The Essays of Montaigne: Volume II The Essays of Montaigne, Volume II [Reprint 2014 ed.] 9780674336926, 9780674336452


192 27 20MB

English Pages 403 [412] Year 1925

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Table of contents :
CONTENTS
THE FIRST BOOK (CONTINUED)
CHAPTER L OF DEMOCRITUS A N D HERACLITUS
CHAPTER LI OF THE VANITY OF WORDS
CHAPTER LII OF THE PARSIMONY OF THE ANCIENTS
CHAPTER LIII ON A SAYING OF CESAR'S
CHAPTER LIV OF TRIVIAL MINUTIAE
CHAPTER LV OF ODOURS
CHAPTER LVI OF PRAYERS
CHAPTER LVII OF AGE
THE SECOND BOOK
CHAPTER I OF THE INCONSTANCY OF OUR ACTIONS
CHAPTER II OF DRUNKENNESS
CHAPTER III A USAGE OF THE ISLAND OF CEA
CHAPTER IV BUSINESS TO-MORROW
CHAPTER V OF THE CONSCIENCE
CHAPTER VI OF EXPERIENCE
CHAPTER VII MARKS OF HONOUR
CHAPTER VIII OF THE AFFECTION OF FATHERS FOR THEIR CHILDREN
CHAPTER IX OF THE ARMOUR OF THE PARTHIANS
CHAPTER X OF BOOKS
CHAPTER XI OF CRUELTY
CHAPTER XII APOLOGY FOR RAIMOND SEBOND
Recommend Papers

The Essays of Montaigne: Volume II The Essays of Montaigne, Volume II [Reprint 2014 ed.]
 9780674336926, 9780674336452

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

T H E ESSAYS O F MONTAIGNE VOLUME II

LONDON : HUMPHREY MILFORD OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS

THE ESSAYS OF

Montaigne TRANSLATED BY GEORGE B. IVES INTRODUCTIONS BY GRACE NORTON

VOLUME II

CAMBRIDGE HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS 1925

COPYRIGHT, I 9 2 5 B Y HARVARD U N I V E R S I T Y

PRESS

PRINTED AT T H E HARVARD U N I V E R S I T Y CAMBRIDGE, M A S S . , U . S . A .

PRESS

CONTENTS BOOK

I

(CONTINUED)

L. Of Democritus and Heraclitus

3

LI. Of the vanity of words

7

LIL Of the parsimony of the ancients

12

LIII. On a saying of Casar s

13

LIV. Of trivial Minutia

15

LV. Of Odours

19

LVI. Of Prayers

22

LVII.

Of Age

34

BOOK

II

I. Of the inconstancy of our actions

41

II. Of Drunkenness

50

III. A usage of the Island of Cea

62

IV. Business to-morrow

80

V. Of the Conscience

83

VI. Of Experience

88

VII. Marks of Honour VIII. Of the affection offathers for their children IX. Of the armour of the Parthians

102 . . . .

107 130

X. Of Books

134

XI. Of Cruelty

150

XII. Apology for Raimond Sebond

170

ESSAYS OF M O N T A I G N E THE FIRST BOOK (CONTINUED)

CHAPTER L OF

DEMOCRITUS

AND

HERACLITUS

THE Essay opens with a recognition of the universal usefulness of the judgement, and Montaigne says that in the essays — the tests — he here makes of it (he does not allude to his writings in the modern sense of essays) he avails himself of every opportunity; and he goes on to describe the assistance it gives him; and, still further, his manner of composing, and the advantages of it to a man of not more assured and powerful mind than himself. B u t his avoidance of going to the bottom of things does not (he implies) conceal from the reader the manner of man he is; " e v e r y motion reveals u s " ; and in fact, perhaps, the soul is best seen " w h e n she is jogging quietly along." In its higher planes of existence it is more carried on the winds of passions, and is more engrossed by each separate thing to which it gives itself. This train of thought leads to a passage — " T h i n g s by themselves . . . " e t c . — w h e r e the extreme use of figures (not at all common with Montaigne) makes the clear understanding of the thought somewhat difficult. 1 Returning from this thought, that it is our opinion of a thing and not the thing itself which affects us (one of the dominant doctrines of the Stoic philosophy), Montaigne recurs to the thought that every chord of our mind may be touched and sounded by commonplace conditions, bringing forward in illustration the game of chess — " that foolish and puerile game," as he thinks it: " I dislike it and shun it because it is not play enough." And he again insists that " e v e r y occupation of a man betrays and reveals him equally with any other." Originally Democritus and Heraclitus came on the stage before now: this long philosophy was inserted in 1595; but it is of little consequence when they appear, as they have but small parts to play. T h e y are introduced only as figure-heads of two different ways of judging of this poor human creature who cannot disguise himself and whose state may be considered either as ridiculous or sorrowful. Montaigne thinks man is fit only to be laughed at, that he is worthy neither of compassion nor of hatred: " I t seems to me that we can never be despised as much as we deserve." It is not often that we find Montaigne in so bitter a mood. 1 When I say this style is not frequent with Montaigne, I mean the extreme and confusing use of figurative language. Never was there a writer who made such incessant and illuminating use of figurative expressions of a kind that interpret themselves with the utmost plainness. It is what gives his style its constant beauty of colour.

ESSAYS OF M O N T A I G N E

4

T

H E judgement is a tool for all subjects, and enters into every thing. For this reason, in the essays I here make of it, I employ it on every sort of occasion. If a subject is unfamiliar to me, for that very reason I essay it, measuring the depth of the ford from afar; and when I find it too deep for my stature, I remain on the shore; and this recognition of my inability to cross over is a form of its action, 1 aye, one of those of which it is most proud. Sometimes, with a hollow and empty subject, I essay to see if it 2 can find any thing to give it substance and with which to support it and prop it up. Sometimes I direct it to a famous and much-travelled subject about which it can find nothing original, there being such a beaten way that it must needs travel in the track of others. There it plays its game in selecting the road which seems to it the best, and of a thousand paths it says that this one or that one has been the better choice.

(c) I take by chance the opening theme, since one is as good as another in my eyes, and I never plan to produce them completely. For I do not see the whole of any thing; nor do those who promise to make us see it. Of a hundred members and aspects that every thing has, I take one, sometimes to taste it, sometimes to skim it, 3 and sometimes to squeeze it even to the bone. I stab into them, not as widely, but as deeply, as I know how. And I like in most cases to seize them by some unfamiliar side. I might venture to go to the bottom of some subject, if I knew myself less well.4 Scattering a word here, another there, bits taken from their whole, set by themselves, without plan and without pledge, I am not responsible for them, nor bound to hold to them without changing if I so please, nor to refrain from giving myself up to hesitation and uncertainty, and to my dominant characteristic, which is ignorance. Every motion reveals us. (a) T h a t same mind of Caesar's which manifests itself in organising and arranging the battle of Pharsalia, manifests itself also in arranging idle and amo1 2 3 4

That is, of the action of the judgement. The judgement. A effleurer. The edition of 1595 adds: et me trompois en mon impuissance.

BOOK I, CHAPTER L

5

rous matters. We judge a horse, not merely by seeing him when racing, but also by seeing him walk, aye, and by seeing him at rest in the stable. (c) Among the offices of the soul there are some that are inferior. He who does not see her in that wise does not know her wholly; and perchance we observe her best when she is jogging quietly along. The gusts of passion affect her more on her higher planes; moreover, she gives herself wholly to every matter and wholly busies herself in it; and she never treats more than one subject at a time, and treats it, not in accordance with its qualities, but in accordance with her own. Things by themselves have, it may be, their weights and measures and conditions; but within us, she fashions them as she thinks best. Death is terrifying to Cicero, desirable to Cato, indifferent to Socrates. Health, conscience, authority, learning, wealth, beauty, and their opposites, are stripped on entering, and receive from the soul new apparel and such colouring as pleases h e r — d a r k , light, dim, glaring, soft, deep, superficial — and as pleases each of our souls; for they have not agreed in common upon the titles, laws, and nature of their qualities; each soul is queen in her own domain. 1 Wherefore let us no more find excuse in the external qualities of things; it is for us to estimate their value to ourselves. What is well and bad for us depends wholly on ourselves. Let us offer our gifts and our prayers to ourselves, not to Fortune: she can not affect our moral nature; on the contrary, that draws her in its train and moulds her to its likeness. Why shall I not judge of Alexander at table, talking and drinking heavily? or, when he played chess, what chord of the mind does not that foolish and puerile game touch and employ ? I dislike it and shun it, because it is not play enough, and it is too serious a pastime; I feel ashamed to give to it the attention which would suffice for some 1

This whole passage is so perplexing that it is given at length, that readers may interpret it for themselves. La sante, la conscience, I'autorite, la science, la richesse, la beauti, et leurs contraires se despouillent d Γ entree, et recoivent de Fame nouvelle vesture, et de la teinture qu'il luy plait: brune, verte, claire, obscure, aigre, douce, profonde, superficiale, et qu'il plait ά chacune d'elles; car elles n'ont pas verifie en commun leurs stile, regies, et formes; chacune est reine en son estat.

6

E S S A Y S OF M O N T A I G N E

worthy thing. He was no more completely engrossed in preparing for his glorious expedition to the Indies; nor is another man in solving the difficulties of a passage on which the salvation of the human race depends. See how heavy and compressed that absurd amusement makes our mind, if all her sinews do not stiffen themselves; how amply it permits every one to know himself and to judge himself rightly. I do not behold myself and feel myself more completely in any other situation. 1 What passion does not therein play upon us? anger, vexation, hatred, impatience, and a vehement ambition to conquer in a matter in which it would be more excusable to be ambitious of being conquered; for rare excellence, above the common, in frivolous things is unbecoming for a man of high standing. What I say regarding this example may be said of all others. Every particle, every occupation of a man betrays and displays him equally with every other. (a) Democritus and Heraclitus were two philosophers, the former of whom, deeming the human state vain and ridiculous, never appeared in public but with a mocking and laughing countenance; Heraclitus, having pity and sympathy for that same state of ours, wore an unchangeably sad visage, and his eyes were full of tears. (b) Alter Ridebat, quoties a limine moverat unum Protuleratque pedem; flebat contrarius alter.2 (a) I like best the first humour, not because it is more agreeable to laugh than to weep, but because it is more contemptuous and condemns us more than the other; and it seems to me that we can never be despised as much as we deserve. Lamentation and commiseration are commingled with some estimation of that which we lament; the things we laugh at we esteem valueless. I do not think that we have so much ill fortune as inconstancy, or so much bad purpose as folly; we are not so full of evil as we are of inanity; we are not so 1 Than in playing chess. Je ne me vois et retaste plus universellement en nulle autre posture. - The one laughed every time he stepped over the threshold; the other, on the contrary, wept. — Juvenal, Satires, X , 28.

B O O K I, C H A P T E R

LI

7

wretched as we are base. Thus Diogenes, who in idle solitude passed his time rolling himself about in his tub, and flouting the great Alexander, 1 esteeming us as but flies or bladders full of wind, was a judge much more bitter and sharp-tongued, and consequently, to my feeling, more just, than T i m o n — h e who was called the hater of men; for what we hate we take seriously. This man wished us ill, was passionately desirous of our destruction, shunned intercourse with us as dangerous, we being wicked and depraved; the other thought so little of us that we could neither disturb him nor by our contagion harm him; he forsook our company, not from fear, but from contempt for our society; he thought us capable of doing neither well nor ill. Of the same stamp was the reply of Statilius, when Brutus spoke to him to secure his aid in the conspiracy against Caesar; he thought the enterprise a just one, but did not think that men deserved that any trouble should be taken for them. 2 (c) This conforms to the rule of Hegesias, who said: " T h e wise man should do nothing except for himself, inasmuch as he alone deserves to have things done for h i m " ; 3 and that of Theodoras: " I t is unreasonable that the wise man should risk his life for the good of his country, and that he should imperil wisdom for fools." 4 Our peculiar condition is as ridiculous as risible.

C H A P T E R LI OF T H E V A N I T Y OF WORDS IT is easy to understand that Montaigne would have no respect for " the art of rhetoric"; for the tongue that could "make the worse appear the better reason"; for the eloquence " t h a t makes it its business to deceive . . . our judgement and to debase and corrupt the essence of things." He says that Socrates and Plato defined it as the " art of deceiving and flattering." But he might have remembered that Diogenes Laertius (whom he quotes so often) said that Socrates himself (forerunning Mil1 2 3 4

See See See See

Plutarch, Life of Alexander; Cicero, Tusc. Disp., V , 32. Plutarch, Life of Brutus. Diogenes Laertius, Life of Aristippus. Ibid.

8

ESSAYS OF MONTAIGNE

ton's Satan) was ridiculed by Aristophanes " as making the worse appear the better reason." Montaigne thinks that eloquence flourishes less in a monarchical government than under other forms of administration, for one well-educated man (as a prince may be supposed to be) is less under the influence of its poison than the ignorant commonalty. There was never any orator of renown known to come from Macedonia or Persia. All this philosophy about " l a vanite des paroles" was suggested to Montaigne, he says, by a talk he had just been having with an Italian he had taken into his service, the former maitre d'hotel of a cardinal, whose elaborate discourse about his office and " t h e science of the gullet" seemed highly ridiculous to Montaigne. And not less so seemed to him the big words of architects (or mere house-builders), pilasters, architraves, Corinthian and Doric style, and the like, when they were only busy about a kitchen door. And all the strange names used by grammarians—metonomy and metaphor — are rather absurd when they concern the chatter of a chambermaid. But of far more importance than these trivial piperies is the custom of calling State officers by titles too big for their duties and powers; and worse still the unworthy bestowal of such a surname as " D i v i n e " on such a man as Aretino — "which in my opinion will be matter of reproach some day to our age."

A R H E T O R I C I A N of past times said that his trade / \ was to make small things appear great and be thought so. (b) He is a cobbler who makes a big JL J L shoe for a little foot. 1 (a) In Sparta they would have whipped him for professing a cheating and lying art. (ib) And I think that Archidamus, who was king there, did not hear without surprise the reply of Thucydides, of whom he inquired which was the more able in wrestling, Pericles or he. " T h a t , " he said, "would be difficult to say positively; for, when I throw him in wrestling, he persuades those who saw it that he was not thrown, and he wins." 2 (a) Those who mask and paint women do less harm; for it is a small loss not to see them in their natural state; whereas these 3 make it their business to deceive, not our eyes, but our judgement, and to debase and corrupt the very essence of things. Those commonwealths which maintained themselves in an orderly and well-governed condition — like the Cretan 1 2 3

See Plutarch, Apothegms of the Lacedtemonians, under " Agesilaus." See Plutarch, Life of Pericles. The rhetoricians.

B O O K I, C H A P T E R

LI

9

or the Lacedaemonian—made no great account of orators. (c) Ariston sagely defines rhetoric: " T h e science of persuading the people"; 1 Socrates, Plato: " T h e art of deceiving and flattering";2 and they who deny this as a general description verify it everywhere in their precepts. T h e Mohammedans forbid their children to be taught it because of its uselessness; 3 and the Athenians, perceiving how pernicious was its use, which had great vogue in their city, decreed that its principal element, which is to stir the emotions, should be laid aside, together with exordiums and perorations. 4 {a) It is an instrument invented to manage and excite a mob and a disorderly commonalty, and is an instrument that is employed only in diseased states, like medicine; in those where the common people, where the ignorant, where all had universal power,6 like those of Athens, Rhodes, and Rome, and where things were in a continual turmoil— there orators swarmed. And, indeed, there were few persons in those commonwealths who attained to great influence without the help of eloquence: Pompey, Caesar, Crassus, Lucullus, Lentulus, Metellus found in it their main support in rising to that height of authority at which they finally arrived, and were more effectively assisted by it than by arms; (c) contrary to the opinion of more enlightened times. For L . Volumnius, speaking in public in favour of the election to the consulship of Q. Fabius and P. Decius, said: " T h e y are men born for war; great in deeds; unpractised in the strife of words; minds truly consular; the subtle and eloquent and learned are good for the city, as praetors to administer justice." 6 {a) Eloquence was most flourishing (c) at Rome (a) when affairs were in the worst state, and the storm of civil war agitated them, as an open and uncultivated field bears the lustiest weeds. B y which it would seem that the governments that are subject to a monarch have less need of it See Quintilian, II, ι ζ. See Ibid., II, 16; Plato, Gorgias, passim. 3 See G. Postel, Histoire des Turcs. * See Quintilian, II, 16. 5 Oil tous ont tout peu [pu]. 8 See Livy, X , 22. 1

2

10

ESSAYS OF

MONTAIGNE

than the others; for the stupidity and credulity which are found in the common people and which make them liable to be managed and led by the ears at the sweet sound of this harmony, without seeking to weigh and discover the truth about things by the power of reason — this credulity, I say, is not found so easily in a single person; and it is more easy to defend him by good instruction and good advice from the effect of that poison. There was never known to come from Macedonia or Persia any orator of renown. I have quoted this saying 1 in connection with an Italian with whom I have just been talking, who was in the service of the late Cardinal Caraffa, as his steward, until his death. I made him tell me about his office. He discoursed to me on this science of the gullet with a magisterial gravity and demeanour, as if he were speaking to me of some great point in theology. He expounded to me a distinction in appetites: that which exists before eating, that after the second and third courses; how sometimes simply to gratify it, sometimes to arouse and stimulate it; the care of his sauces, first in general, and then going into particulars as to the qualities of the ingredients and their effects; the differences in salads according to their seasons — what ones should be heated, what ones require to be served cold; the way to decorate and embellish them to make them attractive even to the eyes. After that, he entered upon the order of courses, full of fine and important considerations. (b) Nec minimo sane discrimine refert Quo gestu lepores, et quo gallina secetur. 2 {a) And all this inflated with rich and magnificent words and even such as are used in discoursing about the government of an empire. There came to my mind what this man says: Hoc salsum est, hoc adustum est, hoc lautum est parum, Illud recte; iterum sic memento; sedulo That with which the Essay opens. He announces that it is certainly not a thing that makes little difference, in what manner a hare or a hen is carved. — Juvenal, Satires, V , 123. 1

2

B O O K I, C H A P T E R

LI

II

Moneo quae possum pro mea sapientia. Postremo, tanquam in speculum, in patinas, Demea, Inspicere jubeo, et moneo quid facto usus sit. 1 Y e t the Greeks themselves highly praised the order and arrangement that Paulus ^Emilius observed in the feast that he gave them on his return from Macedonia. 2 But I am not talking here of facts, I am talking of words. I know not whether it is with others as it is with me, but when I hear our architects puff themselves out with those big words, pilasters, architraves, cornices, Corinthian and Doric work, and other like ones of their jargon, I can not prevent my imagination from being possessed instantly by the palace of Apolidon; 3 and, in reality, I find that they are but the paltry parts of my kitchen door. (b) When we hear the words metonomy, metaphor, allegory, and other such terms of grammar, does it not seem that they betoken some rare and foreign 4 form of language? They are names that describe the chatter of your chambermaid. (a) It is a deception akin to this to call the dignitaries of our kingdom by the proud titles of the Romans, since they have no resemblance in function, and also less authority and power. And this, too, which, in my opinion, will be matter of reproach some day to our a g e — the employing unworthily, for whomsoever we please, the most glorious titles wherewith antiquity honoured one or two personages in several ages. Plato carried away the surname Divine by a consent so universal that no one bore him a grudge; and the Italians, who pride themselves, and justly, upon having commonly more alert wits and saner judgement than the other nations of their time, have lately endowed with that title Aretino, in whom, save for a bombastic style, padded with witticisms, ingenious, in truth, but far-fetched and fanciful, and besides his eloquence, such as it is, I do not see that there is any thing 1 This is too salt, this is burned, this has not enough flavour; this one is very good; remember another time to have it the same. I carefully teach them what I can out of my wisdom. Finally, Demea, I bid them look into the dishes as into a looking-glass, and I advise them what it is profitable to do. — Terence, Adelphi, III, 3.71. 2 See Plutarch, Life of Paulus JEmilius. 3 In Amadis de Gaule. 4 Pellegrin = pelerin.

12

ESSAYS OF MONTAIGNE

superior to the common authors of his age; so far is he from approaching that ancient divinity. And the surname Great we fasten upon princes who have nothing in them above the ordinary. C H A P T E R LI I OF T H E PARSIMONY OF T H E ANCIENTS THIS is merely a record of the parsimony — or carefulness about expenses — of Regulus and of Cato, of Scipio, Homer, Zeno, and Tiberius Gracchus.

J L T T I L I U S R E G U L U S , commander of the Roman / \ army in Africa, in the midst of his glory and of his victories over the Carthaginians, wrote to the Re1 \ public that a farmer 1 whom he had left alone in the management of his estate, which in all was seven acres of land, had run away, having stolen his implements of husbandry; and he asked leave of absence that he might return home and arrange about this, for fear that his wife and children would suffer from it. T h e Senate arranged to commit to another the care of his property, and had him supplied anew with what had been stolen from him, and decreed that his wife and children should be supported at the public expense.2 The elder Cato, when returning from Spain as consul, sold his war-horse to save the money that it would have cost to take him back to Italy by sea; and, when governor of Sardinia, did all his overseeing on foot, having with him no other than an official of the Republic, who carried for him his robe, and an urn in which to offer sacrifices; and oftenest he carried his pack himself. He boasted of never having had a robe that had cost more than ten crowns, and of never having sent to market more than ten sous for a day's provisions; and that, as to his country houses, there was not one that was rough-cast and plastered outside. 3 Scipio ^Emilianus, after two triumphs and two consulships, went on an embassy with a train of only seven slaves.4 It is believed 1 2 3 4

Valet de labourage. See Valerius Maximus, IV, 4.6. See Plutarch, Life of Cato the Censor. See Valerius Maximus, I V , 3.13.

B O O K I, C H A P T E R L I I I

13

that Homer had never more than one; Plato three; Zeno, head of the Stoic sect, not one. 1 (b) But five and a half sous a day were allowed Tiberius Gracchus when he went on a mission for the Republic, although he was then the first man among the Romans. 2 CHAPTER LIII ON

A

SAYING

OF

CESAR'S

THIS mot de Cisar, from the " D e Bello Civili," is the last sentence of the Essay, and was translated by Montaigne himself (in the early editions): " I t happens by a common natural weakness that we both trust more, and fear more, things that we have not seen and that are hidden and unknown." T h e thoughts with which Montaigne leads up to this do not concern themselves so much with the subject of the saying, as with the point that man's imperfection is demonstrated by the inconstancy of his desires. Even the philosophers have never been able to discover the sovereign good of man.

I

F we occupied ourselves now and then in considering ourselves, and employed the time that we spend in criticising others, and in learning about things with which we have no concern, in sounding our own depths, we should easily perceive that all this our structure is framed of weak and defective parts. Is it not a strange proof of imperfection, to be unable to have settled pleasure in any thing, and that even by desire and imagination it is beyond our power to decide what is needed for us ? T o this, strong testimony is borne by the great discussion which there has always been among philosophers, to discover the sovereign good of mankind, and which still goes on and will go on forever, without decision and without agreement. (b) Dum abest quod avemus, id exsuperare videtur Caetera; post aliud, cum contigit illud, avemus E t sitis sequa tenet. 3 See Seneca, Consolatio ad Albinam, X I I . See Plutarch, Life of Tiberius Gracchus. 3 Whilst what we crave is wanting, it seems to transcend all other things; later, when that has been attained, we crave some thing else, and an equal thirst possesses us. — Lucretius, I I I , 1082. 1

2

ESSAYS OF

MONTAIGNE

{a) Whatever may fall within our knowledge and our enjoyment, we feel that it does not satisfy us, and we go gaping after things to come, and unknown, because those of the present do not suffice us; not, to my thinking, that they have not the wherewithal to suffice us, but that we hold them with a sickly and senseless grasp. (b) Nam, cum vidit hie, ad usum quae flagitat usus, Omnia jam ferme mortalibus esse parata, Divitiis homines et honore et laude potentis Affluere atque bona natorum excellere fama, Nec minus esse domi cuiquam tamen anxia corda, Atque animum infestis cogi servire querelis: Intellexit ibi vitium vas efficere ipsum, Omnlaque illius vitio corrumpier intus, Quae collata foris et commoda quaeque venirent. 1 (a) Our appetite is hesitating and uncertain; it can neither hold to any thing nor enjoy any thing in a worthy way. Man, thinking it to be the fault of these things, supplies himself with, and feeds upon, other things which he knows not, and which he understands not; on which he fixes his desires and his hopes, and holds them in honour and veneration; as Caesar says: Communi fit vitio natures et invisis, latitantibus atque incognitis rebus magis confidamus> vehementiusque exterreamur? 1 For when he [Epicurus] saw that all the things needed for the support of life we already have; more powerful by honour and reputation, overflowing with riches, and uplifted by the good name of their children; and yet the heart of every man was not the less inwardly uneasy, and life tormented by the discontent of the spirit; he perceived the cause of the violence of these threatening lamentations to lie here: it is in the vessel itself [the soul], and all the things, whatever they may be, brought to it from without, however agreeable, are corrupted by fault of this vessel. — Lucretius, VI, 9, 10, 12-14, 16-19. This text differs slightly from the modern text, as does also that of Lambin (Paris, 1563), the edition Montaigne used. 2 It happens by a common natural weakness that we both trust more, and fear more violently, things that we have not seen, and that are hidden and unknown.—Caesar, De Bello Civili, II, 4. In all the editions from 1580 to 1588, the essay closed with the following translation of the passage quoted: II se fait, par un vice ordinaire de nature, que nous ayons et plus de fiance et plus de crainte des choses que nous n'aeons pas veu, et qui sont cachees et inconnues.

BOOK I, CHAPTER LIV

l

5

CHAPTER LIV OF TRIVIAL MINUTIAE all the dry little morsels — legons (in the old sense of the word) rather than "essays" — we have been munching, we come to a bit with more flavour, a more juicy slice. The pleasantness of this Essay is in the personal touch, — in seeing Montaigne playing games with his family, — in that, and in one other passage that I shall speak of directly. I am inclined to believe that the title of the Essay and its first page were merely intended to give, — in a certain inverted, reverted fashion, — by the contempt thrown on trifles, a certain dignity or decorum to the trivial amusement " w e " had just been indulging in chez moy. The game was, who could think of the greatest number of things, called by the same name, that were unlike each other and at the two extremes. The enumeration that Montaigne gives best explains itself. He passes on, evidently, from what they could have said in a game, to what the game had made him think of, and he goes deeper and deeper in thoughts that became later a "Pensee" of Pascal. But what is of most interest is the passage where, after praising the "simple peasants" as few men of his age would have thought of doing, but as he does over and over again, he goes on to praise " the poetry of the people." It was the first time that the phrase had been heard; and his appreciation of this form of poetry is a delightful expression of the freedom and delicacy of his own poetic perceptions. The concluding paragraph has a charming, half-humorous, wholly individual personal note. AFTER

T

HERE are certain frivolous and trivial minutiae, by means of which men sometimes seek commendation; like those poets who make whole works of lines beginning with one and the same letter. We see eggs, bowls, wings, axes, designed in old times by the Greeks, with the measure of their lines, by lengthening them or shortening them in such wise that they came to represent this or that figure. Such was the art of the man who occupied himself in calculating in how many ways the letters of the alphabet could be arranged, and found the incredible number mentioned by Plutarch.1 I agree with the opinion of him to whom a man was brought

1 See Plutarch, Table Gossip: "Xenocrates says that the number of syllables made by the letters combined and mingled together amounts to one hundred million, two hundred thousand."

i6

ESSAYS O F M O N T A I G N E

able to throw with his hand a grain of millet with such skill that he never failed to pass it through the eye of a needle; and from whom was asked some present to reward such rare ability; whereupon he jestingly, and justly in m y opinion, ordered given to this artist two or three bushels of millet, so that such a fine accomplishment should not remain unexercised. 1 I t is marvellous evidence of the weakness of our judgement that it commends things by reason of their rarity or novelty, or even of their difficulty, if worth and usefulness be not combined therewith. We have just been playing in m y family the game of seeing who could point out the most things of which the two extremes are opposed; as " S i r e " is a title which is given to the highest personage of our State, who is the king, and is given also to the common people, as to tradesmen, and is never applied to those between the two. Women of quality we call " D a m e s , " those of the middle class "Damoiselles," and " D a m e s " again, those of the lowest order. (b) T h e canopies that are placed over tables are permitted only in the houses of princes and in taverns, (a) Democritus said that the gods and the beasts had more acute senses than men, who are on a plane between. 2 T h e Romans wore the same attire on days of mourning and on festal days. I t is certain t h a t extreme fear and extreme eagerness of v a l o u r 3 equally disturb the bowels and relax them, (c) T h e nickname of "Trembler," which was given to Sancho, the twelfth King of Navarre, 4 shows that bravery as well as fear causes our limbs to tremble. And when his people, who were arming him, seeing his skin quiver, tried to reassure him by belittling the danger into which he was about to plunge, he said: " Y o u know me ill; if m y flesh were aware how far m y courage will soon carry it, it would be thoroughly chilled." 5 (a) La foiblesse qui nous vient de froiSee Quintilian, II, 20. See Plutarch, The Opinions of Philosophers. 3 Ardeur de courage. 4 "Montaigne certainly alludes to Garcia V, called ' Le Trembleur,' the twelfth King of Navarre, son of Sancho Garcia. He reigned near the close of the tenth century." — M. Villey. 5 Elle s'en transiroit tout d plat. 1

2

B O O K I, C H A P T E R L I V

17

deur et desgoutement aux exercises de Venus, eile nous vient aussi d'un appetit trop vehement et d'une chaleur desreglee. Extreme cold and extreme heat boil and bake. Aristotle says that masses of lead melt and liquefy with cold and the severe temperature of winter as well as with fierce heat. 1 (c) Desire and satiety fill with distress the regions above and below pleasure, (a) Stupidity and wisdom in the endurance of human conditions meet- at the same point of discernment and steadiness.2 The wise curb and command evil, and the others do not recognise it; the latter are, so to speak, on this side of conditions; the former beyond them, who, 3 having well weighed and considered the circumstances, and having measured them and judged them for what they are, fling themselves on them, with lusty courage; they scorn them and trample upon them, having a strong and stout soul, against which the shafts of fortune striking must of necessity rebound, blunted, meeting a body on which they can make no impression. The ordinary, average disposition of man is found between these two extremes: it is that of those who perceive evils, discern them, and can not endure them. Infancy and decrepitude are alike in feebleness of brain; avarice and lavishness, in a similar desire to attract and to obtain. (,b) It may be said with reason that (c) there is an abecedarian ignorance that goes before learning; another, belonging to teachers,4 that comes after learning; an ignorance which learning makes and engenders, just as she unmakes and destroys the first. (b) Of simple souls, less heedful and less instructed, there are made good Christians, who, from reverence and obedience, simply believe and keep themselves within the laws. In minds of medium strength and medium capacity mistaken opinions are engendered; they follow the suggestion of the first impression and have some right to interpret it as shallowness and stupidity that we have stayed in the old ways, those of us who are not therein 1 See Aristotle, De Auscultationibus Mirabilibus. Montaigne interprets the text inaccurately. 2 La bestise et la sagesse se rencontrent en mesme point de sentiment et de resolution ά la souffrance des accidens humains. 3 The wise. 4 Doctorale.

18

ESSAYS OF MONTAIGNE

instructed by study. Great minds, being more stable and clear-sighted, make another sort of true believers; who, by long and devout investigation, discern a deeper and more hidden light in the Scripture, and perceive the mysterious and divine secret of our ecclesiastical polity. But we see that some of these have arrived at this last stage by way of the second, with marvellous profit and strengthening, as the extreme limit of Christian understanding, and that they enjoy their victory with solace, thanksgiving, reformation of morals, and great modesty. And in this category I do not propose to place those others who, to clear themselves from the distrust due to their past error, and to give us confidence in them, become extreme, indiscreet, and unreasonable in the handling of our cause, and mar it with endless reproaches of violence. (c) The simple peasants are worthy people, and worthy people the philosophers, or, as our age calls them, naturally strong and clear in mind, enriched by wide education in useful knowledge. The mongrels (of whom I am one, and so many others) who are above the first condition, of ignorance of letters, and have not been able to reach the other, sitting between two stools, are dangerous, useless, troublesome; these disturb the world. Therefore, for my part, I draw back as far as I can to the first and natural condition, whence I have to no avail tried to depart. Popular and purely natural poetry has simplicities and graces by which it rivals the main beauty of poetry excellent in art; 1 as may be seen in the mllanelles of Gascony and in the songs that are brought to us from nations that have no knowledge of learning, or even of writing. Mediocre poetry, which halts between the two, is despised, without honour and without value. (a) But since, after the way was opened to the mind, I found, as commonly happens, that we had regarded as a difficult exercise, and concerning a rare subject, one that is not at all so; and that, after our searching power has been aroused, it discovers an infinite number of similar examples, I will add only this one: that, if these essays were worthy to be pronounced upon, it might well happen, in my opinion, 1 Parfaicte selon Γart.

B O O K I, C H A P T E R

LV

r9

that they would scarcely please common and ignorant minds or rare and learned ones; 1 the former would not understand them well enough, the latter would understand them too well; they might make shift to live in the middle region.

CHAPTER

LV

OF ODOURS THE title does not seem to promise much of interest, but interest is awakened by one of the first sentences; for it has the personal expression that is the charm of the Essays. " T h e most exquisite odour for a woman is to have no odour," Montaigne remarked in 1580, when all the poets around him were singing in rapturous phrases the odorous breath of woman. Listen to Ronsard describing "les beautes qu'il voudrait en s'amie." L a dens d'ivoire, odorante l'haleine A qui s'egalerait ä peine Les doux parfums de la 83Βέβ Ou toute l'odeur d6rob6e Que l'Arabie heureusement amine.

This was the fashion of the day. Montaigne, with the ancients, was of another mind. The remark that follows has the same flavour of oldtime opinions; and it is worth observing that Montaigne suppressed it in his later editions; but there are yet some hearts that welcome it. This Essay in the first edition consisted only of this one paragraph. It ended with Posthume, non bene olet, qui bene semper olet

(a line of Martial); but in the next important edition (1588) Montaigne added another page or two, of which one paragraph is interesting from its theory of the use of incense, and another from its account of the luxurious possibilities and practices of the day, and another — the last — for its personality.

I

T is said of some persons, for example, of Alexander the Great, that their sweat gave forth a sweet odour, by virtue of some rare and extraordinary constitution of the body; of which Plutarch 2 and others seek the cause. But the usual bodily habit is different;

1 Esprits communs et vulgaires, ny guiere aux singuliers et excellens. In 1580 the last clause reads esprits grossiers ei ignorans, ny guiere aux delicats etsavans. And this sentence is added: lis tromerointplace entre ces deux extremit&s. 2 See Plutarch, Life of Alexander.

ίο

ESSAYS OF MONTAIGNE

(.c) and the best possible condition is to be odourless. (a) The sweetness of the purest breath can have no greater excellence than to be without any odour that offends us, as are the breaths of very healthy children. That, says Plautus, is why Mulier turn bene olet, ubi nihil o l e t : 1 the most exquisite odour for a woman is to have no odour; (b) as we say that the best odour of her acts is when they are impalpable and noiseless.2 (a) And we are justified in regarding the pleasant external odours as laying open to suspicion those who use them, and in thinking that they may be employed to conceal some natural defect in that direction. Whence are derived the quips of the ancient poets: " T o smell sweet is to stink." Rides nos, Coracine, nil olentes; Malo quam bene olere, nil olere.3 And elsewhere, — Posthume, non bene olet, qui bene semper olet.4 (b) I like very much, none the less, to be surrounded 6 with pleasant odours, and I hate beyond measure bad smells, which I perceive at a greater distance than any one else. Namque sagacius unus odoror, Polypus, an gravis hirsutis cubet hircus in alis, Quam canis acer ubi lateat sus.6 (c) The most simple and natural odours seem to me the most agreeable; and this matter chiefly concerns the ladies. In the densest barbarism, the Scythian women, after bath1 A woman then smells most agreeably when she does not smell at all. — P l a u t u s , Mostellaria, 1,3.117. Montaigne translates after quoting. 2 The last clause was omitted in 1595. 3 Y o u laugh at me, Coracinus, for not being scented; I prefer not to smell at all rather than to smell sweet. — Martial, V I , 55.4. 4 Posthumus, he does not smell agreeably, who always smells agreeably. — Martial, II, 12.4. The essay ended here in 1580. 6 A estre entretenu. 6 For my nose detects more acutely a cancer or a rank arm-pit than does a keen hound where lurks the boar. — Horace, Epodes, X I I , 4.

BOOK I, C H A P T E R L V

21

ing, powder and anoint the whole body and the face with a certain odoriferous plant which grows in their country, and having removed that fard, preparatory to rejoining their mates, their skin is softened and perfumed by it. 1 (b) Whatever the odour may be, it is wonderful how it clings to me, and how adapted my skin is to absorb it. He who complains of Nature because she has left man with no instrument to carry odours to his nose is in error: for they carry themselves. But particularly in my case, my moustaches, which are thick, do that for me: if I put my glove or my handkerchief to them, the smell will last a whole day; they reveal the place I have come from. The warm kisses of youth, sweet and greedy and cloying, used in old times to cling to them, and remain for several hours. And yet I find myself but little subject to the common diseases which are taken by communication, and which arise from the contagion of the air; and I have escaped those of my time, of which there have been several varieties in our towns and in our armies, (c) We read of Socrates that, although he never left Athens during several returns of the plague which so many times cruelly afflicted her, he alone was never the worse for it. 2 (b) The doctors might, so I think, derive more profit from odours than they do; for I have often noticed that they affect me and act on my spirits according to their nature; which makes me think well of what is said, that the use of incense and perfumes in churches, so ancient and so widespread among all nations and religions, is to delight us and to arouse and purify our senses, the better to fit us for profound meditation. (c) I should well like, in order to judge of it, to have had personal knowledge of the a r t 3 of those cooks who knew how to unite foreign odours with the flavour of the meats, as was observed particularly in the service of that king of Tunis who, in our day, came to Naples to speak face to face with the Emperor Charles. His meats were stuffed with odoriferous ingredients so expensively that one peacock and two pheasants cost a hundred ducats to prepare in their way; 1 2 3

See Herodotus, IV, 75. See Diogenes Laertius, Life of Socrates. Avoir eu ma part de ΐart.

22

ESSAYS OF MONTAIGNE

and when they were carved, not only the banquet hall, but all the rooms in the palace and even in the neighbouring houses were filled with a very sweet vapour which did not immediately pass away. 1 {b) M y chief care in selecting my lodging is to avoid illsmelling and heavy air. Those beautiful cities Venice and Paris impair the good opinion I have of them by the offensive smell, in the one, of her marshes, in the other, of her mud. CHAPTER LVI OF

PRAYERS

THIS Essay originally (in 1580) began with the sentence, " I know not whether I am mistaken." In 1582 the first lines were added, with the exception of the sentence concerning "l'Eglise catholique, apostolique et romaine," which was added in 1595. M. Villey observes: "This declaration, which appeared for the first time in the edition of 1582, was unquestionably induced by the warning given Montaigne by the maestro del sacre palazzo, of which Montaigne speaks in his Journal de Voyage." He there says (18th March, 1580): "To-day in the evening, my Essays were returned to me corrected in accordance with the judgement of the Docteurs Moines. The Maestro del sacre palazzo had been able to judge of them only by the report of some French Frater, he [*.