215 27 16MB
English Pages 272 [280] Year 2000
"
lc
COMMON LAW
MIND
Medieval and Early
Modern Conceptions
W. T LI BBS
J.
cholars of comparative law and English
L y legal history have traditionally distinguished the
civil
laws emphasis on legislation
the primary source of legal authority
common law. In
law’s
from the
emphasis on custom and on case
The Common Law Mind lawyer and ,
cal scientist
support
this
as
James Tubbs
politiBOSTON
finds little evidence to
and other traditional understandings
Boston,
Copley
of English jurisprudence.
Examining thousands of legal and
uments
for references to the nature
judicial
doc-
PUBLIC
MA
and authority Square
of custom, case law, statutes, equity, and reason,
Tubbs depicts the tensions within and the evolution of English legal thought between the twelfth
and seventeenth centuries. Most lawyers, he concludes, never thought of
tomary
in nature
common
all
English law as cus-
and never understood the
law to be
a
fundamental
law, superior
to statute. Instead, statute law was
much more
central to English jurisprudence than has
usually been believed, and
stood to be superior law.
it
was always under-
in authority to the
The Common Law Mind revises
tion of thinking about the nature
ment of common law and interpretation.
its
a
common
whole
tradi-
and develop-
role in statutory
02116
LIBRARY
Digitized by the Internet Archive in
2016
https://archive.org/details/commonlawmindOOjwtu
s
THE
COMMON LAW MIND
sr.
THE
COMMON LAW MIND
Medieval and Early Modern Conceptions
J.
IV
Ttibbs
*
The Johns Hopkins University Press Baltimore and London
© 2000 The Johns Hopkins
University Press
2000
All rights reserved. Published
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper 9 8 7 6 5
The Johns Hopkins 2715
4
3
2
1
University Press
North Charles
Street
Baltimore, Maryland 21218-4363
www.press.jhu.edu
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data will
be found
at the
A catalog record
end of this book.
for this
book
is
available
from the British Library.
isbn 0-8018-6209-4
CONTENTS
Acknowledgments Introduction
ONE
TWO THREE
vii
ix
Conceptions of English
The Jurisprudence
Law
in the
of the Year Books
FIVE
22
Legal Theory in Fortescue, Littleton, and Fifteenth-
Century Readings and Moots
FOUR
Medieval Treatises
53
The Early Sixteenth Century: Christopher St. German 71 Plowden’s Commentaries and the Sixteenth- Century
Law
Reports
no
Common Law Mind
SIX
Sir
John Davies and the
SEVEN
Sir
Edward Coke and His Contemporaries
EIGHT
Reason and the
NINE
Common Law Maxims
173
The Common Law Mind: A Summary and Commentary 179 Notes
197
Bibliography
Index
249
237 ,
129 141
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I
owe enormous
intellectual debts to Professors
Woodford Howard
J.
and J. G. A. Pocock of Johns Hopkins University, who through their examples gave
me
arship, even if
I
a
glimpse of
am
me
to approach legal
and
historical schol-
unable to match their high standards.
be grateful, too, for the to
how
many
I
shall always
personal kindnesses that they have
shown
over the years.
Early in this project
I
was substantially aided by
a fellowship at the
Folger Institute Center for the History of British Political Thought.
Norman Doe provided a close stage and made many very helpful
Professor
an early
reading of the manuscript at suggestions.
My former col-
leagues John Rohr, Patrick Neal, and Robert Taylor also read the script, in part or in
manu-
whole, and their encouragement and suggestions are
appreciated. Finally, the
whole project would have been impossible without the
love and long-suffering support of
my wife, Virginia.
>»
INTRODUCTION
his
T
is a selective historical
study of
common
fore the middle of the seventeenth century.
more than one common meaning. In roots it means the science or study of law legal
for law.
The term jurisprudence
the sense closest to
has
somewhat pretentious synonvm
law jurisprudence be-
in general. It
More
its
Latin
also used as a
is
technically,
it
refers to
philosophy or theory, or the product or activity of thinking about
or examining questions or problems having to do with law’s nature, sources,
its
authority,
its
elements and their relation to each other,
lation to morality, equity, or justice,
and so on. This work
with jurisprudence in the third sense; tive legal doctrines
it is
may
re-
concerned
not concerned with substan-
of property, contract, and the
discussion of such doctrines
is
its
its
like,
except where
a
shed light on the more abstract and
fundamental questions of jurisprudence being investigated.
The
study
is
selective because a completely
thorough discussion of
English approaches over several centuries to even one of the fundamenquestions of jurisprudence — say, the problem of authority — could
tal
easily tial
amount
to a large book.
I
concentrate on some of the jurisprudeh-
questions that traditionally are grouped together under the heading
sources of law.
Like jurisprudence
itself,
the term source
ent senses by writers on jurisprudence historic event, practice, or
or principle of law in
1
.
of' law is
used in several differ-
may be
used to refer to some
It
borrowing that
a particular
that the source of a particular
led to the existence of a rule
system. For example,
common
law
maxim
it
is
might be
said
the civil law.
In a quite different sense, Percy H. Winfield primarily uses the phrase to refer to the “available oral or
any
fact in issue .”
1
documentary evidence
for the existence of
In other words, he uses the term to refer to the stat-
IX
Introduction
X
and so on
utes, reported cases, public records,
at
and obtain information about the law Although 3
which one could look
concerned with the historical origins of particular cepts, or tirely
modes of conceptualization, and my
frequently
is
con-
legal practices,
discussion
almost en-
is
based on sources of law in Winfield’s sense, such sources are not
the subject of
my
what used to be
investigation. Instead,
on
I
am concerned
primarily with
These
called the formal sources of the law.
which “by reason of force
book
this
.
are sources
their accepted authority, confer validity
principles or rules
drawn from them. They
law- creating and law- declaring agencies
and
legal
are the recognized
from which come
valid rules of
law .” 4
One
of the timeless questions in jurisprudence, asked both abstractly
and philosophically,
is,
What
matically, this question can
is
law? Asked
become,
more concretely and prag-
Is this rule
or principle
now
being
alleged to cover the facts of this case an authoritative, binding legal rule
or principle?
A time-honored means of answering the latter question in-
volves posing and answering a further question:
come from dence
at
a
Does the purported
rule
recognized formal source? In Western European jurispru-
one time and place or another, the recognized sources of law
have included custom, legislation, judicial precedent, reason, equity, and
two thousand years
natural law. For
the twelfth century in the
in the civil law,
common
law, jurists
and since the end of
have explicitly debated
and discussed what the authoritative sources of law are and the theoretical justifications for
considering them to be sources and have compared
and ranked admitted sources in terms of their
One who
reads
many of the
classic
works
relative authority.
in historical
comparative
ju-
way of knowing from the evidence presented whether the modes of thought reported in them were ever actually used by anyone. It is even harder to determine whether modes of thought asrisprudence has
little
serted to be representative of their time and place really were. sic
The
clas-
nineteenth-century and early twentieth-century works in English
tend to be long on assertion and short on documentation. Frederic
comment to Frederick Pollock on the historical work of Sir Henry Maine could be made about any num-
Maitland’s disparaging
accuracy of the
ber of such works: “You spoke of Maine. Well, reluctance, for
I
that played
once read .”
5
always talk of
on the few occasions on which
statements of fact
memory
I
came
him
I
sought to verify his
to the conclusion that he trusted tricks
and rarely looked
him with
at a
book
much
to a
that he had
Introduction
xi
s The two classic works in English on the formal sources of law are John Chipman Gray’s The Nature and Sources of the Law and Sir Carleton 6 Allen’s Law in the Making Historical claims are made in both, but nei.
ther
is
Allen shift
easily,
and without warning, from their own analytical schema
and normative theoretical claims to Allen far surpasses
work
is
Gray and
primarily historical in intention or execution. Both
Gray
and back again.
historical assertion
in historical scope
and documentation, but
his
primarily analytical in focus, not historical.
Maitland’s revolutionary approach to legal historical scholarship, with exhaustive examination of original sources and clear documentation,
its
still
has not completely taken root a century
the last generation found
it
Towering
later.
common
acceptable to write treatises on
The
history with only the merest skeleton of documentation. sions reached in such works
may be
legal historiography has always
on acceptable and perhaps
this
is
openly
a
work not
because
I
much
if
The
a substantial literature
a
great influence
many
to the kind of history of political and legal as
J.
G. A. Pocock, Quentin Skinner,
7 .
historian following this approach seeks to guard against erro-
detail as possible the context in
speaker
made
a statement.
A
as
it
others.
or a
him from saying
Other important parts of the context include the
and institution or peculiar to
the context of the discourse he
is
common
a particular author.
the practice of a historian of political discourse
measure of our
a text
worked and which
possible to say certain things and prevented
large
richness of
substantial part of this context consists in
philosophical, juridical, or political assumptions
It is a
much
which an author created
the linguistic conventions within which the author
place,
legal histori-
of those historians see as the
neous interpretations by trying to reconstruct with
made
on
been
not always in execution, the approach
thought advocated by such scholars
Dunn
Although work
have found recent writings on historiog-
raphy helpful; and in conception
and John
faith.
ideas but institutions and practices. But since
study of ideas,
taken here owes
conclu-
desirable approaches to the history of ideas has
at least partly
subject of their
them on
been sparse,
produced. This literature has not had ans,
law
correct and profound, but even ex-
perts in the field frequently have to take
on
figures of
examining:
who
is
theological,
to a time,
Pocock describes seeking to
know
'
historian’s practice to learn to read
and
recognize the diverse idioms of political discourse as they were
xii
Introduction
v?
available in the culture
them
and
time he was studying: to identify
at the
they appear in the linguistic texture of any one text, and to
as
know what
they would ordinarily have enabled that text’s author to
propound or
“say.”
The
extent to which an author’s
them was out of the ordinary comes first
later.
The
historian pursues his
goal by reading extensively in the literature of the time and by
sensitizing himself to the presence of diverse idioms
The
employment of
8 .
historian’s claim that he has correctly identified a language, rheto-
mode of thought will always be open to challenge, but the greater the number and diversity of instances that he can document, the greater the number of actors, texts, and contexts in which he can locate the idiom or mode of thought, “the more the hypotheses erected by those who would imprison him within the hermeneutic circle must come to ric,
or
resemble
Ptolemaic universe, consisting of more cycles and epicycles
a
than would satisfy the reasonable mind of Alfonso the Wise; in short, the
1
more
it
will exhibit the disadvantages of non-refutability.”
Of course,
it is
much
than actually to do
it
easier to prescribe
well.
A
description
'
how to do a study of this kind of how I went about studying a better sense of my own ap-
common
law jurisprudence
proach.
read most extant works on English law, not including case re-
I
ports, written
may
provide
between the twelfth and seventeenth centuries. Beginning
with the Year Books from the reign of Edward the fifteenth century,
I
read
all
I
and continuing through
the cases reported for entire years, select-
ing years at regular intervals — a total of about five thousand Year cases. I read all the cases reported in
sixteenth century and of the tury.
As
first
three decades of the seventeenth cen-
notes of any statements that have the sources-of-law questions that
common
most of the named reports of the
read the case reports and other legal literature,
I
law,
common
right,
Book
a I
I
kept detailed
bearing on general legal theory or
was examining: statements about
common
erudition, custom, reason, law
and reason, time, time of memory, time immemorial, usage, prescription, equity, hardship, mischief, inconvenience, statutes, interpretation,
precedent, and so on.
Next,
I
compiled comprehensive indexes of what
I
found.
The
pur-
pose of these exercises was to understand the idioms, rhetorics, and
modes of discourse amined
in
available to the
common
lawyers in each period ex-
order to be familiar enough with their ways of talking and
Introduction thinking to he able to recognize nuances, to
tell
when
shifts in
xi 11
ways of
speaking and thinking were occurring, and to say with some confidence
whether time I
in
a particular
which
it
had conducted
was
statement about the law was representative of the
was made or whether a similar
it
was out of the ordinary. Because
study of civilian jurisprudence of the period,
in a positron to judge
with reasonable confidence which,
sources-of-law approaches or theories are peculiar to the
mind.
if
common
I
any,
law
’
S'
THE
COMMON LAW MIND
s
’sr
(
V.
—
CHAPTER ONE
W*
w-
w
V'
s
Conceptions of English
Medieval Treatises
in the
O
ne
who
sets
out to investigate medieval ways of thinking and talk-
ing about the nature and sources of English law will find
tematic discussion of general jurisprudence in the
of the period. parts of
A
few paragraphs in Glanvill
a
Sir
find
enough
to
few pages in Bracton, and
1
.
in trying to
common
ment of
Most appear content
because the medieval
common
literature of the sort so
no
law
law courts and the develop-
lawyers did not develop
to
assume that
a jurisprudential
among contemporary
civilians
and
characteristic understanding of the nature
and
widespread
sources of English law, or
if
they did, they
left little
Other historians believe that there was, cussion of jurisprudence in the period
The common
is
dominant medieval
we do not
find
much
dis-
that everyone took this theory
lawyers, Charles
ers assert, conceived of law as a
trace of it.
in fact, a
English theory of law and that one reason that
for granted.
common
understand and explain
the practices and procedures of the
substantive legal doctrine.
legal the-
widespread assumption that
a
In any event, historians of the
occupy themselves
canonists, they had
field. Little
comprehensive history of medieval English
to write about
sys-
little
common law literature
John Fortescue almost exhaust the
ory has not been written: there has been is little
a
,
two works by
wonder, then that
there
Law
Howard Mcllwain and
oth-
body of immemorial custom, which was
discovered or declared by kings, judges, or parliament and was not created or made. This
immemorial customary
law,
Mcllwain adds, was un-
derstood to be fundamental in the sense that rules inconsistent with
were void
2 .
Even scholars who know very
well that the
common
law
it
is
not the custom of the English people take the viejv that whatever the real
nature of that law, English lawyers have always understood
custom. Pollock,
for,
example, writes that “the
Common Law
to be
it
is
a
cus-
i
The Common Law Mind
2
tomary law lief
if,
in the
course of about eight centuries, the undoubting be-
and uniform language of everyone who had occasion to consider the
matter were able to make
This greatly overstates the evidence,
it so.”'
even from the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, when several promi-
common
make statements with custom. 4 An argument can be made nent
common
lawyers did
lawyers understood the
common
identifying the that at least
common
law
some medieval
law to be custom, but the ev-
idence from the literature of the period, particularly in the Year Books, is
too mixed to establish custom as the only or even the primary way of
conceptualizing the
common
law.
The Twelfth Century Two
twelfth-century books set out to describe contemporary English
The
law.
known,
first,
the Leges Henrici Primi
not an
is
,
despite the
title
by which
it is
compilation of the legislation introduced by
official
disorganized book,” 6
Henry I. “An untidy and 5
it
collects English laws of
various kinds, emphasizing the importance of the royal jurisdiction but also describing the division of English law into three geographical areas:
“one
is
the law of Wessex, another
Danelaw” differ evil
is
the law of Mercia, and the third the
adds that the “laws of the counties themselves
{Leges, 6, 2). It
very often from shire to shire, according as the rapacity and the
and hateful practices of lawyers have introduced into the
tem more serious ways of variations
among
inflicting injury” {Leges, 6, 3a).
There
the courts of hundreds, boroughs, and lords.
bination of the multiplicity of jurisdictions and
human
legal sys-
also are
The com-
perversity, the
Leges notes, produced great confusion and uncertainty in the law:
There
is
so
much
perversity in
human
affairs
and so much profu-
sion of evil that the precise truth of the law or a settled statement of the legal
The
remedy can seldom be found.
{Leges, 6, 4)
vexations of secular legal proceedings are beset with wretched
anxieties of such
many
number and magnitude, and
are enveloped in so
fraudulences, that these processes and the quite unpredictable
hazard of the courts seem rather things to be avoided.
As
a
balance against
its
{Leges, 6, 6)
recognition of diversity in jurisdictions, and of
the bad consequences that followed
from
it,
the Leges draw special atten-
English
tinual
in the
Medieval
Treatises
tremendous authority of the royal majesty tremendum
tion to “the
[
imperium which we
maiestatis
Law
worthy of attention
stress as
and beneficial pre-eminence over the laws”
of the king’s preeminence over the laws
is
dinance, recently restated by the king’s
3
regiae
for its con-
Evidence
(Leges, 6, 2a).
to be found in the ancient or-
command,
“that the general
courts of the counties should meet at fixed places and terms and at an
appointed time throughout the several counties of England, and that they should not be harrassed by any burdens of further meetings until
own need
the king’s
or the
more
require that they be held
though,
common
advantage of the kingdom should
often” (Leges,
7,
1).
the principle that the law of the king’s court
is
More is
important,
superior to the
three kinds of English law and to the law administered in the local courts: “over
and above everything stand the pleas of the royal court,
which preserves and in
all
While
its
usage and custom [usus
et
consuetadines ] at
all
times
places and with constant uniformity” (Leges, 9, 10a). it is
notable that the pleas of the royal court are described as
usage and custom,
it
should not be concluded that the author of the Leges
therefore conceives of
all
English law as custom. In the
first
place, the
Leges does not treat the placita curiae regis as being the equivalent of
the expression “the law of the land.”
It
describes with considerable
specificity the jurisdictional rights of the king, including matters in-
volving the peace and security of the realm, treason, contempt of the
commands, outlawry, military
king’s writs or
matters, cases involving
the king’s land or money, failure of justice, and violation of the king’s
law (Leges,
10,
1).
This description of the jurisdiction of the royal court
is
considerably narrower than the scope of the law of the land as described in the Leges.
(Furthermore, the expression “the king’s law”
[legis regie]
suggests legislative activity by the king, not the operation of usage and
custom.) Second,
when
the Leges does speak of the law of the land,
does not appear to describe
it
in
terms of custom or usage. Speaking of
the operation of the hundred courts,
For nothing
shall
plication of law
says:
[iure et ratione ], in
law of the land [per legem
terre]
of the court, as has been
laid
tion
it
be expected or taken by anyone except by the ap-
and reason
and
justice
down
on the part of the barons and
and the honest judgment
after the
their
accordance with the
most careful delibera-
worthy predecessors
in the
whole realm, and approved by the great assembly of God’s servant and wise
men
it
of the whole kingdom. (Leges,
8, 16)
The Common Law Mind
4
Even
if this
lished
may
passage
by being
“laid
not suggest that the law of the land
down”
after deliberation
proved” by the great assembly,
it
with the law of the land was sembly. This,
does suggest that the cardinal legal
down by
would seem, makes
it
Leges conceives of
The second
laid
all
estab-
by the barons and “ap-
hundred court decisions are to be made
principle that
is
it
in
accordance
the barons and approved in as-
impossible to conclude that the
English law as customary. 8
twelfth-century book, Glanvill
a
considerably greater
and more systematically organized jurisprudential achievement, was written near the end of the reign of Henry II
(ca.
1187-89) and primarily
gives an account of the writs used in the king’s courts and the proce-
dures that flowed from them. 9 Virtually everything Glanvill has to say of
nature concerning English law
a theoretical
graphs in
its
is
few para-
set forth in a
prologue, which are worth quoting in substantial part:
Not only must
and nations which also fitting that
power be furnished with arms against
royal
it
rise
rebels
up against the king and the realm, but
should be adorned with laws
nance of subject and peaceful peoples.
.
[leges]
it is
for the gover-
.
.
For truly he does not scorn to be guided by the laws and customs [leges et
consuetudines of the realm
which had
and have long prevailed; and, what
is
their origin in reason
more, he
is
even guided by
those of his subjects most learned in the laws and customs of the
realm
[iuris et regni consuetudinibus]
whom
he knows to excel
all
oth-
wisdom and eloquence, and whom he has found to most prompt and clearsighted in deciding cases on the basis
ers in sobriety,
be the
of justice and in settling disputes, acting
now with
severity and
now
with leniency as seems expedient to them.
Although the laws
seem absurd to have
to call
[leges]
of England are not written,
them laws
[leges]
those, that
been promulgated about problems
is,
it
does not
which are known
settled in council
on the
advice of the magnates and with the supporting authority of the
prince for this also
is a
the force of law.” For
deemed
to be laws
written laws tice
of him
them.
if,
[leges],
[leges] a
who
law
[lex],
that
“what pleases the prince has
merely for lack of writing, they were not then surely writing would seem to supply
force of greater authority than either the jus-
decrees them or the reason of
him who
establishes
Law
English
in the
however, utterly impossible for the
It is,
Medieval Treatises
leges et iura
5
of the realm
to be wholly reduced to writing in our time, both because of the ig-
norance of scribes and because of the confused multiplicity of those
same
But there are some general rules frequently ob-
leges et iura.
served in court which
me presumptous
does not seem to
it
to
com-
mit to writing/ but rather very useful to most people and highly necessary to aid the
have decided to put into writing at
I
of these general rules, adopting intentionally
least a small part
commonplace
memory
style
and words used in court
in order to provide
knowledge of them for those who are not versed elegant language.
(
a
in this kind of in-
Glanvill 1-3) ,
In this passage Glanvill makes several statefhents about English law: that
first,
it is
power be adorned with
fitting that the royal
government of the people; second, guided by the
the
that the king does not scorn to be
of the realm which had their origin in
“leges et consuetudines
reason and have long prevailed,” third, that the king
who
leges for
is
guided by those
are learned in the iuris et regni consuetudinibus; fourth, that although
the leges of England are not written, “it does not
them
leges ” (at least
seem absurd
to call
those promulgated about problems settled in council
on the advice of the magnates and with the supporting authority of the prince), for if English laws are not
deemed
to be leges merely for the lack
of writing, then the absence of writing has more weight than either the justice or reason finally,
that
it is
of the king
who
decreed or established them; and
impossible to reduce
all
the leges et iura to writing be-
cause of their “confused multiplicity”
Although
from
summary
aim of the prologue
is
not to provide an analysis of the sources of English law but to give
a
it is
clear
this
that the
body of English law
justification for putting part of the
prologue does provide several clues about the nature of English law. clearly takes
Glanvill
much
is
Roman
a variation
The
first
law as
its
on the
first
is
the fact that the prologue
starting point.
of the remainder of the prologue evidently
the law books of Justinian."’
When,
leges” he almost certainly
is
first
sentence of
Institutes
,
and
written with an eye
civilians,
which
is
based on
for example, Glanvill insists that “al-
though the laws of England are not written,
them
The
sentence of Justinian’s
toward the jurisprudence of contemporary
call
author’s understanding of
its
of these
into writing, the
is
it
does not seem absurd to
responding to several specific texts
The Common Law Mind
6
found
in the Corpus Juris. Texts are
unwritten
(jus
divide
t ^iat
Institutes (1.2.3)
all
both the Digest
in
law into the written
and canonists
civilians
who was exposed
naturally have
felt
to the
some pressure
new
legal learning
it
un-
The
author of
of Europe, might
to defend the validity
the unwritten English law and to assert that
1
conditions, both
traditions tended to give that law secondary status. 12 ,
non scriptum.
ius
some
t ^ie
and the
in principle recognized that
written usage could operate as law, at least under
Glanvill
an d
1.6.3)
(jus scriptum )
non scriptum ) and that accept custom as
Although both
(i.
and prestige of
was not absurd to
call
the
laws of England “laws.” 13
But how does he understand the nature of the unwritten laws that he is
defending?
When
he speaks of the “laws and customs of the realm,”
his reference
only to the
statutory and
common
common
law, or
does he have in mind both
Does he understand
law?
is
the unwritten English
law to be essentially customary in nature? His inconsistent use of legal
terminology complicates the resolution of such questions.
The civilians and canonists to whom the prologue is a response most commonly use the word lex to refer to enacted law and the word ius, in its widest sense, to encompass the whole of the law, both legislation and cus-
tom. 14
If the
author of Glanvill is following standard usage
tions the unwritten
that he
means
and customs of the realm,” we might expect
leges
to signal that English law
and customary fact that
u
law.
when he men-
The problem with
he appears to use
ius
and
is
composed of both enacted law
this interpretation
begins with the
lex interchangeably: in the
same sen-
tence he speaks both of the “leges and customs of the realm” and of the “iuris
and customs of the realm.” Later, when he
insists that the
unwrit-
ten English laws really are entitled to be called laws, he drops the
custom altogether and refers to
whether in using the phrase
them simply
as leges raising the ,
“leges et consuetudines regni ”
distinguish between leges and consuetudines: 15
We
word
question
he even means to
cannot,
it
seems, draw
any firm conclusion about how he understands the nature of English law based upon the standard meanings of the Latin terms he uses to describe it.
It
may
be, as
Maitland suggests, that English lawyers of
not carefully discriminate
had technical meanings
among ius,
lex,
in the “learned
consuetudo,
his
time did
and other terms that
law” of Europe because as yet
they had no clear theory “as to the relationship between enacted and un-
enacted law, [andl the relationship between law and custom.” 16 If the
Latin terminology of the prologue provides no sure guide to
its
English
Law
in the
Medieval
Treatises
7
s author’s understanding of the nature of English law, does the fact that that law all
is
uniformly described
as
unwritten suggest that he conceives of
English law as customary? After
prologue
partially
is
ary in origin.
1
On
upon which
the Institutes
all,
,
modeled, describes unwritten law
as
being custom-
balance, the prologue does not appear to treat
glish law as customary.
The
sentence that asserts that
it is
all
clear that the status as lex
is
not being claimed for
En-
not unreason-
able to call the unwritten English laws leges adds limiting clauses to it
the
make
English laws but
all
only for those “known to have been promulgated about problems settled in council
on the advice of the magnates and with the supporting au-
thority of the prince
— for
this also
is
a lex, that
^
has the force of law.’”
‘what pleases the prince '
This passage suggests that when the author of Glanvill refers to the unwritten laws of England he has in mind the conscious enactments and decisions of the king,
made on
the advice of the council, that have not
been reduced to writing. The quotation of the famous Roman maxim
Quod
principi placuit legis hahet vigorem in justification
may
unwritten English laws force this interpretation rectly
makes the
(
of the claim that
reasonably be called laws appears to rein-
Digest 1.4.1; Institutes, ,
will of the prince the
1.2.9).
determining
^
t ^ie
factor,
Digest cor-
then the en-
actments or decisions of the English prince have the force of
whether they are
The
in writing or not.
author’s concern appears to have
been to establish the validity of English royal law despite character, rather than to defend
it
as
law,
customary
its
unwritten
law.
Bracton The
greatest medieval treatise
tributed to
on the common law
Henry de Bracton and goes by
his
name.
is
It
traditionally at-
was long thought
to have been written about halfway through the thirteenth century, but
much
of recent opinion holds that the original manuscript was written
some twenty years
earlier
and that the versions we know passed through
the hands of revisers, one of
whom may
Glanvill’s example, Bracton begins is
unwritten
it
have been Bracton. IS Following
by arguing that although English law
nonetheless deserves the
title
of law: *
Though turn,
in almost
all
lands use
is
made of the
leges
and th ejus scrip-
England alone uses unwritten law and custom. There law de-
The Common Law Mind
8
rives
from nothing written
Nevertheless,
it
will
from what usage has approved.
[but]
not be absurd to
call
English laws
leges,
though
they are unwritten, since whatever has been rightly decided and ap-
proved with the counsel and consent of the magnates and the general
agreement of the
having been
res publica , the
authority of the king or prince
added thereto, has the force of
first
law.
England has
many local customs, varying from place to place, for the Enhave may things by custom which they do not have by law, as
as well
glish
in the various counties, cities, boroughs,
and
vills,
ways be necessary to learn what the custom of those
who
Eminent
allege
it
use
it. ( Bracton 2: 19)
is
will al-
and how
19
Mcllwain,
who
assert the identity of
law in medieval England, see this passage as the 20
a place
it
scholars disagree radically over the interpretation of this pas-
sage. Historians like
trine.
where
Others,
with custom
is
who
locus classicus
custom and of that doc-
believe that the medieval tendency to identify law
overstated, see in this passage proof of their point of view.
Let us examine
it.
Part of the passage clearly significant additions
is
a
paraphrase of Glanvill, but there are
and modifications. The Bracton passage magnifies
the theoretical significance of the advice of the magnates mentioned in Glanvill because
it
ties it to
the idea of consent: “Since whatever has
been rightly decided and approved with the counsel and consent of the
magnates and the general agreement of the the king or prince having been (
Bracton 2:19).
A
little
first
res publica , the
authority of
added thereto, has the force of law”
farther along, Bracton again emphasizes the role of
consent in giving English laws their authority: “Since they have been ap-
proved by the consent of those cannot be changed without the
who
use them [consensus utentium ] they
common
consent of all by whose counsel
and consent they were promulgated. They cannot be their consent, but
At
first
may be changed
for the better”
(
nullified
Bracton
without
2:21).
glance, the clause that asserts that English laws “have been ap-
proved by the consent of those claim that Bracton
modeled on
a
classifies
famous
use them” appears to support the
English law as custom.
The
clause clearly
text in the Institutes tying the authority of
ary law to the consent of those
which usage has established; the consent of those
who
who
who
use
it:
custom-
“The unwritten law
is
that
for ancient customs, being established
use them, are like
is
leges ” (Institutes 1.2.9).
by
T his
Law
English
text
seems straightforward enough, and
Medieval
in the
Treatises
9
were the only passage in the
if it
Corpus Juris bearing on custom and consent, civilian constitutional the-
ory might be considerably
less
complex.
Walter Ullmann claims that medieval tion, base the ple.
A
21
One
jurists,
binding force of custom upon the
series of texts in the Digest
text, attributed to the
almost without excep-
tacit
seems to make
second-century
consent of the peo-
this
point explicitly.
jurist Julian,
argues that be-
cause statutes themselves are binding only because they have been ac-
cepted by the people through their votes,
it is
people approve through the substance of
its
on everyone ( Digest third-century
a late
their being “a tacit
1.3. 32.1).
Another
jurist, also
also fitting that
what the
actions should be binding
Hermogenian,
text, attributed to
bases the binding force of customs on
agreement of the citizen” ( Digest
1.3.35).
The
civilian
knew these texts well, and as a gloss in the Brachylogus makes “ they also knew Cicero’s definition of customary law: Consuetudo is
glossators plain,
thought to be that which lapse of time has approved by the
common
consent of all without the sanction of statute.” 22 This doctrine
may seem
self-evident merely
from the
definition of
custom — as Ullmann remarks,
the very idea of customary law presupposes the participation of the
people. Nevertheless, other ideas keep cropping up.
The
jurist-theologian Francisco Suarez, a few centuries later,
great Spanish
felt
the need to
take considerable pains to refute the idea that the long continued practices
of a single person, even
customary
law.
2 -
if
that person were the ruler, could establish
But to say that customary
presupposes the participation of the people
law, as a definitional matter,
Ullmann
does, that technically
it is
is
not necessarily to
say, as
the voluntas populi rather than the vol-
untas principis that gives legal character to custom. Medieval doctrine
on
the critical element in the transformation of customary practices into
binding rules
legally
Some sent
is
is
more complex than
of the earlier medieval
jurists
that.
24
do indeed hold that popular con-
the element that gives legal force to customary usages. Vacarius, a
who is most famous for having been the first known expositor of Roman law in England, takes that position in a gloss on the words tacito consensu in Digest 1.3. 32.1. 25 The twelfth-century glossator educated
at
French
jurist
Petrus de Bellapertica
ions of
some
glossators that there
ship between usages
(:
is
Bologna,
(d.
1308), reacting against the opin-
a direct
cause-and-effect relation-
mores) and customary law ( consuetudo ), insists that
the actions of usage of themselves produce
no
legal force; the
binding
ef-
io
The Common Law Mind
*
custom comes
feet of “ JJsus
On
non
est
from the
solely
tacit
consent or will of the people:
26 causa consuetudines, sed tacita voluntas populi?
number of
the other hand, because a substantial
emperor “held
postglossators taught that the
Romanus
that the populus
as the result
,
the people’s consent
2
It
.
laws in his breast” and
lex regia
,
methe legal effect of customary law comes from was sometimes claimed that a fragment from
the Institutes of Ulpian, reproduced twice in the Corpus starting point of
century.
Romanist doctrine on government
The argument was two quite
basis for
glossators to
thority
all
is
no longer held
an overstatement to say that virtually
it is
dieval jurists agreed that
and
complete and irrevocable
a
emperor through the
transfer of imperium to the
any lawmaking power,
of
all
glossators
all
Jims was ,
the
after the twelfth
based on the fact that that text served
different constitutional theories. It
is
as the
hard for the
deny that the immediate source of imperial power and au-
an act of transfer by the populus Romanus of that potestas and
much
imperium since that ,
stated clearly
is
in Justinius’s Corpus Juris}*
enough
in at least four places
But there their agreement ends.
It is
possi-
ble to interpret the lex regia as the basis either of imperial absolutism
or of popular sovereignty. In the lex regia
is
its
immediate context
in the Corpus Juris,
quoted in support of the claim that “what the emperor
pleases has the force of law,” but the texts speaking of the lex regia
not say whether
and permanent
a full
thereby made or whether individual
only
emperorT Some of the
a definitive alienation
for good,
it is
and
not resume
its
it
limited and revocable concessio to an
leading glossators hold that there was
30 .
its
power
In this view, even the custom of the peo-
make and unmake law 31 Other glossators, howas a mere concessio whereby an office and a usus are
to
.
,
created but the substance of the imperium remains with the ple.
is
no longer held lawmaking power and could
former power
ever, see the lex regia
of imperium and potestas
whereby the Roman people renounced
as a result
power
ple loses the
a
translatio
do
Roman
peo-
Bulgarus, Johannes Bassianus, and most significantly for our pur-
poses because of his influence on Bracton’s jurisprudence, Azo, hold that the people did not totally and irrevocably alienate their
power
32 .
This divergence of views among the glossators may be traced stantial part to the particular set of Justinian’s texts that a writer
to emphasize.
One who
—a
chooses
concentrates on one set of texts might naturally
be led to think of the emperor istrator of the law
in sub-
ruler
as the sole
maker, interpreter, and admin-
bound by no
legal limitations, particularly
Law
English
in the
Medieval
n
Treatises
s any limitations tied to
Another
of power or authority in the people.
a reservoir
writer, focusing
on
a different set
of texts, might
come
to think
of the emperor as limited in power and authority, bound by the law, and sharing his lawmaking power with the people, at least in the sense that
customs have the power to become
their
The famous
statement of Ulpian, “quod principi placuit, legis habet
vigorem” ( Digest
mean
that the
emperor has the power to do whatever he
Justinian can be read as
making
By the present enactment,
who
plaining
taken by few medieval
1.4.1; Institutes 1.2.6), is
imply that the emperor alone can make
For
law.
law.
peror
does not
However, an enactment of
the
emperor alone can make
laws.
.
.
them
to
all
persons, except he
shall justly
be regarded
who
alone
permitted to be
is
doubts being cast aside, the
as the sole
maker and interpreter
1.14.11)
em-
these texts are considered with others proclaiming that “the is
not bound by the laws” ( Digest
prevail against statutes
(
Code
1.3. 31)
and that custom
(as
long
as
it is
assumed that these
will
not
can be made that
8.52.2), a plausible case
the people’s transfer of political and lawmaking
manent
.
appears to be capable of solving legal enigmas, and ex-
of the laws. ( Code
When
likes; it
precisely the latter claim:
legislator? Therefore, these ridiculous
emperor
33
jurists to
power
is
total
and per-
texts are as dispositive of the
allocation of political and legislative authority in medieval
Europe
as in
sixth-century Constantinople). 34 Justinian can be read, then, as supporting both “ascending” and “descending” conceptions of government, to use Ullmann’s famous terminology — conceptions in which consent critical
and conceptions in which
difficult to settle
it
plays
no
part.
35
This
fact
makes
is it
with certainty the jurisprudential implications of Brdc-
discussion of the place of consent in English law.
ton's
Matters are complicated by the fact that in the same sentence in Bracton
we
who and
find
both
a
reference to laws “approved by the consent of those
use them” (clearly drawn from the a
mon
Institutes' s
discussion of custom)
statement that English laws cannot be changed “without the com-
consent of
gated” (evidently
all
a
the earlier passage
by whose counsel and consent they were promul-
reference not to the people’s usage of a custom but to
making the
validity of English laws
counsel and consent of the magnates"). plausibly
may be
A
depend on “the
reference to consent, which
read as suggesting that English law
is
customary,
is
thus
The Common Law Mind
12
joined with another that reflects the feudal idea that the king’s
make
laws
power
to
conditioned on the counsel and consent of the great barons
is
or magnates of the realm. 36 While there can be no disputing the importance of consent in the latter passage, there a
claim that Bracton conceived of
all
is
no way
to use
it
to support
English law as customary. There-
fore,
although the passages on consent do not uniformly point in the
same
direction,
on balance we must conclude
the claim that Bracton characterizes
do not support
English law as custom.
made even clearer in the discussion of the role of consent in creation of new writs. The assumption that runs throughout Brac-
This the
all
that they
ton' s
is
discussion of writs
is
that the stock of
common
law writs
is
not
some long forgotten customary practice but is evolutionary and growing. There are standard original writs “formed on specified cases” which are “of course” Bracton 4:285)* These are the static
or fixed by
(.
writs “granted and approved by the counsel of the whole realm totins regni\
and
[that]
can in no way be changed without their consent
and agreement.” Considerable room writs to
[consilio
is left
for the
development of new
meet circumstances not encountered before
in the law if
such
a
writ “is in accordance with reason and not contrary to law” and “pro-
has been granted by the king and approved by his council.”
vided
it
know
that the creation of
bility:
new
We
writs was not merely a theoretical possi-
the registers of writs that contained 50 or 60 writs at the begin-
ning of Henry IIEs reign grew to about 120 decade of the fourteenth century
it
When we consider that for both primarily found in the
common
had grown to 890
his council”
ity that the
customary.
goes
a
By
writs.
the second
37
Glanvill and Bracton legal authority
is
law writs, 38 the assertion that newly in-
vented writs are valid in English law
proved by
at its end.
if
“granted by the king and ap-
long way toward eliminating the possibil-
author of Bracton understands English law to be essentially It
removes any possible doubt that he well knows that new
writs are drafted and approved by identifiable royal officials to deal with particular factual and legal circumstances.
Bracton to suggest that
its
There
is
nothing elsewhere in
author conceptualizes the creation and adop-
tion of writs as an essentially customary practice, even
understood only
as the
if
that practice
is
“custom of the courts” and not the more encom-
passing “custom of our realm of England” often mentioned in contem-
porary writs. If the texts
we consider do not support
the claim that Bracton treats
Law
English
Medieval Treatises
in the
13
s English law as being entirely, or at least essentially, customary, what
then are
we
to
make of
the fact that the treatise asserts that “England
alone uses unwritten law and custom” (Bracton
speaks of “English laws and customs” {Bracton
2:19),
that
it
repeatedly
2:19, 21), that it states that
law in England “derives from nothing written but from what usage has
approved” ( Bracton classified as ethics
and that
2:19),
holds that
it
or moral science “since
it
all
of
De
Legibus
must be
customary princi-
treats of
ples of behavior” {Bracton 2:20)?
One when
possible solution
is
found
the author of Bracton asserts that “England alone uses unwritten
laws and custom,” he
drawing
is
consuetudines
were
a distinction
local customs.”
terms, Tierney argues, there
39
meaning of consuetude
to the
and consue-
whole king-
to suppose that he uses
Tierney
to local
leges
Bracton having thus defined his
no reason
is
different senses elsewhere in his work. limit the
between
body of laws common
tudines: “ Leges constituted the
dom;
in Brian Tierney’s contention that
is
them
in
led into his attempt to
customs by
his
concern to refute
Mcllwain’s argument that because the word consuetudo does not appear in
power of the king “to cause the
the Bractonian text setting forth the et constitutiones et assisas
observed” {Bracton
tomary
law.
40
refers to laws
provided, approved, and sworn in his realm to be
2:22),
the king
Tierney’s point
governing
all
is
shown
is
that
to have
the term that in Bracton
if leges is
of England (that
no authority over cus-
is,
the
Mcllwain’s primary proof text for his claim that the
damental law in the sense that
shown not
leges
it is
common law), then common law is fun-
beyond the control of the king
is
to support his thesis.
The Tierney
interpretation of what Bracton
means by the terms
suetudo and leges has a certain textual plausibility, particularly
ignores the
common
law tradition, running at least from the
if
con-
one
late thir-
teenth century to Blackstone, of explicitly distinguishing between general
and particular
have
its
seems
(or local)
customs — a tradition widely thought to
foundation in BractonT However, another reading of the passage
just as plausible textually
speaking about custom used by
and yet conforms to the standard way of
common
lawyers from the Middle Ages
When
Bracton states that “it will not
through the seventeenth century. be absurd to
on to add
call
that
English laws
“England has
leges
,
as well
though they be unwritten” and goes
many
son to suppose that the intention of the limited, technical definition of the
local custorhs,” there latter
word
statement
is
is
no
rea-
to provide a
consuetudo, distinguishing
it
The Common Law Mind
H from
leges.
seems
It
merely to make
when
just as plausible to
suppose that the intention
between general and
a distinction
local
is
customs and that
discussing the unwritten laws of England Bracton intends to in-
clude the general customs of the realm. the passage relied
On
this reading, the
on by Tierney should be on the word
emphasis in
local,
pointing
out a distinction from customs governing the entire realm. If
Tierney misunderstands Bracton
customs. In the leges
Bracton
,
mistaken in concluding that the word
at least as
word
use of the word consuetudo he
s
consistently
resists the
using the word
wrong passage
is
suspect; there
almost universal
leges in a
does not encompass
assumption that Bracton uses the
place, Tierney’s
first
leges
is
no reason to suppose that
is
of his time — of
juristic practice
variety of ways. 42 Second, Tierney relies
on the
for his definitions; Bracton includes a clearly labeled
definition passage a few paragraphs farther along:
What
law
is
and what custom.
command,
general
We
must
Law
see
what law
is.
the decision of judicious
men, the
restraint of
is
a
offenses knowingly or unwittingly committed, the general agree-
ment of
the res publica. Justice proceeds
justice lies in the creator
jus from man], and thus
synonymous. And though law be everything that
said to just
{lex)
may be
read {legitur)
is
use
it, is
where
it is
sometimes observed
passage rests heavily on
defined,
“Lex
est
is
and
lex are
its
special
its
meaning
opposite.
be
is
a
Custom,
approved by the practice of those as,
the authority of custom and long use
The
jus
that
in the broadest sense
sanction ordering virtue and prohibiting
in truth, in regions
who
from God, assuming
Roman
and takes the place of lex. For is
not
law.
slight.
The
first
Bracton 2:22) 43
(
part, in
an almost exact quotation from the Digest
commune praeceptum, virorum prudentum
which
which
1.3.1,
lex
is
reads:
consultum, delic-
torum, quae sponte vel ignorantia contrahuntur, coercitio, communis reipublicae sponsio.” Bracton' s discussion of ius and lex
is
taken from Azo: “auctor
secundum hoc
tom
iuris est
idem
ius et lex
significant.”
in this passage, while itself
relation of els. Its
custom to
lex.
In
homo, acutor 44
its
connection with
iustitiae est deus, et
Bracton' s treatment of cus-
not quite a definition, does set forth the
this, too, Bracton is
following
Roman mod-
treatment parallels an excerpt of Julian in the Digest
1.3.32:
In any kinds of cases in which there are no written laws the rule that
ought to be observed
is
that
which has come to prevail by use and
Law
English
Medieval Treatises
in the
15
/*•
custom. ...
Immemorial
1.
( inveterata )
not unreasonably; and this
what
is
is
custom
is
observed pro lege,
called the law established
by
/
usage. 45
Because Bracton
s
Roman models
do not limit the use of
for this passage
the term custom to -local customs,
it
seems highly unlikely that
has only local customs in mind. If the Tierney thesis
author
its
accepted, one
is
must ask what Brae tons author thinks about the relationship of general customs to
law.
That general customs hold no place
seems inconceivable, considering
The
in his legal
Roman
his learning in
law.
system
46
fact that the treatise repeatedly refers to the “leges et
consue-
tudines” of England surely reflects an understanding that custom
portant in the English legal order, but withouEmore that
its
author understands
it
is
im-
does not suggest
of English law to be customary or even
all
that he conceptualizes the unwritten law applied in the king’s courts as
custom. Although
it
may be
linguistically possible to read the phrase as
suggesting an identity between
most natural reading. There compels the conclusion that
is
its
and
leges
consuetudines, that
is
not the
nothing stated in the Bracton text that author understands
all
of English law to
be customary. In the end, to prove that the author of Bracton understands all
of English law to be customary, one must rely on presumptions or
evidence brought in from outside the Bracton text and argue that, in the light
of those presumptions or extrinsic materials, Bracton “must”
what one
claims.
Leading
mean
47
common
lawyers repeatedly, from the fourteenth through
common
the seventeenth centurv, describe the
law as the
common
or
general custom of the realm. Although this should not be ignored by one
who
is
trying to understand Bracton
'
s
jurisprudence,
tablishes that the treatise takes that position.
tradition concerning the nature of the lar tradition exists is
no proof that an
author of Bracton does. greatest medieval
Many
earlier
its
law,
work
work
later lawyers
is
by no means is
more than one
and that
a particu-
in that tradition (in
itself). It is
particularly
hold a certain view, the
of the qualities that
make De
rest
of Europe,
its
Legibus the
interest in general ju-
attempt to systematize and rationalize English law — are
unimportant to the generations of common lawyers that
from the
es-
work on the common law — its awareness and knowl-
edge of the learned law of the risprudence,
There
common
the absence of convincing evidence in the
dangerous to assume that because
48
it
follow.
literature these later lawyers left behind, they
Judging
appear to be
i6
The Common Law Mind
«}
largely unread in the the learned law little
and jurisprudence and interested in
beyond pleading and procedure. As T.
F.
T. Plucknett notes, some-
one reading the Year Books of the next two centuries would have reason to suspect that
The
book
a
Bracton that
poraneous
all
English law
writs.
De
customs” because
had been written. 49
like Bracton
extrinsic evidence that is
little
most compellingly supports customary
is
reading of
a
in the formulas of
contem-
Legibus almost certainly uses the phrase “laws and
its
subject
is
principally the law that has
grown up
around the writs used in the central courts, and those writs commonly use as a formula a variation on the phrase “according to the custom of
our realm of England”
(
secundum consuetudinem regni
Clauses in which the law applied by the royal courts
is
nostri Anglic)
called
A
“custom”
appear to be used interchangeably, from one writ to the next, with clauses in
which the person to
whom
the writ
directed
is
is
ordered to do
and custom of our realm” {secundum
justice “according to the law
lege?n
consuetudinem regni nostri ), or “according to the law and custom of
et
England” {secundum legem
et
consuetudinem Anglie) {Early Registers 55, ,
148, 166). If the writs at the very heart of the developing
common
law
use the phrases “custom of England” and “law and custom of England” interchangeably, then
it is
who
drafted
built
around
plausible to conclude that those
the writs, and the lawyers and judges
whose practice was
them, understood the law comprehended in the phrase “law and custom of England” to be customary law.
The
author of Bracton in writing of the
“law and custom of England” would be well aware that in the law writs that phrase land,” las
and so
it
common
used interchangeably with “the custom of Eng-
is
seems entirely plausible,
if
we only consider
the formu-
of the writs, that he might understand the law used in the central
courts to be customary.
The
difficulty
with such
conclusion, however,
a
tonian passages that are hard to reconcile with
it.
is
that there are Brac-
How does
one, for ex-
ample, explain the statements that in order for laws to have force they
have to meet several tion and
whom
tests,
which look to us
would certainly have so appeared
Bracton draws
much
make of those passages
that
like
conditions upon legisla-
to the medieval civilians
of his jurisprudence? 51
may be
And what
is
from
one to
read as suggesting that prior judicial
new law
may be considered a source of law, or of those suggesting that may be created upon new and unusual matters by reasoning a
similibus
ad similiaV 2
decisions
English
Law
in the
Medieval
Treatises
17
/*
Pollock and Maitland write that the English lawyers of Bracton’s time
had “no definite theory
between enacted and une-
as to the relationship
nacted law, the relationship between law and custom, the relationship
between the law strong
a
as
it is
and the law
as
it
ought to be.” 53 This may be too
statement in regard to Bracton himself. But
more can be
little
confidently said of Bracton’s explicit discussion of custom than that he
holds that its
it
sometimes observed
“is
authority “is not slight,” and that
as,
and takes the place of
cannot be changed or abrogated
it
without the consent of those by whose consent
no claim that custom stands assuming that custom
is
absurd” to regard
it
it
was adopted. There
in a superior position to
always what Bracton has in
to ins non scriptum. Bracton as law.
is
lex,” that
is
enacted law, even
mind when he
merely concerned to assert that
refers
it is
“not
54
Bracton and Case Law If
the characteristic medieval and early
ing English
common
modern approach
to distinguish-
law from Continental law involves contrasting En-
glish lex non scriptum with the Continental lex scriptum, the characteristic
approach of modern scholars of comparative law asserts
tween the
common
law as a case law system, governed by binding prece-
dent, in which the standard
mode
ticular cases to general rules,
in fixed
contrast be-
a
and authoritative
of reasoning
and the
texts
civil law',
and arrived
at
is
by induction from par-
whose
embodied
rules are
by means of deductive rea-
soning from general principles. Although one commentator
may em-
phasize the case law aspect of English law, a second, the role of binding
precedent, and
a third,
the theory of inductive reasoning,
most would
generally agree with the formulation. 55
Arthur L. Goodhart rightly observes that precedent in the Oxford Dictionary sense of “a particular instance or case which taken as an example or role for subsequent cases” systems. 56 But
more
is
The famous
sums up the modern theory of case
followed in
1833 case of Mirehouse
may be all
v.
legal
in the
Rennell
law:
law system consists in the applying to
new combi-
we
derive from
nations of circumstances those rules of law which legal principles
or
sometimes claimed for the role of precedent
English system of case law.
Our common
is
is
and
judicial precedents;
and for the sake of attaining
The Common Law Mind
i8
uniformity, consistency, and certainty,
where they cases
which
abandon
all
we must apply
are not plainly unreasonable
and we are not
arise;
those rules,
and inconvenient, to
at liberty to reject
all
them, and to
analogy to them, in those to which they have not been
judicially applied, because
and convenient
as
we
we
think the rules are not as reasonable
ourselves could have devised
5 .
Once a prior case directly in point is found, it “is no longer one which may be used as a pattern; it is one which must be followed in the subsequent case .”- 8
There
is
about
a small dispute
just
when
hold in English law. Carleton Allen dates while Holdsworth says that
it
this
modern theory took
in the nineteenth century,
it
was “reached substantially by the end
of the eighteenth century.” 59 Nevertheless, there
throughout most of its history the
common
little
is
dispute that
law operated without
ory of binding precedent. Except for Bracton, there
no
virtually
is
a the-
tion of earlier decisions by early English legal treatise writers.
Chipman Gray Britton,
,
and only eleven in
contains about
John
one reference each in Glanvill and Fleta none
finds
Littleton’s Tenures
60
his
notebook; his trea-
hundred references to cases
five
in
.
Bracton collected some two thousand cases in tise
cita-
61 .
There
is
some
question whether, in citing cases, he merely follows contemporary practice
or whether he invented such a practice. Plucknett, cautioning us
against assuming that Bracton’s use of case law
is
any part of contempo-
rary legal thought, argues that certainly his use of plea rolls since access to
them was
virtually impossible to obtain
62 .
garded
as
trates the
law to be case law or for
binding authority;
if
custom of the court.
leged in court, but as
a
used
a
is
far
merely
occasions, precedents
63 .
evidence that by the citation
was frequent
Whatever
al-
feel is
bound strong
quarter of the thirteenth century the practice of
64 .
the standard practice of his time, the author of Bracton in
addition to his dicial
may be
on the other hand, claims that there
Allen, last
illus-
general rule the judges regard themselves as
having implicit knowledge of the consuetudo curiae and do not to argue past cases
too early
previous judgment to be re-
at all, a prior decision
On rare
unique,
Maitland takes
an even firmer stance, holding that the thirteenth century a date for the
is
,
own custom
decisionmaking that
of citing prior cases, lays
is
frequently taken as the
down first
a rule
of ju-
English state-
English
Law
in the
Medieval
Treatises
19
s ment of the doctrine of precedent and of legal reasoning by analogy: “If new and unusual matters arise which have not before been seen in the realm, if like matters arise let them be decided by like (si tamen similia ergood one
for pro-
inerint per simile iudicentur), since the occasion
is
ceeding a similibus ad similia
ironic that this passage
’
(Bracton 2:21). It
is
a
should be considered the foundation of the doctrine that, more than any
common law from Roman law, for it clearly Roman legal doctrine. An excerpt of Julian’s
other, distinguishes English
on standard
rests heavily
reads:
When
a rule is laid
down
in the first instance, a
more
precise pro-
vision has to be made, either by interpretation or else by direct legislation. It is
.
.
.
impossible for every point to be expressly comprehended in
statutes or senatorial decrees;
meaning of the enactment
still
if in
clear, the
is
any case that
arises, the
presiding magistrate ought
to extend the rule to analogous cases to the one expressed and lay
down
the law accordingly. (Digest
Another
parallel
is
found
1.3.11,12)
Summa
in the
of the great civilian glossator
Azo:
Sometimes affair is to
of a law.
It
be
settled;
If the
consulted, ble,
in court proceedings there
if
he
sometimes there
doubt concerns present and
is
one must proceed de
must be understood
de similibus ad similia
seen,
is
new
if it is
similibus
is a
doubt about how
a
novel
doubt about the meaning
affair
the
Emperor
possible. ... If
ad similia
that, for Bracton’s
it is
is
to be
not possi-
65 ,
Roman
models, proceeding
means emphasizing the authority not of any
particular but of a series or
we have
a
is a
group of cases creating
a practice.
66
case in
This, as
not true of the modern English notion of case law and
precedent, wherein every court
is
cisions of courts superior to itself
held to be absolutely
bound by
all
de-
and generally bound by the decisions
of coordinate courts “in the absence of strong reasons to the contrary.” 67
We
do not know
dent, but
it
is
if
Bracton entirely accepts the
quite clear that he does not hold the
which the most recent case
While he
Roman view
in point
is
modern
entitled to the
freely uses prior cases in his treatise, they
of preceview, in
most weight.
were old
cases;
and
20
The Common Law Mind
fj
he uses them for the purpose of criticizing more contemporary cases that he thinks perverted the old law. His cases are carefully selected to
show what
the law ought to be, not because he thinks they have any
binding authority 68 .
Still, his
use of decided cases accustomed lawyers of
the thirteenth and early fourteenth centuries to discussing cases, and this
is
a significant step in the
development of
a case
law system.
Bracton’s Revisers
The
unsettled state of English legal theory near the end of the thirteenth
may be
century
breviation of
whole law
seen in the fact that Bracton' successor, Britton an ab,
De
Legibus written in the time of
as statutory
— that is,
as
Edward
I,
represents the
proceeding from the king’s authority
and direction:
Edward by
God
the grace of
have caused such laws
... to
all
his faithful people.
will
.
We
have heretofore been used in our realm to
as
be reduced into writing according to that which
And we
.
.
is
here ordained.
and command, that throughout England and Ireland
they be so used and observed in
all
points, saving to the
power of
we
repealing extending restricting and amending them, whenever shall see
good, by the assent of our earls and barons and others of
our Council; saving also to
all
persons such customs as by prescrip-
tion of time have been differently used, so far as such customs are
not contrary to law 69 .
In this view, the law depends
even repeal here
is
it
upon
the king’s will, and he can change or
subject to the assent of his council.
The custom mentioned
clearly that of local, particular usage in derogation of the law of
the land. instead,
There
custom
certainly is
no idea here of custom
is
as a
fundamental law;
subordinate even to the law created by the king’s com-
mand. The necessary assent of the council provides some the king’s actions, but there
At about the same time the
work known
revise Bracton in tial
as Fleta.
is
no notion of the rule of law
as Britton
,
upon
restraint
in Britton.
an anonymous royal
official
wrote
His primary purpose appears to have been to
view of the legislation of Edward
I.
From
a
point of view, the most significant contribution of Fleta
jurisprudenis its
treatment of the law courts. Although mostly based on Bracton
,
original its
pro-
English
Law
in the
Medieval
Treatises
21
s logue, containing
most important discussion of the
its
fact that
some
English laws were unwritten, follows not Bracton but Glanvill:
The call
laws of England, although unwritten, leges— since lex
may
considered to be
if,
solely for
so, the
them This or
is
in council,
agreed should be
by the advice, that
is
who
want of being written, laws were not
same laws would seem
greater authority from the
of him
it is
magnates and with the prior or subsequent authority
of the prince; for
tice
which
laws, to wit,
promulgated upon doubts resolved to say, of the
not unreasonable to
thus be defined, “the prince’s pleasure has
— those
the force of law”
it is
to be fortified with a
mere writing of them than from the
decrees them or the reason of
*
70
him who
jus-
establishes
.
so close a paraphrase of Glanvill that nothing by
commentary needs
to be added here to
what was
way of
analysis
said of GlanvilPs
treatment of custom. All the medieval treatise writers
whom we
consider (except the author
of Britton) take pains to claim for English unwritten laws leges,
but none of them unambiguously claims that
written or customary. Moreover, none of is
fundamental, either in the sense that
that the king
There
is
is
subject to lex
no support
in these
,
is
most of its
English law
that
is
un-
customary law
1
It is
true that
all
of them hold
but they do not restrict lex to custom.
works for the doctrine that law cannot be
created or for the idea that custom council. Thus, in
them claim
standing as
cannot be changed or that con-
it
trary actions or enactments are invalid.
all
full
is
superior to law created by king and
aspects, the doctrine of immemorial
not to be found in these writers.
custom
W/
V
CHAPTERTWO
b-
The Jurisprudence
T
he philosopher imagine that
of the Year Books
political
movement had taken power
and abolished the teaching of science, executing stroying
all
scientific
fc.
Alaisdair MacIntyre once asked his readers to
know-nothing
a
V
law expression of the length of the time is
no memory.” 21 The
“cuius
non
Thomas
“from time whereof there
similarity of this expression to the canonists’s
memoria hominum”
exstat
is
striking.
is
Littleton’s explicit recognition, near the
period, that custom’s required time of usage
“And note
well, that
been used by
memory
no custom
less striking is Sir
end of the Year Book prescriptive concept:
is a
custom
allowable, but only such
is
of prescription, that
title
No
is
to say,
from time whereof the
man runneth not to the contrary.” 22 Once the common lawyers adopt the civilian-canonist of
do the
mean. In
civilians
23
“But divers opinions have been concerning
Littleton’s words,
Some common
of prescription, which
title
lawyers argue that time of
(September
to the time of Richard
I
Statute of Westminster
I (1275) as a
argue that what
is
time whereof the that
no man then
trouble
and canonists in agreeing about what the formulas
time of memory, &c, and of law.”
formulas for
much
the time necessary to establish customs, they have just as as
as has
limitation
meant by saying
memory alive has
of
memory
1189), the date
3,
that
is all
one
in the
extends back
provided in the
on writs of
Others
right.
custom has been used “from
man runneth
not to the contrary”
knowledge to the contrary. 24 The
is
only
latter inter-
pretation imposes a considerably less onerous burden of proof regarding
customs than the former, but
it still is
twenty years’ “time of memory”
The Year Books
more burdensome than
common among medieval
civilians.
only report the application of the “time of
test to local, particular
customs, not to the
common
law.
the ten or
memory”
did find one
I
instance in which a lawyer objects that a claim based on the law and cus-
tom of
the realm
fails
to allege that the
custom existed from time im-
memorial, but the court rejects the argument out of hand. 2
The
greatest difference in the
usage of custom and that of the
Middle Ages between the
common
lawyers does not
ception each tradition has of the elements that tests for
the for
proving custom.
common its
The
'’
make
valid
lie
civilians’
in the con-
custom or the
conceptions are naturally very close, since
lawyers borrow their definition of custom and their tests
validity
from the Roman
law, either directly
indirectly through the canonists.
The
from the
great difference
civilians or
lies in
the fact
that the civilians engage in a detailed theoretical examination of the na-
ture of custom, the bases of
its
binding force
sources of law, and so forth and that the
nothing to say about these matters. 26
as law, its relation to
common
other
lawyers have virtually
The Jurisprudence of the Year Books
29
s
The Common Law and Legal Change If
there
mon
is little
support in the Year Books for
law as immemorial custom, there
is
conception of the com-
a
even
less for
the contention
that medieval lawyers consider
it
to be immutable. In case after case, be-
ginning in the reign of Edward
I
and running through the fifteenth cen-
tury, lawyers
and judges openly recognize that
no longer what
it
a
is a
A
statute.
lawyer
custom which he
the
or doctrine
few examples make the point clearly
(Isle) asserts,
alleges in his favor
the Statute of Merton, everyone then
was the
common
law before
havingcommon, and the ten-
ant being able to prevent the land from approving: but that
mon law is
is
has once been. In most instances, the recognized in-
strument of change enough. In 1292,
a legal rule
altered
com-
by the Statute of Merton which allows the lord to
approve against his tenant. 2 In 1305, a lawyer (Lanfar) states, “Before the Statute [Westm. I c. 2]
party might
a
make
default
and the form of pleading
statute,
From time
.
.
is
now that process much changed.” 28 .
but
to time, a particular legal rule
is
is
2, 13
Edw.
abridged by
said to have always existed
unchanged. For example, in 1339 Justice Shareshulle announces that “the course of law has always been that the plaintiff should have a writ to the bishop without affirming any other disturbance in him,” and in 1343 Justice Shardelowe says, “It has always been held for law that no one shall have
29 Such statements, Warrantia Chartae but tenant in demesne.”
a
however, should not be understood as assertions that the a
whole
is
immutable. There are
nition of change in the
common
lawyer,
of an immutable
The varies,
common
no matter how
common
law.
-
just
too
many
common
instances of
law as
open recog-
law for us to conclude that any medieval insular his outlook, believes in the
myth
0
reaction of a particular lawyer to a change in the
not surprisingly, according to whether his ox
is
common
law
being gored, but
one does not get the impression from the Year Books that bench and bar generally take the attitude that changes in the
common
law are likely to
be bad or dangerous — an attitude most famously held some centuries later
by
Sir
Edward Coke and
be characteristic of the times. Instead,
that
common
one frequently
unwary
historians therefore take to
law mind in medieval and early
finds a recognition that a
modern
change
in the
30
The Common Law Mind
§
law
is
made
to
remedy some problem with the common
alter the existing
common law are
law. Statutes that
frequently explained in terms of an at-
tempt to remedy some hardship, mischief, or lack of reason
mon
in the
com-
For example, in 1294 Justice Bereford, responding to an asser-
law.
tion of counsel, says,
As
for
that
your statement that the writ takes
is
true; but
Statute;
it
was
its
origin
from the
Statute,
to provide for a case occurring before the
and to remedy hardships which occurred before the Statute
that the writ
was provided. 31
In 1308, Scotre describes a statute under discussion in very similar terms:
The
statute
common
was made to remove the hardship that there was
law in case a presentation was made while heirs were
women
under age or writ of right. statute
in the
were covert, who had no remedy except by
was because of
It
hardship (duresse) that the
this
was made. 32
In 1310, Chief Justice Bereford explains
a
change
in the law
by saying,
“you should understand that the statute was not made for nothing, but because a remedy accordant with
The Year Books
ley
was not ordained by the old
thus leave no doubt that the
common
changed or abrogated by statute and that when there
tween the two forms of law, statutes
prevail.
To
make
common
it
'
3
law can be
a conflict
say this, of course,
say that the cases reported in the Year Books
lawyers of the period do not understand the
is
law.”
beis
to
clear that the
law to be funda-
mental law to which other forms of law are inferior in authority. 34 Statutes are not the only recognized dieval England.
Sometimes there
is
form of
legal
change
in late
me-
an open acknowledgement in the
Year Books that the practice of the court has changed, without identifying any specific case or judge as the occasion for the change. For example,
Malore,
J.,
says,
“Formerly when people were commonly with the
king in war we more readily allowed the essoin than we do now.” 35 But
it is
also clear
‘in
the king’s service’
from the arguments sometimes
made by counsel that it is not unheard of for the judges amend the common law, especially when they are convinced chief” will result from the application of the existing statute law.
The
following colloquy illustrates this point:
to suddenly
that a “mis-
common
and
The Jurisprudence of the Year Books
31
s Sharshulle J. ... he ,
is
common law; and no joinder wherefore & c. Mohray. Sir, when you
not aided by the
is
given to him by the Statute;
see the mischief to be so outrageous in our behalf,
not admitted,
common
it
law, as
infant under age
of
full age,
seems that you
you did
joinder be
admit us in amendment of the
will
another case
in
if this
at
common
law,
when an
was vouched, and the demandant said that he was
and prayed that he might be viewed, and you granted to
the tenant a Venire facias and after that a Distringas and an Alias ,
,
was
Distringas and a Pluries Distringas, and so that the process ,
in-
by reason of such mischief you then granted to the tenant
finite,
Sequatur
should not
\suo periculo ] if the infant
Distringas;
wherefore
it
seems that
reason of this great mischief,
come
in this case. also
amend
a
at the Pluries
you can
by
well,
the law, &c. 36
Judges sometimes recognize that their decisions have the effect of
new
creating
law. In
one of the clearest of such instances, Bereford,
announces, “And by
decision on this avowry
a
we
throughout the land”; and pleased with the court’s
shall
people.” 3
For every example of open
new
role in creating asserts that
desirable
it
hard line on
law
law for poor
judicial recognition of the court’s
might be to have
no power to change the
a particularly
a
however, one can find another in which
no matter how
the judges have
have taken
law,
a
he adds, “For
effort,
twenty years there has not come into England so good
make
C.J.,
a
judge
a different rule,
law. Justice Hillary
seems to
this matter. In the sixteenth
year of
Edward III, he tells one Thorp that he would have to wait for a writ. Thorp protests, “Then I shall be delayed without cause, and shall not recover damages.” Hillary’s response
“What
is
of that?
We
will
not and
cannot change the ancient usages.” 38 In a case a few years at least a
for
later,
Chief Justice Stonore appears to argue for
circumvention of the normal
any judgment of this court ever to
Hillary replies, fect
“What
ut
Bereford changes
it to:
“judgments should be based not on examples but on reason.” In quoting Bracton, Bereford apparently
where Bracton
relying
on
refers to “law,” Bereford’s
indication of just
a telling
is
how
memory, and
his
the fact that
memory substitutes
“reason”
strongly he identifies law with reason.
opinions” are to be trusted, not blindly because they
If the “ancient
are old but because of the reason they presumptively represent, then is
not necessary to read expressions of faith in them
patible with a series of Year
new
Book
cases in
as logically
law. In Venor v.
it
incom-
which judges announce,
manner, that the decision they are
a straightforward
create
is
now making
in
will
Blund for example, Chief Justice Bereford ,
announces:
And by
A
the land.
man
decision]
[a
do
to
through
bad
suit,
on
this
avowry we
rascal of a bailiff or
is
this false possession.
needed to make
compatible with
make
a
law throughout
hayward might cause
and thereby he would remain charged for .
not come into England so good All that
shall
this
.
a
.
a
poor
all
time
For twenty years past there has law for poor people. 124
proclamation of the creation of new law
a respect for ancient
opinions
is
a
conclusion by Bere-
ford and the other judges that in this particular instance the presumption that the ancient usages reflected reason failed. It is
one thing, however, to conclude that some of the most important
common
lawyers in the Year
Book period understand law
another to infer from that that medieval hold this conception of law.
mon
law or
civil
I
common
have yet to find
law traditions in which
all
a
this
way and
lawyers uniformly
period in either the com-
the lawyers agree
on any-
52
The Common Law Mind
$
thing.
A
generation after Bereford proudly makes
new law
in Venor
v.
Blund, another judge emphatically refuses to do so, saying, “It was law
we were born make a new law.” 125 before
...
we cannot change
it
... so sue to Parliament to
common lawyers no doubt differ among themselves about the nature of the common law and how it is to be known. For almost any statement in the medieval legal literature about common law jurispruMedieval
dence one can find others that appear to contradict ferences
may be more
apparent than
real.
it.
Some
But when,
of these
dif-
in a single case,
three leading jurists express three different opinions about the nature
of the
common
law,
one cannot deny that
end, therefore, any attempt by a
modern
real differences exist. In the
legal scholar to claim that in the
common law is essentially common or the common erudition j3f the legal elite
conception of medieval lawyers, the custom, or case law, or reason, is
to
impose
common
a
theory from the outside rather than to find the medieval
law mind.
v.
CHAPTER THREE
v.
w'
v*
v
S
Legal Theory in Fortescue, Littleton,
and Fifteenth- Century Readings and Moots
Sir Sir
John Fortescue
the
is
John Fortescue
first
common
lawyer after Bracton to write
works containing overtly theoretical discussions of jurisprudence first
1
.
His
book, De Natura Legis Naturae written with the ultimate aim of ,
showing how the Lancastrian claim to the throne was ples of natural law, contains in the first
the law of nature and
its
relation to
Laudibus Legum Angliae, presents
volume
human
itself as a
law
by princi-
a
lengthy discussion of
2
His second book, De
dialogue in which Fortescue,
young prince about
as chancellor, instructs the
.
justified
the features of English
law that are important for him, as the future king, to understand.
The
first
thing that the prince needs to
Fortescue teaches,
depend upon the
is
that unlike the law in
will of the
For the king of England
dom
at pleasure, for
also
is
is
the case
far is
a
does not
government not only
were to preside over them with
tallages
the sort of
state that
because he
it
a
power
would be able to change the laws of his realm and
when they is
land,
not able to change the laws of his king-
he rules his people with
impose upon them
ing them; this
some other
law,
king alone.
regal but also political. If he
entirely regal, he
know about English
and other burdens without consult-
dominium which
What pleased
the civil laws indicate
the prince has the force of law.
But
otherwise with the king ruling his people politically,
not able himself to change the laws without the assent
of his subjects
3 .
In a later work, Fortescue
makes more
explicit his distinction
between
two kinds of political arrangements:
53
54
The Common Law Mind
$
Ther
bith
kyndes off kyndomes, of the wich that on
ii
dominium
callid in laten
And
politicum et regale. his peple sett self,
withowt
,
and that other
is
thai diuseren in that the first
by such lawes
vppon thaim
regale
tayles
as
he makyth
hym
self.
And
is
a lordship
callid
dominium
kynge mey rule
and other impositions, such
thair assent.
that,
is
a
kingdom politicum
et regale.
Just
he
as
The secounde kynge may
people by other laws than such as thai assenten unto
England
mey wol hym
therfore he
not rule his
4 .
what Fortescue means by
and by suggesting that the English king is not free to change the law
without the people’s consent,
is
the subject of considerable controversy
among modern commentators. Charles Plummer,
in his introduction to
the Governance of England, takes the view that by his dominium politicum
Fortescue means
regale
a constitutional
limited by the coexistent
wain and Stanley advocating
B.
monarchy
in
which the king
et is
power of parliament.' Charles Howard Mcll-
Chrimes, on the other hand, understand him to be medieval theory of
a typically
a
king limited by law — not
a
law manifesting parliamentary control, but customary law 6 .
As Walter Ullmann points out ent of customary law
people to adhere to 7
rule .” If law
is
is
in another context, a material ingredi-
“the will and consent of the relevant group of
a particular practice
and thus turn
it
into a binding
primarily thought of as customary, then the “assent of the
people” might be expected to be manifested not through acts of parlia-
ment but through
a
change in usages and practices. There
dence, however, that Fortescue thinks of the
The
of the consent of the community.
tween consent and
a
form of English law
common
law
no
is
as the
evi-
product
only connection he makes beis
with statutes, which, he says,
made not only by the prince’s will, but also the assent of the whole realm.”* In De Natura Legis Naturae he just as clearly associates the con“are
sent required in tion:
a
dominium politicum
et regale
with parliamentary
legisla-
“For in the kingdom of England the kings make not laws, nor im-
pose subsidies on their subjects, without the consent of the Three Estates of the
Realm .” 4
There can be no doubt In
De Natura he
writes, “For laws put forth
toms or Statutes .” 10 Given
mon
common by men are
that he classifies the
this limited classificatory
law could only be custom.
He
is
law as custom. all
either
Cus-
scheme, the com-
concerned to praise English
law,
Fortescue Littleton, Readings ,
including
its
customary
law, in
,
and Moots
55
comparison to the laws of other nations.
In a form of argument that certain
common
lawyers in the
first
decades
of the seventeenth century were to find particularly appealing, he claims that English customs are the best because they are the
customs:
most ancient of all
they were not the best, someone in the long succesion of
if
kings would have abolished
them
“for the sake of justice or
by the im-
pulse of caprice.” 11
But though he praises English custom, he does not give
it
pride of
place in respect to statute law. If anything, he holds the opposite view, for he states that statutes.
praising are
He its
is
customs are strengthened when they are reduced to
just as interested in praising English statutory
law as in
customs. English statutes are the best, he says, because “they
made not only by
the prince’s will but by the assent of the whole
realm” and “promulgated by the prudence not of one counsellor nor of a
hundred
There
only, but of is
more than
three hundred chosen men.” 12
nothing in De Laudibus that suggests that Fortescue regards
customary law to be fundamental king or parliament. In
De
in the sense of putting limits
Natiira,
on
either
he does ascribe to the law of nature
the kind of superiority that Alcllwain and
Chrimes think he
ascribes to
custom:
Oh how great and which
all
This law
is
to
to be extolled with
human the
all
praise
is
that law of nature
laws are obedient.
mother of
all
human
law s, and r
if
they degenerate
they deserve not to be called laws.
For we said above that human customs and constitutions are subject to the rules of the law of nature, and having issued aries
do so partake of
its
nature that
if
from
its
bound J
not ratified thereby, such
customs and constitutions deserve not to be called laws, but rather corruptions. 13
Fortescue does not say whether this theoretical proposition
is
to he ap-
common law and statutes and, if so, who would have the authority to do so. What is clear is that he never attributes an equivalent superiority to the common law, even at the level of plied in practice to the English
The Common Law Mind
56
Thomas Littleton
Sir Sir
Thomas
glish law
Temurs has
Littleton’s
book
since Bracton
.
been called the
justly
H Probably written
great
En-
in the third quarter of
summary of English
the fifteenth century, this lucid
first
real
property law
was for three centuries the standard introduction to the study of land law.
Although
1 -
general jurisprudence,
we
draw
are able to
from what he
dential significance his
purpose surely was not to write
Littleton’s
writes,
a
a
work on
few conclusions of jurispru-
most particularly concerning
understanding of the sources of authority for the rules of English
land law. It
be true,
Plucknett says, that cases play a large role in the
as T. F. T.
disposition of the law that Littleton describes. 16 But one
know as
from what he
that
evidence for
This rarity
a
would hardly
writes; although he does occasionally cite a case
proposition that he
is
because
itself is interesting
much
so easily and without fanfare in
medieval Year Books. For example, in
a
advancing, he does so only rarely.
when he does
he does
cite a case
the style frequently found in the
discussion of Estates
upon Con-
dition he notes:
An
of novel disseisin was sometime brought against A.,
assise
pleaded to the case
is
assise.
bound by
.
.
.
Mowbray
the law to
death of his testator, and
and so there was
it is
the sale as soon as he
may after
the
sale,
him; and so by force of the devise he
the profits of the lands to the use of the dead,
found that he took them to
default in him.
recover.
all
Justice, said, the executor in this
found that he refused to make
it is
a default in
was bound to put and
make
,
who
Wherefore
it
own
use,
and so another
was adjudged that the
plaintiff should
his
1
There appears
to be
no
clear reason
handful of instances in which he does so regarding
all
why so,
he cites case authority in the
nor
why he
refrains
the other points of doctrine he advances.
from doing
The
reason for
the widespread absence of case citation cannot be a belief that cases do
not constitute evidence of the law, for on one occasion he sertion by saying: Ill, in a writ
“And
that this
is
the law
you may
see in a plea
an
M.
31
as-
E.
of formedon in the reverter.” 18
Littleton’s citation of cases
is
better understood as an endeavor to
provide evidence of the consuetudo curiae or the ,
bench and
justifies
bar,
common
learning of the
than as an early reliance on the doctrine of binding judi-
Fortescue, Littleton Readings ,
,
and Moots
57
s precedent
cial
19 .
common
of the
This may be seen
— an
law”
in a series of references to “the course
expression that suggests a practice, usage, or
may
understanding that has become established.
It
too, in Littleton’s frequent reference to the
“entendment [understand-
ing] del ley” is
and
in his use
justification of a conclusion
dition”
in the Tenures
is
question were
been given on
now being
decided for the
implication of this passage
issues according to their able; they
own
known
is
been given on
this question.”
many judgments have it is now the law, and
20 .
ideas of what
in this instance
would be reasonable or
“is
now
“because
broader than the
in the
is
common
an issue that he
statute.
desir-
cur-
is
many judgments have
But the judgments establish the law not be-
doctrine of binding judicial precedent but because they show
law that Littleton
cusses the
What
the law.”
what the usage of the courts have been: “usage makes the
If
goods of
that judges are not free to decide legal
must decide according to what
rently the law
a
is
my
time, in
first
plaintiffs take the
and because
this question,
usage makes the law without reason, etc
The
eru-
most unambiguously
stated
the execution themselves. But because so
cause of
common
“un
but in an argument reported in the Year Books:
opinion no judge would decide that the
The
it is
to be.
it
perhaps the clearest of such expressions. Littleton’s association
is
If the
to understand
by asserting that
of the law with the usage of the the court
not
be found,
of similar expressions suggesting that the law
what the judges and practitioners have come
The
arguably
is
common
concerned with explicating
law;
examining law; if
it is
is
it is
later
governed by the
covered by
not understand the
made famous by
common
in his Tenures
is
English law regarding real property.
Nothing that he writes suggests
manner
law.”
Sir
common
a statute,
law,
he dis-
he discusses the
that he idolizes the
Edward Coke. He
common
law
certainly does
law to be superior to statutes either in au-
thority or reason, nor does he suggest that
it
exists
immemorial. Instead, he follows the practice of
unchanged from time
his
contemporaries, ex-
tremely widespread in the reading and moots of the period, of openly recognizing that statutes frequently change the
Tenant
in fee tail
is
common
law:
by force of the statute of Westminster
for before the said statute,
all
II, cap
inheritances were fee simple; for
,
i;
all
the gifts which be specified in that statute were fee simple conditional at the
common
law, as
appeareth by the rehearsal of the same
The Common Law Mind
58
statute.
that
And now by
this statute, tenant in tail
to say, tenant in
is
tail
general and tenant in
two manners,
in
is
tail
special
21 .
common contemporary practice of referstatutory change of a common law rule as an ef-
Littleton does not follow the
ring to the cause of the
remedy a “mischief” or “inconvenience,” but he does occasionally
fort to
“remedy” of the existing
refer to a statutory rule as a
the
common
Also
at the
law.
common
law, before the statute of Gloucester, if tenant
by the curtesy had aliened
was
a
state of affairs at
bar to the heir
.
.
.
in fee with warranty, after his decease this
but
it is
remedied by the same
the warranty of tenant by the curtesy shall be
statute, that
no bar to the heir 22 .
In addition to justifying his conclusions by referring to previous deci-
common understanding or opinion
sions, statutes,
and the
sion, Littleton
sometimes supports
a rule
nience” would otherwise threaten.
He
of the profes-
by asserting that an “inconvediffers considerably
from the
prevailing practice in not alleging potential “mischiefs” to support his
maxim, “the law would sooner
positions. In citing the
than an inconvenience,” he recognizes
gues that
as the
common
between mischiefs
a distinction
and inconveniences, but he does not define the terms
suffer a mischief
23 .
Norman Doe
ar-
lawyers of the period use the terms, “inconve-
nience” involves repugnancy between cases or inconsistency with established practice,
and “mischief”
is
wrong, most usually that of being legally or justly
due
24 .
Doe
associated with the occurence of a left
without
remedy when one
a
arrives at these definitions primarily
is
though
an analysis of the situations in which the terms are used in the fifteenth-
century Year Books, and in the main he
is
persuasive. Littleton’s use of
“inconvenience” can generally be explained in terms of Doe’s analysis, although sometimes
it
may
plausibly be read in terms closer to Doe’s
definition of “mischief.” For example, in his discussion of villenage Lit-
tleton states:
Also,
him
if a villein
be made
as his villein,
and
a secular chaplain, yet his lord
seise his goods, &c.
But
it
may
seemeth, that
and
is
professed, that the lord
take nor seise him, because he
is
dead in
villein enter into religion,
law.
.
.
.
And
lord have an action against the sovereign of the house,
and admitteth
his villein to
so
seise if
may may
the
not the
which taketh
be professed in the same house, without
the license and leave of the lord, and he shall recover his
damages
to
Fortescue, Littleton Readings ,
,
and Moots
59
s the value of the villein. For he which
monk
professed a
is
be taken for term of his natural
shall
life,
monk, and
as a
unless he be de-
railed by the law of holy church. And he is bound by his religion to keep his cloister, &c. And if the lord might take him out of his house, then he should not live as a dead person, nor according to his religion,
Although
which would be inconvenient,
this
passage certainly
nience that would result
if a
may be a
the law’s recognition that a professed a
such
fact that
25 .
read as attributing the inconve-
lord could take or seize one
and enters into religion and becomes
seems to be
Sec
power
would
in the lord
harm
one occasion Littleton closely associates
nience” with
a lack
is
connected with the
interfere with the
gious duties and thus would bring a wrong or
On
professes
monk to an incompatibility with monk is “dead in law,” there also
suggestion that the inconvenience a
who
of reason and, in doing
to the
his use
monk’s
reli-
monk. of “inconve-
seems to have in mind by
so,
“reason” the internal reason or coherence of the law. 26 His use of “reason,” however, tency.
not limited to an attempt to maintain the law’s consis-
is
His most
common
reference to reason
in assessing the validity
is
of some manor, borough, or other local customary rule that diverges
from the general law of the
land.
Such customs have to be evaluated
for
compatibility with reason, but by definition their reason or lack of
it
does not depend upon their agreement with the general law of England. In the absence of established and clearly defined tests for the reason of
such a custom, Littleton seems to resort in some instances to ad hoc
common
a
kind of
sense assessment of the custom’s reasonableness. For ex-
ample, he writes of the custom of gavelkind in the county of Kent, which diverges from the primogeniture of the
there,
common
law, that
where by the custom and use out of the mind of man, the
sues male ought equally to inherit, this custom it
standeth with
as the eldest
valor.
some
son
is,
reason; for every son
and perhaps
will
grow
is
is-
allowable, because
as great a
gentleman
to greater
honor and
is
27
This example
fits
well with Doe’s suggestion that a primary
reason for fifteenth-century sense,” hut
common
what makes good sense
Littleton’s conclusion
is
lawyers
is
meaning of
sofnething like “good
not self evident. 2S
about the the reason of gavelkind seems to be
founded on the commonsense observation throughout human history
6o
The Common Law Mind
V
that virtue or
accomplishment
argument
their birth; his
younger sons may be is
as
is
in children
that gavelkind accords with reason because
honorable or valorous
arguable, however, that his reasoning
moral premise
lated
younger
is
not fixed by the order of
is
supplied
son’s equal valor or
Littleton’s discussion of
— one
as their elder brothers. It
makes sense only
an unarticu-
if
connecting the possibility of
honor with the right to inherit
borough English
also
may
a
land.
be read as making
an attribution of reason on the basis of what might be called good sense, but
too,
it,
may
contain an unarticulated moral premise:
Also, where by the custom called
Borough English,
ough, the youngest son shall inherit
tom son
also stands (if
least
some bor-
in
the tenements, &c., this cus-
all
with some certain reason; because that the youngest
he lack father and mother) because of his younger age,
of
all
his
brethren help himself,
&c
may
29 .
This argument reduces to the claim that the custom that prescribes that the youngest son shall inherit everything
is
reasonable because of his po-
on the moral
tentially greater need. Arguably, this conclusion rests
premise that greater need
The problem these
justifies inheriting everything.
with concluding that Littleton’s attribution of reason in
two examples
rests
on unarticulated moral premises
is
that the
customary rules of inheritance that he declares to be reasonable are consistent with each other (and with the to be reasonable too).
Most
likely,
common
Littleton
made explicit by Christopher St. German tom satisfies the criterion of reason when
God
is
law,
which
its
it is
“neither against the law of reflects standard
principles are quite general (for example,
man) and “cannot be applied great diversity of human
to
affairs,
all
assumed
in the next century, that a cus-
nor the law of reason .” 30 This position
nations,
in-
operating on the theory,
natural law theory, which holds that although natural law all
is
two
is
medieval
common
to
do harm to no
people in the same way because of the
and hence
arises the diversity
of Positive
Law among different peoples .” Further, according to this doctrine, although human law is derived from natural law by reason, reason can31
not deduce from the general principles of natural law rules necessary in particular societies
32 .
all
the detailed
This means that there could be,
consistent with natural law and with reason, a wide variety of schemes
among human St.
German,
societies regarding the inheritance of land. after noting the inconsistent
arrangements found in En-
Fonescue Littleton Readings, and Moots
61
,
,
/*
gland for the inheritance of land (“the lawe of Englande by dyuers cus-
tomes doth sometyme gyue the lande hollye to the eldest sone/some-
tyme
to the
Nor
is
yongest/& sometyme to
there need to labour
much
all”),
remarks:
in these cases, for practically the
whole body of the law consists of cases of lawyers hold that where there
is
and so English
this sort;
any law duly had and ordained for
the disposition of things real, personal or mixed, which law
r
contrary to the law of
binding upon
This
is
all
God
is
not
or the law of reason, then that law
is
that are subject to it.”
perhaps the best way to understand Littleton’s comment, in the
paragraph immediately following his discussjpn of gavelkind and bor-
ough English, nor
will
The
it
that a prescription “if
it
be against reason, this ought not,
be allowed before judges; quia malus usus abolendus est
practical effect of such an understanding of the limitation placed
reason on custom would be that
it
the
a
ates as a limitation
might think
on the
What
validity of
is
how
reason oper-
customs may help explain how he
it still
leaves a large hole in our understanding of
common
against the law of
lawyers assess the reasonableness of
God
and of reason
not beyond controversy, and yet we are given very the lawyers reason about such questions.
Do
is
little
itself certainly
evidence about
they ask themselves,
think of any principle of the law of God or reason that this custom
violates?
Do
able?
derived
two contradictory customs both to meet
possible for
it
Littleton and other
I
is
conflict with those laws.
the test of reason, but
how Can
custom
a
This interpretation of Littleton’s understanding of
custom.
by
higher law; the judges would only have to be persuaded that
custom does not
how
M4
would not have to be proved by de-
duction from the law of God, nature, or reason that
from such
.’
And
if
the answer
is
they ask themselves,
no, do they proclaim the
Can
I
custom reason-
conceive of a plausible scenario in
which these customary rules of inheritance
will
not be completely arbi-
And if the answer is yes, do they proclaim the custom to be reasonable? Or are their conclusions about the reasonableness of customs less reasoned and more intuitive? Such as, I may not be able to define reason but I know it when I see it? Neither Littleton nor the other fifteenthtrary?
century sources provide sufficient information to support
a
confident
answer to such questions, and again we are reminded of the difficulty in fully
understanding the
legal
thought of the medieval
common
lawyers.
62
The Common Law Mind
i?
Readings and Moots Advanced
common
law education in the fifteenth century centered on
the four great Inns of Court. Organized instruction was oral and consisted of readings
and disputations.
3 -
The
readings,
which are analogous
were presented during the two learning vacations
to university lectures,
by persons selected by the benchers from among the utter
We
barristers.
36
have no detailed fifteenth-century description of the readings and
their place in the learning
regimen of the Inns. Our best evidence about
them, apart from surviving manuscripts of the readings, 1540 report of
is
found in the
Thomas Denton, Nicholas Bacon, and Robert Cary
King Henry VIII on
the organization of the Inns of
Court and the
legal
training provided there:
First,
Reader and the Ancients appoint the eldest utter-
the
barrester in continuance, as one that they think
roome
to reade
amongst them openly
Summer-Vacation.
.
.
.
8 of the clock, he that
fore
all
the
shall please
And is
then the
in the
first
day
most able
for that
House during
after Vacation,
the
about
so chosen to reade openly in the Hall be-
company shall reade some one such act, or statute, as him to ground his whole whole Reading on, for all that
Vacation; and that done, doth declare such inconveniences and mischiefs as
were unprovided for and now by the same statute be
amended; and then reciteth certain doubts and questions which he hath devised that
may grow upon
the said statute, and declareth his
judgement therein. That done, one of the younger utter-barresters rehearseth one question propounded by the Reader and doth by
way of argument labour to prove the Readers opinion to be against the law; and after him the rest of the utter-barresters and Readers, one
after the other in their ancienties,
and judgments
in the same;
doe declare their opinions
and then the Reader who did put the
case indeavoreth himself to confute objections laid against to confirm his
own
opinion, after
whom
any be present, declare their opinions.
him and
the judges and serjeants,
And
if
after they have done,
the youngest utter-barrester again rehearseth another case, which
is
ordered as the other was. Thus the Reading ends for that day; and this
manner of Reading and
or thereabouts. 37
to
disputations continue daily two houres,
Fortescue, Littleton, Readings,
From
this description
sitions of the statutes.
quence so that
begun is
may be seen that readings are primarily expoThey normally are organized in a definite seexposed to
is
3s period of study at the Inn.
his
again.
At
63
it
student
a
and Moots
least until the
all
Once
the important statutes during
the sequence
completed,
is
middle of the fifteenth century,
a
it is
reading
not expected to be original:
A lawyer called
upon
do more than
to
for a reading
reflect the
seems not to have been expected
work of
his predecessors
who
the particular reader was.
agreed with the reading and any
we
.
Since the
it
names and arguments of those who
for a hearer to note the
Since
It
.
made little differwas rather more important
reading thus remained substantially the same,
ence
.
new
dis-
pointsj:hat they might make.
are searching not for originality but for evidence of standard
jurisprudential assumptions
among
the fifteenth- century
common
law-
an examination of the readings and disputations should serve
yers,
39
as a
useful supplement to our study of the case reports and treatise literature.
The
fact that the
formal lectures presented
expositions of statutes rather than of the
ported in the Year Books
no similar formal
body of
orderly
tem
suitable for
is
most
at the
Inns of Court are
enormous body of case law
interesting.
So
far as
we know,
re-
there are
lectures that seek to reduce the Year Books’ great, dis-
legal discussions
and debates to an understandable sys-
mastery by students
at the Inns.
A.
W.
Simpson hy-
B.
pothesizes that the readings given as part of the learning exercises at the
may be concerned with
Inns of Chancery least
one of the functions of a Chancery reader was to read year books.” 40
Most
who examine the matter find this suggestion unpersuasive, among other reasons, the contents of the Year Books, concerned
scholars
because as
they are with the niceties of pleading, are too difficult for the kind of
elementary students found Ives writes, even
when
meaning
is still
Books
important for
are is
the Year Books and “that at
is
in the
the law-French text of a yearbook
a proficient lawyer,
One
why
If so, just
the statutes
is
is
as E.
W.
clear, the
not
at the
one must wonder why there
Inns of Court.
One
method of studying reports was
that “the accepted 42
if,
often obscure and mastery of the contents of the Year
no readings on the Year Books
place.”
Inns of Chancery. 41 But
that
is
explanation
to
common-
acceptable for the Year Books but not for
clear.
possibility
is
that the content of the learning exercises in the
The Common Law Mind
64
Inns of Court reveals something fundamental about
how
Book reports — that whatever
lawyers understand the Year
of these documents, they are not understood to reflect
common
the
the interest
a legal
authority
that has to be followed, in the sense that statutory authority has to be
made
followed, and thus they are not
Mastery
central to the curriculum.
of pleading seems to be learned from two principal sources: attendance
where the practice of experts can be observed, and the
at the courts,
mooting
exercises at the Inns,
Common
oral pleading at the
“which mirrored the process of ‘tentative’ Pleas .” 43
The
cases argued at these exer-
We
how
they
were used during learning vacations; in term time, exercises were
also
cises are constructed for pedagogical purposes.
have seen
conducted in the “arguing and debating of cases
after
moting
as is heretofore pre-
used and kept in
after supper,
like
forme
dinner and the
scribed in the Vacation-time .” 44 If the cases that serve as the basis artificial
of the disputations in the Inns are
constructions, designed to raise difficult questions and to train
students “to find the correct procedure to adopt in court,” at least the
members in discussing so-called readers Year Book cases in support of a proposition being
readings themselves, and the cases, occasionally cite
defended
45
It
.
cannot be said that reference to an actual case
method of establishing
cipal
way
correct
common in the
quent
either the
common
law on
a
the prin-
question or the
to read a troublesome statutory passage, but
in these learning exercises as in the court
is
it is
as least as
arguments reported
medieval Year Books. Such citations are considerably more frein the disputations of readers’ cases
readings themselves
sometimes
46
Just as in the Year Books, citations of cases are
.
without even
indefinite,
reign the case was heard.
been adjudged
that,”
has been held in
than in the fifteenth-century
a reference to the
The most common
king in whose
of such locutions
without further identification.
A
is,
variation
some books,” or “That has often been adjudged
books .” 47 The reporter comments, regarding the
last assertion,
“It has is,
in
“It
our
“But he
did not say where. Note.” This, and the fact that most of the case citations in the Inner this
Temple arguments
point in the fifteenth century the expectation
when
a case is cited it will
is
It is
supplied. clear
that
is
specified; as often as not, the regnal
4S
enough
they think they
may be growing
be identified. In the great majority of in-
stances at least the reigning king
year
are identifiable, suggests that at
made by disputants because contentions more persuasive. It is not so
that case citations are
make
their
Fortescue Littleton Readings
-
,
,
clear that a prior case, or even a series of cases,
,
tfW Moots
regarded as
is
a
65
binding
authority:
Therefore
tenant for
if a
life
disseised, the disseisee shall not
is
avoid the lessor in a writ of waste, because the disseisor or the dis-
continue do not hold of the donor, be held of the donor. Yet
may, which It
is
est
But
I
has been held in
it
some books
formedon
that
would not agree with
men nowadays
is
that,
to the contrary.
might
differ
but
it is
some books
lies
avowson
in
and the opinion of the wis-
what has been
to be that
for an
that he
49
cases might occasionally be regarded as a matter,
estate in fee simple can
my mind.
The assumption seems on
no
clearly not the law to
has been said in
gross.
since
said or held in earlier
good evidence of what the law
is
not the same as the law, and on occasion the law
from what
is
reported in the books.
It
might
differ
because
the law has changed (the “nowadays” in the last quoted statement
Or
reflect that conclusion).
it
might
may
because the lawyers and
differ
judges quoted in the Year Books are mistaken about the true state of the law. If the latter
derstanding
is
is
the assertion,
we may properly wonder what
the un-
concerning where the correct law could be found.
The
disputations associated with the readings contain several promising candidates for the repository of the law of England, and in the end
conclude that there the law
One
is
no
to be found or
is
single, universally
how
it is
to be
accepted theory about where
known.
of the most promising candidates
is
the
common,
or established,
learning of the elite bench and bar. This seems to be what it is
argued that despite what
the wisest
port of
a
eruditio ),
men nowadays
contention that
common
is
said in
some
contrary.”
is
common
It is
is
meant when
case reports, “the opinion of
repeatedly asserted, in sup-
learning ( comen erudicion or communis
understanding ( comen entendment ), or
common
ion (comen oppinion or communis oppinio) supports the claim.
adds references to
common
experience and to
dence seems very strong for
a
common
view that the law
is
of communal understanding within the profession. is
not to be entirely clear about what such
like
or
how
it is
created, and
it
may
we may
a
to be
To
opin-
When
one
sayings, the evi-
found
in a
kind
say this, however,
commonality of opinion
suggest the presence of
a
is
wider con-
sensus in the profession than ever existed. 50
We
should not be too quick to entirely dismiss the idea of case au-
The Common Law Mind
66
thority. In
one interesting passage, the reporter of a disputation notes
regard to an assertion by Frowyk: “Query
common
in
amazing, the
this, for it is
opinion being to the contrary. But he said that he knows of au-
thority [auctorite] to support his opinion.”'
!
Here we have the common
opinion of the profession set against alleged authority (evidently case authority).
What
this
means
to the writer
we can only
possible that the notion of case law as authority
part of the fifteenth century.
and the citations of cases
One
is
guess, but
seems
it
incipient in the latter
reading the Year Books of the period,
in the disputations at the Inns, gets the impres-
sion that occasionally a lawyer believes that in citing a case he has settled the matter at issue. This
is
not to suggest that one cannot also find in-
stances of the citation of cases in which the lawyer citing a case uses
merely
common
pears
to have
still
The most widely held view
in.
ap-
been that prior cases constitute evidence of the com-
erudition, but ambiguities regarding case authority
creeping
may
have been
52
Alleging that
a legal rule is a
ground, principle, or maxim appears to
have been an even stronger claim of legal authority than to allege that is
a
is
subject.
opinion held by the court in 10 Edw. IV.”
mon
learning or opinion
For example, Grantham says that “the opinion in 14 Hen. that the writ is not allowable for either of them. That clearly is the
on the
IV is
an example to show what the
as
it
common
two
learning, although the
While references
ideas are closely associated. 53
to principles or grounds are fairly
putations, they are
made
in a
it
summary manner
common
that affords
in the dislittle
basis
for assessing their jurisprudential meaning.'’ 4 For a fuller understanding
common
of the place of maxims or principles in fifteenth-century thought,
we must turn
Fortescue.
A
case
from
Books of the period and to John
to the Year
YB
13
Hen. VII suggests that principles are un-
derstood to be very firmly established Kebell:
And
it
me
seems to
common
that one could
erudition:
impose upon
fee simple the condition that he could not alienate.
a feoffee in
Bryan
ff] inter-
rupted him, and said that they did not wish to hear him argue conceit, because
and E.
W.
is
now,
it is
plainly contrary to our
in a sense, a principle [in
Ives argues that the
and “maxim”
as
law
common
common
maner an principle
]
this
erudition,
V
lawyers sometimes use “erudition”
synonyms. 56 But the case upon which he principally
re-
Fortescue Littleton Readings ,
,
for this claim
lies
seems to support
,
and Moots
67
between the terms
a distinction
rather than an equivalence:
Yet the law as
is
not
an erudicion:
as I
understand in
WTere
the party.
nor erudicion for what you say the party shall only have. I
Ives
have never heard
makes
“maxim.”
his
see
I
The
.
.
.
.
Kebell:
no
T here
is
been held
neither ground
but this has been an erudicion that
.
,
But
this erudicion
of which you speak,
before."
argument by translating basis for
seems to be drawing dicions.
it
.
.
.
.
this case, for this has
doing
erudicion in each instance as
so; instead, Kebell, in his first
between grounds
a distinction
(or
sentence
maxims) and eru-
interpretation of principles as very firmly established erudi-
tions accords with John Fortescue’s
more
detailed explanation of
common lawyers’
use of
about reasoning, describes them
as the
earlier in the century. Fortescue, associating the
maxims with
Aristotle’s teaching
maxims
foundational principles from which legal reasoning must proceed, and
quotes Aristotle for the propositions that force of
argument nor by
for holding
it.”"*
logical demonstrations” but “is its
Quoting
known by own ground
“not
a principle is
Aristotle again, Fortescue asserts that there
could be no arguing with those
who deny principles. The
reason for
this,
apart from the fact that Aristotle says so, seems to be that since principles or
grounds are understood to be the most firmly established points
of the
common erudition of in YB 13 Flen. VII) do
Bryan,
the profession, the judges (for example,
not wish to waste time with an argument
59 that seeks to overturn the existing paradigm.
Though
“erudition”
is
not used as an exact equivalent of “maxim,” one
anonymous argument does use in
“positive law” in precisely the
same sense
which Fortescue uses “maxim”: 1
And
the court said that writs of right, of
[of novel disseisin],
mon
formedon, and other such writs
law, are positive law [ley positif]
available to
There
is
no
;
as
w ere r
[such]
at
assize
com-
and no answer whatsoever
deny them, or to prove why they are writs of
what law provides them, or why '
mort d’ancestor and
their nature
is
is
right, or
such, and so forth.
answer because they are positive law which can-
not be denied. But in other writs, which are provided by statute,
one may make answer and have the benefit of denying and disproving
them
in cases
where they are not warranted by the
statute. It
is
The Common Law Mind
68
upon formedon upon
the same
because
a record,
not positive
it is
law but special or temporal law 60 .
This
most unusual usage and turns on
a
is
its
and early modern usage of the term “positive that
which
is
found
in Stowell
v.
Lord Zouch
a
head the normal medieval law.”
The normal
few decades
later:
usage
is
“Acts of
Parliament are laws positive .” 61 Examples such as this one, demonstrably
out of the mainstream of legal historian to
there
from
a small
a
reminder to the
sample of usages of terms, particularly
no trustworthy way
is
law usage, serve as
be cautious and modest in his efforts to draw jurispru-
dential inferences
when
common
to check the representativeness of a
particular usage. Justifications of legal assertions are occasionally based
that the rule
more commonly, ever, the Statute
their authority
is
common
law.”
Even
attributed to usager “Because,
how-
established “by the course of the
is
of Marlborough has been confirmed in another form,
and the law has always been used to the contrary,
makes
a
law.” 62
It is
this
usage makes
unlikely that these expressions reflect a conceptual-
ization of legal authority as is
on the claim
customary
in character, unless that
custom
understood in terms of the accumulated experience and learning of
the profession.
In addition to explanations of their conclusions in terms of prior cases,
common
erudition or opinion, maxims, and
common
usage — all
of which arguably are associated with the developed consensus of the profession on an issue rule
— the
lawyers sometimes argue that a different
would offend against reason or produce
legal rule
harm
is
is
of
a different
claim depends if so,
A
claim that a
required by reason, violates reason, or produces or avoids a character from one that relies on a correct repro-
duction of accepted opinion.
and,
a mischief.
upon whether
there
how accurately it is
essentially factual in nature.
The
persuasiveness of the latter sort of is
an accepted opinion on the subject
mirrored by the asserted
Claims that
a
mischief or
rule.
The
harm
will
claim
is
be suf-
fered because of, or in the absence of, a rule are highly fact-dependent
but also require an assessment of whether the mischief
Claims that the rule
at issue
is
some normative
likely to occur.
either reasonable or contrary to reason
require a different kind of evaluation the rule against
is
— one
that depends
upon
testing
standard. Such a standard could be one
that merely seeks to maintain a kind of doctrinal order and coherence in
Fortescue, Littleton Readings
,
,
the law,
it
could be as amorphous as an appeal to
could be one that,
ported from
kind of claim
and moots. all
is
It is
law. It
is
common
69
sense, or
it
enforce moral norms im-
at least implicitly, seeks to
system outside the
a
and Moots
not always possible
tell
what
being made in the references to reason in the readings clear that
no
single conception of reason runs
through
the references^
An
assertion of lack of reason that seems to appeal to the felt need for
maintaining
a rational
consistency in the law
is
found in an argument
made by Thomas Kebell in response to the question, Three joint tenants make a lease for life reserving the rent to one of them: is that reservation good or not? Kebell argues
There
is
in the affirmative, saying in part:
also another reason, for a gift in tail
tenants, reserving the rent to
reserved were to have
it
one of them,
if
made by
the one to
as reserved, as in the case
of
three joint
whom
a lease for life,
whom
then the tenant [would hold] by two services: of the one to the reservation
other two to
is
made by
virtue of the reservation, and also of the
whom no rent is reserved,
hold over, which
is
against reason [quell nest
on the same
is
of the creation of an “inconvenience,” as
injustice
as
they
lack of reason
made
gift,
which
is
my raw?]. 63
This sort of assertion of lack of reason
that the point being
by the same services
another kind of tenure, and so the land would be
held by several services and tenures
Sometimes
it is
is
is
sometimes expressed
we have
that the offending rule a
terms
seen.
asserted in contexts that
being done. For example
in
make
would
it
appear
result in an
lawyer argues, “Therefore,
if
he has
had the punishment and done that for which the action was brought against
him
it is
that ought to be
not reson that he should remain in prison for something
done by someone
else .”
64
The
point of this use of reason
seems to be broader than the idea underlying the assertion sometimes
made that a particular rule would result in a mischief; it seems to be more closely analogous to a notion of justice or desert 65 This is perhaps seen more clearly in an argument made in response to a Middle Temple .
hypothetical question: “If the aunt recovered the place wasted, then the niece would have been able to enter with the aunt and hold in
and
it
would be against reason
where she had no
Doe
loss .”
common,
for the law to give her such an advantage
66
suggests that the
common
lawyers’ use of “reason” has things in
The Common Law Mind
7°
common with
the iustitia of the medieval theologians and civil and canon
lawyers, although the concepts are not identical correct, with the qualification that
67 .
This seems essentially
some of the common
lawyers’ usages
of reason address concerns that overlap with those of iustitia but some do not. Certainly, the lawyers in the last
two examples from the Inns’ learn-
ing exercises appear to be making the point, by alleging a lack of reason, that
someone
that
is
is
being treated unfairly — either by being given something
undeserved or by being compelled to bear an unmerited burden.
This usage of “reason” seems very close to the conception of widespread in medieval theory, son,” used in this sense, in
for a rule
mischief than to what they itself (for
rendering to each his due
seems closer to what the
mind when they argue
word “reason”
as the
common
on the ground
mean on
that
it
justice,
68 .
“Rea-
lawyers have
would avoid
a
other occasions by the use of the
example, the maintenance of intellectual consis-
tency in the law).
The readings and arguments at the Inns of Court suggest that a lawyer who wishes to claim that a particular rule or interpretation is or is not the law has a variety of proofs at his disposal: he could allege a previous
court decision, claim that his view or opinion, quote
a
is
is
of law
arranged in
a
the law, and
to a situa-
What we do
on one occasion
said or decided in an earlier case
lawyer seems to suggest that
a
it is
what reason requires and what the law requires might
impression created by
disputations
is
a series
not
is
conceiv-
differ
69
.
of statements in the readings and
that previous cases will be
erudition or by maxims. it
opposes an outcome.
erudition
heirarchy of authority. Occasionally a speaker ac-
knowledges that what has been
The
common
any grand theoretical statement in which each of the sources
not find
able that
with
maxim, assign mischief or inconvenience
tion, or assert that reason supports or
is
in accord
overcome by present
common
We have seen in our discussion of Littleton that
was an established principle that “the law
will
sooner suffer
a
mischief
than an inconvenience.” Although there might be considerable debate over what a particular statutory provision means, there seems to have
been universal agreement that ing and import
is
if
there
is
a statute
on
a subject its
mean-
What we cannot tell from the available how the lawyers of the period understand
controlling.
fifteenth-century evidence
is
the authoritative weight of reason in comparison with other recognized
sources of law.
CHAPTER FOUR
The
Early Sixteenth Century Christopher
F
ollowing fortescue, English law by
a
death. St.
German,
German
the next explicitly theoretical discussion of
common
German’s Doctor and
St.
lawyer
is
to be
found
in
Christopher
St.
Student, published half a century after Fortescue’s
a barrister
of the Inner Temple, was well read in the
canon law and medieval philosophy and theology. Doctor and Student consists of
the
two dialogues between
common law. The
first
was published in English
a
doctor of divinity and
student of
a
dialogue appeared in Latin in 1523; the second
The
in 1530.
dialogues were not printed to-
German intended that they together should make up one coherent work. Our concern here is primarily with the first dialogue, which, as St. German gether until after
tells
St.
German’s death, and
us in his prologue, “shows
it is
doubtful that
what are the principles or grounds of the
laws of England, and how conscience ought in
many
cases to be fanned in ac-
cordance with those same principles and grounds.” St.
St.
German’s treatment of English law
is
1
only understandable in the
context of his general jurisprudence. This general jurisprudence
out largely by the doctor, who, in an exposition that owes
much
set
is
to the 1
schoolmen, Gerson, and the canon lawyers,. divides law into four kinds: law eternal, the law of nature (“the which as
them
that be learnyd in the law of
I
haue heard saye
is
called
by
England the lawe of reason”), the law
of God, and the law of men. 2
Law eternal the doctor describes God — the wisdom by which God good end. This law eternal all
other laws and because
is
all
God shows
supreme wisdom of the law of
wills that all things
called the first law because
he guided to it
other laws are derived from
except the blessed souls that see
law eternal, but
as the
as
God
as
is
existed before it (9).
No man
entirely
know
this
necessary to man.
Man
has
face to face
much
may
a
71
The Common Law Mind
72
knowledge of eternal law
known
Man
way
known
man by the
is
called the law of reason (or nature).
is
God.
Finally, eternal law
may be shown
order of a prince or of a secondary governor, and then
an ambiguity in England.”
man
it is
(n).
St.
When
When
used in connection with eternal law of,
it
appears to refer
and to the ultimate authority
it
seems to signify only the means by which
know the ultimate law. The law of nature, according
ways — generally and
specially.
by nature to
Considered
all
men
may be understood in two Considered generally, k refers to certain
living creatures, reasonable
specially, the
contrary to
grounded
him by it is
law of nature
is
the natural light of reason.
and unreason-
the knowledge of the
in this law, including the law of
The
will of
Any
man and
statute or
custom
void (13-19). All other laws except the law eternal are
as a certain law, given
them the
can come
to the doctor,
eternal law in a rational creature, written in the heart of every
revealed to
English
for,
used in reference to the three other kinds of law identified
by the doctor,
rules given
is
German’s use of the phrase “grounds of the laws of
both to the ultimate source
able.
and when
evident from the doctor’s exposition up to this point that there
It is
to
light of natural reason,
the eternal law through “heavenly revelation,” and the
called the law of
called the law of
laws.
by the
the eternal law
knows
also
law so to
this
first
God
God, which the doctor
defines
by revelation to reasonable creatures, showing
(21).
law of man, or positive law,
is
derived by reason as necessarily and
probably following the law of reason and the law of God; every well-
made
positive law contains
of the law of
The
God
something of the law of reason (nature) and
3
(27).
doctor concludes his exposition by saying that he has shown the
general grounds of the law of England, on which
based the
if it
more
Where
all
English law must be
be good law, and then he invites the student to explain to him particular grounds of English law
(31).
Fortescue finds three grounds of the law of England,
man’s student finds
six:
the law of reason, the law of
toms, maxims, particular customs, and statutes. signs the law of reason as the
first
St.
God, general
Of these,
Gercus-
the student as-
and principal ground of the law of
England: It is
not vsed amonge them that be lernyd in the lawes of Englande
to reason
what thynge
is
commandyd
or prohybyt by the lawe of
The Early Sixteenth Century nature and what not: but this
maner:
as
all
the resonynge in that behalfe
when anythyng
is
in the law of
vnder
groundyd vpon the lawe of nature:
they say that reason wyll that such a thyng be don.
Those learned
is
73
(31, 33)
England, he continues, divide the law of
reason into the law of reason primary and the law of reason secondary.
The law of reason primary is commanded or prohibited by without the addition to
it
so called “because the things which are that law are derived
of any other law”
(33).
from reason
For example,
murder, perjury, deceit, and the breaking of the peace.
secondary
prohibits
law of reason
divided into two branches, secondary reason general
is itself
and secondary reason “is
The
it
alone,
The
particular.
law of secondary reason general
groundyd and deryued of that generall l^we or generll custome of
proprety whereby goodis mouable and vnmouable be brought in to certayne propretye so that euery
man may knowe
law of reason secondary particular
“is that
his
owne
lawe that
is
ordeyned and held
in this
son secondary particular because only held for law in
The
realme”
(35). It is called
reason
its
a particular realm,
is
all
derived of a law that
maxims of
the law of the realm
law of reason, but the student does not think that this
with such
he
a claim,
says, lies in the fact that
reason secondary particular
is
difficult to
come
is
the realm) that
provable by the
is so.
'The problem
knowledge of the law of by, derived as
it is
from
To deduce secondary reason from them is not because much depends upon the manner and form of English legal
maxims of English easy
is
the law of rea-
so full of such secondary rea-
sons (derived out of the general customs and that
maxymes &
and in no other.
student admits that English law
some men have affirmed
is
The
thynge.”
dyryuyed vpon
dyuers customes general and pertyculer and of dyuers statutes
a
argumentation
law.
(37).
We
return to this discussion of the relation of rea-
son to English law when we come to
St.
Germans
discussion of general
customs and maxims. T he law of God
One must assume that it holds the same meaning for him as it does for the doctor. Any statute or general custom directly against the law of God the student holds to be void
(41).
is
not defined by the student.
General customs, the student’s third ground of English
law,
are defined as those
of olde tyme vsed through
all
the realme: which haue
and approuyd by our soveraygne lorde the kynge and
ben acceptyd his
progeny-
The Common Law Mind
74
tours and
theyr subgettes.
all
And
because the sayd customes be
neyther agaynst the lawe of god not the lawe of reason alwaye taken to be good and necessarye for the
&
haue ben
common welth of all
the realme. Therfore they haue optayned the strengthe of a lawe in
so
moche
them doth agaynst Iustyce and
that he that doth agaynst
And these be tho customes that proprely be called the common lawe. And it shall alwaye be determined by the Iustyces whether
law.
there be any suche law or generall custome as alleged, or not and
not by
The
.xii.
men.
(45, 47)
fourth ground of English law, says the student, “standyth in
maxymes realme” (57). The
dyuers pryncyples that be called by those learned in the lawe the which haue ben alwayes taken for law in this identification of
uct of
St.
maxims
ground of law
is
seen as the prod-
German’s confusion of the formal and material sources of the
law: Stanley
Chrimes and Stephan
concluding that there rate
as a separate
is little
Siegel are not entirely mistaken in
reason for designating maxims as a sepa-
ground from general customs. 4 The student himself
says that
all
maxims of English law “might be conveniently numbered among the said general customs of the realm” and distinguishes maxims from customs on the ground that while customs
are
known
generally throughout
maxims
the realm by the unlearned as well as the learned,
only in the king’s courts or law”-
Chrimes contends
of maxims are accurate. St.
all
among them
that the
numerous examples
known by
— very
from the standpoint of
difficult to see the utility
German
is
common
St.
gives
not quite law rules,
arcane and technical rules
the general public. All the same, while
be analytically useful to distinguish maxims law,
German
St.
pithy statements of general customs. This
but those rules are of a particular type
“known
that take great study in the
German’s examples are statements of
not likely to be
are
as a subclass
it
of customary
German’s general jurisprudence,
of assigning them as
a
may it is
separate ground. 6 St.
speaks of customs and maxims interchangeably in his discus-
sion of the imperfect participation of customs and
maxims
in the law of
reason, and this presents a problem in relation to the authority of these
grounds
The
as law.
fifth
ground of English
law, the student says,
is
particular cus-
toms. These differ jurisprudentially from general customs only in the fact that their jurisdiction
is
geographically limited.
The Early Sixteenth Century
Most of
75
the law of England, according to the student, depends
Customs provide not only
general customs or maxims.
large part of the substantive and procedural law of basis of authority for
all
the content of a
England but
the king’s courts. Although
some
also the
institution of the courts or that they should exist at
custom of the realm upon which
“all
is
the
The
all.
ground and beginning” of the
king’s courts depends “is of so high authority that the said courts
may
their authorities
Parliament”
Indeed, no general customs of the realm that have ob-
(47).
student
may
be changed without Parliament (49).
very careful to maintain that even the customs that
is
have obtained the strength of a law cannot be proved only by reason
How
57).
can
it
and
not be altered and their names changed without
tained the force of law
The
not
England” that provides either for
statute nor law written in the laws of first
and
statutes
books of English law mention the authority of such courts, “there
the
upon
(55,
be proved by reason, he argues by way of example, that
only the eldest son
may inherit at all, and
ters shall inherit the land? In
there
if
is
no son,
all
the daugh-
view of this imperfect connection between
made
general customs and reason, a statute
against general
custom
is
valid law (57).
There
is
evidence that
German
St.
recognizes that he has created a
theoretical predicament for himself concerning the source of authority
of general customs.
He
twice approaches this problem — once in his dis-
cussion of general customs and once in his treatment of
never satisfactorily resolves tent that any law
is
In
it.
entitled to the
St.
maxims — but
German’s jurisprudence, to the ex-
name
“law,”
derived from God’s will — the eternal law.
it
must be grounded
God makes
in or
his eternal law
man through three agencies: reason, revelation, and the order of a prince (11). The student assents to the doctor’s statement that the law of man — customs, maxims, and statutes — “is deryuyed by reason as known
a
&
to
thinge whiche
is
necessaryly
of the lawe of god”
&
probably folowyng of the lawe of reason
But the student also says that many English
(27).
customs cannot be proved only by reason to have the strength of (57).
not
The most important
a
law of reason but
a
law of England, the law of property,
greatest part of the law of
name
The England may be
law of custom.
problem, then,
is
is
a
law
itself
how
the
said to be entitled to the
“law.”
This
S is
not
a
new problem
and Fortescue are
all
in
English jurisprudence. Glanvil, Bracton,
concerned with establishing the authority of En-
The Common Law Mind
76 glish
customs
For them, however, the primary problem lay in the
as law.
was largely unwritten,
fact that English law
prince. For St. difficulty lies
when
England, following the Corpus
legal culture outside tinian, primarily
time
at a
European
the
luris Civilis
of Jus-
conceived of law as written and promulgated by the
German
the problem
is
not in being able to make
different
and more
a plausible case for
difficult.
The
unwritten law
but also in maintaining the coherence of the whole jurisprudential scheme,
which
he, uniquely
among common
nub of the problem
lies in
general customs and
The doctor
lawyers, sets out in great detail.
the question of
maxims — might be
how
The
the bulk of English law —
tied to the eternal law.
brings up the problem in a question directed to the
student: I
pray thee show
me by what
authority
is it
proved in the laws of
England that the cases of general customs of the realm
.
.
.
and such
other which thou callest maxims ought not to be denied
.
.
.
for
since they cannot be proved by reason as thou agreest thyself they
cannot, they
some
may
be denied
as lightly
as affirmed unless there
be
statute or other sufficient sufficient authority to approve
them. (69)
The
student’s response does not directly answer the doctor’s question.
Instead,
it
consists of an
argument that many of the customs and maxims
of English law are so well
known
that
it is
writing, and those that are less widely
not necessary for them to be in
known among
may
the people
be
known partly by the law of reason:
&
gland called years and terms in the king’s courts
and
partly by the books of the laws of En-
partly by divers records remaining
&
in his treasury ...
&
also
by divers statutes
wherein [many of] the said customs and maxims be
oft recited. (69,
7 1)
This
is
not
a
convincing answer to the doctor’s question, which assumes
that unless customs can be proved
some “other fact that
sufficient authority.”
What
is
not demonstrated
is
why
the
customs are widely known, or that some of them may be found
in certain books,
them
by reason they have to be proved by
as law.
may be
What is
regarded as “sufficient authority” to establish
needed
custom to the eternal
law.
is
some theory connecting
these facts about
The Early Sixteenth Century
when
Fortescue,
77
faced with the problem of setting forth the grounds
for the legitimization of custom, argues that
through
succession of five
a
nations “the realm has been continuously ruled by the same customs as is
now, customs which,
would have changed
if
they had not been the best, some of those kings
for the sake of justice or
and totally abolished them.”*
by the impulse of caprice,
G. A. Pocock reads
J.
argument of
this
we now
Fortescue’s as an attempt to deal with the very problem that St.
it
find
faced with — the Aristotelian problem of getting from ab-
German
stract universal propositions to particular rules for the resolution of
concrete
human
problems. 9
From
universal propositions reason can de-
duce further propositions, but only abstract universal can be deduced
from abstract
universals. Plato’s question remains:
be made to
the particular? Aristotle’s answef
fit
is
How may the
his
to be
done by
suggests, in
making
that
means of “common experience.” Fortescue, Pocock
it is
argument concerning the antiquity of English customs
variation of Aristotle’s appeal to
common
number of men whose experience firming of
a particular rule,
rational in the sense that
natural law.
The
making
a
higher the
has gone into the making and conis
consonant with the abstract universals of
it is
deduced, from the fact that
If
experience.
is
the greater the probability that that rule
The consonance
proved from so
general
of English custom
may be
inferred, but not
has survived so long and has been ap-
it
many men.
Fortescue intends his argument about the antiquity of English cus-
toms to be an Aristotelian resolution of the problem of universals and
German, who knows De Laudibus gives no indication Fortescue that way or finds the argument from antiquity
particulars, St.
that he reads
,
useful for tying the
common
law to the eternal law.
St.
German
uses
“the olde custome of the realme” and “the ancient custome of the
realme” as synonyms for the
common
law, but
he makes no attempt to
common law. 10 Inof the common law,
develop any theory concerning the antiquity of the deed, he shows no interest at
even If
if
he does describe
it
all
as “olde
in the antiquity
custom.”
general customs are not immemorial for St.
they immutable. This the law of reason.
is
German,
neither are
so because they do not exactly correspond with
A statute
made agaynst suche
[general]
customes
is
perfectly valid
and ought
to be obseruid as law (because they be not merely the lawe of rea-
78
The Common Law Mind
*
And
son.)
certain
that there
it is
reason that could be changed. there
no
is
is .
.
.
not,
and never has been
And
it is
And
holden for lawe.)
therefore after
lawe: (ne
theym
why
them
may
be thought
a little
setting out a universal
they shuld be
the only and
is
in that behalfe. (57)
many pages
strange that after devoting so
scheme of law
to
beginning with
in great detail,
and working downward to the particular human laws of En-
God’s
will
gland,
when
St.
German
gets to the
ground upon which, he
pendyth moste part of the lawe of this realme” thority as law only by saying, in effect, that offers
begyn-
that be lernyd in the
lawes of the realme: the old custome of the realme
suffycyent auctorytie to
law of
to be vnderstande that
statute or other written law that treateth of the
nyng of the sayd customes of English
It
a
no suggestion
why
as to
(47),
he can justify
it is its
this justification
suasive, except that those learned in the law of
says, “de-
own
its
au-
authority.
He
should be thought per-
England believe
it.
Unlike
Coke, he makes no argument about the importance of giving weight to the opinions of a succession of learned men. that he
is
is
tempted to conclude
stumped by the problem of showing how, within
dential scheme, the
The
One
sixth
and
common
final
his jurispru-
name of law. ground of English law named by the student is law
is
entitled to the
that
of
dyuers statutes made by our soueraygne lorde the kynge
&
hys pro-
genytours and by the lordes spyrytuell and temporall and the com-
mons of
the whole realme in dyuers Parlyamentis in such cases
where the lawe of reason the lawe of good customes maxymes neother groundes of the lawe of England semyed not to be suffycyent
For
St.
(to
punish euyll
German,
natural law; they
men and
to reward
good men).
(73)
do not merely declare existing customary or
statutes
make new
to be superior to custom: “a
law.
Furthermore, he explicitly holds statutes
custom
in this realm prevaileth not against a
statute as to the law” (163).
There
common tion
is
evidence that
German’s professional colleagues hold the
St.
law in higher esteem than he does. In
a tract entitled
A
Replica-
of a Seiyaunte at the Laws of England, written anonymously as a re-
sponse to Doctor and Student and particularly against ,
St.
German’s sug-
The Early Sixteenth Century gestion that writs of subpoena and
from the chancery that
no
relief
thor argues,
is
a serious
problem
is
common
law.
common In the
1
law,
first
it is
argued
place, the au-
German’s student himself has “righte well shewede howe
St.
the lawe of Englande
This
of conscience might be obtained
to mitigate the rigor of the
needed from the
is
bills
79
groundede upon the lawe of reason”
is
overestimation of
St.
German’s accomplishments. The
common
not any defect in the
(Rep. 99).
law but
a lack
of knowledge on
the part of the chancellor “of the goodnes of the lawes of the realme” (Rep. 101). is
The
chancellor
not lernede in the lawes of the realme, for
when suche
a bill
is
hym to be a matier of grete conreformation. And tlje matier yn the bill ap-
putte unto hym, yt apperithe to science and requyrethe
hym, because
perithe so to
that he
ferre
is
from the understanding
and the knowledge of the lawe of the realme, and the goodnes therof.
the
But
if
he drawe nere to the knowledge and understanding of
commen
perfite
may cumme
lawe of the realme, so that he
knowledge and goodnes of yt, he
matier conteynede in the
him
putte to
bill
shall well
in the
to the
perceyve that the
chauncerye
is
no
matier to be refourmede there. (Rep. 102) In an argument reminiscent of Fortescue and that foreshadows Coke,
wisdom of
the sergeant contends that the
than the discretion of one man, even the virtues of
good law
is
its
if
the
that
common
man
law
is
chancellor.
is
greater
One
certainty, but “if the subgiettes of
of
any
realme shalbe compellede to leve the law of the Realme, and be ordered
by the discretion of oon man, what thing may be more unknowen or
more uncertayn?” single
man, even
if
sumes much more
common
law,”
(Rep. 101). If the law
that
man
is
1531, St.
cerning
V/i'its
common
wiser than the discretion of a
the chancellory St.
German’s student pre-
in thinking that his “conceit
and leaving “the
common
goodnes, ne of no reputacion” (Rep. In
is
German
lawe as
is it
1
were
a
than the
thing of no
103).
responds to the Replication in
of Subpoena.
far better
A
Little Treatise
Con-
Regarding the sergeant’s argument that the
law has the advantage over the discretion of the chancellor in
respect to certainty,
St.
German
asserts that in fact the law of
God
and
the law of reason, which are to be the grounds of the chancellor’s decrees, “are
moche more evydente and
apparaunte* to gyve Jugemente
The Common Law Mind
8o
upon then the
realmeT
1
simply
It is
lor s decrees will
bound
of
he contends, to suggest that the chancel-
false,
be uncertain because they are based on the unbridled
discretion and conscience of one is
summe customes
maximes, and
ar the generall grounds,
to follow
is a
man,
for the conscience the chancellor
conscience “groundede upon the lawe of God, and
the lawe of reason, and the law of the realm not contrary to the saide
lawes of
realm there
God
nor to ye lawe of reason.” Even
if
one takes the law of the
law grounded upon the law of reason and the law of God,
as a
an imperfect correspondence between the law of England
still is
and the higher laws, for the English law
remedy when he has
a right
not always give
will
a
man
a
14 .
Equity and Conscience The
ancient Greeks noticed that there was a problem with law and pro-
posed
means of dealing with
epieikeia as a
epieikeia
orates
:
justice requires
on
All law
fundamental idea of
expressed by Plato in the Statesman legal generalizations are
is
never adequate to take into account
and thus
A
it.
this idea in a
some supplement
famous passage
some
universal, but about
is
circumstances and contingencies,
all
to legal rules.
1
'
Aristotle elab-
in his Nico?nachean Ethics:
things
not possible to make
it is
a universal
statement which shall be correct. In those cases, then, in
which
necessary to speak universally, but not possible to do so
it is
though
correctly, the law takes the usual case,
the possibility of error. is
And
none the
not ignorant of
less correct; for the
error
not in the law nor in the legislator but in the very nature of the
thing.
which
.
.
is
When
.
the law speaks universally, and a case arises
not covered by the universal statement, then
where the
legislator failed us
correct the omission.
.
.
correction of law where fact, this is the
reason
about some things is
it is
it is
needed. For
nite, like the
it is
when
.
And it is
why
all
it is
on
it
right
and has erred by oversimplicity, to this
is
the nature of the equitable, a
defective
owing
to
its
universality. In
things are not determined by law, that
impossible to lay
the thing
is
down
a law, so that a
indefinite, the rule
is
decree
also indefi-
leaden rule used in making the Lesbian moulding; the
rule adapts itself to the shape of the stone
too the decree
is
adapted to the facts
16 .
and
is
not
rigid,
and so
The Early Sixteenth Century Aristotle’s point
very nature
it
that
is
no matter how carefully
must be written
words of the
it
with
drawn, by
some
its
cases pre-
text will not resolve. In
,
,
made
it
a
crime to injure
a
weapon, and of necessity that law spoke in general terms for
a
would take
make
a lifetime to
of weapons with which
man
in
is
time in his Rhetoric Aristotle illustrates
epieikeia this
the difficulty with an example: Athenian law
man
This
in general terms.
sents a difficulty that resort to the
another passage on
a statute
81
it
of
a list
the different sizes and shapes
all
would be possible to
with nothing more than
inflict
wounds. Suppose
a
ring strikes another and injures
a finger
him? According to the words of the law he apparently would be guilty of the crime. Equity, says Aristotle, would correct the law to achieve the
correct result, namely, that such an actor would be innocent of the crime
*
of injuring with a weapon.
Aristotle here identifies a fundamental conceptual and practical prob-
lem with attempts
What
is
at a literal interpretation
of authoritative legal
needed in cases in which the law speaks
means by which
it
may be
decided
how
terms
in general
the general provision
texts.
is
is a
to be ap-
plied to the wide variety of particular circumstances presented in actual cases.
Unless
it
can be shown that such
a
means
exists,
much
of the cer-
tainty and predictability that constitutes an important part of the rationale for the existence of law at
Aristotle
is
interested in the
would appear to be unattainable.
all
problem of whether the particular
facts
of
an individual case could and should be subsumed under the law’s state-
ment of a general rule, not just as a technical problem of legal reasoning and decision making but because justice requires some rather subtle discriminations between the facts presented by different cases. justice into legal justice tice that
about is
all
and equity; equity
goes beyond the written law.
how
a
judge
is
to determine
what
1
is
He
the particular kind of jus-
Unfortunately, he
it is
divides
unclear
is
that equity requires
employed to make subtle distinctions between
when
it
different sets of facts,
of which arguably are covered by the general words of the law. Fol-
lowing
his discussion in the Rhetoric
of the hypothetical case of injury by
finger ring, he provides several aphoristic statements of the require-
ments of equity, not The second kind fects of a uity;
all
of which have
[of right
common
underlying principles:
and wrong conduct] makes up for the de-
community’s written code of law. This isywhat we
people regard
it
as just;
goes beyond the written
law.
it is, .
.
.
call
in fact, the sort of justice
eq-
which
Equity must be applied to forgiv-
The Common Law Mind
82
able actions;
and
it
must make us distinguish between criminal
acts
on the one hand, and errors of judgment, or misfortunes, on the other.
.
.
Equity bids us to be merciful to the weakness of human
.
nature; to think less about the laws than about the
them, and
man who framed
about what he said than about what he meant; not to
less
much
consider the actions of the accused so
much
as his intentions,
nor
ber benefits rather than injuries ... to be patient
rememwhen we are
— for
an arbitrator
this or that detail so
wronged
this
as if
it is
story. ... It bids us
judge by the strict law
a case, a
treatment of equity lacks in coherence
Some medieval jurists,
fertility.
whole
... to prefer arbitration to litigation
goes by the equity of
What
as the
nothing more than
law; others focus
18 .
it
makes up
for in
citing Aristotle as authority, treat equity
a technical
means of
on what we may loosely
concentrate on equity as mercy for
filling
lacunae in the
call equity^as-fairness.
human
Some
weakness, while others see
the primary function of equity to be to emphasize a legislator’s intentions over his words.
Some of Aristotle’s conceptions of equity are common in ancient Roman law. They appear to have been imported into Roman legal thought through the
Roman
at least
rhetoricians.
two intermediaries, the Stoic philosphers and
The
rhetoricians were
much more
interested in
developing a wide variety of arguments about interpretation, which
might be used by advocates terpretation.
on both cero’s
They were
sides of
De
in legal cases, than a scientific theory of in-
pragmatists,
any question.
Inventions,
which
is
who
taught their students to argue
We see this most clearly in works like Ci-
a slight
reworking of a textbook of rhetoric
widely used in the time of his youth. In De Inventions noting that con,
troversy often arises between those defending the letter and those de-
fending intent, Cicero presents
a series
who
a
have the task of persuading
of arguments useful to speakers
judge to adopt
a strict,
or
literal,
read-
ing of a legal text. Then, playing no favorites, he sets forth corresponding arguments useful to speakers table, interpretation
The there
who need
to argue for a freer, or equi-
19 .
rhetoricians were primarily interested in forensic advocacy, and
is little
evidence that they preferred one set of arguments about in-
terpretation to the other.
The Roman
jurists,
ated their arguments, soon
came
one side or the other
to take
however,
who
appropriin
dead se-
riousness, and this tendency
arguments compose
cians’
a
The Early Sixteenth Century
83
The
rhetori-
continues
still
among
jurists.
major part of the arsenals of both camps
our current disputes over approaches to the interpretation of legal
To
suggest that the rhetoricians were
advocacy than in jurisprudence
more
in
texts.
interested in techniques of
not to say that their arguments do not
is
contain points that deserve to be taken very seriously by legal theorists.
Many
of the rhetoricians’ standard arguments in favor of
a freer inter-
men-
pretation take into account problems with strict interpretation
tioned by Aristotle in his discussion of equity, and their arguments in
support of
strict interpretation identify serious
tation that
is
controlled by considerations of equity.
minor declamations contains
a
skillful
purpose [rationem] of
*
mean what
it
says.
pernicious. For
in laws to find
what
.
.
.
Before
this particular statute [legum ]
one remark to make to the court, that is
is
just,
if
this
the court
what
is
when it
always properly seeking
is
lives.
and
is fitting,
may have been
be, a definite
minds
a
settle
in different ways,
with certainty what
form of law was established
That form the authors of statutes expressed
if
what
equitable, and
justice appealed to different
was therefore impossible to
ought to
have just this
the law was nothing but a kind of simple [nudam] justice.
But because
and
examine the
I I
,
It
kind of so-called inter-
then statutes are completely superfluous. There time
of Quintilian’s
advocates would have us “interpret” this statute.
does not, they claim,
pretation
One
powerful statement of the problem with
equitable interpretation:
Today
problems with interpre-
everybody
is
allowed to change
it
to govern our
in explicit words:
and pervert
purposes, the whole purpose and force of the law
it
is
it
to his
own
torn away. 20
Several themes in this short oration have been repeated time and again
over the centuries. Perhaps central
mary purpose of law our
lives
is
is
the idea that a pri-
to provide a sure, predictable standard for living
and doing business
in society.
by the use of written laws expressed fail as
among them
Such certainty
in explicit words.
is
to be achieved
Equity and
justice
guides to interpretation because they “appeal to different minds in
different ways.” 21
For the past two thousand years there have been of
jurists
who
a substantial
number
have thought this line of reasoning compelling, and
easy enough to see
why
this
is so.
Whether or not we
it is
believe that there
The Common Law Mind
84
and equity, our history and experi-
exist universal principles of justice
ence teach us that if
having
a predictable
tions against
provide
men
is
not agree about what they
But the case for preferring the
much
letter
of the writ-
of its compulsion unless
be shown that certainty and predictability are attainable by such ism. Aristotle fundamentally
and unless
a
is
possible.
means
sistency decide
exists
how
So
then justice and equity are unlikely to
us,
ten law to an unwritten equity loses
terminate text
are.
standard to measure our anticipated future ac-
important to
consistently.
it
will frequently
undermines the idea that
The
a
it
can
literal-
completely de-
law by necessity speaks in general terms,
by which judges may with certainty and con-
the general provisions are to be applied to the wide
variety of particular fact situations presented in actual cases,
much
of the
certainty and predictability that constitutes an important part of the rationale for strict interpretation (and ultimately for the existence of law itself)
would appear unattainable.
Just as there have long been adherents of a jurisprudence of strict interpretation, there have also been jurists
who
support
a freer, equitable
interpretation. Several distinguished students of ancient
claim to have detected a steady
movement
in
Roman
law
toward the triumph of
it
the equitable approach to interpretation, but this
is
controversial.
Most
we know about the classical Roman jurisprudence of interpretacomes from texts preserved in Justinian’s sixth-century codifi-
of what tion
cation,
and there, despite Justinian’s claim to have eliminated
dictions, apparent contradictions
on the subject of
interpretation abound.
A
“what the people enact
at the request
statute
cord, an excerpt in the Digest
is
“the sole
(1.14.11.1)
of
from the
and their
a senatorial magistrate.” In ac-
holds that statutes
jurist Julian
by the people. Yet
holds that the emperor
maker and interpreter of the
statutes
contra-
defined in the Institutes (1.2.4) as
are binding only because they are accepted
passage of the Code
all
is
a
famous
to be regarded as
laws.”
Several passages, including the one quoted above, provide that the
emperor
is
the sole interpreter of the law.
Martian commands that these laws,
and
a
it
if
The emperors Valentiman and
“anything should be found to be obscure in
must be explained by the interpretation of the emperor,”
constitution of Constantine holds that “it ...
to interpret questions involving law and equity” tinian, in
an attempt to limit
all
hibited the interpretation of, or
(
is
lawful for
Code
1.14.9;
1.
Us
alone
14. 1). Jus-
law to the text of his codification, pro-
commentary
on, that text, but within
The Early Sixteenth Century
his
own
commentaries, abridgements, and gen-
lifetime a profusion of
summaries appeared. His own Digest contains excerpts from the
eral rist
85
Julian explaining
why
interpretation
is
ju-
unavoidable:
way that all cases which might at any time occur are covered; it is however sufficient that the things which very often happen are em-
Neither statutes nor senatus consulta can be written in such
a
braced.
And, therefore
... [in such cases]
made
[juristic]
gest
either
1. 3.
This
by
is
interpretation or by a legislative act.
is
the
same rationale
for the necessity
rff
(
Di-
interpretation that Aris-
need to deal with the problem of the omitted
But the Digest solution (again taken from Julian) to
case.
must be
exact provision
10; 1.3.11)
totle gives in his Ethics: the
first
more
problem
this
at
glance appears to be quite different from Aristotle’s solution, which
to appeal to equity to
the gap in the law.
fill
Some
explicitly invoke the principle of equity, but they
problem of the omitted
to the
mentioned
as a principle,
case. Instead,
when
equity
and equity, rather than the
things, the principles of justice
law should be observed” ( Code
do not do so
in respect
explicitly
is
set in opposition to strict law: “in all
is
it
Corpus luris texts
3.1.8).
strict rules
Consideration of equity
is
of
not to be
reserved for cases in which the legislator blunders or shows lack of foresight;
it is
to be considered “in
all
matters, and especially those relating
to the law” (Digest 50.17. 90). This conjunction of equity less like Aristotle’s
view of equity
enunciated in his Ethics and more ,
as a principle
and
justice looks
of interpretation, as
like his description, in the Rhetoric,
of
equity as eternal and immutable.
The
Digest
remedy
for the overgeneral statute or the omitted case
not equity but analogy: “It
hended
is
not possible for every point to be compre-
in statutes or senatus consulta;
meaning of the enactment
is
1.3. 12).
still, if
clear, the
proceed by analogical reasoning (ad ingly” (Digest
in
any case that
similid)
Analogical reasoning
makes
a
connection. In
comparison, after asserting that what
is
arises, the
presiding magistrate ought to
and declare the law accord-
may
at first
have nothing to do with equity, but Cicero, some fore Justinian,
is
a
six
glance appear to
hundred years be-
discussion of arguments by
valid in respect of
one of two
equal cases should be valid in the other, he adds, “Equity should prevail,
86
The Common Law Mind
-c
which requires equal law
in equal cases.”
22
This statement reminds us
immediately that one of the fundamental ideas of (species, as Aristotle notes, of the
quired to be treated
alike.
same genus)
is
justice
and equity
that like cases are re-
Therefore, even though the Corpus Iuris does
not deal with the problem of the omitted case by explicitly referring to equity,
its
solution to the problem implicitly draws
upon one of the fun-
damental concepts associated with equity.
The
use of analogy presupposes consistency in the law. iMore pre-
cisely, in
reasoning by analogy
to another
upon
is
drawn from one instance
the assumption that a generic rule (often called a princi-
The
cover both cases.
ple) is discoverable that will
became
conclusion
a
universally self- conscious in the
search for such
Middle Ages and indeed
a rule is
one
of the identifying marks of the jurisprudence of the fourteenth- century postglossators of the tests
demanding
Roman
But in
law.
that jurists proceed
classical
Roman
law, despite the
by analogy and despite the
fact that
make up Justinian’s
the collection of juristic fragments and statutes that
Corpus luris was put together with the purpose of bringing coherence
and consistency to
Roman
law (and hence presupposed a theory consis-
tent with the use of analogy), at least
two
texts
seem
to
deny that
legal
interpretation by analogy can or should work.
One
Digest text (1.3.20) holds that
ciple of every rule of law laid
adds the next text
be inquired into, there
(1.3. 21),
“impossible to assign the prin-
down by our
forefathers.”
For
down ought not to may not be inquired
of laws
can be no basis for proceeding ad similia; one
The
is left
,
of
a rule to
all.
how-
an omitted case by analogy,
not the theoretical basis of such an operation but whether at
with only
greatest question raised in the Digest
ever, in respect to the extension
done
this reason,
“the reasons of the law laid
into.” If the principles or reasons
intuitive comparisons.
is
it is
it
should be
Despite the texts quoted, and another attributed to Papinian
(Digest 22.5.13) that holds that
“what has been omitted by the laws should
not be omitted by the conscientious judge,”
at least
one text refuses to
permit such an extension: “The law only speaks of the husband and heir.
Nothing
cessors;
is
mentioned with reference to
and Labeo notices
stances, therefore, the law
is
this as
a
his
father-in-law and his suc-
having been omitted. In these in-
defective,
and not even
a
praetorian action
can be granted” ( Digest 24.3.64.9).
Most of the
discussions of interpretation preserved in the Corpus luris
are not about the extension of
words by analogy but about whether the
The Early Sixteenth Century
words themselves, or the intention and
will
87
of the legislator, are to be the
primary concern of the interpreter. Hence there
also a
is
connection
with equity because one of the defining characteristics of equity for Aristotle lay in
its
attention to the legislator’s intent rather than to his
words. In terms of sheer numbers of texts, the Corpus luris seems to favor spirit
and intention over the
letter
or the word.
The
following are repre-
sentative texts:
To know
the statutes does not
mean
to have got hold of the actual
words, but to be acquainted with their sense and application. ( Digest i-3- r 7)
Statutes ought to he interpreted indulgently so as to preserve the
intention [voluntas]. ( Digest
1.3.18)
There
is
violates the law
letter,
attempts to destroy
apply to
A
no doubt that he
all
its
spirit.
.
.
.
who, while obeying
We
legal interpretations in general.
(
order that this shall
Code
1.14.5)
few texts are included that unambiguously prefer
the law to the
demands of
Ulpian holds that
a
equity.
its
For example,
a literal
reading of
a text attributed to
law imposing limitations on the right of
a
woman
separated from her husband to alienate her property “is to a certain extent a hardship, but
The
it is
the written law” ( Digest 40. 9. 12. 1).
richness of the variety of Corpus luris texts
on interpretation and
equity was to have great influence on the legal theory of the Middle
Ages, not only ians.
among
Not only was
the civilians but also
among
canonists and civil-
the Corpus luris a fertile source of inspiration for
dieval thinkers about law,
it
me-
was the source of much of the controvery
that arose about interpretation.
Equity and Interpretation To
a
drew
considerable degree, medieval civilians, canonists, and theologians their ideas about equity
from the same
common
store
— principally
Aristotle and the Corpus luris— but since these sources presented
more
than one idea about the nature of equity, the potential existed, with the emphasis of one passage rather than another,
for considerable
disagreement.
Unlike philosophers such
as
Aquinas, medieval civilians do not
feel
The Common Law Mind
88
free to discuss equity in the abstract; their glosses are constrained
need to take into account and to harmonize the authoritative
by the
texts of the
Corpus Iuris— texts that are not philosophical in nature, that often appear contradictory, and that do not appear in their original context. that original context
theory of
it is
unlikely that they are
and interpretation.
justice, law,
It is
embedded
Even
in
in a general
not surprising, then, that
thinkers like Aquinas were freer to attempt a coherent theory of justice
and law into which equity
fit.
While Aquinas,
on
too, bases his theory
who is attempting to He draws upon Roman legal texts, but he
certain texts, he uses those texts as a philosopher
construct a theory of law.
draws upon them
selectively,
quoting those that support his point of
view 23 .
Bound
they were to the disparate texts of the Corpus Iuris
as
,
surprising that the glossators
come
it is
not
to different conclusions about the
nature and process of statutory interpretation and the role of equity in that process.
As
early as the
first
founder of the famous school
at
generation after Irnerius, the reputed
Bologna,
a division
developed between
two of the four leading doctors, Bulgarus and Martinus Gosi, over and equitable interpretation. This dispute polarized medieval their contemporaries other.
The
and
tend to
later jurists
fall
into one
his
Bulgarus
is
for equity,
camp or
the
not entirely
clear.
contemporaries and modern scholars sometimes talk
as if
of the law, allowing no place
at all
defending the
strict letter
whereas Martinus
is
is
described as a committed champion of a
by what the law actually
free, equitable interpretation unfettered
The
civilians;
dispute generated a lot of heat between the followers of the
two men, but the precise nature of the disagreement Both
strict
says.
followers of Bulgarus (who include Johannes, Azo, Accursius, and
usually Jacobus, Hugolinus, and Odofredus) refer to themselves as nostri doctores
and to the followers of Martinus Gosi (who include Vacarius,
Rogerius, Placentinus, and Pillius) as the Gosiani. attack the aequitas Martiana
,
calling
“ it
feta ,”
by maintaining that to
nostri doctores
“ bursalis,” “capitanea”
contemptuous expressions suggesting arbitrariness their interpretation
The
24 .
The
—
Gosiani defend
stick to the strict letter of the
law often leads to injustice. In other words, the argument, at least at this level of polemics,
ducted in the same terms taught to
thousand years
more
earlier.
all
students of rhetoric
is
con-
more than
Beneath the superficial invective, however,
a
lies a
serious and thoughtful dispute about the nature and relationship
The Early Sixteenth Century
89
of law and equity and more agreement than frequently appears on the surface of the dispute.
Summa
In his statutes
Codicis
Irnerius sets forth the general principle that
,
must be given an equitable reading by judges:
Written laws are more richly understood when one pays heed to the
when they are read out of harmony only when the written laws are adjusted to the
insight they possess, and not
and equity. For
it is
from them
principle of equity that true legal rules can be gleaned
by the judge. 25 Bulgarus fully accepts this view. In commenting on Digest 50.17.90, a quotation from the jurist Paulus that says that “in ularly those relating to the law equity serts that
and
we must always consider not,
if it is
strict law.
it
is
matters and partic-
all
Bulgarus as-
to be'tonsidered
carefully
whether any law
is
equitable;
must be abolished. The judge must prefer equity to
26
Bulgarus’s central dispute with Martinus
important but over what
it is
and how
Irnerius distinguishes between
which has no textual
is
not over whether equity
to be
it is
known and understood.
two kinds of equity, and
this distinction,
books of Justinian,
basis in the law
is
to
dominate
civilian discussions of equity for centuries. First, says Irnerius, there
aequitas constituta is
— top\\x.y reduced
is
to writing in the law. 2
is
Second, there
aequitas rudis— equity not yet enacted into law, or natural law. Because
not
all
law
is
aequitas constituta the law ,
unjust. In such a case, the law has
immediately to abrogate law to make
it
it.
The
no
is
sometimes inequitable and even
force,
and the lawmaker
judge, however, has
is
required
no power to modify
accord with equity. In accordance with Code
1.14.1,
Irner-
concludes that “the interpretation that reconciles these differences
ius
(between equity and
law),
making equity into
law,
is
reserved to the
princes only.” 28
Both Bulgarus and Martinus accept aequitas constituta tion. vail
over
Thus in
When
masters distinction between
and aequitas rudis but they ,
differ
regarding
its
applica-
Bulgarus and his followers proclaim that equity should pre-
strict law,
they have in mind equitas constituta not aequitas ,
for Bulgarus to say that the judge
no way to suggest that
form
their
a
judge
to his understanding of
rudis) requires.
2 ''
is
to
is
rudis.
to prefer equity to strict law
is
modify or correct the law to con-
what natural law or natural
justice
aequitas
(,
Instead, he begins with the assumption that the Corpus
The Common Law Mind
90
Juris already
is
aequitas constituta. Because this
is
so, the task
by identifying
that equity prevails over strict law could be accomplished
the ratio
legis
of seeing
(purpose) of the text being interpreted. Scholars differ over
whether Martinus holds that Code
means
3.1.8
that a judge, as well as the
emperor, can apply aequitas rudis in preference to the
strict law.
30
Maniana suggests the contemporaries understand him to be suggesting
The
heat of the medieval attack on the aequitas
likeli-
hood
that a
that his
judge holds that power. 31 Occasionally, a jurist might appear to waver between the two positions: Vacarius, a student
of Irnerius
who brought the new civilian
learn-
ing to England, states as a general proposition that even rude equity,
where
it is
clear, is to
be preferred to
terpretation of the judge, though
it
law.
32
But he also
resolves the case
states,
“The
between the
in-
parties,
should not attempt to reconcile equity and law for fear of prejudicing the case of others.” 33
The argument can be made
that there
read these two glosses as being inconsistent. Bulgarus,
might be
said,
perior to law.
it
is
no need
quite correctly
would be perfectly happy to grant that aequitas
The
question for
him
to
rudis
is
su-
whether the emperor alone can
is
apply rude equity to the law or whether judges also have that power. Since Vacarius clearly says that judges are not to try to reconcile equity
and the
can be made that he says nothing inconsistent with
law, the case
the position of Bulgarus.
A
plausible case
Vacarius
is
taking
might a
be made, however, that in the two glosses
also
consistent Gosian position
the right to interpret legal texts
on the
— one
according judges
basis of rude equity. Vacarius
does not simply state the abstract proposition, with which no medieval civilian
ten
would disagree, that rude equity
human
argued,
is
law; he adds the clause
a critical addition, it
rude equity
“clear,”
because
is
is
it
it is
clear.”
superior to writ-
This,
it
might be
would be pointless and even mis-
attempt to subject the written law to
never be clear in the abstract; reading
“where
is
not contemplated that someone would actually,
leading were is
(natural law)
it
can only be clear in
a
it.
when
Equity can
concrete case. This
abetted by the fact that Vacarius does not say that rude equity
superior to law; he says that
it is
to be preferred to law. Preference sug-
gests action in a particular case rather than an abstract
judgment about
the merits of equity.
The second
gloss presents
terpretation, but
it
may
more
difficulty for
not altogether
an attempted Gosian in-
resist one.
A
Gosian interpreta-
The Early Sixteenth Century tion of the gloss
would see
it
91
not as an attempt to bar judges from resort-
ing to equity in their interpretation the law but as a statement of the
maxim non
exemplis
,
which proclaims that
based on the law and not on precedent ( Code develops from this
maxim
is
be
judicial decisions are to 34
7.45.13).
The theory
that
that the interpretation of a judge in a case
establishes the rule for that case, but for that case only,
and
in future
cases the judge will again need to refer directly to the law to find the rule for the case; he cannot rely
earlier interpretations.
This interpreta-
becomes more convincing when the whole
tion of the second gloss is
on
examined. 3 Vacarius begins by saying that the emperor -
thor and interpreter of the laws. (for
example, judges)
may have
The
to lay
law comes from his
down
judge interprets the law, his interpretation
him and then only to the extent against him. So when Vacarius goes on fore
is
gloss
the sole au-
will,
but others
When
the law by necessity.
a
only the litigants be-
biirtfs
that they have
no
legal
remedy
to say that the interpretation of
the judge should not attempt to remove any discrepancy between equity
and
law, his point
seems not to be that the judge
is
forbidden from con-
sidering rude equity in deciding cases but that judicial interpretations
bind no one but the present another
gloss:
“Sed
Vacarius supplements this point in
litigants.
iudicis interpretatio unius de
qua cognoscit tantum
36 cause, imperatoris uero et consuetudinis interpretatio perpetua est.”
The
position that gained ascendancy
among medieval
civilians
is
that
the equity to be preferred to strict law and to be applied by persons
other than the lawmaker ten into the law
itself,
is
the aequitas scripta or constituta
not equity that
is
the product of someone’s per-
Christopher
sonal understanding or invention.'
— equity writ-
St.
German
adopts
version of this view regarding the role of equity and conscience in
a
En-
glish law. 1
The Canonists
The
canonists were greatly influenced by the civilians’ formulations
regarding equity, although
a strain
runs through their writings that em-
phasizes the connection of equity with mercy. 3K Gratian adopts the stan-
dard civilian doctrine that the lawmaker cannot legitimately in disregard of equity. legal decisions are
3< '
His views on the place of equity
more complex.
On the one hand,
tence contrary to equity has the same force as the subject to
do
evil, for
obedience
is
a
make in
a
law
ordinary
he states that “a sen-
law which would oblige
not due to prelates in matters that
92
The Common Law Mind
J!
illicit .”
are law:
40
But he rejects the idea of judges using equity to correct the
“These things
are to be considered at the time the law
once the law has been enacted,
made, for
is
not possible to judge concerning
it is
them, but judgment must be made according to the law
” 41
In explana-
tion of these apparently inconsistent positions, the canonists adopt the
between rude equity and equity that has been
civilians’ distinction
duced to writing
in the law. It
ever, that relaxing the rules
re-
becomes common canonist doctrine, how-
of the law
not the same
is
changing the
as
law: rude equity can soften the rigor of the law, but only written equity
truly governs and can alter the law 42 .
Medieval Theological Literature
The most important
medieval philosophical treatment of equity
is
that of Aquinas. Following Aristotle, he explains the need for equity in
terms of the impossiblility of laying down
a rule for
he writes, “rather take into account what
lators,”
and formulate the law accordingly.” But, lowing
a legal rule
made according
at least in
to follow the to “follow
ordinarily the case
some
situations, fol-
to that principle runs counter to
and the public good intended by
“justice
is
every case. “Legis-
all
law.”
words of the law “would be an
When
evil,”
and
that
it
the case,
is
would be good
what the meaning of justice and the public good demand,
let-
ting the letter of the law be set aside .” 43
As
to Aristotle’s statement that epieikeia
suggests that
taken in (that
is,
its
some
we understand
understood
“it is a
norm
“legal justice” to involve is
a part
Aquinas
of justice
of the law ”). 44 If
obeying both the
is
letter
form of legal
and the justice.
better than the legally just
just; for this
from natural
reason
it
45
surpasses
This
raises
question that greatly concerned medieval thinkers about equity:
Were
legal justice a
when
letter
the principal
contained under the naturally
is
justice,
over and above legal justice”
Elsewhere, Aquinas states that the equitable is
form of
“obedience for the
as
intent of the legislator, the epieikeia
and
a
distinctions need to be made. It
widest sense, but
justice
is
men in
so
when
.
the
two
differed? Aquinas’s position
in principle the strict letter should not be followed
would damage the all
justice
general, and judges in particular, to act in accordance with equity
rather than law
though
legal justice departs
the
same notice
common this: if
is
that al-
when doing
welfare,
observing the letter of the law does not
involve a sudden danger calling for instant decision and to be dealt
The Early Sixteenth Century with
at
once,
it is
not for just anybody to interpret what
the state and what
who
not but
this is solely for the rulers [principes]
46
when
only in the case of sudden danger,
there
to the rulers, that- the requirements of the law
“the very necessity carries a dispensation with law.”
useful for
because of such cases, have the authority to dispense with the
law's.
It is
is
is
93
is
no time
may be
it,
for recourse
dispensed with:
for necessity
knows no
47
Jean Gerson, equity through
who
influenced the
common
German’s Doctor and
St.
lawyers’ understanding of
Student, also sees
it
largely in
Aristotelian terms as a kind of justice that takes account of individual
when
circumstances
dealing with general legal rules, interpreting gen-
eral laws in their application to singular cases.
describes equity in terms that
combine
48
Occasionally,
this Aristotelian idea
emphasis on mercy found in some canonists: “Equity having weighed
all
the particular circumstances
is
Gerson with the
justice
which
tempered with the
is
sweetness of mercy.” 49
Gerson does
differ
from Aquinas on the question of who has the right
to apply equity: whereas Aquinas reserves that
power
to the principes ex-
cept in cases of necessity, Gerson extends the power to invoke equity to the
u
praesidentes of
whatever status
in the ecclesiastical heirarchy.”
50
Christopher St. German on Equity and Conscience Before the sixteenth century, no
about equity as
and
in Bracton
equity
is
a juristic
Sir
common lawyer had
written extensively
concept, although short discussions are found
John Fortescue’s De Natura
opposed to “the law
in
all its
Legis Naturae. In Bracton,
rigor” and
is
defined as “the bring-
ing together of things, that which desires like right in like cases and puts all
things
on an
matters of
equality.
fact, that
is,
Equity
is,
so to speak, uniformity, and turns
on
the words and acts of men.”"
This very brief discussion of equity associates different notions, both of
it
with two somewhat
which are ultimately traceable to
Greek and Roman discussions on the
subject.
The
first,
classical
which opposes
equity to strict law, runs back to Aristotle’s treatment of epieikeia as “the sort of justice
which goes beyond the written law”
(fyracton 2:25).
52
The
second, which “turns on matters of fact” and “desires like right in like cases,” resonates
with Aristotle’s insistence that the kinds of general or
94
The Common Law Mind
>
universal statements necessarily found in the law cannot always take
account of the wide variety of differences possible in factual circumstances and that justice requires like cases to be treated alike and differ-
ent cases differently. idea
made by
is
The
classical association
of equity with the latter
Cicero: “Equity should prevail, which requires equal
laws in equal cases .” 53
More
than two centuries after Bracton this general ,
By
principle resurfaces in the doctrine of the equity of a statute. fifteenth century, that doctrine
sion of a statute beyond
is
sometimes used to describe the exten-
words to cases which were
its
in the
same mis-
chief that had led to the adoption of the provision: “This statute larges the in the
common
law
.
.
and
.
the
if so,
.
en-
.
.
should be taken largely, and cases
same mischief included by the equity.” 54
Fortescue frames his discussion of equity in terms of the king’s power to rule “regally”; as part of that regal power, the king has discretion in
certain matters, including the mitigation of criminal punishments and
the application of equity: “Equity (epikaia) also the strictness of the law, confounding the
common good .” 55 The
its
is left
to thy sagacity, lest
intent [mentum \
,
should hurt
attribution to equity of the function of pre-
serving the law’s intent in preference to the strict application of
words has roots that go back to
Aristotle. Fortescue cites Aristotle later
in the chapter, but this sentence’s
serve the lustrate
common good
how
its
presumption that the
law’s intent
gives his treatment a Thomistic flavor.' 6
equity, in preserving the law’s intent, serves the
is
to
To
il-
common
welfare, Fortescue recites the ancient example of a law forbidding the
scaling of the city walls and contends that such a law should properly be
understood not to have been violated by one repel the sudden attack of the
enemy because
would have swallowed up the law along with
The
equitable function
tentimes the written law
is
who
climbs the walls to
“the observance of the law
its
authors.”'
necessary, Fortescue suggests, because “of-
lies as it
were dead under
a
covering of words”
and because frequently “the mind of the lawgiver did not perceive that the
words of the law embrace.” The
latter
all
claim seems to suggest, as
does Fortescue’s example concerning city walls, that the function of equity
is
to take exceptions
from overly general statutory language.
It is
not clear whether he also thinks equity should extend the words of
a
narrowly drawn
from
law. Equity, in rousing the law’s “vital spirit as if
sleep” does not violate the law or detract
the hands of the prince
it is
a
from
legal justice,
too
although in
“superior authority” that has “absolute
The Early Sixteenth Century power.” Instead, nature, which
function
its
is
“to
is
fulfill a
95
law ... by reason of the law of
natural equity.” Fortescue has already described the
function of equity as that of reviving the spirit or intent of the law; just
what the law of nature has to do with that function he
The
treatment of equity in Bracton
borrowed from the
is
civilian
Azo;
appear to be Aristotle and Aquinas; in
in Fortescue, the chief sources
German’s Doctor and Student the principal direct ,
theological writers. St.
leaves unclear.
intellectual debt
St.
is
to
German’s doctor, following Gerson, defines eq-
uity as “a ryghtwysenes [rightousness] that consideryth
culer cyrcumstaunces of the dede the whiche also
the perty-
all
temperyd with the
is
swetnes of mercye.”"* This definition combines Aristotle’s concern with particular circumstances with the canonists’ association of equity with
mercy.
1
he explanation of
cumstances
is
why
is
concerned with particular
in dyuers
men
for
maners infynytlye.
generall rewle of the lawe but that
whiche lawes ben ordayned
It is
not possyble to make any
shall fayle in
it
some
therfore makers of lawes take hede to such thynges as
come and not they wolde.
some It is
cir-
purely Aristotelian:
Syth the dedes and actes of
happen
equity
And
case.
may
often
to euery particuler case for they coulde not though
And
therfore to folowe the wordes of the lawe were in
case both agaynst Iustyce
the part of equity, St.
&
the
German
common welthT
continues, to leave the words of
the law and to follow what reason and justice require
mitigate the rigor of the law. Equity
is
called
by some
“
— to
temper and
epicaia ,”
which
is
an excepcyion of the lawe of god or of the lawe of reason from the generall rewles of the lawe of
man: when they by reason of theyr
generalytye wolde in any partyculer case luge agaynste the lawe of
god or the lawe of reason the whiche excepcion
secretely vnder-
is
stande in euery generall rewle of euery posytyue law. 60
The
part of St.
German’s
earlier definition of equity,
which emphasizes
“the sweetness of mercy,” and his attribution in this passage of equity’s role in keeping the
human
law in
harmony with
the law of
God
and of
reason came to have more application to the chancellor’s equity than to the equity frequently cited by
common
lawyers later in the century in
connection with the interpretation of statutes.
The
often discussed in the sixteenth-century reports,
is
Equity of
a statute,
cited to justify either
The Common Law Mind
96
extending the words of an act to cover or, less it
commonly,
restricting the application of general language so that
does not include
uity
commonly
they do not mention
a situation
a situation
it
appears to cover. In neither usage
explained in terms of an attempt to
make
is
eq-
statutory
words agree with the law of
God
of the equity of a statute
most commonly associated with the Aris-
totelian
is
or the law of reason. Instead, the idea
problem of the impossibility of writing laws that take into
count the great particularity of human frequently tied to St.
German
a
ac-
This problem, in turn,
affairs.
is
search for legislative intent.
himself, in a later passage, says that “equytie rather folo-
weth the intent of the lawe then the wordes of the lawe .” 61 Medieval theologians have a comprehensive explanation of the law of
God
and of reason are
all
the law of
God
mind
words of the law is
good — a good presumed
and reason
62 .
and
equity, intent,
tied together. Aquinas, for example,
in writing of the intent of the legislator, has in
to legislate for the public
how
Therefore,
when
the assumed intent
to be in accord with
equity departs from the
in order to accomplish the legislator’s intent, its effect
to uphold the law of
God
and reason.
St.
German may
hold
a similar
comprehensive view of the connection between equity, the law of reason, and legislative intent, but
Although
St.
German
if so,
he does not set
ties
forth clearly.
occasionally associates epicaia with the function
of applying the law of God and the law of reason to
more frequently
it
human
law,
he
much
those higher laws to the idea of conscience. His dis-
cussion of the relationship between equity and conscience
is
not always
clear;
he defines them in ways that distinguish between them, but he also
shifts
back and forth between them in
that he sees
German The
them
a
manner occasionally suggesting
as interchangeable principles
63 .
In his prologue,
St.
states his authorial intention:
present dialogue shows what are the principles or grounds of
the laws of England, and
formed
in
how
conscience ought in
many
cases to be
accordance with those same principles and grounds.
It
likewise discusses briefly the question of when English law ought to
be rejected or not on account of conscience.
knowledge of English law and
its
grounds
direction of conscience in this realm
.
is
The theme
is
that a
essential for the
good
.
.
64 .
In setting out to examine these questions concerning conscience, St.
German
is
pursuing both an interest in the proper ordering of the indi-
The Early
Sixtee?ith
Century
97
vidual consciences of Englishmen and a concern about the appropriate role of conscience in the English legal system.
Conscience had become
a jurisprudential
concern
England by the
in
Middle Ages. In 1414 the Commons complained that the chancellor, by means of writs of subpoena, was interfering with matters deterlate
minable
common
at the
law and was determining them according to the
*
procedures of the law.
65
By
civil
the reign of
common
law and the church in subversion of the
Edward
IV, the Year
Book
reporters are noting
that the chancellor claims to proceed according to conscience or ac-
cording to the law of nature. 66 By the fifteenth century, then, the chancellor
is
intervening in
common
law matters and justifying his actions in
terms of conscience. Cardinal Wolsey,
German’s contemporary,
St.
takes a strong view of the role of the the chancellor in regard to con-
science and the law:
The
king ought for his royal dignity and prerogative to mitigate
the rigour of the law, where conscience hath the
more
force;
and
therefore in his princely place he hath constituted a chancellor to
And
order for him the same.
been commonly risdiction to
therefore the court of chancery hath
called the court of conscience; because
command
the law in every case to desist
it
hath ju-
from the ex-
ecution of the rigour of the same, whereas conscience hath the
most Given
effect.
this
67
background,
St.
German’s question about “when English law
ought to be rejected or not on account of conscience”
is
more than an
abstract one. His treatment of the subject, near the end of the period in
which the Court of Chancery was cellor,
in the
hands of the
ecclesiastical
chan-
provides both justification for the continued operation of the
chancery
as
a
court of conscience and
a
rationale for limiting the
chancery’s power to regulate English secular law. St.
German’s understanding of conscience
is
strongly influenced by
medieval theological and canonist treatments of the subject and be confused with conscience’s modern definition as
perhaps subjective, of right and wrong. For
knowledge that enables
a
St.
is
not to
a person’s sense,
German,
it is
a
kind of
person to translate the dictates of the law of
nature into specific rules of conduct. Following conventional medieval theory, St.
German
ciples of natural law.
distinguishes between primary and secondary prin-
The primary
principles are infallible but very gen-
98
The Common Law Mind
eral (for
example,
them
into
more
“Do good and
practical guidance for
of the rational soule euyll.”
68
The problem
.
.
.
mouynge and
moral action in the world.
sterrynge
Men
to
it
good
&
abhor-
recognizes and embraces the basic moral
principles of natural law. In Gerson’s phrase, ural inclination to
it
“receives a certain nat-
good immediately from God.” 69
Sinderesis, writes St.
major premise (“No 0
to translate
Sinderesis, thus understood, functions as a nondelibera-
tive intuition that infallibly
science.
is
by sinderesis, an innate “naturall power or motive force
are aided in this
rynge
avoid evil”).
German, can be understood
evil is to
Conscience has no
be done”) in
forming the
as
a syllogism
about con-
difficulty in correctly assenting to this
premise; the problem comes in descending to a minor premise that ap-
major premise to some particular case or
plies the
“This
is evil.”
because
it
The minor premise
is
fact in the form,
formed by “inferior reason” and,
has to deal with particular circumstances,
is
not always true.
1
Conscience assents to the minor premise and draws the conclusion:
may err in drawing the minor premise, it is possible that conscience may reach a false conclusion by assenting to that premise. Error in conscience may come from a variety of “This
is
not to be done.” 72 Since reason
causes, including negligence
concerns
German comes through
St.
rance of the the law."
upon some
The about
and pride, but the error that particularly
law.”
law of
3
ignorance, and especially igno-
“All conscience,” he holds,
“must be grounded
74
God
and the law of reason,
a matter, are the preferred
if
they have something to say
foundations for the operations of con-
science, but they are frequently silent about the kinds of issue typically
contested in English law, such as
when conscience the lawe of
god
man serue not there is no grounde case may be groundyd” (163). The con-
... if the law of in this
science of an English subject, then,
is
to be ruled not only
by the law of
and the law of reason,
but also of the lawe of man that
nor the lawe of god: but that ter
land shall descend. Therefore,
“can no be groundyd vpon the law of reason nor vpon
wherupon conscyence
God
how
orderyng of the
common
is
it is
not contrary to the lawe of reason
superaddyd vnto them for the bet-
welth for such a law of
to
go fro
it
is
alwayes
it is
not lawfull for no
on the one syde ne on the other
for suche a lawe of
to be sett as a rewle in conscyence so that
man
man
The Early Sixteenth Centrny
man
hath not only the strength of mannes law but also of the lawe
of reason or of the lawe of god wherof
man whiche haue
by
99
it is
dyryved for lawes made
receyued of god power to make lawes be made
of god. (iio-ii)
The
principle that in
England conscience must normally be ordered by
the rules of English secular law applies not only to the ordinary subject
but also to the the chancellor himself:
“The
lorde Chauncellor
must
ordre his conscyence after the rewles and groundes of the lawe of the
realme” (104-5).
German’s
St.
initial
question concerning
be rejected on account of conscience
is
when English law ought
an important one:
lor could interfere
with the ordinary course of the
straining a litigant
from pursuing
a
claim on
tfte
from the
cellor’s
own
the situation
rules of the
common
the chancel-
common
law by re-
ground that the remedy
sought by the litigant offends against conscience — not rived
if
to
conscience de-
a
law but one informed by the chan-
personal sense of what justice or rightousness required in
— then
the chancellor’s conscience could reasonably be seen
as a threat to the legal
and even constitutional rights of Englishmen.
The
limited to writs of subpoena issued before judg-
practical
ment
is
entered in the
Henry IV '
for
is
common
if
a statute
from the reign of
from providing
relief after judg-
law courts;
prohibits the chancellor
ment. 7 But of the
problem
the chancellor’s conscience can interfere with the course
common
law up to the point of judgment, that
some of the common
lawyers. St.
is
threat
German’s treatment of conscience,
including the principle that even the chancellor’s conscience
ordered after the rules of the
enough
common
law,
can be seen
is
to be
as a substantial
common law by an unconfined common lawyers were reassured. The
mitigation of the danger posed to the
Not
chancellor’s conscience.
opening for
a
all
continued concern
is
provided in
St.
German’s statement
that
it is
also to be
understood that the law
is
to be left aside in favour of
conscience in such particular cases as those mentioned before in chapter
15
which are excepted from the general rules of English law
by equity, the law of reason, or the law of properly speaking,
it
God — cases
wherein,
cannot be proved that the law willed those
things thus excepted. 76
The Common Law Mind
ioo
Here, equity:
seems,
it
when
we
are brought full circle back to a consideration of
the law
to be set aside in favor of conscience,
is
chancellor does in exercising that conscience
appear to be deep ambiguities in
Some law’s
passages suggest that
its
There
to apply epieikeia.
German’s treatment of
St.
function
is
what the
is
equity.
to enforce the ratio legis or the ,
purpose or intent, when the general words
fail
to capture
77
it.
Such
statements link up with the part of the passage just quoted, which asserts that the law
speaking,
to be left for conscience in “cases wherein, properly
is
cannot be proved that the law willed those things thus ex-
it
Other passages, though, assign to equity the task of taking
cepted.”
exceptions from the general rules of the law ular cases “luge agaynste the lawe of
Those passages
when they would
in partic-
god or of the lawe of reason”
(97).
are also associated with leaving the law in favor of con-
science (116-17). St.
German
evidently believes that any tension between these two
rather different descriptions of the functions of equity his
statement that exceptions based on the law of
God
is
resolved by
or the law of rea-
son are “secretely vnderstande in euery generall rewle of euery posytyve lawe” (96-97). His acquaintance with civilian and canonist legal theory
medium
appears to have been indirect, through the ers,
and so he does not seem to have been applying, in
famous distinction between aequitas the idea that
all
human
of evidence that he
would make no
is
sense:
law
is
that of aequitas rudis
But
aequitas constituta).
it
is
(under
is
is
distinction, since the
to apply the ratio or purpose of a law, and
to hold positive law to the standards of natural
his
conscience by applying equity,
to take both into account.
if this is a
not
constituta
Apart from the absence
would have obliterated the
and the chancellor, exercising
evidently
and aequitas
German’s description, performs both of those func-
law. Equity, in St.
tions,
rudis
this statement, the
familiar with the distinction, such an application
function of aequitas constituta
it is
of theological writ-
correct reading of the passage that
at all clear
what
St.
German
has in
sizing that the chancellor’s conscience
grounds of English
law.
Or
to put
it
is
we
are considering,
mind by repeatedly empha-
to be ordered
the other
by the rules and
way around,
cellor, in his application
of conscience and equity,
English law in terms of
its
is
if
the chan-
limited to assessing
underlying purpose and intent, what can be
meant by
attributing to equity the function of taking exceptions
the law to
make
it
agree with the laws of
God
and nature?
from
The Early Sixteenth Century
One
possibility
is
that St.
German, although holding
oretical principle that “equity
IOI
as a general the-
must always be observed
in every law of
man,” really does mean the chancellor’s application of equity to be limited to discovering his
meaning, he manages to obscure
sibility is that in
it
quite well (94-95).
holding that the chancellor’s conscience
by the rules of the is
and enforcing the law’s reason or purpose.
common
law,
is
If this is
Another posto be ordered
he merely means to point out that that
what the exercise of conscience comes down to
of cases, since neither the law of
God
in the great majority
much
nor of reason has
to say
about land law or the appropriate form of contracts, and conscience has to be founded
And
on some
law:
there can be none other cause assygned^why conscyence in the
fyrst case
is
with the eldest brother
&
brother and in the thyrde case with
in the all
second with the yonger
the bretherne but bycause
the lawe of England by reason of dyuers customes doth
gyue the land hollye to the
somtyme
Nor
to
eldest sone
to the yongest
&
all. (121)
much
there need to labour
is
somtyme
somtyme
in these cases, for practically the
whole body of the law consists of cases of lawyers hold that where there
is
this sort;
and so English
any law duly had and ordained for
the isposition of things real, personal or mixed, which law
contrary to the law of
binding upon
all
God
is
not
or the law of reason, then that law
that are subject to
it,
is
in the tribunal of conscience.
( I2 9)
Such an interpretation
leaves
open the question of what
is
to be
done
in
those cases that the law of England does not cover or in which English
law conflicts with the law of reason or the law of God. swer, in the
Second Dialogue,
is
far
from
a
St.
German’s an-
model of clarity. The student,
having been asked by the doctor to explain the reason for the law’s
lowing
a
husband to be tenant by the courtesy of
repeats his earlier assertion that
maxim of
it is
it
rent but not of land,
unnecessary to assign
the law but only necessary that the
taken for law and that
a
al-
a
reason for a
maxim
has been always
God
and reason. The
not be against the law of
student adds, “and therfore yf the husbande in this case be not holpen by
conscyencce he can not be holpen by the lawe [since the law was against him].”
To
this the
doctor responds:
io2
The Common Law Mind
*
And
yf the lawe helpe
it
not: conscyence can nat helpe
hym
in
conscyence must alway be grounded vppon some law
this case for
and
hym
can not in
this case
be grounded vpon the law of reason nor
man
vpon
the law of god for yt
shall
be tenaunt by the curtesy but by the custome of the realme.
And
not dyrectely by those lawes that
therfore yf that custome helpe
in thys case
of
is
man
nothynge haue
not: he can
by conscyence for conscyence neuer resysteth the lawe
nor addeth nothing to
selfe dyrectely
than properly
agaynst the law of reason or it
can not be
law but
a
agaynst the said lawes ... or
prouyded for
but where the law of
it
hym
a
els
And
in
where there
in
it-
any partyculer case is
no lawe of man
by the lawe of rea-
than somtyme there
to execute that in conscyence as
is
corrupcyon, or where the
that hath ryghte to a thynge
son or by the law of god.
man
the lawe of god and
els
man worketh
generall groundes of the law of
gyuen
hym
a
by
is
remedye
sub pena but not in
a
all
somtyme it shall be referred to the conscyence of the partye and vppon this grounde (that is to saye) that whan there is no tytle gyuen by the comon lawe: that there is no tytle by conscyence.
cases for
(207)
German
St.
asserts in this passage that
when
the law does not provide
for a claimed right, conscience will not help the claimant because “con-
science never resisteth the law of
man
principle appears to be qualified a
little later,
nor addeth nothing to however:
if
it.”
This
someone has
a
right
by the law of reason or the law of God, then he sometimes may
have
a
may
appear, at
remedy
in conscience
by
a
writ of subpoena.
The
qualification
glance, to be inconsistent with the principle that
first
conscience never adds anything to the law, but the idea seems to be that
when
the right itself
privation, then
science
may
if
may be found
there
provide
a
is
in the law, but
also a right to a thing
remedy by
a writ
of
subpeona may
God St.
also be
had
if
for
its
de-
by the law of reason, con-
of subpoena from the chancery.
Less complex, but perhaps more interesting, that a
no remedy
English law
is
the evident suggestion
is
directly against the law
or law of reason.
German seems
science (and equity)
to hold, then, that in the vast majority of cases conis
limited to the task of seeing to
the law does not incorrectly induce a departure
would be so
in nearly
all
it
that the letter of
from the
ratio legis.
situations because “practically the
This
whole body
The Early Sixteenth Century of the law” consists of rules on subjects about which the law of
103
God
and
the law of reason have nothing to say but which are not inconsistent with
those higher laws. In the rare instance, however, in which a rule of English law conflicts with the higher laws,
it
would
also be appropriate for
What is not clear is the standard case. St. German never says that the
to be used in
conscience to intervene. this
second kind of
of reason in fashioning
in
is
a
remedy.
He
so often emphasizes that the chan-
to order his conscience after the law that
mind here
is
also
something
like a
most
likely
search for the ratio
what he has
legis
— perhaps
one that focuses on the reason or purpose of a whole area of the just
is
draw upon his own understanding of the requirements of the law
free to
cellor
chancellor
law,
not
of the troublesome rule.
Such cellor,
a
if
taken seriously by the chan-
in practice severely limit the
scope of operations of the
theory of conscience and equity,
would
Court of Chancery by
shifting the inquiry
concern with the requirements of abstract
from the kind of unbounded which sometimes un-
justice,
derlay the decrees of the ecclesiastical chancellor, to a concern about the the
meaning and purpose of
a
common
law or statutory rule. Over the
next century and a half, the Court of Chancery was transformed into
another law court with established procedures and precedents, and
it
can be plausibly argued that
a
developing body of
German’s treatment
St.
of conscience greatly influenced that transformation.
Not
all
of the
common
lawyers’ concerns about the chancellor’s appli-
cation of conscience to English law are assuaged by Doctor and Student.
Although
it is
common law many common
possible to overstate the opposition of the
bar to the chancellor’s equitable jurisdiction — after
lawyers eagerly take advantage of
— nevertheless
it
all,
there
is
considerable
evidence that some lawyers find the interjection of the chancellor’s conscience into matters normally determinable at the
of professional
undesirable, and not merely for reasons
anomymous author of The
common
Replication of a Serjeant at the
law to be
jealousy.
The
Laws of England
states serious jurisprudential objections to the nature of the chancellor’s
conscience — objections that
St.
German
never sucessfully addresses,
ther in Doctor and Student or in his reply to the Replication in Treatise Concerning Writs of Subpoena
The fundamental problem cellor’s conscience,
with
Little
78 .
St.
German’s treatment of the chan-
argues the sergeant,
as the basis for intervention in the
A
ei-
is
that
if
course of the
that Conscience
common
is
law, “it
used
must
The Common Law Mind
104
common
needs follow that this good
law must be
made
as void
and
set at
naught.”™ This conclusion follows, the sergeant suggests, from observa-
how
tion of
common
conscience has operated in actual cases. For example,
law
who
debtor
a
a written acquittance
if
by
the debtor has
if so,
,
a
writ of subpoena in chancery.
subpoena the obligee
a
no common law remedy.
and Student indicates that in such
in Doctor
might be helped by that
has paid his debt on time but neglects to get
may, despite his payment, be sued in an action of
debt by the obligee, and
German,
of debt, and the obligor
The
common
law:
St.
debtor
a case the
sergeant argues
prohibited from pursuing the action
is
admit in chancery to plead payment of the
is
obligation without a writing, the inescapable effect would be to
void the
at the
“So that
if it
must be admitted
for law, the
make com-
mon
law, that
laws,
one being contrary to the other, cannot stand together, but one of
is
contrary to that, must needs be no law. For these two
them must stand
By
may
this
as void.”
example, then, the sergeant shows that whatever
say about the chancellor’s conscience being ruled by the
law, in practice the chancellor
mon thus a
would be making
law rules “void and of no is
be able to substitute
effect.” It
a different
law that the sergeant contends
laws of
God
is
is
Englishmen
will
German
common
clearly established
bad enough
if
com-
the chancellor
law for established English law —
reasonable and in accord with the
and reason — but the situation actually
the chancellor’s conscience that
St.
is
worse because
if
to determine such cases, the result will be
is
be ruled by no law
at
gues, because the chancellor’s conscience
all. is
This
is
so, the
sergeant ar-
no more than the discretion
of a single man: the chancellor,
own
regarding no law, but trusting to his
judgment
as
it
wit and wisdom, giveth
pleaseth himself, and thinketh that his judgment,
being in such authority,
is
far better
and more reasonable than the
judgment’s that be given by the king’s justices according to the
common
law of the realm
80 .
Saying that conscience depends upon the chancellor’s discretion other
way of saying
Conscience
is
a
that
it is
an-
uncertain and unpredictable:
thing of great uncertainty, for
they tread upon two straws that science;
is
and some man think
if
lie
some men think
across, that they offend in
he lack
if
con-
money and another have too
The Early Sixteenth Century
much, he may take part of
his
And
with conscience.
io 5
so divers
men,
divers conscience.
If
law)
the Chancellor’s conscience (which is
may
in practice override the
so uncertain, then suit by subpoena in chancery works against the
common
weal of the realm,
common
for the
well of every realm
the subjects of the realm plain
is
may be justified by
and open that law
is,
good
to have a
the same; and the
well of the realm. But
leave the law of that realm,
one man, what thing
At
least
shall
more
and the more knowledge and under-
standing that the subjects have of that law, the better
common
law, so that
if
it is
for the
the subjects shall be compelled to
and to be ordered by the discretion of
be more
unknown and
from the time of the Roman rhetoricians,
uncertain?
a
standard argument
against equitable interpretation has been that since equity depends
the understanding and discretion of the one
who
applies
it, it
upon
threatens
one of the central benefits of rule by an established law — the security of having legal rules certain enough and plain enough that citizens can
know
their rights
Replication fits
is
common
duties.
We have no evidence that the author of the
acquainted with this tradition of argument, but this passage
neatly within
ment an
and
it.
While
it
may be
inappropriate to see in this argu-
anticipation of the conceptualization in the next century of the
law as
a
repository of the constitutional rights of Englishmen,
and of the jealousy against royal encroachment that accompanied that conceptualization, in the Replication
it is
may
not hard to see
how
the kind of thinking reflected
have helped lay the foundation for some of the
constitutional thought of the seventeenth century.
Those passages conscience
understood decrees.
is
and Student that hold that the chancellor’s
to be ordered after the rules of English law
may
partly be
an attempt to mitigate any uncertainty in the chancellor’s
as
The
in Doctor
sergeant does not address those passages directly, but he
does attribute
much
of the uncertainty of the chancellor’s conscience to
lack of knowledge of the law. If the chancellor really understands English law, he argues, a
he would understand that rules such as the one requiring
writing for the discharge of debt are not unjust but operate for the
public good:
The Common Law Mind
io6
For most commonly the Chancellors of England have been
men, that hath but and when such
superficial
spiritual
knowledge of the laws of the realm;
hath been made unto them, that such
a bill
a
man
should have great wrong to be compelled to pay two times for one
knowing the goodness of the common
thing, the Chancellor, not
inconvenience that might ensue by the said suit of
law, neither the
subpoena, hath temerously directed
commanding him
the king’s name,
subpoena to the
a
plaintiff in
to cease his suit that he hath be-
fore the king’s Justices.
It is
because of the chancellor’s ignorance of English law, and thus of
goodness, the sergeant suggests, that he
is
tempted into “trusting to
its
his
own wit and wisdom.” To
the sergeant’s charge that compelling English subjects to be or-
dered by the chancellor’s conscience placed them in uncertainty, St.
German responds
that although
a
position of great
some men’s consciences
might err by being overscrupulous, and others by being too
lax,
there
is
no reason to be concerned about the chancellor’s conscience because he is
always appointed by the king “as a
man
of singular wisdom and good
conscience” and therefore he “will not be deceived through such errors in conscience, shall
have
” sl
having so
The
strait rules to the
order of his conscience as he
rules that are to guide his conscience are those of “the
law of God, and the law of reason, and trary to the laws of
God, nor
.
.
.
the law of the realm not con-
to the law of reason.”
The
fails
part of this
wisdom and good
response, which asks the reader to take on faith the
conscience of the chancellor,
first
entirely to address the Replication
s
concerns: the chancellor might, however great his wisdom, reach conclusions at variance with the law of England, and this possibility inevitably leads to uncertainty.
The second
claims that the chancellor’s conscience
only persuade those
who
is
part of the response, which
confined by “strait rules,” will
are convinced that the rules of the law of rea-
son are plain and certain enough to eliminate the possibility of error. St.
German
pursues three lines of argument in justification of the
chancellor’s intervention by
means of writs of subpoena. In the
contended that the chancellor its
deeper reason.
this rationale will
much
The
merely following the
sergeant’s
not explain
like rejections
is
all
argument makes interventions;
it
first, it is
law,
bringing out
clear,
though, that
some simply look too
of established law. For such situations
St.
German
The Early Sixteenth Century
107
has two other explanations not entirely consistent with each other and neither of which
The
first
of these
and repeated will
not
universally applicable.
is
is
the distinction, introduced in Doctor and Student
in the Little Treatise
,
to give a petitioner a
lie
between right and remedy. Subpoenas
new
no remedy, the chancellor’s conscience
right exists but
where
a legal
at least
some-
right in the law, but
The example St. German gives is drawn Quia emp tores. 82 The statute, he notes, gives a right to
times might supply the want.
from the
statute
every free
man
this is that
no rent service can be reserved on
make
to
of his lands.
a free alienation
a fee
A
consequence of
simple grant because
the grantee holds not of the grantor but of the grantor’s chief lord. 8
Any
-
agreement under which the grantor takes no deed and keeps no reversion, therefore,
is
not enforceable
common
at the
argues that nevertheless such an agreement
reason and enforceable by subpoena. law only denies the remedy; reservation.
There
is
it
The
is
a
German
consistent with the law of
reason, he suggests,
is
that the
does not deny the right to make such
a right to the reservation
not specifically say that such
law, but St.
a
because the statute does
reservation will be void;
if it did,
there
could be no subpoena.
Such
remedy
a
conception of rights
distinction
cretion. Indeed,
is
so expansive that the use of the right-
would place few constraints on the chancellor’s
one who closely reads
St.
German’s treatment, here and
elsewhere, of the right-remedy distinction
may
he does not make serious application of
but uses
conceal
a reliance
dis-
it
get the impression that it
as a
subterfuge to
on what he understands the law of reason to
require.
In the case under Quia emptores, he argues the appropriateness of a sub-
poena because “though yet
it is
it
be void
as for
good by the law of reason.” 84 In
German
indeed examines the law to see
any remedy
his
at the
common
law,
reasoning in such matters,
if it
St.
provides the remedy at issue,
but he does not engage in a similarly close examination to determine
whether the law of the realm cellor
is
to rely; his
really protects the right
presumption appears to have been that
protected by the law of reason, St.
German
on which the chan-
it is
if it is a
right
protected by English law.
does not rely on the right-remedy distinction to justify
the use of a subpoena to forestall an action of debt by a creditor
who
has
already been paid; instead, he maintains that different courts have differ-
ent rules and the the
common
law,
maxim
requiring formal acquittance only has force “at
and that only
in courts of record,” not in the
chan-
The Common Law Mind
io8
ceryT D. E. C. Yale writes of single
body of law, then we might charge
central crux, but
minimum may
at a
St.
notion that
just this
it is
expounds the idea of different laws
man
argument: “If we are to think of
this
German with evasion of the St. German denies when he
is
to be ruled
“For there
rectly against a statute, nor directly against the lie,
And
therefore as a
statute
lieth
no subpoena
maxims of the
To emphasize
if it
were enacted that
pilgrim and died, that
all
if
law, for if
may not
this point,
an alien came through the
goods should be
his
were against reason and not to be observed
yet there should
no subpoena
lie
rectly against the statute,
statute be not good,
it
forfeit, this
in conscience,
for the executors of the pilgrim,
judgment
for if there should, then should the Chancellor give
and that may not be in no wise; but
must be broken by parliament
German’s principle sems to
St.
di-
statutory example:
a
realm
by the maxims of En-
then the law should be judged to be void, and that
be done by no court, but by the parliament .” 87 he gives
Ger-
If so, St.
be charged with equivocation of the issue of
glish law, for in Little Treatise he writes,
should
86
for different courts .”
whether the chancellor’s conscience
it
a
as
be, then, that writs of
it
if
di-
the
was made.
subpoena do not
maxims of the law, even when they are against reason, unless they happen to be the kind of maxims that are binding only in common
lie
against
law courts of record and not in chancery. standing that makes sense of
must conclude that
St.
this,
German
If St.
German
he does not explain
fails
it.
has an under-
In the end, one
to produce a reasoned, coherent set
of criteria for the interposition of the chancellor’s conscience into com-
mon
law matters.
John tional
Guy
and
J.
view of the
H. Baker provide
common
a service in correcting the tradi-
law courts and their personnel as locked in
near mortal combat with the Court of Chancery and the other courts of
conscience
at the
that the balance
beginning of the sixteenth century, but
may
have tipped too
the Replication speaks for
many
far
88 .
of his fellow
I
it is
possible
suspect that the author of
common
lawyers in express-
ing an outlook at odds with an English jurisprudence in which courts of
equity and conscience are thought necessary to supplement the
law and the
common
law courts. For these
common
common
lawyers, the
com-
mon
law
who
have “the very and trewe knowledge of the lawes of the realme .” 89
is
sufficient for
all
exigencies
if
only
it is
administered by
men
The Early Sixteenth Century
St.
German, though
a
common
lawyer,
may
109
thus be seen as a figure
the question of the nature of the
common law thought, especially on common law and its place in the entire
system of English jurisprudence.
The
slightly outside the
mainstream of
tematic treatise on jurisprudence that cal
is
itself
enough
lawyers of his time. the
common
law,
to distinguish
And
he set out to write
fact that is
more philosophical than
him from
the other
all
a sys-
practi-
common
the fact that he denies the perfect reason of
and denies that the
common
in the law of reason, serves to separate
law
is
perfectly
grounded
him from the growing ideology,
stemming perhaps from Fortescue and pointing toward the extreme views of Sir John Davies, that glorifies the
common
law.
CHAPTER
FIVE
Plowden’s Commentaries and the Sixteenth-
Century Law Reports
E
dmund plowden, now
universally regarded as the best
law reporter of the sixteenth century, set
passed for
many
generations
1 .
them) that we turn for
calls
It is
a
common
standard that was not sur-
to his reports (or commentaries, as he
a sense
of
how
the
common
law bench and
the practicing bar of the mid-sixteenth century conceptualize the
com-
mon law, including how they understand the relation of general custom to common law, how they view the relation of both to reason and the law of nature, and their approach to statutes and their interpretation.
Common
said that “there are three
Kinds of
Realm of England, by which the King’s People
are gov-
In the case of Reniger
Laws
in this
erned,
viz.
Law, Custom, and Reason
the
Law
v.
Fogossa
it is
general, Customs, and Statute
part division of English law, after the St.
German’s
division
human and
is,
Law.” This 2
manner of Fortescue,
six-part division did not take hold.
The
three-
indicates that
Reniger
v.
Fogossa
however, not the same as Fortescue’s. Fortescue divides
all
laws, including those of England, into the law of nature, customs,
statutes.
realm (the
His customs encompass both the general customs of the
common
law)
and
local customs. In the Reniger
scheme, the word “customs” refers only to the “law general” refers to the
common
local, particular
law.
This
is
made
v.
Fogossa
customs, and
clear in a pas-
sage a few lines later that repeats the three-part division in slightly different language:
“And so we
see that
some Cases
shall
be construed con-
trary to Statutes, contrary to Customs, and contrary to the ordinary
course of the
One no
finds
common two
Law.”
'
different statements of the nature of the
common
law
Plowden s Commentaries
Plowden, one identifying the
in
identifying
with usage.
it
The
common
iii
law with reason and the other
statements identifying the
common Law ... is no other common Law is no other than pure
common law common rea-
with reason vary: “the
than
son” and “the
and tried reason.” 4
There
is
no elaboration of what
pure and tried reason.
I
meant by
is
common
either
common reason common erudition
suspect that
reason or
used as
is
syn-
a
onym
or parallel expression for the
in the
Year Books and Inns’ learning exercises of the fifteenth century.-'
Common
often mentioned
lawyers of the late fifteenth and early sixteenth centuries
still
had no doctrine of binding precedent. Their appeals to authority take
form not of
the
appeals to the
citations to the rulings of judges in earlier cases but of
common
learning acquired by
sion at the Inns of Court.
common
the
reason
law
What is common
all
members of
about the reason with which
identified in Plowden’s reports
is
is
not so
held for law throughout the entire realm but that
is
common
by the
legal profession.
Edward Coke, who
the profes-
Here we have
a
much
it is
that
held in
foreshadowing of Sir
identifies the “artificial reason” of the law with the
long training and experience of the lawyers. Still,
synonym of not merely being idiosyncratic when
the term reason as used in Plowden, ,
common
erudition. St.
German
is
is
not always
a
he identifies reason with the law of nature. In several instances recorded in
Plowden,
common
lawyers use reason to
mean
natural law. In Colthirst
Morgan states that “there are two principal Things from whence Arguments may be drawn, that is to say, our Maxims, and Reason, which is the Mother of all Laws.”
v.
Bejushin
(
Commentaries
1:27) for
example, Serjeant
Maxims, the immediate foundations of the common ular English “conclusions” of universal reason, and
law, are the particit is
for this reason
that they “ought not to be impugned, but always admitted”
(
Commen-
taries 1:27). 1
Sharington
v.
Strotton contains several unusual
the law of nature as one of the foundations of
common The .
.
.
and all
explicit citations
laws, including the
law.
Philosophers have searched so deeply for the
and
in their
Laws have commended us
Law
of Nature
to follow Nature, and
have taken Nature to be one of the Foundations whereupon
Laws
are based ...
Law were
we ought not
to think that the
remiss in searching after the
Law
of
all
Founders of our
of Nature, or that they
1
The Common Law Mind
12
were ignorant of greatest and
For there
also.
.
They who made them were Men of
as
with the
Law
Maxim
of the
common Law
.
.
.
and
Consideration of Nature ... so that
from Nature
is
Law of God God ... so that
of
this is
shall
be charged
grounded upon the
Consideration proceeding
a
Consideration in our Law. (Commen-
a sufficient
explicit citation of the law of nature
is
extraordinary. St.
correct in observing that the practice of the stitute reason for nature.
The
with
as well
1:304-6)
taries
The
Law
nothing ordained in our
is
the
of Reason, and the
Advancement of the Daughter the Father
for the a
.
.
most profound Judgment, and acquainted
Law of Nature,
the
by
it.
common
German
lawyers
is
is
to sub-
6
claim that nothing
is
common
to be found in the
trary to the law of reason or nature conflicts with
law that
what
St.
con-
is
German
taught earlier in the century. Indeed, this claim represents a minority
view even
in Plowden’s time. In Willion
v.
Berkley for Example, ,
it is
said
common Law did suffer it, nevertheless it was Wrong. And some Things the common Law does
that “notwithstanding the
not well done, but
a
permit to be done, which are tortious and wrong” ( Commentaries In Wimbish
For
v. Tailbois it is
at the
said of the Statute of
common Law
the Intent of the
Donor was
eluded, which was contrary to right and
therefore the Statute, being
made
Westminster
be extended by Equity
.
.
.
infringed and
to restrain that vicious Liberty of
for the
common
not permit him to be received, suffered I:
II:
good Conscience, and
breaking such Intents, which was suffered by the shall
1:247).
a
common
Law,
Law, which would
Wrong.
(
Commentaries
53)
It
might be thought that the apparent disagreement among sixteenth-
century
mon
common
lawyers on the question of the congruence of the
law with the law of nature can be explained
versal practice of advocates to
to help
win the case
at
make
as a
com-
product of the uni-
use of any arguments that promise
hand. But the arguments in Plowden’s reports on
this issue are
hardly extemporaneous inventions — they are
clearly part of the standard
equipment of the lawyers. LTless we are pre-
both sides of
pared to assume complete cynicism on their part, this suggests that the
common
lawyers are ambivalent about the relation of the
common
law
to a higher, universal law (whether conceived as reason, natural law, or
n3
Plow den ’s Commentaries
the law of God). VVe find this ambivalence throughout the history of the
common law. Besides common reason, and reason as the law of nature, the common law is also described in Plowden as “no other than pure and tried reason.”
This locution suggests
argument that English laws
similar to that represented in Fortescue’s
the best of
all
human
— one
a different idea altogether
laws, because they have
been
tried
through
are
a suc-
cession of English kingdoms and would have been rejected otherwise.
The
conceptualization of the
seems to be linked to identifies the
This
1:195).
reason” equivalent
second
a
law as “pure and tried reason”
set of statements in
Plowden, which
common Use” ( Commentaries two questions: Are “common use” and “common terms? Are they tied to the concept of common eru-
common raises
common
law as “nothing but
modes of reasoning, and cuscommon law beneh^md bar)? Despite the re-
dition (understood in the sense of learning,
tom or
practice of the
peated use of these terms in the cases reported by Plowden, to judge with assurance the
the identification of the is
made
meaning they had
common
law as
the phrase in question
— very much
as if
use or
v.
Adams Brown, ,
J.,
common
reason
few clues to the meaning of
counsel and judges are reciting
by rote tags of jurisprudence remembered from their case of Wrotesley
difficult
for their users. Typically,
common
cryptically, in a context providing
it is
and Dyer,
statement reported by Plowden identifying
C
.J.,
common
training. In the
make
the fullest
common
law with
use:
A Farm
is a
together,
collective
Word
whereof one
is
a
consisting of divers Things collected
Messuage, and the others are Lands,
Woods, Commons and other Things lying or appertaining thereto. And yet all this does not make it be called a Farm, if it has not another Thing also; and that is, that it has been
Meadows,
Pastures,
.
.
.
or demised to another for Life, for Years, or at Will. ... So
let
Farm contains and
it is
divers Things, as hath
a capital
Alessuage and
and demised, and so
Reason the Law
also
Is
is
nothing but
Grange
does;
Demesn which have been
let
commonly taken in every Place. For which says it is so, for the Law is the Custom in rela-
common
and Judgments, and the
Use. ( Commentaries
the law referred to as “the
Pleas,
said, as a
it is
tion to Letters, Counts, Pleas,
Law
great
a
been
a
Custom
and Judgments” thought of
common
1:195)
77
in relation to Letters, I
as different
from the
Counts,
common
law,
The Common Law Mind
n4 which
said to be “nothing but
is
erences in the passage are to the
one asks what kind of “the
Custom
law, in the three-part division
in relation to Letters,
not statutory law but
tom
common
pleas,
is
is
no
The custom
not the custom of the
is
It is
local, particular cus-
and judgments. Therefore,
law of the realm.
and judgments
of English law,
Counts, Pleas, and Judgments .”
form of custom. There
a
in respect to counts, pleas,
only be the
common Use?” I submit that both refcommon law. This becomes clear when
law can
this
in respect to counts,
folk.
Only lawyers and
judges have customs or usages in respect to these matters. This custom,
may also be understood
then,
bench and
son, of the
as the
common erudition,
common
Use”? Does
bench and
does
bar, or
common rea-
is
“nothing but
bar.
But what about the statement that the
common
or
it
have
a
common
law
use refer only to the
common
usages of
We cannot be sure. In
wider application?
the Wrotesley Case the judges state in respect to their definition of “farm” ,
that “so
it is
commonly taken
argument on the
basis of a
in every Place,”
common
and
this
appears to be an
usage broader than that merely of
judges and lawyers. This interpretation of the judges’ dictum in Wrotesley is
strengthened by an argument in Reniger
[YB 26 Hen. ment,
& c.
and
mon Usage at certain
ferred to
8] is in
this
is
agreement
after”
is
“Which
Payment or Agree-
intended to be executory, as the com-
usual to
clearly the usage of the vicars, parsons, is
and others
a
who
are
not the usage of lawyers in applying the
Lawyers, then, are accustomed to using the phrase
usage” in
Statute
make an Obligation for the Payment ( Commentaries 1:9). Here the common usage re-
it is
the subjects of the statute and statute.
Fogossa:
the disjunctive, and speaks of
proves, for
Days
v.
“common
sense that includes the usages of people in the ordinary
course of living and doing business.
It
seems most natural to read the
“commonly taken in every Place” in this sense. But we must remember that our question is whether sixteenthcentury lawyers, and particularly Justices Brown and Dyer, identify the Wrotesley phrase
common law with such standard practices of laymen. Wrotesley suggests that the common usages of the people indeed make up part of the common law, for Brown and Dyer add to their statement that the meaning they ascribe to “farm” sion, “for
is
“commonly taken
which Reason the Law
lematic association of the
also says
common
in every Place,” the conclu-
it is
so.”
A somewhat less prob-
law with custom
is
found
in the re-
cently published reports contained in the notebooks of Sir James Dyer.
In a 1558 case,
it is
Plowden V Commentaries
n5
common
law and
held that “by the custom of the
may be
order of the realm, and of that that court, no interest
granted by
letters patent.”
What may we now say of the sixteenth-century conception of the common law, if indeed a single such conception existed? In Plowden’s reports the common law is identified with both reason and usage. Reason is used in two senses: the common erudition of the legal profession and the law of nature. Usage
is
also used in
two
senses: the usage of those
learned in the law and the usage of the people.
weld these disparate ideas into
It is
tempting to try to
coherent sixteenth-century theory of
a
common law. It might be suggested, for example, that sixteenthcentury common lawyers assume, when they use any one of the several formulas found in Plowden, that their fellow lawyers possess a common the
jurisprudential framework, in which each sucjj formula has
its
heirarchy of concepts — much as in Doctor and Student. But
I
much
if
many
sixteenth-century
common
lawyers, any
place in a
doubt very
more than
counterparts today, had a conscious, coherent theory of the
their
common
law.
A
few lawyers, of course, such
century and
Thomas Hedley
as St.
German
shortly after
at the
its close,
beginning of the
had theoretically so-
phisticated understandings of the place of usage and reason in the
mon
law in the English legal system
as a
com-
whole. 8 Plowden’s Commentaries
themselves, by virtue of the fact that they report a few snatches of explicit jurisprudential discussions, fail into this exclusive category.
contemporary law reporters such
as Sir
James Dyer seldom report
cussions about such jurisprudential questions as the nature of the
mon
law, usage,
custom or
legal reason.
Other
g
dis-
com-
possible that such discus-
It is
sions frequently occurred in court and are unreported because the re-
porter assumed that every lawyer had received a solid grounding in the
fundamentals of jurisprudence Court. 10 Phis, however,
is
at the
Inns of Chancery and the Inns of
not the impression one gets from reading
wide range of sixteenth-century reports. profession with very
little
The
interest in legal philosophy,
go to the trouble of attempting to formulate
The
mon
profession has available to
law, several possible
description
pends
less
is
impression, instead,
it,
a
its
one that does not
out of the long history of the com-
ways of describing that
user’s sense of
of a
coherent jurisprudence.
law.
chosen for employment in any given
upon
is
a
what
a
Which
legal
particular
argument de-
coherent jurisprudence re-
The Common Law Mind
ii6
quires than
upon whether
present difficulty.
imagine
how
The modern
scholar can, by straining his ingenuity,
the sixteenth-century English lawyer might fashion a co-
herent theory of the little
that description will help his client out of his
common
law out of the materials
at
hand. There
is
evidence for such a theory in the sixteenth-century reports.
Equity, Statutes, and Interpretation St.
German’s principal concern with equity involves
remedies in the court of conscience, but
use as a basis for
its
century un-
as the sixteenth
folded, practitioners, in their court arguments, increasingly
on equity
as a principle
come
to rely
of statutory interpretation. By the fifteenth cen-
tury, the idea of the equity of a statute as a guide to interpretation a basis for
extending or restricting the words of a law came into
use,
and an understanding about
The
sixteenth century, though,
ration and development
In the classic
its
is
meaning and
limits
and
as
common
was developing.
the period of the idea’s greatest elabo-
11 .
modern treatment of
sixteenth- century
common
law
approaches to statutory interpretation, Samuel Thorne contends that “in a very real sense the history of statutory interpretation begins in the
sixteenth century.” 12 This that statutes
is
so,
he suggests, because
began to occupy
a
words of an
was only then
position roughly comparable to that
which they hold today and that judges in restricting the
it
first
became conscious
act ... or extending
them
that
to include
equally deserving but unmentioned cases, they were performing
something more than an incidental, routine function of
judicial
administration.
Although by the equity of
fifteenth century judges rely
a statute to justify
on the doctrine of the
the extension of a statute
beyond
its
words
and begin to develop rules to put some boundaries on the application of that doctrine, they as in
do not think of the process of applying the doctrine
any way involving
cial authority;
of justice
13 .
a potential conflict
they merely see
it
as a facet
In fact, although several rules
between
legislative
and judi-
of the routine administration
— such
as the
one holding that
penal statutes would not be taken by the equity — are announced in fifteenth-century cases, in practice the only principle that
extensions by the equity
is
lies
behind
the one stated by Paston: “lex beneficialis rei
Plow den ’s Commentaries
consimili
non
remedium
extendit.” It
is
praestat, odiosa
autem casu quo
only after acts of Parliament gain
acts
become
new
status
common
clear that in the sixteenth century
It is
of importance
a rule
lawyers
when
legislation
and au-
one be-
14 .
show an un-
precedented interest in problems of statutory interpretation. the Middle Ages,
7
efficitur vlterius
thority, in the sixteenth century, that such distinctions as the
tween penal and beneficial
11
1
'
Unlike in
“the government’s vague reply to
is
vaguely worded complaints,” constitutional developments in legislative
procedure lead “to an increased concentration on the text of
bills, as
containing the propositions to which each house in turn was asked to give
assent,” with the result that a text
its
is
16
produced that has been con-
sidered
word by word by the lawmakers
Thorne
suggests that the evolution of doctrine about statutory interpre-
.
But
it is
not nearly
principally driven by such changes irup'arliamentary procedure.
tation
is
While
it is
plausible to conjecture that such constitutional developments
should have an effect on judicial thinking about statutes, to say with confidence just
do not
as clear as
what that
explicitly discuss statutes in
opments.
very
It is
clear,
effect
is
it is
impossible
common
since the
lawyers
terms of those parliamentary devel-
not only from the treatises but also from the
case reports, that lawyers’ views
on interpretation
are also being influ-
enced by exposure to the writings of Aristotle (sometimes through the
medium civilians
of
a
medieval commentator), of
and canonists
Roman
rhetoricians,
and of
1 .
The most striking difference between
the later Year
Books and the
re-
ported cases in the second half of the sixteenth century in the treatment of issues of statutory interpretation involves the degree to which the
six-
teenth-century lawyers frame such issues in terms of the intent of the
makers
(lentent del feasors)?*
nouncements that those
There
are occasional fifteenth-century pro-
statutes are to be construed according to the intent of
who made them,
but in Plowden’s reports the intent becomes
predominant focus of interpretation
words of an
act,
19 .
a
Questions about extending the
or of taking exceptions out of them, are
still
frequently
discussed in terms of the equity of a statute, but then, as likely as not,
what that equity requires In Reniger
v.
Fogossa
,
is
made
to
depend on
legislative intent.
Saunders, one of the king ’s sergeants, even ex-
plains the force of the principle that the makers’ intent
is
to guide to in-
terpretation in terms of legislative intent: “It has always been the
mind
of the legislature, that their intent should be observed in the construe-
ii8
The Common Law Mind
$
tion of statutes”
makers an
(
Commentaries
1:82).
He
goes on to cite the intent of the
as a general justification for taking exceptions
out of the words of
act:
Where
the words of a statute are general, as they are in this case,
all
things which are within the general words are not taken within the
purview of the
statute; but
such things as the makers of the statute
meant; so that the intent of the legislature
and
shall abridge the generality
The words
of a statute,
For example, in Reniger
the judge of the words,
of xhem.(Co?mnentaries
1:10)
frequently said, do not settle what the law
it is
v.
is
is.
Fogossa Serjeant Pollard states:
For in every law there are some things which when they happen
man may break the words
of the law and yet not break the law
and such things are exempted out of the penalty of the
a
itself;
and the
law,
law privileges them although they are done against the letter of it,
for breaking the
words of the law
the intent of the law
is
is
not breaking the law, so as
not broken. ... So that the efficacy of
statutes consists not only of the words, but in the intent thereof,
which intent ought always to be considered, and made agreeable with the words. rects the words,
.
.
.
And
so the intent of the makers of statutes di-
and the equity of them. ( Commentaries
In a similar vein, Saunders, in Panridge that “words,
which
are
v.
Stange and Croker, asserts
no other than the verboration of the
constitute the statute, but are only the image of statute rests in the
1:18)
it,
and the
minds of the expositors of the words, that
ers of the statutes”
(
Commentaries
such statements justifying
a
1:82). It
air,
life is
do not of the
the
mak-
should not be imagined that
departure from the words of an act on the
basis of legislative intent are limited to advocates seeking to avoid the
evident meaning of a law; the judges frequently express a similar ap-
proach to statutory interpretation. In Stradling all
v.
Morgan
,
for example,
of the barons of the exchequer agree that although “treasures, re-
ceivers, or ministers
accountant of
words of the statute (YB
7
common
persons” are within the
Edw. VI), they are not within
its
purview or
penalty because “the intent of the makers of the Act was only to punish the treasurers, receivers, and ministers of the King, and not of
persons”
(
Commentaries
1:203).
20
common
After citing several precedents for de-
parting from the letter of statutes, Saunders, Chief Baron, concludes:
n9
Plozvden V Commentaries
From which
cases
appears, that the sages of the law heretofore
it
have construed statutes quite contrary to the letter in some appearance, and those statutes which
comprehend
things in the
all
letter,
they have expounded to extend but to some things, and those which generally prohibit
people from doing such an
all
terpreted to permit
some people
to
do
it,
they have in-
act,
and those which include
every person in the letter they have adjudged to reach to some persons only, which interpretations have always been founded upon ( Commentaries 1:205).
the intent of the makers. Finally, in Eyston
Studd
v.
the intent of the makers
For they took
all
is
the judges of the
Common Bench agree that
determinative in statutory interpreteation:
that the intent of statutes
it
than the precise
letter
is
more
to be regarded
of them, for oftentimes things, which are
within the words of statutes, are out of the purview of them, which
purview extends no further than the intent of the makers of the Act,
and the best way to construe an Act of Parliament the intent rather than according to the words.
(
a statute for the
letter is unclear,
it is
makers’ intent
sometimes
is
according to
Commentaries 2:464)
Although the understanding may not be that words of
is
a
search beyond the
appropriate only
said that the intent sould
when
be sought
the
if
the
words are unclear: [Montague, terms and
C.J.:] First,
letter
we have
a
learning in our law, that
of any statute are obscure and
difficult to
we ought to have recourse to the intent of thereby we shall come at the meaning of the letter. statutes have always
the the
be under-
the makers, and
stood,
ambiguous words of
if
.
.
.
And
thus the
been expounded accord-
ing to the intent of the makers ... so that the intent of the legislators
is
to be sought for in the exposition of the
statutes, I:
and the
letter shall
ambiguous words of
be aided by the intent.
(
Commentaries
—
57 58)
The
author of A Treatise Concerning Statutes gives the intent of the legis-
lators a similarly central place in interpretation:
For when the words express not the intent of the Makers, the Statute must be further extended than the bare words, but ever
it
must be thought that the meaning of the Makers'was such, when
The Common Law Mind
120
there
is
any proceeding other than the words
surd thing to
make an
bear, for
it
were an ab-
exposition go further than either the words,
or the intention of the Statutaries reached unto. 21
Of
course,
intent, cise
and
if
if
statutory interpretation
that intent
is
to be
is
more than
by the makers’
to be guided a fictional
cover for the exer-
of judicial discretion, eventually consideration has to be given to the
how the intent can be known. In the second half of the sixcentury, we are still far from anything like a scientific approach to
question of teenth
uncovering
legislative intent,
that intent
is
slight, that
not least because documentary evidence of
generally unavailable; but there
common
some evidence, even
is
lawyers are beginning to think about such prob-
lems. For example, after Saunders argues, in Panridge ker,
that “the
words, that
Strange a?id Cro-
v.
of the statute rests in the minds of the expositors of its
life
is,
if
the makers of the statutes,” he adds, “and
persed, so that their
they are dis-
minds cannot be known, then those who may ap-
proach nearest to their minds sages of the the law
if
whose
meritaries 1:82). Saunders
is
shall
construe the words^and these are the
talents are exercised in such matters”
(
Com -
proposing no investigatory technique in thus
suggesting that questions about legislative intent be
left
standing of the judges, but his statement does show
a
to the under-
recognition that
questions might exist concerning what has been in the minds of the
makers.
Sometimes,
as in Fulmerston v.
Steward the suggestion
is
,
made
intent “must” be as the lawyer contends because anything else
unreasonable:
“it
avoid leases newly it is
would be
cannot be reasonably taken that such was the intent of
the makers of the statute, for
Morgan ),
that the
it
would be against
made” ( Commentaries
1:109).
all
reason and equity to
Other times ( Stradling
v.
openly acknowledged that the intent of the makers regard-
ing particular words has been established by presumption: “and so they [the judges]
have qualified the rigour of the word (presently) according to
reason, in such
manner
as the intent
presumed to be” ( Commentaries
of the makers of the Act might be
1:205).
Edmund
Plowden’s
bution to the problem of identifying the makers’ intent
commentary on
And
the case of Eyston
in order to
restrained,
form
a right
v.
is
own
contri-
found in
his
Studd
judgment when the
and when enlarged, by equity,
it is
a
peruse a statute, to suppose that the law-maker
letter
of a statute
is
good way when you is
present, and that
Plow den
you have asked him the question you want equity, then
Commentaries
's
to
know touching
you must give yourself such an answer
he would have done,
if
legislative intent. In
as
the
you imagine
he had been present. ( Commentaries
more empirical approach
Occasionally, a
121
is
suggested for determining
perhaps the most famous of these, Dyer,
Stowell v. Lord Zouch, describes the preamble of an act as “a key to
C.J., in
pen the
minds of the makers of the Act, and the mischiefs which they intended to redress” ( Commentaries 1:369). Saunders, Chief Baron, after describing in Stradling
v.
Morgan how
the judges sometimes construe statutes
more
widely and sometimes more narrowly than their words, and stating that
such expositions “have always been founded upon the intent of the Legislature,”
adds that the intent
is
“collected sometimes by considering the
cause and necessity of making the Act, sometimes by comparing one part
of the act with another, and sometimes by foreign circumstances” (Commentaries 1:205).
The
author of
A
— the problem of collective
the fact that in considering the
legisla-
intent, or, as the author phrases
mind of
the problem that “so manie heades as statute makers, so
and Understandinge of
one of the sources of modern disputes about
Statutes anticipates tive intent
Discourse upon the Exposition
it
it,
the legislature one encounters
were, so
many
many myndes.” 23 Notwithstanding
wittes; so
this
many
problem, the
author contends, there are ways of knowing legislative intent. For example, there is
always the possibility that the makers of a law
may have
ex-
pressed their minds on an issue, and “if they have not gyven any declara-
cion of theire myndes, then in use,
is
to be sene
how
the statute hathe bene put
and theire authoritye must persuade us that were moost neerest
the statute.” 24
In the cases reported by Plowden, extensions and restrictions of the
words of statutes are often islators.
On
justified
by reference to the intent of the leg-
other occasions, however, such departures from the letter
are explained in terms of the equity of a statute.
how
The
question, then, of
the principle of interpretation by makers’ intention
to relate to the doctrine of the equity of a statute
Plowden reports no equity.
Sometimes
it
is
is
understood
most
interesting.
explicit discussions of the relationship of intent
appears that the two terms are viewed as essentially
equivalent. Serjeant Pollard, for example, arguing in Reniger that a statute
is
and
v.
Fogossa
penal, protests against an interpretation that goes be-
The Common Law Mind
i22
yond the
on the ground
letter,
wrests the words to
Molineux,
J.,
a
that
the coverage of the statute, “and
mentaries
it
“puts
a gloss
upon
the text, and
kind of intent and equity” ( Commentaries
once argued ( Wimbish
statute, then ...
it
v. Tailbois)
if it
1:17). is
within
letter
of the
that a situation
was not within the
And
should be within the equity and intent of
it”
(
Co?n -
1:50).
The problem with not quite the same
these examples
as the “intent
notes a purposive state of
is
that the “intent of the statute”
of the makers”; the latter phrase con-
mind on
the part of the legislators, but in the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries the former likely
more than “the meaning of
is
the statute.”
We
come
meant nothing
closer to an explana-
tion of the connection between equity and the intent of the makers in
an argument by Saunders, in Partridge
though
The
a statute is penal,
statute
is
it
v.
Strange and Croker that even ,
should be interpreted equitably
penal, but because the expositors of the statute took
the intent of the makers of cases of like nature, that
to be such, viz. to give
it
the reason thereof.
is
And
damages
in
so the intent of
the makers of statutes directs the words, and the equity of them. (
Commentaries
There is
is
1:82)
reason for thinking that this view (that
that legislative intent
is,
the guide to the content of the equity of a statute) was the most
mon
understanding in the
late sixteeth century.
Treatise Concerninge Statutes
,
tion of statutes into
two
“according to equity”
2 -
The
com-
author of the
for example, after dividing the interpreta-
sorts
— “according
— immediately
to the precise
adds: “For
when
words” and
the words express
not the intent of the Makers, the statute must be further extended than the bare words.” 26 This ders,
who
is
consistent with the analysis of Serjeant Saun-
argues in Reniger
v.
should be taken by the equity mentaries
Fogossa that although a statute if
such are the minds of
its
is
penal,
it
makers ( Co?n
1:10).
Plowden, in
pended to
his
famous discussion of interpretation and equity ap-
his report
of Eyston
v.
Studd seems to have ,
a similar
under-
standing. After stating that the general words of statutes are often cor-
rected and abridged by equity, he gives as an example of equitable interpretation the case of an undersheriff
who took twenty pence more
than permitted by statute from prisoners in his custody, an action upheld by the court. Plowden contends that
Plowden V Commentaries
the
payment of
and
it
with reason and good conscience,
this fee stands
was not the intent of the makers of the Act to take
From which
case
it
123
it
away.
appears that equity or epichaia puts an excep-
tion to the generality of the text of the statute law.
(
Commentaries
2:465) /
As another example of equitable the Statute of Westminster at sea that if a
I,
interpretation,
cap. 4,
which provides regarding
“man, dog, or cat” should escape
goods found were to be held
Plowden considers
and
for a year
from
alive
a
wreck any
a ship,
a day, to give the
owner an
opportunity to seek their return, and penalties are to be imposed for an
But what of perishable goods that
earlier disposal of the goods. last for
the time prescribed by the statute? If the sheriff immediately
them, Plowden
says,
goods within
has punctually observed
a year, yet it,
ports
is
that the
to be
happening
common
tional learning: that
^the
as
law.
(
he has observed the intent
Commentaries 2:466)
in the period
lawyers
words of the law by
he has not broken the law, but
inasmuch
and meaning of the makers of the
What appears
sells
he should not be punished because
although the sheriff has done contrary to selling the
not
will
covered by Plowden’s re-
uneasily hold
still
on
any departure from the words of
described in terms of the equity of a statute.
The
to their tradi-
a statute
is
to be
fifteenth-century con-
ception of that equity as merely having the function of extending the
words of the law to cases
in the
same mischief is on the way to breaking
down, however. In several cases the judges are willing to depart from the words of
a
rectly rely
law by taking exceptions to
it;
on the intent of the makers
statute, they
move beyond
in the next century,
still
beyond
by coming to
that,
di-
in establishing the equity of a
the de similibus principle.
It is
true that Coke,
defines equity in fifteenth-century terms, but
the judicial practice after the middle of the sixteenth century does not reflect so limited a
In the
view of the doctrine. 2
many references
the principle of similarity
found
in
to the equity of a statute in Plowden’s reports, is
seldom mentioned. 2 *
Robert Brook’s argument
in Reniger
v.
One
such reference
Fogossa in ,
is
which he says
of an old decision that “the ancient fathers of the law, seeing that those cases were in equal mischief, took
them
to be in like law, and in such
sense they construed the minds of the makers of the statute, out of mere
The Common Law Mind
124
necessity to avoid a mischief” trates
Commentaries
(
what appears to be happening: the search
the cause of the
making of the
statute
is
may
not certain; an important element
illus-
for the mischief that
was
being reconceptualized as
search for the intent of the legislators. Just what is
This passage
1:13).
is
a
driving this evolution
be the developing understand-
ing of the place of Parliament in the English constitution.
Despite the growing importance of the intent of the legislature in law interpretive practice and theory — and of the close associa-
common
tion of that interpretive principle with the doctrine of the equity of a statute
— it
should not be thought that the
bethan England settled on
Sometimes the equity of
makes
seem
less like a principle
ing at an outcome that seems
Robert Brook, for example, ster, cap. 3
(Reniger
v.
a statute
is
lawyers of Eliza-
view of the equity of a
a single, consistent
statute. it
common
described in a
way
that
of interpretation than a basis for arrivreasonable, or merciful to the judges.
fair,
states in regard to the Statute of
Westmin-
Fogossa ):
But the ancient fathers of our
law, considering the said statute,
saw
should be taken according to the words, great inconvenience
if it
would follow from thence
.
statute according to equity
allow of
some
.
.
and therefore they construed the said
and reason, although the words did not
but seemed against
it,
it;
so that in
all
statutes there are
private cases excepted out of the general provision by equity
of reason, in avoidance of a greater mischief. ( Commentaries
1:13)
Serjeant Pollard, in the same case, asserts:
And
therefore the words of the law of nature, of the law of the
realm, and of the law of
some that
acts
is,
God
also will will yield
and give way to
and things done against the minds of the same laws, and
where the words of them
are
broken to avoid greater incon-
veniences, or through necessity, or by compulsion, or involuntary
ignorance.
Montague, tial
(
Commentaries
C.J.,
1:18)
on more than one occasion openly considers poten-
mischief and hardship in arriving
Dive
v.
great,
Maninghatn he
it
states,
(
an interpretation of a statute. In
“And therefore seeing the mischief was so
cannot be taken but that
statute to cure it”
at
Commentaries
it
was the intent of the makers of the
1:67).
And
in Partridge
Croker he says, “For to construe the statute, that he,
who
v.
is
Strange and
in possession
Plow den
shall
not make
v.
all
would be
reason and equity” ( Commentaries
Lord Zouch, Brown,
Commentaries
I2 5
bargain, or feoffment, except he has been in pos-
a lease,
session, or taken the profits for a year before,
contrary to
's
J.,
a
hard law, and
1:88). Finally, in
Stowel
urges the general interpretive principle that
the mischiefs and inconveniences, which are in the
letter,
are to be
considered and avoided by the application of reason, and by putting
such construction on the law positive
as shall exclude all rigours
mischiefs, and stand with equity and
and
good reason. ( Commentaries
0363)
To modern
eyes, a theory of interpretation in
judges to read statutes in such mischiefs
may be
is a
way as to avoid hardships, rigor, and enormous discretion to judges and that
a
theory that grants
difficult to reconcile
which equity requires
with the frequently stated rule that equi-
table interpretation involves following the intept of the legislators.
implication in 1615:
is
This
recognized by Lord Ellesmere in The Earl of Oxford's Case
“And the judges themselves do play the Chancellors Parts upon
Statutes,
making Construction of them according
to Equity, varying
from the Rules and Grounds of Law, and enlarging them pro bono publico against the Letter and Intent of the Makers.”-
The
great interpretive discretion of judges
9
is
widely acknowledged in
the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries.
The
author of the
contends that
Treatise Conceiving Statutes
the Sages of the law
whose wits
are exercised in such matters, have
the interpretation in their hands, and their Authority
taketh in hand to control: wherefore their Power high, and
we seek
,
is
no man
very great, and
these Interpretations as Oracles from their
mouthes. 30 Justice If
Hobart makes
a similar
assessment:
you ask me then, by what
this diverse exposition
swer,
it
rule the judges guided themselves in
of the self-same word and sentence?
I
an-
was by that liberty and authority which judges have over
laws, according to reason
and best convenience, to mould them to
31 the truest and best use.
Not every lawyer of the discretion a
good
period thinks the exercise of such interpretive
thing, even
if
the Elizabethan case reports are remark-
The Common Law Mind
u6
ably free of reported
demands
for strict interpretation
and of protests
about the dangers of departing from the statutory words. 32 Ellesmere, noting that judges “played the Chancellor’s part” in construing
after
statutes, suggests that
cellor sits in
Power, and
is
it is
Chancery according
to an absolute
to judge according to that
the judges of the
“The Chan-
inappropriate for them to do so:
Common Law are
dinary (or limited) Power.” 33
It is
which
is
and uncontrollable
alleged and proved; but
to judge according to a strict
established doctrine, says Ellesmere,
that “the Acts and Statutes of Parliament ought to be revers’d
ment
(only)
It is
power
and or-
by
Parlia-
and not otherwise.” 34
unclear whether those lawyers and judges to enlarge or restrain the
who
advocate
words of statutes pro bono
a judicial
do so
publico
because of their understanding of the nature of equity or whether this
view of the
judicial role
There does appear
is
unconnected to how they understand equity.
to be in the Elizabethan period a substantial dis-
agreement about the nature of the equity that guides interpretation the
common
law courts.
more
surface, to
easily
The view
of equity that appears,
on the
support the use of wide judicial discretion
Aristotelian conception cited by Catline, C.J., in Stowel
“And Catline
at least
said, that Aristotle defines
rectio justae legis qua parte deficit
v.
in
is
the
Lo?'d Zouch:
equity thus, Aequitas est cor-
quod generatim
lata est”
(
Commen-
taries 1:375).
This understanding of equity rects
it is
Eyston
v.
as
something outside the law that cor-
repeated and elaborated by Plowden in his
Studd.
Plowden suggests that equity operates
applies the de similibus principle
first
commentary on in
two ways: one
described in English law by Bracton
and that was the staple of the fifteenth- century Year Books; the other “enlarges or diminishes the letter according to
its
discretion” and
is
the
kind described by Catline in the Stowel Case ( Commentaries 2:467, 465).
The
equity that worked a “correction of the general words
in the law of England,” a
way
uity,
Plowden
asserts,
is
called
by some epichaia
generality of the text for
.
.
much
used
and he goes on to describe
that gives considerable latitude to those
which
is
.
some reasonable
who would
apply
it:
it
in
“Eq-
often puts an exception to the cause.” Unlike the other kind
of equity, which applies the reason contained within the law, this equity,
Plowden
says, “is
no part of the
the law,” and judges, in using
it,
law,
but a moral virtue which corrects
“have softened the severity of the text
and made the law tolerable” {Commentaries 2:466).
Plow den's Commentaries
Edward Hake,
I2 7
in his Epieikeia takes pointed issue with Plowden’s ,
un-
derstanding of equity.? 5 Loveless, a character in Hake’s dialogue, expresses concern about judicial discretion:
A man
would thincke that where the lawe
discretion of ye judge
above ye lawe
(as
it is
is
any waye
lefte to the
either for that the judge hath authoritie
to alter ye lawe at his discretion) or els that in the
exposition of ye lawe hee hath power to use or not to use Equity ac-
cording to his discretion
36 ,
Hake, the character who speaks for the author, attempts to assuage these concerns by describing an understanding of equity that
differs
markedly
from Plowden’s Aristotelian conception:
Whereas
Equity
is
bated that that saying
were
a
be adhibita
said to
legi, it
hath bin therein also de-
not so to be understood as thoughe Equity
is
thing owt of the lawe of beside the lawe, or as
were the
if it
Equity of the judge, and not of the lawe, but that the Equity thereby
ment
is
to be taken (as
Equity, in this view, side the law (possibly failed; it is
This
is
is
it is
indeede) to be within the lawe
3 .
not something that the judge brings from out-
from
his
own
discretion) to correct
found within the law and expresses
the position taken by St.
German
its
it
when
it
has
underlying reason.
earlier in the century.
Of
course, the assumption that such a conception of equity would in practice
impose serious
limits
on
judicial discretion
is
questionable at best;
lawyers and judges could be just as ingenious at imagining a
accord with their inclinations as
at
ratio legis in
concluding that equity supports their
views.
know whether the Plowden version or the Hake verwas more widely accepted by practitioners of the period;
It is difficult
sion of equity
to
with the exception of Chief Justice Catline, they do not express themselves
on the subject
of equity as
a
in court
argument.
It
might be argued that the view
moral virtue that corrects the law
is
more
theoretically
compatible with the practice of shaping interpretation to lessen hardship or mischief. In practice, though, under the other view, an inventive
lawyer or judge could just as easily argue that is
a central
reason of the law
to abate the kind of hardship at risk in the case.
Just as in the fifteenth century, the doctrine of the equity of the statute serves in the sixteenth century as a justification for avoiding a
The Common Law Mind
u8
rigid, literal statutory interpretation. It
is
difficult to avoid the
sion, however, that despite the frequent references to is
not
tion.
a
it
impres-
in the reports,
it
doctrine that serves an important analytical or ideological func-
One
does not find in the sixteenth- century reports
much
evidence
of the kind of sharp ideological division over strict and equitable inter-
among Roman lawyers of certain periods or among medieval civilians. And despite the evidence that at least certain
pretation that one finds
of the lawyers are familiar with the writings of Aristotle, the classical rhetoricians, and civilians
to use very
little
those sources.
and canonists, the discussions in the cases put
of the arsenal of arguments and analysis to be found in
CHAPTER
Sir
J.
SIX
Common Law Mind
John Davies and the
G. A. Pocock’s description of the common law mind has
for
more
common common law
than forty years dominated scholarly discussion of the way lawyers of the early seventeenth century understood the
and
its
place in the English legal and political order. Central to his inter-
pretation of the
he
calls the
common
lawyers
s
jurisprudence of that period
is
what
doctrine of the ancient constitution. This doctrine, he ar-
gues, was shaped by the assumptions, first,
that
all
the law in England might properly be called
law; second, that
common
law was
common
common
custom, originating in
the usages of the people and declared, interpreted and applied in the courts; third, that
all
custom was by definition immemorial, that
which had been usage and law since time out of mind, so that any declaration of law, judgment or (with not quite the same certainty) statute,
was
immemorial
The common came
a declaration that its
content had been usage since time
1
.
lawyers,
Pocock contends, “holding that law was custom,
to believe that the
common
law,
and with
it
the constitution, had
always been exactly what they were now, that they were immemorial .” 2
Pocock supports tion,
his thesis
and the mentalite he
about the doctrine of the ancient constitu-
calls the
common
law mind, almost entirdy
with quotations from Sir Edward Coke and Sir John Davies, but he holds that the doctrine and the outlook were widely shared by
common
lawyers of their time:
But by Coke’s time the increasing activity of
monarchy had made
it
seem
to
most
common
nearly sovereign
a
lawyers that
if a
right
y
129
I
The Common Law Mind
3°
was to be rooted .
.
The
.
in
idea of the
custom
...
it
must be shown to be immemorial.
immemorial therefore took on an absolute
oring. ... It ceased to be a convenient fiction
serted as literal historical truth
common
Important
and was heatedly
same lawyers and
3
lawyers in the early seventeenth century certainly
“common
they had Pocock’s
their equally
quently spoke of the
as-
.
did sometimes talk and write in ways that plausibly as suggesting that
col-
prominent
common law in ways
legal
may be
interpreted
law mind,” but those
contemporaries also
fre-
that are hard to reconcile with
the Pocockian interpretation.
At the beginning of the seventeenth century, Pocock argues, the com-
mon
lawyers came to conceive of the
common
law as the
common
cus-
tom of the realm, and the myth of the law’s immemorial antiquity became central to that conception. The strongest basis for this contention is
found in
Sir
identifies the
John Davies’s preface
common law more
lawyer before or since
strongly with custom than any
which he
common
4 .
Common Lawe of England is nothing else but the Common
For the
custome of the Realme; and force of a lawe,
made
to his Irish reports, in
is
a
custome which hath obtained the
always said to be lus non scriptnm; for
it
cannot be
or created, either by Charter or by Parliament, which are Acts
reduced to writing, and are alwaies matter of Record; but in use and practise,
it
can be recorded and registered no where, but in the
memory of the For
a
people.
Custome taketh beginning and groweth
When
this
manner:
and
beneficiall to the people,
position, then
a
reasonable act once done,
do they use
it
is
to perfection in
found to be good
and agreeable to their nature and and practise
it
dis-
againe, and againe; and
so by often iteration and multiplication of the act,
it
becometh
a
Custome, and being continued without interruption time out of mind,
it
And lent,
obtaineth the force of a law.
this
Customary Lawe
is
the
for
the edicts of Princes,
perfect,
and most excel-
make and preserve a the written lawes which are made eyther by or by counsells of Estate, are imposed upon
and without comparison the
Common-wealth;
most
best, to
the Subject before any Triall or Probation made, whether the same
Sir John Davies
be
fit
breed any inconvenience or no. But
will
doth never become
law to bind the people, until
a
and approved time out of mind; during thereby arise no inconvenience, for nient at any time,
consequently
I
had
it
if it
all
lost the virtue
common
of talking about the
had been found inconve-
law
is
“nothing
common
law,
identifies the English
identification
is
else
Common
but the
but he departs from tradition in
common law as common usage the usage or
law."
following an established
is
an important way. Unlike sixteenth-century
mean only
hath been tried
which time there did
and force of a
custome of the Realme,” Davies arguably
describing the
it
Custome
a
had been used no longer, but interrupted, and
it
In asserting that the
always
3
and agreeable to the nature and disposition of the people, or
whether they
mode
I
common lawyers, who in or common custom nearly
custom of the bench and
people as the source of the
an occasionally recurring fiction
several centuries, but in appearing to take this
bar,
Davies
common law. Such an in the common law for
and other
fictions liter-
how the characteristics of the comfictions make the common law “the most
Davies attempts to demonstrate
ally,
mon
law represented in those
perfect,
and most excellent, and without comparison the best” law in the
world. 6 In the fifteenth century, Sir John Fortescue claims that English
customary law
is
does not compare finds it is
it
better than any other nation’s
to be better than statute law because statutes are
known whether
no,” while a
law, but he
favorably to English statutory law. Davies does, and
it
they are
sition of the people, or
it
customary
“fit
imposed before
and agreeable to the nature and dispo-
whether they
will
“custome doth never become
a
breed any inconvenience or law to bind the people untill
hath bin tried and approved time out of mind”
(
Works
2:251).
Davies pursues two distinct lines of argument in praising English cus-
tomary
law.
The
first
and disposition of framed and
holds that law must be appropriate to the nature
a people.
fitted to the
English customary law, he claims,
(
Works
2:255).
^
the English people’s particular nature because they “have
that formeth
course, vides
is
all
their
her
wisedome and experience
web out of her
selfe only).”
(like a
ls
it
fated to
made
their
silke-worme
This argument, of
directed at the advantages of customary law in general;
no reason
“so
nature and disposition of this people ... so as
cannot possibly be ruled by any other law”
owne Lawes out of
is
it
pro-
to prefer English to French or any other national cus-
132
The Common Law Mind
>
tomary
second
law. In his
of argument, Davies suggests that because
line
custom, by definition, does not become law until
approved time out of mind,
it is
bound
a
has been tried and
and incon-
to have fewer defects
veniences than laws instituted without long
Davies finds
it
trial
and experience. 8
kind of wisdom and reason in custom that surpasses
anything an individual or legislature can devise. In extolling the com-
mon
law for
its
reasonableness, he
civil
more reason
and canon law)
qualify
as law.
it
g
for the
After
common
of reason” (Works 2:259). If the
all
mere presence of reason
there are
it is
law
law, that
common
in the
First, the
not likely to match (Works
vantage the lie,
law.
is
is
necessary to
nothing but
no
2:255).
common
a rule
special merit in
common
many
trialls”
wisdom and.reason
Th e common this respect,
law
neces-
that legis-
is
no better
however.
The
ad-
law has over the other systems of customary law
then, in the peculiar
“England having had
law
civil
According to Davies,
“long experience and
than any other nations customary law in
must
“law
reason, there
is
sary to produce customary law ensured a is
minimum
two things that make the wisdom and reason of the
law extraordinary.
lation
reasonable. But he wants to
law than the
common
maxim, appropriated by the
reasonableness; a custom
is its
he himself quotes the standard
all,
law
law definition of customary law
can never attain the status of law unless claim
common
squarely within the
common
tradition. Indeed, part of the
(imported from the
is
a
wisdom and
virtue of the English people:
good and happy Genius from the beginning,
hath beene inhabited alwaies with
a
vertuous and wise people,
embraced honest and good Customes,
full
who
ever
of reason and convenience”
(Works 2:254). 10
Pocock suggests pure sense
in
upon custom, in word than upon the activity of
that “Coke’s emphasis
which Davies uses the
judges in constantly refining the law.”
1
It is
is
less
certainly true that in the
common
law
is
customary law and
is
cerned to draw implications from that conception. In preface, the active agents in the shaping of the
the
first
several pages of his preface to his Irish reports Davies concentrates
the idea that the
the
on
primarily conthis part
of his
common law appear to
be
the wise and virtuous English people. But in the remainder of the pref-
ace
it is
not the people
wisdom, is
gravitie,
not explicit on
labor: the people
preserve
it:
who
get the credit but rather “the great learning,
and constancies of our Judges” (Works this point,
form the
2:261).
Davies
but he seems to have in mind a division of
common
law,
and the judges articulate and
Si?- John
and the Law, which
If therefore Justice,
Justice,
no
ilie,
be so necessary for city,
all
hut
a rule
how
needful it
the service of learned
is
the rules of the Law,
ing, or the course of
if
proceeding
men
cannot possibly stand?
selfe
no man did study the reason of the Law,
memory
or lesson of
persons, times and places, as no fam-
the law, without which Justice if
133
no common-wealth, no kingdome, can stand without
the support thereof;
For
is
Davies
if
.
no man kept
in .
.
in
no man knew the forme of pleadin the law,
the publique Justice in a short time, or
how
what would become of
should the benefit of the
law be derived and communicated unto the people? For as in
a nat-
body the reasonable soule cannot use or transmit any of her
urall
powers, but by speciall organs of the same bodie, disposed and
by nature for every function,
fitted
as the eye to see, the eare to
heare, the tongue to speake, and the like of the rest: so in the
Common-Wealth,
of a
politique
thereof, produceth
no
Law, which
the
effect or operation at^all, but
is
body
the soule
by such of her
Ministers as by art and experience are enabled and qualified for her service.
(
Works 2:275)
In the preface to his Irish reports, Davies writes “to vindicate the use
of English law in Irish courts,” but in The Question Conce?~ning bnpositions, Tonnage Poundage Prizage Customs &c., he writes for
pose— to law in
a
,
,
,
,
vindicate the king’s prerogative
very different
to exalt the
common
light.
12
In the
presents the
situation,
first
law; in the second,
— and
it
a different
does not.
it
suits his
The
pur-
common purposes
technical ques-
tion he sets out to answer in the second chapter of The Question Concern-
ing bnpositions instituted
is
by the
whether the customs duties payable to the Crown were
common
law or by statute. In the course of answering
common law that may lead us to wonder whether his description of the common law in his Irish reports should best be seen as a reflection of the common law mind or this question,
merely
Davies says some things about the
as the effort
the task at hand. the
of an advocate
Much more
power of the king
is
who is making the
at stake in the
best case he can for
impositions debate than
to levy impositions; the broader question concerns
the nature and sources of the king’s authority and
power
in
and the relationship of that authority and power to English In this dispute, Davies
comes down
solidly
prerogative unconstrained by England’s laws. the
common
on the
He
government law.
side of a royal
argues that neither
law nor statutes gives the power to collect customs to the
134
The Common Law Mind
•
Crown; they
arise
from the law of nations.
proposition that “Jus Gentium equal force in
Law ity
all
Kingdoms,
of Nations” ( Impositions
9).
quotes Justinian for the
or the generall
,
for
He
all
Kingdoms had
From
Law
of Nations,
their beginning
of
is
by the
the origin of kingdoms by author-
of the law of nations, Davies not only draws conclusions about the
king’s legal right to duties and impositions; he also draws
more funda-
mental conclusions about the king’s relationship to the laws of England,
both statutory and customary. His authorities on the question of the
England
king’s prerogative and of his relationship to the law of
most without exception, Roman law
many
prerogative in England find that
power support admirably the
authorities.
of the
are, al-
Defenders of the royal
Roman
texts
on imperial
king’s claims of prerogative if “king”
substituted for “emperor.” Indeed they find that civilian jurists their path easier
dom est
by creating the doctrine that
a
is
made
own king-
king has in his
those powers that the emperor holds in the empire ( Rex in regno suo
imperator). Davies defends his position against the charge that the
rules of imperial law he uses as authorities apply only to the
emperor and
not to the king of England by quoting “a learned Civilian”: “Plus habet Rex in Regno
quam Imperator
regnum ad successionem quod non
in imperio, quia
facit
Rex
juris
transmittit
imperator, qui est tantum elec-
tionis, &c.” (Impositions 21). It is
important for those
or to expand
it
at the
who
set
out to defend the royal prerogative,
expense of statute and
common
law, to establish its
origins and authority as independent of any customs of the people or any
parliamentary grant. As in the case of the
time
a royal
ple, there is
power
is
lex regia in
Roman
said to derive, directly or indirectly,
also be
withdrawn. That
pains to claim that the king’s prerogative
is
any
from the peo-
always the possibility that the argument can be
what has been granted can
law,
made
why Davies
that is
at
comes from the law of nations:
Law of Nations was before Kings, for Kings were made by the Law of Nations, Ex jure Gentium Reges originem traxerunt saith Baldus; So Kings were no sooner made by the Law of Nations, but presently the same Law which is the Law of Nature or NaFor
as the
,
.
tions
.
.
.
.
.
did annex this Prerogative to their several Crowns. ( Impo-
sitions 10)
Like the medieval popes and emperors
who wished
to leave
no doubt
about their authority, English defenders of the royal prerogative
fre-
Sir John Davies
J
quently claim that their kings received their authority directly from
means of human
rather than indirectly through the people by is
the point Davies
is
making when he
law.
35
God This
identifies the law of nations with
the law of nature and says that kings are
made by
the law of nations.
Roman
Davies again resorts to the imperial language of
law to
make
the claim that, regarding his prerogatives, the king has absolute power:
“wherein the King hath sole and absolute power merum imperium
mixtum ”
(Impositions n).
At
first,
says Davies,
King had an absolute and unlimited power ( Impositions
25).
by Bracton,
in
a result
In contrast to the medieval
which the king receives
Law
“by the in
all
of Nations the
matters whatsoever”
common
his authority
never has absolute power because he
& non
law doctrine taught
from the
law,
and
as
subordinate to the law,
is
Davies claims that the king had an absolute power in
all
matters before
England had any particular law of its own:
Hereupon by
came due
to the
Government tract,
the
.
.
.
same Law of Nations, Tributes and Customes be-
King or Prince and
all
to maintain
him
these things, namely Property and
and Kings, and Customes, were before any positive
made; then came the positive Law, and limited the whereas by the
power
ited
Davies
is
in
Law of Nations
all
Law
Con-
Law was
of Nations,
the king had an absolute and unlim-
matters whatsoever. ( Impositions 2 4, 25)
quite explicit about the chronology of the development of
the English constitution. At
held in
in his place of
common
first,
by the law of nature,
all
things were
and there was neither king nor subject; then, with the
inauguration of the law of nations, the law of nature was limited and
property was established.
The
existence of property requires the institu-
tion of kings and rulers to protect
the chronology, there
is
it ( Impositions
no law of England, whether statutory or cus-
tomary. There are no legal limits on the king. the king exist not by the law’s operation
voluntary creation this left
is
the
Roman
of,
or acquiescence
positive
his absolute
Law,
in
in,
Any
legal restrictions
on the king but by the
Law
the
is
on
king’s
law that has that effect. That
imperial theory of the ruler’s relation to the law
to the reader’s inference; Davies
By the
24). Until this point in
is
not
explicit:
King himself was pleased
to limit and stint
power, and to tye himself to the ordinary rules of the
common
and ordinary
cases, worthily
and princely, accord-
The Common Law Mind
136
ing to the
Roman Emperour, Dignissimum
ibus confiteri retaining ,
Principe se alletatnm leg-
and reserving notwithstanding in may points
that absolute and unlimited
power which was given unto him by the
Law
of Nations, and in these cases or points, the King’s Preroga-
tives
do
him by
were not granted unto
consist; so as the king’s prerogatives
when
the people, but reserved by himself to himself,
was
positive law
established;
first
and the King doth exercise
dou-
Merum Imperium when
ble power, viz. an absolute power, or
doth use Prerogatives onely, which
a
the
,
is
he
not bound by the positive
Law; and an ordinary power of Jurisdiction, which doth co-operate with the Law, and whereby he doth minister Justice to the people, according to the prescript rule of the positive Law. (Impositions
Davies
power he
is
nice in his choice of language describing the
25)
two kinds of
attributes to the king. In regard to his prerogatives, the king
has an “absolute power
.
.
.
which
is
not bound by the positive law.” 13 In
regard to his power of ordinary jurisdiction, he
may
have “tied” himself
to the positive law, but only in the sense that he will “cooperate” with
not in the sense that he
is
bound by
it,
it.
This distinction of two powers held by the English king, one absolute
and one ordinary, ambassador, in
by no means original with Davies. 14 The Venetian
is
1551, writes
gland exercises two powers dinary and
from
legal.”
1612 to 1628
mon
1 -
Sir
of the English monarchy: “the king of En.
.
.
the one royal and absolute, the other or-
John Dodderidge,
a justice
of the King’s Bench
and among the most learned and distinguished com-
lawyers of the early seventeenth century, late in Elizabeth’s reign
distinguishes between the “absolute” and the “ordinate” king.
16
made
The most famous
English statement of the king’s double power
by Chief Baron Fleming
in 1606
power of the
in deciding Bate 's Case (or the
“Case of Impositions”) in the Court of Exchequer:
The
King’s power
several lawes
is
double, ordinary and absolute, and they have
and ends. That of the ordinary
is
for the profit of par-
ticular subjects, for the execution of civil justice, the
meum; and
this
courts, and
by the
common
law:
is
determining of
exercised by equitie and justice in ordinary
civilians
is
is
nominated jus privatum and with
and these laws cannot be changed, without
us,
parlia-
ment; and although that their form and cause may be changed, and interrupted, yet they can never be changed in substance.
The
ab-
Sir John Davies
solute
power of the King
is
not that which
is
converted or executed
to private use, to the benefit of any particular person, but
that
which
is
applied to the general benefit of the people and
populi; as the people
the body, and the
is
King
is
and
most properly named Policy and Government; and
is
constitution of this
which direct only
at the
body varieth with the time, so varieth
solute law according to the
wisdome of
the King, for the
good; and these being general rules and true as they
done within these
rules are lawful.
only
is
salus
common
is
rules,
is
the head; and this
power
guided by the
137
law,
as the
this ab-
common
are, all things
1
Statements by royalist lawyers in support" of the king’s prerogative agree that the king has both an ordinary and an absolute power, but they
vary in the extent of the claims made for both kinds of power. Davies’s statement of the doctrine of the two powers does more to subordinate the law to the king than does Fleming’s judgment.
own wisdom
ing to Fleming the king’s
do within the scope of rules are lawful.”
his absolute
But Fleming
dinary power, the king
is
true that accord-
It is
the only limit
power:
“all
things done within these
also suggests that in the exercise of his or-
subject to the dictates of the
is
on what he may
common
law as
applied by the ordinary courts and that he cannot change that law with-
out parliament. There
is
no suggestion
in Fleming’s
judgment that
ordinary power the king “cooperates” with the law because
him
to
do
so,
with the implication that
if at
it
in his
pleases
some point he should no
longer be pleased to follow the law he would be within his rights to act
contrary to
This
is
it.
precisely the implication to be
drawn from Davies’s descrip-
tion of the king’s ordinary power: the king
is
law even in the exercise of his ordinary power. In is
fact, the
permitted to exist only by the king’s grace: “the King doth suffer the
customary law of England to have her course” ( Impositions assign to the
common
law
a
Edward Coke, who
stoutly defends the king’s prerogative, attributes to that “the
common
remaines
still.”
also it
law has no controler in any part of
count of parliament; and
26).
This
is
to
very different role in English constitutional
jurisprudence from that which
it
common common law
not bound by the
if it
on occasion
when he it,
asserts
but the high
be not abrogated or altered by parliament,
IH
Davies’s attempt to separate the king’s prerogative from the
common
The Common Law Mind
138
and
law,
common
his claim that the
king’s permission had
law’s existence
any, support
little, if
depends upon the
lawyers of his day, even from those like Bacon and Ellesmere, ally
Case expands at ,
some length on
usu-
Crowne and sometimes called,
.
the King, .
sometimes
it is
Lex Regia.
.
.
the nature of the
Lex Anglicanae
called
it is
When
.
.
Chamber concerning
common
Calvin's
law and what
common law into three aspects: “When it
encompasses and divides the
respects the church,
is
who
could be counted on to support the king’s interests. Lord Chancellor
Ellesmere, in his speech in the Exchequer
it
common
from the leading
it
called
.
.
.
When
respects the
it
Lex Coronae.
.
common
respects the
.
.
and
.
subjects,
.
.
it
Lex TerraeL 19
Ellesmere’s successor as lord chancellor, Sir Francis Bacon, on the oc-
casion of the swearing in of Sir
Thomas Chamberlain
as a
judge on the
King’s Bench, shows exasperation at the suggestion that the king’s preV,
rogative
is
not based on the
common
law:
The Lord Chancellor took occasion to enlarge himself much upon the Prerogative and how near it was akin and of blood (as he termed it)
to the
common
law; saying further, whatsoever
lawyers might prattle, that tion of the
To add one
common
was the accomplishment and perfec-
it
law 20 .
final authority, Sir
author of what
is
some unlearned
Henry
Finch, a sergeant-at-law and the
arguably the most distinguished English legal treatise
of his time, takes what seems to be the standard of the relationship of
common
common
lawyer’s view
law and prerogative in the early seven-
teenth century: It
must be remembered that the King’s prerogative stretcheth not
to the doing of any wrong; for
the
common
much
law,
is
as
it
groweth wholly from the reason of
were
a finger
differing in fashion (as the head
proportion) that it
and
it
if
you
them
set
of that hand, although so
and body can never be of one
in parallels together
to be law almost in every case of the King, that
a subject; yet for all that
common
law
is
their contrary course
shall find
law in no case of
they are not two, but one law: only the
primnm
as the
is
you
mobile
,
which draws
all
the planets in
21 .
Davies also uses planetary imagery in his discussion of the prerogative
and the
common
primum
mobile:
law, but for
him
the king, not the
common
law,
is
the
Sir John Davies
The Government and
ordering of Traffique, Trade, and
merce, both within the Land and without, doth rest in the
wherein the King
as a principall Prerogative,
which carrieth about
mobile,
Course, and yet doth suffer their divers
all
all
all
is
139
ComCrown
Primum
like to a
the inferior Spheres in his superior
the Planets underneath
him
to finish
and particular courses; or rather he doth imitate the
Divine Majesty, which in the Government of the world doth suffer things for the most part to passe according to the order and course
of Nature, yet
many
times doth show his extraordinary power in
working of miracles above Nature.
And
truly, as the
on the one
to have her course
mit, and give
way
King doth
suffer the
customary
side, so doth^the
Law of England
same law
yeeld, sub-
to the King’s Prerogative over the other.
( Imposi-
tions 26)
common
two pictures of the
Davies’s
law — the one found in his Irish
reports and the one drawn in The Question Concerning bnpositions — are
not entirely incompatible.
not inconsistent to praise the
It is
law as the most perfect law in the world and
by the king’s sufferance and
is
still
hold that
it
common
exists
subordinate to his prerogative. But
only
it is
a
common law mind, if by that phrase one means the understanding most common lawyers in the early seventeenth century have about the nature of the common law mistake to choose Davies as
and the place
it
a
representative of the
holds in English jurisprudence.
Davies because he
extreme in
is
mistake to choose
common law in the Irish that the common law is the
his praise of the
reports and uncharacteristic in his insistence ancient,
It is a
immemorial custom of the people and
seems to find in describing the
common
in the significance
law that way.
He
is
he
extreme,
too, even
compared
to other leading royalist lawyers, in seeking to di-
vorce the
common
law from the king’s prerogative and in making the
very existence of the
To
mon
say that Davies
law
is
common is
law subject to the king’s sufferance.
extreme
in the
not to suggest that one
views he expresses about the com-
may
not find in the
ature and reported cases of his day examples of says.
Pocock
is
common
many
law
liter-
of the things he
not imagining things when he finds claims about the com-
mon law in Coke’s writings that seem of a piece with Davies’s description of the common law in his Irish reports. But when one looks at the entire corpus of Coke’s writings on the law and of his judicial opinions, the portrait
of the
common
law that emerges
is
quite different
from the one
140
§
The Common Law Mind
Davies paints in the preface to his Irish reports. Similarly, although one
may
find references to the antiquity of the
mon
law as the
common custom
common
law, or to the
com-
of the realm, scattered through the sev-
enteenth-century case reports, one
who
systematically reads
all
these re-
ports and the legal treatises of the time cannot avoid the impression that
common law are not central to the of the common law. Most particularly,
the things Davies emphasizes about
leading
common
lawyers ’s vision
Davies and Coke are unusual in the extent to which they
worthy
qualities of the
common
law to
its
tie
the praise-
antiquity or to immemorial
CHAPTER SEVEN
Sir
Edward Coke and His Contemporaries
The Antiquity of the Common Law J.
G. A. Pocock writes: If
the idea that law
is
custom implies anything,
it is
that law
constant change and adaptation, altered to meet each
ence in the
life
of the people; and
theory more likely to lead to law.
Yet the fact
is
in
experi-
might seem that there was no
a historical
conception of the nature of
common lawyers, holding that law was that the common law, and with it the con-
that the
custom, came to believe stitution,
it
new
is
had always been exactly what they were now, that they
were immemorial: not merely that they were very were the work of remote and mythical
were immemorial
old, or that they
legislators,
but that they
in the precise legal sense of dating
from time be-
yond memory — beyond,
in this case, the earliest historical record
that could be found. This
is
myth of
the doctrine or
the ancient
constitution, which bulked so large in the political thought of the
seventeenth century
1
.
Sir
Edward Coke
mon
law
is
is,
like Sir
John Davies, anxious
to claim that the
the best law in the world, and he ties
its
com-
excellence to
its
antiquity: I
say to thee (gentle reader) next to thy duty and piety to
his anointed, thy gracious Sovereign,
ents, yield
and thy honour to thy par-
due reverence and obedience to the
England: for of all laws
(I
common
laws of
speak of human) these>are the most equal
and most certain, of greatest antiquity, and beneficial
God, and
and easy to be observed. ...
least delay,
If the
and most
ancient laws of this
142
The Common Law Mind
$
noble island had not excelled
all
others,
it
could not be, that some of to say, the
Ro-
mans, Saxons, Danes, or Normans, and especially the Romans,
who
the several conquerors and governors thereof, that
(as
they justly may) do boast of their
them might) have
altered or
civil laws,
changed the same
is
would
every of
(as
2 .
In these passages, Coke, following Fortescue, asserts that the
common
law has survived a thousand years of conquests by other peoples without
having been changed in any way.
He
compelled to admit that
is
it
has
been modified since the time of William the Conqueror, but he argues that such changes have
Out of
all
been for the worse:
these books and reports of the
common
law, I
have ob-
some time by acts of parliament, and some time by invention and wit of men, some points of the ancient common law have been altered or diverted from his due course, yet in revoluserved that albeit
tion of time, the
same
(as a
most
skilful
and
faithful supporter of the
commonwealth) have been with great applause,
many
inconveniencies, restored again
for the avoiding of
3 .
common
Since Coke’s belief in the immemorial antiquity of the
has
come
law
to be regarded as a central part of the seventeenth-century
common law mind,
let
us examine the extent to
the leading lawyers of his time.
antiquity of the
common
It is
which
it
was accepted by
certainly true that references to the
law are scattered through the case reports of
the early seventeenth century, although their concentration in cases re-
ported by Coke and their relative paucity in other early seventeenth-
century case reports the cases actually
raise the question
whether the lawyers and judges
made them or whether most of them
in
are the product of
common law 4 It is not un-
Coke’s
own preoccupation with
known
for a lawyer arguing a case to raise doubts about the unaltered
antiquity of the
common
law.
the age of the
.
For example, Sherley, Serjeant, argues in
The Case of Modus Decimandi that
judgments and precedents
in the
time of Ed.
2
E.
1.
H. John, R.
and more ancient are not authorities or precedents to be now lowed, unless that they concur and agree with the law, and
experience and practice at this day; for (and
some of them not
extant) have
many Acts
fol-
common
of Parliaments
changed the ancient laws
divers cases: and desuetude has antiquated and time and
hath taken away divers others.-
1
in
custom
Edward Coke
Sir
In his speech in Calvin's Case, a
appears not at
all
much
changed over time but
also that
it is
Lord Ellesmere,
greater lawyer,
reluctant to admit not only that the desirable that
it
H3
common
had done
so.
law has 6
Upon this reason it is, that some lawes, as well statute lawe as common law, are obsolete and worne out of use: for, all humane lawes are but leges temporis:
and the wisedome of the iudges found them to
bee unmeete for the time they lived essarie for the time
humanae nascuntur, .” ortum, statum, et occasum and upon
this rule also,
although very good and nec-
And
wherein they were made.
saide “leges
By
in,
therefore
it is
vigent, et moriuntur, et habent
this
reason
that often
it is,
it is
that
auncient lawes are changed by the interpretation of the judges, as well in cases criminall as civile. Later, in
one of
common
lawes are soe
Ellesmere laments that “the auncient
his law tracts,
much
neglected, contemned, and almost
obsolete and out of use that for the most part
but the shadow of the auncient
Common
we haue not the substance
lawes.”
s
Although
instances his attitudes toward the changes time has
mon
law
may
differ,
he
is
grown
wrought
in these in the
two
com-
emphatic in both that the law has greatly
changed.
common
References to the antiquity of the
made tury.
law are also frequently
in the parliamentary debates of the first three decades of the cen-
This
is
especially true of the
references are
made without
Commons
Debates of 1628. Most such
elaboration as assertions that particular dis-
puted liberties of the subject have long existed in English law and not affirmations that the
from remote
common
law as
a
whole has continued unchanged
antiquity. Occasionally, however,
more sweeping claims are Sir Dudley Digges, one of
made about the antiquity of the common law. four members appointed by the Commons to speak the Lords
on April
ment without
7,
1628,
on the question of the
at a
conference with
legality of imprison-
the assignment of cause, asserts that
the laws of England are grounded
books, consisting
much
on reason more ancient than
in unwritten customs, yet so full of justice
and true equity that your most honorable predecessors and ancestors
propugned them with
a
as
nolomus mutare and so ancient that
from the Saxon days, notwithstanding the
,
injuries
time, they have continued in most parts the same, as
and ruins of
may
appear in
The Common Law Mind
H4
old remaining
monuments of the
laws of Ethelbert, the
tian king of Kent; Ina, the king of the
West Saxons;
Mercians; and Alfred, the great monarch.
.
.
.
And
first
Chris-
Offa, of the
here,
my
Lords,
by many cases frequent in our modern laws strongly concurring with those of the ancient Saxon Kings,
more
might,
I
time were not
if
precious, demonstrate that our laws and customs were the
same. 9
Despite the Commons’s designation of Digges to speak for conference, the is
it
would be
a
common law survived
it
at the
mistake to presume that his contention that largely
universally believed by the
unchanged from the days of the Saxons
common
House of Com-
lawyers in the
Commons
mons. Another of the four speakers representing the
at the
John Selden (1584-1654), whose task is “to insist on the remedy when the law is violated, and shall cite the precedents and anconference
is
member who
swer the objections against them.” 10 That he should be the is
given the task of searching out the legal precedents and then of pre-
senting and defending his peers
them
to the lords shows
something of the respect
have for his legal learning.
Selden, like
many
other speakers in the 1628 Parliament, occasionally
claims antiquity for a particular legal rule, but in a series of works published
between 1610 and 1618 he demonstrates that the myth that the
common
law survived unchanged from pre-Norman times to the seven-
teenth century
is
historically unsupportable.
although particular
common
11
Selden’s position
law rules survived the
is
that
Norman Conquest
unchanged, many other rules were afterward added or modified. For example, in his Jani Anglorum Facies Altera (1610),
a
work
in
cusses the traces of the laws of the Britons, Saxons, and
which he
dis-
Normans
that
can be found in English law, he writes: “For the times on
Normans entrance rights of
are so full of new laws, especially such as belong to the
Tenancy or Vassalage; though other laws have been
enough kept up from the time of the date.”
this side the
Saxons,
carefully
and perhaps from an
earlier
12
In 1616 Selden prepared a
new
edition of Sir
John Fortescue’s De
Laudibus Legum Anglie, the direct authority for Coke’s claim in the prefaces of his Second and Third Reports that the eral foreign
common
law survived sev-
conquests unchanged. In his notes thereto, Seldon rejects
Fortescue’s history:
Edward Coke
Sir
But questionless the Saxons made
H5
mixture of the British customes
a
with their own; the Danes with old British the Saxon and their own; ,
and the Normans the
The
like.
old laws of the Saxons mention the
Danish (Danelage) the Mercian law (Mercenlage) and the Westsaxon law (Westsaxonlage) of which also some Counties were governed by
some by
one,
More
another.
'
important, Selden goes on to reject the premise that the excel-
lence of laws depends
But
1
in truth,
upon
their antiquity:
and to speak without perverse affectation,
all
general are originally equally ancient. All were grounded
and no Nation was, that out of
ture,
nature being the same in
same.
.
.
.
all,
it
laws in
upon na-
took not their grounds; and
the beginniil^ of
all
laws must be the
But the divers opinions of interpreters proceeding from
mans reason, and the several conveniencies of dihave made those limitations, which the law of Nature
the weakness of vers States,
And hence
hath suffered, very different.
which have come
all
that those customs
is
out of one fountain, Nature, thus vary from
and cross one another tions, as divers
it
in several
men, have
Commonwealths.
their divers collections
and so make their divers laws to grow to what they
we have now
and the same root.
Infinite laws
on D. years
Then were many
since.
.
.
.
Divers
Na-
and inferences, are,
out of one
that were not thought
that D. years before had
no
being, and less time forward always produced divers new; the be-
ginning of all here being in the
by nature being
civil
first
creatures
peopling of the land,
grew
to plant a
when men
common
society.
This rationally considered, might end that obvious question of those,
which would say something against the laws of England
they could. ’Tis their
mon
laws
trivial
Questionless
all
a State in that land which the ,
ural laws limited for the
limitations have been
demand, When and how began your com-
its fittest
in like kind as the laws of
answered by affirming, when and
other States, that
When
there
was first
common law now governs: then were
from thence, increased, are;
nat-
altered, interpreted,
although perhaps, (saving the meerly
immutable part of nature) now,
in regard of their first being, they
are not otherwise than the ship, that first
is,
conveniency of civil society here, and those
and brought to what they
of the
if
by often mending had no piece
materials, or of the house that’s so often repaired, ut nihil
The Common Law Mind
146
ex pristina materia supersit
counted the same
still.
.
which yet (by the Civil law)
,
honor or
Little then follows in point of
.
.
to be ac-
is
excellency specially to be attributed to the laws of a Nation in general,
by an argument thus drawn from difference of antiquity, which
in substance
is
Those which
best
name of the
alike in
Neither are laws thus to be compar’d.
the state wherein they are, clearly deserve the
fit
best laws. 14
Glenn Burgess attempts lier
all.
to
minimize such statements
works, arguing that taken as
model” of English
legal history,
that English laws are derived tinuity.
model”
1
Burgess provides
'
is
a
whole
his writings
support
a
which includes Gothicism
“standard
(the belief
from the Saxons), immemoriality, and con-
little
persuasive evidence that his “standard
among common
indeed standard
in Selden’s ear-
lawyers of the early seven-
teenth century. His proofs are largely limited to the later writings of
John Selden, but the passages on which he Selden accepted the “standard model.”
relies
He
do not suggest that even
pulls together three passages
Ad Fletam Dissertatio, saying that they “form a very neat sketch of English common law seen as originating among the customs of the Saxfrom
ons and having
a
continuous history therefrom
(in spite
of subsequent
invasions and conquests).” 16
The Anglo-Saxon
invaders of England used neither this [the
Theo-
dosian Code] nor any similar code, but only their native Germanic
customs, differing in this respect from the other northern invaders
who
penetrated farther south.
About
the time
when Lothair and
his successors
introduced the law
of Justinian into public government, or just after the Anglo-Saxons, the
Danes and the Normans had
in succession,
during
a
period of
about 740 years, used their own laws (/>., our English common law) without any Roman admixture, then the imperial law, in the form of the
Codes of Theodosius and
Justinian,
was brought into England
where previously they had been almost completely unknown.
There
are
two reasons why the
own and quoted the reign of
with
Edward
it,
III]
civil law,
had no greater
however mixed with our
effect in this period [before
of its public use by our lawyers.
unconcealed aversion which our ancestors had to
it,
One
so far as
it
is
the
con-
Sir
cerns principles of government. in
which the English or
faithfulness to
as
common
other
147
the remarkable esteem
is
law was held, and our constant
something immemorially
fitted [antiquitate
adap-
the genius of the nation. 17
tata] to
Nothing
mon
it
The
Edward Coke
in these passages suggests that
Selden believes that the com-
law originated with the Saxons and has a “continuous history,” or as
Burgess describes
it
earlier, a
“constant unbroken evolution” thereafter. ls
Normans in succession used their own laws for a long period before Roman jurisprudence was introduced into England.' To say that each used its own
To
the contrary, he writes that the Saxons, the Danes, and the
1
'
to imply nothing about transmission of legal ideas,
laws in succession
is
rules, or practices
from the Saxons to the Danes to the Normans.
Burgess appears to be misled in his reading of Fleta?n partly tate
by the
translator’s
The
way the common lawyers use
20
is
the
word “immemorial.”
,
The word “immemorial”
in the law implies this
paradigm usage “immemorial” means only
“a
unbroken evolution .” 21
common makes
it
He
in usage. After defining
lose their
Selden and
in its
rules in constant
custom
Coke
custom
as “a law or
which being established by long use and the consent of is
daily practised,” he adds, “and for usage,
the efficient cause, or rather the
common
body of
clear that he, at least, does not have an understanding of
our ancestors, hath been and
scription
and contends that
provides, however, not a single example of a
would permit any gaps
is
an unbroken usage
lawyer giving that meaning to the word. Sir Edward
right not written
that
Selden’s antiqui-
non exstat memoria hominum not antiqui-
from time beyond memory. Burgess denies
that
Ad
Latin phrase normally used in the law to convey the idea of im-
memorial usage or custom .
unhappy rendering of
passage from
adaptata as “immemorially fitted” and partly by his evident misun-
derstanding of the
tas
this
life
of both; for custom and pre-
being if usage fail
many
,
of his contemporaries certainly believe that the
law has been in constant evolution over the centuries, but they
do not attach that belief
to the notion of immemoriality. In
view of the
— that many prominent common lawyers of the period recognize that the common law has undergone substantial change over the centuries — it is inaccurate to define the common la\y mind in terms of a belief in the unchanged, immemorial antiquity of the common law. evidence
The Common Law Mind
148
The Common Law, Custom, and Reason Some
leading lawyers, like Coke, have a great deal to say about both
time of usage and reason in their discussions of the nature of the com-
mon
law.
Others, like Sir
Henry
Finch, mention both elements but de-
vote their attention almost entirely to the element of reason. like Sir Francis
Bacon, show no interest in the age of the
Still
others,
common
law.
Except for those of Coke and Davies, the theoretical writings about law concentrate on the element of reason in the
time of usage. Even though reason
its
ments
is
common
law rather than on
one of the two necessary
is
no evidence
in the
rate discussions of the relationship
between the
common
for proving custom, there
ele-
sometimes elabolaw and reason
works of Finch, Dodderidge, Bacon, or Ellesmere that the atten-
in the
tion given to the idea of reason have anything to do with a perceived
need to prove the elements of custom. It
may
common Book
be that the
common
lawyers ’s association of reason with the
law — an association made from the time of the earliest Year
cases
— stems in part from a
tomary law and from the took over from
civil
tests for valid
customs
and canon law doctrine. But the widespread me-
dieval association of the
common
law with reason can as easily be based
on the standard medieval theological and is
based on the classical tradition, that
is
based on reason. It is likely
the early
all
common
who
juristic view,
in the
is little
and fourteenth centuries emphasize the
common
when Stonore announces
There
Chief Justice Stonore and the el-
law do so because they are trying con-
common
sciously to establish the customary validity of the
law. Instead,
that “ley est resoun,” he seems to be proclaim-
ing the essential nature and character of the universal medieval assumption that
more
in turn
law — not just customary law —
lawyers’s preoccupation with reason.
in the thirteenth
ement of reason
the
which
that both of these strands of thought mutually reinforced
textual support for the proposition that
others
common law as custhat the common law
conception of the
all
law
is
common
law based on the
based on
reason.-”'
When
theoretical of the seventeenth-century legal writers turn their
attention to the element of reason in the are explicitly based
rather than
on the
common
classical, scholastic,
law, their discussions
and
civilian traditions
on an understanding that they need to prove the
law’s reasonableness in order to establish
it
as
custom.
common
Sir
To make
common
century J.
these points
not to advance
is
law mind entirely
H9
model of the seventeenth-
a
odds with the one suggested by
at
G. A. Pocock. Coke and Davies certainly write passages that suggest
common
that the conception of the
law
immemorial custom
as
common
to their understanding of the essence of the
Year Books also contain is
Edward Coke
a series
and long usage.
common
possible to hold both ways of looking at the it
seems most
common law common lawyers
to conceptualizing the turies
and that the
two
likely that
critical
The medieval
common
of statements in which the
identified with ancient past practices
contradiction, but
law.
is
logically
It is
law,
law
without any
different approaches
existed side-by-side for
many
cen-
tended to gravitate to one view or
the other. This does not prevent a lawyer with one basic orientation
from occasionally speaking of the other orientation. writes that “the
I
take
it
common
common
that this
khv in the language of the
what
is
law of England
a
is
is
happening when Finch
law used time out of mind,
or by prescription throughout the realm” and then proceeds with an
common
elaborate examination of the nature of the gives
no attention to the length of its use or
Only
Christopher
St.
common
scription of the
German
is
largely unsuccessful in
common
Commons
in
To
at a de-
roles
is
found not in
Thomas Hedley
a
law case or
to the
House
1610T The key to Hedley ’s linkage of custom and rea-
to be found in the idea of “tried reason.” Early in his speech,
Hedley considers and law.
effort. In
law in which both custom and reason play
but in the famous speech of
legal treatise
one such
most successful attempt
complementary and equally important
is
24
law are compatible. In the sixteenth century,
the seventeenth century perhaps the
son
antiquity.
rarely does a lawyer feel the need to demonstrate that both con-
ceptions of the
of
its
law in which he
say that the
rejects several possible definitions of the
common
more correct than saying reason because
definition because not
that the
common
profitable for the
law
is
merely whatever the judges
that the truth
is
whatever the jury
be more correct to say that the
ceedings 2:173). It rnight
common
law
all
all is
law
reason
is is
reason, but this law. It
is
is
common will
wills
common
is
(
no
Pro-
law
is
not an adequate
even more correct to say
reason approved by the judges to be good and
commonwealth, but
statute laws are also reasonable
and good and profitable for the commonwealth, and yet neither the judges nor even the king could
Some might
suggest that
it is
make them
laws without the parliament.
the parliament that gives
form and force to
150
the
The Common Law Mind
>
common
law,
but that has matters backward: the parliament has
power from the common law
{Proceedings 2:174).
The proper
Hedley concludes, gets back to the idea of reason;
it
or the quintessence of reason”
The
can try reason
(
Proceedings 2:175).
its
definition,
“was tried reason, only thing that
is
human wisdom, learning and knowledge, and from whom all human laws receive their chiefest strength, honor and estimation. Time is wiser than the time,
which
is
the trier of truth, author of all
judges, wiser than the parliament,
Hedley proffers
when
time
his
way wiser than
conception of the
common law as
the doctrine of binding precedent
foothold in English jurisprudence.
peers are elaborating conceptions of the
common
elite.
tried reason at a
beginning to gain
is
time, too,
It is at a
reason and wisdom of the professional
the wit of man.
when
a
several of his
law as the
artificial
Hedley takes aim
at
both
tendencies:
And
if a
judgment once given should be preemptory and trench
succession to bind and conclude the law in that point or to vary
all
from
in
future judges from examining it,
common law could
then the
never have been said to be tried reason grounded upon better rea-
son than the statutes, for
The
wisdom
then should be grounded merely upon
3
reason that serves as the ultimate ground of the
be proven to be real by stuff
To
and no part of the say that Hedley ’s
tempt to build an
come
or 4 judges, which must needs of the parliament. {Proceedings 2:178-79)
the reason or opinion of
short of the
it
“trial
of time”; otherwise,
common is
the
law” {Proceedings
common
“it is
law must
but counterfeit
2:178).
most successful seventeenth- century
intellectually coherent theory of the
of the ideas on long usage, custom, and reason
is
common
at-
law out
not to suggest an ab-
sence of loose ends in his theory. For example, he at some points seems
common law with custom and at deny that the common law is custom. He
to identify the
others emphatically
seems to
defines the
common
law as “a reasonable usage, throughout the whole realm, approved time
out of mind in the king’s courts ... to be good and profitable for the
commonwealth” and,
tom of
a little later, says that
“the
common
law
is
the cus-
the realm approved in the king’s courts” {Proceedings 2:175,
Yet he also says, “I would not be mistaken, as though
I
meant
x
^ 2 )-
to con-
Sir
found the
common
Edward Coke
much
law with custom, which differ as
reason and bare precedents” ( Proceedings
l
5l
as artificial
2:175).
common law as custhe common law with
Part of his reluctance unequivocally to define the
tom
is
explained by his desire to avoid confusing
local customs:
Customs
and particular places,
are confined to certain
by
triable
the country, but their reasonableness or unreasonableness by the
and precedent,
judges, to be taken strictly according to the letter
and therefore admits small discourse of
art or wit. {Proceedings
2:
75-76) In distinguishing particular customs
and
by the country, Hedley
triable
on the grounds is
that they are local
merely making
a
his colleagues (for
example,
Coke and Finch)
that does not suggest that the
common
law
number of
More
interesting
is
wit,”
which the
make and
not customary in nature.
common
law,
which
broadly and even extended by equity), they leave ercise of “art or wit”
also
because particular customs are
his suggestion that
to be taken strictly (unlike the
is
point that any
is
to be interpreted
little
scope for the ex-
by lawyers and judges. 26 This “discourse of
common
law requires lawyers to engage
what Hedley,
earlier in the
Just what he
means by
same passage,
appears to be
refers to as “artificial reason.”
either of these terms he does not spell out, al-
though there are clues that what he has
Edward Coke’s famous
in,
art or
in
association of the
mind
is
closely linked to Sir
common
law with
artificial
reason. Because this and other important elements of Hedley ’s theory of
the
common
law appear to reflect the teaching of the
much more emi-
nent legal figure, perhaps the most productive approach to understanding
some of
the
more obscure
parts of
Hedley ’s discussion
is
to try to
understand Coke. 2 It is
hazardous to attempt to systematize Coke’s jurisprudence; con-
sistency and organization are not writer. Still,
it is
run throughout
among
his strengths as a thinker or
possible to discover fundamental ideas and themes that his
work, even
if it is
says to be consistent with those ideas
not possible to show everything he
and themes.
To understand Coke’s pronouncements on the nature of the common law, one must understand how he thinks the common law fits into the fabric of English law as whole. Part of the
enough: Coke repeatedly makes
a
answer to
this question
is
clear
three-part division of English law:
!
The Common Law Mind
52
common law, statutes, and
customs. 28
standard division of English law
law of England
parts;
i,
may be found
in his discussion of Little-
term “common law”:
ton’s use of the
The
A representative example of Coke’s
is
divided, as hath beene said before, into three
common law, which is the most generall and ancient law
the
of the realme, of part where of Littleton wrote; parliament; and
2,
statutes or acts of
particular customes (where of Littleton also
3,
maketh some mention).
tome of the realme,
say particular, for
I
it is
part of the
be the generall cus-
if it
common
law.
(Coke, Institutes
1:115b)
This division
den
in the
no invention on the part of Coke;
is
it is
reported by Plow-
middle of the sixteenth century.
To understand Coke’s jurisprudence, one next needs to know as nearly as possible just what Coke understands the common law, customs, and statutes to be and what their relationship is, one with another. The first thing to be learned from the passage just quoted is that Coke is careful to distinguish the common law from custom. When Coke speaks of custom, he means not the the
common
Kingdom
1:110).
local, special
customs derogating from the
law: “but a
law,
custom cannot be alleged generally within
of England; for that
This has always been the
word “custom.”
common
is
the
common
common
law” (Coke,
Institutes
lawyer’s standard usage of the
When one finds it unmodified in the Year Book cases,
in the reports of the sixteenth
or
and seventeenth centuries, the reference
always to local custom and not to the
common
is
law.
Apparently there was developing, in the early seventeenth century,
some looseness by the bar in the use of this terminology, however, for not only does Coke remark with considerable asperity on several occasions that
it is
improper to
leading lawyers
plead that there is
make is
a
the
allege a
same
custom throughout the realm, other
point. For example, Finch writes: “For to
custom among merchants throughout the realm
not good, inasmuch as that which
common
law,
is
.
current throughout the realm,
.
.
is
not custom.” 2 These remarks by Coke and Finch appear '’
to be directed only at getting lawyers to use the correct legal jargon, not at
making
a
substantive point about the nature of the
instruct lawyers not to say the
words
“a
common
law.
To
custom used throughout the
realm” because the proper way to make that allegation
is
to say that “the
Sir
Edward Coke
$
153
common law holds this” seems tacitly to agree, however, that the common law really is the common custom of the realm. But do Coke, Finch, and the other common lawyers of their time really conceptualize the common law as custom? For the common lawyers, just as for the civilians, the
tion.
The Year Book
concept basic to custom
discussions of local
is
that of prescrip-
custom focus on the prescrip-
elements of time and usage. 30 In the second half of the fifteenth cen-
tive
tury, Littleton
is
explicit
about the need for proof of the prescriptive
elements of custom:
And
note, that
no custome
hath bin used by
title
is
to bee allowed, but such custome, as
of prescription, that
is
from time out of
to say,
minde. But divers opinions have beene of time out of minde, &c.
and of title of prescription, which
Coke,
in
commenting on
one in the
is all
law.
this passage, distinguishes
31
between prescrip-
tion and custom:
Prescription
by the is
is
a title
law. ... In the
for the
taking his substance of use and time allowed
common law a
prescription,
most part applied to persons.
local, is alleged in
.
.
.
And
a
which
is
personal,
custome, which
is
no person, but layd within some mannor or other
place. (Coke, Institutes 1:113a, 113b)
He
goes on to say what was
common
to customs and prescriptions: “But
both to customes and prescriptions, these two things are incidents inseparable, viz. possession or usage, and time. Possession qualities:
it
must be long, continual, and peaceable
”
must have three
A little earlier in the
same work he describes the prescriptive elements of custom different language:
“Of every custome
and usage; time out of minde,
(as shall
there be
two
common
law.
His
uity” of that law.
that
Coke
is
a
”
(Coke, Institutes
1:110)
preoccupied with the age of the
legal writings are filled
On
essential parts, time
be said hereafter) and continuall
and peaceable usage without lawfull interruption
There can be no doubt
in slightly
with references to the “antiq-
very few occasions he also uses the traditional
formulas for alleging time of usage in describing the
common
law.
32
perhaps the most striking of such instances he writes: That by like time there had been writs of assise and other original writs returnable into the King’s courts, which (seeing they be, as
In
The Common Law Mind
*54
Justice Fitzherbert saith in his preface to his
book of Natura Bre-
vium, the rules and principles of the science of the manifestly prove that the
out of mind of
man
common
law)
do
law of England had been time
before the conquest, and was not altered or
changed by the Conqueror. {Reports
The
common
3:vi—vii)
however, that Coke only rarely uses the traditional formulas
fact,
common law, but still very common law, suggests that his
customs when he refers to the
for alleging
frequently alleges the antiquity of the
common law is not good custom. What he is
interest in the age of the
directed at proving the
common law to be the common law’s superiority
interested in proving
sense that
it is
better or
Whether Coke
more
to other kinds of law
it,
common
law
is
common
superior to stat-
one of the most disputed aspects of Coke’s
jurisprudence and merits a brief discussion. There literature
is
under some circumstances, can overturn them
or declare them to be void
growing
in the
excellent than other kinds of law.
also believes that the
utes in the sense that
— superiority
is
is
and
a large
still
on Coke’s understanding of the relationship between
law and statute, fueled by the fact that Coke says, in different
times and places, things on the subject that appear difficult to reconcile.
3 -
Scholarly disagreement on the subject often begins with a discus-
how
sion of
Coke’s famous statement in Dr. Bonham's Case relates to
other statements of his that have sometime been read as implying legislative
And
supremacy. In the famous Bonham's Case passage, Coke writes: it
appears in our books, that in
will controul
many
cases, the
common
law
Acts of Parliament, and sometimes adjudge them to
be utterly void: for when an Act of Parliament
is
against
common
right and reason, or repugnant, or impossible to be performed, the
common
law will controul
it,
and adjudge such Act to be void.
{Reports 8:118a)
In a second version of the case, statutes are
any
man
made
Coke
is
reported to have said “that
against law and right, and so are these,
judge in his
own
cause
.
.
.
that this
is
a
if
any
which makes
void statute, for
it is
im-
pertinent to be observed.” 34 In contrast to the Bonham's Case dictum, in the part
4 of
his Institutes
tion of the parliament for
Coke
asserts that “of the
making of laws
transcendent and absolute, as
it
power and
in proceeding
by
jurisdic-
Bill, it is
so
cannot be confined either for causes or
persons within any bounds” (Coke,
Institutes 4:36).
Sir
Some
distinguished scholars,
limit
its
see in
Coke understands
the
law to be superior in authority to statute law and thus able to
common
scope and content or that he thinks that
might declare statutes to be void superior law — perhaps the
of reason. C.
perhaps natural law or the law
law,
common
Mcllwain, for example, contends that the
H'.
and that
law judges
they consider them to violate some
if
common
lawyers always understood the rior law,
155
more often than not American,
the Bonham's Case dictum evidence either that
common
Edward Coke
common
law to be
statutes, at least until the
Long
a
fundamental, supe-
Parliament, were un-
derstood not to make or change law but merely to affirm existing law. 35
Other
historians,
though not committed to
all
the parts of Mcllwain’s
agree that Coke’s Bonham's Case dictum does reflect his under-
thesis,
standing that statutes are limited by
a
higher^ fundamental law Edward r
.
Corwin, the distinguished American constitutional historian, agrees
common law — or at least the maxims or “fundamental points” of the common law. When Coke states that if Parliament makes an Act “against common right and reason” the common law would control it, Corwin asserts, ‘“common
with Mcllwain that fundamental law
right it is
and reason’
is
.
.
.
is
for
Coke
the
something fundamental, something permanent;
higher law.” 36 Corwin identifies the maxims of the
Coke’s jurisprudence, with his famous
“artificial
common
law, in
reason and judgment of
the the law,” and that, in turn, he identifies with the law of nature. 37 Lest it
be thought that only American scholars
glish law give such readings to
Coke,
who
are not experts
on En-
should be noted that T.
it
F.
T.
Plucknett, one of this century’s finest English legal historians, also interprets Coke’s
Bonham
's
Case dictum as representing “the idea of a funda-
mental law which limited
Crown and
he identifies that law not as the
Parliament indifferently,” although
common
law hut as the law of reason. 38
In contrast to these interpretations of Coke, Samuel tends, in
dictum
what has come to be the reigning view, that the Bonham's Case
reflects neither a belief in a
ity to statutes
power
nor
a
fundamental law superior
contention that the
to overturn statutes. Instead,
reflects the standard sixteenth-
tion that
Thorne con-
common
common
Thorne
law judges have the
argues, the dictum merely
and early seventeenth-century expecta-
law judges had wide powers of interpretive discretion,
which allowed them to enlarge or narrow the scope of
what
a literal
Coke
states that
in author-
reading of
when
its
words might seem to
a statute is
“against
repugnant, or impossible to be performed,
a statute
suggest.^'’
from
Thus, when
common right and reason, or the common law will controul
156
it
The Common Law Mind
?
and adjudge such an Act to be void,”
all
he means
is
that the judges will
use their natural powers of interpretation to restrict the words of statute “in order to reach
sound
results.”
40
This reading
key words in the passage are “repugnant” (that “impossible to be performed,” and that
Thorne
so,
to be void
continues,
the
is
power
all
that
is
asserts that the
self- contradictory)
Coke understands
and
these words to
common right and
reason.” If all this
meant by the power
to adjudge an act
be essentially equivalent to “against is
is,
a
way as
to interpret the act in such a
to
make
“inef-
fective” the parts that are inconsistent with the other portions of the act
or that are impossible to be performed. 41 Nothing
higher law invalidating parliamentary
is
implied about some
acts.
All of these interpretations of Coke’s understanding of the relation
between larly if
common
one
is
law and statute have plausibility and power, particu-
willing to put aside one’s
Coke’s writings that It is
may
raise
doubts about
even possible to construct
statements by
Coke
that at
memory
first
of other passages in
a particular interpretation.
a plausible story or
may seem
blush
scheme
in
which
to be contradictory are
revealed in their true light to be consistent. Nevertheless, although
may
be true,
as
one scholar urges, that we ought to presume continuity
in Coke’s works, the
danger
exists that the interpretation that
Coke’s disparate statements part of the scholar’s
own
a
seamless theoretical
I
tween
know what
common
web
ingenuity rather than Coke’s understanding. 42
nearly as certain as other readers of Coke’s that
it
is
makes
reflects 1
am not
work sometimes appear
to be
the correct reading of his view of the relation be-
law and statute, but
a close
comparative reading of the
whole body of Coke’s published word seems to support the view expressed by Glenn Burgess that there are deep ambivalences or tensions, if
not outright contradictions, in Coke’s expressed beliefs on the sub-
ject.
43
This
is
not to deny the possibility that one of the standard inter-
pretations of Coke’s theory has exactly captured his thought but only to
suggest that there are reasons for being skeptical about the adequacy of
any of those standard interpretations.
Mcllwain makes an important contribution
to our understanding of
Coke’s thought about Parliament by emphasizing that Coke and his contemporaries think of Parliament
as a court,
sustained discussion of Parliament
is
not
found
a legislature.
Coke’s most
in his Fourth Institutes— the
part of the Institutes devoted to a discussion of English courts — and
appears there under the chapter heading,
it
“Of the High and Most Hon-
Sir
orable Court of Parliament.”
Edward Coke
his general practice,
It is
discussions of Parliament to refer to
Coke’s classification of Parliament as
it
new law — that statutes
common (as is
common lawyers
the time of Coke, the
own
lawyers do
appropriate for
the judgments of courts) are merely declaratory of existing
By
moreover, in
court through the lens of his
a
57
But Mcllwain reads
as a court.
mistaken theory that medieval and early modern not admit that statutes make
1
common
law.
have for centuries openly rec-
ognized that statutes make new law, often directly contradictory to the then existing
common
that Parliament’s isting
common
Coke himself repeatedly recognizes
law rules.
lawmaking power goes well beyond memorializing ex-
He certainly common law:
thinks that certain statutes are largely
law.
declarations of the
do affirm that the statutes of Magna
I
Merton, Marlebridge
.
.
.
Clfarta,
Charta d Foresta,
and some few others that be ancient
.
.
.
common law) of the common
(which for the most part are but declarations of the .
.
.
are the very body,
and
as
it
were the very
text
laws of England. (Repons 8:preface)
But he does not conceptualize statutes est court,
which declares what the
as written
common
In his discussion of acts of Parliament,
ment, some be introductory of new law, law,
is.
Coke writes, “Of acts of parliasome declaratory of the ancient
and some be of both kinds by addition of greater penalties or the
like” (Coke, Institutes 4:25).
making laws law,
law
judgments of the high-
44
He
repeatedly cautions about the danger of
that alter or abolish the fundamental points of the
but he does not suggest (unless that
a statute that alters the
common
law
or would not be binding. 45 In Rowles
is
v.
his point in
is
Bonham
's
common Case) that
beyond Parliament’s competence
Mason Coke ,
as chief justice states
the very function of statute law to be that “which corrects, abridges and
makes
it
common
and in the preface to Part 4 of his Repons clear that he understands conectio legum to be the same thing as
explains the
altering or changing
it
law,”
(Repons 4:vi,
ment can make new law change the
common
,
law,
ix).
46
Since
Coke
believes that Parlia-
that, admittedly at considerable hazard, it is
hard to see
how
can
recognizing that he con-
ceptualizes Parliament as a court helps to reconcile the Bonham's Case
dictum with the is
Institutes'
claim that Parliament’s power of making laws
“so transcendent and absolute, as
it
cannot be,confined either for
causes of persons within any bounds” (Coke, Institutes 4:3b). 47
158
The Common Law Mind
*
The argument
that Coke’s
dictum
in
Bonham's Case need not be seen
with his statements about Parliament’s lawmaking powers
as conflicting
because Coke, in Bonham's Case only has in mind
a
,
tory construction on the part of the sibility.
The
Because
statu-
law judges has great plau-
great interpretive discretion of judges was widely acknowl-
edged in the 5).
common
power of strict
late sixteenth
this
is
and early seventeenth centuries
(see chapter
within the bounds of the then avail-
so, it certainly is
able legal discourse to read Coke’s remarks as an exercise of strict inter-
pretation.
What we
cannot
know
for certain
is
whether such
a limited
reading captures Coke’s intentions. There are other modes of discourse besides that of statutory construction in which the Bonham's Case state-
ment would be
of discourse in Calvin's 1.
Coke himself engages Case when he argued,
intelligible.
That ligeance or obedience of the
by the law of nature: England:
That
3.
2.
That
this
subject to the sovereign
law of nature
is
That
the law of nature
due
is
pact of the laws of
the law of nature was before any judicial or
nicipal law in the world: 4.
form
in an alternative
is
mu-
immutable, and
cannot be changed. ( Repons 7:4 6) law of nature (or reason, as
If the
lawyers)
is
attempts to change
case, as the statute at issue in
to be against is
often
part of the laws of England, and
a statute that
Coke
it
common
right
it
if it
by making
by the
common
cannot be changed, then a
man
a
judge in his
own
Bonham's Case does, might plausibly be said
and reason, and hence void.
not the only distinguished
ciate English law
called
is
common lawyer of his time
to asso-
with the law of reason or nature. Sir Henry Finch,
writing of rules of reason deduced from the law of reason, asserts,
such
is
their singular
mount they
rule
and incomparable use,
that, as lords para-
and over-rule the grounds themselves: and rather
than that any of these (rightly understood) should
maxims and
states,
the very
principles of the positive law will yield, as to a higher
and more perfect Finch
fail,
law.
4*
even more
directly, that “it
is
truly said
&
all
men must
agree, that lawes in deed repugnant to the law of reason are as well void as those that cross the
law of nature.” 44 Chief Justice Hobart, only
years after the decision in Bonham's Case asserts in ,
Day
v.
a
few
Savadge that
“even an Act of Parliament, made against natural equity, as to make
a
Sir
man
own
judge in his
case,
is
void in
Edward Coke
159
for jura naturae sun im-
it self,
mutabilia, and they are leges legum.” 50
Coke cannot be making an appeal
Assertions that
to the law of nature,
the law of reason, or natural equity are surprisingly
Thorne’s principal argument, apart from is
that if
Coke
his defense
Case he would cite
St.
German and would make
asserts that judicial review
name of natural law
common
mental
for
law of England.”' 2 His proof
is
entirely
founded on
lawes are aptly and properly called the lawes of England, because
government
mind
the law of England
in is
Coke cannot have
natural law or nat-
Bonham's Case because he elsewhere claims that not dependent upon any foreign law. But Coke
never identifies natural law or equity as “foreign law”
— as may be seen in
famous association of the law of England with the law of nature
Calvin's Case.
The
natural law theory
interpretation of Coke’s dictum; after the
for
Institutes 2:98).
Burgess’s point seems to be that ural equity in
fit
and have no dependency upon any forreine law
thereof,
whatsoever” (Coke,
his
same
The
sorts of reservation as
suggestion
excluded as
is
is
mind
in
is
subject to
the theory of interpretation argument.
may
not be as easily
what Coke has
in
the idea that judicial review of statutes can be
is
common
law courts “in the
name of
the fundamental
law of England.”' This interpretation, unlike Mcllwain’s, does '
a basic
way on
the conception of Parliament as a court, nor
presume that Parliament can only declare existing
carried out by Burgess,
means when he right
this interpretation
only that the natural law theory
Bonham's Case
not depend in it
all,
not offered here as the correct
for our consideration the claim that
conducted by the
common
is
is
in
sometimes thought.
There remains
does
a
“Our com-
they are appropriated to this kingdome of England as most apt and the
5
Coke “not conducted in but in the name of the funda-
is,
or natural equity,
in Calvings Case.
serious misreading of a statement in Coke’s Second Institutes:
mon
theory,
the kind of direct state-
ments about natural law that he made two years before the
own
of his
appealing to the law of nature or reason in Bonha?n's
is
Glenn Burgess
defended.
ill
it
says that
and reason
.
.
.
the
law. Instead, as
proceeds by means of an analysis of what Coke
“when and Act of Parliament is
common
law will controul
it,
against
common
and adjudge such
an Act to be void.” For Burgess, the central interpretive problem
termine what Coke means by
and thoughtful
analysis,
“common
right
Burgess shows that
and rgason.” In
“common
reason”
is
to de-
a careful is
widely
i6o
The Common Law Mind
5?
used in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries as
common
54
law.
He
a
synonym
wishes to claim the same thing for
for the
“common
right,”
although he admits that one can find seventeenth-century examples in
common right and common
which
The
issue,
Institute
the
though,
how Coke understands
the terms, and in the First
he asserts that they are equivalent: “of common right, that
common law”
as far as
it
Coke
that
is
reason are distinguished.
goes. is
(Coke, Institutes 1:142a). This
The problem
is, it is
persuasive argument,
is a
on the
built
explicit
Coke’s discussion of
toms
in
common
common
is
The
two
senses.'’"’
about the validity of
raises questions
Burgess’s whole argument, as impressive as the validity of customs. 56
at least
right as a test for the validity of local cus-
The Compleat Copyholder
The second
presumption
precise and consistent in his use of terms, although Burgess
concedes that Coke uses the word “right” in
later
by
is,
first,
he
it is.
Coke
says, is that
it
lists six tests
for
must be reasonable.
that “customs and prescriptions ought to be according to
right.”
Coke then
gives an example to illustrate
by the requirement of accord with
common
right:
what he means
“And therefore
if
the
lord will prescribe to have of every copyholder for every court he keepeth, a certain
according to
sum of money,
common
this is a void prescription,
right; for
because
he ought for justice to do
it
it is
gratis T
not
51
should be noted that holding local customs, or customs of the
It
manor, to the standard of accordance with
common
right cannot
mean
common law. Such customs, almost by definition, differ from the common law. It is clear from Coke’s example that he means by common right not the common law but justice or natural equity — the very thing that Burgess claims he cannot mean by his reference to common right in Bonham Case. of divergence from the
a lack
’s
One
lesson to be
drawn from
ing of the relation between ject,
examination of Coke’s understand-
common
law and statute
is
that
on
this sub-
and on many others concerning Coke’s jurisprudence, scholarship
may help is
this
us narrow the range of his possible meanings, but his language
so rich and ambiguous, and his writing so unsystematic, that he cannot
be pinned law
is
down
exactly.
When
Sir
John Davies claims that the
superior to statute law because
it
does not become
had been tried and approved time out of mind, during there did thereby arise
ment
no inconvenience,” he
is
a all
common
law “until
which time
echoing Coke’s state-
that “if the ancient laws of this noble island had not excelled
others,
it
it
all
could not be but that some of the several conquerors and gov-
Sir
ernors thereof
.
.
would
.
.
.
.
Edward Coke
161
8 have altered or changed the same.”'
To
common law not only constitutes proof of the
Coke, the antiquity of the
absence of inconveniences the law occasions,
shows that law to
also
it
contain a kind of wisdom not available to the wisest individual men, or
even to groups of such men. In Calvin's Case he notes: ,
We
are but of yesterday, (and therefore had need of the
those that were before us) and had been ignorant ceived light and knowledge from our forefathers)
wisdom of
we had not reand our days upon (if
the earth are but as a shadow, in respect of the old ancient days and
times past, wherein the laws have been by the excellent
men,
in
experience (the
many
wisdom of
the
most
successions of ages, by long and continual
of light and truth) fined and refined, which no
trial
man (being of so short a time) albeit h^had in his head the wisdom of all the men in the world, in any one age could ever have effected or attained unto. And therefore it is optima ?‘egula ... no man one
ought to take
upon himself
it
to be wiser than the laws.
(
Reports
7:6-7) If
one compares Coke’s discussions of the antiquity of the
common
law in the prefaces to his Reports and in his report of Calvin's Case with his later discussions in his Institutes
there
is
a
it is
,
easy to get the impression that
considerable evolution over time in his views about the sig-
nificance of the law’s antiquity. In the prefaces and in Calvin's Case his
treatment of the law’s antiquity
common law is shown to Had it not been the best
is
a reprise
of Sir John Fortescue: the
be the best and wisest of laws by it
would
it
would not
still
of Coke’s Institutes published in 1628, there
part
1
allel
to the one
I
rate
and refine
his
is
a
,
quote from Calvin's Case. In
law consists in “an
And
this is
artificial
itself is
artificial
be around. 59 In the passage that
is
par-
to elabo-
common
law: that
perfection of reason.”
another strong argument in law, Nihil quod
nothing
very age.
Coke appears
conception of the wisdom of the
tione?n est licitum; for
law
it
its
reason
is
the
else but reason,
life
est
contra ra-
of the law, nay the
common
which
is
to be understood of an
perfection of reason, gotten by long study, observation,
and experience, and not of every man’s naturall reason; nascitur anifex.
the reason that
This is
legal reason est
dispersed into so
for,
Nemo
summa ratio. And therefore if all many several heads, were united
\
The Common Law Mind
6z
into one, yet could he not
make such
a
law as the law of England
is:
many successions of ages it hath been fined and refined by an infinite number of grave and learned men, and by long exbecause by
perience grown to such
a perfection, for
the
government of
this
may justly be verified of it, Neminem oportet legibus: no man out of his own private reason ought
realm, as the old rule sapientiorem
esse
to be wiser than the law,
which
the perfection of reason. (Coke,
is
Institutes 1:97b)
The
law has not arrived by chance
which,
if altered,
at this exalted state
of perfection,
inevitably leads to dangerous consequences.
It
has not
even done so through the accumulated wisdom of the folk — a plausible
way of reading the passage in Calvin's Case. In his commentary on Littleton, Coke does not, like Davies, view the common law as the kind of custom
that,
“being only matter of
fact,
and consisting in use and prac-
memory of the people.” Here, the repository of the common law is not the “memory of the people” but certain “grave and learned men” — the common law judges and lawyers. 61 The “reason” of the law is not, like that of St. tice
.
.
.
can be recorded and registered no where but in the 611
German’s doctor, “written artificial
in the heart of every
man”; instead,
it is
“an
perfection of reason” gotten only by “long study, observation,
and experience.”
The
hypothesis that between the time of his early Repons and the
writing of the part
ception of the
A
of his
common
Coke
evolves or discovers his con-
artificial
perfection of reason does not
Institutes
law as an
famous account of a 1608 colloquy ( Case of ProhiDel Roy) between himself and King James is to be believed:
hold up, however, bitions
1
if his
controversy of land between parties was heard by the King, and
sentence was given, which was repealed for to the
common
law: then the
King
said, that
this,
that
it
did belong
he thought the law was
founded upon reason, and that he and others had reason,
as well as
the Judges: to which
was, that
God
it
was answered by me, that true
it
had endowed His Majesty with excellent science, and great
endowments of nature; but His Majesty was not learned
in the laws
of his realm of England, and causes, which concern the
life,
or in-
heritance or goods, or fortunes of his subjects, are not to be decided
by natural reason but by the
artificial
judgment and reason of
law,
Edward Coke
Sir
which law
is
fore that a
man
Thus
it
an act which requires long study and experience, be-
can attain to the cognizance of it. (Reports 12:64)
appears that
Coke
arrived at his conception of the
common
reason by the time his early Reports are published. 62
as artificial
case, however, that
Coke much more frequently
law with reason in his as
Institutes
shifts the focus
61 .
This suggests
reason increases
as
of his conception of the
its
hold on
common
from the element of time and toward the idea of reason. Time part in his conception of the
common
law, but
It is
law the
common
identifies the
than in his Reports
time passes, the idea of che law
and that he
a
163
that,
Coke
law away still
plays
plays that part in the
it
service of reason.
There
are several scholarly interpretations of Coke’s
meaning when he
writes of the artificial reason of the law. Pococlc, for example, emphasizes the passage from Calvin's Case in which the laws by “excellent point,
Pocock
finds,
Coke speaks of the refinement of
men” by “long and
is
continual experience.” 64 Coke’s
that “philosophic reason could not
forts reconstruct the law, because the law’s origin
is
by
its
own
ef-
not in any philo-
sophic assumption but in a multitude of particular decisions.” In addition,
Coke
general principles since another,” with each
is,
it
arises
intellect
cannot reduce the law to
from “one emergency following upon
emergency being unique. By
wood Lewis concludes law; that
human
believes that the
that Coke’s concern
is
contrast,
John Under-
the reasonableness of the
with “the internal consistency of English law
as a
system and
not, primarily, with a defense of the notion that a law should be defined in
D. E. C. Yale, is,
65
In this view, further elaborated by
common
law not primarily as case law (that
terms of reason rather than
as the
Coke
sees the
will.”
product of individual emergencies) but
sense that
it
represented the product of
a
professional
refinement and co-ordination of social habits into
There readings.
is
To
a
skill
working
say that, though,
is
system of rules.” 66
to identify a further set of problems that
in the large
are dozens of references to reason
body of Coke’s writings there
and the law and that these references,
not inconsistent, make several different points, to what extent
sible to say that
law? 67
Do
a
language in Coke’s writings that appears to support both
need examination. Given that
if
as reasonable “in the
he has
a
his statements
is it
pos-
coherent pattern of beliefs about reason and the
about the
artificial
reason of the law add up to a
The Common Law Mind
164
coherent vision? In what ways
is
Coke’s exposition of the relationship
between law and reason different from that of raries,
and
what respects
in
doctrine of the
vented or that
is
common
similar? Is
it
contempo-
accurate to speak of “Coke’s
reason of the law” as
artificial
if it is a
doctrine he in-
peculiar to him?
no innovation
It is
is it
his leading
for
Coke and
his
contemporaries to hold that the
law must be in accord with reason. In being held to this stan-
common law is no different from statute law or local custom: common lawyers early on accept the civilian and canonist doctrine
dard, the
the
no purported law
that
is
really law if
it is
contrary to reason. This idea
reflected in the case reports of Coke’s day
is
by statements of the general
necessity for the law, whether customary, statutory, or
common
be in harmony with reason. Consonance with reason
one of two stan-
is
law, to
dard tests that an alleged local custom has to pass in order to be held valid. In a
void
68 .
few instances, Coke also
states that statutes against reason are
In the case reports, a typical recognition of this. principle justifies
the rejection of a rule or interpretation contrary to reason, but
times a rule or interpretation
son
69 .
Finch
states
more
fully
is
upheld because
it
some-
comports with rea-
than Coke the general requirement that
laws be consonant with reason:
The
law of nature and of reason, or the law of reason primary and
secondary, with the rules framed and collected thereupon; which three are as the sun and the to
all
moon and
the seven stars, to give light
the positive laws in the world.
Positive are laws framed in their light; and
grounds and maxims of
common
law
is
not
a
all
common
word new and
from thence came the
law: for that
it,
call
strange, or barbarous, and
proper to ourselves, and the law that we profess, learnedly would have
which we
but the right term for
all
as
some un-
other laws.
.
.
.
Therefore laws positive, which are directly contrary to the for-
mer
[the
at all
.
law of nature and reason], lose their force, and are no laws
70
Although there this generally
is
evidence from the case reports that
Coke recognizes
accepted principle, none of his statements about reason in
his Institutes clearly reflect
it.
He
does quote two standard Latin maxims
often used for stating that principle, but he goes on to gloss the in such a
way
as to suggest that the
reason he has in mind
is
maxims
not the law
Sir
Edward Coke
i6 5
of reason (or nature) but “the reason of the law,” which he says
understood of an
perfection of reason.”
artificial
“is to
be
1
Just as the case reports contain a series of references to reason that
may
best be understood as reflections of the principle that
be in harmony with the law of reason, they also contain in
law must
all
many
passages
which the references are much closer to Coke’s treatment of reason
his Institutes they
in
have to do with the reason of the law rather than the
law of reason. 72 As Coke informs King James in the Case of Prohibitions, this
reason of the law
is
not everyman’s natural reason but the
judgment and reason of law” ( Repons
why
“artificial
he
this conversation
12:64).
is
make legal judgments: he does not have the “artificial” reason necessary for making such judgments. In a parallel passage in the part of his Institutes Coke extends this idea; judgments not only have to be made by means of this artificial reason, “the common explaining
the king cannot
1
law
itselfe is
artificial
,
nothing
but reason; which
else
is
to be
understood of an
perfection of reason, gotten by long study, observation and ex-
perience, and not of every man’s natural reason” (Coke, Institutes 1:97b).
Coke law
explicitly contrasts the artificial reason of
which the
common
composed, and which has to be known and mastered by anyone
is
who makes
a legal
judgment, with natural reason. This helps us put some
may mean by
boundaries on what he possibly
may be opposed
calling legal reason “arti-
more than one sense. One such sense, that of something feigned or fictitious, Coke clearly does not have in mind. Relying on another sense of the word, ficial.”
But the
artificial
to the natural in
Charles Gray writes that the “expression stitute for reason.”
to describe
^
It is
in
is
is
a substitute for,
ing.
specific refers to
The
“artificial
sub-
may be
used
of,
the real or
reason” that suggests that
as a substitute for natural reason.
standard senses of “artificial” that
more
or imitation
a
nothing in the contexts of the several passages
which Coke uses the expression
he sees legal reason
reason suggests
true that the adjective “artificial”
something that
natural thing, but there
artificial
Coke may have
in
There
mind.
The
are
two
first
and
something attained to only by education or
Oxford English Dictionary uses
lustration of this sense:
“Not
.
.
.
a
quotation from
Coke
train-
as
an
il-
understood of every unlearned man’s
reason, but of artificial and legal reason” (Coke, Institutes 1:62a). In
Coke’s references to tion 138 of artificial
On
artificial
Littleton
,
reason in the Case of Prohibition and in sec-
his point clearly is that
and not natural
is
the fact that
what makes
legal
no one possesses
it
reason
sponta-
1
66
The Common Law Mind
§
No
4
neously.
how
matter
great that persons natural gifts,
it
can be de-
veloped only through education, training, and experience.
There
are reasons, however, for not limiting our reading of Coke’s ex-
pression “artificial reason” to reason produced by study or education.
understand Coke’s doctrine of the
make is is
artificial
To
reason of the law one must
Coke himself does not make clearly, although it implicit in what he says. That distinction is between how legal reason to be learned by those who will practice law and make legal judgments a distinction that
how that grew to much and
legal reason
reason
reason got to be what
by
legal professionals
skill
of lawyers.
is
It is
a natural process,
is
play a critical role.
I
am
Littleton
it
the knowledge of
artificial:
constructed by the art and
Coke sometimes
common
law grew to
not one in which
human
talks as if the
its
state of per-
artifice
and
skill
thinking of those passages injwhich he empha-
formation of the law — for example,
“by long experience growne to such realme” (Coke,
it is
true that
sizes the role of experience in the
this
how
Coke’s language,
not spontaneous or innate, and the
sense that
process by which the reason of the fection
— in
perfection. Both processes are
itself is artificial in the
professional
it is
Institutes 1:97b).
a perfection, for the
75
But there
is
government of
another passage, in
On
that portrays the reason of the law as the product of an active
,
exercise of the professional craft and skill of lawyers:
And by
reasoning and debating of grave learned
of ignorance
is
expelled,
and by the
discerned, and thereupon judgment is
The
men
the darkness
light of legall reason the right is
is
given according to law, which
the perfection of reason. (Coke, Institutes 1:232b) fining
shown
and refining of legal reason by grave and learned
men
to be an active, perhaps even unruly, constructive process
a passive ratification
Coke
is
is
thus
and not
of previous experience.
not being original or idiosyncratic
when he
links the “reason-
ing and debating of lawyers” with the “artificial reason of the law.”
When Thomas son, he
is
Hedley
ties
the “discourse of art or wit” to artificial rea-
making the same point
in slightly different language.
76
The
most complete discussion associating the disputations of lawyers artificial
The
reason, though,
efficient cause
is
written by Sir John Dodderidge:
of Rules, Grounds, and Axiomes
natural reason sifted
is
the light of
upon disputation and argument. And hence
it
to
Sir
is,
that the
Law
...
hend the same; but
is
Edward Coke
reason; not for that every
wisedome, learning, and long experience are
their
of men, and
fairs
know what is
fit
skilfull in the af-
and convenient to be held and ob-
served for the appeasing of controversies and debates
Both Hedley and Dodderidge
ment of
common
the
tie
can compre-
reason; the reason of such, as by
artificiall
it is
man
167
the role of
argument
among men. in the develop-
and the attainment of knowledge about
law,
to
it,
the determination of secondary principles of reason. In the Aristotelian logic in
which they were
primary conclusions of reason are uni-
and are to be accepted without question or demonstration
versally true (191).
trained,
Secondary
principles, though, are contingent
and only probably
Most common law
rules,
Dodderidge teaches, are secondary prin-
ciples and, as such, rest
upon
“discourse of Reason deducted in argu-
true.
ment”
(196).
Even though
at first
may seem
highly probable,
false (207).
This
is
doubtful question bate,
upon consideration they may prove
where the
“to find out the truth by is
glance the truth of such propositions
art of logic proves valuable;
argument and disputation”
proposed, the truth
and discourse of reason on both
is
it
teaches
whereby the corn
To summarize, one of
is
parts, as in
all
our law arguments
and
artifice
This
art
was passed down to them in
whom
they learned
dialectic, occasionally rhetoric, (ars disserendi).
78
the fact that for
it
be
said to
common
as the
law-
product of
and, particularly, the product of the art of argument.
skill
authors from
The
because they see
is
(63).
the reasons seventeenth-century is
a
found out by Argument, de-
severed from the stubble”
yers call legal reason artificial
how
“When
(62).
appeareth; and therefore such debate and conflict of reason the flayle
to be
a
it
long tradition from Aristotle.
sometimes
call it logic,
and more generally, the
The
sometimes
art of discourse
Perhaps most interesting, though, for our purposes
many
centuries
it
was
is
called ratio artificialisC
passages from the legal literature of the seventeenth century that
more about why Coke and other lawyers
we examine here
tell
reason of the law
artificial
of the answer
is
us
than about
summed up
in
why Coke
calls the
call
the
law reason. Part
Hedley ’s expression “tried reason.” Coke,
Hedley, and to some extent Davies understand the law to be reason,
indeed perfect reason, because long
trial
and experience shows
it
to be
The Common Law Mind
i68
reasonable — perfectly fitted for England and insufficient to tell us just
common lawyers of the
how widespread
people.
its
The
is
among the do know that sev-
theory was
this
early seventeenth century.
We
of the period’s most prominent lawyers do not espouse
eral
evidence
Two
it.
of
them, Sir Henry Finch and Sir John Dodderidge, wrote books containing substantial sections on general jurisprudence. 80 Both efforts to locate the
explain
common law in
serious
a larger jurisprudential universe
place not only in respect to other
its
make
human
— to
laws but also in re-
gard to the laws of nature and reason. Finch, in a line of argument that owes
man,
is
concerned to connect the
reason, to the law of nature.
The
of Adam’s
sult
common
to Christopher St.
law,
law of nature
men’s nature “which ministereth
These common
much is
by means of the idea of a
kind of reason fixed in
common principles
of good and
principles are self- evident and very general.
fall,
the originally perfect
human
and are reflected
arguing of any case”
81
the re-
still
percep-
our course in the
in the rules of reason that “direct
(5).
As
evil.”
ability to discern these
principles has been greatly weakened, but the principles are tible
Ger-
Indeed, Finch states, the “law of nature and of
reason, or the law of reason primary and secondary, with the rules
formed and collected thereupon,” of the grounds and maxims of
are the source of
common law (74). Finch does not limit English common law: references to the
“common
common
laws of Greece by Euripides and Plato
law” to the
term and prove the
This
common
reason
common is
law to be nothing but
He
explains
reason by quoting Cicero and Plato:
nominatur
cometh of
all.”
show
rite sapientia , as
“
reason.
what he means by refined
Quae cum
adolevit atque perfecta
How?
— is
it
test for the pri-
dialectal reasoning proceeds.
although Finch does not explicitly say
when
’’generally received
nothing else than Aristotle’s
mary premise from which
it,
generally received by the consent
His gloss on the meaning of these authors — all”
common
Tully saith, and as Plato hath
to be opinio or decretum.
by the consent of
the antiquity of
“not that which every one doth frame unto
himself, but refined reason” (75).
est
and
all
the term
the
positive laws
all
so, that
This suggests,
he means by refined rea-
son the maxims or grounds of the law — a standard understanding
among
the lawyers of his time.
1 here
is
the whole
no hint
in
Finch of the strand of thought, running through
body of Coke’s
judicial opinions
and
legal writings, that asso-
Sir
ciates legal reason with the antiquity of the
experience that antiquity represents.
with the existence of
a
Finch shows no interest in the age of the sion of legal philosophy
conform
Such are the so
appears only to be concerned
is
it
self
con-
common
His entire discus-
law.
directed at showing that
all
positive laws
s:
must
Unlike Coke, he
in altering established rules of law:
common
many laws: and
and the
a
takes to be achieved. Indeed,
to the law of nature and the law of reason.
no danger
sees
law and with the
not with the process by which such
arrived at or the length of time
is
common
169
consensus in support of any ground from which
legal reasoning will proceed,
sensus
He
Edward Coke
laws of England; and almost so
as those laws are diverse
same laws may be
long as no alteration
is
altered
many people
from one another, so one
and changed
in themselves, so
permitted against the two main laws of na-
ture and reason. 83
Dodderidge’s The English Lawyer remains to
this
day one of the most
comprehensive treatments of the relationship between law and reason English; in his 84
He
own
time, there was nothing to which
it
in
could be com-
Coke and other contemporaries in associating English law with reason. The laws of England “are grounded upon the depth of reason and invested oftentimes by the name of reason in our
pared.
agrees with
Reported Cases.”*' Like Finch, however, he shows no inclination to praise the all
common
1
law in comparison with other peoples laws. Because
laws “are derived from the
in the principles of
great agreement the
common
of Nature, and do concurre and agree
Nature and Reason,”
among them
(158-59).
it
follows that there
This may be seen
must be
in the fact that
law borrows “some thousand Axioms and Conclusions of
Reason” from the
Doddridge has
common
Law
civil law. little
sympathy with
common
lawyers
who
praise the
law largely for the long accretion of experience, gotten through
the decision of the thousands of particular cases that the experience represents. It
is
better,
he argues, to begin with general rules and proposi-
tions and reason our
way
to particular conclusions.
Things proposed
in
known and most familiar to our understanding; our memory better. They are the precepts of art and
their generality are best
they also stick in
therefore are called perpetual and eternal (140).
sentence repudiating
much
that
Coke
stands
for,
On
the same page, in a
h^ adds:
The Common Law Mind
170
For the orderly proceeding of every Art, Methodically handled,
from the due regard had of the
generall, to descend vnto the spe-
cials contained vnderneath the same: wherefore
knowledge: for experience, which
is
it
ensueth hereof,
most speedy instruments of
that generall Propositions are the
wholly gotten by the observa-
tion of particular things (being deprived of speculation) blinde, doubtfull,
is
is
slow,
and deceiueable, and truly called the mistress of
fools.
He
does not, however, draw the conclusion that the laws of England
should be published, after the manner of the
with their conclusions.
cial rules
It is better,
deliberation and debate of reason, by
on the occasions of cases
ultie”
than to try to decide
tion,
positive laws (241).
all
men
civil law, as
general and spe-
he
frame
says, “to
skilful
Law upon
and learned in that
fac-
arising that required judicial determina-
cases in advance through the
enactment of
Having deprecated experience, Dodtieridge proceeds
common law“not for that every man can com-
to demonstrate that he can be as inconsistent as the next yer.
The
law
is
called reason, he writes,
prehend the same; but
reason; the reason of such, as by
it is artificiall
wisedome, learning, and long experience are
their
skillful in the affaires
of men” (242).
Although Finch and Dodderidge do not
mon it,
find the reason of the
com-
law proved by the English people’s long and happy experience with
they do join with the adherents of that view in deriving from the Aris-
much
totelian tradition
reason to law. All
Christopher
St.
of their understanding of the application of
common
lawyers
who
German were exposed
logic and rhetoric, even if they had
read Sir John Fortescue and
to the Aristotelian tradition in
no formal university
training.
86
By
the mid- sixteenth century the Inns of Court were attracting substantial
numbers of students who had studied academic philosophy sities.
and
8
Coke himself attended
a half years,
Trinity College, Cambridge, for three
and afterward emphatically recommended university
training in logic as a basis for studying the
By
this
essary
argument it is
at the univer-
logically
drawne a
common
divisione
,
it
law:
appeareth
how
nec-
come from one common law, where he may
that our student should (as Littleton did)
of the universities to the studie of the
learne the liberal arts, and especially logick, for that teacheth a
man
not onely by
just
argument to conclude the matter
in question,
Sir
Edward Coke
but to discerne betweene truth and falsehood, and to use
method and
is
and probably to speake to any
in his studie,
defined thus, dialectica
whereby
disserendi,
est scientia
appeareth
it
how
171
a
good
legall question,
probaliter de quovis themate
necessary
it is
for our student.
(Coke, Institutes 1:235a)
common
Dodderidge
also urges
Responding
to the objection that natural reason
lawyers to apply logic to their study.
derstanding of law, he writes: “Reason Art, and therefore is
is
is
is
un-
sufficient for the
naturall, but yet
best by the Art of Reason, which
is
it is
polished by
Logicke A
88
Logic
necessary to the study of law because:
The Art
of Logicke
is
the Art of reasoning, Ars argumentandi, as
one of the properties thereof, teaching
ment and
ter find
out truth by argu-
Common Law of this Land
disputation. But the
name of common
often stiled in our Bookes by the
(which
reason)
is
is
de-
duced from principles evident and knowne, for the decision of such things as are drawne into doubt, and are
thereof are taught by Logicke.
.
.
man
Againe, Logicke teacheth a ples,
.
grounds and rules observed
unknowne. The precepts
to collect the
in that
Axiomes, princi-
Art which he studieth, and
being so collected aptly to dispose the same. 84
The
recommended by Coke and Dodderidge
Aristotelian logic
foundation for
common
mon
claim that
lawyers
reason and
is
s
law reasoning provides
common between
knowledge. Scientific knowledge tion (demonstration)
by
from which
scientific is
attained through syllogistic deduc-
logical necessity
scientific
and practical reasoning and
from
first
91 themselves demonstrable. This
principles.
90
The
first
reasoning proceeds are true, universal,
and primary, but their truth and status
certain,
is
the
not arbitrary.
Aristotle distinguishes
principles
comfounded on
a rationale for
law decision making
as a
is
as first principles are
not
so because in order for principles to
be proved by syllogistic reasoning, other more fundamental priciples
must
lie
behind them to serve
principles are apprehended
known
as the
premises for that reasoning:
first
by induction from experience, and are
92 Neither their existence nor to be true by intellectual intuition.
their truth can be established
by reasoning or proof. Instead, they are
self-evident: “in regard to first principles
it is
improper to ask any
fur-
The Common Law Mind
172
why and the wherefore of them; command belief in and of itself.” 93
ther for the
should
The knowledge certain, law.
each of the
first
principles
acquired through demonstration, though true and
not immediately applicable to questions concerning
is
Human
affairs are
human
made up of too many complex combinations and
arrangements of particulars to admit of exact reasoning leading to certain truths
94 .
In theoretical science, reasoning “by demonstration” starts
from premises that are cal science,
true, universal,
immutable, and certain; in practi-
reasoning starts from premises that are only probable.
are probable in the sense that they are “generally accepted”
or by the majority or by the philosophers
— i.e.,
by
or by the most notable and illustrious of them.”''-
all,
They
by “everyone
or by the majority
CHAPTER EIGHT
Reason and the
T
he
common law
Common Law Maxims
of England, made up as
it is
of a huge, chaotic, ap-
parently inconsistent mass of particular rules and cases, to
mon
noncom-
lawyers often seems to be incapable of being even an Aristotelian
practical science.
As
common
a result,
charge that certainty of decision
is
lawyers are forever rebutting the
impossible. Beginning with Sir
John
Fortescue in the late fifteenth century, and for the next two centuries,
many common
lawyers respond in Aristotelian terms: they can reason
way to sure conclusions because there exist fundamental principles of law — maxims — that are accepted without question by the profession. Quotation of maxims, in the modern sense of short, pithy statements or showy proverbs, is common among medieval common lawyers and judges, but until Fortescue, there is no evidence that the common lawyers conceive of maxims technically as the principles from which correct their
legal reasoning legal
maxims
can with assurance proceed
1
.
explicitly to Aristotle’s teachings
Aristotle, in the first
book of the
Fortescue
ties the
about reasoning:
Physics says that ,
We
think
we know
anything when we know the causes and principles of it as far as the
On
ments of it.
this the
Commentator observes
by principles effective causes final causes ,
,
form. In the laws, indeed, there
is
,
and
use of
that Aristotle
meant
by elements matter
no matter and form
ele-
,
as there
and is
in
physical things and in things artificially devised. But nevertheless
there are in
them
certain elements out of which they proceed as out
of matter and form, such as customs, statutes, and the law of nature,
from which
all
the laws of the realm proceed as natural things do
out of matter and form, just as
which are
also called elements.
all
we read comes out of
The
the letters
principles, furthermore,
which
*73
*74
The Common Law Mind
is
the
Commentator
said are effective causes, are certain universals
which those learned alike call
maxims,
just as rhetoricians
These
ians of rules of law.
force of
argument nor by
quired, as
first
speak of paradoxes, and
logical demonstrations, but they are ac-
taught in the second book of the Posteriora by induc-
is
,
book of
memory. Wherefore
Aristotle says in
the Physics that Principles do not proceed out of other
things nor out of one another, but other things proceed out of them.
book of the
in the first
ground for holding
whoever
written that Any principle
it is
For that reason, Aristotle
it.
as
,
Ethics, there
is
final causes, to
principles.
its
which one
it is
is
is its
own
no argu-
written in the sixth
is
any branch of knowledge must
For out of them are discovered the
brought by
a
process of reasoning
upon
knowledge of principles. 2
Throughout the sixteenth and seventeenth yers continue to speak of
and
totelian logic
dialectic
maxims
and to see them
3
stitute,
more than once
maxime
is
describes
Sir
maxims be of
a proposition, to
common
centuries,
law-
in the technical language of Aris-
argument and reasoning. For example,
A
says, There
Hence
no rational ground for principles. Therefore,
are anxious to understand
learn thoroughly
a
Topica
who deny principles because,
ing with those
book of the
civil-
known by
principles, indeed, are not
tion through the senses and
the
England and mathematicians
in the laws of
all
as a starting point for legal
Edward Coke,
in his First In-
in such terms:
men
confessed and granted
without proofe, argument, or discourse. Contra negantem principia non
est
disputandum.
Maxime,
i.e.
a
.
.
sure foundation or ground of art, and a conclusion of
reason, so called quia atque quod
.
maxima
est ejus
maxime omnibus probetur, so sure and uncontrollable
And
they ought not to be questioned.
and in other places calleth ple;
and
dignitas et certissima authoritas,
it is all
axiome, and
it
one with
a
that
which our author here
maxime, hereafter he
a ride, a
that
common ground,
calleth a princi-
postulatum, or an
were too much curiositie to make nice distinctions
betweene them.
And
it is
well said in our bookes, n
Pancient principles del ley. (Coke,
The problem with
the
Institutes 1:67a,
common
}
est
my
a disputer
iob-na)
lawyers’s reliance
guide to the Aristotelian understanding of principles
on Fortescue is
as a
that Fortescue
Common Law Maxims
Reason and the
defines the science.
maxims of
Not only
is
fit
this a
misunderstanding of Aristotle, the ideas thus
common
law do not
well with other parts of the received understanding about the
To be
law.
15
the law according to the principles of theoretical
enshrined as part of the standard description of the always
l
sure, applying Aristotle’s notions
oretical science to legal
combat the charge
maxims hold
that the
common
about the principles of the-
who wish
attractions for those
law
to
radically indeterminate. It al-
is
lows the lawyers to attribute to their maxims universality, perfection, certainty,
and self-evidence. Further,
H.
as
F.
Jolowicz writes about Sir
Edward Coke, it is convenient for those of authoritarian temperment “who perhaps did not wish people to inquire too closely into their [the maxims’s] antecedents.” 4 Unfortunately, repeated assertions that
maxims
“without proofe, argument, or discourse” (Gbke,
are to be accepted
Institutes 1:67a)
do not
keep disputes from arising concerning alleged maxims. Disagreements 5
concerning maxims are predictable, for
as St.
German
has his doctor of
divinity point out, “sythe they cannot be proued by reason as thou
agreest thy selfe they can not they
onles there be
some
them.” 6 This
a
is
may
as lighty
be denyed
as affirmed
approue
statute or other suffycyent auctorytie to
problem that demanded
a solution,
because
if
maxims
are to be the reliable starting point of legal reason, there has to be agree-
ment about what they mining
their validity.
or at least
are,
The common
German and Dodderidge, seem
some accepted method of
deter-
lawyers, with the exception of St.
content to rest on their assertion of the
nondisputability of maxims.
Dodderidge ’s treatment of the disputability of maxims ably
more complex than Coke’s or even
whether is
a
a
maxim can be
primary or
a
Sir Francis Bacon’s.
contested depends principally
secondary conclusion of reason.
clusion of reason, then
it is
If
consider-
is 8
For him,
upon whether
it is
a
it
primary con-
imprinted on the mind of every person by na-
ture,
needs no proof, and cannot be disputed (Lawyer 191-93). Most com-
mon
law maxims, though, are secondary principles of reason, derived
from general customs or the primary conclusions of the law of nature
(
Lawyer 194). 9 Dodderidge follows standard medieval and early
modern teaching on logic in asserting that knowledge of such secondary principles is more problematic, due to “the weaknesse of men’s understanding and the difficultie of the matter” (Lawyer 207). Indeed,
“much
of the manner and forme of Arguments in the Lawes of England” are
176
$
The Common Law Mind
produced by those obstacles ( Lawyer
presumed
to be true,
and the law
194).
will
Some secondary principles
are
“permit no allegation to impugn
them, or any speech or averment to impeach their credit,” even though
do containe manifest and apparent falshood” (Lawyer
in fact “they
204). But
more commonly, secondary
known by
principles are
197,
“dis-
course of reason conducted in argument” and are permitted to be challenged and to be “restrained by exceptions” (Lawyer 196, 207-9). 10 scarcely possible,” says Dodderidge, “to
Law, but that
it
shall faile in
some
"h
ls
make any secondary* Rule of
particular case.”
By reason whereof they doe permit the Rules, Axiomes, and Propositions of the common Law, upon discourse & disputation of reason, to be restrained by exceptions; which are grounded upon two causes. The one is Equity: the other is some other Rule or Ground of Law, which seemeth to encounter the Ground or Rule proposed: wherein, for conformities sake, and that no absurdity or contradiction be permitted, certain exceptions are framed. (Lawyer 209)
might appear that Dodderidge,
It
basis for disputing legal
maxims
that
maxims,
is
in holding that equity can serve as the
radically
undermining the certainty
are alleged to provide as premises for legal reasoning
thus undermining the claim of the law to be called reason. stead, that equity serves to increase the reason of the law a
check to keep secondary principles of
sult
law,
which are
of man’s imperfect reasoning capacity, in
fully
He argues,
He
in-
by operating
fallible as
harmony with
and perfect reason of the law of God and nature.
— and as
the re-
the higher
shows himself to be
aware of the hostility that some of his colleagues hold toward equity
by citing the
common
be controlled
contentions that “if
as often in
should be ... no
all
Lawes should change and
every case as equity would require, then there
Law certaine,” and
all
cases
would be decided according
to “the Arbitrary conceipt of the Iudge” (Lawyer 212).
compromise (which surely would not which “the
common Law in some
the constancy of the law
cases,
proposes
a
satisfy the critics of equity) in
should follow equity, as farre as
would permit, and
one Rule thereof with another: which
He
for the better conformity of
common Law againe in other cases
should refuse equity for the better avoiding of confusion.”
As
his
second basis for permitting
for subjecting
them
to exceptions,
rienced lawyers know, but
many
legal
maxims
to be questioned, and
Dodderidge points out what
all
expe-
nontheless deny: that in a legal system
Reason and the
Common Law Maxims
177
developed over sevefal centuries one will find rules and principles that conflict with other rules
and principles. Serjeant Morgan, in
sixteenth-century discussion of
common
his
famous
law maxims, partially antici-
pates Dodderidge:
But maxims are the foundations of the
law,
and the conclusions of
reason, and therefore they ought not to be impugned, but always to
be admitted; yet those maxims
may by
the help of reason, be
com-
pared together and set one against another (although they do not vary) where to
may
it
be distinguished by reason that
a
thing
is
nearer
one maxim than to another, or placed between two maxims, yet
nevertheless they ought never to be impeached or impugned, but al-
ways to be observed and held
as firm principles
and authorities of
themselves." #
Morgan opens
the door slightly for the examination of
maxims by
permitting the comparison of two maxims for the purpose of determining whether a factual situation
fits
other, but he contends that such a conflict.
comparison
Although Dodderidge claims that he
gan’s statement, he clearly goes
maxims
better under one
are false,
maxims (Lawyer
some
beyond
it,
conflict with equity,
is
will
maxim than
the
never show them to
simply elucidating
freely admitting that
Morsome
and some conflict with other
229). It is for these reasons that
he says that some sec-
ondary principles can be impeached and that exceptions can be taken to them.
The Morgan-Coke
doctrine of the nondisputability of legal
maxims
can be traced back to Fortescue’s fifteenth-century pronouncement that
who deny holding it. 12 The
there can be no arguing with those ciple
is its
own ground
for
principles, because a prin-
doctrine has
its
origins in
Fortescue’s confusion of Aristotle’s description of the principles of theoretical science (which are absolutely true but
cannot be demonstrated
by reason and, hence, cannot be the basis of a reasoned dispute) with the principles of a practical science (such as law),
which are only probably
true and that are properly the subjects of reasoning and argument.
consequence of the
common
As
a
lawyers ’s confusion about the logical the-
ory on which they explicitly rest their treatment of legal maxims, their statements about those maxims sometimes appear to be incoherent. For
example, they frequently assert that maxims are “the conclusions of reason,” but they also hold that they are to be accepted without proof, dis-
The Common Law Mind
178
cussion, or tle
argument on the
that “there
no
is
basis of Fortescue’s quotation
rational
ground
sion and debate
14 .
Coke
for principles .” 13
takes the position that the preeminent
from Aristoordinarily
method of legal reason
is
discus-
But he apparently sees no need to explain why, since
he says that maxims are the conclusions of reason. the reason that underlies
maxims
is
not
He
also insists that
of debate,
a legitimate subject
discourse, or evaluation.
Dodderidge’s sophisticated understanding of the philosophical tradition that underlies his treatment of realistic
maxims
allows
him
to give a
common
and theoretically coherent account of the reason of the
many
law than that offered by
of his contemporaries.
He
more
can admit that
parts of the law are uncertain, inequitable, wrongheaded, or in conflict
with other parts and yet claim that the law
as a
whole
is
reasonable be-
cause of the reason worked out artificially through the debate and dis-
course of lawyers. Although
Coke
at
times also speaks of the the
reason of the law in terms of the erudition and plied to the law through debate
and argument,
scribes that reason in terms of the
skill
at
artificial
of the lawyers ap-
other times he de-
happy experience, without inconve-
nience, that generations of Englishmen have with the law. This suggests that even if he in attaining It is
rigor,
is
concerned with theoretical coherence, he has
it.
not surprising that Coke, with his notorious lack of theoretical
should
feel
no need to harmonize the apparently inconsistent parts
of his discussion of maxims, reason, and the a
difficulty
common
law. It
is,
however,
testament to the hold that the formulations of the traditional ideology
of the
common
law had on the lawyers of the era that
cally acute as Francis
Bacon should pay
a
man
at least lip service to
as theoreti-
them
at the
momment when he is reinventing the conceptualization of maxims the common law. Bacon was instrumental in shifting the common
very in
law conception of maxims from that of “a body of absolute and unquestioned detailed rules” to that of “broad premises for legal reasoning.”
'’
1
Despite this great innovation, however, he illustrates the hold of traditional
common
law ideology on the lawyers of his time because he de-
clines to disclose the reasoning or evidence that lies
of the
new kind of maxims he
undue and preposterous
behind
his
proposes, saying, “I judged
to prove rules and
examples a
it
maxims; wherein
I
matter
had the
example of Mr. Littleton and Mr. Fitzherbert, whose writings are the stitutions of the laws of
England .” 16
in-
CHAPTER NINE
The Common Law Mind
A Summary and Commentary
Case Law Writers on comparative jurisprudence have long stressed attitude toward precedent as the
mon
law and
Roman
a difference in
primary disfinction between the com-
John W. Salmond
legal traditions.
states the stan-
dard view:
T he importance of
judicial precedents has always
guishing characteristic of English law. ever,
.
.
.
been
Nei ther Roman
a distin-
law,
how-
nor any of those modern systems which one founded upon
it,
allows any such place or authority to precedent.
They
further or no other influence than that which
possessed by any
other expression of expert opinions
it
no
1 .
begun
Recently, comparative lawyers have
is
allow
modify
to
this
view of the
standing of precedent as a source of law but only because they conclude that courts
on the Continent began openly to
reaching their decisions. ditions
on the
The
is
on
earlier cases in
standard distinction between the two tra-
basis of their attitudes
element of truth but
rely
toward precedent
based on an
is
extremely misleading, both historically and
jurisprudentially.
The germ emperor
Roman jurists
is
of truth the sole
lies in
the fact that Justinian, by decreeing that the
maker and interpreter of the law and reducing
jurisprudence to a written code, attempted to keep judges and
out of the business of developing the law by further decreeing that
“decisions should be based not
on precedents but on
dle Ages, the civilian jurists took the
and universally taught that
a judicial
maxim non
decision
is
laws.”
:
In the
Mid-
exemplis very seriously
binding only on the par-
179
The Common Law Mind
i8o
ties to the case in
which
since “other judges It is likely,
it is
made but can have no other
must not decide according
legal effect,
to that example.”
however, that as faithful as civilian
jurists
were
3
in repeating
the non exemplis formula, case law always played an important part in the
development of
how
Roman
legal doctrine. If judges
similar cases were decided, there
dictability in the law.
would be
never paid attention to little
coherence or pre-
This would lead to the violation of what has been
regarded as a central requirement of justice since the time of Aristotle — that similar cases be treated similarly. Therefore
nental judges were always aware of what
Medieval
civilians easily
hibition against a reliance
found
a
way
w as done r
I
suspect that Conti-
before in similar cases.
to justify circumventing the pro-
on precedents. Even though precedents them-
selves could not serve as authority for judicial decisions, these civilians
developed the doctrine that lish the existence
it
takes only
two
judicial decisions to estab-
of a legally binding custom. In other words,
upheld in two decisions,
it is
proved to be
a
if a
rule
is
custom. Since the civilians
agreed that customs were “law” within the meaning 5 f Justinian’s Code 7.45.13,
two
earlier judicial decisions could serve as legal authority for
present decisions. If the civilians’ avoided their rule against the authority
of earlier decisions by the exercise of a jurisprudential sleight of hand, the
common lawyers,
contrary to widespread
doctrine of binding precedent. Bracton
is
belief,
alone
had for centuries no
among
the early treatise
writers in showing any interest in decided cases, referring to several hun-
dred cases in De Legibus and collecting some two thousand cases in his Notebook. But Bracton did not intend his cases or case citations to be re-
garded
A
as
having binding force in future cases.
workable doctrine of the binding authority of earlier cases
difficult to achieve
Within it
a
very
is
without reliable reports of what those cases hold.
generation of Bracton’s death the Year
continued until the sixteenth century.
Book
series began,
The Year Books
and
are crude law
reports, but they were not designed for the purpose of recording precedents. Instead, they
were used for teaching law students and lawyers the
techniques of pleading.
The judgment
users of the Year Books, and so
it is
in a case
was of no interest to the
not ever reported.
The
object of
pleading was to determine the issue, which was then decided as a question of fact.
The
idea
was to
arrive at an affirmative proposition
coun-
tered by a direct negative. Pleading was done orally and tentatively; no
written record was
made
until the
end of the term. Pleas could be
tried
Summary out and withdrawn
if
arid
Commentary
181
problems were encountered. The Year Book
re-
porters were interested in what happened to particular pleas and in the
arguments surrounding the pleas and demurrers.
As long
as the interest
of the profession concentrated on the formula-
tion of the issue rather than
was
on the decision of
pressure for the kind of accurate reporting that the theory of
little
binding precedent requires. Such pressure
ment of
come only with
the develop-
the view that particular decisions are authoritative in regard to
the issues they decide.
from
particular points, there
The
shift,
beginning in the fifteenth century,
oral pleadings to written pleadings “enabled the point at issue to be
defined
more
clearly,
and concentrated attention more firmly upon the
decision of that point.” 4 This in turn led a shift in interest from the for-
mulation of the issue to the decision of the est
from the debate
the growth of the cases and to the
According to the Year
Books
in court to the decision
modern view
issue.
as to the authority
is
in fewer than
the shift in inter-
ofThe court eventually led to
growth of the practice of citing
my count,
And
of particular decided
cases.'
one of twenty cases reported
in
there any mention by counsel, judge, or reporter of
any earlier case. Reference to an earlier case specific enough for identification
is
much
rarer.
more frequently
As the Year Book period came
to an end, cases are
cited than in the earlier Year Books, “but at
were the citations
sufficiently
practice of relying
on
numerous
judicial decisions.”
to say that there
was
no time
a general
6
After 1535 the Year Books ceased, but they were replaced by reports of cases compiled
by named reporters. Some of the early reports, such
those of J. Dyer, closely resemble the Year Books.
Commentaries which cover ,
are very different
much
and establish
a
Edmund
as
Plowden’s
of the same period as Dyer's Reports,
model
for accurate, detailed, clear re-
porting of the questions at issue, the debates of council, the judgments,
and the reasons for the judgments. Although Plowden’s reports were greatly admired, they were not emulated until Burrow's Reports of the
mid- eighteenth century. And
until accurate reports
were
available, the
modern theory of case law and precedent, which holds that a case once decided binds a court to make the same decision in a future similar case, could not be fully established in practice. "Phis
is
not to suggest that the
view that particular decisions are binding was arrived can see
its
at
suddenly.
We
foreshadowing in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.
Neither Plowden nor Dyer contain assertions that precedents are bind-
1
The Common Law Mind
82
both continue the practice, begun in the
ing, but
creased citations of earlier cases. 8
Some
den contain more than twenty case
coming
By
the time of
Coke and Bacon
common
of the cases reported by Plow-
common
for
were
lawyers.
in the early seventeenth century,
became
authoritative.
But seventeenth-
lawyers like Coke, Bacon, and later
Matthew Hale do
prior decisions unquestionably
century
Year Books, of in-
citations. Clearly, decided cases
much more importance
to have
later
not regard individual decided cases as law; they see cases as the “evi-
dence” or “proof” of law. “Our Booke Cases,” writes Coke, “are the best proofes of what the law
by
Sir
0
is.”
This understanding
is
stated in
more
detail
Matthew Hale: the Decisions of Courts of Justice, tho’ by Virtue of the
It is true,
Laws of
this
Realm they do
bind, as a law between the parties
thereto, as to the particular
Case
or Attaint, yet they do not
make
in Question, a
Law
’till
revers’d
by Error
properly so called, (for that
only the King and Parliament can do); yet they hav^a great weight at
Authority in Expounding, Declaring, and Publishing what the
law of this kingdom
is,
especially
when such Decisions hold
a
Con-
sonancy and Congruity with Resolutions and Decisions of former times; and tho’ such Decisions are less than a Law, yet they are a
greater Evidence thereof than the Opinion of any private Persons, as such, whatsoever.
The view parties
is
10
that individual legal decisions are binding only identical to the civilian
sions. Just like the civilians, the
bound to give Vaughan put it If a
cording to law. For
my
judicially,
This sounds
lawyers teach that judges are
As Chief
Justice
like
a like cause.
is
not bound to
first
given was ac-
another Court
think that judgment
in another
sworn to judge according ought not to give the
it
Court may
judgment given
having
common
in 1670:
give like judgment, unless
man
view of the authority of judicial deci-
their decisions according to the law.
Court give judgment
ceives a
between the
err
.
.
.
Court
to law, that
therefore,
if a
judge con-
to be erroneous, he being
is,
in his
own
conscience
judgment, for that were to wrong every
11
like a civilian gloss
on
Justinian’s decree that “decisions
should be based not in precedents but on laws.”
Summary and Commentary Undoubtedly, the history,
much more
cided cases.
mon mon
It is
common
law has always been,
at
.83
every point in
its
receptive than the civil law to the influence of de-
case law rather than
book
law.
But when leading com-
lawyers and judges feel called upon to announce the official
com-
law theory regarding the authority of precedents, they usually say
something that
have no quarrel with. Sometimes they
civilian jurists
even quote from Justinian,
when Chief Justice
as
Bereford, in the early
fourteenth century, states a garbled but clearly recognizable version of the
maxim non
T If there
is
an important difference between the
common law doctrines of precedent, it lies in the fact that common lawyers do not teach that judges have to ignore precedent.
civilian
the
exemplis
and
They hold hold that
that precedent has to
it is
conform
to reason and the law, and they
the law and not precedent that constitutes the authority for
judicial decisions.
But they are always open
yers and judges might learn something
from
to.
the possibility that law-
earlier cases.
Common Law and Statute The common
lawyers never accepted the view that general custom can
abrogate statutes, notwithstanding Mcllwain’s thesis that the medieval
common
common
lawyers regarded the
fundamental law to which
all
mon
To
a
Not
a
other forms of law are subordinate.
by
single statement of that doctrine
found.
law (conceived as custom) as
a
medieval
the contrary, the Year Books
make
it
common
lawyer
is
to be
very clear that the com-
lawyers universally held that statutes controlled the
common
law in
cases of conflict.
In the seventeenth century, in Dr. livered himself of
some remarks
will
it
that are
common
that he understands that the
And
Bonham V law
appears in our books, that in
Case, Sir
Edward Coke
sometimes taken is
as
de-
evidence
superior to statute:
many
cases the
common
law
controul Acts of Parliament, and sometimes adjudge them to
be utterly void: for
when an Act of Parliament
is
against
common
right and reason, or repugnant, or impossible to be performed, the
common In Rowles
v.
law will controul
Mason,
a later case
law and local custom, the
common
it,
Coke
and adjudge such Act to be void. 13
involving a conflict between the
sets
common
out to explain the relationship between
law and the other two kinds of English law:
184
The Common Law Mind
§
Fortescue and Littleton and sists
others are agreed that the law con-
all
common
of three parts. First,
Secondly, Statute Law,
law.
common
which corrects, abridges and explains the
Custom, which takes away the common corrects, allows
law:
law: the third,
But the
common
law
and disallows both statute law and custom, for
if
there be repugnancy in a statute, or unreasonableness in a custom, the
common law disallows
and rejects
it,
as
Bonhams
appears by Dr.
Case. 14
some
cir-
law will override the authority of statutes.
Un-
Both of these statements do appear to hold that cumstances the
common
fortunately for those the
common
liament,
law as
who contend
a
“power and
in these cases
Crown and
Par-
which are established by Parliament” and that the
jurisdiction of the Parliament, for the it
causes within any bounds.”
Coke
1 -
and he may well be on
discover pretty
much what
Those disposed
to see
Bonham's Case that the
all
is
“so
cannot be confined either for persons or is
manifestly capable of being incon-
this subject. Scholars find
as a theorist
possible to
it
of
a
fundamental law superior
other law find support in the statement in
common and
void, acts of Parliament,
making of laws”
they want to discover in these passages.
Coke
to king, parliament, and
law will sometimes control, and even
in the Rowles statement that the
law corrects, allows, and disallows other law. Those as
presenting
is
and most binding laws
asserts that “the highest
transcendent and absolute as
sistent,
Coke
fundamental law that limits both
Coke elsewhere
are the statutes
that
at least in
who want
common
to see
him
an advocate of parliamentary sovereignty happily notice that in Rowles
he says that statute law corrects the tutes
common
law and that in the
Insti-
he asserts that the highest laws are those made by Parliament.
Perhaps the most plausible interpretation based only on
a
reading of
Coke tries out the fundamental law idea and then either changes his mind or is pressured into offering a different view. 16 Although in chapter 7 I attempt to show how hard it is to be certhese four passages
is
that
tain about Coke’s views, in Botihatn 's Case
I
tend to side with those
Coke never
teaches that the
authority to statute, although
from
A
theirs.
my
reasons
who contend
common
may
law
is
that even
superior in
be somewhat different
17
passage in Justinian’s Digest
interpreter of statutes.”
Even
(1.3.37)
holds that “custom
civilians like
is
the best
Lucas de Penna, skeptical of
Summary and Commentary
185
custom’s powers to abrogate statutory law, allow custom considerable
scope in interpreting and supplementing statutes. Similarly, although
common law was always that legislation is suthe common law, the common law is frequently
the settled doctrine in the
perior to custom or to
said to be the best interpreter of statutes. In the sixteenth century,
common
lawyers and judges became increasingly interested in the prob-
lems of statutory interpretion and developed rules to guide their interpretive practice.
tation holds that the best interpretation
18
is
Byzantine network of
a
One
of the rules of interpre-
most consistent with
the one
reason — not reason in the abstract but the reason of the
“And
also statutes
common
law.”
1
common
law:
ought to be construed according to the reason of the
Perhaps because the judges were losing the power they
''
once possessed to openly exercise discretion in interpretation, they begin to show
a willingness to find that statutes fail the test
When
ableness.
they find
a statute to
read
it
Stowell
in a
manner
would make
that
it,
Lord Zouch three judges say
v.
be unreasonable or to create mis-
do not declare
chiefs or inconveniences, they
,
of reason-
it
in their
to be void; they simply
judgment, reasonable. In
that:
Acts of Parliament are laws positive which consist of two parts. first is,
the words of the Act, the other
is
the sense, for the letter
without the sense does not make the law, but the together.
.
common
law,
.
.
And
and has
said),
the
which a
way
is
to
letter
apprehend the sense
is
and the sense
to consider the
the ancient of every positive law (as
Brown
place in the exposition of the law positive; and
thereby the mischiefs and inconveniences, which are in the
letter,
are to be considered and avoided by the application of reason,
by putting such construction on the law positive rigors
as shall exclude all
v.
Steward also upholds the power of the
judges to construe statutory language differently from in order that the statute
might meet the
“And so the Judges have expounded the particular, which exposition is contrary contrary to reason. statutes,
.
.
.
And
common
text
test
which
is
common its
law
apparent
of reasonableness: general to be but
to the text, because the text
is
so reason shall guide the exposition of
and the equity of them.” 21
of the powers of the against
and
and mischiefs, and stand with equity and good reason. 20
Fulmerston
meaning
The
common
When Coke
speaks in Bonham's Case
law to control statutes
when they
are
right or reason, or repugnant, or impossible to be per-
The Common Law Mind
i86
formed,
mon
suspect but cannot prove that he
I
law
is
common I
know
common
superior to statutes or that the
power of judicial review; he
not claiming that the com-
is
law judges have the
merely continuing to assert the power of
is
law judges to interpret statutes in ways consistent with reason.
of no sixteenth- or seventeenth-century
common
law case in
be void.
We
today, having been ex-
posed to the jurisprudence of legal realism,
may
feel inclined to say that
which the judges hold
a statute to
power hardly distinguishable from the
common
approach to interpretation gives the
in fact this
common
that of judicial review
law judges
and
a
that, if
law truly does provide the measure for the reasonable-
ness of statutes, then
That, however,
is
a
conclude that
fair to
it is
view from the outside.
his sixteenth- century
models looked
it is
doubtful that
It is
at the
superior to statute.
Coke and
matter in that way.
Custom Medieval
civilian jurists
took
They concern
thoritative source of law. as
what custom
is,
as a given that custoiti
it
thority
status as law
its
might have once
it
There were two dence about theories has
The major
to create law,
what
by whose aulegal effect
it
attained legal force, and as usual each of those
origins in apparently incompatible Corpus Juris texts.
on custom base custom’s
Some of the
on the
legal authority
texts,
however, assert that only the emperor
earlier
medieval civilians took very seriously
the Digest texts that hold custom’s binding authority derived people’s agreement or consent
(1.3.32. 1
and
1.3.35)
the medieval civilians was to the contrary;
they taught, had by means of
a lex regia
from the
an d taught that
voluntas populi that gives legal character to custom.
among
law,
basic and quite different theories in civilian jurispru-
Digest texts
law.
power
might become
has been established.
consent of the people; other
can make
its
it
might be established, and what
how customs its
themselves with such questions
under what circumstances
theoretical justifications underlie
could be an au-
sometime
lawmaking power
it is
the
The majority view the Roman people,
in the distant past ir-
to the emperor,
and
revocably transferred
all
therefore ultimately
was only the emperor’s consent, either express or
tacit, that
it
could give legal force to custom.
Not many medieval the
their
most committed
civilians held either
imperialists
theory in
its
were impelled to find
pure form. Even a place for
popu-
Summary lar
a?id
Commentary
187
action and consent in the development of customary law because the
very idea of custom presupposes the people’s action and participation.
By
the fourteenth century nearly
remote
(or intermediate,
legal force
civilians accepted the
depending upon the
view that the
cause of custom’s
jurist)
the people’s usage and the proximate or primary cause
is
the sovereign
is
power of the emperor.
common
Although the the tests for
all
its
validity
lawyers borrowed the concept of custom and
from the
civilians,
they did not borrow
its justi-
They certainly never based its authority on the idea of popular consent. The early treatise writers clearly feel a burden to estabficatory theory.
lish that the
unwritten laws of England have the status of binding law,
but they are satisfied that paraphrasing civilian texts that recognize that
To
laws could be unwritten accomplished that purpose.
the extent that
they take into account the theory behind those civilian texts, they support the imperial theory rather than the theory of popular consent. Glanvill, in its twelfth-century defense of the legal authority
glish unwritten laws, asserts that
not absurd to
it is
call leges
of En-
those laws
that were settled in council with the supporting authority of the prince.
To make
certain that
ity that gives
no one misunderstand
that
it is
the king’s author-
English laws their legal character, Glanvill immediately
quotes the famous
Roman
maxim, “What pleases the prince
imperialist
has the force of law.” Half
a
century
later,
Bracton also attributes the
authority of English unwritten law to the king’s approval.
argued that both Glanvill and Bracton developed their
what eventually came to be standard
civilian doctrine
own
It
might be
versions of
about the source
of the authority of customary law, for they both suggest that English
unwritten laws originate in the decision and approval of the magnates (remote cause) but get their authority from the approval of the king (proximate cause). This interpretation does not work, however, because if
the unwritten laws originate with the magnates’ decisions and ap-
proval,
we
clearly are not talking about
custom but about proposals
for
At the end of the thirteenth century an abbreviated version
legislation.
of Bracton s De Legibus appeared. several centuries,
it
represents
Known
all
as Britton
,
and widely used for
English law as proceeding from the
king’s authority.
There
is
no discussion of what gave custom
Year Books.
shown
It is
its
authority as law in the
true that a custom, in order to be held valid, needs to be
to be reasonable. Therefore,
it
might be
said that the
common
The Common Law Mind
188
lawyers in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries held that reason
reasonableness
law’s validity;
binding
it is
necessary background condition for any
just a
not the primary or proximate cause of
common
Sir
John Fortescue
status as
lawyers praise the
in the fifteenth century, a succes-
common
law for
and should they have perceived
law, they
might have argued that people ought to obey
all
human
laws.
a
need to
However, unlike the
and Bracton, they evidently
felt
wisdom and
its
cellence,
best of
its
law.
Beginning with sion of
is
the
But for medieval lawyers, both English and
basis of custom’s authority. civilian,
is
ex-
justify its authority as
civilians,
it
because
it is
the
and unlike Glanvill
no need to provide any
theoretical basis
for the binding character of English custom.
Christopher
St.
and early modern
German
is
common
an interesting exception to the medieval
lawyers’ almost total lack of interest in legal
theory, and in an exposition that
primarily dependent on medieval
is
theology, he locates the general custom of England in a hierarchy of laws.
this far,
it
should have
him to model his theory of custom’s authority on teachings of someone like Aquinas. He does not. Instead he merely
been the
Having followed the medieval theologians relatively easy for
says that
By
custom
itself is the
the sixteenth century
doubt that custom or the
only authority for
it
its
status as law.
no longer occurred to
the seventeenth century too, but sometimes,
like Sir
common
when
is
bind-
generally true of
there was a conflict
law and the king’s prerogative, royalist lawyers
John Davies would
common
lawyers to
common law is law or to imagine that the
ing legal character of either needs exploration. This
between the
common
feel the
need establish the dependence of the
law on the king’s authority and consent. In making this case,
royalist lawyers rely heavily
Corpus Juris of Justinian.
and
Had
explicitly
Davies
on
known
imperialist passages in the Glanvill and Bracton better,
he could have built his case from English materials. Most of Davies’s peers rejected out of hand his claim that the king’s prerogative
is
not
common law, but if they objected to Davies’s assertion that common law itself is allowed to exist only by the king’s grace, they
part of the
the
leave
no record of it.
With only
a
few exceptions, from the
late twelfth
century on, the
common
lawyers recognize custom as an authoritative source of law 22
They do
not, despite
all
.
English law
is
what C. H. Mcllwain and others claim, think that
customary
in nature.
Summary and Commentary
Two
may
things
be said with assurance about the authors of the
twelfth- and thirteenth-century Bracton:
what
little
common
law treatises, Glanvill and
they have to say about the nature of customary law
borrowed or derived from the writings of civilian
much
have
189
is
and they do not
jurists,
Both Glanvill and Bracton are concerned to claim for
to say.
the unwritten English laws the status of law. So far as their authors knew, for the entire civilized world outside of England, the
primary source of
law was legislation. Unwritten customs, they were taught by the civilian authors they read, could only be a secondary source of law. So what of
England,
in
laws? This
which
is
laws are unwritten?
all
Must
it
be said that
has no
it
the threshold question that Glanvill and Bracton set out to
on Roman
answer. Relying
legal sources,
they both conclude that the
law was not reduced to writing does not keep
fact that English
it
from
being law. It is far
from
clear that either Glanvill or Bracton conceive of
English laws as custom.
More
precisely,
it is
all
the
not clear that either con-
ceive of the general law of the whole realm as custom. If they do, their
conception of custom
of
all
different
common
civilians or all of the
One cannot say with
is
from that held by either the medieval
lawyers only
a half
century after Bracton.
certainty that Glanvill and Bracton do not conceive
written laws as custom; both wrote treatises on “the laws and cus-
toms of England.” The mere use of the expression “laws and customs” tells
us very
however, about whether they conceive of all unwritten
little,
laws as customs.
The
phrase by
itself is
ambiguous; while
it
does not sug-
gest that English laws are equivalent to customs, neither does sarily suggest that laws
it
neces-
and customs are to be distinguished. In the only
unambiguous use of the word “custom” only to local customs.
When
to the laws governing
all
in either
work, Bracton refers
Bracton and Glanvill unambiguously refer
of England, they use the word
leges.
This alone
does not suggest that they did not conceive of the general law of England as
custom;
lex ius ,
glish lawyers.
that law
,
and
cotisuetudo are
But both works’ discussions of the law of the realm make
seem much more
like legislation
the medieval civilians and later
When
used interchangeably by early En-
common
than
like
custom
(at least as
lawyers understood custom).
they write of the unwritten laws of England, the Glanville and
Bracton make
it
clear that they have in
sions of the king,
been recorded
made with
in writing.
mind
the enactments and deci-
the advice of the magnates, which have not
190
The Common Law Mind
§
Glanvill and Bracton say very
and what they say
from
is
little
about the nature of customary law,
borrowed either directly from the Corpus Juris or
medieval glossators. Glanvill speaks of “customs of the realm
its
which had
and have long prevailed.” Here, in very
their origin in reason
general terms, are the two basic medieval civilian criteria for valid cus-
tomary law — long usage and reasonableness. Bracton does not hold custom to the standard of reasonableness, but
usage has approved. clearly based
on two
The
does identify
it
passage in which
Digest texts
reasonableness a test of custom
(1.3.1
and
it
it
with what long
defines lex and consuetudo
and
1.3.32),
may perhaps be
its
is
omitting to make
explained by the fact that
the Digest itself does not require that customs be reasonable.
During the Year Book period (from the teenth century) the
common
late thirteenth to the six-
law conception of custom
tinguishable from the medieval civilian conception.
about custom by virtually differ
all
common lawyers and
almost indis-
The
discussions
judges reported in the Year Books
have to do with the validity of alleged local customs, which
from the
rules established
biguous identification of the
common
is
common
by the
common
law literature or case reports
law.
The
law as custom that is
the last half of the fifteenth century. All
made by
human
Sir
I
first
unam-
found in the
John Fortescue
laws, he says, “are either
laws of nature, customs, or statues.” 23 Given these possibilities, the
mon law can only be custom.
in
com-
Fortescue praises English customs for their
antiquity and their reason, but he does not present either as a test of the
common
law’s validity.
Fortescue’s three-part division of law did not take hold
common
lawyers.
By
the mid-sixteenth century
it
among
became the
the
universal
practice to distinguish three kinds of law in England: “the law general (that
is,
the
common
law),
customs, and statute law.” 24 This distinction
was retained for centuries. By “customs” the sixteenth-century
common
mean only local custom. For a local custom to be allowed, proof had to be made that it had existed “from time immemorial” and that it was in harmony with reason — the standard civilian and medieval common law tests for the validity of custom. The increased frequency and lawyers
sharpness of challenges to customs for failing to meet these
compared ing
to the Year
less tolerant
Book
period, suggest that the courts were
tests, as
becom-
of local deviations from the law of the whole realm. In
any event, the sixteenth- and seventeenth-century reports are examples of customs being held
strictly to the
filled
with
time-of-usage and reason-
Summary and Commentary ableness standards, with
more than
a
few failing the
tests.
The
191
sixteenth-
how one
century reports, however, provide no more information about
know when the tests had been met than do the Year Books. The hardest question to answer about the sixteenth-century common law approach to custom is whether, despite the fact that it was now the could
universal practice to distinguish the
common custom.
lawyers
The
common
law from “customs,” the
really follow Fortescue in conceptualizing
still
evidence
is
it
as
inconclusive.
*
On mon
the one hand, the medieval practice of never examining the
law to see
met
if it
com-
the time-out-of-mind requirement of cus-
tom was continued. Indeed,
just as
with the Year Books, the sixteenth-
century reports contain not even an abstract statement of any require-
ment
common law rule must have been practiced for a of time. If the common law was really conceptualized as
that to be valid a
certain length
why was
custom,
never held to the central'Test for the existence of
Furthermore,
valid customs?
common
it
law suggest that
it
many of the
was thought of more
ing of the professional elite than as the
On the other hand, common which
law
it is
is
Plowden records
is
common
at least
one instance
common law is
learn-
common
which the
in
another in
use,”
usage which proves what the law
is,”
and
a
described as “the custom in relation to
third in
which the
letters,
counts, pleas and judgments
common
as the
custom of the realm.
described as “nothing but
asserted that “it
suggest that the
reported discussions about the
All these statements appear to
law was conceptualized as custom, but there
are reasons to be cautious about reaching that conclusion. Sixteenth-
century
mon
common
lawyers were accustomed to using the phrase “com-
One
usage” in two quite different senses.
refers to the usage of
those learned in the law, the other to the usages of the people.
one instance
in
which the term “common usage” apparently
usages of the people (when the reference
is
td the
I
found
refers to the
common
law rather 1
than to local custom); in the other instances, the phrase can more naturally
be taken to refer to the usages of the
case in
which the
common
clear that the reference
is
law
is
to the
said to be
common
law courts. In the
custom, the context makes
custom of the
common
it
law bench and
bar and not of the people. I
read this inconclusive evidence as suggesting that the sixteenth-
century ing the
common lawyers had available to them several ways of describcommon law, one of which is in terms of custom and usage. But
The Common Law Mind
192
if
some of them
ception has
did conceive of the in
little
common
Most important, they do not of prescription. Second, professional
Such
elite.
law as custom, that con-
with their conception of local custom.
common
insist that a
law usage have
a
time
the usage not of the people but of a tiny
it is
a
common
conception of custom not only
is
incompatible
common law description of custom, it is also incomRoman law doctrine from which that traditional de-
with the traditional patible with the
scription
drawn.
is
The common
law conception of the nature of particular custom, and
the tests prescribed for validating custom’s existence, did not change in
Custom
the seventeenth century.
is still
defined as a reasonable usage of
the people, continued time out of mind. But
if
custom did
the tests for
not change, the rigor with which they were applied greatly increased to-
common law judges became common law and began to ex-
ward the end of the sixteenth century. The zealous in supporting the authority of the
amine
local
strictness
customs very
strictly
26
.
The
historian
is
not
left
from the increasing frequency with which the courts found
that customs violated the reasonableness test; the rule stated that
In the
portant
to infer this
“when
first
a
custom
is
pleaded
it
shall
be pleaded
part of the seventeenth century, for the
common
is
frequently
stricti juris .”
first
time, an im-
lawyer began unequivocally to describe the
law as the custom of the English people.
have discovered, describes
it
in
He
also, for the first
terms of all the
tests that
27
common
time that
I
had before been
applied only to local custom. In the law reports of the second half of the
common law is sometimes referred to as the “com-
sixteenth century, the
mon custom of the realm,”
but
we
find little evidence that sixteenth-cen-
tury lawyers understood that phrase as referring to anything other than the learning of the judges and lawyers
With
Sir
law, as tices
John Davies,
all
common custom
who work
in the king’s courts.
that changed. Davies teaches that the
of the realm,
of the English people and
memory. Furthermore, he
is
is
common
created by the usages and prac-
recorded nowhere but in the people’s
explicitly describes the
common
law in terms
of the standard tests for valid custom: a reasonable act continued time
out of mind. Davies’s views are not representative.
Only
lawyer in the early decades of the seventeenth century make defining the
common
common
rarely does a a
point of
law as custom and then proceed to draw important
Summary and Commentary from that
jurisprudential or political conclusions
definition.
193
This
is
from
ticularly true of the period’s purely legal literature, as distinguished political tracts,
who was
posed by someone
I
believe
it
very likely that
pressed to classify the
common
common
if
Having
common
the typical
would have done so not because he made
mon
law.
he would have called
law,
be com-
Even Coke does not consistently
a lawyer.
emphasize the customary nature of the however,
may
speeches in parliament, and so forth that
par-
a fetish
it
said this,
lawyer was
custom.
He
of thinking of the com-
law as custom, or because in some deep way he understood
it
to be
custom, but because he lacked the conceptual tools for thinking of
human
Many common
law in any way other than as custom or statute.
make
lawyers said things that
it
clear that they well
understood that
call-
common law custom was a fiction. Even the way Coke underthe common law required a new classification and terminology lo-
ing the
stood
cated conceptually between custom and judicial precedent.
:s
common lawyers used two common law — “common erudition” and “common
In the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries, expressions for the
reason”
— that
might have served
captured the essence of
stood the
purpose
this
well, for together they
how many seventeenth-century
common law. Having gone
lawyers under-
through the process of education
at
the Inns of Court, apprenticeship at the bar, and practice and intimate intellectual association with the tiny legal elite, they
that if the
common
law was custom at
sense that custom of a borough or a lar rule existed at
common
common
vill
in the
was custom. Whether
since time immemorial.
it
same
a particu-
When a
puta-
law rule was being discussed in court, no one ever asked
whether the English people had practiced tice
was not custom
law did not depend upon factual proof that
the English people had lived by tive
all, it
understood clearly
it
or, if so,
whether that prac-
had continued without interruption time out of mind. Such ques-
tions were not even asked regarding so-called “customs of the court” (that
is,
the rules established by a court for the conduct of court busi-
ness):
“For the customs and courses of every of the King’s Courts are
a law,
and the
of them, and
common it is
law, for the universality thereof,
as
doth take notice
not necessary to allege in pleading any usage or pre11
scription to warrant the same.”-
The
'
reason no lawyer discussed the
time of usage of a consuetudo curiae or of any alleged
common
that he understood that the existence of such a rule
would be
,
law rule, settled
is
by
J
The Common Law Mind
94
“common
the
erudition” of the profession (the accumulated lore passed
on from one generation of lawyers
to the next) and
by “common reason”
(the accepted, artificial, reasoning of the profession).
The language for use in a
mon
common
of
more
realistic
erudition and
common
reason
may be
com-
conceptualization of the nature of the
law, but for a variety of reasons
it
was not used for such
apt
a reinter-
may be found in the enormous inEdward Coke. Although Coke himself frequently talks
pretation. Part of the explanation
fluence of Sir
common law in ways more consistent with its conceptualizathe common erudition of the legal profession than as custom, he
about the tion as is
the ultimate traditionalist and so occasionally
more important, from the
it
was very hard for the
calls it
common
lawyers to break away
as
name
fication for
is
why
explaining
they called
it
its
their law
Had
law be-
no theory worthy of
was authoritatively binding. As long
custom they did not need
authority, because
over Europe.
all
common
traditional descriptive terminology for the
cause, unlike their civilian counterparts, they had
the
custom. Perhaps
to provide a theoretical justi-
custom was
a
recognized source of law
they taken the position that the
common law really
not custom but rather the accumulated learning and accepted reason
of the legal profession or even of the judges, they would have to build justification
from the ground up. And that would require more jurispru-
them
dential innovation than their practice-oriented training provided
the resources for, especially since they had
mon
law or in the
nally, part
civil law, for a
common
no models, either
common
law in terms of
common
We
com-
lawyers did not formally
common
the fact that the law was developing in a direction that
eventual conceptualization as the
in the
theory of judicially developed law. Fi-
of the reason that the
reconceptualize the
the
a
sum of
erudition
lies in
would lead to
its
the precedents established by
law courts.
must conclude that the
legal literature of the early decades of the
seventeenth century does not reveal an understanding of the nature of
common law which was so dominant that it can accurately be called the common law mind. But if it is not possible to find a single, dominant common law mind, it is possible to identify two broad orientations toward the common law. Coke, Davies, and Hedley are representative of the
the
more
traditional of the
two orientations:
in
important passages,
not consistently, they emphasize the antiquity of the identify
it
common
if
law and
with custom. Bacon, Dodderidge, Finch, and Selden are rep-
Summary and Commentary resentative of those lawyers
who brought
l
95
either their educations in phi-
losophy, logic, and other legal systems or their training in the
methods
of humanistic scholarship to bear on their consideration of the
common
law; hence, they are less
formulas. the
We
common
prone to limit their discussions to traditional
cannot describe the jurisprudence of the great majority of lawyers because they
left
no record of
we can say, on the evidence we have, mon law mind ip the period, it was divided.
most
that
is
their thoughts.
that
if
there was
a
The
com-
NOTES
Introduction See John William Salmond, Jurisprudence nth
1.
ed., edited
,
(London, 1966), 109-12; Carleton Allen, Law
in the
Making 7th ,
by
P. J.
FitzGerald
ed. (Oxford, 1964),
1-66.
Percy H. Winfield, Chief Sources of English
2. J
9 2 5), 4 2
Ijrgal History
(Cambridge, Mass.,
-
William Holdsworth, Sources and Literature of English Law (Oxford,
3.
1925), also
takes this approach. 4.
David M. Walker, The Oxford Companion
5.
Frederic William Maitland, The Letters of Frederic William Maitland edited by
to
Law
(Oxford, 1980), 1156. ,
Cecil H.
S.
The
Fifoot (London, 1965), 222.
1901) says of Maine that “his inability for
Dictionary of National Biography (London,
drudgery shows
itself
by one weakness of his
books, the almost complete absence of reference to authorities.”
John Chapman Gray, The Nature and Sources of the Law (New York, 1921 [1909]); Allen’s Law in the Making was first published in 1927; Allen revised his book seven 6.
,
times.
See
7.
G. A. Pocock, “The History of Political Thought:
J.
quiry,” in Philosophy Politics ,
man
,
and
Society edited ,
by Peter Laslett and Walter G. Runci-
(Oxford, 1962), 183-202; Pocock, Virtue
1985), 1-34;
History
ing of Texts,”
Commerce and History (Cambridge, ,
New
Dunn, “The
in the
(1969): 3-53; Skinner, “Motives, Intentions,
Literary History
3
(1972):
393-408; Skinner,
Thought and Action,”
Analysis of Political
Political
Theory
History of Ideas,”
and the Understand-
“Some Problems 2 (1974):
in the
277-303; John
Identity of the History of Ideas,” Philosophy 43 (1968): 85-116.
8.
Pocock, Virtue Commerce and History
9.
Ibid., 10.
,
,
Chapter in 1.
,
Quentin Skinner, “Meaning and Understanding
and Theory 8
A Methodological In-
Norman Doe
fifteenth century in
,
9.
Conceptions of English Law the Medieval Treatises
i:
has done solid work on
Fundamental Authority
common
in Late
law jurisprudence of the
Medieval English
Law (Cambridge,
1990).
l
97
Notes to Pages
198
Howard Mcllwain, The High
Charles
2.
(New Haven,
1910), vii,
Court of Parliament and
A
First
Book ofJurisprudence, 6th ed. (London, 1929), 254.
For example, early in the sixteenth century
4.
Supremacy
Its
44.
Frederick Pollock,
3.
1-6
German wrote
St.
that “the thyrde
grounde of the lawe of Englande standeth vpon dyuerse generall Customes of olde
tyme vsed through
all
called the
common
Theodore
F.
a
.
.
And
.
these be tho customes that proprely be
lawe.” Christopher St.
German, Doctor and Student
common
law was “nothing else but the
Common
practice,
it
always said to be lus
can be recorded and registered no where, but
John Davies, The Works
ple.”
is
scripts
in Verse
Henry
1972),
2.
I,
.
.
but in use and
memory
of the peo-
and Prose Including Hitherto Unpublished Manu-
Leges Henrici Primi, edited and translated by L.
Downer
J.
(Oxford,
Hereafter, Leges.
6.
Theodore
7.
“They”
F.
T. Plucknett, Early English Legal Literature (Cambridge, 1958), 29.
refers to those
by the bishops,
mentioned
in the text:
earls, sheriffs, deputies,
“The meetings
shall
be attended
hundredmen, aldermen, stewards,
barons, vavassors, villege reeves, and other lords of lands it
in the
.
no?i scriptum;
of Sir John Davies, edited by Alexander Grosart (Blackburn, 1869-76), 2:251-52.
5.
to
custom of the Realme; and
cannot be made or created, either by Charter or by Parliament
it
edited by
the strongest of such statments in the seventeenth century, asserting
custome which hath obtained the force of a lawe,
for
,
T. Plucknett and John L. Barton (London, 1974), 45, 47. Sir John Davies
made perhaps that the
the realme.
who
shall
reeves,
with diligence see
that failure to punish evildoers or the viciousness of officials or the corruption of
judges shall not destroy those suffering under their accustomed afflictions.” Leges, 8.
If,
as
Liebermann
teenth century,
it is still
suggests, this passage difficult to
is
7,2.
an interpolation from the early thir-
conclude that
all
English law was understood in
the twelfth and thirteenth centuries to be customary in nature. See F. Liebermann,
Die Gesetze der Angelsachen (Halle, 1903),
The
9.
3:316; Leges 317.
identity of the author of Glanvill
is
the subject of considerable scholarly
may have been Rannulf de Glanvill or another royal judge, or it may have clerk who was familiar with the royal court. See Rannulf de Glanvill, The Trea-
dispute. It
been tise
a
on the Laws and Customs of the Real?n of England
Commonly
Called Glanvill, edited
G. D. G. Hall (Oxford, 1965), xxx-xxxiii. Hereafter, Glanvill. 10. Justinian, Institutes, translated by J. A. C. Thomas (Capetown, Institutes.
“The
imperial majesty should not only be
strengthened by laws, that the people
may
made
Krueger; translated by Alan Watson (Philadelphia,
P.
is
1975). Hereafter,
glorious by arms, but also
be properly governed in time of peace as
well as war”; Justinian, The Digest ofJustinian, edited by
hereafter as Code
by
Theodor Mommsen and Paul
1985). Hereafter, Digest.
Also cited
Justinian, Code, in The Civil Law, edited and translated
by Samuel
Scott (Cincinnati, 1932). 11.
Institutes 1.3.9:
“The unwritten law
[ras] is
that
which usage has established;
for
long- established customs [diutumi mores], being sanctioned by the consent of those
who adopt them,
are like
leges"-,
Digest
1.3. 32.1:
“Long-established custom
is,
not unde-
servingly, held pro lege." 12.
Irnerius, nearly a century before,
wrote that
ius is established
and by the necessity of nature. (“Quod constituitur turn
by
lege, turn
lex,
by custom,
moribus, turn et
Notes to Pages A
naturae necessitas induxerit, triplex jus esse constat”)
gloss
6-7
199
on Digest
1.3.40
is
quoted in Friedrich Karl von Savigny, Geschichte des Romischen Rechts im Mittelalter (Darmstadt, 1956),
vol. 4, chap. 27, n. 49.
Not
all
medieval civilians admit that custom
any longer had the force of law. See also Robert Warrand Carlyle and Alexander James
A
Carlyle,
History of Medieval Political Theory in the West (Edinburgh, 1903-36), 2:52.
Roman
Although the canonists accept from ciple that
jurists
and the church fathers the prin-
custom can be law (indeed, Gratian teaches that
in nature), they
do not believe that
custom
all
is
human
law
law and generally prefer
Common Law
C. Van Caenegem, The Birth of the English
all
,
is
customary
2d ed. (Cambridge, 1988),
Pope Gregory VII captures the tone of canonist skepticism about custom: suetudinem tas.’
Non
fortassis
dixit:
opponas, advertendum est quod Dominus
ego sum consuetudo, sed
Canonici (Leipzig, 1879, 1881), dist. classificatory
chap.
8,
scheme of the Roman
purposes. Gratian, in the
first
5.
3.
“Si con-
‘Ego sum veri-
dicit:
Emil Friedberg,
veritas.”
See R.
leges.
ed.,
Corpus Juris
Canonists borrowed from the Digest the
jurists and,
over time, adapted
part of his Decretum
(ca.
it
for their
own
1140; hereafter, Decretum) (see
Gratian, Concordance of Discordant Cations, in Friedberg, Corpus Juris Canonici), distinguishes various kinds of law and states the relationships
which
(dist. post.,
tiones
will, is
chap, n;
dist. 9,
of secular princes
law,
superior to both ecclesiastical law and the laws of princes
God’s
reflects
among them. Natural
chap.
1).
Church law
chap.
(dist. 10,
1).
is
Custom
superior to the is
at
the
leges
and
constitu-
bottom of the heirarchy,
subordinate not only to divine and natural law but also to the enacted law of the
church and of princes
(dist. 11,
para.
See
1).
J.
Gaudemet, “La doctrine des sources du
droit dans le Decret de Gratien,” Revue de droit canonique dieval
Canon Law (London,
A passage is
1995), 158-59.
in the Digest (1.3.32) suggests that the place
limited to situations in which there 13.
nizational ,
is
of unwritten custom in the law
no written law on
a subject.
made clear not only in the prologue but also in the basic orgascheme and method of the treatise and in some of its terminology. See
This exposure
Glanvill
Brundage, Me-
(1951); J.
1
xi, xv-xviii,
is
xxv-xxix, xli-xlii;
John L. Barton, “Roman Law
in
England,” in i
Romanum Medii Aevi (Varese, 1971), pt. 5, 13a, 8-13; Charles Donahue, Tus Commune, Canon Law, and Common law in England,” Tulane Law Review 66 (1992): 1751-52. R. C. Van Caenegem describes the substantive influence of Roman law on the Ius
treatise in Royal Writs in
dist.
15.
tis et,
silio,
the Conquest to Glanvill
Gratian, for example, asserts that ius
14.
tum,
England from
1,
chap.
quos
the genus and lex a species of
et
laudibilius est, talium
morum
16.
licet
ius.
Decre-
consuetudinibus de ratione introductis et diu obten-
uirorum
licet
subditorum non dedignatur regi con-
grauitate in perita luris et regni consuetudinibus peritissimos sue
sapientie et eloquencie prerogatiua alios nouit precellere”
Anglicanas
1959), 360-90.
2.
“Legibus namque regni
quod
is
(London,
non
scriptas leges appellari
(
Glanvill
non uideatur absurdum”
1);
(
“Leges autem
Glanvill
2).
Frederick Pollock and Frederic William Maitland, The History of English
Law
Time of Edward I, 2d. ed. (Cambridge, 1898), 1:175-76. Although the author of the Leges uses both lex and consuetudo in referring to English law, one can get no sure
before the
how he understands these terms. “The unwritten law is that which
sense of 17.
usage has established; for ancient customs,
Notes to Pages 7-10
200
who
being sanctioned by the consent of those
adopt them, are
Jolowicz asserts that for Justinian custom
1.2.9.
like leges." Institutes
essentially unwritten law, but
is
that view minimizes several passages emphasizing the length of usage (for example,
Digest 1.2.9,
1.3.33,
Digest
Digest 1. 3.
32.1).
ims,” in L'europa :
1.3.35,
Code 8.52.2) and the consent of those
romano: studi
in
them
use
“Roman Regulae and
See Herbert Felix Jolowicz,
e il diritto
who
memoria
{Institutes
English
di Paolo Koschaker, vol.
Max-
(Milan,
1
954 )18.
Bracton,
On
the
Laws and Customs of England edited by G. E. Woodbine and ,
E. Thorne, 4 vols. (Cambridge, 1968-77), 3:xiii-lii. Hereafter, Bracton. For a dense, learned, recent argument that Bracton is indeed the author of De Legihus see J. L. S.
,
Barton, 19.
“The Mystery of Bracton,” Journal of Legal History
“Cum autem
fere in
14 (1993):
omnibus regionibus utatur legibus
1.
et iure scripto, sola
Anglia usa est in suis finibus iure non scripto et consuetudine. In ea quidem ex non scripto ius venit
quod usus comprobavit. Sed non
erit
absurdum
leges Anglicanas
licit
cum leges cum legis vigorem habeat quidquid de consilio et consensu magnatum et rei publicae communi sponsione, auctoritate regis sive prinnon
scriptas leges, appellare,
cipis praecedente, iuste fuetit definitum et
approbatum. Sunt etiam
in Anglia
con-
secundum diversitatem locorum. Habent enim Anglici ex consuetudine quae non habent ex lege, sicut in diversis comitatibus, civitati-
suetudines plures et diversae plura
bus, burgis et
villis,
ubi semper inquirendum erit quae
sit lllius loci
consuetudo
et
qualiter utantur consuetudine qui consuetudines allegant.” 20.
A
See, for example, Carlyle and Carlyle,
History of Medieval Political Theory
,
H. Mcllwain, The Growth of Political Thought in the West (New York, 1932), Mcllwain, Constitutionalism: Ancient and Modern (Ithaca, 1940), 69-89; George L.
3:41-42; C. 192;
Haskins, “Executive Justice and the Rule of Law,” Speculum 30
(1955): 532.
Walter Ullmann, The Medieval Idea of Law as Represented by Lucas de Penna (London, 1946), 63. 21.
22.
Cicero,
De
Inventioine (Cambridge, 1949): 2:xxii, 67.
The
Brachylogus
two outstanding works of the early French offshoots of the school enly attributed by Savigny to Irnerius. See
Hermann Kantorowicz,
Roman Law (Cambridge, 1938), 43, 12-13. Francisco Suarez, De Legibus, Ac Deo Legislatore,
sators of the 23.
25.
1927).
Bologna, mistak-
Studies in the Glos-
Walter Ullmann, Law and
7,
chap.
in Selections from Three
Works of
9.
Middle Ages (London, 1975), 62. Vacarius, The Liber Pauperum of Vacarius, edited by F. de Zulueta (London,
To
this
may be added
Politics in the
his gloss
on the words
consensus fecit in Digest 1.3.40, in
which he interprets the agreement there spoken of as being that 26.
one of
1
Francisco Suarez (Oxford, 1944), bk.
24.
at
is
Petrus de Bellapertica, Lectura super primus
et
secunda parte
“in populo. codicis
"
(on Code 8.52.1)
(Prostat Parrhisijs, 1519). 27.
Irnerius, Placentinus,
centinus,
Summa
and Rogerius
Institutionum
Two Bodies (Princeton, 1966),
1:2.
all
took
this position.
For example, Pla-
For discussion, see Ernst Kantorowicz, The King's
103.
28. Justinian, Digest 1.4.1; Institutes 1.2.6;
Code
1.17.7.
29.
See Ernst Kantorowicz, The King's Two Bodies (Princeton, 1966),
30.
Irnerius, Placentinus,
and Rogerius
all
103.
take this position. For example, Pla-
Notes to Pages Summa
centinus,
Institutionum
tem
“Nam
(Augustae Taurinorum, 1973):
1:2
communem
principem transferendo
10-13
potestatem, nulla
sibi reservavit,
201
populos in
ergo potesta-
leges scriptas contendi, interpretandi, et abrogandi.”
31.
See, for example, Irnerius, gloss
on
Digest
“Loquitur haec
1.3.32:
lex
secundum
sua tempora quibus populus habebat potestatem contendi leges, ideo tacito consensu
omnium
per consuetudinem abrogabantur. Sed quia hodie potestas translata est in
imperatorem, 32.
The
desuetudo populi.”
nihil faceret
implication
strong in
is
Azo
sense, the source of legislative authority 3.53.6 33.
law,
and
Summa Azon is (Lyon,
1.14.8 in
T'he
word
placere
and
political
or proclaimed in an edict,
itself,
Novel
different twist in
is
without doubt
which added,
in the Institutes version,
letter or
decreed in
est.”
in
that
God made the laws themselves subject to men as a lex animata with the effect that he is
him
to
,
two inconsistent theories of government and law operated in the
Walter Ullmann,
power
descending conception, governmental authority and
law-creating power was thought to descend earth.
Civilis.
the same time. In the ascending conception, lawmaking
was ascribed to the people;
on
hearing
Justinian gives this idea a slightly
not subject to legal rules. Justinian, Novellae Constitutions, in Corpus luris
Ullmann shows medieval Europe at
a
105, asserting that
the emperor’s control by giving
35.
Codicis
a law.” Institutes 1.2.6.
“Princeps legibus solutus
1. 3.31:
Summa
1533).
“Consequently, whatever the emperor has ordained by
Digest
power. Azo,
was commonly understood to mean only the power to make
an inference drawn from the text
34.
some
that the people continued to be, in
downward from God
Principles of Government
and Politics
to his vice-regents
in the
Middle Ages (Lon-
don, 1961), 19-26.
and Theologian on Kingship,” Proceedings of Third International Congress of Medieval Canon Lave (1968).
36.
the
See Gaines Post, “Bracton
as Jurist
Law
Courts of Medieval England (London, 1973), 77.
37.
See Alan Harding, The
38.
See Plucknett, Early English Legal Literature 80. ,
It is a
mistake to think that for
English lawyers of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries legal authority was conceived as substantive rules
rules of pleading
of property or contract that were to be contrasted with ancillary
and procedure; the principles of the
the writs.
“What caused
common
law was the early tendency for the
had been issued
it
became
change the formula
known formula
to
the original writs to
if it
fit
a
39.
become fundamentally important formulae to become fixed. Once
was found serviceable.
his case, or apply for a ,
in large
measure to be found
in
A
plaintiff
new one
.
.
.
65.
a writ
reluctance to
had either to find
to be invented.”
(London, 1990),
a
to the
J.
H. Baker,
a
An
Legal authority, then,
recognized writs.
Brian Tierney, “Bracton on Government,” Speculum 38 (1963): 295-309. Phis
argument
is
seconded
in
Donald Hanson, From Kingdom
opment of Civic Consciousness
in English Political
Tierney’s interpretation has this in
reference
is
made
to
Commonwealth: The Devel-
Thought (Cambridge, Mass., 1970), 107-8.
40. Mcllwain, Constitutionalism: Ancient and 41.
law grew up around
precedent for the future, and there was
Introduction to English Legal History 3d ed.
was
common
its
Modem,
78.
favor: in almost
to “custom” in the medieval Year
all
Books and
the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, that reference
is
instances in which
in the law reports
of
to local, particular customs.
202
Notes to Pages
\
14-16 Law
42. See Pollock and Maitland, The History of English
“Quid
43.
quod
lex est
Videndum
quid consuetudo.
sit lex et
secundum quod
tor iustitiae est deus, lex
idem
etiam quid
est
commune praeceptum virorum consultum
sponte vel ignorantia contrahuntur coertio,
Et
significant.
1:175.
,
prudentium, delictorum quae
publicae sponsio communis. Item auc-
rei
iustitia est in creatore.
dicatur lex
licet largissime
Et sciendum
sit lex.
Et secundum hoc
omne quod
ius et
tamen spe-
legitur,
sanctionem iustam, iubentem honesta, prohibentem contraria. Con-
cialiter significat
suetudo vero quandoque pro lege observatur in partibus ubi fuerit more utentium approbata, et vicem legis obtinet. Longaevi enim usus et consuetudinis non est
vilis
auctoritas.”
Summa super Institutis
44. Azo,
“De quibus
45.
moribus
et
1.1,
non utimur,
causis scriptis legibus
consuetudine inductum
merito custoditur
Summa Azonis.
in
hoc
et
est
.
quod
est ius,
.
.
1.
custodiri opertet,
id
Inveterata consuetudo pro lege
dicitur
quod
non im-
moribus constitutum.” Also see Code
8.53; Institutes 1.2.9.
46.
now
It is
generally accepted that Maitland greatly underestimates Bracton’s
learning in and reliance
The
47.
not Mcllwain’s method. Instead, he largely
is
ping argument. that of an
He
immemorial custom, which can be found but not made. His proof is
found
proof texts mean what he
manner
as the relation
view of
in
interpretation
says,
in the
this point.
is
for this
very texts we consider here. His knows that his
because that
is
how medieval
established his fundamental point, he
on such matters
meant
on the bootstrap-
relies
begins with the proposition that the medieval conception of law
sweeping proposition
in this
law.
use of extrinsic materials can certainly be helpful in the interpretation of
but that
texts,
upon Roman
moves
lawyers thought. Having
to other Bractonian texts,
of the king to the law, and shows what they must have
Then
he
in a position to
is
on the question of custom
is,
because he
show how correct
now
has
his original
many other
texts
con-
sistent with his original interpretation.
Edward
48. See, for example, Yearbooks of the Reign of King
(London,
Edw.
1883); hereafter,
Ill 506; St.
Year Books are referred to
German, Doctor and
as
YB:
the Third
YBB
Student, 45-47; Reniger
v.
18
Edw.
Ill 326, 19
Fogossa in
Plowden, The Commentaries or Reports of Edmund Plowden (London, The Works in Verse, 2:251. ,
Rolls Series
,
,
Edmund
1816), 1:9; Davies,
49. Plucknett, Early English Legal Literature, 94. 50. 1970), glie, is
Elsa de 1,
12.
Haas and George D. G.
Hereafter, Early Registers.
shorter version, Secundum consuetudinem
Registers, 21, 24, 25, 27, 55, 57, 38, 65, 67,
An-
143-46, 148, 170.
“Since whatever has been rightly decided and approved with the counsel and
consent of the magnates and the general agreement of the
res publica, the
the prince having been added thereto, has the force of law”
sage was heavily influenced by Digest
time read 52.
(London,
even more frequently used in writs roughly contemporaneous with the writing
of Bracton. See Early 51.
A
Hall, eds., Early Registers of Writs
this Digest text as
For example,
have turned
“I,
my mind
1.3.1,
which defines
Bracton 2:19). This pas-
a lex. Civilians
of Bracton’s
having to do with the prince’s legislative function.
Henry de
Bracton, to instruct the lesser judges,
to the ancient judgements of just
their decisions, consilia
(
authority of
and responsa ” ( Bracton
2:19).
men, examining
if
no one
else,
diligently
.
.
.
Notes to Pages Law
Pollock and Maitland, The History of English
53.
Bracton does not, in
54.
He
various forms of law.
,
203
1:176.
straightforward way, provide a hierarchical analysis of
a
does state that “justice proceeds from
justice “all rights \iura] arise”
17-22
(
God” and
that
from
Bracton 1:22-23). Thus, by implication at least, he takes
the standard contemporary view that a
human
law
subordinate to divine and natural
is
law.
See Peter Stein, “Logic and Experience in
55.
Roman and Common
Law,” Boston
Law Review 59 (1979): 433-35; Arthur L. Goodhart, “Precedent in English and Continental Law,” Law Quarterly Review 197 (1934): 40-42; Carleton Allen, Law University
in the
Making 7th ,
ed. (Oxford, 1964), 162.
56.
Goodhart, “Precedent
57.
Clark and Finnelly's Reports (London, 1847), 527, 546.
58.
Goodhart, “Precedent
59.
Allen,
Law
in the
in English
and Continental Law,”
41.
English and Continental Law,” 41.
in
Making
219;
Wiliam Holdsworth, “Case Law,” Law Quarterly
Review 50 (1934): 180. 60.
John Chipman Gray, The Nature and
the Sources of the
Law (New
York, 1921),
212, 213. 61.
See Allen,
62.
T.
343
F.
Law
in the
,
188, 189.
Concise History of the
Common Law
,
52d ed. (London, 1956),
-
63.
Pollock and Maitland, The History of English
64. Allen,
Law
in the
Summa
Making
Azo,
66.
Goodhart, “Precedent
67.
Holdsworth, “Case Law,”
69.
Britton
A
70.
non
habet vigorem,’ eas
and Continental Law,” 42.
181.
in
M. Nichols (Washington,
French it
in the
form of
a
1901),
1.
Hereafter, Britton.
code issued by royal authority.
was widely used for several centuries.
and translated by Henry G. Richardson and George O. Sayles
1955), 2:2-3. Hereafter, Fleta.
leges appellari
1:183, 184.
Concise History, 343, 344.
translated by F.
Fleta, edited
(London,
dem
in English
approximately 1290-92,
at
,
Codicis 1.12.
This book was written
Dated
Law
188.
65.
68. See Plucknett,
absurdum,
est
scilicet
“Leges autem Anglicanas,
cum hoc ipsum
lex sit
licit
non
scriptas,
‘quod principi placet legis
quas super dubiis in consilio deffiniendis, procerum qui-
consilio et principis auctoritate accordante vel antecedente, constat esse promul-
gatas. Si
minime censerentur maioris procul videretur accomodare scriptura quam decernen-
enim ob solum scripture defectum
dubio auctoritatis robur tis
A
T. Plucknett,
Making
ipsis legibus
legis
equitas aut ratio statuentis.” 71.
The
claim was not that
leges
could be altered or abolished only in
Chapter 1.
John
P.
Thomas
a
certain manner,
upon
certain conditions.
The Jurisprudence of the Year Books
Dawson, The
ceptions are Sir ton, 1903); Sir
2:
could not be altered or abolished but that they
Oracles of the
Law (Ann Arbor,
Littleton’s Tenures, edited
The principal exby Eugene Wambaugh (Washing1968), 47.
John Fortescue’s De Laudibus Legum Anglia e, edited and translated by
Stanley B. Chrimes (Cambridge, 1942); Christopher
St.
German’s Doctor and
Student,
Notes to Pages
204
edited by T.
F.
T. Plucknett and
22-25 (London, 1974); Henry Finch’s Law and John Dodderidge’s The English Lawyer (Lon-
John
or a Discourse thereof { London, 1627);
don,
L. Barton
,
1631).
T. Plucknett, Early English Legal Literature (Cambridge, 1958),
2.
T.
3.
See Ralph V. Turner, The English Judiciary
F.
(Cambridge,
Oxford
1
13—14.
Age of Glanvill and Bracton 235-36. Civil and canon law were taught at
1985), 36-38, 97, 150, 231-32,
in the
until 1234.
4.
See William Holdsworth, Sources and Literature of English
5.
T. F. T. Plucknett, Legislation of Edward 1 (Oxford, 1970),
6.
YBB
7.
I
Law
(Oxford, 1925),
30.
18-19 Edw. Ill 326; 19 Edw. Ill 506.
found only one other fourteenth- century case and in
clearly described as custom,
YB
the law and custom.”
Year Books are “
166) or to
a half
is
8.
12-13
The
it
Edw.
dozen references to usage du pays ”
(YB
1-2
Edw.
Ashton
is
YB
example,
30-31 Edw.
it
clear,
as
I
“custom
however, that the refer-
he
cieved.”
And
in
YB
as well
2-3
Edw.
YBB
Also see
who is under
1990),
age as he
who
Edw.
YB
statutory rule. For example, in aid yourself?
is
of
is
given to the heir
.
Wherefore by the
full
age ought to be re-
.
.
Herle complains, “Under the old law [aunciene
II 87,
33-35
“This action
says,
I
should have had
I
Edw.
554; 1-2
II 58, 77.
quently required counsel to choose between the former
YBB
Law (Cambridge,
he had no remedy.
before the writ ‘occasione cuuis vendicionis’ lessor.”
sans autre reason,” quoted in
fait ley
Medieval English
quoted in Doe, 25 1-2 Edw. II 80, Malberthorpe
the
is
YB
In
in Late
words of the statute
see
(for
some region of the country, not to the customs of the-whole realm. Fortescue, De Laudihus Legum Angliae, 37. In his capacity as chief justice of
[aunciene laye
you
law
to
where by the ancient law
any
common
which are usually translated
II 66),
context of most of these makes
Norman Doe, Fundamental Authority 9.
which the
through the fourteenth-century
Ill 304. Scattered
King’s Bench, Fortescue also states, “l’usage
23. J.
in
the reporter directly quotes the writ: “according to “
custom du pays ”
of the country.”
ence
6, 8.
32-33
Edw.
common
my
recovery against
Medieval judges
fre-
law rule and the
new
“How
will
ley]}"
Also
258, Bereford, C.J., asks:
I
by the old law or the new law [par novel ley or par aunciene
21-22 Edw.
I
326, 476. In
YB
32-33
Edw.
I
lei],
288, Scoter, in response to Herle’s
attempt to apply the statute to the case, says “You shall not get to that; for we are pleading on the old law [auncyen
our old law by the new law 10.
For example, in
YB
ley],
and you have pleaded and tried to drive us from
[novele ley]!'
12-13
Edw.
Ill 292, Shareshulle,
J.,
states that “the course of
course of law has always been that the plaintiff should have a writ to the Bishop with-
out affirming any other disturbance in him”; in “It has always
been held for law that no one
demesne”;
YB
in
12
Rich. II 72, Thirning,
shall J.
YB
17
Edw. 586, Shardelowe,
J.,
says,
have Warrantia Chartae but tenant in
asserts,
“and (the law) was never other-
wise.” 11.
YB
10
Edw. IV
38.
Catesby does not claim that the
alteration since the creation 12.
The
that the
Year Books are
common
common
law existed without
of the world.
filled
with evidence that medieval lawyers fully recognized
law had undergone great change.
T he Year Books
report several
Notes to Pages 26-28
no memory,” the most common ny ad memorie” (YBB 33-34 Edw. I 12-13; 33~35 Edw. I
variations of the phrase “from time of
of which
is
“du temps dount
204-5; 1-2 Edw. reporters 1
6 Edw.
of Gavelkind temps}."
32-33 1
81;
.
.
Also see
Edw.
I
The
is
phrase was so
common
(YB
to merely “du temps etc.”
it
Edw.
1-2
II 180,
which customs they have enjoyed from time immemorial
YBB
Book
that the Year
(Eyre of Kent), Passeley alleges that “they have divers customs
II 18
262-63,
Edw.
2-3
.
which there
2-3 Edw. II 62).
abbreviating
felt safe in
YB
In
81).
II 105;
il
205
12-13
Edw.
2 7 ° -7 b
430— Edw. Ill
II 62; 12-13
Edw.
Ill 216-17; 1 ;
Edw.
33-35
226, 227; 16
I
Ill 162-63;
I
7~ 1 ^ Edw. Ill 216-17;
204-5; 1-2 Edw. II 39, 82,
Edw.
[de tut
Edw.
Ill 552-52; 17-18
83, 180,
130, 131;
18-19 Edw. Ill 538, 539.
and Law
Fritz Kern, Kingship
13.
in the
Middle Ages, translated by
S. B.
Chrimes
(Oxford, 1948). Bracton (2:28) for example, states that “long
14.
custom
be ex-
[longa consuetude] will
plained below,” but the explanation never comes.
For an example of
15.
a
thirteenth-century work
Dominorum
several others, see Dissensiones 16.
YBB
17.
If
Edw.
33-35
I
Edw.
96, 554; 3-4
and
sejtting forth these positions
(Leipzig, 1834), 15 1. II
1
12-13,
I
3
-I 4
Edw.
Ill 24.
“long” means ten years with regard to prescription, they argue,
it
means
also
ten years regarding custom. Justinian, Novellae Constitutiones
18.
Azo
1973).
(d.
131,
chap.
6.,
in Corpus
Inns
1220) says that earlier civilians asserted times ranging
years; he asserts that
it
was an
obscure quaestionem
what was
Civilis
(Dublin,
from ten to
a longa consuetudo.
fifty
Summa
Codicis 8.53.2. “Ilia
19.
consuetudo praeiudicat
iuri
quae excedit
berg, ed, Corpus Juris Canonici (Leipzig, 1879
common
Although medieval
20.
x
hominum memorium .” A.
Fried-
88i), Deartals, I.4.11, gloss.
lawyers frequently identify the the
common
law
with reason, in doing so they never suggest that they are attempting to establish one of the required elements of valid custom.
“Du temps dount
21.
Edw.
Edw.
Ill 206-7;
il
ny ad memorie.”
Ill 162-63;
j
7 -i 8
YBB
Edw.
6 Edw.
tain
necessary,
if
you wish
to prove
is
against
common
J.,
says:
right
.
.
.
your estate by that custom, that you should main-
by long continuance of time [par long continuance de
it
(Eyre of Kent); 12-13
Ill 216-17. In 1304, Bereford,
“Since you affirm your estate by a custom which custom it is
II 18
tens ].”
YB
32-33
Edw.
I
264-65. 22.
Littleton, Tenures, sect. 170.
23.
Ibid.
24. Ibid. 25.
YB
2
Hen. IV
18.
The Corpus Juris ofJustinian does not provide a coherent theory about the relationship between customary law and legislation. Digest 1.3.32 and Institutes 1.2.11 pro26.
vide that statutes can be abrogated by falling out of use by
common
consent, but these
texts are not easy to reconcile with the imperial theory that the prince alone can law, or
with Code
8.52.2,
which, while admitting that the authority of custom
small, nevertheless holds that
Faced with the tension
custom cannot overcome either reason or
among
make is
not
statute.
these texts, medieval civilians give several different
Notes to Pages 29-30
2o6
answers to the question of whether custom can overcome or abrogate statutory law.
The answer perium
a
Do
resides:
given them
all
Roman
the
up by means of
people
a lex regia?
any lawmaking powers, or have they
retain
still
The more
imperialist of the civilians insist
no custom could abrogate statutory law or derogate from
that
peror could make or interpret law. Others teach that
can abrogate written law but that
tom
on where im-
particular jurist gives correlates highly with his position
bad
prevails over a
since only the
make
statute. Still others if
the
em-
general custom observed by
custom cannot. Others teach that
a local
the people intend to abrogate a statute:
a
it
a
all
good cus-
outcome depend upon whether
they follow a custom with knowledge that
not abrogated
is
contrary to the statute, then the statute
if
the people practice a contrary custom and are ignorant of the statute. See
abrogated, but a statute
is
it
is
Dawson,
The Oracles of the Law 129-30. Among the civilians, one of the strongest supporters of custom’s power to abrogate ,
statutes
He
Vacarius,
is
who was
instrumental in introducing civilian learning in England.
power
teaches that custom’s
to
overcome
statute
comes from the
consensu populi.
Vacarius, The Liber Pauperum of Vacarius, edited by Francis de Zulueta (London, 1927), gloss
Legem non ignorancium and
ently had
influence
little
gloss Generale et nature congruum.
His views appar-
on the common lawyers, who never accepted the view
that
general custom could abrogate statute law.
YB YB
27.
28.
20-21 Edw.
Edw.
33-35
alters the
common
86-87;
Edw.
96.
I
For additional examples of clear recognitions that
YBB
law, see
33-35
Edw.
400, 554; 1-2 Edw.
I.
YB
Edw.
30.
Examples of recognition of alterations
II 80; 2-3
320; 18-19 31.
32.
YB YB
terms of 33.
12-13
48, 152; 21-22 Edw.
Edw.
Edw.
Edw.
a
Edw.
saying that the shortly. In a
320, 322; 32-33
v.
Edw.
II 87; 12-13
Edw.
II
YB 17 Edw. Ill 586. common law include YBB
Edw.
in the
Edw.
I
288, 378; 33-35
Ill 266; 17
Ill
Edw.
Rich. II 127;
2; 7
Edw.
Ill 122, 12
I
20-21
96, 400, 554;
404; 17-18 Edw. Ill
Rich. II 48, 195.
322.
I
II 31.
remedy
Sampson
I
Ill 128, 202; 20
20-21 Edw. 1
II 58, 80; 2-3
Ill 292; Shardelow,
Shareshulle,
I
a statute
Ill 146.
29.
Edw. 2
354-56.
I
For an explanation of a statutory change
for a “mischief,” see
Grene
,
common
YB
3-4 Edw.
II
YB 1
in the
common
17-18 Edw. Ill 178.
12-13.
What Chief Justice
Bereford means by
we consider have said, “The cause
law does not ordain a remedy consistent with
second version of the
law in
case, Bereford
is
reported to
ley
of the statute was that this writ was not founded on any reason [sur nul resoun]” 34.
C. H. Mcllwain contends that the
and fourteenth-century
common
English statutes, in the
late
common F.
lawyers as having “supreme binding force” and that
Middle Ages, were made either to affirm the established
in Constitutionalism
and
the
“Magna Carta and
Changing World (New York,
1939), 132, 143.
T. Plucknett long ago pointed out that the Year Books do not support Mcllwain’s
position and that even The Mirror of Justices ally
law was regarded by thirteenth-
law or to remove abuses of the existing law. Mcllwain,
Common Law,” T.
common
,
on which Mcllwain
largely relies, actu-
proves the opposite of what he claims. Statutes and Their Interpretation in the First
Half of the Fourteenth Century (Cambridge, 35.
YB
32-33
Edw.
I
378.
1922), 28. Hereafter, Statutes.
Notes to Pages 36.
YB
37.
Venour
YB YB
38.
39.
i
7
16
Edw. v.
207
31-35
Ill 98.
YB
Blund,
Edw.
3-4 Edw.
II 161.
Ill 90.
17-18 Edw. Ill
12.
40. Justice Hillary’s hard line
on such questions
a little puzzling considering the
is
position he takes in a later discussion about the proper basis of judicial decision.
Thorp,
a pleader, says, “I
we do not know what of the
justices.”
YB
Edw.
YBB
Citation by
43.
20-21 Edw.
44. 1-2
Justice Hillary’s response
I
I
Edw.
22
I
528;
Edw.
was
fairly
Magna
354;
20-21 Edw.
II 71;
45. Mutford:
4 Edw.
Carta
YB
,
I
3-4 Edw.
454; 21-22 Edw.
“The
8; 13
Rich. II
49.
Edw.
law or
Statute of Merton
and
West.
II,
398 fStatute of Carlisle, 20 Edw. Ill 98.
Edw.
I
78, 230; 33-35
Edw.
80;
I
9.
him such
you
a writ.”
are out of the
YB
30-31 Edw.
words of the
I
412.
statute.”
YB
Ill 346.
Edw.
Ill 320.
32-33
Edw.
I
30-31 Edw. I
414;
400.
12-13
30-31 Edw.
I
common
I
232; Statute of Gloucester, 32-33
I
528; 32-33
statute does not give
I
48.
30-31 Edw.
105-6; 12-13 Edw. Ill 296; 16 Edw. Ill 516; 17 Edw. Ill 76;
II
Rich. II
2
I
30-31 Edw.
47.
YBB
law.)
30-31 Edw.
to be aided by the statute, but
16
Also see
II 85.
common. For example,
“You think
YB YB YB YB
the will [volunte]
is
xiii.
,
were sometimes called special
title
17-18 Edw. Ill 202;
46.
Statutes
284; Statute of Marlborough, 32-33 Edw.
YBB
“It
is,
they would have help of the law they must rely on
II 58: “if
special law.” (Statutes
Edw.
is.”
18-19 Edw. Ill 378.
42. Quotations in
YB
the law
Harold Dexter Hazeltine, preface to
41.
1-2
think you will do as others have done in the same case or else
290.
I
For other examples of the inspection of statutes see
226.
496; 33-35 Edw.
Edw
430, 532; 2-3
I
II 33; 16
Edw.
Ill 18; 17-18
YBB
Edw.
Ill
542, 550. 50.
See, for example, Statute of Westminster
II,
and
c.2
c.9; for discussion, see Stat-
utes, 134.
51.
Chief Justice Bereford explained the court’s abatement of
“If the statute ordains another writ then
was that of
it.”
Grene
v.
YB
3-4 Edw.
the court’s understanding that the
about
its
Staunton,
cial process.”
52.
II
1
12-13.
common
6-7 Edw.
II
(Eyre of Kent),
common 3,
Edward Coke, The Repons of Sir Edward
7 vols. (Dublin, 1792, 1793),
1
18.
53.
YB
Pasch. 8 Edw. Ill 26.
54.
On
this issue
55.
“E
401; 32—33
This statement suggests more about
law has to conform to reason than
“A statute does not change
said:
YB
il
est hors
Edw.
I
law writ:
abolished this one; the cause of the statute
understanding of the relationship between the J.,
common
was not founded upon reason, so that another was ordained instead
this writ
Sampson
it
a
Plucknett
Edw.
I
99.
law and statutes.
law process unless
See
does
it
gives spe-
Statutes, 131-34.
Coke, Knt. In English, in Thirteen Parts,
Hereafter, Reports.
entirely sound. Statutes, 68-71.
de cas de statut,”
99, 287; 33-35
cas de statut,” 32-33
is
134.
common
it
Edw.
1
YB
32-33
107; 1-2
Edw.
Edw.
II
I
29.
Also see “
104;
YBB
30-31 Edw.
Henghan,J Vous .:
estes
I
en
Notes to Pages 36-39
208
YB
56.
Edw.
31-32
254-55; also see 318-19. “Malberthorp. Although the Statute of
I
Westminster the second on which
this writ
founded gives the
is
suit to the king, yet
it
does not take away the suit of any other person for the statute does not say the king alone and no other person shall have the suit.”
YB
57.
may
21-22 Edw.
responds by pointing out that while the statute
326. Spigurnal
I
not have mentioned Mortdancester, neither did
58.
YB
59.
For cases during the reign of Edward
Edw.
33-35
YBB
and argued, see 30-31 Edw.
1
20-21 Edw.
I
326- 28, 344, 354, 356, 412, 434, 452, 454, 476, 528;
400, 412, 436; 32-33 Edw.
Such cases were
YBB 32-33 Edw. YB 3-4 Edw. II
61.
was not made
1
just as
YB
1-2
Edw.
It
was because of
idem
Also see statute ford,
YB
11
Edw.
YB
his
“the cause
why
Rouge, 1978),
YB
63.
“The
common
at the
cause of the statute was to
law in case
covert,
presentation was
a
who had no is
recovery save by
stand
32-33
Edw.
aid
“The
the cause
the same, quia ubi
intention of
by statute for each
writ.”
YB
was made was that where
it
est
eadem
him
2-3
at the
made
that
Edw.
II 38:
beginning
the
Berea
man
means
should be lawful for him to enlarge his court.” Also see
Walter C. Richardson,
in
it
better
YB
A
History of the Inns of Court (Baton
28-30.
I
Hengham, J.,
takes
umbrage
at a lawyer’s
made and remonstrates, “Do not gloss than you, for we made it.” YB 33-35 Edw. I 82.
has been
Edw.
33-35
statute and (said he)
I
we
30.
will
Also see not
YB
2-3
Edw.
now determine
II 33:
the
explanation of
this statute;
“Bereford,
meaning of the
J.,
we under-
looked
at the
statute; but in the
present case, because of the hardship which would otherwise ensue,
we
will
not de-
a statute,
he must
him of his voucher.”
66. In
show
And
415.
a statute
prive
was not
his court sufficiently large, then, if afterwards his
64. In a notable exception,
65.
II 31: Scotre,
ley
28-30.
I
King Henry VIII;
why
remedy accordant with
Report by commissioners Thomas Denton, Nicholas Bacon, and Robert Cary
62.
to
Edw.
a
hardship that the statute wasYnade.
this statute
household increased,
32-33
II.
“you should understand that the statute
Bereford, C.J.,
II 36:
had not the means to make
and
Edward
ins. ”
was that there should be
J.,
288, 398, 416, 426-30, 476, 496,
I
same here, and consequently the law
[of grievance] is the ratio ibi est
this
76-78, 98, 120, 174, 230, 254,
532.
women were
were under age or
I
in the time of
was made because
remove the hardship that there was writ of right.
I
12-13: Bereford, C.J.,
for nothing, but
heirs
common
290; 33-35 Edw.
I
ordained by the old law.”
made while
it.
which the words of statutes are cited
in
I
280, 284, 286, 290, 314, 318, 406, 450; 33-35 Edw.
60.
forbid
426-30.
I
126, 226, 232, 272,
532, 560, 586.
it
11
Edw.
that he
is
II 35,
in
Scrope
says, “If a
man wishes
to have help
by
circumstances wherein the statute operates for him, for
a statute
cannot be invoked in every circumstance where hardship can be assigned.” Scrope takes a similar view in another case later that year: “I cannot help the hardship of the law.”
67.
YB
11
Edw.
II 324.
The terminology
See also
YB
33-35
Edw.
I
434.
changed; lawyers in the reign of Edward III more
commonly
Notes to Pages speak of “mischief” in the kinds of cases that would have evoked in the
times of Edward
YBB
68.
12-13
492, 516, 538; 17
I
and Edward
209
39-43 a
claim of hardship
II.
Edw. HI 84, 98, 156, 302, 316; 16 Edw. Ill 16, 58, 226, 340, 350, 456, Edw. Ill 4, 40, 92, 94, 98, 306, 370, 542; 17-18 Edw. Ill 8, 32, 208,
246, 316, 326, 344, 422, 450, 506, 636; 18-19 Edw. Ill 300, 302, 490; 20 Edw. Ill 92.
Common
69.
lawyers as early as the time of
Edward
I
occasionally note a distinc-
between the rigorous and the equitable. Kyng, speaking of
tion
Berrewik, says
that.it is “de rigore
quam
YB
de equitate.”
the reporter applauds a statutory interpretation by Kave,
YB
ing to equity and law, and was good.”
20-21 Edw.
I
30-31 Edw. J.,
a I
judgment by 120-21. In 1292
saying “this was accord-
106-7.
Doe, Fundamental Authority, 104.
70.
72.
John Fortescue, De Natura Legis Naturae, vol. 1, chap. 24 (London, 1869). YB 4 Hen. VI 26. For discussion, see Doe, Fundamental Authority, 104-6.
73.
Choke, Illingworth, and Yelverton,
71.
cording to the intent of those that made
it,
YB
IV, Pasch. 4. All the judges agree in
“Every statute made must be taken ac-
JJ,:
when
21
words are ambiguous.”
its
Hen. VU,'Hil.
one must construe the intent of those that made the
YB
74.
Hen. VII
14
and Heyden’s Case,”
Hil.
7.
Quoted
in
Law Review
Illinois
YB 4 Edw.
28, that “in every statute
statute.”
Samuel E. Thorne, “The Equity of a Statute
31
(1936): 202, 21
1.
John Hamilton Baker and Samuel E. Thorne, eds. Readings and Moots at of Court in the Fifteenth Centuty (London, 1990), 1:43. 75.
Constantinus Rogerius, Tractatus de
76.
the Inns
iuris interpretation (1463), in Tractatus
Uni-
Hans Baade, “The Casus Omissus: A Pre-History of Statutory Analogy,” Syracuse Journal of International Law and Commerce
versi Iuris
(Venice, 1615), vol.
1
1,
pt. 6,
39or-39iv;
20 (1994): 4 5, 55-56. 77. Baker and Thorne, Readings and Moots,
YBB
247;
Mich.
18; 7
16, 6; 15
Hen. VI
Hen. VII
De Natura
in
5, 9;
14
The most prominent
78.
Edw. IV Pasch.
Hen. IV Pasch.
7
1:38, 181, 186, 198, 213; 2:237, 239,
Hil.
2,
Hil.
5; 11
A
Hil. 20;
3
Hen. VI
7.
fifteenth-century exception
Legis Naturae, vol.
Hen IV
240,
is
Fortescue’s brief discussion
chap. 24.
1,
79.
William Holdsworth,
80.
Plucknett, Early English Legal Literature, 102.
History of English Law, vol. 2 (London, 1936).
Holdsworth,
History, 2:553; a Eo see Plucknett, Early English Legal Literature,
82.
Holdsworth,
History, 2:555-56.
83.
Plucknett, Early English Legal Literature 103, 104.
81.
103.
84. Carleton Allen,
YB YB YB YB
85.
86. 87.
88. 22;
1
Edw.
32-33 16
I
80
Edw.
Edw.
I
in the
Making, 7th ed. (Oxford, 1964), 190.
(1292).
28.
Ill 6.
17-18 Edw. Ill 390. Also see
Hen. VI
YBB Edw.
I
I
152;
3-4 Edw.
II 28; 2 Rich. II 9, 11,
25.
Instances of these phrases can be found in
89.
Edw.
21
Law
36, 248,
300 (1304);
33
Edw.
I
YBB
378 (1305); 4 Edw.
22
II
Edw.
67-69,
I
1
502 468 (1294); 12-13
O3 10);
11
32
Edw.
Notes to Pages 44-46
210
II 97,
Edw.
(1317), 323 (1318); 16
256
O344), 444, 446, 452
Ill 534; 17
Edw.
Edw.
Ill 172, 186 (1343); 18
Ill 18
(1343).
90. Preface, Reports 10 (1793).
YB
91.
YBB
Edw.
32
Edw.
16
I
248 (1304); other examples of
Edw.
Ill 250, 530; 17
form of rebuttal
this
Ill 22 (1342-43); 19
Edw.
Ill
are
found
in
446, 448, 490, 492
6344-45). 92.
YB 4 Edw.
II
109
Similar rejoinders are to be found in
(1310).
YBB
19
Edw.
Ill
408, 490 (1344-45). Sometimes neither judge nor counsel cites the contrary case but the Year
Edw.
Book reporter
does, as in
4 Edw.
II
138-39
(1310), 17
Edw.
Ill 52 (1343),
and
18
Ill
634 (1343-44). 93. YB 6 Edw. II 189, 190; other examples may be found in YBB 32 Edw. I 28 (1304); 32-33 Edw. I 452; 4 Edw. II 127, 164 (1310); 17 Edw. Ill 172, 186 (1343); 18 Edw. Ill 282 6344), 538, 540 (1343-44);
13
Rich. II
94.
YB
95.
Long Quinto, M.f. no. Quoted
dent,” 96. (pt. 2)
97.
YB
in T. E. Lewis,
“The History of Judicial Prece-
Quarterly Review 47 (1931): 412-13.
YBB
18-19 Edw. Ill 392. Also see
12-13
Edw.
Ill 294; 16
Edw.
Ill (pt.
1)
230,
248; 18-19 Edw. Ill 390; 2 Rich. II 37, 78.
YBB
7 Rich. II 18; 16
YT
“Et
f.
custume
le
Edw.
Ill (Pt. 2) 430; 20
Edw.
Ill (pt.Y) 540; 12 Rich. II 162;
24b.
Long Quinto M.f. ,
99.
124 (1390).
18-19 Edw. Ill 490, 492 (1344-45).
Law
34 Hen. 98.
123,
et course
en un Court, ou Presidents en un Court font un
ley.”
109.
Dawson, The
Oracles of the
Law
3.
,
100. Ibid., 10.
lowing
Dawson finds explicit references to common erudition in the folYBB 20 Hen. VI 5 (1441); n Edw. IV 10 (1472); 4 Hen. VII 1 (1489); 16
63-64.
101. Ibid.,
cases:
Hen. VIII
16 (1501). It
the phrase
“common
is
my distinct impression that although
erudition” exists throughout the Year
gained widespread currency only in the
itself
the idea encapsulated in
Book
of the fifteenth century. In the
last half
fourteenth century the same idea was normally referred to as
“common
intendment.”
YBB
17
Edw.
the fifteenth century the expressions
“common
,
“common
Edw.
“common
Ill 252; 18-19
opinion,”
“common
2:155,
l
9 °i *98, 22 7
2 39
’
>
2
4^
opinion” or
Edw.
Ill 300. In
intendment,” and
erudition” appear to have been used interchangeably. This
clear in fifteenth- century readings
Moots
Ill 98; 17-18
period, the phrase
is
perhaps most
and moots. See Baker and Thorne, Readings and 2 7 2 > 2 73> 2 9 2
-
YBB Hen. VII 3 (1485); Hen. VII 10 (i486). 103. YB 21-22 Edw. I 430. Norman Doe, in his fine study of fifteenth-century common law jurisprudence, argues that medieval common law judges believed that “judicial consent alone shaped the common law.” Doe, Fundamental Authority, 26. He cites no evidence for this other than those cases that base the common law on usage of the court. Such cases, however, suggest nothing about what the common lawyers thought 102.
about
judicial consent. If
common 104.
1
1
law, they
they believed that consent
never say
“Every writ brought
common
law or statute.”
an important element of the
so.
in the King’s
YB
is
22
Edw.
I
Court ought
528. Also see
to be framed according to the
YB
3-4 Edw.
II
1
12-13.
u
L)enom:
Notes to Pages 46-50 The
common
statute does not abrogate the
YB 4 Edw.
law.”
II 85.
“
Bereford C.J.: ,
should understand that the statute was not made for nothing, but was
remedy accordant with remedy
gives a
cordant with 105. It
was not ordained by the old
ley
in the aforesaid case,
YB 4 Edw.
ley''
law, so
You
made because
inasmuch
a
as the statute
you must understand that the remedy
is
more
ac-
II 85.
would be interesting to know whether the two Year Book versions report the
same point
in the discussion
of the case.
It is
not
uncommon
cover the same point more than once in the discussion of
sometimes one reporter would
ment given
at
for judges
and counsel to
a case and, in
doing
so, to
When several reporters were taking down what was said in such in-
vary the language. stances,
211
one point
on
seize
in the discussion
a
variation of a judge’s pronounce-
and another reporter upon
a
second varia-
tion given at a different point in the discussion. 106. 107.
YB 17 Edw. Ill 98. YBB 11 Edw. II 105; Edw.
Ill 40; 17-18
108.
YBB
17
12-13
Edw.
Ill 84, 156, 316; 16
Ill 316; 18-19
Edw.
Ill
Edw.
Edw.
Ill 306; 30-31
I
490;
12
10; 1-2
Rich.
Edw:
Edw.
Ill 16, 58, 538; 17
Edw.
II 10.
II
44; 2-3 Edw.
II 33; 11
Edw.
II
324; 7 Rich. II 90. 109.
YB
Edw.
15
no. Aristotle,
Ill 126.
bk.
Politics,
into English , edited
3,
chap.
by William David Ross (London,
hi. Cicero, The Republic bk. ,
1
12.
Cicero, The Laws bk.
1
13.
Ibid.
14.
The
1
,
civil
16, in Artistotle,
1,
The Works of Aristotle Translated 1913).
chap. 22 (Cambridge, 1988).
3,
chap. 7 (Oxford, 1998).
law and the canon law (especially the canon law) were important
sources of medieval natural law theory. Pollock argues that the reason the lawyers speak of “reason,” instead of referring to the law of nature by name, fact that the
mon
lawyers
is
felt
threatened by, and jealous
1
17.
1
18.
The disagreement between
15.
116.
of,
the canon lawyers. Frederick Pollock,
in Jurisprudence
1961).
Hillary and the other judges repeats the argument
Summa
Theologica (60 vols.,
whether “law pertains not to the reason, but to the
120.
and Legal Essays (London,
1
of Question 90 of Aquinas’s
119.
the
sheer speculation.
YB 4 Edw. II 12-13. YB 19 Edw. Ill 376. YB 19 Edw. Ill 378.
1
lies in
canon law was the principal vehicle of the law of nature and that the com-
“The History of the Law of Nature,” This
common
YB YB
London, 1964-76) regarding
will.”
17-18 Edw. Ill 12 (1343). 15
Edw.
Ill 126. It
is
possible, of course, to read the qualifying clause, “ex-
cept where the contrary practice has been in use,” as limiting only the taking away of
mischief and not affecting the
demand
that law be in accordance with reason.
pect, though, that a qualification both of the
demands of reason and
I
sus-
also of the relief
of hardship better reflects standard judicial practice of the time. 121.
YB
21
and 22 Edw.
dent,” 349, 350. 122.
YB
16
Edw.
Ill 90.
I
430.
Quoted
in Lewis,
“The History of Judicial Prece-
Notes to Pages
212
123.
124. 125.
YB YB YB
8 3
8
Edw.
51-55
II 273-74.
and 4 Edw. II 161. Edw. Ill; quoted in Lewis, “The History of Judicial Precedent,”
350.
Chapter 3: Legal Theory in Fortescue, Littleton, and Fifteenth-Century Readings and Moots Chief justice of the King’s Bench (1442-61),
1.
castrian party and in exile,
went into
he never exercised
exile
with the queen; evidently named chancellor while
Thomas
IV and was
he submitted to Edward
office; in 1471
doned. His contemporary, Sir
Lan-
Sir John Fortescue joined the
Littleton, wrote a greater law
par-
book than any-
thing that Fortescue wrote, but that work, Tenures (edited by Eugene
Wambaugh
[Washington, 1903]) is a scientific doctrinal analysis of English land law that, while it undoubtedly carries jurisprudential implications, does not openly tackle questions of general jurisprudence.
Norman Doe, Fundamental Authority
2.
Late Medieval English
in
1990), provides a thoughtful treatment of Fortescue’s theory
the important influence of medieval theology
on
Law (Cambridge,
this subject
and shows
on Fortescue’s jurisprudence. For
cussion of Fortescue’s treatment of equity and
its
a dis-
4 of the
relation to law, see chapter
present work.
John Fortescue, De Laudihus Legum Chrimes (Cambridge, 1942), 25.
by
Angliae, edited and translated
3.
S.
B.
John Fortescue, The Governance ofEngla?id, edited by Charles Plummer (Lon-
4.
don, 1885), 109.
For another statement of this interpretation see R. Hinton, “English Constitu-
5.
tional
Theories from
Sir John Fortescue to Sir John Eliot,” English Historical
Review 75
(i960): 410, 412-17. 6.
Charles
Howard Mcllwain, The Growth
York, 1932), 359. In his Ancient and
Modem
last
jurisdictio.
(Ithaca, 1940),
politicum et regale Bracton' s
is
He
(New
published discussion of John Fortescue, Constitutionalism:
86-90, Mcllwain asserts that the central concep-
tion of the medieval English constitution
lum and
of Political Thought in the West
Bracton' s distinction
is
between gubemacu-
adds that Fortescue’s intention in using the phrase regimen
to identify his politician with Bracton' s jurisdictio and his regale with
gubemaculum. The problem with
this analysis
is
that there
is
no textual sup-
port in Bracton for Mcllwain’s distinction between jurisdictio and gubemaculum. Since
Mcllwain’s analysis of Fortescue assumes
every turn that Fortescue
at
is
lowing an intellectual tradition derived from Bracton his interpretation ,
tially
undermined. Stanley
B.
Chrimes, English Constitutional Ideas
merely is
fol-
substan-
in the Fifteenth
Cen-
tury (Cambridge, 1936), 319, 321, 339. 7.
Walter Ullmann, Law and
8.
Fortescue,
9.
John Fortescue, De Natura
10.
De
Politics in the
Laudibus, 41.
Ibid., 1:194. Similarly, in
Legis Naturae
De Laudibus
either laws of nature, customs, or statutes.” 11.
Fortescue,
12.
Ibid., 1:41.
Middle Ages (London, 1975), 62.
De Laudibus
,
1:39.
,
(London, 1869),
37,
1:205.
Fortescue says,
“all
human
laws are
Notes to Pages 13.
14.
De Natura, chap.
Fortescue, T.
T. Plucknett,
F.
A
chap
5,
Concise History of the
Common
a
judge of
15.
After 1628,
it
was principally read with
16.
Plucknett, Concise History, 278.
17.
Littleton, Tenures
18.
Ibid., sec. 702.
19.
The
,
3,
2I 3
10, 241.
was
277. Littleton
55-62
Common Law
5th ed. (Boston, 1956),
Pleas, 1466-81.
Edward Coke’s commentary.
Sir
sec. 383.
following are from
ibid., 41, 82, 132, 241, 365, 737; 2, secs. 103, 108, 229, 396,
647. 20.
in
YB
34 Hen. VI,
f.
24a.
21.
Littleton, Tenures
22.
Ibid., sec. 724; also see sec. 725.
23.
Ibid., 2, sec. 231; that this
,
3,
sec. 13.
was standard fifteenth-century doctrine may be seen
YBB 3 Hen. VI
44; 12 Hen. VI 7. 24. Doe, Fundamental Authority, 15 5-69. 25.
Littleton, Tenures
26.
“And so always upon
,
2, sec.
202;
3,
-
secs. 269, 478.
partition the lands given in frankmarriage remain to the
donees and to their heirs according to the form of the should have any of that which
convenience and
a
is
gift:
for if the other parcener
given in frankmarriage, of this would ensue an in-
thing against reason, which the law will not suffer.” Ibid.,
3,
sec.
269. 27.
Ibid., 2, sec. 210.
28.
Dot, Fundamental Authority,
29.
Littleton, Tenures,
30.
Christopher
St.
1,
sec. 21
113-20.
1.
German, Doctor and
Student, edited
T. Plucknett and
F.
L. Barton (London, 1974), 45, 47.
J.
31.
Summa Thcologiae, 60 vols. (London,
Aquinas,
1964-76): vols. 1-2,
q. 95, a. 2, ad.
also see Isidore of Seville, Etymologiae (Paris, 1983), 5:4.
3;
32.
Aquinas,
33.
St.
34. 35.
Summa
Theologiae, vols. 1-2, q. 95,
German, Doctor and
Littleton, Tenures,
Court
2, sec. 212.
For discussion of what
in the Fifteenth
is
known about
these educational exercises, see
36.
“The
space of
I
and
vol. 2,
the Early Stuarts
5;
John H.
Readings and Moots at the Inns of
Century (London, 1990); Walter C. Richardson,
Inns of Court (Baton Rouge, 1978), chaps. 4,
under Elizabeth
a. 2, c.
Student, 129, 121.
Baker and Samuel E. Thorne, introduction to
a
by T.
A
History of the
Wilfred R. Prest, The Inns of Court
(Totowa, 1972), 115-36.
utter barristers are they which, after they have continued in the house by
five
of barristers
is
of a
six
years and have profited by the study of law.
preferment or degree given to him for
.
.
.
his learning.
And
this
making
Also the benchers
are those utter barristers which, after they have continued in the house for the space
of fourteen or fifteen years, are by the elders of the house chosen to read, expound and declare
some
statute openly unto
cipal times of their learning,
all
the
company
which they
ing the time of his reading he hath the
call
of the house in one of the two prin-
the grand vacation in
name of
reader,
and
summer; and dur-
after of bencher.”
Report
written ca. 1539 on the customs and learning exercises of the Middle Temple, quoted in
Baker and Thorne, Readings and Moots
,
2:lix.
Notes to Pages 62-66
214
Report by commissioners
37.
King Henry VIII;
to
Thomas Denton, Nicholas
in Richardson,
A
A
Bacon, and Robert Cary
Histoiy of the Inns of Court, 414-15.
38.
See Richardson,
39.
Baker and Thorne, introduction to
History of the Inns of Court 102. ,
vol.
1,
Readings and Moots.
40. Alfred William Brian Simpson, Legal Theory and Legal Histoiy (London, 1987),
67-91, 80.
“The Purpose and Making of the Later Year Books,” Law Quanerly Review 89 (1973): 64; Desmond S. Bland, “Learning Exercises and Readers at the Inns of Chancery in the Fifteenth and Sixteenth Centuries,” Law QuarSee Eric William Ives,
41.
terly
Review 95 (1979): 245.
42. Ives,
“The Purpose and Making,”
66.
Baker and Thorne, Readings and Moots
43.
,
2:xlix.
44. Richardson, History of the Inns of Court, 418.
These were
45.
propounded without pleadings,
cases
statute and recited “certain doubts and questions
grow upon himself,
and
after the reader read the
which he hath devised that may
the said statute,” which were argued by the utter barristers, the reader finally
by any judges and sergeants who were present. Richardson, Histoiy
of the Inns of Coun, 418. See Baker and Thorne, Reading and Moots,
2:xlvi, lxiv-lxxiii.
46. In one of the few examples of the citation of prior cases in a reading, the case miscited: “But
now clear, by the
it is
equity of Gloucester, ca.
3,
that the warranty
Ewd.
is
is
no
bar without assets, as
Thorpe
where
length and said that in the eyre this case was [adjourned] before
it
was argued
at
says in 38 E.
10 or 25 [E.
3 [23];
3]
[really 15
Ill],
Herle and adjudged ut supra, and that he had no other reason except that Heng-
ham, who made the Lincoln’s Inn, Moots, 47.
statute, so interpreted
Autumn
on West.
1489,
First
it.”
II, cc.1-2, in
Reading of Robert Constable
at
Baker and Thorne, Readings and
1:181.
Ibid., 2:123, 2 ° 2 > 22 9> 2 3^’ 2 6°-
48. Ibid., 2:124, 228-30, 236, 244-45, 2 5^ 2 6°> 282, 288, 291-92, 297-98, 323. ?
49. Ibid., 2:202, 188.
reached inconsistent 50.
Obviously the
On
results:
occasion u
Frowyk:
common
it
was openly recognized that the cases had
has often been held both ways.” Ibid., 2:273.
it
training received at the Inns, the reading cycle re-
peated from one generation to the next, and the small size of the group of judges and sergeants at any one time would contribute to a commonality of outlook. For text references, see ibid., 2:47, 155, 190, 193, 198, 239, 248, 272, 283, 292. 51.
Ibid., 2:248.
52.
I
have in mind those passages in which
then cites
a case in
such
a
way
3.”
53.
Sir
These terms — ground, Institutes
principle,
and fee
is
Edw.
Ill, at the
13
Hen. VII,
is
and
saying Q.E.D.
beginning of quire
f,
folio 2
2 ^°-
and maxim — are used interchangeably. See
quoted as arguing “to the contrary: for
shall
P. pi. 9,
f.
it is
a principle
not pass out of anyone’s person without livery”
Baker and Thorne, Readings and Moots,
YB
a legal assertion
of the Laws of England (Buffalo, 1986 [1787]), 1:10b.
For example, Kidwelly
in law that freehold
55.
2
Baker and Thorne, Readings and Moots, 2:214,
Edward Coke,
54.
lawyer makes
that he creates the impression that he
For example, “And that was decided in or
a
23.
2:124; a ^ so see 2:II 9>
r
44>
237.
Notes to Pages “The Purpose and Making,”
56.
Ives,
57.
YB
58.
Fortescue,
59.
For
Hen. VII, H.
11
pi. 11,
f.
dence, see chapter
2I 5
68.
15.
De Laudibus, 21, 23. much fuller discussion of the
a
66-71
place of principles in
common
law jurispru-
8.
60.
Baker and Thorne, Readings and Moots 2:42.
61.
Edmund
,
Plowden, The Commeritaries, or Repons of Edmund Plozvden (London,
1816), 1:363. 62.
Baker and Thorne, Readings and Moots
63.
Ibid., 2:132.
Also see
IIO 2 3&> 289.
1:15; 2:105,
,
>
2:67, 236.
64. Ibid., 2:141.
make a variety of claims of harm or wrong, a claim of mischief most commonly was made in a situation in which someone would be left without a legal remedy or process that the law would ordinarily provide or in which some procedural burden, such as a delay, woul$j, result. “There is no doubt but While “mischief” could be used
65.
that the
first
may
lessor
enter because of the alienation, because of the mischief which
would otherwise follow
for him; for if he waited until the first lessee for
for breach of condition ... in the
occur so
as to bar his recovery.”
against the tenant even
to
if
meantime
“And
a collateral
as to the process infinite, that
he had never vouched, for
it is all
For an excellent discussion of the use of mischief
319.
warranty or
a
life
entered
descent might
mischief exists as
the same delay.” Ibid.,
2:121,
in the fifteenth- century
Year
Books, see Doe, Fundamental Authority, 155-61.
“Note
66.
that
which they hold issue
and
dies,
if
make
there are two coparceners, and they
in coparcenary,
and then waste
is
and the
lessee
a lease for life
of land
commits waste, and one of them has
again committed, the question
is:
if
the aunt and the
niece bring a writ of waste for the waste committed after the sister’s death, shall the
aunt recover the moiety of the place wasted, and damages accordingly, for the waste
committed 67.
Baker and Thorne, Readings and Moots
definition,
many
medieval theorists this conception had
reproduced twice
its
1. 1.
Bracton offers this definition
and Fortescue, noting the
word
civilian origin
69.
Kebell the
voucher
lies
Thorne, Readings and Moots,
Chapter
1.
Christopher
St.
own
See also
it
man
is
and In-
definition of justice,
of the definition (De Natura,
by reason, and
2:319.
[right].” Digest 1.1.10
for word^as his
says that justice “is the will that assigns to every “
origin in Ulpian’s famous
in Justinian, Corpus luris Civilis (Dublin, 1973): “Justice
steady and enduring will to render unto everyone his ins
stitutes
2:70.
Doe, Fundamental Authority, 120-21.
68. For
a
in her sister’s land?”
1,
chap. 35) also
his right” (chap. 39).
seems that
it is
law also.” Baker and
ibid., 2:188, 202, 319.
The Early Sixteenth Century: Christopher St. German 4:
German, Doctor and
Student, edited by
Theodore
F.
T. Pluck-
and John L. Barton (London, 1974), 3. 2. Ibid., 7. Although the device of the dialogue always puts distance between the
nett
reader and the author’s intention,
it is
as clear in Doctor
and Student
as
it
ever
is
in a
Notes to Pages 72-80
21
dialogue that both the doctor and the student speak for are given in text for passages
The term
3.
wider sense,
it is
from
ins positivum
this
used by the medieval canonists in two senses. In
is
used to distinguish
positive enactment. St.
human
German seems
law from
it
more
its
special-
used to refer to law created by some
it is
to use
ius naturale. In its
in the first sense.
See Stanley B. Chrimes, English Constitutional Ideas
4.
German. Page numbers
work.
and eventually more common, sense
ized,
St.
in the Fifteenth
Century
(Cambridge, 1936), 210-12; Stephen Siegel, “The Aristotelian Basis of English Law,”
New
York University
Law Review 56
German, Doctor and Student 59. can think of two arguments for treating maxims
5.
St.
6.
I
,
from general custom. same strength and
made
(i98i):i8, 23.
German
at
one point
ground of law separate
states that
maxims
are of the
effect in the law as are statutes. Since he also says that statutes
custom are
against general
proved by reason,
First, St.
as a
it
would seem
valid (57), because general
to follow that
customs cannot always be
maxims, being equal to statutes
in their
strength and effect, might also stand against contrary general customs and deserve
recognition as a separate ground. However, the student holds that maxims, like cus-
toms, are subject to being changed by statutes
(65),
so
have more strength in this respect than do statutes, after directly concerning the relative strength of
The second argument If
he
is
being
a
is
manner,
at
The
student says nothing
grounds only on the
portion of the eternal law, then
it
basis of separate
might be argued that maxims,
the erudition of legal specialists, should be assigned as a
separate ground. But although this
all.
German’s understanding of the term “ground.”
involves St.
known only through
turns out that they do not
maxims and customs.
to be understood to be assigning separate
means of knowing
it
St.
German
does sometimes use the term “ground” in
other times he uses the term as a
synonym
for “authority.” If
understood in the sense of “authority,” there appears to be no basis in
maxims from general customs. German, Doctor and Student 47. Page numbers are given
St.
“ground”
German’s
jurisprudence for distinguishing 7.
St.
from
this
8.
,
work.
John Fortescue, De Laudihus Legum Angliae, edited and translated by
Chrimes (Cambridge, 9.
in text for passages
See
J.
1942), chap.
St.
from
this
B.
17.
G. A. Pocock, The Machiavellian Moment (Princeton,
German, Doctor and Student
10.
S.
,
49. Page
numbers
1975), 14-22.
are given in text for passages
work.
11.
A
Replication of a Serjaunte at the
12.
A
Little Treatise
Laws of England (hereafter, Rep. in text) was written about 1530 and printed most recently in J. A. Guy, Christoper St German on Chancery and Statute (London, 1985), 99-105. Concerning Writs of Subpoena was most recently printed in Guy,
Christopher St German, 106-26. 13.
14. 15.
Ibid., 123.
Ibid., 109-10.
“Law could never
accurately embrace what
same time, and so prescribe what and their actions, and the
is just;
is
best and
for the dissimilarities
fact that practically
nothing in
most
just for all at the
between human beings
human
affairs
ever remains
Notes to Pages 80-89
prevent any kind of expertise whatsoever from making any simple decision in
stable,
any sphere that covers by C. 16.
21 7
all
cases and will last for
Rowe (Warminster,
J.
time.” Plato, Statesman, translated
all
1995), 294a-b.
The Works of Aristotle Translated
Aristotle, Nicho?nachean Ethics in
into English
edited by William D. Ross (London, 1913), 1137b. 17.
Aristotle, Rhetoric in Works i374a-b.
18.
Ibid., 1374a.
19.
Cicero,
20.
Quintilian, The
,
De
Winterbottom
Inventions (Cambridge, 1949), 2:xlii— xlviii.
Minor Declamations Ascribed
He
was
Quintilian, edited
(Berlin, 1984), secs. 264.7-264.9. Quintilian (35-95 A.D.)
of the most important school of oratory courts.
to
at
Rome and sometimes
by Michael
became head
pleaded in the law
great admirer or Cicero and hoped to raise the orators of his age to
a
the level of the age of Cicero. His most important surviving
work
is
the Institutio Ora-
(Cambridge, Mass., 1985) in twelve books. 21. English and American jurists have repeatedly jnade similar points. John Selden,
torio
the great seventeenth-century scholar and
“Equity [But]
is
a
roguish thing, for
Equity
is
[in]
law
common
we have
a
lawyer, spoke bitingly of equity:
measure to know what to trust
according to the conscience of him that
larger or narrower, so
is
equity.” Table-Talk
Supreme Court
in the 1798 U.S.
chancellor, and as that
is
(London, 1689), 49. Justice James
case of Colder
v. Bull,
to. is
Iredell,
rejected Justice Chase’s appeal
to principles of natural justice as bases for constitutional decisions, saying in re-
sponse:
“The
purest of
ideas of natural justice are regulated
men
have differed on the subject.”
3
22.
Cicero, Topica (Cambridge, 1949), 4.23.
23.
For example, Aquinas quotes Code
who by obeying
by no
fixed standard; the ablest
U.S. 386, 398 (1798).
1.14.5 (“he doubtless acts
contrary to the law
the letter goes against the legislator’s intention [voluntas]”) but ig-
The who
nores texts such as Digest 33.10.7 and 40.9. 12. 1, which do not support his point. civilians
knew 24.
could be selective, too, but always did so
the law books as well as they would catch
See
and
Hermann Kantorowicz,
other jurists
at the risk that
them
out.
Studies in the Glossators of the
Roman Law (Cam-
bridge, 1938), 88. 25.
Irnerius,
Summa
sunt benignius ut
praecepta tunc
Codicis (Berlin, 1894), 1.14.6:
mens earum
demum
a
“Conditae leges intelligendae
servetur et ne ab aequitate discrepent: legitima
iudice admittuntur,
cum
enim
ad aequitas rationem accompdan-
tur.”
26.
“Aequitas in singulis causis et negotiis spectanda
est,
inquirendum an decern pro decern
tia,
lex Fusia, lex Papyia,
est,
maxime tamenin
reddi, vel aliquid simile,
sit
iure,
hoc
aequum. Verba gra-
quae quia aequitatem non habet, tolluntur:
lex Falcidia, quae,
quia continet aequitatem, confirmatur. Vel dicit, in omnibus professionibus et artibus,
maxime
in iuris professione.
.
.
.
Maxime autem
aequitas, ut iudex earn stricto iuri praeforat.”
Alexander
J.
Carlyle,
A
in iuris professione, ut dixi, spectatur
Quoted
in
Robert
W.
Carlyle and
History of Medieval Political Theoiy in the West (Edinburgh,
1903-36), 2:15- 16. 27.
Apparently the concept of aequitas
civile est aequitas constituta."
constituta
came from Cicero,
Topica, 2.9: “Ius
2l8
Notes to Pages
V
28.
This gloss
is
reproduced
(Oxford, 1929), app. 4.
The
89-91 in Paul
Vinogradoff,
full gloss reads:
“Cum
enim proprium
versentur, differunt tamen. Equitatis
proponere. Juris autem idem proponere volendo, necti.
Quod
quam
equitas dictaverit continendo, partim plus
quoque
29.
modis equitas
aliis
fiat, solis
hominum
propter
lapsus
Rowan Law
est id
quod justum
quam
est simpliciter
aliquantum auctoritate sub-
ea distare contingit, partim minus
quam
operteat proponendo. Multis
et jus inter se differunt, cujus dissensus interpretatio, ut lex
principibus destinatur.”
See Peter Stein, “Vacarius and the Civil Law,” in Church and Government in the
Middle Ages, edited by Christopher Brooke (Cambridge, 1978), 30.
Medieval Europe
equitas et jus in hisdem rebus
scilicet
multum ab
in
Code
“Placuit in
3.1.8:
omnibus rebus praecipuam
119, 124.
esse iustitiae aequitatisque
rationem .” Stein argues that Martinus did not disagree with Bul-
stricti iuris
garus over whether judges or jurists could use aequitas rudis as a standard for the interpretation of written law; he agrees that jurists and judges were limited to the aequitas constituta in passing
Stein suggests, rule
is
on the equity of
that Martinus
The
difference
between them,
was willing to derive the equity pertaining to
given
a
from the entire body of established law whereas Bulgarus wanted to narrow the ,
down
issue
Law,” 124, 31.
to the ratio
legis
Azo,
Summa
Codicis
,
in
Summa Azonis Comm.
capitanea, aequites bursalis, martiniana
1533):
“Licet
M.
dedit
ei
ex sua
Decret. C.9.10. “et dicunt:
ficta
hae est aequitas
.”
William Cahill, “Development by the Medieval Canonists of the Concept of
Equity,” Catholic Lawyer 7 (1961): 33.
(Lyon,
actionem.” Odofredus, Dig. Vetus 50.4.5. “Dixit Martinus, de sua
aequitate et bursali .” Hostiensis,
32.
and the Civil
for that particular rule. Stein, “Vacarius
125, 129.
ficta aequitate
J
a legal rule.
115.
Vacarius, The Liber Pauperum of Vacarius, edited by Francis de Zulueta (London,
9 2 7)> l6
-
34.
“Non
35.
Vacarius, Liber Pauperum:
perator.
exemplis sed legibus iudicandum
Obseruare
(1)
“1.
est.”
Conditor autem
autem leges debent
tarn ceteri
et interpres
quam
legum
solus est im-
imperator. Sed ipse ex pro-
pria uoluntate, ceteri ex necessitate. Item, iudicis interpretatio nulla intelligitur,
preterquam
si
nullo ab his inter quos iudicat iuris remedio infirmetur,
eos tantum tenet.
2.
quo constructum
est.
Generale
reclamante interdum,
(2) et
nature
congruum
Reproduced
eo
modo
fieri
contingit et ualet.
Ergo
in Paul
Vinogradoff,
Roman Law
et durat ut a
in
principe
inter
soluatur quid
Imperatoris autem constitutionem inuito populo,
abrogari possit, nisi prius imperium et potestatem iat.”
est ut
quo casu
immo
etiam
nec per consuetudinem
amotam populus
recip-
Medieval Europe (Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1929), p. 149. 36.
Ibid., 13.
37.
Azo,
Summa
Institutis, in
potius debet servare aequitatem, tate scripta,
non de
ea
quam
Azo,
quam
Summa
Azonis, 4:17,
jus scriptam.
Quod
2:
“Item in pronunciando
est
intelligendum de aequi-
quis ex corde sou inveniat: ut et majori reverentia vel
ti-
more serventur omnia aequitatis, seu justitae praecepta.” Brocardica, Rub. lxxvi: “Aequitatem dico, lege, non cujusquam ingenio excogitatam.” For discussion, see Carlyle,
A
History of Medieval Political Theory, 2:18.
Notes to Pages 91-93
This association has roots going back to Aristotle’s statement that “equity bids
38.
human
us to be merciful to the weakness of
found the idea
dieval jurists also
nius] interpretation
justice
is
nature.” Rhetoric in Works ,
1374a.
,
Me-
in Digest 50.155.2: “In penal cases, the milder [benig-
to be adopted.”
is
of Hostiensis: “Equity
43 1
219
The
classical canonist definition
tempered with mercy.”
of equity
is
Summa Aurea (Lugduni,
that
1556),
-
See Decretum Cau.
39.
25,
,
was the
first
1,
diet. p.c. 16.95.
Influenced by the civilians, Gratian
canon law systematically. The
to organize the sources of the
title
that he
chose for his work ( Concordia discordantium canonum ) reflects his intention to organize the law of the church into a harmonius system out of an great variety of diverse, even
contradictory elements. 40. Decretum, Cau.
Decretum Dist. 4, Medieval Canonists.” 41.
is
For discussion, see Cahill, “Development by the
diet. p.c. 2.
,
42. ‘“Equity
diet. p.c. 90.
11, 3,
the law’s law’
is
only true of equity, reduced to writing, for rude
equity only softens the rigor of the law.” Decretum Gratian i cum Glossa
Durham
Cathedral Ms. C.
II, fol.
Anonyma
49, quoted in Cahill, “Development by the
,
Me-
dieval Canonists,” 117. 43. Aquinas,
Summa Q.
Ibid., I la Ilae,
44.
Aquinas, In
45.
46. Aquinas, Ibid.
47.
Theologiae
120, 2; Aristotle,
V Ethic
Summa
,
(London, 1964-76):
la Ilae,
Q. 96,
if
(New
York, 1948-50).
6.
Aquinas uses an example that goes back
enemies are pursuing citizens outside the
violation of the letter in order to serve the
Cicero,
De
Invention
,
at least to
De
rieux (Paris, 1960-70), T. 9,
is
Cicero:
for the
walls, the gates
common
utility
a
law requires
common welfare,
should be opened in
intended by the lawmaker.
II, xlii.
48. See Jean Gerson,
49. Ibid., T.
6.
,
that the gates of the city be kept closed, and ordinarily this
but
Q. 96,
Nichomachean Ethics 113833.
Opera Omnia
lect. 16, in
,
la Ilae,
95-96.
2,
St.
Religionis in Oeuvres Co?npletes, edited ,
by Palemon Glo-
233-39.
German borrows
tion of the words “having weighed
all
this definition.
Rueger sees
in the addi-
the particular circumstances” to Hostiensis’s
famous definition evidence of an important difference between Gerson and the canonists. Zofia Rueger,
“Gerson’s Concept of Equity and Christopher
History of Political Thought
(1982): 10-11.
3
But the canonists long
tied the
St.
German,”
equity-m^rcy
idea to that of taking account of particular circumstances. Gratian traces this connec-
tion to Isidore of Seville in Decretum Dist. 29, ,
Medieval Canonists,” 50. isted
116.
Rueger, “Gerson’s Concept,” 14-15. Rueger sees more disagreement than ex-
between Aquinas and Gerson. Her evidence that Aquinas
of equity to the prince totle says, tent,
Proem. See Cahill, “Development by
is
the following text: “Further, the function of equity, as Aris-
seems to be to look to the
however,
is
legislator’s intent. Interpreting a legislator’s in-
competence of a
in the sole
ruler; thus Justinian says,
lawful for us alone to evaluate an interpretation
Aquinas,
Summa
limits the application
Theologiae Ilallae, Q. 120, ,
1.
It is
proper and
between equity and written
But reliance on
law.”
this text indicates a fail-
ure to recognize that the objections, or auctoritates presented at the beginning of a ,
Notes to Pages 93-98
220
discussion by Aquinas do not represent his views
Guy makes
John
in his responsio or corpus.
on the matter; these
same
the
slip in
are to be found
“Law, Equity and Con-
science in Henrician Juristic Thought,” in Alistair Fox and John Guy, Reassessing the
(New
Henrician Age 51. tutes
York, 1986).
Bracton, 2:24. Bracton's treatment of equity
Summa
borrowed from Azo,
is
Insti-
1. 1.
52.
Aristotle, Rhetoric 1374a.
53.
Cicero, Topica IV,
,
YB
54.
14 Hen. VII, Hil.
Heydon’s Case,”
Illinois
John Fortescue,
55.
23.
,
7.
See Samuel E. Thorne, “The Equity of
Law Review 31 (1936): 202, 208-11. De Natura Legis Naturae (London,
and
a Statute
1869), chap. 24. In associ-
ating equity with the king’s discretionary power, Fortescue appears to be following the canonist tradition of encouraging secular princes to intervene in cases in which
the positive law
though such
tem
is
inadequate. See introduction to
treatment of equity
a
which the creation of
in
St.
German, Doctor and Student. Al-
may be somewhat easier
legislation
is
to justify in a political sys-
understood to be wholly the province of
the prince (so that an equitable intervention can be understood as an adjustment that the lawmaker himself
lowed),
it is
makes to ensure
own
that his
intention in the law
is
possible to justify the king’s intervention, even in a system in
being
fol-
which the
king does not legislate alone, as necessary to recover the true meaning or intention of the law from the confusion sometimes found in
its
Fortescue teaches that the English king’s rule
not able to change the laws
De
Fortescue,
at his pleasure
Theologiae, la Ilae,
De Natura chap. 24. German, Doctor and Student
Fortescue,
58.
St.
Q. 96,
,
omnibus circumstantiis
95.
,
,
German, Doctor and Student
German’s discussion
tory of Political
1.
Thought 4
97. J.
,
95-96.
H. Burns shows that
“St.
Summa
of
St.
Theologiae
German, Gerson, Aquinas, and Ulpian,”
,
His-
(1983):
,
Ibid., 99.
62.
Aquinas,
63.
Introduction to
Summa
Theologiae Ilallae, Q. 120.
St.
,
German, Doctor and Student
German, Doctor and Student
Rot. Pari,
and Student
YBB
,
iv,
,
,
xlviii-xlix.
3.
84, No. 46. For discussion, see introduction to St.
9
German, Doc-
xl-xli.
Edw. IV
Edw. IV
4 Hen. VII 4. 67. Quoted in Albert F. Pollard, Wolsey (London, 1929), 96. 68. St. German, Doctor and Student 81. Chapter 13 is devoted to 66.
this part
443, 447. German, Doctor and Student 97.
61.
tor
9,
closely parallels Aquinas’s treatment in the
James H. Burns,
aequitas jus-
particularibus, dulcore misericordiae temper-
Regulae Morales in Oeuvres Completes T.
Ilallae, Q. 120.,
6.
Compare Gerson, “Est autem
ata.”
65.
is
,
pensatis
64. St.
he
but depends upon the assent of his people.
titia
St.
political:
1885), 109.
Summa
57.
60.
not only regal but
,
56. Aquinas,
St.
is
Laudibus, 25; Fortescue, The Governance of England edited by Charles
Plummer (London,
59.
words.
14; 8
8;
,
excellent discussion of the idea of synderesis in medieval and early
sinderesis.
For an
modern thought,
Notes to Pages 98-108
221
see Robert A. Green, “Synderesis, the Spark of Conscience, in the English Renaissance,” Journal of the History of Ideas 52 (1991): 195. 69.
Gerson, De Theologia Mystica,
70.
St.
German, Doctor and Student 88-89.
71.
St.
German
in
Oeuvres Completes 3:260-61. ,
,
no
distinguishes between the “higher part” of reason, which “hath
regard to transitory things or temporal things” (84-85) and the “lower part” which
“worketh most to govern well temporal things” (86-87). 88-89.
72.
Ibid.,
73.
“Error in conscience follows upon
defective application of Ibid., 132-33. St.
74.
in text for passages
YB 4 Hen.
75.
it
IV,
this
repeats this assertion
mained concerning whether such amining even
German
a
German
a
two
on
163.
Page numbers are given
recognizes that a theoretical problem re-
would prevent the chancellor from ex-
a statute that
judgment against the law of reason
provides
science, or a
work.
23. St.
c.
some
to an act.” Ibid., 90-91.
German
from
defect of knowledge of
a
is
conscience.
itself against
-part answer. First, he argues, if the chancellor or others
examine judgments of the king’s courts, lawsuits would have no end,
plaintiffs
be damaged and impoverished, and the inconveniences thus invited would be tially
greater evil than the occasional injury to a party. Second, conscience
trated
by such
a
self and, indeed,
must do so to save
German, Doctor and Student
“Equity rather followeth the intent of the law than the words of the
Page numbers are given
not frus-
Although
St.
in text for passages
this
work.
St.
and Student the two characters seldom take speak for the author.
from
law.” Ibid.,
German himself may have written the Replication is not German may favor the dialogue as a literary form, in Doctor
suggestion that
persuasive.
poten-
116-17.
77.
,
The
would
his soul.
St.
78.
might
law because the offending party can always redress the problem him-
76.
99.
is
a
St.
The
issue with each other,
and both appear to
character of the sergeant in the Replication as David E. C. ,
Yale notes, takes serious and acrimonius issue with
St.
German’s treatment of con-
science in Doctor and Student. David E. C. Yale, “St. German’s Little Treatise Concerning Writs of Subpoena ,” Irish Jurist 10 (1975): 326-27. For a thesis that St.
German may
more
favorable view of the
be the author, see Guy, Christopher St German 56-58. ,
reply to Doctor and Student written in the form of a dialogue between St.
student and
posed 79.
a
sergeant at the
in the early 1530s.
The
common
law, the Replication appears to
Guy, Christopher
Replication of a Serjeant at the
St.
German
A
German’s
have been com-
64.
Laws of England
in
Guy, Christopher St Ger-
man, 100. 80.
Ibid., 101.
The
following quotations are to be found on this page.
German, A Little Treatise Concerning Writs of Subpoena, St. German on Chancery and Statute, 123-24. 81.
St.
82.
Statute of Westminster III,
83.
Yale, “St.
84. St. 85.
German’s
German,
Ibid.,
1
A
YB
18
Edw.
Little Treatise',' 329.
Little Treatise, 109.
12.
86. Yale, “St.
German’s
Little Treatise," 330.
I, st. 1, c. 1.
in
Guy, Christopher
Notes to Pages
222
St.
87.
German,
A
108-112
Little Treatise, 116.
John Guy, The Cardinals Court: The Impact of Thomas IVolsey in the Star Chamber (Totowa, 1977). John Spelman, The Reports, edited by J. H. Baker (Longon, 1978), 88.
vol.
2.
Guy, Christopher St German
Replication in
89.
,
103.
Chapter 5: Plowden’s Commentaries and the Sixteenth-Century Law Reports Edmund Plowden, a lawyer with abilities of the first rank (Holdsworth suggests that he may have been the most learned lawyer of the century), reinvented the case re1.
port in the two volumes of his Commentaries, which cover cases from the 1550s to
1571.
Edmund Plowden,
See
1816).
The Commentaries, or Reports of Edmund Plowden (London, Hereafter, Commentaries. Although his Commentaries are more like the Year
Books than some of his contemporaries’ reports
arguments
in their interest in the oral
of counsel and judges, in other respects they are very different from the Year Books.
The Year
Books, concerned with the intricacies of oral pleading, ordinarily pay more
how
attention to
framed than to how they are resolved. The change from
issues are
toward the decision of an
oral to written pleading naturally directs interest so,
Plowden
the cases he reports are
tells us,
upon Demurrers or
special verdicts, copies
“upon points of law
tried
and
issue,
and debated
whereof were delivered to the judges, who
studied and considered them, and after great and mature Deliberation, gave Judgment
thereupon.” Commentaries
summarizes the
facts
argument on both
and
sides
Plowden ordinarily provides the written pleadings,
i:v.
legal issues,
summarizes the substance of what was
and by the judges (taking care to check
counsel and judges), reports the judgment, and often adds his tary.
For discussion of Plowden, see L.
W.
Abbott,
Law
1485-1585 (London, 1973), 198-239; William Holdsworth, (London, 1922-66), 5:364-66, 369-73. 2.
Commentaries
3.
Ibid.
law.
This passage
The
details
with both
learned
commen-
Reporting in England, History of English
Law
1:9. is
interesting as well for
precedents) were in the sixteenth century
mon
A
own
said in
still
its
suggestion that “cases” (judicial
not regarded as the same as the com-
notion that ancient precedents are not necessarily the law
is
found
also
The Case of Modus Decimandi Coke’s Reports 13:14, although there it is explained that the reason is that statutes often have changed the ancient law and that time and cusin
,
tom have 4. is
also altered
The
first is
it.
from
Platt
from The Case of Mines, 5.
in
v.
The
Sheriffs of London, in
Commentaries
Commentaries
For further discussion of the expression
“common 3
erudition,” see the discus-
of this volume; John Spelman, The
by John H. Baker (London, 1978), introduction to Ives The Common Lawyers of Pre-Reformation England (Cambridge, Reports, edited
to
Calvin's Case, early in the seventeenth century,
mind
in
which
explicit resort
is
made
the second
1:316.
sion of case law and precedent in chapters 2 and
6.
1:36;
is
vol.
2;
and Eric
W.
1977), 156-65.
the only other case that
to the law of nature for legal authority.
comes
Notes to Pages 115-117 James Dyer, Reports from Baker (London, 1994), 1:25. 7.
Thomas
8.
the Lost Notebooks of Sir James Dyer, edited
Hedley’s speech before the House of
of 1610, Proceedings
in Parliament
1610
2 vols.,
Commons,
1610.
223
by John H.
See Parliament
Reed Foster (New
edited by Elizabeth
Haven, 1966), 2:172-7 6.
James Dyer, admitted to the coif
9.
mon
in 1552,
Pleas in 1557. His reports extend from
was constituted
YB 4 Henry VIII
a
judge of the
Com-
to the time of his death
in 1582.
Plowden reports such
10.
by Dyer himself in the Wrotesle
Norman Doe, Fundamental
Also see
11.
a discussion
case.
Law
Authority in Late Medieval English
(Cambridge, 1990), 103-6.
Thomas
12.
Egerton,
A
Discourse upon the Exposicion
with Sir Thomas Egerton's Additions, edited by Samuel E. Ibid.,
13.
Understandinge of Statutes
Thorne (San Marino,
Thorne’s view that
this
his repeated
merely
as a facet
For the
15.
3.
the only principle regarding the equity
is
of a statute that really mattered for fifteenth-century judges must be taken on
must
1942),
45-46.
Ibid., 48-51.
14.
&
faith, as
claim that they viewed the application of the equity of a statute
of the routine administration of justice.
first
time, an abridgement devoted a separate
interpretation (Robert Brooke,
title
La Graunde Abridgment [London,
to statutes 1573]),
and their
the cases after
the middle of the century, especially those reported by Plowden, contain fuller dis-
cussions of interpretive questions than had ever been reported before, and two books
on
statutes
and their interpretation were written (A Discourse upon
the Exposicion
Understanding of Statutes, unprinted until 1942 and possibly the work of Sir
Egerton, and
A
Treatise Concerning Statutes, or Acts of Parliament
,
and
and
Thomas
the Exposition
Christopher Hatton and published posthumously in London
thereof, attributed to Sir
in 1677).
See Theodore
16.
T. Plucknett, “Ellesmere
F.
on
Statutes,”
Law
Quarterly Review
60 (1944): 242, 248. For the understanding that parliamentary legislation required the separate consent of king, lords, and commons, see John H. Baker, An Introduction to English Legal History, 3d ed. (London, 1990), 235-36.
Plowden, for example,
17.
identifies the doctrine of the equity of a statute
and in elaboration, quotes from
Aristotle’s notion of epieikeia,
tor
on
Aristotle. Eyeston
vide attribution,
many
v.
Studd, in Commentaries 2:465.
a
with
medieval commenta-
Although he does not pro-
of Sir Edward Coke’s Latin maxims on interpretation can be
we know, contained standard civilian and canonist texts as well as Roman works on rhetoric. See William O. Hassall, A Catalogue of the Library of Sir Edward Coke (New Haven, 1950). Hatton’s Treatise Concerning traced to civilian sources. His library,
Statutes evinces a familiarity with with civilian tion.
See Hans Baade, “T he Casus Omissus:
Syracuse Journal of International 18.
and canonist approaches to interpreta-
A
Pre-History of Statutory Analogy,”
Law and Commerce
20 (1994): 67-68.
Categorical assertions, such as the one by Baade, that reliance on the intent of
the makers of statutes
dominant one,”
is
not
a
illustrate the
“cardinal rule of statutory interpretation
let
alone the
hazards of making claims about what the cases hold
Notes to Pages 117-126
224
without the advantage of having read the cases. Baade bases his assertion on
a
count
of entries made in an index to Plowden’s Commentaries he found only three regarding ;
“The Casus Omissus 78. Even a casual reading of the would have uncovered many more statements of the rule that interpretation was
the intent of the makers. Baade, cases
to be governed by the intent of the makers. 19.
Christopher
St.
German,
whether ignorance was an excuse
in discussing
English law, remarks regarding one statute that
“it
in
hath alway been taken that the in-
terne of the makers of the said statute was that they that were ygnoraunt of the fyrste
reteynoure sholde not renne in any penalty of the statute.” Doctor and Student edited ,
by T. 20.
F.
T. Plucknett and
J.
L. Barton (London, 1974), 283.
For other examples of
1:50, 53,
on
judicial reliance
Commentaries
legislative intent see
54, 67, 87, 161, 162, 250.
21.
Hatton,
22.
Some of the
Treatise Concerning Statutes 28-29.
lawyers of Plowden’s time had begun to speak as
if
the equity of a
statute has the principal function of effectuating the makers’ intent. 23.
Egerton,
A
Discourse upon the Exposition, 15 1.
24. Ibid., 152. 25.
An argument
around, that
is,
by Serjeant Bromley does appear to put the matter the other way
to suggest that equity provides the basis for a conclusion about leg-
islative intent. “It
cannot be reasonably taken,” he contends, “that such was the intent
of the makers of the statute, for
it
would be against
avoid leases newly made.” Fulmerston
v.
Hatton,
Treatise Concerning Statutes, 28.
27.
“Equitie
is
statute, yet
construction
reason and equity utterly to
Steward, in Commentaries 1:109.
26.
a
all
made by
the judges, that cases out of the letter of the
being within the same mischiefe, or cause of making the same, shall be
within the same remedie that the statute provideth.” Edward Coke,
Laws of England (Buffalo, 1986 [1787]), 1:24b. 28. Such a reference is made by Hales, J., 1:54:
ful
“So we see where the
common
or prejudicial to another, and
in
Wimbish
a statute is
made
in
v. Tailbois,
law suffers anything to be done for the redress of
Institutes
.
.
it,
Commentaries
which
.
of the
is
hurt-
that by the eq-
uity of the statute a like thing shall be taken within the like purview.” 29.
Chancery Reports
30.
Hatton,
Treatise Concerning Statutes, 30.
31.
Sheffield
v.
1:12,
Ratcliffe in
in
The English
Reports, vol.
H. Hobart, The
Reports of that Learned Sir
Knight (London, 1641), report 346 (1616). 32. The dearth of arguments for strict interpretation occasionally a judge would citation of Cicero
show
48 (Edinburgh,
familiarity with the
and quotation of the maxim
is
33.
since
words of Cicero. See Saunders’s
summum jus summa
injuria in v. Tracy,
support in
Com-
1:161.
Chancery Reports
1:14-15.
The chancellor’s
expression of views such as
sociating the chancery with unlimited prerogative power, that goes
Henry Hobart
somewhat surprising
of following the intent rather than the words of deeds. Throckmerton mentaries
1932).
may
beyond the defense of res judicata why Coke and other
came embroiled
in a dispute
this, as-
help explain in a
common
way
lawyers be-
with chancery. For discussion of the dispute, see John
Dawson, “Coke and Ellesmere Disinterred: The Attack on Chancery
P.
in 1616,” Illinois
Notes to Pages Law Review
36 (1941): 127;
1616,” Irish Jurist
i
953),
Lawyers and the Chancery:
1:12.
Hake’s Epieikeia: A Dialogue
35.
Common
225
(1969): 368.
4
Chancery Reports
34.
H. Baker, “The
J.
126-132
was written
in
Three Parts edited by David E. C. Yale (London, ,
in the late sixteenth
century but remained unpublished until this
century. 36.
Ibid., 43.
37.
Ibid., 46. *
Chapter
6:
Sir
John Davies and the Common Law Mind
1.
John Greville Agard Pocock,
2.
J.
Politics ,
Language and Time (New York,
G. A. Pocock, The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law:
Retrospect
(Cambridge, 1987),
A
Reissue with a
36.
Ibid., 37.
3.
Davies (1569-1626) was sent by James
4.
to Ireland in 1603 as solicitor general; in
I
1606 he was appointed attorney general for Ireland; in 1609 he was made
The
1626 he was appointed chief justice, but he never took office.
published at Dublin in 1615 as Le Primer Repo?~t des Casses adiudges in 5.
scripts
1973), 209.
les
et
a
sergeant; in
Irish reports
were
Matters en Ley resolues
&
Courts del Roy en Ireland.
John Davies, The Works
in Verse
and Prose Including Hitherto Unpublished Manu,
of Sir John Davies, edited by Alexander Grosart (Blackburn, 1869-76), 2:251-52.
Hereafter, Works. Fictions and artificial conventions had a definite place in the
6.
has even been suggested that they were the glue that held
need, however, for lawyers to believe in
from the doctrine of trespass,
ple
trespass, or
them or take them
in the thirteenth
it
common
law;
it
together.
There was no
To
take an exam-
literally.
century the rule was that
a
claimed
wrong, could be heard in the king’s courts only upon an allegation that
the king’s peace had been broken. In nearly
all
cases of trespass, therefore, the plain-
wrong had been done him by means of force and arms, usually adding wit with swords and bows and arrows.” As the law of trespass expanded
alleged that
tiff
the words “to
to cover cases in client’s case
which no force or arms were used,
heard
still
lawyer
a
had to make the old allegations of vi
et
who hoped
to have his
armis although he and ,
the other legal professionals understood well that he was using a fiction. 7.
8.
John Fortescue claims that this argument is Aristotelian. The argument is plausible, but it is vulnerable to the following counterarguSir
ment from supporters of statutory statute law
enough
to
is
said to be
become law
law.
Customary
demonstrated by the
if it
law’s
fact that
it
supposed superiority to
would not have
lasted long
had contained important defects or produced serious
in-
conveniences. This claim can be challenged on a factual basis, as Sir Francis Bacon
we
accept the claim that immemorial custom has proved
did.
But even
free
from inconveniences, there remains the
if
upon may prove statute
on the
fact that
be
not every practice embarked
to be free of inconveniences. In weighing the merits of
scale of the inconveniences to
itself to
custom and
be found in each kind of law, should we
not take account of failed usages? According to Davies’s and Coke’s theory of custom,
22 6
Notes to Pages
x
usages and practices error. It
any
are
become
132-142
established as customs through a process of trial and
not self-evidently clear that errors that turn up in the usages of the people
is
less
inconvenient than misjudgments made by legislators.
One might
argue,
9.
too, that there
and
winnowing out process with
a
is
statutes just as there
is
with usages,
harmful or inconvenient usages are dropped, statutes that prove faulty are
just as
revised or repealed.
common
Davies asserts of the
law that “no
human Law,
written or unwritten,
hath more certaintie in the Rules and Maximes, more coherence in the parts thereof, or more harmonie of reason in
There
10.
law, in
is
Works 2:254.
it.”
no evidence that Davies recognizes that
comparison with other nation’s
laws, could be
his praise for the
common
reduced to the claim that the
English people are more virtuous and wise than other peoples. 11.
Pocock, The Ancient Constitution
12.
The
quotation
is
from
ibid., 25.
,
25.
For
of Davies’s aims in his
a general discussion
Repons, see Hans Pawlisch, Sir John Davies and the Conquest ofIreland (Cambridge,
Irish
1985). Davies’s Question Concerning Impositions
after his death. It 13.
reproduced in volume
common
Seventeenth-century
both statute and 14.
is
For
common
3
was unpublished
of Works. Hereafter, Impositions.
lawyers use the term “positive law” to refer to
^
law.
a fuller analysis
until 1656, thirty years
of the development of this doctrine, see Francis Oakley,
“Jacobean Political Theology:
The
Absolute and Ordinary Powers of the King,” Jour-
nal of the History of Ideas, 29 (1968): 323-46. 15.
1949),
Quoted
in
Margaret Judson, The
(New Brunswick,
112.
John Dodderidge, brary, London. 16.
17.
Crisis of the Constitution
Thomas
B.
Treatise on the King's Prerogative, Harl.
Howell,
A
ed.,
MS.
5220, British Li-
Complete Collection of State Trials (London, 1809),
2:387. 18.
Edward Coke,
19.
Louis A. Knafla, Law and
Institutes of the
Laws of England
Politics in
(Buffalo, 1986 [1787]), 1:115b.
Jacobean England: The Tracts of Lord Chancel-
(Cambridge, 1977), 216. 20. Sir Frances Bacon, The Works of Francis Bacon edited by J. Spedding
lor Elles?n ere
et
al.
(Lon-
don, 1874), 14:118. 21.
Sir
Henry
Finch, Law, or a Discourse thereof (London, 1627 [1759]),
William Holdsworth tional
book before Blackstone.” A
Chapter 1.
called Finch’s
J.
7:
Sir
the
History of English
(Cambridge, 1987),
Reports, preface to vol.
3.
Ibid., xvii.
institu-
1922-66), 5:399.
the Feudal
Law:
A
Reissue with a
36. 2.
For example, in Chudleigh's Case (Reports
made
Sir
Edward Coke and His Contemporaries
2.
ences are
most complete and best
Law (London,
G. A. Pocock, The Ancient Constitution and
Retrospect
4.
work “much
85.
to “the ancient
common
1:124a, 125a, 130a), at least three refer-
law”; in Caudrey's Case ( Reports
5),
mention
is
Notes to Pages 142-144 made of “the
227
*
ancient law of the crown,” “the ancient right and law,” and “the ancient
common laws of England” (15b, 38a, 39a); “the ancient common laws of this realm” (40b). Dozens
laws of the realm” (8b); “the ancient
good ancient laws”
(19a),
and “the
of such examples are to be found in the Reports. 5.
Reports 13:14.
6.
Lord Ellesmere’s contemporaries regarded him
See
as a great lawyer.
Thomas
The History of Worthies of England (London, 1662), 176. Elizabeth made him, successively, solicitor general (1581), master of the rolls (1594), and lord keeper (1596). Fuller,
James
I
made him Baron Ellesmere, and he assumed
1603.
He was
mon
law courts and the equity courts,
the
of lord chancellor in
title
Coke’s great opponent in the dispute over supremacy between the com-
teenth century. See Louis A. Knafla,
a dispute that
was revived
Law and Politics
at the
end of the
in Jacobean England:
The
six-
Tracts of
Lord Chancellor Ellesmere (Cambridge, 1977), 155-81; J. H. Baker, “The Common Lawyers and the Chancery: 1616,” Irish Jurist 4 (1969); John P. Dawson, “Coke and
The
Ellesmere Disinterred:
Attack on the Chancery in 1616,”
(1941): 127-52.
^
Thomas
7.
A
Howell,
B.
Co?nplete
Collection
Illinois
Law Review
36
-
of State Trials (London,
1809),
2:674-75.
“A Breviate or Direccion for the Kinges Learned Councell Collected by the
8.
Lord Chauncellor Ellesmere, Mense Septembris
Law and
Politics , 326.
Parliament of 1628, Commons Debates, 1628, edited by R. Johnson,
9.
M.
1615,” in Knafla,
Cole, and
W.
Bidweli
Ibid., 2:327.
10.
(New
M.
Keeler,
Plaven, 1977-83), 2:333.
Selden was recognized by his contemporaries as one of the greatest
English scholars of his time
ported in this land”
— and
methods to the study of
— John
Milton
was one of the
called first
him “the chief of learned men
common
re-
lawyers to apply humanist
he appears never to
legal history. Called to the bar in 1612,
have had a large practice, but from time to time he argued important cases that re-
He became
quired great learning.
engaged
in politics in 1621, before
he became
a
member of the House of Commons, by helping prepare the protestation of the Commons concerning the rights and privileges of Parliament. He was imprisoned for his pains.
In 1626, as a 1627,
member
he appeared
as
for refusing to lend
Commons
of Commons he participated in the attack on Buckingham. In
counsel to challenge the imprisonment of Sir
money
to Charles
The
I.
next year he took
a
Edmund Hampden leading role in the
debates over the legality of such imprisonments without assignment of
cause and without the availability of habeas corpus, serving as the chairmen of the
committee appointed to review the
legal
precedents in the matter. For further bio-
graphical details, see Dictionary of National Biography (London, 1901), 20:1150 -62;
David Berkowitz, John
Selden's Eoi'mative Years
Discourse on Ilistoiy Law, ,
and Governance
(Washington, 1988); Paul Christianson,
in the Public
Career ofJohn Selden, 1610-1635
(Toronto, 1996). 11.
Selden, in his speech
on April
7,
argues for “the ancient and fundamental point
of liberty of the person to be regained by habeas corpus
Parliament of 1628,
Commons
Debates, 2:356.
development of Selden’s argument
when any man
is
imprisoned.”
For excellent and detailed analyses of the
in his early
works, see Paul Christianson, “Young
Notes to Pages 144-147
228
John Selden and the Ancient Constitution, Philosophical Society, 128 (1984): 271-315,
John Selden, The Reverse
12.
cot (London, 1683),
sig.
and Christianson, Discourse on
common
Selden was not the only
Bacon
by R. West-
a3v-a4in Sir John Fortescue,
edited and translated by Stanley B.
gliae,
History.
or Back-face of the English Janus, translated
upon Fortescue,”
Selden, “Notes
13.
of the American
ca. 1610-1618,” Proceedings
asserts that English laws
De Laudibus Legu?nAn-
Chrimes (Cambridge, 1942
[1672]), 6-7.
lawyer of distinction to make this point. Francis
were
“as mixt as
our language, compounded of British,
Roman, Saxon, Danish, Norman customs.” See “A Proposition
to his
Majesty by
Sir
Francis Bacon, Knight, his Majesty’s Attorney- General, and one of his Privy Council
Touching the Compiling and Amendment of the Laws of England,” Works of Francis Bacon, edited by
common
Flakewill (1574-1655), a
J.
Spedding
lawyer with
et
al.
(London, 1874),
in
13:13.
who was a in the Comof the com-
law by asserting “that the laws of the Britaines were utterly extinct by the Ro-
mans; their laws again by the Saxons; and
much
altered.”
W.
by the Danes and Normans
Thomas Hearne (London,
Island,” in
A
Collec-
1571), 2.
upon Fortescue,” 15-18. In his famous metaphor, Selden plays meaning of the claim that the common law was the “same” in the
Selden, “Notes
14.
upon
fancifully
the
seventeenth century as into the
metaphor
had been for many centuries
it
a belief
seventeenth- century
on
common
law really was the
his point in writing the entire passage
all,
law
better than other laws because
metaphor, in fact
it
now
seems to me,
it
existed
it
medieval
common
law.
a
mistake to read
some deep metaphysical sense the same as the medieval common law.
is
to refute the claim that the
unchanged
longer. All he
once was, he concedes
speak of greatly altered ships and houses as
we might
is
to say that, having demonstrated that the
is
very different than
nally built, so
past. It
Selden’s part that in
After is
lastly, theirs
“The Antiquity of the Laws of this
Hakewill,
of Curious Discourses, edited by
tion
William
reputation for learning
a
member of the first Society of Antiquaries about 1600 and a participant mons Debates of 1628, criticized Coke’s contentions about the antiquity
mon
Bacon, The
if
that, just as
common
means by the
common
law
is
we sometimes
they were the same structures as origi-
modern common law as the same law as the which Selden refers in making this concession
also speak of the
The
recognizes the sameness of
civil a
law to
greatly modified ship not for the purpose of settling an
ontological dispute but to resolve questions about ownership and 15.
Glen Burgess, The
16.
Ibid.,
17.
John Selden,
Politics
liability.
of the Ancient Constitution (University Park, 1992), 58,
63.
63-64. Ioannis Seldeni
Ad Fleta?n
Dissertatio, translated
by D.
Ogg (Cam-
bridge, 1925), 105, 165.
of the Ancient Constitution, 6-7.
18.
Burgess,
19.
Although Selden believes that the use of Roman law
Politics
largely disappeared as the civil
by the beginning of Edward
Year Books of Edward
II
in the
Ill’s reign,
common
law courts
he recognizes that
as late
“one finds not only the very words and maxims of the
law as cited in pleadings before the king’s judges (although without express refer-
ences to their sources — a custom occasionally found today
among our
lawyers), but
Notes to Pages sometimes one
229
hangs on the interpretation of
also finds there that a question
Ad Fletam Dissert at io, 149. 20. Much more frequently, the common
47—1 5
i
civil
law”
memorie ne
lawyers used the law French “de temps dont
court. ”
21.
Burgess,
22.
Sir
Politics
of the Ancient Constitution 6-7. ,
Edward Coke, The Compleat
Copyholder.
in Three
;
Law
Tracts
(Abington,
^82), 59.
YB
23.
Edw.
19
Ill 378.
Law
24.
Henry
25.
Parliament of 1610, Proceedings
(New Haven,
Foster
,
or a Discourse thereof (London, 1627), 77. in Parliament 1610, edited
1966), 2:170-97. Page
numbers
by Elizabeth Reed
are given in text for passages
from
work.
this
26.
the
Finch,
“Whereas
same reason
27.
the
will
common
law
is
extended by equity, that whatsoever
be found the same
Although Coke’s voluminous writings
Reports q:vi;
(hereafter,
Coke,
Edward Coke.
Institutes);
v.
Mason
borough, Reports of Divers Choice Cases 29.
Finch,
30.
YBB
31.
Law
,
them
all
together in such
,
in
coherent way.
Laws of England 1:110b, 115b, 344a Richard Brownlow and John Goldes,
Law (London,
in
a
all
1675), 2:895
O^ 12 )-
or a Discourse 77. ,
6 Edw. II 18
Thomas
one place or another contain nearly
in
Institutes of the
Rowles
under
law.” Ibid., 2:176.
the pieces of Hedley’s theory, he never tied 28.
falleth
Edw.
(1313); 17
Ill 216,
Littleton, Tenures edited ,
224
(1343).
by Eugene
Wambaugh (Washington,
1903),
sec. 170. 32.
For example, Coke uses the expression “time out of mind” several times in the
preface to the third volume of his Repons. 33.
case
Thorne’s remark more than sixty years ago that “the literature upon Bonham’s
voluminous and repetitious”
is
is
even more apt today. Samuel E. Thorne, “Dr.
Bonham’s Case,” Law Quanerly Review 54 (1938): 543. Classic discussions include Charles H. Mcllwain, The High Coun of Parliament and Its Supremacy (New Haven, 1910);
Edward Corwin, The
win, The Higher
Doctrine ofJudicial Review (Princeton, 1914);
Law Background
of American Constitutional
MacKay, “Coke — Parliamentary Sovereignty or
Law
Edward Cor-
(Ithaca, 1955); R. A.
Supremacy of the Law,” Michigan T. Plucknett, “Bonham’s Case and Judicial Review,” the
Law Review 22 (1923): 215; T. F. Harvard Law Review 40 (1926): 30; John W. Gough, Fundamental Law in English Constitutional History (Oxford, 1955). More recent discussions are found in Raoul Berger, “Doctor Bonham’s Case: Statutory Construction or Constitutional Theory?” University
of Pennsylvania
ited,” Proceedings
Common Law and and
the
34.
Stuan
Law Review
117 (1969): 521;
Charles Gray, “Bonham’s Case Revis-
of the American Philosophical Association 116 (1972): Liberal Theory (Lawrence, 1992);
Constitution
(New Haven,
College of Physicians Case , in
Glenn Burgess,
Brownlow and Goldesborough,
36. 37.
Ibid.,
,
44-46.
James Stoner,
Absolute Monarchy
1996).
Mcllwain, The High Court of Parlia?nent, chap. Corwin, The Higher Law Background 47.
35.
35;
2.
Reports 2:265.
Notes to Pages 155-160
s
230
38.
Plucknett, “Bonham’s Case and Judicial Review,”
39.
Thorne, “Dr. Bonham’s Case.”
An
earlier version of this
Mackay, “Coke — Parliamentary,” although he cial strict
construction
Fundamental Law this
is
31.
also
argument
is
found
in
contends that the purpose of judi-
to limit statutes to the requirement of fundamental law. In
in English Constitutional History, a
work of very high merit
that
is
to
day the best and most thorough examination of the idea of fundamental law in
English history,
on the
Gough
largely agrees with the
Thorne
Gray argues when Coke announced his
interpretation.
basis of an unpublished report of Bonham's Case that
views from the bench he made his argument in terms of
a
theory of statutory
construction but that in rewriting his remarks for publication in his Reports he
strict
moved
further toward endorsing the idea of judicial nullification of a statute by a higher law
standard. 40.
E. Thorne, introduction to
S.
Thomas
Egerton,
and Understanding of Statutes (San Marino, 1942), 41.
Ibid.,
Common Law and Liberal Theory,
See Burgess, Absolute Monarchy,
44. Also see Reports 45. law, is
Discourse upon the Exposicion
88.
86-87.
42. Stoner, 43.
A
48.
181, 186, 192.
4:iii-iv.
For example, Coke states that “for any fundamental
it is
a
maxim
in policy
most dangerous.” Reports
and
poijnt
of the the
common
by experience, that the alteration of any of them
a trial
4:v-vi. Part of the danger comes, he teaches,
from
altering
what has been proved good by long experience, and part comes from the uncertainties that arise
when good
old laws are replaced by new. See Reports 2:preface, Reports
9:xii— xiii.
46. For Rowles
v.
Mason, see Brownlow and Goldesborough, Reports 2:197-98.
Coke himself does not gloss this statement at any length, but John Selden, who along with Coke was chosen to speak for the Commons in conference with the lords in the Parliament of 1628, suggests that Parliament’s power of making laws is so limit47.
less that
“were
made death
it
established here by act of parliament”
Commons
(New Haven, 1977), 2:576. 48. Henry Finch, Law, or a
would be lawful
for
it
to “be
and Coke says nothing indicating that he
to rise before 9 a clock,”
agrees. Parliament of 1628,
it
Debates, 1628, edited
by Robert C. Johnson
Discourse thereof (London, 1627),
diset
al.
5.
49. Ibid., 76. 50.
Henry Hobart, The
Reports of that Learned Sir
Henry Hobart Knight (London,
1641), report 87. 51.
A
Thorne,
argument from 52. 53. 55.
Discourse, 86.
silence. Berger,
Berger
is
convincing in showing the weakness of
this
“Doctor Bonham’s Case,” 528-30.
Burgess, Absolute Monarchy, 193. Ibid., 183.
Burgess
(ibid.,
184) says that “fortunately
with words as his great of both ‘reason’ and
critic
Coke was
Thomas Hobbes; and
in his
own
way, as careful
he defined carefully the legal sense
‘right.’”
56.
Coke, The Compleat Copyholder,
57.
Ibid., 61.
in Three
Law
Tracts
(Abington, 1982), 61-62.
Notes to Pages John Davies, preface,
58.
Irish Reports
,
The Works
161-163
231
and Prose Including Hith-
in Verse
Unpublished Manuscripts of Sir John Davies edited by A. Grosart (Blackburn, 1876),
erto
Coke
2:251.
translated by
Chrimes (Cambridge,
S. B.
Coke’s great
59.
makes
rival, Sir
The
stack of
of this line
long continuation:
its
Indians
mean
(I
wood, and so
“We
whole night
may
amples
17.
“Of Custom and Education,” of argument. It is not a custom’s wisdom
see also the reign or tyranny of custom,
the sect of their wise
sacrifice
themselves by
with the corpses of their husbands. will sit a
1942), chap.
Francis Bacon, in his essay
a telling implicit criticism
that explains it is.
paraphrasing John Fortescue, De Laudibus Leguni Angliae, edited and
is
.
.
.
men)
lay themselves quietly
Nay
fire.
till
upon
a
the wives strive to be burned
There be monks
in a vessel of water,
what
in Russia, for penance, that
they be encased with hard
ice.
Many ex-
be put of the force of custom, both upon mind and body.” Sir Francis
Bacon, The Works of Francis Bacon edited by J. Spedding ,
60.
Davies, preface to Irish Reports in Works, vol.
61.
This
,
is
as
it
law as custom. As
would have been had Coke
Thomas Hedley
et
al.
(London, 1874), 4:471.
2.
essentially conceived of the
notes, customs were “triable
which was the technical way of saying that
their existence
common
by the country,”
was to be determined
as a
matter of fact by ordinary inhabitants of the locality in which they were alleged to have force. Proceedings
in
Parliament 1610, 2:176. ,
Even Coke’s report of
62.
evoking the notion that
Calvin's Case contains a clause
it
wisdom of the professional elite, not of the English people, that forms the common law: “The laws have been by the wisdom of the most excellent men.” Coke's Rethe
is
ports 7:6-7.
In the prefaces to his Reports, Coke’s emphasis
63.
is
on the antiquity of the com-
mon
law and the wisdom produced and guaranteed by this antiquity. In the prefaces
to
of the
all
There
first
eight parts of his Reports, he repeatedly dwells
on the
law’s antiquity.
are scattered references to the law’s antiquity in his Institutes (1:115b), but refer-
ences to the law’s reason predominate there in
much
the same
way
that references to
antiquity does in the Reports. Important discussions of reason and the
its
are
found
64. 65. ficial
J.
in Institutes i:iob-na, 97b, 183b, 232b,
G. A. Pocock,
Politics,
common
law
394b~95a.
Language and Time (New York,
1973), 214-15.
John Underwood Lewis, “Sir Edward Coke (1552-1633): His Theory of ArtiReason’ as a Context for Modern Basic Legal Theory,” Law Quarterly Review 84
(1968): 334-35.
66.
D. E. C. Yale,
“Hobbes and Hale on Law,
Law Journal 31 (1972): 125-26. To say that Coke had a theory about
Legislation, and the Sovereign,”
Cambridge 67.
this
matter
is
to elevate his views to a
higher level of abstraction than perhaps his cast of mind allowed. This as a pejorative statement.
concerning laws have written either precepts
fair in
as
law. “All
who
Roman
bonds.” Bacon,
have written
philosophers or lawyers. T he philosophers lay
argument, but not applicable to use: the lawyers, being
subject and addicted to the positive rules either of the laws of their else of the
not intended
Bacon, with his usual clarity of mind, sees both advantages
and disadvantages in Coke’s characteristic approach to the
down many
is
own country
or Pontifical, have no freedom of opinion, but as
De Augment is,
in Works, vol. 9.
it
were
or
talk in
Notes to Pages 164-168
232
68. For example, Dr: Bonham's Case Coke’s Reports 8:652 (1609); Rowles
Brownlow and Goldesborough,
An
69.
would not William
,
Coke’s Reports 1:190 (42
Eliz.); a
it
was “repugnant to law and reason,”
doctrine was rejected because “the law
thing so absurd, and against the law of nature and reason,” Sir
let in a
Archbishop of York, Hobart, The Reports of Sir Henry Hobart report 459
Ellis v.
(17 Jac. I).
in
Report 2:895 (1611-12).
interpretation was rejected because
Corbet's Case
Mason
v.
,
“And they
said that this construction
was
just,
and consonant to reason and
equity.” Chudleigh's Case Coke’s Reports 1:320 (31 Eliz.). ,
Finch,
70.
“ 71.
Ratio
Law
,
or a Discourse thereof 74-75.
anima
est
legis"
(quoted in Coke’s Institutes 1:394b), and
contra rationem est licitum" (quoted in
In Ratcliff
72.
law
is
Coke’s
,
may be
collected
from the
common
law,
make
common
law, will not, against
the grant good”; Ferrer's Case
law”; Englefield's Case Coke’s Reports 7:430 (33 and 34 Eliz.): “and ,
common
Edward Coke,”
in Culture
Coke’s Reports
all
and
74. Coke’s Reports 12:64:
From Puritanism
Politics:
Perez Zagorin (Berkeley, 1980),
this agrees
The Jurisprudence
which
the
is is
life
man can
of Sir
31.
“Causes which concern the
reason and judgment of law, which law
reason
with
Enlightenment, edited by
to the
life,
or inheritance, or goods,
or fortunes of his subjects, are not to be decided by natural reason but by the
ence, before that a
common
law.”
Charles Gray, “Reason, Authority, and Imagination:
73.
,
which was remedied by the rule and reason of the
Eliz.): “all
common
said ancient authors of the law”; Bozoun's
,
the reason of the
est
Institutes 1:97b).
Case Coke’s Reports 4:972 (1584): “a non obstante of the
the reason of the
Nihil quod
Case Coke’s Reports 3:728 (1592): “And the reason of the
's
notable, and
6:266 (40 and 41
u
is
artificial
an act that requires long study and experi-
attain to the cognizance of it.” Coke’s Institutes 1:97b:
of the law, nay the
common
law
itselfe is
nothing
else
“For
but reason;
to be understood of an artificial perfection of reason, gotten by long study,
observation, and experience, and not of every man’s naturall reason.” 75.
Aristotle, in a
famous passage,
“Now
experience:
ties art to
art arises
from many notions gained by experience one universal judgment about jects is
produced.” Metaphysics, bk.
English, edited
1,
chap.
1,
by William D. Ross (London,
in
a class
when of ob-
The Works of Aristotle Translated
into
1913).
76.
Parliament of 1610, Proceedings, 2:175-76.
77.
John Dodderidge, The English Lawyer (London,
1631), 242. Solicitor general,
sergeant to the king, and a justice of the court of the King’s Bench from 1612 to 1628,
Dodderidge was
fully
Coke’s peer in knowledge of the
common
law and vastly his su-
perior in theoretical jurisprudence. Page numbers are given in text for passages from this
work.
78.
Eleonore Stump,
79.
See Alessandro Giuliani,
and Pleading,” Juridical Review 80.
Finch was educated
called to the bar in 1585
work on
his treatise
De topicis differentiis (Ithaca, 1978), 2^. “The Influence of Rhetoric on the Law of Evidence
Boethius's
at
7 (1962): 216-51.
Cambridge
in the
mid-^os and
at
Gray’s Inn; he was
and called to the degree of sergeant-at-law
toward the end of the sixteenth century;
it
in 1616.
was
law French in 1613 as Nomotechnia, cestascavoir un Description del
first
He began
published in
Common
Leys d'An-
Notes to Pages gleterre solonque les Rules del Art Parallelees ove les Prerogative
version was published posthumously, in 1627, entitled
systematic exposition of the
method served
method
it:
“Sir
Henry Finch’s
superior to
is
,
An
Roy &c., &c. ,
English
or a Discourse thereof.
Blackstone invidiously
discourse of law
that were before extant.”
all
2 33
As
work has been highly regarded.
law, this
as a basis for Blackstone’s Commentaries.
pares Coke’s Institutes with character; his
common
Law
le
168-172
is
a
Its
com-
of a very different
William Blackstone,
and Laws of England (Oxford, 1771), vi. Finch, Law or a Discourse thereof 4. Page numbers are given in text for passages
Tracts Chiefly Relating to the Antiquities 81.
,
from
this
work.
82.
Ibid., 76.
83.
Ibid.
,
Finch
many common
common
is
at pains to
claim that the
common
law of England
is
just
one of
laws in the world. Indeed, he says that the laws of every people are
laws and are “the golden and sacred rule of reason.” His point seems to be
that there
is
no
basis for invidiously
comparing the laws of different people because
if
they are truly law they will be in accord with the law of nature and the law of reason.
Dodderidge was
84.
a
man
of so
hard to say whether he was better called to be a sergeant in licitor general. In
that Sir Francis
many
parts that Fuller says of
artist, divine, eivil
or
common
him
was
that “it
lawyer.”
He was
1604 and in the same year was appointed to the office of so-
1607 he was obliged to resign his office in order to create a vacancy
Bacon might
fill.
As repayment, he was knighted and promised
on the court of the King’s Bench
at the first vacancy.
This occurred
in 1612,
a seat
and he
served on the court until he died in 1628. See E. Foss, The fudges of England
(New
York, 1966), 6:306-10.
Dodderidge, The English Lawyer,
85.
150.
Page numbers are given in text for pas-
sages from this work. 86.
men it
It is
probably true, as Stephen Siegel writes, that the thinking of
all
educated
of Coke’s time was influenced by Aristotelian epistemology, whether they knew
or not. Stephen A. Siegel,
versity 87.
Law
Review 56
Aristotelian Basis of English Law,”
New
York Uni-
(1981): 18, 30-31.
There undoubtedly were common lawyers who had no training
rhetoric, except for sisted
“The
what they had gotten indirectly
at
and
in logic
the Inns of Court, and
who
re-
such learning. William Fulbecke and Sir John Dodderidge ’s detailed arguments
for the utility of a liberal education for legal study
A
erwise. See Fulbecke and Dodderidge,
would be hard to understand oth-
Direction or Preparative to the Study of the
Law
(London, 1600). 88.
Dodderidge, The English Lawyer.
89.
Ibid., 62.
65.
;
90. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics bk. 6, chap. 6; Posterior Analytics, bk. ,
1,
chap.
2,
in
Works. 91.
Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, bk.
1,
chap.
3.
Dodderidge (The English Lawyer,
193)
echoes this point, saying of the primary conclusions of reason that “the manifest truth
and great Reason of which said Grounds
is
evident to any person of any Judgment,
and need no proofe for demonstration and establishing of them.” 92. Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, bk. 93.
See Aristotle, Nicomachean
1,
chap.
Ethics, bk. 6,
2;
bk.
chap.
2,
chap.
8; Topics,
19.
bk.
1,
chap.
1.
234
Notes to Pages
$
172-175
94. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics bk. ,
Dialectic is the
95.
1,
chap.
term that Aristotle uses
from opinions that are generally accepted.”
Chapter
8:
3;
bk. 6, chap. 8.
for the
Topics, bk.
branch of logic that “reasons chap.
1,
Reason and the Common Law Maxims
Such maxims were frequently borrowed from the
1.
1.
civil
or canon law.
W.
F.
Maitland even asserts that “when in any century, from the thirteenth to the nineteenth an English lawyer indulges in a maxim, he
be profoundly ignorant, quoting from the Sext. History of English
Law
Sext {Liber Sextus)
a
is
before the
is
generally,
though of
Pollock and
F.
Time of Edward /, 2d
ed.
F.
W.
this
he
may
Maitland, The
(Cambridge, 1898),
1:196.
The
compilation of decretals ordered by Pope Boniface IX and com-
pleted in 1298. Following the example of Justinian’s Digest
,
contains a
it
title
of regulae
,
many of which are taken from, or modeled on, the Digest. See Roscoe Pound, “The Maxims of Equity,” Harvard Law Review 34 (1921): 818-819 (1921); Peter Stein, Regulae luris: From Juristic Rules to Legal Maxims (Edinburgh, 1966), 148-55. 2. John Fortescue, De Laudibus Legum Angliae, edited by S. B. Chrimes (Cambridge, 1949),
21, 23.
For example, in
3.
Termes of the
Rastell’s
Law (London,
An Exposition
of Certain Difficult and Obscure Wordes and
1592), the discussion
of maxims
from Fortescue: “Maximes bee the foundations of the
tirely
of reason, and are causes efficient, that they
may not be
at
&
^borrowed almost enlaw,
and the conclusions
certain universal propositions so sure and perfect
any time impeached or impugned, but ought alwayes to bee
observed and holden as strong principalles and aucthorities of themselves although they cannot be proued by force of argument or demonstration logical, but are
by enduction by the way of sence and memory.” Tenninorum Legum Anglorum in
as Exposiciones
William were published Herbert
4. diritto
F.
in
nett and
J.
L.
his
son
and 1667.
English Maxims,” in L' Europa
St.
e il
,
,
Tracts of Lord Chancellor Ellesmere St.
German, Doctor and Student
7.
St.
German’s student are so well
no proof of them
is
,
England:
218.
69.
in the laws of
known by
Law and Politics in Jacobean
(Cambridge, 1977),
6.
many maxims
by
di Paolo Koschaker (Milan, 1954), 1:215.
jushin in Commentaries 2:44; Louis A. Knafla, ed.,
The
published
German, Doctor and Student edited by T. F. T. PluckBarton (London, 1974), 57; Serjeant Morgan, arguing in Colthirst v. Be-
Also see Christopher
5.
“Roman Regulae and
memoria
first
1527; editions translated
in 1567, 1579, 1592, 1595, 1602, 1641,
Jolowicz,
romano: studi
work was
Rastell’s
known
England gives
a
response in several parts:
the English people through usage and
custom that
known by the people can be known can be known through a variety of authoritative
necessary; others not so well
through the law of reason;
still
others
written materials such as the Year Books, records of the king’s courts and treasury,
and
69 and 71. John Dodderidge follows standard
statutes. Ibid., 8.
common
law practice in referring to the
propositions from which legal reasoning proceeds indiscriminately as grounds, maxims, principles, eruditions, and rules. The English Lawyer (London, 1631), 150-51. Page
numbers
are given in text for passages
from
this
work.
Notes to Pages
175-182
235
9.
This approach to secondary principles of reason, allowing deduction from English customs as well as from the law of nature, follows Doctor and Student and thus limits the
German, Doctor and Student
Dodderidge says that there were
10.
maxims
putable
in the
common
Colthirst v. Bejushin in
12.
Fortescue,
13.
See for example Rastell,
,
Coke’s
De
Laudibus,
,
law.
See
J.
in
which
L. Bar-
xxix.
many thousands”
“at the least
of such dis-
law.
Commentaries
11.
1:27.
21, 23.
An
Morgan
Exposition Serjeant ;
in Colthirst
Bejushin
v.
;
Institutes 1:11a.
“And by reasoning and debating of grave learned men the darknesse of igno-
14.
expelled, and
by the
Certaine
of
legall
reason the right
that in matters of difficultie the
more
seriously they are debated and argued, the
rance it is,
closer to Gerson’s treatment than to Aquinas’s,
secondary law of nature to deductions from the primary
ton, introduction to St.
more 15.
16.
is
is
discerned.
.
.
.
Roscoe Pound, “The Maxims of Equity,” Harvard Law Review 34 (1921): 833. Francis Bacon, preface to The Maxims of the kaw, in The Works of Francis Bacon
Chapter 1.
light
truely they are resolved.” Coke’s Institutes 1:232b.
edited by James Spedding et
1
is
German’s treatment
St.
9:
al.
(London,
,
1874), 14:184.
The Common Law Mind: Summary and Commentary
John W. Salmond, “The Theory of Judicial Precedents,” Law Quarterly Review
6 (1900): 376. 2.
“Non
3.
Irnerius, Questiones de Iuris Subtilitatihus des Imerius edited
exemplis sed legibus iudicandum
est.”
Code 7.45.13. ,
by Hermann Fitting
(Berlin, 1894), 3:1-2. 4.
William Holdsworth,H History of English Law (London, 1922-66),
5.
Ibid., 5:372.
6.
T. E. Lewis,
“The History of Judicial
Precedent,”
Law
5:371.
Quarterly Review 47
(193O: 411, 415. 7.
8. 10.
James Dyer, Reports (London, 1794), covers the period from 1537 to 1582. In Brett v. Rigden (a 1565 case found in the recently published James Dyer, Reports
by J. H. Baker [London, 1994], 1:111), Dyer denies cases vouched in Fitzherbert (A. Fitzherbert, La Graunde Abridgement the Lost Notebooks of Sir James Dyer, edited
from
[London, 1577]) and in Perkins’ Profitable Book asserting that the propositions contained in them “are absolutely repugnant to the grounds of the law, and none of them ,
may be found
Browne, J.,
in the year-books.” In Stucley v. Thynne, a 1567 case,
Year Book case that Bendeloes shows the court. “And
BROWNE said that if any rea-
son had been given in the year-book he would have given more credit to not see any reason in
it.
.
.
.
subdue
9.
my reason
Coke’s
it,
but he did
Nevertheless, since Jenour prothonotary said in 19 Hen.
VIII that there are many precedents will
rejects a
(as
he said there),
if I
can see such precedents
I
to the precedents.” Dyer, Reports from the Lost Notebook 1:128. ,
Institutes 1:254a.
Matthew Hale, The (Chicago, 1971), 45.
History of the
Common Law
of England edited by C. ,
Gray
23 6
Notes to Pages
$
182-193
John Vaughan, The Reports and Arguments of That Learned Judge Sir John Vaughan (London, 1677), 360, 382. 12. Whiteacre v. Marmion YE 8 Edw. II 27374. Bole
11.
Horton
v.
in
,
Coke’s Reports
13.
14.
Richard Brownlow and John Goldesborough, Reports of Divers Choice Cases
Law (London, Coke’s
15.
8:52, 653. in
1675), 2:895.
proeme;
Institutes , vol. 2,
2:25^ See T.
ibid.
F.
T. Plucknett, “Bonhams’s
Case and Judicial Review,” Harvard Law Review 40 (1926): 30. 16. Louis Boudin, “Lord Coke and the American Doctrine of Judicial Review,”
New
York University
17.
S.
6 (1929) 233.
E. Thorne,” Dr. Bonham’s Case,”
W. Gough, 18.
Law Review
Fundamental Law
Law
Quarterly Review 54 (1938): 543;
in English Constitutional History
John
(Oxford, 1955).
Plucknett wrote of these rules that “So great was their variety, and so diverse
were the
rules, that
almost any conclusion could be reached, simply by selecting the
appropriate rule.” T.
F.
T. Plucknett,
A
Concise History of the
Common Law
,
5th ed.
(Boston, 1956), 334. 19.
Reniger
20.
Commentaries
21.
Ibid. 1:172-73.
22.
One
sents
all
v.
Fogossa, in
Commentaries
1:16.
1:551.
exception
Britton a revision of Bracton in the timeTof
is
Edward
I; it
repre-
the law of England as being statutory — as proceeding from the king’s mouth.
John Fortescue, De Laudibus Legum Angliae, edited and translated by Stanley Chrimes (Cambridge, 1942), 37. 23.
24. Reniger 25.
The
v.
Fogossa in Commentaries ,
three cases are Wrotesley
in Commentaries 1:485; Wrotesley 26.
v.
custom
Adams,
in
in
in
Commentaries
Commentaries
of the
common
W. Leonard,
and penal
unreasonableness
is
Wray Justice was
laws.”
A
customs are reported
as
1:195.
law.
and Cases of Law (London, law shall be taken strictly, con-
typical instance of a
found in Stebbs and Goodlacks
that the
The Case of Mines,
Reports
1686), 3:526. Also see ibid., 4:846: “for three things in ditions, customs,
1:195;
in their treatment of equity decrees as well as in
in derogation
The Lord Cromwell's Case,
27.
1:9.
Adams,
This attitude was manifested
their treatment of
v.
custom was against
custom being rejected
Case, ibid., 1:92:
common
reason, and so void.”
Ratcliff's Case, 2:332 (32 Eliz.);
official
29.
and Jeroms
law had not yet
source of law, even
cases they decided
More
having been rejected for lack of reasonableness in Leonard’s
such cases are Leigh and Oakley and Christmass Case,
The common
for
“And the opinion of
Reports than in other reports of sixteenth- and seventeenth-century cases.
28.
B.
if
ibid., 1:286 (32 Eliz.);
Among
Devered and
Case, 4:787 (30 Eliz.).
come
to recognize judicial precedent as
an
medieval judges sometimes frankly admitted that the
made new law throughout
Lane's Case, Coke’s Reports 2:16b.
the land.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Primary Sources Aquinas, Saint Thomas. Opera Omnia. .
Summa
Aristotle.
Theologiae.
vols.
York, 1948-50.
London, 1964-76.
The Works ofAristotle Translated
London,
into English.
Edited by William D. Ross.
1913.
Summa Azonis.
Azo.
60
New
Lyon,
1533.
Bacon, Sir Francis. The Works of Francis Bacon. Edited by James Spedding et
al.
Lon-
don, 1874. Bellapertica, Petrus de. Lectura super primus et secunda parte
codicis.
Prostat Parrhisijs,
I
5 I 9Blackstone, William. Commentaries on the Laws of England. 4 vols. London, 1765-69.
and Laws of England. Oxford, 1771. Bracton. On the Laws and Customs of England. 4 vols. Edited by George E. Woodbine and Samuel E. Thorne. Cambridge, 1968-77. .
Tracts Chiefly Relating to the Antiquities
.
Britton. Translated
by
F.
M.
Nichols. Washington, 1901.
Brooke, Robert. La Graunde Abridgement London, 1586.
De
Cicero.
Cambridge, 1949. Cambridge, 1949.
Inventione.
.
Topica.
.
The
.
The Laws. Oxford, 1998.
Republic.
Cambridge, 1988.
Coke, Edward. The Compleat Copyholder. In Three Law .
Institutes
Tracts.
Abington, 1982.
of the Laws of England. Buffalo, 1986 (1787).
Cowell, John. The Interpreter. Cambridge, 1607.. Davies, John. The Works in Verse and Prose Including Hitherto Unpublished Manuscripts
of Sir John Davies. Edited by Alexander Grosart. Blackburn, 1876. Disscnsiones
Dominorum
Leipzig, 1834.
Dodderidge, John. The English Lawyer. London, .
Treatise on the King's Prerogative. Harl.
1631.
MS.
5220, British Library,
London.
Egerton, Thomas. The Egerton Papers. London, 1840. .
A
and Understanding of Statutes with Sir Thomas Edited by Samuel E. Thorne. San Marino, 1942.
Discourse upon the Exposicion
Egereton's Additions.
,
2 37
Bibliography
238
“Ellesmere’s Tracts.” In
.
Lord Chancellor
Law and
Politics in
Jacobean England: The Tracts of
by Louis A. Knafla. Cambridge, 1977
Ellestn ere, edited
Finch, Henry. Nomotechnia. London, 1613. .
Law, or a Discourse thereof London, 1627.
La Graunde Abridgement.
Fitzherbert, Anthony. Fleta. J
2 vols.
London,
1577.
Henry G. Richardson and George O.
Edited and translated by
Sayles.
London,
955*
Fortescue, John.
De Natura
Legis Naturae.
London,
1869.
The Governance of England. Edited by Charles Plummer. London, 1885. De Laudibus Legum Angliae. Edited and translated by Stanley B. Chrimes.
.
.
Cambridge, 1942. Friedberg, Emil, ed. Corpus Jims Canonici. Leipzig, 1879, 1881. Glanvill,
Rannulf de. The
Commonly
Laws and Customs of the Realm of England Edited by George D. G. Hall. Oxford, 1965.
Treatise on the
Called Glanvill.
Gerson, Jean. Oeuvres Completes. Edited by Palemon Glorieux.
Paris,
Gratian. Concordance of Discordant Canons. In Corpus Juris Canonici.
Emil Friedberg. Leipzig, Guy, John.
1960-70.
2 vols.
Edited by
1879, !88 i.
Replication of a Seijeant at the
Laws of England. In Christopher St German on
Chanceiy and Statute. London, 1985.
Haas, Elsa de, and George D. G. Hall, eds. Early Registers of Writs. London, 1970.
Hake, Edward.
Epieikeia:
A
Dialogue in Three Parts. Edited by D. E. C. Yale. London,
053-
“The Antiquity of the Laws of this
Hakewill, William.
by Thomas Hearne. Vol.
rious Discourses, edited
Hale, Matthew. The History of the
Common Law
2.
Island.” In
London,
A
Collection of Cu-
1771.
of England, Edited by C. Gray.
Chicago, 1971. Hargrave,
F. Collection
Hatton, Christopher. position thereof.
Hearne, Thomas,
of Tracts Relative
A A
Law
Collection of Curious Discourses Written by
de. Radulphi de
ham. Cambridge,
Henry I.
2 vols.
London,
the
Ex-
Eminent Antiquaries 1771.
Hengham's Summae. Edited by William H. Dun-
1932.
Leges Henrici Primi. Edited and translated by L.
Hostiensis.
and
1677.
upon Several Heads on our English Antiquities.
Hengham, Radulphi
of England. Dublin, 1787.
Treatise Concerning Statutes, or Acts of Parliament,
London,
ed.
to the
Summa Aurea.
J.
Downer. Oxford,
1972.
Lugduni, 1 556.
Irnerius. Questiones de luris Subtilitatibus. Berlin, 1894.
Summa
.
Codicis. Berlin,
1894.
Isidore of Seville. Etymologiae. Paris, 1983. Justinian. Code. In The Civil Law. Edited and translated x
93 2 .
.
by
S. P.
Scott. Cincinnati,
-
Corpus luris Institutes.
Civilis.
Dublin, 1973.
Translated by Joseph A. C. Thomas. Capetown, 1975.
The Digest ofJustinian. 4 vols. Edited by Theodor Mommsen and Paul Krueger; translated by Alan Watson. Philadelphia, 1985. .
Lambarde, W. Archeion:
or,
a Discourse Upon the High Courts ofJustice in England.
Edited by Charles H. Mcllwain and Paul Ward. Cambridge, Mass., 1957.
Bibliography
s Littleton,
Thomas.
Tenures. Edited
Parliament of 1610. Proceedings Foster.
New
239
by Eugene Wambaugh. Washington, 1903. Edited by Elzabeth Reed
in Pai~lia?nent 1610. 2 vols.
Haven, 1966.
Parliament of 1621. Commons Debates 1621. Edited by Wallace Notestein, Francis ,
and Hartley Simpson. 7
Relf,
Parliament of 1625. Debates
in the
vols.
New
Haven,
House of Commons
1935. in 1625.
Edited by Samuel R.
Gardiner. London, 1873.
Parliament of 1628. Commons Debates 1628. Edited by Robert Johnson, ,
Maija Cole, and William Bidwell. 6
vols.
New Haven,
Summa Codicis. Turin, 1962 (1536). Summa Institutionum. Augustae Taurinorum,
Mary
Keeler,
1977-83.
Placentinus. .
by C.
Plato. Statesman. Translated
Port, John. Notebook. Edited by
Quintilian. The
J.
1973.
Rowe. Warminster,
1995.
John H. Baker. London, 1986.
Minor Declamations Ascribed
Quinfflian. Edited
to
by Michael Winter-
bottom. Berlin, 1984. .
Institutio Oratoria.
Rastell, John.
An
Cambridge, Mass.,
1985.
Exposition of Certain Difficult Words
and Termes of the Lawes of This
Realme. London, 1592. Readings and Moots at the Inns of Court in the Fifteenth Century. \ols.
1
and
2.
London,
954, OS* 0 Rogerius, Constantinus. Tractatus de iuris interpretatione (1463). In Tractatus Universi J
-
luris, vol.
1.
Venice,
upon Fortescue.” In
Selden, John. “Notes
London, .
1615.
Sir J. Fonescue
,
De Laudibus Legum Anglie.
1672.
The Reverse or Back-face of the English Ja?ius. Translated by R. Westcott. Lon-
don, 1683. St.
German, Christopher, Ogg. Cambridge, .
loannia SeldiniAd Fletam Dissertatio. Translated by David
1925.
Doctor and Student. Edited by T.
F.
T. Plucknett and
J.
L. Barton.
London,
1974. .
A
Little Treatise
Concerning Writs of Subpoena. In Christopher
St.
German
on
Chancery and Statute edited by John Guy. London, 1985. ,
Statutes of the Realm. Vols. 1-6. Buffalo, 1993 (1810).
Suarez, Francisco.
De
Francisco Suarez.
Legibus
,
Ac Deo
Legislatore. In Selections from
Three Works of
Oxford, 1944.
Vacarius. The Liber Pauperum ofVacarius. Edited by Francis de Zulueta. I
London,
9 2 7-
Case Reports Brownlow, Richard, and John Goldesborough. Reports of Divers Choice Cases
London,
in
Law.
1675.
Clark and Finnelly’s Reports. London, 1847.
Coke, Edward. The Repoits of Sir Edward Coke Knt. In English ,
vols.
Dublin, 1792, 1793.
Dyer, James. Reports.
3
vols.
London, 1794.
,
in Thirteen Parts. 7
Bibliography
240 .
Repoits fro??/ the Lost Notebooks of Sir James Dye?: 2 vols. Edited
by John H.
London, 1994.
Baker.
The English
Edinburgh,
Repoits. Yols. 23, 48, 73-77, 79-87, 123, 124.
1932.
Hobart, Henry. The Repoits of that Learned Sir Henry Hobait Knight. London, 1641. Howell, Thomas, ed, A Co?nplete Collection of State Trials. Vols. 1-3. London, 1809.
Leonard, William. Repo?ts and Cases of Law. 4 vols. London, 1686. Plowden, Edward. The Co??mientaries or Repoits of Edmund Plowden.
2 vols.
,
London,
1816.
Les repoits des cases en
ley
Edward
cinque an du roy
le
Quart: communement appelle Long
Quinto. Abington, 1979 (1680).
Cou/t of King's Bench under Edward
Select Cases in the
I.
Selden Society Series. Lon-
don, 1936.
Vaughan, John. The Repoits and Arguments of That Learned Judge, Sir John Vaughan.
London,
1677.
Edward
Yearbooks of the Reign of King
Edw.
vol.
I;
21-22 Edw.
2,
Michaelmas Term, Yearbooks of Edward
Edw.
II; vol. 2,
II; vol. 9,
6 Edw.
Edw.
Edw.
8
1,
11-12
Ill; vol. 5,
vol. 4,
Edw.
Edw.
II; vol. 23, 12
vols.
II; vol.
II; vol. 11,
6-7 Edw.
II; vol. 15,
9 Edw.
Edw.
Edward
vol. 5,
I;
5
London, 1903-64. Vol. 1, 1-2 4, 3-4 Edw. II; vol. 6, 4 Edw.
Edw.
Edw.
II; vol. 16, 7
II; vol. 20,
II; vol.
II; vol. 12,
10
Edw.
Edw.
24, 12
5
Edw.
8
II; vol. 17,
II; vol. 25, 12
Series.
II; vol. 13,
II; vol. 21,
London,
14-15 Edw. Ill; vol.
Edw.
Edw. HI;
6, 15
Edw.
Edw.
Ill; vol. 14,
London,
London,
1931. 10
vol.
3,
10
Edw.
Edw.
II.
1910-13. Vols.
1883.
Ill; vol. 8, 16
Edw.
Ill; vol. 15,
Ill; vol. 12,
20 Edw.
Edw. 18-19
III.
Edw. IV; 49 Henry VI.
1933.
Yearbooks of Heniy VII.
London,
Yearbooks of Richard
Cambridge, Mass., 1975-96. 6 Rich.
II.
Edw.
Ill; vol. 11, 18
20 Edw.
London,
12-14 Edw. Ill; vol. 4, 14 Edw.
Ill; vol. 7, 16
Edw.
Ill; vol. 10, 17-18
Ill; vol. 13, 19
Yearbooks of Henry VI.
the Third. Rolls Series. 15 vols.
Ill; vol. 2, 12-13
Yearbooks ofEdwai'd IV.
Rich.
32~33^Edw.
20-21
II.
Edw.
Ill; vol. 9, 17
Edw.
5
II; vol. 19,
Yearbooks of the Reign of King
Vol.
I;
The Eyre of Kent. Seldon Society
II,
6-7 Edw.
30-31 Edw.
II; vol. 3, 3
6 Edw.
Edw.
Yearbooks of Edward 5, 7, 8,
Edw.
II; vol. 10,
II; vol. 14,
II; vol. 22, 11
3,
1,
33,
2-3
II; vol. 18,
vol.
34-35 Edw. I. Selden Society Series. 25
II.
4 Edw.
I;
London, 1863-79. Vol.
the First. 5 vols.
1679, 1979. Vol. 10. II; 7
Rich.
II;
8-10
II.
Secondary Sources W. Law Reporting in England, 1485-1585. London, 1973. Allen, Carleton. Law in the Making. 7th ed. Oxford, 1964. Arnold, Morris. “Statutes as Judgments: the Natural Law Theory of Parliamentary Activity in Medieval England.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 126 (1977): Abbott, L.
329.
Arnold, Morris,
et
al.
Thome. Chapel
On
the
Laws and Customs of England:
Hill, 1981.
Essays in
Honor of S.
E.
Bibliography
s
241
Avery, Margaret. “History of the Equitable Jurisdiction of the Chancery before 1460.” Bulletin of the Institute of Historical Research 42 (1969): 129.
“The
Baade, Hans.
Casus Omissus
Journal of International
A Pre-History of Statutory Analogy.” Syracuse
Law and Commerce
20 (1994): 45.
John Hamilton. “Coke’s Notebooks and the Sources of His Reports.” Cambridge Law Journal 1972A (1959).
Baker,
.
.
.
Common
“The
The Legal
An
Lawyers and the Chancery:
Profession
Introduction
and
the
Common Law. London,
the Fifteenth Century. 2 vols.
(1969).
1986.
London, 1990. Readings and Moots at the Inns of Court
Law
in
London, 1990.
“Law and
Review 56 (1940): 75. Barton, John L. “Roman
4
English Legal History. 3d ed.
to
Baker, John H., and Samuel E. Thorne, eds.
Barraclough, Geoffrey.
1616.” Irish Jurist
Legislation in Medieval England.”
in England.” In Ius
Romanum
Law
Quarterly
MediiAevi. Varese, 1971.
Pt. 5, 13a. .
“Equity
tems, edited .
in the
Medieval
Common
by R. A. Newman. Brussels,
1973.
“The Mystery of Bracton.” Journal of Legal History H.
Beale, Joseph
Berger, Raoul.
Theory?”
Bibliography
14 (1993):
1.
London, 1904-6. of Early English Law Books. Cambridge, Mass.,
Bateson, Mary. Borough Customs.
2 vols.
1926.
“Doctor Bonham’s Case: Statutory Construction or Constitutional University of Pennsylvania
Law Review
Berkowitz, David. John Selden's Formative Bland,
Law.” In Equity in the World's Legal Sys-
Desmond
S.
Years.
117 (1969): 521.
Washington, 1988.
“Learning Exercises and Readers
Lifteenth and Sixteenth Centuries.”
Law
at the
Inns of Chancery in the
Quarterly Review 95 (1979): 244.
Bolland, William. The Year Books. Cambridge, 1921 .
A Manual of Year Book Studies.
Cambridge,
192^.
Boudin, Louis. “Lord Coke and the American Doctrine of Judicial Review.”
Law Review 6 (1929): 233. “Roman Aequitas and English
New
York University Brice, Charles. (I
9 I 3) l6 :
Equity.” Georgetown
Law Journal
2
-
Brie, Siegfried. Die Lehre
vom
Gewohnheitsrecht. Breslau, 1899.
Brooks, Christopher, and Kevin Sharpe. “History, English Law, and the Renais-
and Present 72 (1976): 133. Brundage, James. Medieval Canon Law. London, sance.” Past
1995.
Buckland, William W., and Arnold D. McNair. Roman
Law and Common Law. Cam-
bridge, 1936.
Burgess, Glenn. The .
Politics
Absolute Monarchy
Burns, James H. “St.
of the Ancient Constitution. University Park, 1992.
and
the Stuart Constitution.
New
Haven, 1996.
German, Gerson Aquinas and Ulpian.”
History of Political
Thought 4 (1983): 443. Cahill, William. “Development by the Medieval Canonists of the Concept of Equity.,” Catholic
Lawyer
7 (1961).
Carlyle, Robert W., and Alexander the West. 6 vols.
J.
Carlyle.
Edinburgh, 1903-36.
A
History of Medieval Political Theory in
Bibliography
242
Cheyette, Frederick. “Custom, Case Law, and Medieval ‘Constitutionalism’:
Examination.”
Chrimes, Stanley
Re-
Quarterly 78 (1963).
Political Science
B. English Constitutional Ideas in the Fifteenth Century.
93 6 Christianson, Paul. I
A
Cambridge,
-
“Young John Selden and
the Ancient Constitution, ca.
1610-1618.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 128 (1984): 271.
“Royal and Parliamentary Voices on the Ancient Constitution.” In The Men-
.
World of the Jacobean Court edited by Linda Peck. Cambridge, 1991.
tal
,
.
Discourse on History, Law,
and Governance
in the Public
Career ofJohn Selden,
1610-1635. Toronto, 1996. Coquillette, Daniel. “Legal Ideology and Incorporation
Writers, 1523-1607.” Boston University .
.
The
61 (1981):
English Civilian 1.
The Civilian Writers of Doctors' Commons, London. Berlin, 1988. Francis Bacon. Stanford, 1992.
Corwin, Edward .
Law Review
I:
The Doctrine ofJudicial Review. Princeton, 1914. The Higher Law Background ofAmerican Constitutional Lqw. Ithaca, 1955 S.
Cross, Rupert. Statutory Interpretation. London, 1976.
Dawson, John.
1616.” Illinois .
.
“Coke and Ellesmere
P.
Law Review
The Oracles of the Law.
Attack on the Chancery in
Cambridge, Mass., i960.
Ann
Arbor, 1968.
Dictionary of National Biography. 66 vols.
Doe, Norman. Fundamental Authority “his
The
36 (1941): 127.
A History of Lay Judges.
Donahue, Charles,
Disinterred:
London,
in Late
1901.
Medieval English Law. Cambridge, 1990.
Commune, Canon Law, and
Common Law in
England.” Tu-
Law Review 66 (1992): 1751-52. Dunn, John. “The Identity of the History lane
of Ideas.” Philosophy 43 (1968): 85-116. Elton, Geoffrey R. The Tudor Constitution. 2d ed. Cambridge, 1982.
and Sources of the Common Law. London, 1949. John. The Divine Right of Kings. Cambridge, 1914.
Fifoot, Cecil. History Figgis,
Edward. The Judges of England. New York, 1966. Fox, Alistair, and John Guy. Reassessing the Henrician Age Foss,
New York,
1986.
Thomas. The History of Worthies of England. London, 1662. Gaudamet, J. “La doctrine des sources du droit dans le Decret de Gratien. Revue Fuller,
droit canonique
1
de
(1951).
Giuliani, Alessandro.
“The
Influence of Rhetoric on the
Law
of Evidence and Plead-
Review 7 (1962): 216. Goodhart, Arthur L. “Precedent in English and Continental Law.”
Law
Review 197 (1934): 40-42. Gough, John W. Fundamental
Oxford, 1955.
ing.” Juridical
Law
in English Constitutional History.
Quarterly
Gray, Charles. “Bonham’s Case Revisited.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society .
tory .
1
16 (1972): 35.
“The Boundaries of the Equitable 20 (1976):
Function.” American Jour~nal of Legal His-
192.
“Reason, Authority, and Imagination:
Coke.” In Culture and
Politics:
The Jurisprudence
From Puritanism
Perez Zagorin. Berkeley, 1980.
to the
of Sir Edward
Enlightenment, edited by
Bibliography
New York,
Gray, John Chapman. The Nature and the Sources of the Law.
Green, Robert A. “Synderesis, the Spark of Conscience Journal of the History of Ideas 52
Guy, John. The
1921.
in the English Renaissance.”
(1991): 195.
The Impact of Thomas Wolsey
Cardinal's Court:
243
$
in the
Star Chamber. To-
towa, 1977.
German
ed. Christopher St
,
Hanson, Donald. From Kingdom ness in English Political
Harding, Alan. The
Law
on Chancery and Statute.
London,
1985.
Commonwealth: The Development of Civic ConsciousThought. Cambridge, Mass., 1970. to
London,
Courts of Medieval England.
1973.
Haskins, George L. “Executive Justice and the Rule of Law.” Speculum 30 (1955): 53 2
Hassall,
William O.
A
Catalogue of the Library of Sir
Edward
Coke.
New Haven,
1950.
Hastings, Margaret. The Court of Common Pleas in Fifteenth- Century England. Ithaca, I
947-
Helmholz, R. H. Canon Law and
the
Law
Hill, Christopher. Century of Revolution,
of England. London, 1987.
1603-1714. Edinburgh, 1961.
Hinton, R. “English Constitutional Theories from Sir John Lortescue to Sir John Eliot ” English Historical Review 75 (i960): 410.
Holdsworth, William. “The Relation of the Equity Administered by the
Law Judges (1916): .
.
.
.
A
Common
Law Journal 26
to the Equity Administered by the Chancellor.” Yale
1.
History of English Law. 17 vols.
Sources
London, 1922-66.
and Literature of English Law. Oxford,
1925.
“Case Law.” Law Quarterly Review 50 (1934): 180. Some Makers of English Law. Cambridge, 1938.
Magna Cana. Cambridge, 1965. W. “The Purpose and Making of the Later Year
Holt, James C. Ives,
Eric
Books.”
Law
Quarterly Re-
view 89 (1973): 64. .
Jolliffe,
The Common Lawyers of Pre -Reformation England. Cambridge, 1977. John E. A. The Constitutional History of Medieval England. New York,
Jolowicz, Herbert
mano: Jones,
studi in
W. J. The
F.
“Roman Regulae and
memoria
di Paolo Koschaker. Vol.
1.
Maxims ”
Crisis of the Constitution.
Kantorowicz, Ernst. The King's Two Kantorowicz, Hermann. Studies
New
Brunswick, 1949.
Bodies. Princeton, 1966.
in the Glossators
of the
Roman Law. Cambridge,
1938.
Bractonian Problems. Glasgow, 1941.
tory in the French Renaissance.
Kern,
e il diritto ro-
Milan, 1954.
Kelley, Donald. Foundations of Modem Historical Scholarship:
.
In L'europa
Elizabethan Court of Chancery. Oxford, 1967.
Judson, Margaret. The
.
English
1961.
New York,
Language Law and His,
,
1970.
“History, English Law, and the Renaissance.” Past and Present 65 (1974): 24.
Fritz. Kingship
and Law
in the
Middle Ages. Translated by
S. B.
Chrimes. Ox-
ford, 1948.
Kiralfy, Albert.
“Custom
in
Medieval English Law.” Journal of Legal History 26
(1988).
Knafla, Louis A. Ellesmere.
Law and Politics
Cambridge,
1977.
in Jacobean
England: The Tracts of Lord Chancellor
2
Bibliography
44
Lange, Hermann. “Ius aequum und
ius strictum bei
den Glossatoren.”
Zeitschrift der
Savigny-Stifrung fur Rechtsgeschicbte 71 (1924): 319.
Levack, Brian. The Civil Lawyers in England 1603-1641. Oxford, 1973. ,
Lewis, Ewart. Medieval
Political Ideas. 2 vols.
“King above Law ‘Quod Principi
.
London,
1954.
Placuit’ in Bracton.” Speculum 39 (1964):
240.
Coke
Lewis, John Underwood. “Sir Edward
Reason’ as
His Theory of ‘Artificial
(1552-1633):
Context for Modern Basic Legal Theory.” Law Quarterly Review 84
a
(1968).
“The History of Judicial
Lewis, T. E. 207, 341;
47
Liebermann,
(1931): 411;
48
Precedent.”
3
vols. Halle, 1903.
MacKay, R. A. “Coke — Parliamentary Sovereignty or Michigan
MacLean,
Law Review
and Meaning
Maine, Henry. Ancient Law. London,
.
.
.
W.
the
Supremacy of the Law?”
22 (1923): 215.
Ian. Interpretation
Maitland, Frederic
Quarterly Review 46 (1930):
(1932): 230.
Die Gesetze der Angelsachen.
Felix.
Law
Cambridge, 1992.
in the Renaissance.
1917.
Select Passages from the
Works of Bracton andAzo. London, 1895.
The Forms ofAction at Common Law. Cambridge, 1909. The Constitutional History of England. Cambridge, 1926. The
Letters ofF.
W. Maitland. Edited by Cecil H.
Mcllwain, Charles H. The High Court of Parliament and
Fifoot.
S.
Its
London,
Supremacy.
1965.
New Haven,
1910. .
.
.
The Growth of Political Thought in the West. New York, 1932. Constitutionalism and the Changing World. New York, 1939. Constitutionalism: Ancient
and Modem.
Ithaca, 1940.
Milsom, Stroud Francis Charles. The Legal Framework of English Feualism. Cambridge, 1976. .
Historical Foundations of the
.
Studies in the History of the
Newman,
Common Law. 2d ed. London, Common Law. London, 1985.
1981.
Ralph. Equity in the World's Legal Systems. Brussels, 1973.
An
Roman Law. Oxford, Notestein, Wallace. The House of Commons 1604-1610. Nicholas, Barry.
Introduction
to
,
Oakley, Francis. “Jacobean Political Theology:
1979.
New Haven,
1971.
The Absolute and Ordinary Powers
of the King.” Journal of the History of Ideas 29 (1968): Ogilvie, Charles. The King’s Government and the
323.
Common Law 1471-1641 Oxford, ,
95 8 Pawlisch, Hans. Sir John Davies and the Conquest of Ireland. Cambridge, 1985. T
-
Plucknett,
Theodore
teenth Century. .
.
.
F.
T. Statutes and Their Interpretation in the First Half of the Four-
Cambridge,
1922.
“Bonham’s Case and Judicial Review.” Harvard Law Review 40 “Ellesmere on Statutes.” Law Quarterly Review 60 (1944): 242.
A
Concise History of the
Common Law.
5th ed. London, 1956.
.
Early English Legal Literature. Cambridge, 1958.
.
Legislation of Edward
.
“The
I.
(1926): 30.
Oxford, 1970.
Relations between
Roman Law and
English
Law down
to the Six-
Bibliography
A General
teenth Century:
245
Survey.” In Studies in English Legal History.
London,
1983.
Pocock, John Greville Agard. “The History of Inquiry.” In Philosophy Politics ,
Runciman. Oxford,
and
Society, edited
Thought:
A Methodological
by Peter Laslett and Walter G.
1962.
Language, and Time.
New York,
.
Politics,
.
The Machiavellian Moment. Princeton,
.
Virtue,
.
The Ancient Constitution and
1973. 1975.
Commerce, and History. Cambridge, 1985.
Pollard, Albert F. Wolsey.
Pollock, Frederick. .
Political
A
London,
First
Law. Cambridge, 1987.
the Feudal
1929.
Book ofJurisprudence 6th ed. London, 1929.
Jurisprudence and Legal Essays.
W.
Pollock, Frederick, and Frederic
London,
1961.
Maitland, The History of English
Time of Edward I. 2d ed. 2 vols. Cambridge, 1898. Post, Gaines. “A Romano- Canonical Maxim, Quod Omnes Tangit
Law
before the
in Bracton.” Traditio
(1946): 197.
4
.
Studies in Medieval Legal Thought: Public
Law and
the State,
1100-1322.
Princeton, 1964.
and Theologian on Kingship.” Proceedings of the Third International Congress of Medieval Canon Law (1968). .
Potts,
“Bracton
as Jurist
Timothy C.
Pound, Roscoe. .
Prest,
Cambridge, 1980.
Conscience in Medieval Philosophy.
“Common Law
and Legislation.” Harward Law Review
“The Maxims of Equity.” Harvard Law Review 34
Wildred R. The bins of Couit under Elizabeth
1
and
21 (1908): 383.
(1921): 833.
the Early Stuarts.
Totowa,
1972.
Radin, Max. “Early Statutory Interpretation in England.”
0943)
:
l6
Richardson,
Illinois
Law Review
38
-
Henry G.
“Azo, Drogheda, and Bracton.” English Historical Review 59
(1944): 22. .
“Studies in Bracton.” Traditio 6 (1948):
.
Bracton: The Problem of His Text.
61.
London,
Richardson, Henry G. and George O. Sayles,
1965.
“The Early
Statutes.”
Law
Quarterly
Review 50 (1934): 201-23, 540-71. Governance of Medieval England. Edinburgh, 1963. .
.
Law and Legislation from Aethelberht
Richardson, Walter C.
A
to
Magna
History of the Inns of Court.
Carta. Edinburgh, 1966.
Baton Rouge, 1978.
Rueger, Zofia. “Gerson’s Concept of Equity and Christopher Political
Thought
3
St.
German.”
History of
(1982).
Conrad. Parliaments and English
1621-1629. Oxford, 1979. Salmond, John W. Jurisprudence. 12th ed. Edited by P. J. Fitzgerald. London, 1966. Russell,
.
“The Theory of Judicial
Politics,
Precincts.”
Law
Quarterly Review 16 (1900): 376.
Savigny, Friedrich K. von. Geschichte des Romischen Rechts im Mittelalter. 6 vols.
Darmstadt, 1956. Sayles,
George O. The
King's Parliament of England.
Scrutton, E. The Influence of Roman
Law
on the
Law
London,
1975.
of England. Cambridge, 1985.
Bibliography
246
Stephen A. “The Aristotelian Basis of English Law.”
Siegel,
Review 56
Law
W.
B.
A
History of the
Land Law. 2d
ed.
Oxford, 1986.
Common Law. London, 1987. Common Law.” University of Miami Law Review
Legal Theory and Legal History: Essays on the
Singer, Barbara. 37
York University
(1981): 18.
Simpson, Alfred .
New
09 8 3)
:
“The Reason of the
797-
Skinner, Quentin.
“Meaning and Understanding
in the
History of Ideas.” History and
Theory 8 (1969): 3-53. .
3
“Motives, Intentions, and the Understanding of Texts.”
Literary History
393~4° 8 “Some Problems in the Analysis of Political Thought and Action.”
(*97 2 ) .
New
Theory
:
-
2 (1974):
277-303.
Sommerville, Johann
Spelman, John. The
Political
P. Politics
and
Reports. 2 vols.
Ideology in
England 1603-1640. London, 1986. ,
Edited byj. H. Baker. London, 1978.
Spence, George. The Equitable Jurisdiction of Chancery. Philadelphia, 1846-49. Stein, Peter. Regulae Iuris:
From Juristic
Rides
to
Legal Maxims. Edinburgh, 1966.
.
Roman Law and
.
“Vacarius and the Civil Law.” In Church and Government
English Jurisprudence Yesterday and Today. Cambridge, 1969. in the
Middle Ages,
edited by Christopher Brooke. Cambridge, 1978. .
“Logic and Experience
in
Roman and Common
Law.” Boston University
Law
Review 59 (1979): 433-35. .
The Character and Influence of the Roman Civil Law:
Historical Essays.
London,
1988.
Common Law and Liberal Theory. Lawrence, 1992. Stump, Eleanore. Boethius's De topicis differentiis. Ithaca, 1978. Thompson, Faith. Magna Carta: Its Role in the Making of the English Stoner, James.
Constitution,
1300-1629. Minneapolis, 1948.
Thorne, Samuel E. “The Equity of a Statute and Heyden’s Case.” 31 (1936): .
Illinois
Law Review
202.
“Dr. Bonham’s Case.”
Law
Quarterly Review 54 (1938): 543.
Tierney, Brian. “Bracton on Government.” Speculum 38 (1963): 295-309.
Cambridge, 1979. Philosophy and Government, 1 372-163 1 Cambridge,
Tuck, Richard. Natural Rights .
Theories.
Turner, Ralph V. The King and His Courts,
1
1993.
199-1240. Ithaca, 1968.
Age of Glanvill and Bracton. Cambridge, 1985. Ullmann, Walter. “Bartolus on Customary Law.” Juridical Review 52 (1940): 265. .
.
.
The English Judiciary
in the
The Medieval Idea of Law as Represented by Lucas de Penna. London, 1946. Principles of Government and Politics in the Middle Ages. London, 1961.
Law and Politics
Middle Ages. London, 1975. Van Caenegem, R. C. Royal Writs in England from the Conquest .
in the
to Glanvill.
London,
1959-
The Birth of the English Common Law. 2d ed. Cambridge, 1988. Vinogradofif, Paul. “Reason and Conscience in Sixteenth- Century Jurisprudence.” .
Law Quarterly Review 96 (1908): 373. Roman Law in Medieval Europe. Oxford, .
1929.
Bibliography Walker, David
M. The
Oxford Companion
to
2 47
Law. Oxford, 1980.
White, Stephen D. Sir Edward Coke and “ The Grievances of the Commonwealth 1621-1628. Chapel Hill, 1979.
W.
Whittaker, William J., and Frederic
Maitland. The Mirror ofJustices. London,
1893.
Wilkinson, Bertie. Constitutional History of England
in the Fifteenth
Century
,
1399-1485. London, 1964. Winfield, Percy H. Chief Sources of English Legal History. Cambridge, Mass., 1925.
Woolf, Cecil N.
S. Barrtolus
of Sassoferrato. Cambridge, 1913.
David E. C. Lord Nottingham's Manual of Chancery Chancery and Equity .’ Cambridge, 1965.
Yale,
.
“Hobbes and Hale on Law,
Journal .
(J
“St.
975)
:
3
and Prolegomena of ‘
Legislation, and the Sovereign.” Cambridge
Law
31 (1972).
Germans
Little Treatise
Concerning Writs of Subpoena." Irish Jurist 10
2 4-
Yntema, Hessel. “Equity of Comparative Zaller, Robert.
197L
Practice'
Law
in the Civil
Law and
the
Common
Law.” American Journal
15 (1967): 60.
The Parliament of 1621: A Study
in Constitutional Conflict. Berkeley,
INDEX
abridgement,
on
title
statutes,
223m
159-60;
15
common
right and reason,
159-60; natural law or equity, 159
(117)
advice of magnates, in Glanvill, aequitas, constituta
and
nidis,
Burns, James H., on
4-6
German and
St.
Aquinas, 22on. 59 (95)
89-90, 100
ancient constitution, Pocock on, 129-30 antiquity of
Coke
146-47; 143;
common
law: Burgess on,
Calvin's Case
on, 141-42; Digges on,
Ellesmere on, 143; Pocock on,
141;
Selden on, 144-47
Aquinas, on equity, 92
on
Aristotle:
knowledge
and English artificial
Azo,
170-71; logic, rhetoric,
9, 19,
20m.
reason,
on custom, 26-28, 1990. 12 (6); on equity, 91-92; influence on English
canonists:
maxims, 234m
1
(173)
case law and precedent: authority of
prior cases, 45; Bracton and, 17-20;
Coke on common law
common
162-67;
artificial
161-63
legal
law, 170-75
reason:
Coke on
jurisprudence, 48; as source of English
equity, 80-82, 95; lawyers’ of,
,
as,
erudition and, 50-51
case citation in Year Books, 42-44; in
Inns of Court disputations, 64-66;
on scant case
Littleton
32 (10)
citation, 56;
practice of distinguishing cases, 44;
Baade, Hans, on intent of makers, 223m
Bacon, Francis: on Coke’s approach to
23m. 67
23m. 59 others,
(163); criticism
(161);
228m
of custom,
English laws mixed with 13
Vaughan on,
182
literature on,
229m
in, 155-61;
influence on, 16; counsel and consent, law, 12-17; equity, 93;
unwritten law, 7-8; writs, Britton, king’s authority
82 civilian jurists:
on consent, 9-1 1; on cus-
141-42, 153-54,
law,
20
J 6i;
Bonham's Case
law,
,
155-61; Calvin's Case 161-63; case ,
authority, 182;
on
common
law:
—as
reason, 162-67, 2 3 2n 74 (166);
artificial
12
makes
202n. 51 (16); on interpretation, 88-91
Coke, Edward: antiquity of common
33 (154)
Bracton, 7-20: case law, 17-20; civilian
customary
Cicero: on equity, 94; on interpretation,
tom, 26-28; influence on Bracton,
(145)
Bonham's Case: Coke’s meaning
8-12;
on, 179-83;
chancellors, conscience, 103-9
18 (117)
law,
summary
-
— nature
of, 151-67;
—and
statute,
Bulgarus, dispute with Martinus, 88-90
154-61; custom, 132, 152-54; equity of
Burgess, Glenn: on Bonham's Case
statute,
,
224m
27 (123);
maxims, 174-75;
250
Index
§
Coke, Edward ( continued
on natural custom,
223m
tion,
on prescription and
law, 159;
153;
Digges, Dudley, 143
on statutory interpreta(1 17);
17
study of logic,
common
erudition: cited in Inns of
Court
Readings, 65; and maxims and princi-
66-67; i n Year Books, 50, 2ion.
common
law: altered
Coke
183-86;
by
8 (4); differing
Doe, Norman: on Fortescue, 212m
on
1
8 6-95, 198ml.
medieval ideas
Egerton, Francis. See Ellesmere Ellesmere, Lord:
144-47; and reason,
227m 6
162-72; St.
German
148-50,
132,
on, 78-80;
wisdom
law mind:
as
immemorial cus-
tom, 129-30; Pocock on, 129-30
law, 143; biographical
com-
summary,
on equity
(143); Discourse , 121;
88-91; and conscience, 93-109; and interpretation, 87-93, 80;
consent, and customary law, 8-12
83
Corpus Juris. See Justinian 155
custom: antiquity
of, 141; Bracton
(123);
law, 12-17; civilian
Coke
26-28;
Plowden on,
equity of
Corwin, Edward,
on,
132,
and cus-
152-54; and
law, 1-3, 6-17, 77, 129-33,
fictions, legal,
225m 6
memorial,
on prerogative,
75-78; in St.
129-30, 141-47, Littleton on, (74);
224m
27
5;
and
and reason,
German, 74-78; and
(131)
Finch, Henry: biographical summary,
mon
maxims, 2i6n. 6
on,
century cases, 121-28
on, 131-32; Fortescue on, 54-55; im-
12 (25);
Coke
medieval view, 40-42; in 16th-
reason, 168-69;
25,
Plato on,
121-23; Quintilian on,
a statute:
98nn. 4 (2) & 8 (4); common law idea of customary law, 26; Davies
1,
n 6-28;
treatment
x
204~5n.
antiquity of
and interpretation, 125-26
conscience, 96-99, 101-7
common
on
equity: x\ristotle on, 80-82; civilians on,
of, 79, 132
186-95,
on
4
mon
of,
2 (53);
judicial consent, 2ion. 103 (46);
hardship, 30; and legal change, 29-31,
tomary
136
8 (182)
about, 52; Fortescue on, 53-55; and
common
on powers of king,
75~78;
Dyer, James, on authority of cases, 235m
statute, 29-31,
on, 151-67; as custom,
1-3, 6-17, 77, 129-33,
&
i
mischiefs, 215m 65 (69)
101 (46)
(2)
mary, 232m 77 (167), 233m 84 (169); on logic and common lawyers, 171-72;
maxims, grounds, and reason, 166-71,
170-71
ples,
Dodderidge, John: biographical sum-
232~33n. 80 (168);
on custom and com-
on law of reason,
law, 152-53;
Fleta law ,
on common law and
158;
138
dependent on king’s
will,
20
Fortescue, Sir John: on Aristotelian idea
of principles and
common
law maxims,
statute in civil law, 205~6n. 26 (28);
173-74; biographical summary, 212m
summary
(53);
on, 186-95; i n Year Books,
24-32
Davies, Sir John: biographical summary,
225m 4
(130);
custom,
— and views
on common
131-32;
reason, of,
law:
—as
on
common
law as custom, 54;
on consent, 54; on customary law, 54-55; on equity, 93-95, 22on. 55 (93); Mcllwain on, 54; on statutory law, 55
—prerogative, 133-40;
132;
—two
contrasting
139-40; customary law, praise
of, 131-32, 22$n. 8 (132)
1
Gerson, Jean, on equity, Glanvill: advice of
tomary
93, 95
magnates, 4-6; cus-
law, 7; enacted law, 6; leges et
Index consuetudines, 4, 6; reliance
on unwritten
law, 5, 6;
Gratian: on custom, equity, 91-92
on Roman
199m
12 (6);
law of nature: canon law influence re-
De Natura,
on
75-76; in
Coke and
German, 72-73
St.
Leges Henrici Primi: and
artificial
reason, 165
custom and
usage, 3-4; legislation,
grounds. See maxims
Littleton, Sir
and
Hake, Edward, Epieikeia 127 ,
Hakewill, William, on antiquity of com13
3;
in
medieval Year Books, 32-35
by,
2i9~2on. 50 (93)
228m
3
and Leges Henrici Primi,
legislation:
Guy, John, misreading of Aquinas
law,
on, 159; Fortescue’s
and law of reason, 72-73,
53;
'
Gray, Charles, on
mon
Coke
garding, 48;
law, 6, 7
251
§
Thomas: on common law few cases
statute, 57-58;
cited, 56;
on inconvenience, 58-59; jurisprudence in Tenures, 56; law and usage, 57; on reason, 59-61; Tenures, 56-61
(145)
Hale, Sir Matthew, on case authority, 182
hardship and statutes, 2o8n. 61
Hatton, Christopher, Statutes,
in
,
125,
Treatise Concerning
223m
Hedley, Thomas, on
Mcllwain, C. H.: on
(37)
17 (117)
common
law, cus-
tom, and reason, 149-51, 166-67
Hobart, Sir Henry (chief justice), on nat-
damental
argument, 202m 47 (14) Martinus, dispute with Bulgarus, 88-90
16th-century cases,
on, 174-75;
erudition, 66-67; D°cl-
interpretation of law: Cicero on, 82; and
214m
53 (66); as legal authori-
66; and positive law, 67-68;
ties,
Rastell on,
234m
171—78; Serjeant
Egerton’s Discourse on the Exposicion,
in and
Coke
interchangeable term with principle and ground,
117-28
;
common
178;
on, 173-74; and general customs, 74; as
intent of makers of statutes: Baade on, 18 (117); in
of bootstrapping
deridge on, 166-71; 175-78; Fortescue
Readings and Moots
223m
155,
1,
as court, 156-57; use
and Inns of Court learning exercises. See
law as fun-
2o6n. 34 (30); on Fortescue, 11m. 6 (54); on parliament law,
maxims: Bacon on,
ural equity, 158-59
common
equity, 87-93; an