263 84 3MB
English Pages 255 [273] Year 2011
The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion
Edited by Christopher Hobson and Milja Kurki
Democratization Studies
The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion
How do different meanings of the concept of ‘democracy’ operate in democracy promotion? How do conceptual decisions influence real political events? How is policy and reflection on democracy promotion shaped by the way different practitioners and scholars understand democracy? The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion explores the way in which the meaning, content and context of ‘democracy’ are interpreted by different actors in democracy promotion, and how these influence political decisions. Introducing a theoretically new approach to the study of democracy promotion, the volume shows how the alternate ways that democracy can be understood reflects specific interpretations of political and normative ideals, as well as being closely tied to social power relations, interests, and struggles between political actors. With original contributions from some of the most prominent specialists on democracy promotion and democratisation, the book examines a number of concrete cases of democracy promotion and contestation over democracy’s meaning. Re-examining democracy promotion at its time of crisis, this book will be of interest to scholars and students of democracy and democratisation, politics and international relations, international law, development studies and political theory. Christopher Hobson is a Research Associate in the Peace and Security section, Institute for Sustainability and Peace, United Nations University, Japan. Milja Kurki is a Lecturer in International Relations Theory in the International Politics Department at Aberystwyth University, UK, and the Principal Investigator of ‘Political Economies of Democratisation’ (European Research Council, 2008–2012).
Democratization studies (formerly democratization studies, Frank Cass)
Democratization Studies combines theoretical and comparative studies with detailed analyses of issues central to democratic progress and its performance, all over the world. The books in this series aim to encourage debate on the many aspects of democratization that are of interest to policy-makers, administrators and journalists, aid and development personnel, as well as to all those involved in education. 1 Democratization and the Media Edited by Vicky Randall 2 The Resilience of Democracy Persistent practice, durable idea Edited by Peter Burnell and Peter Calvert 3 The Internet, Democracy and Democratization Edited by Peter Ferdinand 4 Party Development and Democratic Change in Post-communist Europe Edited by Paul Lewis 5 Democracy Assistance International co-operation for democratization Edited by Peter Burnell 6 Opposition and Democracy in South Africa Edited by Roger Southall 7 The European Union and Democracy Promotion The case of North Africa Edited by Richard Gillespie and Richard Youngs 8 Democratization and the Judiciary Edited by Siri Gloppen, Roberto Gargarella and Elin Skaar
9 Civil Society in Democratization Edited by Peter Burnell and Peter Calvert 10 The Internet and Politics Citizens, voters and activists Edited by Sarah Oates, Diana Owen and Rachel Gibson 11 Democratization in the Muslim World Changing patterns of authority and power Edited by Frederic Volpi and Francesco Cavatorta 12 Global Democracy: For and Against Ethical theory, institutional design and social struggles Raffaele Marchetti 13 Constructing Democracy in Southern Europe A comparative analysis of Italy, Spain and Turkey Lauren M. McLaren 14 The Consolidation of Democracy Comparing Europe and Latin America Carsten Q. Schneider 15 New Challenges to Democratization Edited by Peter Burnell and Richard Youngs 16 Multiple Democracies In Europe Political culture in new member states Paul Blokker 17 Globality, Democracy and Civil Society Edited by Terrell Carver and Jens Bartelson 18 Democracy Promotion and Conflict-based Reconstruction The United States and democratic consolidation in Bosnia and Afghanistan Matthew Alan Hill 19 Requisites of Democracy Conceptualization, measurement, and explanation Jørgen Møller and Svend-Erik Skaaning 20 The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion Edited by Christopher Hobson and Milja Kurki
The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion
Edited by Christopher Hobson and Milja Kurki
First published 2012 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2012 Christopher Hobson and Milja Kurki for selection and editorial matter, individual contributors; their contributions The right of Christopher Hobson and Milja Kurki to be identified as the authors of the editorial material, and of the authors for their individual chapters, has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data A catalog record has been requested for this book ISBN: 978-0-415-59687-9 (hbk) ISBN: 978-0-203-80480-3 (ebk) Typeset in Times by Wearset Ltd, Boldon, Tyne and Wear
Contents
Notes on contributors Acknowledgements Foreword
ix xii xiii
T homas C aroth e rs
Introduction: the conceptual politics of democracy promotion
1
C hristoph e r H obson and M il j a K urki
Part I
Orientations
17
1 On ‘cultivating’ democracy: enlivening the imagery for democracy promotion
19
L aur e nc e W hit e h e ad
2 Conceptualizing democratization and democratizing conceptualization: a virtuous circle
38
P iki I sh - S halom
3 Liberalism and democracy promotion
53
B e at e Jahn
4 The past and future of social democracy and the consequences for democracy promotion
68
S h e ri B e rman
5 Democracy promotion: neoliberal vs social democratic telos
85
H e ikki P atom ä ki
6 Misunderstanding the maladies of liberal democracy promotion R ichard Y oun g s
100
viii Contents Part II
Cases
117
7 The conceptual politics of democracy promotion in Bolivia
119
Jonas W olff
8 Liberal democracy promotion and civil society strengthening in Ghana
131
Gordon C rawford and A bdul - Gafaru A bdulai
9 Concepts of democracy among donors and recipients of democracy promotion: an empirical pilot study
151
V al e ri e J . B unc e and S haron L . W olchik
10 Arab democratization and the de-imagining of authoritarian community: beyond Orientalism and Occidentalism
171
L arbi S adiki
11 The conceptual politics of democracy in international law
189
H ilary C harl e sworth
12 From ‘fortunate vagueness’ to ‘democratic globalism’: American democracy promotion as imperialism
201
T ony S mith
Conclusion: reflections on a new approach in a new era of democracy promotion
215
C hristoph e r H obson and M il j a K urki
Bibliography Index
224 245
Contributors
Abdul-Gafaru Abdulai is a PhD candidate at the Institute for Development Policy and Management (IDPM), University of Manchester, UK. He holds an MPhil in Development Studies from the University of Cambridge, UK, and worked as a Research Officer at the Institute for Democratic Governance (IDEG), Ghana, from March 2007 to September 2009. Sheri Berman is Associate Professor of Political Science at Barnard College, Columbia University. She is the author, most recently, of The Primacy of Politics: Social Democracy and the Making of Europe’s Twentieth Century and is currently working on a project re-examining European political development in order to figure out what relevance and lessons the European experience has for countries struggling to establish well-functioning states and political systems today. Valerie J. Bunce is Professor of Government and the Aaron Binenkorb Chair of International Studies at Cornell University. She is the co-author (with Sharon L. Wolchik) of Defeating Authoritarian Leaders in Postcommunist Countries (Cambridge University Press, 2011). Hilary Charlesworth is an Australian Research Council Laureate Fellow and Professor of International Law at the Australian National University. She has been a visiting professor at a number of Asian, European and United States universities. Gordon Crawford is Professor of Development Politics in the School of Politics and International Studies, University of Leeds, UK, where he also directs the University’s Centre for Global Development. He is the co-editor of Democratization and academic lead in the World Universities Network (WUN) research group on ‘Transformative Justice’. Christopher Hobson is a Research Associate in the Peace and Security section, Institute for Sustainability and Peace, United Nations University. His research focuses primarily on the various ways in which democracy intersects with international politics.
x Contributors Piki Ish-Shalom is a Senior Lecturer at the Department of International Relations, the Hebrew University of Jerusalem. He has published articles in different scholarly journals such as International Studies Quarterly, European Journal of International Relations, Political Science Quarterly, and Perspec tives on Politics. Beate Jahn is Professor of International Relations at the University of Sussex. Her publications on liberal internationalism and classical theory appear in International Organization, the Review of International Studies, International Theory, and the Journal of Intervention and Statebuilding. Milja Kurki is a lecturer in the International Politics Department at Aberystwyth University and currently the Principal Investigator of ‘Political Economies of Democratisation’, a four-year European Research Council funded project based at the same department. She is the author of Causation in International Relations: Reclaiming Causal Analysis (Cambridge University Press, 2008) and co-editor of International Relations Theories: Discipline and Diversity (2007, 2009). Heikki Patomäki, b.1963, is Professor of International Relations at the University of Helsinki, Finland. In 2011, he is also Visiting Professor at the Ritsumeikan University in Kyoto, Japan. Patomäki’s research interests include philosophy and methodology of social sciences, peace research, futures studies, global political economy and global political theory. His most recent book is The Political Economy of Global Security: War, Future Crises and Changes in Global Governance (Routledge, 2008). Larbi Sadiki teaches Middle East politics at the University of Exeter, UK, specializing in Arab democratisation, and is a columnist with Al-Jazeera (English). Tony Smith is the Cornelia M. Jackson Professor of Political Science at Tufts University. A new edition of his book America’s Mission: The United States and the Worldwide Struggle for Democracy will be published by Princeton University Press in 2012. He is currently working on a book on the religious fundamentals of Woodrow Wilson’s ideas behind democracy promotion. Laurence Whitehead is an Official Fellow in Politics at Nuffield College, Oxford University, and Senior Fellow of the College. In March 2011 he takes up a one-year post as Senior Proctor of the University. His most recent books are Latin America: A New Interpretation (Palgrave, 2006 and 2010) and Democratization: Theory and Experience (OUP, 2002). Recent articles include: ‘Losing “the Force”? The “Dark Side” of democratization after Iraq’, Democratization (2009) and ‘The Crash of “08” ’, Journal of Democracy (2010). He is editor of an Oxford University Press series, ‘Studies in Demo cratization’, and President of the Conseil Scientifique of the Institut des Ameriques in Paris.
Contributors xi Sharon L. Wolchik is Professor of Political Science and International Affairs at George Washington University. She is the co-author, with Valerie J. Bunce, of Defeating Authoritarian Leaders in Postcommunist Countries (Cambridge University Press, 2011). Jonas Wolff is Chairman of the Research Council and Senior Research Fellow at the Peace Research Institute Frankfurt (PRIF ), Germany. His research interests include Latin American politics, democratisation and international democracy promotion. Richard Youngs is Director of FRIDE, Madrid, and Associate Professor at the University of Warwick, UK. His latest book is Europe’s Decline and Fall: the Struggle against Global Irrelevance (Profile Books, 2010).
Acknowledgements
This book was initially conceived by the editors as part of their work on the ‘Political Economies of Democratisation’ (PEoD) project, based at the Interna tional Politics Department, Aberystwyth University since 2008. We would like to first express gratitude for the generous financial assistance of the European Research Council in facilitating the conception of this volume. Funded under the auspices of the Seventh Framework Programme (ERC grant agreement 202 596), the PEoD project has not only provided the resources for the editors to conceive of and develop the core themes of this book, but it also funded ‘The Conceptual Politics of Democracy Promotion’ workshop held in Aberystwyth, 27–29 July 2010. This workshop allowed most of the contributors to come together to present initial versions of their chapters and to discuss the central ideas of the volume. In addition to the contributors, Thomas Carothers, Carole Pateman and Phil Cerny visited Aberystwyth to participate in the workshop, and we are deeply appreciative of the invaluable advice and comments they provided about the direction of the project. The meeting proved to be a great success and would not have been possible without the invaluable assistance of Jeff Bridoux and Anja Gebel in its organisation and management. Jeff went above and beyond the call of duty, and we are especially grateful for all his help. We would also like to thank Mike Foley for his departmental support for the workshop. In particular, we would like to thank the contributors for responding so positively to our invitation to explore the theme of ‘conceptual politics’ in regards to democracy pro motion and democratisation. Finally, we are extremely grateful to the editors at Routledge for their support of this project, and to Eric Fong for his hard work in helping to prepare the final manuscript. Christopher Hobson and Milja Kurki Tokyo and Aberystwyth, January 2011
Foreword
International democracy promotion rushed out of the gates in the late 1980s and early 1990s. Events in the world were moving fast – authoritarian regimes were collapsing with startling rapidity and frequency and attempted democratic transitions were multiplying in their wake. The relatively small community of organisations and persons engaged in supporting democracy across borders threw themselves into the breech, infused with a strong sense of certainty about the importance of their mission and the universal validity of liberal democracy. Twenty years later the picture has changed. The international democracy pro motion community is much larger now, comprising a panoply of public, private, and multilateral actors based in many countries. Their activities are present in something like 100 countries around the world. Despite this growth, the optim ism and momentum of earlier years are much tempered and a strong sense pervades the community of a need for reconsideration and renovation. Sobering changes in the international political landscape are in part behind this change. Democracy’s spread has been replaced by fears of a democratic recession – the first decade of this century saw no net gain in the number of democracies in the world, though recent developments in the Arab world now raise the possibility of a better decade ahead. Assertive challengers to democracy, including but not limited to China and Russia, have cracked the assumption that this century will necessarily be liberal democracy’s extended moment. The established democracies of North America and Europe are less self-confident about their own success, buffeted as they have been by economic woes and also socio- political tensions over how to balance their democratic norms with concerns over security and various internal issues. The practice of democracy promotion itself has also experienced problems. The close association of democracy promotion with the US intervention in Iraq and with the broader regime change aspirations of President George W. Bush significantly damaged the legitimacy of the enterprise. These controversial US policies fueled a backlash against democracy support activities in many recipient countries, caused many Europeans to disassociate themselves from the topic, and weakened US public support for it as well. More broadly, democracy support – traditionally focused on political institutions and processes – has found itself struggling to respond to the widespread disappointment of citizens in many new
xiv Foreword democracies with the lack of improvement that pluralistic politics have brought to their socio-economic condition. This new context is very much on the minds of policy-makers and aid practitioners in Western governments, multilateral organisations, and private aid groups, prompting many of them to search for new and better ways forward. This present volume is thus well timed. It is the most serious effort yet coming from the scholarly research community to raise hard questions about the conceptual bases of international democracy support, about models and methods, prin ciples and practices, entry points and end points. The editors have steered their critical enterprise with care, avoiding the pitfalls that could easily undermine such a venture. The book avoids the trap of hewing to just one narrow line of critique that would seek to dismiss the whole enterprise as ill-intentioned and ill- conceived, what the editors refer to as ‘the neo-Gramscian critique’, and instead usefully pursues a pluralism of critical perspectives, including a strong chapter that critiques what some practitioners view as a critical orthodoxy. It also avoids the trap of hermitic abstraction. The volume boasts a strong set of case studies well-informed by research on democracy promotion in practice and all of the authors are attentive to practicalities of the democracy support enterprise. And it avoids the trap of predetermined answers, preferring instead to establish the legitimacy of a range of important, neglected questions about both methods and goals. The result is a volume that could play a valuable role in the larger effort to reconsider and renovate international democracy support. The exact nature of this will itself be the subject of interesting debates ahead as scholars and practitioners take up the arguments contained within and react to them in diverse ways, very much in keeping with the overall spirit of this lively book. Thomas Carothers Carnegie Endowment for International Peace
Introduction The conceptual politics of democracy promotion Christopher Hobson and Milja Kurki1
Consensus and contestation in democracy promotion Democracy promotion quickly emerged as one of the defining characteristics of the post-Cold War international order. The context within which it appeared has shaped and arguably warped it in ways that are only now becoming more evid ent. Crucially, the practice of democracy promotion became embedded within international politics at a unique historical moment, a time in which there was unusually little discussion over alternate forms of rule. Communism followed fascism into the dustbin of history, and democracy was left as the most legitimate and accepted method of government. The liberal Zeitgeist was perfectly captured in Francis Fukuyama’s ‘end of history’ thesis, which confidently announced ‘Western liberal democracy as the final form of human government’ (Fukuyama 1989: 3). Looking back on this period, the faith placed in liberal democracy undoubtedly appears excessive and overly optimistic. It may not be accurate to equate the failure of communism with the success of liberal demo cracy, but this is what many did. This confidence in liberal democracy prevailed within the nascent democracy promotion community. Furthermore, after com munism, more experimentation was the last thing people wanted in many target countries of democracy promotion. Above all, there was a deep desire for normality and prosperity, which was thought to mean liberal democracy in the political sphere and free market capitalism in the economic realm. In this regard, Timothy Garton Ash (2009) has recently suggested that the Velvet Revolutions of 1989 heralded a new form of regime change, one that is ‘typically anti-utopian, or at the very least non-utopian. In a given place, it aspires to create political and legal institutions, and social and economic arrangements, that already exist elsewhere (for example, in established liberal democracies)’. One key consequence of this non-revolutionary attitude was that there were few questions about forms of rule: liberal democracy was widely accepted as the answer. As Krastev (2010: 117) observes, ‘the politics of “normalization” replaced deliberation with imitation’. This impacted not only on transitional states in East Central Europe, but also more generally on the way democracy promotion was being conceptualised and instituted: liberal market democracy became the consensus end point being worked towards.
2 C. Hobson and M. Kurki 1989 and its immediate aftermath is distinctive for the unusual lull in debate and discussion over democracy’s meaning and value. This exceptional period has been mistakenly taken for the norm, however, with consequences for the way democracy promotion and democratisation has been subsequently understood. Notably, democracy’s lack of systemic challengers significantly shaped perceptions about the role external actors could, and should, play in assisting its spread across the globe. In this regard, Michael McFaul (2004–5: 148) suggested that not only has, ‘the norm of democracy . . . achieved striking universality in the current international system’, but that the promotion of democracy ‘has also become an international norm’. This claim now appears distinctly premature, given the growing ‘backlash’ against these practices (Carothers 2010). On a deeper level, such developments are reflective of the end of the liberal interregnum of the 1990s, as there is again more contestation surrounding the meaning and value of democracy. This is the historically more regular situation, one that needs to be recognised and adjusted to by those involved in assisting the global spread of democracy (Hobson 2009a). Recent academic literature has highlighted some of the problems and dilemmas democracy promoters now face, and have sought to devise new ways of tackling these issues (Diamond 2008; Burnell and Youngs 2010; Barany and Moser, 2009; McFaul 2010). Yet, these responses have remained limited in crucial respects. The focus has been almost exclusively on questions of policy and implementation, with insufficient consideration given to the theoretical and conceptual frameworks that inform these practices. The starting point for this volume is to examine precisely what so many classical policy frameworks and academic accounts have taken for granted: demo cracy’s meaning in democracy promotion. We suggest that the consensus view of what is meant by ‘democracy’ when it is advanced and supported abroad needs to be analysed systematically and, where necessary, challenged and rethought. Indeed, the view that democracy need not be conceptually probed and questioned any more may be rather deceptive. With more conceptually nuanced tools we might discover that there may in fact be considerable differences in how various actors involved in democracy promotion actually understand this contested idea. One should not presume that all the different actors involved – external donors, target populations, international organisations, NGOs and other intermediary bodies etc – conceive of democracy in a comparable manner. For instance, do the United States, the European Union and the United Nations really work with the same notion of democracy? Do these actors even employ a clear and static idea of democracy, or are there shifts and contestations within their own conceptual frameworks? And how do understandings of democracy held by external actors relate to localised conceptions? Rather than taking democracy’s meaning as a constant across a wide variety of actors and contexts, this volume identifies it as an open question in need of careful and reflective study. In so doing, we seek to initiate more empirically accurate and theoretically penetrating analyses of contemporary practices of democracy promotion. Conceptual pol itics, it will be seen in the various chapters presented here, play an important role in the practice of democracy promotion; and we contend that it is better to tackle
Introduction 3 these conceptual politics directly, rather than sideline or ignore them, despite their complexity and the occasionally discomforting uncertainty that they may raise. This introduction is divided into three parts, and provides a basic framework for the detailed analyses and case studies that follow. First, the conceptual pol itics approach is outlined. Second, a number of core themes and issues that arise from adopting such a perspective are discussed. Third, a brief summary of the chapters within the volume is provided.
Conceptual politics and democracy promotion Before outlining what the conceptual politics approach entails, it is helpful to briefly clarify what this framework is being applied to, namely, democracy pro motion. Both within the academic literature and in policy discourse there are some differences over what the term ‘democracy promotion’ is seen to cover. Democracy promotion is understood here in a broad, overarching manner: it means the processes by which an external actor intervenes to install or assist in the institution of democratic government in a target state. Democracy promotion incorporates a wide variety of strategies and actions, operating across a spectrum from peaceful to forceful means. It can entail coercive actions, political con ditionalities, economic or financial concessions or sanctions, as well as various ‘soft’ measures such as grass roots civil society support (see Burnell 2000). It should be noted that today coercive democratisation is relatively rare, even if the prominence of the Bush administration’s behaviour has encouraged a view that links democracy promotion with the exercise of military force (Carothers 2010: 64). Reflecting the wide range of democracy promotion activities that exist, the chapters in this volume also engage with many of the different actors that constitute the democracy promotion community: states, international organisations, NGOs, political foundations, contractors and more. Having identified how ‘democracy promotion’ is understood, it is necessary to explain what exactly is meant by the notion of ‘conceptual politics’. A crucial first step is clarifying this framework, as well as outlining its value for the study of democracy promotion. ‘Conceptual politics’ describes the ways in which con tested concepts – like democracy – are interpreted, used, and fought over by actors, and how certain meanings and definitions come to influence real world phenomena. From this perspective, the way concepts are understood is not somehow prior to, or removed from, politics, but is an unavoidable component, and thus form a necessary part of our study. Connolly (1993: 3) expresses the point well: ‘since the discourse of politics helps to set the terms within which that politics proceeds, one who seeks to understand and to assess the structure of political life must deliberately probe the conventions governing those concepts’. The suggestion that politics extends to the way the ‘real’ world is conceived and described builds on interpretivist and constructivist scholarship, which has strongly argued that language is fundamental in constituting social reality. As Koselleck (1996: 61) explains, ‘concepts are both indicators of and factors in
4 C. Hobson and M. Kurki political and social life. Put metaphorically, concepts are like joints linking language and the extra-linguistic world.’ Concepts are not epiphenomenal: the manner in which they are understood and used by both practitioners and scholars has an important role in giving substance to the world that is being observed. In essence, what ‘conceptual politics’ conveys is the way key concepts are debated, transposed and imposed, and how these outcomes impact upon, and help shape, reality. The conceptual politics approach is one that is well suited for studying demo cracy, a term that is both politically powerful and heavily contested. Guizot’s (1849: 2–3) observation rings true: ‘such is the power of the word Democracy, that no government or party dares to raise its head, or believes its own existence possible, if it does not bear that word inscribed on its banner’. These words were written in the middle of the nineteenth century, but are equally applicable to con temporary politics. One element that unites countries as diverse as the United States, South Africa, Congo, Russia, and Sweden is that all publicly define themselves – in one form or another – in relation to democracy. Yet despite the ubiquitous references to democracy, what is meant by the concept is far from clear or uncontested – and indeed in many instances references to democracy may be more rhetorical than substantive. The contested nature of democracy has been widely documented and commented upon by political theorists. W. B. Gallie (1956) famously suggested that democracy is best understood as an ‘essentially contested concept’. It is the aim of this volume to take seriously Gallie’s contention and, as a result, directly tackle the nature and consequences that this contested-ness involves for demo cracy promotion. But do political theory insights necessarily apply to the much more concrete realm of democracy promotion? Within the existing literature, a majority of scholars would suggest that it does not. The common pattern is to define democracy at the outset: it is a precursor to the analysis, rather than constituting part of the study itself (Kurki 2010). This reflects the overwhelming tendency in this field to adopt an objectivist view of politics and language. As such, the discussion that has taken place over defining democracy has done so within a largely positivist framework, which regards definitional issues as separate from practice and analysis. In scholarship on democratisation and democracy promotion, the near universal starting point for conceiving of democracy has been, and to a significant extent still is, the influential definition of democracy espoused by Joseph Schumpeter (1943) and extended by Robert Dahl (1971). From their perspective, democracy is viewed in procedural terms, with elections and related procedural elements of representative government taken as the ‘sine qua non’ of democracy (Huntington 1993: 9). While this approach continues to have a strong group of adherents, it should also be noted that scholarly consensus has been refined in response to the so-called ‘electoral fallacy’, whereby elections and democracy are equated, something the minimalist procedural approach is susceptible to. By themselves, elections have come to be seen as insufficient; a functioning, consolidated democracy also requires a supportive liberal democratic ‘culture’: freedom of speech and
Introduction 5 association and the protection of other basic rights. This has given rise to an important distinction between ‘electoral’ and ‘liberal’ democracies (Diamond 1996). The former accords with the minimalist approach, while the latter is a more extensive understanding that incorporates liberal constitutionalism, culture and rights. There is now a remarkable level of agreement on the view that both aspects of the two-part definition of democracy are essential to democratisation. Peter Burnell (2010a: 2), for example, has recently concluded that, ‘democracy is of course a much-contested concept. But in most of the discourse on democratization and in the understandings held by democracy promoters also there are certainly widely accepted notions of electoral democracy and liberal democracy’. This position is echoed by Michael McFaul (2010: 28–32), a leading scholar in the field and now a member of the Obama administration: ‘broad agreement in academia and the policy community has emerged on both a minimalist definition of democracy and the kinds of institutions and attributes needed to transform electoral democra cies into more robust democratic systems of government.’ The widespread scholarly agreement over democracy’s meaning is beneficial insofar as it allows for a greater level of comparability between studies, and thus it creates the possibility for the further generation of knowledge in this area. Measuring democracy and success of democracy promotion – and indeed demo cracy promotion practice itself – is easier when an agreed-upon set of criteria for what constitutes democracy can be worked with. On another level, however, the tendency to decontest democracy’s meaning and remove interpretive aspects from this field of study can actually impair our understanding. Indeed, a key claim of this volume is that in examining democracy promotion and democrat isation it is essential to seriously engage with the way the idea of democracy is defined and employed by different actors in order to better understand and explain the dynamics and effects of democracy promotion practices and dialogues. Thus, contributions by Laurence Whitehead, and Valerie J. Bunce and Sharon L. Wolchik, for example, illustrate how engaging with the conceptual foundations of these practices can be harnessed in producing stronger explanat ory accounts of democracy promotion and democratisation. Given that this sub- field has been strongly criticised for its failure to generate a larger body of knowledge (Geddes 2007, 2009), expanding its remit to explicitly include such conceptual and theoretical issues has considerable potential. Simultaneously, a conceptual politics perspective has strong affinities with critical theory and post-positivist approaches amongst which not only better understanding but also normative questions and critique can be an important aim of study. For instance, Ish-Shalom’s contribution here illustrates how a conceptual politics framework can bring to light hidden normative and political positions embedded in democracy promotion practices. From this perspective, defining and understanding democracy is an unavoidably political and normative act, with serious ramifications both for democracy promotion and the role of scholars studying the subject. This volume is premised on the belief that engaging with the conceptual politics of democracy promotion is a fruitful and neces sary exercise for both mainstream ‘explanatory’ scholars and ‘critical’ theorists.
6 C. Hobson and M. Kurki It is important to emphasise that the approach adopted in this volume is explicitly pluralist, and should be distinguished from the existing neo-Gramscian literature on the conceptual dimensions of democracy promotion. These scholars have argued that democracy promotion is dominated by a narrow, elitist model of liberal democracy, one that is limited strictly to the political sphere and does not extend to, or challenge, the socio-economic order. Noting its close corres pondence to the influential definition of Robert Dahl, Robinson (1996) suggests that what is being promoted is not democracy, but ‘polyarchy’: an impoverished replica that serves the interests of a transnational elite. Gills, Rocamora and Wilson (1993) make a similar argument, proposing that the United States seeks to institute ‘low intensity democracy’, a kind of regime geared towards their economic interests. What these vocal critics have illustrated is that the way democracy is conceived of has real and significant consequences. Indeed, given some of the important insights generated by this scholarship, it is surprising the work done in the 1990s has not been consolidated and extended. This volume certainly has some points of overlap with these neo-Gramscian studies: it concurs with the need to investigate the conceptual foundations of these practices, and it also appreciates the importance of recognising how normative systems of meaning are tied in complex ways to the interests of actors. Nonetheless, there are also crucial differences. First, a strongly pluralistic perspective is adopted here. While the conceptual politics framework is informed by a minimal set of interpretivist assumptions (see also Whitehead 2002), this volume is not based on one theoretical approach, neo-Gramscian or otherwise. Rather, it incorp orates contributions from different normative standpoints, theoretical traditions, regional specialities and academic disciplines. Second, the neo-Gramscians do successfully highlight certain conceptual aspects of democracy promotion, but the picture painted often seems too black and white. For instance, to talk of a transnational bloc of ruling elites simply does not accord with a far more complicated reality, in which there is considerable difference between different democracy promoters (Guilhot 2005: 15–17). As some contributions to this volume suggest, the dominance of a liberal democratic model should not blind us to the conceptual – and political – diversity and variation that exist nowadays within and around democracy promotion practice. As Richard Youngs argues, in the case of the EU, for example, the conceptual politics of democracy promotion are far more complex and multi-faceted than the neo-Gramscian perspective has allowed for. Third, in the neo-Gramscian literature there is a tendency to present an overly binary reading of democracy, opposing a stylised version of liberal democracy against a vague model of participatory democracy. This volume supports expanding discussion on different forms of democracy, but seeks to venture much further in pluralising the debate, examining a wide variety of conceptions of democracy.
Analytical themes Having provided an outline of what a conceptual politics approach to democracy promotion entails, it is necessary to consider in more detail exactly how this can
Introduction 7 be applied. To provide a broad analytical framework for the chapters that follow, a two-fold categorisation is provided here. First, three kinds of conceptual debate are distinguished. Second, three different contexts within which conceptual contestation can occur are identified. This categorisation is, of course, in part arbit rary – for example, the three kinds of conceptual debate overlap and speak to each other in complex ways – and further kinds of analytical distinctions could be developed. Yet, we argue that it is analytically useful to separate these basic kinds of debate and sites of conceptual contestation as a framework within which the reader can position the individual chapters in the volume. Kinds of conceptual debate 1 Models of democracy The most fundamental axis around which the conceptual politics of democracy promotion operates is the basic question of what democracy means. Within polit ical theory, this issue has crystallised around debates between different ‘models’ of democracy (Macpherson 1977; Held 2006). For example, in clear contrast to the democratisation literature, which generally refers only to ‘electoral’ and ‘lib eral’ democracy (e.g. Diamond 2008: 20–6; McFaul 2010: 28–32), David Held (2006) identifies a much wider range of democratic models: classical, republican, liberal, direct, elitist, pluralist, socialist, deliberative and cosmopolitan. These forms are distinguished by the way the nature, scope, and purpose of democracy are understood. Debates between alternate models reflect the fact that throughout democracy’s history there has been an uneasy coexistence between two central principles: liberty and equality. Liberal theories have prioritised the former, emphasising core civil and political rights of individuals, as well as certain polit ical institutions and procedures. In contrast, social democrats have placed more weight on equality, which has led to a concern with protecting socio-economic rights and regulating the economic realm. Liberal and social democratic models are perhaps the most well known and commonly practised (and also made refer ence to most often in this volume) but these are by no means the only conceptions that exist. Participatory and deliberative democrats draw upon the legacy of ancient Greece to call for greater involvement by people in decision-making pro cesses. Meanwhile, radical and cosmopolitan democrats reject the traditional boundaries of democratic politics, arguing for transnational and global forms of democracy. These various understandings, and the many others that exist, may share certain points of overlap or agreement, but all have differing visions of the core values, institutions and priorities of democratic governance. Most existing scholarship on democracy promotion has consciously rejected the kinds of questions that animate discussions over models of democracy. These are instead seen as being about the way democracy performs and functions, rather than composing part of the actual definition. To the extent that variations in democracy are considered, these tend to be understood in institutional terms, i.e. parliamentary versus presidential (McFaul 2010: 32–4). The discussion over
8 C. Hobson and M. Kurki different models of democracy in political theory is in reference to deeper ideo logical, normative and political dynamics, however. Of interest are not merely specific institutional forms, but also the underlying values and ideas that give them life and meaning. Given the extensive contestation and discussion in polit ical theory between different models of democracy, it is remarkable how little of this has filtered through to debates in democracy promotion and democratisation. The result is that when considering democracy promotion, we are left with an incomplete and impoverished understanding of the most important component: democracy. By explicitly engaging with different models of democracy, this volume seeks to initiate deeper reflection on what exactly actors are doing, and should be doing, when they engage in or with democracy promotion. 2 Vagueness versus precision Considering different models of democracy is perhaps the most obvious entry point to the conceptual politics approach. Nonetheless, a central purpose of this volume is to demonstrate the multiplicity of ways conceptual and theoretical issues shape democracy promotion. Another axis around which contestation takes place is over the way democracy is defined. Within existing literature there has been an ongoing debate about whether democracy and autocracy should be measured in a dichotomous or graded fashion. The latter viewpoint has largely prevailed in recent years, partly due to the empirical reality of a considerable amount of ‘semi-democracies’ or ‘hybrid regimes’, which have complicated attempts to draw strict distinctions. Notably, influential data sets, such as the annual Freedom House surveys and the Polity index, work with a graded scale. Both are widely utilised by policymakers and academics in assessing the amount of democracies in the world. As such, how these surveys understand democracy is not without consequence, and the political effects of these definitional practices need to be considered. The degree of specificity in democracy’s meaning has consequences for how democracy promotion policies are conceived. Certain actors may seek to keep democracy’s meaning vague, thereby allowing a wider range of regimes and behaviour to be labelled ‘democratic’. This is hardly a new phenomenon. Con sidering the meaning of democracy in 1920, Brown (1920: v) complained that ‘the word has come to mean nothing; or rather it means so much that it means nothing at all’. Writing shortly before the onset of the Cold War, partly defined as a conflict between liberal and people’s democracies, George Orwell (1946) offered a sceptical perspective: In the case of a word like democracy, not only is there no agreed definition, but the attempt to make one is resisted from all sides. It is almost univer sally felt that when we call a country democratic we are praising it: con sequently the defenders of every kind of regime claim that it is a democracy, and fear that they might have to stop using that word if it were tied down to any one meaning.
Introduction 9 The considerable political capital gained from being associated with the demo cratic label encourages actors to use it when attempting to legitimate themselves or their actions. One of many examples is that states lacking liberal democratic institutions, such as China, Iran, North Korea and Russia, all still employ the language of democracy. Speaking to the 17th Congress of the Chinese Communist Party in 2007, General Secretary Hu Jintao used the term ‘democracy’ no less than sixty-one times (McFaul 2010: 38). Whether or not attempts at employing or extending the term are successful will depend largely on how closely new meanings relate to received understandings, as there are limits on how broadly a concept can be stretched (Skinner 2002). In this regard, against those seeking to keep its meaning relatively indeterminate, other political actors may instead aim to fix and restrict democracy’s definition in a manner that accords with their own interests. Just as being able to claim the democratic label is important, actors can benefit from defining it in such a way that they are included within the definition, while others are excluded. The resulting situation is contestation between, on the one hand, those that seek to keep the idea of democracy as broad and indeterminate as possible, and on the other, those that try to limit its definition to something far more precise and seek to prevent conceptual ‘stretching’. These opposing positions represent an interesting point of analysis when con sidering the conceptual politics of democracy promotion: do actors seek to render precise the meaning of democracy, or do they gravitate towards vagueness? Definitional practices are reflective of the political context within which these actors are operating, and the specific goals they seek to achieve. Thus, the United States may push for a specific understanding in terms of liberal demo cracy, so as to bolster its universalist justifications for democracy promotion and to have an unquestioned model to advance on the ground. In contrast, in her con tribution, Charlesworth illustrates how the United Nations has tended towards a more open and vague definition of democracy, in part because of considerable conflict between member-states from the north and south. Both definitional tactics offer strategic advantages and dangers; and both have different kinds of political consequences. A fixed route narrows debate on the meaning of demo cracy, and potentially adds to the value of the label, but at the same, also increases the chances of hypocrisy, which can be especially problematic for external actors trying to support democracy. Vagueness also allows for the pos sibility of reconciling and managing potentially contradictory policies or approaches, but this may come at the expense of being able to maintain clarity of purpose or justification for democracy promotion. Arguably, the EU’s conceptually ‘fuzzy’ approach to democracy promotion is characterised by some of these dynamics (Kurki forthcoming a). 3 Process versus product On a more abstract level there is the question of how to conceive of democracy. Is democracy best seen as a specific set of institutions, such as elections, the rule of law, transparent and accountable rule? This is generally how it has been
10 C. Hobson and M. Kurki defined by those working within the Schumpeter/Dahl tradition. Or is democracy something diffuse, identified more by a culture or ethos than any particular set of governing procedures? This is not a purely academic question, as the answer has important consequences for the possibilities of democracy promotion. Ish- Shalom (2006) has argued elsewhere that if democracy is understood in institutional terms it can suggest that it is readily exportable, as opposed to a cultural approach, which is much harder to directly transfer. More often than not, there has been a tendency to view democracy as a finished product that can be transported to other locales. As Václav Havel (1995: 7) caustically observes, ‘demo cracy is seen as something given, finished, and complete as is, something that can be exported like cars or television sets.’ In contrast, if democracy is seen more as an ideal to strive towards, it potentially suggests a different framework for democracy promotion. For instance, scholars as diverse as Guillermo O’Donnell (2007), John Keane (2009) and Jacques Derrida (2005) all propose that democracy can never be finished, it is always ‘yet to come’. Indeed, it is notable that one of the leading figures of democratisation scholarship, Guillermo O’Donnell (2007: 5–11) proposes that ‘what is best and most distinctive about democracy’ is the never-ending gap between what it promises and what it delivers. From this perspective, democracy is given meaning and substance through the ongoing attempt to develop it further. Democracy is not simply a condition, but an open-ended process. In this regard, Havel (1995: 7) argues that it is more productive to see democracy as an ‘open system that is best able to respond to people’s basic needs – that is, as a set of possibilities that continually must be sought, redefined, and brought into being’. Is this perspective incompatible with democracy promotion? Or, conversely, does it provide a more dialogic and open form of engagement, where learning is a two-way process, such as Teivainen (2009) has argued for? As Whitehead suggests in his contribution, these two understandings are not completely separate, one can often find democracy simultaneously being understood and referenced as both an ideal and a set of institutions. Contexts and sites of conceptual politics Having set out a number of axes around which conceptual contestation occurs, it is necessary to consider the different contexts and locales within which these types of contestation occur. 1 Conceptual politics in and between democracy promotion actors The United States may have once held somewhat of a monopoly on supporting democracy abroad, but this is certainly no longer the case with a wide range of states, international organisations, NGOs and TNCs all participating in these practices (McFaul 2004–5). Given the considerable size the democracy promo tion community has grown to, one clear realm of conceptual politics is the issue of how similar or different the conceptions of democracy held by various
Introduction 11 external actors are. Is there a hegemonic conception of democracy? If difference does exist, how great is it? For instance, do the United States and the European Union both operate with an essentially similar liberal democratic model? Or are there considerable differences between the way these actors understand both democracy and processes of democratisation, as Kopstein (2006) suggests? What role do international organisations play? Is the conception of democracy the World Bank holds, for instance, simply reflective of its largest stakeholders? In examining the different (or similar) conceptions of democracy held by various actors, to what extent do these reflect certain political interests or ideologies? Contestation may not only occur between democracy promotion actors, but also within them. In this regard, perhaps the most obvious example is the Euro pean Union. Composed of 27 member-states, there is considerable variation in the way different countries conceive of, and practice, democracy and democracy assistance. For example, the United Kingdom has a liberal democratic model much closer to that found in the United States, whereas Scandinavian countries have sought to defend and maintain their tradition of social democracy. The work of different development institutions, not to even mention political founda tions, can be directed by very different ideological models of democracy, even if these differences are moderated by the depoliticising background discourses which facilitate debate on ‘European’ democracy promotion today (Kurki forthcoming a). Divergences of views on democracy are not unique to the complex European scene, however. In an important report on the American democracy promotion ‘bureaucracy’, Melia (2005) has argued that it is far more fragmented and pluralist than is generally portrayed. This suggests that it is worth con sidering whether various agencies within the United States – State department, USAID, the NED and so on – are working with the same conception of demo cracy (Bridoux 2011). Given how heavily contested the concept of democracy is, and its simultaneous position as both an institution and an ideal, there is con siderable room for variation between and within democracy promotion actors, with potentially significant ramifications for the way policies are formulated and implemented. 2 External agents and local conceptions One of the most important sites of contestation over democracy’s meaning takes place between the conceptions of democracy held by local and external actors. Opinion polls suggest widespread support for democracy across the globe, but there is considerable variation over how this term is actually understood, depending on which part of the world you are in. There may be widespread consensus in Western academic and policymaking circles over what democracy entails, but it is far from certain how far this understanding extends. For example, following the end of communism in East Central Europe, liberal democracy was widely desired and supported as the successor regime. Yet liberal democracy was often equated simply with economic prosperity and now, two decades later, the fact that liberal democracy has meant something else has given rise to considerable
12 C. Hobson and M. Kurki dissatisfaction with the idea of democracy more generally. A false sense of confidence in the universalism of democracy has often encouraged potential disjunctures between how democracy is understood by the democracy promotion community and by target populations. It is time to seriously explore this gap, and also to consider ways of bridging it. Here Valerie J. Bunce and Sharon L. Wolchik, Jonas Wolff, Larbi Sadiki, and Gordon Crawford and Abdul-Gafaru Abdulai explore such tensions and differences. In considering the way local conceptions of democracy align (or not) with those held by external actors, it is also important to consider whether this may prevent the recognition of existing democratic practices. Put in more concrete terms, the way democracy is conceived of by democracy promoters may inhibit an awareness of local practices that are understood within that specific context as democratic but may not be labelled as such by external actors. A clear example of this can be found in the Middle East, where there is a strong tradition of broadly democratic practices, but these are regularly missed by external agents operating with an ill-fitting conception of democracy, an issue Sadiki explores in his contribution. At the very least, these kinds of issues complicate suggestions that democracy is a ‘universal value’, and challenge the Western-centrism that often dominates the discourse on democracy promotion, whereby democracy is unproblematically equated with the specific experience of Western Europe and North America. In looking at potential differences between the conception of democracy held by external actors and that held by local agents, one needs to be careful not to essentialise these positions. As Richard Youngs points out in his chapter, there is potential for just as much conceptual contestation to take place between local actors as there is between external and local agents. Indeed, as Bunce and Wolchik consider in their chapter, the manner in which outside funding has given rise to a culture of externally supported NGOs could result in there being considerable similarity in the viewpoints held by certain local actors and external agents. Similarly, the government may understand democracy in a way that differs from elements of civil society. 3 The conceptual politics of academia and policy making Scholarship on democracy promotion and democratisation is undoubtedly one part of political science that has a real and direct influence on policymaking and practice. Over the years, many leading academics have moved between the two realms. It is notable that arguably the leading journal in the field – the Journal of Demo cracy – is closely associated with the National Endowment for Democracy, a prominent democracy promotion actor created and funded by the US government. Looking at policy documents, it is evident that scholarly developments have been picked up: most clearly the distinction between transition and consolidation, as well as arguments for a fuller conception of democracy that entails more than just elections. These are just a few examples of the close linkages that exist between the scholars and policymakers in this field (Guilhot 2005; Robinson 1996).
Introduction 13 More generally, much of the academic work in this area is geared towards policy relevance. What this means is that the way democracy is understood, used and debated by academic observers can have direct real-world consequences. As such, it is particularly important that as scholars we reflect on the role (real and potential) our ideas and theories can play. Can theories be simply objective? Is it possible to analyse democracy promotion practices removed from our normative commitments and political biases? Or do these unavoidably influence our findings? These questions encourage us to think about whether existing research on democracy promotion and democratisation facilitates the hegemony of certain conceptions of democracy. Or alternatively, does it open up space to broaden the way democracy is thought about? These issues are addressed across this volume, most notably in the contributions from Laurence Whitehead, Piki Ish-Shalom, and Richard Youngs.
Chapter outline The contributors to the volume engage with a wide range of examples of conceptual contestation in the thought and practice of democracy promotion. The chapters in the first section do so through engaging with some of the core theor etical, normative and historical dimensions of the conceptual politics of demo cracy promotion. The authors explore a variety of motivations that may drive engagement with conceptual politics, and examine what such an approach is capable of revealing about democracy promotion practice. Building on these studies, the second section focuses on contemporary empirical cases where the conceptual politics of democracy promotion can be witnessed. In the first part, Laurence Whitehead guides our initial orientation towards conceptual politics by investigating the stakes – theoretical and practical – involved in how we conceptualise the core ideas of democracy, democratisation and democracy promotion. He suggests a shift towards more dynamic biological over mechanical conceptions in democratisation and democracy promotion, illustrating the need to engage with the conceptual dimensions in more open and innovative ways. His opening gambit is followed by Piki Ish-Shalom’s attempt to set down a normative case for taking account of the contested nature of demo cracy in democratisation and democracy promotion scholarship. He argues that academics specifically are normatively obligated to challenge the de-contesting trends characteristic of current debates and to actively reflect on and pluralise how democracy is understood and discussed. The following three chapters set the scene for debates on models of democracy in democracy promotion. They especially explore in more detail the nature and role of the liberal and social democratic models. Beate Jahn focuses on the relationship between liberalism and democracy, an issue that has been hotly debated as a result of Zakaria’s (see 2003) ‘illiberal democracies’ argument. Revisiting the thinking of Locke, a foundation figure for liberalism, Jahn argues that a misreading of the historical and theoretical relationship between liberalism and democracy has given rise to misunderstandings about how successful democratisation occurs and what role
14 C. Hobson and M. Kurki external forces and actors play in these processes. Adopting a historical- theoretical approach to conceptual politics, Sheri Berman argues in her chapter that much of democracy’s successes in the twentieth century have been misattributed to liberal democracy. The consolidation of stable democratic regimes in post-Second World War Europe is actually a story of the development of social democracy. This, she suggests, has important consequences for what models of democracy the West should advocate and how: in the long term, social demo cracy may offer a much greater chance of stability and wealth. Building on these discussions of liberal and social democracy, Heikki Patomaki examines the politico-economic context of democratisation and democracy promotion, pointing to the need to recognise the politico-economic underpinnings of different conceptions of democracy in democracy promotion. Contrasting the theoretical and practical premises of neoliberal and social democratic models as potential blueprints for democracy promotion, he argues that what is needed today, in order to achieve genuine democratisation, is movement towards a global social democratic model. In contrast to the first five chapters, which explore the variety of motivations – theoretical, practical, normative, historical – for engaging with conceptual pol itics of democracy promotion, Richard Youngs strikes a more cautionary note. He warns against the tendency in some critical literature to assume that a narrow set of conceptual foundations are involved in democracy promotion, and argues that some critical accounts are not sufficiently empirically grounded. In practice, democracy promoters can be more reflexive and reactive than some critics enthralled by a conceptual politics approach (especially of a critical theory orientation) may suggest. His chapter provides an important caution to those studying conceptual politics: key problems in democracy promotion today may lie less in the failures in the way democracy is conceptualised and have more to do with an inconsistent and unprincipled commitment to promoting democracy – liberal or otherwise. Responding in part to some of the concerns raised by Youngs, the second section of the volume is composed of a strong set of empirical studies on the conceptual politics of contemporary democracy promotion. Jonas Wolff con siders the recent experience of Bolivia, an exemplar case of how a conceptual politics approach can shed light on the way democratisation and democracy pro motion operates. Conceptual disagreement and contestation stands at the heart of the dynamics of the Bolivian democratic experiment today, a fact which raises unique challenges for external actors involved in the complex processes of the democratisation taking place. In the following chapter, Abdul-Gafaru Abdulai and Gordon Crawford focus on one core component of liberal democracy – civil society – and how external support for it has manifested in Ghana. Far from being a conceptually innocent or insignificant site, the civil society support programmes that they examine tell a powerful story of the kind of liberal civil soci ety that is advanced and the role conceptual choices play in defending specific interests of external actors, often at the expense of ‘holistic’ or ‘truly representative’ democratisation. In their chapter, Valerie J. Bunce and Sharon L. Wolchik
Introduction 15 examine the conceptual politics of democracy promotion in East and Central Europe. They apply a comparative empirical perspective to the examination of conceptions of democracy that democracy promoters in this context work with, finding an unexpected set of conceptual dynamics at work here, which they argue warrant further detailed examination. Larbi Sadiki’s chapter explores the conceptual politics of democracy promotion in the Middle East, interrogating the Orientalist and Occidentalist assumptions embedded in these practices. He powerfully illustrates the way assumptions about democracy and its possibilities limit both the implementation and reception of democracy promotion. Departing from the way democracy promotion operates in specific regional contexts, Hilary Charlesworth considers the larger international framework provided for these practices by international law, and specifically how democracy is understood within the structures of the United Nations. She examines the way democracy has become increasingly prominent in the UN, even though – or because of – a considerable degree of vagueness in the way democracy is defined and used. Building on this theme, Tony Smith argues that US democracy promo tion since the 1990s has lost its ‘fortunate vagueness’. It has instead become defined by a rigid and decontested set of conceptual foundations, which, he argues, facilitate the projection of American imperialism and corrupt the positive role the United States could play in supporting democracy in world politics. The volume finishes with a conclusion that reflects on the larger consequences of adopting a conceptual politics approach to the study of democracy promotion. We argue that engagement with a conceptual politics approach provides an inter esting new theoretical avenue for scholars (both critical and mainstream) studying democratisation and democracy promotion, as well as having potential to help in re-orienting policy practice at a time when democracy promotion is increasingly contested and questioned.
Note 1 The research leading to these results has received funding from the European Research Council under the European Community’s Seventh Framework Programme (FP7 ⁄ 2007–2013) ERC grant agreement no 202 596. All views remain those of the authors.
Part I
Orientations
1 On ‘cultivating’ democracy Enlivening the imagery for democracy promotion Laurence Whitehead
The conceptual politics of democracy promotion This chapter – and indeed this whole volume – is concerned with democracy promotion at the conceptual level. Other levels of analysis are also essential in order to gain a full understanding of the topic, and some of the other contribu tions included here incorporate more comparative historical, empirical, and policy-based considerations. This chapter tries to take such insights into account, but its focus lies elsewhere. It rests on an initial assumption that the conceptual level has been understudied or taken for granted, and that recent experience has underscored the costs that can arise from inadequate reflexivity. It was written during a period of rather dark days for democracy promotion, a policy objective that has been in retreat for some time now. While the most notable disappoint ments and reversals have been in Afghanistan, the post-Iraq Middle East, and perhaps Pakistan, there have also been setbacks in Africa (the Ivory Coast and Kenya, among others), and more generally. Such developments should not be disregarded in a project of this kind. But neither should they take centre stage, especially since they could prove fleeting. Indeed, just as this chapter was about to go to press, an unanticipated popular revolt in Tunisia abruptly reintroduced the question of democracy support onto the agenda of hitherto inattentive Western policymakers.1 Standing back from such contingencies, a ‘conceptual politics’ approach to the topic of democracy promotion invites deeper probing into the background assumptions and underlying commitments of its practition ers, meriting consideration regardless of whether the immediate context is atypi cally favourable and enthusiastic (as in the late 1990s) or perhaps overly negative (as may have been the case one decade later). Twenty years after the fall of the Berlin Wall there has been no shortage of hopeful initiatives pursued by activist agencies, and there now exists a very extensive literature on the practicalities of supporting, encouraging, stimulating and even imposing what the international community classifies as democratic political arrangements in the many post-Cold War countries where such systems are not as yet in place or are not fully secure. In this sense, ‘democracy promo tion’ is an established sub-field of policy-relevant investigation and comparative study. But neither the theoretical foundations nor the practitioner distortions of
20 L. Whitehead this branch of activity have received adequate attention in this literature, the focus of which has been mainly pragmatic, applied, and heavily process- oriented.2 Despite the proliferation of literature referring to ‘democracy promotion’, it is far from clear that the scholarly community has yet settled on a unified and coherent consensus about what the term must encompass or exclude, or on who owns it and how boundary disputes over its meaning are to be arbitrated. Still less is there agreement on how, or indeed even whether, it is supposed to work. Among the diverse elements that could fall within its ambit, there are interna tional conventions; national government programmes and agencies; non- governmental agencies such as party foundations and human rights monitors; electoral observation missions; solidarity networks; some journalism and blog ging activities; and perhaps even a wider range of ‘international civil society’ exchanges and initiatives.3 With such a wide range of activities under consideration, the question arises about how they might be coordinated (or might conflict) and which aspects should be viewed as central rather than incidental. There is also the question of where the resources come from to support effective ‘promotion’ activities, and what possibly hidden conditions might be associated with such financing. Since the promotion of democracy has been widely viewed – at least in the West since 1990 – as a public good, there is also the possibility that this political capital might be appropriated by actors pursuing less noble objectives. This is where the question of ownership and monitoring becomes important, indeed increasingly so in recent years as evidence has accumulated that economic sanc tions, invasions and covert interventions may also be undertaken in the name of this cause. As the evidence has accumulated that a multitude of sins could be sanc tified under this rubric, the need for more analytical precisions, including more conceptual clarification, has become more urgent. But the democracy promotion community is a network of competing and partially overlapping institutions pursu ing multiple agendas at the behest of a diverse set of sponsors, and it may not be easy for them to stand back and reflect dispassionately on what they are collect ively trying to achieve, or on what the outcomes actually amount to. This is readily understandable, and not to their discredit – the situations they confront often require urgent responses, and too much self-criticism could easily demoralise and re-direct the resources of backers. Even when best efforts are made to evaluate outcomes, process tracing remains a debatable art, while causal attribution and the identification of criteria for success are also difficult and often disputed. This may help to explain why public opinion in many long-established democracies has begun to get restive about what can be portrayed as a substantial mismatch between what was promised and what is being delivered. In this context, the case for a revision of the first principles involved seems quite compelling. This chapter pursues one approach out of several alternative possibilities. It investigates the imagery deployed to explain and justify the democracy promo tion enterprise. In particular, it reflects on the background assumptions underpin ning the two key terms: ‘democracy’ and its ‘promotion’. It does so from a
On ‘cultivating’ democracy 21 specific and perhaps idiosyncratic standpoint. Elsewhere I have suggested that the democratization sub-field has been too dependent on vivid imagery – meta phors and analogies – drawn from the physical sciences, with their assumptions of tightly specified causal linkages between sharply delineated interacting enti ties. I have argued for an ‘enlivening’ of this conceptual toolkit, through the introduction of an alternative set of analogies drawn from biology and the life sciences.4 This chapter recapitulates some of my arguments in this respect, and argues that democracy promotion is best conceptualised not as the engineering or imposition of an alternative set of political design principles, but rather as a cooperative process of ‘cultivating’ or even ‘nurturing’ locally pre-existing democratic potentialities. The bulk of the chapter is concerned to demonstrate how this shift in concep tualization might contribute to a revision of established assumptions about democracy promotion. Clearly, this is not the only avenue worth pursuing. The terminology and theoretical foundations of democracy promotion can also be re- examined from other standpoints, notably through comparative historical enquiry. Moreover, conceptual innovation should be grounded on the available evidence. Contributions from these other perspectives can help us select the most appropriate sources of analogical reasoning, and can steer us away from vivid but misleading metaphors and theorizations. The second section looks at an enlivening metaphor drawn from biology that could open the way to a more relevant and illuminating conceptualization than the prevalent terminology of ‘democracy promotion’. The title to this chapter suggests ‘cultivating’ democracy, an analogy derived from agriculture and gar dening. But this is not the only option. Equally valid would be ‘nurturing,’ a metaphor drawn from nutrition and healthcare. Other images – such as ‘trans planting’ – are also considered below. These three suggestions each amplify and reconceptualise the activity usually designated as ‘promotion’. Section three then turns to the practices to be promoted (what do biological analogies suggest about the re-conceptualization of ‘democracy’?), and argues for a more contextualised understanding of democratization processes. In light of these suggestions, section four reflects more broadly on the morphology of core political concepts and how it pertains to democracy and democratization. Section five elaborates on the resulting benefits derived from the incorporation of biological rather than mechanical sources of conceptual innovation, but also recognises the associated risks and limitations of such a procedure. The concluding section six offers a fuller statement of the implications of the ‘enlivening’ perspective for the re- conceptualization of democracy promotion and support as core public policy objectives.
‘Promotion’ or ‘nurturing’? What unites the large array of initiatives and activities conventionally encom passed by the terminology of ‘promotion’? In what relationship do these activities stand to currently ongoing processes of democratization observable
22 L. Whitehead around the globe? From a mechanical perspective, all democracy promotion activities are designed to increase the probability of durable democratic regime outcomes.5 From the same prevalent perspective, successful democracy promo tion activities are those that demonstrably deliver such outcomes. Would it get us any closer to reality if we substituted with the imagery of ‘cultivation’ or ‘nurturing’ the straightforward and easily intelligible causal attribution associ ated with ‘promotion’? Here it seems best to bring in some illustrations. Let us start with an extreme case, chosen not because it is representative, but because it indicates the non-consensual status of some major public policy claims about democracy promotion, and highlights the contrast between altern ative underlying conceptualizations of the subject. In its own terms, the Helms- Burton law enacted by the US Congress and signed into effect by President Clinton in 1996 constitutes a clear attempt at ‘democracy promotion,’ even though fifteen years later it has yet to deliver on its promised outcome. There is far more scope for doubt as to whether, even in its declaratory intentions, it can be classified as an effort to ‘cultivate’ or ‘nurture’ Cuban democracy. The idea is to impose such overwhelming sanctions – unilateral in origin, even if extra- territorial in effect – that insular resistance to its Washington-determined demands is either crushed or disintegrates. This is an example of ‘coercive’ democratization, the imposition of an externally crafted institutional design regardless of local choices or preferences. The engineering design is what vali dates the structure, not any internal response or rootedness. In fact, it is probable that this method of democracy promotion has maximised the chances of resist ance and rejection owing to its perceived arrogance and illegitimacy. Certainly Helms-Burton is an outlier among democracy promotion initiatives (although other examples of the ‘coercive’ approach can also be cited), but it belongs within that diverse family of initiatives, at least so long as mechanistic assumptions persist about what is to count as democratization, and how it may be caused. In a similar vein, one might conclude that over-mechanical and intru sive conceptions of democracy promotion in various parts of the Middle East have underestimated the centrality of local agency and consent, with the result that their assumptions about causation have proved unreliable and potentially more fruitful strategies have been pushed aside. However, the contrast between physical and biological images of how to support democracy is not reducible to a ‘coercion vs. persuasion’ dichotomy: it is more complex and cross-cutting than that (a ‘transplant’ is a drastic external imposition), and embraces multiple dimensions of policy variation. Between the two extremes of intense local resistance to democratic innovation and irresistible local enthusiasm for the same, there exists a wide gamut of intermediate situ ations. This is where internationally coordinated initiatives are most likely to alter the balance of probabilities and may potentially shift finely balanced polit ical trajectories – at least temporarily – in a pro-democracy direction. But such intermediate contexts are not uniform or mono-causal. They are not, therefore, promising sites for the application of ‘one-size-fits-all’ democracy promotion formulae. Mechanical and de-contextualised approaches of the kind often
On ‘cultivating’ democracy 23 favoured by prevalent conceptualizations are therefore unlikely to engage with the crucial participants at the strategic sites in the moments of critical choice. To switch to the gardening metaphor for a moment, the skilled cultivator is very attentive to the soil, the micro-climate, and the specific survival character istics of the species she wishes to propagate. Such ‘cultivation’ skills may be more valuable to the democracy promotion community than the horsepower available to an undiscriminating mechanical digger. In a similar vein, from the healthcare perspective, an effective intervention may require an accurate dia gnosis of a specific case, together with well-timed action based on a detailed understanding of the specific syndrome involved. Such attributes tend to be undervalued by mechanistic conceptions of democracy promotion and support. Proponents of ‘large N’ causal models are liable to object that these hypothet ical cases of skilled cultivation and contextually sensitive doctoring are unscient ific, because they are not easily validated by statistical corroboration. At the extreme, they may be dismissed as travellers’ tales, or unrepresentative anecdotes. This is not a debate that can be resolved in abstract – the rival evidential claims need to be compared, and in some areas it may well turn out that mechanistic models work as well as, or better than, some biological alternatives. The case being made here is not for the wholesale abandonment of all existing methods, but only for openness to a wider range of possible strategies, approaches, and concep tualizations. After all, skilled gardening or good medical practice are also evidence-based approaches informed by scientific general laws. And on the evid ence of the past twenty years one should not be too confident that any ‘large N’ findings in the area of democracy promotion and support can be relied upon to deliver consistent and reliable results in all contexts. Indeed, at the simplest aggregate level it would seem worthwhile to check whether most democracy pro motion activities since 1990 can be rated as leading (i.e. causally relevant precur sor) factors, or whether, on the contrary, they register mostly as lagging indicators (i.e. when the prospects for democracy advance for other reasons, that is when democracy promotion agencies respond by becoming more active). After all, democracy promoters will be rewarded for associating with success, whether or not they are responsible for it. And it is they – if anyone – who have the know ledge and resources to undertake the fullest evaluations of the outcomes they are aiming for. On this basis, it could be concluded that there is still scope for methodological pluralism and conceptual innovation when assessing what is con ventionally referred to as the ‘democracy promotion’ community of interests.
‘Enlivening’ and contextualizing democracy: a conceptual innovation If the ‘promotion’ half of this binomial can benefit from re-conceptualizations derived from biological sources of reasoning, so too can the ‘democracy’ half, as we shall now see. Political theory, political history, political science, compara tive politics, political sociology, and political economy have all studied the concept of democracy topic exhaustively and from every conceivable angle. So
24 L. Whitehead what level (or levels) of analysis are appropriate for testing or investigating the diverse claims generated by the concept of democracy? There is also a broader issue at stake. In the physical sciences, knowledge mostly progresses through accumulation and refinement, within conceptual frameworks that are so univer sally accepted that they rarely require re-examination. But in the human sciences, the objects under observation are also the observers, and the concepts used to frame analysis of their experiences may not match their self-understandings. Con sequently, the consensual, stable, and externally given framing devices that underpin most ‘hard’ scientific reasoning (henceforth referred to as ‘stipulatively defined’ concepts) may be exposed to periodic challenge (Shapiro 2005). This is especially likely with highly abstract or normative political concepts, which draw significance from socially constructed associations that are external to the formal definition (‘tacit’ knowledge in Polanyi’s (2009) sense).6 The concept of ‘political democracy’ currently meets all these conditions, and its practical instantiations (‘conceptions’) encounter intense feedback from a global array of rapidly changing historical realities. Democracy is a paradigmatic example of an ‘essentially contested’ concept and differentiates the comparative study of democratization from the model of scientific specialization that works so well in the physical sciences. It may be possible to generate a stipulative defi nition of such a democracy and thus derive a small number of empirically verifi able indicators by which to measure the ‘state of democracy’ in a succession of political entities. But if democracy is a deontological and an ‘essentially con tested’ concept, then it is both a really existing set of procedures and practices and a desired ideal. Analysts therefore must recognise that there will always be at least some aspects of democratic aspirations that are not yet fully realised. The discrepancy between actual and ideal conditions is what drives all processes of ‘democratization,’ and it also obliges empirical comparativists to incorporate ‘quality of democracy’ considerations into their exercises in calibration. To evaluate variations in the ‘quality’ of democracy requires both some uniformity of underlying criteria and also due recognition that differences in per formance may be partially determined by local context. Moreover, prevailing con ceptions of ‘democracy’ also vary considerably according to setting. Iceland has one experience of it, Switzerland another, and Zimbabwe a third. Beyond con temporary nation states, the city of São Paulo practises democracy in a somewhat different manner to that of Stockholm or Salt Lake City. What Fox News viewers understand by democracy is not quite what most BBC viewers have in mind. More historically, democracy has been ‘invented’ on multiple occasions and in a wide variety of contexts (Goody 2006: 247–56; Keane 2009). Over time and space, democracy has assumed many guises (from Athenian direct self-rule in city states to French Republicanism), and in each place, democratization is associated with different constitutive processes (apartheid in South Africa, Zionism in Israel, for example) that are heavily charged with local contextual associations. Different understandings derive in good measure from unanalysed preconcep tions7 and tacit assumptions about the nature of the polis, the demos, and polit ical order. Traditionally, British citizens are liable to ‘free associate’8 political
On ‘cultivating’ democracy 25 democracy in terms of Labour versus Conservative; first past the post constitu encies; party political broadcasts and doorstep leaflets; and parliamentary major ities. These ‘Westminster’ features are highly specific and are not core components of the abstract concept of democracy, but they have been shared and taken for granted so widely and for so long that they frame the British collective understanding of the general category. In the US, free association would invoke some similar features but also some contrasts such as federalism, the Supreme Court, the fixed electoral calendar, and the right to bear arms. British and Amer ican attitudes to democracy and democratization elsewhere will also be shaped by these contextual presuppositions. In Belgium or Canada, the demos would have to be pluri-lingual, whereas in Britain and France mono-lingualism is typic ally assumed. When democratic nations establish ‘democracy promotion’ programmes or institutions they each tend to institutionalise features that (perhaps without reflection) incorporate their own tacit national assumptions about the nature of democracy. Thus, Germany has highlighted doctrinal party linkages and divi sions, the National Endowment for Democracy has stressed electoralism, the Westminster Foundation has had a parliamentary focus, and Sweden has privi leged social solidarity – although over time cooperation and exchange between these national entities have produced a somewhat pooled approach. Features uncovered by ‘free association’ are held together by an integrative narrative that links a specific contextual variant of democracy with a particular collective identity and historically constructed account of how it emerged. The contextual background informs, colours or distorts successive conceptions of political democracy, challenges the concept of political democracy as timeless, stable, and universal, and opens the way for a more hermeneutic (in Gadamer’s sense) apprehension of democratization. Thus free association around the concept of democracy in Mexico, China or Iraq will not produce an easy conver gence around the US conception, and there is scope for misunderstanding and contestation because of contrasting historical memories and tacit associations. The point can be further illustrated by reference to the democracy vs. totalitarianism binary of the Cold War period, now replaced by the democracy vs. radical Islamism binary. These schema pit a timeless and abstract conception of democracy – best exemplified by Western political institutions and practices – against another, equally abstract, model, which is seen as incapable of evolution because of its self-reinforcing negative properties. Binary social classifications are often as much about identity-formation as objective description and can be misleading. Totalitarianism covered sins as diverse as Nazism, Stalinism, and Maoism; and the democratic world exemplified ‘virtues’ such as those of Franco’s Spain or the Shah’s Iran (but not Gomulka’s Poland or Allende’s Chile). By the 1980s, as the extreme polarity of the Cold War years began to fade, total itarianism was supplanted by the broader and looser ‘authoritarian regimes’ classifi cation and the binary schemas ceased to be de rigueur within the ‘transitions to democracy’ frame of interpretation. But there emerged what we can call a ‘step- change’ view of the Spanish transition to democracy (1975–81), which became the
26 L. Whitehead basis for a generalised account of the logic of democratization, and which preserved the essence of the binary analysis. However, the ‘step-change’ assumption has proved a poor guide to the realities confronting most democracy promotion opera tives in the post-Cold War period. One clue to its limitations can be derived from the attempt to translate it out of the English original. On mathematical principles it might be rendered as an ‘inflection point,’ or in material science as a ‘phase trans ition’, but both these images convey the idea of a categorical contrast between before and after, with little scope for evolutionary continuities. Biology might provide a more helpful source of guidance for most cases, but even here it would be necessary to choose between rival possibilities – was the Spanish transition a ‘change of skin’ rather than a completely binary metamor phosis? In general, it has proved more accurate to conceptualise contemporary democratizations as incremental, partial, and potentially reversible (i.e. evolu tionary) processes, rather than as radical discontinuities. Regime change is more complex, protracted, erratic, and diverse in its possible trajectories than this binary model suggests. Its widespread acceptance owed much not just to its par simony and moral convenience, but also to the fact it dovetailed with the ‘end of history’ discourse that flourished as the West won the Cold War. Twenty years after the dismantling of the Berlin Wall, that receptive interna tional environment has dissipated, and developments in countries like Iraq, Iran, Afghanistan, Thailand, Colombia, and even Italy are outpacing and destabilising existing frameworks. The convergence between Western hegemonic require ments and the ‘step-change’ model of democratisation has come to an end, as the ‘war on terror’ fills the void left by the disappearance of the Soviet menace. A ‘step-change’ that questions Western security in Egypt or Palestine or Afghani stan or Pakistan – or perhaps even Mexico – would show that not all good things necessarily go together when democratization gets underway. Democracy promotion only occurred sporadically and hesitantly during the Cold War, but it has since been undertaken on a much larger and less discrimi nate scale. Old scruples about ‘non-intervention’ and respect for the sovereignty of nation states were largely set aside by international agreements and under standings that have widened the discretionality available to self-described estab lished democracies, whenever they judge it appropriate to intervene in the political affairs of non-approved regimes. Since September 11, 2001, such inter ventions have often conflated broader security concerns with the international democracy promotion agenda and taken a harsher and more coercive form.9 So, control over what counts as a democracy and democracy promotion has become a major site of political contestation and dispute, once again highlighting the essential contestability of the terminology. In these circumstances, it seems appropriate to revisit some old debates about concept-stretching.
Morphology and metaphor A changing historical and contextual environment is not the only reason why collective understandings of such core political concepts as ‘democracy’ and
On ‘cultivating’ democracy 27 ‘democratization’ change; the internal characteristics of the enterprise of con ceptualization, rather than contingent external factors, is also crucial. Michael Freeden’s (1996: ch. 2) account of the ‘morphology’ of major political concepts in general and democracy and liberalism in particular, helps to explain why, at the very least, democratization – and in his account the concept of democracy as well – is so prone to elude the stipulative constraints of a fixed definition, how ever skilfully crafted.10 For Freeden, although there has to be some ‘inelimin able’ element at the heart of a concept (probably ‘rule of the people’ in the case of democracy), that may be too thin or underspecified to stabilise the idea. A key feature of Freeden’s morphological approach which is crucial for our purpose here is that he does not view each concept as a freestanding and self- sufficient entity. Instead, a succession of concepts combine and interact in any political discourse (or ideology), and overlap with each other. Thus, one particular version of democracy will be very closely associated with one version of lib eralism – each supporting and influencing the other. But other versions would be equally tenable, such as some form of republican, socialist, or capitalist demo cracy. In each case, the optional additional features of the concept of democracy would be ordered in a particular way to accommodate the appropriate adjacent concept. The acceptance of this view would raise some challenging issues for con temporary practitioners of democracy promotion, since it could imply the embrace of not just liberal, but also republican – and even socialist or religiously orthodox – ideological options, provided they were also genuine democratic choices. At this point it is appropriate to bring in a discussion of analogies and meta phors as the – often hidden – devices that serve to rationalise the selection of conceptual variants and to render plausible the narrative or discursive sequences in which our key political concepts are normally embedded. The underlying rationale for such expressions is to evoke an image imported from a different domain in order to elucidate an otherwise less accessible social process. Although all language (even the most arid – note the metaphor – social science) is impregnated with such metaphorical allusions, only a limited range of these are capable of structuring analytical social thought. These may be called ‘consti tutive metaphors’ (Klamer and Leonard 1994: 21). Since metaphors are con densed analogies, ‘the first step in making sense of a metaphor is to unpack the implicit analogy’ (Murphy 1994: 542). As regards democratization, it is not so much the sense of an individual metaphor that needs to be unpacked as the overall analogical structure within which a sequence of constitutive metaphors has been embedded. The ‘step-change’ binary model (analogical structure) of a democratic transition, for instance, invokes not just one or two but a whole con tinuous sequence of physical metaphors. Below, I consciously substitute a comparable sequence of biological meta phors. The rationale for this is two-fold. It makes explicit what is currently hidden – the metaphorical structure of the prevailing characterization of the concept. And it deliberately sets out to elucidate an otherwise difficult-to-grasp social process by the deployment of a more relevant, appropriate, and flexible analogical structure than the one currently in use.
28 L. Whitehead
The benefits – and limits – of biological analogies The toolkit of democratization studies is replete with physicalist imagery (waves, snowballs, electoral mechanisms, institutional design, constitutional engineering, among others). Even ‘transition’ (change of state, as from liquid to gas) and especially ‘consolidation’ invoke implicit analogies with physical processes. Biological processes offer an alternative source of relevant analogies. They refer to ‘the dialectic of specificity and plasticity during development, the dialectic through which the living organism constructs itself. The central property of all life is the capacity and necessity to build, maintain and preserve itself, a process known as autopoiesis’ (Rose 2005: 18). In that spirit, I suggested two metaphors drawn from the life sciences: contagion and viability. In contrast to Huntington’s snowballing, the contagion metaphor aimed to separate the various specific pro cesses through which the establishment of democracy in one country might alter the probability of a similar development in adjacent countries. Three of the possibilities I proposed (control, conditionality, and consent) involved interna tional and organised strategic action by identifiable political actors; contagion was included to allow for the possibility of the unorganised influence of a demo cratizing neighbour (the example I had in mind was the impact of the Portuguese revolutionary transition on Franco’s Spain). Contagion couples with ‘consent’ – an active process of self-organisation which can be viewed as broadly autopoi etic. Following the biological analogy, contagion involves a micro-level transmission that activates a chain of individual responses, which reverberates through the ‘body politic,’ destabilising the pre-existing homeostasis. This involves a ‘dialectic of specificity and plasticity’, not causal reductionism (Rose 2005: 18). The contrasting presuppositions of consolidation and viability also illustrate my argument. I introduced the concept of viability to democratization studies, arguing that consolidation assumes too much about the necessary components of an eventual stable post-democratization regime (Whitehead 2001: 3). Viability concerns more than mere persistence, as a democracy can lose viability even while its institutional forms persist. Like a plant in inhospitable soil, a democratic regime may be able to adapt and survive, but only by accountability to local realities [. . .] viability at least allows us to explore the extent to which such a variant of democrat isation may be able to reproduce and defend itself. (Rose 2005: 7) Consider how such a shift in sources of analogy might relate to two crucial topics that are currently prominent in comparative democratization studies and therefore also to concepts of democracy promotion and support: assessing the relative ‘quality’ of different democratization processes; and the question of ‘hybrid’ regimes (the only example I can think of in the mainstream literature that makes use of a biological metaphor) (Morlino 2009). A static physicalist
On ‘cultivating’ democracy 29 vocabulary is ill-equipped to tackle these issues. By contrast, a biological per spective directs attention to the adaptive processes and developmental potential that can generate diversity within a lifeline; and it offers guidance about the pos sible emergence of new organisms only partially related to established types. As regards ‘quality’, the obvious biological analogy would be with a ‘healthy’ organism. There are various potential sources of ill-health, and different afflic tions are countered in different ways. There is ageing and degeneration. This would correspond to the ‘cyclical’ or three generation model of democracy pop ular among the ancient Greeks. Here the source of decline or threat to good health arises from a weakening of the organism’s capacity to maintain and pre serve itself over time – perhaps, because vital defences are not preserved since they seem no longer needed; or perhaps because the organs are patched and renewed, the replacements are less efficient than the originals. It could be productive to explore these possible analogies as sources of vari ation in democratic quality over time. There is infection by hostile bacteria or parasites. This connects with arguments over democratic quality of the ‘enemy within’ type. Since even the healthiest organism is in constant interaction with potentially harmful assailants, disinfection and isolation are insufficient to contain such dangers. The healthy organism/democracy is the one best organised to absorb or domesticate threats rather than to survive behind an artificial cordon sanitaire. Ill-health can also arise from a breakdown of the required harmony between the major specialised organs. Dysfunctional interactions between exec utive and legislative or judiciary and security forces seem plausible counterparts in a democratic system. It is worth highlighting a parallel treatment of the state by Sven Steinmo (2008: 166), which also explicitly takes on board the benefits of adopting bio logical metaphors. Historical institutionalists, he notes are something like the environmental biologist who believes that in order to understand the specific fate of a particular organism or behaviour, she must explicitly examine that organism or behaviour in the ecology or context in which it lives. This implies a different scientific ontology than that com monly found in the hard sciences of physics and chemistry. At the root of evolutionary biology is the assumption that the objects of analysis – living organisms – are fundamentally different from inanimate matter. While objects in the physical world often adhere to constant ‘laws’ of nature, bio logical organisms often defy attempts to reduce them to their essential com ponents because of their complexity. Steinmo cites evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayer, who makes the point that ‘the development of biology as a science has required an investigation of “additional principles” that applied only to living organisms. He argues, “This required a restructuring of the conceptual world of science that was far more fundamental than anyone had imagined at the time” ’. Similarly, in historical institutionalism.
30 L. Whitehead to understand historically specific events and long term political outcomes, one could not strictly apply methods and epistemologies drawn from the study of invariant variables that have fixed relationships across space and time. This, of courses, does not mean that it is not science – unless one’s definition of science would exclude biology as well; rather, it implies that the scientific methods applied should fit the subject being studied. (Steinmo 2008: 167; see also Steinmo 2010) This being the case, why have social scientists come to resist the import of biologi cal metaphors? During much of the twentieth century, the kind of biology that inspired the last generation of political metaphors was often deeply conservative and indeed even anti-democratic in its implications (see Whitehead 2010). But while it is vital to guard against the hidden assumptions that can get smuggled into any model of a social explanation, there is no reason in principle why metaphors and analogies drawn from current biological thinking need to carry anti-democratic connotations. The sequence of biological metaphors outlined above – viability, contagion, health, and hybridity – can all be deployed to illuminate features of democratization that concern inter-subjective deliberation between free citizens. A democratic political system can be modelled in biological terms without under mining the democratic postulates of individual choice and commitment. Indeed, the master concept in biology and the life sciences is no longer based on a static equilibrium: it has been ‘punctuated’ by Stephen Jay Gould, sidelined by evolu tionary development (Carroll), challenged by homeodynamics (Rose) and negative entropy (James Lovelock) (Gribbin 2004: 196–7), and pushed aside by co- evolution and adaptation ‘to the edge of chaos’ (Kauffman 1993). Kauffman offers a source of biological analogies for modelling the spread, and also the reversal, of democratization processes both within and between political communities, and sharply contrasts this with the ‘system-maintenance’ functionalism that character ised mid-twentieth century conservative social theory. What these contributions to modern biology share is that they identify regu latory principles that generate change in order to explain the diversity, complex ity, interconnectedness and directional thrust of living organisms. They recognise that life is dynamic, developmental and in a permanent process of emergence. Thus, modern biology differs from the version practised during the fascist era: the organism could then be pictured as a hierarchical control system, whereas differentiation, complementarity, interdependence, and adaptability are the hall marks of autopoiesis. The authoritarian model of the healthy organism was always a distorted way to analyse political life. It is how component cells and organs develop, specialise, communicate, and cooperate that largely determines the viability of the whole organism (Rose 2005: ch. 8). This imagery bears some limited comparison with the modern understanding of democracy as a collective enterprise founded on the creativity, adaptability and capacity for cooperation and specialization of the individual citizens who constitute the indispensable basis of all democratic political organization. At any rate, this comparison is fresher and more flexible that the physicalist metaphors that currently
On ‘cultivating’ democracy 31 prevail in an ossified form. It may therefore serve to ‘enliven’ concept formation in a field where academic ‘flight from reality’ would be particularly harmful. Metaphors such as democratic ‘transition’ and ‘consolidation’ belong to a subset that has been called ‘constitutive,’ in the sense that they become ‘an irre placeable part of the linguistic machinery of a scientific theory; cases in which there are metaphors which scientists use in expressing theoretical claims for which no adequate literal paraphrase is known’ (Boyd 1979: 360). A systemati cally elaborated sequence of such metaphors can generate a constitutive analogi cal structure, and it is my claim here that the political science of democratization has indeed been constructed around such a sequence of physical analogies. Constitutive analogies and their related metaphors typically generate or inspire further ‘heuristic’ metaphors (metaphors that work by motivating enquiry into the principal subject by juxtaposing attributes or relationships of the subsidi ary subject). ‘Waves’ and ‘snowballs’ provide relevant illustrations in our field. Because ‘heuristic metaphors are not literally true, reasoning as if they were implies that (the associated) models are fictions’ (Klamer and Leonard 1994: 46).11 However, over time, the fictional nature of such a metaphorical inter pretation may become forgotten – both constitutive and heuristic metaphors can become ‘ossified’. And the accumulation of empirical evidence and the advance of detailed enquiry may expose the limitations of an initial metaphorical device. It may therefore cease to be irreplaceable. Whereas in Boyd’s account the advance of science could permit the replace ment of an initial metaphor by a literal paraphrase, at least in the case of con temporary democratization studies no such vocabulary has yet emerged. Indeed, it seems that the accumulation of evidence and cases is serving only to destabil ise existing theorizations and not to ground more precise and rigorous scientific categories and reliable laws. In view of that, my approach has been to seek to improve on the established analytical framework by consciously substituting a more flexible and appropriate analogical structure in place of our currently exhausted and ossified sequence of metaphors. But just like other social images drawn from biological thought (‘survival of the fittest,’ ‘the selfish gene’), there are also limits to the transferability of this conception. Although biological analogies are more illuminating than their phys ical precursors, they are still only analogies, and it is important to keep in mind their limitations as well as their insights. Since analogy is not homology, the transfer of reference from, say, biology to politics can only be partial and never uncritical. Metaphors derived from the physical world and from engineering tend to picture an idealised piece of machinery – something that can be assumed to be timeless and given. So, by assumption rather than demonstration, the outcome of a democratization is taken to be a permanent and fully operational democratic regime. The biological analogy brings that hidden assumption into the open for inspection. All living organisms are finite. They either perish, or evolve into something quite different. Thus, metaphors derived from this source – including the open-ended self-construction inherent in autopoiesis – invite us to consider the ‘life cycle’ or at least the temporality of democracy and democratization.
32 L. Whitehead Aristotle (1976: 64–5) asserted that ‘politics is not an exact science: our account of this subject matter will be adequate if it achieves such clarity as the subject matter allows; for the same degree of precision is not to be expected in all discussions’. Aristotle thus warns against the abandonment of serious enquiry into those topics that do not respond well to ultra-precision. He also cautioned against any assumption that, once established, a democracy would be self- perpetuating. ‘We shall know not to regard as a democratic [. . .] measure any measure that will make the whole as democratic [. . .] as it is possible to be, but only that measure which will make it last as a democracy [. . .] for as long as pos sible’ (Aristotle 1981: 373). This portrays democratization as a precarious under taking, and accords with a biological image of ‘viability’ rather than with a physicalist assumption of permanence and purity. One reaction to the diversity of ideas associated with a core concept could be to stand back from all contexts and seek to isolate the timeless truth or essential meaning that underlies them all. The hermeneutic alternative would be to explore the range of meanings that have been attached to a particular abstract term, enriching their connotations by teasing out the unspoken assumptions on which they rest in each specific discursive environment. The third possibility would be to take that contextualizing logic to its extreme. What the term means to each user in each context could be differentiated. From there it is a short step to deconstructing (or destabilizing) all political discourse, and thereby cancelling the subject of this presentation – and this conference – in its entirety. It is a legitimate intellectual activity to pursue any one of these paths and to explore with care and clarity where it might lead. But, from my pluralist per spective, it is not intellectually respectable to resolve on a priori grounds that only one of these routes can be allowed, while the results of the alternative explorations are shut down. Thus one should resist on principle the demand that all scientific work on democratization must be conducted only within the con fines of a single disciplinary-imposed stipulative definition of the concept. On the same principle, one should resist the counter-claim that all discourses about democratization are entirely ungrounded in personal subjectivity and therefore merely instruments of social control. Equally, it would be unacceptable to limit the field of enquiry to the kind of conceptual morphology pursued here. All three approaches deserve exploration and can be productively tested against each other. That is what methodological pluralism recommends, whenever a singular method leaves core issues unresolved and seeks to conceal its failings by disqualifying productive alternative approaches on a priori grounds. Above all, we need to keep open the avenues of dialogue and communication between these fragmenting epistemic communities.
‘Cultivating’ and ‘nurturing’ democracy This conceptual discussion also has implications for the practice of democracy promotion. Thomas Carothers (2007a) has already introduced the notion of ‘decontamination’ to the discussion of democracy promotion. His shift in
On ‘cultivating’ democracy 33 terminology from ‘promotion’ to ‘support’ for democracy also captures the thought behind the idea of ‘cultivation’. After Iraq it has become much harder to convince observers that coercive measures adopted in the name of spreading democracy can be relied on to deliver their purported benefits. Indeed, the true motives, as well as the actual effectiveness, of such forceful interventions have been brought into doubt. After all, those willing to expend such efforts in the transmission of democracy to Euphrates – and to Afghanistan – had not taken so much trouble to perfect electoral procedures in Florida in the presidential elec tion of 2000; nor in informing citizens accurately about the evidence concerning ‘weapons of mass destruction’ allegedly deployed by the Baghdad regime. Given such antecedents, the only way strong claims about commitment to the course of democracy promotion might be restored to international credibility was if both the motives and the evaluation of results associated with subsequent initiatives of this kind were thoroughly insulated from such extraneous distortions. In a word, democracy promotion after Iraq would need to be ‘decontaminated’. In what follows we shall make the simplifying – albeit heroic – assumption that democracy promotion can henceforth be assessed on its own terms, rather than judged for its association with other causes. On that assumption, any genuine programme of support for democracy elsewhere would have to be founded on an initial commitment to protect and sustain democratic potentialities at home. This could be asserted as a purely ethical argument, but it is also a matter of credibility and intellectual coherence. A plausible biological analogy would be that the introduction of healthy crop into a virgin field presupposes the accompanying observance of good agricultural practice on established farmlands. Among other biological analogies that come to mind in this context one might discuss ‘transplant’; ‘domestication’ (Australia, New Zealand, Commonwealth Caribbean); ‘symbiosis’ (democratization and national liberation in South Africa); and ‘mimicry’ (the establishment of so-called ‘façade’ democracies aimed at flattering external powerbrokers without necessarily dismantling tradi tional local structures of social control). Other, less positive, sources of biologi cal analogy might include dismemberment (Kosovo, Timor); predation (Sierra Leone); and even scavenging (Somalia). This miscellany of examples may suffice to demonstrate that there is a topic here worth exploring further. One uncomfortable implication that requires brief acknowledgement here is that a full repertoire of biological analogies would extend far beyond such gentle and beneficent activities as plant breeding and healing. Fiercely destructive possibilities also exist, and the defence of democracy can encompass possibil ities of confrontation as much as of cultivation. Hybridity and adaptive viability complicate the picture further, since they raise difficult questions about which characteristics are to be classified as democratic potentialities and which must be understood as threats to democracy. Farmers and physicians also confront such dilemmas, but they are at least trained, unlike engineers, to make finely discrimi nating, contextual judgements about such matters. In any case, this section focuses on a particular subset of biological analogies concerning democracy
34 L. Whitehead promotion as a specialised activity, rather than on the survival of democracy as an overarching concern. If the dominant mode of theorising about democratization is inappropriately mechanistic, this is likely to be magnified when such theory is drawn on to deliver ‘democracy promotion’ solutions. The ‘step-change’ model and ideas about ‘constitutional engineering’ convey the image that the established Western democracies are in possession of a reliable and universally applicable toolkit of techniques for bringing about unquestionably appropriate political outcomes wherever their inherently beneficent influence can be extended. The alternative imagery sketched in this chapter subverts that conceit. The notions of adaptive viability, hybridity, contagious transmission and reactions to it, and democrat isation as an autopoietic (self-organised) undertaking all question such under lying assumptions. Biological analogies for democracy promotion such as the ‘cultivation’ or ‘nurturing’ of potentially democratic tendencies abroad highlight the merit of approaches that support and reinforce locally rooted democratizing impulses, and that allow them sufficient autonomy to flourish in their own ways. This per spective contrasts with physicalist ‘institutional design’ and blueprint imagery which tends to impose an externally validated model without regard for its endo geneity or adaptability to contextual conditions. So let us consider more closely a biologically informed alternative perspect ive on democracy promotion. The starting point would be that, like any complex living organism, a democracy is a purposive enterprise. It therefore requires a capacity for coordination from within to determine its collective objectives (sur vival, reproduction, and adaptation to its environment), and to execute the con sequent responses. The organism/political entity in question is not secure so long as its purposes are set from outside, or if its capacity to coordinate responses is over-ridden by external direction. A democracy promotion programme that seeks to substitute the promoters’ purposes for those of the collectivity is a colonising rather than a liberating enterprise, since the individuals who make up the collect ive do not own it. In the absence of sovereignty, such a democracy is a sham. (As a rough biological analogy, in the absence of a queen bee a swarm is a direc tionless mass). Any complex living organism – and any democracy – requires not only an internal capacity for coordination of its components for basic shared purposes, but also a time horizon. It needs a capacity for autonomous action that persists long enough to make its purposes attainable. Democracy promotion therefore requires a significant degree of self-denial by the promoters. Like parents with the power to intrude on their dependent offspring, they must grant leeway for their charges to make their own mistakes and assume responsibility for their own decisions. Only thus can an emerging democracy acquire autopoiesis. Effective democracy promotion requires acceptance that the new entity cannot be a mere replica of an existing democratic regime. Like all living organ isms it will combine many familiar features with some distinctive characteristics, responding to its distinctive history and environment, and consequential set of
On ‘cultivating’ democracy 35 purposes. Sean Carroll’s (2006) observation that nature works by cobbling together and rearranging already existing materials is relevant here. Carroll high lights four separate features of the evolution of new forms in nature: tinkering, multi-functionality, redundancy, and modularity. All of these contrast with the optimization ideals of the mechanic and the economist and can alert democracy promoters to the dangers of a ‘tabula rasa’ engineering blueprint approach. All of them can also contribute to the viability not only of living organisms but argu ably of democratic regimes as well. Take modularity, as when democratic assemblies are replicated across a large territory (e.g. in federal systems), so that the destruction of one would be insuffi cient to eliminate all; or take multi-functionality, as when elected representatives not only choose governments and write laws, but also conduct constituency sur geries and serve as conduits between their party’s rank and file and its leader ship. The balancing of such competing functions is not something that can be prescribed in detail in advance, and it can easily be destabilised by ill-advised ‘efficiency’ reforms, but without it a democracy can be hollowed out or never fully established. Redundancy is also critical for evolutionary success, since it provides backup resources to provide flexibility and to cope with shocks and disasters. Two hands, ten digits, two legislative chambers may seem wasteful and inefficient to an optimising designer, but may nevertheless improve the long-term survival prospects of organisms/organizations prone to occasional dismemberment. Few of the stipulative definitions of democracy relied upon by professional political scientists give much weight to such superficially sub-optimal features of political representation and, accordingly they can easily fall below the radar of the demo cracy promoters. From a biological perspective, the essence of democratic via bility is successful innovation and adaptation, whereas from the engineering perspective, the leanest, toughest, most freestanding and rigid structures are those which are expected to endure. There is a substantial history of what may be termed the wholesale ‘trans plant’ of democratic institutions from one jurisdiction to another – most famously to Japan after Hiroshima. The biological analogy does allow for the possibility of ‘root and branch’ transfer of an integrated system into a hitherto unfamiliar setting. With skill and experience it is possible to ‘graft’ a plant with desirable characteristics onto the trunk of a less favoured specimen. Modern genetic and cellular biology is rapidly extending the range of manipulations available. Modern democracy promotion may also be proceeding along an upward learning curve. But some major caveats are also in order. A successful transplant or graft requires a receptive host organism. Even a beneficial organ transplant can fail if the recipient misidentifies and rejects the implant as an intruder. Many complex organisms operate on the basis of elaborate systems of symbiosis with a large variety of related living creatures, from digestive bacteria to pollinating insects. So it is insufficient to transplant a single structure; the newcomer must also be capable of co-existing and co-evolving in its new envir onment. This helps explain why most successful breeding programmes still
36 L. Whitehead involve small incremental modifications selected over successive generations, rather than one-shot overhauls. There is also the biological phenomenon of mimicry. If an organism (or a political regime) is threatened by powerful pred ators which have identified some visible characteristic as grounds for attack, a common defensive strategy is to copy the external features most likely to deflect this unwelcome attention. Hence a butterfly may display false eyes on its wings, or a pharaonic ruler may stage a simulacrum of an election in order to secure Western acquiescence in the perpetuation of his dynasty. This illustrates the potential insights that can be derived from a biological perspective on democracy promotion, but some of the imagery sketched above also has the potential to be refined into fairly precise and even empirically test able propositions. Those who require democracy promotion policies to be ‘evidence-based’ do not need to limit their conceptualizations to mechanical accounts of causation, which are in any case prone to mis-describe the dynamics of their interventions. We can objectively assess plant breeding and grafting techniques over time; similarly, like their engineering rivals, biologically inspired models of democracy assistance can be measured and validated. In both cases, a considerable lapse of time may be required before the results are visible. And, as the ‘tinkering’ analogy suggests, the relevant practice may con sists of multiple, partial, tentative, and reversible interventions, rather than a one-off checklist of best practices (such as the Copenhagen criteria applied by the EU). Rather than assuming the neutrality of the scientist, the biological models help us to recognise that the democracy promoters are themselves potentially flawed moral agents with their own distorting interests and questionably demo cratic identities. For this reason – and in light of the adverse consequences of some recent interventions – democracy promoters should be held to the ‘do no harm’ principle that governs medical science.
Notes 1 On 15 January 2011 the Elysée Palace in Paris proclaimed its ‘determined support’ for the democratic will of the Tunisian people. It remains to be seen how this will be received by those who experienced twenty-three years of seedy French support for President Ben Ali’s kleptocratic police state, including the provision of training and equipment to the forces of repression, support renewed as recently as one week before his ignominious flight to Saudi Arabia. The EU’s moribund ‘Barcelona Process’ may also require some agile retouching. 2 The big exception is, of course, Thomas Carothers (1999). But that is over a decade old and has not spawned many imitators. More recently, however, Philippe C. Sch mitter has published an insightful chapter about what he terms the ‘theory vacuum’, which includes a set of ‘sceptical propositions’ that help to explain ‘why democracy promotion is such a difficult and paradoxical activity’, and which attempts to test a model suggesting that suitably specified democracy promotion activities could have some positive effects regardless of cultural context or stage of regime change. But he also speculates that democracy promotion may be better at protecting democracy than at promoting it (Schmitter 2008: 32). 3 One useful source of guidance, albeit partial, is Youngs (2006).
On ‘cultivating’ democracy 37 4 See Whitehead (2011). This is an extension of earlier work (Whitehead 2001b) where I argued for ‘viability’ as preferable to the now standard terminology ‘democratic consolidation’. 5 See section two on what that might refer to, either on engineering principles, or from the standpoint of a biological analogy. 6 Polyani (2009) says ‘we can know more than we can tell’ because tacit knowledge – prejudgments and implied values, tradition and inherited practices – is crucial in human knowledge. 7 What Gadamer (1989) calls ‘prejudices’. 8 Paul Jorion (2009: 102) reminded me of the utility of the technique of free association as a device for uncovering the unstated presuppositions that stand behind all formal analysis. 9 See the chapters by Bermeo, Carothers and Whitehead in Burnell and Youngs (2010). 10 I have therefore characterised democratization as a ‘floating but anchored’ idea; Leon ardo Morlino (2005) has also independently elaborated his notion of ‘democratic anchoring’. 11 They discuss economic models, but the same principle applies to models of democrat ization.
2 Conceptualizing democratization and democratizing conceptualization A virtuous circle Piki Ish-Shalom Introduction In the yet uninstitutionalized Olympics of political concepts, democracy along with other political concepts such as power, freedom, equality, sovereignty, and state, would surely be a gold medal favorite in the contested-ness match. The meanings attached to democracy are many and varied, ranging from the proced ural, through the participatory, all the way to the direct. This paper addresses the contested-ness of the concept of ‘democracy’, and prescribes a constitution for the community of students of democracy and democratization (and other contested political concepts); constitution both internal and external. To say that a concept is essentially contested implies it has several meanings, each of them acceptable and legitimate, and each of them having a complete moral and ideological groundwork. There is something a priori in the moral and ideological groundwork each of us holds, and this a priori dimension also affects the meanings we attach to our concepts. This dimension is what makes political concepts essentially contested, and what makes politics ‘conceptual politics’. As a social science philosophy, positivism is not well equipped to study conceptual politics as it has an inbuilt rationale for finding a single true and objective meaning that doesn’t hinge upon subjective traits and/or intersubjective moral commitments. This rationale is evident from the attitude of positivism towards definitions; from its attempt to fixate definitions. In other words, positivism, cannot fathom the phenomenon of essentially contested concepts. On the other hand, mainstream constructivism lacks sensitivity to politics and hence cannot but fail in identifying and analysing the political processes operative in conceptual politics. To study conceptual politics most efficiently I propose the theoretical framework of political constructivism, a Gramscian-inspired analysis of the sociopolitical world’s socio-political construction. Through its sensitivity to politics and to political mechanisms and processes, political constructivism is best equipped to study the essential contested-ness involved in conceptual politics. In what follows, I will examine the phenomenon of essentially contested concepts, in particular with regard to the concepts of democracy and democrat ization, and analyse the mechanisms for attaching essentially contested concepts with meaning. There are two such (ideal-type) mechanisms: first, politically
Conceptualizing democratization 39 fixating a meaning on the public and framing the public commonsense (the Gramscian mechanism); second, conducting a dynamic and critical public examination of those available meanings in the public sphere (the Habermasian mech anism). The Gramscian mechanism is too common a feature of the daily practice of politics. But this observation should not lead us to despair. On the contrary, it should encourage theorists to cultivate a dual analytical gaze involving both a Gramscian sensitivity to how conceptual politics is routinely practiced and a Habermasian-inspired responsibility for changing the way present-day conceptual politics is practiced. This, I argue, is a social responsibility all theorists bear, and it is also an epistemological upshot of understanding and fathoming the phenomenon of the essential contested-ness of political concepts. Having established political constructivism as the appropriate theoretical framework for conceptual politics, I will propose several measures to improve our capacity to study and morally engage with conceptual politics. These meas ures are: self-reflexivity, locating research in communal setting, encouraging pluralism, a commitment to transparency, and civic engagement outside academia. These are of significance in considering academic engagements with democracy promotion. I will conclude by discussing the virtuous circle in which my argument is trapped through being based on a participatory and deliberative conceptualization of democracy, which it tries to help to actualize.
Political constructivism Political constructivism is that variant of constructivism which takes politics ser iously – politics, that is, as the mundane human and social realm in which lofty ideals are truthfully and honestly pursued alongside earthly interests which require (at times) dirty little means; politics as the social sphere in which agents and structures intermingle, producing some consequences that are intended, and some that are not. Politics, that is, as the subject matter of our study really is (Ish-Shalom 2010, forthcoming a). Constructivism theorizes about the way our known social world came to be as it is, and the constructivist contention is that it became this way through social knowledge and social construction (Adler 1997; Guzzini 2000; Weldes 1996). Social knowledge is the people’s intersubjective understanding of their physical and human environment. This intersubjective understanding forms the building blocks in the construction of social reality. This is because people act according to their understanding of their world and their expectations based on those understandings. Political constructivism concurs with those contentions, yet emphasizes the political dimensions of social construction. It is not that politics is the only dimension involved in social construction, but it plays an important and (among constructivists) insufficiently appreciated role. Political constructivism tries to amend this theoretical lack, for example by focusing on political concepts and their contested-ness. Following Antonio Gramsci’s theory of hegemony, the thrust of the political constructivist argument is that framing the public commonsense is the most
40 P. Ish-Shalom efficient political tool of mobilization (Gramsci, 2007, 1996, 1992). On Gramsci’s introduction to the study of International Relations, see Bieler and Morton 2001; Cox and Sinclair 1996; Davidson 2008; Gale 1998; Gill 1990, 1993; Joseph 2008; Puchala 2005. Framing the public commonsense shapes how people intersubjectively understand their world, the expectations they develop about the world and the processes in which they are involved and participate. In other words, public commonsense is an essential apparatus for constructing social knowledge and social reality. And because public commonsense is at times framed politically, so the construction of social knowledge is partially political, and social reality should be better understood as a constructed socio- political reality. Furthermore, framing the public’s commonsense shapes the repertoire of public actions that people hold to be possible, legitimate, and effective. Accordingly, rather than use brute force, a sophisticated, resourceful politician will use the third face of power, and if successful will set the political agenda and thence public behaviour (Lukes 2004). Gramsci, the Marxist, theorized hegemony as a totalistic state of affairs in which the commonsense of the (almost) entire public is framed, and stupefies the people into conceding to capitalist interests. The public en masse, including the proletariat, unwittingly betrays its own objective interests for the interests of a small, sectarian segment of society, the capitalists. My understanding of hegemony is less ideological, hence less dogmatic and totalistic. Hegemony is partial and transient. It is partial regarding its grip on the public. Usually, it has an effective grip on certain groups, not the public en masse, and its content is restricted, not totalistic. It is transient in the sense that it comes and goes, influenced, for example by successful political campaigning. This understanding is more suitable to a pluralistic society segmented along different cleavages lines and interests. Hence, I prefer using a different term to Gramsci’s ‘hegemony’, namely ‘public convention’, to denote that partial and transitory framed commonsense (Ish-Shalom forthcoming a, Ish-Shalom 2010). Still, political constructivism shares with Gramsci’s theory of hegemony the appreciation of the political effectiveness and powerfulness of framing the commonsense, even when its effect is only partial and transitory.
Essentially contested concepts A concept is ‘a mental representation of an element or phenomenon of the phys ical, social, or psychological world’ (Davis 2005: 12). As mental representations, concepts are inherently vague, ambiguous, and fuzzy (Davis 2005: 5–6). Polit ical concepts are not only inherently fuzzy, they are also characteristically and essentially contested (Gallie 1956). Three conditions must be met for a concept to be contested. First, the concept must have several possible meanings. Second, there must be disagreements over the appropriate meaning of the concept. Third, these disagreements are important enough to some parties to become politicized. Such politicized concepts play a fundamental role in the socio-political construction of reality (Ish-Shalom 2010).
Conceptualizing democratization 41 Political concepts play an important role in politically framing the public commonsense. As a mental representation of the world, a concept’s meaning is one of the ways people understand the world. To attach meaning to concepts is to conceptualize the world: form an understanding of the world, appropriate aims in it, and the most efficient means to secure them. Therefore, politics involves constant effort in conceptualizing political concepts and attach meaning to them. By fixating a meaning on a contested political concept politicians can frame the public commonsense in order to mobilize the public into action unhindered by critical reflection. In other words, committing the public to an unreflected conceptualization, making the public adhere to a certain set of public conventions, can act as navigational roadmaps. Thus, decontesting political concepts is an exemplar political act. But as polit ical concepts are contested by their essence, politics turns out to be (among other things) an effort to decontest that which cannot be decontested. To be able to fixate a political concept with meaning, politicians try to present it as neutralized, beyond ideological debate: having only one natural meaning. Ian Lustick similarly characterized Gramsci’s hegemony as ‘politics naturalized to be experi enced as culture’ (1999: 339). This is the Gramscian route via which public conventions are created, and it is this process of socio-political construction of the socio-political world that political constructivism theorizes. It is here that the contested-ness of political concepts plays such a fundamental and foundational political role, being both a political arena to win over and a tool for achieving it. Think of democracy, for example. However intricate and contested a political concept it is, in the public arena it becomes quite a cliché, evaluated and meas ured with a set of fixed criteria. Those fixed criteria are propagated by, for example, think tanks such as Freedom House and Transparency International, which then use them as benchmarks for comparing countries and defining them as democracies or non-democracies (Löwenheim 2008; Steele 2010: 63). Furthermore, the fixated meaning of democracy was used as a political yardstick to determine who is with ‘us’ and who is against ‘us’ in the Bush administration’s declared global war on terrorism. This is an example of how a public convention of democracy and its merits was converted into a political conviction and thence the strategic necessity to promote democracy, at gunpoint if needs be. The Bush administration demonstrated that fixating meanings on political concepts bears with it a number of grave political implications. The adventurism of the Bush administration in Iraq and Afghanistan exemplifies a second conceptual phenomenon. Fixating the concept of democracy with meaning spills over into its derivative concept of democratization; the conceptualization of democratization and the policies of democracy promotion dovetail with fixating the meaning of democracy. If democracy is understood as a structure, democracy promotion will be understood as building the structural attributes of democracy, a relatively easy and swift political act. Alternatively, if democracy is understood as a moral and cultural political phenomenon, democracy promotion will be understood as spreading democratic norms and values—an intricate, slow, and daunting process. It was the fixated structural
42 P. Ish-Shalom understandings of both democracy and democratization that prevented the Bush administration from seeing the difficulties of trying to democratize Iraq and Afghanistan, and significantly contributed to its bogged down adventurism. This Gramscian reading of politics and constructivism may elicit feelings of pessimism regarding human and social existence. It may provoke the argument that humans are merely captives of their own irrationality and that human soci ety will forever be locked in power struggles where the public is just a tool exploited by manipulative politics and sectarian interests. Personally, I do not subscribe to this pessimism, and political constructivism should by no means promote it. Hence the Gramscian reading should be supplemented with a Habermasian perspective. Political constructivists should be encouraged to adopt an analytical dual gaze. This is a duality of gaze that is difficult yet crucial to attain. Political constructivists should cultivate both a Gramscian sensitivity to how politics is practiced and a Habermasian-inspired responsibility for changing how present-day politics is practiced. This is a social responsibility that all theorists bear, and it is also an epistemological upshot of understanding the contested- ness of political concepts, of conceptual politics. Introducing Habermas’ theory of communicative action can help to check Gramscian pessimism and enable us to cultivate the aforementioned duality of gaze (Habermas 1987, 1989, 1984). For his introduction to the study of Inter national Relations, see Anievas 2005; Checkel 2001; Diez and Steans 2005; Müller 2004; Mitzen 2005; Risse 2000; Weber 2005. Habermas’ theory introduces a different strategy for decontesting political concepts, one that is committed to human reasonableness, at least to the potentiality of realizing it. As discussed above, meaningful political concepts are the building blocks of social knowledge. According to the Habermasian ideal, meaningful political concepts do not hinder rational argumentation, rather they help produce rational arguments and the ensuing public elucidation of aims and means, values and facts. According to the Habermasian ideal, the process of attaching meaning to political concepts is both reflective and critical and, in this process, the meaning of political concepts is able to withstand the trial of reason and be elucidated in the ideal speech situation through ideal speech acts. Accordingly, the meanings of political concepts are not fixated into public conventions. They continuously undergo critical public scrutiny and clarification. The communicative rationality, reason, criticism, and reflectivity that Habermas summons both enable the ideal speech situation and are enabled by it, and con sequently empower the participants of public deliberation to scrutinize and elucidate the political concepts’ meanings without accepting them at face value. The public deliberation participants engage in is a sincere and public dialogue that allows them to achieve a mutual understanding of each interlocutor’s understanding of the meaning and conceptualization of the political concepts under debate. Sectarian interests and power considerations are put aside, and hence, so the Habermasian argument goes, social knowledge is intersubjectively and truthfully constructed, paving the way to a reasonable public understanding of the public good and efficient and moral political action.
Conceptualizing democratization 43 But how can the gap between the Gramscian and Habermasian understandings of conceptual politics be reconciled? How can the pessimism and optimism be bridged? Is there a strategy for salvaging human society and politics from fixating meanings on political concepts, from public conventions accepted without reflection? Is there a group that can help to implement this strategy? Is there, in Hegelian (1942: 197–8) and Marxian terminology (1975: 243–57; see also Avineri 1972: 155–61, 1968: 41–64), a universal class with the potentiality of transcending human society’s Gramscian fixation of one meaning and to achieve the Habermasian dynamic elucidation of many meanings? The answers to these questions, I would argue, lie in academia and the nature of the academic discussion (or at least the ideality of academic discussion) regarding political concepts, their contested-ness, and their different meanings. Especially relevant are the meanings of the political concepts explored in this volume: democracy and democratization. Academia has the theoretical resources to understand the essential contested-ness of political concepts, and hence may potentially be equipped to defend against the political manipulation of fixating meanings. If it succeeds, academia can serve as the universal class. However, to achieve this it has to realize its potential, and for that several measures are needed. Two caveats are in order. The first is that academia is not immune to the ramifications of decontesting what is essentially contested. As standpoint epistemologists rightly point out, academics have blind spots (see below). They can be (and sometimes are) captives of a hegemonized commonsense. Feminists excel in exposing the masculine blind spots so operative in academia (Carroll and Zerilli 1993). The same can be said of nationalistic and chauvinistic trends. The point is not that academia does not suffer from those maladies, but rather that it is better equipped in engaging with those maladies and blind spots, and aca demics should indeed be committed to engage with them. As discussed later, it is the positivist philosophy of social science that is least equipped for this task. The second important caveat is that accepting the contested-ness of concepts does not imply moral or analytic relativism. By embracing an anything-goes attitude, relativism dodges any sort of engagement, political or moral, with the essence of contested-ness. Relativism is the sidestepping of moral judgment necessitated by the fact of contested-ness. What I will call for later is pluralism. Pluralism recognizes the existence of a variety of legitimate meanings, and accepts them within the limits established by the criteria of reasonableness. Additionally, pluralism is retained only when one does not discard the commitment to one’s own moral grounding. Pluralism, that is, does not relinquish the ethical responsibility of having to morally evaluate different meanings. Pluralism, contrary to relativism, accepts contested-ness, respects it, and values the reasonable meanings people hold fairly. Relativism sidesteps meaningful dialogue. Pluralism practices it.
Definitions The academic equivalent of meanings and conceptions is definitions. In academia, meanings are attached through definition – a necessary and
44 P. Ish-Shalom fundamental phase in conducting research. Definitions are taken seriously in academia and it is demanded that they be as exhaustive, exclusive, and opera tionalizable as possible. Standing up to these demands, a definition would supposedly be accurate in the sense of covering all the cases and concepts which are relevant to the research, and not including the cases and concepts which are not research-relevant. Definitions are also supposed to provide the foundation for the research, which is why definitions require opera tionalization. Operationalization gives us the ability to collect, measure, and compare data, and even to repeat a study by other researchers. Definitions allow us to work and communicate our work with our colleagues. It is when we accurately define the categories we work with that our studies and our theories become meaningful. That is to say, although definitions are more precise than meanings, and though they operate in different arenas, their function is similar. In other words, meanings and definitions convene.1 The convening of meanings and definitions indicates that the same set of questions that were raised regarding the attachment of meanings to concepts is also relevant for academic definitions of cases, categories, and concepts. Inasmuch as political concepts are contested, they will have several legitimate aca demic definitions, just as they have several legitimate public meanings. This contested-ness is the source of the different definitions of democracy and demo cratization employed in the academic literature. Democracy can legitimately and reasonably be defined structurally or normatively, as liberal or electoral, as an elitist project or a participatory project, and so on. And as is the case in the public and political arena, so it is in academia: as we will define democracy so we will define democratization. If democracy is defined as the structure of elections, the division of powers, and of checks and balances, so democratization is conceptualized as building this structure; that is, emphasizing the formal, the procedural, and the structural. Policy-oriented scholars will take this conceptualization as an invitation to focus on the state apparatus, on ‘old’ or institutional politics. If, on the other hand, democracy is defined as a culture and morality of the sort that creates a civic community, democratization will be conceptualized as constructing this community; that is, as involving the socialization and dissemination of democratic values in order to encourage a democratic society and culture, mainly by empowering domestic agents of political and social transformation in the target country. And policy-oriented scholars will take this conceptualization as an invitation to invest effort at the social and individual levels, in an attempt to construct a civil society of informed, involved, and participating citizens. These are indeed familiar and legitimate disagreements. What is interesting is not so much the existence of the disagreements, but rather the way academia approaches them. The disagreements are far too starkly present to be overlooked or ignored. Instead, there are two additional, and overlapping, questions which are important and worth exploring: where do the dis agreements arise? And, what are their foundations? Regarding the first question, there are two possible answers. Definitional disagreements can either emerge at the operationalization layer of the definition, or can be located in the more
Conceptualizing democratization 45 substantive layer. The substantive layer is the one which comprises the exhaustiveness and exclusiveness requirements of definitions. That is the layer which ensures the definition is accurate and helps us identify cases that fall under the studied concept and those that fall outside it. The question of the foundations of the definitional disagreements, though overlapping with the question of the location, runs deeper and also has two alternative answers. The first is that the dis agreements, which are located at the operationalization layer, arise from inaccuracy and faulty scientific procedures. That is, they are caused by technical errors and can thus be easily corrected. The second answer is that the different definitions arise in the same way that different public meanings arise – from different and unreconciled normative and ideological foundations. Put differently, a plethora of definitions employed in the academic world is legitimate, and, more over, is a necessary condition which is due to the essentially contested nature of the political concepts studied and used in academia. Definitional disagreements are here to stay. Contested-ness is a legitimate and necessary state of affairs in academia, just as it is outside it. After stating the different answers available to the two overlapping questions and their underlying rationales, it becomes clear that the four answers group into two parties. Furthermore, it is quite easy to identify which parties they are. The first party consists of adherents to the positivist philosophy of social science. The second party comprises adherents to post-positivism, especially interpretivists and critical theorists (preferably merged under political constructivism). Inter pretivists and critical theorists are concerned with issues of morality and ideo logy and are aware of their constitutive role in conducting research. If the present analysis is correct, the positivists fail to understand correctly the contested-ness in which social reality and social research are embedded. Accordingly, they confine themselves to fixating definitions, along with the errors that were indicated above regarding this strategy of attaching meanings to concepts. They deny the essential contested-ness of the concepts they study and employ, and thus accept their own selected definitions in a way very similar to fixated public conventions. Positivists can fuss around technical matters of definitions, but do not argue about them morally (for a similar argument see the introduction to the volume). The interpretivists and critical theorists, on the other hand, understand the contested essence of political concepts – that the definitional disagreements are irresolvable – and its inherent ideological and normative groundwork. Linking this to the focus of this book, democracy and democratization, crit ical theory understands what positivism cannot but fail to understand. The different academic definitions of democracy and democratization are firmly grounded in different normative and ideological groundwork. The minimalist and structural academic definition of democracy is embedded in a conservative scepticism about human faculties, which argues that a mix of perennial desires, instincts, and communal traditions underlies human action; an extrarational mix, which pushes human beings to seek power. The skeptical conservative view warns of two major consequences. First, because everyone is interested in power there is always a danger of destabilization in the social and political
46 P. Ish-Shalom order. Second, there is a constant threat of a dictatorial concentration of power in the hands of those who succeed in gaining power. The conservative solution for these two dangers is minimal, structural democracy. On the one hand, regu lar democratic elections guarantee that no power will last forever and there will be no dictatorial concentration of power. On the other hand, by confining polit ical participation to elections, structural democracy prevents political and social destabilization. The normative and cultural academic definition of democracy is more comprehensive than this, being based on an optimistic liberal view of human ration ality. According to this liberal optimism, human beings are rationally driven creatures. It is not that they lack emotions, desires, or communal attachments: they have them, but are largely controlled by rationality. Moreover, this view sees the rational individual as the locus of indivisible civic rights. Thus, this normative and cultural definition of democracy centers on the concepts of parti cipation, deliberation, and rights, seeking to enlarge the scope of citizens’ polit ical participation. There is little fear of destabilizing the polity because political participation and deliberation are believed to be rationally based. Academic definitions, that is, are intrinsically and unavoidably constituted on a normative and ideological groundwork (as are their public conceptualizations). But as soon as we add political constructivism’s theoretical sensitivity toward conceptual politics to the interpretivists and critical theorists’ understanding of the constitutive role of normative and ideological groundwork in theory-making, then we get theorists who are well equipped to escape fixated definitions and engage in Habermasian-like deliberation – deliberation which helps to breed pluralism and the elucidation of what each interlocutor means by the definitions she employs.2
Looking ahead Political constructivism is thus well positioned epistemologically and well equipped to cope with and study conceptual politics and use it to theorize the socio-political world. In what follows I propose several measures and principles that will help in realizing the epistemological potential in political constructivism. The most important principles that should be embraced and implemented are self-reflexivity, communal setting, pluralism, a commitment to transparency, and civic engagement. A social science that is committed to these principles can fully engage conceptual politics and improve both academic research and the world outside academia. As explored extensively in feminist epistemology (see for example Engelstad and Gerrard 2005: 6; Harding 1998: 188, 1986: 137–8, 1991: 163; Potter 2006: 140; Smith 1987: 92), reflexivity, or strong reflexivity, is characterized as a critical awareness of the normative and ideological assumptions and social and cultural commitments comprising the standpoint from which each theorist studies and analyzes the social world. Self-reflexivity is looking inward, exploiting all those extra-theoretical mechanisms which, while confining
Conceptualizing democratization 47 theorizing, also enable it (Ish-Shalom 2011). Being critically aware of the normative and ideological assumptions operative in theorizing ensures aware ness of the essential contested-ness of our definitions. Therefore, self- reflexivity by its very essence works against the strategy of fixating meanings on concepts and definitions, against attempting to decontest that which is essentially contested. Accordingly, self-reflexivity is a vital component of studying and employing conceptual politics. However, there is a problem with self-reflexivity. As committed as feminist epistemology is to self-reflexivity, its adherents are also aware of the difficult ies in achieving it. As Mary Hawkesworth (1996: 92) justly argues, ‘The notion of transparency, the belief that the individual knower can identify all his/her prejudices and purge them in order to greet an unobstructed reality has been rendered suspect.’ She further explains that ‘the perspective of each knower contains blind spots, tacit presuppositions, and prejudgments of which the indi vidual is unaware’ (Hawkesworth 1996: 96). Despite the demands of both the feminist standpoint epistemology project and political constructivism, self- reflexivity may prove unachievable. This is due to the blind spots that prevent theorists (and other individuals) from being aware of the normative and ideo logical assumptions and social and cultural commitments on which their views are based. If this is indeed the case, then how can we achieve our goal of self- reflexivity? The answer to this difficulty is in setting research communally. Yes, it is difficult for individuals to identify and overcome their own blind spots and to recognize the assumptions and commitments that form part and parcel of their theorizing. But overcoming blind spots is possible within the community of researchers as a community. Research is communally embedded and to a large extent it is also communally conducted (Engelstad and Gerrard 2005; Weldon 2006). It is not that we all conduct our research jointly, but even those of us who research and write alone are reliant on the community of researchers. We study and train in academic intuitions under experienced professors, and in due course teach future generations of researchers, all the while engaging with our colleagues’ studies. This is how research works. We circulate our work-in-progress to our colleagues, seeking their useful comments, and comment on their work when asked. On another level, we peer-review articles and research proposals and are peer-reviewed in turn. We hope and expect that this peer-review process is in good faith. The notion of ‘peers’ itself suggests a communal setting and these practices and others embed our research in a community. And it is this communality that helps in solving the problem of blind spots, because although we may be blind to the specificities of our own assumptions and commitments, we can and should be aware of their existence and their constitutive role, and of their function in generating the essentially irresolvable contested-ness of the concepts we study and use in our research. Consequently, there are two levels of self-reflexivity (Ish-Shalom 2011). The first is a general awareness that theorizing involves the use of assumptions and social and cultural commitments and that these have a crucial and
48 P. Ish-Shalom constitutive function in conceptual politics. The second is a specific awareness of the precise content of those assumptions and commitments and the intricate ways by which they produce contested-ness. The first is attainable by the indi vidual theorist. Each theorist, including those considering democracy promo tion and democratization, can be critically aware of the existence and importance of assumptions and commitments in theorizing. The second, more specific level of self-reflexivity is available to the community of researchers working in a common field of either empirical or theoretical interest. As a matter of fact, this second level is achieved quite regularly. Theorists (critical theorists at least) for example usually scrutinize critically their colleagues’ theories and point out the assumptions and commitments embedded in them. Thus, we can safely argue that the community of theorists is well equipped to employ self-reflexivity, which is one of the crucial epistemological principles of studying conceptual politics. An important note of clarification is necessary. The theorists’ community is not a homogenous group sharing a complete belief system. Theorists do not share all norms, values, assumptions, commitments, and expectations. As the discussion of the contested-ness of concepts and definitions shows, this is impos sible. The research community is a group of people loosely united by certain core beliefs, but diverging on many other important beliefs. It is a pluralistic community joined by norms, values, commitments and expectations which centre on truth-seeking and done publicly, openly, and with a sense of healthy scepticism. Yet it is also a community that diverges on numerous assumptions and commitments, such as how to reach that truth, the content of that truth, and what to do with that truth once it is attained. The combination of agreement and disagreement is part and parcel of the internal pluralist composition of the com munity of IR theorists. Disagreements between members of this community are tightly linked to the contested-ness of the concepts we study and the definitions we employ, and may raise concerns as to incommensurability of theories. One could argue that, if indeed different theorists embrace different definitions due to irresolvable assumptions and commitments, it might impede fruitful discussion and prevent understandings across theories. If this were the case there would not be much point in talking about a community of theorists, because instead there would be a number of separate and distinct communities, each united by its own set of complete belief-systems. Perhaps what we really have in International Relations, for example, is a realist community, a liberal community, a Marxist community, a constructivist community, an English school community, etc. Perhaps these communities are subdivided still further into classical realism, structural neo- realism, neoclassical realism, and let us not forget, offensive and defensive realism, each organized around its particular shared set of belief system. And the same internal subdivisions can be applied within the liberal, Marxist, constructivist, English school, etc. communities. And how about communities that are organized not around theoretical assumptions but around subject matter? Is it not sensible to talk about communities of theorists who study international political
Conceptualizing democratization 49 economics, conflict resolution, human rights, democratization and democracy promotion, transitions to peace, transitions to war, globalization, global justice, integration, identity formation, civic-military relations, and the rest? And then we have the methodology criterion, generating separate quantitative and qualit ative communities each of which can naturally be subdivided again. And we can continue dividing theorists along even more axes, to the logical yet absurd end of having countless communities, each of a single theorist (if, indeed, each of us is a coherent entity, entitled to be addressed as a [communal] individuality). And that would not just be absurd, but senseless. Senseless because, underneath it all, these groups can and do share the abovementioned norms, values, commitments, and expectations of seeking truth and doing it publicly, openly, and with a sense of healthy skepticism. These are the ideals at the heart of the theoretical endeavor which allow theorists to overcome their differences and disagreements – at least potentially and if pluralism is adopted as an organizing principle of theorizing. Pluralism, or more accurately, political pluralism, is associated with lib eralism. John Rawls (1993), entitling it reasonable pluralism, championed plur alism as constitutive of his political liberalism. For Rawls, political liberalism acknowledges that values and virtues will always be politically contested. And reasonable pluralism allows political liberalism to function as a political scheme for attaining a just, fair, and cooperative coexistence between different reason able doctrines. It allows regulating and guiding democracy with its ‘Fact of Democratic Unity in Diversity’, which is the fact ‘that in a constitutional demo cratic society, political and social unity does not require that its citizens be unified by one comprehensive doctrine, religious or nonreligious’ (Rawls 1999: 124). For Rawls (1999: 59) tolerating, under the dictate of reasonable pluralism, is to acknowledge and respect the moral worthiness of different stands or doctrines. At least, that is, those doctrines that are reasonable, namely those which themselves embrace reasonable pluralism. According to Rawls (1993: 44), this reasonable pluralism works towards ‘a fair and stable system of cooperation between free and equal citizens who are deeply divided by the reasonable comprehensive doctrines they affirm’. And the same holds true for cooperation between theorists with different (reasonable) sets of belief systems. Pluralism as an organizing principle of the diverse com munity of theorists can facilitate exactly that, a fair and stable system of coopera tion. Accordingly, it will enable this community to function in fruitful and enriching ways, overcoming – even utilizing – the disagreements arising from the contested-ness of the concepts we study. Pluralism is a necessity in an arena such as the academic arena, in which diversity is a fact, and a welcome fact. But another principle is necessary for the proposed pluralism to operate, namely a commitment to transparency in the sense of disclosing and acknowledging the moral commitments that are at the foundation of theorizing. Understood thus, a commitment to transparency is a prerequisite for truthful deliberation between theorists, whether in the form of John Rawls’ original position, or Habermas’ Ideal speech situations (Dryzek and List 2003: 26), and as such it can help clarify agreements, disagreements, and their sources: that is of the moral groundwork of the
50 P. Ish-Shalom contested-ness of the concepts studied and employed in the theoretical studies. Without a commitment to transparency, following the individual and communal exercise of self-reflexivity, we have no sound basis for fruitful and enriching deliberation. Self-reflexivity, is insufficient by itself. Self-reflexivity centers excessively on the self (even the communal self ), and therefore to facilitate bridges between reasonable, yet contesting, theories, researchers have to disclose those things they discovered while engaged in self-reflexivity. Transparency is making public that which was private, and making it public enables the sought-after truthful deliberation; it renders theorists into interlocutors, and a commitment to transparency forces our theoretical reflections into an academic communal public sphere in which we can honestly strive towards elucidating the phenomenon of contested- ness, its sources, and its implications. Put differently, and in line of this chapter’s thrust, a commitment to transparency based on self-reflexivity and community and organized around pluralism would help theorists acknowledge the contested-ness of the concepts they study, and deal with it fruitfully, both for the sake of their research and their wider society. Scanlon (1998) wrote about ‘substantive responsibility’, which he defined as the things people are required to do for each other. Theorists are not above substantive responsibility. And just as this responsibility binds other people, so it binds theorists in an obligation toward wider society. Substantive responsibility calls on theorists to use their advantageous resources for the benefits of society, which in this paper’s framework includes their (potential) capacity to act as a universal class and enhance understanding of the essential contested-ness of political concepts. As already discussed, this understanding, especially in the context of addressing conceptual politics in political constructivism, has the benefit of both avoiding the political manipulation of fixating meaning and facilitating public Habermasian-like deliberation, which helps breed pluralism and construct reasonable and democratic understandings. In so far as theorists enjoy this capacity, they are bound by substantive responsibility to share it with the wider society. Yet, there is one point that needs addressing before we can embrace this normative conclusion. The analysis so far may imply an inherent and essential difference between theorists and the wider society. And it also might imply an elitist, even paternalistic, conceptualization of democracy. If the elitist reading is correct, and the differences between theorists and the wider public are indeed inherent and essential, theorists simply cannot spread their (potential) beneficial capacity. If this reading of society and democracy is correct, then theorists should enclose themselves in their ivory tower and be shielded from the Gramscian-like tactics of fixating meanings. Bringing down the walls surrounding the ivory tower would not encourage a Habermasian-style of public deliberation but undermine the serenity of academia and the privileged standing of the theorists working on conceptual politics. I cannot fully develop here an argument refuting the elitist reading of society. It is part of the normative debates surrounding the understanding of society and democracy. Put differently, it is itself part of the conceptual politics surrounding the irresolvable differences in
Conceptualizing democratization 51 conceptualization of democracy: whether it is elitist and structural or participatory and deliberative. I would limit myself to the argument that an elitist reading of democracy shows lack of respect for the humanity and sociability, the reason ableness of judgment, and for the political faculties all people encompass (or at least potentially encompass). As Avner de-Shalit (1997: 74) argues so forcefully in his justification of participatory and deliberative democracy, ‘we value parti cipation itself, not simply as a means of reaching decisions’. Participation and deliberation are the political apparatuses that duly respect the above human traits and faculties and help to actualize them by nourishing and developing an aware ness of the essential contested-ness of concepts and the political mechanisms available to address this contested-ness. According to this reading, the potential advantage of theorists to understand and address the contested-ness of concepts does not stem from an intrinsic characteristic the rest of society does not share. It is rather due to the institutional settings of academia and research, and the theoretical competence theorists acquire through are training. As such it can be shared, albeit with difficulty, with society at large. It is not something that by nature is secluded in academia and naturally possessed by theorists. It is rather a social privilege provided, among other things, by public resources. Consequently, theorists should seek for civic engagement and, acting as theoretician-citizens (Ish-Shalom 2008), try to cultivate the principles of self-reflexivity, communal setting, pluralism, transparency, and civic engagement with the wider public. Their aim should be to raise public awareness of the contestedness of concepts and the ensued competence of commanding Habermasian-like ways of openly and dynamically attaching meaning to political concepts, en route to achieving public deliberation. This is what the dual analytical gaze requires: cultivating both a Gramscian sensitivity to how conceptual politics is practiced and a Habermasian-inspired responsibility for changing the way present-day conceptual politics is practiced. This should be taken into account in debates on democracy promotion. What it means in practice remains for the academic community to work out; the focus here is on making the normative case for the importance of this move.
Conclusions This chapter analysed conceptual politics, meaning a depiction of politics as that public domain in which concepts are essentially contested. It suggests that polit ical constructivism is the most appropriate theoretical framework for analysing conceptual politics. Political constructivism is a Gramscian-minded constructivism sensitive to the political aspects of social constructions: how meanings are purposefully fixated by crafty politicians to secure a political agenda, by framing the commonsense and manipulating it into public conventions and political convictions. Analysing the positivist attitude to definitions, which are the academic equivalent to meanings, I argued that positivists are captivated by the Gramscian mode of approaching concepts. They are fixated on fixating definitions; they
52 P. Ish-Shalom seek to fix one definition on each of the concepts they work with, often unaware that they are essentially contested. Hence they miss a fundamental aspect of pol itics, and offer a mistakenly static picture of the social world. Accordingly, I argue for a post-positivist reading of the social world, especially political constructivism. I also argue, however, for a dual analytical gaze: a Gramscian sensitivity to how conceptual politics is practiced, and a Habermasian-inspired responsibility for changing how present-day conceptual politics is practiced. To actualize this dual gaze I put forward several principles for conducting research: self-reflexivity, communal setting, the encouragement of pluralism, a commit ment to transparency, and civic engagement. I suggest these should be con sidered in academic work on democratization and democracy promotion. Yet, and with this cautious remark I wish to conclude the chapter, these prin ciples quite tightly follow the deliberative and participatory understanding of democracy and democratization. Hence the title of the paper. In a sense, my proposal is circular, but not – I hope – tautological. It is circular since it is founded on a participatory and deliberative conceptualization of democracy, which it then attempts to help actualize. However, it is a virtuous circularity and a logical and reasonable outcome of embracing conceptual politics that democracy and demo cratization are essentially contested, drawing from different moral backgrounds. Those who adhere to a structural and elitist conceptualization of democracy will probably find my proposed measures unattractive. This is the sort of disagree ment we expect when we understand politics according to the parameters of conceptual politics. Accordingly, it is a disagreement I can live with, even welcome for the pluralism it represents.
Notes 1 Elsewhere (Ish-Shalom forthcoming a) I treated definitions too loosely, and argued erroneously that defining is a feature of the wider public. I believe the theoretical move suggested here of distinguishing between academic definition and the looser public act of decontesting is appropriate. 2 It should be noted, though, that by being ideologically committed, many critical theorists fall into the same trap as positivists and are fixated on one definition. Hence, they fail to acknowledge the contested-ness of concepts and become dogmatically attached to one fixated definition. Indeed, many critical theorists dogmatically engage in such conceptual politics, demonizing all those who dare define concepts differently to the way they do themselves. To escape dogmatism and fixation, pluralism should accom pany the sensitivity to morality, ideology, and conceptual politics.
3 Liberalism and democracy promotion Beate Jahn
Introduction Democracy promotion constitutes a core aspect of the foreign policy of liberal states today. Though it has a long history, at least in the foreign policy of the US (Cox et al. 2000: 10), it has gained particular prominence since the end of the Cold War, with roughly US$2 billion per year spent on democracy-related aid projects (Carothers 2004: 2). And this amount is, since the end of the Cold War, even outweighed by the spending of other international actors like the EU (McFaul 2004–05: 156). Despite these efforts, however, democracy promotion policies have, at best, ‘very modest’ success and frequently fail to produce the ‘hoped-for dramatic results’ (Finkel et al. 2006: 86; Carothers 2004: 5; Diamond 1999: 23). Such failure may, as Hobson and Kurki imply, be attributed to an unsatisfact ory conception of ‘democracy’. More specifically, some authors argue that it is the liberal nature of the democracy being promoted that accounts for the failure of these policies (Robinson 1996); a position which is countered by the argument that democracy promotion policies in practice now do not focus enough on key liberal principles (see Youngs’ chapter). In contrast to these positions, this chapter, which approaches the democracy promotion debates from a political theory-informed perspective, argues that unsatisfactory outcomes of democracy promotion policies frequently have their roots in a poor understanding of lib eralism and its relation to democracy. In order to substantiate this claim, I will show first that in the democracy pro motion literature, liberalism is associated either with private property or indi vidual freedom. This separation of the economic and political dimensions of liberalism lead to different and, indeed, contradictory accounts of the relationship between liberalism and democracy which, in turn, provide the basis for contradictory democracy promotion policies. The second step of the argument introduces the work of John Locke in order to resolve this problem. Locke, I will show, posits a dynamic and constitutive relationship between economics and politics as the definitive core of liberalism. Moreover, Locke’s account of the establishment and democratization of lib eralism highlights the constitutive role of relations between international actors
54 B. Jahn for the promotion of ‘liberal democracy’, a crucial dimension of democracy pro motion largely neglected in the contemporary literature. In a third step I will show that this Lockean theory resolves some of the contradictions of the present democracy promotion literature and provides an explanation for the core weaknesses of contemporary democracy promotion pol icies. The chapter concludes by setting out three core conditions for a successful promotion of liberal democracy.
Liberalism and democracy The goal of democracy promotion policies has predominantly been the estab lishment of ‘modern, representative, liberal, political democracy as practiced within nation-states’ (Schmitter 1995a: 15) – that is, of liberal democracy. Yet, it was only the recent ‘rise of illiberal democracy’ (Zakaria 1997) that led to the recognition that liberalism and democracy do not necessarily go hand in hand (Bova 1997: 112; Plattner 2008: 10–11). The promotion of liberal democracy thus requires an account of the conditions under which liberalism and democracy reinforce each other. Yet, attempts to specify these conditions have led, I will now show, to contradictory results. In the context of the democracy promotion literature, democracy is generally understood as the rule of the people which, in the contemporary world, is expressed in the election of legislative representatives by virtually universal adult suffrage. Democracy, thus, determines who rules and ‘elections . . . are regarded as embodying the popular or majoritarian aspect of contemporary lib eral democracy’ (Plattner 2008: 48). Liberalism, in contrast, is not concerned with who rules but how rule is exercized. It ‘is essentially a doctrine devoted to protecting the rights of the individual to life, liberty, property, and the pursuit of happiness’ (Plattner 2008: 60). This definition of liberalism, combining the rights to liberty and property as it does, is indeed widely accepted. All the more surprising, then, is the fact that the standard accounts in the democracy promo tion literature fail to reflect this relationship and instead rest on a separation of these two core dimensions of liberalism – leading to a contradictory, a com plementary, and a contingent conceptualization. The claim that liberalism and democracy are potentially contradictory is most frequently based on the assumption that the protection of private property is a ‘sacred’ principle of liberalism (Plattner 2008: 67). Yet, this protection of private property may run counter to the interests of a majority of the population if the latter is poor and does not hold any private property. Historically, liberals widely resisted the introduction of democracy precisely on these grounds. Universal suffrage, they argued, would result in the plunder of the rich by the poor and hence suffrage could be extended only to those social groups ‘which cannot be supposed to have an interest in overturning the right to property’ (Ricardo cited in Przeworski 1992: 53; Macaulay cited in Plattner 2008: 64–5). Historically, this assessment was shared by socialists and communists who fought for political power precisely in order to overturn – to a greater or lesser extent – this liberal
Liberalism and democracy promotion 55 principle of private property. The association of liberalism with the principle of private property thus gives rise to the thesis that liberalism and democracy are potentially incompatible. In contrast, the association of liberalism with individual rights and political freedom provides the basis for the claim that liberalism and democracy are ultimately complementary. Here, individual freedom is seen as a ‘necessary con dition’ for democracy (Sartori 1995: 101–2). Individuals are not just sovereign ‘within the legal framework of the private law society’ but also sovereign at the constitutional level, the level ‘at which the “rules of the game” are chosen’ (Vanberg 2008: 143). Since the constitutional arrangements can only be chosen by the voluntary consent of individuals, ‘constitutional liberalism is . . . naturally “democratic” ’ (Vanberg 2008: 143). In other words, liberalism understood as the ‘freeing of the people’ provides the basis for democracy understood as ‘empowering the people’ (Sartori 1995: 101–2). The consequence of this line of argument is that in the democracy promotion literature the widely agreed understanding of democracy as majority rule based on universal suffrage is redefined. If the freedom of the individual is a precon dition for democracy, then the latter must not be confused with majority rule (Vanberg 2008: 146f.). After all, ‘there is reason to fear that a government responsive to popular majorities will be tempted to violate the rights of unpop ular individuals or minorities’ (Plattner 2008: 60). In this view, only liberal democracies are democracies – even if they limit the franchise (Sartori 1995). Historically, the fact that liberalism was in most cases established before demo cracy is cited in support of this thesis. Both the contradictory and complementary conceptions of the relationship between liberalism and democracy, however, are, in their strict version, undermined by historical evidence. The insight that ‘liberalism, either as a conception of political liberty or as a doctrine about economic policy, may have coincided in some countries with the rise of democracy, but has never been immutably or unambiguously linked to its practice’ (Schmitter 1995: 16) thus provides the basis for the third account, that considers the relationship between liberalism and democracy as contingent upon certain circumstances – at a first glance combining the economic and political dimensions of liberalism. ‘Few relationships between social, economic, and political phenomena are stronger than that between the level of economic development and the existence of democratic politics’ (Huntington 1991: 30; Przeworski et al. 2000: 273). Conversely, ‘poverty is a principal – probably the principal – obstacle to democratic development’ (Huntington 1991: 31). And yet, economic development, or capit alism as the source of this development, are widely seen as a ‘necessary – though not sufficient – condition for democracy’ (Berger 1992: 11; Schmitter 1994: 66; Bhagwati, 1992: 40; Diamond 1990: 50, 59). Other helpful conditions mentioned in the literature include Western culture and values (Huntington 1996: 4) as well as state capacity, liberal and rational economic structures, a secure social and political order, horizontal accountability and the rule of law, lack of corruption, strong political parties linked to social groups, a non-fragmented party system,
56 B. Jahn autonomous capacity and public accountability of legislatures and local govern ments, and a vigorous civil society (Diamond 1996: 33). Though these lists entail some political characteristics, they fail to establish, first, which of these features are ‘necessary’ for the development of liberal democracy and which are contingent. After all, not all illiberal states suffer from corruption, fragmented party systems, or the absence of civil society – just as not all stable liberal democracies arguably fulfill all these criteria (O’Donnell 1996: 166). Second, the literature does not provide a theoretical account of the relationship between the ‘necessary but not sufficient’ economic and additional political factors. It empirically identifies certain political features in addition to the economic conditions as widely present in liberal democracies (or, conversely, absent in non-liberal states) and it draws on a connection between the economic and political dimensions of liberal democracy in its historical narrative, as I will show in the third part below. But it fails to integrate the two dimensions theor etically. In effect, this account thus slips right back into the previously outlined contradictory thesis which simply focuses on economic development. Hence, ‘for those countries whose economies are unsuccessful, democracy is bound to be precarious in any case’ (Plattner 2008: 81). The political strand of the contingency thesis perfectly mirrors the fate of its economic counterpart. It identifies certain political features – the protection of individual rights, limited government – as at the core of liberalism and then appears to add to these some socioeconomic conditions such as pre-existing social structure and economic development (Bova 1997: 116; Fukuyama 1992a: 108). Fukuyama offers ‘the desire for recognition’ as ‘the missing link between economic development and democracy’ (Fukuyama 1992a: 107). Yet, while eco nomic development is designated as ‘very helpful’, it is ‘neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for stable democracy’ (Fukuyama 1992a: 108). This status of economic development as, in fact, unnecessary is explicitly stressed when it is argued that liberalism, a hundred years ago, was not at all associated with providing economic benefits – and thus ‘a “poor democracy” is equally conceivable and possible’ (Sartori 1995: 105). Hence, while economic development is seen as ‘helpful’, it is neither distinguished in its importance from other additional factors such as Western culture and values, religion, and ethnicity (Bova 1997: 116; Fukuyama 1992a: 108), nor is a satisfactory theoretical link between the political and economic dimensions of liberalism established. On the contrary, economic development is presented as ultimately unnecessary for the development of liberal democracy. Like its eco nomic counterpart, in effect this thesis thus slips back into the previously outlined complementary position which holds ‘that the philosophy of liberalism contains within itself the seeds of its own democratization’ (Plattner 2008: 60). In effect, then, the three available theoretical accounts of the relationship between liberalism and democracy boil down to two: an economic account which is based on the association of liberalism with private property and fails to theoretically establish its link to individual freedom; and a political account which associates liberalism with individual freedom and fails to provide a
Liberalism and democracy promotion 57 theoretical link to private property. This separation of the economic and political dimensions of liberalism, in turn, provides the ground for different, and at times contradictory, democracy promotion policies. Modernization policies focused on the promotion of economic development which was expected, eventually, to lead to political democratization. In contrast, democracy promotion policies in the post-Cold War period initially focused more on political reform. The widespread failure of both (Rose 2000–01: 191–3; Jahn 2007: 94–102), in the meantime, has led to a situation in which a host of different actors (states, IGOs and NGOs) pursue a multitude of different policies – ranging from support for economic development through political democrat ization and institutional support, to the development of civil society – in a variety of different settings, with successive changes of strategy as well as ‘genuine doubt over the most suitable paths forward’ (see Youngs’ chapter). In short, democracy promotion policies are today characterized by a lack of coordination between actors, integration of policies, consistency over time – drawing in an ‘ad hoc fashion’ on a rich menu of policy options that lacks, however, a ‘systematic’, ‘common’, or ‘comprehensive’ core (see Youngs’ chapter). This inconsistency, I argue, has its roots in the failure to understand the relationship between the political and economic dimensions of liberalism and their implications for democratization. Thus, while most authors agree that political and economic development provide the best conditions for democratization, the failure to establish the nature of their relationship allows policy-makers to pick and choose from policies in any one of these areas – without considering the preconditions for, and consequences of, such policies for other areas.
The Lockean account An answer to the question of how the political and economic dimensions of lib eralism relate to each other, I will now show, can be found in the work of John Locke, in which ‘the central elements of the liberal outlook crystallized for the first time into a coherent intellectual tradition expressed in a powerful, if often divided and conflictual, political movement’ (Gray 1986: 11). It is thus not surprising that Locke is widely mentioned in the democracy promotion literature (Sartori 1995: 101–2; Ake 1992: 33–4; Plattner 2008; see Youngs’ chapter). For the most part, however, these references to Locke are fairly cursory and do not entail a serious engagement with his theory. Such an engagement is nevertheless fruitful because Locke offers a theoretical account of the relationship between the core liberal principles of private property and individual freedom. Moreover, Locke himself was confronted with the challenge of promoting ‘liberalism’ in a largely non-liberal environment. His solution to this problem accords a crucial role to international opportunities for the promotion of domestic liberalism – and the historical emergence, expansion, and eventual democratization of liberalism largely followed the trajectory outlined by Locke. Like most classical authors, Locke begins his reflections on government with assumptions about the state of nature. This state of nature of all men, he argues,
58 B. Jahn is ‘a State of perfect Freedom to order their Actions, and dispose of their Possessions, and Persons as they think fit’ (Locke 1994: 269). Yet, upholding this freedom requires self-preservation (Locke 1994: 271). And it is this requirement, Locke argues, that can only be fulfilled if ‘every Man has a Property in his own Person’ and ‘the Labour of his Body and the Work of his Hands’ (Locke 1994: 287f.). Self-possession, property in one’s person and the fruit of one’s labor, thus allows individuals ‘the taking any part of what is common, and removing it out of the state Nature leaves it in, which begins the Property’ (Locke 1994: 289). The right to private property therefore exists already in the state of nature, and it is this right that underpins and upholds the natural freedom of the individual who would otherwise perish (Locke 1994: 289, 294). Locke supports this theoretical argument with reference to the historical origins of government largely based on information about indigenous communities in America (Inayatullah and Blaney 2004: 35–43; Jahn 2000). ‘Men are naturally free, and the Examples of History shewing, that the Governments of the World . . . had their beginning laid on that foundation, and were made by the Consent of the people’ (Locke 1994: 336). And since this freedom is based on property, the ‘great and chief end therefore (of government) is the Preservation of their Property’ (Locke 1994: 351). For Locke, then, both the freedom of the individual and its right to private property already exist in the state of nature. Yet, they do not simply coexist. Private property provides the necessary basis for individual freedom; such free individuals then demand government by consent which in turn has to protect private property as the basis for their freedom. In short, Locke argues that indi vidual freedom is and must be based on private property, for without private property the individual is necessarily dependent on others for its survival and thus not free. Yet, this ideal formulation did not reflect the social and political conditions at the time of Locke’s writing. In fact, it was precisely because most governments in Locke’s time and throughout history had not been governments by consent, and because private property had not necessarily been protected, that Locke developed this theory and propagated it against the prevailing political positions, such as Filmer’s defense of paternal government which he attacks in the first treatise (1994).1 In practice, he thought it ‘evident that there is a difference in degrees in men’s understandings, apprehensions, and reasonings to so great a lat itude, that one may, without doing injury to mankind, affirm, that there is a greater difference between some men and others in this respect, than between some men and some beasts’ (Locke 1959, II: 446). A liberal polity could therefore not be established by simply introducing elections. Locke thus had to show how society could be based on the principles of private property and government by consent in the absence of a majority of individuals supporting such developments or, conversely, how the majority of the population could be made sufficiently rational to establish and maintain such a polity. In other words, Locke saw himself confronted with the task of promoting ‘liberalism’ in a non- liberal environment.
Liberalism and democracy promotion 59 Locke’s solution to this problem was faithful to the fundamental premises of his theory – and in particular to the linkage between freedom and private property. If private property was the basis of individual freedom, Locke argued, property owners would demand that government protect private property and hence their freedom. He thus advocated the extension of full political rights to property owners only – and the concomitant denial of these rights to those who did not own prop erty. ‘Paternal Power is . . . where Minority makes the Child incapable to manage his property; Political where Men have Property in their own disposal; and Des potical over such as have no property at all’ (Locke 1994: 384).2 Yet, such rule by a relatively small and wealthy elite clearly did not satisfy his claim that, in principle, all people were born free and equal and thus had a right to consent to government. Moreover, Locke saw the tiny minority of prop erty owners, ‘the rich’, who would have been accorded full political rights, as ‘mostly corrupt’ (Dunn 1969: 217). Hence, Locke was interested in extending the franchise and, perfectly in line with his theory that private property provides the basis for individual freedom and the rights that follow from this, he argued that an extension of the franchise could be achieved by turning more, and ideally all, sections of society into property owners. This was a neat theoretical solution, but in practice it threw up the problem of where all this additional property was to come from. After all, having committed himself to the protection of private property, redistribution was not an option. So, Locke argued that private prop erty was more productive than common property and thus of greater benefit to all of humankind (1994: 296–8). It was therefore justified to turn common into private property: God gave the land ‘to the use of the Industrious and Rational’ (Locke 1994: 291). People could simply attain property by mixing their indi vidual labor with the original common property. The privatization of common property was thus the solution to the problem. But there was simply not enough common land – at the time the most import ant additional source of wealth – left in England to provide the vast and rising number of poor with property. Locke thus looked abroad: ‘Yet there are still great Tracts of Ground to be found, which (. . .), lie waste, and are more than the People who dwell on it, do, or can make use of, and so still lie in common’ (Locke 1994: 299). It was this common land in America which could be used, at least in principle, to furnish all individuals with property and thus make them eligible to full political rights. In short, ‘Locke . . . was offering the New World, specifically the colonial settlements of America, as validation of his sociopolit ical philosophy’ (Lebovics 1986: 577). According to this theory, the expansion of liberalism and its subsequent democratization required three steps: first, polit ical rights were to be given only to property owners who would establish a lib eral society; secondly, common property could then be expropriated and transformed into private property thus increasing the number of property owners; and thirdly, on the basis of this wider distribution of property, political rights could be extended.3 Historically, the establishment of liberalism and its eventual democratization broadly followed the trajectory outlined by Locke. First, land owners and
60 B. Jahn merchants who had become rich from the trade with the colonies – among them Locke’s own long-time patron, the Earl of Shaftesbury – increasingly demanded political rights with direct reference to their property which led to a huge increase in the members in the House of Commons (Perelman 2000: 175; Acemoglu and Robinson 2006: 350). And these men subsequently used their polit ical power to establish a liberal state characterized by the transference of de jure political power into the hands of commercial and capitalistic interests and the stabilization of property rights in seventeenth century Britain (Acemoglu and Robinson 2006: 349–50).4 Once in power, however, these men were not content with securing the existing property arrangements but systematically engaged in the transformation of common into private property – both in the domestic and the international sphere. Thus, Locke’s work was frequently cited in Parliament in support of private enclosure acts which, between 1710 and 1815, transferred 6.5 million acres or 20 percent of the total land from common into private property (McNally 1988: 62, 8–9; Perelman 2000: 175).5 These domestic policies were accompanied by the propagation of colonialism in which the Earl of Shaftesbury and also Locke himself played a crucial role. Locke was secretary to the Lord Proprietors of Carolina (1668–71), secretary to the Council of Trade and Plantations (1673–4), a member of the Board of Trade (1696–1700), he invested in the slave-trading Royal Africa Company (1671) and the Company of Merchant Adventurers to trade with the Bahamas; he was a Landgrave of the proprietory government of Carolina, wrote parts of the Fundamental Constitutions of Carolina, handled the day-to-day correspondence with the colonists in Carolina, and Edisto Island was originally called Locke Island. His writings, political and theoretical, cover all aspects of colonialism and consistently defend it (Tully 1993: 140–1; Tuck 1999: 167). And it was these writings, particularly Locke’s theory of property, that ‘preachers, legal theorists, and politicians’ used to base first the land claims of the British colonists and then those of American citizens for the enclosure and cultivation of land (Arneil 1996: 169). The same argument was also influential in Australia, New Zealand, and Canada throughout the eighteenth and well into the ninteenth century (Ivison 2003: 93). These policies thus allowed European colonists to acquire property and, perfectly in line with the dynamic outlined by Locke, it was in settler soci eties like New Zealand, the USA, and Australia that the promise based on such wider distribution of property – the introduction of universal franchise – was first realized. In Europe, meanwhile, the gradual democratization of liberalism was sim ilarly in line with Locke’s theory. Until well into the nineteenth century, voting rights were limited by property qualifications and liberals widely and passion ately resisted the extension of the franchise on precisely the grounds that Locke had set out: namely that those who did not own property could not be expected to support and maintain laws protecting private property. Such resistance was necessary because the poorer sections of society vociferously demanded political rights. Upheavals, rebellions, and the threat of revolution were widespread and
Liberalism and democracy promotion 61 integral features of society: rulers had to be forced to give up power (Tilly 2004; Kim 1992: 24). Yet, it was precisely the ruling elite’s resistance to extending the franchise which ultimately guaranteed the liberal character of Western demo cracy (Bova 1997: 116; Ake 1992: 33–4). For the enclosure of commonly owned land domestically, colonial appropriation of land internationally, and the industrial revolution all contributed to the economic growth that led to a wider distribution of property in society – in line with the widely noted link between economic development and liberal democracy (Przeworski et al. 2000; Acemoglu and Robinson 2006: 58). In other words, a sizable middle class slowly emerged and allowed liberals to lower the property threshold for voting rights gradually, thus extending the franchise – but only to those sections of society that had actually achieved a measure of individual freedom based on private property and who therefore had a stake in upholding the liberal character of gov ernment. Thus, general evidence suggests that a successful democratization of liberalism requires the inviolability of property rights (Acemoglu and Robinson 2006: 82; Chirot 2009: 107). Moreover, the transformation of common into private property remains at the core of liberal strategies to foster economic growth today. The last two decades have seen a remarkable revival of liberalism in the form of market economics, the privatization of state-owned industries, and the trimming of welfare benefits by liberal democracies (Plattner 2008: 68). This latest round of ‘privatization’ and ‘liberalization’ targeted communal ownership of water and electricity supplies, education, and health care and the establishment of ‘new enclosures’ in the form of intellectual property rights over natural products and their uses (May 2000). Policies of privatization and marketization also lie at the core of the development policies of international organizations like the IMF and World Bank as well as those of individual liberal states. Locke’s theory thus provides two crucial insights concerning the estab lishment and democratization of liberalism that are missing from contemporary accounts. The first is that private property constitutes individual freedom. The expansion and democratization of liberalism, according to this theory, requires a wider distribution of private property in society, which in turn constitutes indi viduals as free in the liberal sense and thus disposed towards pursuing liberal policies: government by consent, the protection of private property and indi vidual liberties. Second, Locke’s theory highlights the constitutive role of international pol itics for the establishment and democratization of liberalism. For it was the appropriation of foreign property – in addition to domestic privatization – that provided the necessary resources for a wider distribution of property in domestic society. America (and subsequently other colonies) offered common land (as well as cheap labor, access to natural resources, and (captive) markets) for capital accumulation that was simply not available in Europe. Colonialism, in short, is now widely regarded as having played a crucial role in economic development in Europe (Marks 2007; Washbrook 1997). But colonialism also allowed the ruling elite to pursue a large part of its economic goals abroad and
62 B. Jahn thus relieve political pressure at home. It provided the domestic poor and polit ically disenfranchised with the option to emigrate and allowed the government to export its poor, its criminals, its orphans, as well as offer employment in the administration of the colonies. In short, colonialism provided the economic and political means to resist demands for political rights in Europe long enough for a sizable middle class to emerge – and common political interests in the appropriation of indigenous peoples’ land for rich and poor alike in the settler communit ies themselves. The very possibility of colonialism in turn depended on unequal power relations in the international sphere. International politics thus played a constitutive role in the establishment and democratization of liberalism.
Liberal democracy promotion These two dimensions of the establishment and democratization of liberalism – the constitutive role for private property in individual freedom, and for international politics in domestic liberalization and democratization – are variously disregarded in contemporary democracy promotion literature. In contrast to Locke, the political narrative of the relationship between liberalism and democracy in the contempor ary literature assumes that liberalism, both political and economic, arises out of a particular political culture characterized by secularization, tolerance, and the ‘taming of politics’ (Sartori 1995: 104, 106; Fukuyama 1992b). The subsequent historical expansion of liberalism is explained by ‘the spread of liberal ideas of the natural freedom and equality of all human beings’ which ‘doomed any special and substantial privileges enjoyed on the basis of heredity’ and ‘eventually undermined any effort to exclude people from political participation on the basis of such factors as race, religion, or sex’ (Plattner 2008: 67). Democracy promotion policies based on this narrative therefore identify a traditional political culture as the main barrier to the development of liberal demo cracy. They assume that (the Nietzschean) ‘slave must be educated slowly and painfully to understand that he or she is a human being with a unique dignity that can best be recognized by certain kinds of social and political institutions’ (Fukuyama 1992a: 107) and consequently propagate policies focusing on the spread of liberal ideas and institutions: issues of citizenship and civil society in current democracy promotion programs are designed to address precisely this political backwardness (Plattner 2008: 53). The Lockean theory highlights, however, that this narrative puts the historical cart before the horse. The period before the emergence of liberal ideas at the end of the seventeenth century was neither characterized by a ‘tame’ political culture nor by secularism and tolerance but instead by the bloodiest civil war in English (and European) history – a war, no less, which was in large part religious. Indeed, Locke’s work and with it the development of liberal thought can be understood as an attempt to find a solution to the problem of religious violence (Inayatullah and Blaney 2004: 35). This solution lay in the ‘privatization’ of religion, in a clear distinction between the private and the public sphere. The public sphere, or ‘political society’, as Locke terms it, ‘is instituted for no other
Liberalism and democracy promotion 63 end but only to secure every man’s Possession of the things of this life’ and thus has no right to adjudicate on matters of the afterlife (1983: 48). Conversely, while individuals may follow their particular faiths in the private sphere, they may not ‘obtrude those things upon others, unto whom they do not seem to be the indubitable Doctrines of the Scripture’ (Locke 1983: 57). This ‘privatization’ of religion, however, required the protection of the private sphere based on the protection of private property. In short, a secular, tolerant6 and ‘tame’ political culture was not a precondition for the development of liberalism but rather a result of this development. Historical evidence also contradicts the claim that the spread and democrat ization of liberalism required the undermining of a traditional political imagination by liberal ideas (Plattner 2008: 62). Instead, radical political demands were voiced by the population throughout this entire period – attesting not to a traditional but rather to a radical political imagination (Tilly 2004; Ake 1992: 33–4). Instead of originating in the ideological development of ruling elites (Plattner 2008: 66), historical evidence shows that ‘most moves toward democracy happen in the face of significant social conflict and possible threat of revolution. Democracy is usually not given by the elite because its values have changed. It is demanded by the disenfranchised as a way to obtain political power and thus secure a larger share of the economic benefits of the system’ (Acemoglu and Robinson 2006: 29; Kim 1992: 24). The constitutive role of private property in the development of liberal policies and polities, moreover, also explains the earlier democratization in European settler societies like America. In such societies, the transformation of common into private property that would eventually turn the majority of the population into property owners, was based on the expropriation of indigenous – that is, ‘foreign’ – political communities. Instead of pitching different sections of society against each other, as in Europe, this process created an alliance of inter est between all settlers in the expropriation of the indigenous communities. Hence, ruling elites had nothing to fear, but a lot to gain, from extending the franchise in settler communities. The democratization of liberalism was thus not achieved by a simple spread of liberal ideas and institutions, but rather by a spread of the economic conditions that ensured that these ideas meaningfully reflected the conditions of the people’s existence and their interests. The failure to attend to these economic foundations of liberal ideas and institutions explains the ironic results of democracy promotion policies focusing on the latter: for while such policies often succeed in establishing liberal institutions – democratic elections, a free press, civil society organizations – the policies subsequently pursued through these institutions are frequently highly illiberal (Berman 2009; Carothers 2004; De Zeeuw and Kumar 2006). In the absence of a sufficient spread of private property in society, the survival of individuals and their real existing freedom depends on communal property and redistribution (ethnic, religious, or otherwise). In such circumstances, ‘liberal’ institutions facilitate the defense of communal rather than individual rights – as nation-building processes have shown historically (Chirot 2009: 101).
64 B. Jahn This intimate link between the economic and political dimensions of lib eralism is at least empirically – if not theoretically, as I have argued above – recognized by the economic narrative and reflected in debates about shock-therapy or the advantages of authoritarian regimes in pushing through rad ical economic reforms (Zakaria 1997; Geddes 1994). Such reforms involve ‘significant social costs’ (i.e., the expropriation of communal property) and thus raise the question how best to manage the political consequences of these costs (Przeworski 1992: 56). And yet, the economic narrative fails to recognize the centrality of the inter national for the emergence and democratization of liberalism. All historical attempts at modernization, it holds, ‘conceived of development as a project linked to national economic and political independence’ (Przeworski 1992: 55). Hence, American and European economic and political development are seen as separate and radically different cases of liberalization and democratization. While America was blessed with abundant land, a small population, and the absence of a traditional propertied class, Europe was characterized by the oppos ite: a limited supply of land, a large population, and a traditional propertied class. The fact that, in spite of these differences, both successfully established liberal democracies underpins the claim that such development is, in principle, possible anywhere (Plattner 2008: 68; Huntington 1991: 33). And even altern ative interpretations of these cases, giving rise to alternative models – such as social rather than liberal democracy – treat economic and political development as an entirely endogenous process (see Berman’s chapter). Democracy promo tion policies based on this narrative therefore aim to trigger economic development by following the European and American example, that is, by propagating privatization and marketization (more or less rapidly and with varying degrees of social redistribution). Yet, such policies show extremely uneven results – ranging from highly successful to apparently hopeless cases (Przeworski et al. 2000: 277). This disjuncture between theory and practice has lately been explained with reference to the unprecedented ‘internationalization’ of modernization processes in the context of globalization (Przeworski 1992: 55; Acemoglu and Robinson 2006: 347–8). The Lockean theory and subsequent history show, however, that even in the West economic and political development never was a largely endogenous, national, or domestic phenomenon. Instead, international policies of colonialism played a constitutive role and intimately linked the emergence and democrat ization of liberalism in Europe and America. And such policies, in turn, depended on unequal power relations within the international system which enabled Europeans to deny indigenous communities rights to sovereignty, to suppress their resistance, and to export a large part of the negative consequences of privatization to these weaker communities. Attention to this early and constitutive role of international politics explains why economic development in ‘late, late developing countries (mainly in Africa)’ is so much more difficult (Huntington 1991: 33). Unlike Europe at the beginning of its development, contemporary poor states are also weak states
Liberalism and democracy promotion 65 within the international order. They do not enjoy the opportunity of privatizing other communities’ property or of exporting the negative consequences of domestic privatization policies into the international sphere. On the contrary, they operate within an international economic and political system that has been set up in the interests of the rich and powerful liberal democratic states. And these interests, precisely because the latter have become democratic, continue to lie in growth necessary to provide economic benefits to their own populations. Hence, these states have a strong incentive to keep the terms of the international economic and political order in their favor. The international order thus provides the framework demarcating the possibilities and limits of political and economic development for individual states, and thus the possibilities and limits of democracy. This international context is equally important for, albeit neglected in, the political narrative. Liberalism and democracy are generally, and correctly, understood to be attributes of a domestic or national socio-political system. Yet, in light of the historical account guided by Locke’s theory, the process of lib eralization and democratization was not a domestic or endogenous one. It depended on the economic opportunities available in the international sphere whose exploitation, in turn, was made possible by unequal power relations. In other words, the extension of political rights in the domestic sphere ultimately required the denial of political rights to weaker communities in the international sphere. More generally, the Lockean theory explains why democracy promotion pol icies modeled on previously successful cases fail to produce similar results. The constitutive nature of the relationship between private property and individual freedom, as well as between domestic and international politics, leads to a dynamic process in which developments in one of these areas lead to fundamental changes in the others. That is, the wider distribution of property in society constitutes actors with new and different political and economic interests and consequently also a domestic and international environment shaped by different political and economic forces. The constraints and opportunities provided by these new conditions should not be ignored by democracy promotion policies designed to emulate historically successful cases.
Conclusion On the basis of this Lockean theory, the prospects for contemporary democracy promotion policies depend on three core reforms. First, if private property is indeed constitutive of individual liberty and thus also of liberal policies and polities, democracy promotion policies must aim to support a wider distribution of property in society (where such conditions do not yet exist). Second, this aim to produce a wider distribution of property within society, the Lockean account shows, was crucially dependent on the ability to appropriate property within the international sphere and to export the negative consequences of domestic privatization. Since such opportunities do not exist for economically
66 B. Jahn and politically weak states in the contemporary international system, democracy promotion policies, if they are to be successful, have to focus on creating equi valent opportunities for capital accumulation as well as for the international ization of the negative consequences of domestic privatization. In other words, successful democracy promotion policies must replace their traditional focus on bilateral relations between sponsors and targets with attention to the ‘macro- multilateral’ policies that ‘affect the systematic constraints’ provided by the international system (see Youngs’ chapter). For these wider policies may, indeed, ‘work at cross purposes’ with the aim to promote liberal democracy – as in the case of ‘US support for neo-liberal economic reforms . . . that undercut the political reforms’ promoted by democracy assistance (Bermeo 2009: 259). In other words, successful democracy promotion policies require that at least as much attention is paid to the World Trade Organization as to assistance for elections or support for civil society (Rose 2000–1: 201). Third, the dynamic nature of the development of liberalism and its democrat ization historically calls for reform of the methodological approach in designing democracy promotion policies. The conventional approach – comparative analysis providing models for emulation – ignores the dynamic nature of the process of (lib eral) democratization which fundamentally reconstitutes the political context and its constraints and opportunities. Successful democracy promotion policies thus have to be based on an analysis of the specific domestic and international opportunities and constraints that particular target states face (Rose 2000–1: 189).
Notes 1 Locke developed a philosophy of history explaining such counterevidence. In a nutshell, he argued that while states had originally been established on the basis of consent, over time rulers exploited their position and justified authoritarian government with reference to illiberal custom and tradition that gradually shaped the political imagination of the people (Locke 1994: 329, 343). 2 This does not mean that the emancipatory potential of Locke’s thought is strictly limited to property owners. Locke simply aims to exclude those deemed unable or unwilling to uphold this principle as foundational for society from political rights. Once based on this principle, society could curtail individual property rights for purposes of international competition and defense and in order to allow every individual to fulfill its rights and obligations to God – that is, to work for its upkeep (Arneil 1996: 159; Tully 1982: 63; Dunn 1969: 246; Laslett 1994: 105). Similarly, political rights could be extended to non-property owners well socialized into the principles and practices of such a society. 3 Expropriation and political oppression were, of course, not Locke’s goals but side effects of his theory, or more appropriately, of the use that was made of his theory. For Locke (1994: 288) argued that the transformation of common into private property was justified only ‘where there is enough, and as good left in common for others’. This limitation on the practice of transforming common into private property can be, and has been, used to justify a liberal ‘welfare state’ with quite considerable limitations on private property (for example, Tully 1982). Locke’s work thus lends itself to the justification of radically ‘neoliberal’ as well as more ‘social democratic’ policies. Debates over which normative interpretation of Locke is more appropriate, however, fall outside the remit of this chapter, which uses Locke’s theory only for explanatory purposes.
Liberalism and democracy promotion 67 4 This role of colonialism in the development of liberalism is compatible with accounts that see its roots in the plutocratic nature of English society which forced the rich to invest abroad for lack of a domestic market. It was, after all, precisely those plutocrats who demanded political rights in order to protect their property; yet, doing so they were confronted with the politically volatile nature of an economically deeply divided society and consciously propagated colonialism not only as a good investment but also as an economic opportunity for the domestic poor. 5 McNally reports that in 1710 the first private enclosure act was presented in Parlia ment, followed by 100 between 1720 and 1750, 139 between 1750 and 1760, 900 between 1760 and 1779, and 2000 between 1793 and 1815 (1988: 11). 6 Arguably, however, this solution did not lead to tolerance but rather ‘elided the prob lem of tolerance, obviated the necessity to be tolerant, rather than make people tolerant’ (Seligman 2009: 125).
4 The past and future of social democracy and the consequences for democracy promotion Sheri Berman
During the nineteenth and first half of the twentieth century, Europe was the most turbulent region on earth, convulsed by war, economic crises and social and political conflict. Yet, during the second half of the twentieth century it was among the most stable, a study in democracy, social harmony and prosperity. How can we understand this remarkable transformation? The answer, of course, lies in changes that occurred after 1945. Among the most important of these changes was a dramatic shift in understandings of what it would take to ensure democratic consolidation in Europe. Across the political spectrum people recognized that bringing stable, well functioning democracies to Europe would require much more than merely eliminating dictatorships and changing political institutions and procedures; it would necessitate revising the relationship that existed among states, markets and society as well. After World War II, in other words, a new understanding of democracy developed in Western Europe, one that went beyond what we think of today as ‘electoral’ or even ‘lib eral’ democracy (Schumpeter 1954; Diamond 2009, 1999; Collier and Levitsky 1997) to what is best understood as ‘social democracy’ – a regime type which entails dramatic changes not merely in political arrangements, but in social and economic ones as well. Although it seems odd to us today, it is important to remember that before 1945 it was widely believed that democracy could not in fact be reconciled with capitalism and social stability. Indeed, this was one point on which classical lib erals and traditional Marxists agreed. From J. S. Mill to Alexis de Tocqueville to Friedrich Hayek, liberals have lived in constant fear of the ‘egalitarian threats of mass society and democratic . . . politics, which, in their view, would lead, by necessity, to tyranny and “class legislation” by the propertyless as well as unedu cated majority’ (Offe 1983: 225–66). Karl Marx, meanwhile, expressed skepti cism about whether the bourgeoisie would actually allow democracy to function (and workers to take power), but felt that if they did, democracy might contrib ute to bringing about an end to capitalism – a potential, of course, that he, unlike his liberal counterparts, welcomed (Offe 1983: 225–6). And indeed such pessim ism found ample support in European history. During the nineteenth through the mid twentieth centuries Europe had undergone several democratic waves, all of which had been failures. Indeed, not only had the continent proved unable to
The past and future of social democracy 69 consolidate its myriad democratic experiments, conflicts over regime type had directly contributed to large-scale violence, including the most brutal dic tatorships and deadliest wars the world had ever experienced. Understanding how Europe overcame this past and finally managed during the post-World War II era to change its political trajectory is a story with important implications for how we think about democratic development and democracy promotion today.
The development of democracy in Europe Europe’s first democratic experiment came with the French revolution.1 After the overthrow of what had hitherto seemed Europe’s most powerful monarchical dictatorship, various groups in French society proved unable to agree on pre cisely what type of regime should follow it. The first attempt to create a new political order out of the ashes of the old was in 1791, when a form of constitu tional monarchy was proposed. This fairly moderate regime received little support, and conflict between more radical and conservative forces continued until 1793, when the radicals emerged triumphant. The king, Louis XVI, was sent to the gallows and a republic with universal suffrage declared. Despite the initial excitement greeting this unprecedented democratic experiment, the new regime soon faltered. The Republic believed it was circled by enemies both within and without and embarked on a campaign of internal repression and external war. Between 1793 and 1794, France’s democracy descended into a ‘Reign of Terror’, during which approximately 20,000–40,000 French citizens were executed for ‘counter-revolutionary activities’ and the country plunged into war against much of the rest of the continent. This turmoil was not what most French people had hoped for when the ancien régime collapsed and by 1799 the country, exhausted from its battles, submitted to a coup by a strongman promis ing a return to order – Napoleon Bonaparte, the original ‘man on horseback’. In the space of a decade France had gone from a hereditary dictatorship, to demo cracy, to war and domestic chaos, and then back to dictatorship, but of a new variety: military dictatorship. In the decades after the revolution debates about its meaning and the implemen tation of its ideals – liberty, equality, fraternity – and about how to deal with the nationalist and democratic forces unleashed by it divided European publics, ren dering France as well as the rest of the continent politically divided and prone to political instability. To these political divisions, economic and social ones were added, since during the early nineteenth century the industrial revolution had begun sweeping across Europe, increasing the size of the working and middle classes and generating new forms of economic dislocation (Sperber 2005; Stearns 1974). One result was a growing frustration on the part of these groups with polit ical regimes that were neither responding to their needs nor allowing them influ ence commensurate with their growing numbers and economic power. As Eric Hobsbawm (1996: 356) put it, by 1848 European politics was ‘out of balance’. Just as in 1789, it was events in France that got the ball rolling. When the government attempted to prohibit a reform banquet that had been called for
70 S. Berman February 1848 to discuss the political situation, protests broke out. And when the government responded to these protests with force, barricades began to appear in the streets; within short measure another French political regime was headed for the dustbin of history. These events sent shock waves across Europe: from north to south, east to west, Europeans took to the streets demanding an end to the dictatorships that ruled their lands. At first, these uprisings were remarkably effective. Dictatorships began to totter even in what had seemed some of the continent’s strongest regimes (e.g., Austria and Germany). But almost as soon as the old order began to crumble, fissures began to open up in the opposition camp. In country after country it became clear that although there was massive discontent with existing dictatorships, there were also massive dis agreements about the nature of the political regimes that should replace them. In particular two divisions that had appeared first in 1789 returned to shape the outcome of the democratic wave in 1848. The first was between what we might broadly call liberals and democrats – that is, between people who wanted to reform the old regime while also ensuring safeguards against unchecked mass participation and those who insisted that nothing less than a transition to full democracy would be acceptable. To some degree this was a class division, with middle-class groups largely in the former camp and the emerging working class in the latter (Langer 1969; Jones 1991; Stearns 1974; Kranzberg 1959). The second division that shaped the fate of the 1848 wave, especially the further east one traveled, involved national and communal issues. Nationalism had appeared as a powerful political force with the French revolution and spread across Europe with Napoleon’s armies. Since then, economic development, along with the social discontent, political mobilization and new forms of com munication that it brought in its wake, helped bring identity issues further to the forefront of many peoples’ consciousness. Thus, as the old order began to weaken in 1848, not only did frustration with unrepresentative and unresponsive regimes explode, suppressed national, ethnic and linguistic conflicts also came to the fore. These conflicts, in turn, made it difficult to keep opposition to the old order unified. This dynamic was particularly clear in the lands of the Habsburg Empire where different national groups spent almost as much time fighting each other as the reigning political order. The Hungarians, for example, demanded autonomy from the Germans but refused to grant their own Croatian, Serbian and Romana nian minorities similar privileges, thereby alienating the latter from the former. The Czechs, meanwhile, also longed to be free of German domination and so refused to join with German reformers, despite their joint interest in political lib eralization. The result, as Jonathan Sperber (Sperber 2005: 138) notes, was that, although ‘the Austrian Empire was the very heart of nationalist contention in 1848–9 . . . rather than a crescendo of nationalist demands tearing the realm to pieces, the different national movements fought each other, and cancelled each other out’. We can also see how deadly the confluence of political and national divisions could be when we turn to perhaps the most consequential political experiment in
The past and future of social democracy 71 1848 – that of the Frankfurt parliament. Representatives from across central Europe’s German states met in Frankfurt’s Paulskirche to try to draft a constitu tion for a new liberal unified Germany. Once they began negotiating, however, conflicts quickly emerged over which groups/peoples should actually be included in the new Germany (with debate about the inclusion of Catholic Austria proving particularly difficult) and over how far political reform should actually go. With regard to the latter, this was once again to some degree a class conflict, with middle-class liberals beginning to fear what they viewed as working-class rad icalization. By 1851, little was left of the democratic wave that had swept through Europe in 1848. Several features of the 1848 wave are striking. First: how rapid the emergence and how extensive the reach of the democratic wave was. Second: how quickly and completely many long-standing dictatorships collapsed in the face of the mass pressures that produced the wave. And third: how soon after wards divisions within European societies appeared – over national/communal issues and over regime type – and how difficult it was to maintain momentum once these disagreements appeared. As a result of such divisions, 1848 became – in the words of the great historian G.M. Trevelyan – ‘the turning point at which modern history failed to turn’ (Kranzberg 1959: xi). In 1848 as in 1789, although Europe did not ‘turn’ permanently towards democracy, the unfinished business of the time, politically and nationally, did not disappear with the receding of the democratic wave. Indeed, the issues and dynamics that emerged in 1848 drove political development in Europe during the decades to come. In Italy and Germany, for example, the second half of the nineteenth century was taken up with trying to complete the national projects that had been started in 1848. After the liberal-led attempt at German unification failed in 1848, the second, successful, attempt took place under the leadership of a conservative authoritarian – Otto von Bismarck. Politically, the new German Reich formed in 1871 tried to square a political circle, mixing monarchical and democratic elements in an attempt to satisfy the forces of the ancien régime and the masses. This political mishmash proved increasingly difficult to sustain as the political aspirations of the middle and working classes increasingly ran up against the intransigence of conservatives. By the beginning of the twentieth century, conflict over the political future of Germany was making it difficult for the national government to function, breeding political frustration, and feeding the rise of nationalist and other extremist organizations that peddled increasingly vociferous and violent criticisms of the reigning order (Berman 2001; Eley 2001). Indeed, by 1914 the political system was so deadlocked and political dissatisfaction was so high that some scholars have asserted that German elites rushed the country head-long into war in a vain attempt to head off the political explosion that seemed bound to come (Fisher 1975, 1967; Kehr 1983). In Italy, meanwhile, a not dissimilar trajectory was evident as the political system of the newly unified country excluded most citizens from meaningful participation and became mired in an institutionalized system of corruption known as Trasformismo. Partly as a result, the state proved unable to deal
72 S. Berman satisfactorily with the new country’s myriad problems, especially growing class conflict and the immense divisions that existed between the poor and underde veloped South and the more advanced North. The consequence was that by the end of the nineteenth century political frustration was on the rise in Italy, as was the draw of nationalist and other extremist movements that fed off dissatisfac tion with the reigning political order (Salome 1991; Patrucco 1992). This general pattern – rising class conflict, growing nationalist mobilization, and increasing political instability – characterized most of Europe during the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. Returning to France, for example, the country underwent another transition to democracy in 1871, but not before having to endure another revolutionary uprising (the Paris Commune) that cost perhaps 20,000 French citizens their lives. (Reflecting the frequency of political upheaval in France, a long-standing joke had it that the National Library kept its copies of the constitution in the ‘periodicals’ section [Bell 2010: 32]). The Third Republic that emerged from this chaos was the only real democracy that existed in Europe at the time. Although it achieved many important successes, in today’s terms we would probably not consider it fully consolidated since significant groups on both the left and right rejected the democratic ‘rules of the game’ (Linz and Stepan 1996), with the nationalist right growing particularly rejection ist, anti-semitic and even violent over the course of time. The divisions that weakened the Third Republic were, of course, nothing new, but they had become so deep that many wondered whether France would ever be able to achieve polit ical stability. The historian Augustin Thierry, for example, mused ‘We think we are one nation, yet we are two nations in the same land; two nations, hostile in their recollections of the past, irreconcilable in their projects for the future’ (Theirry 1856: xiii; Bell 2010: 32). Thus, by the eve of World War I, Europe already had behind it several decades of rising political instability, mobilization and conflict. The end of the war unleashed yet another democratic wave, bringing political change to places as diverse as Germany, Austria, Sweden and Poland. Many of these new demo cracies were, however, burdened with a huge number of problems generated by the war, including economic devestation, high debt, inflation, and in those coun tries on the losing side (like Germany), a sense of national humiliation. In addi tion, the war and its aftermath worsened many problems inherited from the prewar period. Class conflict, for example, increased during the interwar period as a result of economic difficulties and the rise of communism. Communist par ties not only fed off and exacerbated existing class resentments and divisions, they also injected into European polities powerful anti-democratic actors, able and willing to use terrorism and other forms of insurrectionary activity to achieve their goals. Another problem inherited from the prewar period was nationalism. After 1918 a number of new countries were created in central and eastern Europe out of the wreckage of the Habsburg empire. Many of these new countries had deeply divided and very mixed populations, with borders that did not correspond to their citizens’ sense of identity or history. These new democratic, multiethnic
The past and future of social democracy 73 states were beset by ethnic and social conflict almost from the moment of their birth; many experienced significant amounts of violence during the interwar years; none survived the interwar years and the Nazi onslaught. Nationalism was not, however, a degenerative force only in Europe’s new states. The continent’s older nations had to deal with nationalist movements carried over from the prewar period that grew even more violent and popular after the war; many of these groups provided the foundation upon which fascist and national socialist parties were built during the interwar years. These parties were much stronger and more dangerous than their predecessors, mobilizing large, cross-class con stituencies around an anti-democratic but mass mobilizing ideology that mixed elements from both the left and right and directly targeted the growing number of Europeans who felt frustrated and alienated by the rapidly changing world around them (Berman 2007; Sternhell 1995a, 1995b). Thus, by the time of the Great Depression, many of Europe’s young democra cies were already in serious trouble, weakened by deep divisions in their soci eties and attacked by extremists on the left and right. The economic suffering and social chaos generated by the Depression simply pushed many of these regimes over the edge. By 1940 the democratic wave of 1918 was but a dim memory across much of the continent and Britain was standing alone against the Nazi dictatorship. Not only had democracy once again failed in Europe, this time failure led to the rise of possibly the most brutal regime and the most destructive war the world had ever known. If there was ever a time and place where demo cracy seemed to be a lost cause, Europe in 1940 was it.
Consolidating and reshaping democracy in (Western) Europe It was only after the most destructive war history that (Western) Europe was finally able to put an end to the long-standing political and national struggles that it had suffered through since 1789.2 In retrospect, we can see that this was because many of the problems that had helped foil democratic consolidation in the past were solved during the postwar period. Some of this, ironically, was a consequence of the war itself. The old order, for example, was discredited by the collapses of the interwar years and the war that followed, and certain groups that had supported anti- democratic regimes and movements in the past were eliminated by the chaos and destruction of the 1940s. As Mark Mazower (2000: 213) has noted, ‘Wartime losses tore gaping holes in the social and physical fabric; they provoked bitter memories and angry emotions, but also new challenges and opportunities’. This was particularly true in Germany, where old social hierarchies were shattered by the Nazis (Dahrendorf 1969; Kogan 1968; Schoenbaum 1967) and the old conser vative and Junker elites were disproportionately killed off in large numbers during the war (and then dispossessed by the Communist regime in the East after it). In addition to eliminating many social obstacles to democratic consolidation, the war also helped deal with another long-standing impediment to consolidation
74 S. Berman in Europe: nationalism. One way it did this was through the ethnic cleansing that happened during the war – between them, Stalin and Hitler uprooted, trans planted, expelled, deported and dispersed some 30 million people in the years between 1939–43 (Wimmer 2002; Naimark 2001). And after the war, ethnic cleansing and population transfer continued, rendering many of the countries of central and Eastern Europe in particular more ethnically homogenous than they had ever been. To quote Mazower once again, ‘War, violence and massive social dislocation had turned Versailles’s dream of national homogeneity into realities’ (2000: 218). Also important, of course, in promoting democratic consolidation in Western Europe after 1945 was the changed international situation and the role of the United States. A relatively long-term occupation helped set the continent’s most problematic country – Germany – firmly on the path to democracy. And with the Soviet Union and the developing Cold War prodding it forward, the United States, the world’s strongest democracy, made a firm commitment to ensuring that Western Europe would be both a political and economic success. However critical these factors were in promoting both democratization and consolidation in Western Europe after 1945, without socioeconomic stability, the whole project would have come crashing down. As we have seen, class, social and communal conflicts had been an ongoing source of political instability and violence throughout modern European history. In addition, the experience of the Great Depression – where the collapse of capitalism had led to social chaos, dis illusionment with democracy and a widespread embrace of extremism – led many to recognize that finding a way to ensure both economic prosperity and social peace was absolutely necessary if democracy were to succeed in Europe after 1945. On top of all this, the condition the continent found itself in after the war heightened fears that socioeconomic instability might quickly return and scuttle democratic experiments. The war itself had been the most destructive in history, flattening the conti nent’s urban and industrial areas and generating postwar inflation, migration and other problems that left Europe’s economies incapacitated in 1945. As the 1947 Report of the Committee of European Economic Cooperation declared, ‘The scale of destruction and disruption of European economic life was far greater than that which Europe had experienced in the First World War. . . . The devast ated countries had to start again almost from the beginning’ (Clough et al. 1968: 328). In addition, the commanding position of the Soviet Union after the war and the heroic role played by many communist resistance movements during it (combined with a sense that capitalism had failed during the 1930s), led many at the time to fear that communism rather than capitalist democracy was the wave of the future. And indeed, communist parties in Western Europe did get off to an auspicious start after the war, receiving much higher shares of the vote almost everywhere than they had before the war and being included in a number of postwar governments as a result. Such conditions, in short, reinforced the belief that ensuring socioeconomic stability and drawing people away from the siren song of (communist) extremism would be absolutely necessary if the democratic
The past and future of social democracy 75 wave of 1945 was not to meet the same fate as its predecessors. So ‘how did Western Europe achieve political and social stability after two great destructive wars and the intervening upheaval’ (Maier 1981)? Or to put it another way, ‘What made capitalism and democracy compatible after 1945 when they had proven incompatible before’ (Offe 1983)? To a large degree, the answer to these questions lies in the way in which the relationship between states, markets and society was restructured after World War II. After 1945, actors across the political spectrum came to recognize that if democracy was finally going to work in Europe, not merely a change in political forms and institutions but also a restructuring of social and economic structures and relationships would be necessary. Such views had long been championed by many parties on the democratic left; what changed after 1945 is that they were embraced by other key groups as well. The 1947 program of the German Christian Democrats, for example, declared that, ‘The new struc ture of the German economy must start from the realization that the period of uncurtailed rule by private capitalism is over’ (Sassoon 1998: 140). In France, meanwhile, the Catholic Mouvement Republican Populaire declared in its first manifesto in 1944 that it supported a ‘revolution’ to create a state ‘liberated from the power of those who possess wealth’ (Sassoon 1998: 140). Even the Americans, least affected by the war and most committed to the restoration of a global free-trade order, recognized that their commitment to stability and democracy in Europe meant that there was no going back to the socioeconomic status-quo ante. Reflecting this, in his opening speech to the Bretton Woods conference, U.S. Treasury Secretary Henry Morgenthau noted, ‘All of us have seen the great economic tragedy of our time. We saw the worldwide depres sion of the 1930s. . . . We saw bewilderment and bitterness become the breeders of fascism and finally of war.’ To prevent a recurrence of this phenomenon, Morgenthau argued, national governments would have to be able to do more to protect people from capitalism’s ‘malign effects’ (Ikenberry 1992; Kapstein 1996). After 1945, accordingly, West European nations began constructing a new order, one that could ensure economic growth while at the same time protecting societies from capitalism’s destructive and destabilizing consequences (Arm strong et al. 1945; Marglin and Schor 1991). This order represented a decisive break with the past: states would not be limited to ensuring that markets could grow and flourish, nor would economic interests be given the widest possible leeway. Instead, the state was to become the guardian of society rather than the economy, and economic imperatives would often have to take a back seat to social ones. This shift to a ‘social democratic’ understanding of the relationship between states, markets, and societies (Berman 2007) was based on a recogni tion that, for democratic consolidation to finally succeed in Western Europe, the social conflict and divisions that had helped scuttle democratic experiments in the past would have to be confronted head-on. After 1945, therefore, democratic governments in Western Europe explicitly committed themselves to pursing pol icies designed to foster social solidarity and stability.
76 S. Berman The two most oft-noted manifestations of this change were Keynesianism and the welfare state. Keynesianism’s significance lay in its rejection of the view that markets operated best when left to themselves and its recognition that substantial state intervention might be necessary in economic affairs. Keynes argued that state action was often necessary to help avoid economic crises that could threaten both democracy and the capitalist system itself. Having experienced the rise of the Soviet Union and the Great Depression, Keynes understood that unchecked markets could be socially and politically dangerous. As his biogra pher Robert Skidelsky has noted, ‘Keynes was quite conscious in seeking an alternative to dictatorship . . . a programme on which to fight back against facism and communism’ (Skidelsky 1989: 35–6). It is important to stress that Keynes favored a more active role for the state not only for economic but also for polit ical reasons: he understood the power of communism’s insistence that capitalism could not be rescued from its flaws and that a large part of fascism’s appeal had stemmed from its critique of liberalism’s ineffectiveness in the face of economic crisis, combined with its own anti-socialist solutions to the Great Depression (Skidelsky 1989: 35–6). Keynes hoped that by designing a ‘system that held out the prospect that the state could reconcile the private ownership of the means of production with democratic mangement of the economy’ (Przeworksi 1985: 207) he could convince people that there was a democratic solution to capitalism’s problems. Like Keynesianism, the welfare state helped transform the relationship among states, markets and societies during the postwar era in ways that helped promote democratic consolidation. As C.A.R. Crosland (1967: 98) noted, after 1945, ‘it was increasingly regarded as a proper function and indeed obligation of Govern ment to ward off distress and strain not only among the poor but almost all classes of society’. West European welfare states were significant not only because they protected individuals from economic distress – they were also crit ical because they gave renewed importance to membership in a national com munity, since they both required and fostered a sense of kinship and solidarity among citizens: welfare states could only be sustained if individuals believed that ensuring a basic level of well-being for all citizens was a worthy goal. Wel fare states thus mark a significant break with a liberal gesellschaft – the anomie, dislocation and atomization that proved so politically destabilizing in Europe – and a move towards a more communitarian gemeinschaft where societies were committed to taking care of their own. This move towards expanding welfare states after the war was thus not merely a reflection of a desire to rectify past mistakes but also a deliberate attempt to undercut the support of extremist ideo logies on the left and right that had played off anomie, dislocation and atomiza tion in the past in order to undermine support for democracy. Of course, Keynesianism and welfare states were not the only ways in which postwar European political economies changed. Each European nation developed its own set of policies that used the power of the state to protect society from capitalism’s most destructive effects and promote social solidarity and stability. In France, for example, the Fourth Republic engaged in significant nationalization
The past and future of social democracy 77 and planning, which were designed, among other things to ensure not merely economic growth but also that ‘the main sources of common wealth [were] worked and managed not for the profit of a few individuals, but for the benefit of all’ (De Gaulle, quoted in Shennan 1989: 251). In Italy, a large state sector was carried over from the fascist period and was viewed as part of a broader strategy for using the state to ensure economic growth as well as general social health and well-being. The idea that democratic governments were responsible for both steering the economy and protecting citizens was enshrined in Italy’s postwar constitution, which which declared the country a democratic republic ‘founded on labor’ and promised that all ‘economic and social obstacles’ to workers’ advancement would be demolished. Recognizing the primacy of certain societal goals and needs, the constitution refrained from according private property the status of ‘absolute right . . . instead emphasiz[ing] its social obligations and lim itations’ (Di Scala 1998: 283; James 2003: 257). In Germany, the picture was more complicated, since largely in reaction to the extreme statism of the Nazis and the more direct influence of the the U.S. there was a clearer commitment to economic liberalism than in most other parts of Europe. But even in postwar Germany, the state intervened in the economy in myriad ways and made a firm commitment to social protection and the promotion of social peace and stability. Alongside an expansion of the welfare state, Germany developed a number of innovative policies, including codetermination, which gave workers the ability to oversee, and in some cases even help direct, business decisions and activity. In the decades after the war this system proved very successful in helping workers and management come to view themselves as ‘social partners’ rather than adversaries, thus breaking a pattern that had contributed to economic, social and political instability in the past. Not surprisingly, such changes went furthest in Sweden, where the welfare state became more generous and more universalistic than in most other European countries and the state’s commitment to growth as well as social solidarity and protection even more explicit (see Patomäki’s chapter). What is also notable about the Swedish case is the explicit emphasis on the complementary rather than contradictory nature of these goals. As Gunnar Adler-Karlsson, a well- known theorist of the postwar Swedish order, noted: All the parties of the economic process have realized that the most import ant economic task is to make the national cake grow bigger and bigger, because then everyone can satisfy his demanding stomach with a greater piece of that common cake. When instead, there is strong fighting between the classes in that society, we believe that the cake will often crumble or be destroyed in the fight, and because of this everyone loses. (Adler-Karlsson, 1967: 18) Across Europe, in short, the postwar order represented something historically unusual: capitalism remained, but it was capitalism of a very different type from that which had existed before the war – one tempered and limited by the power
78 S. Berman of the democratic state and often made subservient to the goals of social stability and solidarity, rather than the other way around. As we know, this social demo cratic order worked remarkably well: despite fears after the war that it would perhaps take decades for Europe to recover economically,3 by the early 1950s most of Europe had easily surpassed interwar economic figures and the thirty years after 1945 were Europe’s fastest period of growth ever. This economic growth, in turn, helped legitimize capitalism and show that it was compatible with both democracy and social stability. The restructured political economies of the postwar era seemed to offer something to everyone and this in turn helped to eliminate the belief – long held by liberals, Marxists and others – that demo cratic states could not or would not protect particular groups’ interests. As a result, both workers and employers (and the organizations and parties that catered to them) underwent a remarkable deradicalization after 1945 and became more willing to work together to achieve what came to be seen to many as common interests. As Claus Offe noted, What was at issue in class conflicts [after 1945] was no longer the mode of production, but the volume of distribution, not control but growth, and this type of conflict was particularly suited for being processed on the political plan through party competition because it does not involve ‘either/or’ ques tions, but questions of a ‘more or less’ or ‘sooner or later’ nature. Overarch ing this limited type of conflict, there was a consensus concerning basic priorities, desirabilities and values of the political economy, namely eco nomic growth and social . . . security. (Offe 1983: 237) In short, by reshaping the relationship between states, markets and society the social democratic postwar order helped underpin the consolidation of democracy in Western Europe after 1945. It helped prove that liberal fears that democracy ‘would lead by necessity to tyranny and expropriation by the poor and unedu cated’ (Offe 1983: 225–6), Marxist assertions that giving the poor and workers the vote would lead inexorably to the end of bourgeois society, and fascism’s and National Socialism’s claim that democracy stood in direct contradiction to national cohesion and social solidarity, were false. The emergence of ‘social’ democracy in postwar Western Europe showed that, under the right conditions, democracy, capitalism and social stability could, in fact, be combined.
Lessons learned Although we tend to take social stability and democracy in Europe today for granted, historically they are anomalous. Up through the second half of the twen tieth century Europe had not been able to sustain stable, well-functioning demo cracies despite a century and a half of attempts. The silver lining to Europe’s final collapse into barbarism during the interwar years is that leaders and publics emerged from the experience with a greater appreciation of the virtues of
The past and future of social democracy 79 democracy and an understanding that social peace and stability were necessary if it was to work. After World War II a fairly broad consensus therefore reigned in Europe that the continent needed to not merely rebuild democratic institutions and procedures, but also revamp the relationship that existed among states, markets and society. Economic and social reform was thus recognized as import ant as political reform in promoting democratic consolidation since it addresed the social and political divisions that had scuttled so many democratic experi ments in the past. In the years after 1945, in other words, a new understanding of democracy developed in Western Europe, one that went beyond what we think of today as ‘electoral’ or even ‘liberal’ democracy (Schumpeter 1954; Diamond 1999, 2009; Collier and Levitsky 1997) to what is best understood as ‘social’ demo cracy. Scholars have long recognized that this new order represented both a decisive break with the past, most often focusing on its (perhaps surprising) repudiation of the radical left’s hopes for an end to capitalism (Maier 1981; Offe 1983). What they have often failed to appreciate, however, is just how much of a repudiation it was of traditional liberalism as well. Core features of the new system, especially its recognition that states would need to do a better job of controlling and reshaping social and economic development in order to ensure social peace and political stability, went against key tenets of classical liberalism’s theory and its long-standing practice. The most common term used to describe the postwar system, Ruggie’s (1982) concept of ‘embedded lib eralism’, is thus a misnomer. If liberalism can be stretched to encompass an order that saw unchecked markets as dangerous, that had public interests trump private prerogatives, and that granted states the right to intervene in the eco nomy to protect the common interest, then the term is so elastic as to be nearly useless. In fact, rather than a modified and updated form of liberalism, what spread like wildfire after the war was really something quite different: ‘social’ democracy (Berman 2007). As we know, this new ‘social democracy’ worked remarkably well: for the first time in modern history, Europe managed to combine rapid economic growth, social stability and democracy. Europeans, for the most part, with a well-developed sense of their own history, recognize what an unprecedented achievement the postwar order was and how difficult, more generally, overcom ing historical divisions and creating social peace actually is. Americans, on the other hand, despite exhibiting some recognition of these problems immediately after World War II, seem to have forgotten those lessons. Indeed, by the time the next democratic wave erupted at the end of the twentieth century, a widespread assumption reigned in the U.S. that democracy, capitalism and social stability went naturally together. Such beliefs seem to be based on an overly simplistic reading of the U.S.’s distinctive past (where class and ethnic conflicts – with the glaring exception of slavery – are not seen as having seriously threatened demo cracy) and a failure to remember some key lessons from the interwar and postwar periods; they have, as we have seen, little to do with either European history or the experience of much of the rest of the world.
80 S. Berman Beyond making us rethink what it took to finally ensure democratic consoli dation in Europe, a reconsideration of Europe’s political development should be of interest to students of democratization and consolidation more generally as the continent’s experience also has broad conceptual, theoretical and practical implications. Conceptually, the European experience makes clear the importance of adding ‘social democracy’ to our list of democracy’s varied forms. For the most part, the existing literature focuses on the contrast between electoral and liberal democracy (see Youngs’ chapter for the problems with this). The former defines democracy by its key procedure – elections. The classic modern state ment of this view belongs to Joseph Schumpeter, who argued that the ‘demo cratic method is that institutional arrangement for arriving at political decisions in which individuals acquire the power to decide by means of a competitive struggle for the people’s vote’ (Schumpeter 1943). The advantages of this concept are that it is narrowly focused on concrete political procedures and refreshingly simple, thereby facilitating comparisions and the charting of polit ical progress across time and space. For advocates of the electoral view, what differentiates political systems is the way leaders are chosen: ‘free and fair’ elec tions (and those civil and political freedoms that make such elections possible) are the essence of democracy. Not surprisingly, many scholars find this definition too restrictive and argue that, by equating free and fair elections with democracy, advocates of the elect oral view ignore the possibility that elections can bring to power undemocratic leaders (e.g., Napoleon, Hitler) or put in place governments that support extremely illiberal if not undemocratic policies (e.g., communal discrimination, anti-labor laws). In addition, critics argue that electoral definitions of democracy are too ‘thin’ because they ignore the necessary connection between liberalism and democracy. Such critics therefore advocate a ‘liberal’ definition of demo cracy and argue that in order to be considered truly democratic a political regime must not only have free and fair elections but also be able and willing to protect the broad range of political and civil liberties and rights that we associate with liberalism (Zakaria 2007). Even a brief reconsideration of European political development makes clear the difference between these two forms of democracy: although there were a significant number of experiments with electoral democracy from 1789 on, very few of these experiments progressed to the point where they could be considered ‘liberal’ democracies as well. Probably partially because of this, these electoral democracies proved very weak, often giving way fairly quickly to dictatorships. But a reconsideration of European history makes clear that electoral and liberal democracy do not exhaust the list of possible democratic forms. As we have seen, what developed in Europe after 1945 went ‘beyond’ both electoral and lib eral democracy: not only did it include free and fair elections and explicit pro tections of individual rights and liberties, it was also committed to ensuring certain social and economic rights and outcomes as well. This new ‘form’ of democracy was based on an explicit recognition that the state must take respons ibility for heading off social divisions and conflict and actively work to promote
The past and future of social democracy 81 the sense of community and legitimacy that are the necessary prerequisites for well-functioning democracy. It was only this ‘social’ form of democracy that was finally able to ensure democratic consolidation in Europe. An analysis of different concepts of democracy segues naturally into a con sideration of their theoretical implications. There is, of course, a huge debate among both scholars and practicioners of what it takes to make democracy ‘work’ – i.e., what it takes to move countries from democratization to consolida tion. Here too the European experience with different forms of democracy seems to offer some intriguing lessons. As we have seen, a key reason why democracy was not able to consolidate in Europe before the second half of the twentieth century has to do with social divi sions and conflicts. This dynamic, of course, is not limited to Europe. Indeed, the need to deal with the political instability generated by the social divisions and conflict that accompany economic development is a problem many scholars have long recognized. Samuel Huntington’s Political Order in Changing Societies remains the classic analysis of this dynamic, and more recent scholarship has also documented a close connection between social divisions/inequality and political instability/democratic failure (Boix 2003; Przeworski 1991; Houle 2009; Kapstein and Converse 2008). We do not, of course, need to look very far to see concrete examples of this dynamic today. In Thailand, for example, political instability has been caused by social ten sions generated by economic development. As one observer notes, ‘instead of political calm, growth . . . has brought increased tension’. The country is ‘beset by political inequality’ and as the gap between rich and poor has widened the ‘fortunes and expectations of [the latter] have risen, [and] so too has their frus tration’. As one supporter of the Red Shirt protests notes, ‘We now know what is going on. . . . We know what we want and don’t want.’ And what they don’t want is a ‘government that only looks after the rich, instead of ordinary people’. Another Red Shirt supporter described Thailand as a ‘nation divided between hard-working but impoverished serfs and an oppressive greedy aristocracy’. In this person’s view, the cause of conflict in Thailand lies in ‘government bureau cracy out of touch with an increasingly well-informed and better-off population that now demands much more than before’ (Higgins 2010). We can see a similar dynamic in what is clearly the most important and inter esting case of political development today – China. The country has recently been beset by increasing labor protests and other expressions of social discon tent. For example, in response to a recent horrific attack on school children, the Chinese premier, Wen Jiabao, stated, ‘We need to pay attention to the root causes of these problems. . . . That includes dealing with social conflicts and dispute resolution at the grassroots level’. It is precisely fear of increased social divisions and conflict that the Chinese regime uses to justify its continued rule. Given China’s history and the rise in social instability that recent economic growth has brought, it is perhaps not surprising that the emphasis on the need to maintain a ‘harmonious society’ above all else resonates with many citizens. As one observer notes: ‘China’s society is entering a high-risk phase. The unfair
82 S. Berman distribution of wealth, official corruption, the failure to safeguard people’s basic needs, the inability to solve all these problems has created an inharmonious environment’ (Hille 2010). Although every country and each era is different, one lesson modern Euro pean history makes clear is that political stability in general and democracy in particular requires dealing forthrightly with the social divisions and con flict generated by economic development. All scholars recognize that guaran teeing free and fair elections is a necessary component of democracy; increasing numbers have come to accept that a state willing and able to ensure civil liberties and human rights is fundamental to democracy too. What the European experience seems to suggest is that, especially in coun tries prone to deep social divisions and conflicts, a state willing and able to deal with the destabilizing consequences of economic development in par ticular and modernity in general may be a prerequisite for a consolidated, well-functioning democracy as well. Social democracy, this chapter has argued, was an attempt to do just this – to come up with a form of democracy explicitly focused on dealing with the social and economic dynamics that had scuttled democratic experiments in the past. It was, of course, only with social democracy that consolidation finally occurred in Europe and there is every reason to believe that this is likely to be true in many other parts of the world as well, since Europe’s political experience is probably much more common than that of the U.S., where (with the glaring exceptions of slavery and the civil war) social tensions and divisions have not presented a major threat to democracy. A recognition of the relevance of social democracy to debates about con solidation has some natural practical or policy implications. As Hobson and Kurki note, the manner in which democracy is understood by different actors – such as democracy promotion agencies, target populations, and scholars – shapes their judgment on the possibility of ‘exporting’ democracy, the demo cracy promotion policies and instruments they prefer, and the manner in which they wish to see policies implemented. Analysts need, in other words, to recognise the political consequences of the way democracy is conceived in democracy promotion (see Introduction). What the European experience seems to show is that a focus on social democracy might make democrat ization not only more likely to succeed but also more attractive to populations across the globe. The Bush government’s fiasco in Iraq had the one positive effect of showing that a shift in political procedures and institutions is merely the beginning rather than the end of a transition to democracy. What Iraq’s collapse into chaos after the removal of Sadaam Hussein made painfully clear was the importance of dealing forthrightly with the broader political, social and economic problems that can scuttle fledgling democratic experiments. Although Iraq might be an extreme example, it is generally the case that many countries that made transitions to democracy during the late twentieth and early twenty-first centu ries were beset by deep social and communal divisions (as well as dysfunctional
The past and future of social democracy 83 economies). As we have seen, in Europe’s case such divisions scuttled demo cratic experiments for over a century and a half. It was only when European governments proved both willing and able to deal with them, that democratic consolidation was finally able to occur. The European experience makes clear that building social democracy is no easy task. It took the Europeans until the second half of the twentieth century until they were willing and able to forthrightly address the social and economic problems that had led their continent to ruin in the past. Although social demo cracy as a political movement is on the defensive in Europe, this does not mean the democratic model most closely associated with it – ‘social’ democracy – is in decline. Europeans have themselves shown time and time again that they are uncomfortable with prescriptions of liberalism, fearful of what it would do to their societies and democracy. Indeed, so embedded is social democracy in Europe that even parties of the center (and even radical) right do not, for the most part, questions the need for social protection and stability. Instead, what they differ on is the extent and nature of and best way to ensure these things. In addition, it would be wrong to see social democracy as a purely European phe nomenon. Social democracy does exist in the ‘global periphery’ (Sandbrook et al. 2007) and it is no coincidence that some of the best functioning democracies in the developing world (e.g., Costa Rica, Mauritius, Brazil) are those that scholars most often recognize as the closest approximations to ‘European’ social democratic models. In short, democracy promoters have lessons to learn from Europe’s experi ence: when thinking about what it will take to make democracy work in many developing countries, it is as important to pay attention to social and economic as it is political reform and the institutionalization of liberalism. Such considera tions are not merely a luxury for the rich. A concern for social protection, equal ity and community should be built into considerations of political and economic development in order to ensure the stability that is a basic prequisite of both. While it is surely the case that promoting social democracy is more complicated and more difficult than fostering electoral or even liberal democracy, it is also more likely to ultimately succeed. In addition to its potential to contribute to democratic consolidation, social democracy also has the advantage of providing a more attractive rallying cry than electoral or liberal democracy in many parts of the developing world. Too many people have experienced meaningless elections or elections that have eventuated in corrupt and even despotic rulers to wish to invest in them alone. In addition, liberalism has unfortunately become associated with ‘Westernization’ or an assault on indigenous traditions in many parts of the non-Western world and reforms associated with a move towards liberal democracy are therefore greeted with suspicion by many. Social democracy, on the other hand, by explicitly addressing social justice, inequality, and need and desirability of social solidarity may appeal to people in many parts of the world where such things are desperately desired. By showing that democracy is not just compatible with, but actually dependent on, the solving of social and economic problems, social
84 S. Berman democracy holds out the promise of not merely making democracy work better but also making people across the globe understand that it is, in fact, the best political game in town.
Notes 1 This may not be entirely true if one considers the Commonwealth produced by the English civil war, Europe’s first major attempt at democracy; nonetheless, the outcome of this democratic experiment was more or less the same as that of the French first republic. 2 This was not of course true of Eastern Europe, which had to suffer through another four-plus decades of colonial rule before achieving its own (hopefully stable) demo cratic outcomes. 3 German residents polled in the American zone after World War II expected that it would take at least twenty years for the country to recover. De Gaulle had similarly informed French citizens that it would take twenty-five years of ‘furious work’ before France would be back on its feet again (Judt 2005: 89).
5 Democracy promotion Neoliberal vs social democratic telos Heikki Patomäki
Introduction What is the aim of democracy promotion? Is there a goal, end or telos of history that can be understood in terms of democracy? I defend a weak version of tele ological reasoning: human history has been directed towards the ethico-political goal of realising democratic self-determination. However, ethico-political pro gress is contingent. Collective learning occurs via political debates and struggles under circumstances in which asymmetric relations of structural power tend to favour a particular outcome. Moreover, history is open-ended; even if a set end point has been achieved, the future must remain open, so there is nothing final about any telos. From this kind of post-Nietzschean teleological position it is easy to acknowledge that democracy is also about contestation over the meaning and substance of democratic self-governance. It follows that the goal of democratization is constituted by different models of democracy, primarily neoliberal and social-democratic. In the neoliberal model, private property rights are primary. Only free markets can provide eco nomic freedom, the key ingredient of democracy; thus commodification emerges as a key goal. For a social-democratic model, the welfare state provides an insti tutional form for further democratization and, eventually, realization of demo cratic socialism. I argue that the social-democratic model is more in line with collective human learning and thus more advanced and progressive than the neoliberal model, but not confinable to a national state. A parallel argument is that also reflexively consistent transnational democracy promotion implies global democracy. There fore, my conclusion is that at this world-historical conjuncture, a plausible telos of democratization is critical-reflexive global social democracy, promoted demo cratically.
Considering the teleology of democracy promotion When it is stated that ‘for the vast majority of the world, democracy is either the practice or the stated goal’ (McFaul 2004–5: 149), it is assumed that some nation-states have already reached the general goal of history, while others are
86 H. Patomäki getting there. Democracy promotion is about facilitating the process of getting there. It is usually not specified whether democracy in this sense is supposed to be the ultimate goal of history or its deep intrinsic purpose, but the underlying assumption appears clearly teleological. The question is: is there really an end point to world history? A strong version of teleology claims that there is an inherent, universal purpose or final cause for human history as a whole and that we can see this purpose, or final cause, already. In philosophy and social theory, the strong version of teleology has faced so much criticism (e.g., Adorno and Horkheimer 1979; Popper 1960; Foucault 1984, 2001; Lyotard 1984) that many scholars were taken by total surprise by the popularity of Francis Fukuyama’s (1989, 1992) neo-Hegelian argument, according to which world history has now come to an end in economic and political liberalism. In order to make the argument that liberal democracy is indeed the ultimate goal, Fukuyama had to fuse norm ative arguments about the best principles for organizing society with a linear account of actual world history. In this chapter, I am not arguing against teleological reasoning per se, although I think the strong version of geo-historical teleology is wrong. It is wrong to the degree in which human history is not pre-determined and things can be otherwise in the future. All social events, actions and processes take place within open systems, in which a diversity of actions, mechanisms, fields and forces interact. Neither intrinsic nor extrinsic conditions of events, actions and processes remain constant. Social-historical systems change qualitatively, including through human learning, and new normative viewpoints and valid reasons can emerge. At multiple levels, the future is open-ended. Yet, not everything is contingent. There is a case for what I call critical-reflexive tele ology, which provides a vantage-point for understanding and justifying the process of democratization. There are good – and empirically confirmed – reasons to think that certain kinds of structures emerge in a logical order that constitute what can be called ‘stages’ (seen as iconic models of generic structures, idealized and abstracted from complex and in some ways also vague and ambiguous reality). Stages are inner generative of cognitive processing embodied in the habitus of individuals. Each stage is able to answer questions or problems unsolved at the previous stage. A partial analogy can be made between individual and collective learning, although there are also decisive ontological and normative differences between the two. As far as the valid part of the analogy is concerned, in both cases the sequence of cognitive stages is conceptual-logical rather than just empirically correct. This explains why an individual can reach higher stages in a sufficiently enabling context spontaneously and why the order of learning must be roughly the same in both cases. The generative structures of reasoning can come to be embedded in social practices and institutions, although this is always contingent on many things, including political struggles. Collective learning concerns both (i) natural laws, mechanisms and processes and (ii) social relations and human history.1
Neoliberal vs social democratic telos 87 Collective human learning explains the quest for democratization. Rules are not anymore taken as something external to individual actors and thus sacred or conventional in the authoritative sense, but rather come to be felt as the free product of mutual agreement and an autonomous conscience. In other words, actors come to understand that collective rules are the product of their autonomy and free, mutual agreement (Piaget 1977: 24–5; Kohlberg 1971: 164–5). Given this learning process, human history can be argued to be directed towards the ethico-political goal of realizing democratic self-determination, even if only in terms of logically ordered potentials. Thus understood, democracy is not the only purpose or the ultimate end point of history, but it provides a normatively compelling long-term direction to world history. Collective learning occurs via political debates and struggles that can take the form of: consensus or compromise agreements; dialogues and debates; majority-decisions; manipulation of the background context; outright force; or a combination of these. Typically asymmetric relations of structural power sys tematically favor a particular outcome. Moreover, history is open-ended: even if an end point should have been achieved, the future must remain open. In this critical-reflexive sense, there is nothing final about any particular historical telos such as democracy. Within this framework (see also Patomäki forthcoming), I argue that when collective rules are understood as the free product of mutual agreement and an autonomous conscience, the precise telos of democratization must also be the free product of mutual agreement. Democracy is thus also about contestation and co-operative argumentation over the meaning and substance of democratic self- governance. It follows that the precise telos of democratization can be consti tuted in different ways, in terms of different models of democracy, whether actual or just potential. Moreover, consistent democracy promotion must itself comply with the principle of free, mutual agreement. From this point of view, I focus on, and compare critically, two existing models of democracy, namely the neoliberal and social-democratic models.2 I argue that when applied to the practices of democracy promotion, the generic lessons of collective learning can yield conclusions that go against the conven tional wisdom of the Western powers-that-be. Instead of history ending in neoliberalized nation-states, it points towards global social democracy, which itself is also unlikely to be more than a temporary end point.
The neoliberal model Standard liberal modernization theory has taken Britain and the US as the end point of linear progress in history (Rostow 1960). The most important practical problem of development, political and military ‘aid’ has been to get others there too. Since the 1980s, this starting point has often been replicated in accounts of democratization and democracy promotion. A cautious advocate of the neolib eral model may of course qualify the basic idea in various ways:
88 H. Patomäki U.S. practice of democracy is itself flawed, tainted by antiquated practices such as the use of the electoral college, serious charges of disenfranch isement during the 2000 presidential election, and seemingly illiberal pol icies including the continued use of the death penalty. For many around the world, several democracies have become strong alternative and more attrac tive models to the U.S. practice of democracy. (McFaul 2004–05: 152) Also in this case, however, the ‘more attractive model’ is provided by an already-existing ‘democracy’, usually a North-Western European one. European states too have been neoliberalized and are struggling with the implications of Europeanization for democracy. These kinds of qualifications thus amount to rel atively small differences within the same basic model. Similarly, Richard Youngs (2005) aims at illuminating the diversities and complexities of promot ing Western-style democracy. Youngs’ account of the variety of opinions and positions among his interviewees is indeed useful to many students of democrat ization. Yet, Youngs’ image of democracy essentially replicates the established democracies. It takes for granted a narrow conception of democracy that is limited mostly to regular multiparty elections and confined within the borders of nation-states (Patomäki 2006; Eds: for Youngs’ view on debates on democracy see his chapter in this volume). What is neoliberalism? The term neoliberalism first appeared in Germany in the interwar era 1919–1933, when a number of intellectuals and politicians wanted to qualify classical economic liberalism in order to make it more viable. In the 1960s, some pro-market Latin American intellectuals found these writings and started to talk about neoliberalismo, in admiration of the post-war ‘German economic miracle’. The early neoliberals coined the term social market eco nomy. For these people, neoliberalism was a qualified form of economic lib eralism that should assume primacy after the failure and marginalization of the classical economic liberalism after 1914 and especially from the early 1930s. (See Boas and Garse-Morse 2009, especially 145–50). Milton Friedman and Friedrich Hayek were more conservative, however, and advocated a return to what they considered pure classical economic liberalism. ‘We neither can wish nor possess the power to go back to the reality of the nine teenth century, [however], we have the opportunity to realize its ideals . . .’ (Hayek 1944: 240; cf. Friedman 1955). It is in this sense that the term is now adays used. Neoliberalism is a program of resolving the problems of, and developing, human society by means of competitive private markets. Competit ive markets are assumed to be efficient and just and maximize freedom of choice. Competitive markets can be private and actual, or they can be simulated within organizations, whether private or public. Neoliberalism is comprised of in some ways contradictory theories, all of which can be developed in different dir ections; and yet all posit competitive markets as superior in terms of efficiency, justice or freedom, or a combination of them. Neoliberal theories also constitute a framework for identifying things and processes and seeing them as noteworthy
Neoliberal vs social democratic telos 89 problems (e.g., inflation and state ‘competitiveness’ as the most important politico-economic problems). In neoliberalism, as in classical economic liberalism, private property rights are fundamental and primary. They define the essence of freedom and the rule of law. Any deviation from the rule of law would violate natural law or sacred social conventions. Government should do nothing without the consent of property-owners/citizens.3 The basic thrust of this idea can be seen as demo cratic, but many forms of liberalism have been, and remain, ambivalent about the ultimate value of democracy. Characteristically for the elitist model of democracy, Joseph Schumpeter rein terpreted the idea of representative government in terms of replacing the ruling group or party with another section of the elite. Schumpeter went so far as to maintain that elites in effect create the will of the people: ‘[. . .] the will of the people is the product and not the motive power of the political process.’ (Schum peter 2008: 263) The meaning and significance of democracy is first and fore most in the guarantee that the national ruling elite can be replaced via elections, i.e., that there is electoral competition within states. However, stability of the capitalist socio-economic order is the main goal. In the Lockean-Schumpeterian tradition, stability is preferred over uninformed and potentially dangerous parti cipation of people or ‘mobs’. Followers of Schumpeter have argued that it is good if people belonging to lower socio-economic groups are detached from politics (Almond and Verba 1963). Related criticism of democracy includes the ideas that social choice, as aggregated from individual preferences, is problematic; bureaucracies and politi cians maximize their own interests and tend to make politics a negative-sum game, which is detrimental to general welfare; and many democratic demands have exceeded the capacity of states (for criticism, see Mackie 2003). However, especially since the explicitly ideological days of Margaret Thatcher and Ronald Reagan, things have become more complex. Neolib eralization has often been realized in incremental and technical terms. Actors involved in implementing the day-to-day program of neoliberalization, espe cially in the OECD countries but also elsewhere, have usually taken for granted the background of liberal democratic institutions and related human rights. Often they fail to see the big picture that emerges from their own actions; and they tend to assume that neoliberal theories, or memorandum and newspaper versions of them, are compatible with fostering values not reducible to neoliberalism. This is the background context of the mainstream attempts to promote demo cratization, whether in its US or Western European variation. For constitutive reasons, then, the third wave of democratization has resonated dialectically with the penetration of the neoliberal ‘new world order’ into every part of the world. The claim to global legitimacy is based on the representation of the idea of liberal-democracy and basic human rights (including property rights) as univer sally valid. One aspect of this resonance is the explicit democracy promotion by the US, the EU and a number of international organizations such as the OECD and various parts of the UN system. Mostly these Western or West-led actors
90 H. Patomäki have been promoting ‘polyarchy’ (Robinson 1996), or ‘low-intensity demo cracy’, or what Held (1996: 157–98) calls ‘competitive elitist democracy’ (for an alternative account, see Youngs in this volume). For instance, many spontaneous democratic civic movements have found exter nal (Western) support, which has often been translated, once the democratic move ment has entered government, into a full-scale program of neoliberal restructuration. However, the program of transforming state and society into private markets, in the context of rapid internationalization of many aspects of state governance (Gill 2008 talks about ‘neoconstitutional locking-in of economic lib eralism’), tends to reduce the sphere of politics and democratic self-determination. Thus the processes of neoliberalization and liberal-democratization have been accompanied by a multi-faceted process of depoliticization (e.g., Teivainen 2002). The fact that at one point the IMF directly controlled the economic policy of every third sovereign state is another case in point. IMF governance has always been represented as technical, not political (Swedberg 1986). When democracy promo tion means neoliberalization, participation through civil society is seen as espe cially worthy of support if it is based on the principle of private charity, thus reinforcing the primacy of private property; or if it promotes, directly or indirectly, economic freedoms (for an empirical example, see the chapter from Crawford and Abdulai).
Problems with the neoliberal model How would it be possible to justify the idea that private property rights come before anything else; or are fundamental to any society; or are somehow beyond demo cratic politics, for one reason or another? Alfred Marshall, in his classic Principles of Economics, discussed characteristic justifications of the private ownership of the means of production. Before the time of French and Industrial Revolutions, authors defending private property rights tended to appeal to God or Nature (Marshall 1959: 625). In the nineteenth century, the appeal was made instead to Science. Marshall argued that the ‘authority of the science has been wrongly assumed by some of who have pushed the claims of vested rights to extreme and antisocial uses’ (Marshall 1959: 40). Marshall’s own approach was open-minded but (warily) pro-capitalist: [. . .] in the past [the rights of private property] have been inseparable from solid progress; and that therefore it is the part of responsible men to proceed cautiously and tentatively in abrogating or modifying even such rights as may seem inappropriate to the ideal conditions of social life. (Marshall 1959: 40) The rhetorical strategies identified by Marshall have also prevailed in the twenti eth century. Neoliberals such as Friedrich Hayek, Milton Friedman and Robert Nozick came close to assuming that rights of private property – as applied to means of production – are not merely customary but can be justified as given by nature or something equally metaphysical.
Neoliberal vs social democratic telos 91 In the absence of space for a comprehensive discussion of all relevant thinkers, I focus, briefly, on Nozick’s argument. Nozick (1974: 6) starts by asserting that the only complete and full explanation of the realm of politics is to explain it in terms of the non-political (he does not explain why an explanation would have to be reductionist in this sense). He further argues that the explanation and thereby normative justification of the state can be based on a logic that has nothing to do with real historical processes. What matters for Nozick are universal moral con straints and permissible and impermissible actions that would be valid also in a ‘state of nature’ (Nozick 1974: ch. 2). Nozick maintains that certain principles must rise from generalized reciprocity, especially rights of private property. These rights are fundamental; any deviation from them would be ‘redistributive’. Only ‘returning stolen money or compensating for violations of rights’ (Nozick 1974: 27) are not redistributive but fundamental or ‘natural’. Nozick asserts strongly that we must respect the separate existence of each person: [. . .] there is no moral outweighing of one of our lives by others so as to lead to a greater overall social good. There is no justified sacrifice of some of us for others. (Nozick 1974: 33) To reach this conclusion, Nozick appeals to (the state of ) non-political nature and uses loaded ways of posing the question, amounting to merely declaring that private property rights are universally and categorically valid independently of any real historical social processes. Departing from Nozick’s natural rights liberalism, neoclassical economics appeals to Science. A good example is Kenneth Arrow and Frank H. Hahn’s General Competitive Analysis (1971). This tries to show, with mathematical cer tainty and precision, that the basic conclusion of Walras and other neo-classicists is valid: (i) competitive markets can yield an efficient Pareto-optimal equilib rium, and (ii) prices of factors can equal marginal productivity. This is more a theory of justice than of economic efficiency in any meaningful, realistic or empirical sense. As a theory of justice, it is an attempt to show in a mathematical-technical way that private property rights lead inevitably, through competitive markets, to an outcome that is the best possible world for all participants concerned. It is interesting to note how Arrow and Hahn justify their analysis. ‘At the moment the main justification [. . .] is that there are results to report on the tâtonnement [tentative proceedings] while there are no results to report on what most eco nomists would agree to be more realistic constructions’ (Arrow and Hahn 1971: 322). In line with Nozick, their argument is built on a fictional account of a possible world, not on facts about complex reality. By a ‘result’ they mean a mathematical possibility that a market system can solve a system of equilibrium prices. From the point of view of the democratic principle that societal rules and principles are the free product of mutual agreement and the autonomous con science of actors, the neoliberal project is contradictory and self-defeating. The
92 H. Patomäki natural rights and general equilibrium approaches are clearly critical-reflexive attempts to define morality and ethico-political principles which have validity and application apart from the authority of the groups or persons holding these principles, and apart from the individual’s own identification with these groups. At the same time, however, the point is to prove that the existing liberal capi talist and – possibly – democratic institutions are non-political and beyond dis cussion. To prove that the rights of private property are ‘natural’, the authors must presuppose what they are trying to prove or appeal to pre-moral reciprocity which is a matter of ‘you scratch my back and I’ll scratch yours’, not of gen eralized loyalty or gratitude or principles of justice. Alternatively, as in general equilibrium models, the authors must prove, in a manner that is beyond any doubt – that is, with the authority of mathematical Science – that free markets can be harmonious and just – even at the expense of conflating a fantasy world with the really existing, complex historical world. While all complex societies tend, for good reasons, to associate personal belongings to one’s personhood, the question is: how should we organize the mechanisms of control and regulation over the means of production? Any attempt to articulate public normative arguments in naturalist or pre-moral terms can only result in paradoxes and contradictions (e.g., Fried 2005). Attempts to anchor private property rights in Nature, Science or the Sacred also imply potential for anti-democratic and authoritarian practices, Chile 1973 being a case in point. Hence, it seems to me that the neoliberal model of demo cracy involves regressive moral learning and is ambivalent about the import ance of democracy.
The social democratic model: a Rawlsian perspective It is useful to compare natural rights liberalism and standard neoclassical eco nomics to the political liberalism of John Rawls’ Theory of Justice. Rawls (1973: 522–5) argues – in a historically more plausible way than fiction-based ‘state-ofnature’ arguments – that human powers require socialization, communication and learning in terms of conceptual and other resources developed by past gen erations; and that production in complex societies can only be based on social cooperation. This ontological-historical starting point also means that all humans are equal in their potential powers, generic moral personality and abstract sense of justice. For Rawls, the first principle of justice is that each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive scheme of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar scheme of liberties for others. Rawls specifically underlines that ‘the right to own certain kinds of property (e.g., means of production) and freedom of contract as understood by the doctrine of laissez-faire are not basic’.4 The second principle of justice consists of two parts, specifying the way inequalities are to be arranged: a) they are to be of the greatest benefit to the least advantaged members of society (the difference principle); b) offices and positions must be open to everyone under conditions of fair equality of opportunity.
Neoliberal vs social democratic telos 93 The choice of the shared institutions of political economy can never be only a matter of instrumental rationality. The choice of institutions also ‘determines in part the sort of persons they want to be as well as the sort of persons they are’ (Rawls 1973: 259). Institutions are to foster the virtue of justice and discourage desires and aspirations incompatible with it. Justice always has priority over claims to efficiency. As a corollary, liberty (in the sense of free development of all) has priority even over objective social and economic advantages. For a con science at this level of ethico-political learning, authoritarian institutions can never be justified. In chapter 4, §36, Rawls develops a political sociology of democracy accord ing to which social and economic inequalities tend to accumulate. Therefore ‘. . . inequities in the economic and social system may soon undermine whatever political equality might have existed under fortunate historical conditions’ (Rawls 1973: 226). Political justice has two aspects: 1 2
It includes a just procedure satisfying the requirements of equal liberty of all. It is to be framed so that of all arrangements which are feasible, it is more likely than any other to result in a just and effective system of legislation.
Satisfying these conditions is not easy. It is misleading to read Rawls only as a mere supporter of a given list of tax-and-transfer policies or welfare state institu tions. To the contrary, according to Rawls, the best institutional arrangement in a society cannot be determined a priori. In general, Rawls argues in favor of market-based political economy. Markets can ensure procedural justice (in terms of scalar distribution); are by and large consistent with equal liberties and fair equality of opportunity; and decentralize the exercise of economic power. However, ‘there is no essential tie between the use of free markets and private ownership of the instruments of production’ (ch. 5, §42). This raises the question whether private ownership of the means of pro duction is compatible with the general principles of justice? ‘To see the full force of the difference principle, it should be taken in the context of property-owning democracy or a liberal socialist regime’ (Rawls 2001: 420). Rawls argues that ‘in a society allowing private ownership of the means of production, property and wealth must be kept widely distributed and government monies provided on a regular basis to encourage free public discussion’ (Rawls 2001: 225). Among other things, this means that there must be no private funding of political parties. Rawls (2001: 226) proposes steady dispersal of the ownership of capital and resources by the laws of inheritance and bequest; fair equality of opportunity is secured by provisions for education; and training insti tutions that support the fair value of the political liberties. In socialism, means of production and natural resources would be publicly owned. A price system can still be used, especially for the purpose of allocating resources but less for distribution. There can be different combinations of state ownership and plan ning and workers’ control of market enterprises. Both can be mixed in various ways with elements of a privately owned market system.
94 H. Patomäki Rawls developed his theory of justice in the Bretton Woods era (1944–71). Neoliberalization made his theory much less self-evident or consensual. ‘I con tinue to think the difference principle important and would still make a case for it . . . but it is better to recognise that this case is less evident. . . .’ (Rawls 2001: 418–19). At the same time, Rawls seems to have concluded that the welfare state compromise was not sustainable; something more would be needed to sustain a just and democratic society. In a 1987 preface to the French edition, Rawls argued that ‘[welfare state efforts are] either insufficient or else ineffective given the dis parities of wealth and the political influence they permit’ (Rawls 2001: 419).
The social democratic model from a historical-institutional perspective Eduard Bernstein (1907) stated at the outset of the twentieth century that ‘social ism is a movement towards an order of society based on the [co-operative and democratic] principle of association’. It was in this spirit that the institutions of democratic welfare states were built during the Bretton Woods era and until the rise of neoliberalism in the 1970s and 1980s (see Berman’s chapter). Under standably, real world ethico-political struggles and historical contingencies resulted in various compromises. From a historical-institutional perspective, thus, there is no pure social democratic model. The following brief account of the underpinnings of social democratic emancipatory project comes closest to the Swedish model. The universalistic social democratic welfare state is distinguished by the fol lowing features (modified from Meyer 2007: 137–8): 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8
Legal entitlements to social services apply equally to all citizens (universal social citizenship). Wage-replacement benefits can be nearly high enough to approach the claimant’s previous income level. The social welfare state is overwhelmingly financed from general revenues and services are free or nearly free. Apart from the health and education sectors, the system offers many other social services, for example in care of the elderly and morning-until-evening daycare. An active family policy aims to allow women to enter the labor market on equal terms with men by providing complete daycare for their children and other supplementary services. Job protection policies are generally supported by active labor market and adult education policies. Centralized collective bargaining follows the principle of solidaristic wage policy across sectors, thus creating an impetus for labor productivity and technological dynamism. The state obliges itself to pursue a macroeconomic policy of full employment.
Neoliberal vs social democratic telos 95 The contrast with the neoliberal model of democracy is sharp. For neoliberals, the free market system can best provide freedom, justice and efficiency. Thus, commodification and the intensification of dependence on markets emerge as key political goals at all levels of society, also in areas such as education and health. In the social democratic model, the aim is largely the opposite, namely reduction of market-dependence and de-commodification in order to overcome the alienation and atomism generated by competitive markets (see Esping- Andersen 1990: 21–8, 35–54; Ryner 2002: 48–59, 85). This is connected to developmentalist ideas about democracy. The welfare state is not an aim in itself but is rather meant to provide an institutional form for further democratization. As part of the idea that the choice of institutions ‘deter mines in part the sort of persons they want to be as well as the sort of persons they and their children will become’, every citizen is granted free and equally good universal public education. Goals of education include well-informed public opinion and widespread civic virtues. The purpose is also to counter established relations of class and power. In a society allowing private ownership of the means of production, accumulated property and wealth tend to be concentrated in a relatively few hands and can be easily translated into cultural classifications and political influence. However, the social democratic idea is that, through mass mobilization, labor can counter the economic power of private owners of means of production with political power in liberal democracy. In the social democratic model, further democratization has often been taken to mean gradual movement towards democratic socialism. Thus various wage- earner fund proposals were advanced in Europe during the 1970s and 1980s aimed at receiving income from taxation (of profits) and using it to accumulate capital on behalf of wage-earners. The more far-reaching proposals for wage- earner funds were attempts to socialize capital in order to give workers a share in capital formation and a say in corporate decision-making. Wage-earner funds were realized only in Sweden, and even there in a form that fell short of the original ambition behind them.
Problems with the social democratic model The neoliberal model includes ideological elements, disguising mere faith in par ticular non-grounded beliefs such as Science or Nature (cf. Klapwijk 2008), whereas the starting point of the theorists of social democracy has been the full recognition of the moral capacity of all actors to make judgments about any issue at stake. Therefore, the social democratic model operates at a higher stage of collective learning, and is ethico-politically more justified than the neoliberal model.5 There are philosophical reasons for this account – i.e., without the recog nition of the possibility of collective learning all kinds of performative contra dictions arise – but first and foremost it consists of hypotheses that can be falsified by means of empirical and historical studies. So far it has stood most tests well.
96 H. Patomäki From a normative point of view, a key consideration is the degree of gen eralizability and the related capacity for abstract role-taking. These indicate plausibility and stability of judgements in differentiated and complex multi-actor contexts. Moreover, higher stage reasoning is simultaneously both more differ entiated (involving a nuanced understanding of psycho-social realities) and more integrated (implying symmetry and consistence of judgements) than prior stages. Empirically, it has been established that higher stages are not only cognitively more difficult but also perceived by subjects as more adequate. This is in part because, as social contexts change also due to collective learning, earlier stages may seem increasingly obsolete and inadequate (Kohlberg 1973). However, also the social democratic model is contradictory. Its main normative contradiction reflects the more general universalism/particularism contradiction of the French Revolution. The emergent abstract determinations whereby people could know themselves as one with their fellow citizens as (a) free and equal sub jects of civil law (the citizen as private commodity owner), (b) morally free sub jects (the citizen as private person), and (c) politically free subjects (the citizen as democratic citizen of the state), are best suited to the identity of world citizens, not to that of the citizen of a particular state. The modern human became homme and citoyen in one (Habermas 1979: 114–15). The same applies to universalist social democracy. Although in some cases the cosmopolitan promise has been explicit,6 in practice social democracy has been about welfare states. Of the social democratic regimes of the Bretton Woods era, the Swedish model was probably the most radical and universalist. It was economically successful and sustained highly egalitarian economic policies for more than forty years, and trans lated those aspirations into a progressivist foreign policy of active neutrality of the Third Way (see Ryner 2002). A critical problem of the social democratic model is that, as liberal capitalist systems of production, exchange and finance expand worldwide, attempts to realize social democracy – not to speak of democratic market socialism – within the confines of a sovereign state eventually become unsustainable. Moreover, the trade-union based Keynesian social democratic model has also created its own bureaucratic and technocratic relations of domina tion, leading, over time, to various critical ethico-political responses. The problems of the Swedish model stemmed from insurrections against local relations of domination at the workplace; transformation of occupational struc tures and class relations; the crisis of the Bretton Woods system for regulating the global economy; and the liberalization of the exit options of capital, among other processes (for a more detailed account, see Patomäki 2000; 2002: ch. 8). Together with the end of the Cold War, this interplay reinforced neoliberal- oriented discourses, which then replaced the earlier, rather Marxist, concepts of the theorists of the Social Democratic Party. This shift led to various articula tions of the requirements of ‘new times’ and gradual changes in the meaning of the Third Way, constituting a new neoliberal framing of social problems. The standard critical political economy explanation is that since the 1970s, policy-makers of all OECD countries have been liable to adopt monetarist and orthodox positions as a particular, biased response to perceived problems such as
Neoliberal vs social democratic telos 97 stagflation that have emerged since the late 1960s. This particular and mostly false response is best explained in terms of a change in power relations in favor of transnational capital. According to this account, there were also objective structural and evolutionary reasons for this shift, for it originated, in large part, in changes in the relations of production, which can be summarized as a shift from the Fordist towards a post-Fordist regime of accumulation of capital. However, the standard critical political economy hypothesis is problematical. Some authors rightly question the coherence of any distinct ‘post-Fordist’ regime of accumulation. What is called ‘post-Fordism’ is actually the result of a mixture of processes that include the deepening of consumerism and product differentia tion (themselves important aspects of the on-going process of economic concen tration); the emergence of new communication and information technologies and thus new technological possibilities for organizing production across time and space; transformation of relations of power within the workplace in favor of the owners and professional managers; and the application of new (neoliberal) man agement ideas of first in private and then in public organizations. Thus what is called ‘post-Fordism’ is actually more a result of the rise of neoliberalization than the other way around. If my argument is right, the origins of neoliberalization lie in the discrepancy between territorial states and spaces of world economy, and in the struggles over income distribution and power in which some actors started to exploit this dis crepancy.7 By the early 1960s, the re-integration of the world economy had opened opportunities for many private market actors to resolve their day-to-day problems by spatial relocation. Explicit political choices were also involved in the ensuing transformations. The key choice was made by President Richard Nixon in 1971, when he ended the link between dollar and gold. The choice was between unilateralism and multilateralism, but the former was justified also in terms of belief in ‘free markets’. Ethico-political ideas associated with neo liberalism entered the public sphere more forcefully only after 1971–3. Throughout the Bretton Woods era, territorial states remained the main locus of regulation and the sole locus for tax-and-transfer policies. At the same time, the rules and principles of the Bretton Woods system and the GATT-agreement were meant to ensure liberalization and re-integration of the world economy. Once the movement towards democratic socialism had come to a halt and once the only remaining aim was to manage and civilize capitalism, the inherent tendencies of private market-related orthodox ideas took over. The structural power of trans national capital and neoliberal globalization gained rapid ascendancy and the pro cess of neoliberalization started to follow its own dynamic. This process has also generated the dominance of the neoliberal model in democracy promotion.
Conclusion: a call for a global democratic framework Critical-reflexive consciousness understands that democratic principles and systems are the product of an autonomous conscience and human agency, and should thus be subject to free mutual agreement. When collective rules are
98 H. Patomäki understood as the free product of mutual agreement and an autonomous con science, the precise telos of democratization – and other related normatively ori ented processes – must also be the free product of mutual agreement. Because transnational democracy promotion must be grounded on this universalizing conviction and as it must be applied reflexively to one’s own practices, it calls for a global framework of democratic institutions within which different under standings and models of normative principles can freely compete and engage in dialogue with each other. In a parallel way, the lessons from the fate of the state-based social demo cratic model call for reversing the order of priorities. The nation-state can no longer provide a sufficient framework for progressivist political action. The socially flavored foreign policy idealism appears as a somewhat anachronistic basis for ‘progressivist internationalism’. Local and national struggles are essen tially connected to regional and global struggles and cannot be taken as separate spheres anymore (‘first progressivism at home, and then exportation of these universalist ideals to the rest of the world’). What is required is a globalist strat egy of carrying out global social/democratic reforms. Future reforms along these lines can come about as a result of effects of multiple simultaneous processes and contradictions among various on-going tendencies.8 So what is the telos of democratization? We have come to understand that morality and ethico-political principles must have validity and application apart from the authority of any particular groups or persons or individual identification with any particular groups or institutions – including nations and states. With human learning advancing towards discourse ethics and beyond, there is a further call for a more differentiated dynamic between intra-humanity self and others. Various critical and post-structuralist theories can be seen as correctives not only to Rawlsian but also to discourse-ethical moral reasoning. At the stage of discourse ethics and beyond, people identify themselves critical-reflexively as world citizens (which is already a latent possibility at earlier levels). Thereafter, the telos of democratization becomes global and culturally pluralistic social democracy, promoted democratically by world citizens. Global social democracy too would be no more than a transient phase. Moreover, its actualization is contingent. Ethico-political progress is a struc tural possibility built upon earlier layers of material-structural possibilities and learning. Yet, there is nothing inevitable about human progress. Its potentials may not be actualized either in the short or long run – or ever. Analogically to the decline of past empires and civilizations, contemporary individuals and institutions may fail to realize the available human potential and fall back, even in terms of their learning potential. To fully understand the implications of our fallibility is part of the process of learning to assume responsibility for the rules, principles and institutions we humans create and for the con sequences of our actions. The limits and illusions of our present understanding can best be seen from a future standpoint of an ever wider and more perceptive horizon.
Neoliberal vs social democratic telos 99
Notes 1 The ideas and claims of this paragraph are based on the well-known works of Jean Piaget (2002, 1977), Lawrence Kohlberg (1981, 1973, 1971) and Jürgen Habermas (1990a, 1990b, 1979). For discussions of the empirical validity of the Kohlbergian framework in particular, see Boom et al. (2007); Dawson (2002); Gibbs et al. (2007); Krebs and Denton (2006); and Sonnert (1994); Patomäki (forthcoming). 2 In terms of Held’s (1996) historical models of democracy – which are useful for ana lytical purposes but do not directly correspond to any existing historical formation or tendency – the contemporary neoliberal model is close to liberal and elitist models, but may include elements of the pluralist model. Also the social democratic model involves many liberal values and principles, but is, in addition, also republican and socialist, and often incorporates deliberative and cosmopolitan considerations as well. It should be noted that the argument of my chapter as a whole is cosmopolitan (for a discussion about different conceptions of cosmopolitanism and global democracy, see Held and Patomäki 2006). 3 This vacillating and inconsistent use of the criterion for full membership in political community is part of the Lockean heritage. See MacPherson (1964: 248). Eds: see the chapter by Jahn for a detailed discussion. 4 This quotation is from p. 54 of the 1999 revised edition. In the 1972 original edition, there was apparently no need to underline that absolute and exclusive right to property and contract is not basic. 5 I am of course presupposing the account of ethico-political learning scheme explained in the beginning of the chapter. 6 Olof Palme, for example, expressed the idea that in the long run the difference between national and world politics would disappear. In this sense, Palme also advocated ‘inter national democracy’ (see Jerneck 1990: 128–9). 7 In open systems, there have been several mechanisms and processes at play. For instance, for a detailed discussion of the consequences of the Triffin dilemma, see Patomäki (2008: 133, 136, 187–8); and for the role of the US and British governments in facilitating the re-emergence of global finance, Patomäki (2008: ch. 6). 8 Patomäki and Teivainen (2004) is a systematic analysis of the normative justifiability and political viability of different global democracy proposals, synthesising the most viable ones into a strategy. Patomäki (2008) and Patomäki (2010) are attempts to build scenarios about the next forty to fifty years from a more general perspective, focusing on the dialectics between limited-scale future wars and economic crises, and the pos sible rise of a transformative movement that could respond to the problems and contra dictions of the global political economy in terms of collective learning and by building new global institutions.
6 Misunderstanding the maladies of liberal democracy promotion Richard Youngs
Democracy promotion has lost traction around the world. This atrophy has myriad causes and a range of consequences. One of its several results is that calls have become more audible for a fundamental rethink of what type of ‘democracy’ should be supported in different regions. Much opinion now choruses the view that the ‘democracy’ in ‘democracy promotion’ requires re- examination. Most critics of international policies berate Western governments for an inflexible and inappropriate adherence to a specific form of ‘liberal demo cracy’. They are right to take democracy promoters to task for many unduly narrow ways in which they conceive political reform. But it is not convincing to argue that democracy-promotion’s most serious problem today is its excessive adherence to a ‘liberal’ form of democracy. This critique fails to grasp the way in which democracy support policies have evolved and confuses what is entailed in meeting local demands for reform in non-democratic states. The routine admonishments cast at Western governments under the now- standard critique of liberal democracy do not weather the scrutiny of empirical evidence. They risk becoming widely accepted myths that have little grounding in reality. Democracy promoters do not overwhelmingly prioritise the procedural over the social and substantive elements of reform; they do not seek deliberately to hollow out the state; they do not conflate economic with political liberalisation; they are not brow beaten into backing facade democracy by multinational com panies; they are not fixated on elections; and they are not completely unreceptive to alternative forms of representation. The problem with democracy promotion lies not in its unbending and overly zealous imposition of liberal norms. Rather, its most serious pathology is governments’ failure to defend core liberal norms in a way that would allow local variations in and choices over democratic reform – along with genuine civic empowerment and emancipation – to flourish. Current criticisms of the democracy agenda risk pushing policy deliberations in exactly the opposite direction of their required improvement.
The roots of misunderstanding Doubts are growing over liberal democracy. The constituent parts of the preoccupying panorama are now well known. The number of democracies worldwide
Misunderstanding the maladies 101 has ceased to augment. Non-democratic, emerging powers appear to be on the front foot. Many commentators now assert that the appeal of democracy as a universal value lies in tattered shreds. Of more particular significance, the ‘liberal’ in liberal democracy attracts increasingly critical attention. As democracy finds itself on the defensive, the notion gains currency that these travails owe much to its unduly narrow conceptualisation – especially on the part of Western powers and international institutions. The liberal form of democracy is widely seen as restrictive, unhelpfully value-laden and out of tune with citizens’ demands in different regions of the world. Its Western sponsorship is increasingly seen as insular and solipsistic. The crisis that besets the democracy support agenda today extends as far as many suggesting that the whole concept of ‘democracy’ in democracy promo tion needs to be recast. The financial crisis has compounded the sense that a gen eral crisis now afflicts liberalism, in both its economic and political guises. The liberal strand of democratic theory has increasingly taken a conceptual beating, and from the stature of expert that demands serious attention. A vast array of writings now takes the core liberal agenda to task, and largely consigns it to the dustbin of history (see Gray 2008; Kagan 2008; Saul 2005; Hurrell 2007). The whole notion that weakly democratic states stand at a stage of immaturity on their way to something more ‘advanced’ is increasingly questioned. Many analysts’ prognosis is of a rise of ‘state-capitalism’ and ‘authoritarian- capitalism’ as viable and, indeed welcome alternatives to liberal democracy (Bremmer 2009; Gat 2007). Cosmopolitanism, it is suggested, will in the future need to make space for the emergence of a demand for less liberal types of polit ical regime (Fine 2007). The political consequences of the economic crisis are widely judged also to be illiberal. History shows that hard times can be fertile ground for the rise of values that give priority to order over individual liberties. The critique of liberal democracy is not confined to any one school of polit ical thinking; it is becoming something akin to generally believed received wisdom. But it is of particular vehemence in the writing of those approaching the subject from the perspective of critical theory. The severest critics deride the whole democracy agenda as a straight jacket of power-driven liberal norms (Habermas 2006; Duffield 2007). As outlined in the introduction to this volume, the strongest attack on liberal democracy promotion has come from neo- Gramscian writers. They dismiss democracy promotion as an elite-driven project designed to legitimise the prevention of far-reaching reform to the capitalist eco nomy (Robinson 1996; Gills, Rocamora and Wilson 1993). There are many eloquent critiques that have added much of value to debates over democracy’s international trajectory. But what is now the mainstream gen eral critique tends rather easily to assume many things that in fact require more careful interrogation. Is it really the case that to recover legitimacy, the demo cracy support agenda requires a whole new concept of democracy? Is the prob lem really that democracy promoters have insisted upon an unduly narrow form of either electoral or liberal democracy? Is liberal democracy really quite the demon that many now suggest it is?
102 R. Youngs This chapter offers a modest but hopefully distinctive contribution to the current volume. Many of the book’s chapters delve into political theory and regional specificities. Written by someone with one foot in academia and one foot in the world of policy-oriented think-tanks, this chapter rather focuses on the nexus between conceptual debate and policy practice. Amelioration of this link is sorely needed. At present, academics and diplomats’ perceptions of each other are hardly positive. Academics dismiss policy-makers as hopelessly reductionist in their understanding of democracy. Policy-makers see academics as self-absorbed, abstract and behind-the-curve. It is argued here that the stance required is a nuanced one. Some of the key aspects common to critical perspectives are sound and have made an important contribution to debates over democracy promotion. Some of the key assumptions made in the introduction to this volume, that the ‘conceptual politics of demo cracy’ needs to be opened up to a wider range of ideas, are also entirely valid and well made. However, this chapter questions how far the scepticism heaped on liberalism’s shoulders captures what is most seriously wrong with real-world policy developments. The argument can be summarised: shortcomings in the conceptual politics of democracy certainly merit attention, even if they are not democracy promotion’s primary inadequacy; but it is more doubtful that critical theory provides the best guide to the way in which democracy support requires betterment. Policy examples in the chapter are drawn mainly from European democracy strategies (although the implicit purpose is not to comment on the well-worn question of EU-versus-US comparisons, a topic covered exhaustively in many other writings). Two commonly made assumptions rest on empirical ground that is not firm. The first of these is the assumption that Western powers are in essence over- promoting liberal democracy. The facts suggest instead that they are not doing much to promote democracy of any type, whether liberal or otherwise. This is the most notable policy trend of recent years, under-stressed if not entirely ignored by arguments that derive from critical theory. Second is the supposition that where they are active in democracy support, Western powers follow a rigidly liberal template that is inappropriate and inattentive to local demands and specificities. Of course, in places some such concerns are well founded and injustices are undoubtedly committed in the pursuit of political change. But this argument is far too sweeping when forwarded as a general meta-critique of democracy promotion. Real-life policy formulation is much more ad hoc and varied in its conceptual bases. This is evident if one takes the trouble to look at the nitty-gritty substance of what democracy promoters are doing on the ground. In some cases Western powers assertively promote liberal democracy. But other combinations are also adopted. Sometimes policy favours illiberal demo cracy; sometimes it seeks advances in liberal rights without democracy; and sometimes it is active in supporting neither the ‘liberal’ nor the ‘democracy’ strands of liberal democracy. The precise nature and balance of such policy
Misunderstanding the maladies 103 options varies across different democracy promoters, different ‘target’ states and over different moments in time. Critical theory inspired approaches risks seeing a uniformity that simply does not exist in concrete democracy support strategies. It is if anything more straight jacketed than the policy-makers it mocks as rigidly simplistic in their conceptual understanding of democracy. This is not to suggest that all is well in the democracy promoters’ house; but the renovations needed are more subtle in nature.
Democracy, economic interests and development A first, frequent criticism is that Western powers limit themselves to supporting a form of liberal political reform that excludes any interest in social democracy. The evidence demonstrates that this is not a convincing line of argument. The routinely made suggestion is that a key problem with the democracy support agenda is that donors do not realise that ‘democracy must deliver for economic development’ and help reduce poverty and inequality. Western governments can be criticised for many things, but this now standard accusation is wide of the mark. The argument (made in some places in this volume) that donors place such absolute priority on political liberty in their foreign policies that they are blind to economic development challenges and possibly alternative means of achieving these is not one that bears any close resemblance to reality. At the level of concrete funding initiatives the balance of priorities appears to be the very inverse. Donors give significantly more resources for social development and efforts to reduce inequality than they channel to political aid aimed at ‘imposing’ liberal democracy. By far the largest slices of funding are managed by development agencies, most of whom remain reluctant to let any engagement on political reform divert attention from core social development aims. Of course, it would be fair to argue that on such issues still not enough is being done, and that trade policies often cut across the stated aims of enhancing social democracy. However, this is a problem more related to the prioritisation of commercial self-interest and broader structural constraints of the international system than to a ‘conceptual politics of democracy’ that negates social demo cracy. What requires improvement is the linkage between democracy promotion policies and other aspects of Western foreign and commercial policies that relate to structural impediments and injustices at the global level. Conceptually, Euro pean governments would categorically question the suggestion that there is a trade off between core liberal democracy and the goals of social democracy. President Obama’s discourse also now focuses routinely on linking democracy to social justice – as, for example, in his September 2010 speech to the United Nations General Assembly (Obama 2010). Theoretically, there is resonance here with the later work of John Stuart Mill that pointed to the mutually reinforcing links between liberal political rights and social democratic ends (Ginsborg 2008: 42). Yet, as one commentator observes, many self-styled progressives have come to believe that these are largely
104 R. Youngs mutually exclusive policy choices – and that concerns over the restriction of civic rights are little more than a middle-class diversion from the pursuit of systemic socio-economic change (Kampfner 2009: ch. 7). The impact on democracy of structural conditionality aimed at reducing the economic role of the state continues to be problematic in many countries. But even here the financial crisis has hastened a shift away from the use of structural adjustment conditionality (if only for the self-serving reason that many Western governments are now borrowers from the international financial institutions). In broad diplomatic terms, most countries pursuing socialistic paths to development have been rewarded more than castigated. Think of the way in which Spain and France have deepened relations with Húgo Chavez’s Venezuela or the generous amounts of European aid channelled to Vietnam. To some extent, it might even be said that the imbalance tips the other way. The problem is not so much that of European governments limit themselves to liberal democracy without supporting measures of social democracy, rather it is that they support measures of social democracy without aiming their policy instruments at the core tenets of liberal democracy. Asked to list the most important elements of his country’s democracy policies, the reply of one senior Nordic diplomat reveals this confusion: ‘support for health and education’, which is ‘much more legitimate than free elections’. In practice, policy aims (rightly, it might be felt) at the end goals associated with social democracy, but without prioritising its democratic procedural components: the ‘social’ without the ‘democracy’ of ‘social democracy’. A second critique is that democracy promoters neglect the necessary role of the state, the flip side to their belief in unbridled liberalism. In fact, donors’ aid programmes exhibit a notable state orientation, with the aim of building states’ social and economic competences – to such an extent that citizens often complain that such statist approaches neglect the civic sphere. Development agencies such as the UK’s Department for International Development (DFID) have developed some impressively sophisticated concepts of ‘building coalitions for change’. But local actors complain that such approaches are invariably out- weighed by political-level diplomacy. European governments have allowed regimes to neuter reform dynamics in their (perfectly desirable) efforts to include state bodies in their projects. Donors are correct to insist that the democracy agenda is as much about strengthening state as civic capacity. But the way this is being done tilts the balance too far away from the latter. Local stakeholders are highly critical of the fact that European Commission projects on judicial and administrative reform are agreed with governments and include mainly regime-backed partners. In the Middle East people talk of a ‘legal complex’ – judges working with civil society activists and party reformists to broaden out the hitherto very statist approach to legal reform favoured by the international community. Fieldwork reveals civil society organisations’ complaints that they are pushed by donors into ‘coalitions’ with ministries – the new box to be ticked on donor check lists – when the problem for social development is the illiberal repression wrought by this very same state (Youngs 2010).
Misunderstanding the maladies 105 Among European policy-makers there is indeed growing recognition that it is this imbalance that requires attention. The Commission’s ‘political economy’ approach to governance reform has uncovered concern that millions of euros of budget support given straight to non-democratic regimes for social development purposes is simply empowering autocratic state structures that evade local accountability over the way in which such funds are used. Third, central to critical perspectives is the contention that liberal democracy is joined at the hip with economic liberalism, of a type that works against the interests of non-Western states. This is the essence of the neo-Gramscian line. This would claim that all the discourse on supporting social justice and accepting other models of democracy is entirely disingenuous – a feint to hide what is in fact a self-interested, narrow preference for liberal democracy. The financial crisis has also nourished a resurgent Marxist critique. Slavoj Žižek sees in this crisis proof that not only is market liberalism the flip side of political liberalism, but that tension between the two is inherent to liberalism itself. He contends that the financial crisis shows that the political economy of class is back as prime shaper of struggle, negating the notion that liberal norms are universal. This influential thinker advocates that the left return to the Hegelian notion of a strong state and move away from support for liberal individual empowerment (Žižek 2010: 5, 37, 157, 200). It is absolutely true, and vital to highlight, that many injustices are carried out in the name of democracy support, and that the latter can easily be used as a cloak for self-centred Western economic interest in a way that militates against high-quality political pluralism. However, the detailed policy record once again shows a more varied picture than is often painted. In most cases, Western states are more than happy to delink the commercial and democracy agendas. The EU is currently negotiating a large number of trade deals with autocratic regimes, without any apparent worries over the absence of democracy in these states. And conversely, the main post-financial crisis trend in the West is pulling back from support for trade liberalisation. The Doha round is stuck; most bilateral trade deals are in fact ‘trade light’. Another point of relevance in response to the ‘elitist democracy’, Marxian critique is that the one sector rarely included in democracy initiatives is the business sector – trade unions get far more support from Western democracy promotion agencies. None of this is to argue that neo-imperial dynamics do not exist. But it is a plea for greater forensic rigour in determining what kind of policy outcomes can be attributed to such dynamics. Western governments are often admonished for striking commercial deals with autocrats, but then also for ‘democratic imperialism’ when they do emphasise liberal norms in their foreign relations – damned if we do, damned if we don’t, some diplomats might feel. A good dose of imperialism could be said to lie in the convenient sidelining of democracy more than any pernicious liberal understanding of political reform. Research suggests that people in autocratic states see ‘imperialism’ in Western double-standards – sometimes supporting, sometimes deferring democracy – more than in any adherence to a particular conceptual model of democratic reform (Youngs 2010).
106 R. Youngs Many critical points raised are important and valid. They certainly offer a welcome complement to the focus of constructivism on identities: it is important to redress the dominance of purely identity-centred debates and recognise that the potential for and blockages to democracy continue to be rooted in material interests and social structures. But there is much, perhaps wilful over-conflating of the criticism of neo-liberal economics with criticism of liberal democracy. It is not true to say that Western powers neglect the economic dimension of democratisation in favour of a narrow focus on elections and political activists. Again, in the case of European policy exactly the reverse is the case: efforts aimed at the dispersal of economic power are given clear priority. The problem is more subtle: not so much a narrow exclusion of the economic dimension from the ‘conceptual politics of democracy’ as a failure to articulate more symbiotic linkages between economic and political change. For economic change to unleash pro-democratic potential is not automatic but path-dependent on parallel change in political rights, if the benefits of economic democratisation are not to be captured by incumbent autocratic regimes. A fourth contention is that approaches to democracy promotion are largely determined by pressure from multinational companies for shallow rather than emancipatory reform. This views fails to weather scrutiny. Empirical research has found that business views and actions vary enormously. Some firms in some markets have indeed played a role in pushing for a curtailed form of low intens ity democracy. But on other occasions, other firms – especially bigger natural resources companies – prefer autocracy to low intensity democracy. For example, some Middle Eastern regimes are now setting up business courts that are more efficient and predictable but act outside the purview of normal courts – and investors declare themselves happy with this situation. Companies’ actions in this sense might help explain the lack of commitment to democracy promo tion but not to a particular, pernicious limited-liberal form of democracy. In still other cases, international companies have arrived at more enlightened conclusions that their own interests depend on high-quality democracy, with active cit izen participation, high education and social welfare provision, and improving Gini coefficients of equality. Not only is there much diversity in the positions adopted by international capital. Much uncertainty also exists among executives over how their narrowly defined commercial interests are affected by political structures. Most look for a lead on issues of politics from diplomats rather than attempting to push the latter into a particularly detailed line on democracy promotion. It is simply unconvincing to posit international capital as prime actor in herding Western states towards a uniform focus on a particular form of limited liberal democracy everywhere in the world. Its actions are far more reactive than this suggests, and more varied – sometimes worse and sometimes better (Youngs 2004: ch. 3). The book that did most to engender the neo-Gramscian take on democracy promotion is unsatisfactory in generalising from an account centred on US policy in Latin America at one particular historical moment (Robinson 1996). Many states where a neo-Gramscian approach is alleged represent such small
Misunderstanding the maladies 107 markets it is doubtful that they represent major interests for international capital: if the neo-Gramscian account were correct we might expect the most assertive promotion of limited democracy to be found not in Ecuador or Niger but in China – precisely where we see an accommodation with the authoritarian regime. Moreover, the Gramscian framework must struggle with the fact that much low intensity democracy today is of a leftist variety, certainly not falling over itself to meet the requirements of international capital. It is worth pointing out that John Locke’s now much-maligned focus on private property (as being constitutive to political freedom) was part of his cam paign against serfdom – a progressive product of its time, now pilloried as con servative dogma. A focus on property rights may not always be as regressive to substantive democracy as many critics assume: in many countries a major social concern of lower income groups is the impunity with which the government is able to grab land from them. Often civil society organisations themselves push for a stronger focus on private property rights within donor policies. Moreover, whether one thinks economic liberalisation is a good or bad thing, the fact that property rights have been extended around the world is hardly the result of a par ticular conceptualistion of democracy support policies.
Forms of representation In one of the most eloquent of recent analyses, John Dunn asserts that demo cracy today enjoys only a ‘reluctant deference’ because it has lost its original sense of popular participation in decision-making but is seen more narrowly as a population bestowing legitimacy upon the state through the principle of repres entation. There is no genuine democratisation of life, but victory of the (classically rooted) notion of a ‘partially elective aristocracy’. This is valuable in setting limits on the state but carries none of the stirring pretensions of demo cracy’s origins. Democracy endures, Dunn argues, as ‘a recipe for nurturing the order of egoism’ (Dunn 2005: 17, 158, 176). The relevant implication here is that the West has failed to find a way of promoting a really vibrant form of democratic representation that extends beyond formalistic institutional change – a failure in some ways reflective of its own internal political travails. Flowing from this, fifth in our list of key strands to the critique of liberal democracy is the standard criticism that Western democracy promoters reduce democracy to the holding of free and fair, competitive elections. While this admonishment continues, it is not convincing today to accuse democracy promoters of this ‘electoral fallacy’. No one seriously involved in democracy support today argues that ‘democracy equals elections’. The issue is how much effort is invested into pushing for free, multiparty elections compared to other components of high-quality democracy. Here it is simply not the case that Western democracy promoters over-concentrate their political capital or resources on elections to the detriment of more ‘substantive’ reforms. Indeed, if anything, policy has shifted to the other extreme: the importance of elections is rather under-estimated. Western governments prioritise social
108 R. Youngs projects, civil society initiatives, good governance and many other reforms in countries where they happily accept autocratically manipulated elections. Neither the US nor European governments have tended to adopt punitive measures in response to unfree elections with any significant degree of frequency. Countries routinely win policy upgrades from the European Union in the aftermath of unfree elections: Ethiopia, Rwanda, Armenia, Egypt, Azerbaijan, Tunisia and Morocco are just a few recent examples of this happening. The European Parlia ment is in battle with member-state governments that fail to act in any way upon criticisms made by observer missions of flawed elections. The percentage of democracy aid that goes to electoral projects is no longer disproportionately high. In China, European donors have switched funding from village election projects to supporting the Chinese regime to build a social security system – exactly the opposite of the standard charges made against democracy promoters. Western powers are not imposing a form of democracy inappropriately based on or limited to elections. Indeed, the demand for freer elections is higher than the supply of support for free and fair elections from the international commun ity. Moreover, it is a myth that donors do not accept electoral results they do not like. In most cases they do: Viktor Yanukovich’s victory in Ukraine and the AKP’s dominance in Turkey are two examples. Not every case is like the Hamas victory in 2006. Today the danger must be that the liberating role of elections is given insufficient due. Donors commonly argue now that free elections should only come after all other kinds of reforms have been implemented. However, in many cases it is free elections that provide the breakthrough for other gains in political and social rights; a lack of free and fair elections is a block to other reforms, they are not just the end of a process. Moreover, Western powers often presume people will wait more than they actually want to for an independent voice in the choice of their government (McFaul 2010: 66). Ironically, in their concern not to be foisting ‘Western-style elections’ on other states, Western governments fall into the trap of thinking that reforms should everywhere follow the same path as European history, that saw fully free and inclusive plebiscites come at the end of centuries of gradual reform (see Berman’s chapter). In this sense, withholding support for free elections could be said to be rather more Eurocentric than trying to temper non-democratic regimes’ control of voting. A much repeated line is that (a softer) democracy support policy should be guided primarily by recognition that ‘democratisation in Europe took 300 years’. But this seems to underplay the fact that this drawn out process witnessed untold bloodshed and upheaval – hardly an appropriate model for today’s democrats. A sixth point: the associated criticism that Western democracy promoters are resistant to ‘alternative’ forms of representation. This accusation is also less than fully seized of the facts. Development agencies and political foundations have increasingly engaged with tribal leaders and village level courts in the developing world. Debates over conflict stabilisation initiatives have tilted strongly towards ‘vernacular’ understandings of democracy based on informal and patronage-based distributions of power (Elhawary et al. 2010: 17). The EU
Misunderstanding the maladies 109 talks of ‘specificities’ even in places like Georgia where democrats themselves reject the framing of debates in such terms. And most democracy aid projects are today about bridge-building and mediation, not replicating Western institutions. From Afghanistan to Central Africa, from Nepal to Guatemala, the new leitmotif is support for ‘indigenous forms of reconciliation’. Several European gov ernments have supported projects designed to organise representation around indigenous rights in Bolivia; the US has been tougher on Evo Morales’ drugs policy but has also sought to work in cooperation with his government’s altern ative concept of representation. European governments have backed the African Union Panel of the Wise, which includes tribal elders. In general, policy shows evidence of becoming more pragmatic. It is simply untrue to say that donors are intent on imposing liberal democracy in a way that overrides local participatory dynamics. In fact under the Accra and Paris development agendas, the focus is now on supporting village-level monitoring bodies overseeing municipal-level budgets. The problem lies not so much with a blind refusal to consider other forms of representation – indeed all the official discourse insists on quite the opposite – but rather in understanding what this really means in practice. For example, exactly how should donors respond to and engage with disparate social movements that do not fit the Western model of representative bodies? All donors espouse ‘country-specific approaches’. But this risks becoming an empty, if mellifluous, cliché. This author has certainly not heard any democracy promoter advocate ‘country-blind approaches’. When one probes what ‘country specific’ really means it appears bereft of clear operational guidance in many contexts. On the ground, donor coordination is identified as the big challenge; this is lacking precisely because a multiplicity of programmes and approaches are offered. In fact, the debate has already moved into a subsequent phase: donors that had recently been supporting traditional structures have now become more circumspect due to their less than favourable experiences on the ground. For example, the EU supported traditional Gacacca courts in Rwanda, as these were seen as a quicker, paperless track for genocide cases not serious enough to be sent to the Arusha-based International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda. But these courts have been dogged by complaints of witch-hunts and controversial and often delayed rulings. Likewise, in the Democratic Republic of the Congo in the early 2000s the international community supported customary justice in some instances, but then stopped. This was because of a series of controversial decisions, for example involving rape cases in which tribal chiefs often ruled that the rapist and the victim should be forced to marry. Land ownership systems managed by chiefdoms have proven a barrier to ‘democratising’ citizenship rights over land. The situation now among donors is one of great uncertainty about how to engage with customary justice. The drift is towards, rather, looking at ‘transitional justice’, which aims to provide redress for moments of egregious rights abuses but often appears delinked from the longer-term reform agenda. Neither is it quite true to accuse Western governments of adhering to a liberal democratic model that allows no room for religion-based representation, as some
110 R. Youngs critics now do. Western governments have long provided fulsome support for Lebanon’s confessional-based democracy. Progress has been halting on engaging Islamists, and this remains an area of concern in Western policies. But this is not primarily a problem of a narrow ‘conceptual politics of democracy’. In recent years, Western-democracy promoters have taken a step away from equating democracy with pure secularism. Hundreds of Western funded projects now facilitate religious dialogue. Many, many deliberative forums are funded on identity questions – all very Habermasian in nature. The West is not good at engaging with Islamists. But shortcomings in such engagement are not because it is working to a conceptual model of democracy that excludes religiosity. The liberal tendency has actually been towards ‘understanding religious differences’ much more than towards pressing liberal political norms as antidote to the root causes of radicalism. A seventh and final line of attack is the routine assertion that local demand is always for something other than liberal democracy. The reality is more mixed. Traditional local forms are themselves highly contested. There are undoubtedly concerns with Western forms being inappropriately implemented. But there are also concerns that the West patronises many local civic groups, assuming they hanker after some kind of tribally based identity when what they really want is external help with the basic protection of liberal rights. Many local groups complain that donors have become far too indulgent towards traditional forms that are deeply undemocratic, for example in their treatment of women. The interna tional community’s attempt to ‘bring in the Taliban’ may seem perfectly sensible and desirable, but it has also unleashed howls of protest from the ‘democratic’ opposition to the Karzai government. Asked the very question about ‘the need for alternative models of democracy’ explored by some contributors to this volume, the replies of civic actors in the target states of democracy support are often thought-provoking. ‘Traditional forums must continue, yes; but a different model of democracy, no’, replies one Nepalese student activist. ‘Just word games’, sighs one African NGO leader. The positive view now taken by policy-makers towards ‘traditional structures’ may have extremely welcome elements. But – right or wrong – it is the very antithesis of the philosophical roots of political liberalism in the conceptual war on ossified tradition. Interestingly, Marxists are now in the forefront of critiquing this support for traditional forms: in their idiom, this ‘organic lifeworld’ is replete with ossified forms of domination. The Marxist line is that the liberal tolerance for such alternative forms is now so great it will form part of liberalism’s self-destruction – as a creed tolerant of its antitheses. Bernard-Henri Lévy maintains that imperialism was the negation of, not the insistence on, the universality of standard liberal politics (Lévy 2009: 194). The latter years of British imperialism represented the defeat, not the apogee, of Gladstonian liberalism. Strategies need to look forwards. Where a new ‘conceptual politics of demo cracy promotion’ is required is in pre-empting qualitative shifts in the forms of citizen accountability. Cyber-activism is the big new focus, especially among younger sectors of the population. Donors still struggle to build this into their
Misunderstanding the maladies 111 democracy-support profiles. The problem is not an overdose of outside support for liberal individual empowerment but a preference for state-controlled limited governance reform against such new forms of civic organisation. The interna tional community supported the Equity and Reconciliation Commission in Morocco, which most observers saw as an effort to pre-empt democratic breakthrough; at the same time, clampdowns against social networks and new media in Morocco elicited no critical international response. Similarly in Egypt, most genuine civil society activists now register as law firms or civil companies to get around regime restrictions on civil society, but at the time of writing neither the US nor the EU have responded to this in their funding rules, for fear of upsetting the Mubarak regime. In short, debate over different forms of democracy is needed; but the West does little to advance the core liberal freedoms of thought and expression that would enable such preferences to be freely deliberated.
Reflections on liberalism’s future Current international political trends are complex and still in flux. History shows that there are no iron laws of democratisation, and dominant political dynamics can prove strikingly changeable. The easy triumphalism of the liberal democracy agenda in the 1990s was misplaced. However, much criticism now risks over- shooting (Garton-Ash 2004; Halliday 2009: 37–51). The Bush administration provided an easy dog to kick. But its excessive awfulness skewered the nature of conceptual debate: critical theory has become as lacking in self-reflexivity as the ‘liberal imperialism’ it everywhere sees and excoriates. A nuanced view is warranted of the ‘democracy backlash’ (Burnell and Youngs 2010). We should indeed be attentive to a lack of flexibility in the conceptualisation of democracy. The consideration of a variety of models is neces sary and desirable. However, the evidence does not sustain the suggestion that the most serious problem with democracy promotion today is an excess of the ‘liberal’ in liberal democracy. Indeed, in many places quite the reverse is true. The most worrying problem is not practitioners’ lack of willingness to consider varieties of democratic institutions but the lack of priority attached to advancing core liberal rights. As Western powers decline, this trend is likely to deepen in the future. Liberalism will increasingly be on the back foot not overly dominant. In this sense, assuming that liberalism is dominant risks lagging behind the policy curve. Dahl’s definition of democracy may be partial and narrow, but can we really not with confidence say that it is better than the authoritarianism that the West is still propping up under the guise of respect for ‘local values’? Moreover, the ‘liberal overdose’ argument is curious to the extent that since the end of the 1990s a central thrust of debate common to development, security and governance circles has been ‘the rediscovery of the state’. The stress on core liberal political norms is today under- not over played. It continues to be the centrally important area where local reformers look to the
112 R. Youngs international community for support – most commonly, in vain. Deliberations over precise institutional configurations and second-generation reforms are of a lesser order of importance. Michael McFaul observes that some debates about the intricate sequencing of reform and different varieties of institutional path ways look incongruous, as the US can today do little to influence such details but only back core democratic values (McFaul 2010: 154). Yet it still hesitates to do so, for all the standard commentary on US ‘liberal imperialism’. Liberal inter nationalism is still de-legitimised by the pervasive assumption that it is concerned primarily with mobilising military force in support of democratic values; it must be made clearer that military power is simply anathema to the standard day-to-day agenda of democracy support. There are different levels of critique, which risk elision. One thing is to argue that Western powers should support core liberal democratic principles, then from this base work to build into their policies a concern with social equality, parti cipation, deliberation and religious identity. It would be entirely convincing to argue that, while democracy promoters have advanced, they could and should be doing more in this direction. But it is quite another thing to suggest that such aims should be supported against or instead of core liberal norms. In practice, what many critics appear to advocate is not a cumulative combination but a dilution of the liberal component in favour of other forms. They betray a core inconsistency: they dislike democracy promotion for being overly intrusive but then advocate modifications that would make it more, not less, intrusive. This is because most suggested ‘alternative forms of democracy’ breach the line between process and substantive policy outputs – they advocate particular ends, not just a type of policy-making means. The concrete examples of European policies demonstrate that it is hardly credible to ‘accuse’ Brussels of being an unthinking citadel of blinkered lib eralism. Indeed, in this author’s experience, conversations with policy-makers reveal this to be akin to an almost unmentionable L-word. When so much doubt and ambivalence now suffuses democracy support strategies, it is unconvincing to admonish the latter for being uniformly, heavily prescriptive. Donors’ tendency to see democracy through the prism of their own political systems still often surfaces. But in terms of the way that the ‘democracy’ in democracy support is defined conceptually it would seem somewhat redundant now to warn donors of the dangers of heavily prescriptive institutional templates. There is some evidence of the self-reflexive policy-learning on the part of democracy promotion practitioners that many critics assume is entirely lacking. Indeed, genuine doubt over the most suitable paths forward has reached the point where some actors are reduced to immobilism. If Laurence Whitehead is right (in this volume) to argue for a conceptualisation of democracy that is ‘floating but anchored’, it is apt to note that current democracy support policies exhibit as much that is floating as is anchored. The problem is that while policyrelevant knowledge has accumulated, it has done so in an ad hoc fashion and has not been systematised into common or comprehensive new approaches (Carothers 2009b).
Misunderstanding the maladies 113 The influences on democracy strategy of academic traditions are eclectic. If we were to trace the philosophical roots of European good governance and democracy support policies it is simply not the case that Locke prevails over all else. The breadth of democracy assistance programmes goes way beyond the Schumpeterian. The stress on the role of the state and the existential identity-value of the political community found in many current policy initi atives finds resonance (if unconsciously) in thinking that historically stood as the antithesis to political liberalism. Such a line can be traced from Aristotle’s view of the political community as a biological organism; to Rousseau’s insistence that the general will embodies a mystical, spiritual collective identity of the political community above and beyond the will of the majority; through to Hegel’s system centred on the state as the organic embodiment of collective interests and identity, the ‘absolute’ within which the individual finds his very meaning. This is not to say any such strand of thinking would capture entirely the ideas that inform today’s foreign policies. However, the pertinent point is that the underpinnings of these policies can be seen in writers who were in combat with Lockean liberalism. The standard European discourse on equality being more important than formal political democracy has a direct echo in (polit ically) anti-liberal Rousseau. Concerns over the ‘tyranny of the majority’ that inform power-sharing strategies in post-conflict situations have a long line of antecedent philosophers who inveighed strongly against the will of the majority, from Aristotle through even to Kant (who was concerned with the repub lican separation of executive and legislation but certainly not with augmenting popular power against the aristocracy). Even Benthamite radical utilitarianism shines through, with its concern with a strong rule of law to restrain indi vidual freedoms and ensure greater equality in the furtherance of collective interests. If any modern philosopher is the thinker of choice for today’s discerning Eurocrat it is Habermas, not the classic liberals. In general, deliberative demo cracy has been most widely advocated as a means of situating abstract cosmo politan universalism within concrete and varied social settings (see Chatterjee 2008). And all this offsetting of pure liberalism is quite apart from the more obvious cases of cynical realpolitik that take their cue from the more violent illiberalism of Machiavelli and Hobbes.1 It is self-evident that liberal democracy now shares the conceptual field with rivals in a way that it did not in the 1990s. This may provide for vibrant debate and much-needed self-examination. But it does not necessarily mean that alternatives have superior legitimacy. Allowing analytic space for a wider variety of forms and definitions of democracy does not mean that sovereign democracy, Islamic democracy, tribal democracy or Bolivarian democracy are necessarily superior or more in tune with local demands. With the West accused of being overly prescriptive of a liberal form of democracy, it would be corruptive of the critique to jump straight into advocating other pre-cooked forms. It should be remembered that a form such as social democracy is just as
114 R. Youngs ‘Western’ in its origins as liberal democracy: there is no reason a priori to assume that it corresponds more closely to ‘local demands’ in the way that is routinely and rather uncritically suggested (however much one may oneself desire socially democratic outcomes). If the ascendance of conceptual competitors can add usefully to the parameters of desirable political reform, it is not incompatible with this that they should at the same time sharpen the West’s defence of core liberalism. Critical theorists skate a thin line: they issue pleas for a rethinking of demo cracy, but scratch beneath the surface and what they really lionise is undemo cratic state-led development; theirs is in fact not a genuine concern with reconceptualising democracy so much as a pretty wholesale questioning of the democracy agenda, dressed up in softened discourse. A central pivot of many such critiques is the criticism of liberalism’s teleological arrogance. But this centres too much on one influential book published at one rather distinctive moment in time (Fukuyama 1992); liberalism more broadly and properly understood is not teleology. Moreover, many writers argue against teleology and prescription but then in the next breath confidently assert that social demo cracy must be a superior and more acceptable form of democracy outside the West and one which has a more sustainable long-term future (cf. Patomäki’s chapter). This may be the case, but these critics have no philosophical justification for saying so without replicating the very same presumptiousness they profess to dislike in ‘liberal’ tenets – and thus contradicting themselves. Clearly, more debate about different forms of political representation would be healthy. Allowing space for a plurality of routes to and types of political reform would sit well with the core spirit of democracy. However, while more flexibility and open-mindedness are still required in democracy promotion, there is a risk of being unduly defensive about the virtues of liberal demo cracy’s core tenets. The problem in many places of the world is the absence of liberalism’s core values, not their excess. Vigilance in the need for demo cracy’s reconceptualisation is indeed merited. But it would be a muddled reasoning that took this to provide a case for the wholesale pullback from (already anaemic) support for liberal democracy’s notion of fundamental political rights. We need more fully to understand local demands. But there is an automatic assumption routinely made that such demands are for more diverse, anti-liberal political forms. This may in many places be the case, but the evidence must be assembled. One cannot simply assert this as if it were axiomatic to the emerging world order; there is no reason for supposing a priori that this is a natural outcome of the rebalancing of international order. The evidence that exists points, again, to a more nuanced conclusion: a demand for the essential tenets of liberal universalism, made relevant to and expressed through the language and concepts of local cultures and histories. A growing focus within political philo sophy has been on ‘capabilities’: negative liberal freedoms need to be deepened but also combined with the locally rooted capabilities that ensure their effective realisation.2
Misunderstanding the maladies 115 The central thrust of Locke’s liberalism was anti-dogmatism and prudence. The irony – and, for anyone concerned over democracy’s health, the tragedy – is that international support for a supposedly liberal democratic agenda is today associated with exactly the opposite of these values. It is the non-dogmatic spirit that liberalism must work to recover: liberal democracy as a system that (simply) creates space for a variety of different local choices. Advocates and opponents of liberalism are trapped in a circular debate over this matter: while core liberal freedoms are required to make such local choices, critics insist that those very liberal rights are themselves a corruption of local autonomy. The imperative is not for liberalism to cede to other creeds, but to work towards squaring the circle that has always existed at its heart: that is, liberalism is in its very essence the rejection of utopian political design, yet, if not pursued with care, itself can appear as an unbending utopia. This defines its challenge: can liberalism stand convincingly as an anti-utopian creed whose own propulsion requires courageous normative conviction? Can it strike the Rawlsian balance of deepening a plurality of values without descent into relativism? Where it is most convincing to argue that a reconceptualisation is required is in relation to the multilateral dimension. Western powers’ strategies of democracy support within particular national contexts take place in complete isolation from their own multilateral diplomacy. It is the fact that the multilateral pursuit of eco nomic liberalism has no counterpart in the sphere of political liberalism that risks leaving the latter devoid of its original, classical idealism (Kienle 2010). The changing world order and deepening interdependence across many spheres renders this separation prejudicial to the chances for success at both levels. Rectifying this is not a matter of a highly idealist claim in favour of a cosmopolitan democracy, that in light of today’s shifting power constellations looks increasingly improbable. Neither is the link simply a matter of getting rising powers signed up to the Western agenda of democracy support; such instrumentality is likely to backfire badly. But, conversely, it is essential to avoid the opposite extreme of presuming that the link must be entirely negative: that any effort in favour of globalism hollows out national-level democratic rights or that advances in democratic rights nationally must undercut support for globalism. The nature of national-international links is multifaceted and complex, and thus needs far more careful deliberation. Debate continues between two possible routes: a democratisation of traditional inter-state relations (‘a democracy of democracies’) versus a more radical and qualitative shift in multilateralism. Certainly, there must be a case for understanding that the pursuit of power-based, state-centric forms of multilateralism risks working against the very kind of local empowerment central to national-level democracy support programmes. Demo cracy promoters must begin to understand how their macro-multilateral policies effect the systematic constraints and potential relevant to the health, vibrancy and impact of democracy at the national level. In the absence of such a rethink on this question, advances at the level of specific democracy support initiatives are likely to be overridden by systemic imbalances that sap the desired ‘demo cratisation of democracy’.
116 R. Youngs
Notes 1 This mix exists not only at a superfic ial level, but extends right back to the cleavage in philosophical method that separates liberalism and illiberalism: the deductive positing of a priori ideals, in a line extending from Plato through to Hegel, standing in distinction to the inductive empiricism of the English liberals. 2 For a summary of the long-running and complex debates over ‘capabilities’, see Chatterjee (2008).
Part II
Cases
7 The conceptual politics of democracy promotion in Bolivia Jonas Wolff 1
Introduction Bolivia presents a text-book case for the conceptual politics approach outlined in the Introduction to this volume. During the 1990s Bolivia became a much-lauded development model (Mayorga 1997; Puhle 2001; Whitehead 2001a): following a turbulent, but ultimately successful transition to democracy in the early 1980s, Bolivia first implemented a program of drastic macroeconomic stabilization, then embarked on a strategy of second-generation reforms that included (neo- liberally guided) structural adjustment, like privatization, and political reforms that deepened decentralization and popular participation. All this took place in a democratic setting that was dominated by three major political parties that gov erned the country in changing coalitions and that were united by a broad consensus around liberal democracy and neo-liberal economics. Bolivia’s ‘pacted democracy’, as it was called, appeared to follow a rather linear path towards consolidating into a liberal democracy, understood as ‘constitutional, representative, individualistic, voluntaristic, privatistic, functionally limited, political democracy as practiced within nation-states’ (Schmitter 2006: 1). The ‘donor community’ enthusiastically endorsed and supported Bolivia’s reform process, with democracy and governance – alongside economic reforms and poverty reduction – being the main areas of support. In this context, not much debate about the meaning and value of democracy seemed necessary. At least in a general sense, both the Bolivian government and external actors took liberal democracy ‘as the consensus end point being worked towards’ (Introduction: 2). The general path towards this destination seemed equally uncontroversial. After the turn of the century, this situation has changed fundamentally. Since the first election of Evo Morales as President of Bolivia in 2005, the country has been undergoing a process of profound political transformation that affects the most basic parameters of how democracy is conceived (cf. Crabtree and Whitehead 2008; Kohl and Bresnahan 2010; Wolff forthcoming). The issues at stake in this contentious transformation are: the model of democracy (representative vs. participatory democracy), the relationship between liberalism/liberty and democracy/equality, the nature and breadth of human rights, the relation between politics and economics, and even the very
120 J. Wolff nature of the state (unitary vs. plurinational). In this context, external democracy promotion is confronted with fundamental questions that directly relate to the conceptual politics of democracy promotion: What kind of democracy should be supported? Towards what destination is Bolivia’s political transformation headed? What would a desirable and feasible ‘end point’ look like? How should democracy promoters deal with contested meanings of democracy that erupt both within the ‘recipient’ country and between external actors and the local government? Which political practices and institutions are legitimate within a broad understanding of democracy (and thus to be accepted or even supported), and which represent a deviation from democratic standards (that is to be criticized or even punished)? Bolivia, in this sense, represents an exceptional case for the debate on and practice of democracy promotion. The contemporary transformation of democracy in this Andean country constitutes one of the very few experiences world-wide in which there is a serious effort to construct a demo cratic regime that, at least partially, deviates from mainstream conceptions of liberal democracy.2 Contestation about democracy and democracy promotion occurs not only between external and local actors, i.e. between democracy promoters and the ‘recipient’ country. As Hobson and Kurki argue in the Introduction, another site of conceptual politics concerns different democracy promotion agencies. In this regard, comparing the US and Germany is especially interesting. Both are among the most important actors in the field but are usually associated with quite different approaches. Although systematic comparative studies are missing, the ‘superpower’ and ‘liberal hegemon’ US and the ‘civilian power’ and ‘export nation’ Germany are usually seen as representing rather different approaches to democracy promotion: a political (and revolutionary) versus a developmental (and evolutionary) conception of democratization, a missionary versus a reluct ant attitude towards meddling in other countries’ affairs; an offensive/confrontational versus a cooperative/dialogue-oriented stance; and dominance of security-related vs. economic concerns (Spanger and Wolff 2007a: 280–4).3 These are, of course, overly simplistic ascriptions. Yet, they at least signal that we should expect conceptual differences between the US and Germany, should there be any substance behind the claim that conceptual contestation over demo cracy’s meaning occurs also between different democracy promoters (see Introduction). Systematically speaking, then, what follows is a plausibility probe of the conceptual politics approach applied to rather easy cases: both between Bolivia and external democracy promoters in general and between the US and Germany, contestation and divergence are most likely or, in fact, obvious. Thus, we should expect the conceptual politics perspective to bear significant insights. This chapter will start from the Bolivian experience, i.e. the conceptual challenges to democracy promotion in general that arise from the ongoing transformation of democracy in Bolivia. These challenges relate to the mainstream conceptualization of democratization (section 2), as well as to the dominant model of liberal democracy (section 3) that generally inform North-Western efforts to promote
Democracy promotion in Bolivia 121 democracy. Then, in a brief comparison of US and German policies towards Bolivia, the relevance of the conceptual politics for the behavior of these two particular democracy promoters will be assessed (section 4).
Contestation in democratization: challenging democracy’s ‘instrumental value’ and ‘illusions about consolidation’ An important line of argument in justifying democracy promotion draws on the supposed ‘instrumental value’ of democracy: Democracy is seen as not only a good and noble thing in and of itself but also as contributing to a whole series of other goods, including intra- and inter-state peace, human rights, economic wel fare, poverty reduction and social justice (cf. Spanger and Wolff 2007b). How ever, Bolivia’s recent history makes it clear that a deepening of democracy – in the sense of increased democratic participation and political inclusion of formerly marginalized sectors of society – can lead to substantive outcomes that are not in line with ‘donor’ preferences, which assume that ‘all good things go together’. In the mid-1990s, Bolivia saw sweeping political reforms, most notably in terms of ‘decentralization’ and ‘popular participation’. An important aim was to increase the democratic participation at the local level in order to bring demo cracy closer to the people and, thereby, make the democratic institutions both more effective and more stable. These reforms included the nationwide estab lishment of municipal governments with democratic elections and additional mechanisms of social control at the local level. Furthermore, part of the national parliament was now to be elected in uninominal (single-member) electoral districts. A direct consequence of these political reforms was an opening up of the political system and, in particular, a strengthening of political forces with strong regional or local presence. For example throughout the Chapare, one of Bolivia’s major coca-growing regions, representatives of the cocalero (coca-growers) federations were elected Mayors. In 1997, four cocaleros won seats in Congress, including Evo Morales, the leader of the main cocalero federation, who was elected with the highest share of votes in the whole country. This political rise and inclusion of formerly marginalized sectors of society culminated in the election of Morales as Bolivia’s first indigenous president in 2005. Although, of course, a series of factors contributed to this political success story, there is ample evidence that the deepening of democracy, brought about by the political reforms in the 1990s, played an important enabling role (cf. Van Cott 2005: ch. 3). The victory of Morales in 2005 indicates a successful political incorporation of formerly marginalized sectors of society and, thus, a deepening of Bolivian democracy. At the same time, however, the new government has clearly challenged ‘donor’ preferences. Morales has abandoned the US-driven ‘War on Drugs’ in favor of cooperative coca eradication only and turned away from the neoliberal development model in favor of a greatly enhanced role of the state in the economy (cf. Kohl and Bresnahan 2010; Wolff 2011).4 Yet, the problem is
122 J. Wolff not limited to the well-known conflict of aims between democracy promotion as a (weak) normative orientation and pursuing economic and/or security concerns as (hard) material interests: the state-based economic and social policies promoted by Morales and his government – and, in particular, the policy of ‘nationalizations’ – clearly differ from what the US and Germany conceive of as ‘good democratic governance’ (cf. BMZ 2007: 4; Franco 2006: 18). In addition, the political empowerment and inclusion of the indigenous and social movements in Bolivia did not in fact stabilize or consolidate the democratic system (cf. Crabtree and Whitehead 2008; Yashar 2005: ch. 5). Instead, it resulted, first, in a period of political turbulence and crisis (2000–2005) that included the toppling of two presidents and culminated in a conflict-ridden dismantling of the existing institutional setting with a view to building a largely new political system (2006–present). This contrasts with another mainstream conception characterizing democracy promotion: the notion that the deepening and the consolidation of democracy are two sides of the same coin; that improving the breadth and quality of participation helps strengthen democratic institutions, and vice versa. As a con sequence, protecting the existing democratic institutions and promoting their further democratization are seen as complementary tasks without major contradic tions. The risks associated with democratization are generally attributed to the initial phase of transition from authoritarian rule only (cf. Mansfield and Snyder 2008). Yet, the democratic state (as any state) institutionalizes social power relations; post-transition democracies are regularly built on (institutionalized) pacts and social compromises; and, in general, democracy under conditions of structural social inequalities depends on systematic limits to democratic participation in order to include the elites in the political game (cf. Rueschemeyer et al. 1992). Hence, a deepening of democracy that aims at leveling the democratic playing field by enhancing the participation of marginalized sectors will lead to demands for institutional change and, if successful, to a de-consolidation of real-existing democratic institutions. Such processes may not ‘only’ undermine the liberal democratic institutional order: if radical demands for redistribution in economic resources and political power meet the fierce resistance on part of threatened elites (including the privileged middle class), polarization can lead to escalating violent conflict, with the threat of civil war looming. At the heart of the dubious ‘instrumental value’ of democracy and the ‘illusions about consolidation’5 is a conception of democracy promotion that Tony Smith once dubbed ‘conservative radicalism’. This ‘paradoxical form’, that according to Smith, constitutes the ‘genius’ and ‘tragedy’ of US democracy pro motion, is ‘radical in that for many countries, democracy has meant an abrupt and basic political change away from the narrow-based authoritarian govern ments’, and at the same time ‘conservative in that in fundamental ways, the Americans have not meant to disturb the traditional social power relations based on property ownership’ (Smith 1994: 17–18). The Bolivian transition to democracy largely followed this model.6 In extending this experience, the predominant expectation on the part of the ‘donor community’ was that when the poor and indigenous sectors of Bolivian society began to participate in the
Democracy promotion in Bolivia 123 processes of formal politics they would ‘learn’ that liberal democracy, neoliberal economics, abandonment of a project of larger redistribution of social power relations, continuous efforts in coca eradication, etc. were ultimately in their own best interest. Yet, as will be seen, this was not precisely what happened.7
Contested models of democracy: challenging the ‘transition paradigm’ and ‘liberal universalism’ The ongoing transformation of democracy in Bolivia is clearly characterized by contestation about the model of democracy. Between 2006 and 2009, this contestation was centered on the project to rewrite the country’s constitution. In 2006, a Constituent Assembly was elected in order to draft a new Magna Carta. After a complicated and contentious process, in January 2009 a new constitution was adopted by referendum. Both the process of rewriting Bolivia’s constitution and the new constitution itself demonstrate the relevance of contested conceptions and models of democracy (cf. Romero et al. 2009). Regarding the process of constitutional reform, a continuous question concerned the relative weight of basic democratic legitimacy based on the political will of the majority and specific questions of legality and procedural correctness (particularly with a view to protecting the rights of minorities). On the one hand, impressive electoral victories since 2005 have demonstrated that Morales, his Movimiento al Socialismo (MAS) and the project of constitutional reform could rely on solid and clearly majoritarian support among the population.8 On the other hand, the whole process of constitutional reform has been accompanied by controversial decisions and, in part, open irregularities. For example, in a highly disputed procedure the draft for the new constitution was adopted by the Constituent Assembly by a two-thirds majority of the present members of the Assembly only, with the most important opposition groups being absent. Fol lowing some nine months of political struggle, a two-thirds majority in Congress agreed on a detailed revision of the constitutional draft; this procedure lacked any legal basis but was crucial for enabling the constitutional reform to be accepted even by parts of the opposition and, thus, for preventing a further escalation of political conflict (cf. Böhrt 2009). The general problem concerning this process of political change is that it is just as undemocratic to stick categorically to procedural regulations that grant a veto to the (institutionally) vested interests of privileged elites as it is to enforce a redistributive political project that has majoritarian support but overrides all constitutional protection of minorities. Very clearly we are dealing here with a political struggle that involves conceptual politics: whether one emphasizes the procedural/constitutional or the substantive/republican dimension of democracy is politically consequential. From the former perspective, the Morales government brought a deterioration in terms of horizontal accountability and transparent, effective, efficient and rule- bound (‘good’) governance. It lacked respect for the established institutional order and gradually dismantled institutional controls and procedural rules while
124 J. Wolff new ones had yet to be established. From the latter perspective, in contrast, the quality of Bolivian democracy in terms of representation and participation (inclusion and vertical accountability) has greatly improved. Both Bolivia’s gov ernment and the parliament are considerably more representative today than any predecessors, the new constitution can count on more democratic legitimacy than any constitution before, and political participation – measurable in, but not limited to electoral events – has clearly grown (cf. Barrios 2008; Wolff 2009). The transformation of Bolivian democracy is, thus, a contradictory process that does not follow a linear path from less to more democracy. A dogmatic emphasis on procedure assumes that the path to democracy is linear, that other forms of democratic progress are realized only after polyarchy is first perfected, and that therefore any country where polyarchy is more advanced is necessarily more democratic than one where polyarchy is less advanced or absent. Yet one might reject this assumption and, consequently emphasize social realities over formal structures – even while conceding that polyarchy, other things being equal, greatly enhances the prospects for a demo cratic outcome and is necessary for the consolidation of such an outcome. (Roth 2000: 496) A look at the new constitution confirms this point: adopting the terminology proposed in the Introduction, it expresses the result of both contestation within liberal democracy and a contentious attempt to go beyond liberal democracy. In general, Bolivia’s new Magna Carta corresponds to the usual standards of demo cracy and human rights but includes important deviations from mainstream liberal-democratic (and thus ‘donor’) conceptions. On the one hand, the new constitution includes the ‘classical’ series of political and civil rights and the new political system is dominated by ‘traditional’ mechanisms and institutions of representative democracy. On the other, this basically liberal-democratic order is amended and modified to an important extent: indigenous (customary) law is established as a second justice system besides ordinary law, with equal ranking; indigenous collective rights provide for self-government in autonomous indigen ous territories following indigenous customs and practices; indigenous minority groups in rural areas elect their delegates in national parliament through special electoral districts; mechanisms of direct democracy like recall and other referendums or popular legislative initiatives are established; the highest branches of the judiciary will be elected by popular vote; ‘organized civil society’ gains vaguely defined but potentially far-reaching rights to participate in the design of public policies and control public administration; finally, social and economic rights clearly go beyond anything usual in North-Western liberal democracies, possibilities for privatization (e.g., of public social services) are constrained, and property rights (e.g., in land) are delimited (cf. Böhrt 2009; Wolff forthcoming). The general problem here is two-fold. It concerns, first, the ‘Transition para digm’ as dubbed and criticized by Thomas Carothers (2002).9 Bolivia is but one example in a long row of countries around the world that demonstrate that
Democracy promotion in Bolivia 125 political regimes regularly deviate from the assumed linear path from authorit arian rule to liberal democracy. Second and related to this, the idea that there is a single and universal model of liberal democracy (‘Liberal Universalism’) is openly challenged. Each really existing democratic order is a specific blend of contradictory democratic principles (e.g., sovereignty of the people vs. constitu tionalism, majority rule vs. protection of minorities, political equality vs. indi vidual freedom, individual equality vs. recognition of cultural differences) and in this sense the transformation of democracy in Bolivia can be read as an attempt to readjust and rebalance these principles by strengthening the plebiscitary and participatory aspects of democracy as well as the economic, social and cultural dimensions of human rights. Very clearly, as Laurence Whitehead (2008: 26) has argued, ‘it is possible for more than one constellation of democratic prin ciples to capture the collective imagination of a political community’.10
Conceptual politics in the practice of democracy promotion: US and German reactions to political change in Bolivia Looking back at the so-called wave of democratization since 1974, Philippe Schmitter (1995b: 16) noted that ‘experimentation beyond the basic institutions of lib eral democracy’ has been ‘completely absent’. In any case, such an empirical observation cannot refute the claim that democracy is and remains, in principle, an essentially contested concept as defined by W. B. Gallie (Kurki 2010: 370–2). The contemporary transformation of democracy in Bolivia, however, represents one of the very few experiences worldwide which shows that we are dealing here not only with an abstract debate among academic scholars, but with the possibility that alternative models of democracy have immediate relevance for the thinking on and practice of democracy promotion.11 How, then, did the US and Germany – two key protagonists in the business of international democracy promotion – react to this exceptional Bolivian experience? This is not the place to systematically analyze US and German policies towards Bolivia (see Wolff 2011), but rather an opportunity to have a brief look at basic patterns with a view to the conceptual politics dimension. At first sight, there are important differences between the US and Germany in terms of both their perception of the state of democracy under Morales and their respective attitudes towards the new government. While acknowledging the elect oral legitimation of President Morales, the US government viewed the political predominance of Morales and the MAS party and the absence of any strong opposition at the national level as a serious problem for democracy. In line with a conception of democracy that emphasizes checks and balances and limits on the discretionary power of elected governments, then USAID Assistant Administrator Adolfo Franco (2006: 19) argued in 2006 that the US was to promote Bolivian democracy by supporting ‘counterweights to one-party control’. In fact, USAID activities in the area of democracy promotion – including the Office of Transition Initiatives – shifted towards the departmental level12 and civil society. In addition, the National Endowment for Democracy (NED) significantly increased its support for civil society activities (cf. Gratius and Legler 2009: 207; Wolff 2011: 12–15).
126 J. Wolff An interesting example for the conceptual politics perspective concerns the US Millennium Challenge Account. Here, a series of indicators has been set up to measure, inter alia, if countries ‘govern justly’ according to a fixed and universal standard and, thus, deserve support from the Millennium Challenge Corporation (MCC). During the Morales government, two democracy-related World Bank Governance Indicators (Government Effectiveness, Rule of Law) actually declined and in December 2008 the MCC Board of Directors decided to not reselect Bolivia as eligible for the program (Wolff 2011: 10). Even if this gradual decline in some indicators would never have caused the suspension, had it not been in combination with the open crisis in US–Bolivian relations (see below), Bolivia’s ‘violation’ of universally conceived standards of good democratic governance was clearly important for justifying the decision. In contrast, the German government – and, especially, the German Ministry of Development (BMZ) – viewed the election of Morales as an opportunity for making Bolivian democracy more representative of and responsive to the formerly marginalized majority of the population. The broad support for Morales, here, was taken as a reason to support the government (cf. BMZ 2007). Accordingly, Germany not only continued its development cooperation with Bolivia but adjusted its democracy assistance to the new political setting and the agenda of the new Bolivian government: for example, the German Gesellschaft für Technische Zusammenarbeit (GTZ) directly supported the Constituent Assembly, generally increased its support for the national level (relative to subnational entities) and focused much more on structural political reforms than previously (cf. Wolff 2011: 19–23). However, Germany suspended some very specific coopera tion projects with Bolivia as well. When, for example, irregularities and conflicts surrounding the Constituent Assembly peaked (in December 2006 and again during the last months of the Assembly), German support for the process was suspended. Reacting to the contentious adoption of the constitutional text by the MAS majority in the Constituent Assembly, Germany stepped back from the ori ginal plan of supporting the public dissemination of the draft constitution. Yet, the rationale behind these decisions was not so much an adherence to demo cratic/constitutional standards as a conflict-related aim to ‘do no harm’: con siderations of empirical legitimacy or factual approval rather than formal legality and democratic correctness led German agencies to suspend or restart its cooperation (Wolff 2011: 24–5). Again, however, the ‘violation’ of crucial democratic rules of the game was important for justifying German reactions. This is even clearer in another instance where German development cooperation was suspended. In reacting to Bolivia’s policy of ‘nationalization’, which affected one German company, Germany suspended a project in the area of climate and energy as a punitive response to Bolivian resistance to what would be, from the German perspective, an ‘appropriate’ compensation (Wolff 2011: 8). While this clearly represents an interest-driven decision in support of a German company, at least in justifying the suspension conceptual politics are again relevant: in the German understanding, private property rights are a crucial element of the rule of law (the Rechtsstaat) and democracy and the rule of law
Democracy promotion in Bolivia 127 are inextricably linked in the official German discourse.13 Thus, the sanction against Bolivia in defense of German economic interests was, at the same time, presented as support for ‘democracy and the rule of law’ in Bolivia. This last point already suggests that the differences in US and German reactions are only part of the story. In general, both the US and Germany officially reacted with an attitude of respect for alternative paths and models. Both govern ments acknowledged the electoral legitimation of both the government of Evo Morales and the constitutional reform. Support in terms of development assistance basically continued and, although there was some shift in US priorities (see above), even the US maintained a rather cooperative posture and signaled con tinuous interest in remaining engaged with the Bolivian government. US concern was, arguably, not driven by the perceived risks for Bolivian democracy but focused primarily on the policy changes in the area of counternarcotics/coca eradication and on what was seen as a hostile, anti-American attitude on the part of the Bolivian government. In fact, US sanctions against Bolivia were either acts of diplomatic retaliation – for example, the expulsion of the Bolivian Ambassador to Washington in 2008 following the expulsion of the US Ambas sador to La Paz – or justified by a lack of cooperation in the ‘Drug War’ – for example, the ‘de-certification’ of Bolivia and the following suspension of trade preferences in late 2008 (cf. Gray 2009: 171–6; Wolff 2011). At the same time, both the US and Germany perceived the changes in Bolivian democracy with skepticism. The partial deviance from what they regard as universal standards of democracy and human rights was seen as a problem by German and US representatives, even if this concern was not publicly articulated in the German case.14 Thus, the decision to react flexibly and cooperatively to Bolivia’s process of political change – a decision openly taken by the German government, but only partially so by the US – was to a big extent more a pragmatic and, in fact, reluctant adjustment to Bolivian ‘realities’. It was arguably driven by the recognition of broad majoritarian support within the country, the intention having some moderating influence on the Bolivian government, and the strong will to remain somehow engaged in Bolivia, be it out of the self-interest of the different development agencies, or because of the general political decision that a withdrawal from the country would be the worst option.
Concluding remarks There can be not much doubt that the conceptual politics approach sheds light on a crucial dimension of external democracy promotion. Democracy promotion, always and everywhere, relies on a specific conception of democracy (the end point), of democratization (the path) and of the proper role for the democracy promoters (the external contribution). Such conceptions are necessarily particu laristic (cf. Kurki 2010). Even from a basically liberal perspective, there can be quite different understandings of democracy, democratization and democracy promotion (cf. Spanger and Wolff 2007a; Wolff and Wurm 2011). Such understandings, then, clearly shape the ways in which the state of democracy in the
128 J. Wolff ‘recipient’ country and the ‘needs’ in terms of democracy promotion are perceived. As always, the causal effects of such conceptual pre-decisions on the politics of democracy promotion are almost impossible to measure. Most prob ably it makes no sense at all to look for such distinct effects – in contrast to, for example, the role of ‘material interests’ – because such conceptions and understandings shape the very definition of interests and vice versa. What the examples from US and German democracy promotion in Bolivia show, however, is the relevance of conceptual politics for justifying specific policies and decisions. And this is not a minor thing: factors that enable (and constrain) the public justification of political decisions are per se crucial (and causal) for policy-making, particularly in democratic states. Beyond specific US and German policies, the transformation of democracy in Bolivia has important consequences for the conceptual debate on democracy pro motion. Contemporary Bolivia shows, first, that real-existing democracy is a specific blend of contradictory democratic principles. Thus, democracy promotion based on a linear conception of democratization that simply tries to help countries along the assumed path from ‘less’ (and more ‘faulty’) to ‘more’ liberal demo cracy misses the complex reality of democratic change. Second, the (preliminary) results of the deepening of democracy in Bolivia (in terms of increasing participa tion and representation) defy the overly harmonious conception of democracy pro motion based on the notion that ‘all good things go together’ (cf. Spanger and Wolff 2007a, 2007b). Promoting democracy from the outside, especially if it is successful, can have consequences that are not in line with ‘donor’ preferences – be these particular interests or conceptions of how ‘real’ democracy should look. Third and finally, democratic experimentation in Bolivia, that at least partly transcends the mainstream model of liberal democracy, confirms the expectation that the conceptual contestability of democracy has immediate relevance for the thinking on and practice of democracy promotion. However, for democracy promotion, the notions behind both the ‘Transition Paradigm’ and ‘Liberal Universalism’ are not dispensable ideological distortions that can be corrected easily. The general project, as well as the actual practice of democracy promotion, depends on the assumption that democracy is in fact not essentially contested. Democracy promoters need to (assume to) know where countries are to go, along which path, and in what way external actors can help. Yet, democracy promotion in a situation a la boliviana can only be conceived of as a joint search process, in which external actors accompany contradictory domestic processes of political change that neither have a predefined end point nor follow a known path. In the Bolivian case, Germany – not by way of a deliberate decision but as result of pragmatic muddling through – came to adopt, more or less, such a strategy. The implication was that the explicit promotion of democracy took a back seat while the support for inclusive processes of dialogue, constructive conflict resolution and the like became the focus. Ideally then it is not a specific end point – a given model of democracy – that is striven for, but a peaceful and inclusive process of constructing a model appropriate for the specific country.
Democracy promotion in Bolivia 129
Notes 1 This chapter draws on research conducted in the framework of the research project ‘Determinants of democratic states’ handling of conflicting objectives in democracy promotion’ conducted by the Peace Research Institute Frankfurt (PRIF ) and Goethe University Frankfurt, and funded by the German Research Foundation (DFG). The author thanks Thomas Carothers, Svenja Gertheiss, Dominik Hübner, Laurence Whitehead and the editors of this volume for valuable comments. 2 I owe this point to Tom Carothers. 3 Cf. Carothers (2009a); Kopstein (2006); Monten (2005); Pospisil (2009: 163–281); Rüland and Werz (2002); Schraeder (2003); Smith (1994); Youngs (2004: 31–7). 4 In fact, USAID has been very hesitant to cooperate with Mayors representing the cocalero movement. For examples, in the framework of the Alternative Development program, USAID is reported to have ‘resisted working with Chapare municipalities, even though the municipal governments are the designated planning unit’; the US even applied pressure on the European Union’s Alternative Development program PRAEDAC not to work ‘through the municipalities’; in April 2004 only, ‘USAID/ Bolivia declared that it would expand its working relationship with Chapare muni cipalities’ (Farthing and Kohl 2005: 193, 194, 195). According to another source (Ledebur and Youngers 2008: 5), it was ‘in 2003’ that ‘USAID began working directly with Chapare municipal governments, which are led by coca growers [. . .]. Previously, confrontational USAID policies intended to weaken coca grower unions through the formation of parallel producers’ associations [. . .].’ As regards to Evo Morales, the decision taken by the Bolivian parliament in January 2002 to exclude Morales from Congress – under the allegation of instigating violence in the Chapare – was, at least in Bolivia, attributed to US pressure, and during the 2002 presidential elections the then US Ambassador Manuel Rocha openly threatened with a possible withdrawal of US assistance if the Bolivian people should dare to elect Morales (Van Cott 2003: 772–3). 5 This latter expression is borrowed from Guillermo O’Donnell (1996). 6 The success of Bolivia’s ‘pacted democracy’ after 1985 – and especially the implementation of drastic measures of economic restructuring – was enabled by the weakness of the organized popular sectors: while the once-strong labor union federation (COB) was weakened decisively by the economic crisis of the early 1980s (and additional political repression), the indigenous and social movements that would lead the social protests from 2000 onwards had yet to gain strength (cf. Conaghan and Malloy 1994: 150–1; Yashar 2005: 182–5). 7 As a consequence, the US had to learn that tardy attempts to threaten and exert pressure against the political changes enabled by the 1990s deepening of democracy, i.e., against the rise of Evo Morales and his Movimiento al Socialismo (MAS), were largely counterproductive. In the end, the US had to basically accept the Morales gov ernment and the process of political transformation promoted by it (cf. Wolff 2011: 8–17). The German government – which has no major stake in Bolivia – could even afford to pragmatically support the Morales government (cf. Wolff 2011: 17–25). 8 Morales was elected in 2005 (with 52 percent), confirmed in a recall referendum (67 percent) in 2008 and re-elected in December 2009 (63 percent). Equally, the MAS won national elections in 2005 (only narrowly missing the absolute majority in Congress), in 2006 (absolute majority in the Constituent Assembly) and 2009 (two-thirds majority in the new parliament). In January 2009, the new constitution was adopted in a referendum by a clear-cut majority of 61 percent. 9 Guilhot (2005: ch. 4) and Smith (2007: ch. 5) trace the influence of transition studies on the rise of the democracy promotion paradigm. 10 ‘Out of this mixture [of the broadly shared ‘elements of political democracy’] it is possible to distill more than one set of democratic priorities that can be defended on
130 J. Wolff the grounds of highest principles. Moreover, beyond this long but restrictive list of components it would be possible to identify additional features that are regarded in certain contexts as integral to democracy for some societies (upholding free market principles, opposing totalitarian evil-doers, correcting historical injustices against excluded population groups, etc.) but not for others.’ (Whitehead 2008: 36; Whitehead’s chapter). 11 Regarding ‘the kinds of non-liberal democratic or extra-liberal democratic models that might already exist’, Milja Kurki (2010: 370) points to ‘advocates of radical democracy in the World Social Forum’ and ‘development activists that wish to reclaim a social rather than liberal democratic form of democracy in Africa’. The main empirical examples for democratic experiments and initiatives that go ‘beyond the liberal democratic canon’ assembled by Boaventura de Sousa Santos (2005) refer to the local level or social movements. These examples are already important arguments against the ‘widespread tendency to decontest democracy’ noted by Hobson and Kurki (Introduction: 6); however, with a case like Bolivia, where democratic experimentation includes basic political institutions at national level, the debate on potential alternatives to liberal democracy gains another quality. 12 Already before the election of Morales in December 2005, the USAID Democracy Program in Bolivia had a focus on subnational governments, and it was in 2005 that it was decided to shift this support from the municipal to the departmental level – in reaction to the first popular election of departmental governors (prefectos) in that year. It is impossible to say if the new focus on regional governments reflects a deliberate US decision to support the departmental governments (and the autonomy movements behind them) as a counterweight to the MAS or even a preventive adjustment to an expected victory of Morales in late 2005. However, as the 2005 candidates in opposition to Morales won most (six out of nine) prefecturas, USAID de facto focused support on the one level of the state mainly governed by the opposition to the new central government. OTI activities, equally targeting the departmental level, reinforced this tendency (Wolff 2011: 11–12). 13 When dealing with democracy, official documents and speeches on democracy pro motion regularly mention both elements together (‘Demokratie and Rechtsstaat’), as two sides of the same coin. 14 The local offices of the German political party foundations, however, did so – in par ticular the center-right organizations Konrad-Adenauer-Stiftung and Hanns-SeidelStiftung.
8 Liberal democracy promotion and civil society strengthening in Ghana Gordon Crawford and Abdul-Gafaru Abdulai
Introduction The role of civil society rose in significance in democratisation generally and in democracy promotion specifically in the years following the end of the Cold War. Great claims for its contribution have been made by academic writers and democracy promotion practitioners alike. With regard to the role of civil society in democratisation, Diamond (1994: 7–11) outlined ten democratic functions of civil society, with the ‘first and most basic’ being ‘the limitation of state power,’ while others included stimulating political participation, developing a demo cratic culture of tolerance, recruiting new political leaders, and so forth. In the context of Africa, Harbeson et al. (1994: 1–2) asserted strongly that civil society was the ‘missing key to sustained political reform, legitimate states and govern ments, improved governance, viable state-society and state-economy relations, and prevention of the kind of political decay that undermined new African gov ernments a generation ago’ – the key to all good things, it would seem. This emphasis on the role and significance of civil society has also been evident in the discourses of international democracy promotion actors, notably the bilateral and multilateral ‘donor’ agencies. Civil society assistance has been a key element in USAID’s democracy and governance programmes since 1993, introduced ini tially by the Clinton administration and today continuing to be a central dimen sion (USAID 2010). UNDP (2002: 4) has also asserted a strong linkage between democratic politics and human development, with its focus on strengthening democratic institutions including the customary reference to a ‘vibrant civil soci ety’ as key to monitoring government and promoting political participation. In Funding Virtue, Ottaway and Carothers (2000) have traced this burgeoning inter est in civil society assistance within the democracy promotion programmes of the US and other aid-giving countries, notably from the mid-1990s onwards. They have highlighted the common enthusiasm for ‘civil society strengthening’ to the extent that ‘the idea that civil society is always a positive force for demo cracy . . . is unassailable’ (Ottaway and Carothers 2000: 4), and thus its funding is regarded as virtuous.1 In line with the ‘conceptual politics’ approach, this chapter investigates the underlying meaning of civil society within the context of democratisation and
132 G. Crawford and A.-G. Abdulai democracy promotion. It does so by examining bilateral donor support (i.e. from Western governments) to civil society organisations in Ghana and analyses the underlying concept of civil society contained within such programmes. Our starting point is influenced by critical perspectives such as those of Baker (2004, 2002) and Hurt (2006). Baker has firmly located the current orthodox view of civil society within a framework of liberal democracy, described as the ‘taming of civil society’. In his view, this has entailed the ‘instrumentalisation’ of civil society as ‘merely supportive of liberal democracy, rather than [a] site for demo cratic participation’ (Baker 2004: 45). Civil society thus becomes functional for liberal democracy by providing mechanisms for controlling the state, such as a channel for interest groups into parliamentary deliberation, and through under taking a scrutiny or ‘watchdog’ role over those in power (Baker 2002: 1). This orthodox view of civil society is deeply embedded in what Held (1996: 81) describes as a central tenet of modern European liberalism, in which ‘govern ment must be restricted in scope and restrained in practice’ with civil society conceived as an important means of limiting state power. Baker (2004: 43) contrasts this liberal democratic model of civil society with a more radical model of democratic participation and self-management, where democracy and democratisation within civil society become ends in themselves. We would add that such a model is generally in accord with the democratic prin ciple of popular control over collective decision-making in various spheres, including that of the state (Beetham et al. 2002). For Baker, this alternative, rad ical model is influenced by Antonio Gramsci’s (1971) writings on state-society relations in the 1930s, notably his emphasis on civil society as a possible site for the development of counter-hegemonic forces opposed to the hegemonic rule of the state and its dominant economic class. In Baker’s view, such a model of civil society was more evident in the 1970s and 1980s in Central and Eastern Europe and Latin America, where opposition to different forms of authoritarian rule was based on self-organisation from below and the construction of popular resistance to the state and the economy (2004: 58). However, Baker (2004: 43) highlights how this radical model only flourished briefly and subsequently has largely been eclipsed by the hegemonic, liberal democratic model of civil society that emerged post-1990. In looking specifically at the role of civil society in European Union development policy, Hurt (2006) develops a similar critique, though one that draws attention to a neo-liberal concept of civil society which places greater emphasis on the economic dimension of liberalism, notably an intent to reduce and restrict state interventionism in the economy. He notes that EU civil society support programmes ‘need to be understood within the broader economic aims of EU development policy,’ which is itself distinctly neo-liberal in character, promot ing economic liberalisation and greater integration into the global economy, and thus influencing the type of civil society that is promoted (Hurt 2006: 109–10). Prompted by such perspectives, the analytical framework developed here makes two distinctions between differing conceptualisations of civil society. Firstly, following Baker (2004, 2002), it makes the distinction between an
Liberal democracy and civil society in Ghana 133 orthodox liberal concept of civil society and a radical approach. Secondly, within the liberal concept of civil society, it distinguishes between a liberal democratic model and a neo-liberal model, where the former focuses on political processes that control and constrain the state, while the latter places emphasis on the eco nomic sphere and aims to limit the scope of state intervention through economic liberalisation policies. Critiques have also been made of the civil society assistance programmes provided by international democracy promoters, ones which also highlight the liberal democratic and neo-liberal approaches to civil society. In a key contribu tion that chimes with the analysis of a liberal democratic concept of civil society, Ottaway and Carothers (2000) have noted the concentration of efforts to strengthen civil society on a very narrow set of professionalised NGOs, similar to Western advocacy organisations and with little accountability to domestic constituencies, while the wider range of organisations that typically make up civil society is largely ignored (2000: 11). Focusing on the neo-liberal dimen sion, Hearn (2001) extends this critique in her analysis of civil society assistance as part of democracy promotion programmes in Ghana, Uganda and South Africa, and emphasises the linkages with building a consensus around neo- liberalism. She also recalls Gramsci, though focusing on his view of hegemonic rule as achieved through a mixture of coercion and consent in which civil soci ety also constitutes an arena for the creation and reproduction of consent, rather than as a site of counter-hegemony. She reminds us that civil society is not necessarily a site of progressive politics and resistance but more a contested arena in which states and other powerful actors, including international agencies, intervene to influence political agendas and defuse opposition (Hearn 2001: 43). In a separate report specific to the Ghanaian context, Hearn (2000: 24) found that political aid to civil society was aimed at promoting consensus around eco nomic reform and neo-liberalism, as demonstrated by ‘the kinds of CSOs being supported by donors and those that receive the most funding’. This chapter builds on such work by examining two recent bilateral donor civil society projects in Ghana: the Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme (G-RAP) and the Ghana Rights and Voice Initiative (RAVI). G-RAP receives multi-donor funding from the governments of the Netherlands, the United Kingdom, Denmark and Canada, while RAVI is funded solely by the UK’s Department for International Development (DFID). Both programmes were implemented from 2004 to 2010, when the first phase of both came to an end.2 The chapter addresses the following questions: • • •
What underlying concept of civil society is contained within these civil society support programmes? To what extent do these programmes emphasise a liberal democratic and/or a neo-liberal concept of civil society? Alternatively, do they provide evidence of donor support for a more radical model of democratic participation within civil society and the extension of popular control over collective decision-making?
134 G. Crawford and A.-G. Abdulai The chapter proceeds in five sections. After this introduction, the second section briefly provides the context of civil society strengthening activities in Ghana. The third and fourth sections look in detail at G-RAP and RAVI respectively, examining their history, the nature of donor objectives, the kinds of organisa tions supported, and teasing out the underlying concept of civil society embed ded in these programmes. Finally, the conclusion summarises the findings and considers whether democracy has been promoted or undermined through these civil society support programmes.
Ghana, democracy promotion and civil society strengthening Ghana is one of few African countries where democracy has become increas ingly consolidated after the democratic transition in the early 1990s (Abdulai and Crawford 2010). Beyond holding five successful national elections between 1992 and 2008, Ghana’s rankings on political rights, civil liberties and press freedom have improved considerably and are now among the best in Africa.3 Ghana also boasts an active civil society, with the European Union acknowledging the role played by ‘a vibrant, mobilized and well-organized civil society’ (EU 2009: 25) during the country’s December 2008 elections. While the emergence of this lively civil society sector is largely endogenous, with Ghana’s non-governmental organisations being largely responsible for its development, the principal bilateral development aid donors active in Ghana, (namely Canada, Denmark, Germany, The Netherlands, the United Kingdom and the United States) have all included ‘civil society strengthening’ measures in their democracy promotion programmes in the last decade or so. That said, focusing on EU efforts, Crawford (2006: 148) has argued that such assistance up to the mid-2000s has been limited and ad hoc. This point had also been acknowledged by the donor agencies themselves in their statement that previ ous donor support to CSOs had been ‘short-term and project related, with little or no co-ordination’ (G-RAP 2004: 6). Somewhat paradoxically, the significant development that led to a more con centrated donor focus on ‘civil society strengthening’ was the shift in 2003 to Multi-Donor Budget Support (MDBS) in support of the Government of Ghana’s (GoG) poverty reduction strategy. MDBS represented a move away from a sec toral, project-driven approach to development assistance, and involved the direct transfer of financial resources from participating donor agencies to the GoG to support the implementation of the Ghana Poverty Reduction Strategy (GPRS). Substantial sums were involved, with US$500 million being pledged for GPRS I (2003–2005) (G-RAP 2004: 5), and the nervousness on the part of the bilateral donor agencies was palpable. One response was the new focus by donors on ‘strengthening the capacity of civil society to engage the Government in active dialogue’, stated as having ‘become a key objective for DPs’ [development part ners] (G-RAP 2004: 5). The message was that donor interventions ‘are not sufficient’ to keep the government on track, and that ‘there is a need to strengthen public accountability and broaden the inputs into the policy process
Liberal democracy and civil society in Ghana 135 from across Ghanaian society’ (G-RAP 2004: 5). This context led to the initiation and establishment of both G-RAP and RAVI by 2004, with the former involving a pooled funding mechanism between the four bilateral agencies (The Netherlands, the UK, Canada and Denmark) and the latter funded solely by the UK’s DFID.
Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme (G-RAP) Context The Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme (G-RAP) was launched in September 2004 in support of the development of Ghana’s civil society institu tions, with a particular focus on Research and Advocacy Organisations (RAOs). Accordingly, the ‘overall objective of G-RAP is to improve the funding base of RAOs, to enhance their capacity to carry out evidence-based research and advo cacy, and to promote networking activities in support of pro-poor and gender sensitive policies in Ghana’ (Ahadzie 2007: 12). One underpinning assumption was that civil society was critical in ‘ensuring the transparency of government and holding it to account for its policies and use of public resources’ (G-RAP 2004: 6) – a core concern of donors with respect to MDBS. It was perceived, however, that although Ghana has had relatively active civil society organisa tions, their ability to influence public policy had been hampered by various factors, including the ‘fragmented and short-term nature of their funding base’ (G-RAP 2004: 6). G-RAP was thus initiated to create a more predictable funding base for Ghana’s RAOs with a view to strengthening their institutional capacity and enhancing their ability to engage in policy processes. Typical beneficiaries of G-RAP funding have been think-tanks, development organisations and advo cacy networks, with funding generally targeted at those RAOs that have the potential of contributing to national policy dialogue (G-RAP 2010). At its inception, G-RAP offered three types of funding, namely: multi-annual (three-year) core grants to individual RAOs with established track records of influencing public policy processes; institutional and capacity building (ICB) grants, aimed partly at strengthening inter-RAO networking; and technical assistance (TA) grants in support of enhanced human resources and technical (IT) equipment (G-RAP 2007: 17). Following a mid-term review of the pro gramme in 2007, however, the ICB and TA grants were both phased out (G-RAP 2008: 6), such that the programme subsequently provided only two types of grants, namely core grants and Special Project Grants in support of effective net working and coalition building among RAOs on specific advocacy issues. Together, the four bilateral agencies, made commitments of US$7 million to support G-RAP over the first three years of implementation (G-RAP 2004: 12), and a further commitment of approximately US$9 million over the period 2008–2010 (Awori 2009: 2).4 In total, G-RAP has supported 29 RAOs and net works in Ghana (G-RAP 2009: 3), and the first phase of the programme ended in March 2010.
136 G. Crawford and A.-G. Abdulai G-RAP’s underlying concept of civil society It is important to note from the outset that G-RAP’s participating donors recog nised that research and advocacy CSOs in Ghana operate largely within central government circles in the national capital. This meant that the programme’s exclusive focus on RAOs was likely to circumscribe its benefits to the well- established Accra-based organisations that, unlike their community-based coun terparts, are by ‘nature self-appointed in their efforts to represent the poor’ (G-RAP 2004: 8). The participating donors emphasised, however, that they wanted to ‘encourage and support new entrants into G-RAP’ so as to ‘avoid cre ating an elite club of RAOs’ (G-RAP 2004: 8–9). This was to be achieved in two main ways: first by encouraging all beneficiary RAOs to work in collaboration with community-based organisations; and by providing one-off ICB and TA grants to smaller, but promising organisations which did not qualify for G-RAP multi-annual core funding (G-RAP 2004: 8–9). Taken at face value, this would seem to suggest G-RAP’s commitment to offering support to broad-based civil society in Ghana, one that is aimed at encouraging greater societal participation within democratic processes. How ever, a closer scrutiny of the overall design and implementation of the pro gramme suggests a contrary view. We argue in this section that G-RAP’s particular intent for ‘strengthening civil society’ capacity, especially in its early days, was more of an attempt to enable CSOs to challenge and limit the powers of the Ghanaian state and less of an attempt to extend popular control over democratic decision-making. Indeed, the Programme Memorandum of 2004, reflecting the original thinking of the donors, exhibited a degree of state scepti cism. Here, civil society was perceived largely as a watchdog institution, such that the G-RAP initiative was seen as critical in creating ‘[s]ufficient political space . . . for RAOs to challenge Government policy choices’ (GRAP 2004: 16, emphasis added). In what follows, we undertake a more detailed investigation of G-RAP’s underlying concept of civil society through an analysis of the type of organisa tions that have been supported; the operation of the institutional capacity build ing (ICB) and technical assistance (TA) grants; and the underlying intent of G-RAP’s emphasis on inter-RAO networking. Type of organisations supported Beyond the general focus on national-level CSOs, G-RAP has been emphatic that its funding was to specifically target only those ‘RAOs [that] have a solid track record of engaging the Government on its policy choices and holding it to account for its actions’ (G-RAP 2004: 6). This narrow focus led to the estab lishment of very restrictive eligibility criteria for the receipt of multi-annual core funding. For the first selection round (2005) these included: the demonstration of existing capacity through satisfactory responses in a highly demanding organisa tional assessment of 109 questions; an emphasis on both research and advocacy
Liberal democracy and civil society in Ghana 137 activities; and, above all, an annual financial turnover of at least US$400,000. These criteria, especially the latter financial threshold, effectively excluded smaller organisations that were not already in receipt of substantial donor funding. The criteria were stated to have been necessary in order to limit the number of respondents to G-RAP’s calls for proposals (G-RAP 2007). Yet, if the participating donors wanted to ensure that the programme did not result in the promotion of an elite club of RAOs, as claimed, then why were such high eligi bility criteria set, ones that were certain to exclude a whole range of organisa tions that were potentially relevant to democratisation processes? Not only was funding limited to a small number of already relatively well- endowed organisations with significant capacity, but also their ideological orienta tion is highly pertinent. It is notable that the most well-established, Accra-based, pro-market think-tanks are amongst the major recipients of multi-annual core funding in the early years. Such organisations explicitly espouse a liberal philo sophy and include the Institute of Economic Affairs (IEA), the programmes of which are overwhelmingly geared toward the ‘promot[ion of] good governance, democracy and a free and fair market economy in Ghana’ (IEA 2010),5 and the Ghana Center for Democratic Development (CDD-Ghana), the explicit mission of which is to ‘promote democracy, good governance and the development of liberal political and economic environment in Ghana in particular and Africa in general’ (CDD-Ghana Annual Report 2006: 1). Indeed, these organisations, together with the Centre for Policy Analysis (CEPA) – all of which have consistently remained among the top five recipients of G-RAP core funding – have been described by Ohemeng (2005: 445) as Ghana’s ‘conservative think tanks,’ ones that are prim arily ‘concerned with the adoption and promotion of the neoliberal agenda in changing the state and enhancing political [and economic] openness’. However, two qualifications to these findings are necessary. First, an excep tion to the support for pro-market organisations is the inclusion of Third World Network (TWN-Africa) as a core grantee, an Accra-based, pan-African research and advocacy organisation that focuses on socio-economic development issues from a social justice perspective. Nonetheless, of the nine organisations that obtained multi-annual core grants in the first round of funding in 2005, only TWN-Africa could be said to be a persistent critic of the neo-liberal development strategies promoted by donor agencies. Second, since 2007, there has been a significant expansion in the range of organisations that have been awarded G-RAP core funding, beyond those that have been explicitly supportive of the neo-liberal development discourse (see Table 8.1). This broader range has included those concerned with security and development issues, legal advocacy organisations, private media organisations and anti-corruption agencies, with the latter two types perhaps aimed at ensuring a more prudent utilisation of donor funds. What has been particularly noticeable has been the increasing prominence of women’s rights organisations among G-RAP’s core grantees, with three out of 14 core grantees in 2007 and six out of 23 in 2008 being primarily concerned with gender-related issues, as indicated in Table 8.1. However, from interviews and documentary evidence it would appear that some of the participating RAOs
ABANTU for Development International Federation of Women Lawyers, (FIDA) Ghana ARK Foundation Women in Law and Development in Africa Network for Women’s Rights (NETRIGHT) Gender Studies and Human Rights Documentation Centre African Security Dialogue and Research Foundation for Security and Development West Africa Network for Peace Ghana Centre for Democratic Development Institute for Economic Affairs Centre for Policy Analysis Institute for Democratic Governance Integrated Social Development Centre Third World Network (TWN-Africa) Social Enterprise Development Foundation (SEND Foundation) Institute for Statistical, Social and Economic Research (ISSER), University of Ghana Northern Ghana Network for Development Ghana Integrity Initiative Centre for Public Interest Law Legal Resource Centre Media Foundation for West Africa
Gender and women’s rights promotion
Peace-building and security
Economic and political governance
Policy advocacy on socio-economic development
Higher education
Networks
Anti-corruption
Legal advocacy organisations
Media
–
– –
–
45,000
237,500
115,000 237,500 –
209,100 283,500 280,000 252,040
47,500 10,500 112,500
– –
86,250 38,600 58,100
2007
62,500
75,000
90,000 80,000
100,000
65,000
195,000
240,000 225,000 50,000
182,500 195,000 220,000 175,000
– –
137,500 89,000 107,500 127,650 40,000 50,000
2008
Amount (in US dollars)
Source: compiled from G-RAP (2008), ‘G-RAP Fund Account, Contract Number CNTR 03 5188’, April 2008, and G-RAP (2009), ‘G-RAP Fund Account, Contract Number CNTR 03 5188’, March 2009.
Core grantees
Thematic areas of organisations
Table 8.1 G-RAP fund disbursement to core grantees, 2007–2008
Liberal democracy and civil society in Ghana 139 themselves played a critical role in determining these changes through their con testation of certain aspects of G-RAP’s design, with the relationship between some RAOs and the Programme Management Team (PMT) described as ‘fraught’ (G-RAP 2007: 19) in the early years of the programme. The outcomes of such contestation were the relaxation of the $400,000 threshold, the incorpo ration of gender mainstreaming as a programme objective, and a reduction in the number of questions used in the initial organisational assessment of potential core grantees from 109 to 51, though this still implied a fairly detailed manage rial assessment format (see G-RAP 2007: 17–19). While acknowledging that this recent support for a more diverse range of organisations could be interpreted as a gradual shift within G-RAP towards the promotion of broader-based civil society participation, one significant pattern has remained relatively unchanged, namely the continued dominance (in funding terms) of the major Accra-based, pro-market organisations – IEA, CDD-Ghana and CEPA. Table 8.1 shows that IEA was G-RAP’s highest core grantee in 2007 ($283,500), receiving slightly more than CEPA ($280,000). Along with CDD- Ghana, these three organisations received approximately 37 per cent of total core funding to 21 organisations in 2007, and continued to feature heavily in 2008, although TWN-Africa also received substantial funding, slightly more than each of the three prominent pro-market NGOs in 2008. In sum, we argue here that the restrictive eligibility criteria for G-RAP’s core funding plus the concentration of funds on pro-market think-tanks were intended to groom a narrow set of CSOs that could serve as a proxy for the participating donors in limiting the powers of the Ghanaian state and holding it accountable in respect of its policy choices and use of donor resources. G-RAP’s award of institutional capacity building and technical assistance grants A further point relates to the operation of the Institutional Capacity Building (ICB) and Technical Assistance (TA) grants. As indicated earlier, these two grant categories were claimed to have been introduced in order to avoid funding only an ‘elite club of RAOs’ and to help smaller but promising RAOs graduate to the level where they would meet the criteria for G-RAP’s multi-annual core funding. Yet a closer examination of the quality and quantity of these grants, as well as their short-lived nature, raises critical questions about the real motives behind their introduction. Indeed, in 2007, TA grants were awarded to three organisations only, totalling $98,465 (G-RAP 2008: 7), in contrast to the total of $772,600 received by CDD, IEA and CEPA.6 Given that these organisations probably failed to secure multi-annual core funding due to their lower capacities, itself partly a consequence of financial constraints, it is questionable how such limited sums could sufficiently build their capacities to enable them to become ‘new entrants’ of G-RAP. Perhaps more significantly, both the ICB and TA grant categories were phased out in 2007 (G-RAP 2008), despite the initial recognition of their importance if G-RAP was to avoid funding only an ‘elite club’.
140 G. Crawford and A.-G. Abdulai It would appear that both the ICB and TA grants were partly introduced to serve a public relations function, and to mask the real thrust of the programme in supporting only a narrow set of CSOs in whom the donors had greater confi dence in their ability to challenge and limit state power. Indeed, the Mid-Term Review Team of the programme would seem to concur with this view when they described these two grant categories as a ‘compensation mechanism’ meant to ‘reward organisations not selected for mainstream core funding’ (G-RAP 2007: 26). Nonetheless, whereas the rather poor quality of these grants and their sub sequent withdrawal amounts to the relative neglect of many of the so-called ‘promising’ small RAOs, the ‘high performing’, Accra-based liberal NGOs con tinued to enjoy multi-annual core funding. It is also important to recognise that the phasing out of the ICB and TA grants had nothing to do with a shortage of funds, given that pledged funds were not fully expended. Rather, it had more to do with the donor focus on carefully selected RAOs that were perceived as able to influence and impact on government, as partly acknowledged in G-RAP docu mentation itself: The fundamental premise of G-RAP design was not the need to develop sys tematic RAO organisational capacity, but rather . . . to free up high- performing RAOs from the external constraints that were inhibiting them from fully impacting on pro-poor policy. (G-RAP 2007: 21) This argument is further supported by the introduction of a new form of grant in 2008 – the Special Project Grants – aimed largely at providing support for effect ive networking and coalition building among these selected and privileged RAOs on specific advocacy issues, thus strengthening another key dimension of the overall G-RAP strategy, as discussed below. G-RAP and inter-RAO networking Inter-RAO networking has been an important element of G-RAP’s design and implementation arrangements from the outset. Indeed, as a funding condition, it has been criticised by a number of RAOs during the programme’s mid-term review in 2007, highlighting the ‘pressures on them to increase their networking activities’ as a key challenge. Not only do G-RAP’s pre-qualification criteria7 for core funding include the requirement that a given ‘organisation participates in civil society coalitions/networks’ (G-RAP 2004: 31), but also the performance review of core-funded RAOs includes an assessment of ‘their ability to develop . . . networks and alliances with other actors across Ghana’ (G-RAP 2004: 14).8 In principle, civil society networks have the potential to play several useful roles in consolidating democratic governance, inclusive of serving as a collect ive mouthpiece for various marginalised groups in society. However, in practice, they can also fulfil the role of creating a more united front amongst RAOs in challenging the state and holding it to account on behalf of donors. We would
Liberal democracy and civil society in Ghana 141 argue that G-RAP’s interpretation of the notion of networking, and its under lying emphasis on inter-RAO collaboration, is geared largely towards the latter. This is evident in at least two respects. First, the Mid-Term Review Report (G-RAP 2007: 43) indicates that the ‘stated intention’ of networking in ‘G-RAP parlance’ is to ‘reinforce inter-RAO interaction and solidarity,’ and thus facili tate more effective interactions with the Ghanaian state. Second, although an early intention of G-RAP was that all beneficiary RAOs should work in collabo ration with community-based organisations (G-RAP 2004), it is acknowledged by G-RAP insiders that this has not happened.9 Indeed, the evidence suggests that while the programme has apparently placed much emphasis on inter-RAO networking as well as on the RAO-government interface, there has been no sim ilar effort aimed at promoting effective collaboration between RAOs and the very poor whose interests they purportedly serve. On the contrary, the RAOs continue to operate largely within central government and donor circles, and there is virtually no evidence of increased collaboration between them and community-based organisations. This is rather surprising given the participating donors’ acknowledgement of Accra-based RAOs as being significantly distant ‘from their constituencies in Ghanaian society’ (G-RAP 2004: 8). Yet the dis tinct lack of concern about this clear programme failure would seem to suggest that it was never a donor priority, indicating that their intentions are less about extending popular control over democratic decision-making and more about strengthening an elite group of civil society organisations with the capacity to challenge and limit the state, ones that can be relied on to interact with donors in mutual cooperation.
Ghana Rights and Voice Initiative (RAVI) Context The Ghana Rights and Voice Initiative (RAVI) was a DFID-funded project from 2004–2010, with a budget of £4.7 million. As indicated above, RAVI was ‘designed as a complementary aid mechanism [to Multi-Donor Budget Support]’ (Haden and Ahadzie 2008: 1), and its stated goal was to ensure ‘improved account ability and responsiveness of the Government of Ghana towards its citizens, par ticularly the poor’ (DFID Ghana 2004: 30). Additionally, RAVI’s emergence was related to two broad DFID policies in the areas of ‘rights’ and ‘voice’. First, increasing ‘citizen voice’ in policy-making and enhancing government accountability, rationalised as likely to improve the ‘pro-poor’ nature of govern ment policy, was in line with DFID’s approach to the state at that time. This is summarised as the CAR framework – Capability, Accountability and Respon siveness – in which these three overlapping elements are seen as forming a ‘vir tuous cycle of governance’, with ‘an effective state [being] a CAR state’ (Loughhead 2009, cited in Holland and Thirkell 2009: 4).10 From a development aid perspective, enhancing state capability clearly requires assistance to state institutions, the supply side, while leveraging increased accountability and
142 G. Crawford and A.-G. Abdulai responsiveness of government requires the strengthening of non-state actors and organisations, the demand side. This emphasis on ‘voice and accountability’ and on the role of civil society in ‘help[ing] to build effective and accountable states’ (DFID 2006: 2) has become a familiar element of DFID policy rhetoric in the past half-decade. However, the language is deceptively alluring. Such discourses can also serve to disguise an underlying state scepticism where ‘voice and accountability’ are valued for their role in constraining state actions and limiting its powers. This point is reinforced by reference to the World Bank’s approach to state and civil society, one that advocates ‘bringing the state closer to the people’ through ‘giving people a voice’ and ‘broadening participation’, as out lined initially in the 1997 World Development Report on ‘state effectiveness’ (World Bank 1997: 10). Again the beguiling nature of such apparently pro- democratic language is evident. Yet the World Bank’s underlying negativity towards the state becomes clear in its frequent references to an ‘arbitrary’ and ‘capricious’ state, echoing classical liberalism’s deep-seated fear of excessive and unrestrained state power, with a chapter devoted to this exact topic in the 1997 Report (World Bank 1997: ch. 6). Given the extensive influence of the Bank in the adoption of development discourses, it is contended here that DFID’s notion of an ‘effective state being a CAR state’ is similarly underpinned by political liberalism and state negativity in which the ‘voice and account ability’ mechanisms attributed to civil society are perceived as fulfilling an instrumental function to restrain and restrict state power. Second, the particular focus on ‘rights’ within RAVI relates to the separate but closely linked DFID policy on human rights and a rights-based approach to development (DFID 2000), one that was evident for a decade, at least until the change of government in the UK in May 2010. ‘Realising human rights for poor people’, as the policy was entitled, was to be achieved through three principles: participation, enabling people to participate in policy-making processes; inclusion, emphasising the human rights values of equality and non-discrimination; and fulfilling obligations, pertaining to the responsibilities of state duty-bearers to promote human rights (DFID 2000: 7). These idealised principles relate closely to the above policy on ‘voice and accountability’, with human rights to be secured through poor people’s participation and expression of voice, listened to in turn by a responsive government. One difference however is that pro-active state action is required for rights realisation. RAVI is distinctive, though not unique, in combining these two elements of voice and accountability and a rights-based approach. As stated in the Project Memorandum, the goal of improving government accountability and responsive ness through ‘enhance[d] citizen engagement with the state’ is situated within the specific framework of ‘the protection and fulfilment of civil, cultural, eco nomic, political and social rights’ (DFID Ghana 2004: 5). Thus, as a civil society support project, it has a specific human rights focus and seeks to strengthen the capacity of rights-holders to exercise their voice and demand their rights and to enhance citizen-government engagement, with rights realisation by the state as an anticipated outcome.
Liberal democracy and civil society in Ghana 143 RAVI was managed for DFID by a consortium of international NGOs headed by ActionAid Ghana, with project implementation by a secretariat based in Accra. A total of 34 Ghanaian CSOs were provided with two-year grants in three rounds of grant-making between 2005 and 2007. These grantees included 11 ‘intermediary’ organisations who worked in turn with a total of 109 local NGOs and CBOs, thus extending support to ‘grassroots’ organisations (RAVI 2009a). In addition, RAVI attempted to contribute to a culture of rights through provi sion of training programmes for grantees on a rights-based approach and by holding public events at which the rights work of its grantees was showcased. RAVI’s underlying concept of civil society What is the concept of civil society that underpins RAVI? Despite the original pro ject goal, as outlined above, implying a liberal democratic orientation in which civil society is primarily conceived as a mechanism for controlling the state, there is some evidence that in practice RAVI has gone beyond such an orthodox and instrumental approach. First, RAVI has encompassed a wide range of civil society organisations and would appear to have operationalised ‘a broad and inclusive view of “civil society” ’ (DFID Ghana 2004: 6), as promised. Second, rights cover age has entailed not only civil and political rights but also economic, social and cultural rights. Third, the emphasis on citizen-government engagement has encour aged democratic participation and collective action, including alliance-building amongst local and national CSOs. We look at these three aspects in turn. Range of civil society organisations RAVI supported a wide range of organisations through its financial assistance to direct beneficiaries and intermediary organisations, extending well beyond the narrow range of professional and westernised NGOs that may be most able to perform a watchdog role on state institutions. Although direct beneficiaries have only totalled 23 in number, these have been diverse in terms of both type of organisation and thematic focus. Grantees have included: • • • • •
membership organisations, including trade unions such as the General Agricultural Workers Union (GAWU); faith-based organisations such as the Christian Council of Ghana; media organisations, for instance the Foundation for Female Photojournal ists and Public Agenda, a weekly newspaper that focuses on development and rights issues often ignored by both private and state-owned media; legal advocacy organisations such as Centre for Public Interest Law (CEPIL) and the Legal Resources Centre (LRC), both focusing on access to justice for the poor; and coalitions and networks, for example, the National Coalition on Domestic Violence Legislation (DVC), the Northern Network for Education Development and the Community Radio Network. (RAVI 2009a)
144 G. Crawford and A.-G. Abdulai The grants disbursed to 11 intermediary organisations have extended cover age to over 100 local NGOs and CBOs. These have included organisations of poor, rural people, often far from Accra and regional capitals, who have been introduced to a rights-based approach and whose organisational capacity has been strengthened. RAVI’s own publicity has highlighted various success stories in which poor and often vulnerable groups and communities have actively engaged with government agencies in attempts to protect and promote rights (RAVI 2009b). One such example is Solidarity Action for Community Empowerment (SOLACE), a community-based organisation sup ported by the Belim Wusa Development Agency (BEWDA), itself a small development NGO, in the Upper East region of northern Ghana. SOLACE focuses on health issues, being particularly concerned about the high rates of maternal and child mortality in the local area. The two-year partnership with BEWDA (2006–2007) as an intermediary organisation entailed the development of SOLACE’s organisational capacity, including training in rights-based approaches. Consequently, it appears that SOLACE has been able to engage more effectively with local government in making right claims, with some success in the areas of water provision (water storage tanks) and sanitation (renovation of public toilet facilities), both vital for improved health (RAVI 2009a: 4; interview SOLACE coordinator, 11 November 2009). Additionally, in community education work, SOLACE promotes awareness of women’s rights, notably through drama and education around themes of gender equality and anti-FGM (female genital mutilation) (Interview, SOLACE coordinator, 11 November 2009). Coverage of rights The broad coverage in RAVI of different types of human rights is already evid ent in the varied thematic orientations of the organisations listed above and is further demonstrated by looking at the concerns of beneficiary organisations. The coverage is clearly not limited to those elements of civil society that are supportive of economic neo-liberalism, with many organisations advocating for greater state regulation and government protection against big business. Eco nomic rights are promoted by the General Agricultural Workers Union and by organisations involved with natural resource-dependent communities. For instance, Forest Watch Ghana promotes the rights of marginalised socio- economic groupings in forestry, while Friends of the Nation seeks to ensure that the voices of fisher folk are heard, with these organisations also having an envir onmental rights dimension to their work. Social rights are promoted through RAVI’s support for a variety of rights-deprived social groupings, including: • •
disabled people, e.g. Ghana Federation of the Disabled and the Ghana Association of the Blind; women, e.g. Women in Law and Development (WiLDAF ) and the Ark Foundation, promoting women’s and children’s rights. Both organisations
Liberal democracy and civil society in Ghana 145
•
are also members of the Domestic Violence Coalition, which itself received RAVI support; and children and young people, e.g. Youth Alive, working with street and other vulnerable children.
There is some limited coverage of cultural rights through assistance to the Center for Indigenous Knowledge and Organisational Development, while civil and political rights are protected through the support provided to legal advocacy organisations such as CEPIL and LRC. Both organisations engage in court liti gation and have been responsible for taking landmark cases in relation to social rights, for example CEPIL’s work in housing rights and eviction. The work of one RAVI beneficiary, WACAM, an association of communities affected by mining, itself encompasses a wide range of human rights abuses perpetuated by multinational gold mining companies, inclusive of violations of civil rights (e.g. violence by private security and Ghanaian security forces), of economic rights (e.g. loss of land and displacement), of environmental rights (e.g. pollution of water supplies by cyanide spills), and of women’s rights (e.g. loss of income through forest degradation). Again, demands are more for state action and inter vention than inaction and deregulation. Democratic participation and collective action Finally, the focus on citizen-government engagement has encouraged democratic participation and collective action and the strengthening of local and national CSOs both individually and collectively. While many RAVI-supported organisa tions have engaged with state duty-bearers through the formal channels of demo cratic representation, especially at local government level, some organisations have also adopted a more direct action approach in advocating for rights. In such ways, new forms of democratic expression and participation have occurred, including in ‘created spaces’ (Cornwall 2002), where like-minded individuals and civil society organisations have come together and created more autonom ous spaces for interaction and political mobilisation. One outcome has been alliance-building and the formation of coalitions, themselves the basis for stronger and more concerted action in pursuit of various rights. One example is the Domestic Violence Coalition (DVC) that successfully campaigned for the passing of a Domestic Violence bill into law. One feature of the DVC was the range of strategies that it utilised in pursuit of its key aim. These entailed a com bination of conventional lobbying of government and various forms of peaceful direct action, including the picketing of parliament, a night vigil, men’s marches and ‘the Teaser’. This latter action involved women, who were dressed in wedding gowns with battered faces and bandages, standing at strategic locations across Accra with placards stating, ‘This could be your wife’, ‘I did not bargain for this when we got married’, ‘I am your partner and not your punch bag’ and so forth. Together, these contributed in drawing attention to the issue of domestic violence in Ghana in an innovative and participatory manner. Such examples
146 G. Crawford and A.-G. Abdulai indicate that, within RAVI at least, CSOs have been valued not simply as coun tervailing forces to state power, but also for their role in advocating for rights realisation by the state and in contributing to democratisation processes through broad-based political participation. The evidence above has suggested ways in which RAVI has moved beyond an orthodox and instrumental approach to civil society, simply perceived as a mechanism for controlling state institutions. In particular, the types of organisa tions supported and the nature of their activities could be construed as attempts to extend popular control over democratic decision-making, albeit mainly at a local and decentralised level. However, there are also a number of limitations and caveats concerning the extent to which RAVI has contributed to this demo cratisation of political life. First, there is the issue of attribution. Although posit ive stories can be told about the activities of RAVI beneficiaries, such success is not necessarily attributable to RAVI’s support and may have happened anyway, especially as some organisations, WACAM for instance, had a significant his tory prior to RAVI funding, with established activities, strategies and networks. While financial support from RAVI was doubtless welcome, it may not have made a substantial difference to the organisation concerned or contributed sig nificantly to its success or effectiveness. Second, RAVI funding has been short- term – two years only. At best, within such a timeframe, only limited progress can be made, with the likelihood that momentum will not be maintained and backsliding may occur after such short-term funding has ceased. Finally, RAVI ended in June 2010, following a decision by DFID not to go ahead with a second phase. A new project, the Ghana Accountability and Responsiveness Initiative (GARI), has replaced both G-RAP and RAVI with multi-donor funding. Is it the case that a project that appears to have contributed to the development of pro gressive political discourses in Ghana around issues of rights, democratic parti cipation and the state as duty-bearer is not actually a donor priority?
Conclusion: democracy promoted or undermined? We have examined two civil society support programmes in Ghana undertaken in the second half of the 2000s by bilateral donor agencies as part of their demo cracy promotion activities, and in doing so have sought to tease out the particu lar concept of civil society that underpins them. In particular we have asked whether these programmes emphasise a liberal democratic and/or a neo-liberal concept of civil society, or alternatively whether they provide evidence of donor support for a more radical model of democratic participation within civil society and popular control over decision-making? Our findings are three-fold. First, the picture is complex and multifaceted, and there is a significant difference between the two programmes. Second, notwithstanding this complexity and diversity, the predominant intent of these programmes, especially G-RAP, is about checking the power of the state. Third, following on from this, we posit that international agencies are not only engaged in reconstructing state-society relations in their own (idealised) Western image but also in their own interests. In this concluding
Liberal democracy and civil society in Ghana 147 section, these three findings are examined in more detail, followed by considera tion of their implications for democracy. First, in examining these recent civil society programmes in Ghana it is appar ent that their organisational coverage is more diverse than in those studied previ ously by Hearn (2001: 24), which were found to have focused narrowly on those CSOs that promoted market-led economic reform. Therefore the picture has become more multifaceted, especially with the introduction of RAVI, although the same proponents of neo-liberal economic policies, such as the Institute of Economic Affairs, continue to feature amongst the largest G-RAP beneficiaries. Differences between RAVI and G-RAP are also evident, ones that suggest some variation in the underlying concept of civil society. Whereas G-RAP assistance was mainly limited to the narrow range of professional and westernised NGOs that are most able to perform a watchdog role and scrutinise state activities, RAVI beneficiaries often play a more positive role in processes of democrat isation through political participation and collective action and in demanding the realisation of human rights by the state. Admittedly, we traced the changes in G-RAP in its provision of support to a somewhat broader range of CSOs, inclu sive of those with a focus on women’s rights and gender relations, but noted that this occurred largely due to the challenges to the programme from a section of Ghanaian civil society itself. In this respect, the content of an externally funded programme has been contested and partly re-shaped by those who were doubt less expected to be grateful and passive recipients. Overall, therefore, we note a degree of difference in the model of civil society that underpins RAVI and G-RAP, with some evidence in RAVI of donor support to a broader-based notion of civil society, with inklings here of a more radical model of democratic parti cipation in which CSOs engage with the state in struggles to secure rights for people living in poverty or otherwise vulnerable. However, such hints of an alternative model of civil society may be short-lived. RAVI was the initiative of one donor agency, the UK’s DFID, and its enthusiasm for human rights and democratic participation has clearly diminished, as indicated by DFID’s decision to discontinue with RAVI. Second, notwithstanding such complexities and degrees of difference, our investigation indicates that the predominant intent of donor programmes is to promote a model of civil society that seeks to limit the state’s power, one char acterised by Baker (2004: 45) as the ‘instrumentalisation’ of civil society. This is demonstrated especially through G-RAP, as well as through the overall context in which both G-RAP and RAVI were introduced, in other words as a com plementary aid mechanism to the Multi-Donor Budget Support provided to the Government of Ghana. The project goals of both G-RAP and RAVI focus on ‘holding government to account for its policy choices’ (G-RAP 2004: 1), and display a negative orientation towards the state. Both projects are underpinned by the assumption that the Government of Ghana cannot be trusted to implement donors’ preferred policy choices, ones that remain economically neo-liberal while being labelled as ‘pro-poor’ (Crawford and Abdulai 2009). Therefore, driven by the fear of state arbitrariness that pervades a liberal perspective, donor
148 G. Crawford and A.-G. Abdulai agencies have turned to civil society organisations as a perceived control mech anism on the state through the provision of inputs into policy-making processes and the scrutiny of policy implementation. There is evidence here that donors’ high regard for the role of CSOs is underpinned by state scepticism and intent to constrain state power and limit state interventionism. Donors’ own external intervention is simultaneously rationalised and legitimised as ensuring that gov ernment delivers pro-poor policy, and the assumption is that CSOs ‘advocate on behalf of the poor and socially excluded in Ghanaian society’ (G-RAP 2004: 1). This rose-tinted view justifies and legitimises the selection and support of par ticular organisations, even though it is highly debatable whether many G-RAP beneficiaries do in fact represent the poor, given that such Accra-based organisa tions mainly operate in central government (and donor) circles, with little or no evidence of collaboration with community-based organisations. What has been evidenced here, especially with G-RAP, is the capacity-building by donors of a narrow set of elite CSOs as the major, large-scale beneficiaries of G-RAP funding, inclusive of all the leading pro-market think-tanks. It would seem that this elite group of G-RAP beneficiaries are perceived as offering the most likely challenge to state power. They may be small in number but, as noted by Caroth ers and Ottaway (2000: 16), such professionalised NGOs can have ‘inordinate influence’ in terms of policy-making, especially in circumstances where govern ment departments are weak and overstretched. Therefore we conclude that the underlying concept of civil society within donor civil society support pro grammes in Ghana is predominantly a liberal one. Returning to our initial dis tinction between a liberal democratic and a neo-liberal approach within an overall liberal model, there is evidence within G-RAP of support for both those organisations that are specifically engaged in the promotion of neo-liberal eco nomic reforms and those that function to limit and control the state more gen erally. The broadening of support within G-RAP suggests that it now displays general liberal democratic characteristics as well as the specific neo-liberal dimension which aims to limit state economic interventionism. Third, such donor intervention in African societies, as exemplified by the case of Ghana, could be construed as an attempt by Western ‘donor’ governments to construct civil society in their own image, motivated ideologically by the notion that this constitutes ‘good governance’ where the state is increasingly held to account by a liberal public sphere or civil society. However, we also detect a more self-interested motivation. Again the context of the transition from the Structural Adjustment era of programmes to that of Poverty Reduction Strategy Papers is critical. Under the rhetoric of ‘country ownership’, donors are less able to impose policy-based conditionality and have to seek other ways to maintain policy influence. One means has been apparent in this study. It entails a two-fold approach. The first aspect involves the requirement by donors that the govern ment show evidence of its engagement with civil society in policy formulation and implementation as part of the ‘triggers’ for the release of MDBS funds (Crawford and Abdulai 2009: 107). The second aspect entails the processes that have been examined in this paper. Through a funding mechanism like G-RAP,
Liberal democracy and civil society in Ghana 149 donor agencies develop a close relationship with selected elite NGOs, to whom they provide substantial core support. Consequently, such NGOs have both the capacity and the status to engage more effectively with government. It is pre cisely these NGOs that are then invited to engage with government, as required by funding ‘triggers’, while other local NGOs and CBOs remain at the margins.11 And thus the circle is complete. We contend that it is through the cultivation of civil society proxies in this manner, alongside donor insistence that government consult with them, that donors aim to retain policy influence and to ensure that government policies remain consistent with their own policy choices, that is, ones that promote economic liberalisation and private sector development.12 Therefore, finally, what are the consequences for democratisation in Ghana of such alleged democracy promotion activities? Some disturbing democratic defi cits are revealed. First, despite being democratically elected, the Government of Ghana remains an object of mistrust, whereas NGOs, who have no democratic credentials and often represent no one but themselves, are regarded as virtuous and pro-poor by Western ‘donor’ governments. Second, the concern for greater government accountability is shared by donors and NGOs alike. Yet, unlike the Government of Ghana, which will be held accountable by its citizens for its per formance at the next elections, donor agencies are entirely unaccountable to Ghanaian citizens, and many NGOs have become increasingly accountable to their external funders rather than to a domestic constituency. Third, G-RAP and RAVI both emphasise the project goal of pro-poor policy implementation by a government that is responsive towards its citizens. Yet attempts by donor agen cies to indirectly influence government economic policy via its civil society champions, notably the G-RAP beneficiaries, is not only profoundly undemo cratic but also demonstrates continuity from the SAP era in undermining demo cracy through the removal of policy sovereignty from national governments.
Notes 1 Van Rooy (1998) has also examined the rise of civil society assistance within development aid more generally, including in democracy promotion. 2 Although a second phase of each was anticipated, this has not happened and they have effectively been replaced by a new project – the Ghana Accountability and Respon siveness Initiative (GARI) – which was being established at the time of writing. 3 For example, Freedom House scores for political rights and civil liberties in Ghana have reached almost the highest level possible in recent years, scoring 1 for political rights and 2 for civil liberties in the 2010 report, where 1 is the highest level of freedom and 7 the lowest (Freedom House 2010). The 2009 Freedom House indic ators for press freedom place Ghana at a higher level than Italy, Greece and Israel, and first equal (with Mali) in Africa (Freedom House 2009). 4 However, there appears to be a significant gap between these pledges and the actual amount disbursed so far, with the total grants awarded as at December 2008 amount ing to US$5,012,741 (see G-RAP 2009: 3). 5 The IEA’s overall orientation toward the neo-liberal development agenda is also apparent in its membership in the Economic Freedom Network and its role as a co- publisher of Freedom House’s annual Economic Freedom of the World report for several years (www.freetheworld.com).
150 G. Crawford and A.-G. Abdulai 6 In addition, fixed ICB grants of $15,000 were regularly awarded to the elite core grantees. 7 In Annex D of the G-RAP Joint Programme Memorandum, two lists of criteria for GRAP eligibility are presented, namely a pre-qualification stage (using 27 criteria) and full qualification (24 criteria pertaining to ‘organisational competencies’). 8 Importantly, these pressures did not go without opposition and contestation by some RAO representatives, as exemplified in a letter from NETRIGHT, itself a gender network, that rejected an offer from G-RAP of an ICB grant: We are also very concerned by the PMT’s [Programme Management Team] attempts to use the promise of capacity building support to force a number of women’s organisations into so-called strategic partnerships. . . . We do not believe that the PMT has the mandate to re-engineer the women’s NGO landscape. Letter of 18/1/05 from NETRIGHT to the PMT, quoted in G-RAP 2007: 41) 9 Interview with official from Royal Netherlands Embassy, Accra, 11 March 2010. 10 Capability is the extent to which leaders and governments are able to get things done. Accountability describes the ability of citizens, civil society and the private sector to scrutinise public institutions and governments and hold them to account. Responsiveness refers to the extent to which public policies and institutions respond to the needs of citizens and uphold their rights. (Holland and Thirkell 2009: 4). 11 One recurrent element in the narrative reports of G-RAP grantees is their attendance at various policy forums initiated by government. This is presented as growing recog nition of the role of civil society in policy formulation and the creation of more space for participatory decision-making. Yet government is forced to invite NGOs to such forums in order to demonstrate to donors that they have engaged with civil society, while NGO grantees have to report to donors about how and when they have engaged with government in policy discourses. Both are responding to donor funding require ments, almost acting out parts in a theatrical performance created by donor agencies. 12 Our findings tend to confirm the views of Ghanaian lawyer and academic, Raymond Atuguba, who bluntly stated: In simple terms, development agencies give money directly to the government, in Ghana through an agency known as the Multi-Donor Budgetary Support (MDBS), and ask them [the government] to spend it on specific programs. They then give money to CSOs and ask the CSOs to watch that the government spends the money on what the government is supposed to spend the money on. The donor countries and development agencies then sit back, relax and watch the fight. That is the rights-based approach to development. (Atuguba 2011:11)
9 Concepts of democracy among donors and recipients of democracy promotion An empirical pilot study Valerie J. Bunce and Sharon L. Wolchik 1 Democracy assistance has been a controversial enterprise since its inception. In addition to doubts about whether states should engage in activities designed to promote the development or strengthening of democracy in other sovereign entities, questions have arisen concerning the effectiveness and overall utility of such actions, as well as the benefits to the providers. For the most part, critics have focused on the practical problems involved in democracy assistance, including the short time horizons of many donors, the bureaucratic nature of reporting requirements, difficulties in identifying and supervising the most appropriate projects and the tendency for a good deal of the funds involved to be spent on consultants and administrative costs in the donor countries. Other analysts have highlighted the impact of asymmetries in money, know-how, and therefore power which have characterized the relationship between donors and recipients in many cases, as well as the lack of knowledge of local conditions and the resulting inapplicability of suggested techniques that have plagued some efforts to provide democracy assistance (For example, see: Barany and Moser 2009; Wedel 2009; Guilhot 2005; Traub 2008 and McFaul 2010). Still others have noted the dependence of local NGOs involved in democracy promotion on foreign funding and the tendency such funding has had to create a web of NGOs that have little connection to their populations and are, in fact, heads without bodies that exist largely to take advantage of funding opportunities and provide employment for well-educated, generally young, urbanites in the recipient coun tries (for example, see: Hendersen 2002; Cooley and Ron 2002; Green 2007; Green and Kohl 2007; Finkel et al. 2006). However, very few have examined, especially in a systematic way, the extent to which there are, in addition, deeper issues that affect democracy assistance, that is, differences in the conceptions of what democracy is, and therefore, of what is needed to promote it, on the part of providers and recipients of democracy assistance (for example, see: Barany and Moser 2009). As the editors of this volume note in their introduction, such dif ferences may be important not only in the realm of ideas but also in terms of the concrete actions different groups of actors take in an effort to promote what they perceive to be democracy, and therefore the practical outcome of democracy assistance efforts. They may also have an impact on the success of efforts to establish or strengthen democracy in particular contexts.
152 V. J. Bunce and S. L. Wolchik This chapter attempts to address this issue by focusing on the perspectives of providers and recipients of democracy assistance in the post-communist world. We chose to focus on this region in part because of our own expertise, but also because of a larger project we have conducted over the past six years on demo cratizing elections in post-communist Europe and Eurasia. It is also merited by the fact that from 1990 to 2005 the post-communist region was the largest recipient of US government democracy assistance (see also Finkel et al. 2006; Bunce and Wolchik 2006). We approach this chapter, as we did the larger project from which our sample was drawn, from the perspective of empirical social scientists trained at the University of Michigan who have each spent over three decades focusing on the politics of communist and then post-communist regimes in Europe, as well as on various aspects of democratization. We also draw on our familiarity with and interactions with both democracy promoters in Washington DC and in the field, and recipients of such assistance in the field over the last 20 years. In our earlier study, we focused on the wave of democratizing elections in the post-communist world that began with the ousting of Vladimir Meciar in Slovakia in 1998, moved to Croatia where the successors of Franjo Tudjman were defeated and to Serbia where Slobodan Milosevic was ousted in 2000, Georgia in 2003, Ukraine in 2004, and Kyrgyzstan in 2005. We also examined efforts to use elections to unseat semi-authoritarian rulers that failed in Belarus, Armenia and Azerbaijan (Bunce and Wolchik 2010, 2011). As part of this project, we conducted approximately 200 in-depth interviews with participants involved in these elections, including US and European demo cracy assistance providers, US embassy and government officials, officers of US and European NGOs active in the region, and political leaders, NGO activists, academic analysts, and others in the countries under study. Although parts of these interviews touched on democracy promotion and its effectiveness, we did not explicitly ask our respondents about their views concerning the meaning of democracy. While our conclusions are thus informed by the understanding of how democracy promotion works at the center and on the ground from the per spectives of a variety of actors in numerous countries, we cannot use these elite interviews directly to address the questions examined in this chapter or the broader volume of which it is a part. Instead, we used those interviews as a pool of respondents to whom we sent an email questionnaire specifically focused on this aspect of democracy promotion, as well as on perceived problems with such activities. It is this subset of our interviews that forms the basis for our analysis of concepts of democracy in this chapter. Since our interviewees for the larger project as well as this chapter were by no means selected randomly but rather for their roles in the elections we were analyzing, our conclusions cannot be gen eralized to all providers and recipients of democracy assistance in the post- communist world or even those in the countries we studied. This is particularly true for the responses we received through our email questionnaire, as the rapid turnover of democracy assistance, embassy, and NGO personnel both in the US and abroad made it difficult to contact all of those we interviewed over the six
An empirical pilot study 153 years of our larger project. The small size of our sample is yet another reason why the results we discuss cannot be generalized. Our results, therefore, should be seen as a pilot study that can highlight patterns that can be investigated more thoroughly and systematically in later research with larger samples. However, as with other types of qualitative evidence, such interviews can provide insight that is difficult to obtain via more structured survey research. We also hope that this study will provide an illustration of how such research can be conducted more systematically in the future. The central question we focus on in this chapter is how providers and recipients conceptualize democracy. In other words, are there any consistent differ ences in these conceptions across countries that differentiate the two groups? After analyzing responses to an open-ended question about the meaning of democracy among our elite sample, we then turn to conceptions concerning the largest obstacles to democratic development and respondents’ views concerning the biggest problems in democracy assistance. We also discuss the impact of participation in democracy assistance on the way providers and recipients view democracy. In our discussion of conceptions of democracy and problems with democracy assistance, we compare our findings briefly with several larger-scale studies of elite and citizen conceptions of democracy and a recent survey of the views of democracy assistance recipients on problems with such assistance. We conclude with observations about what our study tells us about the broader questions of interest in this volume, including the possible consequences of our findings for the effectiveness of democracy promotion, as well as fruitful areas for further research.
Methodology and hypotheses In order to assess possible differences in conceptions of democracy we used a variant of an open-ended question used by several other researchers (For example, see: Miller et al. 1997; Dalton et al. 2007; see Appendix in this chapter for questions and nature of the sample). In analyzing the responses we received, we used the three general categories Russell Dalton et al. (2007) used in their synthetic analysis of a number of large-scale surveys of citizens’ conceptions of democracy.2 Thus, we categorized responses as falling into those that emphas ized: (l) freedom, (2) the rules of the game and institutional aspects of demo cracy, and (3) social/economic benefits as the primary meaning of democracy. The first two categories both fit within what can be termed a liberal definition of democracy, while the latter is consistent with a socialist or social democratic definition. In addition to tables presenting summaries of our results, we have also included excerpts from the responses we received in order to provide a better sense of the nature of the responses of different groups and to allow readers to ‘hear’ the ‘voices’ of some of those we interviewed. Our research was guided by several hypotheses. First, since all respondents in our sample were involved in democracy assistance, which included interaction with donors on the part of recipients as well as work on the part of both to
154 V. J. Bunce and S. L. Wolchik further democracy, we did not expect to find large differences in how those in the two groups conceptualized democracy. This expectation was bolstered by another aspect of our sample. Since we had what was in effect an elite sample, we expected that there would be less difference in the responses of donors and recipients of democracy assistance than if we had compared samples of ordinary citizens in both groups of countries. This expectation was based on the well- documented finding that elites tend to have political values and attitudes closer to the official or unofficial ‘ideologies’ of their societies than mass publics. We were also interested in the views of those individuals who had originally been recipients of democracy assistance who went on to provide democracy assistance to others in the post-communist region. We hypothesized that the views of these respondents, whom we identify as recipient-donors in the discussion that follows, would be closer to those of ‘Western’ donors, due to the fact that, as active participants in providing democracy assistance to others, they had higher levels of interaction with donor organizations over several years or even decades. On the other hand, since these individuals were part of the same soci eties as other recipients of assistance and had shared many of the experience of living under communism as well as common efforts to transform their political, social, and economic systems, it seemed possible that their concepts of demo cracy and views of what was problematic with democracy assistance would more closely resemble those of other recipients. Alternatively, since these respondents did in fact have a foot in both worlds, we thought it possible that their views would fall somewhere in between those of providers and respondents who received democracy assistance. Their role in bridging the two groups, in fact, was one that was often noted in our earlier interviews with people in this cat egory, who often emphasized the advantages their experience in successfully ousting semi-authoritarian rulers and prior to that living under communism gave them in working with groups and individuals trying to do the same thing (Bunce and Wolchik 2011: ch. 10). In respect to views regarding the greatest obstacles to democratic development in recipient countries, we expected both providers and recipients of assistance to identify domestic, or internal, issues as the primary impediments. This expectation derived from the generally shared consensus that domestic factors remain the most important determinants of democratic progress, despite the important role of the external environment and actions of external actors in supporting or threatening such development. We also expected few systematic differences in donor and recipient views of the main problems with democracy assistance. At the same time, we thought that recipients would be more likely, given the asymmetry of power and resources involved, to identify problems related to the actions of external actors than those actors themselves.
Conceptions of democracy As Table 9.1 illustrates, the largest number of our respondents (16 of 36) defined democracy primarily in institutional terms. Nine or 25 percent of respondents
An empirical pilot study 155 Table 9.1 Conceptions of democracy Institutions
Freedom
Mixed
Social/economic Total
Donors Recipients
8 = 80% 8 = 30.8%
l = 10% 8 = 30.8%
l = 10% 10 = 38.9%
0 0
10 = 100% 26 = 100%
Total
16 = 44.4%
9 = 25%
11 = 30.6%
0
36 = 100%
identified freedoms of various sorts as the central element of what democracy meant to them. Eleven or 30.6 percent gave replies that we have classified as mixed, which included responses that fell into more than one category. The majority of the latter mentioned some combination of institutional features and freedoms. Only two of our respondents mentioned economic security or prosperity at all, and none of these put this factor first. Thus, almost all of our respondents shared some variant of a liberal democratic concept of democracy. Our analysis thus deals largely with variations within this common conception. The response of a US official who worked in Kyrgyzstan was typical of those who identified institutional factors and rules of the game as central to their concept of democracy: ‘Citizenship participation in government and decision making. The ability of the citizenry to hold the government accountable.’ An NGO activist in Kyrgyzstan emphasized similar dimensions. ‘Democracy,’ he noted, is accountability of the government to civil society and merit-based selection of the national and sub-national leaders. This democratic accountability makes anti-corruption efforts and economic planning much easier and more effective than is the case under less transparent authoritarian regimes. In short, I see democratic governance as an effective tool for gradual eradication of pervasive corruption and for improvement of decision-making in economic planning and foreign policy. A Georgian NGO activist also highlighted accountability, stating: ‘At its simplest, a government that is accountable and the possibility of a peaceful transition of power, as determined by the electorate.’ A US donor who worked in Georgia had a response that paralleled the first part of this observation, noting that ‘Democracy means the rules by which the state operates are written and available for all to see. That periodically the people choose who will govern them, and that citizens have some specified rights.’ Yet another donor active in Serbia also focused on transparency: ‘Democracies are transparent participatory pluralistic systems of governance with many varied, informed, and mobilized interest actors actively engaged in decision making. Over time, they generate superior policy outcomes.’ Those whose responses fell into the ‘freedom’ category, on the other hand, identified features such as the ability of the individual to chart his or her own course, individual choice, and freedoms of speech, assembly, and travel as key
156 V. J. Bunce and S. L. Wolchik to their understanding of democracy. The response of a US official who worked in Armenia was typical of this category: Democracy is less about elections (the practice of democracy) but about instilling a culture that the individual has a sacred and powerful tool in the vote that he or she casts to determine his or her future. As a result, there is a distinct correlation between democracy and freedom. Freedom or liberty is the hallmark of a democratic society. The response of a US donor active in a number of post-communist countries was more specific, noting that democracy means A clear balance of rights and responsibilities between the rulers and ruled—a series of individual and collective rights: assembly, speech, confession, commerce, fair and transparent legal treatment and responsible gov ernment. But also the responsibility to take active part to ensure these rights are safeguarded and take an active part in the society you live in. Still another respondent linked democracy to professional freedom: For me personally, democracy means freedom to deliver lectures on sensitive political issues without any fear of the KGB informers from among students sitting in a classroom. It also means freedom of travel abroad and participation in different international cooperation projects, defending my rights, and support political force according to my own consideration. A recipient in Serbia who later became a democracy promoter also emphasized freedom as the key dimension of democracy, noting that democracy ‘means freedom of choice . . . it means freedom of speech and movement, in the social aspect it means freedom of different opinion and behavior, politically it means that THOSE WHO VOTE decide about the election results, instead of THOSE WHO COUNT VOTES. . . .’ Referring to the ‘democratic revolutions’ in Serbia, Georgia and Ukraine,’ this respondent noted that the ‘MAJOR FOUNDATION of those revolutions’ was that FOREVER you will have the free and fair elections. . . . Fair elections itself, are of course the FIRST STEP. Non violent movements mobilize huge numbers of people and participating in nonviolent movement often changes (the) way people see themselves . . . So in short freedom of choice + free and fair elections + developed active citizenship. An NGO activist in Armenia stated: For me, personally, democracy means – somewhat vaguely perhaps – altern atives, choice between the good and the better in all walks of life; it means
An empirical pilot study 157 an avenue of resolving internal and external conflicts in a peaceful, non- violent manner; it means enablement of people’s talents and strengths and a way of shunning violent manner; it means enablement of people’s talents and strengths. Eleven of our respondents gave replies that we categorized as mixed, i.e., that combined two or more of the categories we used. All but two of these responses combined institutional factors and freedom. As noted earlier, all but one of these respondents were either recipients or recipient-donors. The one US donor whose response fell into this category, who had worked in Slovakia, focused on the role of citizens in politics, but also mentioned freedom of expression, noting that Democracy means that the people have a direct role in shaping their govern ment. This requires that they have equality of treatment and opportunity before the law and the ability to express their opinions freely and without fear of reprisal. This requires an effective rule of law and a media not controlled by the government. The brief response of an NGO activist in Ukraine reflects a perspective common to many of the responses we classified as mixed: ‘Fair elections, freedom of expression, protection of citizens’ rights and freedoms.’ A recipient-donor in Armenia gave a similarly mixed response: Democracy is associated with accountability, responsibility, freedom of expression, access to diverse sources of information (including state-owned information), availability of channels to tangibly influence a decision- making process on various levels, equality before the law, lack of fear of state/clan punishment, political and economic stability . . . and progress. An NGO activist in Ukraine noted, ‘To make it short – I share more or less lib eral idea of democracy with political competition, rule of law and freedom of speech.’ A recipient in Kyrgyzstan noted similar factors: ‘Rule of law. Laws recognized generally as respecting all basic individual freedoms and rights.’ A Slovak NGO activist who fell into the recipient-donor category noted: For me democracy means: stable rules for public life on the base of political legitimacy, people’s involvement (including myself ) into public life and governance, protection of human rights, including freedom of expression, academic freedom etc., protection of minorities, free participation in public debate, ability to influence governance, rule of law. Very few (two of 36) of our respondents gave responses that in any way mentioned social and/or economic benefits as central to their concept of democracy, and none of our respondents listed such benefits first. Rather, reference to social and economic well-being was the second or third aspect mentioned. The
158 V. J. Bunce and S. L. Wolchik response of an NGO activist in Azerbaijan reflected this pattern, noting that democracy means ‘Equal opportunities of access to power and resources to all people, tolerance, political pluralism, fair elections.’ A recipient-donor in Azerbaijan also mentioned economic stability and progress, but these elements were secondary to others that focused on accountability of government and freedom of expression. As we will discuss more fully later, this finding is not surprising, given the elite nature of our sample. It is also consistent with the findings of the surveys of citizens’ conceptions of democracy that Russell Dalton et al. (2007) analyzed, which contradict many early expectations about how postcommunist citizens would understand democracy. As Table 9.1 illustrates, our initial hypothesis that donors and recipients would not differ greatly in their concepts of democracy was only partly supported by our data. Both donors and recipients, as well as recipient-donors, identified institutional factors or freedoms as central to their concepts of democracy, and for none in any of these categories were social/economic benefits crucial. As Table 9.1 illustrates, institutional factors were paramount for respondents in all categories aside from the recipient-donor category. As we noted in the introduction to this chapter, the nature of our sample and the small number of respondents require caution in generalizing from our findings. But, while our study should be seen as a pilot of what a larger, more systematic study might confirm or dispute, our findings do suggest a number of possible explanations for the prevalence of this focus on institutional factors. Thus, donors and recipients may share a focus on institutional features of democracy due to the emphasis both elites and ordinary citizens place on elections and the ability of citizens to choose their leaders as central elements of democracy,3 irrespective of country or other aspects of context. Such an explanation would support the view that democratic norms have become widespread in the modern world, even in the semi-authoritarian contexts in which many of our recipients work or worked prior to the ousting of a semi-authoritarian leader. The focus on institutional aspects of democracy among donors and recipients, however, may reflect another factor, and that is the nature of democracy assistance. Here, we refer, for example, to the tendency for both US and other international donors to focus on elections as pivotal events and provide funds, training, and other forms of assistance to try to ensure free and fair elections, encourage opposi tions to run energetic and effective campaigns, and facilitate efforts by NGOs to organize voter registration drives and get-out-the-vote campaigns, public opinion and exit polls, and, if elections are stolen, mass protests in support of the opposi tion. This possibility may be especially likely in our sample, since it was drawn from those individuals we interviewed who were involved as donors and recipients of assistance in the course of democratizing elections that tried and in some cases succeeded in ousting semi-authoritarian leaders and in others tried but failed to do so. Thus, even though the US has been more likely to fund civil society activities over the long-term in these societies than European donors, US officials and NGO representatives also were highly focused on elections and voter choice during the events we studied. The fact that our findings differ from the tendency Dalton et al. (2007) found among mass publics in a variety of nations, including the US as well
An empirical pilot study 159 as several post-communist European countries, for more respondents to identify freedoms as central to their concepts of democracy than institutional factors (Dalton et al. 2007: 146, 152ff.) supports this conclusion, as the professional focus of both donors and recipients may counter the tendency to emphasize freedoms. At the same time, it is striking that a much larger proportion of donors than recipients identified institutional factors as key to their concepts of democracy (80 percent versus 30.8 percent). It is also striking that only a single respondent in the donor group gave an answer that featured freedoms, in addition to another respondent whose response included freedoms as well as institutional factors. This difference is open to a number of interpretations. It may be that donors, who have grown up in as well as lived for much of their lives in democratic soci eties, are more likely to take the existence of basic democratic freedoms for granted. Recipients of democracy assistance, on the other hand, who live in soci eties that either were until recently or are still not free, may see these aspects of democracy as more critical as the result of their experiences in less than free societies. It may also be that recipients are more likely to reflect the emphasis on freedoms found among mass publics. In Table 9.2, we divide our sample into three categories instead of two, which allows us to examine the views of a crucial category of respondents, those who were initially recipients of democracy assistance and later went on to be demo cracy promoters (recipient-donors) (see Table 9.2). These ‘graduates’, as we have called them in our previous work, are those who, having succeeded, with outside assistance, in bringing about democratic breakthroughs through elections in their own countries, were funded to share their experiences and help train activists in other countries who wanted to emulate their success. There were eight such individuals in our sample. As we discussed at the outset, we origin ally anticipated that their views would be closer to those of donors than to those of recipients of aid, given the fact that numerous ‘graduates’ have worked with US funders for several years or even a decade. Alternatively, since they have lived in the post-communist world and thus have shared the experiences of other recipients of democracy assistance, it is possible that their views will be closer to those of the latter category. In fact, as Table 9.2 illustrates, the concepts of democracy of this category of our respondents, the recipient-donors, appear to resemble those of other recipients more than those of donors. Thus, like other recipients, recipient-donors were considerably less likely than donors to identify institutional factors alone as key to their concepts of democracy. As was the case with other recipients, their responses were more evenly distributed between institutional, freedom, or mixed institutional/freedom categories. The small size of this group in particular cautions against attributing too much importance to the distribution of their responses. However, it is interesting that, contrary to what one might expect, given the emphasis on institutional aspects among donors and the higher level of interaction among donors and recipient-donors, recipient-donors are less likely than those who were only recipients to identify institutional aspects of demo cracy as key.
160 V. J. Bunce and S. L. Wolchik Table 9.2 Conceptions of democracy: donors, recipients, recipient-donors Institutions Freedom
Mixed
Social/economic Total
Donors 8 = 80% l = 10% Recipients 6 = 33.3% 5 = 27.8% Recipient-Donors 2 = 25% 3 = 37.5%
l = 10% 0 7 = 38.9% 0 3 = 37.5% 0
10 = 100% 18 = 100% 8 = 100%
Total
11 = 30.6% 0
36 = 100%
16 = 44.4% 9 = 25%
Main obstacles to democratic development Although not the central focus of our investigation for this chapter, we also asked respondents to share their views concerning the main obstacles to demo cratic development and main problems with democracy assistance. We were particularly interested here in the extent to which donors and recipients might assign different weights to internal versus external factors as impediments to democratic development. As Table 9.3 illustrates, most respondents identified internal problems or factors as the main impediments to democratic progress. These responses parallel those found by Joel Barkan, who in a recent study of how recipients viewed democracy assistance conducted for the National Endowment for Democracy found that most respondents identified internal factors as the most significant obstacles to democratic development in their countries.4 Thus, only two of our respondents identified external factors as the main impediment, and approximately 20 percent listed both internal and external factors. There is, however, an interesting difference among donors and recipients in the extent to which they view external factors as key impediments to demo cratic development. Although only two of our respondents felt that external factors alone were key, over twice as many recipients as donors viewed such factors as well as internal issues as critical. Given the greater exposure of recipient-donors to the donor community, as well as their greater experience in general with democracy assistance, we anticipated that recipients who went on to work as democracy promoters would be more likely than other recipients to be aware of and identify problems stemming from external factors as key. As Table 9.4 illustrates, the only two responses that listed these factors alone did in fact come from respondents in Table 9.3 Main obstacles to democratic development, donors and all recipients Internal
External
Both
Total
Donors Recipients
9 = 90% 18 = 69.2%
– 2 = 7.6%
1 = 10% 6 = 23.1%
10 26
Total
27 = 75%
2 = 5.6%
7 = 19.4%
36
An empirical pilot study 161 Table 9.4 Main obstacles to democratic development, donors, recipients, recipient-donors Internal
External
Both
Total
Donors Recipients Recipient-Donors
9 = 90% 12 = 66.6% 6 = 75%
– – 2 = 25%
1 = 10% 6 = 33.3% –
10 18 8
Total
27
2
7
36
this category. However, recipient-donors were less likely than other recipients to identify a combination of internal and external factors as major impediments and more likely than those who were only recipients to focus on internal factors alone. As Table 9.5, which breaks both internal and external impediments down farther, illustrates, respondents most frequently identified problems with political culture in the country, lack of preconditions for democratic development, and aspects of history, including the legacy of communism and Soviet rule, as the primary impediments to democratic development. Problems stemming from weak institutions and bad governance were next. Smaller numbers of respondents identified corruption and vested interests, the behavior of political elites, expectation overload or problems with the democratization paradigm leading to popular disappointment with democracy as critical impediments. Relatively few respondents linked problems with democratic development to economic factors, either poverty or lack of development, or, conversely, the presence of too many resources (energy).
Table 9.5 Main obstacles to democratic development by category of response internal Internal Political culture, lack of preconditions, history Weak institutions, bad governance Corruption, vested interests Political elites Weak civil society Expectations overload/problems with democratization paradigm Poverty/lack of development Resources (resource curse) External Lack of commitment of external powers/vested interest in status quo Problems with democratization strategy, attitudes Economic and political crisis of the developed world Geopolitical environment Russia Note All responses given by respondents were categorized.
26 15 7 5 5 4 3 1 4 2 1 1 1
162 V. J. Bunce and S. L. Wolchik Lack of commitment to promoting democracy, unwillingness to challenge violations of democratic norms, and a vested interest on the part of external actors in the status quo were the most frequently mentioned external factors impeding democratic development. Other respondents mentioned problems with the democratization strategy and attitudes of those involved in democracy assistance as key. Single respondents identified the global economic and political crisis, the geopolitical environment of a particular country, and a single external actor (Russia) as significant. The response of a donor active in Armenia illustrates the impact given to political attitudes and beliefs by many of our respondents among both donors and recipients: Explaining to people that they should defy attempts to bribe or intimidate them for their votes is difficult because most people who do not live in a democratic culture do not see their own political power, but are worried about the short-term, tangible reality of feeding their families. If someone offers them money for their vote, it makes no logical sense for them not to take the deal. Moreover, in countries with strong, imposing governments, it is difficult for the individual to believe that his vote makes any difference . . . for the democracy developer, the challenge is two-fold: creating a culture in which people feel empowered democratically, and being at odds with a gov ernment structure that feels threatened by the empowerment of its own people. Another donor respondent, who also emphasized popular attitudes, in this case the lack of ‘widespread social acceptance of short-term sacrifices for long-term gain,’ as a key obstacle, noted that in post-communist countries this unwillingness was ‘likely exacerbated by hearing the “sacrifice for long-term goals” song and dance from the communists as well’. A recipient from Ukraine, whose response fell into the same category, noted that Politics in the region works like the used car market – the less honest you are, the faster you get to the top. So acting in accordance with the principles mentioned above [democratic principles] makes one look a stupid loser [who is thus] in need of special training. Still others specified certain political values and attitudes as key impediments. A recipient who later became a donor from Slovakia included ethnic nationalism, as well as a ‘low level of democratic political culture, adherence of [a] big portion of the population to non-democratic values,’ and corruption and ‘murky interlinks between politics and business’ as impediments. Institutional factors most commonly mentioned included lack of division of powers, election mechanisms that did not work to transfer power, and problems with or the lack of the rule of law. The response of a donor in Armenia identified, in addition to corruption and the low level of democratic values in society, ‘the
An empirical pilot study 163 attitude that a group of power holders (visible and invisible) are considered as ‘the only players in town,’ and lack of channels of influence’. Those who identified elite behaviors as key impediments most frequently noted the lack of commitment of supposedly democratic elites to democracy or the actions of authoritarian governments as key. The response of a recipient active in the NGO world in Georgia captured the first perspective very succinctly: ‘Saakashvili’. A recipient from Kyrgyzstan couched his views in somewhat more general terms: ‘In [the] post-Soviet context, the factor of personality is [a] crucial one. Empirical observation suggests that strong presidents in post- Soviet society abuse their power.’ A donor active in Kyrgystan identified, ‘Opposition to power-sharing by those in power and reluctance by leaders of developing states to follow through on commitments (e.g., ICCPR, OSCE) as elements of elite behavior detrimental to democratic development.’ Perceived problems with the democratization paradigm were well-captured by the response of a recipient from Georgia who noted the biggest obstacle for democracy development is the [sic] democratization. The paradigm of this 30 years’ process was one sided. It made too much stress on promotion of competition, without enough stress on cooperation, but the version of competition that developed in effect is zero-sum, which is a version of chaos, rather than that of democracy. . . . Societies may become very unhappy with chaos and prefer some forms of dictatorship stability instead. A recipient from Armenia voiced similar perspectives, identifying ‘cynicism about democracy and its genuineness’ as the main impediment: Many people believe that democracy is, by and large, a myth, and even those countries that are believed to be democracies stage and stage- manage their democratic theatre. The reason for this extreme view of democracy lies in the very literal and absolute comprehension of what democracy is. Over the years various domestic and international actors have presented democracy in such lofty, supernatural, maybe even ‘divine’ terms that a huge capabilities-expectations gap has emerged in developing countries, resulting in unrealistic hopes of democracy being a panacea to all pains of the world. . . . In other words, the propaganda of what might be called textbook democracy has bred vast socio- psychological problems among the population of authoritarian and semi- authoritarian countries . . . The response of a donor active in Georgia was typical of those who identified elite behaviors and values as key impediments: ‘patrimonial elites, and a disconnect between the preferences of the electorate and the projections and intuitions of the political elite, including the opposition’. The response of a recipient from Georgia captured the sentiments of the few respondents who
164 V. J. Bunce and S. L. Wolchik mentioned social or economic issues as impediments to democratic development: I think it is difficult to think of democratic development as separate from development in general. Poverty eradication, equal and fair distribution of wealth and other issues related to economic development are directly related to democratic development. . . . So I think that democratic development should be understood in the wider context of development where all aspects of economic and social development are paid attention to. As noted earlier, most of our respondents, both donors and recipients, identified internal factors as the primary impediments to democratic development. Recipients were more likely than donors to include external as well as internal impediments in their responses, and it was only two recipients who later became donors who gave answers that focused only on external factors. The one donor who also included external factors and who was active in Kyrgyzstan identified the ‘general lack of support for democratic development, compared to other strategic interests such as security, military, energy’ as key. As Table 9.5 illustrates, lack of commitment on the part of outside actors and their unwillingness to hold governments accountable for violations of demo cratic procedures were the primary external impediments identified. The response of a recipient in Georgia put this view very succinctly: ‘In general, in the post-Communist countries like Georgia, the biggest obstacle is the ignoring from the international community of violations of fairness of the elections and human rights.’ A recipient from Azerbaijan, who also identified post- Soviet legacies as a key impediment, echoed the response of the US donor whose response we discussed above: ‘vested external interests in the energy resources.’ The responses of the two recipient-donors who identified solely external factors merit further discussion, as they were the only ones in our sample who did not include internal factors among the key impediments to democratic development. The first of these, from a recipient in Slovakia, identified the eco nomic and political crisis in the developed world as the key impediment. The second, from Serbia, gave an extended answer that identified the lack of capability of ‘democratic leaders’ of the world . . . to agree on a concept and focus for democracy promotion and the tendency of other regional or energy interests of such leaders to conflict with their commit ment to democracy assistance, the lack of international focus on pro- democracy nonviolent struggles, the lack of follow up after democratic breakthroughs have taken place, the lack of a ‘scientific approach’ and coordination of scientific research concerning democratic struggles and misconceptions about such struggles, in particular, the depiction of demo cratic movements as ‘tools of the west’ by authoritarian leaders as impediments.
An empirical pilot study 165
Greatest problems with democracy assistance Although our primary concern in this chapter has been with conceptions of democracy, we were also interested to see if there were differences between donors and recipients in terms of their perceptions of the most problematic aspects of democracy assistance. In fact, as Table 9.6 illustrates, the largest number of respondents identified issues with the goals or nature of democracy assistance as the most important problem with such assistance, a factor that is very closely related to conceptions of democracy. This category was followed closely by the neglect of local circumstances or poor understanding of local challenges. A nearly equal number identified some aspect of the domestic situation which complicated the process or made democracy assistance less effective. Lack of flexibility and administrative problems associated with democracy assistance were mentioned by nearly a fifth of all respondents, followed closely by the characteristics of those engaged in democracy assistance and by issues related to the time frame of assistance. Other issues, including those related to the sincerity of the effort to promote democracy, corruption, the amount of assistance, and the lack of legitimacy of the West, as well as a conflict between politics and neutrality, and lack of attention to civil society were mentioned, but by only one or two respondents. Given the numbers of respondents in our sample and the large number of cat egories we have used to summarize their comments, it is difficult to draw many meaningful conclusions concerning differences between donors and recipients. Perhaps the most suggestive difference lies in the fact that higher proportions of recipients than donors identified problems with the goals of democracy Table 9.6 Biggest problems respondents have encountered with democracy assistance Total respondents Number Percent Goals and nature of democracy assistance 11 Neglect of local circumstances, poor 10 understanding of challenges Domestic conditions in receiving country 9 Lack of flexibility, coordination, bureaucracy 7 Characteristics of assisters 6 Time frame of assistance 5 Lack of conditionality and will to change, 3 cooperation with government Corruption 2 Amount of assistance 2 Decreased legitimacy of the West 2 Conflict between political goals and neutrality 1 Lack of attention to civil society 1
Recipients █
Number Percent
30.5 27.7
8 8
30.8 30.8
25 19.4 16.7 13.8 8.3
5 5 7 3 2
19.2 19.2 26.9 11.5 7.6
5.5 5.5 5.5 2.8 2.8
2 2 2 1 1
7.6 7.6 7.6 3.8 3.8
Note Percentages do not add to 100 as respondents were free to name as many problems as they wished.
166 V. J. Bunce and S. L. Wolchik assistance, neglect of local conditions, and bureaucratic/administrative issues as problems. Donors were somewhat, but not significantly, more likely to identify factors related to the domestic situation of the recipient country as critical. It is also interesting that only recipients identified the decreased legitimacy of the West, corruption, and amount of assistance, as well as the lack of conditionality and real will to change, as problematic. Recipients who later became donors offered responses that were less clustered than either of the other groups. The single largest response category for this group (two responses) focused on bur eaucratic/administrative problems. Interestingly enough, none of the recipients who later became donors gave responses related to the goals or nature of demo cracy assistance. These results provide both parallels and contrasts to the recent email survey of recipients of democracy assistance Joel Barkan conducted for NED. Barkan asked a question that differed from ours to some degree (‘What are the two most common mistakes that providers of democracy assistance often make when assisting organizations such as yours?’). Nonetheless, we can combine some of his categories to approximate several of our categories. The largest single cat egory of ‘mistakes’, or problems recipients who participated in the NED survey had with democracy assistance, involved timing, both the length of time it took to reach recipients and the length of time of funding. The second category of ‘mistakes’ consisted of the administrative and reporting requirements of funders, a category we have termed bureaucratic/administrative problems. Nearly a fifth of ‘mistakes’ identified dealt with issues we have re-classified as related to the goals of democracy assistance. Issues related to neglect of local conditions and the amount of financial assistance accounted for approximately a fifth of the responses, and a very small proportion with the inappropriateness of technical assistance.5 In order to facilitate comparison of our results with those of Barkan, we have provided results for recipients only as well as for all of our respondents in Table 9.6. If we look at this category, several contrasts stand out between our findings and those of the NED survey. Our recipients were more likely than those in NED’s much larger sample to identify problems with the goals and nature of democracy assistance as problematic. They were nearly twice as likely as NED’s respondents to identify neglect of local circumstances as a key problem and less likely to mention problems related to the amount of funding. Our recipients were less likely to list problems with timing, the most frequently mentioned category in the NED survey, as key. In addition, approximately a fifth of our respondents identified issues related to domestic conditions and over a quarter characteristics of those involved in democracy assistance as key problems, categories not found in the NED study. These differences may relate to the fact that we did not restrict our respondents to only two issues, as the NED survey did. But they may also reflect the fact that the Barkan survey was conducted under the auspices of NED, one of the primary providers of democracy assistance around the world. Even though respondents were assured of anonymity, some may have nonetheless been hesitant to be too critical of the goals of democracy assistance, or mention
An empirical pilot study 167 objectionable characteristics of those engaged in democracy assistance. Our respondents showed no such hesitancy. As with all of our conclusions, further research is needed to determine whether these differences would also be evident in a larger study that included respondents from other world areas, as the NED survey did.
Impact of participation in democracy assistance on conceptions of democracy The final question we were interested in was the impact of participation in demo cracy assistance on participants’ concepts of democracy. We anticipated that participation in these endeavors might lead to such change, given the daily work such assistance involves in dealing with various aspects of democracy and obs tacles to it. As Table 9.7, which summarizes the responses of donors and recipients to the question of how such participation influenced their concepts of democracy, illustrates, the largest group of our respondents indicated that their concepts had in fact changed in some way as the result of their participation in democracy assistance. These changes were particularly evident among donors, 80 percent of whom indicated that their concepts of democracy had changed, compared to 57.7 percent of recipients. A somewhat larger proportion of recipients who later became donors (62.5 percent) than of all recipients as a group indicated that their participation in democracy promotion had changed their concepts of democracy, but this difference was not great. Most of those in all cat egories who indicated that their concepts of democracy had changed stated that they had become more realistic and more appreciative of local conditions than they had been prior to their participation in democracy promotion (see also Youngs’ chapter). Of those who indicated that their concept of democracy had changed, approximately 70 percent of all respondents, including 88 percent of all donors and 80 percent of all recipient-donors, compared to 60 percent of all recipients indicated that they had become more realistic about the chances for democracy. Only one donor and one recipient-donor, compared to five of all recipients, indicated that the nature of their concept of democracy had changed. A single respondent, a recipient, stated that he had become more optimistic about the chances for democracy as the result of his participation in democracy assistance (see Table 9.8.)
Table 9.7 Impact of participation in democracy assistance on concepts of democracy Total
Donors
Recipients
Recipient-Donors
Not at all Changed No answer
11 (30.6%) 23 (63.9%) 2 (5.6%)
2 (20%) 8 (80%) –
9 (34.6%) 15 (57.7%) 2 (7.6%)
2 (25%) 5 (62.5%) 1 (12.5%)
Total
36
10
26
8
168 V. J. Bunce and S. L. Wolchik Table 9.8 Type of change in concept of democracy as the result of participation in democracy assistance among those whose concepts changed Total
Donors
Recipients
Recipient-Donors
More realistic 16 (69.3%) More optimistic 1 (4.3%) Change in nature of concept 6 (26.1%)
7 (87.5%) – 1 (12.5%)
9 (60%) 1 (6.7%) 5 (33.3)
4 (80%) – 1 (20%)
Total
8 (100%)
15 (101%)
5 (100%)
23 (99.7%)
These results, which, as with our other results, stand in need of being confirmed by a study with a larger sample, at the very least suggest that the concepts of donors are more affected by participation in democracy promotion than are those of recipients of such assistance. The fact that the perspectives of donors and recipients who become donors are closer than those of recipients as a group, particularly among those whose concepts changed, is particularly suggestive as it may reflect higher expectations on the part of donors prior to their experience with democracy assistance, and/or the impact of additional experience on the perspectives of recipients who later become donors.
Conclusions As we noted at the outset, our ability to generalize from our findings is limited by both the nature and size of our sample. At the same time, several of the results of our study were not anticipated and merit emphasis. Thus, although neither donors nor recipients defined democracy in terms of social or economic benefits, there were important differences in the two groups in the extent to which they identified institutional factors or freedoms as key elements of democracy. The greater emphasis on freedom among recipients, including those who later became donors, may reflect their experience in societies that were not or are not free. Given the very heavy emphasis on institutional factors among donors, however, it is easy to see how misunderstandings concerning the purpose and focus of democracy assistance could arise. Differences between the two groups were also evident in the factors each identified as the most important obstacles to democratic development. The tendency of the donor community to focus on domestic con ditions within the country receiving assistance and the recipients to allocate blame more evenly between domestic conditions and external factors, including the goals and nature of democracy assistance and the characteristics of democracy assisters, further increases the potential for miscommunication and conflict. The frequent lament that outsiders involved in democracy assistance do not understand or pay enough attention to local conditions among recipients of assistance, and a corresponding lack of awareness of such a possibility among donors is an additional potential source of conflict. These differences, which may well decrease the effectiveness of democracy assistance, merit additional research, both within the post-communist region and in other parts of the world.
An empirical pilot study 169 Another set of findings that is intriguing concerns the position of recipients who later become donors. Our expectation that they would bridge the two worlds was only partially borne out. In terms of concepts of democracy and perspectives on the greatest obstacles to democracy, they more closely resembled other recipients than they did donors. Their views on problems with democracy assistance and the impact of participation in democracy assistance on their concepts of democracy, however, were closer to those of the donor respondents than to those of other recipients. These findings suggest that these respondents do indeed have a foot in both worlds. The influence of interaction with other donors involved in democracy assistance appears to be greatest in those areas most closely related to democracy assistance itself and their work as professional promoters of democracy. In more general terms, their views reflect those of other recipients. Given the dispersal of our sample across several countries that differ in terms of their degree of demo cracy and the small size of the recipient-donor category in particular, further research is clearly needed to investigate the perspectives of this important group of actors, who are perceived by many in the region to have greater legitimacy as actors in democracy assistance than outsiders. The differences we found among donors and recipients in terms of the main problems with democratic development and with democracy assistance also have a conceptual dimension. The fact that recipients, including those who later become donors, more often see external factors, or a mix of internal and external factors, among the main problems of democratic development, and the tendency of those who identify external factors as important to point to problems with the democratization strategy and attitudes of external democracy promoters, could be indicative of a difference in concepts of what democracy is as well as of how to attain it. Similarly, the fact that nearly a third of those receiving assistance identified issues related to the goals and nature of democracy assistance as prob lematic aspects of such assistance suggests that recipients may be dubious about the way in which donors conceptualize democracy. In short, our preliminary study suggests that donors and recipients, at least in the post-communist world, may conceptualize democracy is somewhat different ways. Although these conceptions, as explicitly articulated, can for the most part be classified as those of liberal democracy, views regarding the greatest prob lems with democratic development as well as democracy assistance hint at other differences that may influence communication and cooperation between donors and recipients that merit further study.
Appendix A: sample Our sample was a sample of opportunity drawn from the approximately 200 participants in all aspects of democracy assistance interviewed in Armenia, Azerbaijan, Croatia, Georgia, Kyrgyzstan, Serbia, Slovakia and Ukraine as well as in Washington, New York, and London between 1996 and 2010. Most of the interviews took place between 2004 and 2008. Of the 36 responses to our email questionnaire, ten were donors or worked with organizations in the US or Europe
170 V. J. Bunce and S. L. Wolchik that provided democracy assistance and 26 were recipients of such assistance. Eight of the latter were first recipients and then providers of assistance, in many cases funded by western organizations. Respondents were contacted by email and asked to respond to four open-ended questions provided in Appendix B. They were assured that they would not be identified in our discussion by name or position unless they explicitly gave us permission to do so. Nine of the respondents we have identified as donors came from the US and one from Germany. Recipient responses came from Slovakia, Georgia, Kyrgyzstan, Armenia, Azerbaijan, Serbia, and Ukraine.
Appendix B: questionnaire Respondents were contacted by email and asked to share their views on the fol lowing open-ended questions: 1 2 3 4
There is considerable argument concerning the meaning of democracy. What does democracy personally mean to you? What do you see as the biggest obstacles to democratic development? What are the biggest problems you have encountered with democracy assistance? How, if at all, has your conception of democracy changed as the result of your experience with democracy assistance?
Respondents were assured that we would not cite them by name or position unless they gave us explicit permission to do so.
Notes 1 We would like to thank our respondents for their time and thoughtfulness in answering our questionnaire. We are also grateful to Kallie Knutson for her research assistance and to the Institute for European, Russian, and Eurasian Studies, The George Washington University, for its support of her work with us. 2 See Dalton et al. (2007), footnote 15 for information regarding criteria for classifying responses into the three categories. 3 See Bunce and Wolchik’s Democratizing Elections (2011: ch. 1) for sources confirming this tendency. 4 See World Movement of Democracies, Powerpoint, http://democracy.assistance. sgizmo.com?rg=JAK. 5 Drawn from presentation by Joel Barkan at the World Movement of Democracies, Powerpoint, Slides number; see http://democracy.assistance.sgizmo.com?rg=JAK questions used; 1,125 respondents had taken the survey at the time the powerpoint was prepared.
10 Arab democratization and the de-imagining of authoritarian community Beyond Orientalism and Occidentalism Larbi Sadiki Introduction How do we explain democracy (in)transition in the Arab World? How does Western democracy promotion spell agency demotion for the Arab Middle East? How can we elicit answers that go beyond the explanatory tools of Orientalists and Occidentalists? These are the key questions this chapter shall attempt to address. To this end, the chapter reframes the problematic of democracy/demo cratization in the Arab Middle East (AME). Integral to this exercise is an exami nation of how democracy and community are being ‘de-imagined’ and ‘re-imagined’ in the Arab world. Up to sixty years of independence has all but proved the failure of the postcolonial ‘imagining’ of Arab nationalist communit ies. Democracy has mostly been sidelined in such postcolonial imagined com munities. Today the Arab Middle East faces new de-imagining and re-imagining of communities from the Atlantic coast (Morocco) to the shores of the Red Sea and the Arab Gulf (Yemen, Saudi Arabia, etc.). The Arab Middle East’s relationship with democracy and democratization (and by implication ‘the West’) since the advent of European colonialism in the mid-1800s has been fraught with ideational tension. The relationship has been weighed down by epistemological tension, if not rivalry. From the outset, the Arab-Western encounter was not going to be easy. ‘The West’ (European colo nizers and much later the US) has arrogated to itself the role of an all-knowing agent in all matters of organizing the full spectrum of the socio-political world. This is particularly true of matters related to the art of government. For Oriental ists (formulators of anti-Arab or Muslim constructs) hold the Western experi ence, especially post the Enlightenment, to be nothing less than an exemplary democratic foundation worthy of emulation by and exportation to an ‘Orient’ bereft of civic cultures and practices. They hold this to be the yardstick for meas uring degrees of modernity and tradition, transition and stagnation, and demo cracy and autocracy. By contrast, Occidentalists (formulators of anti-Western constructs) mount a defense against this position, noting that the indigenous mind is not a tabula rasa. The conceptual and epistemological ground for organ izing the political should be local political know-how, history, culture and reli gion. Neither line of argument is fully compelling. Perhaps both narratives,
172 L. Sadiki being equally ‘ethnocentric’ and ‘culturalist’, tend to distract from the normative crux of democracy as an ethos of pluralism and equality. Going beyond both narratives and their exaggerated sense of ‘self-exceptionalism’ is vital for reframing the parameters of a new line of inquiry of Arab democratization. To this end, the constructs of both narratives produce calls for a brief comparative discussion in order to re-visit the postulates of each. This exercise allows for a re-interpreting of how and where to look for Arab democracy and democrat ization. Subsequent to this discussion, the inquiry turns to an investigation of the failed project of ‘imagined communities’ and counter-projects of ‘de-imagining’ communities, thus bringing more complexity to our understanding of Arab democratization. The aim behind this innovative line of inquiry is to ‘prob lematize’ or re-cast the question of Arab democratization. Without understand ing of the dismantling of the postcolonial modernization of state society, no firm grasp of the problem of why and how democracy resists transition to the AME can be attained. Before turning to a contextualization of Arab democratization, the chapter briefly defines Orientalism and Occidentalism.
Orientalism and Occidentalism: definitions Edward Said’s iconoclastic work provides the best deconstruction of the Euro centric style of thinking and writing on ‘the East’. Thus, at the core of the defini tion Said’s work puts forth is an ontological and epistemological polarity, which makes ‘the Occident’ and its ‘other’, ‘the Orient’, antitheses. Central to this style of thinking and writing is the tendency to ‘generalize’, condemning ‘the Orient’ to a fixed and single monolith. This ignores important dimensions of culture, his tory, geography, and a variety of socio-economic variables that would suggest ‘the Orient’ to be a place of diversity not unity. Islam is placed in this Orientalist frame as a hindrance to modernity and civic culture; and it is seen to clash with democracy and the Western dogmas of rationality, secular politics and policies of inclusiveness towards women and minorities. In particular, the failure to locate an analogue within Islam of the characterizing standard of all Western democratic polities of a division between the sacred and profane predisposes the Muslim Middle East to being condemned to the box of the ‘other’ (Sadowski 1993: 14–21). ‘Islamic’ is then read not only as ‘non-democratic’ but also as being not congenial with all things ‘democratic’ or amenable to democracy. In my own work, over the years, I have made two observations worth reproducing here. The first is that ‘Orientalist essentialist constructions of [Islam] as bereft of multi-polar voices and multilateralism’ call for revision and interrogation. The second is that, with special reference to political Islam, ‘generalizing is generic to Orientalizing. Islamists are not one and the same even if they share a common political telos’. (Sadiki 2004). This brand of binary knowledge-making is geared towards privileging Euro-American modes of being, thinking and acting. This is relevant to our inquiry of democracy promotion by Western governments. In promoting democracy, they repeat the cardinal sin of demoting
Beyond Orientalism and Occidentalism 173 the Arab and Muslim worlds’ agency. These entities and the cultural, epistemological and political ‘universes’ they encompass are deemed hardly capable of producing democratic knowledge. Democratic know-how and know ledge have to be transposed and introduced from without, rather than allowed to evolve gradually through local and global knowledge from within. Occidentalism may be thought of as Orientalism in reverse: in this style of thinking and writing ‘the West’ is essentialized, generalizations and reduction isms are committed akin to those characterizing the Orientalist style. Again, referring to my own work, I have previously noted that Occidentalism produces ‘essentializations about a monolithic “West”, disaggregated Westerners, and selected elements of Western modernity and culture’ (Sadiki 2004: 96). Orien talism is incubated within the matrix of Western ascendancy, domination and colonialism: it is the language of the powerful – to an extent the ‘colonizers’ or ‘former colonizers’. In contrast, Occidentalism is reactionary: the former colon ized striking back, thinking back and writing back. It is almost a decolonizing discourse (Sadiki 2004: 96). Sardar makes a similar point very eloquently: If ‘Orientalism is a discourse of power, with the strength of a dominant, globalized civilization behind it,’ then Occidentalism is the language of the ‘powerless’ (Sardar 2004).
Contextualizing Arab democratization The intellectual artifacts diffused by Euro-American transitologists do not yield the same resonance in the Arab Middle East (AME). Once deracinated of their temporal and spatial contexts, they struggle to germinate democratically – as they are expected and intended to by their inventors. Similarly, a fledgling ‘Arab transitology’ mimetically engaging with its Western counterpart fails to transfer the democratic knowledge and knowledge-making de-coupled from time and space. Thus the problematic of discussing Arab democracy and democratization stumbles from the outset upon fundamentally conceptual and theoretical prob lems. Democracy and democratization resist transition to the Arab context as much as the AME’s political and civil societies and establishments resist transit ing to democracy and democratization. Western theoretical frameworks and con cepts do not always explain Arab peculiarities. This is despite the wide usage of neologisms such as ‘dimuqratiyyah’, ‘damaqratah’ or ‘tahawwul dimuqrati’, respectively the Arabic terms for ‘democracy’, ‘democratization’ and ‘demo cratic transition’. The nature of the intellectual engagement with this problematic remains wanting in rigour, continuity and cumulative knowledge production. The Arab engagement with the problematic is also troublesome without local democratic knowledge to supplement whatever comparative learning that can be gleaned from global examples. This local democratic knowledge remains limited the underdeveloped and unsupported by empirically didactic setting. The twin ills of conceptual/theoretical borrowing and empirical paucity furnish limited material for inquiring into the problematique of democracy and democratization in the AME. Furthermore, it is no exaggeration to say that the crux of the
174 L. Sadiki discussion has for a long time been shaped and marred by Orientalist- Occidentalist sparring. This sparring reflects a longstanding history of mutual exclusion. The vestiges of this mutual exclusion have got in the way of a sober dialogue – or dialogical disputation. This has interfered with mutual accommo dation and exchange of learning beneficial for democratization in the AME. Recent analyses of the complex dynamics of Arab movements toward lib eralizing authoritarian structures are fragmentary. Until very recently, demo cracy has been considered to be irrelevant to the Arab context. Hudson deprecates this exceptionalism, the by-product, inter alia, of the genre of Orien talist literature that excludes the AME from the study of democratization (for instance, Hudson 1991). An extension of this Orientalist bias is the often assumed incompatibility of Islam and democratic practices. But there are counter-arguments (Esposito and Piscatori 1991). The prejudicial view against Islam has roots in an adversarial history with Christendom (Cantori 1994: 507). Knowledge-making and practices in the study of Arab politics are not neutral: they are embedded in the historically biased attitude of Euro-American ideas towards Islam and Arabism (Cantori 1994: 507). The corollary is that ‘the West feels that its stereotypes constitute “knowledge” of the Middle East’ (Cantori 1994: 507). Generalizations about Islam and Islamists and their assumed hostil ity to democracy aside, ‘Islamic and Western democratic values tend to overlap’ and include basic concepts of equality, justice and so on (see Binder 1994; Korany 1994; Parens 1994). The post-1945 democratic model, filtered through American pluralism, cannot and should not be precisely reproduced in the AME. This is not to argue either that democracy should be ‘occidentalized’ as exclu sively Western or that the Arab democratic model will be sui generis. At least in theory, common denominators already exist. Islam’s concepts of consultation and consensus jostle for recognition as equal to and compatible with demo cracy’s most basic principles of participation and contestation. Islam’s principles of equality and justice, claim many Muslim scholars, have analogues in Western democracy. Democratization ought to be defended and instituted in the AME. However, the danger of homogenizing meanings of democratization lies in the attempt to enclose them in a single framework (such as ‘third wave’) to the point where they cannot speak to a different setting. For such meanings are trapped in a single way of understanding the world. A paradigm that speaks with the singu larity of ‘truth’ requires reassessment of its basic precepts. Attempts by Laurence Whitehead and Thomas Carothers to critically reassess the ‘status’ not only of ‘third wave’ democratization, but also with the whole paradigmatic edifice of democratization provide food for thought for any serious study of how demo cracy and democratization fare outside their Western settings.
Arab election ‘fetishism’ The Arab Middle East is today awash in electoralism and what I call election fetishism. That is, ubiquitous elections but continuous absence of democratic rule
Beyond Orientalism and Occidentalism 175 and rulers (Sadiki 2009). Indeed, it is apt to talk about ‘election fever’ in the Arab Middle East. More than a decade ago, elections were noted for their infre quency. Today they take place with frequent regularity. In fact, not a year passes without at least half-a-dozen elections. They happen in Arab monarchies and republics, in secular and religious states, in oil-rich and less well-to-do countries, and in political realms with and without rigid ideologies. In 2009 alone at least four major polls took place: parliamentary elections in Lebanon and Kuwait, two sets of provincial elections in Iraq and Iraqi Kurdistan. Iraqis voted again in early 2010 to choose parliamentary representatives. However, it took nine months for a new government to be formed due to disagreement over who actu ally won the elections and who had a ‘mandate’ to rule. Electoralism has not translated into democratic attitudes and ethical capacity to share power and accept defeat at the polls. Yemen’s parliamentary elections scheduled for 2010 have been postponed for 2011. Egypt’s two-round elections of November 2010 produced the most rigged and, subsequently, mono-chromatic parliament since elections began thirty years ago. The country’s formidable Muslim Brotherhood, which won 20 percent of the seats in 2005, did not win a single seat in the first round due to violence and fraud, forcing it to withdraw from the second round. Closer to the southern rim of the Mediterranean, Algeria’s April 2009 presiden tial elections gave Abdelaziz Bouteflika a third term after the National Assembly removed in November 2008, a constitutional provision limiting tenure to two terms. In October 2009, Tunisians went to the polls to elect a new parliament, and returned Bin Ali to the presidency, although Tunisians changed their minds courageously contesting the limits of his power in 2011. This electoralism, however, insistently begs the question: elections to what end? This very question must be broken down into a series of questions that facilitate a coherent and clear inquiry into a very complex issue. Such an inquiry must account for ‘specificity’. The Arab Middle East is not a monolith. Diversity of time and space points to a diverse tapestry of electoral experiences. Whilst there are no ‘neat constructs’ of how to analyse elections in twenty-one different settings, investigation of the local experiences may yield some generalizable value as to the ‘ills’ of election ‘fetishism’ in the AME. Yet, even through a his torically situated and contingent study we must conclude that at this historical juncture, democratic transition within an Arab setting can only mean ‘elect oralism’. Elections are an important democratic institution; but democracy cannot be reduced into a merely periodic electoral exercise. Elections are a positive step in the right direction. They have the potential to ‘habituate’ voters into the art of participatory politics, peaceful contest of power, the ethic of dialogue and consensus-building, and the affirmation of civil and political rights to representa tion and accountability through elected deputies. Hence, do Arab elections further democracy? In other words, do elections produce a ‘demonstration effect’, multiplying the deepening and widening of democratic ethics, skills and values of citizenship? Or are they simply ‘demonstration events’ – ‘PR’ exercises aimed at external consumption? Do Arab elections break political
176 L. Sadiki monopolies of dominant ruling parties, ruling houses, and sectarian and ethnic dogmas? Do they produce future political societies and leaders? Last but not least, do they weaken narrow loyalties to tribe, sect, family, and ideology and do they enhance democratic value-sharing and democracy-learning? These queries form part and parcel of my continuous research agenda (Sadiki et al. 2011; Sadiki 2011). However, for now it seems that the answers to these questions are in the negative. Elections are held almost entirely for the sake of holding them and parading them as ‘ticked boxes’, evidence of superficial ‘political correctness’. Further understanding of this problem warrants a brief re-visitation of Orien talist and Occidentalist pre-constructions of matters concerning Arab democracy and democratization, the subject of the ensuing brief discussion.
Beyond orientalism and occidentalism This ‘recycling’ of autocracy and democratic impasse is challenging for both Orientalists and Occidentalists. Does it validate Orientalist stereotypes that the AME is bereft of the necessary ethical, civic and democratic ‘toolkit’ that may mediate democratic transition? Or does it validate Occidentalist propositions that Western tutelage, including democracy promotion, have all along been spurious, intended to impede rather than promote the rise of democratically elected gov ernments in the AME? It is through attempting to answer such questions that Orientalists and Occidentalists seek primarily to justify their mutually exclusive positions and claims. The Orientalists carry on ignoring external factors in their explication of persistent Arab authoritarian rule. They advance ethnocentric claims that condemn the AME to democratic ‘exile’. The Occidentalists, by con trast, seem to filter their counter-discourses and assessment of Arab authorit arianism through a mind-set that still seems to be injured by the colonial encounter and experience. ‘The West’ is totalized and through a typically con spiratorial mode of thinking is accordingly relegated to an infinite ‘adversarial’ position. Orientalism and occidentalism The Arab Middle East has since its encounter with the ‘West’ served as a spatial laboratory for ‘testing’ borrowed ‘isms’. Democracy and democratization are no exception. They are Anglo-Euro-American inventions. It is in Britain, the US and Europe where they have been applied and tested longest. Today they con tinue to be tested in Southern and Latin America, Southern Europe and the Euro- Mediterranean area, South East Asia and, more recently, Eastern Europe. They have also ‘travelled’ to the AME. Nationalism, secularism, socialism, the free market and now democratization have all followed the same travel itinerary: from ‘the West’ to the rest. This ‘travel’, however, is not without ‘checkpoints’. These ‘checkpoints’ have made the travel arduous, and open to contingency and disputation.
Beyond Orientalism and Occidentalism 177 Not since the 1850s has democratization been a fully home-grown undertak ing. Early partly elected institutions were motivated by the eagerness of British and French mercantile interests for the local mercantile class to have representa tion at the level of the state. This representative agenda was not intended for the benefit of the local populace. Rather, it was meant to defend the opening of free trade with Europe and promote the passing of laws for the protection of these interests. Colonialism followed when remote-control hegemony failed to make much of an impact. After the long hiatus of corporatist and socialist bureaucratic authoritarianism in many parts of the AME, democracy and democratization returned. First, it returned qua elections in Sadat’s Egypt in the late 1970s. Then it proved somewhat infections when the ‘bread bargain’ collapsed. The rewriting of state-society contracts involved the exchange of bread for votes. It was the late 1980s and the distribution had to be adjusted to shift from welfare provision to power distribution, which never went above safeguarding the hegemonic state by other means. Then it took a political ‘tsunami’, two Gulf wars coupled with the invasion of Iraq, for democracy and democratization to once more make the rounds of the AME, this time embedded within military machines. The Iraqi experiment, aided by US mentoring and protection, has thus far yielded nothing but election fetishism.1 The democratization project, however, seems to be losing its explanatory power at the time of its arrival in the AME. Carothers has declared the trans itions paradigm to have reached an end point. Whitehead, amongst others such as O’Donnell within the vast terrain of transitology, strongly notes the specificity of transition theory. Huntington’s ‘third wave’ theory resonates with the same specificity of process (consolidation), of time (1840s to 1970s), and of space (the Americas and Europe). Its utility where the AME is concerned may not stop at the northern rim of the Mediterranean. But the 1974 Portuguese coup that was to herald a new wave of democratization in Southern Europe never ‘washed’ south wards onto the shores of the Arab Mediterranean states. As democracy continues to rekindle its moral flame across the globe, the full panoply of diverse ‘modernities’, histories, cultures, religions, languages, levels and models of development, and memories dictate against paradigmatic fixity or singularity. The contest continues unabated. If democracy is an essentially contested concept, so is democratization. Thus Whitehead, inter alia, interro gates the monism of democratization qua ‘consolidation’. Like Carothers, Whitehead’s interrogation ‘resists’ the reign of third-wave wisdom across boundaries of time and space. Specific knowledge-making about transition in specific space and specific time invites comparison but not standardization of the terms and tools of ana lysis. The contest affirms the view that democratization defies linearity, unfold ing through contingency, incompleteness and open-endedness. But this incompleteness is the impetus for continuing the search for clues in the ‘narra tion’ of democratization from disparate geographies, modernities, theories and experiences. In the AME, democratization may not yet be the only ‘game in town’. Democratization competes with other ongoing currents – primordialism,
178 L. Sadiki pan-Arabism, Islamization, unruly civism, and empire-building. This is where Orientalists and Occidentalists fail to appreciate and assess the problematic of democratic transition: democracy and democratization are neither single nor fixed; their temporality and spatiality defy fixity to a single template or brand of knowledge; and the moral verities underpinning democracy and democratization are subject to variability and contestability. Orientalists tend to be fixated on generalizing models of democracy and democratization that are today showing the strains of fierce contests about meaning, content and form. Similarly, Occidentalists tend to invoke hegemony and cultural relativism in their bid to resist imposition of democracy and democratization from without. What they fail to grasp are the lessons of the democratic revisionism in Western scholarship. Had they engaged more critically with this brand of learning, they would have learnt what democracy and democratization to seek. Plus, the Western democratic repertoire with its pluralist and diverse experiences is invaluable. If the colonial or hegemonic tendencies of US pluralism offend Arab or Islamist Occidentalists, there is nothing stopping them from absorbing relev ant lessons from the non-colonial Scandinavian model. Indeed, ‘word’ and ‘world’ are challenging when it comes to mapping out democratic learning from without on a local terrain. But the long-term, open-ended, complex and contin gent process of democratic learning must be open to creative adjustment and the wider search for ideas that may be amenable to cross-fertilization with the local repertoire of democratic knowledge. For Occidentalists to engage in reduction ism by pretending the West is monolithic is the same as Orientalists labouring under the illusion that ‘one size fits all’ is the right way to proceed with when promoting democracy in the AME. Orientalism post-9/11 and post the invasion of Iraq In relation to democracy promotion, Orientalism, as a body of scholarship/ policy-making, reproduces many of the normative and ideological assumptions of its colonial intellectual forebears and practitioners. In particular, its claim to a ‘positional superiority’, as Said calls it, in the realm of ideas and technologies, remains intact. Democracy, exclusively appropriated as a ‘Western’ not ‘human’ heritage, is uncritically deemed exportable. It is at the core of a new ‘civilizing mission’ whose worst manifestations continue to be displayed in Iraq. From the outset it was ‘security’ not democracy that guided the whole Iraqi mis-adventure in forging a future for a people whose common ‘cake of values’ is non-existent. Indeed, post-9/11 democracy is wrapped up in the cause celèbre of security. Democracy and democratization are effectively being ‘securitized’. They are thought of as added ‘ammunition’ in the fight against terror and not as ends in themselves. Possibly this is one reason why in neither Afghanistan nor Iraq has the imposition of democracy and democratization come to any promising fru ition. In both, local knowledge and values are ignored, and democratization is somehow ‘short-circuited’ through routinized electoral exercises, which yield little or no democracy.
Beyond Orientalism and Occidentalism 179 As part of a repertoire and vocabulary of ‘expert’ views and opinions they give us an example of the cultural construction of an ‘imagined geography’ that locates ‘the same’ and ‘the other’ as two binary opposites that are mutually exclusive and incompatible. In their bid to acquire credibility as policy-makers and experts on all things Islamic, the neo-orientalists expound their views as what Said (1978: 255) has termed summational statements that in effect express the authority of knowledge that they possess in knowing an alien culture and being the gatekeeper of the transmission of democratic knowledge of that par ticular culture (Islam) to another (the West) – the reception of the foreign to the familiar. The ‘securitization’ of the role of the scholarly practitioner of the study of Islam has resulted from the influence of public policy and domestic issues on the questions of political violence and terrorism (Marcuse 2004: 265–6). Epi thets of ‘radical’, ‘fundamentalist’, ‘Wahhabi’, etc., all serve to reinforce the imaginary of an Islam that is a source of danger and totally antithetical to demo cracy. An imagined geography of ‘the other’ in a far-off land in an alien milieu evoking an image of the fanatical ‘jihadi’ collapses into a world where ‘the other’ dwells within the immediate confines of ‘the same’ (Gregory 2004: 20–21). A plethora of discourses have emerged which, attack the alleged insin cerity and disingenuousness of Muslims residing in the West and also the Islam ists in the Muslim world as anti-democratic, despite all the evidence to the contrary. Within the West, security and surveillance of these sources of risk con stitute the primary means of addressing the problem of political Islam. Within the AME, the securitization of the assumed threat of political Islam seeks to identify systematically not terrorism as such but the existence of Muslims with explicit religiously and anti-democratically informed political views. This atti tude is perfectly exemplified by Daniel Pipes’s list of questions to Muslims to ascertain their ‘moderate-ness’!2 Thus, the threat is not the spectre of political violence per se; rather, it is the erosion of Western values and ‘Islamization’ of Arab and Muslim societies. Within ‘the West’, ‘the other’ inhabits the space where the same is seemingly threatened on the physical and ideological planes. Without ‘the West’, in the AME in particular, the Muslim ‘other’, being terror- prone and non-democratic, must be subjected to direct ‘civilizing’ through a dynamic democracy promotion agenda, which in the case of Iraq necessitated direct military intervention. That agenda has been dropped by the Obama Administration. Bush and his neo-cons, the instigators of that invasion as well as an ambitious civilizing mission in the AME, caused Mayhem in the region with no democratic return of import to justify the drastic actions taken.
‘Orientalization’ of the AME and ‘double promotion’ Three modes of essentialism mark the Western approach to democratization in the Arab Middle East. The first regards the standard tendency by many policy- makers and scholars to treat Islam as an obstacle to democratization. Post-9/11, the gist of the reform ‘tool-kit’ packaged to the region – such as under the Greater Middle East Initiative – tended to place premium on changing the way
180 L. Sadiki the AME ‘thinks’ and ‘knows’. When ‘West’ meets ‘East’, contrast and differ ence reign high. ‘The West’ is privileged as the sole source of all knowledge and understanding of democracy. In such mirror images, the ‘non-West’ is marginal to rationality, peripheral to theory, and on the sidelines of knowledge-making. One glaring omission within the wide field of transitology displays the prejudi cial position of ‘the Occident’ as the ‘knower’ of democracy. Political Islam or Islamism is not monolithic, however: it speaks with many tongues, for and against democracy. This hardly justifies the caricaturing of political Islam into a unitary movement – Al-Qaida-led, almost a ‘jihadist Caliphate’, with a univocal discourse and interpreting of Islam as much as demo cracy. This caricaturing preceded 9/11 (for example, Pipes 1995) but intensified in the aftermath of those bloody and tragic events. The need for disaggregation cannot be emphasised enough so that the nature of the encounter and interaction is treated and captured with proper veracity.3 Failure to represent the nuanced and diffuse nature of the encounter and interaction serves to turn Huntington’s ‘clash of civilisations’ into a self-fulfilling prophecy. More importantly, it denies space to brands of organised political Islam which persist with the onerous task of carving out a shared platform with democracy. The second mode of essentialist ‘speech’ regards the ‘AME as no more than a ‘workshop’, where experimentation ensues with the ideas and the theories invented in and by ‘the West’ in their ‘travel’ outside the precincts of the demo cratic world. Indeed, following the 2003 invasion of Iraq, the US-led effort with regard to democracy promotion is a perfect example of, how on the ground, ‘coaching’ the AME into the Western democratic ways was pursued. Many Western governments and NGOs are guilty of this patronising attitude. Dozens of Western think-tanks from Spain to the US thrive on and build careers dedic ated to probing democracy, gender issues, minorities, and human rights. These are funded and staffed largely by the West and, despite producing thousands of papers and organising workshops, seminars and conferences, little on the ground has been produced in the AME to justify their work. The Western ‘democratic’ expert in these think-tanks has become part and parcel of the pathology of Western hegemony. Yes, lots of these think-tanks provide a forum for Arab dis sidents and opposition forces. But at the end of the day, these forums work in tandem with Western policy predilections and preferences when it comes to democracy promotion. Their normative templates and motivation serve the funding parties, not the AME. Plus, the Western world’s most focused initiative to promote democracy during G. W. Bush’s Administration has left the AME’s political map intact. Maliki’s death squads, Gaddafi’s crimes against his own people, Ben Ali’s singular rule, Mubarak’s dynasticism and various Gulf states’ autocratic ways were neither hindered nor mitigated by the Western democracy promotion agendas, whether US or EU-led. A third type of essentialism that can be identified is the way that the AME is stripped of all agency to learn democracy unaided by ‘the Occident’. In fact, the whole crux of the Greater Middle East Initiative was to turn the various Arab states into ‘pupils’ in a US-led and funded brand of schooling, with ‘teachers’ or
Beyond Orientalism and Occidentalism 181 ‘instructors’ recruited from the EU. This approach looks and sounds neo- colonial. Even the gurus of modernization theory in the height of the 1970s and 1980s, despite being teleological and linear in the way they conceptualized the eventual ‘passing of tradition’, did not prescribe ‘direct’ Western coaching of the newly-founded postcolonial states, whether in Africa or the Middle East. They were guilty of prescription but not of direct instruction on how to modernize the ‘other’. The Greater Middle East Initiative represents a discourse of power, leaving no doubt as to who is the sole ‘knower’ of a ‘fixed’ brand of democracy or which agency is promoted for the purpose of democracy promotion. Here ‘Orientaliza tion’ is manifest in the ‘double promotion’ inherent in the Greater Middle East Initiative: democracy promotion advances specific values pertinent to Euro- American ‘imagining of community’, which inherently and inevitably promotes the ‘promoter’ to the ‘promotee’ and the ‘promoter’ not the ‘promotee’. This somewhat approximates the old civilized-barbarian dyad. Indeed, for the various Arab publics at the receiving end of US-led invasion concomitant with a large- scale democracy promotion campaign, there is no other way of viewing it in terms of colonization-civilization-cum-modernization-cum-democratizationcivilization. As shall be demonstrated below, the textuality pertinent to the Greater Middle East Initiative in its entirety – speeches, texts, official docu ments, summits, press releases – treats the AME as a clean slate, bereft of any knowledge worthy of consideration in the US-led bid under G. W. Bush to promote democracy, by force if necessary. Deconstruction of the US-led democracy promotion has produced endless papers. My own critique differs in that it revolves around aspects of knowledge- making and practice. It brings into sharp focus the construction of power rela tions of domination and subjugation through textual reading of the initiatives – the Greater Middle East Initiative (GMEI) and Broader Middle East Iniative (BMEI). The usage of terms like ‘greater’ or ‘broader’ Middle East is a classic example of the persistent Orientalist understanding of the AME. The monolithic label ‘Middle East’, already vague, is now rendered even more imprecise as its boundaries are stretched further afield to include in addition to the AME Afghan istan, Iran, Israel, Pakistan and Turkey. The term that still begs the question ‘Middle of where East of what’ now calls for definition as to ‘greater’ or ‘broader’ in what sense. Even though the use of ‘broader’ is considered a Euro pean refinement of its precursor – ‘greater’ – it is intriguing as to why Arab rulers or peoples would find it less imprecise or more acceptable. Generally, there is a tendency of Arabs to view with suspicion attempts to ‘lump’ them together with non-Arabs. Such schemes, many argue, derail the search for an Arab community of interests. The GMEI is a successor to a plethora of schemes super imposed top-down and from without. Like its precursor, the Middle East Partnership Initiative (MEPI), the GMEI reflects the persistent road-mapping the US began under Bush Senior (e.g. New World Order) following the liberation of Kuwait in 1991, continued through the Madrid Conference and subsequent calls for a ‘New Middle East’ (by Shimon Perez), up to George W. Bush’s issuing in
182 L. Sadiki 2003 and Condoleezza Rice’s idea of a ‘New Middle East’ in July 2006 (in the midst of the thirty-three day war between Hezbullah and Israel). This discourse of power can be clearly seen in the GMEI’s ‘working paper’ published by Al-Hayat newspaper. The ownership of its text is American. The rationale given for the GMEI is American. So are the strategies. The text maps out power relations in which the Arab side is subordinate – silent. The text deftly invokes the UN Arab Human Development Reports as if to record Arab prior agreement to the GMEI. It is a text that smacks with unilateralism. Through the text the only superpower is attempting to order the AME in its own image: the three pillars of democracy, knowledge society and capitalism reflect not only American values but also criteria of success as noted by President Bush in his NED speech of 2003 (Bush 2003). This is one aspect of the GMEI and the BMEI that critics have invariably ignored. There is a one-way flow of information, knowledge, know-how and values. The BMEI adopts the GMEI’s initial three pillars addressing the three deficits – democracy, knowledge and economy – and expands on them by toning down the American stress on the political and emphasising ‘dialogue’ and ‘part nership’. However, there is no equality in it. The G-8 side is clearly the knowledge-maker, with exclusive ownership over the content of the initiatives. The BMEI text literally opens up candidacy for ‘apprenticeship’ into good gov ernment and governance. The mentoring is top-down. The learning is unidirec tional. What the BMEI practically sets up is a form of ‘classroom’ for ‘coaching’ the AME into measuring up to globalization. In this ‘classroom’, Jordan is the most proactive ‘pupil’, partaking in all activities and benefiting from most funds. Whilst Jordan clamours for the ‘carrots’ of training and funding at the levels of state and society, the Arab Gulf states have a level of financial resources that render these ‘carrots’ insufficiently tempting. There are discretionary ‘carrots’ (e.g. the US concluding a deal with Morocco days before its September 2007 parliamentary elections to reward democratizing steps taken by King Mohamed VI, with US$697.5 million of grants under the Millennium Challenge Corpora tion).4 There are no ‘sticks’ in the initiative, as Ottaway and Carothers point out. But this is not entirely correct. ‘Sticks’ are implicit in the risk of missing the pecuniary rewards and ‘train’ of ‘modernization’, stability, moderation and reform for countries that choose not to partake in the BMEI’s activities. The oil- rich Arab Gulf states do not need the initiatives and assistance available in limited programmes, especially in relation to WTO membership; they can choose to keep their participation to a minimum. The less well-to-do states cannot do so, despite the non-binding nature of the BMEI. The ‘mentoring’ is assigned to Canada (e.g. voter registration and electoral transparency in Afghan istan), the EU (e.g. Palestinian elections and electoral commission), France (e.g. elections in Yemen), UK (e.g. parliamentary capacity in Bahrain), UNIFEM and Canada (e.g. development of women’s rights in Algeria, Jordan, Lebanon, Morocco, ‘Palestinian Territories’ and Tunisia), Germany (e.g. gender equality in Jordan, Morocco and Yemen), Italy (e.g. ‘education for all’ in Afghanistan and Libya), Japan (e.g. women’s empowerment in Egypt, Jordan and the
Beyond Orientalism and Occidentalism 183 ‘Palestinian Territories’), US (e.g. funding regional women’s campaign schools in the AME). There are additional mentoring roles for the G-8 countries in media training, public administration, strengthening civil society, improving education systems, and local development. There is a missing link in this chain of learning and mentoring. Because the GMEI is built on assumptions of G-8 leadership in knowledge-making and dif fusion, little or no effort has been made to explore ‘local’ knowledge in the AME and opportunities of intra-Arab learning. Not all of the ‘goods’ that could be deployed for democracy promotion are in the sole possession of the G-8 states, the mentors. Individual states in the AME have deficits in democracy and know ledge. However, as a whole the AME possesses forms of knowledge, albeit dis persed across the vast Arab canvass, with the potential to help democratization.
Re-framing the ‘problematic’ of Arab democracy and demo cratization The intention here is to seek out an explanatory method integral to the unfolding realities of the AME rather than following one that is dictated by the democrat ization paradigm that has generally been inspired by studies of experiences grounded in specific temporal and spatial contexts of limited relevance to the AME. From this perspective, specificity and relevance are at the core of schol arly soundness. For study of democratic (in)transitions does not seek some kind of episteme, which is detached from the temporal and spatial milieu of the social world under study. Nor should it be tainted by the uncritical positioning of either Orientalist or Occidentalist discourses. The problematic of democratic (in)trans ition must account for the key factor that inhibits democratic transition: demo cratic faragh or void. It is within this void that that renegotiation of power takes place, mostly through occupying of the void by society and dismantling of the myth of the state, that is, the authoritarian state. The postcolonial Arab state is a hegemon, what Nazih Ayubi (1996) calls the ‘over-stated Arab state’. This brand of state has historically invested itself with all the attributes of power (coercive, financial, legal, tribal, ideological, informa tional, social, etc.). It has thus left society with little shared space for normaliz ing state-society relations, and even less space for societal contests of state power. Since its emergence into territorial existence, the Arab postcolonial state’s design of this brand of statecraft fulfils what might be called ‘total pol itics’ or ‘total state’. Such a state has a notable blind spot: the ‘void of power’. This is where society strikes back to invent the vocabulary of self-recognition and self- existence, as well as the attendant thought-practice congenial to speaking and acting back at the hegemon. There lies the promise of negotiating the democratic void or faragh. In the ongoing struggles to cohabitate or populate the ‘void of power,’ potentially, and sometimes actually, Arab societies seek to convert the ‘void of power’ into the ‘power of the void’. In every state retreat/absence there emerges potential for advancement/presence by society, as if (state) ‘zero-power’
184 L. Sadiki equates with (societal) ‘positive power’, at least potentially. The aim of refram ing the problematic of democratization creatively and critically is to go beyond sterile Orientalist and Occidentalist propositions that no longer speak to the struggles to dismantle authoritarianism on the ground. This captures the essence of the nature of democratic struggles in the AME. The fight is primarily to defeat the structures of authoritarianism. This begins with de-imagining the postcolo nial nationalist authoritarian communities, paving the way for a new type of re- imagining of democratic community. Conceptually and theoretically, this exercise opens up a vista for considering the agential dynamic in democrat ization in the AME, as well as accounting for the structural ills that might be stumbling blocks in the way of democratic transition. ‘De-imagining communities’ and imagining ‘un-imagined communities’ ‘De-imagining’ marks the onset of ‘speaking back’ at the ‘hegemon’, striking back, as it were, at the state. The linchpin of the postcolonial hegemonic order in the AME is the ‘total state’.5 Accordingly, and in reference to the AME, the brand of ‘total state’ is one that has mainly engaged society through its ambi tion to occupy the entirety of the field of political action – from the manage ment of theatre and football to defense policy design. To this end, it has deployed various instruments (ranging from coercive to distributive and dis cursive), exclusively guarding politics as a narrow and closed bastion, thus inhibiting the rise of public arenas for the habituation of society to the skills and ethics of citizenship. As the exclusive bastion of the few, the brand of ‘imagined community’ that has been produced for the enactment of politics through nation and state-building in the AME has been subject to ongoing and fierce contests. The resulting ‘imagined community’ has not been all- embracing and universal in the exercise of ‘power over’. It has relegated to a secondary class of citizenship its minorities, dissidents and even its own members who have in many instances throughout the AME sought to act through unimpaired free choice and voluntary judgment. In essence, the ‘ima gined community’ of the ruling few has grown unaccustomed to all forms of autonomous checks by society or legally sanctioned rival projects of ‘imagined communities’. From a theoretical standpoint, the persona of such a state has never been established. States may reserve the prerogative to develop visions, values and rules for their conduct within their own territories. But this kind of ‘legal’ or ‘constitutional’ state is a rarity in the AME. The power-bidders occu pying the centre of the postcolonial state have doubled as rulers and façades for the state. Mainly, the state in the AME is endowed with external legitimacy – having fulfilled some requirements of the Westphalian and Weberian tem plates after independence. These comprise a combination of internationally demarcated and recognized borders (along with the regalia of the state, flags, armies, national anthems, coat of arms, etc.) and a centralized authority backed up by coercive and legal might.
Beyond Orientalism and Occidentalism 185 The fierce contests against the hegemonic ‘imagined communities’ of the Arab Middle East within the realm of the void allow for ‘imagined communities’ in reverse. That is, they signal the onset of de-imagining of the existing hege monic ‘imagined communities’ seeking their overthrow for being parochial, private-public, privatized and primordialized whilst still claiming a universal nationhood of sorts, and for inhibiting free choice in the exercise of ‘power over’. To re-state Benedict Anderson (2006), nations or communities are ima gined through a number of processes: 1 2 3 4
De-primordialization, i.e. ‘imagining’ or ‘inventing’ a community super sedes kinship ties and close knowledge and association of a clan or tribe. Nationalization of identity and belonging: imagined nations pander to nationalist ‘ethnocentricity’. De-divinization of the newly ‘imagined’ nations and states (owing to the ascendance of Enlightenment and revolutionary rationality, as Anderson points out). Indeed, having de-divinized religion, the new Enlightenment-based rational ity mythologized and sacralized the ‘imagined’ nationalist community, a ‘fraternity’ or association of compatriots, as a ‘deep, horizontal comrade ship’ to die for in the name of patriotism.
The imagining of the postcolonial community or nationhood has more or less followed a similar trajectory in the AME. The itinerary of the power-bidders and new ‘occupiers’ of the postcolonial state have from day one at the helm set out to dismantle primordial association and symbols of identification and anchors (and even arms in many instances) in the name of centralization and moderniza tion. ‘The passing of tradition’-type correctness of the postcolonial era has also set to relegate religion to a secondary role. Literally, to use Eric Hobsbawm’s phrases, the age of postcoloniality has been at once an ‘age of revolutions’ (by free officers, pan-Arabists, secularists, and eventually Islamists) and of ‘extremes’ (Hobsbawm 1962; Hobsbawm 1994) (national vs. tribal, modern vs. traditional, universal vs. parochial, etc.). The new rallying myths through which the newly born ‘imagined communities’ are to be mediated exalt the state and loyalty to its centre. Thus the postcolonial imagined orders unfolded through what might be called ‘re-intellectualization’ (Eickelman and Anderson 2003). The new masters of the postcolonial state had in their possession the state press, radio, and eventually TV, the arts, and educational syllabi to ‘coach’ or induct their subjects into the new faith, nationalism, and moor it in the new anchors of national identity and patriotic loyalty. The reality today is almost the opposite – as if it were the ‘passing of nationalism’, or at least of authoritarian nationalism. Anderson’s four processes that have collectively constructed and entrenched the ‘imagined com munity’ are more or less coming unstuck. Rather, and more precisely, they are witnessing reversal, varying degrees, throughout the AME. The multitude that once substituted nation for tribe, clan or family or other primordial associations
186 L. Sadiki is today having second thoughts. Many are already joining the swelling March back from the ‘imagined community’ and towards the protection, certainty and anchorage of these primordial associations. When the Ba’thist ‘imagined com munity’ collapsed in Iraq, these were surviving sanctuaries within which counter-imagined communities are being constructed post-Saddam Hussein. In Yemen, the centre’s never-ending duels with peripheral counter-imaginings of ‘imagined communities’ that embrace tribe, sect and unruly activism (Al-Qaida) are chipping into the already limping nation-state. From Sudan to Somalia, sim ilar manifestations are evident in various corroding ‘imagined communities’ in the AME. The power-bidders themselves lead the ‘de-primordialization’ in reverse. They tap into kinship and confessional repertoires of belonging in order to mobilize for their own ‘imaginings’ of community. The za’amat or business and political ‘lordships’ of Lebanon are a case in point. The Hariri family holds sway – through a combination of clientship and Saudi-backed confessionalism – over the country’s Sunnis. Families are the training grounds for the training and recruitment of future political leaders (e.g. GeMayel, Faranjie, Junblat, etc.). The operative term is ‘confession’ not a universal ‘image of communion’. Elsewhere a form of ‘dynastic republicanism’ best embodies the de-primordialization in reverse in the AME. Worse perhaps is when the power-bidders mix business with politics (for instance, see Dib 2007). Those members of the innermost circles of the nation’s field of action pick the cherries of the exercise of ‘power over’, becoming the media barons, landed millionaires and aristocrats (e.g. Egypt), beneficiaries of lucrative arms contracts in the AME (e.g. the Arab Gulf ), and, increasingly, control prime real estate (e.g. the Hariris’ land pur chases in Amman), the shores and the beaches (numerous cases, notably Bahrain). This compounds the realm of the moral void, setting up the imagined community for non-compliance by the excluded or estranged power-compliers. For the greater part of postcoloniality, compliance is incumbent on welfarism (distribution of subsidized goods as opposed to distribution of power) or on coer cive control. Apathy has been one coping mechanism with authoritarianism. Apathy is at once a negative form of compliance and non-compliance. However, in the realm of the void, not only are compliance and apathy partly withdrawn, but a profusion of dynamic voices and forces populating the realm of the void set the scene for discursive and practical resistance – speaking and acting back. The corollary is the profusion from below of voices and forces with their own projects to de-imagine the existing ‘imagined communities’ that are beset by the rot of moral void. Religion is back as one source feeding counter-imaginings of community. Again, this is a reversal of the process of de-divinization that coupled the rise of ‘imagined’ nations in the modern era. Perhaps nothing has reified it more than the failure of the project of modernity constructed on the pedestal of ‘imagined community’. Copts, Shiites and Sunnis are turning in droves to faith. In the democratic moment, the intersection of the profane and sacred gives birth and nurtures hybrid identities. Religious symbols, dictums, metaphors interpenetrate with democratic language, infusing it with nuance and hybridity. The return of religious verities seeped into politics through maverick,
Beyond Orientalism and Occidentalism 187 populist, popular, and charismatic challengers to the status quo. Those thrust into the AME’s political stage, such as Hassan Nasrallah, Muqtada al-Sadr, Rashid Ghannushi, Ismail Haniyyah, Khalid Mish’al and Nadia Yassine, have become celebrated symbols and names. Their discourses lace religion with politics with a fierce burning passion, managing to influence public opinion and command wide followings once reserved for the likes of Hassan Al-Banna, Sayyid Qutb, Shaykh Kishk, Abdelaziz Al-Rantissi and Ayatollah Khomeini. In particular, the charismatic Shiite Nasrallah of the Lebanese Hizbullah enjoys popularity enjoyed before him only by Sunni Jamal Abd Al-Nasser of Egypt. Rights and wrongs aside, fugitive Osama bin Laden has been the subject of private and secret reverence by millions of Arabs and Muslims. These figures’ rise to polit ical centre stage coincided with and partly even accounted for the secular leaders’ receding authority and credibility throughout the AME.6 The myth of ‘watan’ (homeland), already shattered by mal-distribution of power under the postcolonial imagined community in the AME, is being erased further in the minds of the new publics. These publics cannot imagine the ‘watan’ to be a place in which they are accorded little or no space to exercise the agency of unimpaired choice. Moreover, they cannot imagine the ‘watan’ to be a place where they face potential economic banishment from its shores, beaches, and economic opportunities, as they have been excluded in polity. Therefore the preconstructions of their newly imagined forms of identity and their attendant discourses and praxis lead them towards resistance.
Conclusion What is certain in the AME today is that power voids are proliferating. It is no exaggeration to suggest that a process of de-imagining ‘imagined communities’ is under way. Western democracy promotion projects have thus far shown its uselessness, not its worth. Bush’s Greater Middle East Initiative has failed, even in Iraq, where one set of bloody rulers has been substituted by another. Electoral ‘fetishism’, there as elsewhere in the Arab Middle East, was standardized, not to aid democracy but, rather, shore up delegitimized ruling elites and families. Egypt that once held the promise of an Arab ‘demonstration effect’, was after the November 2010 parliamentary elections, the furthest from democratization.7 Unlike Bush, Obama dropped the democratization agenda in the AME. Maybe Obama is aware of the pitfalls of democracy promotion without the backup of a local agency, itself empowered by civic practices, local know-how and enabling civil societies. Today, the story of Arab democratization may be said to be unfolding through speaking and acting back. This has become, for now, the only means to ‘de-ima gine’ the postcolonial ‘imagined communities’ – That is, resist authoritarianism. The democratic void remains a space where the possibilities of new becoming are tested not only discursively but also practically. Acting and speaking back at the hegemonic state is a twin function of the profusion of new voices, discourses and actors from below as well as the atomization of power. At the core of this
188 L. Sadiki atomization of power is the endeavour by these emerging voices and actors to inhabit the democratic void with a view to record presence (and thus roll back absence) and dynamically seek, create and maintain spaces of democratic struggle. Two brief theoretical qualifications are in order. First, the space of democratic void repudiates the Orientalist stigma of Arabo-civic passivity and absence. Fur thermore, it affirms Ibn Khaldoun’s thesis of the presence of a space independent of or detached from the state – a very good approximation of a civic sphere for societal self-help and self-affirmation (Gellner 1989). For more than 600 years, Ibn Khaldoun’s classic text, the Muqaddimah, has affirmed the possibility of dis tinctive civic and state realms in Arab politics. Secondly, the type of civic engagement described in this chapter is resistance-based in orientation. It incorp orates elements of passionate politics of identity, perhaps antithetical to the Euro-American model of political rationality. Nonetheless, this must not dampen its inherent ethos of anti-authoritarian resistance and its telos of dismantling the structures of authoritarianism as a prelude to future democratization.
Notes 1 This chapter was written a few months before the Arab revolutions of 2011. Nothing today tests the ‘democratization paradigm’ more than the unfolding Arab spring, which so far has led to the ousting of two of the most dynastic and unrepresentative regimes in the Arab world. The Arab spring comes to force Orientalist and Occidentalist inputs on democratization to revise assumptions about good government, democracy promo tion, the preconditions of democracy, and how democratization happens. It is unfolding locally, through Arab agency, with minimum Western machination (except in Libya) and with no link whatsoever to the grand narratives of transitology such as by Huntingdon. 2 See Pipes (2004) for an example of the unwarranted hounding and ad hominem attacks of an Egyptian-American Islamic scholar at the hands of an Orientalist. For Daniel Pipes’ list of questions for Muslims to find out whether they are really moderate or not, see Pipes (2003). 3 One notable attempt to do so is Esposito (1992). 4 The Millennium Challenge Corporation rewards performance in three areas: just rule, investing in people, and promoting economic freedom. 5 From Haenal, in Schmitt’s interpretation, we find a distinction between the ‘universal state’ and the ‘total state’. The former derives its mission from law and acts as one organization of many within a given society, distinguished by its ability to rise above them for the purpose of being everyone’s state. It is charged with ‘delimiting and organizing socially effective forces’ according to the spirit of the law. According to Haenel, a ‘total state,’ by contrast, has the potential to exercise power in order to make ‘all social goals of society its goals’. See Schmitt (1996: 24). 6 Now that bin Laden is dead that reverence may subside in some regions but increase in others where the United States is presenting Al-Qaida. 7 On 11 February, 2011 Egyptians forced Mubarak out of power, changing the course of politics in that country, and with it the future of democratization, which now has a chance.
11 The conceptual politics of democracy in international law Hilary Charlesworth
This chapter explores the conceptual politics of democracy in the area of interna tional law and the institutions in which it is developed, particularly the United Nations. How has the meaning of democracy been fought over and shaped in these contexts? The chapter first sketches the relationship of international law and concepts of democracy. It then examines the way that the United Nations has developed the idea of democracy. The chapter observes that, after a long period of detachment, international lawyers and international organisations have created a constrained, institution-based definition of democracy. This has pro duced an unstable foundation for democracy in cases of international interven tion after conflict. International legal approaches to democracy provide a nice case study of some of the conceptual debates identified by the editors in their introduction to this volume. Various understandings of democracy jostle for space in the inter national arena, from those focused on elections, to those that give priority to the protection of human rights, to versions that focus on institution-building. These understandings are theoretically rather muddled and do not fit easily within the standard typologies of democracy. International lawyers tend generally to opt for vagueness rather than precision in this area and avoid discussions of demo cracy’s meaning and value. The most recent international accounts of democracy reject the idea of any type of democracy template and insist that local conditions must influence its design. However, the practice of the United Nations in pro moting democracy after conflict suggests that local concerns and voices in fact occupy an uncertain and insecure place in this enterprise and that more attention is paid to process than to the final democratic product.
International law International law has traditionally had little interest in the idea of democracy. Indeed it is often regarded as itself the product of undemocratic processes: many developing states argue that some international legal principles have been derived from the interests and practices of imperial powers (Anghie 2005). The principle of uti possedetis is an example, confining the territorial boundaries of decolonised states to those at the time of colonisation. Another apparently
190 H. Charlesworth undemocratic feature of international law is that it largely regulates the state without taking the effect of its strictures on individuals within the state into account (Crawford 1993: 117–18). International law also asserts primacy over domestic legal rules, even if democratically adopted (Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties 1969, Article 27), leading to the charge that it creates a ‘demo cratic deficit’ in national legal systems. Classical accounts of international law did not investigate the internal govern ance arrangements within states and regarded the system of government inside states as simply a matter of national law. The Swiss jurist Emerich de Vattel wrote in 1758 that a country’s constitution was of ‘purely national concern’ and this view prevailed into the twentieth century, with Lassa Oppenheim confirm ing in his classic treatise in 1905 that, from an international law perspective, each state had ‘the faculty of adopting any Constitution it likes and of changing such Constitution according to its discretion’ (quoted in Marks 2000: 31). A striking exception to this general lack of interest in democracy by inter national lawyers was an address to the American Society of International Law in 1917 by its President, Elihu Root, a former Secretary of State (Root 1917). Root had great faith in the inevitability of the march of democracy and its cen trality to the integrity of international law. Democracy was ‘one of those great and fundamental movements of the human mind which no power can control, and which run their course inevitably to the end in an unknown future’ (Root 1917: 158). As democracy developed, autocratic and dynastic forms of gov ernment would wither away, their memories ‘faded and grown dim in the minds of millions of men in the civilized nations’ (Root 1917: 158). For Root, democracy was the key to the development of international law as democracies were unlikely to be involved in international wrongdoing. He regarded dynas tic politics as largely responsible for war and democracy as an antidote through its tempering of dynastic ambition (Root 1917: 161). Although Root conceded that democracies were capable of folly and wrongdoing, the fact that these missteps would be widely exposed made them susceptible to reason and delib eration: ‘democracies are incapable of holding or executing those sinister pol icies of ambition which are beyond the reach of argument and the control of law’ (Root 1917: 163). Moreover, as there would be inevitable conflict between democratic and non-democratic governments, democracies had to strike against non-democracies by ‘kill[ing] its enemies when it can and where it can’ (Root 1917: 166). Root’s prediction of the inevitability of democracy and the likelihood of democracies acting consistently with international law was quickly undermined by events and had little echo in the field for much of the twentieth century. The founding of the United Nations in 1945 altered the formal framework of international law from a Westphalian model, concerned with the preservation of national sovereignty, reliance on force as the basic form of legitimation and decentralised dispute resolution to one that recognised the human rights of indi viduals within states, placed significant limitations on the use of force and accorded international institutions great power (Cassese 1986). Despite this
Democracy in international law 191 considerable shift, democracy was not on the agenda of the new ‘Charter’ model of international law, reflecting a broader international ambivalence about demo cracy’s value. The term ‘democracy’ did not appear in the Charter of the United Nations and was not a prerequisite for membership of the organisation; rather, the United Nations was declared to be open to all ‘peace-loving states’ (UN Charter 1945, Article 4). This requirement was originally intended to disqualify governments with a fascist history from membership in the United Nations, par ticularly Spain (Simma 1995: 163). The San Francisco Conference of 1945 resolved that ‘peace-loving’ was not synonymous with democratic institutions, as this would amount to interference in the domestic affairs of sovereign states. In the mid-1950s, Western powers, including the United States and the United Kingdom, unsuccessfully invoked the ‘peace-loving’ conditionality to oppose the admission of Bulgaria, Hungary and Romania on the grounds that they were not democratic governments (Simma 1995). The drafting of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights by a sub- committee of the United Nations Commission on Human Rights between 1947 and 1948 prompted a more explicit discussion of democracy at the international level, with contention about the best form of governance for the protection of human rights (Morsink 1999: 59–61). The final outcome of this debate was Art icle 21 of the Declaration which presents an election-focused notion of participa tion in government, without using the term ‘democracy’: 1 2 3
Everyone has the right to take part in the government of his country, directly or through freely chosen representatives. Everyone has the right of equal access to public service in his country. The will of the people shall be the basis of the authority of government; this will shall be expressed in periodic and genuine elections which shall be by universal and equal suffrage and shall be held by secret vote or by equival ent free voting procedures.
Henry Steiner has pointed out that the drafting history of Article 21 ‘reflects concern by states on both sides of the Cold War divide to ensure that their own system of politics was not in instant violation of [the provision]’ (Steiner 1988: 77). The only reference to democracy in the Universal Declaration is found in Article 29, which declares ‘the general welfare in a democratic society’ as a pos sible limitation on the exercise of rights. The language of Article 21 of the Universal Declaration was incorporated into Article 25 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) in 1966 in an amended form: Every citizen shall have the right and the opportunity, without [discrimina tion] and without unreasonable restrictions: a
To take part in the conduct of public affairs, directly or through freely chosen representatives;
192 H. Charlesworth b c
To vote and to be elected at genuine periodic elections which shall be by universal and equal suffrage and shall be held by secret ballot, guar anteeing the free expression of the will of the electors; To have access, on general terms of equality, to public service in his country.
Thirty years later, the ICCPR’s monitoring body, the United Nations Human Rights Committee, described this treaty provision as lying ‘at the core of demo cratic government based on the consent of the people’ (General Comment 25 on Article 25, 1996). The General Comment however provided a rather thin legal articulation of the value of democracy. It was mainly concerned with the details of electoral practices, although it noted the significance of citizen participation in the conduct of public affairs through ‘public debate and dialogue with [political] rep resentatives or through their capacity to organize themselves’ (General Comment 25 on Article 25, 1996: para 8). The General Comment also emphasised the pro tection and promotion of freedom of expression, assembly and association as ‘essential conditions of the right to vote’ (General Comment 25 on Article 25, 1996: para 12), but it did not develop the concept of democracy more fully. Another treaty provision that arguably supports a democratic ideal is common article 1 of the ICCPR and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights of 1966, which proclaims the right to self-determination, includ ing the right of a people to ‘freely determine their political status’. The meaning of this phrase is open to debate. James Crawford has argued that the right to self- determination does not necessarily mean the establishment of a form of govern ment based on the idea of ‘one vote, one value’ (Crawford 2006: 333). He pointed to cases such as Swaziland, where the United Nations General Assembly sanctioned governance by traditional authorities (in Swaziland’s case a heredi tary monarchy) because they have the support of the people. In the case of Fiji, the United Nations approved the adoption of a constitution in 1970 that discrimi nated between racial groups, giving preference to indigenous Fijians over Fijians of Indian ancestry (Crawford 2006). On the other hand, Crawford has noted that the minimum core of the right to self-determination must be government that has the support of the relevant people and in this sense represents them (Crawford 2006: 334). The linkage of democracy and self-determination was also suggested in the 1993 Vienna Declaration on Human Rights, which referred to democracy as ‘based on the freely expressed will of the people to determine their own polit ical, economic, social and cultural systems and their full participation in all aspects of their lives’ (UN Doc. A/Conf./157, 12 July 1993, para I (8)). Such a formulation requires identification of ‘the people’ in a particular context. This question is raised in an acute form, for example, in the case of the 1998 Nouméa Accord in New Caledonia, which was a response to a movement among the Kanak population for independence from France. Are the New Caledonian people simply the indigenous population (which makes up 44 per cent of the population), or do they include permanent and temporary residents of French
Democracy in international law 193 origin? The Accord provides for a vote by ‘the populations concerned’ to decide the final status of the islands at a date to be fixed between 2014 and 2018, imply ing that there may be a voting system somewhat different to one vote one value (Crawford 2006: 334, n 18). International lawyers’ long-standing wariness about explicitly endorsing democracy as an international norm dissipated somewhat after the ending of the Cold War as part of the more general global pause in contestation over demo cracy’s value, described by the editors of this book. In particular, American international lawyers began to articulate a right to democracy in international law. For example, Thomas Franck identified an ‘emerging right to democratic governance’ (Franck 1992). He reflected on the contemporary tumult within the Soviet Union and the strong international reaction to the overthrow of President Aristide in Haiti in September 1991, observing a ‘cosmic, but unmysterious, change’ in the preparedness of governments to argue for a democratic entitle ment (Franck 1992: 47). Franck presented this development as almost entirely as the product of Western thinkers, such as Hume, Locke, Jefferson and Madison (Franck 1992: 49). His writing was infused with spiritual language, suggesting both the inevitability and moral value of the move to democratic governance; indeed Franck’s article’s final sentence argues that ‘[t]he task is to perfect what has been so wondrously begun’ (Franck 1992: 91). Other international lawyers have developed the notion of a human right to democracy. Thus Christina Cerna (1995), Gregory Fox and Georg Nolte (1995) have argued that the legitimacy of governments should be assessed by interna tional rather than national criteria, that the international requirement is of demo cratic government and that individuals everywhere have a right to democratic government (see also Steiner 1988). Similarly, Steven Wheatley (2005: ch. 3) has argued that creating and sustaining democracy is an international legal obli gation, enabling the international community to scrutinise the substance and pro cesses of a state’s political system. He has also suggested that international law endorses a form of Habermas’ deliberative democracy – a system that engages citizens in active deliberation and allows broad participation in politics, resulting in consensus positions – as opposed to what he terms ‘aggregative’ democracy – a form of democracy that is focused on competitive elections (Wheatley 2005: 185–7; see also Wheatley 2010). Michael Reisman (2000) presented the argument that a right to democracy could be discerned in international law to support ‘pro-democratic intervention’. He inverted the traditional notion of state sovereignty in international law to argue that the critical sovereignty protected in international law was not that of the ruler, but that of the people. This led him to conclude that if the people’s preferences for government were usurped, international law would support inter vention to remove the usurper. Gregory Fox and Brad Roth have similarly artic ulated the idea of a ‘democratic entitlement’ in international law, arguing that ‘measures to implement democratic rights, undertaken by foreign states collect ively and/or individually, need not respect the sovereign prerogatives of govern ments that violate those rights’ (Fox and Roth 2001: 336).
194 H. Charlesworth Some international lawyers who adopted an explicitly liberal democratic political approach, such as Anne-Marie Slaughter (1995) and Fernando Tesón (1992), argued that a fundamental distinction should be drawn between liberal democracies and non-liberal democracies in international law. For them, undemocratic governments did not have the requisite sovereignty to enjoy full status in the international community and liberal democracies could be relied on largely to self-regulate. A further context in which international lawyers have addressed ideas of democracy has been within international institutions. This has inspired chal lenges such as those to the permanent membership of the United Nations Secur ity Council and the associated veto power and proposals for global peoples’ assemblies that would give voice to civil society and transnational interest groups (e.g. Falk 2007). Both types of reform projects are animated by an idea of democracy based on broader participation in decision-making. In their introduction to this book, the editors note that the post-Cold War enthusiasm for a norm of democracy has been mistakenly interpreted as a sign of universal acceptance. The brief survey of international lawyers’ attitudes to democracy indicates that, overall, American international legal scholars have manifested the greatest dedication in demarcating a right to democracy.1 This national connection of course has parallels in the democracy-promotion literat ure. It has meant that the impact of these views has been limited on international law generally. International lawyers have become more cautious about embrac ing the concept of democracy at the global level both because of inconsistent international practice in supporting it (e.g. Farrall 2009) and because ‘pro-demo cratic’ intervention has rarely delivered on its goal.2 In this sense, Tony Smith’s concerns about the effect of ‘the liberal jurists’ on definitions of sovereignty and the just war expressed in this volume can be confined to a particular national context.
International institutions As we have seen, the development of the concept of democracy within the United Nations was restrained initially by the concern that this would constitute illegitimate interference in the domestic affairs of states. The decolonisation era, starting in the 1960s, deepened distrust of the language of democracy. Demo cracy was regarded by some Southern states as a Trojan Horse, masking the imposition of Western values as a form of government (Anghie 2005). These states found recourse to the Westphalian language of national sovereignty a useful device to resist the development of international standards relating to democracy. The end of the Cold War and the apparent triumph of democracy encouraged the United Nations to endorse the concept of democracy, but it remained vague about its content and meaning, anxious not to antagonise any of the regional groupings within its membership. This is evident in the first full discussion of democratisation by the United Nations in Secretary-General Boutros Boutros-Ghali’s An Agenda
Democracy in international law 195 for Democratization published in 1996. The Agenda did not give the idea of democracy any real substance, noting that the ‘[i]mposition of foreign models . . . contravenes the [United Nations] Charter principle of non-intervention in internal affairs’. The Agenda referred to the ‘undeniable fact there is no one model of democratization or democracy suitable to all societies’ and claimed that ‘it is not for the United Nations to offer a model of democratization or democracy or to promote democracy in a specific case’. The role of the United Nations was simply to offer only ‘assistance and advice’ and allow each member state ‘to choose the form, pace and character of its democratization process’. In practical terms, United Nations assistance included help with drafting constitu tions, establishment of justice systems and police forces that abide by the rule of law, the depoliticisation of the military, the creation of institutions to promote and protect human rights, and the fostering of civil society and an independent media (Boutros-Ghali 1996: 1–2). The elaboration of the notion of democracy within the United Nations occurred primarily in the Commission on Human Rights. The Commission adopted a series of resolutions on democracy from 1997 onwards, which illus trated North-South divergence on the concept. Some of the resolutions endorsed the process of democratisation of states and presented ‘free and fair elections [as] an essential feature of democracy’ (e.g. CHR Resolution 2001/41). These resolutions were typically supported by the United States, the United Kingdom and Canada as well as some Southern states, while China, Cuba, Saudi Arabia and Syria abstained from voting. Another strand of resolutions adopted during the same sessions countered this understanding by supporting the ‘promotion of a democratic and equitable international order’ (e.g. CHR Resolution 2001/65). They avoided any reference to elections and emphasised the economic and social dimensions of democracy. In defining democracy, these resolutions invoked many concepts promoted by the developing world, such as self-determination, permanent sovereignty over natural wealth and resources, the right to development, the principle of solidarity (which calls for the distribution of the costs of global challenges ‘in accordance with basic principles of equity and social justice’), and the right to a healthy environment. Unsurprisingly, these res olutions attracted support from the abstainers on the Northern-sponsored resolu tion and negative votes from all Western states on the Commission. The Commission on Human Rights was replaced by the United Nations Human Rights Council in 2006. The Council has continued the tradition of adopting twin resolutions on democracy; one that attracts support from the Northern members of the Council and one that they vote against. Thus a 2008 resolution on ‘The role of good governance in the promotion and protection of human rights’ (HRC Res. 7/11) linked corruption with violations of human rights and was approved by the North, as well as some Southern states, although a number abstained from the vote. Three months later, a familiar resolution on the ‘promotion of a democratic and equitable international order’ (HRC Res. 8/5) prompted negative votes from all the Northern states in the Council’s membership.
196 H. Charlesworth In 2005, on a United States initiative, the United Nations established a Democracy Fund to ‘support democratization throughout the world’. The mandate of the Fund does not define the idea of democracy and it eschews the promotion of ‘any single model of democracy’ (UNDoc. A/RES/60/1, para. 135). The 2005 Summit Outcome document agreed to by Heads of State of United Nations members on the United Nations’ sixtieth anniversary offered a slightly more detailed account of democracy, stating that ‘democracy is a uni versal value based on the expressed will of people to determine their own polit ical, economic, social and cultural systems and their full participation in all aspects of their lives’ (UN Doc. A/RES/60/1, para. 135). It noted that ‘demo cracies share common features’, but did not identify any. The Summit Outcome also repeated the rejection of a ‘single model of democracy’, observing that ‘democracy does not belong to a single country or region’. The document shows the influence of Southern states’ scepticism about the Northern demo cracy agenda by reaffirming ‘the necessity of due respect for sovereignty and the right of self-determination’ and emphasising that ‘democracy, development and respect for all human rights and fundamental freedoms are interdependent and mutually reinforcing’. The most recent United Nations’ contribution to the development of the idea of democracy is the Secretary-General’s Guidance Note on Democracy, issued in 2009. Its stated aim is to set out the United Nations framework for democracy ‘based on universal principles, norms and standards, emphasizing the interna tionally agreed normative content’. The Note is committed to ‘principles, coher ent and consistent action in support of democracy’. Strikingly, the Note attempts to retrofit democracy into the United Nations Charter against the historical record, insisting that ‘democratic principles are woven throughout the normative fabric of the United Nations’. The Guidance Note remains at a general level and echoes the mantra that there is ‘no one model’ of democracy. At the same time, it asserts that there is an ‘internationally agreed normative content’ of the concept of democracy and pro poses some substantive elements. It links democracy to the rule of law and presents democracy as a means to achieve international peace and security, eco nomic and social progress and development, and respect for human rights. At the same time, the Note regards democracy as based on human rights. The Note is bolder than previous United Nations statements in urging a ‘holistic’ understand ing of democracy that encompasses procedure and substance, formal and infor mal processes, majorities and minorities, men and women, government and civil society, politics and economics, national and local communities. It endorses the idea of local ownership of democracy and emphasises the need to include minor ities and marginalised groups in government. An interesting development in the Guidance Note on Democracy is the deployment of the pithy injunction ‘do no harm’ in the context of post-conflict peace-building. ‘Do no harm’ is the language of the Hippocratic oath, which is traditionally taken by doctors as a commitment to ethical practice and marks a considerable shift in international discourse on democracy. In this context, it
Democracy in international law 197 implies that attempts to bring democracy through international intervention are not necessarily beneficial for the people who are the object of the intervention, and can exacerbate division and violence. The use of the Hippocratic oath in the Guidance Note may be a reaction to international interventions such as those in Afghanistan and Iraq in the last decade, where crude forms of democracy- building have been used almost as a form of punishment of rogue regimes and as a method of shoring up the security of the democracy-builders.3
Democracy-building after conflict Post-conflict interventions by international institutions illustrate both interna tional legal developments and the practices of the United Nations with respect to democracy. All major United Nations missions now include significant democracy-building components. Although much attention has been paid to the legality of the democracy enterprise when it is conducted in the aftermath of an invasion, such as in the case of Iraq, international lawyers have generally side stepped the question of the form of democracy-building after conflict. Interna tional lawyers have tended to assume that there are few legal issues in democratisation if the affected state has agreed to an international presence (e.g. Farer 2004). An example of the complexities generated by such United Nations’ interven tion practice is the case of Timor Leste. It has often been held up as an example of successful international democracy-building and the adoption of a new consti tution provided an apparently simple exit strategy for the international commun ity. The intervention was guided by faith in multiparty elections as a signifier of democracy paralleling the limited terms of Article 25 of the ICCPR, discussed above, although it also reflected the United Nations rhetoric of ‘local ownership’ of governance structures. The United Nations Transitional Authority in East Timor (UNTAET) was formed in 1999 after Indonesia had agreed to withdraw after 24 years of occupa tion. The focus of UNTAET’s work was to establish Western political institu tions based on concepts such as the separation of powers and there was little attention given to existing local structures, or how they might interact with the proposed new constitutional edifice. The United Nations was unable to grapple with specific Timorese social networks that did not map readily on to the Western model of citizen/state relations, where formal institutions such as the judiciary, the legislature and the executive structure political life (Hohe 2004: 303). The goal of multi party elections was an alien concept in Timor Leste because of the local unitary and hierarchical idea of political power which made ‘peaceful political opposition . . . logically impossible’ (Hohe 2004: 306; see also Chesterman 2004: 93). The role of kinship relations in Timorese society was poorly understood by UNTAET officials. Traditionally, political authority and ritual authority were separate in Timor Leste; political authority depended not on political ideology but on ancestral will (Hohe 2004: 304). Timorese political leaders have both
198 H. Charlesworth used and manipulated this indigenous political culture to try to achieve exclusive authority, while nevertheless using the international vocabulary of democracy. Factions in Timor Leste politics are not so much based on philosophical differ ences as on ‘a struggle for personal power and cultural denominators’ (Hohe 2004: 310). The United Nations did not seem aware of the local political para digms and made no serious attempts to accommodate them. UNTAET regarded the Timorese as without a political system (Chesterman 2004: 93–4). The United Nations had little grass-roots contact, apart from a civic education project and the constitution-drafting exercise. It did not have interest in local government and concentrated on the national level, engaging only with a limited elite. While it championed the virtues of democracy, the structure of the UNTAET mission approximated what Simon Chesterman has described as ‘a benevolent autocracy’ (Chesterman 2004) or in Hohe’s words, ‘feudal democracy’ (Hohe 2004: 302). Although its mandate required consultation and cooperation with the Timorese people (Security Council Resolution 1272, 1999), UNTAET was designed in a steep hierarchy, with decisions being made by the Special Repre sentative of the Secretary-General and passed down the ranks. This style of organisation has become accepted in United Nations missions, but the Special Representative was also the transitional administrator of Timor Leste, with almost unfettered political power. This conflation of roles meant that ‘authoritarian-style decision-making was not only conducted internally within the mission, but also in the administration of the country’ (Hohe 2004: 315). In this sense, the form of governance modelled by UNTAET was completely at odds with the form of governance it was preaching. The two-track salary struc ture and different working conditions between international and local staff also caused considerable tension and did not seem consistent with democratic ideals (Devereux 2005: 319–20). The language of local ownership was regularly deployed in Timor Leste perhaps, as Chesterman has argued, to obscure the assertion of almost unlimited powers to shape the governance system of the new polity by the international community (Chesterman 2004: 100). This led to the appointment of East Timor ese staff without proper training. More fundamentally, it distracted attention from the military force that underpinned UNTAET’s presence (Chesterman 2004: 108) and did not acknowledge that local ownership could only be achieved incrementally; that it was the goal but not the means of democratisation (Ches terman 2004: 100). UNTAET’s attitude to protecting human rights also created a sense of doubledealing which undermined its democratic credentials. While UNTAET saw itself as having a role in promoting human rights in Timor Leste, it did not seem to consider that international human rights standards applied to its own work. The way UNTAET handled allegations of human rights violations against its own employees had little transparency, with investigations conducted ‘in house’ and in secret. The major sanction was being sent home rather than being prosecuted and victims were not informed of the result of investigations (Devereux 2005: 318–19).
Democracy in international law 199
Conclusion The conceptual politics approach is useful in studying international law and institutions’ approach to democracy, as law and politics are closely entwined in this area. A range of understandings of democracy have influenced the international arena, ranging from the thin to the relatively thick. It now is de rigueur however to discount the notion of a single model of democracy and to endorse the significance of engaging with local populations. There has been little exploration in theory and practice of concepts of democracy beyond the establishment of the standard suite of Western governmental institutions. International lawyers and institutions have largely slipped into endorsing an idea of democracy that focuses on state institutions and political parties, not unlike that promoted by scholars such as McFaul, discussed in the introduc tion to this volume. Many vital institutions of daily life, such as workplaces, are outside this concept. Although there are references in United Nations documents on democracy to the role of civil society in generating and sup porting democracy, civil society is understood essentially as non-government organisations that derive their status and legitimacy from adherence to liberal values (Rajagopal 2003: 260–1). This sidelines broader social movements and narrows the possibility of true local ownership of or participation in the new political order. Attention to the conceptual politics of democracy in international law and institutions suggests the need for a sustained debate on what democracy means in international law. As Susan Marks has pointed out, ‘low intensity’ forms of democracy, such as those contemplated in Timor Leste, ‘concentrate attention on forms and events, and . . . shift the emphasis away from relationships and pro cesses’ (Marks 2000: 52). The effect is to consolidate existing social orders and to reduce the prospect of political and social change through redistributive claims. International lawyers and institutions should instead become more con scious of the weaknesses of external solutions in cases of conflict. They must also be careful to distinguish law and order from peace and security. The editors remind us of Guillermo O’Donnell’s insight that democracy always offers more than it can deliver; that it is a commitment to a journey rather than an end in itself, and this is its great virtue. It has important implications for international lawyers, suggesting the inutility of devising formulas for demo cracy, or associating democracy with a fixed set of institutions. The principle of democratic inclusion, described by Marks, is useful in this task, influencing the interpretation and application of international law (Marks 2000: 109–11). The idea of democratic inclusion reaches beyond institutional forms of democracy to emphasise the ‘enlarge[ment of] opportunities for popular participation in polit ical processes and [to] end social practices that systematically marginalize some citizens while empowering others’ (Marks 2000: 109). It also emphasises the importance of identifying and strengthening local institutions that enhance self- government and responding to social and economic inequalities as they affect the capacity to have access to political power (Marks 2000: 64–5).
200 H. Charlesworth
Notes 1 Some of the strongest ripostes to this scholarship have also come from American schol ars, e.g. Alvarez (2001). 2 There has been greater attention to the concept of democracy in regional settings, for example, see Wheatley (2005), Bowden and Charlesworth (2009: 97–9). 3 The ‘do no harm’ language also appears in the OECD Guidelines (for example, see OECD 2010).
12 From ‘fortunate vagueness’ to ‘democratic globalism’ American democracy promotion as imperialism Tony Smith The ideas of economists and political philosophers, both when they are right and when they are wrong, are more powerful than is commonly understood. Indeed the world is ruled by little else. Practical men, who believe themselves to be quite exempt from any intellectual influence, are usually the slaves of some defunct economist. John Maynard Keynes
Introduction American democracy promotion has never been disinterested. At times its concerns have been geo-strategic, at times economic, at times ethno-religious. But its most serious ambition has always been to defend the national security of the United States by promoting a type of government for others that, while extending the blessings of liberty abroad, would also redound to the security of Amer ica by establishing a form of international order where the threat of war based on dangers arising from anarchy and predatory authoritarian governments would be replaced by a community of peace anchored in the character of democratic peoples and their ability to work together. Think of it as a secular religion if you will (and you surely should), but as first articulated in the United States in self- conscious form with practical consequences by Woodrow Wilson (president from 1913 to 1921) what came to be called ‘liberal internationalism’ (or in its American context, ‘Wilsonianism’) was a set of ideas with powerful con sequences for foreign peoples and for world order. In some circumstancese the ambition bore bitter fruit: one need only think of Wilson’s interventions in the Dominican Republic, Nicaragua, and Haiti, for example, not to speak of Iraq and the intended ‘transformation’ of the ‘Broader Middle East’ after 2003. Elsewhere, its effects were more a mixed blessing: the American impact on the Philippines is an instance. In yet other circumstances, the hope became a reality: during Wilson’s time, Czechoslovakia was a country that gained handsomely from the American president’s efforts. But Wilsonianism’s greatest triumphs came later, more than two decades after Wilson’s death in 1924, thanks to the liberalising efforts of American occupation forces in Japan and Germany after the Second World War. In my opinion, these
202 T. Smith occupations may be counted as the greatest accomplishments in the history of the Republic’s involvement in world affairs, contributing as they did not only to the transformation of these two militaristic nations into liberal democracies typified by relatively open markets and participation in multilateral institutions, but also to America’s eventual victory over the Soviet Union with the end of the Cold War in 1989. Here was the most enduring example of what liberal interna tionalism could accomplish (Smith 1994). When Wilson talked as he so often did about the ‘disinterested spirit’ in which the United States acted, not even he believed his words to be exactly true; self-interest, as well as altruism, was always a feature of teaching South Amer icans [or anyone else] to elect good men, as he put it in 1913.1 Yet the argument for altruism was ever present. For the peculiarity of American imperialism exercised in the name of democracy was that it was designed to exist only temporarily, long enough to transform an occupied people politically and economically, but then to turn them over to what Wilson always insisted must be their own ‘national self-determination’, to work out as they would their collective destiny as independent, democratic states acting in a world order he hoped to see dominated by multilateral institutions dedicated to preserving the peace. When such a goal was accomplished on a large enough scale, then the world would be ‘made safe for democracy’ as he famously put it in his war address to the Congress on 2 April 1917 (Link 1983: 519ff., see also Link, 1982: 533ff.). Over time, American democracy promotion gained in conceptual richness and from experience gained on the ground. Wilson at Versailles had learned from his experiences in Latin America; the United States acting in occupied Germany and Japan was far more skilful than it had been in the Philippines. Conceptually, there was growth as well, with liberal internationalism as a political doctrine gaining in ideological complexity, coherence, self-confidence, and purpose. What I would call the ‘classic phase’ of American democracy promotion under Wilson was superseded by the far broader and deeper efforts attached to this program during its ‘hegemonic phase’ following the Second World War, when multilateral institutions appeared to coordinate the economic and security inter ests of the world’s market democracies. This stage gave way in turn to the frankly ‘imperialist phase’ of sponsoring democracy abroad that set in in the 1990s, as the United States contemplated its role in world affairs at a moment of unrivaled power after the collapse of the Soviet Union (Smith 2007). Yet if there were changes in the way the mission of liberal internationalism was conceived, there was consistency too. Wilson’s contemplation of the global duties of his countrymen as ‘apostles of liberty and self-government’ when he considered the Philippines as a laboratory for democracy after its conquest in 1898 had much in common with President Bill Clinton’s call for ‘democratic enlargement’ in the 1990s, as well as with President George W. Bush’s memor able assertion in his Second Inaugural Address that the best hope for peace in our world is the expansion of freedom in all the world. . . . So it is the policy of the United States to seek and support the
American democracy promotion as imperialism 203 growth of democratic movements and institutions in every nation and culture, with the ultimate goal of ending tyranny in our world.2 Establishing just what Wilson’s position was on democracy promotion is a subject that has bedeviled all who have addressed it. Part of the problem comes from the fact that Wilson’s statements can be cherry-picked; at times he seemed extremely cautious that one people might foster the democratisation of another, at others he seemed fully confident that the task could, and should, be accomplished. He could talk about the ability of the United States to ‘teach South Americans to elect good men’ while recognising that American influence in Mexico during the 1910–1917 revolution could only be limited. He could write with authority about the long time and discipline necessary for a society to be capable of being governed democratically, yet he could also speak of American military intervention in Haiti or the Dominican Republic as leading with apparent certainty to the creation of representative government through an electoral process backed by American advisers. He could insist on regime change in Berlin in 1918, yet in the same address declare that should Austria-Hungary leave the war he would not demand that it end its empire or restructure its gov ernmental institutions. He could make it clear in his drafts for the Covenant of the League of Nations and in his speeches to the Congress and the American people that he regarded a multilateral organisation dominated by democratic nations as an essential condition for its successful functioning, yet he could soon afterwards accept states entering the League that manifestly were authorit arian, just as he could allow provisions for democracy promotion that he had insisted on for the League’s Mandates to be unceremoniously discarded whatever his hopes for an American Mandate over both Armenia and Constant inople.3 In short, in operational terms, Wilson as president could temper his idealism, recognize that he had to work with the material at his disposal, not with circumstances as he would like them to be, and so douse his optimism in a cold bath of realism based on a considered judgement of the logic of historical development, a matter he had written about extensively for two decades, beginning in the late 1880s.4
Liberal internationalism matures into a ‘hard ideology’ Whatever the continuities in the American liberal internationalism from Wilson’s time until ours, my purpose in this essay is to emphasise change. My con tention is that from the late 1980s until today a neo-Wilsonianism has been appearing, a way of thinking characterized at once by a voluntarism and a pseudo-scientific certitude that it had not had in earlier periods. There are those who would compare liberal internationalism as it was articulated by Wilson at the time of the Paris Peace Conference in 1919 as equivalent to Bolshevik thinking. True, Wilson was quite aware that his hopes sponsoring democratic government and liberal capitalism as far abroad as possible ran counter to the Bolshevik model for political and economic order and that
204 T. Smith communists were hoping to push their revolutions globally. Yet in trying to face up to the Soviet threat, Wilson had no hard ideology at his disposal in 1919, no vision of the evolution of world history that saw with pseudo-scientific certitude the logic of the road hitherto taken by humanity, no firm (as opposed to intuit ive) sense of the logic of the crossroads at which History (with a capital H) then stood, no relatively operational guidelines as to how next to proceed to reorder world affairs. Yes, the seeds of a pseudo-scientific vision of history were there; one can indeed trace them back to Wilson’s earliest ruminations on the character of democratic government in his first publications on this question in the 1880s. Yet neither Wilson nor liberal internationalists elsewhere had worked out concepts that saw an iron logic to history or a form of action to bring about a future of world freedom and peace thanks to a particular form of government with the degree of precision and assurance that communists enjoyed in the aftermath of the Great War. For this development to occur for liberalism, history had to proceed over seven more decades, over the horrors of the Second World War and the existential fears of the Cold War, to the post-Cold War era when finally, but then with amazing speed, liberal internationalism and its agenda of demo cracy promotion engendered an ideology with arguments equivalent in complexity, coherence, and purposefulness to those communism had come to possess decades earlier. This point may not at first seem self-evidently true. Yet as long-term and multifaceted as American democracy promotion was in the century between the Spanish American War and the collapse of the Soviet Union (1898–1991) and basic as the rhetoric of such a mission was to American self-confidence during the trials of a terrible period that included two world wars, the Great Depression, and the struggle against Soviet communism, just how the United States conceived what it was doing had not been very rigorously defined prior to the 1990s. To be sure, in its occupation of the Philippines beginning in 1898 and lasting until 1946, the Americans were never at a loss for how they would proceed. Elections would be held first at the local, then the provincial, and finally the national level, conducted through parties freely recruited, with positions which might be critical of how American power was exercised. American officials introduced the practices of a free press and universal primary education; they purchased church lands from the Vatican with the notion of creating a broad- based, independent farming community; they rapidly Philippinised the central government’s bureaucracy; and they talked often about when independence would be granted to the Philippines as a democratically constituted country. So too, during the occupations of Japan and Germany, Washington had voluminous planning documents for how these countries would be demilitarised and demo cratised, documents whose directives were critical to the eventual success of American ambitions in these two countries.5 What is nonetheless striking about American democracy promotion in these very different circumstances is how thin the actual conceptual structures were upon which Washington erected such ambitious undertakings. It was as if the Americans were working with the pieces of a puzzle whose final composition
American democracy promotion as imperialism 205 escaped them. The relations between economic and political development were poorly conceived (see Jahn’s chapter), to the extent they were argued at all, during the days when the Philippines were American. The wholesale political reconstructions of Germany and Japan after 1945 were far more sophisticated in their planning than anything that had gone on with respect to the Philippines, yet much of the success was due to local German and Japanese leaders whose sense of national purpose in working with the United States explains as well as what the Americans were doing why these historic enterprises were the great successes they were. In short, in American hands, liberal internationalism during these years was never a highly coherent ideology – on this score, Marxism– Leninism was a far more impressive intellectual achievement – and it always depended on the willing collaboration of local democratising leaders. If Konrad Adenauer was indispensable to the American mission in Germany after 1945, no less can be said of liberals who embraced what was increasingly an international creed in the 1990s, especially in the persons of such leaders as Oscar Arias, Vaclav Havel, Kim Dae Jung, Nelson Mandela, Pope John Paul II, and even Mikhail Gorbachev (not to speak of more anonymous freedom fighters, from Chile to the Iberian peninsula to Greece and Taiwan, who were vital to the transformation of their lands). Why was the American sense of mission so ideologically thin relative to either communism or what it would itself become during the 1990s? Certainly the United States had leaders possessed of a world vision, who felt that whatever was meant by such lofty words as civilisation, justice, freedom, and peace, these hopes would perish should America not play a role in articulating their meaning and defending their integrity on a global scale. But unlike communism, liberal internationalism had intellectual reservations built into its very construction as a system of thought, a reluctance, almost an inability, to be pure in doctrine and in practice clear cut – at least in comparison with its communist, and later fascist, opponents, who would often mock ‘bourgeois parliamentarianism’ for what they called its ‘weakness’. Instead, liberalism’s success seemed to depend to a large measure on ‘muddling through’ at home and on progressive movements and individuals working independently the globe around, without the benefit of the kind of unity Lenin had created through the Third International. The notion that liberal democracy could be successfully transmitted to the entire planet according to a single blueprint backed up by the American military, the result being the creation of a Kantian ‘perpetual peace’, was an intellectual ambition that awaited the late twentieth century. Should we perhaps not conclude that it was the variety of sources of liberal internationalism, the multitude of circumstances to which it had to adjust, and the very self-imposed restraints within its basic concepts, that made its effort to be formulated in highly ideological terms virtually impossible? With its insistence on national self-determination, its respect for personal choice and group diversity, its ethic of individual freedom and social tolerance, its concession to allowing ‘market forces’ to dictate economic reality, and its endless internal debates and sense of constant change based more on improvisation than fixed
206 T. Smith doctrine, how could any complex, coherent, and commanding version of the lib eral democratic mission ever gain a hammerlock on foreign policy with a fixed blueprint for action? Writing in 1952, Reinhold Niebuhr expressed this point in what remains argu ably the single best book on the United States in world affairs, The Irony of American History. ‘There is a deep layer of Messianic consciousness in the mind of America,’ the theologian wrote. Still, ‘We were, as a matter of fact, always vague, as the whole liberal culture is fortunately vague, about how power is to be related to the allegedly universal values which we hold in trust for mankind’ (Niebuhr 2008: 69). ‘Fortunate vagueness’, he explained, arose from the fact that ‘in the liberal version of the dream of managing history, the problem of power is never fully elaborated’ (Niebuhr 2008: 73). Here was a happy fact that distinguished us from the communists, who assumed, thanks to their ideology, that they could master history, and so were assured that the end would justify the means, such that world revolution under their auspices would bring about uni versal justice, freedom, and that most precious of promises, peace. In contrast, Niebuhr could write: On the whole, we have as a nation learned the lesson of history tolerably well. We have heeded the warning ‘let not the wise man glory in his wisdom, let not the mighty man glory in his strength.’ Though we are not without vainglorious delusions in regard to our power, we are saved by a certain grace inherent in common sense rather than in abstract theories from attempting to cut through the vast ambiguities of our historic situation and thereby bringing our destiny to a tragic conclusion by seeking to bring it to a neat and logical one . . . This American experience is a refutation in parable of the whole effort to bring the vast forces of history under the control of any particular will, informed by a particular ideal . . . [speaking of the communists] All such efforts are rooted in what seems at first glance to be a contradictory combination of voluntarism and determinism. These efforts are on the one hand excessively voluntaristic, assigning a power to the human will and the purity to the mind of some men which no mortal or group of mortals possesses. On the other, they are excessively deterministic since they regard most men as merely the creatures of an historical process. (Niebuhr 2008: 75, 79) The Irony of American History came out in January 1952, only months after the publication of Hannah Arendt’s The Origins of Totalitarianism, a book that reached a conclusion similar to his. Fundamentalist political systems of thought, Arendt (1966: 467–9) wrote, are known for their scientific character; they combine the scientific approach with results of philosophical relevance and pretend to be scientific philo sophy . . . Ideologies pretend to know the mysteries of the whole historical process – the secrets of the past, the intricacies of the present, the
American democracy promotion as imperialism 207 uncertainties of the future – because of the logic inherent in their respective ideas . . . they pretend to have found a way to establish the rule of justice on earth . . . All laws have become laws of movement. And she warned: Ideologies are always oriented toward history. . . . The claim to total explanation promises to explain all historical happenings . . . hence ideological thinking becomes emancipated from the reality that we perceive with our five senses, and insists on a ‘truer’ reality concealed behind all perceptible things, dominating them from this place of concealment and requiring a sixth sense that enables us to become aware of it. . . . Once it has established its premise, its point of departure, experiences no longer interfere with ideo logical thinking, nor can it be taught by reality. (Arendt 1966: 470) For Arendt as for Niebuhr, then, a virtue of liberal democracy was its relative lack of certitude in terms of faith in an iron ideology that rested on a pseudo- scientific authority that its worldwide propagation would fulfill some mandate of history, or to put it more concretely, that the United States had been selected by the logic of historical development to expand the perimeter of democratic gov ernment and free market capitalism to the ends of the earth, and that in doing so it would serve not only its own basic national security needs but the peace of the world as well. True, in his address to the Congress asking for a declaration of war against Germany in 1917, Wilson had asserted, ‘the world must be made safe for democracy. Its peace must be planted upon the tested foundations of political liberty.’ (Link 1982: 533). Yet just what this meant and how it might be achieved were issues that were not resolved intellectually – at least not before the 1990s. Reinhold Niebuhr died in 1971, Hannah Arendt in 1975, some two decades short of seeing the ‘fortunate vagueness’ Niebuhr had saluted during their prime be abandoned by the emergence of what can only be called a ‘hard liberal inter nationalist ideology’, one virtually the equal of Marxism–Leninism in its ability to read the logic of History and prescribe how human events might be changed by messianic intervention into a world order where finally justice, freedom, and peace might prevail. The authors of this neo-liberal, neo-Wilsonianism: left and liberal academics. Their place of residence: the United States, in leading universities such as Harvard, Yale, Princeton, and Stanford. Their purpose: the instruction of those who made foreign policy in Washington in the aftermath of the Cold War. Their ambition: to help America translate its ‘unipolar moment’ into a ‘unipolar epoch’ by providing American leaders with a conceptual blueprint for making the world safe for democracy by democratising the world, thereby realizing through ‘democratic globalism’ the century-old Wilsonian dream – the creation of a structure of world peace. Their method: the construction of the missing set of liberal internationalist concepts whose ideological complexity,
208 T. Smith coherence, and promise would be the essential equivalence of Marxism– Leninism, something most liberal internationalists had always wanted to achieve but only now seemed possible.
Democratic globalism as imperialism in the 1990s The tragedy of American foreign policy was now at hand. Rather than obeying the strictures of a ‘fortunate vagueness’ which might check its ‘messianic consciousness’, as Niebuhr had enjoined, liberal internationalism became possessed of just what Arendt had hoped it might never develop, ‘a scientific character . . . of philosophic relevance’ that ‘pretend[s] to know the mysteries of the whole historical process,’ that ‘pretend[s] to have found a way to establish the rule of justice on earth’ (Niebuhr 2008: 74; Arendt 1966: 470). Only in the aftermath of the Cold War, with the United States triumphant and democracy expanding seemingly of its own accord to many corners of the world – from Central Europe to different countries in Asia (South Korea and Taiwan), Africa (South Africa), and Latin America (Chile and Argentina) – had the moment arrived for democracy promotion to move into a distinctively new mode, one that was self-confidently imperialist. Wilsonians could now maintain that the study of history revealed that it was not so much that American power had won the epic contest with the Soviet Union as that the appeal of liberal inter nationalism had defeated proletarian internationalism. The victory was best understood, then, as one of ideas, values, and institutions – rather than of states and leaders. In this sense, America had been a vehicle of forces far greater than itself, the sponsor of an international convergence of disparate class, ethnic, and nationalist forces converging into a single movement that had created an histor ical watershed of extraordinary importance. For a new world, new ways of thinking were mandatory. As Hegel has instructed us, ‘Minerva’s owl flies out at dusk’, and liberal scholars of the 1990s applied themselves to the task of understanding the great victories of democratic government and open market economies over their adversaries between 1939 and 1989. What, rather exactly, were the virtues of democracy that made these amazing successes possible? How, rather explicitly, might the free world now protect, indeed expand, its perimeter of action? A new concept of power and purpose was called for. Primed by the growth of think-tanks and prestigious official appointments to be ‘policy relevant’, shocked by murderous outbreaks witnessed in the Balkans and Central Africa, believing as the liberal left did that progress was possible, Wilsonians set out to formulate their thinking at a level of conceptual sophistication that was to be of fundamental importance to the making of American foreign policy after the year 2000.6 The jewel in the crown of neo-liberal internationalism as it emerged from the seminar rooms of the greatest American universities was known as ‘democratic peace theory’. Encapsulated simply as ‘democracies do not go to war with one another’, the theory contended that liberal democratic governments breed peace
American democracy promotion as imperialism 209 among themselves based on their domestic practices of the rule of law, the increased integration of their economies through measures of market openness, and their participation in multilateral organisations to adjudicate conflicts among each other so as to keep the peace. The extraordinary success of the European Union since the announcement of the Marshall Plan in 1947, combined with the close relations between the United States and the world’s other liberal democracies, was taken as conclusive evidence that global peace could be expanded should other countries join ‘the pacific union’, ‘the zone of demo cratic peace’. A thumb-nail sketch cannot do justice to the richness of the argument. Polit ical scientists of an empirical bent demonstrated conclusively to their satisfac tion that ‘regime type matters’, that it is in the nature of liberal democracies to keep the peace with one another, especially when they are integrated together economically. Theoretically inclined political scientists then argued that liberal internationalism could be thought of as ‘non-utopian and non-ideological’, a scientifically validated set of concepts that should be recognized not only as a new but also a dominant form of conceptualising the behaviour of states (Moravcsik 1997). And liberal political philosophers could maintain on the basis of democratic peace theory that a Kantian (or Wilsonian) liberal world order was a morally just goal for progressives worldwide to seek so that the anarchy of states, the Hobbesian state of nature, could be superseded and a Golden Age of what some dared call ‘post-history’ could be inaugurated (Rawls 1999). Yet if it were desirable that the world’s leading states be democratised, was it actually possible to achieve such a goal? Here a second group of liberal inter nationalists emerged, intellectuals who maintained that the transition from authoritarian to democratic government had become far easier to manage than at earlier historical moments. The blueprint of liberal democracy was now tried and proven in terms of values, interests, and institutions in a wide variety of countries. The seeds of democracy could be planted by courageous Great Men virtually anywhere in the world. Where an extra push was needed, then the lib eral world could help with a wide variety of agencies from the governmental (such as the Agency for International Development or the National Endowment for Democracy in the United States) to the non-governmental (be it the Open Society Institute, Human Rights Watch, Amnesty International, or Freedom House). With the development of new concepts of democratic transition, the older ideas in democratization studies of ‘sequences’ and ‘preconditions’ could be jettisoned. No longer was it necessary to count on a long historical process during which the middle class came to see its interests represented in the creation of a democratic state, no longer did a people have to painfully work out a social contract of tolerance for diversity and the institutions of limited government under the rule of law for democracy to take root. Examples as distinct as those of Spain, South Korea, Poland, and South Africa demonstrated that a liberal transformation could be made with astonishing speed and success.
210 T. Smith When combined, democratic peace theory and democratic transition theory achieved a volatile synergy that neither alone possessed. Peace theory argued that the world would benefit incalculably from the spread of democratic institutions, but it could not say that such a development was likely. Transition theory argued that rapid democratisation was possible, but it could not estab lish that such changes would much matter for world politics. Combined, how ever, the two concepts came to be the equivalent of a Kantian moral imperative to push what early in the Clinton years was called ‘democratic enlargement’ as far as Washington could while it possessed the status of the globe’s sole superpower. The result would be nothing less than to change the character of world affairs that gave rise to war – international anarchy system and the character of authoritarian states – into an order of peace premised on the character of democratic governments and their association in multilateral communities basing their conduct on the rule of law that would increasingly have a global constitutional character. The arrogant presumption was, in short, that an aggressively liberal America suddenly had the possibility to change the character of History itself toward the reign of perpetual peace through democracy promotion. Enter the liberal jurists. In their hands a ‘right to intervene’ against states or in situations where gross and systematic human rights were being violated or weapons of mass destruction accumulated became a ‘duty to intervene’ in the name of what eventually became called a state’s ‘responsibility to protect.’ (ICISS 2001). The meaning of ‘sovereignty’ was now transformed. Like pirate ships of old, authoritarian states could be attacked by what Secretary of State Madeleine Albright first dubbed a ‘Community of Democracies’, practicing ‘muscular multilateralism’ in order to reconstruct them around democratic values and institutions for the sake of world peace. What the jurists thus accomplished was the redefinition not only of the meaning of sovereignty but also that of ‘Just War’. Imperialism to enforce the norms a state needed to honor under the terms of its ‘responsibility to protect’ (or ‘R2P’ as its partisans liked to phrase it) was now deemed legitimate. And by moving the locus of decision-making on the question of war outside the United Nations (whose Security Council could not be counted on to act to enforce the democratic code) to a League, or Community, or Concert of Democracies (the term varied according to the theorist), a call to arms for the sake of a demo cratising crusade was much more likely to succeed. For all of these concepts to come together and to change world affairs, Amer ican leadership was obviously indispensable. Indeed, beginning with its first use in 1998, Albright’s characterisation of the United States as ‘the indispensable nation’ gained an enduring currency: ‘If we have to use force, it is because we are America. We are the indispensable nation. We stand tall, and we see further into the future (Madeleine Albright, February 18, 1998).’ As an action-oriented ideology, liberal internationalism and its mission to promote democracy worldwide by the use of force if necessary had now come of age in intellectual terms. Woodrow Wilson had perhaps intuited democratic
American democracy promotion as imperialism 211 peace theory when he tried at Versailles in 1919 to construct a League of Nations based on democratic states and dedicated to the kind of spiritual and institutional, changes that would make the world safe for democracy by promoting liberalism globally. But his ideas lacked the empirical proof, the theoretical sophistication, and the philosophic weight that they came to enjoy in the 1990s when interna tional relations specialists at America’s leading universities put their minds to the task. By the year 2001, a country of imperial possibilities was thus finally possessed of a doctrine of imperial responsibility. If the worm were in the fruit with Wilson as president – if all the ingredients for the concepts that came to fruition in the 1990s were present in embryonic form by 1919 – it was only 80 years after he left office in 1921 that, with the inauguration of George W. Bush as president in 2001, liberal internationalism came to have the impact it had always portended but never possessed, either in terms of power or purpose. In this sense, the attack of September 11 was not a crisis so much as an opportunity. As Pres ident Bush put it in September 2002, in the document most often referred to as defining the Bush Doctrine, the National Security Strategy of the United States: ‘The great struggles of the twentieth century between liberty and totalitarianism ended with a decisive victory for the forces of freedom and a single sustainable model for national success: freedom, democracy, and free enterprise.’ (White House 2002: 1). Referring to the American ambition to secure world peace six times on the first page of the document, the president concluded his opening remarks by saying: Freedom is the non-negotiable demand of human dignity; the birthright of every person in every civilization. Throughout history, freedom has been threatened by war and terror; it has been challenged by the clashing wills of powerful states and the evil designs of tyrants; and it has been tested by widespread poverty and disease. Today humanity holds in its hand the opportunity to further freedom’s triumph over all these foes. The United States welcomes our responsibility to lead in this great mission. (White House 2002: 2) With the invasion of Iraq in March 2003, democracy promotion had become a justification for war. To be sure, the general public was sold on the idea that Saddam Hussein was harboring weapons of mass destruction, to be used most probably against Israel but with a longer-term threat to others as well. It is doubtful that the American public would have rallied to war in the name of democracy promotion alone. Equally sure, the goal of the invasion was not simply regime change in Baghdad but was also the establishment of the United States in a magnificent Middle East location, one that would allow it to project power not only with respect to Iraq’s neighbours (Iran, Syria, and Saudi Arabia most importantly, plus Jordan, Kuwait, and Turkey) but also, through its influence over local oil production, to have added leverage over OPEC as well as both Russia (whose main trump in world affairs besides its military was energy
212 T. Smith exports) and China (whose main economic weakness was lack of adequate energy resources). These factors acknowledged, it remains the case that democracy promotion was not just a camouflage for intervention on other grounds but a motive in its own right for the American invasion of Iraq. Indeed, for many it was the leading motive. For it was not just Iraq that the United States hoped to transform by demo cratization in 2003 but the entire Middle East, perhaps all the Muslim world, and were this not ambition enough, perhaps the non-democratic world in general! For good reason, many may doubt that such an outrageous ambition could truly have been an inspiration for action. Yet tempting as it surely is to Realists thinking in power terms, Marxists thinking of economic interests, or simply those thinking with common sense to discount the democratisation of the Arab world as a prime goal of American policy, there are good reasons to take this explanation seriously. For democracy promotion had become something of a secular religion during the 1990s and far too many advocates of war in 2003 were convinced by the arguments discussed above for us to believe that only narrow eco nomic concerns, or the security of Israel, or Realpolitik, or even these three factors combined, explain more than a part of this invasion.7 Underwriting ‘Operation Iraqi Freedom’, democratic peace theory had successfully persuaded many that the sole remedy for the Arab (if not Muslim) world’s political corruption, cruelty and incompetence, and thus to outbreaks of terrorist violence these problems generated within increasingly agitated popula tions, could be found only if responsible, effective, legitimate democratic gov ernments were in place there. Peace theory therefore dictated the imperative of regime change in the Arab world.
Democracy promotion and the future of American foreign policy The result of neo-liberal involvement in the creation of new thinking about American democracy promotion was that many of the chief advisers to President Barack Obama in 2009 were recruited from the ranks of those who called for the invasion of Iraq in 2003 for the purposes of democracy promotion based on the trilogy of concepts laid out above: democratic peace theory, democratic transition theory, and a new international jurisprudence on Just War. Anne-Marie Slaughter, Ivo Daalder, Ronald Asmus, Philip Gordon, Michael McFaul, James Lindsay – here are the names of but a few of the neo-liberal intellectuals who supported the invasion of Iraq on the grounds laid out above and who became active in the making of policy for America’s 44th president. In his 2008 presidential campaign, candidate Obama made clear his endorsement of liberal internationalist aims, whatever his earlier condemnation of the attack on Iraq. And in 2009, during his first year in office, he reaffirmed these beliefs, nowhere more strikingly than when he accepted the Nobel Peace Prize on 10 December 2009. Asserting, ‘Make no mistake: evil does exist in the world’, Obama announced,
American democracy promotion as imperialism 213 I believe that force can be justified on humanitarian grounds . . . inaction tears at our conscience and can lead to more costly intervention later. That is why all responsible nations must embrace the role that militaries with a clear mandate can play to keep the peace. As to the nature of his goal: ‘Only a just peace based upon the inherent rights and dignity of every individual can truly be lasting.’ And again, evoking the Universal Declaration of Human Rights adopted by the United Nations in 1948: ‘if human rights are not protected, peace is a hollow promise’. In some countries the failure to uphold human rights is excused by the false suggestion that these are Western principles, foreign to local cultures or stages of a nation’s development . . . I believe that peace is unstable where citizens are denied the right to speak freely or worship as they please; choose their own leaders or assemble without fear. Pent up grievances fester, and the suppression of tribal and religious identity can lead to violence. . . . Only when Europe became free did it finally find peace. America has never fought a war against a democracy, and our closest friends are governments that protect the rights of their citizens. No matter how callously defined, neither America’s interests, nor the world’s, are served by the denial of human aspirations. So even as we respect the unique culture and traditions of different countries, America will always be a voice for those aspirations that are universal. Obama thus continued to talk in what I would call ‘the American vernacular’, the widespread assumption that American nationalism is best expressed in world affairs by liberal internationalism – words, that is, of progressive imperialism. One can imagine that Ronald Reagan would have been impressed; after all, his famous Westminster speech of June 1982 had virtually been plagiarised by Obama’s speech writers. Can the defeats in Iraq and Afghanistan finally wake up radical liberals to the illusions of their ideology? Indeed, liberalism had compounded these reversals by an economic melt-down that, like American militarism, was the expression of national hubris backed up by the pseudo-scientific arguments of economic theory that produced the ‘Washington Consensus’, the conceptual foundation of ‘globalism’ and the disasters that followed. Yet the network of interests, institutions, and rhetorical values that surrounded liberal internationalism continued through 2011 to hold ideas in place that were the intellectual equivalent of the emperor without clothes. Liberalism may be able to retrench – to pull back from its military missions, to work out its economic dysfunctionalities – and regroup its forces – to prove that effective multilateral cooperation among like-minded peoples is possible under American leadership. But, for today, such a development seems unlikely. Economic chaos may feed on itself; more self-defeating military interventions may yet be undertaken; and all the while the banner of democracy will be lifted
214 T. Smith at the very moment that it is being undermined at home by vested interests and delusional thinking. All this was forecast six decades ago in the final lines of Niebuhr’s Irony of American History: For if we should perish, the ruthlessness of the foe would be only the secondary cause of the disaster. The primary cause would be that the strength of a great nation was directed by eyes too blind to see all the hazards of the struggle; and the blindness would be induced not by some accident of nature or history but by hatred and vainglory. (Niebuhr 2008: 174)
Notes 1 ‘I am going to teach the South American republics to elect good men’, Wilson declared with respect to Mexico, to British envoy William Tyrrell in November 1913. 2 Woodrow Wilson, ‘The Idea of America’, The Atlantic Monthly, December 2002 [a talk originally delivered December 2001] in volume 12 of Link’s Papers of Woodrow Wilson (1972: 208ff.); Clinton can best be read in his National Security Strategy Docu ment of 1995 (White House, 1995), while Bush’s Second Inaugural is readily available on line, dated 20/2/2005. 3 On Wilson and American Mandates see Link (1989: 240, 246, 253). 4 Wilson (1889: esp. II, 1171–81), and Link (1968: 65ff.). 5 On the Philippines, see ch. 2 of Smith (1994); on the occupations of Germany and Japan, see ch. 4. 6 For a longer version of the argument in this section, see Smith (2007: chs 4–6). 7 For one of the most strident expressions of this conviction in influential circles, see Kaplan and Kristol (2003); for an earlier statement see Kristol and Kagan (1996).
Conclusion Reflections on a new approach in a new era of democracy promotion Christopher Hobson and Milja Kurki 1
In the last three decades there has emerged a democracy promotion community made up of states, international organisations, quasi-governmental organisa tions, NGOs, transnational corporations and other private actors. This rapid growth has been mirrored by an equally large expansion of research, analysis and policy commentary on democratisation and democracy promotion. Despite the considerable insights generated, much of this scholarship has been limited, and perhaps even distorted, by certain assumptions that have been uncritically accepted and repeated. The focus of this volume has been to carefully examine and challenge the taken-for-granted conceptual frameworks that shape demo cracy promotion scholarship and practice. Utilising what we have termed a ‘conceptual politics’ approach, the contributors have explored the ramifications and consequences of how democracy is understood and defined. In so doing, underlying this volume has been an empirical claim and a normative one. The empirical proposition is that conceptual politics do take place in the field of democracy promotion. This has been amply demonstrated throughout the collection, most clearly by the chapters in the second section. The normative claim is that democracy promotion should be understood and practiced in a pluralist manner, an argument implied in the introduction and also explicitly made by some of the contributors, most explicitly by Ish-Shalom. Not only does this normative impetus partly reflect the contestation that takes place over the meaning of democracy in political life, it also accords with many of the core values now associated with democracy, such as pluralism and freedom of expression. In light of the richness of the preceding chapters, the aim of this conclusion is not to provide an extensive summary, but rather to draw out some of the major analytical themes and the consequences that flow from their findings. The fol lowing issues will be focused on: (1) the strengths and limitations of the conceptual politics approach; (2) what a conceptual politics framework tells us about the role of liberalism in shaping democracy promotion practices; (3) the norm ative consequences of adopting such an approach, in particular whether it facilitates or encourages relativism; (4) the more general relevance of considering the conceptual politics approach of democracy promotion at a time when the inter national political landscape is increasingly in flux.
216 C. Hobson and M. Kurki
Strengths and weaknesses Collectively this volume amply demonstrates the value-added of examining democracy promotion from a perspective that takes into account the conceptual and theoretical dimensions of these practices. Saying this, it is interesting to note the variation in why the different contributors think this is the case. For example, Ish-Shalom and Patomäki both highlight the theoretical and norm ative reasons for foregrounding the conceptual contestability of the idea of democracy. On a theoretical level, different models of democracy can be identified, each of which may point towards a different route to promoting demo cracy, such as Patomäki suggests in contrasting the liberal democratic and social democratic versions. Meanwhile, Ish-Shalom argues for a pluralistic ethic when considering meanings of democracy. In this regard, it is important to recognise, as Whitehead emphasises, that conceptions of democracy are not abstracted; they are deeply embedded and contextualised in relation to the values and practices of societies and the individuals that compose them. This insight is one that, while theoretical in nature, has direct empirical and prac tical ramifications: if the version of democracy advanced has little purchase or relevance within the specific socio-economic, historical and cultural circumstances of the target country, the chance of successful democratisation is slim. This argument is also forcefully made by Sadiki in his exploration of the pathologies and potentialities for greater democracy in the Arab Middle East. The point we wish to make is that while this volume is partly motivated by the oretical and normative interests in the contested nature of democracy, it would be a mistake to regard it as a purely theoretical exercise. What many of our contributions have shown is how a conceptual politics approach sheds new light on empirical cases. For example, in their chapters, Berman, Jahn and Smith all do so through providing theoretically informed historical accounts. Both Jahn and Berman argue, for different reasons, that liberal democracy and its historical development have been misunderstood, and this has serious ramifications for present-day decisions and policies. Jahn uncovers a much more ambiguous relationship between liberalism and democracy compared to stand ard accounts. Meanwhile, Berman suggests that the success of democracy in post-1945 Europe has been misattributed to the liberal model, proposing that it has actually been due to the consolidation of social democracy. In both chapters, a conceptual politics approach reveals how contemporary practices are shaped by a partial or questionable reading of liberal democracy and its history, and how an alternate interpretation can lead to a different set of policy recom mendations. In Smith’s chapter, he strongly argues that over time the theor etical underpinnings of America’s democracy promotion efforts have hardened and become rigid in their ideological structure, with adverse and destructive consequences. Implicit in this argument is a preference for the ‘fortunate vagueness’ that previously marked America’s efforts. Smith’s discussion highlights one of the forms of conceptual contestation considered in the introduction, that of vagueness versus precision in the way concepts are defined, or in
Conclusion 217 this case larger ideological constructs made up of different concepts. Charlesworth offers another illustration of this dynamic: while the vagueness of the concept of democracy facilitated its embedding within the ideational structures of the United Nations and international law, conceptual imprecision also con tinues to replicate minimalist understandings of democracy, and potentially undemocratic tendencies in UN actions. Other chapters brought to the fore one of the clearest manifestations of conceptual politics in this field, contestation between different forms of democracy. Wolff uses the conceptual politics framework with great effect to illustrate how the deepening of democracy has not led to the expected end of a more consolidated liberal democracy but rather a transition to another kind of democracy. He also discusses the different ways in which two external actors – the United States and Germany – have responded to the unique conceptual politics of democracy in Bolivia. Crawford and Abdulai focus on one central component of liberal democracy – civil society – and show the way it is understood influences and shapes the policy decisions of external agents engaged in supporting democrat isation. Bunce and Wolchik shed light on another realm where conceptual pol itics operates, that between external donors and local recipients. One conclusion of their pilot study is that democracy continues to be understood primarily within a liberal framework. There was, however, a tendency for donors to conceive of (liberal) democracy more in institutional terms, in contrast to recipients who took a somewhat more expansive, ‘cultural’ view that notably incorporated less tangible notions related to freedom. In an important contribution, Richard Youngs strikes a more cautious note, acknowledging that a conceptual politics approach has its uses, but warning that it could facilitate a misdiagnosis of the most pressing problems facing demo cracy promotion. He argues that ‘shortcomings in the conceptual politics of democracy certainly merit attention, even if they are not democracy promotion’s primary inadequacy, but it is more doubtful that critical theory provides the best guide to the way in which democracy support requires betterment.’ Youngs is right to highlight the potential pitfalls of a conceptual approach, in particular the danger of critique not being sufficiently based on actual practice, and he is also on solid ground in suggesting that some critical theory accounts have over- emphasised the shortcomings of liberalism and liberal democracy. Nonetheless, the editors would caution against equating a conceptual politics approach with critical theory, even if neo-Gramscians have done the most work in this area to date. Rather, the framework outlined in this volume is consciously much more open and pluralist, and one that has potential to be adopted by positivist and post-positivist scholars. For example, while Ish-Shalom argues for an explicitly constructivist and critical theory-orientated approach, Bunce and Wolchik dem onstrate that the more classical methods of political science can be adopted to study the dynamics of conceptual politics. Admittedly, as a result, differences remain in how conceptual politics is engaged, data gathered and evidence evalu ated. Indeed, across the collection one can find a wide range of epistemological and ontological assumptions informing the contributions.
218 C. Hobson and M. Kurki
Understanding the role of liberalism in democracy promotion A recurrent theme in this volume – one that has echoes elsewhere in the literat ure – is the central, arguably defining, role of liberalism in shaping the way democracy is understood and the manner in which it is promoted abroad. On this point, there is relatively widespread consensus within the volume. Where there is less agreement is over the conclusions that one can draw from this situation. For more mainstream and policy-orientated scholars, the prevalence of liberalism and liberal democratic models in democracy promotion is obvious, perhaps even unremarkable. Bunce and Wolchik’s chapter, for example, notes the strong role liberal democratic criteria in the way democracy is understood by both promoters and recipients. For many mainstream scholars and policy analysts, the role of liberalism is readily apparent, important and not normatively problematic in the way some neo-Gramscian accounts propose. Indeed, consider Zakaria’s (2003, 1997) prominent argument that there has been insufficient emphasis on the ‘lib eral’ in liberal democracy; a suggestion that can also be found in Youngs’ con tribution. On the surface, this explicit acceptance of liberalism in democracy promotion – normatively and/or empirically – may seem to suggest that a conceptual politics approach is either superfluous or problematic insofar as it may encourage a misreading of the role and value of liberalism in democracy promo tion (Youngs’ argument), with it possibly being unjustly blamed for the travails democracy promotion has been facing. Yet, if one reflects more carefully, it can be seen that this point actually validates the conceptual politics approach: it is only through examining the issue on a conceptual and theoretical level that one can properly consider the role of liberalism – positive or otherwise – in shaping the way democracy is understood and supported in democracy promotion practice (Hobson forthcoming). If many regard the central role of liberalism in democracy and democracy promotion as ‘common sense’, for critical theorists this is precisely the reason that it needs to be much more closely interrogated. Not questioning or examining liberalism’s position is in itself a move pregnant with political consequences; it can powerfully operate to entrench a specific vision of what democracy is and how it should be achieved. Engaging in these issues from a more critical theory inspired perspective entails a refusal to accept liberalism’s role at face value, nor accept such a claim as being neutral. To be clear, however, one needs to distinguish between adopting a critical theory approach to considering liberalism’s role and being critical of it. Admittedly, in many analyses both points are made and closely intertwined, as can be seen in Patomäki’s chapter in this volume, and in the neo-Gramscian literature on the topic (Robinson 1996; Gills, Rocamora and Wilson 1993). Yet an empirical proposition about the centrality of liberalism does not necessarily lead to a normative claim. One finds in Jahn’s contribution an argument that is primarily focused on the analytical consequences of accepting liberalism’s position, making a strong case that as a result the relationship between liberalism and democracy has been seriously misunderstood, which has
Conclusion 219 ramifications for policymaking. Given the significance of liberalism, and its close relationship to contemporary understandings of democracy, it is likely that there will continue to be contestation not only over liberalism’s role in the practice of democracy promotion, but also how it should be analysed. A further issue that arises from the position of the liberal democratic model in democracy promotion relates to one of the key axes of conceptual contestation that was identified, namely, that between different models of democracy. In political theory one can find a range of democratic theories, but even here there is a danger of overstating the amount of debate that exists. Turning to the real world, lib eralism’s primacy is pronounced. If one looks for major empirical examples of alternative models of democracy, they are admittedly few and far between. Nonetheless, they do exist. As Berman and Patomäki show in their chapters, the social democratic model that has been instituted in Europe, most significantly in Scandin avia, has a different set of priorities and values to the Ango-American liberal demo cratic tradition, even if there are important points of overlap and commonality. The Scandinavian model is certainly not the only empirical alternative, as Wolff shows in his important chapter on Bolivia. While acknowledging the contextual factors unique to this case, there is considerable ferment elsewhere in Latin America and rising dissatisfaction with the current regimes. One conclusion that can be drawn from the Bolivian case is that what we may be seeing is not a rejection of demo cracy in toto, but the specific neo-liberal version that has emerged since the 1980s, and the potential growth of a new form of democracy that draws on different traditions and influences. In this regard, it is worth recalling Whitehead’s thought- provoking discussion on understanding democratisation and democracy promotion with reference to biological metaphors, where he describes democracies as ‘complex adaptive system[s]’, and further notes the trend towards regime hybridity. A conceptual approach allows for a much more nuanced and textured framework for understanding such developments, compared to prevailing approaches that see democracy and non-democracy in dichotomous or gradated terms. In reflecting on the role of liberalism, a further issue is its relationship not only to the form of democracy advanced, but to the very practice of democracy promo tion. As noted in the introduction, the context for the considerable extension and embedding of democracy promotion within international politics was the liberal Zeitgeist that attended the end of the Cold War. Given that liberal principles are now under greater challenge and it appears that a more complicated balance of power is replacing the unipolar interregnum, it might be asked whether demo cracy promotion practices will be altered or sidelined in this less favourable envir onment. Liberalism’s position may be under greater challenge and liberal principles are not always systematically defended by key actors, but it would be foolish to downplay its present role or misjudge how deeply embedded it has become within international politics. In our view, liberalism continues to strongly influence not only democracy and its promotion but also the way these policies are received, interpreted, adopted, rejected and modified. Indeed, liberalism it seems structures the field within which support and opposition for these practices takes place (Hobson and Kurki 2010). Liberalism constitutes a deep-seated
220 C. Hobson and M. Kurki discursive framework for democracy promotion, despite the increasing rhetoric that accepts pluralism, contested-ness and local ownership as core starting points for democracy assistance (Hobson and Kurki 2010; Kurki forthcoming b). This is a point that Crawford and Abdulai too demonstrate in their chapter: even broader notions of civil society still largely operate within a liberal framework. This may not be a bad thing – and perhaps what is needed is indeed even more and more explicitly principled liberalism, as Youngs suggests. Yet, in this context it still remains an interesting point to consider just how possible it is for other altern ative models of democracy to be promoted with any real force in an international order that remains deeply, and implicitly, liberal.
The normative perils of conceptual politics? At a time when the ‘democracy promotion backlash’ shows few signs of dimin ishing (Carothers 2010), and publics in many transitional and consolidated democracies are suffering from a growing sense of disenchantment with this regime type, it might be asked whether conceptually unpacking democracy is particularly prudent. This volume could be open to the same line of criticism that Plattner (1998) levelled at Zakaria’s (1997) work, in which he cautioned against going too far in ‘ “unpacking” the component elements of modern liberal demo cracy’. In this sense, a conceptual politics approach might be regarded as norm atively problematic if it facilitates or encourages relativism. As noted in the introduction, democracy already suffers from considerable rhetorical abuses, with almost all states making some claim to be democratic, no matter how farfetched such attempts may seem. Put differently, there are very few governments that openly repudiate democracy. Is it possible to pluralise conceptions of demo cracy without further encouraging this state of affairs? Does a conceptual approach leave us unable to distinguish ‘real’ democracy from the many regimes that have a democratic façade but lack the freedoms and rights that give demo cracy meaning and value? This is a pressing matter when one considers that increasingly powerful states such as China and Russia are deploying the language of democracy to legitimate their governments. A concern with the dangers of relativism is understandable, especially at a time when faith in democracy may be faltering and democracy promotion practices are increasingly contested, even countered through so-called ‘autocracy promotion’ (Burnell 2010b). Nonetheless, we would deny that this charge can be levelled at this volume. The strongest counter to this line of potential criticism is provided in Ish-Shalom’s chapter, where he identifies the difference between relativism and pluralism: By embracing an anything-goes attitude, relativism dodges any sort of engagement, political or moral, with the essence of contested-ness. Relativism is the sidestepping of moral judgment necessitated by the fact of contested-ness. . . . Pluralism, contrary to relativism, accepts contested-ness, respects it, and values the reasonable meanings people hold fairly.
Conclusion 221 Just because conceptual politics recognises a plurality of potential kinds of democracy, it does not force us to accept that all democratic forms are equally democratic or democratic in the same way (see Kurki 2010). Russia can still be criticised for its inadequate democratic credentials, but needs to be done within a more politically self-aware and open environment, where Western democracy promoters recognise the politics of their own approach rather than simply assuming its priority or universality. Indeed, the pluralising moves attempted in this volume arguably lay the groundwork for a stronger defence of democracy. By denying or ignoring the conceptual contestation that does take place within democracy promotion – something that this collection has clearly demonstrated does exist theoretically and empirically – leaves us ill-equipped to distinguish the difference between legitimate and illegitimate invocations of the democratic label. Not only does conceptual pluralism facilitate debate and dialogue – in themselves important democratic activities – it has potential to encourage a more egalitarian approach to democracy promotion. A distinguishing feature of these practices to date is their unidirectional nature, in which the prioritisation of a certain model of democracy can work to privilege those actors that conform to the dominant understanding (Hobson 2009b: 397). In this regard, Teivainen (2009: 163–5) suggests that within democracy promotion there is a ‘pedagogy of power’ in which external actors perform ‘the social function of the teacher whose role is to instruct and guide the more “child-like” countries’. In contrast, the pluralist ethic underwriting the conceptual politics framework outlined in this volume is one that is more open and attuned to the range of meanings and models of democracy that exist, without automatically privileging a certain version or set of actors. Put differently, a conceptual politics may help to inject a more egalitarian and politically sensitive ethos into the thought and practice of democracy promotion, a trend that many democracy promotion practitioners have also been calling for in recent years.
The relevance of conceptual politics A defining feature of much of the literature on democracy promotion and demo cratisation is that it seeks to be of relevance to policymakers and those in the field. At first glance, the conceptual politics approach might seem like an overly abstracted endeavour that is of little assistance to practitioners. In his chapter, Youngs suggests a weaker version of this position: a conceptual politics approach might have merit, but it does not address the most pressing issues and challenges the democracy promotion community presently faces. One of the biggest criticisms of democracy promotion in recent years has been the undemocratic ways it has often been implemented. The attempts at coercive democratisation of Afghanistan and Iraq are the most obvious examples, but one can find similar complaints in reference to the way EU accession criteria have been applied in Central Eastern Europe, and the harsh structural adjustment programmes that went hand in hand with a large number of
222 C. Hobson and M. Kurki third wave transitions. The pluralist ethic that informs a conceptual politics framework has potential to encourage greater consistency between the means and ends of democracy promotion. Even introducing a more open, self-reflexive and humble language could have potentially significant ramifications. This is interesting to consider in the context of the backlash against democracy promotion, as well as the Arab spring. There is overlap and engagement between the scholarly and policy communit ies when it comes to democracy promotion, and thus there is potential for a conceptual politics approach – or some of its ethos – to filter through to policy circles. Admittedly, a conceptual politics framework would likely influence the activities of practitioners primarily in an indirect sense. Yet as Ish-Shalom argues, academics have a commitment to each other and the larger community to recognise the conceptual contestability of democracy, and the consequences that flow from this situation. Practitioners may not share this commitment yet, but can still benefit from it: not only by being able to engage in more reflective practice, but also by being able to think laterally about policy options available to them. Even if this framework might not provide simple, straightforward policy recommendations, this is certainly no reason to discount it. And where inter action between the two realms takes place, there is a need for mutual dialogue. As Youngs notes, democracy promotion scholars should not preach at policy makers about conceptual models without understanding the real world constraints within which they are generated and must function. At the same time, policymakers should not simply deny the conceptual contestation surrounding democracy, which this volume has demonstrated exists both empirically and the oretically.
Conclusion Focusing on the conceptual politics of democracy promotion does not offer a magic bullet to the troubles and ills the practice now suffers from. Furthermore, it by no means claims to explain all aspects of democracy promotion and demo cratisation. Nonetheless, at a time of flux and uncertainty, there is considerable value in exploring such an approach. In this regard, Carothers (2010: 72) has recently argued that: . . . at the same time that the Western policy community comes to grips and grapples with how to respond effectively to the [democracy promotion] backlash, it must also confront the larger imperative of finding new ideas and approaches to fit an international context for democracy work that has fundamentally changed from that of decades past. The conceptual politics framework advanced in this volume provides tools for reassessing the assumptions that have shaped practice to date, and suggests a different way of thinking about democracy promotion and democratisation. Given that the deeply unpopular ‘freedom agenda’ of the Bush administration tainted
Conclusion 223 not just American efforts but also the larger democracy promotion project, it may be an opportune, and necessary, time to undergo a deeper and more far- reaching assessment of these practices. Considering the conceptual contestation that surrounds democracy and democracy promotion injects a strong democratic ethos of pluralism into the debate, and highlights the inherently political and ideological nature of these practices.
Note 1 The research leading to these results has received funding from the European Research Council under the European Community’s Seventh Framework Programme (FP7/2007–2013) ERC grant agreement no. 202 596. All views remain those of the authors.
Bibliography
Abdulai, A.-G. and Crawford, G. (2010) ‘Consolidating Democracy in Ghana: progress and prospects?’, in Democratization, 17(1): 26–67. Acemoglu, D. and Robinson, J. A. (2006) Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Demo cracy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Adler, E. (1997) ‘Seizing the Middle Ground: Constructivism in World Politics’, Euro pean Journal of International Relations, 3: 319–63. Adler-Karlsson, G. (1967) Functional Socialism, Stockholm: Prisma. Adorno, T. and Horkheimer, M. (1979) Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. J. Cumming, London: Verso. Ahadzie, W. (2007) ‘Review of RAO Programming and Key Policy Processes in Ghana 2005–2006’, Consultancy Report prepared for the Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme, Accra. Ake, C. (1992) ‘Devaluing Democracy’, Journal of Democracy, 3(3): 32–6. Almond, G. and Verba, S. (1963) The Civic Culture: Political Attitudes and Democracy in Five Nations, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Alvarez, J. (2001) ‘Do Liberal States Behave Better? A Critique of Slaughter’s Liberal Theory’, European Journal of International Law, 12(2): 183–246. Anderson, B. (2006) Imagined Communities, London & New York: Verso. Anghie, A. (2005) Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law, Cam bridge: Cambridge University Press. Anievas, A. (2005) ‘Critical Dialogues: Habermasian Social Theory and International Relations’, Politics, 25: 135–43. Arendt, H. (1966) The Origins of Totalitarianism, New York: Harcourt. Aristotle (1976) Ethics, London: Penguin. Aristotle (1981) The Politics, London: Penguin. Armitage, D. (2004) ‘John Locke, Carolina, and the “Two Treatise of Government” ’, Political Theory, 32(5): 602–27. Armstrong, P., Glyn, A. and Harrison, J. (1991) Capitalism Since 1945, New York: Basil Blackwell. Arneil, B. (1996) John Locke and America. The Defence of English Colonialism, Oxford: Clarendon. Arrow, K. J. and Hahn, F. N. (1971) General Competitive Analysis, Amsterdam: North Holland. Atuguba, R. A. (2011) ‘Human rights and the limits of public interest law: Ghana’s reaction to a messy world phenomenon’, unpublished manuscript.
Bibliography 225 Avineri, S. (1972) Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State. London: Cambridge University Press. Avineri, S. (1968) The Social and Political Thought of Karl Marx. London: Cambridge University Press. Awori, T. (2009) ‘G-RAP Phase II Design Options: Background Report for G-RAP Stakeholders Retreat’, Akosombo, Accra, 11–12 July 2009. Ayubi, N. (1996) Over-Stating the Arab State, London: I. B. Tauris. Baker, G. (2002) Civil Society and Democratic Theory: Alternative Voices, London, Routledge. Baker, G (2004) ‘The Taming of the Idea of Civil Society’, in P. Burnell and P. Calvert (eds) Civil Society in Democratization, Abingdon: Frank Cass, pp. 43–71. Barany, Z. and Moser, R. G. (eds) (2009) Is Democracy Exportable?, Cambridge: Cam bridge University Press. Barrios Suvelza, F. X. (2008) ‘The Weakness of Excess. The Bolivian State in an Unbounded Democracy’, in J. Crabtree and L. Whitehead (eds) Unresolved Tension: Bolivia Past and Present, Pittsburg, PA: University of Pittsburg Press, pp. 125–44. Beetham, D., Bracking, S., Kearton, I. and Weir, S. (2002) International IDEA Handbook on Democracy Assessment, The Hague: Kluwer Law International. Bell, D. (2010) ‘Pogroms of Words,’ The New Republic, June 24, 2010. Berger, P. L. (1992) ‘The Uncertain Triumph of Democratic Capitalism’, Journal of Democracy, 3(3): 7–16. Berman, S. (2001) ‘Economic Modernization in Historical Perspective’, World Politics, 53(3): 431–62. Berman, S. (2007) The Primacy of Politics. Social Democracy and the Making of Europe’s Twentieth Century, New York: Cambridge University Press. Berman, S. (2009) ‘Re-Integrating the Study of Civil Society and the State’, in Z. Barany and R. G. Moser (eds) Is Democracy Exportable?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 37–56. Bermeo, N. (2009) ‘Conclusion: Is Democracy Exportable?’, in Z. Barany and R. G. Moser (eds) Is Democracy Exportable?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 242–64. Bernstein, E. (1907) Evolutionary Socialism, trans. Edith C. Harvey, London: The Inde pendent Labour Party. Online. Available at: www.marxists.org/reference/archive/bernstein/works/1899/evsoc/index.htm (accessed 22 June 2011). Bhagwati, J. (1992) ‘Democracy and Development’, Journal of Democracy, 3(3): 37–44. Bieler, A. and Morton, A. D. (2001) ‘The Gordian Knot of Agency-Structure in Interna tional Relations’, European Journal of International Relations, 7: 5–35. Binder, L. (1994) ‘Islamic Liberalism’, PS: Political Science and Politics, 27(3): 514–15. BMZ (Bundesministerium für wirtschaftliche Zusammenarbeit und Entwicklung) (2007) Länderkonzept Bolivien (June 2007), Bonn: BMZ. Boas, T. C. and Gans-Morse, J. (2009) ‘Neoliberalism: From New Philosophy to Anti- Liberal Slogan’, Studies in Comparative International Development, 44(2): 137–61. Böhrt Irahola, C. (2009) ‘Cuarenta días que conmovieron a Bolivia y un pacto político forzado’, in C. Romero, C. Böhrt and R. Peñaranda (eds) Del Conflicto al Diǎlogo. Memorias del acverdo Constitucional, La Paz: pBDM/FES-ILDIS, pp. 49–105. Boix, C. (2003) Democracy and Redistribution, New York: Cambridge University Press. Boom, Jan, Wouters, Hans and Keller, M. (2007) ‘A Cross-Cultural Validation of Stage Development: A Rasch Re-Analysis of Longitudinal Socio-Moral Reasoning Data’, Cognitive Development, 22: 213–29.
226 Bibliography Boucher, D. (2006) ‘Property and Propriety in International Relations: The Case of John Locke’, in J. Beate (ed.) Classical Theory in International Relations, Cambridge: Cam bridge University Press, pp. 156–77. Boutros-Ghali, B. (1996) An Agenda for Democratization, New York: United Nations. Bova, R. (1997) ‘Democracy and Liberty: The Cultural Connection’, Journal of Demo cracy, 8(1): 112–26. Bowden, B. and Charlesworth, H. (2009) ‘Defining Democracy in International Institutions’, in B. Bowden, H. Charlesworth and J. Farrall (eds) The Role of International Law in Rebuilding Societies After Conflict: Great Expectations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 90–110. Boyd, R. (1979) ‘Metaphor and Theory Change: What is Metaphor For?’, in A. Ortony (ed.) Metaphor and Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 481–532. Bremmer, I. (2009) ‘State Capitalism Comes of Age: The End of the Free Market?’, Foreign Affairs, 88(3). Bridoux, J. (2011) ‘Obama’s Democracy Promotion: Return to Normality?’, unpublished manuscript. Brown, D. (2007) ‘Governance Structure Brief ’, G-RAP Governance Review undertaken for LTS, International (UK). Brown, I. J. C. (1920) The Meaning of Democracy, London: Richard Cobden-Sanderson. Bunce, V. J. (2010) ‘Defeating Dictators: Electoral Change and Stability in Competitive Authoritarian Regimes,’ World Politics, 63(1): 48–86. Bunce, V. J. and Wolchik, S. L. (2006), ‘Favorable Conditions and Electoral Revolu tions’, Journal of Democracy, 17(4): 5–18. Bunce, V. J. and Wolchik, S. L. (2011) Defeating Authoritarian Leaders in Postcommunist Countries, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press. Burnell, P. (2010a) ‘New Challenges to Democratization’ in P. Burnell and R. Youngs (eds), New Challenges to Democratization, London: Routledge, pp. 1–23. Burnell, P. (2010b) ‘Is there a New Autocracy Promotion?’, FRIDE Working Paper 96. Burnell, P. (ed.) (2000) Democracy Assistance, London: Frank Cass. Burnell, P. and Youngs, R. (eds) (2010) New Challenges to Democratisation. London: Routledge. Bush, G. W. ‘Remarks by the President at the 20th Anniversary of the National Endowment for Democracy’, United States Chamber of Commerce, 6 November 2003, Washington, DC. Cantori, J. L. (1994) ‘Introduction’, Political PS: Political Science and Politics, 27(3). Carothers, T. (1999) Aiding Democracy Abroad: The learning Curve, Washington DC: Carnegie Endowment. Carothers, T. (2002) ‘The End of the Transition Paradigm’, Journal of Democracy, 13(1): 5–21. Carothers, T. (2004) Critical Mission: Essays on Democracy Promotion, Washington, D C: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. Carothers, T. (2007a) Democracy Promotion During and After Bush, Washington DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. Carothers, T. (2007b). ‘The “Sequencing” Fallacy’, Journal of Democracy, 18(1): 12–27. Carothers, T. (2009a) ‘Democracy Assistance: Political Vs. Developmental?’, Journal of Democracy, 20(1): 5–19. Carothers, T. (2009b) ‘Stepping Back from Democratic Pessimism’, Carnegie Working Paper 99. Carothers, T. (2010) ‘The Continuing Backlash Against Democracy Promotion,’ in P. Burnell and R. Youngs (eds), New Challenges to Democratization, London: Routledge, pp. 59–72.
Bibliography 227 Carothers, T. and Ottaway, M. (2000) ‘The Burgeoning World of Civil Society Aid’, in M. Ottaway and T. Carothers (eds) (2000) Funding Virtue: Civil Society, Aid and Democracy Promotion, Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, pp. 3–20. Carroll, S. (2006) The Making of the Fittest, W.W. Norton. Carroll, S. J. and Zerilli, L. M. G. (1993) ‘Feminist Challenges to Political Science’, in A. W. Finifter (ed.) Political Science: The State of the Discipline II, Washington, DC: The American Political Science Association, pp. 55–76. Cassese, A. (1986) International Law in a Divided World, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Center for Democratic Development-Ghana (2003) ‘2002 Annual Report’, Online. Avail able at: www.cddghana.org/documents/Annual%20report%202002.pdf (accessed 22 June 2011). Center for Democratic Development-Ghana (n.d.) ‘Annual report for the year ending December 2006’, Online. Available at: www.cddghana.org/documents/Annual%20 Report%202006%20%20CDD-Ghana.pdf. Cerna, C. (1995) ‘Universal Democracy: An International Legal Right or the Pipe Dream of the West?’, New York University Journal of International Law and Politics, 27(2): 289–329. Chatterjee, D. K. (2008) Democracy in a Global World, Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield. Checkel, J. T. (2001) ‘Why Comply? Social Learning and European Identity Change’, International Organization, 55: 553–588. Chesterman, S. (2004) ‘Building Democracy through Benevolent Autocracy: Consultation and Accountability in UN Transitional Administrations’, in E. Newman and R. Rich (eds) The UN Role in Promoting Democracy: Between Ideals and Reality, Tokyo: UNU Press, pp. 86–112. Chirot, D. (2009) ‘Does Democracy Work in Deeply Divided Societies?’, in Z. Barany and R. G. Moser (eds) Is Democracy Exportable?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 85–109. Clough, S. B., Moodie, T. and Moodie, C. (eds) (1968) Economic History of Europe: Twentieth Century, New York: Harper and Row. Collier, D. and Levitsky, S. (1997) ‘Democracy with Adjectives’, World Politics, 49(3): 430–51. Conaghan, C. M. and Malloy, J. M. (1994) Unsettling Statecraft. Democracy and Neo liberalism in the Central Andes, Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press. Connolly, W. (1993) The Terms of Political Discourse, 3rd Edition, Oxford: Blackwell. Connolly, W. (1995) The Ethos of Pluralization, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Cooley, A. and Ron, J. (2002) ‘The NGO Scramble: Organizational Insecurity and the Political Economy of Transnational Action’, International Security 27(1): 5–39. Cornwall, A. (2002) ‘Making Spaces, Changing Places: Situating Participation in Development’, IDS Working Paper 170, Brighton: Institute of Development Studies. Cox, M. G., Ikenberry, J. and Inoguchi, T. (2000) ‘Introduction’, in M. G. Cox, J. Ikenberry and T. Inoguchi (eds) (2000) American Democracy Promotion. Impulses, Strat egies, and Impacts, Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 1–17. Cox, R. W. and Sinclair, T. J. (1996) Approaches to World Order. Cambridge: Cam bridge University Press. Crabtree, J. and Whitehead, L. (eds) (2008) Unresolved Tensions: Bolivia past and present, Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press. Crawford, G. (2006) ‘The European Union and Strengthening Civil Society in Africa’, in M. Lister and M. Carbone (eds) New Pathways in International Development: Gender and Civil Society in EU Policy, Aldershot: Ashgate, pp. 139–58.
228 Bibliography Crawford, G. and Abdulai, A.-G. (2009) ‘The World Bank and Ghana’s Poverty Reduction Strategies: Strengthening the state or consolidating neo-liberalism?’, Labour, Capital and Society, 42(1–2): 82–115. Crawford, J. (1993) ‘Democracy and International Law’, British Yearbook of Interna tional Law, 64: 113–33. Crawford, J. (2006) The Creation of States in International Law, 2nd edn, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Crosland, C. A. R. (1967) The Future of Socialism, London: Fletcher and Son. Dahl, R. (1971) Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition. New Haven: Yale University Press. Dahrendorf, R. (1969) Society and Democracy in Germany, New York: Anchor. Dalton, R., Shin, D. C. and Jou, W. (2007) ‘Understanding Democracy: Data from Unlikely Places’, Journal of Democracy, 18 (4): 142–56. Davidson, A. (2008) ‘The Uses and Abuses of Gramsci’, Thesis Eleven, 95: 68–94. Davis, J. W. (2005). Terms of Inquiry: On the Theory and Practice of Political Science, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Dawson, T. L. (2002) ‘New Tools, New Insights: Kohlberg’s Moral Judgement Stages Revisited’, International Journal of Behavioural Development, 26(2): 154–66. De Angelis, M. (2000) Keynesianism, Social Conflict and Political Economy, New York: St. Martin’s Press. De Zeeuw, J. and Kumar, K. (2006) Promoting Democracy in Postconflict Societies, Boulder: Lynne Rienner. Denton, G., Forsyth, M. and Maclennan, M. (1968) Economic Planning and Policies in Britain, France and Germany, London: George Allen and Unwin. Department for International Development (2000) Realising Human Rights for Poor People, strategy paper, London: DFID. Department for International Development (2003) ‘G-RAP Concept Note’, Online. Avail able at: www.g-rap.org/docs/FC%20white%20paper%20July%202003.pdf (accessed 24 July 2010). Department for International Development (2006) Civil Society and Development: How DFID works in partnership with civil society to deliver the Millennium Development Goals, London: DFID. Department for International Development, Ghana (2004) Project Memorandum, Ghana Civil Society Rights and Voice Initiative, Accra: DFID Ghana. Derrida, J. (2005) Rogues, translated by P. Brault and M. Naas, Stanford: Stanford University Press. De-Shalit, A. (1997) ‘On Behalf of “the Participation of the People”: A Radical Theory of Democracy’, Res Publica, 3: 61–80. Devereux, A. (2005) ‘Searching for Clarity: A Case Study of UNTAET’s Application of International Human Rights Norms’, in N. White and D. Klaasen (eds) The UN, Human Rights and Post-Conflict Situations, Manchester: Manchester University Press, pp. 294–321. Di Scala, S. (1998) Italy: From Revolution to Republic, Boulder: Westview Press. Diamond, L. (1990) ‘Three Paradoxes of Democracy’, Journal of Democracy, 1(3): 48–60. Diamond, L. (1994) ‘Towards Democratic Consolidation’, Journal of Democracy, 5(3): 4–17. Diamond, L. (1996) ‘Is the Third Wave Over?’, Journal of Democracy, 7(3): 20–37. Diamond, L. (1999) Developing Democracy: Toward Consolidation, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Diamond, L. (2008) The Spirit of Democracy, New York: Times Books.
Bibliography 229 Diamond, L. (2009) The Spirit of Democracy, New York: St. Martin’s. Dib, K. (2007) Umara’ Al-Harb wa Tujjar Al-Haykal: Rijal Al-Sultah wa al-Mal fi Lubnan; trans. Warlords and Merchants: Lebanon’s Business and Power Estab lishment, Beirut: Dar al-Nahar. Diez, T. and Steans, J. (2005) ‘A Useful Dialogue? Habermas and International Relations’, Review of International Studies, 31: 127–40. Dryzek, J. S. and List, C. (2003) ‘Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy: A Reconciliation’, British Journal of Political Science, 33: 1–28. Duffield, M. (2007) Development, Security and Unending War: Governing the World of Peoples, Cambridge: Polity Press. Dunn, J. (1969) The Political Thought of John Locke. A Historical Account of the Argu ments of the ‘Two Treatise of Government’, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dunn, J. (2005) Setting the People Free: The Story of Democracy, London: Atlantic Books. Eickelman, D. and Anderson, J. (2003) New Media in the Muslim World: The Emerging Public Sphere, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Eley, G. (1991) Reshaping the Radical Right, Ann Arbor: Michigan University Press. Elhawary, S., Foresti, M. and Pantuliano, S. (2010) ‘Development, Security and Transitions in Fragile States: Meeting Series Report’, Overseas Development Institute and Netherlands Ministry of Foreign Affairs, Online. Available at: www.odi.org.uk/ resources/download/4772.pdf (accessed 30 January 2011). Engelstad, E. and Gerrard, S. (2005) ‘Challenging Situatedness’, in E. Engelstad and S. Gerrard (eds) Challenging Situatedness: Gender, Culture and the Production of Know ledge, Delft: Eburon, pp. 1–26. Esping-Andersen, G. (1990) The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism, Cambridge: Polity. Esposito, J. L. (1992) Islamic Threat: Myth or Reality?, New York: Oxford University Press. Esposito, J. L. and Piscatori, P. J. (1991) ‘Democratization and Islam’, Middle East Journal, 45: 427–40. European Union Election Observation Mission (2009) ‘Ghana Final Report: Presidential and Parliamentary Elections 2008’, Accra, Ghana. Falk, R. (2007) ‘What Comes After Westphalia: The Democratic Challenge’, Widener Law Review, 13(2): 243–53. Farer, T. (2004) ‘The Promotion of Democracy: International Law and Norms’, in E. Newman and R. Rich (eds) The UN Role in Promoting Democracy: Between Ideals and Reality, Tokyo: UNU Press, pp. 32–61. Farthing, L. and Kohl, B. (2005) ‘Conflicting Agendas: The Politics of Development Aid in Drug-Producing Areas’, Development Policy Review, 23(2): 183–98. Fine, R. (2007) Cosmopolitanism, London: Routledge. Finkel, S. F., Pérez-Liñán, A., Seligson, M. A., and Azpuru, D. (2006) Effects of US Foreign Assistance on Democracy Building: Results of a Cross-National Quantitative Study, Final Report, USAID: Final Report Version #34. Available at: www.pitt. edu/~politics/democracy/downloads/USAID_Democracy_Assistance_and_its_Impact_ on_Democratization_v34.pdf (accessed 28 Jan 2011). Fischer, F. (1967) Germany’s Aims in the First World War, New York: W.W. Norton. Fischer, F. (1975) War of Illusions, New York: W.W. Norton. Foucault, M. (1984) ‘Nietzsche, Genealogy, History’, trans. D. Bouchard and S. Simon, in P. Rabinow (ed.) The Foucault Reader, London: Penguin, pp. 76–100. Foucault, M. (2001) Madness and Civilization, trans. D.Cooper, London: Routledge. Fox, G. and Nolte, G. (1995) ‘Intolerant Democracies’, Harvard International Law Journal, 36: 1–70.
230 Bibliography Fox, G. and Roth, B. (2001) ‘Democracy and International Law’, Review of International Studies, 27(3): 327–52. Franck, T. (1992) ‘The Emerging Right to Democratic Governance,’ The American Journal of International Law, 86(1): 46–91. Franco, A. (2006) ‘Statement of the Honorable Adolfo Franco, Assistant Administrator, Bureau for Latin America and the Caribbean, U.S. Agency for International Development’, in Democracy in Latin America: Successes, Challenges and the Future (Hearing before the Committee on International Relations, House of Representatives, 21 June 2006), Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. Freeden, M. (1996) Ideologies and Political Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Freedom House (2009) Freedom of the Press 2009. Available at: www.freedomhouse. org/template.cfm?page=470 (accessed 23 June 2011). Freedom House (2010) Ghana Report. Available at: www.freedomhouse.org/template. cfm?page=21&year=2010 (accessed 23 June 2011). Fried, B. H. (2005) ‘Begging the Question with Style: Anarchy, State and Utopia at Thirty Years’, in E. F. Paul, , F. D. Miller, and J. Paul (eds) Natural Rights Liberalism from Locke to Nozick, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 221–54. Friedman, M. (1955) ‘Liberalism, Old Style’, in Collier’s Year Book, New York: P. F. Collier & Son, pp. 360–3. Fukuyama, F. (1989) ‘The End of History?’, The National Interest, 16: 3–18. Fukuyama, F. (1992a) ‘Capitalism and Democracy: The Missing Link’, Journal of Demo cracy, 3(3): 100–10. Fukuyama, F. (1992b) The End of History and the Last Man, London: Penguin. Gadamer, G. (1989) Truth and Method, London: Continuum. Gale, F. (1998) ‘Cave “Cave! Hic Dragones”: A Neo-Gramscian Deconstruction and Reconstruction of International Regime Theory’, Review of International Political Economy, 5: 252–83. Gallie, W. B. (1956) ‘Essentially Contested Concepts,’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56: 167–98. Gamarra, E. A. (1999) ‘The United States and Bolivia: Fighting the Drug War’, in V. Bulmer-Thomas and J. Dunkerley (eds) The United States and Latin America: The New Agenda, Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard University Press, pp. 177–206. Garton Ash, T. (2009) ‘Velvet Revolution: The Prospects’, New York Review of Books, 56 (19), December 3, 2009. Available at www.nybooks.com/articles/23437 (accessed 23 June 2011). Garton Ash, T. (2004) Free World, London: Penguin. Gat, A. (2007) ‘The Return of Authoritarian Great Powers’, Foreign Affairs, 86(4). Geddes, B. (1994) ‘Challenging the Conventional Wisdom’, Journal of Democracy, 5(4): 104–18. Geddes, B. (2007) ‘What Causes Democratization?’ in C. Boix and S. Stokes (eds) Oxford Handbook of Comparative Politics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 317–39. Geddes, B. (2009) ‘Changes in the Causes of Democratization through Time,’ in T. Landman and N. Robinson (eds) Sage Handbook of Comparative Politics, London: Sage, pp. 278–98. Gellner, E. (1989) Muslim Societies, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. George, D. (2008) ‘On Being “Competitive”: The Evolution of a Word’, Real-World Eco nomics Review, 48(6): 319–34. Online. Available at: www.paecon.net/PAEReview/ issue48/George48.pdf (accessed 23 June 2011).
Bibliography 231 Ghana News Agency (2008) ‘CDD calls for conventions to curb executive discretion’, General News of Monday, 28 July 2008. Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme (G-RAP) (2004) Joint Programme Memorandum (Draft), Online. Available at: www.grap.org/docs/joint_programmememorandum. pdf (accessed 23 June 2011). Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme (2005) Newsletter No. 2, 15 April 2005, Accra: G-RAP. Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme (2007) ‘G-RAP Mid-term Review: 2004–6’, consultancy report prepared for the Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme, 25th July 2007. Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme (2008) ‘Project Completion Report incorporating: G-rap 2007 Annual Progress Report, January 2007 – March 2008’, Contract Number CNTR 03–5188, Accra. Online. Available at: www.g-rap.org/docs/prog%20 rep%202007%20version%20290308%20-v3.pdf (accessed 23 June 2011). Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme (2009) ‘G-RAP Fund Account: Financial Report for the Period July 2008-December 2008’, Contract Number CNTR 03 5188, March, Accra. Online. Available at: www.g-rap.org/docs/fund_reports/g-rap_fund_fin_ report_2008-q34.pdf (accessed 23 June 2011). Gibbs, J. C., Basinger, K. S., Grime, R. L. and Snarey, J. R. (2007) ‘Moral Judgment Development Across Cultures: Revisiting Kohlberg’s Universality Claims’, Develop mental Review, 27: 443–500. Gill, S. (1990) American Hegemony and the Trilateral Commission. Cambridge: Cam bridge University Press. Gill, S. (1993) Gramsci, Historical Materialism and International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gill, S. (2008) Power and Resistance in the New World Order, 2nd edn, Houndmills, Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan. Gills, B., Rocamora, J. and Wilson, R. (eds) (1993) Low Intensity Democracy. London: Pluto Press. Ginsborg, P. (2008) Democracy: Crisis and Renewal, London: Profile Books. Goody, J. (2006) Europe and the Theft of History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gramsci, A. (1971) Selections from the Prison Notebooks, London: Lawrence and Wishart. Gramsci, A. (2007) Prison Notebooks. I, trans. Joseph A. Buttigieg, New York: Columbia University Press. Gramsci, A. (1996) Prison Notebooks. II, trans. Joseph A. Buttigieg, New York: Columbia University Press. Gramsci, A. (1992) Prison Notebooks. III, trans. Joseph A. Buttigieg and Antonio Callari, New York: Columbia University Press. G-RAP (2010) ‘What is G-RAP’, Online. Available at: www.g-rap.org/ (accessed 20 October 2010). Gratius, S. and Legler, T. (2009) ‘Latin America Is Different: Transatlantic Discord on How to Promote Democracy in “Problematic” Countries’, in A. Magen, T. Risse and M. A. McFaul (eds) Promoting Democracy and the Rule of Law. American and Euro pean Strategies, Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 185–215. Gray Molina, G. (2009) ‘The United States and Bolivia: Test Case for Change’, in A. Lowenthal, T. Piccone, and L. Whitehead (eds) The Obama Administration and the Americas. Agenda for Change, Washington, DC, pp. 167–82. Gray, J. (1986) Liberalism, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Gray, J. (2008) Black Mass: Apocalyptic Religion and the Death of Utopia, London: Penguin.
232 Bibliography Green, A. (2007) ‘Democracy and Donor Funding: Patterns and Trends’, Woodrow Wilson Center Eastern European Studies Newsletter, September/October 2007. Green, A. T. and Kohl, R. D. (2007), ‘Challenges of Evaluating Democracy Assistance: Perspectives from the Donor Side’, Democratization, 14 (1): 151–65. Gregory, D. (2004) The Colonial Present, Malden, MA: Blackwell. Gribbin, J. (2004) Deep Simplicity: Chaos Complexity and the Emergence of Life, London: Penguin. Guilhot, N. (2005) The Democracy Makers. Human Rights and International Order, New York: Columbia University Press. Guizot, F. (1849) Democracy in France, 3rd edition. London: John Murray. Guzzini, S. (2000) ‘A Reconstruction of Constructivism in International Relations’, Euro pean Journal of International Relations, 6: 147–82. Habermas, J. (1979) Communication and the Evolution of Society, trans. T. McCarthy, Boston: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 1: Reason and the Rationalization of Society, trans. Thomas McCarthy, Boston: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1987) The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 2: Lifeworld and System, trans. Thomas McCarthy, Boston: Beacon Press. Habermas, J. (1989) The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Habermas, J. (1990a) ‘Justice and Solidarity: On the Discussions Concerning “Stage 6” ’, in M. Kelly (ed.) Hermeneutics and Critical Theory in Ethics and Politics, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 32–52. Habermas, J. (1990b) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, trans. C. Lenhardt and S. Weber Nicholsen, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Habermas, J. (2006) The Divided West, Cambridge: Polity Press. Haden, P. and Ahadzie, W. (2008) ‘Rights and Voice Initiative (RAVI)’, End of Project Review, Final, October, unpublished document. Halliday, F. (2009) ‘International Relations in a Post-Hegemonic Age’, International Affairs, 85(1): 37–51. Harbeson, J. W. et al. (eds) (1994) Civil Society and the State in Africa, Boulder and London: Lynne Rienner. Harding, S. G. (1998) Is Science Multicultural?: Postcolonialisms, Feminisms, and Epis temologies, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Harding, S. G. (1986) The Science Question in Feminism, Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press. Harding, S. G. (1991) Whose Science? Whose Knowledge?: Thinking from Women’s Lives, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Havel, V. (1995) ‘Democracy’s Forgotten Dimension,’ Journal of Democracy, 6(2): 3–10. Hawkesworth, M. E. (1996) ‘Knowers, Knowing, Known: Feminist Theory and Claims of Truth’, in B. Laslett, S. G. Kohlstedt, H. Longino, and E. Hammonds, (eds) Gender and Scientific Authority, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, pp. 75–99. Hayek, F. A. (1944) The Road to Serfdom, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Hearn, J. (2000) ‘Foreign Political Aid, Democratization and Civil Society in Ghana in the 1990s’, CDD-Ghana Research paper No. 5, Accra: CDD-Ghana. Hearn, J. (2001) ‘The “uses and abuses” of civil society in Africa’, Review of African Political Economy, 28(87): 43–53. Hegel, G. W. F. (1942) Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox, Oxford: The Clarendon Press.
Bibliography 233 Held, D. (1996) Models of Democracy, 2nd edn, Cambridge: Polity Press. Held, D. (2006) Models of Democracy. 3rd edn, Cambridge: Polity Press. Held, D. and Patomäki, H. (2006) ‘Problems of Global Democracy: A Dialogue’, Theory, Culture & Society, 23(5): 115–133. Henderson, S. L. (2002) ‘Selling Civil Society: Western Aid and the Nongovernmental Organization Sector in Russia’, Comparative Political Studies, 35(2): 139–67. Higgins, A. (2010) ‘Out of poverty but in dissent’, Washington Post, June 9, 2010. Hille, K. (2010) ‘Child killings cast spotlight on China’s social stresses’, Financial Times, May 15/16, 2010. Hobsbawm, E. (1962) The Age of Revolutions, 1789–1884, London: Abacus. Hobsbawm, E. (1994) The Age of Extremes: A History of the World, 1914–1991, London: Michael Joseph. Hobsbawm, E. (1996) The Age of Revolution: 1789–1848, New York: Vintage Books. Hobson, C. (2009a) ‘Beyond the End of History: the Need for a “Radical Historicisation” of Democracy in International Relations,’ Millennium 37(3): 627–53. Hobson, C. (2009b) ‘The Limits of Liberal Democracy Promotion,’ Alternatives, 34(4): 383–405. Hobson, C. (forthcoming). ‘Liberal Democracy and Beyond: Extending the Sequencing Debate’, International Political Science Review. Hobson, C. and Kurki, M. (2010), ‘Democracy Promotion as a Practice of Liberal World Order’, paper presented at ‘Liberalism and World Order’ Workshop, London. Hohe, T. (2004) ‘Delivering Feudal Democracy in East Timor’, in E. Newman and R. Rich (eds) The UN Role in Promoting Democracy: Between Ideals and Reality, Tokyo: UNU Press, pp. 302–19. Holland, J. and Thirkell, A. with Trepanier, E. and Earle, L. (2009) ‘Measuring Change and Results in Voice and Accountability Work’, Department for International Development, Working Paper No. 34, London: DFID. Houle, C. (2009) ‘Inequality and Democracy: Why Inequality Harms Consolidation but Does Not Affect Democratization’, World Politics, 61(4): 589–622. Hudson C. M. (1991) ‘After the Gulf War: Prospects for Democratization in the Middle East’, Middle East Journal, 45: 407–27. Huntington, S. (1969) Political Order in Changing Societies, New Haven: Yale University Press. Huntington, S. (1991) The Third Wave: Democratization in the Late Twentieth Century. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press. Huntington, S. (1991) ‘Democracy’s Third Wave’, Journal of Democracy, 2(2): 12–34. Huntington, S. (1996) ‘Democracy for the Long Haul’, Journal of Democracy, 7(2): 3–13. Hurrell, A. (2007) On Global Order: Power, Values and the Constitution of International Society, Oxford University Press. Hut, S. R. (2006) ‘Civil Society and European Union Development Policy’, in M. Lister and M. Carbone (eds) New Pathways in International Development: Gender and Civil Society in EU Policy, Aldershot: Ashgate, pp. 109–22. Ikenberry, G. J. (1992) ‘A World Economy Restored’, International Organization, 46(1): 289–321. Inayatullah, N. and Blaney, D. L. (2004) International Relations and the Problem of Dif ference, New York: Routledge. Institute for Economic Affairs (2010) ‘Welcome’, Online. Available at: www.ieagh.org (accessed 20 December 2010). Institute for Economic Affairs (2007) ‘Narrative Progress Report of January–June 2007
234 Bibliography submitted to G-RAP’, Contract Ref. No. 01/core/31/IEA, Accra, 25 July 2007. Online. Available at: www.g-rap.org/docs/rao_reports/nar_2007–12_iea.pdf (accessed 23 June 2011). International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS) (2001) ‘The Responsibility to Protect’, Ottawa, Ontario: International Development Research Centre. Ish-Shalom, P. (2006) ‘Theory as a Hermeneutical Mechanism: The Democratic-Peace Thesis and the Politics of Democratization’, European Journal of International Rela tions, 12(4): 565–98. Ish-Shalom, P. (2008) ‘Theorization, Harm, and the Democratic Imperative: Lessons from the Politicization of the Democratic-Peace Thesis’, International Studies Review, 10: 680–92. Ish-Shalom, P. (2010) ‘Political Constructivism: The Political Construction of Social Knowledge’, in C. Bjola and M. Kornprobst (eds) Arguing Global Governance: Agency, Lifeworld and Shared Reasoning, New York: Routledge, pp. 231–46. Ish-Shalom, P. (forthcoming a) ‘Defining by Naming: Israeli Civic Warring over the Second Lebanon War’, European Journal of International Relations. Ish-Shalom, P. (2011) ‘Theoreticians’ Obligation of Transparency: When Parsimony, Reflexivity, Transparency, and Reciprocity Meet’, Review of International Studies 37(3): 973–96. Ivison, D. (2003) ‘Locke, Liberalism and Empire’, in P. R. Anstey (ed.) The Philosophy of John Locke: New Perspectives, London: Routledge, pp. 86–105. Jahn, B. (2000) The Cultural Construction of International Relations. The Invention of the State of Nature, Basingstoke: Palgrave. Jahn, B. (2007) ‘The Tragedy of Liberal Diplomacy: Democratization, Intervention, Statebuilding I’, Journal of Intervention and Statebuilding, 1(1): 88–106. James, H. (2003) Europe Reborn, New York: Longman. Jones, P. (1981) The 1848 Revolutions, New York: Longman. Jorion, P. (2009) Comment la verité et la realité furent inventeé, Paris: Gallimard. Joseph, J. (2008) ‘Hegemony and the Structure-Agency Problem in International Relations: A Scientific Realist Contribution’, Review of International Studies 34: 109–28. Judt, T. (2005) Postwar, New York: Penguin. Kagan, R. (2008) The Return of History and the End of Dreams, London: Atlantic Books. Kampfner, J. (2009) Freedom for Sale, London: Simon and Schuster. Kaplan, L. F. and Kristol, W. (2003) The War over Iraq: Saddam’s Tyranny and Amer ica’s Mission, Encounter Books. Kapstein, E. B. (1996) ‘Workers and the World Economy’, Foreign Affairs, May/June: 16–37. Kapstein, E. and Converse, N. (2008) ‘Why Democracies Fail’, Journal of Democracy, 19(4): 57–68. Kauffman, S.A. (1993) The Origins of Order: Self-Organisation and Selection in Evolu tion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Keane, J. (2009) The Life and Death of Democracy; London: Simon & Schuster. Kehr, E. (1983) Battleship Building and Party Politics in Germany, 1894–1901, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kienle, E. (2010) ‘Global Competitiveness, the Erosion of Checks and Balances, and the Demise of Liberal Democracy’, Open Democracy, Online. Available: www.opendemo cracy.net/global-competitiveness-erosion-o f-checks-a nd-balances-a nd-demise-ofliberal-democracy (accessed 30 January 2011).
Bibliography 235 Kim, K. (1992) ‘Marx, Schumpeter, and the East Asian Experience’, Journal of Demo cracy, 3(3): 17–31. Klamer, A. and Leonard, T. C. (1994) ‘So What’s an Economic Metaphor?’, in P. Mirowski (ed.) Natural Images in Economic Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 20–51. Klapwijk, J. (2008) Purpose in the Living World?: Creation and Emergent Evolution, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kogan, N. (1968) ‘Fascism as a Political System’, in S. J. Woolf (ed.) The Nature of Fascism, London: George Weidenfeld & Nicolson, Ltd. Kohl, B. and Bresnahan, R. (eds) (2010) Latin American Perspectives (two issues on ‘Bolivia under Morales’), 37(3/4): 11–18. Kohlberg, L. (1971) ‘From Is to Ought: How to Commit the Naturalistic Fallacy and Get Away with It in the Study of Moral Development’, in T. Mischel (ed.) Cognitive Development and Epistemology, New York: Academic Press, pp. 151–235. Kohlberg, L. (1973) ‘The Claim to Moral Adequacy of a Highest Stage of Moral Judgment’, Journal of Philosophy, 70(18): 630–46. Kohlberg, L. (1981) The Philosophy of Moral Development. Moral Stages and the Idea of Justice. Essays on Moral Development Volume 1, San Francisco: Harper & Row. Kopstein, J. (2006) ‘The Transatlantic Divide over Democracy Promotion’, Washington Quarterly, 29(2): 85–98. Korany, B. (1994) ‘Arab Democratization: A Poor Cousin’, PS: Political Science and Politics, 27(3): 511–13. Korpi, W. (1978) The Working Class in Welfare Capitalism, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Koselleck, R. (1996) ‘A Response to Comments on Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe’ in H. Lehmann and M. Richter (eds) The Meaning of Historical Terms and Concepts: New Studies on Begriffsgeschichte. German Historical Institute, Occasional Paper 15, pp. 59–70. Kranzberg, M. (1959) 1848 A Turning Point?, Boston: D.C. Heath and Company. Krastev, I. (2010) ‘Deepening Dissatisfaction’, Journal of Democracy, 21(1): 113–119. Krebs, D. L. and Denton, K. (2006) ‘Explanatory Limitations of Cognitive-Developmental Approaches to Morality’, Psychological Review, 113(3): 672–5. Kristol, W. and Kagan, R. (1996) ‘Toward a Neo-Reaganite Foreign Policy’, Foreign Affairs, 75 (4 Summer) Kurki, M. (2010) ‘Democracy and Conceptual Contestability: Reconsidering Conceptions of Democracy in Democracy Promotion’, International Studies Review, 12 (3): 362–386. Kurki, M. (forthcoming a) ‘Democracy through technocracy? Reflections on technocratic assumptions in EU democracy promotion discourse’, Journal of Intervention and State building. Kurki, M. (forthcoming b) ‘Governmentality and EU Democracy Promotion: The Euro pean Instrument for Democracy and Human Rights and the Construction of Democratic Civil Societies,’ International Political Sociology. Langer, W. (1969) Political and Social Upheaval, 1832–1852, New York: Harper and Row. Langer, W. (1969) The Revolutions of 1848, New York: Harper and Row. Laslett, P. (1994) ‘Introduction’, in J. Locke, Two Treatises of Government, P. Laslett (ed.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3–126. Laslett, P. (ed.) John Locke, Two Treatise of Government, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–133.
236 Bibliography Lebovics, H. (1986) ‘The Uses of America in Locke’s Second Treatise of Government’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 47(4): 567–581. Ledebur, K. and Youngers, C. (2008) ‘Balancing Act: Bolivia’s Drug Control Advances and Challenges’, Online. Available at: www.wola.org (accessed 9 January 2009). Lévy, B.-H. (2009) Left in Dark Times: A Stand Against the New Barbarism, New York: Random House. Link, A. (1969) The Papers of Woodrow Wilson, vol 5. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Link, A. (1972) The Papers of Woodrow Wilson, vol 12. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Link, A. (1982) The Papers of Woodrow Wilson, vol 40. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Link, A. (1983) The Papers of Woodrow Wilson, vol 41. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Link, A. (1989) The Papers of Woodrow Wilson, vol 61. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Linz, J. and Stepan, A. (1996) ‘Toward Consolidated Democracies’, Journal of Demo cracy, 7(2). Lizardo, O. (2004) ‘The Cognitive Origins of Bourdieu’s Habitus’, Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 34(4): 375–401. Locke, J. (1959) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, 2 Vols., collated and annotated by Alexander Campbell Fraser, New York: Dover. Locke, J. (1983) A Letter Concerning Toleration, J. H. Tully (ed.) Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. Locke, J. (1994) Two Treatises of Government, P. Laslett (ed.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Löwenheim, O. (2008) ‘Examining the State: A Foucauldian Perspective on International “Governance Indicators” ’, Third World Quarterly, 29: 255–74. Lukes, S. (2004) Power: A Radical View, 2nd edn, Houndmills, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Lustick, I. S. (1999) ‘Hegemony and the Riddle of Nationalism’, in L. Binder (ed.) Ethnic, Conflict and International Politics in the Middle East, Gainsville, FL: University Press of Florida, pp. 332–59. Lyotard, J.-F. (1984) The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans. G. Bennington and B. Massumi, Manchester: Manchester University Press. Mackie, G. (2003) Democracy Defended, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. MacPherson, C. B. (1964) The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. MacPherson, C. B. (1977) The Life and Times of Liberal Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Maier, C. (1981) ‘The Two Postwar Eras’, American Historical Review, 86(2): 327–52. Mansfield, E. D. and Snyder, J. (2008) ‘Democratization and Civil War’, Saltzman Working Paper, 5. Online. Available at: www.siwps.com/programs/SWP.html (accessed 30 Sep 2010). Marcuse, P. (2004) ‘The “War On Terrorism” and Life in Cities after September 11, 2001’, in S. Graham (ed.) Cities, War, and Terrorism: Towards an Urban Geopolitics, Malden, MA: Blackwell: 263–75. Marglin, S. and Schor, J. (eds) (1991) The Golden Age of Capitalism, New York: Clarendon Press.
Bibliography 237 Markoff, J. (1991) The Abolition of Feudalism, College Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. Marks, R. B. (2007) The Origins of the Modern World. Fate and Fortune in the Rise of the West, Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield. Marks, S. (2000) The Riddle of all Constitutions: International Law, Democracy, and the Critique of Ideology, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Marshall, A. (1959) Principles of Economics. London: Macmillan and Co. Marx, K. (1975) ‘A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right. Introduction.’, in Karl Marx: Early Writings, New York: Vintage Books, pp. 243–57. May, C. (2000) A Global Political Economy of Intellectual Property Rights, London: Routledge. Mayorga, R. A. (1997) ‘Bolivia’s Silent Revolution’, Journal of Democracy, 8(1): 142–156. Mazower, M. (2000) Dark Continent, New York: Vintage. McFaul, M. (2004–5) ‘Democracy Promotion as a World Value’ The Washington Quarterly, 28(1): 147–63. McFaul, M. (2010) Advancing Democracy Abroad: Why We Should and How We Can. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. McNally, D. (1988) Political Economy and the Rise of Capitalism. A Reinterpretation, Berkeley: University of California Press. Melia, T. (2005) The Democracy Bureaucracy: The Infrastructure of American Democracy Promotion. Discussion paper prepared for the Princeton Project on National Security. Meyer, T. with Hinchman, L. (2007) The Theory of Social Democracy, Cambridge: Polity. Miller, A., Hesli, V. and Reisinger, W. (1997) ‘Conceptions of Democracy among Mass and Elite in Post-Soviet Societies’, British Journal of Political Science, 27(2): 157–90. Mitzen, J. (2005) ‘Reading Habermas in Anarchy: Multilateral Diplomacy and Global Public Spheres’, American Political Science Review, 99: 401–17. Monten, J. (2005) ‘The Roots of the Bush Doctrine. Power, Nationalism, and Democracy Promotion in U.S. Strategy’, International Security, 29(4): 112–156. Moravcsik, A. (1997) ‘Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Pol itics’, International Organization, 51(4): 513–53. Morlino, L. (2005) ‘Anchors and Democratic Change,’ Comparative Political Studies, 38 (7): 743–70. Morlino, L. (2009) ‘Are There Hybrid Regimes? Or Are They Just an Optical Illusion?’ European Political Science Review 1(2): 273–96. Morsink, J. (1999) The Universal Declaration of Human Rights: Origins, Drafting and Intent, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Müller, H. (2004) ‘Arguing, Bargaining and All That: Communicative Action, Rationalist Theory and the Logic of Appropriateness in International Relations’, European Journal of International Relations, 10: 395–435. Murphy, J. B. (1994) ‘The Kinds of Order in Society’, in P. Mirowski (ed.) Natural Images in Economic Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 536–82. Niebuhr, R. (2008) The Irony of American History, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Nozick, R. (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. O’Donnell, G. (1996) ‘Illusions About Consolidation’, Journal of Democracy, 7(2): 34–51. O’Donnell, G. (2007) ‘The Perpetual Crises of Democracy,’ Journal of Democracy 18(1): 5–11. Obama, B. (2010) ‘Remarks by the President to the United Nations General Assembly’, Online. Available at: www.whitehouse.gov/the-press-office/2010/09/23/remarks- president-united-nations-general-assembly (accessed 30 January 2011).
238 Bibliography OECD (2010) ‘Do No Harm: International Support for Statebuilding’, Online. Avail able at: http://www.keepeek.com/digital_asset_management/oecd/development/doc_ no_harm9759264046245-en (accessed 24 June 2011). Offe, C. (1983) ‘Competitive Party Democracy and the Keynesian Welfare State: Factors of Stability and Disorganization’, Policy Sciences, 15(3): 225–46. Ohemeng, F. L. K. (2005) ‘Getting the state right: think tanks and the dissemination of New Public Management ideas in Ghana’, Journal of Modern African Studies, 43(3): 443–65. Orwell, G. (1946) ‘Politics and the English Language’. Available at www.mtholyoke.edu/ acad/intrel/orwell46.htm (accessed 31 January 2010). Ottaway, M. & Carothers, T. (eds) (2000) Funding Virtue: Civil Society, Aid and Demo cracy Promotion, Washington, DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. Parens, J. (1994) ‘Whose Liberalism? Which Islam?’, PS: Political Science and Politics, 27(3): 514–16. Patomäki, H. (2000) ‘Beyond Nordic Nostalgia: Envisaging a Social/Democratic System of Global Governance’, Cooperation and Conflict, 35(2): 115–54. Patomäki, H. (2002) After International Relations. Critical Realism and the (Re)Con struction of World Politics, London: Routledge. Patomäki, H. (2006) ‘Liberal-Democratization as a Global Political Project’, Interna tional Studies Review, 2(8): 336–8. Patomäki, H. (2008) The Political Economy of Global Security. War, Future Crises and Changes in Global Governance, London: Routledge. Patomäki, H. (2010) ‘Exploring Possible, Likely and Desirable Global Futures: Beyond the Closed vs. Open Systems Dichotomy’, in J. Joseph and C. Wight (eds) Scientific Realism and International Relations, London: Palgrave, pp. 147–166. Patomäki, H. (forthcoming) On the Stages of Ethico-Political Learning, unpublished manuscript. Patomäki, H. and Teivainen, T. (2004) A Possible World. Democratic Transformation of Global Institutions, London: Zed Books. Patrucco, A. (1992) The Critics of the Italian Parliamentary System, 1860–1915, New York: Garland Publishing. Perelman, M. (2000) The Invention of Capitalism. Classical Political Economy and the Secret History of Primitive Accumulation, Durham: Duke University Press. Piaget, J. (1977) The Moral Judgement of the Child, trans. M. Gabain, Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin. Piaget, J. (2002) The Language and Thought of the Child, trans. M. and R. Gabain, London: Routledge. Pipes, D. (1995) ‘There are no Moderates: Dealing with Fundamentalist Islam’, The National Interest, 41 (Fall): 48–57. Pipes, D. (2003) ‘[Finding Moderate Muslims:] Do You Believe in Modernity?’, Jeru salem Post, Online. Available at: www.danielpipes.org/1322/finding-moderatemuslims-do-you-believe-in-modernity (accessed 30 January 2011). Pipes, D. (2004) ‘Stealth Islamist: Khaled Abou El Fadl’, Middle East Quarterly, 11(2): 55–62. Plattner, M. (1998). ‘Liberalism and Democracy: Can’t Have One Without the Other,’ Foreign Affairs, 77(2): 171–80. Plattner, M. (2008) Democracy Without Borders? Global Challenges to Liberal Demo cracy, Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield. Polyani, M. (2009) The Tacit Dimension, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bibliography 239 Popper, K. (1960) The Poverty of Historicism, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Pospisil, J. (2009) Die Entwicklung von Sicherheit. Entwicklungspolitische Programme der USA und Deutschlands im Grenzbereich zur Sicherheitspolitik, Bielefeld: Transcript. Potter, E. (2006) Feminism and Philosophy of Science: An Introduction, New York: Routledge. Przeworski, A. (1985) Capitalism and Social Democracy, New York: Cambridge University Press. Przeworski, A. (1991) Democracy and the Market, New York: Cambridge University Press. Przeworski, A. (1992) ‘The Neoliberal Fallacy’, Journal of Democracy, 3(3): 45–58. Przeworski, A., Alvarez, M. E., Cheibub, J. A. and Limongi, F. (2000) Democracy and Development. Political Institutions and Well-Being in the World, 1950–1990, Cam bridge: Cambridge University Press. Puchala, D. J. (2005) ‘World Hegemony and the United Nations’, International Studies Review, 7: 571–84. Puhle, H.-J. (2001) ‘Herausragende Transformations- und Entwicklungsleistungen in Bolivien’, in W. Weidenfeld (ed.) Den Wandel gestalten – Strategien der Transforma tion, Vol. 1, Gütersloh: Bertelsmann Stiftung, pp. 169–87. Rajagopal, B. (2003) International Law From Below, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rawls, J. (1973) A Theory of Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rawls, J. (1985) ‘Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 14(3): 225–26. Rawls, J. (1993) Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Rawls, J. (1999) The Law of Peoples; with, the Idea of Public Reason Revisited, Cam bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (2001) ‘Preface for the French Edition of a Theory of Justice’, in S. Freeman (ed.) Collected Papers, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 415–20. Resiman, M. (2000) ‘Sovereignty and Human Rights in Contemporary International Law’, in G. Fox and B. Roth (eds) Democratic Governance and International Law, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 239–58. Rights and Voice Initiative (RAVI) (2005) Citizen-Government Engagement Initiatives within Ghana: An Overview, Accra: RAVI. Rights and Voice Initiative (2007) Supporting CBOs to do Citizen-Government Engage ment: a guide for RAVI intermediary organisations, March, Accra: RAVI. Rights and Voice Initiative (2009a) Compendium of RAVI Grant Partners, Accra: RAVI. Rights and Voice Initiative (2009b) Enhancing Citizen Government Engagement in Ghana: Stories of Significant Change, Accra: RAVI. Risse, T. (2000) ‘ “Let’s Argue!”: Communicative Action in World Politics’, Interna tional Organization, 54: 1–39. Robinson, W. (1996) Promoting Polyarchy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Romero, C., Böhrt, C. and Peñaranda, R. (2009) Del conflicto al diálogo. Memorias del acuerdo constitucional, La Paz: fBDM/FES-ILDIS. Root, E. (1917) ‘The Effect of Democracy on International Law’, International Conciliation, 117: 153–70. Rose, G. (2000–01) ‘Democracy Promotion and American Foreign Policy: A Review Essay’, International Security, 25(3): 186–203. Rose, S. (2005) Life Lines: Life beyond the Gene, London: Vintage.
240 Bibliography Rostow, W. W. (1960) The Stages of Economic Growth. A Non-Communist Manifesto, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Roth, B. R. (2000) ‘Evaluating democratic progress’, in G. H. Fox and B. R. Roth (eds) Democratic Governance and International Law, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 493–516. Rueschemeyer, D., Stephens, E. H. and Stephens, J. D. (1992) Capitalist Development and Democracy, Cambridge: Polity Press. Ruggie, J. G. (1982) ‘International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Lib eralism in the Postwar Economic Order’, International Organization, 36(2): 379–415. Rüland, J. and Werz, N. (2002) ‘Germany’s Hesitant Role in Promoting Democracy’, in P. J. Schraeder (ed.) Exporting Democracy. Rhetoric vs. Reality, Boulder: Lynne Rienner, pp. 73–88. Ryner, J. M. (2003) Capitalist Restructuring, Globalisation and the Third Way. Lesson from the Swedish Model, London: Routledge. Sadiki, L. (2004) The Search for Arab Democracy: Discourses and Counter-Discourses, New York: Columbia University Press. Sadiki, L. (2009) Rethinking Arab Democratization: Elections without Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sadiki, L. (2011) Hamas and Democracy, London: Routledge. Sadiki, L. et al. (eds) (2011) Arab Democratization: Unmaking Power, London: Routledge. Said, E. (1978) Orientalism, New York: Pantheon. Salomone, W. (ed.) (1970) Italy from Risorgimento to Fascism, New York: Anchor Books. Sandbrook, R., Edelman, M., Heller, P. and Teichman, J. (2007) Social Democracy in the Global Periphery. Origins, Challenges, Prospects, New York: Cambridge University Press. Santos, B. S. (ed.) (2005) Democratizing Democracy. Beyond the Liberal Democratic Canon, London: Verso. Sardar, Z. (2004) ‘Why Do They Hate Us?’, New Statesman, 133: 4708: 48–50. Sartori, G. (1995) ‘How Far Can Free Government Travel?’, Journal of Democracy, 6(3): 101–11. Sassoon, D. (1998) One Hundred Years of Socialism, New York: New Press. Saul, J. R. (2005) The Collapse of Globalism and the Reinvention of the World, London: Atlantic Books. Scanlon, T. (1998) ‘What We Owe to Each Other’, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Schmitt, C. (1996) The Concept of the Political, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Schmitter, P. (1995a) ‘Transitology: The Science or the Art of Democratization?’, in J. S. Tulchin (ed.) The Consolidation of Democracy in Latin America, Boulder: Lynne Rienner, pp. 11–41. Schmitter, P. (1995b) ‘More Liberal, Preliberal, or Postliberal?’, Journal of Democracy, 6(1): 15–22. Schmitter, P. (2006) ‘A Sketch of What A ‘Post-Liberal’ Democracy Might Look Like’, Online. Available at: www.talaljuk-ki.hu/index.php/article/articleprint/502/-1/21 (accessed March 2009). Schmitter, P. (2008) ‘International Democracy Promotion and Protection: Theory and Impact’, in N. S. Tiexeira (ed.) The International Politics of Democratization: Compara tive Perspectives, Abingdon: Routledge, pp. 26–52. Schoenbaum, D. (1967) Hitler’s Social Revolution, New York: W.W. Norton & Co. Schraeder, P. J. (2003) ‘The State of the Art in International Democracy Promotion: Results of a Joint European-North American Research Network’, Democratization, 20(2): 21–44.
Bibliography 241 Schulze, H. (1991) The Course of German Nationalism, New York: Cambridge. Schumpeter, J. (1943) Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. London, George Allen & Unwin. Schumpeter, J. (2008) Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, New York: Harper Perennial. Seligman, A. B. (2009) ‘Democracy, Civil Society, and the Problem of Toleration’, in Z. Barany and R. G. Moser (eds) Is Democracy Exportable?, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 110–28. Shapiro, I. (2005) The Flight from Reality in the Human Sciences, Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press. Shennan, A. (1989) Rethinking France: Plans for Renewal 1940–1946, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Simma, B. (1995) The Charter of the United Nations: A Commentary, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Skidelsky, R. (1989) ‘The Political Meaning of Keynesianism’, in P. Hall (ed.) The Polit ical Power of Economic Ideas, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Skinner, Q. (2002) Visions of Politics. Volume 1: Regarding Method, Cambridge: Cam bridge University Press. Slaughter, A.-M. (1995) ‘International Law in a World of Liberal States’, European Journal of International Law, 6(1): 503–38. Smith, D. E. (1987) ‘Women’s Perspective as a Radical Critique of Sociology’, in Harding, S. G. Feminism and Methodology: Social Science Issues, Bloomington and Milton Keynes: Indiana University Press and Open University Press, pp. 84–96. Smith, T. (1994) America’s Mission. The United States and the Worldwide Struggle for Democracy in the Twentieth Century, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Smith, T. (2007) A Pact with the Devil. Washington’s Bid for World Supremacy and the Betrayal of the American Promise, New York: Routledge. Sonnert, G. (1994) ‘Limits of Morality: A Sociological Approach to Higher Moral Stages’, Journal of Adult Development, 1(2): 127–34. Spanger, H.-J. and Wolff, J. (2007a) ‘Universales Ziel – partikulare Wege? Externe Demokratieförderung zwischen einheitlicher Rhetorik und vielfältiger Praxis’, in A. Geis, H. Müller and W. Wagner (eds) Schattenseiten des Demokratischen Friedens. Zur Kritik einer Theorie liberaler Außen- und Sicherheitspolitik, Frankfurt/New York, NY: Campus, pp. 261–84. Spanger, H.-J. and Wolff, J. (2007b) ‘Why promote democratisation? Reflections on the instrumental value of democracy’, in M. van Doorn and R. von Meijenfeldt (eds) Demo cracy: Europe’s Core Value? On the European profile in world-wide democracy assist ance, Delft: Eburon, pp. 33–49. Sperber, J. (2005) The European Revolutions, New York: Cambridge University Press. Stearns, P. (1974) 1848: The Revolutionary Tide in Europe, New York: W.W. Norton & Co. Steele, B. J. (2010) ‘Of “Witch’s Brews” and Scholarly Communities: The Dangers and Promise of Academic Parrhesia’, Cambridge Review of International Affairs, 23: 49–68. Steiner, H. (1988) ‘Political Participation as a Human Right’, Harvard Human Rights Year book, 1: 77–134. Steinmo, S. (2008) ‘What is Historical Institutionalism?,’ in D. Porta and M. Keating (eds), Approaches in the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 113–38. Steinmo, S. (2010) The Evolution of Modern States: Sweden, Japan, and the United States. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
242 Bibliography Sternhell, Z. (1995a) The Birth of Fascist Ideology, New York: Cambridge University Press. Sternhell, Z. (1995b) Neither Right nor Left, New York: Cambridge University Press. Swedberg, R. (1986) ‘The Doctrine of Economic Neutrality of the IMF and the World Bank’, Journal of Peace Research, 23(4): 377–90. Talavera, A. F. (1992) ‘The Future of an Illusion’, Journal of Democracy, 3(3): 111–17. Teivainen, T. (2002) Enter Economism, Exit Politics: Experts, Economic Policy and the Damage to Democracy, London: Zed Books. Teivainen, T. (2009) ‘The Pedagogy of Global Development: the promotion of electoral democracy and the Latin Americanisation of Europe’, Third World Quarterly, 30(1): 163–79. Tesón, F. (1992) ‘The Kantian Theory of International Law’, Columbia Law Review, 92(1): 53–102. Thierry, A. (1856) History of the Conquest of England by the Normans; Its Causes, and its Consequences, in England, Scotland, Ireland, & on the Continent, vol. 1, trans. W. Hazlitt, London: H.G. Bohn. Tilly, C. (2004) Contention and Democracy in Europe, 1650–2000, NY: Cambridge University Press. Traub, J. (2008) The Freedom Agenda: Why America Must Spread Democracy (Just Not the Way George Bush Did), New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux. Tuck, R. (1999) The Rights of War and Peace. Political Thought and the International Order from Grotius to Kant, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Tully, J. (1982) A Discourse on Property. John Locke and his Adversaries, Cambridge: Cam bridge University Press. Tully, J. (1993) An Approach to Political Philosophy: Locke in Contexts, Cambridge: Cam bridge University Press. UNDP (2002) Human Development Report: Deepening Democracy in a Fragmented World, New York: UNDP. USAID (2010) ‘Our work’, Online. Available at: www.usaid.gov/our_work. (accessed 20 December 2010). Van Cott, D. L. (2003) ‘From Exclusion to Inclusion: Bolivia’s 2002 Elections’, Journal of Latin American Studies, 35(4): 751–75. Van Cott, D. L. (2005) From Movements to Parties in Latin America. The Evolution of Ethnic Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Van Rooy, A. (ed.) (1998) Civil Society and the Aid Industry, London: Earthscan. Vanberg, V. J. (2008) ‘On the Complementarity of Liberalism and Democracy – A Reading of F.A. Hayek and J.M. Buchanan’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 4(2): 139–61. Washbrook, D. (1997) ‘From Comparative Sociology to Global History: Britain and India in the Pre-History of Modernity’, Journal of the Economic and Social History of the Orient, 40(4): 410–43. Weber, M. (2005) ‘The Critical Social Theory of the Frankfurt School, and the “social turn” in IR’, Review of International Studies, 31: 195–209. Wedel, J. (2009) Shadow Elite: How the World’s New Power Brokers Undermine Demo cracy, Government, and the Free Market, New York: Basic Books. Weldes, J. (1996) ‘Constructing National Interests’, European Journal of International Rela tions, 2: 275–318. Weldon, S. L. (2006) ‘Inclusion and Understanding: A Collective Methodology for Fem inist International Relations’, in B. A. Ackerly, M. Stern and J. True (eds) Feminist
Bibliography 243 Methodologies for International Relations, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 62–87. Wheatley, S. (2005) Democracy, Minorities and International Law, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wheatley, S. (2010) The Democratic Legitimacy of International Law, Studies in Interna tional Law, Oxford: Hart Publishing. Whitehead, L. (2001a) ‘Bolivia and the Viability of Democracy’, Journal of Democracy, 12(1): 6–16. Whitehead, L. (2001b) ‘The Viability of Democracy’ in John Crabtree & Laurence Whitehead (eds.) Towards Democratic Viability: The Bolivian Experience, London: Palgrave, pp. 3–20. Whitehead, L. (2002) Democratization: Theory and Experience, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Whitehead, L. (2008) ‘The Fading Regional Consensus on Democratic Convergence’, in Domínguez, J. I. and Shifter M. (eds) Constructing Democratic Governance in Latin America, 3rd edn, Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 13–38. Whitehead, L. (2009). “Losing ‘the Force’? The ‘Dark Side’ of Democratization after Iraq”, Democratization 16(2): 215–42. Whitehead, L. (2010) ‘Biology, Politics and Democracy,’ Taiwan Journal of Democracy, 6 (2): 23–42. Whitehead, L. (forthcoming 2011) ‘ “Enlivening” the Concept of Democratisation: The Biological Metaphor,’ Perspectives on Politics. White House (1995) National Security Strategy of Engagement and Enlargement, Available at: www.fas.org/spp/military/docops/national/1996stra.htm (accessed 31/01/2011). White House (2002) National Security Strategy of the United States (NSS) Available at: www.globalsecurity.org/military/library/policy/national/nss-020920.pdf (accessed 31 January 2011). Wimmer, A. (2002) Nationalist Exclusion and Ethnic Conflict, New York: Cambridge University Press. Wilson, Woodrow (1889) The State: Elements of Historical and Practical Politics, D.C. Heath. Wolff, J. (forthcoming) ‘New Constitutions and the Transformation of Democracy in Equador and Bolivia’, in Nolte, Detlef and Almut Schilling-Vac-afor (eds) New Constitu tionalism in Latin America: Promises and Practises, Aldershot: Ashgate. Wolff, J. (2011) ‘Challenges to Democracy Promotion: The Case of Bolivia’, Carnegie Paper, March 2011, Washington DC: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. Wolff, J. and Wurm, I. (2011) ‘Towards a Theory of External Democracy Promotion: A proposal for theoretical classification’, Security Dialogue, 42(1): 77–96. World Bank (1997) World Development Report 1997: The State in a Changing World, Washington, DC: World Bank. Yashar, D. J. (2005) Contesting Citizenship in Latin America. The Rise of Indigenous Move ments and the Postliberal Challenge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Youngs, R. (2002) The European Union and the Promotion of Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Youngs, R. (2004): International Democracy and the West. The Role of Governments, Civil Society, and Multinational Business, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Youngs, R. (2010) ‘How to Revitalise Democracy Assistance: Recipients’ Views’, FRIDE Working Paper 100.
244 Bibliography Youngs, R. (ed.) (2006) Survey of European Democracy Promotion Policies 2000–2006, Madrid: FRIDE. Zakaria, F. (1997) ‘The Rise of Illiberal Democracy,’ Foreign Affairs, 76(6): 22–43. Zakaria, F. (2003) The Future of Freedom: Illiberal Democracy at Home and Abroad, New York: W.W. Norton and Company. Zakaria, F. (2003) The Future of Freedom, New York: W.W. Norton & Co. Žižek, S. (2010) Living in the End Times, London: Verso.
Index
References to notes are prefixed by n. Page numbers in italics denote tables. academia: blind spots 43; and political concepts 43 academic work: on democracy promotion 12–13 academics: and policy-makers 102, 222 accountability 105, 141–2, 155, 158 Accra development agenda 109 ActionAid Ghana 143 Adenauer, Konrad 205 Adler-Karlsson, Gunnar 77 Afghanistan 19, 178, 181 Africa: reversals in democracy promotion 19 African Union Panel of the Wise 109 An Agenda for Democratisation 194–5 ‘aggregative’ democracy 193 aid projects 53, 103 AKP: Turkey 108 al-Maliki, Nouri 180 Al-Nasser, Jamal Abd 187 Al-Qaida 186 Albright, Madeleine 210 Algeria 175 Alternative Development program 129n4 alternative models 110, 112, 113–14 altruism 202 AME (Arab Middle East): authoritarianism 183–4; context of democratisation 173–4; and democratisation 171–2, 176–8; ‘double promotion’ 181–3; electoralism 174–6; ‘imagined communities’ 184–7; ‘orientalisation’ of 179–83; postcolonial 183, 185; re-framing democratisation 183–7; religion 186–7 Amman 186 analogies 27–32
Anderson, Benedict 185 Arab Gulf states 182, 186 Arab Middle East (AME) see AME Arendt, Hannah 206–7, 208 Arias, Oscar 205 Aristide, President 193 Aristotle 32, 113 Ark Foundation 144–5 Armenia 108, 152 Arrow, Kenneth 91 Asmus, Ronald 212 Atuguba, Raymond 150n12 Austria 72 Austrian Empire 70 authoritarian regimes 25, 111 authoritarianism 183–4 autopoiesis 34 Ayubi, Nazih 183 Azerbaijan 108, 152 ‘backlash’ 2, 111, 220 Bahrain 186 Baker, G. 132 Barcelona Process 36n1 Barkan, Joel 160, 166 Ba’thist ‘imagined community’ 186 Belarus 152 Belgium 25 Belim Wusa Development Agency (BEWDA) see BEWDA Ben Ali, Zine El Abidine 36n1, 175, 180 Bentham, Jeremy 113 Bernstein , Eduard 94 BEWDA (Belim Wusa Development Agency) 144 bilateral donor support: Ghana 132 bilateral relations 66
246 Index bin Laden, Osama 187 binary social classifications 25 biological metaphors 27–32 Bismarck, Otto von 71 blind spots 47 BMEI (Broader Middle East Initiative) 181, 182, 201 Bolivia: conceptual politics approach 119–20, 127–8; consolidation 122–3; constitutional reform 123–4; decentralisation 121; early transition to democracy 119; and Germany 125, 126–7; indigenous rights 109; political reforms 121; political transformation 119–20; popular participation 121–2; and USA 125–6, 127 Bolshevik model 203–4 Bonaparte, Napoleon 69 Bouteflika, Abdelaziz 175 Boutros-Ghali, Boutros 194–5 Bretton Woods conference 75 Bretton Woods era 94, 97 Broader Middle East Initiative (BMEI) see BMEI Brown, I. J. C. 8 Burnell, Peter 5 Bush administration 41–2, 82, 111, 179, 180 Bush Doctrine 211 Bush, George 181 Bush, George W. 181–2, 202–3, 211 business actions: and democracy promotion 106–7 business courts: Middle East 106 Canada: ‘mentoring’ 182; political democracy 25; UN resolutions 195 ‘capabilities’ 114 Capability (CAR framework) 141 capitalism 68, 74, 75, 77–8 CAR framework 141 Carothers, Thomas 32–3, 36n2, 124, 131, 133, 148, 174, 177, 182, 222 Carroll, Sean 35 CDD-Ghana (Ghana Center for Democratic Development) 137, 139 Center for Indigenous Knowledge and Organisational Development 145 Centre for Policy Analysis (CEPA) see CEPA Centre for Public Interest Law (CEPIL) see CEPIL CEPA (Centre for Policy Analysis) 137, 139
CEPIL (Centre for Public Interest Law) 143, 145 Cerna, Christina 193 Chavez, Húgo 104 Chesterman, Simon 198 Chile (1973) 92 China 9, 81–2, 108, 195 Christian Council of Ghana 143 citizen participation 192 citizenship 62, 155 civic engagement 46, 51, 110–11 civic groups 110 civic movements 90 civil society 62, 90, 107, 131–2, 199 civil society assistance programmes: critiques of 133; G-RAP 133, 135–41, 146–9; RAVI 133, 141–9 civil society organisations: and RAVI 143–4 civil society strengthening: Ghana 134–5 civil war (English) 62 class division 70, 71, 72, 78, 81–2 Clinton administration 131, 210 Clinton, Bill 202 codetermination 77 coercive democratisation 3, 20, 22, 26, 181, 221–2 collective learning 86–7, 95 collective rules 87 colonialism 59, 60, 61–2, 177 Commission on Human Rights 195 Committee of European Economic Cooperation 74 common land: privatisation of 59–60 communal issues 70 communal setting 46, 47–8, 51 communism 1, 72, 74, 76, 203–4, 205 communists 54–5 communities of theorists 48–9 Community Radio Network 143 companies: and democracy promotion 106–7 ‘competitive elitist democracy’ 90 competitive markets 88 conceptions of democracy (study) 154–60, 167–9 concepts: contested 38, 39, 40–3 conceptual debate: models of democracy 7–8; process vs. product 9–10; vagueness vs. precision 8–9 conceptual politics: contexts and sites 10–13; notion of 3–4 conceptual politics approach 4–6; Bolivia 119–20, 127–8; civil society and democratisation 131–2; normative perils
Index 247 220–1; relevance 221–2; role of liberalism 218–20; strengths and weaknesses 216–17 conflict stabilisation initiatives 108–9 Connolly, W. 3 conservative radicalism 122 consolidation: biological analogy 28, 31; Bolivia 122–3; Europe 68–9, 73–8, 83 ‘constitutional engineering’ 34 ‘constitutive metaphors’ 27, 31 constructivism: mainstream 38; political 38, 39–40, 45, 46–51 contagion 28 contestation: of concept of democracy 10–12, 24, 119–20, 121–5 contested concepts 38, 39, 40–3 contextual background: conceptions of democracy 24–5 contingency thesis 55–6 corruption 55, 71, 195, 212 cosmopolitan democracy 115 cosmopolitanism 99n2, 101 ‘country-specific approaches’ 109 Crawford, Gordon 134 Crawford, James 192 criteria for success 20 critical-reflexive consciousness 97–8 critical-reflexive teleology 86 critical theorists 45, 46, 114 critical theory 5, 102–3, 111, 217, 218 Croatia 152 Croatian minorities 70 Crosland, C. A. R. 76 Cuba: UN resolutions 195 Cuban democracy 22 ‘cultivation’: as biological analogy 32–6; skills 23 cyber-activism 110–11 Czechoslovakia 201 Czechs 70 Daalder, Ivo 212 Dahl, Robert 4, 6, 111 Dalton, Russell 153, 158 de-Shalit, Avner 51 decentralisation: Bolivia 121 decolonisation era: UN 194–7 ‘decontamination’ 32–3 definitions 43–6 deliberative democracy 51, 193 democracy: and capitalism 68; conceptions of 2, 4, 9–10, 23–4, 154–60; definitional practices 8; definitions 4–5, 44–6; elitist reading of 50–1; as governing
procedures 9–10, 24; as ideal 10, 24; liberalism and 54–7; local conceptions 11–12; local contexts 24; models of 11; and social stability 68; and UN (United Nations) 191, 194–7 democracy assistance: participation in 167–9; problems with 165–7 ‘democracy backlash’ 2, 111, 220 democracy building: post-conflict 197–8 Democracy Fund 196 democracy promotion: action 3; activities 20, 21–2; actors 3, 57; agencies 10–11, 120; Ghana 134–5; and liberalism 218–20; policies 53, 57, 62; shift in conceptualisation 20–1; strategies 3, 20; teleology of 85–7; as a term 3 democracy vs. radical Islamism binary 25 democracy vs. totalitarianism binary: Cold War period 25 democratic development: obstacles to 154, 160–4 democratic enlargement 210 democratic globalism: as imperialism 208–12 democratic imperialism 105 democratic participation 132 ‘democratic peace theory’ 208–11 democratic politics: and human development 131 Democratic Republic of Congo 109 democratic revisionism 178 democratic transition theory 209–10 democratic void 183–4 democratisation: economic dimension 106; fixated structural understandings of 41–2; idea of 37n10; and security 178 Department for International Development (DFID) see DFID Derrida, Jacques 10 developing countries: and economic development 64–5 development agencies 103, 104 developmentalist ideas 95 DFID (Department for International Development) 104, 133, 141, 142, 146, 147 Diamond, Larry 131 dictatorships 70, 71 ‘do no harm’ principle 36, 196–7 domestic violence 145 Domestic Violence Coalition 145 Dominican Republic 201 ‘double promotion’: AME (Arab Middle East) 181–3
248 Index Dunn, John 107 DVC (National Coalition on Domestic Violence Legislation) 143, 145 dynastic politics 190 economic development: and democratic politics 55, 57, 81–2; developing countries and 64–5 economic dislocation 69 economic liberalism 88, 105–6 economic rights 80 economic security 155, 158 Egypt 108, 111, 175, 177, 186, 187 elections 107–8, 152, 158, 191–2 electoral democracy 5, 46, 79, 80, 107–8 ‘electoral fallacy’ 4–5, 107–8 electoralism: AME (Arab Middle East) 174–6, 177 elites: behaviours 163; and conceptions of democracy 50–1, 154 elitist model 89, 105 embedded liberalism 79 enclosure acts 60 ‘end of history’ discourse 1, 26; see also teleology, of democratic promotion Equity and Reconciliation Commission 111 essentialism: and Western approach to democratisation 179–83 ethico-political principles 92, 93, 95, 97, 98 Ethiopia 108 ethnic cleansing 74 ethnic conflicts 70, 73 EU (European Union): aid projects 53; Alternative Development program 129n4; approach to democracy promotion 9; Barcelona Process 36n1; civil society support programmes 132; contestation of concept of democracy 11; electoral democracy 108; and Ghana 134; ‘mentoring’ 182; Rwanda 109; success of 209; trade deals 105 Europe: democratic consolidation 68–9, 73–8, 83; development of democracy 69–73; and liberal democracy 64; policy makers 105; social democracy 78–81, 83 European Commission: political economy approach 105; projects 104 European policies 106, 112 ‘evidence-based’ policies: and biological perspectives 36 external actors: contestation of concept of democracy 10–12
external impediments: to democracy development 160–4 extremism 74 fascism 76 fascist parties 73 feminist epistemology 46, 47 ‘feudal democracy’ 198 Fiji 192 financial crisis 101, 104, 105 Forest Watch Ghana 144 Foundation for Female Photojournalists 143 Fourth Republic: France 76–7 Fox, Gregory 193 France: Catholic Mouvement Republican Populaire 75; Fourth Republic 76–7; ‘mentoring’ 182; Paris Commune 72; political democracy 25; post-revolution 69; protests (1948) 69–70; and revolution 96; Third Republic 72; and Venezuela 104 franchise 60, 61 Franck, Thomas 193 Franco, Adolfo 125 Frankfurt parliament 71 free association technique 24–5 free markets 91–2, 93, 95, 97 Freeden, Michael 27 freedom fighters 205 Freedom House scores: Ghana 149n3 freedom, individual: and liberalism 53, 55, 56–7; Locke on 57–62 freedoms: as element of democracy 155–7, 158–9 French Revolution 69, 96 Friedman, Milton 88, 90 Friends of the Nation 144 Fukuyama, Francis 1, 56, 86 funding 103 Funding Virtue 131 G-8 countries 182, 183; see also Western powers G-RAP (Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme) 133, 135–41, 146–9 Gadamer, G. 37n7 Gaddafi, Muammar 180 Gallie, W. B. 4, 125 gardening metaphor 23 GARI (Ghana Accountability and Responsiveness Initiative) 146, 149n2 Garton Ash, Timothy 1 GATT-agreement 97
Index 249 GAWU (General Agricultural Workers Union) 143, 144 General Competitive Analysis 91 general equilibrium approaches 91–2 Georgia 109, 152 German Christian Democrats 75 Germans 70 Germany: and Bolivia 125, 126–7; comparison with USA 120; economic liberalism 77; Frankfurt parliament 71; ‘mentoring’ 182; political democracy 25; post World War I 72; social hierarchies 73; and USA occupation 201–2, 205 Ghana: bilateral donor support 132; civil society projects 133; civil society strengthening 134–5; democracy promotion 134–5; Freedom House scores 149n3; and the Netherlands 133 Ghana Accountability and Responsiveness Initiative (GARI) see GARI Ghana Association of the Blind 144 Ghana Center for Democratic Development (CDD-Ghana) see CDDGhana Ghana Federation of the Disabled 144 Ghana Poverty Reduction Strategy (GPRS) see GPRS Ghana Research and Advocacy Programme (G-RAP) see G-RAP Ghana Rights and Voice Initiative (RAVI) see RAVI Gills, Barry 6 global peace 209 global social/democratic reforms 98 globalisation 64, 97 globalism 115 GMEI (Greater Middle East Initiative) 179–80, 180–1, 187 Gorbachev, Mikhail 205 Gordon, Philip 212 Gould, Stephen Jay 30 government by consent 58 GPRS (Ghana Poverty Reduction Strategy) 134 Gramsci, Antonio 39–40, 132, 133 Gramscian mechanism 39, 40–2, 50 Great Depression 73, 74 Greater Middle East Initiative (GMEI) see GMEI Guidance Note on Democracy 196 Guizot, F. 4 Habermas, Jürgen 113, 193
Habermasian mechanism 39, 42–3, 50 Habsburg Empire 70, 72 Hahn, Frank H. 91 Haiti 193, 201 Hamas 108 Harbeson, J. W. 131 Hariri family 186 Havel, Vaclav 205 Hawkesworth, Mary 47 Hayek, Friedrich 68, 88, 90 Hearn, J. 133, 147 Hegel, G. W. F. 105, 113 hegemony, theory of 39, 40 Held, David 90, 99n2, 132 Helms-Burton law 22 heuristic metaphors 31 Hezbullah 182, 187 Hobsbawm, Eric 69, 185 Hobson, Christopher 53, 82, 120 Hohe, T. 198 Hu Jintao 9 Hudson, C. M. 174 human development: and democratic politics 131 human rights 81, 82, 89, 142, 144, 191, 192, 195 human rights violations 198 Hungarians 70 Huntington, Samuel 81, 177, 180 Hurt, S. R. 132 ‘hybrid’ regimes 28 Ibn Khaldoun 188 ICB (institutional capacity building) 136, 139–40 ICCPR (International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights) 191–2, 197 identity-centred debates 105, 110 identity issues 70 IEA (Institute of Economic Affairs) 137, 139 ‘imagined communities’: AME (Arab Middle East) 184–7 IMF (International Monetary Fund) 61, 90 imperialism 105, 110; democratic globalism as 208–12 inclusion 142 indigenous forms: of representation 109 individual freedom: and liberalism 53, 55, 56–7; Locke on 57–62 industrial revolution 69 inequality 81, 83 Institute of Economic Affairs (IEA) see IEA
250 Index institutional capacity building (ICB) see ICB institutional factors 154–5, 157, 158, 159, 162 ‘instrumental value’: of democracy (Bolivia) 121–3 inter-RAO networking: G-RAP 140–1 internal impediments: to democracy development 160–4 international capital: and democracy promotion 106–7 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) see ICCPR International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights 192 international institutions: and democracy 194–7 international law: and democracy 189–94; and international institutions 194–7; and national law 190; and UN 190–8 International Monetary Fund (IMF) see IMF internationalisation: of modernisation processes 64–5 interpretivists 45, 46 interviews: post-communist elections study 152–3 IR theorists 48–9 Iran 9, 181 Iraq 82, 177, 178, 186, 187, 201, 211 The Irony of American History 206, 214 Ish-Shalom, P. 10 Islam 172, 174, 179 Islamism 180 Islamists 110 Israel 181, 182 Italy 71–2, 77, 182 Ivory Coast 19 Japan 35, 182, 201–2, 205 John Paul II 205 Jordan 182 Jorion, Paul 37n8 Journal of Democracy 12 Kant, Immanuel 113 Kantian liberal world order 209 Kauffman, S. A. 30 Keane, John 10 Kenya 19 Keynes, John Maynard 76, 201 Keynesian social democratic model 96 Keynesianism 76 Kim Dae Jung 205
Kohlbergian framework 99n1 Kopstein, J. 11 Koselleck, R. 3–4 Krastev, I. 1 Kurki Milja 53, 82, 120, 130n11 Kuwait 175, 181 Kyrgyzstan 152 ‘large N’ causal models 23 Latin America: and US policy 106–7 law, international see international law Lebanon 110, 175, 186, 187 Legal Resources Centre (LRC) see LRC legitimacy 184, 193 Lévy, Bernard-Henri 110 liberal democracy: accepted notions of 5; critique of 100–1; and economic liberalism 105–6; and electoral democracy 80; elitist model 6; faith in 1; and international actors 53–4; and international law 194; postcommmunism countries 11–12; promotion 53–4, 62–5; and social democracy 79; virtue of 206–7 liberal democratic concept: of democracy 155 liberal democratic model: of civil society 132–3 ‘liberal imperialism’ 112 ‘liberal internationalism’ 201–2, 203–8 liberal jurists 210 liberalism: and democracy 27, 54–7, 62–5, 101; and democracy promotion 218–20; dominance of 111; Lockean account 57–62, 115; political and market tension 105; poor understanding of 53; and ‘Westernisation’ 83 Lindsay, James 212 linguistic conflicts 70 literature 2, 19–20 local accountability 105 local actors vs. external actors: contestation of concept of democracy 11–12 local demands 100, 102, 113, 114 local groups 110 local ownership 198, 199 Locke, John 53–4, 57–62, 62–3, 107, 113, 115 Lockean-Schumpeterian tradition 89 ‘low-intensity democracy’ 90 LRC (Legal Resources Centre) 143, 145 Lustick, Ian 41 McFaul, Michael 2, 5, 88, 112, 199, 212
Index 251 Madrid Conference 181 majority rule 55 Maliki, Nouri al 180 Mandela, Nelson 205 market-based political economy 93 market liberalism 105 Marks, Susan 199 Marshall, Alfred 90 Marx, Karl 68 Marxism–Leninism 205, 207 Marxist critique 105, 110 MAS (Movimiento al Socialismo) 123, 125, 126 Mayer, Ernst 29 Mazower, Mark 73, 74 MCC (Millennium Challenge Corporation) 126, 182 MDBS (Multi-Donor Budget Support) 134, 135, 147, 150n12 Meciar, Vladimir 152 Melia, Thomas 11 ‘mentoring’ 182–3 MEPI (Middle East Partnership Initiative) 181 metaphors 27–32 methodological pluralism 32 middle classes 61, 69, 70 Middle East: and aid programmes 104; business courts 106; local conceptions 12; reversals in democracy promotion 19 Middle East Partnership Initiative (MEPI) see MEPI military power 112 Mill, J. S. 68, 103 Millennium Challenge Corporation (MCC) see MCC Milosevic, Slobodan 152 mimicry 36 modernisation policies 57, 64–5 modularity 35 Mohamed VI, King 182 monitoring 20 Morales, Evo 109, 119, 121, 122, 123, 125 Morgenthau, Henry 75 Morlino, Leonardo 37n10 Morocco 108, 111, 182 morphology: of political concepts 26–7 Movimiento al Socialismo (MAS) see MAS Mubarak, Hosni 180 Mubarak regime 111 Multi-Donor Budget Support (MDBS) see MDBS
multilateralism 97, 115 multinational companies: and democracy promotion 106–7 Muqaddimah 188 Muslim Brotherhood 175 Al-Nasser, Jamal Abd 187 National Coalition on Domestic Violence Legislation (DVC) see DVC national conflicts 70 National Endowment for Democracy (NED) see NED national law: international law and 190 National Security Strategy of the United States 211 national socialist parties 73 nationalisation 76–7 nationalism 70, 72–3, 74 nationalist mobilisation 72 natural rights 91–2 Nazis 73 NED (National Endowment for Democracy) 12, 25, 125 NED survey 166–7 neo-Gramscian literature 6, 101, 105, 106–7 neo-Hegelian argument 86 neo-liberal concept: of civil society 132, 133 neo-liberal intellectuals 212 neo-liberal internationalism 207, 208–12 neo-liberal model 85, 87–92, 95, 96 neo-liberalisation 97 neo-liberalism 88–9 neo-Wilsonianism 207 the Netherlands: and Ghana 133 NETRIGHT 150n8 New Caledonia 192 ‘new world order’ 89 Nicaragua 201 Niebuhr, Reinhold 206, 207, 208, 214 Nixon, Richard 97 Nolte, Georg 193 non-intervention 26 normative and cultural definition: of democracy 46 North Korea 9 Northern Network for Education Development 143 Nouméa Accord 192–3 Nozick, Robert 90–1 ‘nurturing’: as biological analogy 32–6; imagery of term 21–3
252 Index Obama administration 179 Obama, Barack 103, 187, 212–13 obligations 142 obstacles: to democratic development 160–4 occidentalism 176–9 Occidentalists 171–3, 178 O’Donnell, Guillermo 10, 177, 199 OECD countries 89, 96–7 OECD Guidelines 200n3 Offe, Claus 78 Ohemeng, F. L. K. 137 Oppenheim, Lassa 190 orientalism 176–9 Orientalists 171–3, 178 The Origins of Totalitarianism 206–7 Orwell, George 8 Ottaway, Marina 131, 133, 148, 182 over-promotion: by Western powers 102–3 ownership 20 Pakistan 19, 181 Palme, Olof 99n6 Paris Commune 72 Paris development agenda 109 participation 142, 167–9 participatory democracy 51 patronage-based distributions: of power 108 peace, global 209 Perez, Shimon 181 the Philippines 201, 202, 204 Pipe, Daniel 179 Plattner, M. 220 pluralism 43, 46, 48–9, 51, 114, 178, 215, 220–1 pluralist model: of democracy 99n2 Poland 72 policy-makers: academics and 102, 222 political concepts 40–3 political constructivism 38, 39–40, 45, 46–51 political democracy 24–5 political economy approach: European Commission 105 political features: and liberal democracy 55–6 political instability 72, 81 political justice 93 political liberalism 49 Political Order in Changing Societies 81 political reform 57 political theory-informed perspective 53 Polyani, M. 37n6
‘polyarchy’ 6, 90 popular participation: Bolivia 121–2 population transfer 74 positivism 38, 43, 45 post-Cold War countries: democratic initiatives 19 post-Cold War era 26, 53, 194–7 post-communist elections study: hypotheses 153–4; interviews 152–3; methodology 153–4 post-conflict interventions: UN 197–8 post-conflict peace-building 196–7 post-Fordism 97 post-positivism 45 post-positivist approaches 5 post-World War I 72 postcolonial Arab states 183, 185 poverty: and democratic development 55 power: of the state 183–4 power voids 183–4, 187 ‘prejudices’ 37n7 Principles of Economics 90 principles of justice: Rawls 92–3 private enclosure acts 60 private property: and liberalism 53, 54–5, 56–7, 62, 63; Locke on 57–62; and serfdom 107 private property rights 89, 90, 91, 92, 107, 126 privatisation 61 process tracking 20 ‘promotion’: imagery of term 21–3 Public Agenda 143 public common sense 39–40, 41 public convention 40, 41 ‘quality’: of democratisation processes 28, 29 radical model: of civil society 132–3 RAOs (Research and Advocacy Organisations) 135, 136, 140–1 RAVI (Ghana Rights and Voice Initiative) 133, 141–6 Rawls, John 49, 92–4 Reagan, Ronald 213 reasonable pluralism 49 rebellions 60–1 recipient-donors 154, 157–8, 159, 160, 169 reconceptualisation 114, 115 Red Shirt supporters 81 redundancy 35 reflexivity 46 regime change: new form of 1
Index 253 Reign of Terror 69 Reisman, Michael 193 relativism 43, 220 religion: AME (Arab Middle East) 186–7 religion-based representation 109–10 religious violence 62 representation: forms of 107–11 Research and Advocacy Organisations (RAOs) see RAOs responsibility to protect 210 responsiveness 141–2 revolution 60–1, 69, 72 Rice, Condoleezza 182 Robinson, W. 6 Rocamora, J. 6 Rocha, Manuel 129n4 Romanian minorities 70 Root, Elihu 190 Rose, S. 28 Roth, Brad 193 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques 113 Ruggie, J. G. 79 Russia 9 Rwanda 108, 109 Said, Edward 172, 178, 179 San Francisco Conference: UN 191 Sardar, Z. 173 Saudi Arabia: UN resolutions 195 Scandinavian countries: social democracy 11 Scandinavian model 178 Scanlon, T. 50 Schmitter, Philippe 36n2, 125 scholarship: on democracy promotion and democratisation 12–13 Schumpeter, Joseph 4, 80, 89, 113 Second Inaugural Address (G. W. Bush) 202–3 security: and democratisation 178, 201 self-determination 192, 196, 205 self-reflexive policy-learning 112 self-reflexivity 46–8, 50, 51 September 11 attacks 211 Serbia 152 Serbian minorities 70 serfdom: private property and 107 Shaftesbury, Earl of 60 Skidelsky, Robert 76 Slaughter, Anne-Marie 194, 212 Slovakia 152 Smith, Tony 122, 194 social benefits: and concept of democracy 157–8
social conflict 73 social construction 39, 40 social democracy: Europe 78–81; post1945 68, 75–8; Scandinavian countries 11 social democratic model: historicalinstitutional perspective 94–5; problems with 95–7; Rawlsian perspective 92–4; and welfare state 85 social development 103 social divisions 81–2 social justice 83 social knowledge 39, 40, 42 social market economy 88 social rights 80 social solidarity 75 social stability 68, 78–9 socialism 94 socialists 54–5 SOLACE (Solidarity Action for Community Empowerment) 144 Sousa Santos, Boaventura de 130n11 sovereignty 26, 34, 193, 194, 196, 210 Spain: transition to democracy 25–6; and Venezuela 104 Special Project Grants 140 Sperber, Jonathan 70 ‘stages’ 86 stagflation 97 state competency building 104–5 state power 183–4 Steiner, Henry 191 Steinmo, Sven 29, 30 ‘step-change’ model 25–6, 27, 34 structural conditionality: and democracy 104 structural democracy 46 substantive responsibility 50 Summit Outcome document (2005) 196 Swaziland 192 Sweden 25, 72, 77 Swedish model 94, 96 Syria 195 Taliban 110 technical assistance (TA) grants 136, 139–40 Teivainen, T. 10, 221 teleology: of democracy promotion 85–7 terrorism 179 Tesón, Fernando 194 Thailand 81 theory of hegemony 39, 40 Theory of Justice 92
254 Index ‘theory vacuum’ 36n2 Thierry, Augustin 72 Third Republic 72 ‘third wave’ democratisation 89, 174, 177 Third Way 96 Third World Network (TWN-Africa) see TWN-Africa Timor Leste 197–8 ‘tinkering’ 35, 36 Tocqueville, Alexis de 68 total state 184 totalitarianism 25 trade liberalisation 105 traditional local forms 110, 111 ‘transition paradigm’ 124 transition theory 177 transitional justice 109 transitions to democracy 25–6 transparency 46, 49–50, 51, 155 ‘transplants’ 22, 35–6 Transformismo 71 Trevelyan, G. M. 71 Tudjman, Franjo 152 Tunisia 19, 108, 175 Turkey 108, 181 TWN-Africa (Third World Network) 137, 139 UK (United Kingdom): DFID 104; liberal democratic model 11; ‘mentoring’ 182; political democracy 24–5; UN resolutions 195 Ukraine 108, 152 UN (United Nations): decolonisation era 194; and democracy 191, 194–7; and international law 190–1; post-Cold War era 194–7; post-conflict interventions 197–8; San Francisco Conference 191; Security Council 210 UNDP (United Nations Development Programme) 131 UNIFEM (United Nations Development Fund for Women) 182 unilateralism 97 United Kingdom (UK) see UK United Nations (UN) see UN United Nations Development Fund for Women (UNIFEM) see UNIFEM United Nations Development Programme (UNDP) see UNDP United Nations Human Rights Council 195 United Nations Security Council 194 United Nations Transitional Authority in East Timor (UNTAET) see UNTAET
Universal Declaration of Human Rights 191 universal suffrage 54, 55 universalist social democracy 96 UNTAET (United Nations Transitional Authority in East Timor) 197–8 upheavals 60–1 US Millennium Challenge Account 126 USA (United States of America): aid projects 53; and Bolivia 125–6, 127; civil society activities funding 158; comparison with Germany 120; conceptual structures of democracy promotion 204–8; contestation of concept of democracy 11; definitional practices 9; democracy assumptions 79; disinterest 201, 202; future foreign policy 212–14; and Latin America 106–7; and liberal democracy 64; ‘mentoring’ 183; phases of democracy promotion 202; political democracy 25; post-Second World War occupations 201–2, 205; practice of democracy 88; procedures of democracy promotion 204; tragedy of foreign policy 208–12; UN resolutions 195; and Western Europe 74 USAID 125, 129n4, 131 uti possedetis 189 Václav Havel 10 Van Rooy, A. 131 Vattel, Emerich de 190 Velvet Revolutions 1 Venezuela 104 viability 28 Vienna Declaration on Human Rights 192 Vietnam 104 voice and accountability (VA) 141, 142 void of power 183–4, 187 voting rights 60, 61 WACAM 145, 146 wage-earner fund proposals 95 war on terrorism 41 weapons of mass destruction 211 welfare state 76, 77, 94, 95 Wen Jiabao 81 Western approach: to democratisation in AME 179–83 Western governments: and AME 172–3; patronising attitude 180 Western powers: conventional wisdom of 87; criticisms of 103–11, 112; democracy support strategies 115; and
Index 255 liberal democracy 101; over-promotion by 102–3; and social democracy 103; and UN Charter 191 Westminster features 25 Westminster Foundation 25 Wheatley, Steven 193 Whitehead, Laurence 112, 125, 174, 177 WiLDAF (Women in Law and Development) 144–5 Wilson, R. 6 Wilson, Woodrow 201, 202, 203–4, 207, 210–11 ‘Wilsonianism’ 201 women: treatment of 110 Women in Law and Development (WiLDAF) see WiLDAF
women’s rights organisations 137, 144, 147 working classes 69, 70 World Bank 61, 142 World Bank Governance Indicators 126 world economy: re-integration of 97 World War II 73, 74 Yanukovich, Viktor 108 Yemen 175, 186 Youngs, Richard 88 Youth Alive 145 Zakaria, F. 218, 220 Žižek, Slavoj 105