aspect 3. C o n c l u s i o n Notes
179 180 180 182 183 185 186 188 191 192 193 193
References
197
Author
211
index
Language Subject
index index
213 215
A typology of entities Simon C. Dik Institute
0.
of General Linguistics,
University of
Amsterdam
Introduction
FG is
based on
the assumption
that linguistic expressions can be
analyzed in t e n s of underlying predications, which in turn consist of predicate frames and term structures. Semantically, predications are interpreted as designating states of as designating
properties or
nating entities (E).
At
affairs (SoA), predicates
relations (P/H), and terms as desig-
the
level
of
the
predication
we have
developed a typology of SoA's, according to which SoA's are divided into a number of semantic types [¿control],
[¿dynamic],
in
terms
[+telic],
of
and
such
properties as
[jjaomentaneous ] .
This
semantic typology helps us understand a number of things concerning the coding
properties and
the behavioral properties (in the sense
of Keenan 1976) of predications. By expression
rules
which
intonational properties we understand constrain
the
coding properties
specify
the
form,
of constituents;
the
we mean the
order,
and the
by behavioral properties
properties concerning the rules and principles which formation
and
the
further
specification
of the
predication. Just as we need a typology of SoA's to account for the differences between predications, so we need a typology of P/R's to understand
a
number
of
differences
between
predicates,
and a
typology of E's to differentiate between terms. This paper concerns the
typology
of
E's.
semantic E types in help understand of terms. The
Such
terms of
a
the differential subject
typology will specify a number of
semantic distinctions
pertains
which make us
coding and behavioral properties to
what
Seiler
has
termed the
dimension of Apprehension, where this term is taken in the sense of 'how language grasps and objects or
represents
items' (Seiler
concepts
account of this 'dimension', Seiler and and
Stachowiak
(1982)
contain
aspects of the problems involved. number of
relevant studies
that
correspond to
1986:9). Seiler (1986) is a theoretical a
Lehmann (1982)
number
Independently
have recently
and Seiler
of detailed studies of of
this
work, a
been published in Craig
2
DIK
(1986) under the heading 'noun classes and categorization*. 1. Entities have mental There is a
mutual
'entity', in
status
relationship
between
the
notions
to E's, and E's are things that can be referred to by important to
'tern' and
that terms are expressions which can be used to refer realize from
reality', but 'things in representations.
The
the outset the liind':
same
terns. It is
that E's are not 'things in E's are
applies
to
mental constructs or
SoA's
and
P/R's, but we
concentrate here on the mental status of E's. There are reasons why
E's must
three main
be assigned mental status rather than 'real*
existence in the outside world. First, there are many about,
but
which
do
things which
not
exist
in
we can
refer to
and talk
reality. Think of mythical,
fictional, or hypothetical things, or of things which only occur in dreams or fantasies. Consider such cases as: (1)
Last night I dreamed themselves with bananas
(2)
In the highlands of New Guinea there are dogs. They feed themselves with bananas
(3)
Suppose there were ants as big as dogs, and that they would feed themselves with bananas
In (1) a dream world is claimed; (2)
of
ants as big as dogs. They fed
described for
pretends to
be a
which no
description of
real existence is
is that,
existential
world
once the
duced, they can be referred to what
exist; in
(3) a
is introduced in a way which signals that the
speaker does not believe such a important here
big as
reality, but it is
unlikely that anyone will believe that reality to counterfactual world
ants as
status
is
to
really
exist.
What is
dog-sized ants have been intro-
again and assigned
talked about,
no matter
to them. What we refer to,
then, is E's which have been mentally construed on the basis of the linguistic information
provided. Reference, therefore, is indepen-
dent of ontological commitment or existence in reality. The second argument is that we can refer to 'real' to the
things only
extent that we have some mental representation of them. For
ENTITIES
3
example, either
if
I want
be
'picture'
the of
descriptive such the
actual
refer
to
by
mental
which
directly virtue
the even
or
for
in
Roie,
already I
has
must to
give
be
able
things which
it
some
must
Rental
sufficient to
construe
are present
in
situation.
connected
the
Colosseum
addressee
talk
with
things
fact
the
about
experienced.
of
and
in t e r m s
second,
things
are
in
nowhere
Such
that
is
that we
reality
to
reference
we either of which
are
retrieving
mental
Johnson-Laird same
addressee
in
be perceived
or
can
possess we can
can
even
be
or
effective
can
then
construe
communicate
information.
Construing
correspond
the
true
these
representations
Entities
the
is
reason,
in
and exchange
(cf.
This
to my
referent,
for
and efficiently
otherwise
2.
intended
communicative
third
situations only
the
that
information
a referent.
The
to r e f e r
case
with
entities
representations.
1983)
the
or
'mental
They
real world outside
properties,
no matter
exist
pictures' us.
whether
in
'mental
which may
Referring
or
not
models'
or m a y
not
to some E
has
there
is
such
a
correspondence. Since
B's
distinguish (4)
The
are things
two main
that
usages
of
can be construed
in t h e m i n d ,
we
can
terms:
(i)
S m a y use a t e r m T in o r d e r to h e l p A c o n s t r u e a referent E for T, a n d t h u s i n t r o d u c e E into his m e n t a l m o d e l
(ii)
S may E for
u s e a t e r m T in o r d e r t o h e l p A r e t r i e v e a r e f e r e n t T, w h e r e E w a s a l r e a d y p r e s e n t i n h i s m e n t a l m o d e l
construction
indefinite typically
of
specific
referents
terms,
as
g u i d e d by definite
in
is
typically
(5);
terms,
the
as
in
(5)
Yesterday
in t h e p a r k
I saw
a black
Yesterday
in the park
I saw
the/that
If w e w i s h
to use we might
the
term
'refer'
distinguish
them
and as
of
through
referents
is
(6):
(6)
of u s a g e ,
achieved
retrieval
cat black
'reference' 'constructive
cat
again
for both
types
reference'
and
4
DIK
'identifying reference',
respectively. In
is to
cooperative action
be analyzed
as a
both cases,
'reference'
which can be analyzed
according to the schema: (7)
S refers A to E by leans of T
where, in all cases, E has the status of a mental construct. 3. The insufficiency In logic it
is
interpreted in
of Set Theory
customary
expressions
be senantically
Set
Theory.
Thus,
a
possible
world is
consisting of individuals, sets of individuals, sets of
sets of individuals, etc. Terms are or to
to
terms of 'possible worlds', the properties of which
are defined in terms of defined as
for
taken to
refer to individuals
sets; properties and relations are interpreted extensionally
according to the schemas: (8)
P = the set of all x such that P(x) is true
(9)
R = the set of all n-tuples xi, R(xi, X2, ..., xn) is true
X2, ...,
xn such that
Set Theory is construed on the basis of the primitive relation: (10) Any set
a c A
'a is a member of A'
thus consists
of members which can be counted. The number
of members a given set A has is the cardinal number of that set. We can conceive of the cardinal as a function which takes sets for its arguments and delivers numbers as values: (11)
c(A) = n
'the number of members of A = n'
This apparatus of Set Theory is not immediately applicable to terms involving mass nouns: (12)
There was 0/some/much water in the pool
Water does not obviously designate a set consisting of distinguishable and countable members.
It is
strange to
talk of
the number
ENTITIES
5
(rather than
the quantity)
out of this predicament:
of water.
There are two possible ways
(i) assume that mass terms, too, designate
sets; this requires that masses be interpreted as having (some kind of) members;
(ii) assume
this requires
that mass
terms do
not designate sets;
a specification of what type of E they do designate,
and it implies that not all E's have
the status
of individuals or
sets. If course
(i) is
taken, we
have to
assume that masses, just
like sets, do have members. He could assume, for example, thing
desginated
by
water
does
example, molecules) which could even if
this may
correspond to about them.
the way And it
and syntactic Finally, it
be true
of smallest parts (for
in principle
in some
in which
does not
differences
consist
that the
be counted. However,
'objective' sense, it does not
we conceptualize
masses and talk
make us understand the many semantic
between
count
nouns
and
mass nouns.
would be very difficult to specify the basic particles
of more abstract
'masses' such as in:
He did not feel much love for his dog
(13)
For these reasons, Bunt along the
(1985) has developed an
alternative theory
lines of course (ii). In this theory, Masses are distin-
guished from Sets, but both are
unified in
the higher
concept of
Ensemble, according to the following schema: (14)
ENSEMBLE has parts has size MASS has parts has measure
SET has parts has members
Ensembles are either Sets or Masses. Sets have members, Masses have measures. Therefore, Ensemble theory of the
primitive relation
cannot be
Masses can be said to have parts, i.e. can be Sets and
Masses. From
developed in terms
'is a member of'. However, both Sets and divided into smaller
this it follows that Ensemble theory can be
6
DIK
developed
on
the basis
(15)
A C B
This
primitive
'A is p a r t o f relation
'intersection', of Ensembles sane parts. then have
Typology
On
the
basis
following
Any a
of
consist
a
an
of
of E n t i t i e s ,
be used
'difference' in t e r n s
'is a « e m b e r
first
to d e f i n e
for
the
Ensembles.
of two Ensembles
of',
in a d e r i v a t i v e
particular
notions Identity
having
for
Sets,
the will
way.
version Bade above,
we
can now
set
up
the
E's:
Individual
Mass.
relation:
B'
then
the distinctions
typology
or
and
defined
Entities:
E is either Set
be
The notion
of
can
"union",
will
to b e d e f i n e d
4.
the prinitive
of
A
or
an Enseiible;
mass nay consist
which can be either
an Ensenble
of sub-Masses; Individuals
or
is
either
a Set
will
Ensenbles,
etc. This
typology
recursively
defines
ing: (16)
a.
Types
of
Entities
Individual Mass Mass of Masses Set of I n d i v i d u a l s Set of Masses Set of Sets of I n d i v i d u a l s etc.
such E types
as
the
follow-
ENTITIES
7
5. Types of terms; types of nominal It
is
clear
that
we
predicates
can now divide t e n s into different types,
corresponding to the type of E that they can be used to refer to: (17)
Individual tern Mass tern Set term
John; this boy some water; much gold these boys; this family
More coiplex, however, is the question nouns (noninal typology of
predicates) into
E's set
up in
whether we
different types
(16a). The
can also divide according to the
main problem
is that most
nouns can be used to designate E's of different types. Consider: (18) a. b. c.
I saw a chicken in the garden I saw three chickens in the garden We had chicken for dinner
[Individual] [Set] [Mass]
(19) a. b.
He is very fond of wine [Mass] He chose two Italian wines for dinner [Set]
(20) a. b.
John was at the party too There were three Johns at the party
For this
reason Bunt (1985) concludes that we should not speak of,
[Individual] [Set]
for exaaple, 'mass nouns', but only of 'Bass occurrences' of nouns. The nouna
as such
they can be used there are
would then to refer
be neutral as to the type of E that
to. A
clear differences
problem with
in aarkedness
this view
is that
between such different
noun occurrences. Consider the following: (21) a. b.
There were too many chairs in the rooa There was too much chair in the room
[unmarked] [narked]
(22) a. b.
I would like sone butter, please I would like three butters, please
[unaarked] [narked]
(23) a. b.
I saw John last week I saw too auch John last week
[unaarked] [Barked]
Intuitively, we would like typically or
and requires soae service for
to
be
able
to
say
that
a
noun is
basically used in teras referring to certain E types, sort
referring to
of
extra other E
operation
to
be
pressed into
types. We can do so by dividing
noninal predicates over different subcategories in
teras of
the E
8
DIK
types that they can be used to refer to in unaarked 'basic' usage, and then allowing these noainals to be 'converted' froa one subcategory to another by a process of 'subcategorial conversion*. Following this line, we of noainals: (24)
may define the following subcategories
Type of nominal Count Noun (Nc) Mass Noun (Na) Collective Noun (Ncoll)
Between these
Designates singular plural Individual Set of Ind. Mass Set Set of Sets
subcategories, we
Example chair butter faaily
can define the following forms of
subcategorial conversion: (25) (26)
Nc -> Na There was too auch chair in the roon Na -> Nc I would like three butters please (= e.g. 'three slices of bread with butter')
(27)
Ncoll -> Na There was too auch faaily in the room
Within the fraaework of FQ, such 'subcategorial conversion' may be regarded as a for« of predicate formation which, in English, is not coded in any morphological signal on the noun. This analysis is strengthened if languages are found in which subcategorial conversions of this type are formally marked in one way or another. For example, the relation between Dutch pairs such as vogel 'bird' / ge-vogel-te 'poultry', or berg 'mountain' / ge-berg-te 'mountain range' could be interpreted as a form of conversion from count to mass or collective. Subcategorial conversion does have an obvious semantic effect on the input noun. For example, if Na is converted into Nc, as in (26), the output noun must be interpreted as referring to a Set, the members of which can in some way or other be individuated. On the other hand, a noun converted from Nc to Nm refers to an B as if it consists of some 'stuff' which cannot be individuated.
ENTITIES
9
6. Do ue need So far
Individuals?
we have
assumed without discussion that we need a distinct
K type of Individuals, as distinct from Sets. Brown (1985), other
hand,
has
interpreted as
suggested
that
singleton Sets,
Individuals
i.e. as
on the
Bay
themselves be
Sets which
have only one
member. Let us consider this question in somewhat »ore detail. Note,
first
of
all,
that
Set
Theory distinguishes
sharply
between individuals and sets consisting of only one individual: (28)
a
(29) a. b.
a e A {a} £ A
t
{a}
However,
when
we
'a is a leiber of A' 'the set of which a is the sole subset of A' consider
how
member is a
(30) could be represented in Set
Theory, there is no a priori reason why (31a) should be better than (31b): (30)
John is one of the winners
(31) a. b.
j c W {j} C W
Since,
as
we
saw
above,
'is
a
relation of Ensemble Theory, we might Another way
leiber
of' is not a primitive
even prefer
(31b) to (31a).
of saying this is that we could define 'Individual' as
a Set of cardinality 1: (32)
X is an Individual =df X is a Set I such that c(I) = 1
Alternatively, we could define an 'Individual'
as a
Set which has
no other non-empty parts than itself: (33)
X is an Individual =df X is a Set I such that for any Y, if Y C I and Y f 0, then Y = X
In both ways, we could arrive relation
'is
a member
at a
typology of
E's in
which the
of' need not occur, neither as a primitive,
10
DIK
nor as
a derived
relation. This
would imply that our typology of
B's set up in (16) could be simplified to the following: (33) a
ENTITY = ENSEMBLE
In other Sets or
words, all
B's are
Masses. Individuals
Ensembles; all
Ensembles are either
are particular kinds of Sets, defined
as in (32) or (33). 7. Arguments At first
for interpreting
sight, the
intuitively not
Individuals as singleton Sets
idea that
very appealing.
Individuals are
singleton Sets is
It seems strange to think of John
or this boy as indicating a Set of cardinality 1, or as a Set whose sole
non-empty
part
is
identical to itself. At second thoughts,
however, there are various linguistic arguments which could support such an interpretation. Let us consider soie of these. Argument
1.
Bvery
there is a fundamental
introduction
to
Set Theory warns us that
difference between
the membership
and the
subset relation, as in: (34) a. b.
John is a painter A painter is an artist
If
difference
this
is
so
j
c P P E A
fundamental,
however,
reflected in the linguistic form of (34a-b)? I language
which
has
distinct
verbs
V
member of' and W = 'is a subset of'. Of claim, as
is often
done, that
other) senses, since that
why is it not
do not
know of any
and W such that V = 'is a course it
does not
do to
be is ambiguous between these (and
amounts
to
begging
the
very question
involved. Moreover, if it is true, as suggested in Dik (1980), that be should be described as then
this
idea
grounds. If, then both
of
a
semantically
ambiguous
be
however, Individuals
(34a) and
(34b) define
is
empty
supportive verb,
not feasible on principled
are defined
as singleton Sets,
a subset relation which can, in
ENTITIES
II
both cases, be represented in the sane way. This corresponds to the fact that the FG representations for the underlying predications of the two constructions are essentially the s u e : (35) a. b.
J E P P C A
FG: P(x: J(x)) FG: A(x: P(x))
The semantic differences between the two constructions are then accounted for by the fact that J, in contrast to P and A, indicates a singleton Set. Argument 2. Consider the conjoined terms in: (36) a. b.
The boys and the girls went to the cinema John and the girls went to the cinema
Note that these conjoined terms are linguistically the same, no •atter whether Sets or Individuals are involved. Set Theory will no doubt represent the boya and the girls as the union of two Sets: (37)
B
U G
However, the union relation can only hold between Sets, not between Individuals and Sets. Therefore, it is not obvious how John and the girls should be analyzed according to Set Theory. If John, however, iB also interpreted as representing a Set, then the conjunction can be represented according to the same format as (37): (38)
J U G
Argument 3. Compare the following constructions: (39) a. b.
John is ill The boys are ill
If John is taken to indicate an Individual, (39a) could be analyzed as follows: (40)
I(j)
where the predicate I ('ill') is applied to the individual j ('John')- However, the boya in (39b) obviously designates a Set,
12
DIK
and thus, at first sight, the following analysis
would sees
to be
in order: (41)
1(B)
where
B
indicates
imply, however,
the
Set
that the
of
the boys in question. This would
predicate ill
can be
applied either to
Individuals or to Sets, a situation which is semantically difficult to evaluate. For that reason, standard logic would underlying structure
assume that the
of (39b) is in fact quite different from that
of (39a), along the lines of: (42)
Vx, xcB: I(x) 'For all x such that x is a member of B, I applies to x'
This, however, has the •ay be
wide apart
far-reaching consequence
from grammatical
form, a
that logical form
consequence which is
indeed accepted in standard logic. If, on
the other
hand, we
assume that
Individuals are Sets,
then (39a-b) can be represented in the same way: (42)' a. b.
I(J) 1(B)
where in
each case I is applied to a Set. This treatment, however,
raises a counter-argument against regarding Individuals
as single-
ton Sets: Countei—argument.
Some
predicates define properties/relations
over individual entities, some assign properties/relations to Sets. Compare: (43) a. b.
The boys are ill The boys are numerous
The difference can be paraphrased as follows: (44) a. b.
Boy1 is ill and boy 2 is ill, and ... and boy" is ill The Set consisting of "the boys' is numerous (= has relatively high cardinality)
How are we to take care of this difference when we do not differen-
ENTITIES
13
tiate between
Sets and
Individual m e m b e r s
of S e t s ?
In b o t h cases
the analysis would be the sane: (45) a. b.
1(B) N(B)
Note, h o w e v e r , (43a) and
that even
in
(43b) cannot
of the argument
term
interpretation.
It
Set
Theory
b e m a d e in t e n s
the boys'.
this term
is c u s t o m a r y ,
indicates a
therefore,
tive' and
a p p l i c a t i o n of predicates
collective
a v a i l a b l e to us, so that w e can (46) a. b.
between
and
predicates.
speak of
differ-
'distribu-
or, more
This
status
Set on any
to locate the
ill
'collective'
numerous,
distinction
ence in the predicates of d i s t r i b u t i v e and
and
the
of a d i f f e r e n c e in
same
briefly, method
is
write:
Id(B) Ne(B)
The d i s t r i b u t i v e
predicate
to the Individuals Sets w h i c h
in
are part
b e interpreted
Id
Set B
will now b e i n t e r p r e t e d (themselves defined
John
w h e r e the
to the w h o l e Set B. The same
is ill
analysis
the s i n g l e t o n
is
representa-
of:
Id(J) interpreted
as indicating that
Sets in J, w h i c h , since J in this
idual, coincide
applying
of B), w h i l e the collective p r e d i c a t e Nc will
as applying
tion can now b e used for the analysis (47)
as
as the singleton
w i t h J.
vs. c o l l e c t i v e predicates
The s e m a n t i c effect can
now
be
case
is
of u s i n g
graphically
I applies an
to
Indiv-
distributive
illustrated
as
f ollows: (48)
John and Mary are Id(J U M )
ill
(49)
John and Mary are Ec(J U M )
engaged
W e may
conclude
that the counter-argument
does not prevent
us from
14
DIK
defining Individuals as singleton Sets. 8. Individuation We can
thus say
Individuals,
of Masses that Sets
defined
ultimate parts of
as
Sets
ultimately consist subsets
can
which
thus
be
have
of smallest parts: cardinality 1. The
considered
as individuated
entities, each separate from the others, the nuaber of which can be counted. Masses do not have such individuated saallest parts. Their content cannot be counted; it can only be aeasured. However,
Masses
can
be divided into individuated quantities,
which can then be counted. Individuated
quantities Bay
be defined
by standard and non-standard quantity measures, as in: (50) a. b.
Three litres of wine [standard quantity) Three bottles of wine [non-standard quantity]
It is clear that, whereas ttine designates a Mass, the whole tern in this case designates a Set, naaely the set of
specified
quantities
of
the
Mass
represent one further way of converting
consisting of
a nuaber
in question. (50a-b) thus Mass expressions
into Set
expressions. It is
not iaaediately
bottle should be analysis
has
clear how expressions such as litre and
represented
been
in
suggested
underlying
in
ten
these quantity expressions as two-place noninal ing to
the scheaa
structure. One
Brown (1985). This is to regard predicates accord-
'x is a litre/bottle of y'. On this analysis we
arrive at structures such as: (51)
three bottles of wine (i3xi: bottle»(xi)(xj: winen(xj)) '3 entities xi that stand in a 'bottle* relation to wine'
Another approach would be bottle
represent
a
to
assune
particular
like
litre and
type of tern operator:
that
words
'measuring
unit', which can occur in such configurations as: (52)
(i3 bottle Xi: wine«(xi))
ENTITIES
A
15
problem
with
the
distinction affects
latter
representation
the measuring
is
that
the number
unit rather than the head noun.
And if both nouns take a plural, as in: (53)
three bottles of peas (i3 bottle xi: pean(xi))
then it is not from; unless
immediately clear
where the
plural on
peas
cones
we consider this as a kind of redundant plural, which
is not unreasonable in view
of
the
fact
that
it
cannot freely
alternate with a singular in this construction: (54)
»three bottle of pea
Measuring units
specify a certain quantity of what is indicated by
the noun with which kinds
of
units will secondary
entity
they combine. that
be used
indicate what
noun designates, since different measuring
for different
'classifying'
Secondarily they
role links
types of
things. Although this
them to so-called classifiers,
they should not be equated with these. The primary role
of measur-
ing units is to specify some quantity. True classifiers do not have that role. We must therefore either follow Lyons guishing
between
'mensural'
and
'sortal'
(1977) in distin-
classifiers,
subsume the measuring units under the classifiers at now
consider
the
true
'sortal'
or
not
all. We shall
classifiers in the light of our
typology of E's. 9. Sortal
classifiers
Sortal classifiers, in the languages that have them, typically come in two types, as illustrated in: (55) a. b.
three animal elephant three flat blanket
'three elephants' 'three blankets'
(56) a. b.
three dog dog three stone stone
'three dogs' 'three stones'
In the type illustrated in (55) the classifier specifies a superordinate category (a hyperonym) with respect to the noun: an elephant
16
DIK
is a kind of aniaal; a blanket is a kind of flat thing. In the type illustrated in (56) the fact, in
'repeats'
classifier
the
head
noun. In
such 'repeater constructions' the classifier and the head
noun are typically the s u e word. Classifiers of this type
have the
following recurrent proper-
ties across languages (cf. Allan 1977): (i) they
aust occur
if the
nuiber of
term containing the head noun; in only
occur
nuaber of
on
its
own
if
entities is specified in a
other words,
the head
noun can
there is no indication at all of the
entities involved.
Thus, a
typical classifier language
has the following pattern: (57) a. b. c. (ii) in
John saw elephant in jungle "John saw (one/iore) elephant in the jungle' »John saw three elephant in jungle John saw three aninal elephant in jungle the ordering of the tera, nuaeral and classifier are never
separated from each other by the head noun. Thus: (58)
three aninal elephant aniaal three elephant elephant three aniaal
»three elephant aniaal »aniaal elephant three elephant aniaal three
This property signals that there is an intiaate nuaeral and
connection between
classifier. In a sense, the presence of the classifier
•akes it possible fo the numeral to occur. (iii) it is exceptional for the head to be aarked for plural in the classifier
construction.
In
fact,
languages in which plural Barking is
classifiers
only
either totally
occur
in
absent, or at
lost optional. (iv)
classifier
languages
typically
have
a
classifiers, which together classify
all
The
necessary
restriction
'classifiable'
is
the
liaited
number of
classifiable nouns. since probably all
classifier languages also have nouns that do not take classifiers. (v) in many classifier languages the
classifiers also
play a role
in aotinoring anaphoric relations of coreference. Thus, we Bay find
ENTITIES
17
such constructions as the following: (58) a.
John shout he animal 'John shouted see then'
see
3
animal
elephant,
but
in a
sense, they
the head noun, so that it quantity, however. aptly
called
quantities) iD
can be
Rather, they them
terms
and
litre
individuate that which is indicated by counted. They
do not
specify a
designate some property or attri-
bute of that which is indicated by the head noun. has
not see
that he saw three elephants, but I did not
Classifiers are similar to measuring units such as bottle in that,
I
Greenberg
(1978)
'unit counters': they specify units (not:
of
which
the
head
noun
referent
can be
counted. We should now address two questions: (a) what is the status of classifiers in term structure? (b) what is the status of the head noun in relation to the typology of Entities? As for question (a), it is clear that some such analysis as that of (51)
is
not
specifies
a
feasible
for
classifiers.
property,
not
a
relation
For
example,
between
'animal'
'elephant'
and
something else. Since the
classifier designates
a property, we might consider
analyzing it as a restrictor on the term variable: (59)
(3 x: animal(x):
elephant(x))
However, this does not account for the intimate numeral and
classifier, and
connection between
it is not feasible in the case of the
repeater construction. No sense whatsoever could be made
of a terra
structure such as: (60) For these
(3 x: dog(x): reasons I
dog(x))
believe that it is plausible that the classi-
fier is a particular type of term operator, as illustrated in:
18
DIK
(61) a. b.
(3 animal x: elephant(x)) (3 dog x: dog(x))
The function of such
tern operators
would then
be to individuate
the head noun referent, so as to turn it into a Set expression. As
for
question
(b),
it
will
languages those nouns which require status of
way to
clear that in classifier do
not
have the
count nouns: they can only be used to refer to Sets when
they have been extended by a they carry
be
classifiers
no suggestion
account
for
languages would
the
be to
classifier; when
of individuation behavior
assuie that
of
used on
their own,
or number. A plausible
head
nouns
they have
in classifier
the basic status of
•ass nouns: taken in isolation they do not
imply any individuation
or quantification. A word such as elephant
in such a language could
then be taken to signify 'elephant-stuff', a meaning which can only be individuated, and thus Bade ready for referring to Sets, through the addition of either a mensural or a sortal classifier. Several authors (e.g. Serzisko 1982; Kolver however,
that
this
following reason: for distinguishing
assumption
even in
cannot
be
maintained,
classifier languages
mass nouns
1982) have argued, for
the
there are reasons
from other nouns. For exanple, mass
nouns could be defined as those nouns which
can only
be individu-
ated through measuring units, not through classifiers. We will then find a pattern such as: (62)
WATER (aass noun) three bucket water •three liquid water
'three buckets of water' 'three waters'
(63)
BANANA (non-mass noun) three basket banana three fruit banana
'three baskets of bananas' 'three bananas'
If mass nouns in can only
classifier languages
be individuated
(63) is not a mass noun. noun either,
it must
are defined
through measuring Since we
be something
saw that
as nouns which
units, then BANANA in it cannot
different from
be a count
either mass or
count. According to Kolver (1982)
we
may
assume
that
a
noun like
ENTITIES
BANANA
19
in
(63)
indicates
the banana-property. entities; to b e
it
able
must
be
nouns
tions
in a s e n s e ,
this
idea
is
can be
usage
is B A N A N A there
'incarnation*
can
be
banana
but
also
fruit,
contextualization, like.
Whatever
entity
or
in
to.
in
that used
in
on
through
most
their
intimation in
status:
that
Let us now
by
banana
is
And
it
to t h e
(65)
by
indicate
classifier
languages
in s u c h
construc-
in
to
trees
is
and,
one
with
banana or
not
however, that
the
is
or
does
the have
referred
concept
to s o m e t h i n g
more
suitable
of m a s h e d b a n a n a s (64),
'something*
can refer
type of
it c o u l d b e
that
only by
to is
virtue
it.
typology
of E's
set up
in
(33a):
ENSEMBLE
SET (Ncount) typology
(66)
suggests
MASS (Nmass) the
following
hypothesis:
N o u n s t h a t t a k e s o r t a l c l a s s i f i e r s in c l a s s i f i e r l a n g u a g e s are Ensemble nouns, undifferentiated for Set/Mass, and n e u t r a l as t o i n d i v i d u a t i o n a n d q u a n t i f i c a t i o n
I do believe ization of t h e
of
that
this
hypothesis
classifiable
typology
describe
the
of E's
, we are
of
nouns. (65).
typological
In n o n - c l a s s i f i e r sion
the
classifier
own,
to what
a bowl
BANANA
there
is a t t a c h e d
as
garden:
also be
BANANA
return
the
one or m o r e
this usage.
the concept
can
to
garden
is n o
it c o u l d
Rather,
the
found
is d e s i g n a t e d
object
the noun
referred
This
defined
be used
entities.
in q u e s t i o n
There
In t h i s
of
('Begriff')
cannot
as:
(64)
by
concept
concept
'reified',
to d e s i g n a t e
A problem with the
the pure
The pure
forced
On
the
when
a choice
correct
it s t r e n g t h e n s
the basis
parameter
languages, to m a k e
embodies If s o ,
of this
involved forming whether
as
character-
the
we
follows:
a referring
the
validity
hypothesis
intended
expresreferent
20
DIK
is t o
be described
however,
this
referent
as
the
intended
precise, into Mass.
as a Set
choice
is n o t
an Ensemble, referent
however,
is
we can
o r as a M a s s .
In c l a s s i f i e r
languages,
forced
us.
describe
upon
leaving unresolved i n d i v i d u a t e d or optionally
a format which unequivocally
not.
turn
We
can
the q u e s t i o n If w e w i s h
the Ensemble
designates
either
a
a
whether
to b e
more
expression Set
or
a
Modal shifts and predication types Louis Goossens Department of Germanic Languages, University of Antwerp
Introduction*
0.
A typical
feature of modals
tions w h i c h bring along question
in
this context
imposed
on
those
in Goossens
Steedman
shift to
take
the diachronic
their epistenic in
according
to
calls
sodality
type
a preliminary
E p i s t e n i c modals 'situations',
"events'.
As
I
answer to this
as a
rule
whereas
pointed out
require
deontic
and
there, one way
shift from f a c u l t a t i v e or deontic modals
counterparts,
is
to look
the combining p r e d i c a t i o n ,
In this paper
upon
w h i c h must
it
to
as involving
change from
a
'event'
X will try to p r o v i d e
some further
to a
better understanding
nically and d i a c h r o n i c a l l y . necessity used
of
adopting
of the At
refinenents
SoA-types
in
sane
tine
the
different yielding
synchro-
illustrate
entity,
case
in
reflecting, some
basic
FG.
world'.
of our
in FG. A
as
Dik SoAs
inquiry,
let's
'state of affairs'
(1978)
puts it,
'what
can be classified dynamism and
this typology
is the
nuclear
tion, i.e. predicates, whether b a s i c or d e r i v e d , w i t h their
into
control,
types of SoA: states, p r o c e s s e s , positions
actions. The correlate for arguments.
the
of the sort
of SoAs within
types, according to the p a r a m e t e r s four
First
contributes
FG
the status of S o A - t y p e s
is a conceptual
we
and g e n e r a l i z a t i o n s
B e f o r e e m b a r k i n g on the s p e c i f i c points briefly recall
of SoAs
(English) n o d a l s , both
the
in this paper in the c h a r a c t e r i z a t i o n
be
clarification
area. The c l a r i f i c a t i o n w i l l serve a double purpose.
we want to demonstrate that a refined treatnent
can
obvious
have to be
'situation'.
in this
1.
the
predica-
An
any restrictions
I presented
(1985a).
(1977)
facultative m o d a l s to view
structure.
nodal.
E c h o i n g work of others what
argument
is w h e t h e r
predications
realized by a given question
is that they c o m b i n e with
their own
and
predicanuclear
22
GOOSSENS
From the start Dik made clear to
further
research.
that his
Obviously,
classification
is open
new proposals must be motivated
linguistically. Such motivation has
been adduced
for the features
[+ Change] (or Telic) and [+ Momentaneousness], which Vester introduces as a refinement of dynamic SoA-types. See
(1983)
also De Groot
(1985) . The data with the should
that I
basic
am going to explore in this paper confront us
question
revisions
going beyond
in
to
the
the SoA-typology
Conceptually, it is not difficult to think of SoAs as expressible
restricted
of
predication.
is
be
whether
nuclear
what
necessarily
the nuclear predication. The addition of
satellites and of temporal or aspectual specifications to a nuclear predication may
affect the
way in
case in some world*. My position broader conceptual
view of
which it reflects
in
this
paper
SoA-types can
'what is the
is
that
be accepted
such a
as a valid
perspective within which work on SoA-types can be undertaken. In section 2 Present-day
we
English
present data,
a to
number proceed
of
findings
with
an
relating to
analysis of Old
English data in a diachronic perspective in section 3. 2. Modality
types and states
2.1. Situations
and
of
affairs
events
As I have argued in Goossens (1985a),the basic insight behind a division of SoAs into two hyperclasses, is that non-epistemic facultative and deontic) modals SoAs, i.e. the
conceived
former
as
'being
'events',
Situations not only include
the
case*.
Steedman
the latter are called
states and
(i.e.
with controlled
actions and positions, whereas epistemic modals
SoAs which are labels
typically combine
require (1977)
'situations'.
processes, but
also other
SoA-types if they are in the progressive or perfective. The
distinction
explains
why
the
naturally interpreted as deontic ((1) ((2), (3), (4) and (6)) respectively. 1
and
following (5))
and
sentences
are
as epistemic
MODAL SHIFTS
23
(1)
John may speak Dutch [unprefixed action; nornally a permission]
(2)
John may be speaking Dutch [progressive action; normally
(3)
John must be Dutch [state; normally epistemic]
(4)
John may still grow an inch or two [process; normally epistemic]
(5)
John may stay where he is [position; normally permission]
(6)
John may have stayed where he is [perfective position; normally epistemic] In order
to illustrate
the opposition between facultative and
epistemic we can resort to can't English)
or
stressed
won't
(positive
{will
stricted
in its volitional
(7)
John can't be Dutch [state; epistemic]
(8)
John can't work any harder [action; facultative]
(9)
John won't be Dutch [state; epistemic]
(10)
John can't temic]
can is not
epistemic in
is becoming more and more re-
sense):
John won't work harder [action; facultative - if phrasable as 'refuses to']
(11)
epistemic]
have worked
not a
harder
future tense
we
have
indicated
the
validation of situations vs. not
absolute.
In
the
'normal'
reading.
events through
next
two
para-
[perfective action;
Obviously, for all of these instances, we can say no that
-
The
epis-
more than linguistic
modality is therefore
subsections
we provide
further
quali ficat ion. 2.2.
The predicate
operators
A first point where exemplified by (12) and (12)
Prosp[ective]and
refinement (13).
John may come tonight
appears
Hab[itual] to
be
in
order, is
24
OOOSSENS
(13)
John must go to the dentist quite regularly According to
what was
that both these sentences
said in
2.1., our prediction should be
are deontic:
non-progressive, non-perfective
facultative in Present-day English). but in
combine with a
may and
must are not
The prediction
is borne out,
can also interpret (12) and (13) as epistemic,
addition we
be it that John may he reading and
the modals
action (and
coming
tonight
is better
in the epistemic
that John must be going to the dentist quite
regularly
is at least as good. What is going on? [Prosp] (or
Semantically
(though neither of these is very expression). The make
events
the
combining
predication is
[Future]) 2 in (12) and [Hab] (or [Repetitive]) in (13) salient: they
get no grammatical
point then would simply be that [Prosp] and [Hab]
also
compatible
with
epistemic
modals;
the event
prefixed by Prosp or Hab can acquire 'situation-like' properties. There is,
however, a
complication. Deontic
volitional ones (within the with
a
[Prosp]
SoA
(again
this
modals as well as
group) 3
facultative
normally combine
'prospectiveness'
is not very
salient and is left unexpressed, at least in English). As [Prosp] actions
a result
and positions are compatible with both deontic and
epistemic must and may or with both volitional
and epistemic will,
which considerably weakens, it would seem, the discriminative force of the event: situation opposition, and hyper-SoAs within
therefore their
status as
FG. The way to partially restore the distinction
in this context is to emphasize again the epistemic reading
marked character
of the
in (12) and the fact that a progressive would be
more current as an alternative. With respect to (13), there is no such [Hab]
with
any
of
the
non-epistemic
context, the noteworthy point is that
favoured correlation of modality
types.
only epistemic
In this
modals would
have a progressive predication as a current alternative. The gist
of it
all is
that an
event prefixed
by [Prosp] or
[Hab] can shift category by acquiring a feature which we label, perhaps
a little
awkwardly, [+
however, the more current alternative of
choose to
situation-1 ike]. There is, turning the
event into a
MODAL SHIFTS
25
situation by Beans of [Progr]. Note in
addition that
in combination with facultative Bodals,
Hab (or Rep[etitive]) can also prefixed
to states,
as illustrated
by (14) and (15):« (14)
John can be absent-minded
(15)
Boys will be boys In
instances
like
these
there
is
a
shift
away
from the
subject-internal meaning which is characteristic of the facultative modal. 5
(14)
means
both
that
John
has
absent-minded and that occasionally he iB that boys
typically exhibit
all the
the
capacity of being
absent-minded; (15) says
characteristics that go with
boys because somehow that is the way they want to has been
called 'existential'
possible stages in the
and can
transition of
be said
be. This pattern to be
facultative to
one of the an epistemic
meaning (which has been developed by will, but not by can).6 2.3. Controlled
situations
With respect to the claim that situations trigger off epistemic readings, the
following sentences
can be
adduced as counterexam-
ples . (16)
You must be more polite to your mother
(17)
The men selected must be six feet tall at least
(18)
You must have finished before I come back
(19)
You must scene
(20)
Why won't he be nicer to her?
(21)
I can't be whispering if at the same whistle that 'got-to-do-my-best'-tune.
be whispering
Sentences (16)-(19)
to Celia when Orlando enters the
time
I
naturally invite a deontic interpretation,
(20) and (21) a facultative one, in spite of the fact that polite,
have to
be more
be six feet tall and be nicer are as a rule states, whereas
in the others an action is prefixed by Perf or Progr. Obviously, there are pragmatic
(or contextual)
reasons why it
26
is
GOOSSENS
the
non-epistemic
rather
than
the
epistemic
reading
that
suggests itself. In (16), (18) and (19), the deontic interpretation follows fron
the fact
that we
get a
sole indication of futurity for the with a
non-past modal
'be lore
second-person subject, plus
combining SoA
(in combination
polite* is easily understood as a
non-realized SoA; 'before I cone back' and 'when Orlando enters the scene* are
normally futurity
Barkers). For
(17) we nay imagine a
context in which the hearer will have to take care tion of
the SoA
of the realiza-
expressed (though here an inferential interpreta-
tion is quite acceptable as well). (20) is a question and therefore not open
to an
an ability,
epistemic reading; (21) actualizes the negation of
because
there
is
an
i/°-clause
which
considers an
obligation which is incompatible with 'be whispering'. At the
level of the SoAs with which the modals in (16) to (21)
combine, however, an additional point must be made.
All these SoAs
are made to fit the deontic or facultative context, because somehow they are viewed as controlled (or controllable) by by whoever
is responsible
for the
the subject (or
selection in (17)).7 Note that
for (16) and (20) one could also argue that a state ( b e nicer) has
been turned
into an
polite,
be
action by predicate formation. In
the other instances we can only interpret the
combining situations
as such, i.e. as 'something being the case', but with an additional meaning
dimension
that this
situation is viewed as controllable/
controlled. An FG representation would ously
optional)
feature
of
have to
include this
situations;
as an (obvi-
(18), for example, would
contain the following predication:® (22)
[perf
[finish»
(you)**
]*ctlon
jsituation [ +
2.4. SoA-types
and modality-types:
a refined
controllable]
correlation
Taking into account the foregoing we can establish ing correlation SoA.
between the
the follow-
different modality types and types of
MODAL SHIFTS
27
Epistemic socials (i)
as a rule combine with situations, i.e. states, processes, perfective SoAs, progressive SoAs
(ii)
are occasionally compatible with prospective and habitual events, which are then viewed as [+ situation-like]
Deontic and facultative models (i)
as a rule require an event, i.e. non-perfective action or position
(ii)
are also tions
compatible
For facultative aodals there
a non-progressive,
with controllable/controlled
is an
additional qualification: they
can coobine with [Hab] SoAs (including states) to produce tial' meanings which
can
be
regarded
as
turn to
readings.
a number of diachronic data to see how they
can enrich our insight they will
'existen-
contaminations between
facultative (internal) readings and 'external* Let's now
situa-
into states
of affairs.
At the
same time
be used as a (partial) testing-ground for the hypotheses
formulated so far. 3. Data
from
diachrony
In Goossens English
(1985c) and (1987) I
samples
of
cunnai?,
what we know about their later demonstrate
from
these
aagan
development we
analyses
about. In this context those shifts point
of
what
they
have
to
present analyses and aotan.
of late Old
Taking into account can to
some extent
how new developments are coming are looked
at from
the view-
tell us about the ways in which we
conceptualize SoAs. 3.1.
cunnan From the
making its of 200)®
cunnan
sample
it can
be demonstrated
how cunnan is
appearance onto the modal scene. In 64 * (of the sample
cunnan
arguments, some
is
a full
predicate, meaning
'knowing' (cognizant)
'know'. It
entity (xi) and some
has two 'know-
able' entity X2. Those cases are not considered here. The ability-sense, which is
still
very
marginal,
appears to
28
GOOSSENS
have developed along the following path: X2 is realized by means of an infinitive (in a bit less than 20 % of the sample), that we
which means
get the shift from 'knowable entity' to a SoA. This SoA is
typically one that involves cognizance (as in (23)), combined with
agency (for
or cognizance
which we use 'potency' as a cover term)
(e.g. (24)) (23)
Forgif me wisdom f)»t ... ic cunne tocnawan betwux Give me wisdom that ... I can/may discern between god and yfel good and evil 'Give me wisdom so that I may discern between good and evil' (¿KCHom II, 45 336.28)
(24)
Ne canst huntian buton aid nettum Not can you hunt except with nets 'You can't hunt except with nets' («Coll 61) The relevance for our discussion of SoA-types is as follows. In
the acquisition
of
cognizance have
a special
cognizance want
of
an
in their a
better
ability-sense part to
pure form term)
are
for
cunnan
SoAs involving
play. Note that SoAs involving
(henceforth 'cognizant states,
SoAs', for
but then states which are
compatible with ability (and the other non-epistemic modalities for that matter).
A recognition
of cognizant
states as distinct from
other states within FG's SoA typology seems therefore in order. 3.2. mag an In late Old English magan is still predominantly modal. This
is duly
reflected in
(1987). At the same time the sample indicates from this
subject-internal type
a facultative
the sample analysed in Goossens the increasing shift
of meaning towards the 'external'
meanings which in later English develop into the permission reading that may will acquire and, later still, into its epistemic sense. Working
with
the
categories
internal, internal/external and
external, we found the distribution presented in table I. 1 0
MODAL
SHIFTS
29
Table
A
I:
Distribution
Internal
B
MAGAN
We
give A,
B
100)
Internal/External
47
plify
(total
C
External
28
one and
instance C
per
25
category:
(25),
(26)
and
(27)
exem-
respectively.
(25)
ne bii he para ahta h l a f o r d ponne hi ne dslan n o t is he of the goods lord when then not distribute ne m e g not can 'he is n o t t h e l o r d of t h e g o o d s if he can't share them o u t * ( « C H o m I, 4 66.5) [general ability, not the "physical ability* w h i c h u s e d to be the core m e a n i n g of aagan at an earlier s t a g e of the language]
(26)
...
J u d a s ... s m e a d e wi& hi hu he Crist him Judas d e l i b e r a t e d w i t h them how he Christ to-then belzwan mihte betray might 'Judas deliberated with them how he might betray Christ t o t h e m ' ( « C H o n I, 1 2 6 . 2 2 ) ( J u d a s ' a b i l i t y is d e p e n d e n t on his personal ability and on 'external' arrangements)
(27)
&urh eastdael m z g o n b e o n g e t a c n o d e p a on through east may be s i g n i f i e d t h o s e t h a t in g e o g o & e to g o d e b u g a i f o r p a n &e ... youth to G o d turn because 'Through the east we nay signify those that c o m e to w h e n t h e y a r e y o u n g ' (fiCHom I , 8 1 3 0 . 2 3 ) Looking
external I could
for
the
possibility discern
is
'track' takes
along
place,
correlated
which
the
I found
with
the
shift
that
type
of
from
God
internal
to
the m a i n
factor
that
SoA
which
aagan
with
comb ines. As under
is A
to
be
expected,
and
B,
and
categories, first
two
cognizant
there
is
categories states
non-cognizant
ones.
we
states
typically in C.
a striking and
(e.g.
Moreover,
in
the
'see', there
is
non-states
states
difference
those
geseon
get
Though
occur
between
third.
the
striking
the
those
In A
tocnawan
('events')
in
and
three in
the
B we
get
'know'), presence
in
C
among
30
GOOSSENS
the 'external' instances of passives ((27) happens, all
is an
instance): as it
in our sample give rise to an external
five passives
interpretation. It is tempting, therefore, to think of passives as belonging to situations (and SoA-type
of
of passivization as a process which may affect the
the
illustrates,
nuclear
some
of
salient) permissive
predication).
these
However, can
instances
sense as
well. This
as
(27)
also
be given (a not very
would be
an argument to
maintain their original event-status. A consideration teaches us,
I
of the
think,
that
following present-day English examples passives
(which
typically
build on
original actions) can go either way: (28)
John won't be convinced
(29)
John must be convinced
(28) and
(29) are ambiguous between an epistemic and a non-episte-
mic reading. In (28) stressed won't can be to'
(the
facultative
reading),
in
paraphrased by
'refuses
(29) must can be interpreted
deontically. In those cases the normal reading would be to take 'be convinced' in a process or action meaning. If we interpret (28) and (29) epistemically the natural reading is words,
it
would
seem
that
passives
a stative can
situation:event dichotomy (the emphasis
go
can be
one. In other
either way in the on the action-pro-
cess or on the resulting state). Looking at (30) and (31), however, we find that other passive events do not
readily invite
a stative
interpretat ion. (30)
John must be told straight away
(31)
John won't be kept out of this
In
these
both
proceed to a obligation;
cases
the
non-epistenic (31)
SoA retains its event-character and we interpretation
as meaning
the future tense reading). The that
passives
from
'refuses to', conclusion
[+contro1]-verbs
events and situations, whereas
(we
take
(30)
as an
at least if we exclude therefore
seems
to be
sometimes alternate between
(more often?)
they simply maintain
MODAL SHIFTS
31
their event-status. 3.3. so tan Diachronically, the
main question
about Old
English aotan is
how it developed an obligational sense, whereas its core is clearly permissive.
This
is
not
to
say
that aotan can semantically be
reduced to just Permission and Obligation. aotan-sample
In the
analysis of the
the following categories suggested themselves:
A Permission (an
external possibility
human/institutional/divine
authority)
A/B Permission/Obligation
(instances
which is
which
dependent on some
were
both compatible
with a permission and an obligation reading) B Obligation (the external authority creates an obligation) A/C Permission/Ability also some focus on
(besides
the
permission
subject-internal potential,
element there is though in
none of
these instances we get a purely internal meaning) (A/B)/D (Permission/Obligation)/Contingency
(the
impact
of some,
human or other, authority has been considerably weakened; other and vaguer external
circumstances are involved; the realization of the
SoA appears as contingent) A/E Permission/Wish (in addition to
the
permission,
there
is an
overtone that the SoA is wished for) Disregarding most
of the
syntactic contexts
guished in my earlier analysis, I
present the
which I distin-
distribution of the
relevant subtypes in table II. The distinction between positive and negative sentences is retained, because it is relevant I want to discuss next.
for a point
32
GOOSSENS
Table II: Distribution of motan (total 100)
Positive A
A/B
B
A/C
(A/B)/D (P/0)/Cont
Perm.
Perm/0
Obi.
Perm/Ab
31
4
12
9
Prohib ition
Absence of Obi.
Prohib/ Neg.Ab.
17
2
6
3
A/E Perm/Wish 16
Negative
As can be inferred from this table, 10E motan atill has a clear permission core, giving rise to (A/B)/D,
A/E)
on
the
instances under B) on exemplify categories
one
all
sorts
of
blends
(A/B, A/C,
hand, and shifting to obligation (the
the other.
The four
instances which follow
A and B, both in a positive and in a negative
context. (32)
ealswa bealdlice mot se feowa clypian god hin to as confidently may the slave call God him to fmder ealswa se cyning father as the king 'as confidently as the king the slave can call God his father' (CCHom I, 19 260.23) [positive permission]
(33)
we motan eow secgan eowre sawle pearfe, licige eow we must you tell of your soul need please to-you ne licige eow, pzt ... not please to-you in order that 'we must tell you about your souls'need, whether it please you or not* («CHom I, 17 (App) 182.240) [obligation ]
MODAL SHIFTS
33
(34)
... and hi to £am men cwsdon (3e xr gehsled wss, and they to the nan said that before cured was Hit is halig restendag; ne most &u styrigan (?ine it is holy rest-day; not must you move your beddinge bed "and they said to the man who had been cured: "This is a holy day of rest; you cannot/may not/must not move your bed"' (iCHom 2 42)
(35)
Cristene men ne aoton healdan nu 4a ealdan s Christian men not need observe now the old law lichamlice ac ... bodily but 'Christians no longer need observe the old law bodily, but ...' (iECHom II, 15 151.36) [Absence of obligation] An analysis of the
with these earlier.
kinds of
two deontic We
typically
instances quoted
SoA that
we find
in combination
modality types confirms what we postulated get
we have
controlled
SoAs
("events').
In the
actions in (32), (33) and (34); for (35)
we may hesitate between an action and a position. Besides, we get a few instances
of states,
but, typically,
cognizant states (as in
(36)). (36)
he ... fancode georne gode (3«t he hine geseon he thanked eagerly God that he him behold aoste might/could 'he thanked God eargerly that he could behold him' (iCHom I, 142.23) There is one instance where a situation (process) is viewed as
controllable, namely (37). (37)
&a se eadiga laurentius ... bemznde flat he ne when the blessed laurentius complained that he not •oste mid his lareowe (>rowian: fa ... could with his teacher suffer : then 'when the blessed Laurentius complained that he could not suffer with his teacher' (jECHomI,29 418.5) As is
to be expected, the differentiation of SoAs developed so
far does not help to account for the shift from the permission core to the
obligational meaning of must in later English. What are the
factors then that have played
a
part
in
this
change?
A closer
34
GOOSSENS
inspection
of
my
they exhaustively
sample
has revealed two. Without claiming that
'explain' the
shift, I
think they
are at least
ingredients in whatever nay count as a real explanation. 11 A first denied
factor relates
permission
oversimplifying
amounts
"logical*
to the
negative instances
under A. A
to
obligation-not-to;
to
an
equation:
n
PERM
p
use an
= OBL w p. Under
negation the distinction between a permission and an
obligation is
largely neutralized. This leaves us with the positive instances, however, as well as with those where the cases under
negation is
B, positive
factor, a more precise
external to
and negative).
the obligation (the
At this
characterization of
point our second
the SoAs,
may help to
uncover what is involved. In a
permission some authority (the speaker in cases where the
permission is created by case of
the very
speech act,
the hearer
in the
a requested permission, or some other authority) is viewed
as not obstructing/requested not to obstruct the realization of the SoA with
which the
an authority realization
is of
permission is concerned. In an obligation such
viewed the
as
SoA
exerting
that
its
authority
towards the
the obligation concerns. A crucial
point here is the appreciation of the SoA by the one who is granted the permission, or, who is held to attend to the realization of the 'obligated' SoA. In the case of a permission viewed positively,
the permitted
negatively (as unwelcome, as difficult etc.). The combination modal
expressing
permission
with a SoA which in the negatively, gives
(at
of a
least in the majority of cases)
given context
can be
taken to
be viewed
rise to an obligational meaning. This is what we
witness in the obligational 'viewed negatively'
SoA is
in the case of an obligation this SoA is viewed
instances in
our sample.
The feature
is saliently present in all the cases under B.
In (35) for example, this appears from the added phrase
licige eow
ne licige eow ('whether it please you or not'): the 'deontee' (as a rule the subject of aotan, here the we) finds it the hearers
{eow) about
difficult to tell
their souls' need to the extent that what
he has to say may displease them. How should such a feature ("viewed negatively or
positively by
MODAL SHIFTS
35
the deontee') be integrated into FG? As far as I can see, this is a pragmatic feature to be
attached
to
events
or controllable/con-
trolled situations. The justification, as I hope to have demonstrated, is linguistic in that
it
helps
to
explain
the
shift from
permissive to obligational. 4.
Conclusion Let's review
for the
the foregoing, both with respect to its relevance
characterization
respect to
of
the implications
predication of such
types
in
an enriched
FG
and with
characterization
for a treatment of modality. (i) There are reasons to
introduce
two
classes
of 'hyper-SoAs',
which (for want of a better term) we label events and situations. Events
are
controlled
SoAs,
they
encompass
unprefixed
(i.e.
non-perfective and non-progressive) actions and positions. Situations are concerned with 'what is the case'
and uncontrolled;
they
Perf(ective)
include
states
and
Progr(essive) SoAs (obviously
processes
and
and
'aspectual' considerations govern the
combination of Progr with the basic SoAs) Epistemic modals (i.e. deontic
as a
rule require situations, non-epistemic ones
and facultative
modals) combine
with events. This,
however, is no more than a (strongly) preferential correlation. (ii) Among the basic SoA-types cognizant states have to be recognized as a separate class, distinct predicates
(like
know,
from other
understand,
states. They include
see, hear etc.) with a first
argument we may call cognizant. Cognizant states differ from other SoA-types in that
in unprefixed
occurrence, they freely combine with both epistemic and non-epistemic modals. 1 2 (iii) Another predicate operator
(besides
appears
of
to
affect
the
status
Perf
and
Progr) which
a basic SoA is Hab(itual) (or
Rep(etitive)). Hab SoAs appear to be compatible with both epistemic and non-epistemic modals. It is
not clear
to me,
however, whether Hab SoAs should be given
36
GOOSSENS
the status of a hyper-SoA like those in (i). (iv) Passivization can both with
the
control
leave an
disensión
(in
Obviously, state-passiveB can be
event controlled
the
case
assigned
or do away
of a state-passive).
to
situations
and are
compatible with epistemic modality. (v) Situations
can be
qualified by
a feature controlled/control-
lable. This Bakes then compatible with non-epistemic modals, though they retain
their character
of being
concerned with 'what is the
case'. (vi) Events can be further characterized [viewed
positively
by
the
deontee]. Such features may
by a
(pragmatic) feature
deontee] or [viewed negatively by the help
to
account
for
the difference
between permissions and obligations. Summing
up
at
the
level
formulated above advocate the SoA-type (cognizant
of the FH>
The principles when
eration
here,
affairs
(SoA
knowledge
The
uttering
- i.e.
in
this
property
of
(>H>)
intended here, particularly, the
mic cf.
and
Q
1983:396).
modality; Horn
or
various
SoA
Thus
in
some the
the SoA in
N)
degrees
ranges of
one,
for
only
(Mx)
degrees
non-absolute
More
in
(Q)
affect
relation-
polarity
(in
(De Schutter
and
cases
of
not
the
the
level
concepts).
only
consider
SoA
world
'x' h a v i n g
a Q does
of
examples
the q u a l i f i c a t i o n
deontic modality
the
of
the
concerning both
from a b s o l u t e
considstate
piece
In
person
but
modality
X only
under
in
(9).
representational
(normally,
involves of
type
particular
but
the SoA,
and
paper
non-occurrence
items,
discussed
understand
a small
involves
complex
Q
of
concerned with
entities -
a
(sic - at
the reasoning
this
of the
with
are
to
conversation).
lexical
is
(In t h i s
but
and
concerned
are no
is a
(1978))
occurrence
construction
is
the
system
suffice
a
this
negativity
concerned, over
the
this
will
"crazy-ness"
there
of
representational
in
relationship
examples
Nuyts
paper
expression
conceptualization
the speaker
existence
ship), our
>H>
the
uttered
provided
of the
this
following
the speaker
to be
syntactic
crazy-ness
behind
(1985).
Basically,
choice
N/Mx
>
Nuyts
>
with
is
episte-
identical
likelihood
the
possible
positiveness
qualification
of
in
of
the a
-
the
world SoA,
gradual
NEGATIVE
order and
RAISING
from
rather
resulting
implies
chically
equal:
that The
use
they
that
neither
(10)
Probably
This
he
construction
must
share
Since
some
from
handle
to u s e
this
too
recourse
to t h e
The (9)
the
at
are
this
hierai—
(Which does
not
constructions
s u c h as
(la-b),
He m i g h t
as
well
crazy expresses of
FG/FPG
in s y n t a c t i c in
this
representational
is,
various level
of options
the with
it
case,
same meaning. (5a-d)
in t h e
is a g a i n
terms
Thus
it
grammar.
inappropriate
(the structural
too,
level
then,
of
one will
contained
can
embedded
clause)
either
(in t h e m a i n
clause)
positive
PA-predicate
course,
about
degrees
is o f
the
the
to
changes
have
in
to
(9)
is r a t h e r (3b-7b)
an
are
(11),
this
a
has
to
take
as
the
in
expression on
some
the
(at
the
(in
can
least
express
such
(3a-b)
latter if the
or
as
of
value
prediin
of
the
Q.
view,
it
(la-b),
are not.
Of
other,
above
possibilities
a
with
(7a-b)).
to e a c h
the
in the
propositional
the
exact of
the
number
the Q
SoA
and he
and
of the
while of
a
expressed by means
options
pairs
choice
with
has
realizing
(3a-b)
the basis
utterance
in m e a n i n g ,
shows
his
To s t a r t
of
one,
(2a-b),
the
conceptualization
a negative
incorporation
that,
see why
or
can be
to a t t u n e
note
related which
PA
negative
contained
appropriate
respect, easy
or
for
or n e g a t i v e ,
a positive
And
of
the speaker
expression
positive
it.
determine
in F G / F P G .
(la-b),
particularly the
of n e g a t i v e type
speaker
to get
In this
make either
(PA)
various
types
disposal,
speaker
attitude
factors
realizations
the p r e d i c a t i o n s
in c o n s t r u c t i o n at h i s
what
alternative
The
schema
the other.
neutral, that
below.)
of r e p r e s e n t a t i o n
fundamental),
alternatives
and
Note
factors
conceptualization.
basically
question the
order
totally
SoA.
level.
between
cate
via
the
(10).
is n o t
level
of
over
obliged
relationship
are much
(9).
scope
the perspective
this
common
has
s u c h as
negative
and modality
- see
is n o t
constructions
rather
negativity
interfere
to e x p r e s s
etc.
to
the polarity
do n o t
speaker
(2a-b),
positive
in a b s o l u t e
analysis mean
113
(3a-7a) Consider of
using
114 NUYTS
PA-predicates for expressing various degrees of PAs. of
predicates
on
this
(The placement
scale is intuitive. The classification
is
only intended to be roughly appropriate.
In general, there seems to
of variability
in the degree of polarity
be a
considerable range
expressed
by
each
predicate,
contextual
factors.)
the
precise
value
being
due to
(U) N impossible
doubt
uncertain
not-believe
+
possible
not-know
believe
not-impossible
improbable It is conceptually express
a
(not
negative
pragmatically -
PA
opposite positive PA
about
a
see below)
(N being the turning point)
about the negated
each time SoA
(la-b), (3a-7a), and (3b-7b) express 'he is
in the
crazy'. But
(3a-b) definitely
PA-predicate does not only
the polarity of the PA expressed, but also its modal is
only
a
correspondence between
their negatives, and PAs and their rather
positive
negative in (3b)
and
The
rather
does
negative proposition negative
not
opposites, in
negative
indicated
the
(which,
before
can
the case
for
the
change
main
clause
of be
influences
other way,
(lb)
(5a)
and
course,
is
correlated
utterance
weaker
is weaker (6a).
clause
from
the
a
the
modality that the
matter
with
one
(i.e.
with
a
more
This
than
(8),
of
modality)
variable
in our
negative in
explicitly
negative
closer to N in (11)) than the utter-
ance with an equivalent, but less explicitly negative Thus
of the
too. Note
the degree of explicitness of the
the PA-predicate. An PA-predicate is
value, and as
lexical items and
in (3a) to its positive alternative in (3b).
in
constructions, viz.
influence
PAs. Thus, the main
compensate
expressed by the predicate in some weakness-effect
to
or to express the
The negative there
equivalent
proposition,
about the same Q of the
such,
know
not-improbable
proposition. Thus, do not.
certain
probable
and
relationship
(5d) and (6d) are seems
to
hold
PA-predicate. weaker
than
even between
NEGATIVE
RAISING
115
non-incorporated clearly the
weaker
and
than
differences
with
a number
confirmed
The
about
difference etc.
is
these this
rather
variants respect
(10)
as
small,
clearer
such
functional
as
focal
of e i t h e r
value
this
account).
(5a)
also
the
topicality (5b) w i l l
The a Q
of a
as
o f t h e Q,
a significant
(cf.
De Schutter
But
the
(la-b)
reduce
choice
to
between
nature,
alternatives
and
in
such
as
of either, chosen
the p r o p o s i t i o n or v i c e
versa.
pragmatic
the n e g a t i v i t y
on
clause);
or b o t h
the main
in
an
too).
they
can
have
intonational
stress
on
(10) m i g h t
chosen
if
be
other
(the
hand,
between in
focal, of
the
but
focal SoA
in
chosen
modality
can b e
an
Focus
is
of
Hence,
a strong
clause
the n e g a t i v e there
compo-
not.
does has
the modality
kinds
two
that
(5b)
result
can be
different
the
is
in t e r m s
the
E.g.,
then,
negativity)
embedded
stress
(i.e.,
(5b),
between
distinction
factor.
the of
and
the
and
or
for
in g e n e r a l
(5a),
it,
the principles
the
in the
of
a much
(1985)
whereas
if t h e Q
part
allow
topical
distinction vs.
(10), in
(5a)
(which will
on
or a
functional
modality
to
difference
between
topical
clause,
It
alternain
certainly
pragmatic
compared
and the negativity
result
explain
(6b-6c).
the speaker's
difference
be
is a s t r o n g
and
of
or f o c a l i t y
topical,
if t h e r e
reasons
can
alternatives
consideration
(5a-b),
(the
probably
while
is
case
allows
of
factor
the
the
in o u r p a i r s .
and
in c o n t e x t ,
in
to be
into
distinction
in
(9))
seems
take
proposition
value,
can,
factor
for
(3a-7a),
choice between
(6a-6d)
e x p r e s s e d by and
observation
speaker's
these
well.
Utterances
nents
the
completely among
too.
the variants
The main can
kind,
are
tested
utterances
(la-b),
between
rather
we
of this
(5b-5c),
(6b) -
responsible
choice
in t h e m o d a l i t y
relevant.
be
variants this
for
these nearly
whether
(5a-5d),
and
relationships
might our
alternatives
of
the results
weakness
variable
account
as
equivalents
and
between
(5b)
- informally
however,
the
does
such
hardly
is,
(I h a v e
Dutch
about
this
and the other
undoubtedly
the
weakness
question
everything tives
So, in
variants:
(6c).
speakers,
intuitions
utterances.) (3b-7b),
and
between
of native
my
difference
incorporated
(5c)
focal
intonational for -
different which
in t h e
is a r a t h e r
will
embedded
small
prag-
116 NUYTS
matic distinctiveness
between the
of (9). The negativity
in itself nay still be in focus: this can be
marked by intonational stress on If
this
analysis
accurate, this
at
of
once
pragmatic functionality
modality and the SoA components
not.
the
differences
implies
that
of FG,
the
of utterances
matter, as is claimed in the current
in pragmatic terms is determination
of the
is not a post-predicational
(i.e.
Dik 1978-based) version
but a pre-predicational matter, as is claimed in FPG.
(That
the pragmatic functions deserve a more central place in the grammar has been recognized
in a number of other publications
ture as well - e.g. Hannay 1985, Bolkestein propose a pre-predicational
in FG-litera-
1985. But
status of the pragmatic
they do not
functionality.)
Pragmatic functions such as Topic and Focus must be assigned on the basis of
representational
level
(9), since
choice of the underlying predications.
they co-determine
the
In fact, there is a need
for
pragmatic notions at an even more basic level. For the differentiation between the alternatives on the back to network
decisions on
which is relevant
and
the
communicative
speaker's hypothesis is
whether
of the
discourse
a SoA
in
a
be
carried
in the
situational
under
consideration or
network
(CSN
a
important factor nature, has
negative
viz.
the
been
at this
the question
present
form,
in the
and whether the
modality of the SoA has been under discussion or not. assignment of topicality/focality
situa-
to the hearer's knowledge of the
SN). One
discourse-functional positive
world knowledge of
in a particular communicative
with respect
same facts as involved level
(9) can
(SN in (9) - i.e. the complete piece of
the speaker tion)
basis of
the basis of a comparison of the situational
in (9) is strongly
In fact, the (but certainly
not uniquely) determined by the need to create utterances which are adequately
discourse
thematicity/rhematicity (9) at
the level
bound,
and
as
such it is sensitive to the
and givenness/newness
of
the
elements in
of the SN/CSN (which represents the level of the
discourse/text) (cf. De Schutter and Nuyts 1983:389, 392 has been noted before - e.g. Hannay
(1985) - that these
pragmatic notions, which are only implicit in the
ff.).
(It
discourse-
FG conception of
the pragmatic functions at the sentence level, should obtain a more
NEGATIVE
RAISING
117
explicit role in FG. FPG provides room for The problem with the ences and hardly
similarities between
accessible
extensive
corpus
on
purely
analysis
is
that the differ-
variants are very subtle, and thus intuitive
might
insight into the variety of determination
their,introduction.)
PA-construction-type
be
factors
grounds.
Probably,
an
helpful in gaining a better involved.
At
least
for the
of the discourse functional factors this would be the
case; but I doubt that the other aspects the intricate
semantic interaction
be enlightened
in
required. But
whatever the
how one will ever
that be
way.
In
of the
phenomenon - e.g.
of polarity and modality - can any
case,
further
research is
ultimate picture will be, I do not see
able
to
account
pattern of relationships and factors
fully
for
the intricate
involved with a model which is
less sophisticated than FPG. 4. The representation
of the
'raised'
construction
A different aspect of accounting for the relationship
between
(lb),
the PA-constructions
(2b), etc.
on the
involves
one hand,
and
constructions of the type of (4) on the other hand. As mentioned 2.,
in
the
traditional
pragmatic
PA-constructions have been representation as
(4). But
(4) the negative is distinct, while,
clained
approach to
as we
to NR, the
underlying
the problem with that claim
is that in
and thus
the
'raised'
same
strongly focal,
have
in
pragmatically
quite
have noted in 3., in the PA-constructions,
the negative is not pragmatically distinct at all. Rather, it seems that a
construction such
as (lb), for example, can be assigned at
least three different readings, in which the negative each time has a different noted that three
functionality (lb) can
different
intonation
difference, viz. the
main
with
clause
or
negative and predicate, variant would with stress on
(scope).
In this respect, it should be
be pronounced
rather be believe.
with
contours,
a neutral with either
a
(at which
least) the following clearly
(slightly rising) clear with
uttered with
mark
this
intonation in
intonational break between stress
on
don't
the non-reduced
(but this do not),
or
118 NUYTS
The reading which has tional pragmatic
been under
consideration
in
the tradi-
approach, then, is the one with the stress on the
negative. This reading is more or
less equivalent
to (4), indeed,
and its meaning can conceptually be represented as (12). (12)
not > =
I.e.,
the
speaker
negates
(holding the view) that main clause entirely
the SoA
predicate does
proposition
the
SoA which involves his believing 'x is
'believe he is crazy' is
in
the
scope
crazy' might
not express
of
be true.
in
itself
a
SoA,
which is
the main clause negative. Whether the
speaker will use (lb) or (4) for that purpose most probably on purely
The
modality anymore; and the
depends
pragmatic factors, such as the degree of focality of the
negative, or the desire of the speaker to
'echo' the
utterance in
which a hearer has claimed that the speaker holds the belief that x is crazy. The meaning of the reading of (lb) with
stress on
believe
can
be conceptually represented as (13). (13)
not Q
In this
utterance, the speaker denies that the view which he holds
with respect to the predicate. Thus, by uttering hold a Again,
embedded
SoA
iB
the
one
expressed
unlike the case conceptually represented
(lb) this way the speaker clearly suggests that he does
view on believe
the Q
of the
SA, but
he leaves
open which one.
does not express modality here.
Only the utterance of (lb) with neutral intonation clause is
a genuine
PA-construction
tically equivalent to (la)). negative is
somehow
involved
(only
As indicated,
in the main
this reading is semanin this
utterance the
in expressing the combination of the
modality and polarity factors in the Q in schema ally,
by the in (12),
(9), and
function-
it simply constitutes a unity together with the verb.
But how
should we
handle these different
relationships
in our
NEGATIVE
RAISING
119
g r a m m a r ? First, consider (lb), and
(4).
construction, tion.
It
is reasonable
it in a cleft case)
status
factivity)
seems
cleft
acceptable
but that not,
A
which of
such
at
the as
to
it is not
(it is p o s s i b l e
to
accounted
for
constructions (lb) and
in b a s i c a l l y are handled to
accept
(Dik
he has
again, the
done
that he
such as
1980a:210ff).
(4)
done
do
not
of
to Dik's
allow
the negative.
treatment
this account,
of
cleft
representation
in common w i t h non-focal u t t e r a n c e s
necessary
in (9)
clefts and
same SoA.
to account
In this respect, note also
and p s e u d o - c l e f t s underlying functions, postulated
requires the
predication
with
excommunicating in FG.
representation,
it
for what
the
is not
really
in the
and
degree can
pseudo-cleft
which
have no
nevertheit
level
treatment of
of
a special
distribution
pragmatic
function
of
seems of the
grammar, for
clefts type of
pragmatic
assignment
deeper
n e c e s s a r y at all to introduce in the
a
But
the u t t e r a n c e s have in
If one is w i l l i n g to introduce a
arbitrary c o m p l i c a t i o n
to
pseudo-clefts
that Dik's fixed
for
syntax,
So, in these cases
introduction a
of us
again to take r e c o u r s e to a representational
indicated
that
The same remark
In
express the
means
(one reading o f ) (lb) and
constructions. less b a s i c a l l y
should be
rules would b e inappropriate.
FG-representations
distinctiveness
it, upon
pseudo-cleft
This
to the FG/FPG principles
for the fact that for the speaker
b e m a d e with respect
or less
embedded it hardly
has
(4) can express the s a m e SoA, w h i l e they only differ
common.
epistemic
the
different u n d e r l y i n g p r e d i c a t i o n s
in terms of s y n t a c t i c
of p r a g m a t i c
kind
it an
the
in
the same way as cleft and
in FG
(4), for, according
correlation then,
noun'
give
nature).
it seems that constructions
necessary
account
that
say not
and thus is of quite a d i f f e r e n t
is
follow
'dummy
can
once p r e d i s p o s e s
SoA
usually
f o c u s s i n g upon
is not a c o n s t r u c t i o n w h i c h can be used for f o c u s s i n g
In any case,
it
and
e.g.) which
cleft
construc-
does not
the insertion of a
(so,
(13) of
to the
argue that it is a cleft
requires
element
independent
reading akin
in linguistic structures,
construction
status
predication.
(4) is functionally
to a s s u m e that, since not
status
or another
(the
relationship between
and one might even
h a v e an independent (the
the
In principle,
as
level of this more
then one can
120 NUYTS
sinply assume has been
the pragmatic
argued above),
placement
of
functions to be pre-predicational
and to
constituents,
determine not
but
also
the
(as
only the syntactic
elementary
choice of
construction types and the lexical elements in them. On the accept
other hand,
three
consider the
different
readings of utterance representations
underlying
(lb). Doing so
would cause
we should
for
the
three
problems for the
in FG, for then it would be necessary to find a way
to mark the differences in matters these underlying do this.
question whether predications
It is
sufficient to
three readings
of
predications. But, at the
scope
handle the
conceptual
of
the
negation in
again, it is not necessary
level
distinction between
to our
of representation, and to
assume that in expressing them, the different
representations
are
mapped onto one predication, viz. the one with a negative as predicate
operator
in
the
main
clause.
The
conceptual
distinction
between them is indicated, then, by using other expressive such as intonation, which can mark
the specific
devices,
conceptual
status
of the negative. 5.
Conclusion
The picture here is
very
of PA- and related constructions which I have sketched incomplete
sufficiently clear
and
fragmentary.
Yet,
in deciding whether FG needs expansion, and if tion. I
have indicated
each
not only
utterances, but
time for the
so, in
what
necessary
to
between this
these predications
assume that
additional
the FG-predications, and co-determine the predications,
functional
role
direcbetween
accept a
level
not only
in
differences
also for their conceptual
ties. And each time, it is necessary to functions operate sion of
it was
of representation than the underlying predications
FG if one is to account, between these
hope
a number of different relationships
constructions, for which it is deeper level
I
to show that this topic can play a central
similari-
the pragmatic
and the level of the actual
expres-
but also the very basic constitution of
itself.
Hence, the above analysis suggests the following
conclusions:
NEGATIVE
121
RAISING
(i) It indicates the need for a much and for
more abstract
more powerful
representations
model than FG,
than the underlying
predica-
(ii) As such, it also indicates that one of the principles
underly-
tions in FG.
ing Dik's conception of FG, viz. that a linguistic theory should be concrete, and
as close
utterances, might the
Wittgensteinian
functional levels of
as possible
to the
surface of
linguistic
in fact be untenable. Rather, it seems to confirm
approach
claim to
that
a
language
consistent
application
automatically
of a
leads to abstract
argumentation.
(iii) Therefore, the above analysis appears to confirm the FPG-view that
speaking
is
essentially
a
matter
of
finding
an optimal
lexicalization and syntactic expression for a thought, in the light of an intricate network of underlying cognitive-pragmatic
relation-
ships .
NOTES *
I am grateful to J. van der Auwera, M. Bolkestein, S. Gillis, I. Goossens, C. de Groot, L. Mackenzie, G. de Schutter, and J. Verschueren; and to M. Hannay for pointing out some small but unpleasant mistakes.
Voice in Ancient Greek: Reflexives and passives Rodie Risselada Department of Classics, University of Amsterdam
0.
Introduction*
In Functional Graaaar, the syntactic function Subject is defined as 'that constituent which refers to the point
of
departure
(or
state of affairs in
entity which
is taken
as a
perspective) for the presentation of the
which it
participates' (cf.
Dik 1978:87-88).
Subject assignment is relevant only in those languages in which the function
Subject
arguaent
but
is
Bay
not
be
autonatically
assigned
to
possibility leads to an opposition
assigned
to
the
first
other arguments as well. This of
voice,
naaely
an unaarked
active voice, which indicates that Subject is assigned to the first arguaent, versus
a
narked
passive
voice,
which
indicates that
Subject is assigned to another arguaent. Languages with a clear-cut active-passive opposition are e.g. Dutch, English and Latin. The Ancient Greek voice addition
to
an
active
so-called aiddle voice.
systea is
and
a
more conplicated,
passive
The aiddle, which
voice,
it
is only
since in
has a third, to sone extent
fornally distinguished froa the passive, expresses various types of reflexivity
and
cannot
assignaent. In this
be
article, I
Greek voice systea on
the
basis
defined
in
teras
of
Subject
propose a unified treataent of the of
the
FG
concept
of Valency
Reduct ion. 1. Voice in Ancient Greek In addition to the active-passive opposition, exeaplified in: (1) a.
b.
the
ho aner zeugnusi tous hippous the aansubj yokesAct the horses 'the aan is yoking the horses' hoi hippoi zeugnuntai hupo tou andros the horsessubj are-being-yokedxp by the aan 'the horses are being yoked by the nan' [Mp = middle-passive]
Greek
voice
systea
contains another opposition, naaely that
124
RISSELADA
between
active
and niddle,
terms
of
reflexivity.
verbal
morphology,
(together between
with
in
infinitive four
tense
(2)
infinitive
are
the
is
an
is t h a t
Ancient
tenses
large group of Greek
given
in
verbs
middle
in the
Creek
distinguish
example,
of a
the active,
in
in all
As
usually,
factor
encoded
does not
middle.
endings
of
the
active
The
defined,
in
(the
(2)
the
so-called
and passive
in
the
middle
and
stems:
present aorist perfect future fact
passive
being
complicating
voice
and mood),
and
endings
thematic verbs)
latter
extra
which
tense
the p a s s i v e
the
An
middle
-ein -sai -kenai -sein
that,
are not
in
justified
label
instance,
a sentence
thematic
verbs:
passive
-esthai -sasthai -(th)enai -sthai -sesthai -(th)esesthai
the
formally
so-called
present
and
distinguished
'middle-passive like
(3)
perfect leads
voice'. can
tenses,
to the
In
morphologically
the present
have
a
number
of
tense,
for
different
interpretat ions: (3)
ho stratos the armysubj a. b. c.
(a)
is
'the army 'the army 'the army the
speaking,
to b y
(...)
is p r e p a r i n g i t s e l f ' is p r e p a r i n g ( . . ) f o r is b e i n g p r e p a r e d '
so-called
conceptually referred
paraskeuazetai prepareSHp
direct
reflexive
the Agent and
the Subject,
(b)
the
itself'
interpretation, Qoal
so-called
indirect the
in w h i c h ,
conceptually
speaking,
Beneficiary
identical
and
to by
(3) b ' .
(c),
are
present,
cf.
referred
in
which,
identical
is t h e
interpretation, usually
are
Agent
the Subject;
and
reflexive and
a Qoal
the is
(3b').
ho stratos p a r a s k e u a z e t a i tas naus the armysubj preparesMp the shipsGoai ' t h e a r m y is p r e p a r i n g t h e s h i p s f o r i t s e l f '
finally,
is t h e s o - c a l l e d p a s s i v e
interpretation,
in w h i c h
the
VOICE IN ANCIENT GREEK
Subject
has
the
1Z5
semantic
function
Goal. An Agent phrase «ay be
present, as in (I). Thus, the presence or absence of certain other sentence (a
Goal; an
Agent phrase)
interpretation. An indication is also given by verb,
since
not
all
Meaning
reflexive
the
of
of
others. In fact, languages,
to a
activities or
performed with respect
the
to se
is
of the
involved,
the direct
the
restricted
most
relatively small
group of verbs
treatments, which Bay normally be
oneself
reflexive verbs
cf. French
verbs
middle-passive
one. This use is restricted denoting physical
the meaning
verbs allow these three interpretations. As
regards the lexical uae
elements in the
usually points to the correct
laver
as
well
of this and
as
with
type are
Dutch
zich
respect to
found in many wassen,
'to
wash'. Some Greek examples are: (4)
active louein 'to wash'
direct reflexive middle louesthai 'to wash oneself, to take a bath'
guanazein
gumnazeBthai
keirein
On the
'to drill'
'to cut off'
keiresthai
'to drill oneself, to exercise'
'to cut one's hair, to shave'
other hand, the middle-passive of verbs denoting activities
that one
usually does
e.g. blaptein
not perform
'to harm' or daknein
with respect
as direct reflexive. For that purpose pronoun in
the accusative
case is
to oneself (like
'to bite') cannot be interpreted the active
plus a reflexive
used, cf. (5b);
see also Cock
(1981:6-7). Note that a passive interpretation of (5a) is perfectly possible. (5) a.
b.
blaptomai I-harm«p *'I am harming myself' [dir. refl.] 'I am being harmed' [pass.] blapto emauton I-harBAct myselfAcc 'I am harming myself'
Unlike the
direct reflexive use, the indirect reflexive use of the
126 RISSELADA
middle-passive is However, here
not restricted
too, the
to certain
types of activities.
restriction holds that it must be possible
to perform the activity denoted by the verb
both in
one's own and
in somebody else's interest. In other words, it must be possible to add a Beneficiary 1 . For instance, the middle-passive of a verb like esthiein
'to
eat', which
ciary , could never holds for
does not normally combine with a Benefi-
have an
the verb ainein
indirect reflexive
meaning; the same
'to praise', something one normally does
in the interest of the Qoal, cf. (6). (6)
tainoumai ton paida I-praisettp the boysoai 'I am praising the boy for myself'
An interesting fact is that
when
the
coreferential
reflexive use) or the coreferential Beneficiary use) is emphasized or reflexive pronoun cf.
contrasted, the
in the
(7); see also Cock (1981:7-8), Huijgh
(7)
(indirect
active may
accusative or
Goal
(direct
reflexive
be used
plus a
dative case respectively, (1975:360).
sfeas te autous keirontes kai tous hippous themnefi and selfAcc shavingAct and the horsesAcc 'shaving both themselves and their horses' (Hdt. 9,24) The passive use of
cally
restricted,
the middle-passive,
but
may
occur
in
finally, is
not lexi-
the case of all transitive
verbal predicates, in some cases even if the second argument is not marked by the accusative case in the active (cf. Mulder forthc.) Furthermore, there
is another
in the case of a restricted causative meaning. In means of which the physical
situation
the active,
Agent brings of
use of the middle-passive voice
number
of
verbal
predicates
these verbs denote an action by about a
change in
of control expresses
of
the
either
physical situation
(8b)
but is
part of
are (8a) and (9a). Depending on the degree
Subject, that
the mental or
the Goal. This causative semantic feature,
however, is not encoded in the morphological form, their meaning. Examples
with a
the or
the
middle-passive
Subject
changes
its
that
change
comes
a
of
these verbs
own
mental or
about
in its
VOICE IN ANCIENT GREEK
situation
127
(9b):
(8) a. b.
ageirein ageiresthai
'to gather together' 'to gather, to assemble'
(9) a. b.
egeirein egeiresthai
'to rouse, to awaken' 'to wake up'
(8b)
i8
an
action;
the
semantic
I
middle-passive as 'pseudo-reflexive'. process; the
semantic function
[transitive] [intransitive]
function
Agent. Following Rijksbaron (1984),
of
the
characterize
Subject is
this
type of
(9b), on the other hand, is a
of the
Subject is Processed. This
type of Biddle-passive can be characterized as Summarizing, the
[transitive] [intransitive]
'pseudo-passive'.
middle-passive can be used with the following
meanings : 2 (10) i. ii. iii. iv. v.
direct reflexive indirect reflexive 3 pseudo-reflexive pseudo-passive passive
2. Valency It must
Reduction
be clear
account for
that Subject
voice oppositions
all the uses of
the
phenomena
a
in
predicate
middle-passive. On number
Croatian, Turkish,
rules
have
that
(cf. Vet 1985;
Schaaik
1983a; for
Dik
predicate formation 1987). In fact,
rules within
other
hand, similar
been
described
in
terms of
a
Dik and discussion the theory
Ovozdanovic 1981; Van of
the position of
of FG,
see De Groot
there seem to be strong indications that, at least
diachronically, valency Greek opposition
the
affect the valency of the verbal
predicates involved 1985;
principle used to
of other languages (e.g. French, Serbo-
Hungarian)
formation
assignment, the
in many languages, does not explain
reduction plays
an important
role in the
active : middle-passive, although on a synchronic
level such an analysis is not entirely unproblematic, of the passive meaning of the middle-passive.
esp. in view
128 RISSELADA
2.1
Valency Seduction
Dik (1983a)
in FG
proposes to
capture a number of different
detransiti-
vization operations in various languages by neans of a general rule of
predicate
formation
that
results in a valency reduction. The
input is an n-place verbal predicate, the output predicate. The
effect
of
n-place relation of the
the
predicate
input predicate
is an (n-l)-place
fornation
rule is: the
applies to
n-1 entities.
Applied to a two-place input predicate, this rule can be formalized as in (11): Valency Reduction Predicate Formation 4
(11)
input:
predv
output: Meaning: The element R is
the formal The one
can be either
first
the
(i = 1,2)
marker of
the reduced
argument left or
the
second
nature of the
in the output
predicate
argument
the input
of
its semantic function may or may not have undergone
a change. Thus, this operations which
(xi)
the relation expressed by predv applies in xi
derived predicate. predicate, and
(xi ) (x2)
predv-R
general
result in
rule
covers
a
number
of specific
various interpretations, all marked by
the same formal marker R. 2.2
Valency
Reduction
In my opinion, express
R,
the
in Ancient
Ancient
i.e. they
Greek
Greek
signal
a
middle-passive reduction
verbal endings
of the valency of the
(active) input predicate. Reduction of the second
argument leads
interpretation, as is shown in (12):
to a
direct
reflexive
129
VOICE IN ANCIENT GREBK
(12)
Direct Reflexive Predicate Formation input:
predv * c t
output:
(XI)AI
predv HP
(XJ)SO
(XI)A