198 94 14MB
English Pages 280 [273] Year 2018
TELLING THE TRUTH
TELLING THE TRUTH
The Theory and Practice of Documentary Fiction Barbara Foley
Cornell University Press
Ithaca and London
Open access edition funded by the National Endowment for the Humanities/ Andrew W. Mellon Foundation Humanities Open Book Program. Cornell University Press gratefully acknowledges a grant from the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation that aided in bringing this book to publication. Copyright © 1986 by Cornell University All rights reserved. Except for brief quotations in a review, this book, or parts thereof, must not be reproduced in any form without permission in writing from the publisher. For information, address Cornell University Press, Sage House, 512 East State Street, Ithaca, New York 14850, or visit our website at cornellpress.cornell.edu. First published 1986 by Cornell University Press Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Foley, Barbara, 1958– Telling the truth. Includes index. 1. American fiction—20th century—History and criticism. 2. Nonfiction novel. 3. Marxist criticism. 4. Historical fiction, American. I. Title. PS374.N6F58 1986 813'.081'09 85-48198 ISBN-13: 978-0-8014-1877-8 (cloth) — ISBN-13: 978-1-5017-2288-2 (pbk.) The text of this book is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/
To Houston, Adam, and Margaret
Contents
Preface
9
PART I: THEORY 1. The D o cumentary Novel and the Problem of Borders 2. The Mimetic Contract and the Problem of Assertion 3. Mimesis, Cognition, and the Problem of the Referent 4. Mimesis, Cognition, and the Problem of the S ubject
PART II: PRACTICE 5. The Pseudofactual Novel
107
6. The Historical Novel
143
7. The Modernist D o cumentary Novel 8.
185
The Afro-American D ocumentary Novel
233
Conclusion Index
7
Preface
There is a regime language that derives its strength from what we are supposed to be and a language of freedom whose power consists in what we threaten to become. And I'm justified in giving a political character to the nonfictive and fictive uses of language because there is a conflict between them.... I could claim that history is a kind of fiction in which we live and hope to survive, and fiction is a kind of speculative history, per haps a superhistory, by which the available data for the composition is seen to be greater and more various in its sources than the historian sup poses .... There is no fiction or nonfiction as we commonly understand the dis tinction: there is only narrative.... We [novelists) have it in us to compose false documents more valid, more real, more truthful than the "true" documents of the politicians or the journalists or the psychologists. Novelists know explicitly that the world in which we live is still to be formed and that reality is amenable to any construction that is placed upon it. It is a world made for liars and we are born liars. -E. L. Doctorow
If contemporary literary theory has anything of value to teach us, it is that all texts inevitably situate themselves with reference to other texts . The present text bears a polemical relation to its context. When I argue that the documentary novel engages in dramatically different representational practices in different eras, but constitutes, nonetheless, a distinct species of fiction and moreover renders cogni tion of its referent, I am not simply describing a literary genre; I am taking a position within central literary debates of our time. In E. L. Doctorow's words I find three propositions that point to 9
Preface important issues in these debates. 1 First, Doctorow says that the b or derline b etween fictional and nonfictional narrative can and should be abolished: " There is no fiction or nonfiction . . . : there is only narra tive. " Fiction is a kind of history, history a kind of fiction; they differ only in the kinds of human potentiality that they portray. S econd, however, Doctorow argues that fiction is " more valid, more real, more truthful" than nonfiction because, as a "false document, " the fictional work openly admits that " reality is amenable to any con struction that is placed upon it. " Curiously, then, fiction is both iden tical with and superior to nonfiction; I shall comment below on the logical problem involved here. Third, Doctorow attaches an urgent political agenda to hils distinction between fiction and nonfiction. The former, associated with a "regime language, " is disciplinary; the lat ter, associated with a "language of freedom, " is liberatory. Presuma bly, then, narrative eradicates the borderline between the two by an admission of the fictionality of reality . This is an emancipatory act, for it asserts the superior explanatory power of "lies" over " facts." Doctorow's comments illuminate his own novelistic practice, to be sure, but they signify much more than a theory of discourse applica ble simply to his own work. Doctorow's remarks set forth the main premises that guide, I believe, a good deal of contemporary writing and theorizing about writing. This book largely grows out of my re sponse to these premises . Let me address first the notion that the borderline between nonfic tional and fictive discourse is an arbitrary boundary, setting up a false discrimination between fact and imagination, when the truth is that "reality is amenable to any construction that is placed upon it. " This is Doctorow's way of expressing an idea that has become highly in fluential and popular among both literary theorists and novelists namely, that reality is itself a fiction, a text, a linguistic convention. Thus Mas'ud Zavarzadeh, setting forth his poetics of the nonfiction novel, argues that the " 'fictuality' of current experience escapes the monoreferential narratives which require an unequivocal pledge to fact or fiction . . . . [The nonfiction novel] is a narrative which is si multaneously self-referential and out-referential, factual and fictional, and thus well equipped to deal with the elusive fusion of fact and fie'E. L. Doctorow, " False Documents, " American Review, 26 (November 1 977): 2 1 7 , 229 - 3 0, 23 l , 232. IO
Preface tion which has become the matrix of today's experience. "2 Robert Scholes declares that "it is because reality cannot be recorded that re alism is dead. All writing, all composition, is construction. We do not imitate the world, we construct versions of it. There is no mime sis, only poesis. No recording. Only constructing. "3 Raymond Feder man holds that "suRFICTION is the only fiction that still means some thing today, . . . because it exposes the fictionality of reality. "4 Jerome Klinkowitz, in his recent The Self-Apparent Word, argues that only writing that he calls "self-apparent" can be an antidote to the "mi metic poison" of inherited fictional modes . "To practice writing is not to parody signifying, it is to destroy the very practice of signi fying itself, " he declares. And the superiority of self-apparent writ ing derives from its superior epistemology. "We know reality only through our fictions, " he concludes . "Reminding readers that fictions are provisional realities and not bedrock truth is the essence of self apparent writing. "5 Many contemporary writers of fiction and j ournalism add their voices to the chorus, pro claiming the unreality of reality and the un decidability of discourse. Norman Mailer, in The Armies of the Night, writes that history inhabits a "crazy-house" and that the "mystery of the events at the Pentagon, " even when reconstructed by means of newspaper reports and eyewitness accounts, can be only a " collective novel. "6 Philip Roth declares that American reality "stupefies, . . . sickens , . . . infuriates , and finally . . . is even a kind of embarrass ment to one's own meager imagination. [It] is continually outdoing our talents, and the culture tosses up figures almost daily that are the envy of any novelist. "7 Ronald Sukenick, whose polemical state ments sometimes verge on self-parody, exclaims, "Reality doesn't exist, time doesn't exist, personality doesn't exist . . . . In view of 2Mas'ud Zavarzadeh, The Mythopoeic Reality: The Postwar American Nonfiction Novel (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1 9 76) , 5 6- 57. 'Robert Scholes, Structural Fabulation: An Essay on the Fiction of the Future (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1 975), 7. 'Raymond Federman, S URFIC TION: Fiction Now . . . and Tomorrow (Chicago: Swal low, 1 975), 7. 5Jerome Klinkowitz, The Self Apparent Word: Fiction as Language/Language as Fiction (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1 984) , 40, 59, 1 3 5 · 6Norman Mailer, The Armies of the Nig ht: History as a Novel, the Novel as Histo ry (New York: New American Library, 19 68), 284. 7Philip Roth, "Writing American Fiction, " Commentary, 3 1 (March 1 9 6 1 ) : 224. II
Preface these annihilations, it will be no surprise that literature, also, does not exist- how could it?"8 " There is, " he concludes elsewhere, "no such thing as fiction. Instead there is a continuing fictive discourse which continually redefines itself. "9 These writers and theorists differ, of course, in their diagnoses of the reasons for this ontological collapse. Some, taking an apocalyptic view of the post- World War II era, argue that the fictionality of real ity is a product of recent historical developments . Thus Zavarzadeh proposes that the "bizarre" and " fictual" nature of contemporary real ity is a result of " runaway contemporary technologies . "10 John Hollowell suggests that the apocalyptic mood of the sixties, with the political protests, televised assassinations, and hippie counterculture, resulted in a "blur . . . of the comfortable distinctions between reality and unreality, fantasy and fact. "11 John Hellmann states that, in the sixties, "long-buried forces in the American psyche were coming to the surface with an almost eerie simultaneity in politics, in national and individual violence, in subcultures, in urban slums , in technol ogy, in the young . " Because of the "added force" of " mass-media journalism, " the individual American "found himself daily con fronted by realities that were as actual as they seemed fictive. "12 Other writers and critics suggest that the experience of the Holo caust has permanently dislocated both reality and our consciousness of reality. Lawrence Langer, for example, states, "The existence of D achau and Auschwitz as historical phenomena has altered not only our conception of reality, but its very nature. "13 Edward Alexander notes, "The nature and magnitude of the Holocaust were such as to mark almost certainly the end of one era of consciousness and the be8Ronald Sukenick, "Fiction in the Seventies: Ten Digressions on Ten Digressions, " Stud ies in American Fiction, 5 (Spring 1 977) : 107- 8 . 9Quoted from a tape recording b y Jerome Klinkowitz, i n The Life of Fiction (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1 977) , 1 8 . 10Zavarzadeh, 2 r . 11John Hollowell, Fact and Fiction: The New Journalism and the Nonfiction Novel (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1 977) , 5 . 12John Hellmann, Fables of Fact: The Newjournalism as New Fiction (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1 9 8 1 ) , 2. BLawrence Langer, The Holocaust and the Literary Imagination (New Haven: Yale Uni versity Press, 1975), xii. See also Alfred Alvarez, "The Literature of the Holocaust, " Com mentary, 5 (November 1 964) : 6 5 - 69, and Alvin Rosenfeld, " The Problematics of Holo caust Literature, " in Con.fronting the Holocaust: The Impact of Elie Wiesel, ed. Rosenfeld and Irving Greenburg (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1 978), l- 30. 12
Preface ginning of another. . . . The human imagination after Auschwitz is simply not the same as it was before. "14 I should point out, of course, that contemporary writers and liter ary theorists do not always say that inherited distinctions between fic tion and nonfiction need to be collapsed because of some especially horrific quality attaching to the reality of the postwar era. More pro grammatic advocates of the reality-as-fiction thesis would declare that what we commonly accept as reality has in fact always been a construct. Jacques Derrida, I am sure, would chide Scholes for his naively logocentric belief that reality could ever be recorded, advo cating that the critic instead " affirm . . . a world of signs" that " deter mines the non-center otherwise than as the loss of the center. "15 The binary opposition fiction/nonfiction, Derrida reminds us, is part of a "hierarchical axiology" that has perpetuated the repressive dualisms ofWestern metaphysics for centuries .16 Michel Foucault insists that all explanatory paradigms are essentially fictional. Referring to his own work on the history of sexuality, he notes, "I am well aware that I have never written anything but fictions . . . . One 'fictions' history on the basis of a political reality that makes it true, one 'fictions' a politics not yet in existence on the basis of a historical truth. "17 Lennard J. Davis, using Foucault's methodology in his recent explo ration of the origins of the English novel, concludes that "novels are framed works . . . whose attitude toward fact and fiction is constitu tively ambivalent. " Throughout its history, Davis maintains , the novel "is a factual fiction that is both factual and factitious. "18 Where the apocalyptic critics endorse a kind of peculiar reflectionism-a dis torted reality produces a distorted discourse- the poststructuralist critics argue that the crisis in reference is an abiding feature of dis course itself. Both schools of critics agree, however, in their convic14Edward Alexander, The Resonance of Dust: Essays on Holocaust Literature (Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1 979 ) , 1 - 2 . 1 5 cques Derrida, "Structure, Sign, and Play, " i n The Languages of Criticism and the Sci ences of Man, ed. Richard Macksey and Eugenio Donato (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Uni versity Press, 1 972) , 264. '6.Jacques Derrida, " Limited Inc abc, " in Glyph: johns Hopkins Textual Studies 2 (Balti more: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1 9 77) , 236. 1'Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, r972-77, ed. Colin Gordon, trans. Gordon, Leo Marshall, John Mepham, and Kate Saper (New York: Pantheon, 1980) , 1 9 3 · 18Lennard J. Davis, Factual Fictions: The Origins ofthe English Novel (New York: Colum bia University Press, 1983 ) , 2 1 2 .
IJ
Preface tion that referentiality is dead-if it ever was alive- and that the task of writers and critics is to get on with the business of living in, and talking about, a fictional world. I encountered various versions of these polemics when I was fresh from writing a (largely nee-Aristotelian) dissertation on John Dos Passos's U. S . A. trilogy, and they struck me as provocative but also profoundly unsatisfactory. On the one hand, such pronouncements gave the final drubbing to the myths of empiricist and positivist ob j ectivism. These straw men, of course, have been dead for some time, but a few more licks can never do any harm. As I surveyed the works of Dos Passos's descendants , I could readily see that contem porary writers interested in the relation between fact and fiction were even more disturbed by the bizarre opacity of social reality than were Dos Passos and his modernist contemporaries. On the other hand, I also became convinced that, despite their bold proclamations about the dissolution of boundaries, contemporary novelists and j ournalists were continuing in their own works to invoke discursive contracts that were decidedly fictional or nonfictional. As Christine Brooke Rose laconically notes, "the very statement that the ontological fact is itself without significance is a signifying statement, imposing a view of reality as non-significant, imposing, that is, the significance of non-significance. "19 D octorow, for all his free play with the felt verifiability of the "facts " included in Ragtime- did Freud and Jung go through the Tunnel of Love together when they visited Coney Island?- treats his major characters and maj or actions as fictive con structs. As in more traditional historical novels, data drawn from pre sumably extratextual sources enter the text primarily to corroborate the text's thematic design and are incorporated into a fictive totality. Mailer, by contrast, proj ects throughout The Armies of the Night a third-person autobiographical presence remarkably similar to that created by Henry Adams in his Education. When, in part 2 of Armies, Mailer switches gears to give a novelistic account of events he did not witness , he tells us in no uncertain terms that he is doing so . Turning to what I could learn about the responses of other readers to contem p orary works of j ournalism and fiction, I found my own reactions provisionally confirmed. None of the reviewers of Ragtime com19Christine Brooke-Rose, A Rhetoric of the Unreal: Studies in Narrative and Structure, Espe cially of the Fantastic (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1 9 8 1 ) , 4.
Preface plained that Doctorow had distorted the historical record; they may have quarreled with him on various scores, but they appear to have acceded to his play with facts on the grounds that he was simply writ ing a novel. By contrast, many readers of works such as In Cold Blood, The Executioner's Song, and Roots have stated that the credibil ity of the narrative collapsed for them when they discovered that cer tain details had been invented or significantly changed to enhance the thematic patterning of the text. 20 Clearly these readers did not feel that the writers' disregard for information existing in the historical record represented support for the proposition that contemporary re ality is weird and unknowable; they simply felt that they had been de ceived. I found, in other words, that even in works asserting the " sig nificance of non-significance, " the idea that history is a fiction has been asserted in conventionally novelistic, j ournalistic, and autobio graphical ways . As I pondered these questions, I became less interested in contem porary documentary writers themselves -whose solipsism I found irritating and barren-and more interested in the literary generally historical and theoretical questions that their writings raised. Was Doctorow correct in his assertion that the novel has always pretended to be a false document? If l was correct in my feeling that fictional and nonfictional discourse are qualitatively distinguished in our time, could I assume that this has always been the case? To answer these questions, I embarked upon an examination of the shifting borderline between fiction and its counterparts in historical, j ournalistic, bio graphical, and autobiographical writing. I discovered - and here is one of the central problems explored in this book- that literary kinds are constitutively historical to a degree that, in my Chicago 2{)For an attack on Alex Haley's veracity in Roots: The Saga of an American Family, see Mark Ottoway, "Tangled Roots, " Times (London) , April IO, 1 977, pp. 17, 2 r . Phillip K. Tompkins questions Capote's claim to have invented none of his materials in " In Cold Fact, " reprinted in Irving Malin, ed. , Truman Capote's "In Cold Blood": A Casebook (Bel mont, Calif. : Wadsworth, 1 968), 4 5 - 59. John Hersey attacks both Tom Wolfe's The Right Stuff and Mailer's The Executioner's Song for specious claims to be telling the truth, in "The Legend on the License, " Yale Review, 70 (Autumn 1 980) : l - 2 5 . Mailer's veracity in Armies is more difficult to assess. Alfred Kazin asserts that Mailer's account of the Pentagon march has been "scornfully rej ected by those who marched with him, " but Dwight MacDonald, who marched with Mailer, maintains that he and Robert Lowell cannot dispute Mailer's ac curacy. See Kazin, "The Imagination of Fact, " in Bright Book of Life: American Novelists and Sto rytellers .from Hemingway to Mailer (Boston: Little, Brown, 1973 ) , 228, and Macdonald, "Politics , " Esquire, May 1 968, 44. I5
Preface
School naivete, I had never imagined. Authors signaled fictional in tentions by widely varying conventions; if mimesis had any continu ous essence, this seemed to consist simply in its being a contractual agreement to understand reality by means of certain analogizing pro cedures. Even the documentary novel, which I had originally sup posed to practice a more or less constant strategy of testimonial cor roboration, turned out to alter dramatically its modes of empirical authentication as it moved from the eighteenth century to the twenti.:. eth. Writers maintained at all times, I could see, some kind of border line between fictional discourse and its various counterparts -be tween analogizing and directly propositional assertion - but this borderline was in no way fixed or permanent. The current debates about factual and fictive discourse turned me in the direction of literary history, but they also motivated me to reformulate some of my ideas about mimesis as a mode of cognition. I became increasingly disquieted by the realization that, in proclaim ing the fictiveness of all reality and all textuality, what seemed to ap peal to writers and theorists about fiction was its presumed reluctance to make assertions about the historical world. The "power of free dom, " it appeared, consisted in fiction's release from any obligation to offer determinate statements about reality . The "power of the re gime, " of determinate reference, was the province of the bad guys . This struck me as a peculiarly backhanded compliment: fiction's claim to privileged status was said to reside in its impotence. The antiassertionist view of mimesis contradicted my own experience: I had learned a tremendous amount from fictional works, not only about how novelists construed their reality, but also (do I dare to say it?) about the reality itself. Certainly Dos Passos had introduced me to a view of American history in the first three decades of the century that I had yet to relinquish, though it might be supplemented or corrected. And yet these new pronouncements cautioned me, and rightly so, about the necessarily ideological encoding of that knowl edge- especially, indeed, when it purported to buttress itself with unmediated extratextual documentation. Perhaps my hero Dos Passos, with his newsreels and biographies, was a villain after all, bent upon epistemological deceit and political obfuscation. Accordingly-here is the second of the principal theses explored in this book- I decided to examine the constitutive features of the mi metic contract and the distinctive qualities of the mimetic mode of r6
Preface cognition. If the referent of the mimetic text was not an inert and self evident set of facts, what was it? If authorial perspective did not en tirely close off cognition of the referent, how did it determine the conditions of knowledge? By what procedure, in other words, did the concrete particulars of character and event represented in a novel mediate and reconcretize actual people, occurrences, and situations? In seeking a way to answer these questions, I found that, once again, the genre of the documentary novel would furnish a useful test case. For, through its various postures of inviolable reliability, the docu mentary novel was especially vulnerable to the charge of ideological distortion and, indeed, fiction-making, in the negative sense of the word. I was not interested in updating Sidney's Defe nce to cover the cases of Lost in the Funhouse or Tell Me a Riddle, though clearly my ar gument would encompass these texts as well. Rather, I wished to de scribe the cognitive powers and limitations of such texts as Behn' s Oroonoko, Defoe's Moll Flanders, Cooper's The Spy, Eliot's Romola, Isherwood's Goodbye to Berlin, Woolf's Orlando, Dos Passos's U. S. A. , and even- resist a s its author might-R ag time . Advocates of fictional assertion are in a peculiar situation these days. If they wish to demonstrate that fictional texts convey knowledge about historical actuality, they are constrained to show that the writer's adducement of a testimonial apparatus does not pose too formidable a barrier to the proj ection of cognition. The literary-historical and theoretical aspects of the problem I was addressing piqued my curiosity, but its political implications invested it with a particular urgency for me. Doctorow is not alone in saying that the eradication of borders constitutes a radical praxis. The whole poststructuralist project of displacing, rupturing, subverting, and overturning the dualisms of Western metaphysics is characterized by a similar panache. Domination consists in the imposition of homoge neity, determinacy, and boundaries; liberation consists in heterogene ity, indeterminacy, and dispersal. My own political commitments - which were distinctly Marxist- made me wary of such pro nouncements, particularly when they adopted a radical posture, claiming to pose a greater threat to bourgeois hegemony than any revolutionary praxis locked into a logocentric paradigm. No doubt the attack on the binary opposition fiction/nonfiction is intended to help us break free from those fetishized conceptions of reality that le gitimate and rationalize the status quo. But it seems to me that the 17
Preface
poststructuralist proj ect deepens the writer's implication .in the reifi cation of advanced monopoly capitalism, insofar as the fetishization of textuality mediates the extreme abstraction of a society in which all human functions are rendered equivalent by the universal market. The authorial subj ect had been banished from the domain of politi cized literary studies; he or she demanded reentry. I felt that a defense of documentary mimesis as assertive discourse, continuous with other kinds of writing in its claim to cognition but distinct and differ ent in its mode of cognition, would help to reorient Marxist literary studies in some hdpful ways. To approach the question of the documentary novel from a Marx ist perspective has p roved no mean challenge, however. It is no longer possible- and in any event was never correct- to argue that the documentary novel replicates a self-evident reality with greater or lesser degrees of historical accuracy, which it is then the task of the critic to assess and evaluate. The reflectionist model of mimesis inher ited from the later Lukacs cannot accurately describe the mode of cognition embodied in the documentary novel, for it leaves insuffi cient theoretical space for a consideration of the extent to which the reality represented in the text is a construction of consciousness . Yet it is a highly questionable practice to argue, as do critics in the Al thusserian school, that mimesis is primarily a signifying gesture, re vealing a good deal about the ideologies that it exposes but nothing determinate about the reality to which the text " alludes. " My indebt edness to these different tendencies in Marxist criticism is present throughout this book, but so also is my uneasiness with their theoret ical premises . In outlining, then, a Marxist approach to the problem of documentary representation - the third, and synthesizing, concern of this study- I have kept a critical distance from most Marxist liter ary theory, preferring instead to turn to the pages of Marx and Lenin for a politics and an epistemology with which to reexamine the knotty problems of representation and mediation. The inadequacy of existing paradigms in Marxist literary theory is further evinced by these paradigms' inability to account for the kinds of mimetic contracts proffered by writers who are, in any era, ex cluded from participation in certain mainstream ideological assump tions - such as black American writers. The reflectionist model can not account for the tensions accompanying black writers' acts of IB
Preface fictional communication, because it presumes too ready an assimila tion of the subj ect to dominant epistemological paradigms. The Althusserian model succeeds no better at this task, however, because it too glibly asserts that texts distance themselves from the ideological viewpoints that they express . My inclusion of a closing chapter on the uses of documentation in Afro-American fiction thus constitutes an attempt to redress several literary-historical and theoretical imbal ances . In the first place, a scrutiny of Afro-American documentary novels reveals the need for the maj or tendencies in Marxist criticism to adj ust themselves - the Lukicsian school to a greater stress upon subj ective displacement in mimetic representation, the Althusserian s chool to a greater stress upon obj ective replication of the referent. Second, since Afro-American writers from the start have attached a particular urgency to their program of telling the truth, their writings contain an implicit challenge to much of the contemporary critical theory I discussed earlier. It is difficult to argue that reality is in any meaningful sense fictional for William Wells Brown or Margaret Walker . Finally, Afro-American literature has too often been con strued as oppositional to dominant ideology merely through its ex plicit assertions about its referent. By incorporating documentary works by black writers into the theoretical framework I set forth here, I have tried to show how these works resist hegemony through the very conventions they assume and the generic contracts they hold out to the reader. It is a commonplace for authors to use their prefaces to apologize for possible shortcomings of their books, and I am as eager as any to avail myself of the opportunity. I have three main reservations about this book. First, my investigation has taken me into many historical areas where I do not have a specialist's knowledge, and I am aware that some of my textual readings - as well as some of my generaliza tions about periods and genres - may be vulnerable to criticism from experts in these fields. Second, my attempt to relate vast social forces to the particularities of individual literary works has required me to treat the problem of mediation at a level of considerable generality. I introduce substantial analyses of philosophy and historiography to flesh out the relation between novels and contemporaneous ideolog ical developments, but these materials reinforce my argument logiI9
Preface cally rather than empirically. In defense of this speculative methodol ogy, I can only affirm that I do not envision the actual, lived relation between base and superstructure as abstract and s chematic, even though requirements of brevity have compelled me to describe this relation in a somewhat s chematic manner. Third, I recognize that my inquiry has required me to cut a wide swath of historical and theoreti cal materials. Had I limited myself to a single period or a single theo retical issue, I might have produced a more modest book, but it would not, I think, have b een a better one. It is in my broad claims about the nature of fictional assertion and mediation that I hope to make my contribution to literary study, and it is on the b asis of these claims that I wish primarily to be j udged. I am indebted to several colleagues and friends for their help and advice. Robert Streeter and the late Sheldon S acks , who directed my dissertation, taught me to ask certain kinds of questions about literary works and literary developments and not to settle for easy answers. Robert Jones, William Andrews, L. S. Dembo, and Walter Rideout, all former colleagues at the University of Wisconsin at Madison, read p ortions of the book in its early stages and offered useful suggestions. John Michael Lennon and John Hellmann helped me to refine my ar gument in the theoretical section. S everal colleagues at Northwestern University- Elizabeth Dipple, Martin Mueller, Paul B reslin, and Gayle Pemberton- commented on various chapters and aided me in shaping the argument of the parts and the whole. Various friends and colleagues in the InterN ational Committee against Racism - Bonnie Blustein, Gregory Meyerson, Houston Stevens , Russell Reising , Finley Campbell, a n d V a l Woodward- contributed to m y knowl edge of Marxism in invaluable ways . Gerald Graff read the entire manuscript at a crucial stage and made highly constructive sugges tions about substance, organization, and style; those familiar with Graff's work will see its imprint on many of my pages . Harry Shaw of Cornell University gave a careful and comprehen sive reader's report that helped me to streamline my argument. Richard Ohmann provided an incisive critique of an early version of the theory section and later offered some valuable caveats when he read the entire manuscript for Cornell University Press . Marjorie Weiner p ainstakingly typed a version of the text in the days before I had access to a word processor. I am very grateful to these individuals for their generosity with their time, energy, and expertise. 20
Preface My greatest debt is to my husband, Houston S tevens , and my chil dren, Adam and Margaret, whose love and patience have enabled me to be a scholar, teacher, political activist, wife, and mother. I dedicate this book to them. BARBARA FOLEY
Evanston, Illi nois
2I
PART
THEORY
I
I
The Documentary Novel and
the Problem of Borders
Belief in fiction cannot be a matter of degree. We either accept the inci dents of a story as if they were true, or we are aware of them as fiction. There can be no halfway house, no keeping an open mind, no sus pending our judgement until further evidence is available. -Vivienne Mylne
In this book I shall be arguing that the documentary novel constitutes a distinct fictional kind. It locates itself near the border be tween factual discourse and fictive discourse, but it does not propose an eradication of that border. Rather, it purports to represent reality by means of agreed-upon conventions of fictionality, while grafting onto its fictive pact some kind of additional claim to empirical valida tion. Historically, this claim has taken various forms . The pseudofac tual novel of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries simulates or imitates the authentic testimony of a "real life" person; its documen tary effect derives from the assertion of veracity. The historical novel of the nineteenth century takes as its referent a phase of the historical process; its documentary effect derives from the assertion of extratex tual verification. The documentary novel in the modernist era bifur cates into two distinct genres . The fictional autobiography represents an artist-hero who assumes the status of a real person inhabiting an invented situation; its documentary effect derives from the assertion of the artist's claim to privileged cognition. The metahistorical novel takes as its referent a historical process that evades rational formula tion; its documentary effect derives from the assertion of the very in determinacy of factual verification. Finally, the Afro-American docu mentary novel represents a reality submitting human subjects to racist obj ectification; its documentary effect derives from the presen25
Theory tation of facts that subvert commonplace constructions of reality. In all its phases, then, the documentary novel aspires to tell the truth, and it associates this truth with claims to empirical validation . If it increasingly calls into question the possibility of truth-telling, this skepticism is directed more toward the ideological assumptions un dergirding empiricism than toward the capacity of fictive discourse to interpret and represent its referent. Clearly the documentary novel, as I define it in this book, is not a minor subgenre that can be readily relegated to the margins of novel istic production in any given era. On the contrary: in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the documentary novel is closely aligned with writing that Lennard]. Davis calls the "news/novel discourse" ; 1 in the nineteenth century, the documentary novel intersects with the maj or tradition of realism; in the early decades of the twentieth cen tury, it participates in the principal concerns of modernism. Much writing in the entire domain of Afro-American prose fiction has a pronounced documentary quality. Thus central texts from each phase in the history of the novel (for example, Moll Flanders, Pamela, Waver ley , Henry Esmond, Orlando, A Portrait of the Artist as a Young Man, Na tive Son) can be adj udged to be documentary novels. But while the documentary novel overlaps with the mainstream tradition of the novel, it is not identical with this tradition. Rather, the documentary novel is distinguished by its insistence that it contains some kind of specific and verifiable link to the historical world. (Whether or not this link succeeds in being "extratextual" in a larger sense remains to be seen . ) It implicitly claims to replicate certain features of actuality in a relatively direct and unmediated fashion; it invokes familiar novelis tic conventions, but it requires the reader to accept certain textual elements - characters, incidents , or actual documents - as possessing referents in the world of the reader. The documentary novel is not su perior to other modes of fictional discourse in its capacity for asser tion - all fictions assert their propositional content with equal force and sincerity, I believe- but it does raise the problem ofreference for explicit consideration. To investigate the truth-telling claims of the documentary novel is thus to illuminate the assertive capacities of fic tion in general. 'Lennard]. Davis, Factual Fictions: The Origins of the English Novel (New York: Colum bia University Press, 1 9 8 3 ) .
26
The Problem of Borders As we shall see in the literary-historical portions of this book, the documentary novel's shift in representational strategy reveals the in evitable historicity of generic definitions . Factual and fictive dis courses are not immutable essences but are historically varying types of writing, signaled by, and embodied in, changing literary conven tions and generated by the changing structures of historically specific relations of production and intercourse. As M. M. Bakhtin has re marked, "The boundaries between fiction and nonfiction, between literature and nonliterature and so forth are not laid up in heaven. Every specific situation is historical. And the growth of literature is not merely development and change within the fixed boundaries of any definition; the boundaries thems �lves are constantly changing. "2 In examining the documentary novel's protean identity, I have had to abandon many prior conceptions about what constitutes fiction, the novel, history, and the elusive quality that I am terming the "docu mentary" effect. Modes of discourse do not remain within "fixed boundaries" ; they change as much as do the modes of social and po litical representation in the worlds that they take as their referents . I have discovered, nonetheless, that the distinction between fic tional discourse and its various nonfictional counterparts -history, j ournalism, biography, autobiography-has remained a qualitative one. The need to distinguish between narratives held to be imaginary and those held to be directly representational would seem to be not a post-Cartesian phenomenon, testifying to the alienation of subject from obj ect, but an abiding feature of discursive production. Even in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, when the documentary novel possessed its most ambiguous generic identity, the issue was not that prose fiction simply blended into purportedly veracious kinds of writing but that its primary locus, the romance, could not ef fectively assert the kind of truth that the early pseudofactual novelists wanted to tell. The pseudofactual novel's ambiguous generic status does not mean that writers and readers of the time inhabited an onto logical haze but that they felt obliged to simulate veracious discourses if they hoped to appear credible to their readers. To say, as Bakhtin does, that the borderline between fiction and nonfiction is "con stantly changing" does not mean that writers have not routinely re spected such a borderline; it means, on the contrary, that writers have 'M. M. Bakhtin, The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays, ed. Michael Holquist, trans . Caryl Emerson and Holquist (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1 9 8 1 ) , 33.
27
Theory composed their fictions in contradistinction to one or more acknowl edged forms of nonfictional writing. Fiction, I would propose, is in trinsically part of a binary opposition; it is what it is by virtue of what it is not . T o some, this argument will seem trivial or self-evident. As I indi cated in my prefatory remarks, however, recent years have witnessed a wholesale assault upon the idea that fictional and nonfictional writ ing can - or should-be qualitatively differentiated. The theoretical arguments for the nonqualitative position come mainly from post structuralism, but many writers and critics have added their voices . In this prolegomenon to my central theoretical and historical discus sions, I shall confront the principal claims of my adversaries by argu ing on logical grounds for the superiority of a qualitative view of mimesis . (By "qualitative" I mean different in kind rather than in de gree . ) In so doing, I run the risk of appearing to endorse an ahistorical or essentialist view of mimesis . Certainly it is true, as we shall see, that many defenses of the uniqueness of mimesis do in fact reify the realms of fictional and nonfictional discourse and deny their continu ally altering character. I believe, however, that a qualitative approach to the matter of defining fictionality is consonant with the premises of a materialist literary theory, so long as we remember that binary oppositions are dialectical oppositions as well. In order to counter the objection that my entire analysis of the theoretical and historical fea tures of documentary mimesis is based on a fallacious premise about the distinctness of discursive kinds , I shall defend my procedure here, trusting that the full validation of my argument will emerge in the chapters that follow. 3 3In Chapters I to 4, I shall frequently be citing- and disputing- the views of critics who use the term "literature" or "poetry" where I use the term "fiction" or " mimesis . " I am aware that this procedure may appear imprecise. The term "poetry , " of course, often refers to verse; the term "literature" can be taken either as an honorific term denoting the quality of a text or as a highly general term denoting the whole province of "imaginative" writing - thus including a good deal of history, biography, autobiography, and journalism. In the discussions that follow, I have tried to adhere as closely as possible to the intentions of the critics cited: I have not adduced in support of my argument an opposition between "litera ture" and "nonliterature, " for example, when its author means a distinction between "seri ous " and "popular" writing. It would have been incorrect, however, to confine my debates to those critics who use the terms " fiction" and "nonfiction, " since critics often do mean "fictionality" when they discuss the essential feature(s) of "literary" or "poetic" discourse. For more on the definition of "literature, " see the various essays in Paul Hernadi's collec tion What Is Literature? (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1 978) ; Raymond Wil28
The Problem of Borders The view that fictional and nonfictional discourse cannot be quali tatively distinguished ordinarily rests on one of three arguments . The first of these, which I shall term the " spectrum" argument, centers on the claim that the significant qualities of factuality and fictionality in here in separate facets of a literary work, rather than in any informing paradigm, and that the task of criticism is to assess the impact of these upon the work's rhetorical effect. Thus Paul Hernadi advocates a "microstructural theory of poetic discourse, " which holds that any given literary work possesses aspects of various discourses and should be analyzed not as a text unified by a single generic frame but as a unity of multiple components reflecting the richness of literary dis course in general. Hernadi repudiates the investigation of "generic conventions as reflections of historically conditioned preferences of writers and readers . " Instead, he asserts, "The finest generic classifi cations of our time make us look beyond their immediate concerns and focus on the order of literature, not on borders between literary genres . "4 Scholes and Kellogg, in The Nature of Narrative, reach a similar conclusion from the opposite direction, for they insist that it is such "historically conditioned preferences " that furnish the logical basis for a nonqualitative definition of mimesis. The novel has histor ically synthesized two narrative impulses, they argue, one directed toward the "empirical, " or historical, and the other directed toward the "fictional, " or imaginary. Empirical and fictional are blended ten dencies , rather than distinctive kinds; history and fantasy stand as the poles of a narrative spectrum, with different narrative forms such as autobiography, realism, and romance occupying positions at various points along the scale. The "recording of specific fact, the representa tion of what resembles specific fact, and the representation of general ized types of actuality, " declare Scholes and Kellogg, are all to be aligned along the empirical part of the narrative spectrum. 5 Iiams, Marxism and Literature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1 977) , 45-54; and Tzve tan Todorov, "The Notion of Literature, " New Litera ry Histo ry, 5 (Autumn 1 973 ) : 5 - 1 6. Note, also, that I use the term " mimesis" interchangeably with " fiction. " Some theorists would include under the rubric of mimesis any discourse purporting to represent reality (that is, history, biography, autobiography, and so forth) but would exclude fictions of the more romantic or fantastic variety. 4Paul Hernadi, Beyond Genre: New Directions in Litera ry Classification (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1 972) , 184. 5 obert Scholes and Robert Kellogg, The Nature of Narrative (New York: Oxford Uni versity Press, 1 969) , 86-87.
29
Theory A second type of nonqualitative argument, which I shall term the "family resemblance" argument, is based upon an invocation- albeit somewhat simplified- of Ludwig Wittgenstein's theory of linguistic reference. In his discussion of the definitive characteristics of concepts such as games, Wittgenstein points out the difficulties involved in the attempt to delineate a limited set of criteria that descriptively include all activities commonly held to be games and exclude all other activi ties: " Consider for example the proceedings we call 'games . ' . . . What is common to them all?- Don't say, there must be something common, or they would not be called 'games' - but look and see whether there is anything common to all. For if you look at them you will not see something that is common to all, but similarities, rela tionships , and a whole series at that. " Drawing an analogy between games and the physical traits shared by the members of the same fam ily, Wittgenstein concludes, "We see a complicated network of simi larities overlapping and crisscrossing; sometimes overall similarities , sometimes similarities o f detail. "6 F o r Wittgenstein, n o fixed s e t of properties defines the term " game, " j ust as no fixed set of physical charaCteristics is shared by all members of the same family. For Wittgenstein, language seduces us into believing that certain words denote actually existing sets of relations , when all that these words really denote is concepts used to order the world of things . Applied t o the problem o f defining mimesis, the "family resem blance" argument proposes that qualitative distinctions between fac tual and fictional discourse are founded upon fallacious logic. Morris Weitz, for example, invokes Wittgenstein when he asserts that all aes thetic categories , including the theory of literary kinds, are concepts with blurred edges and that it is therefore impossible to· formulate a clear description of mimetic discourse. Asking himself whether an experimental fiction utilizing new kinds of referential procedures can be classified as a "novel, " he observes, "What is at stake here is no factual analysis concerning necessary and sufficient properties but a decision as to whether the work under examination is similar in cer tain respects to other works, already called 'novels , ' and consequently warrants the extension of the concept to cover the new case. " Every such classificatory decision is, however, necessarily an ad hoc de c1s10n: 6Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 3d ed. , trans. G. E. M. Anscombe (New York: Macmillan, 1 956) , 1, secs. 66-69. JO
The Problem of B o rd e rs "Art, " itself, is an open concept. New conditions (cases) have con stantly arisen and will undoubtedly constantly arise; new art form s , new movements will emerge, which will demand decisions on the part of those interested, usually professional critics, as to whether the con cept should be extended or not. . . . Art, as the logic of the concept shows, has no set of necessary and sufficient properties , hence a theo ry of it is logically impossible and not merely factually difficult. 7
Charles Stevenson, also invoking Wittgenstein, introduces a mathe matical model to solve the problem of fictional classification. Since fictionality is signaled by a multiplicity of possibly relevant textual properties, he argues , and since no fictional work will possess all the traits associated with mimesis, fictional representation consists of a " weighted average" of mimetic elements. 8 According to S tevenson, an arithmetical computation of discernible features will yield the basis for a definitive decision about a text' s qualification for membership in the class of fictions. The "family resemblance" argument claims for itself the virtues of both historicity and empirical precision: to posit a fixed set of fictional features violates not only the course of literary historical development but also the diversity of features present in any given fictional text. Proponents of the spectrum and family resemblance approaches to generic definition quite correctly alert us to the danger of taking fictionality to reside in an immutable set of textual properties. But their arguments are only superfically empirical and historicist. The spectrum argument conflates the necessary recognition of historical shifts in the mimetic contract with the impossibility oflogical classifi cation, thereby precluding any inquiry into the historically varying 'Morris Weitz, "The Role of Theory in Aesthetics, " Journal
ofAesthetics and Art Criticism,
IS (September 1 956) : 28, J 2 . 8Charles Stevenson, " On 'What Is a Poem ? ' " Philosophical Review, 6 6 Ouly 1 957): p9-62. A l s o see N . W. Visser, " T h e Generic Identity of the Novel , " Novel, II (Winter 1 978) : r n 1 - 14. For a persuasive critique of the application of the " family resemblance" con cept to logical problems in aesthetic theory, see Maurice Mandelbaum, " Family Resem blances and Generalization Concerning the Arts , " in
Book of Readings,
ed.
Morris Weitz,
2d ed.
Problems in Aesthetics: An Introductory Macmillan, 1 970) , 1 8 1 - 98.
(London:
Mandelbaum argues that "family resemblance" theorists err in their focus upon "manifest features" rather than upon "relational attributes, " which would require the critic to " con sider specific art obj ects as having been created by someone for some actual or possible au dience"
( 1 87) .
In mathematics, as Stevenson observes, the quantitative approach to generic
definition entails a repudiation of set theory. See Abraham Kaplan and H. F . Schott, " A Calculus fo r Empirical Classes , "
Methodos, 3 ( 1 9 5 1 ) : 1 6 5 - 90.
JI
Theory epistemological b ases of generic distinctions . Scholes and Kellogg quite rightly point out that the various modes of fictional, historical, and autobiographical discourse have adopted conventions signaled by widely varying textual features, and they convincingly demonstrate that certain markers of generic identity have even reversed their func tions : the unwitnessed monologue, now a sure indicator of an au thor's fictional intentions, was once, they show, an accepted conven tion of heroic history. But a recognition of the relative- that is, historically variable- nature of the fact/fiction opposition does not mean that this opposition is denied absolute status at any given his torical j uncture. A spectrum of empirical possibilities is not the same thing as a spectrum of discursive kinds . As Barbara Herrnstein Smith puts it, "There is no principle of relative differentiation that could allow us to speak of any given composition as 'more' or 'less' fic tive . . . and thereby assign it its proper place on the continuum. The distinction between natural and fictive is absolute. "9 The spectrum argument ends up treating generic categorization as a framework imp osed a posteriori by literary critics, ruling out the possibility that it may constitute a necessary b asis for the contracts formed between actual writers and readers . The central problem with the family resemblance argument is that it treats all textual elements as having an equal claim upon the reader's attention, with no single trait being privileged by convention or authorial intention to exercise a dominant influence in the reader' s ap prehension of the text's generic identity. The text is, quite simply, the sum of its parts; if these parts cannot add up to a sufficient total, then the text is not recognizable as a member of the family of fictions . But to maintain that separate elements in factual or fictive works signal a certain family resemblance does not imply that qualitatively defined sets of relations among these elements cannot also be uncovered. Concepts with blurred edges are not necessarily concepts that lack a principle of unity; indeed, as Wittgenstein himself pointed out, con cepts such as " games , " while not readily definable in descriptive 9Barbara Herrnstein Smith, "On the Margins of Discourse, "
1 975) : 774.
Critical Inquiry , 1
Oune
For a penetrating discussion of the changing boundary between autobiography
and the novel, a distinction that is " dependent on distinctions between fiction and nonfic tion, between rhetorical and empirical first-person narrative, " see Elizabeth Bruss, Autobio graphical Acts: The Changing Situation ofa Literary Genre (B altimore: Johns Hopkins Univer sity Press, 1 976) , 5 - 1 8 .
32
The Problem of Bo r ders terms, are easily definable in practice, since clearly people know when they are playing games and when they are not. Wittgenstein's "insight into the looseness of our concepts, and its attendant j argon of 'family resemblance, ' " remarks John Searle, "should not lead us into a rej ection of the very enterprise of philosophical analysis . " 1 0 The third type of nonqualitative argument- the one developed re cently with the most vehemence-has come from poststructuralist critics, who, invoking Nietzsche, propose that all our discourses about the material world, both factual and fictive, are circumscribed by the texts we construe in relation to that world. The very act of formulating an explanatory scheme is, for Barthes and Derrida, an enterprise inevitably shaped by language and ideology and is there fore fictive, in effect if not in intent. The proj ect of criticism should not be to perpetuate the metaphysical dualisms of Western thought -among which the opposition of fiction and nonfiction figures cen trally-but to reveal the inadequacy of reductive binary oppositions that privilege the products of the "creative" imagination, relegate (non)fiction to the margins of discourse, and ignore the textuality of all writing . Thus Roland Barthes has argued that the only feature which distinguishes historical discourse from other kinds is a paradox: the "fact" can exist linguistically only as a term in a discourse, yet we behave
as
if it were a simple reproduction of some
thing on another plane of existence altogether, some extra-structural " reality. " Historical discourse is presumably the only kind which aims at a referent "outside " itself that can in fact never be reached.
Historical discourse is, therefore, a "fake performative, in which what claims to be the descriptive element is in fact only the expres''John R. Searle, Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language (Cambridge: Cam bridge University Press, 1 9 70) , 5 5 . According to John M . Ellis, Wittgenstein 's theory of language, properly understood, leads to the conclusion that literature can be qualitatively described by means of a "functional" definition. "When we seek a definition, " he argues, " what we are seeking is not a statement of the features held in common by the members of the category, but the appropriate circumstances for the use of the word and the features of those circumstances that determine the willingness or unwillingness of the speakers of the language to use the word"
( The Theo ry ofLiterary Criticism: A Logical Analysis [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1 974] , 3 4) . Weitz is a crude Wittgensteinian, Ellis implies, for Weitz takes the impossibility of definition as the alternative to referential definition. The value of Eilis 's theory is diminished, however, by his adherence to a nonassertive view of mimesis: the functionality of literary works, it turns out, consists in their being "used by society in such a way that the text is not taken as specifically relevant to the immediate con text of its origin" (43 ) .
33
Theory sion of the authoritarian nature of that particular speech-act. " 11 For Barthes, the insistence upon a referent beyond textuality is not simply a gesture of epistemological na1vete: it is an act of political repression. Derrida develops the militantly antigeneric implications of Barthes' s argument. The formulation of the binary opposition fic tion/nonfiction produces, for Derrida, a "hierarchical axiology" that presupposes " an origin or . . . a 'priority' held to be simple, intact, normal, pure, standard, self-identical. "12 One aspect of the opposi tion (in this case, fiction) is implicitly valorized, and the other (non fiction) is defined by subordination or exclusion- that is, by non identity. A deconstruction of such metaphysical categories reveals that what is excluded constitutes much more than nonidentity and that identity itself- as a pure essence beyond difference- is a spe cious category. When brought to bear upon the theory of discursive genres, the deconstructive proj ect therefore reveals that the law of the law of genre . . . is a principle of contamination . . . . The trait that marks membership inevitably divides ; the boundary of the set comes to form . . . an internal pocket larger than the whole; and the out come of this division and of this overflowing remains as singular as it is limitless . . . . The principle of genre is unclassifiable, it tolls the knell of the . . . classicum, of what permits one to call out orders and to order, the manifold without a nomenclature . . . . [Genre designation] gathers together the corpus and, at the same time . . . keeps it from closing, from identifying itself with itself. This axiom of non-closure or non.,. fulfillment enfolds within itself the condition for the possibility and the impossibility of taxonomy. 1 3
11Roland Barthes, "Historical Discourse, " in Introduction to Structuralism, ed. Michael Lane (New York: Basic, 1 970) , 1 5 3 , 1 54- 5 5 . For an instance of the political rhetoric that critics sympathetic with poststructuralism frequently attach to their discussions of the fact/fiction distinction, compare Suzanne Gearhart: " (All theories of literature and all theo ries of history] have consistently sought to fix the boundary between them and to establish once and for all the specificity of the fields in one of two ways: democratically, in that each accepts a mutually agreed on boundary which grants to each its own identity and integrity; or, just as often, imperialistically, in that each tries to extend its own boundary and to in vade, engulf, or encompass the other. . . . In the second [case, the other genre] is overcome, cannibalized, incorporated into the sameness of the imperializing field" ( The Open Boundary of Histo ry and Fiction: A. Critical Approach to the French Enlightenment [Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1 984] , 4) . 12Jacques Derrida, " Limited Inc abc, " in Glyph: Johns Hopkins Textual Studies 2 (Balti more: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1 977) , 236. See also Positions, trans . Alan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 9 8 1 ) , 3 9 - 47. 13Derrida, "The Law of Genre, " quoted in Michael Ryan, Marxism and Deconstruction: A Critical Articulation (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1982) , 1 9 .
34
The Problem of Borders For Derrida, the very attempt to formulate genre distinctions is un dermined by the subversive nature of writing, which interpenetrates among the epistemological categories that ideology sets up to delin eate its terrain. We may be grateful to Derridean deconstruction for calling our at tention to the ideological agenda that is inevitably attached to the bi nary opposition fiction/nonfiction. As I shall argue in the following chapter, the common valorization of "creative" or "imaginative" writing does frequently imply a fetishization of mimetic discourse and a positivist reduction of nonfictional discourse to the unmediated reportage of "what is . " But, while I would certainly agree with Barthes that historical discourse is in its way as saturated in ideology as is mimetic discourse, I would not therefore conclude that historical and mimetic discourse adopt equivalent representational procedures or constitute equivalent modes of cognition. And while I would grant Derrida's point that Western philosophy is pervaded by abstract and ahistorical oppositions that, in the guise of reflecting transcendent es sences, naturalize dominant ideology, I would not therefore conclude that all inherited cognitive oppositions are equally ideological and equally fallacious . Some oppositions -between fact and fiction, for instance- describe very real (and, I believe, necessary) cognitive op erations, in which actual historical people engage and have engaged. Indeed, the Derridean proj ect itself is hardly exempt from the practice of binary opposition. Its universe is unremittingly dualistic, with the forces of logocentrism, homogeneity, and repression locked in com bat with those of differance, heterogeneity, and dispersal. If we rec ognize, as surely we must, that certain binary oppositions have been used to legitimate a hierarchical social order, the solution is not to jet tison binary opposition altogether but to formulate a binary opposi tion to class dominance that will carry political force. In this effort, it is not helpful to argue that all discourses are fictions or that the goal of criticism is to formulate, in Derrida's words, "undecidables" that " can no longer be included within philosophical (binary) opposition, but which, however, inhabit philosophical opposition, resisting and disorganizing it, without ever constituting a third term. " 14 The refusal to constitute a third term cannot go very far toward dislodging the "hierarchical axiology. " 14Derrida, Positions, 43 . See also my "The Politics of Deconstruction, " in the special is sue "Deconstruction at Yale, " Genre, 1 7 (Spring- Summer 1984) : 1 1 3 - 3 4. 35
Theory It should be apparent that, when one argues for a qualitative defini tion of fictionality, much more than the classification of discourse is involved: at stake, ultimately, is a whole debate about the relation between- and the context of-perception and cognition. I have no wish here to extend this debate. To support my assertion that fic tional and nonfictional discourses are distinguishable not in degree but in kind, however, I would point out that most twentieth-century theories of cognition-in fields from psychology to the philosophy of science to linguistics -have found it necessary to postulate that the human mind characteristically uses polarity as an essential device in gaining understanding. Any given particular must be understood as part of a l;irger scheme, these theories tell us, if it is to be considered at all. Th� possible relevance of such theories to the problem of defin ing fictionality should be clear: the genres of fictional discourse en gage informing paradigms qualitatively different from those of the various genres of nonfictional discourse, and even a presumably veri fiable fact must be framed and contextualized before its signification can be determined. From the field of Gestalt psychology, for example, we learn that perception ordinarily operates within qualitative and totalizing frames of reference. The rabbit-duck drawing, Gestalt psychologists would tell us, has two possible, and mutually exclusive, interpreta tions -it is either a rabbit or a duck. The viewer can readily enough grasp both perceptual possibilities but can process only one scheme at any particular instant. Any given detail in the drawing makes sense as part of either ordering scheme, but it demands wholly different inter pretations when it is "read" from each perspective. Only a prior con ventional context, external to the object of perception, can provide decisive criteria for adjudging the correctiness of one or another inter pretation. It is impossible, concludes E. H. Gombrich of this notori ous example, to see "what is 'really there, ' to see the shape apart from its interpretation. "15 There are no innocent perceptions: if perception is to produce cognition, it must invoke a framework of prior assump tions about what is being seen. Gregory Bateson and Erving Goffman have argued that a great va riety of human behaviors can be explained by means of the Gestalt model. Bateson proposes that, in activities such as play, fantasy, and 15E. H. Gombrich,
Art and Jllusion: A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1 960) , 5 .
The Problem of Borders
psychotherapy, the participants agree upon "psychological frames " that perform a " metacommunicative function, " giving the receiver "instructions or aids in his attempt to understand the messages in cluded within the frame. " 16 Psychological frames are, moreover, both exclusive and inclusive, excluding certain messages by including others and vice versa: according to Bateson, Gestalt paradigms are necessary for the unambiguous signaling of complex and overdeter mined meanings . Goffman examines the operations of all sorts of so cial codes - from body language to advertising- in terms of what he calls "primary frameworks" : "Each primary framework allows its user to locate, perceive, identify and label a seemingly infinite num ber of concrete occurrences defined in its terms . [The user] is likely to be unaware of such organized features as the framework has and un able to describe the framework with any completeness if asked, yet these handicaps are no bar to his easily and fully applying it. " 1 7 Pri mary frameworks can also be transformed, or "keyed, " in such a way that almost all the elements in the original activity signal an entirely new meaning when incorporated into a keyed context. Keying in volves an agreement among the parties involved to bracket the keyed activity, pretending to follow the rules of the primary framework but actually following a set of very different rules . For Bateson and Goffman, then, the entire range of human behavior, serious and play ful, is regulated by conventions that bear a "metacommunicative" re16Gregory Bateson, "A Theory of Play and Fantasy, " in his Steps to an Ecology of Mind: Collected Essays in Anthropology, Psychiatry, Evolution, and Epistemology (San Francisco: Chandler, 1 972) , 1 87 - 8 8 . For more on the relations among Gestalt frames, play and fan tasy, and fictionality, see Kendall L. Walton, "Fearing Fictions, " journal of Philosophy, 75 (January 1 978) : 5 - 27. 17Erving Goffman, Frame Analysis: An Essay on the Organization of Experience (Cam bridge: Harvard University Press, 1 976) , 2 r .
37
Theory lation to any given activity . An activity is understood as a kind of thing, and it is defined largely by contradistinction to what it is not. Turning to the field of the philosophy of science, we may note that it has become axiomatic that scientists ordinarily hypothesize gener alizations and then seek out the evidence that would validate, qualify , or refute those generalizations . Early bourgeois science proposed that human beings characteristically construct conceptual categories on the basis of inductively accumulated experience - a procedure that results, in Hume' s words, in " that perfect habit, which makes us con clude in general, that instances , of which we have no experience, must necessarily resemble those of which we have. "18 T. S. Kuhn, by contrast, cautions that "no natural history can be interpreted in the absence of at least some implicit body of intertwined theoretical and methodological belief that permits selection, evaluation, and criti cism . "19 Karl Popper, who sees the growth of scientific knowledge as a process of "conj ecture and refutation, " holds that the mind in trinsically possesses the " expectation of finding a regularity. "20 Mi chael Polanyi, rej ecting those versions of Gestalt psychology that de scribe the perceiver as a passive receiver of preformed paradigms, declares, " I am looking at Gestalt . . . as the outcome of . . . an active shaping of experience performed in the pursuit of knowledge. " 2 1 For these theorists, the scientific method consists in the constant evalua tion of explanatory frames . Particulars do not yield up their meaning; they need to be located within a qualitatively defined larger scheme if they are to possess value as evidence. Finally, it bears noting that such concepts as "tacit knowledge" and "primary frameworks " bear a distinct resemblance to Noam 18David Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Clarendon, 1 907) , 1 3 5 · For more on Hume' s inductive argument, see also I, 3, vi and I, 3, xii. 1 9T. S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2 d ed. (Chicago : University of Chicago Press, 1 970) , 16- 1 7 . 2°Karl Popper, Conjectures and Refatations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge (New York: Basic, 1 962) , 47. 21Michael Polanyi, The Tacit Dimension (Garden City: Doubleday, 1 966} , 6. In citing Polanyi, Kuhn, and Popper, I do not mean to imply that I endorse the particular theories of scientific method and development that these philosophers have evolved. I am simply noting the fact that modern philosophers of science of widely varying ideological orienta tions, neopositivist to intuitionist, have all found it necessary to posit that thought cannot take place in the absence of informing paradigms into which data- even anomalous data - must be incorporated. For a critique of both Popper's rationalism and Kuhn's irrational ism, see Larry Laudan, Progress and Its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth (Berke ley: University of California Press, 1 977) . 38
The Problem of Borders Chomsky' s theory of linguistic competence, which posits that native speakers of a language are governed by an "abstract system underly ing behavior, a system constituted by rules that interact to determine the form and intrinsic meaning of a potentially infinite number of sentences . "22 The process of acquiring language therefore means that "a child must devise a hypothesis compatible with presented data - he must select from the store of potential grammars a specific one that is appropriate to the data available to him. "23 Whenever a speaker utters a statement, then, he or she is invoking a " deep struc ture" that is the basis for the statement' s being coherent and compre hensible (even if the statement is new to the listener) . The goal of the study of the " universal grammar" of language, Chomsky concludes , is not simply to illuminate the procedures of language acquisition and communication; it is nothing less than the discovery of the general properties of human intelligence. 24 These various descriptions of the relation of perception to cogni tion could, I suppose, be taken as evidence that human intelligence can never know reality, but that it merely imposes its fictions on what it encounters . In my view, however, their implication is quite different. There is no reason to suppose that facts are created by inter pretations if they are bound to them. We are free to see a duck or a rabbit, but not a giraffe; the Gestalt figure is not a Rorschach inkblot. The Copernican view of the solar system did not construct the data that rendered it a more powerful explanatory model than the Ptole maic system. Nor is there any reason to conclude that any given "pri mary framework" or " tacit knowledge" or " deep structure" consti tutes innate or transhistorical knowledge of a Kantian or Jungian kind . The human mind may have certain innate proclivities , but these are necessarily enacted through cognitive frames that are p reemi nently social constructs: the manifold variations in past and present human b ehavior testify to the embeddedness of any given conceptu alization in a highly changeable social reality. These theories of cogni tion and language simply suggest that human intelligence characteris22Noam Chomsky, Language and Mind (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1 968), 62. 23Chomsky, Aspects ofthe Theory of Syntax (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1 96 5 ) , 36. 24Chomsky, Language and Mind, 24. F o r a n applicaiton of Chomsky' s theory of " deep structure" to the problem of mobilizing and perceiving generic distinction in imaginative literature, see Sheldon Sacks, " The Psychological Implicaitons of Generic Distinctions, " Genre, l ( 1 968) : ro6 - 1 5 . 39
Theory tically operates in a configurational and -indeed- binary manner. Particulars must b e grasped as functional components in qualitatively defined totalities - and excluded from other possible totalities - if they are to be grasped at all. In this book I shall argue that both fictional discourse and nonfic tional discourse make use of totalizing frames analogous to those ex plicitly formulated by psychology, linguistics , and the philosophy of s cience. Any given element in a narrative, I shall suggest, must be scanned and interprelted as either factual or fictive in order to b e read and understood. There is no specifically linguistic essence of fictional ity that is immediately perceptible in the particulars of a text. As Vic tor Lange aptly puts it, Whether or not we are in the presence of a fictional field is . . . a matter of contextual analysis; it cannot be recognized unless we examine the specific aesthetic and logical uses to which the facts that sustain it have b een put. The quality of the fact itself, whether it is related to any p re sumed actuality or is fanciful and non-realistic, is of little concern for the determination of the fictional mode. The invented speeches in T acitus are clearly part of a non-fictional intention; the actual letter which Rilke incorporated in
Malte Laurids Brigge
assumes, within the
purposes of the novel, a distinctly fictional character. 25
The writer assumes that the reader will possess the " competence" to know how to understand each particular, and that the "tacit knowl edge" undergirding this competence is the knowledge of generic con ventions shared by writer and reader alike. The nonfictional and fic tional Gestalts employed by Tacitus and Rilke, respectively, are a function of the primary frameworks shared by readers of modern novels and ancient histories . I am arguing, in short, for a definition of mimesis as a contract, wherein writer and reader share an agreement about the conditions under which texts can be composed and com prehended. Even when writers take quantitative steps toward altering 25Victor Lange, "The Fact in Fiction, " Comparative Literature Studies, 6 (September 1 969) : 260. For other theories of fictional discourse explicitly invoking the concept of Ge stalt, see S mith, 775 - 76; Ralph W. Rader, "The Concept of Genre in Eighteenth-Century S tudies, " in New Approaches to Eighteenth-Century Literature: Selected Papers from the English Institute (New York: Columbia University Press, 1 974) , 84- 86; and Norman Friedman, Form and Meaning in Fiction (Athens : University of Georgia Press, 1975), 1 96-97. 40
The Problem
of
Borders
the terms of this agreement, they do so in the context of qualitatively defined discursive conventions . And the essence of mimesis - for it has an essence, pace Derrida and company - is that it is a social practice, whereby authors impart cognition of a particular kind to their readers . The documentary novel, accordingly, is a species of fiction dis tinctly characterized by its adherence to referential strategies associ ated with nonfictional modes of discourse but also demanding- to be read within a fictional Gestalt familiar to contemporaneous readers. Its dramatically altering strategies of representation do not mean that fictional discourse and nonfictional discourse are indistinguishable; they point instead to the changing terms of the fictional contract in different social formations. But to assert that the documentary novel does not inhabit some epistemologically hazy realm is merely to render a negative definition of its features and capacities. I turn now to examine the nature of the mimetic contract and then to specify the mode of cognition that is distinctly characteristic of mimetic dis course. We cannot appreciate the problem of asserting reference that confronts particularly the documentary novelist without a fuller un derstanding of the assertive capacities of mimesis in general. We shall now examine those capacities .
4I
2
The Mimetic Contract and the Problem of Assertion The naive reader or critic who claims certain novels are dishonest is sometimes not quite so naive as are theoreticians who have assured him that fiction . . . cannot lie . . . because it cannot assert. -Thomas J. Roberts
Most modern literary theorists would grant fictional dis course a status distinct from that of nonfictional discourse. The oppo nents to the qualitative definition of mimesis, although vociferous , are still in the minoirity. When we examine the various criteria that have been adduced as the basis for fiction's claim to an autonomous identity, however, we frequently encounter a curious anomaly. Fic tion is uniformly praised for its power: it uses language in a concen trated manner prohibited to nonfiction; it arouses the emotions and liberates consciousness from the constraints of ideology; it carries the reader into another world; it offers none of the commitments of state ment and all of the j oys of pseudostatement. None of these formula tions, however, offers a satisfactory account of fiction as a mode of cognition; indeed, what the great majority routinely state or imply is that fiction cannot assert propositions that are to be taken as seri ously as those conveyed through other modes of discourse. Fiction's impotence is therefore a peculiar correlative to its power. In Chapters 3 and 4, I shall set forth my own theory of fictional ref erence and shall argue that mimesis is constitutively a social and histor ical phenomenon. In the present chapter I intend to refute the princi p al formalistic theories of fiction that enj oy popularity at present and to argue for the necessity of viewing mimesis as an intentionally de fined contract. I make no pretension here to offer a full critique of ei ther the individual critics I cite or the s chools to which I assign them. My aim is simply to schematize the main alternative approaches to 42
The Problem of Assertion mimesis and to associate these approaches with familiar critical fig ures . I have three reasons for undertaking this excursus into the realm of opposing theory. First, I hope to show that the inadequacy of the commonly accepted views of mimesis stems from their refusal to view it as a social contract. The hypostatization of elements such as linguistic texture, ontology, and affective response results from a tex tual fetishism that insists upon fragmenting mimetic communication into its component parts and divesting it of social significance. We will grasp the Gestalt by means of which fictional discourse conveys cognition, I believe, only if we see the fictional work as a contract designed by an intending author who invites his or her audience to adopt certain paradigms for understanding reality. Second, however, I wish to demonstrate that even those modern theories of mimesis that acknowledge the central role of the author- such as the speech act theories that I discuss in the last portion of this chapter- fail to give a full account of authorial intention. It is only when the authorial subj ect is viewed as a social subject rooted in a specific historical context- a perspective most effectively developed in Marxist literary theory- that the propositional content and assertive force of the text can be fully appreciated. The argument in this chapter thus sets the stage for my formulations in Chapters 3 and 4, insofar as it prepares us to see that Marxism is not merely one among a plurality of possi ble methodologies . Finally, I wish to ground my discussion of the documentary novel in a theory of mimesis that dispels conclusively the notion that fictional works do not assert their propositional con tents . A critique of antiassertionist theories of mimesis is an essential precondition to the investigation of any type of fictional discourse, I believe, but especially so to the study of the documentary novel, which posits that its reference to actual people and events empowers it to tell a particularly compelling truth. Accordingly, the following critique of formalist theories of fiction should be recalled when we examine the historically varying modes of fictional assertion pre sented in Part 2 of this book. These modes of fictional assertion are meant seriously, I shall argue, and therefore must be taken seriously.
Textual Definitions Many modern theorists seeking the differentia of factual and fictive discourse have looked to the text itself to discover the distinguishing 43
Theory features of mimesis. For the textual theorist, extratextual concerns - conventions , the needs of authors and audiences, social forces of broader kinds - may illuminate the text, but they are irrelevant to the definition of mimesis as such: mimesis is intrinsic to texts that em ploy elements of language or structure in certain ways. Despite their diversity, these approaches share a tendency to isolate a feature found in many mimetic texts and _to identify this feature as the defining quality of all fictive discourse.
The Language of Mimesis Language is in the foreground of much twentieth-century literary theory, so it is no accident that many theorists have discovered the es sence of fictional discourse to consist in its unique use of language. There are three main versions of the linguistic criterion. The first pos its that fiction is distinguished by its characteristic linguistic texture. Monroe Beardsley, for example, maintains that much of the "implicit meaning" of literature derives from the "opacity" of its linguistic tex ture. ' Similarly, Rene Wellek and Austin Warren argue that "liter ary" language (that of prose fiction and of poetry) is characteristically connotative, while that of science is denotative. 2 The second linguis tic criterion for defining mimesis rests on the contention that fictional language is nonparaphrasable. J. M. Cameron states, "I could not give an alternative poetic description, for there could be no criterion (as there would be in the case of a real description) for deciding whether or not the alternative description has succeeded. The poetic description has the form of a description; but it exists only as this de scription, these words, in this order. "3 The third linguistic criterion rests upon the premise that, as Margaret MacDonald says, in a fic tional work languag,e is used "to originate, not to report. " A story teller, she declares, "performs [and] does not- or not primarily 'Monroe C. Beardsley, Aesthetics: Problems in the Philosophy of Criticism (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1 9 5 8 ) , esp . 1 26- 2 8 . 2Rene Wellek a n d Austin Warren, Theo ry of Literature, 3 d e d . (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, Harvest, 1 956) , 22- 2 3 . 3J . M. Cameron, "Poetry and Dialectic, " in The Night Battle: Essays (London: Burns & Oates, 1 962) , 1 3 7 . For further development of the nonparaphrasability theory, see also Da vid Lodge, The Language ofFiction: Essays in Criticism and Verbal Analysis ofthe English Novel (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1 966) .
44
The Problem of Assertion inform or misinform. "4 The definitive quality of fictive language thus becomes its lack of referentiality. Roman Jakobson found a sharp distinction between the "poetic" and the "communicative" or " refer ential" functions of language: "The supremacy of the poetic function over the referential function does not obliterate the reference, " he concludes, " but makes it ambiguous. "5 It should be apparent that these different linguistic criteria are quite closely related to one another. Language that is used in a connotative way cannot be said to possess the same power of reference as lan guage that is denotative, and its force would seem to reside in its in imitable construction . It should also be apparent that each of these criteria poses severe logical and practical drawbacks to developing a comprehensive theory of fictionality. The criterion of linguistic tex ture is arbitrary and inexact: the highly colored, ironic language of Marx's Eighteenth Brumaire poses a sharp contrast to the flat, reporto rial prose of Studs Lonigan, but I would not want to conclude that Marx is therefore a novelist, and Farrell a sociologist. Features such as "semantic density, " remarks Stein Haugom Olsen, are "noticed only when they serve an independently defined funciton" ; in order to iden tify such a feature and to see it as "artistically relevant, " the decision " must already have been reached that the text is a literary work. "6 The criterion of fictional nonparaphrasability encounters comparable difficulties. Writers frequently rewrite their texts, which suggests some prelinguistic formulation in the author's mind to which the var ious stylistic formulations in some way correspond. " Though fic tional worlds emerge from words , " states James Phelan, " and though sometimes the particular words an author chooses are extremely im portant for creating a fictional world effectively, these worlds are fi nally not worlds of words, but worlds of characters, actions, emo tions, and thoughts . " 7 While stylistic theorists claim to discern the 4Margaret MacDonald, " The Language of Fiction, " reprinted in Perspectives on Fiction, ed. James L. Calderwood and Harold Toliver (New York: Oxford University Press, 1 968) , 64. 5Roman Jakobson, " Closing Statement: Linguistics and Poetics, " in Style in Language, ed. Thomas Sebeok (Cambridge: Technology Press of MIT, 1 960) , 3 7 1 . 6Stein Haugom Olsen, " Defining a Literary Work, " Journal ofAesthetics and Art Criticism, 3 5 (Winter 1976) : 1 3 7· James Phelan, Worlds from WMds: A Theory of Language in Fiction (Chicago : University of Chicago Press, 1 9 8 1 ) , 149. Recent work in linguistics indicates that, while the style may be the man, it does not constitute the work. Studies of the reading activity reveal that, in 45
Theory distinctive feature of mimesis in its unique appropriation of language, their argument has a paradoxical premise. " The idea of style, " re marks Richard Ohmann, "implies that words on a page might have been different, or diifferently arranged, without a corresponding dif ference in substance. " To fault an author on the grounds that a sen tence is ill-phrased - as critics often do- is to contend that the sen tence might have been better phrased and thus to imply that the sentence can be a more or less effective tool for getting at a peculiarly solid- and prelinguistic- referent. Ohmann continues, " Another writer would have said it another way . "8 The nonreferentiality criterion at first appears to be a more formi dable adversary . We must conclude, after all, that the name " Bigger Thomas " does not denote an actual inhabitant of Chicago . But- and this point is crucial to an understanding of referentiality in the docu mentary novel- certain words appearing in fictional discourse do carry a power of direct historical reference. As we shall see below, Waverly would not persuade its readers to take a certain view of his-
confronting both fictional and nonfictional narratives of sustained duration, people charac teristically forget the specific linguistic (syntactical) formulations of texts and instead for mulate abbreviated and schematized versions of their conceptual content. Teun A. Van Dij k remarks , " Recall, comparison and other mental operations with sentences are based on semantic representations. Syntactic structures appear to be immediately erased from mem ory, which points at their 'superficial' character. " This discovery suggests that a reader's experience of both fictional and nonfictional texts hinges not p rimarily upon stylistic ef fects, however powerfully these may register in the short-term memory, but upon a gener alized apprehension of propositional content, which is lodged in the long-term memory. Indeed, as Gerald Graff has argued, our reliance upon the interpretive schemes carried in the long-term memory gives aesthetic power to stylistic materials noted in the short-term memory. See Van Dijk, Some Aspects of Text Grammars: A Study in Theoretical Linguistics and Poetics (The Hague: Mouton, 1 972) , 3 24- 2 5 , and Graff, " Literature as Assertions, " in American Criticism in the Poststructuralist Age, ed. Ira Konigsberg, Michigan Studies in the Humanities (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1 9 8 1 ) , 1 52 - 56. 8Richard Ohmann, " Generative Grammars and the Concept of Literary Style, " Word, 20 (December 1 964) : 427. For the argument that any alteration in "surface structure" is an al teration in substance, see Stanley Fish, "Affective Stylistics: Literature in the Reader, " New Literary History, 2 (Autumn 1 970) : 1 2 3 -62. Fish asserts, "We comprehend not in terms of the deep structure alone, but in terms of a relationship between the unfolding, in time, of the surface structure and a continual checking of it against our proj ection (always in terms of surface structure) of what the deep structure will reveal itself to be, and when the final dis covery has been made and the deep structure is perceived, all the ' mistakes, ' the positing, on the basis of incomplete evidence, of deep structures that failed to materialize, will not b e cancelled o u t . They have been experienced; they have existed in the mental life of the reader; they mean" ( 1 44) .
The Problem of A ssertio n
torical process if its Bonnie Prince Charlie did not signify the real Pre tender; the J. P. Morgan who appears in Dos Passos's U. S . A . is not merely a fictional character who comments in a general way upon the depredations of capital. Moreover- and I shall treat this point at con siderable length in the next chapter-it is important to recognize that a fictional text's propositional relation to the historical world cannot be simply equated with the referential capacities of its individual sen tences . Michael Scriven observes : Generally speaking . . . the s entences in a story cannot be said to be true or false, as could the statements in a sermon. But the story as a whole can certainly be s aid to paint a true (or false) picture of its subj ect. D. H. Lawrence on the Midland mining towns, Arthur Koestler on Commu nist interrog ation proceedings, Alan Paton on conditions in the Union of South Africa, can be praised for the versimilitude of their account or criticized for its inaccuracy . 9
Most discussions of fictional reference are muddled by the assump tion that truth attaches exclusively to separate sentences and entities, rather than to things-in-relation. Indeed, a positivist epistemology lurks not far beneath the surface of the nonreferentiality criterion: the only realities, it seems, are palpable "facts , " and if a discourse cannot refer to these, it has no referent at all. The Ontology of Mimesis A second textual definition of mimesis distinguishes factual and fic tive discourse on the basis of textual ontology. Taking as their prem ise Husserl's distinction between the realm of " essential universality" and the factitious sphere of "spatio-temporal facts, " 10 a number of phenomenological critics have attempted to locate the differentia of mimesis in one or more textual features that signal the presence of a realm ontologically discontinuous with that of ordinary experience. One argument centers on the status of the narrator in factual and fic tive discourse: presumably the author of a factual work is the narrator and is therefore wholly responsible for the statements in the narra9Michael Scriven, "The Language of Fiction, " Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supp. vol. 2 8 ( 1 954) : 1 87. 10Edmund Husserl, Ideas: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology, trans. W. R. Boyce Gibson (London: Allen & Unwin, 1 9 3 l), 54 and passim. 47
Theory tive, whereas the narrator of a novel is not necessarily to be identified with the author in propria persona, alike as the two may be in outlook. Thus Laurent Stern, for example, suggests that the narrators in fictions are themselves fictive characters : "We must make-believe that the stories told within the literary work of art are told by fictional characters . "11 Kate Hamburger, who repudiates the notion that mi mesis consists exclusively in the fictiveness of the narrator, asserts that the novel's "lack of an '1-0rigo' " is nonetheless one among sev eral important indicators of the text's removal from the ontological sphere of the reader. 12 Other phenomenological critics focus their attention on the per ceived status of the narrative' s spatiotemporal realm. Disj unction between the spatiotemporal realm of the text and that of the reader signals the presence of fictionality; conj unction b etween the two spheres reveals the presence of factuality. Thus Robert Champigny states, "I interpret a narrative in a novelistic perspective if . . . I do not situate the event of my reading in relation to the narrated event. " Hence there is an unbridgeable gap between the "realities" of text and reader: "Events in a spatio-temporal field can be historical for me only if they are spatially and temporally related to me: I must posit myself as an event or process among others . "13 Roman Ingarden, perhaps the most rigorous - at least the most sonorous- of the phe nomenological critics, articulates the formalism latent in the ontolog ical approach to mimesis . "We remain in the realm of the work it self, " he states, "without taking an interest in extraliterary reality. " The " concretization of aesthetically valent qualities" is thus the goal of the literary work: "In their opalescent dual meaning, the semantic units, clothed in particular sound materials, proj ect an intuitive mate rial permeated with special materially colored qualities, which allows the reader to apprehend j ust that qualitative cluster of values which arises as a necessary phenomenon from such intuitive material. "14 If "Laurent Stem, " Fictional Characters, Places, and Events, " Philosophy and Phenomeno logical Research, 26 (December 1965): 2 1 0. 12Kate Hamburger, The Logic of Literature, 2d rev. ed. , trans. Marilyn J. Rose (Bloom ington: Indiana University Press, 1 93 3 ) , 73 - 74. 13See Robert Champigny, Ontology of the Narrative: An Analysis (The Hague: Mouton, 1 972) , 1 7, and "Implicitness in Narrative Fiction, " PMLA, 85 (October 1 970) : 990. 14Roman Ingarden, The Cognition of the Literary Work of Art, trans . Ruth Ann Crowley and Kenneth R. Olsen (Evanston: Northwestern University Press , 1 97 3 ) , 3 7, 68. For fur ther instances of the phenomenological approach to mimesis, see Knut Hanneborg, The
The Problem of Assertion we can penetrate through the "opalescent . . . meaning" of this state ment, it seems to be saying that the presence of fictionality is signaled by the reader' s loss of interest in the historical world- a loss that is presumably compensated by the semantic resonance of the text. The stipulation that fiction involves ontological displacement re minds us, lest we forget, that even the most transparently realistic fic tive works do not routinely depict real persons and events . But the view of fiction as ontologically discontinuous does not prove particu larly useful in accounting for the phenomenon of the documentary novel, which explicitly attempts to break down ontological barriers by incorporating presumably unmediated elements of actuality into the fictional work. Moreover, unless the ontological definition of mi mesis is understood simply as a restatement of the truism that fiction involves invention, it frequently takes us in circles, for it fails to lo cate identifiable textual features conventionally signaling fictionality and ends up simply conflating reader response and authorial intention with the "text itself. " How is spatiotemporal disj unction a textual property in the absence of a responding reader? How is the presence or absence of an "1-0rigo" inferable from the particulars of the text, without some prior or external conception of the signaled intentions of the author? How can intuitive material- an odd blend of subj ec tive and obj ective features- be signaled by " materially colored quali ties " (whatever they may be) ?15 The very fixation upon individual textual features renders ontological definitions incapable of specifying any precise relation b etween the fictive text and historical actuality. As Kendall Walton has complained, " The ordinary concept of 'fic tional worlds ' - worlds that are different from the real one, but Study ofLiterature: A Contribution to the Phenomenology ofthe Humane Sciences (Oslo: Univer sitetsforlaget, 1 967) , and Felix Martinez-Bonati, Fictive Discourse and the Structure of Litera ture : A Phenomenological Approach, trans. Philip W. Silver (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1981). 15Unlike the other phenomenological theorists, Hamburger cannot be charged with simply transferring reader response to the text. Indeed, she spots this type of circularity as a pitfall of phenomenological criticism and attacks Ingarden on logical grounds: "The desig nation of the sentences in a novel or in a drama as quasi-judgments implies nothing but the tautological fact that whenever we read a novel or a play we know we are reading a novel or a play" ( The Logic ofLiterature, 20) . Hamburger develops an elaborate set of textual markers of fictionality. Her criteria are, however, bound by the conventions of the nineteenth century realistic novel. And she remains open to the criticism posed to the quantitative and family resemblance theorists in Chapter I: How does one determine the necessary and suffi cient properties that define a work of fiction? 49
Theory worlds nonetheless - is a device to paper over our confusion about . whether or not fictions are real; it is an attempt to have it both ways . " 1 6 And if " fictional worlds " have no relation to the real world - fo r this is finally what spatiotemporal disj unction means, at least for Husserl - then what kind of knowledge can they yield? What is the referent of mimesis - if indeed there is one? The Structure of Mimesis Of the various textual definitions of mimesis, those focusing on structure possess the greatest value. Most trace their lineage to Aris totle, who viewed the salient feature of poetry (in the broad sense) as formal unity. Although the materials of history possess no inherent s tructure, he claimed, focusing as they do upon "not one action but one p eriod of time, " those of poetry are selected in accordance with their capacity to elucidate the power of a work as a structurally unified whole. 1 7 C ritics who discover the differentia of fictionality in s tructure argue that fictional works possess a cohering principle of unity, while nonfictional works are characterized by a certain formal incompleteness derived from the intractability of their raw materials. Thus the Russian Formalists, who undertook a rewriting of Aristote lian poetics in the early decades of the twentieth century, declared that the structural transformation of " story" into "plot" constitutes the essence of fiction-making. " Real incidents , not fictionalized by an author, may make a story, " states Boris Tomashevsky. " The plot, " by contrast, in which " events are arranged and connected according to the order of sequence in which they are presented in the work, " is " wholly an artistic creation. " 1 8 Murray Krieger has chosen " teleol ogy" as the trait distinguishing the novel from the factual report: "Teleology is precisely what poetic form boasts as its essential charac16Kendall L. Walton, "How Remote Are Fictional Worlds from the Real World?" Journal of Aesthetics and A rt Criticism, 37 (Fall 1 978) : r 9 . 17Aristotle, Aristotle 's Poetics: A Translation a n d Commenta ry for Students of Literature, trans. Leon Golden (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, r 968) , chap. 2 3 , p. 42. Hardison, in the commentary section of the volume, stresses the point that, in his distinction between poetry and history, Aristotle does not assert that poetry reveals some sort of higher truth, as Sidney supposed. See also Friedman, Form and Meaning in Fiction (Athens: University of Georgia Press , 1 97 5 ) , 5 - 6. 18Boris Tomashevsky, " Thematics, " in Russian Formalist Criticism: Four Essays, ed. Lee T . Lemon and M arion ] . Reis (Norman: University of Oklahoma Press, 1 964) , 6 8 . 50
The Problem of Assertion teristic. It is just the poet's freedom to put teleology where his obj ect of imitation had none that distinguishes him from even the most ar rogant historian who would fashion the past in the shapes of his pri vate fancy. "19 Ralph W. Rader concludes that "in fiction, the form must totally subsume the whole matter of the work. In most factual works, even when there is literary intent, a good deal of material must necessarily remain only passively adj usted to the form. " 20 As we shall see in the next chapter, the reader' s perception of a high degree of internal coherence in fact is essential to the functioning of the mimetic contract, for the configuration of the text as a whole does conventionally signal mimetic intentions. But, I shall argue, the text' s structural Gestalt is inseparable fr o m its cognitive praxis: structure per se, isolated from function, is meaningless as a criterion of fiction ality, for one could readily argue- as Louis Mink has done- that all conceptualization operates in the configurational mode and that many forms of nonfictional writing are indeed highly structured. 21 The re cent historiographical theory of scholars such as W. B. Gallie and Hayden White may have gone too far in the direction of fictionalizing history, but it has convincingly demonstrated that many of the struc tural features ordinarily associated with the novel also characterize the conventions of nineteenth- and twentieth-century historical narra tion. 22 Factual discourse, they suggest, involves not the absence of Gestalt but the invocation of a different Gestalt. I return to my central contention: mimesis entails a social contract; the textual features that signal its different conventions indicate that the fictional contract is being invoked, but they do not in themselves constitute the essence of fictional discourse. The main problem besetting the various textual theories of mime sis b riefly described here is that they attempt to locate the essence of 19Murray Krieger, " Fiction, History, and Empirical Reality, " Critical Inquiry, l (Decem ber 1 974) : 3 42 . 20Ralph W. Rader, " Literary Form in Fictional Narrative: The Example of Boswell's Johnson, " in Essays in Eighteenth-Centu ry Biography, ed. Philip B . D aghlian (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1 968), 3 9 . 21Louis 0. Mink, " History and Fiction as Modes of Comprehension, " New Litera ry His to ry, l (Spring 1 970) : 541 - 5 8 . 22See W . B. Gallie, Philosophy and the Historical Understanding ( 1 964; New York: S chocken, 1968), chaps. l and 2; Hayden White, Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973 ) . 51
Theory mimesis solely in isolated textual features, without reference to the author/reader contracts within which these elements function. Tex tual theories divorce the fictional work from its social and historical context- from its referent on the one hand, from its producer and consumer on the other. The text therefore emerges as a reified entity presumably containing within itself all meaning and value, rather than as a field of force generating constantly varying relations be tween the author's intentions and the audience' s assumptions , expec tations, and needs. Indeed, the text undergoes a process similar to the phenomenon that Marx labeled " commodity fetishism, " whereby , as Georg Lukacs summarizes it, "a relation between people takes on the character of a thing and thus acquires a 'phantom obj ectivity, ' an au tonomy that seems so strictly rational and all-embracing as to conceal every trace of its fundamental nature: the relation between people . "23 Countering the conception popular among contemporaneous politi cal economists that capital is a " thing, " Marx pointed out that capit;il is a social relation, though mediated by the instrumentality of things: Literary theorists should take a cue from Marx and recognize that the fictional text is likewise a social relation, mediated through the instru mentality of obj ectifiable textual features.
Mentalist Definitions Mentalist definitions of mimesis - that is, definitions seeking the differentia of fictionality in the kinds of responses a text evokes would seem to pose a welcome alternative to the false obj ectivis m of textual theories, in that they bring the question of explaining fiction ality into the realm of social experience. But most mentalist theories of mimesis consider only the response of the reader to textual sig nals, thereby denying the functional importance of the text as a meet ing ground between writer and audience. Affective Theories S ome mentalist critics have identified fiction by its characteristic power to evoke an emotional response in the reader. Fiction is here 23Georg Lukacs,
History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics, trans.
Rodney Livingstone (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1 9 7 1 ) , 83. 52
The Problem of Assertion definable by its effects : we know that a discourse is fictional if it cre ates certain kinds of psychic reactions . Norman Holland maintains that fiction arouses the emotions of readers because it does not call upon them to engage in the " reality-testing" that customarily accom panies nonfiction and thus permits their feelings greater freedom . 24 Helmut Gauss argues that the reading of fictions is " an important control mechanism in our emotional housekeeping, " in that " the ex perience of the fictional tension is an attempt at alleviating the exis tential tension. " 25 Simon Lesser proposes that "fiction gives us com promise formations whereby repressed and repressing forces obtain expression in one and the same product . . . it provides a forum in which the positions of the id, the ego and the superego all receive a hearing. " 26 The difficulties posed by the affective argument should be fairly apparent. To begin with, factual and fictive discourse can hardly be distinguished by any difference in their ability to evoke emotion. True accounts such as The Algiers Motel Incident or The Dia ry ofAnne Frank arouse more powerful feelings of indignation and pity than do many fictional narratives; novels such as The Jungle or The Castle, in their different ways, in fact compel readers to test the reality and con front the tension of their own experience. Similar problems exist for the notion that fictional texts intrinsically provide "compromise for m ations " reconciling the conflicts within ego-structure. Moby Dick may or may not proj ect and resolve a clash of forces analogous to the conflict of superego and id, but Barchester Towers could hardly be said to accomplish a similar therapeutic task. As I shall argue below, fic tions do indeed attempt to resolve contradictions that are experienced subj ectively; but these contradictions can become part of a shared public discourse only if they mediate more general social contradic tions. Affective definitions of fictionality rest upon a fundamental di vision of emotion from intellect and of the self from the social. By the very procedure of isolating emotive response as the differentia of mi24Norman Holland, The Dynamics of Literary Response (New York: Oxford University Press, 1 9 6 1 ) . See also his "Prose and Minds: A Psychoanalytic Approach to Nonfiction , " in The Art of Victorian Prose, ed. George Levine and William Madden (New York: Oxford University Press, 1 968), 3 1 4 - 3 7 . 25Helmut Gaus, The Function of Fiction: The Function of Written Fiction i n the Social Process: An Investigation into the Relation between the Reader's Real World and the Fictional World ofHis Reading (Ghent: E. Story - Scientia, 1 979) , 1 07, l 3 I . 26Simon Lesser, Fiction and the Unconscious (Boston: Beacon, 1 957), 78. 53
Theory mesis, affective theories mechanize the very realm of subj ective expe rience that they would invest with privileged value. As Christopher C audwell remarked of subj ectivist aesthetics , "Beauty and all related values become physiological activity. "27 The isolation of the reader' s reactions fr o m their genesis i n author or text thus implies a curiously impoverished concepton of mind, in which feelings are defined with no relation to their stimuli. Reader-Response Theories A second species of mentalist theory, associated with the label "reader-response criticism, " holds that subj ective j udgment (not nec essarily emotionally charged) is the determinant of a text's essential qualities, including its generic identity. For D avid Bleich, who advo cates that criticism base itself on the "subj ective p aradigm, " textual determinacy of any kind is a logical impossibility, for readers create not only their own texts but also their own conditions for reading texts . 28 For Wolfgang Iser, who appears eager to avoid the solipsism implied by the more radical reader-response theory of Bleich; textual indeterminacy coincides with the very essence of fictional discourse itself. The fictional text "by its very nature must call into question the validity of familiar norms, " declares Iser. Mimesis " represents a reac tion to the thought system which it has chosen and incorporated into its repertoire. This reacton is triggered by the system's limited ability to cope with the multifariousness of reality, thus drawing attention to its deficiencies . " The essence of fictionality thus involves the j uxtapo sition of questions and perspectives, rather than the promulgation or endorsement of any single (or for that matter, contradictory) view: " [Fiction] questions or recodes the signals of external reality in such a way that the reader himself is to find the motives underlying the question, and in doing so he p articipates in producing the mean ing . "29 You may discover one meaning, and I another, Iser con27Christopher Caudwell, Studies and Further Studies in a Dying Culture (New York: Monthly Review, 1 9 7 1 ) , 8o- 8 r . 28David Bleich, Subjective Criticism (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978), II.
29Wolfgang Iser, The Act of Reading: A Theo ry of Aesthetic Response (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978), 87, 72, 74. Iser attempts to qualify his stance by noting that some fictions -he cites chivalric romances and socialist realist novels as instances shore up " unstable" systems of ideas: their propositionality is thus presumably an inverse 54
The Problem of Assertion dudes, not because reality evades determinate formulation, but simply because mimesis does . Iser, it must be conceded, at least admits that the fictionality of a text is not determined by its audience. Where Bleich removes the in tending author from the scene entirely, positing that readers , and readers alone, set the terms of the mimetic contract, Iser holds that authorial intention is coterminous with textual undecidability. But we are left with an unconvincing version of the New Critical crite rion of opacity: individual sentences may not proj ect linguistic ambi guity, but the text as a whole does - indeed, must. Mimesis is antag onistic to the propositions it seems to contain: it presents them for consideration only to deny them any power of assertion. If authors intend to propose views of the world that they want their readers to take seriously, they are ill-advised to do so by means of fictional discourse .
Intentionalist Definitions Textual definitions of mimesis fetishize language, and mentalist definitions fetishize subjective reader response. We sense progress, however, when we turn to intentionalist definitions of mimesis, which view the literary work as " a goal-directed effort made by a creating intellect " ; literary theory must therefore " deal with the role of intention and assign it a proper place in literary understanding. "30 Applied to the problem of defining fictionality, this principle, follow ing Thomas Roberts, means that "fiction is make-believe and let's pretend and let's suppose and let's assume. It is not pretending or befunction of the plausibility of the ideas they contain. This argument strikes me as heavily loaded, since Iser clearly regards works of these kinds as inferior; the bourgeois novel is for him both the model and the type of the fictional contract. For a more effective sort of reader-response criticism, see Peter J . Rabinowitz, "Assertion and Assumption: Fictional Patterns and the External World, " PMLA, 96 (May 198 1 ) : 408 - 1 9. Rabinowitz is interested in working back from the response of the reader to the manipulations and assumptions of the author, and he establishes useful distinctions among what he calls "actual, " "authorial, " "narrative, " and "ideal" audiences in order to analyze the various levels of response that are actuated in the process of reading a fiction. See "Truth in Fiction: A Reexamination of Au diences , " Critical Inquiry, 4 (Autumn 1973 ) : 1 2 1 - 4 r . 30Stein Haugom Olsen, "What I s Poetics?" Philosophical Quarterly, 2 6 (October 1 976) : 35I. 55
Theory
lieving or supposing or assuming: it is what follows an invitation to others to share in a pretending. "31 Mimesis is therefore a species of intentionally defined contract. Roberts summarizes, "A work of fic tion by intention is a small or large body of propositions the author thinks true- even in many cases factually true- framed by a s mall or large body of propositions the author thinks false. "32 Mimesis originates historically in the writer and conveys itself to the reader by means of textual signals that invite reader participation: " I'll pretend" is an invalid declaration if it cannot be assumed to mean "let's pre tend . " The intentionalist argument currently enj oying the greatest pop ularity draws its theoretical framework from speech-act theory. Speech-act theorists of fiction follow J . L. Austin's analysis of any given utterance as comprehending three separate speech acts : the locutionary act (that is, the physical ac.t of uttering words) ; the illocu tionary act (that is, the speaker's goal in making the utterance, such as s tating, asking, ordering) ; and the perlocutionary act (that is, the speaker's effect upon the audience, such as arousing curiosity, confus ing, threatening) . 33 The illocutionary act is seen as the crucial act that defines the fictionality or factuality of a given discourse. " There is no textual property, syntactical or semantic, that will identify a text as a work of fiction, " argues Searle. "What makes it a work of fiction is, so to speak, the illocutionary stance that the author takes toward it, and that stance is a matter of the complex illocutionary intentions that the author has when he writes or otherwise composes it. " These " co mplex illocutionary intentions" are signaled to the reader by ap peal to a " set of horizontal conventions that break the conventions es tablished by the vertical rules of factual discourse. "34 Barbara Herrnstein Smith, who constructs an entire theory of fictionality based upon speech-act theory, posits that the essential fictiveness of novels . . . , as of all literary artworks, is not to be discovered in the unreality of the characters , obj ects, and events
31Thomas J. Roberts, " Fiction outside Literature, " Literary Review, 22 (Fall 1978): 9 . 32Roberts, When Is Something Fiction? (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1 972) , 94- I 0 8 . 33J . L. Austin, How t o Do Things with Words ( 1 9 5 5 ; Oxford: Clarendon, 1 97 5 ) , 94- r n 8 . 34John R. Searle, "The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse, " New Litera ry History, 6 (Winter 1 975) : 3 2 5 , 3 2 6 .
The Problem of Assertion alluded to , but in the unreality of the words, in a novel or tale, it is the
act
alludings
themselves . In o ther
of reporting events, the
act
scribing persons and referring to places, that is fictive. The novel
sents
of de
repre
the verbal action of a man reporting, describing, and referring. 35
For S mith, all "poetry" (meaning fictional discourse) is " fiction" in the sense that it takes as its obj ect of imitation one or another species of "natural" discourse. It is by its very nature a pseudostatement. Robert L. Brown and Martin Steinmann, Jr. , point out that the dif ferentia of fictional discourse- which they call the "pretense-of reporting rule" - is not a grammatical rule constituted by textual fea tures but a " genre-rule" constituted by social practice. "A discourse is fictional, " they argue, "because its speaker or writer intends it to b e so. B u t i t i s taken a s fictional only because the hearer or reader decides to take it so. . . . The decision to read a discourse as fictional or nonfictional is a decision to use one set of constitutive rules rather than another, and we really can't read it -interpret it - at all until we have made this decision. "36 In the various speech-act approaches to the definition of fictionality, the differentia is based, we should note, on the intention of the author: mimetic conventions are enacted be cause the author, as determinate historical agent, wishes to enact them. Intentionalism furnishes grounds for a productive inquiry into the nature of the mimetic contract. First, it provides theoretical ground ing for the notion that factual and fictive disocurse are to be qualita tively distinguished . If mimesis involves an invitation on the part of the author and a decision on the part of the reader to follow certain rules that preclude other rules , then it follows that - to reinvoke Wittgenstein- different rules imply different games . One cannot si multaneously engage in "let's pretend" and take literally the content 35Barbara Herrnstein Smith, " Poetry as Fiction, " New Literary History, 2 (Winter 1 97 1 ) : 272. I n its logical extension, Smith's view o f fiction a s the imitation of nonfictional, or " natural, " discourse is indistinguishable from Johathan Culler's contention that "whenever a work seems to be referring to the world one can argue that this supposed reference is in fact a comment on other texts and postpone the referentiality of the fiction to another mo ment or another level" ("Presupposition and Intertextuality, " Modern Language Notes, 9 1 [December 1 976] : 1 3 8 3 ) . Such postponement can g o o n indefinitely, o f course, and the "referent" becomes, in essence, textuality itself. 36Robert L. Brown and Martin Steinmann, Jr. , "Native Readers of Fiction: A Speech Act and Genre-Rule Approach to Defining Literature, " in What Is Literature? ed. Hernadi (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1 978) , 1 49 - 50. 57
Theory
of the pretense; recognizing the rabbit of fictionality necessarily rules out seeing the duck of factual discourse. Second, intentionalism re quires us to see mimesis as a mode of social praxis . As Olsen puts it, " Authors and readers possess a common institutional framework which allows authors to intend texts as literary works and the reader to interpret them as intended to be taken as literary works . . . . [To identify a text as a literary work] is to assign a role to the text in an in stitution of which one knows the rules. "37 Where mentalist theories are only superficially social (they conflate meaning with reader re sponse and lose track of the author altogether) , intentionalist theories see the author as the originating point of a contractual activity that is realized in the reader's response through the invocation of a " common institutional framework. " Third, intentionalism rescues what is valid in textual and mentalist theories at the same time that it offers a supe rior ground for argument. As Ohmann notes, If the work of literature is mimetic of speech-acts, then it is in a sense
hibiting
ex
both quasi-speech-acts and the sentences that purportedly help
to b ring about these acts . To exhibit them is to direct attention to them, and, among other things, to their intricacy of meaning and their formal regularity. Similarly, since the quasi-speech-acts of literature are not carrying on the world' s business- describing, urging, contracting, etc. - the reader may well attend to them in a non-pragmatic way, and thus allow them to realize their emotive potential. In other words , the suspension of normal illocutionary force tends to shift a reader's atten tion to the locutionary acts themselves and to their perlocutionary effects . 38
lntentionalism clarifies textual and mentalist theories, showing how the "formal regularity" and the "emotive potential" of the mimetic work are highlighted through the writer' s decision to invoke the mi metic contract. D espite its usefulness to a contractual view of mimesis, however, the intentionalist position- particularly its speech-act variant- en counters certain difficulties. The intentionalist critic does not ordi narily specify how the genre-signifying intentions of the author are communicated to the reader, nor, for that matter, why this signaling 370lsen, " Defining a Literary Work, " 1 3 8 . 380hmann, " Speech Acts and the Definiton o f Literature, " Philosophy and Rhetoric, 4 (Winter 1 97 1 ) : 1 7
The Problem of Assertion should take place at all. Roberts does not explain the procedure whereby the " framing" propositions that the author thinks to be false are acknowledged as false by the reader. Ohmann does not tell us how we know that the illocutionary force of a fiction has been sus pended. Searle grants that an investigation into the syntactic and se mantic conventions governing the writing and reading of fictions is necessary to determine how the reader knows when the author has invoked a set of fictive "horizontal conventions . " Yet, in his well known comparison of the opening chapter of an Iris Murdoch novel with a news story from the New York Times, he also makes the con tradictory claim that the fictional text is semantically and syntactically indistinguishable from the j ournalistic one. 39 Along similar lines, S mith argues that Clarendon's description of John Hampden in The Histo ry of Rebellion is generically indistinguishable from the first para graph of Tolstoy's " The Death of Ivan Ilyitch" -a difficult point to square with her view that the difference between factual and fictive discourse is absolute. The solution is not, however, to return to "text" or " reader" and to travel the hermeneutical circle once again. For the abstraction accom panying these definitions derives not from any logical deficiencies in herent in intentionalism as such but from the unduly atomistic con ception of the text and the unduly narrow conception of writer and reader that accompany the particular theories we have examined. These theories fail to view the fictional contract as a fully social phe nomenon; they fragment the act of mimetic representation and dehis toricize the people engaging in the text's communicative contract. Richard Gale's version of "suspended illocutionary force, " for in stance, entails the quite absurd dissolution of individual sentences into assertive and nonassertive components : "The effect of a fictive illocutionary act is to drain of illocutionary force every verb that oc39Because Searle omits discussing the actual conventions that are invoked in the novel and the j ournalistic report, he leaves himself open to " intentional fallacy" accusations, even though he purports to carry the discussion beyond this level. As Lubomfr Dolozel has re marked of Searle's theory of fictionality, "When ascrib ing a certain illocutionary intention to the author, we do so a posteriori, after having determined- intuitively or empirically - the fictional or nonfictional status of his utterance. This is a general weakness of inten tional fallacy: first we decide what are the properties of a text and then we ascribe the prop erties to the author' s intentions (or the failure of these intentions) . The intention itself is not independently testable, at least not by logical procedures . " See his " Commentary, " New Literary History, 6 (Winter 1 975) : 468 . 59
Theory curs within its space. "40 On a somewhat broader s cale, S earle's and Smith's isolation of the opening paragraphs from realistic novels as proof of semantic and syntactic ambiguity is equally fallacious . The passages themselves, to be sure, may contain no telltale signs of their fictionality, but the title p ages that p recede, as well as the dialogue, the interiorizing , the development o f character, and the construction of plot line that follow, are - at least for readers in the past two centuries - unequivocal indicators of Murdoch's or Tolstoy's fic tional intentions . The novelist's incorporation of elements associated with familiar models in j ournalism or history simply requires the reader to be alert to the text' s empirical claims. Presumably a fiction that invokes the aura of recognized modes of factual discourse will ask to be read as a realistic- as opposed to a fantastic- rendition of the configuration of social reality. Even Roberts 's apparently more flexi ble formulation of an opposition between " framing" and " framed" statements in fiction divides the text along false lines . I shall be argu ing quite a different p oint: most sentences in a fictional text simulta neously testify to a nonexistent state of affairs while implying propo sitional claims about the historical world. It is the configuration of the text as a whole, not the p resence of isolable elements, that signals to the reader the author's fictive or nonfictional intentions . Even when these elements are documentary particulars presumably making an unmediated reference to historical actuality (Scott's historical foot notes, for example) , they are subordinated to the terms of a generic contract that guides the reader's comprehension of the text as a whole. The tendency of intentionalist critics to locate fictionality in atom ized components of the text implies a correspondingly atomized and ahistorical conception of author and reader. Apparently Searle's read ers approach Murdoch's novel and the New York Times with no p rior conceptions of what they are doing, responding to each text in pris tine innocence. But writers obviously do not issue generic contracts in social vacuums, and readers do not inhabit the Garden of Eden. Writers are perfectly well acquainted with the primary frameworks that they share with their readers and with the ways that their readers are likely to perceive the relation that any part of a text bears to the whole. Even when authors choose to disrupt or alter these frame40Richard Gale, "The Fictive Use of Language, " Philosophy, 46 (October 1 9 7 1 ) : 3 3 6. 60
The Problem of Assertion works , they do so ordinarily by conventional discursive institutions. We may therefore find it useful, as Robert Weimann urges, to substi tute some such term as " genesis " for "intention, " insofar as genesis encompasses not merely the subj ective wills of authors as individuals but the " total context of which the individual ' generative intention' is only a factor. "41 By contrast, the author and reader to whom Searle and S mith refer bear an uncanny resemblance to the abstract Homo economicus of early bourgeois political theory, who approaches epis temological questions with a tabula rasa and contractual relations with an assumption of unfettered autonomy. In addition to the tendency to fragment texts and to isolate authors from their historical worlds , most intentionalist definitions of mime sis have an even more serious drawback, namely, a tendency to argue that mimesis necessarily suspends illocutionary force and, above all, makes no assertions . The intentionalist definitions discussed here do imply a functionalist approach to literary categories, for they state that literary kinds are constituted by the actual uses that people make of them. These arguments usually carry the paradoxical claim, how ever, that mimesis is that species of discourse that is socially agreed upon to have no funciton. Smith claims that " the context of a fictive utterance . . . is historically indeterminate. "42 Roberts contends that au thors do not attribute propositional significance to their " framing" statements . 43 Brown and Steinmann contend that "all . . . truth con ditions are suspended" in mimesis . 44 Olsen, who understands so well the institutional context of the mimetic contract, concludes that " when statements occur in literary works, they . . . are etiolated. "45 Even Ohmann, who throughout his criticism exhibits an acute awareness of the ideological effects of literature as "performance, " concludes that mimesis possesses " suspended" illocutionary force. 46 Mimesis is thus defined by absence, or negation; it is a gesture with out a referent, and it is marked as a species of discourse by its in41Robert Weimann, Structure and Society in Literary History: Studies in the History and The ory of Historical Criticism (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press , 1 976) , 6. 42Smith, " Poetry as Fiction, " 2 7 5 . 43Despite his p onderous and unhelpful differentiation between the " framing" and the " framed, " Roberts does not make the error of positing that fictions are nonassertive. See the epigraph to this chapter. 44Brown and Steinmann, 1 49 - 5 0 . 450lsen, " Defining a Literary Work, " 1 4 1 . 460hmann, " Speech Acts and the Definition of Literature . "
61
Theory tended refusal to make serious interpretive statements about the world. If fictive discourse is indeed defined by the etiolation or sus pension of illocutionary force, then no fictive mode of cognition ex ists, but simply a conventional disclaimer implicitly attached to all mimetic texts that reads , "Do not take any of this seriously. " The view of fiction as nonassertive discourse enj oys virtually unquestioned status these days. But sometimes our unexamined assumptions are those that require the closest scrutiny. Certainly a brief look at the history of criticism indicates that the contemporary conception of mimesis is in fact a fairly recent phenomenon. Plato wished to expel poets from his republic because they were liars ; Pascal called the poetic imagination " man's ruling faculty, queen of lies and erro r " ; Hume stated that "poets themselves, tho' liars by pro fession, always endeavor to give an air of truth to their fictions. "47 I am not advocating that we reinstate the old view of poets as liars; I am simply saying that one can argue for fiction's distinct status as a mode of discourse without conceding that it consists of nonassertive discourse. Indeed, I shall suggest that quite the opposite is the case: mimesis possesses what Graff calls "hyper-assertive" capacities, 48 and it performs highly significant social funcitons when it mobilizes these capacities . Twentieth-century literary theory has clearly made maj or advances in the definition of fictionality. Instead of assuming separate essences for fictive and factual discourse, it has called upon us to s crutinize the logical b ases for the distinctions that we ordinarily erect between the two . Instead of p ro claiming the correspondence of the mimetic text to some a priori aesthetic universal, it has required us to fo cus our at tention upon actual linguistic, s tructural, and ontological properties routinely found in fictional works . Instead of viewing author and reader as figures governed by preordained responsibilities or limita47Plato, The Republic, trans. Francis MacDonald Cornford (Oxford: Clarendon, 1 9 4 1 ) , p9- 3 3 ; Blaise Pascal, Pensees, trans . H . F . Stewart (New York: Pantheon, 1 950) , no . 7 5 , p . 3 9 ; D avid Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, e d . L. A . Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Clarendon, 1 907) , l 2 I . 48Graff, " Literature a s Assertions, " 1 46 . Those who are familiar with Graff's work on propositionality and assertion will recognize the extent of my indebtedness to his ideas throughout this chapter. For an incisive critique of the antiassertive stance of speech-act theory, see Martha Woodmansee, " Speech-Act Theory and the Perpetuation of the Dogma of Literary Autonomy, " Centrum, 6 (Fall 1 97 8 ) : 7 5 - 8 9 .
62
The Problem of Assertion
tions, it has compelled us to examine their varying contributions to the mimetic contract. Despite these theoretical advances, however, many recent discussions of mimesis have been flawed by the ten dency to dissolve the mimetic contract into its component parts and to minimize its embeddedness in material reality. The text is fetish ized, the author and reader are dehistoricized, and mimesis is divested of the capacity to make assertions. We must demonstrate that the mi metic contract involves a commitment to take seriously the text's propositional claims . We shall now therefore discuss the mode of cognition that is distinctly characteristic of the mimetic contract.
3
Mimesis, Cognition, and the Problem of the Referent Art is "knowledge" in a nonconceptual form and shares with science the fact of being bound to the laws of social processes, of being an "essential phenomenon." . . . Art is distinguished from science by the
mode of its
appropriation of reality . . . . The obj ect of artistic appropriation is "the total content of our existence" (Hegel) , the "whole wealth of the world" ; the "total social obj ect" (Lenin) .Aesthetic reflection, that is, re fers to the totality of economic, social, cultural and ideological processes . - Thomas Metscher
The main p roblem besetting the twentieth-century theories of fictionality discussed in the p receding chapter is that they take as their p remise one or another version of the Kantian view of the aesthetic as " purposive nonpurposiveness. " Assuming that the "pur posive" features of mimetic discourse are directed toward the " non purposive" ends o f linguistic reflexivity, emotive release, or pseudo statement, they define a work as fictional to the extent that it divests itself of the power to refer and to assert. The logic of the formalist ar gument is unremittingly circular. If we wish to argue that fiction constitutes a distinct mode of dis course, we need not concede that fr relinquishes the prerogative to tell the truth; on the contrary, we need to examine its characteristic strat egies for conveying knowledge. Mimesis is, I propose, first and fore most a mode of cognition, enacted through a generic contract of which the purpose is to interpret and evaluate past or present historical actu ality. In the realm of prose fiction, its principal strategy of representa tion is the construction of sets of characters and events that, through their relations with one another, suggest to the reader that the reality
The Problem of the Referent he or she inhabits possesses an analogous configuration. Mimesis in herently generalizes, as do all analogies; through this process of gen eralization it formulates explanations of, and j udgments upon, vari ous forms of social existence. Although fiction portrays concrete persons and events, it operates by means of a process of abstraction, since the particular persons and events represented in the fictional text possess their generalizing resonance only because they are reconcreti zations of broader thematic principles . According to Lenin, The universal exists only in the individual and through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal. Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual. E very uni versal only approximately embraces all the individual obj ects. Every in dividual enters incompletely into the universal. . . . Every individual is connected by thousands of transitions with other
kinds
of individuals
(things, phenomena, processes) . 1
Because o f these " thousands of transitions , " mimesis as a mode of cognition is especially empowered to render knowledge. The mi metic text takes as its referent the world of actual "things, phenom ena, processes " ; and in its characters, actions, and settings it repre sents particular " things, phenomena, processes . " But the procedure whereby the latter convey cognition of the former involves an operation of abstraction and generalization. Analogous configuration is therefore a process of mediation, through which the universal as pects of the referent are replicated in the individual features of the mi metic text. As I shall argue in the next chapter, to proffer and to enter into a mimetic contract are ineluctably ideological acts . "Aesthetic repre sentation, " remarks Thomas Metscher, "is never the merely neutral transformation of empirical reality into the beautiful appearance of the art world, but implies the interpretation of this reality and the adoption of an attitude towards it: aesthetic reflection implies the in terpretation and evaluation of reality in the act of its aesthetic formation. " 2 Fictional representation is, among other things, an activity of persua1V. I. Lenin, Progre ss,
Collected Works, 1 967) , 3 8 :3 59.
trans . George H. Hanna, ed. Robert Daglish (Moscow:
2Thomas Metscher, "Literature a n d A r t a s Ideological Form, "
(Autumn
1 979) : 30;
emphases are his . I quote below from p.
23 .
New Litera ry Histo ry, 9
Theory sion, for it undertakes the representation of people and events that do not exist or have not existed in order to propose evaluative attitudes toward people and events that do exist or have existed. The invention of characters and events possessing differential ontological status thus engages the text in representational procedures that are simultane ously referential and j u dgmental. The mimetic work proposes ethical values and historical beliefs that readers may be assumed to share, and on the basis of these, the work attempts to move its readers to accept values and beliefs more or less consciously endorsed by the author, with which they may well not agree. Mimesis is therefore interpre tive, persuasive, j udgmental, and evaluative, at the same time that it deals cognitively with its referent. But- and here is my main conten tion- rather than retreating from the task of formulating proposi tions about the historical world, mimesis possesses, if anything, an intensified propositional power. "The author articulates an act of cognition in the process of creating the work, " maintains Metscher. "He produces cognition in the work and the recipient acquires cogni tion through the work. " As we shall see, the propositions of the fic tional text in no way lose their status as assertive gestures , even when they are filled with contraditions . I am arguing, in short, that as a mode of cognition, mimesis affords knowledge of both the referent and the subj ect. In this chapter and the one following, I shall attempt to consider each of these entities separately. In so doing, it might appear that I am perpetuating the du alistic view of consciousness and actuality that sustains the antiasser tionist view of mimesis I have been opposing, since formalist theories of fictionality, as we have seen, assume the au ton om y of the perceiv ing (and of the creating) self. But there are two important reasons why an analytical distinction between subj ect and referent remains useful and necessary. First, Marxist criticism has to this point achieved only a rudimentary understanding of the ways in which - to borrow Lenin' s terms - the "known obj ect" of the fictional representation rep roduces the " real obj ect" of historical actuality. Theorists working in the Lukacsian tradition emphasize the text's replication of its referent- almost, at times , to the exclusion of any consideration of the specific ideological vantage point of the authorial subj ect. The world, in other words, writes the text. Theorists work ing in the Althusserian tradition, by contrast, contend that the fic tional text' s referential claims are severely compromised by its neces66
The Problem of the
Referent
sary entrapment within the network of assumptions and paradigms that its author takes as a point of origin. Ideology, in other words, writes the text. I believe both that worlds constitute authors and that authors constitute worlds; my consideration of the mimetic text as both reflection and appropriation is an attempt to map out the phe nomenon of mediation in a way that may prove fruitful for further Marxist inquiry. Second, it is important to keep in mind the distinction between ref erent and subj ect when we consider the genre of the documentary novel. For, as we shall see, the documentary novel, in its various modes, buttresses its claims to generalized cognition by invoking a seemingly unmediated reference to an extratextual reality. Whether this invocation of factual authority is relatively naive, as in Cooper, or self-critical, as in Dos Passos, the problem of cognitive adequacy remains an urgent one. To what extent can a factual reference- ei ther veracious or verisimilitudinous - reinforce the text's generaliz ing propositions about the world it represents? To what extent does the summoning of extratextual testimony simply deepen the text's implication in ideology? And how does the author's proclamation of extra-authorial authority (" author-ity" - a term laden with significa tion) affect the terms of the mimetic contract in the documentary novel? By maintaining an analytical separation between subj ect and referent - at least in the initial stages of our inquiry -we remind our selves that the proj ect of mimetic truth-telling may be more problem atic than it first appears . A truth is being told, with "facts " to back it up, but a teller constructs that truth and chooses those facts .
Analogous Configuration and Representational Modes Analogous configuration proj ects propositions about the text's ref erent by establishing relations among separate elements in the text. Mimetic truth clearly cannot hinge upon the reference of single char acters or events in the text to real persons or happenings , since most of its particulars are invented. Rather, the mutual interactions of dif ferent textual features - characters, events , social conditions, philo sophical debates - determine the text's reference to the world of the reader. According to the terms of the mimetic contract, the reader agrees to view the structures and processes represented in the text as
Theory equivalent to structures and processes existing in historical actuality. An equivalence of function establishes the analogy between world and text: whether naturalistic, realistic, romantic, or fantastic, the textual particulars signal that their roles within the fictional totality correspond to roles assumed by (possibly) quite different particulars in the world of the reader. Thus , despite its characteristic proj ection of a dense specificity, the mimetic text produces cognition through generalization. "Novelistic fictions are, " Roy Pascal notes , " ab strac tions, proj ections of actual relationships isolated from some of the associations with which in real life they are bound, and which are thought by the novelist to be irrelevant to his immediate purpose. "3 Paradoxically, illusion resides in the peculiar concreteness of detail; "reality" is conveyed by relationality. All fictions, I propose, operate according to the strategy of analo gous configuration; they vary considerably, however, in the kinds of contracts they call upon the reader to endorse. Part 2 of this study will be devoted to an examination of the historically altering terms of the mimetic contract accompanying the genre I am calling the docu mentary novel. Invoking here a fictional typology more familiar to my readers, I would suggest that the so-called maj or modes of fic tional narrative- sometimes described as naturalism, realism, ro mance, and fantasy- are simply variations on the basic form of the mimetic contract. In each of these modes, authors set up different sorts of expectations about the kinds of evidence that can be adduced to support the anallogies they are asserting. The point could be sche matized as follows. In a naturalistic novel such as Studs Lonigan, the analogy tends toward a high degree of sociological precision.
Studs : Catholic Irish-American worker possessing false conscious ness : : Danny : Ex- Catholic Irish-American proletarian intellec tual possessing class consciousness . I n a more realistic novel such a s Bleak House, by contrast, the analogy tends to be more general, although it still signifies a particular histori cal time and place. 'Roy Pascal, "Narrative Fictions and Reality: A Comment on Frank Kermode's The Sense ofan Ending, " Novel, I r (Fall 1 977) : 49. 68
The Problem of the Referent
Jo : The poor and oppressed in England of the Industrial Revolu tion : : Lady Dedlock : The wealthy and powerful in England of the Industrial Revolution. A romance such as The Scarlet Letter proposes an analogy of increas ingly remote historical reference, although it still relies upon a certain degree of social and historical specificity .
Hester : Female exemplar of acknowledged sin in Puritan New England : : Dimmesdale : Male exemplar of hidden sin in Puritan New England. A fantasy such as Slaughterhouse-Five rests upon an analogy that moves away from quotidian reality and toward ethical schematism.
Billy Pilgrim : Alienated modern man peal of amoral determinism.
:
: Tralfamadorians : The ap
Analogous configuration is an ineluctably totalizing procedure. As in the Gestalt model, each textual particular must be understood in rela tion to the configuration of the whole if it is to be understood at all. Each of the analogies cited above posits, moreover, that the text' s relation to its referent i s diachronic rather than synchronic. That is, the plot articulates what the author sees as the underlying dynam is of essential social realities . Thus the divergent fates of S tuds and Danny suggest Farrell's j udgment of the tragic effects of false consciousness in the American working class ; Lady Dedlock is morally implicated in the diseased b ody politic that eventually destroys Jo; Hester's tri umph over the forces that wear down Dimmesdale poses an ironic commentary on the moral assessments routinely attached to gender and social position in colonial Boston and reveals the purgative effects of admitting membership in the community of sin; Billy Pilgrim' s calm prediction of his o w n absurd death valorizes the Tralfamador ians' ethical passivity. The felt inevitability of the fictional text' s nar rative teleology conveys the author's sense of the moral or historical tendency embedded in his or her materials . As Henry James re marked, the novelist must "find [for characters] the right relations , those that would most bring them out; [he must] imagine, . . . invent 69
Theory and select and piece together the situations most useful and favour able in the sense of the creatures themselves , the complications they would be most likely to feel. "4 " Situations" and " complications " are a necessary correlative of "relations " : configuration implies motion, and analogy implies destiny. In the various modes of the mimetic contract, the fictional work thus proposes cognition by asserting that its configuration is analo gous to an existing state of historical or moral affairs . The reader' s perception of the particular produces cognition of the general. Even though that rendition of the general is inevitably framed from the au thor's ideological standpoint, the analogizing strategy of the text tends to efface the reader's conscious awareness of the informing authorial perspective. Since the particulars of the text furnish the only available data by which historical actuality is known and j udged, ap pearance is, in mimesis, presented as equivalent to essence. Even if- to anticipate my argument in Chapters 5 through 8 - some tex tual details possess p resumably unmediated referents in historical ac tuality, the text's analogizing procedures still enforce the illusion of equivalence. Documentation supplements rather than supersedes the assertion of generalized correspondence. In naturalistic and realistic novels, however, the felt precision of separate data is integrally related to the effectiveness of the text' s pro posed analogy with its referent. Since the author's rendition of ele ments in historical actuality involves a considerable amount of socio logical specificity, the novelistic contract requires that the depiction of the fictional figures - and of their environments - be apprehended as commensurately accurate. Farrell must carefully relate speech pat terns and demographical changes on Chicago's S outh Side that can be readily corroborated, and his characters must engage in activities that continually illustrate the foundations of consciousness in immediate, felt social relations . Studs Lonigan's relation to its referent is dictated by a high degree of quotidian probability: Studs's relations with fam ily, church, and gang convey general propositions about working class life, but these propositions are taken seriously only if the text successfully replicates behaviors and actions that demonstrate socio logical typicality. Dickens enj oys considerably more imaginative lati tude than does Farrell. Nonetheless, the novelistic contract of Bleak 'Henry J ames, The Portrait ofa Lady, ed. Leon Edel (Boston: Houghton Miffiin, 1963 ) , 5 . 70
The Problem
of
the Referent
House places distinct limits upon the text's departure from the realm of familiar probability, and Dickens must keep careful rein on his affinity for supernatural occurrences such as the spontaneous com bustion of Krook. Naturalistic and realistic novelists are therefore compelled to fulfill their contracts by adhering to fairly stringent con ventions of plausibility. If they wish to tell a large truth about the general, they must tell us many smaller truths about the particular . Mary McCarthy remarks on novels in these traditions , We do really . . . expect a novel to be true, not only true to itself (like a poem or statue) , but true to actual life , which is right around the corner . . . . The presence of fact in fiction, of dates and times and distances, is a kind of reassurance- a guarantee of credibility. If we read a novel, say, about conditions in post-war Germany, we expect it to be an accurate report of [these] conditions . . . ; if we find that it is not, the novel is discredited. 5
McCarthy is not simply espousing a naive positivism here. Realism and naturalism create the expectation of empiricist overdetermina tion: the " guarantee of credibility" is an operational condition accom p anying certain forms of the mimetic contract. In romantic or fantastic fictions, by contrast, the quotidian plausi bility of particular details figures a good deal less crucially in the nov elistic contract. In The Scarlet Letter, Hawthorne replicates the history of Puritan B oston with considerable fidelity (there even was a real Mistress Hibbens, who was executed in 1 656 for witchcraft) , but these data are not required by the novelistic contract he invokes. His tale must be plausibily located in historical reality, but he must also be allowed a universe in which letters blaze in the heavens and bore their way into human flesh. The text takes as its referent a set of histori cally specific gender relations, but it constructs an analogous configu ration around moral questions that are presumed to be largely time less. 6 Vonnegut enj oys even greater license to wander from accepted 5Mary McCarthy, "The Fact in Fiction, " Partisan Review, 27 (Summer 1 960) : 45 1. 6Recently the notions that much American fiction is "romance" and that " romance" in volves a repudiation or avoidance of concretely historical reference have come under sharp attack. Much of this attack is warranted. Harry B. Henderson, one of the first to question the ahistorical underpinnings of the "romance" theory of American literature, noted that even Hawthorne, who dabbled with the supernatural more than many other A merican ro mancers, anchored his fictions in a carefully researched historical background (see Versions 71
Theory canons of plausibility. He can make the Tralfamadorians look as bi zarre as he wishes - the more so the better- so long as they voice philosophical views that effectively outline his moral framework. Ev eryday probabilities of chronology are abandoned, and " facts " about Earthlings - often recapitulated in stark concreteness - are j uxta posed with apparently equivalent "information" about Tralfamador ians. Indeed, documentary data enter the text to enhance its sense of irreality. Vonnegut's prefacing of his tale with a patently autobio graphical reminsicence of the firebombing of D resden - " All this happened, more or less"7- anchors the tale in actual historical events to s tress all the more the strange dislocations Vonnegut sees at the core of contemporary historical actualities . "Reality" is therefore as much present in Slaughterhouse-Five as it is in Studs Lonigan, insofar as both texts aim to render the shape and es sential development of historical actuality, not primarily in its p artic ulars, but in what the author sees as being its significant constitutive p rinciples. The issue is not, then, that some fictional modes are more autotelic and others more referential; all are equally autotelic (config urational) and referential (analogous) at the same time. All are, more over, equally assertive. Even if Vonnegut does not adhere to the so ciological precision of a Farrell, he is as committed to representing reality as is Farrell. Neither text asserts that S tuds or Billy Pilgrim ever lived, but neither suspends its illocutionary force. Each marshals every rhetorical resource available to the specific form of its contract to convince its reader of the validity of its general propositions about human life and destiny. I can anticipate two obj ections to the theory I am setting fo rth here. First, it might be asserted that my analogies are themselves subj ective of the Past: The Historical Imagination in American Fiction [New York: Oxford University Press, 1 974] , esp . 1 1 4 - 26) . I would argue, nonetheless, that the conventional signals ac companying the deployment of historical particulars in The Scarlet Letter are quite different from those accompanying particulars in, say, The Pioneers or "Benito Cereno. " The proce dure of reconcretization in The Scarlet Letter removes the world of the novel considerably from that of Puritan New England, since the essential principles shaping the novel's analo gous configuration are conceived as pointing to a transhistorical realm of truth. For more on the argument that " romance" and " realism" characterize American and English fictions of the mid-nineteenth century, respectively, see Nicolaus Mills, American and English Fiction in the Nineteenth Century: An Antigenre Critique and Comparison (Bloomington: Indiana Uni versity Press, I 97 3 ) . 7Kurt Vonnegut, Slaughterhouse-Five; or The Children's Crusade: A Duty-Dance with Death (New York: Delacorte, 1 969) , 1 . 72
The Problem of the Referent constructs, since not all readers would agree that the relations be tween the characters I cite are best described by the particular analo gies I have framed. Indeed, it might be charged that I am simply masking p ositivist assumptions by transposing my penchant for ob j ectivism from facts to relations : my presumably self-evident analo gies are in fact a highly personal- and ideological- interpretation of the texts involved. To this obj ection I would respond that my analo gies are not intended to be exhaustive or exclusionary descriptions or interpretations of the novels cited. Certainly much more can be said about the relation of Jo to Lady Dedlock than that it conveys a cri tique of class relations: their j uxtaposition also moves us to consider the relation of innocence to corruption, of youth to age, of the op pression of poverty to the oppression of gender, as well as to contem plate the interconnectedness of all human destinies. Similarly, Billy Pilgrim' s flight to Tralfamadore invites not only a meditation on contemporary alienation but also an inquiry into the psychological trauma specific to World War II and its aftermath. My point is quite limited and modest: in considering these novels, we could formulate none of these interpretive patterns and themes if we did not first weigh the nature and extent of these characters ' reference to historical actuality. Jo and Lady Dedlock tell us nothing at all about the human condition if they do not tell us about the peculiar intersection of hu man destinies in the era of the Industrial Revolution. The multiple in terpretive analogies that can be derived from their relationship are contingent upon a specifically referential analogy that affixes them in a particular historical actuality. In the case of Billy Pilgrim and the Tralfamadorians , by contrast, we would be hampered in our efforts to construct derivative analogies if we sought too direct a reference in historical actuality. The Tralfamadorians' mode of existence consti tutes an interesting speculation on relativity theory, but these crea tures are patently imaginative constructs nonetheless; while Billy Pil grim, for all his grounding in the commodity fetishism of a distinctly post- World War II American culture, is a cartoon caricature of con temporary anomie. Whatever grounding his psychological dilemma may have in particular realities of World War II- and Vonnegut' s strongly felt autobiographical presence guarantees such a foundation - his existential situation leads to further interpretation insofar as it is seen as a fairly abstracted representation of the contemporary human condition. When we seek to determine the strategy of analogous con73
Theory
figuration practiced in a given text, then, we are not trying to confine its meaning to its reference. Rather, we are attempting to establish its reference in such a way that its meaning can be more fully under stood. As a second possible obj ection , some readers may still disagree that analogous configuration implies assertion. Fictional works presuma bly may contain propositions about the world and may even render cognition of the world, yet they do not necessarily assert their view of things . To this obj ection I would reply that analogous configuration, while indirect in its method of representation, is a quintessentially as sertive strategy of representation . A is to B as C is to D; this formu lation contains two is's to one as. The fact that is does not occupy the central position of as (which constitutes a kind of equal sign, con necting the world of the novel and that of the reader) does not dimin ish the explanatory force of the analogy. The novel poses a complex, ethically charged, and determinate relation between Jo and Lady D edlock, or between Arthur Dimmesdale and Hester Prynne. If, as I have argued above, analogous configuration necessarily involves ref erence, then the is connecting Jo and Lady Dedlock or Hester Prynne and Arthur Dimmesdale carries as much force as does an is in a work of anthropology or history, since it requires the reader to search out the companion is in historical actuality. The fictional is, of course, represents a different kind of is than that discoverable in much nonfic tional discourse, for it conveys cognition of a generalized kind: we cannot expect a novel to offer a direct representation of an actual state of affairs. As we shall see in Part 2 of this book, even when a text draws verifiable historical particulars into its assertions about the world, these particulars must first be framed by the relevant novelis tic conventions . Nonetheless, the two linking verbs connected by the conj unction do constitute a complete thought- and do possess a for midable capacity to tell the truth.
The Problem of the Referent The theory of analogous configuration I am outlining bears a cer tain resemblance to familiar theories of mimesis - New Critical, Ar istotelian, Lukacsian, Althusserian - but differs from each of these in one or more crucial Jrespects . 74
The Problem of the Referent New Critical theories of fictional representation (at least those that do not construe mimesis as consisting completely in linguistic opac ity) hold that the fictional work possesses a highly ordered configura tion but that this configuration has little to do with reference. Wimsatt and Brooks differentiate fictive from factual discourse on the basis that the former aims at " coherence, " the latter at " correspondence" ; Northrop Frye posits that the "final direction of meaning" in imagi native literature is inward, while that in " descriptive or assertive writ ing" is outward. 8 These criteria of coherence and inwardness clearly bear a certain affinity to my stipulation that mimesis refers to histori cal actuality through its proj ection of relationality, rather than of ver ifiable particularity. But for these theorists, the stress upon configura tion leads to one or another version of the formalist claim that mimetic texts cannot make assertions . Presumably, the greater the coherence or internal direction of the text, the lesser its obligation to make verifiable statements about the historical world. Beauty and Truth exist in inverse proportion to one another. My concept of anal ogous configuration leads to quite a different conclusion. The text' s coherence signals the explanatory abstractions by which the author interprets the historical actuality to which the text analogously corre sponds . Its inwardness is constituted by its abstraction of a pattern of configuration from the external reality that furnishes its referent. Analogous configuration is thus not a retreat from reference; it is a means to reference. My notion of analogous configuration clearly has a good deal more in common with Aristotelian poetics than with modern formalism . My discussion of analogy i s quite close to Aristotle's notion of the poetic universal (that is, " what sort of man turns out to say or do what sort of thing according to probability or necessity" ) . 9 More over, my analysis of narrative as the assertion of a moral teleology places my discussion of mimesis in clear alignment with Aristotle' s insistence upon viewing the poetic text a s a coherent whole shaped by an informing power, or dynamis . Finally, my view that the fictional 8William K. Wimsatt and Cleanth Brooks, Literary Criticism: A Short History (New York: Knopf, 1 9 5 7) ; Northrop Frye, The Anatomy of Criticism: Four Essays (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1 9 5 7) , 74. 9A ristotle, A ristotle's Poetics: A Translation and Commentary for Students of Literature, trans. Leon Golden (Englewood Cliffs : Prentice-Hall, 1 968), chap. 9, p. 1 7 . Below I refer to chap. 25, p . 46. 75
Theory text asserts its appropriation of its referent also accords with his con ception of mimesis as a means of conveying truth. Aristotle may have stipulated that poetry and history aim at different kinds of proposi tionality, but he never held that p oetry's "persuasive impossibilities" do not seek to persuade, or that the poet ' s essential (as opposed to ac cidental) errors do not detract from the adequacy of his representa tion. Nonetheless, my theory departs significantly from Aristotle' s in its conception of the way that the referent is reconcretized in the mimetic work. Aristotle assumes that the poet can directly and unproblemat ically render the essential configuration of the social world and that the " sort of man" portrayed in the text replicates a universal that sim ply and unquestionably exists. He does not consider the possibility that authorial p resuppositions might in some way determine the con ditions of access to the universal, or, indeed, that the universal itself might be the product of social experience, susceptible to challenge and change. The problem of selection and construction is therefore, for Aristotle, socially uncomplicated. The definition of " such a man" implicitly entails property and citizenship , and the perspective from which judgments are framed is restricted to deviations from an ethical norm located firmly within that definition. The universal is confined to the range of moral imperatives accessible to the ruling class ; Aris totle simple was not obliged to construct a theoretical model account ing for a discursive situation where, for example, both Gone with the Wind and Jubilee might purport to be treating the " same" referent, and (adj usting for gender) S carlett O'Hara and Vyry might embody the "kind of man" who enables us to grasp the essence of that refer ent. As Alfred Sohn-Rethel has pointed out, the very activity of con ceptual abstraction was, in Aristotle' s time, relegated to a realm of contemplation only tangentially linked to material activity. 10 While signaling the complexity of a society increasingly penetrated by the exchange relation, the process of conceptual abstraction was sealed off from production; philosophical ideas enj oyed virtual autonomy in relation to practice. Accordingly, the issue of mediation did not arise 1 0Alfred Sohn-Rethel, Intellectual and Manual Labor: A Critique of Epistemology, trans . Martin Sohn-Rethel (Atlantic Highlands, N .J . : Humanities , 1 97 8 ) . See also Herbert Mar cuse, " The Affirmative Character of Culture, " in Negations: Essays in Critical Theory, trans. Jeremy J . Shapiro (Boston: Beacon, 1 96 8 ) , 8 8 - 1 3 3 .
The Problem of the Referent as a relevant question in Aristotle's poetics, and the relation between mimetic abstraction and historical actuality was reduced to a problem of form. My argument clearly situates itself in the Marxist tradition. But here it encounters significant opposition from the schools of both Lukacs and Althusser. Invoking Aristotle and Lenin, Lukacs says that the goal of all great art is " to provide a picture of reality in which the contradiction between appearance and reality, the particular and the general, the immediate and the conceptual, etc. , is so resolved that the two converge into a spontaneous integrity in the direct i mpres sion of the work of art and provide a sense of an inseparable integ rity. " 1 1 He argues that "the totality of the work of art is intensive, and that the self-containment of a work of art is therefore the reflec tion of the process of life in motion and in concrete context. " The re alistic novel is especially suited to this task, declares Lukacs, for it de lineates typical characters who , in their intersecting fates, epitomize the essential dialectic of history in their time. Where for Aristotle the referent was the unfolding of an individual destiny within a fixed uni verse, for Lukacs the referent becomes historical process itself; in deed, "the aesthetic illusion is only possible, " declares Lukacs, "when the work of art reflects the total obj ective process of life with objective accuracy . " Mimetic representation thus necessitates, by definition, the penetration beneath appearance to essence- actually, to essence in-motion- and its criterion for value is political: only works that replicate the traj ectory of history can be said to possess genuine aes thetic value. Lukacs' s argument thus provides consistent grounds for determining the superiority ofjubilee over Gone with the Wind on the "Lukacs, "Art and Objective Truth, " in Writer and Critic and Other Essays, ed. and trans . Arthur D. Kahn (New York: Grosset & Dunlap , Universal Library, 1 9 7 1 ) , 34. The pas sages that I quote below appear on pp. 3 8 , 37, and 4 r . Some readers unfamiliar with the canon of Luk:ics' s work may be puzzled by the discrepancy between my relatively harsh treatment of him here and my approving citation of him in Chapter 7. The reason for my different responses to Luk:ics's work is that Luk:ics himself changes substantially over the years: the revolutionary repudiation of reification in History and Class Consciousness ( 1 923) has become ossified into a reflectionist- and in many ways conservative- advocacy of critical realism by the mid- 1 9 3 os. Lukacs' s later position boxes him into several corners . How, for example, can a writer be condemned for creating reified representations of a reified world if fiction reproduces the essential dynamics of reality? For an acute discussion of the contradictions in the later Luk:ics, see the last chapter of Carolyn Porter's Seeing and Being: The Plight of the Participant Observer in Emerson, James, Adams, and Faulkner (Middle town: Wesleyan University Press, 1 9 8 1 ) .
77
Theory basis of something other than the purely formalistic criterion of inter nal coherence. The great value of Lukacs's theory of mimesis is that it effectively demonstrates how mimesis takes as its referent neither inert particu lars nor timeless universals but specific historical processes . But Lukacs's theory also suffers from a somewhat mechanistic reflection ism, for it ends up conflating a normative description of fiction with a prescriptive one. I am not quarreling with Lukacs 's stipulation that the critic should evaluate the author's implied politics, or with his j udgment that these politics can frequently be said to produce superfi cial, inadequate, or incorrect representations of historical actuality. Marxists must hold that some descriptive interpretations of the social world are more valid than others and that a primary criterion for ad judication among them is political. But for Lukacs to equate the rep resentation of typical characters in Homer's epics, Shakespeare's plays, or the realistic novel with the definition of mimesis as such is faulty logic. By his definition, fiction delineates social tensions through the proj ection of imagined microcosms; to the extent that any work fails to perform this task, it is shallow and also, by exten sion, not fictional. Despite Lukacs 's protests against the positivism of the naturalists, his own reflectionism takes certain features of the ref erent as self-evident, with the difference that he asserts the referent to be essence, rather than epiphenomenon. And where A ristotle's obj ec tivism is understandably linked to the epistemological and ideological limits informing the social synthesis of his time, in the case of Lukacs such naive obj ectivism is less excusable. The evident multiplicity of ideological perspectives informing modern mimetic works should lead toward an increased recognition and a more thorough analysis of the function of ideological abstraction in fictional representation, rather than toward a reductionist definition of mimesis that would exclude whole schools of writers on what are, ultimately, formalistic rather than politicali grounds . To the extent that partisanship enters the process of fictional pro d.u ction, for Lukacs it occurs as a dialectic embedded within the refer ent, as "obj ective partisanship . " The subj ective perspective of the writer, therefore, need not enter the overall mimetic process; what matters, finally, is that historical actuality be neutrally reflected within the totality of the mimetic text. Lukacs's discussion illumi nates the process whereby analogous configuration renders knowl78
The Problem of the Referent
edge of essential historical processes, but it encourages no investiga tion into mimesis as praxis . For all its attention to the dialectics of its referent, mimesis can never be more than a replication of that refer ent: there is no dialectic between author and world. Lukacs' s formu lation thus p rohibits inquiry into the possible meaning of Marx's rather enigmatic remark that literature is one of " the acquired forces of production" 12 (italics added) - in other words, a phenomenon that shapes, and is not merely shaped by, social reality. P aradoxically, then, Lukacs' s insistence that mimesis provides knowledge of the ref erent ends up reducing the significance of that knowledge: fiction tells us nothing that history cannot, for there is no specifically fictional mode of cognition. Where Lukacs errs in the direction of obj ectivism, critics working in the Althusserian paradigm err in the opposite direction by repudi ating the notion of reflection altogether. Fredric Jameson, for exam ple, argues that the mimetic text is grounded in a "historical or ideo logical subtext. " The "paradox of the subtext, " he remarks , is that the literary work or cultural object, as though for the first time, brings into being that very situation to which it is also, at one and the same time, a reaction. It articulates its own situation and textualizes it, thereby en couraging and perpetuating the illusion that the situation itself did not exist before it, that there is nothing but a text, that there never was an extra- or con-textual reality before the text generated it in the form of a mirage. 13
12Marx, quoted in Cliff Slaughter, Marxism, Ideology, and Literature (Atlantic Highlands, N.J . : Humanities, 1 9 80) , 205 . The conception of literature as a "productive force" has not yet been adequately explored within Marxist criticism. Brecht spoke of a "production aes thetic" but did not give it a clear theoretical formulation. Fredric J ameson j ustly observes: " One cannot without intellectual dishonesty assimilate the 'production' of texts . . . to the production of goods by factory workers : writing and thinking are not alienated labor in that sense, and it is surely fatuous for intellectuals to seek to glamorize their tasks - which can for the most part be subsumed under the rubric of the elaboration, reproduction, or cri tique of ideology-by assimilating them to real work on the assembly line and to the expe rience of the resistance of matter in genuine manual labor" ( The Political Unconscious: Narra tive as a Socially Symbolic Act [Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1 9 8 1 ] , 45) . Nonetheless, if we are to avoid a passively reflectionist model of mimetic discourse, it is crucial to see liter ature as in some sense " producing" consciousness in its readers. This need not imply, of course, that writers do not mediate ideology-dominant or otherwise-in the process of producing consciousness : what is produced need not be new, even if its specific articulation is unique. 13J ameson, 82. 79
Theory Jameson thus maintains that a " Real" exists beyond the bounds of textuality . In his formulation, however, it becomes difficult indeed to distinguish the text' s " situation" as discourse from its " situation " in historical actuality, or, even, to determine how the Real is not a mi rage o r simply another text (what Julia Kristeva calls the " geno texte") . 14 Jameson is clearly anxious to retain some sort of referential power for mimesis and to avoid the solipsistic conclusion that "be cause history is a text, the 'referent' does not exist. " But he is very uneasy with the notion of mediation, which, he says, " aims to dem onstrate . . . that the same essence is at work in the specific languages of culture as in the organization of the relations of production. " His tory, as "absent cause, " is " inaccessible to us except in textual form, and . . . our approach to it and to the Real itself necessarily passes through its prior textualization, its narrativization in the political unconscious . "15 The problem with this formulation is that, once all reality and experience have been drawn, however hesitantly, under the rubric of textuality, it becomes virtually impossible to work back to the Real, which itself- as is suggested by Jameson ' s peculiar use of capitaliza tion-becomes mystified and opaque. Textuality may not be all there is, but it is all that matters . The Real is reified as a realm of fact icity existing prior to human intervention; once we fall into the world of textuality, the Real is irrecoverable. Jameson exhorts us to be ma terialists ( "always historicize") , but he removes the epistemological grounds that would enable us to carry out his inj unction. Terry Eagleton, who does not share Jameson's divided allegiance between Hegelian and Althusserian Marxism, j ettisons the category of mediation altogether. According to Eagleton, fiction embodies no representation of historical actuality but only the representation of the ideological paradigms whereby historical actuality is apprehended. " History . . . certainly 'enters' the text, " Eagleton concludes, "but it enters it precisely as ideology, as a presence determined and distorted by its measurable absences . " 16 The screening effect of ideology nec essarily obscures the text's reference to historical actuality; indeed, Eagleton argues, "the literary text' s lack of a direct referent consti1 4.J ulia Kristeva, La revolution du language poetique (Paris: Seuil, 1 974) , 3 3 9 - 40. 1 ".J ameson, 3 5 . 16Terry Eagleton, Criticism and Ideology: A Study in Marxist Literary Theory ( 1 976; Lon don: NLB, Verso, 1 978), 72. The passages quoted below appear on pp. 78, 69, and 9 5 . 80
The Problem of the Referent
tutes the most salient fact about it: its fictiveness . " Mimesis thus in vokes, for Eagleton, the illusion of referentiality: if there is a Real, it exists at the vanishing point of an infinite regress of textual codifica tions. Ideology, finally, not only constitutes historical actuality but also supplies the s ubj ect who tries to appropriate that actuality. "Ide ology . . . so produces and constructs the real, " remarks Eagleton, "as to cast the shadow of its absence over its presence . . . . Ideological space is curved like space itself, and history lies beyond it as only God could lie beyond the universe. " When the referent becomes absence, or even the mysterious Prime Mover of " absent cause, " fiction retreats from offering explanations of historical actuality. "History" and "ideological space" become two incommensurable realms of experience, and fiction can represent only signifying practices, but never the material processes in relation to which these signifying practices are deployed. It is no accident, I think, that both Jameson and Eagleton present History, Ideology, and the Real in almost religious terms : materiality becomes that which is by definition inaccessible to representation, and even mime sis and cognition become hypostatized as incompatible- and antago nistic- kinds of activity. 17 Thomas Lewis, another Althusserian critic, offers a more promis ing discussion of the conjunction of ideology and historical actuality in the mimetic referent, for he attempts to argue that mimesis does indeed posit a referent - a material obj ect of representation, existing beyond authorial consciousness. Lewis remarks, "When most of us as critics want to determine the referent of the text- that is , what the text alludes to or talks about other than itself- we have cultural, so cial practices in mind (the thing-for-us) and not the inert, unsignifying (because untransformed by human labor) . . . realm of the thing-in17For much of my criticism of the Althusserians I am indebted to Tony Bennett's useful Formalism and Marxism (London: Methuen, 1 979) , 1 1 1 - 42. Bennett asserts: "Rather than conceiving of particular ideologies, particular works of literature and particular sciences which, according to their nature and the uses to which they are put, may be either progres sive or regressive in their political implications, each being mapped out as an area of class struggle, Althusser' s positions implied that class struggle takes place between the eternal verities of science, the eternal falsehoods of ideology and the eternal equivocations oflitera ture . . . . Class struggle, that is, is displaced from the sphere of each of these practices and comes to occupy the epistemological spaces between them" ( 1 3 8) . I have argued elsewhere, however, that Bennett himself remains wedded to the Althusserian paradigm, if reluc tantly. See my review of Formalism and Marxism in Modern Philology, So (May 1 9 8 3 ) : 443 46. 81
Theory
itself. " 1 8 He therefore describes the referent as the " cultural ideolog ical unit, " that is, an ideologically constructed set of relations. But Lewis does not argue that this thing-for-us forbids access to the thing-in-itself He invokes Lenin' s distinction between the real obj ect and the known obj ect, and he posits a dual referent: the raw materials of historical actuality and, simultaneously, the particular configura tion imposed upon these materials by the author's favored ideological p aradigm. Different " cultural ideological units" may therefore com pete to cover the same conj unction of historical actualities . The artist makes choices among competing ideological conceptions that are, as he rather opaquely states , "rival formal organizations with a common content experience that itself embodies conflicting elements that may function in varying arrangements with differently graded valences . " This conception of the referent as " cultural ideological unit" thus sug gests how it is possible that both jubilee and Gone with the Wind, with their " rival formal organizations, " can claim to portray the " common content experience" of the Civil War South- and, moreover, to render knowledge of it. Even Lewis' s valuable dis cussion encounters a central difficulty that is, however, endemic to the Althusserian proj ect; his analysis adopts the inevitable Althusserian opposition of Literature and I deol ogy. " The aesthetic effect, " Lewis argues , " consists precisely in the work's disruptive relationship to the ideological materials (cultural units , the stuff of lived experience) that it seizes as its obj ect and trans forms . " That is, something inherent in mimesis itself renders prob lematic its own pro cedures of mediation; mimesis is inherently dis ruptive of, and adversarial toward, the interpretive propositions it contains . The thing-for-us is invariably cast into an ironic light by the thing-in-itself, and the distinguishing feature of mimetic discourse, Lewis concludes, is its "privileged s tatus in relation . . . to ideology, on the one hand, and to knowledge on the other. " The referent in this context, while it may " constitute an obj ect that lends itself to knowl edge, " is "itself neither a real obj ect nor a knowledge. " By disrupting ideology, then, the mimetic text also disrupts reference. Situating mimesis in a kind of discursive limbo between Ideology and S cience, Althusserian theory ends up stripping mimesis of its propositional status. In Althusser' s words : 18Thomas E. Lewis, "Notes toward a Theory of the Referent, " PMLA, 94 (May 1 979) : 463 . The passage quoted below is from p. 47 r . 82
The Art . . . does not give us a
k 'J o wledge
Problem of the
in the
Re ferent
strict sense, i t
therefore does
not replace knowledge (in th e modern sense: scientific knowledge) , but what it gives us does nevertheless maintain a certain
specific relationship
with knowledge. This relationship is not one of identity but one of dif ference . . . . The peculiarity of art is to ' make us see, ' . . . 'make us per ceive, ' ' make us feel' something which
alludes
to reality. 19
Although the Althusserians would no doubt deny the charge, it seems to me that this formulation distinctly resembles the antiasser tionist stance that I criticized in the bourgeois theorists covered in the previous chapter. Iser's notion that fictional texts are distanced from their implied propositions and themes bears a kinship to Lewis's statement that mimesis disrupts ideology; Searle's stipulation that fic tion suspends illocutionary force resembles in some ways Althusser's view that literature "alludes" to reality. By consigning all fictive dis course to an epistemological region midway between ideology and science, moreover, the Althusserian definition makes it impossible to judge whether one representation of historical actuality possesses more legitimacy than another. According to the Althusserian argu ment, Gone with the Wind is as disruptive of ideology as is]ubliee, and the texts offer no criteria for adducing the greater or lesser adequacy of each known object as an explanatory account of the real obj ect that is the Civil War. If Marxist criticism considers itself to be politically committed, this is a peculiar place for it to end up. The view of mimesis as analogous configuration enables us to see fiction as a qualitatively defined mode of discourse, characterized not by language, ontology, or reader response but by its own distinct mode of conveying cognition. It enables us, moreover, to formulate the process by which the fictional text appropriates -and asserts its appropriation of-its referent. But the same referent can furnish the raw material for very different configurations and can suggest widely 19Louis Althusser, "A Letter on Art in Reply to Andre Daspre, " in Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster (London: Monthly Review, 1 9 7 1 ) , 222. In his later Essays in Seif-Criticism, trans. Grahame Lock (London: NLB, 1 976) , Althusser criticizes his own "theoretical tendency" in saying that the distinction between " Ideology" and " Sci ence" differentiates bourgeois ideology from Marxism - which, he says, presents their an tagonism in rationalist and idealist terms ( 1 1 9 - 2 5 ) . This seems to me a valid self-criticism. I have not yet seen it applied to a reworking of the relation of "Literature" to " Science" and "Ideology" in Althusserian literary theory, however. 83
Theory varying propositions about the analogous relation between text and world. This variability exists because analogous configuration is a procedure not only of replication but also of abstraction, and because abstraction is a quintessentially ideological activity.
4 Mimesis, Cognition, and the Prob lem of the Subject
The concrete totality is a totality of thoughts, concrete in thought, in fact a product of thinking and comprehending; but not in any way a product of the concept which thinks and generates itself outside or above observation and perception; a product, rather, of the working-up of observation and conception into concepts.The totality, as it appears in the head, as a totality of thoughts, is a product of a thinking head, which appropriates the world in the only way it can....The subject re tains its autonomous existence outside the head just as before; namely as long as the head's conduct is merely speculative, merely theoretical. Hence, in the theoretical method, the subject, society, must always be kept in mind as the presupposition. -Karl Marx
The critical category of analogous configuration refers to the external thrust of mimesis, its appropriation of a world existing be yond the margins of the text. It has as its dialectical counterpart the critical category of ideological abstraction, which denotes the internal or subjective character of mimesis, its necessary interpretation of his torical actuality from the perspective of an individual author's con sciousness . For when the fictional work reconcretizes actual processes and structures in the historical world, it attempts to persuade the reader of the legitimacy of the author's specific conception of those processes and structures . The relations described among the analo gized persons and occurrences are not evaluatively neutral, after all, but inherently interpretive, judgmental, and ideological. The process of generalization is a process of abstraction, and abstraction necessar ily involves orders and hierarchies, elevations and demotions, all emanating from the authorial subject's conception of the nature of the totality of which the referent is a part. An author creates certain char85
Theory acters and circumstances and not others, and depicts them in a certain way and not another; the text's proj ection of certain qualities and re lations as essential represents the author' s view of the essential nature of things . The acts of proposing and accepting the mimetic contract are there fore political acts . The mimetic contract requires that the reader sus pend beliefs and preferences for the duration of reading and that, as Harold Osborne puts it, he or she "put into abeyance his own natural responses and accept those inherent in the art work. In this way a per son enj oying aesthetically a piece of . . . fictional art can savour evaluative and emotional attitudes other than those which are natural to him in everyday life, putting himself for the time being under the direction of the literary work. "1 This statement does not mean, of course, that authors can impose upon their readers whole structures of feeling with which these readers do not agree. Writers may shape some expectations in their readers, but they also fulfill others: as Peter Rabinowitz has recently argued, authors routinely affirm many of their audience's assumptions at the same time that they assert atti tudes or ideas that are new or unfamiliar. 2 Nor does this mean that readers passively accept the terms of the mimetic contract. Indeed, they may find themselves in Ohmann's situation: "I read against the author, " he declares, "the refractory unseen audience, delivering bronx cheers as I go. "3 But to admit that we read against the author is to concede that the author is demanding from us a response. Ohmann concludes , "Literary mimesis implicates the reader in an imagined so ciety by making him party to the acts that imply it. There is no ethic ally neutral way fo r him to fulfill his role. He must give consent to the ethos of the created society, or reserve his endorsement to one de gree or another. Either way, the poem calls his political imagination into play, presses him into political choice. "4 The fact that this politi'Harold Osborne, "On Artistic Illusion (2) , " British Journal of Aesthetics, 9 Quly 1 969) : 22 1 . 2Peter J . Rabinowitz, "Assertion and Assumption: Fictional Patterns and the External World, " PLMA, 96 (May 198 1 ) : 408 - 1 9 . 30hmann, personal communication, March 5 , 1 98 3 . 40hmann, "Literature a s Act, " i n Approaches to Poetics: Selected Papers.from the English In stitute, ed. Seymour Chatman (New York: Columbia University Press, 1973), 1 02. For an other analysis ofideology and reader response that stresses resistance as well as participation on the part of the reader, see Manfred Neumann, "Literary Production and Reception, " New Litera ry History, 8 (Autumn 1 976) : 107- 26. 86
The Problem of the Subject cal choice is embodied in our response to characters who never lived does not diminish its seriousness.
Theories of Ideology and Theories of Mimesis To say that the mimetic text requires an act of political choice is to assert its embeddedness in ideology. But the term "ideology" is clearly one of the most vexed- and vexing-in current critical dis course. Let me first clarify my own definition of the term. "Ideol ogy" denotes the nexus of concepts by which individuals represent to themselves their situation in the social world. These individuals per haps do not construe this relation as political, but their conception of it nonetheless is political- both in its gep.esis and in its implication. Ideology signifies both false and true consciousness . Since the ruling class in any given form of class society possesses hegemony, it is in evitable that the prevalent guide for understanding reality should dis tort actual relations in such a way as to rationalize existing social ine qualities . At the same time, even dominant ideology contains partial truth; it draws together the conceptual abstractions by which very real individuals explain their relation to the social totality. Moreover, not all ideology is dominant ideology. Residual and emergent modes of thinking are also ideological, and even those that propose a revolu tionary overthrow of existing relations of production are ideological. The debate about ideology is one of the most heated issues in Marxist cultural studies - and justifiably so, since much of what one says about the relation of base to superstructure is shaped by the way one construes the nature of ideology and ideological production. Un fortunately, the writings of Marx and Engels on this subject are self contradictory and provide little help in adjudicating a "correct" defi nition. 5 At times they take ideology to signify simply the reference of 'For more on the different significations of "ideology" in the writings of Marx and Engels, see Raymond Williams, Marxism and Literature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1 977) , 5 5 - 7 r . Also see Bhikhu Parekh, Marx's Theo ry of Ideology (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1982) . Parekh ably delineates the connections between idealism and apologia in Marx's discussion of ideology and defends Marx's own implicit claim to be "beyond" ideology. But Parekh's strongly anti-Leninist bias prevents him from seeing the nonantagonistic contradiction between proletarian class partisanship and intellectual objec tivity. Parekh treats Marx almost exclusively as a philosophical critic of bourgeois society,
Theory all thought to its social origins - that is, any conceptual form; "legal, political, religious, aesthetic, or philosophic, " by which "men be come conscious of [the] conflict [between forces and relations of pro duction] and fight it out. "6 At other times, Marx and Engels imply that ideology necessarily entails idealism and apologia. Thus the Young Hegelians were "ideologists, " as was a "base" and "vulgar" thinker such as Malthu� ; who was a "shameless sycophant of the rul ing classes . "7 At still other times, Marx and Engels imply that ideol ogy simply denotes false consciousness . "Ideology is a process ac complished by the so-called thinker consciously, it is true, but with a false consciousness, " remarked Engels . "The real motive forces im pelling him remain unknown to him; otherwise it simply would not be an ideological process . "8 If we are to understand the strategies of propositionality in docu mentary novels purporting to tell the truth, we must have a clear and consistent understanding of the meaning of ideology and of its rela tion to fictional discourse. I shall briefly summarize the four principal definitions of ideology and explore the views of mimesis they imply. In its most restricted and negative sense of "apologia, " or deliber ately imposed false consciousness, "ideology" refers to systems of ideas consciously promulgated by the ruling class to enforce their he gemony. Thus George Fredrickson, in his study of racist pseudosci ence in the United States during the nineteenth century, designates craniologists and ethnologists such as Nott and Gliddon as "racist ideologists . "9 Nott and Gliddon, he convincingly demonstrates, were well aware of the usefulness of their work to the slavery cause: "ideology" here signifies a system of conceptual domination deliber ately imposed from above. The view of ideology as apologia accuphilosophical rather than as a radical engaged in a committed political praxis. Hence Parekh accuses Marx of falling back upon enlightened self-consciousness as the final arbiter of truth and wrongly concludes that "in conferring upon self-consciousness the power to transcend the deepest influences of class and society, [Marx] remained an idealist" (222) . 6Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, in Basic Writings of Marx and Engels, ed. Lewis Feuer (Garden City: Doubleday, 1959) , 44. 7Marx and Engels, The German Ideology, Part I, in The Marx-Engels Reader, 2d ed. , ed. Robert Tucker (New York: Norton, 1 978) ; Marx, Theories of Surplus Value (Moscow: Progress, 1 968) , 2:420. 8Engels to Mehring, July 14, 1 893 , in Tucker, ed. , The Marx-Engels Reader, 766. 9George Fredrickson, The Black Image in the White Mind: The Debate on Afro-American Character and Destiny, 18r7- r914 (New York: Harper & Row, 19 7 1), chap . 3 .
88
The Problem of the Subject rately enough pinpoints the motives of a novelist like Thomas Dixon, who willfully provoked white separatist hysteria through fictional representations such as The Clansman or The Leopard's Spots. But, de spite its usefulness in describing situations in which ruling classes mo bilize systems of ideas for explicitly propagandistic purposes (and novelists aid in this process) , the view of ideology as apologia is clearly inappropriate for the analysis of fictions possessing little im mediate instrumental value to ruling-class interests. Indeed, it excul pates most writers entirely: if they are not conscious propagandists - and most clearly are not - then they are not political agents at all. In a somewhat looser definition, "ideology" can be taken to mean "false consciousness , " or even "necessary false consciousness . " Franz Jakubowski, for example, associates ideology with the necessary con ceptual distortions derivative from any individual's class position. "Ideology as false, partial consciousness corresponds, " he says, "to a particular position in class society from which a correct, total under standing is impossible. " 10 This formulation has the advantage of avoiding the hypothesis of conspiracy that inevitably attaches to the view of ideology as apologia , while still identifying the class-coded values and assumptions that underlie even the most apparently apoli tical and universalistic discourse. The definition of ideology as false consciousness, however, reduces the discursive operations of con sciousness to the level of secondary epiphenomena, usually deter mined by a reified- and crudely "material" - base. Indeed, in some ways this formulation simply inverts the dualistic epistemological hi erarchy for which Marx and Engels faulted the idealism of the Young Hegelians: ideas and social forces do not interpenetrate but inhabit differential realms, of which one always exercises complete hegem ony over the other. The view of ideology as necessary false con sciousness prohibits, moreover, any consideration of ideological con tradiction: individuals simply reproduce the ideological paradigms prevailing in their social groups, and residual or emergent ideological tendencies can never pose a significant challenge to dominant ideol ogy. Taken to its logical conclusion, indeed, the view of ideology as necessary false consciousness precludes the possibility that people can function as purposive agents of historical change. 10Franz Jakubowski, Ideology and Superstructure in Historical Materialism, trans . Anne Booth (London: Allison & Busby, 1 976) , 103 .
Theory Applied to the theory of fictionality, the view of ideology as false consciousness construes mimesis as a superstructural epiphenomenon that is interesting mainly for what it can reveal about class hegemony in the realm of thought. Lukacs' s later writings on modernism, in which writers are seen as inescapably bound by the reification of mo nopoly capitalism, exemplify a relatively mechanistic formulation of the relation between this conception of ideology and the production of fictional works . Lucien Goldmann's "genetic structuralism" offers a more sophisticated methodology, but its limitations point to the lia bilities that inevitably accompany any theory of mimesis that assumes a model of passive reflection. The greatest literary works, for Gold mann, are those that most clearly express the worldview of the au thor's social class or social group . Defining this "world-vision" as the "whole complex of ideas, aspirations and feelings which links to gether the members of a social group , " Goldmann argues that writers are "exceptional individuals who either actually achieve or who come very close to achieving a completely integrated and coherent view of what they and the social class to which they belong are trying to do . "11 The literary text, according to Goldmann, reproduces in its structural coherence the explanatory frameworks whereby an author and his or her social class attempt to account for their position in the order of things . The ideological and formal configuration of the text is thus "homologous " with the dominant structure of consciousness informing both the authorial subj ect and the social group . The primary virtues of Goldmann' s formulation are that it ac counts for the intersection of individual and social consciousness within literary structures and it sees both reference and ideological abstraction as directed toward processes rather than inert particulari ties . Goldmann' s concern with what Raymond Williams calls "struc tures of feeling" 12 thus enables us to grasp ideology as the lived expe"Lucien Goldmann, The Hidden God: A Study in Tragic Vision in the Pensees of Pascal and the Tragedies of Racine, trans . Philip Thody (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1 969) , 1 7 . The passage quoted below appears o n p . 1 9 . As will become clear i n Chapter 6, Gold mann's conception of "homologous structures" is quite different from my conception of "homologous configuration, " which I see as distinctly related to the realist project. For an additional critique of the notion that ruling classes maintain dominance by means of ideo logical hegemony, see Nicholas Abercrombie, Bryan S. Turner, et ai . , The Dominant Ideol ogy Thesis (London: Allen & Unwin, 1 979) . 12Williams, 1 2 8 - 3 5 . For an analysis of Goldmann's influence on Williams's assimilation of continental Marxism into the English tradition, see Edward Said, "Traveling Theory , " 90
The Problem of the Subject
rience of a particular social group. But Goldmann's argument suffers from a perilous apriorism. Presumably one need only investigate Jan senism to know the essential features of Racine's and Pascal's world outlooks, or vice versa; the ideological configuration of the text bears a homologous relation to mental structures in both the author and the group, and identity simply reproduces itself on various levels of structural replication. Apparently no distinct mode of cognition char acterizes mimetic discourse: mimesis is simply a form of ideology. Moreover, we might query whether writers - "great" or other wise- can be so readily assimilated to a "collective group conscious ness" as Goldmann supposes . Ideological determination, I would ar gue, should apply less to the restriction of subj ects to the world outlooks of their classes than to the process by which different classes and ideological perspectives are mutually positioned. Individuals, while likely to be ideologically aligned with the social groups of their origin, are capable of situating themselves at various places in this configuration. The range of conceptual abstractions accessible to a particular individual is limited more by the overall configuration of the mode of production than by the person' s class positioning. Furthermore, Goldmann' s conception of mimesis as a mediation of unified and consistent ideology implies that the coherence of the text is homologous with the coherence of the group consciousness that it presumably mediates . Aesthetic structure reproduces the structure of ideology; coherence signals the supersession of contradiction. Any given ideology indeed attempts to eradicate contradiction and to pro vide a comprehensive- if not always rational- explanatory frame work. But we cannot therefore assume that any person's perspective is wholly constituted by a single ideological stance and uninfluenced by opposing positions . Homology, for Goldmann, ultimately im plies homeostasis; the text may include contradictions, but these can readily be synthesized into a unified world view. Goldmann' s view of mimesis precludes cognition of contradiction, for the subj ect emerges as hopelessly enmeshed in ideological paradigms that are generated by, but can never anticipate changes in, the social relations of produc tion. By a curious twist, then, Goldmann's conception of "homolo gous structures" precludes cognition of the subj ect. The very stress in his The World, the Text, and the Critic (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1 9 8 3 ) , 226-47. 9I
Theory upon "world-vision" precludes attention to the individual author as viewer of the world. Althusser, in the most significant reaction against the Hegelian Marxism of Lukacs and Goldmann, has proposed that ideology is, in stead, a " 'Representation' of the Imaginary Relationship of Individu als to the Real Conditions of Existence" ; 13 it is "determined in the last instance" by the economic infrastructure and the political impera tives of the ruling class and masks the true nature of the social rela tions of production, but it is also inseparable from the infrastructure and indeed constitutes a form of social activity. Ideology thus simul taneously serves the interests of the ruling class and enj oys relative . autonomy in its cognitive operations by "interpellating the individual as a (free) subject in order that he shall submit freely to the commandments of the Subject i . e . in order that he shall freely accept his subjection . " Employing Lacan's conception of the political character of the unconscious, Althusser argues that ideology gives people the illusion that they are independent agents when they are not. Rather than consisting merely of false consciousness , however, ideology articulates the real conditions - the " Subject-ion" -of their existence. The Althusserian formulation at first seems to offer distinct advan tages to a theory of mimesis. First, it suggests that ideology is itself a form of representation, rather than a reflection of preexisting reali ties. The representational procedures of fiction thus reproduce not a passive or static referent but the actual procedures by which con sciousness explains reality to itself. According to Pierre Macherey, In that evocative power, by which it denotes a specific reality, [literary
discourse) imitates the everyday language which is the language of ide ology. We could offer a provisional definition of literature as being characterised by this power of parody. Mingling the real uses of lan guage in an endless confrontation, it concludes by
revealing
their truth.
Experimenting with language rather than inventing it, the literary work is both the analogy of a knowledge and a caricature of customary ideo logy. 14
13Althusser, "Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses (Notes toward an Investiga tion) , " in Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster (London: NLB, 1 9 7 1 ) , 1 62, 1 82 . 14Pierre Macherey, A Theory of Litera ry Production, trans .. Geoffrey Wall (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1 978), 59. 92
The Problem of the Subj ect
Moreover, the Althusserian formulation would appear to take into account the effect of ideological contradiction routinely accompany ing the mimetic contract. As Lewis notes , "The text disturbs ideol ogy . . . by j uxtaposing within itself alternative or competing ideo logical clusters (partial semantic fields) and articulating them within a common but conflictive semantic space so as to point out the artificial unity and false pretensions of individual ideological systems as such. " 1 5 Fiction does not simply reproduce hegemony; it is empow ered to air oppositional views. If we examine the Althusserian theories of mimesis more closely, however, we see that their weakness in providing a description of the referent necessarily affects their formulations of the subj ect as well. For the Althusserians highlight, not an ideological contradiction within the author, but a contradiction between two hypostatized cat egories, Ideology and Literature. Mimesis thus emerges curiously free of the taint of ideology. As Macherey puts it, the fictional work " gives an implicit critique of its ideological content, if only because it resists being incorporated into the flux of ideology in order to give a determinate representation of it. "1 6 The price that mimesis pays for its subversive relation to ideology, however, is considerable. " Fiction, not to be confused with illusion, is the substitute for, if not the equiv alent of, knowledge. " Mimesis represents the procedures of represen tation, but, as metarepresentation, it is ontologically separated from the referent. The subj ect is eradicated; or more precisely, he or she is "inserted" into ideology, and authorial ideology is relegated to an in significant position between " general ideology" on the one hand and the "ideology of the text" on the other. 17 Despite their evident incompatibility on many points , the Luk:icsian and the Althusserian approaches to fictional representation demonstrate a curious convergence. Both obj ectify forces beyond 15Thomas E . Lewis, "Notes toward a Theory of the Referent, " PMLA, 94 (May 1 979) : 47 1 . 16Macherey, 64. 17Eagleton, Criticism and Ideology: A Study in Marxist Literary Theo ry ( 1 976; London: NLB, Verso , 1 978), 5 9 - 60. Tony Bennett, in his critique of the Althusserians, suggests that the later work of Renee B alibar and Dominique Laporte corrects the idealist errors of the work of Macherey and Eagleton. I do not agree: the relation of literature to S cience and Ideology is treated in more complexity in a study such as B alibar and Laporte's Les Fran(ais jictifs (Paris: Hachette, 1 974) , but there abides the notion that literature is somehow espe cially privileged to subvert the material " repressed" by ideology. 93
Theory the subj ect (forces of production and of textuality) and both reduce the significance of authorial intervention in history. Lukacs claims that the contradiction within the author is relatively unimpor tant- B alzac can be a Royalist, S cott a conservative- so long as the text replicates in nuce the contradictions of the historical moment. The dialectic of historical actuality writes the text, in other words: the novelist, preferably the realistic novelist, is its amanuensis . D espite its useful insistence that the text treats an independently existing obj ect of representation, then, the Lukacs/Goldmann formulation ulti mately fetishizes the forces of production; the subj ect emerges as the obj ect of historical forces . The Althusserians, on the other hand, mar ginalize the role of the subj ect because- despite occasional nods to " determination in the last instance" by economic fo rces - ideology becomes virtually omnipotent. Accordingly, the superstructure is fetishized, and the subj ect is enmeshed in a web of hegemonic ideo logical assumptions . Fiction heroically protests this hegemony, but its assertions are impotent, divested of status as knowledge, or S ci ence. For the Althusserians , the act of fictional representation, rather than its substance, produces contradiction, which is obj ectified- in essentially formalistic terms - as a clash between epistemological ca tegories . The most useful definition of ideology remains that of Lenin, who asserted that the necessary incompleteness or distortion of an ideolog ical posture does not preclude access to a reality existing beyond ideo logical appropriation. "In a society torn by class antagonisms there can never be a non-class or an above-class ideology, " 18 Lenin de clared . But, "if truth is only an ideological form, then there can be no truth independent of the subj ect, of humanity. " 19 One need not therefore endorse the positivistic doctrine that thought directly re capitulates the " real obj ect, " he argued, in order to propose a materi alist theory of knowledge. " The existence of the thing reflected inde pendent of the reflection (the independence of the external world from the mind) , is the fundamental tenet of materialism . " While all thought, including science, is ideological ( " that science is non-par tisan in the struggle of materialism against idealism and religion is a 18Lenin, What Is to Be Done? in Collected Works, trans. George H. Hanna, ed. Robert D aglish (Moscow: Progress, 1 967) , 5 : 3 84. 19Lenin, Materialism and Empirio-Criticism, in Collected Works, 1 4 : 1 2 3 . The statements quoted below appear on pp. 1 2 3 , 1 3 9, and 1 3 7. 94
The Problem of the Subject favorite idea . . . of all modern bourgeois professors") , it does not fol low that all ideological stances are equally limited in their appropria tion of the " real obj ect. " On the contrary, dialectics " recognizes the relativity of all our knowledge, not in the sense of denying obj ective truth, but in the sense that the limits of approximation of our knowl edge to this truth are historically conditioned. " And, in this process of historical conditioning, political partisanship is the index to greater or lesser obj ectivity. Ideology is, finally, partisan discourse encoding partisan knowledge. Lenin thus declares unabashedly that "the task of the socialists " is to be the "ideological leaders of the proletariat" ; 20 "indeed, there is only one strictly proletarian ideology, and that is Marxism . " 2 1 According to the Leninist formulation, the representations of dis course necessarily include distortions of some kind; even the "prole tarian ideology" that would propose itself as the most advanced and obj ective form of knowledge must acknowledge its historical limita tion. But this does not mean that ideology is foreclosed from a realm of truth accessible only to science, for science itself is constituted by procedures of ideological appropriation and construction. Ideology is not therefore placed in contradiction with science, as in the Althusser ian formulation, but instead becomes an arena of contradiction: the class struggle takes place in the realm of conceptual abstraction as well as in the realm of social processes . The essence of historical un derstanding, remarked Lenin, is the "recognition of the contradic tory, mutually exclusive, opposite tendencies in all the phenomena and processes of nature (including mind and society) . " 22
Mimesis and Ideological Contradiction Of course, Lenin himself did not formulate a theory of mimesis, but his conception of consciousness as the battleground of ideology does, I believe, carry some significant implications for Marxist liter ary theory. I suggest, for example, that mimesis affords an abstraction of ideological contradictions within the author, contradictions that mediate in a unique way the broader contradictions shaping the soci20Lenin, "What the 'Friends of the People' Are, " in Collected Works, 1 : 298. 21Lenin, "A New Revolutionary Workers' Association, " in Collected Works, 8 : 5 0 5 22Lenin, Collected Works, 3 8 : 3 5 7- 5 8 . 95
.
Theory ety at large. Since any given social formation at a particular historical j uncture is characterized by the contradictory interplay of many ide ologies, any given individual is therefore likely to endorse not one but a constellation of ideological stances - separately univocal and unproblematic, perhaps , but by no means logically compatible when yoked together. For example, an ideology of Christian humanism can contradict, and yet coexist with, an ideology of racism; likewise an ideology of pacilfism with an ideology of patriotism. We see such apparently illogical admixtures everyday; writers, I propose, are not more exempt from this condition than are o ther people. Indeed, I would argue that the highlighting of contradiction is central to the particular kind of cognition that mimesis proj ects. Philosophy, politi cal theory, and o ther modes of discourse that codify ideology s trive toward not merely the containment but the eradication of contradic tion. These modes allow complexity, but not contradiction; a pri marily analytical system of thought derives its effectiveness from the logical consistency of its assertions, as well as from the explanatory power of its central propositions . To the extent that the central pre suppositions of a body o f philosophical or political thought contain contradictions, they lessen its explanatory force. Although formu lated by an individual or individuals, an analytical system of thought is therefore transindividual. One can be a Platonist or a Marxist (Plato and Marx have at least this much in common) , but one cannot in the same sense be a Dickensian; an individual may be only a Dickens fan or a Dickens s cholar, orientations that clearly lead one toward the particularity of the Dickensian mode of appropriating historical actuality. I am not, it should be noted, reiterating in Marxist form a recycled version of the New Critical axiom that fiction conveys irony or para dox, but nothing like determinate explanatory propositions . Quite the contrary: I am arguing that the knowledge that fiction conveys is the
knowledge of the contradictory subjective appropriation of an objective social reality . 23 As a result, aesthetic categories that are frequently thought "Bakhtin also argues forthe centrality of contradiction in mimesis. Compare his de s cription of "heteroglossia" in language: " Every concrete utterance of a speaking subject serves as a point where centrifugal as well as centripetal forces are brought to bear. The pro cesses of centralization and decentralization, of unification and disunification, intersect in the utterance; the utterance not only answers the requirements of an individualized embodi ment of a speech act, but it answers the requirements of heteroglossia as well; it is in fact an active p articipant in such speech diversity. And this p articipation of every utterance in !iv-
The Problem of the Subj ect
of as exclusively technical or structural should instead be viewed as rhetorical articulations of the text's attempt at synthesizing its in forming contradictions. The feature that we often term " conflict, " or "tension, " could be fruitfully viewed as the structural embodiment of the main ideological contradiction in the text. Similarly, the evalua tive criterion that we term "aesthetic coherence" could be seen as an assessment of how persuasive the author was in attributing primacy to one aspect of that main contradiction. Alternate possibili ties -moral, political, psychological-are entertained, savored in their potentiality, but finally subordinated to a specific choice that makes a rhetorical claim upon the reader's allegiance. The aspect we term "complexity" is the full imaginative play given to alternate ten dencies and possibilities . And the completeness we expect for suc cessful closure is a recognition of the fact that the author has plausibly moved the text's represented contradiction toward a synthesis that takes into account the multiple minor contradictions that shape the main contradiction. Yet we are under no compulsion to produce a unified theory of the text that eliminates every contradiction under the guise of a broader principle of formal unity. If the text proj ects irreconcilable propositions, so be it. Such propositions are not nec essarily assimilable to an ironic principle of synthesis; they simply testify to the author's inability to resolve all the contradictory ideological abstractions that the text has set forth for consideration. 24 ing heteroglossia determines the linguistic profile and style of the utterance to no less a de gree than its inclusion in any normative-centralizing system of a unitary language" ( The Di alogic Imagination: Four Essays, ed. Michael Holquist, trans . Caryl Emerson and Holquist [Austin: University of Texas Press, 1 98 3 ] , 272). Clearly Bakhtin would take a strong stand against any literary version of the "dominant ideology thesis . " Because Bakhtin insists upon locating contradiction within language, however, rather than within the subj ect who deploys language, he runs the risk of fetishizing the linguistic medium. The utterance, he declares, is a "contradiction-ridden, tension-filled unity of two embattled tendencies in the life of the language" (272, italics added) . 24ln Language and Materialism : Developments in Semiology and the Theory of the Subject (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1 977) , Rosalind Coward and John Ellis quite correctly argue that the Althusserian theory of ideology reduces the subj ect to a contradiction-free unity incapable of purposive opposition to dominant ideology. Their argument is, how ever, largely vitiated by their Lacanian contention that the primary locus of contradiction within the subject is the conflict between the unconscious and the conscious rather than within the sphere of ideology itself. To be sure, ideological contradiction need not be fully conscious, and often contradiction within the subj ect can be located between conscious be liefs and unconscious proclivities. But to hypostatize the contradiction as one between the unconscious and the conscious and to posit that coherent subjectivity is itself an ideological illusion is, it seems to me, to divest internal contradiction of its full political significance.
97
Theory In short, the critic, by treating the text as a proj ection of ideological contradiction internal to the author, can account for the characteristic admixture of conflicting evaluative attitudes in the mimetic text's representation of its referent. That is, the text's postulation of relationality in its referent- analogous configuration- mediates the ideological relationality within the subject at the same time that it of fers an interpretation of actual relationships and processes in the social world. Textual contradictions and ambiguities do not therefore signal the freedom of art working against the determinism of ideology; rather, they represent the author's involvement with opposing possi bilities existing right within the ideological class struggle. The au thor's conception of these possibilities is determined by the configu ration of social forces in his or her time (by the prevalent form of the exchange relation, as I shall argue) , which disturbs us only if we as sume that consciousness is more autonomous than social. Indeed, when we grant that texts composed in class society ordinar ily - though not always- synthesize their contradictions along the lines of dominant ideology, we simply reaffirm what we already know: the ruling class possesses hegemony . Nonetheless, an investi gation into the process by which any given mimetic text produces ideological synthesis affords a view of the subj ective arena of class struggle. By bringing to light the conflict that precedes synthesis, mi mesis reveals the provisional character of ruling-class hegemony. So long as there is contradiction, secondary aspects may become pri mary; emergent, submerged, or adversarial tendencies may become dominant . The radical insight produced by Marxist criticism here is not the delineation of the determinism of productive forces nor the celebration of the oppositional relation of literature to ideology but the demonstration that ideology, as lived, is never a seamless whole, that where there is hegemony there is also contradiction. This knowl edge, I believe, is useful.
Abstraction, Mimesis, and Mediation Lenin's theory of ideology gives us the basis for resurrecting the authorial subj ect in Marxist criticism and for understanding the cen trality of ideological contradiction in mimesis . It is still necessary, however, to describe the nature and function of ideological abstrac-
The Problem of the Subject tion- that is, the procedure by which the concrete particulars of the referent are abstracted and then reconcretized in the particulars of the fictional text. It is especially important to develop such a description for a study of the documentary novel, for we shall be examining a se ries of mimetic contracts in which the author would have the reader think that the text replicates its referent (or at least certain features of its referent) in an unabstracted and unmediated way. The key term on which I shall focus here is " abstraction, " to which I attach the cluster of meanings developed by Alfred Sohn-Rethel in his Intellectual and Manual Labor: A Critique of Ep istemology . Sohn Rethel argues that the "socially necessary forms of thinking of an ep och are those in conformity with the socially synthetic functions of that epoch. " In particular, the prevalent form of the "social synthe sis " - which he defines as " the network of relations by which society forms a whole " - is determined by the "network of relations " that constitutes the dominant form of the exchange relation. 25 This ex change relation is, essentially, an abstraction, for it requires a dualism between concrete use-values and their abstract character as embodi ments of equivalent labor. Thus, the "first nature" of commodities becomes subordinated to their "second nature" - that is , their func tion as use values becomes subordinated to their function as repre sentatives of an entire system of abstract equivalences. By a curious paradox, then, the concrete and material existence of commodities becomes less real than the "real abstraction" - that is, the structural incorporation of the second nature of commodities into the configu ration of society as a whole. The specific form of this exchange relation varies, of course, from epoch to epoch. In societies in which exchange is facilitated by money (the universal equivalent) but does not penetrate the labor process it self, generality can be discerned in particularity, but it does not as sume a fetish character divorcing it entirely from particularity. As Marx put it, "In the exchange of money for labour for service, with the aim of direct consumption, a real exchange always takes place; the fact that amounts of labour are exchanged on both sides is of merely for mal interest for measuring the particular forms of the utility of labour by comparing them with each other. This concerns only the fo rm of 25Sohn-Rethel, Intellectual and Manual Labor: A Critique of Epistemology, trans. Martin Sohn-Rethel (Atlantic Highlands, N.J. : Humanities, 1 978), 6.
99
Theory their exchange; but it does not form its content. "26 In societies charac terized by capital formation in its various phases, by contrast, the real abstraction comes to pervade all spheres of existence, since the ex change relation comes now to penetrate the process of production it self, the very "interior of the commodity. " The phenomena of com modity fetishism and reification, described by Marx and elaborated subsequently by many theorists, are the fruits of this development, describing both re:al conditions of existence and the conceptual ab stractions to which these conditions give rise. Abstraction is thus a paradoxical historical phenomenon. O n the one hand, it provides the material b asis for all advances in theoretical knowledge, since it establishes the actual immanence of general equi valences within particulars . On the other hand, it increasingly pro hibits the move that Hegel termed the " return to the concrete, " whereby abstraction can realize its progress by altering the concretion to which it is bound. 27 Moreover, abstraction is at once a reflection of existing social and economic realities and also a force that can pro duce new social and economic realities . It is constitutive of both the base and the superstructure, and it furnishes the principal means for mediation between the two . For, as Sohn-Rethel is careful to point out, the connection between the abstractions of intellectual produc tion and those characterizing the exchange relation does not consist merely in their structural resemblance, and abstraction is not simply a heuristic device. " Not only analogy but true identity exists between the formal elemen1ts of the social synthesis and the formal constituents of cognition, " Sohn-Rethel insists . "The conceptual b asis of cogni tion is logically and historically conditioned by the basic fo rmation of 26Marx, Grundrisse: Foundations ofthe Critique of Political Economy, trans. Martin Nicolaus (New York: Random House/Vintage, 1 973), 469. 27For more on the relation between abstraction and obj ectification, see below, Chapter 6. "It is not the fact that the human being objectifies himself inhumanly, in opposition to him self, but the fact that he objectifies himself in distinction from and in opposition to abstract thinking, " Marx remarked in his critique of Hegel, " that constitutes the posited essence of the estrangement and the thing to be superseded. " For Hegel, the " return to the concrete" was rendered problematic not because the social organization of reality prevents such a move but because it is thought itself that produces alienation from the concrete in the first place. For Hegel, Marx observed, "The whole histo ry of the alienation process and the whole process of the retraction of the alienation is therefore nothing but the history of the production of abstract (i. e. , absolute) thought-of logical, speculative thought" (Economic and Philo sophic Manuscripts of r844, trans. Martin Milligan, ed. Dick ] . Struik [New York: Interna tional, 1 969], 1 7 5 ) . JOO
The Problem of the
Subject
the social synthesis . "28 Thus, for example, the conceptual abstrac tions of bourgeois empiricism are, Sohn-Rethel declares, in their es sence "non-empirical, " for they take as their premise the fundamental separation of the activities of the abstracting intellect from the realm of the first nature. The Cartesian compulsion to view the world as an object awaiting the experimental activity of the ego cogitans mediates the emerging dominance of the second nature over the first nature in early capitalist society, producing a "knowledge of nature" in "com modity form. " Similarly, the later hypostatization of a realm of tran scendental subjectivity mediates the consolidated hegemony of the second nature abstraction: Kant's transcendental subject, Sohn-Rethel declares, is a "fetish conception of the capital function of money. " Sohn-Rethel develops his theory of abstraction in relation to his critique of bourgeois science, but it is also useful, I believe, for ap proaching the knotty problems of reference and ideology in mimesis . His description of abstraction as a feature both of the social synthesis and of the ideas people develop to understand the social synthesis has important bearing upon the procedures of abstraction involved in fic tional creation. The mimetic text presents its people and events as concrete, but these elements, as we have seen, are in fact reconcret ized representations of a referent that has undergone a process of ab straction in the author's consciousness . I hypothesize that, just as dominant conceptual abstractions in any era mediate the prevalent form of the exchange relation- whether as explicitly formulated so cial theories or, more likely, as common sense epistemological as sumptions - so the mimetic text mediates these conceptual abstrac tions. It is, in other words, a mediation of a mediation, reproducing both real social relations and ideological constructions of those rela tions. And its distinctive feature, qua mimesis, is its articulation of both real and conceptual abstractions by means of a constructed con creteness; its assertive power resides in its production of illusion. Sohn-Rethel's description of the dual nature of abstraction should 28Sohn-Rethel, 6 1 . The statements quoted below appear on pp. 1 3 2 and 77. While Lukacs, in History and Class Consciousness, holds that the abstraction of thought is engen dered by capitalist reification, Sohn-Rethel argues -and I think he is right-that concep tual abstraction accompanies much less sophisticated social formations in which money comes to serve as the "universal equivalent. " Marx stated, "Money may exist, and did exist historically, before capital existed. " . . . "As a result, the path of abstract thought, rising from the simple to the combined" corresponds "to the real historical process" (Grundrisse, 1 02).
IOI
Theory be helpful for the present study in a number of ways. First, it enables us to locate the problem of mimetic mediation squarely within the base-superstructure paradigm- a procedure that is, as I have indi cated, necessary in any account of literary production that purports to be genuinely materialist. The equivalences that the text asserts be tween its representation and its referent are of course ideological equivalences, since they arise from a process of generalization and ab straction that articulates the author's attempt to make sense of the so cial world. At the same time, the conceptual abstractions that mime sis takes as it premise are not chimerical constructs unable to illuminate real states of affairs; on the contrary, they mediate actual social relations . Abstraction is , in short, a property of both the sub j ect and the referent. Furthermore, Sohn-Rethel's formulation of the relation between conceptual and real abstractions enables us to resolve some of the problems that, as we have seen, beset the Lukacsian and Althusserian theories of mimesis . We need not eradicate the subj ect if we wish to argue that the text Jrenders cognitio n of its referent. Rather, we see that the subj ect's cha.racteristic method of abstraction is itself a media tion of the referent and that conceptual abstraction is a force of pro duction, as well as a reflection of existing realities . Novelists there fore are not simply passive reproducers of dominant ideologies but subj ects who at times press inherited epistemological confines to their limits, preparing the way for revolutionary new types of abstraction, both conceptual and real. At the same time, we need not claim that ideological abstraction produces a screen that filters , distorts, or hides the referent. Rather, the mode of abstraction reproduced in the text can itself be seen as a social reality, articulating real practices of pro duction, consumption, and exchange in the social world. For the ref erent to come to us through this procedure of mediation in no way negates its "reality. "' We are free to argue, in short, that the mimetic text, through its operations of dual mediation, replicates both the ob j ect and the subj ect ·- and that it also asserts this replication. Finally, the view of fiction as the mediation of both conceptual and real abstractions is useful to this study of the documentary novel be cause it requires us to grasp the problem of mimetic representation as an intrinsically historical problem. If the text's abstracting procedures mediate contemporaneous modes of abstraction, then it makes no sense to give an account of representational strategies without exam102
The Problem of the
Subject
ining the specific social situation from which the text arises . Hence we can pay more than lip service to Marx's admonition that in order to study the connection between intellectual and material pro duction it is above all essential to conceive of the latter in its determined historical form and not as a general category. For example, there corre sponds to the capitalist mode of production a type of intellectual pro duction quite different from that which corresponded to the medieval mode of production. Unless material production itself is understood in its specified historical form, it is impossible to grasp the characteristics of the intellectual production which corresponds to it or the reciprocal action between the two . 29
Sohn-Rethel's theory of abstraction provides a crucial bridge between the "determined historical form" of the exchange relation and the continually altering forms of "intellectual production" constituted by the mimetic contract. This model should prove especially helpful in our examination of the documentary novel, which, in its various phases, lays claim to different sorts of privileged access to the "real. " We turn now to a consideration of the historical specificity of these various claims . 29Marx, Theories of Surplus Value, 1 : 276.
103
PART
PRACTICE
II
5 The Pseudofa ctual Novel
I write nothing but what I have seen, o r heard from persons of unques tionable credit: and therefore shall conclude with assuring you that you have here not novel, or story, devised at pleasure; but an exact and most true account of what I met with in my travels. - Marie-Catherine d' Aulnoy
The major mode of the documentary novel in the eighteenth century is the pseudofactual novel. By "pseudofactual novel" I mean a genre of prose fiction that invokes an intrinsically ironic, even a pa rodic contract. According to such a contract, the reader is asked to ac cept the text's characters and situations as invented, which means see ing the text not as having no referent but as referring to relations rather than to particulars allegedly existing apart from their represen tation in discourse. At the same time, however, the writer asks the reader to approach the text as if it were a nonfictional text - a mem oir, a confession, a group of letters . The generic contract of the pseudofactual novel thus involves an agreement, in Mary Louise Pratt's words, to "flout" the conventions of a familiar mode of non fictional discourse. 1 This contract plays with the rabbit-duck Gestalt I mentioned in Chapter I , asking to be read as one kind of discourse but mobilizing perceptual habits and responses routinely associated with another kind of discourse. The pseudofactual novel is therefore an invitation to irony. Indeed, I shall argue that the parodic imitation of nonfictional discourse was the primary convention which first en abled prose fiction to usurp the terrain previously held by the ro1Mary Louise Pratt, Toward a Speech-Act Theo ry ofLiterary Discourse (Bloomington: Indi ana University Press, 1 977) , 1 52 - 200. I0 7
Practice mance: discursive irony was the defining characteristic of the novel in its early phases . But to say that the pseudofactual novel invokes such a self-con scious contract is not to say that the imitation of nonfictional dis course is the defining quality of all fiction, as some theorists have urged. Barbara Hermstein Smith, we will recall, argues that all "po etry" is "fiction" : "The various genres of literary art-e. g . , dramatic poems, tales, odes, lyrics - can to some extent be distinguished ac cording to what types of discourse- e. g . , dialogues, anecdotes of past events, public speeches, and private declarations - they charac teristically represent. "2 For Smith, all mimetic texts signal their fictionality by simulating nonfictional writing- War and Peace as much as Moll Flanders, Native Son as much as Pamela . Moreover, Smith argues that mimetic texts relinquish their status as assertions when they model themselves on nonfictional discourse: they become pseudostatements . My contention is quite different. The pseudofac tual novel's parodic invocation of nonfictional models constitutes a marker of fictional intentions that is historically specific: Tolstoy and Wright were not imitating chronicle and biography in anything like the way that Defoe and Richardson were imitating the rogue's con fession or the set of letters . Moreover, the pseudofactual novelists ' parodic relation to nonfictional discourse does not constitute an eva sion of propositionality; on the contrary, this relation enables them to invest fiction with new and expanded powers of assertion.
Precursors of the Pseudofactual Novel The pseudofactua.l novel attains a definitive generic identity in the work of Defoe, but it comes out of a long tradition of fictional writ ing purporting to tell a truth that is more than the proj ection of the poetic imagination. Apuleius avers that even the more improbable tales in his Golden Ass possess a certain plausibility. " In practice, things do occasionally happen to you and me, as to everybody else, " he reminds his reader, "which are so outrageous that we can hardly believe in them ourselves, and which any ordinary person would cer2 Barbara Herrnstein Smith, "Literature as Performance, Fiction, and Art , " Journal of Philosophy, 67 (August 20, 1 970) : 5 5 7. 108
The Pseudofactual Novel tainly rej ect as mere fiction. "3 Wolfram von Eschenbach holds that his telling of the grail legend in Parzival is based not on the fictional account of Chretien de Troyes but on a centuries-old "original" res cued from oblivion by the tireless efforts of one Kyot. Thomas Deloney asserts that his Jack of Newbury "raised out of the dust of forgetfulnesse a most famous and worthy man. "4 Thomas Lodge, in the fantastical Robert Duke ofNormandie, attempts to retain his author ity as historian. "Many things have happened in time past incredible in our age, " he declares in his preface. "And in our age such things have falne out, as had our fathers knowne they had mervailed. " 5 The play with spurious pretensions to documentary verifiability that characterizes these fictional works also resonates through a good deal of classical, medieval, and Renaissance discourse that we would now term nonfictional. Ancient historians are notorious for including materials of highly questionable authenticity in their narratives. Herodotus depicts the gods as functioning causally in the world of human affairs, and he gives detailed transcriptions of dialogues that had no witnesses. Thucydides may assert that his narrative "rests partly on what I saw myself, partly on what others saw for me, the accuracy of the report being always tried by the most severe and de tailed tests available";6 he accepts as historical fact, however, such a dubious proposition as the existence of Deucalion. Seneca voices a common skepticism about the ancient historian's rights and responsi bilities when he wryly remarks, "Who ever demanded affidavits from a historian?"7 Medieval theological tracts and historical chronicles also make all sorts of specious claims to authenticity, even though, as Erich Auerbach points out, the necessity of establishing the historical existence of Christ gave a new seriousness to these claims . 8 Fabulous 'Apuleius Maurensis, The Transformation of Lucius, Otherwise Known as " The Golden Ass, " trans. Robert Graves (New York: Farrar, Straus & Young, 1 9 5 1 ) , 1 8 . 'Francis Oscar Mann, ed. , The Complete Works of Thomas Deloney (Oxford: Clarendon, 1 9 1 2) , 2. 5 The Complete Works of Thomas Lodge (Glasgow: Anderson, 1 8 8 3 ) , 2:4. 6Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, trans. John F. Finley, Jr. (New York: Modem Li brary, 1 9 5 1 ) , 14. 7Seneca, Apocolococyntosis, in The Satire of Seneca, trans . Allan P . Ball (New York: Co lumbia University Press, 1 902) , 1 3 2 . 'Erich Auerbach, Mimesis: The Representation of Reality i n Western Literature, trans . Wil lard Trask ( 1 9 5 3 ; Garden City: Doubleday/Anchor, 1957), l - 20. For more on prenovelistic forms of prose fiction in Europe, see Arthur Heiserman, The Novel before the Novel: Essays and Discussions about the Beginnings ofProse Fiction in the West (Chicago: University of ChiI09
Practice saints' legends about talking beasts are routinely asserted to be true; Froissart and Geoffrey of Monmouth declare that their often fanciful and mythic tales are founded in unimpeachable sources . It was only in the Renaissance that biography and historiography espoused new standards of rigor. Thomas Cooper's Thesaurus de fined historia as "the declaration of true things in order set forth";9 William Camden argued against the time-honored tradition of mak ing up monologues and presenting them as fact: " Speeches and Ora tions, unless they be the very same verbatim, or else abbreviated, I have not medled withall, much less coined them of mine own Head. " 1 0 Nonethekss, biographies and historical works of the time were unembarrassed about departing from the record. Polydore Vergil's life of Richard III, created to suit the needs of Tudor policy, promulgated the demonic myth of Richard III that persists to this day . Sir Walter Raleigh may have deprecated those cartographers who inserted imag:inary "painters' wives " islands into their maps of recently discovered territories, but he approved of the historian's de cision to fill comparable gaps in the historical record: "In filling up the Blanks of old Histories, we need not be so scrupulous, " he noted. "For it is not to be feared that time should run backward, and by re storing the things themselves to knowledge, make our conjectures appear ridiculous . ' " 1 1 It is clear that modern empirical criteria for historical accuracy are not applicable to the fictions and histories I have just mentioned. It would be mistaken, however, to conclude that premodern historians, biographers, chroniclers, and writers of fiction lived in some sort of epistemological haze. Apuleius's intent in telling his diverting Mile sian tales must clearly be differentiated from Herodotus's desire to "preserve the memory of the past by putting on record the astonishcago Press, 1 977) ; Ben :Edwin Perry, The Ancient Romances (Berkeley: University of Cali fornia Press, 1 967) ; Margaret Schlauch, Antecedents of the English Novel, 1400- 1600 (Lon don: Oxford University Press, 1 965); and Walter L . Reed, An Exemplary History of the Novel: The Quixotic versus the Picaresque (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 9 8 1 ) . 9Quoted i n William Nelson, Fact o r Fiction: The Dilemma of the Renaissance Storyteller (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1 97 3 ) , 40. 1oWilliam Camden, The History of the Most Renowned and Victorious Princess Elizabeth, Se lected Chapters, ed. W. T. MacCaffrey (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 970) , 6. 11Sir Walter Raleigh, The History of the World, Early English Books, 1 475 - 1 640 ( 1 6 1 7; Ann Arbor: University Microfilms, 1 977) , reel 1 462, p. r , bk. 2, chap . 2 3 , sec. 4. 1 10
The Pseudofactual Novel
ing achievements both of our own and of the Asiatic peoples . " 12 Parzival mobilizes expectations very different from those invoked in Froissart's Chronicles, even though b oth texts purport to be based on unimpeachable historical sources . Jacques Amyot's claim that history relates "la nue verite"13 is very different from Sir Philip Sidney' s as sertion that poetry's golden world delivers images of potentiality in accessible in the brazen realm of quotidian reality. Ancient, medieval, and Renaissance writers exhibit no confusion about the difference be tween history and fiction; they simply require no empiricist creden tials from the historian and take care to consign fictions to the realm of the abstract or the ideal. When writers of fiction invoke additional claims to veracity, then, they do so not because they pretend to be writing history or biography but because they wish to assure us that they tell the truth. This truth is not a "factual" truth, and they do not intend to fool us into thinking that it is.
Imposture and Invention: The Emergence of Pseudofactual Fiction This relatively stable situation changes around the seventeenth cen tury, when historians begin to take more seriously the empiricist credo set forth in the Renaissance and when a kind of pseudofactual discourse appears making more emphatic claims to veracity and verifiability. Bishop Pierre Daniel Huet, a theorist of the romance, signals his distaste for works of this emergent genre when he attacks them as "stories carefully shaped in whole and in part, but made up only to falsify truth. "1 4 These new stories differ from their forebears in that they lay claim to a distinct immediacy; since the nonfictional text that they simulate is generally a first-person account, rather than a chronicle or a biography, it is more difficult for readers to deter mine their authenticity. Indeed, for more than a century this mode of dis course would appear to have been conventionally ambiguous. The 12Herodotus , The Histories, trans . Aubrey de Selincourt (Baltimore: Penguin, 1 954), 1 3 . 13Jacques Amyot, " Aux lecteurs, " in Critical Prefaces of the French Renaissance, ed. Ber nard Weinberg (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1 950) , 167. 14Pierre Daniel Huet, Traite sur l'origine des romans ( 1 669; Paris: Nizet, 1971), 49, my translation. III
Practice reader is asked to view the text's speaker as simultaneously part of the text' s analogous configuration- and hence a fictional character- and as an autonomous voice commenting on the referent from a position external to fictionahty. Since the text does not display ironic signals instructing the reader to view the speaker as part of the referent (to characterize the speaker, as it were) , the generic contract requires an agreement to hold in suspension the question of verifiability. As Lennard ]. Davis suggests, such works of fiction characteristically possess an "overt frame" proclaiming the text' s veracity and a " covert frame" admitting to the text's fictionality. "Because the reader is never really certain . . . whether this covert frame indeed exists, a state of ambivalence is produced in the reader which extends through out his or her experience of the novel. "15 These new pseudofactual works did not collapse the distinction between fictional and nonfic tional discourse as such. When Huet angrily declared, "I say falsified stories to distinguish them from true stories, " 16 he was exhibiting a clear sense of the difference between reality and imagination. None theless, these texts hovered around the borderline in such a way as to raise serious doubts about the accepted notion that prose fiction should be restricted to the subject matter of courtly love and heroic exploits. These new pseudofactual fictions, while simulating such discursive forms as the chron:icle, the traveler's report, or the set of letters, at tached new force to their corroborative testimonials and emphatically denied the charge of mendacity. 17 Thomas Nashe, for example, in one of the earliest instances of the genre, announced in I 594 that his The Unfortunate Traveller would be "a reasonable conveyance of historie"18 and presented his narrative as the first-person account of one Jack Wilton, 1cheputative valet of the Earl of Surrey. Unlike Delaney's Jack of l'-Jewbury, who is asserted to be a historical figure but then readily assumes the fictional status of a j est-book character, Jack Wilton proj ects the ambience of a "real-life" person, one who 15Lennard J. Davis, Factual Fictions: The Origins of the English Novel (New York: Colum bia University Press, 1 9 8 3 ) , 2 I . 16Huet, 46-47, my translation. 17For more on the authenticating procedures of early pseudofactual fiction, see Arthur Jerrold Tieje, "A Peculiar Phase of the Theory of Realism in Pre-Richardsonian Fiction, " PMLA, 2 8 ( 1 9 1 3 ) : 2 1 3 - 52 . 1sThomas Nashe, The Unfortunate Traveller and Other Works, ed. J. B. Steane (Har mondsworth: Penguin, 1 972) , 25 I . The passage quoted below is from p . 3 70. I I2
The Pseudo factual Novel frequently interrupts his own narration and apologizes for his forget fulness . A curious quality thus attaches to his " conclusive epilogue" : "If herein I have pleased any, it shall animate me to more pains in this kind. Otherwise I will swear upon an English Chronicle never to be outlandish Chronicler more while I live. " The admission of " outland ishness " obviously calls attention to the possible mendacity of Wil ton' s account. Interestingly, however, it is a genre of historical dis course that Wilton chooses to charge with distorting the truth. To the extent that the reader distrusts chronicle as a reliable index to histori cal events (and surely the perceptive Elizabethan reader must have done so) , Nashe's own discourse retains its status as a " reasonable" - or at least a plausible- " conveyance of historie, " or teller of truth. Aphra Behn, in her prefatory remarks to Oroonoko; or, The History of the Royal Slave, maintained, "I do not pretend, in giving you the history of this Royal Slave, to entertain my Reader with the adven tures of a feigned hero, whose life and fortunes fancy may manage at the poet's pleasure. "19 Behn herself was , she claims, "an eyewitness to a greater part of what you will here find set down; and what I could not be witness of, I received from the mouth of the chief actor in this history, the hero himself. " Behn frequently departs from the terms of this pledge: Oroonoko' s final dismemberment (through which he calmly smokes his pipe) was certainly not "received from the mouth of the chief actor, " and Behn is astute enough to ascribe her narration of this episode to another source. Nonetheless , the story successfully simulates the format of the traveler' s tale, which itself frequently strained credibility; it remains an open question whether the " chief actor" is feigned or real. Mme d' Aulnoy prefaced her letter novel The Lady Travels into Spain with florid assurances of the text' s veracity: I have not doubt there will be some who will accuse me of hyperboliz
ing , and composing romances ; but such would do well to acquaint themselves first with the country, humour, and character of those I treat of. A fact must not be presently condemned as false because it is not public or may not hit every man's fancy . I cite no feigned names , no persons whose death may give me the liberty of attributing what I please to them. 19Aphra B ehn,
Behn
Oronooko; or, The History of the Royal Slave,
in
The Novels of Mrs . Aphra
(London: Routledge & Sons , 1 90 5 ) , 8 8 . I IJ
Practice In a word: I wriite nothing but what I have seen, or heard from per sons of unquestionable credit: and therefore shall conclude with assur ing you that you have here not novel, or story, devised at pleasure; but an exact and most true account o f what I met with in my travels . 20
The text is in fact a fraud, 21 and such fervent overprotestations that it does not engage in the mendacious distortions of other epistolary dis course obviously tease the reader into considering this possibility. As in The Unfortunate Traveller and Oroonoko, however The Lady Travels contains no explicit textual markers requiring the reader to posit the speaker as part of the referent. The reader may not necessar ily take at face value the speaker's truth-telling assertions (the repre sented action poses too great a challenge to everyday canons of credi bility) . But neither does the reader automatically adopt the ironic attitude that the speaker' s discourse primarily serves to characterize the speaker, thus subordinating him or her to the author's informing interpretive framework. D ocumentation goes on the offensive in these texts, securin g a terrain for the propositional value of fiction by decrying the mendacity of other discursive modes charged with the responsibility of telling an unmediated truth. While the early pseudofactual novelists routinely modeled their narratives on familiar types of nonfictional writing , their invocation of a conventionally ambiguous generic contract was made possible by the develop ment ofj ournalism in the seventeenth century . According to the Oxford English Dictiona ry , in the late sixteenth and early seven teenth centuries the term " novel" applied equally to both fictional tales and j ournalistilc accounts and was often used coterminously with "news " ; fiction and j ournalism were frequently conj oined in an undifferentiated discursive matrix that Davis calls the "news/novel discourse. "22 Invoking discursive conventions developed in the ballad-sheets of the late sixteenth century, fiction and j ournalism in-
--
Madame D 'Aulnoy Travels into Spain (The Ingenious and Di Travels into Spain) , trans . and ed. R. Foulche-D elbosc (London: Routledge & Sons, 1 93 0) , 3 . 21 See Percy G. Adams, Travelers and Travel Liars, 1 660 - 1 800 (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1 962) , 97- 1 00. In " Madame d'Aulnoy in England" (Comparative Litera ture, 27 [Summer 1 97 5 ] : 2 3 7 - 5 3 ) , Melvin D. P almer argues that the Travels enj oyed im 2()Marie-Catherine d'Aulnoy,
verting Letters of the Lady
--
mense popularity in England and was a crucial text in the transition from the " true historie" to the novel. 22Davis,
Factual Fictions, 42- 70. I I4
The Pseudofactual Novel creasingly exploited a common fund of rhetorical- even typographi cal- devices . The creation of a " median past tense, " the inclusion of the reader as an engaged spectator, the attribution of the status of "news" to any narrative rendition of the sensational in everyday life - all these activities became the constitutive features of a generic contract that enhanced experiential immediacy and de-emphasized the question of strict verifiability, even as it sometimes laid claim to that verifiability. Thus the testimonials accompanying the fictions of Nashe, Behn, and d' Aulnoy are hardly distinguishable from the sorts of guarantees that were attached to newspapers and j ournals of the time. Behn's and d'Aulnoy's proclamations that they possess privi leged access to their materials find their rhetorical equivalent in the claim of Mercurius Civicus to be "London's Intelligencer or Truth im partially related from thence to the whole Kingdom to prevent dis information. "23 Throughout most of the seventeenth century, a fictional writer was often as liable to legal suit as was a j ournalist: En glish licensing laws of the seventeenth century grouped together all material printed in a j ournalistic format. The Licensing Act of I 663 , for example, covered "all narratives, advertisements, intelligencers , diurnals and other books of public intelligence. " The pseudofactual novel's early association with j ournalism is symptomatic of the way its practitioners were relinquishing the tradi tional subject matter of fiction and breaking new ground. The ac knowledged model of prose fiction at this time was still the romance - a patently aristocratic genre that represented life at the highest level of abstraction and refrained from any representation of the rough grain of everyday life. 24 If writers wished to be taken seriously as in terpreters of social reality, they were constrained to simulate familiar modes of nonfictional discourse. It is therefore no accident that Nashe wrote his The Unfortunate Traveller in the mode of a spurious chroni cle; his text takes as its referent the key events of early sixteenth century European history, from Henry VIII's 1 5 1 3 siege of Terou23Davis, "A Social History of Fact and Fiction: Authorial Disavowal in the Early English Novel, " in Literature and Society: Selected Papers from the English Institute, ed. Edward Said (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1 980) , 1 2 5 . 24See Davis, Factual Fictions, chap. 2, "The Romance: Liminality and Influence, " 2 5 - 4 1 , and loan Williams, The Idea of the Novel i n Europe, 1600- 1 800 (London: Macmillan, 1 979) . While Davis's study is valuable for its many empirical findings about the relation of the novel to broadsheets and journalism, its methodology is flawed in some troubling ways. See my review of Factual Fictions in Genre, 17 (Winter 1 9 84) : 422 - 2 5 . Ilj
Practice anne to his 1 5 20 e:ncounter with Francois I, from Luther' s 1 5 1 9 doctrinal debates to the rising of the Anabaptists at Munster in l 5 3 4 . Moreover, Nashe's Wilton delivers a witty lampoon o n feudalistic decorum through his satirical depiction of Surrey- who hyperbo lizes about his mistress ' s eyes and decks out his horse for the lists "in full proportion and shape of an estrich. "25 If Nashe wishes to tell the truth about aristocratic practices, he must do so through the discourse of the brazen world, not through that of the realm of gold. Similarly, Mme d'Aulnoy's decision to tell her impressions of Spanish customs through a series of spurious letters signals her desire to expand the province of epistolary fiction beyond the realm of courtly intrigue. Her letter-novel contains its share of tales of passion and betrayal, to be sure, but these are always told to the intrepid trav eler and thus incorporated into the text' s investigatory ends . The presumed penchant of Spaniards for telling unbelievable stories (" 'I never was in any place, ' said I, smiling, 'where they relied so much on fabulous tales as they do in Spain' ")26 thus becomes a feature of the referent. The Lady Travels provides its readers with all the pleasures of romance but draws these into its reportorial design. Even Oroonoko, which bears a closer resemblance to the romance than does The Unfortunate Traveller or The Lady Travels, uses I its illusion of veracity to treat such urgent issues as the cruelties of slavery and the declining status of monarchy. As one critic has ar gued, in this work Behn was making a veiled plea for compassionate treatment of James II, in that there is a close resemblance between Behn's dethroned African ruler and the deposed Stuart king, for whom the writer retained a strong loyalty. 27 The social configura tion which the text represents is thus a concretely historical pattern, rather than an abstracted realm where timeless passions play them selves out. When Behn declares that "there is enough of reality to support [the tale] , and to render it diverting, without the addition of 25Nashe, 3 1 7. For more on the historicizing procedures and interests of Nashe and other Elizabethan writers of prose fiction, see Walter R . Davis, Idea and Act in Elizabethan Fiction (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1 969) . 26D'Aulnoy, 348. 21see George Guffey, " Aphra Behn's Oronooko: Occasion and Accompli� �ment, " in his Two English Novelists: Aphra Behn and Anthony Tollope (Los Angeles: William Andrews Clark Memorial Library, 1 975), 1 - 4 1 . II6
The Pseudofactual Novel invention, " she is arguing for the enfranchisement of fiction as a dis course to represent and interpret urgent contemporary realities . While the conventionally ambiguous contract invoked in these early pseudofactual fictions permitted authors to explore issues and materials previously excluded from the realm of mimesis, the emer gent genre also encountered certain difficulties that its eventual adop tion of a greater degree of verisimilitude would resolve. The author's equivocal relation to the historical status of the text's characters and events effectively dehistoricized the very reality that the text meant to certify with the immediacy of an eyewitness report. Nashe's insis tence upon the authenticity of his narrator threatens the integrity of the text's portraiture of historical events. In a tale presupposing the du bious veracity of its narrator, a juxtaposition of events in l 5 l 3 and 1 5 3 4, and the subsequent termination of the narrative in 1 5 20, would not create tremendous confusion. The modern reader, construing Wilton as a kind of ancestor to Huckleberry Finn, would simply dismiss the anachronism as a function of Wilton's desire to tell a "stretcher, " and would see the speaker as a part of the story being told. Behn, too, undermines the credibility of her account when she expects us to take seriously the proposition that Oroonoko retained his maj estic demeanor throughout his dismemberment. Had she sim ply asserted that Oroonoko exemplifies the cardinal virtues of mon archy, she could have offered a persuasive account of both the cruel ties of slavery and the injustices presumably done to the Stuarts . As it is, however, Oroonoko's speech and demeanor- as well as his re markably Caucasian features28- render him virtually indistinguish able from a typical Restoration nobleman and therefore negate his plausibility as an African analogue to James IL The early pseudofac tual novel's postulation of veracity conflicted with its pretensions to verisimilitude: the "sense of the real" and "realism" experienced a truly uneasy coexistence. 29 The text's conventional participation in the "news/novel discourse" enabled fiction to experiment with a fas28That is, "The most famous statuary could not form the figure of a man more admirably turned from head to foot. His face was not of that brown nasty black which most of that nation are, but a perfect ebony, or polished jet. His eyes were the most awful that could be seen, and very piercing; the white of them being like snow, as were his teeth. His nose was rising and Roman, instead of African and flat: his mouth the finest shaped that could be seen; far from those great turned lips, which are so natural to the rest of the Negroes" (8) . 291 owe this handy opposition of terms to Robert Gorham Davis, ''The Sense of the Real in English Fiction, " Comparative Literature, 3 (Summer 1 96 1 ) : 200 - 2 1 7 . II7
Practice cinating new subj ect matter, but the requirements of analogous con figuration and reportage drew the text in opposite directions .
Between the Sense of the Real and Realism The merging of parody with representation, argues M. M. Bakh tin, was the central linguistic development that produced the modem novel: "Languages cease to be merely the object of a purely polemical or autotelic parodying: without losing their parodic coloration com pletely, they begin to assume the function of artistic representation, of a representation with a value in its own right . . . . The hero' s dis course about himself and about his world fuses organically, from the outside, with the author's discourse about him and his world. "30 The crucial phrase here is "from the outside": the conventions of novelis tic mimesis required a contractual agreement that author and charac ter are ontologically distinct, with the former empowered to incorpo rate the latter's dliscourse into an interpretive scheme that clearly emanates from an ethical position external to the discourse itself. The parodic play with nonfictional materials thus became increasingly identified as a marker of fictional intent. Hesitantly in the works of Defoe, then more boldly in subsequent novels of the eighteenth cen tury, the pseudofactual imposture of veracious discourse signaled the invocation of a mimetic contract. Rather than simulating a putative nonfictional model, the text now openly imitated such a text, thereby flouting its own claim to nonfictional status. Irony is thus a crucial marker of the novelistic contract: the text parades its status as a mode of generalizing - and generalized- cognition by denying (or at least calling into question) its own capacity to offer authenticating state ments about particular persons and events. Fictional assertion re quires that verisimilitude supersede veracity. Indeed, it would seem that, as the eighteenth century progressed, readers increasingly tired of tongue-in-cheek authorial disavowals of mimetic intent. Mary Davys remarked as early as 1 729 that "probable 30M. M . Bakhtin, The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays, ed. Michael Holquist, trans. Caryl Emerson and Holquist (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1 9 8 3 ) , 409. II8
The Pseudo factual Novel feigned stories" had been "for some time . . . out of use and fash ion. "31 As a predictor of immediate novelistic trends, D avys was clearly mistaken, since pseudofactual imposture survived to the end of the century and beyond. Nonetheless, the rise of the mode that we term "realism" clearly involved an initial dependence upon, but an ul timate replacement of, the "sense of the real. " The imposture that had been dominant in the early phases of documentary fiction eventually became a residual device, while realistic veris imilitude, previously a by-product of the claim to veracity, became the central determinant of mimetic conventions . As we examine the development of the pseudo factual novel in the eighteenth century, the wonder is not that the novel abandoned the pretense of factual truth-telling but that it took so long to do so. Defoe experimented with a complex and contradictory admixture of veracity and verisimilitude; most of the critical debates about Defoe's status as a watershed figure in the history of the novel rest implicitly or explicitly upon the determination of which strategy of representation more accurately characterizes the majority of his works. Was he, as Ian Watt argues, the first practitioner of novelistic realism? Or was he, as Ralph Rader suggests, a figure "whom studies have shown to have ancestors but no posterity, . . . the last and most perfect artist in a tradition of works designed to exploit the interest naturally attaching to true stories" ?32 I believe that Defoe's works ex emplify both qualities; some represent the final flowering of the tradi tion of the "false true story, " while others experiment with analogous configuration as the primary strategy of fictional assertion. Defoe's A journal of the Plague Year, a fictional reconstruction of the Great Plague of 1 6 8 8 , is essentially a lie. Although it creates the great maj ority of its particulars, it is intended to be read as - and succeeds best when read as - a historical document. Defoe's goal here is to cre ate a gripping portrait of London under biological and moral siege. 31W. H. McBumey, ed. , Four before Richardson: Selected English Novels, 1 720-27 (Lin coln: University of Nebraska Press, 1 96 3 ) , 2 3 5 . 32See Ian Watt, The Rise of the Novel: Studies in Defoe, Richardson, and Fielding (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1 967) ; Ralph W. Rader, "Defoe, Richardson, Joyce, and the Concept of Form in the Novel, " in Autobiography, Biography, and the Novel, ed. William Matthews and Rader (Los Angeles: William Andrews Clark Memorial Library, 1973 ) , 47. I l9
Practice H . F . , the narrator, may see symbolic religious ramifications in his sit uation, but Defoe's primary purpose is to represent the engraving of experience on consciousness , rather than to propose a determinate judgment upon the ideological content of that consciousness . As in The Unfortunate Traveller, the putative historical status of the narrator primarily gives the text its effect of direct reference to reality. The de tailed death rolls invest the text with a compelling authenticity, but the text convince�; the reader that it is telling the truth mainly through its narrative stance. H. F . repeatedly interrupts his narrative to deal with the " shutting up of houses" and the behavior of the watchmen, themes for which he has a morbid fascination. He therefore takes shape not as a created character whose foibles and proclivities Defoe invites us to judge- whether ironically, sympathetically, or harshly but as a real person to whom we react in a manner controlled only by our enforced acknowledgment of the enormity of his experience. As a result, the ideological conceptions that guide H . F . 's behavior and thought- Providence intends for him to survive the plague, the ad ministrators of London maintain social control without unduly sup pressing personall freedoms - stand in a peculiar relation to the mi metic text. Since Defoe does not proffer a novelistic contract, we may agree or disagree with H. F. 's views, admire or disrespect his re sponses; but we stand, in a sense, on equal discursive ground. The text contains few of the rhetorical overdeterminations (e. g. , implicit assertions of typicality and synecdoche) that, in realism, compel- or at least demand- the reader's assent to the author's ideological stance. Definitive opinions on social relations are, it seems, the pos session of the speaker, but not- at least not necessarily- of the au thor. Defoe thus manages to make his views on predestination and the prerogatives of the state a felt presence in the text without requir ing that the reader imaginatively endorse these views in order to par ticipate vicariomly in the experience Defoe describes . Documentary validation serves not to corroborate a view of reality assumed to be true, but to enhance the authenticity of a voice that holds its own con struction of truth to be self-evident. The Journal does contain occasional signs of its fictional nature. For example, the lengthy interpolated story of Thomas and John- two Londoners who, it appears, escaped from the horrors of the city and sequestered themselves in the countryside-is told in a third-person narrative that would never be expected in a memoir such as the Jour120
The Pseudofactual · Novel
nal purports to be. 33 H. F . attempts to cover his tracks, of course. "Their story has a moral in every part of it, and their whole conduct . . . is a pattern for all poor men to follow, or women either, if ever such a times come again, " declares H.F. "If there is no other end in recording it, I think this a very just one, whether my account be ex actly according to fact or no. "34 But the fact remains that H. F. did not accompany Thomas and John, so he could not have witnessed the dialogue and events he relates . Defoe's eagerness to explore as many facets of the plague experience as possible threatens to override his pseudomemoiristic frame; clearly he wishes to construct an analo gous portrait that aspires toward generalization. The episode is framed and contained within the rambling structure of the memoir, however, for it creates few of the thematic resonances that accom pany digressive episodes in novelistic discourse. (Compare, for ex ample, the Man of the Hill episode in Tom Jones . ) Just as "factual" ele ments must be subordinated to the mimetic frame of War and Peace, this "fictional" element must be subordinated to the factual frame of the Journal. H. F. stands forth as a historical subject, one whom we encounter on the nonironic turf of a shared historical actuality. H. F. ' s quirkiness is not a peculiarity that we must take into account in weighing the truth of his account but a voyeuristic means to cogni tion. The truth that he tells about the plague is a historical truth, even if it is a lie. Robinson Crusoe shows Defoe moving toward undisguised mimetic representation and openly exploring the limits of pseudofactual im posture. The text is, to be sure, rife with testimonial materials and even contains several pages of the diary purportedly undertaken by Crusoe on his island. (Fortunately, this tedious document is termi nated early in the narrative, through Defoe's well-planned exhaustion of his hero's ink supply. ) Furthermore, Robinson Crusoe gains histori cal credibility by its close resemblance to the well-known tale of 33For the alternate view that "the Journal's focus on its central character puts it in the cat egory of fiction, " see Everett Zimmerman, Defoe and the Novel (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1975), 107- 2 5 . The quoted sentence appears on p. ro8. Maximilian E. Novak, in Realism, Myth, and History in Defoe's Fiction (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1 9 8 3 ) , argues that "narrative does not function in A Journal of the Plague Year as a mode of 'historical exploration'; to the contrary, it is history that functions as a subsidiary organizational device for various fictions in the narrative" (67) . 34Daniel Defoe, A Journal of the Plague Year, Everyman's Library (London: J . M . Dent, 1 966), 1 3 8 . I2 I
Practice Alexander Selkirk and to other extant and validated j ournals of voy ages to the West Indies, which dissociate it from the apocryphal trav eler's tales popular in Defoe's time. Indeed, Defoe absorbed factual and putative accounts so thoroughly that McKillop has characterized his method as a " compilation and reconstruction rather than a fabrica tion. "35 Nonetheless, the conventional prefatory testimony to authenticity contains a telling overprotestation: "The Editor believes the thing to be a just History of fact; neither is there any Appearance of Fiction in it. "36 What is more, the hero - designated, we note, as " Crusoe, " not "Selkirk" - stands forth as a generalized type of the resilient and self-reliant entrepreneur. His interactions with Friday signal a superi ority that is rooted not in any distinct particularity but in his assured status as a "natural" (that is, European, male, bourgeois) leader. In its adherence to the narrative probabilites of memoiristic form, Robinson Crusoe makes its claim to pseudofactuality; in its signification of a Lockean Homo economicus exercising his natural right to property and dominance, the narrative proposes cognition by means of analogous configuration. Defoe's fortunate situation of his solitary hero on a desert island prevents a practical conflict between these divergent rep resentational claims : veracity is not submitted to any binding test for verification and hence coexists with a compelling verisimilitude. Defoe thus manages to suggest that his Crusoe constitutes a contem poraneous type without committing himself to a full-fledged fiction taking the bourgeois hero as its theme. In Moll Flander5 we see Defoe returning to more commonplace ter rain and staking out a more confident claim to mimetic representation as a way of making assertions about everyday reality. The author cre ates a convincing pseudofactual narrative based on the premise that reality can be stranger than fiction; we can accept Moll's outrageous pronouncements readily enough if we read them as the statements of 35Alan Dugald McKillop, The Early Masters of English Fiction (Lawrence: University of Kansas Press, 1 9 56) , 9 . For more on Defoe's use of factual materials, see Arthur Wellesley Secord, Studies in the Narrative Method of Defoe (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1 926) . 36Daniel Defoe, Robinson Crusoe (New York: Norton, 1975), 3 . In The Farther Adventures of Robinson Crusoe ( 1 7 1 9) , Defoe made a more open admission of fictionality. He declared, "The just Application of every Incident, the religious and useful Inferences drawn from every Part, are so many Testimonies to the good Reign of making it publick and must legit imate all the Part that may be call'd Invention, or Parable in the Story" (Oxford: Blackwell, n.d. ) . I22
The Pseudofactual Novel a real person, similar to one we might encounter in a waiting room or on a bus. Moll's narration of her accidentally incestuous marriage, for example, assumes a bizarre moral neutrality - a quality only en hanced by her cheerful relegation of the experience to the past, never to be dwelled upon again. If Moll is not bothered by this circum stance, neither are we- as neither, apparently, is Defoe. Moll's per sonality is a wondrous phenomenon, remaining remarkably impervi ous to those environmental forces, that would, in full-fledged realism, become part of her social being. As Sheldon Sacks has ar gued, Defoe organizes Moll Flanders around few of the structuring de vices ordinarily associated with the novel. There are no meaningful changes in her character after the opening chapters; the developmen tal pattern of the plot is additive rather than complicative; the main pleasure afforded by most of the episodes derives from the simple fact that Moll is present in them. 37 Accordingly, Sacks concludes, Moll's actions do not provoke the kinds of j udgments that accompany the actions of, say, a David Copperfield or a Bigger Thomas . Nonetheless , the generic contract governing Moll is subtly but crucially different from that invoked in the Journal. For the very out rageousness of Moll's presumably truthful discourse requires the reader to consider criteria of plausibility and verisimilitude: could all these things have happened to one person? Single episodes such as the incestuous marriage may be assimilated into a memoiristic Gestalt, but the text contains so many incredible episodes that their quantita tive accumulation produces a qualitative change in the text' s organiz ing frame. The perception of an actual historical subj ect chatting with us is transformed into the ironic appreciation of a character unwit tingly shaped by her own discourse. As David Goldknopf has ob served, Moll's talk contains a " confessional increment" that requires the reader to acknowledge the "mimetic membrane" separating the world of the novel from the world of the reader. 38 In her contradic tory complexity, Moll relinquishes the self-censorship that routinely accompanies even the most candid spiritual autobiography or rogue' s 37Sheldon Sacks, Fiction and the Shape of Belief A Study ofHenry Fielding, with Glances at Swift, Johnson, and Richardson (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1 967) , 267-70. 38ln first-person narratives that we are intended to pe�eive as fictional, Goldknopf ar gues, "Everything that an I-narrator tells us has a certain characterizing significance over and above its data value, by virtue of the fact that he is telling it to us" ( The Life of the Novel [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1972], 3 2 - 3 3 ) . 12 3
Practice confession; she constantly characterizes herself for the reader, and her statements therefore serve to draw attention to the author' s implied ethical j udgments . Unlike H. F . , or even Robinson Crusoe, Moll is incapable of proj ecting convincing ideological abstractions of her own. The only coherent values represented in Moll Flanders are those of Defoe, located in the apparently unconscious disclosures of Moll's discourse. The tone of D efoe' s preface reveals the distance between this novel and his earlier pseudofactual discourses - and the gulf that separates his strategy from that of a Mme d' Aulnoy . "It is true that the original of this story is put into new words, " the " editor" remarks, " and that the style of the famous lady we here speak of is a little altered; partic ularly she is made to tell her own tale in modester words than she told it at first, the copy which came first to hand having been written in language more like one still in Newgate than one grown penitent and humble, as she afterward pretends to be. "39 The author's posture as editor here entails an ironic obj ectifying of his narrator; it would ap pear that Moll, while chastened, is not above relishing the memory of her past sins nor, for that matter, above exaggerating her account here and there for effect. In Moll Flanders, then, Defoe relegates the pseudofactual imposture to his manner of representation and treats it as a device in the portrayal of personality. Moll is an agent of percep tion- we are required to see the world through her eyes, and hers alone- but she is also an obj ect of perception: the story constructed around her, of which she is a part, becomes the primary means of of fering generalized propositions about both her and her world. D efoe's works mark a critical stage in the development of the doc umentary novel. In his novels the pseudofactual apparatus receded to subordinate status, and mimetic narrative achieved currency as a means of conveying determinate interpretations and evaluations of everyday reality. Textual claims to veracity were first decisively sub ordinated to the direct adoption of analogous configuration in Rich ardson's novels, however, and what Rader calls the " wish-fulfill ment" devolving from p articipation in the mimetic contract took precedence over any presumed propositional value that could be gained from the designation of fictive characters as "real. " 40 Thus 39Daniel Defoe,
The Fortunes and Misfortunes of the Famous Moll Flanders
Random House, Modem Library , 1 9 50), xix. 40Rader, "Defoe, Richardson, Joyce, " 3 r-72 .
I24
(New York :
The Pseudofactual Novel Richardson's prefatory assertion that Pamela; or, Virtue Rewarded is founded upon "Truth and Nature" announced his intent that the reader would be attracted by the moral lesson presumably encoded in the heroine' s career: the narrative, he says, is related "in so probable, so natural, so lively a manner, as shall engage the Passions of every sensible Reader, and strongly interest them in the edifying Story. "41 It is not surprising that Richardson moderated his claims to Pam ela' s historicity, for the complex structure of expectation and vicari ous involvement erected upon Pamela's letters reveals that he was no longer simulating a form of nonfictional discourse, albeit for mimetic ends, but instead was using the epistolary form as a device to lend im mediacy to his portraiture of semi-conscious social ambition and physical desire. The letters themselves become part of the plot of the novel: Pamela' s concealment of the letters on her body and Mr. B. ' s attempts t o snatch them from her reveal the extent t o which the pro tagonist's discourse about herself has become inseparable from the author's representation of that discourse. Richardson thus uses his residually pseudofactual manner of representation in order to air con tradictory ideological positions. The heroine's social ambitions and her covert willingness to bargain her chastity in order to further those ambitions become part of the text's referent; as analogous configura tion, Pamela proposes that the marriage of servant and master is so cially acceptable. At the same time, the very immediacy of Pamela's presence and the almost palpable reality of the letters make it difficult for the reader to inhabit an empyrean position outside the text from which to evaluate Pamela's actions. We partially inhabit the con sciousness that is Pamela, experiencing the same sensations and for mulating the same shifting conjectures about the true nature of her an tagonists. The reader sympathizes with Pamela's behavior, without quite knowing that he or she is doing so, since at any single moment Pamela evades j udgment and interpretation. Richardson thus divests himself of full accountability for the somewhat subversive views encoded in his tale. The residual pseudofactual presence is not there fore merely a stylistic feature of the text; it is an ideological strategem enabling the author simultaneously to make an assertion and to deny responsibility for it. After all, he is just editing the letters, not com posing them. 41Samuel Richardson,
Pamela : or, Virtue Rewarded (Oxford:
Blackwell, n . d . ) , ii. I25
Practice While it must have been apparent to Richardson that he had dis covered a powerful mode of fictional representation (wedding bells were rung all over England to celebrate the nuptials of Pamela and Mr. B . ) , he apparently felt unable to dispense altogether with the im posture of veracity in his " new species of writing. " In Clarissa he in sistently retained his hold upon pseudofactual devices and refused to attach an additional commentary by Bishop Warburton that ac knowledged the tale to be fictional. "I could wish that the Air of Genuiness [sic] had been kept up , tho' not the Letters to be Thought genuine; only so far kept up, I mean, as that they should not p refatic ally be owned not to be genuine. "42 Such stubborn adherence to the posture of factuality involved risks of the most practical kind, how ever. When literary competitors eager to reap some of the returns of the lucrative Pamela market claimed that they too had access to the original Pamela documents, Richardson was caught in a bind: he could uphold his right to legitimate and exclusive Pamela royalties only by admitting that his editorial posture was a fraud. 43 Not all eighteenth-century writers made such extensive use of authenticating documentation, of course: the sense of the real was also at this time gravitating toward the realism that would eventually supersede it. This alternate tendency was most notably exemplified by Fielding , who claimed to have founded a " new province of writ ing , " wherein, he pronounced, "I am at liberty to make what laws I please . "44 In this statment, Fielding openly proclaimed his indepen dence from the pseudofactual tradition and asserted the superiority of a fictional approach that would strive to portray generalized examples " copied from the book of nature. "45 In proposing that the novel could constitute an Aristotelian species of mimesis, the " comic Epic Poem in Prose, " Fielding was taking a radical step toward generic in dependence, for he was wresting from the romance the exclusive rights to representation in prose fiction. Fielding's open endorsement of fictionality as the differentia of the novel would be given explicit theoretical formulation in Clara Reeve's later descrilption of the novel as 42Samuel Richardson, quoted in McKillop,
42 .
Factual Fictions, 1 80 - 82. The History of Tom Jones, A Foundling ( 1 749) , ed. Fredson Bowers (Middletown: Wesleyan University Pres s , 1975), 1 :77. 45Henry Fielding , The History of the Adventures of Joseph Andrews ( 1 742) , ed. Martin B attestin (Middletown: Wesleyan University Press , 1 967) , I O . The passage quoted below appears on p. 4. 43For more on Richardson's legal dilemma, see D avis , 44Henry Fielding,
126
The Pseudofactual Novel a picture of real life and manners , and of the times in which it is written . . . . The Novel gives a familiar relation of such things, as pass every day before our eyes , such as may happen to our friend, or to ourselves; and the perfection of it, is to represent every s cene, in so easy and natural a manner, and to make them appear so probable, as to deceive us into a p ersuasion (at least while we are reading) that all is real , until we are af fected by the j oys or distresses of the persons in the story, as if they were our own. 46
Reeve's awareness of the novel as the successor to the romance is il lustrated b y her prefatory description of her own Gothic narrative in The Old English Baron, which, she claimed, grafted together " the most attractive and interesting circumstances of the ancient Romance and Modern Novel, at the same time that it assumes a character and manner of its own, that differs from both. "47 It is important to note that the definitions offered by both Fielding and Reeve hinge in large part upon their rej ection of pseudofactual imposture as a constitutive feature of the novelistic contract; the rep resentation of generalized human experience in specific imaginary in stances takes precedence over the illusion of actual historicity. It is also important to note that Fielding and Reeve are the first writers to outline a theory of the novel (which is also a theory of realism, even though the term "realism" would not attain currency until the middle of the next century) . Pseudofactual novelists, by contrast, could not devise theories of their own discursive practice, for to do so would involve a contradiction in terms : it was only when the text's analo gized referent was differentiated from its putative veracious referent that novelists could openly discuss the principles of their mimetic craft. Yet we must realize that Reeve insisted that mimesis can " deceive
46Clara Reeve,
The Progress of Romance
(Colchester: W. Keymer,
1 78 5 ) , I:
iii. The terms
"novel" and " romance" have a complicated history in the seventeenth and eighteenth cen turie s . Clara Reeve articulated the common meanings these terms had gained b y the late eighteenth century when she wrote, "The Romance is an heroic fable which treats of fabu lous persons and things. The Novel is a picture of real life and manners , and o f the time in which it was written"
mance ( 1 78 3 )
( 1 1 1) . James
B eattie, however, proclaimed, in his
On Fable and Ro
that Defoe, Richardson, and Smollett- whom he described as " Novel
Novel and Ro mance, I 700 - I 8oo: A Documentary Record [London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1 970) , 3 09 27) . 47Clara Reeve, The Old English Baron (London: Nimmo & Bain, 1 8 8 3 ) , 1 1 .
writers" - all wrote species o f "Romance" (quoted in loan Williams, ed. ,
12 7
Practice us into a persuasion (at least while we are reading) that all is real, " and that Fielding, despite his openness in admitting the imaginary status of his characters , retained for the title p age of Tom Jones the word "history . " Fielding attempted to deflect the criticism leveled by the foes of imagined discourse: " Hence we are to derive that universal contempt which the world, who always denominate the maj ority, have cast on all historical writers , who do not draw their materials from the records . And it is the apprehension of this contempt, that hath made us so cautiously avoid the term romance . . . . Though in deed we have good authority for our characters, no less indeed than Doomsday Book, or the vast book of nature, . . . our labours have sufficient title to the name of history. "48 The distance between these prefactory remarks and those of a Mme d' Aulnoy is, of course, im mense; where Mme d' Aulnoy denied writing not only " romance" but also any "novc�l, . . . or story, devised at pleasure, " Fielding and Reeve openly admit to the fictionality of their practice. Nonetheless, it is significant thait even the novel's boldest defender� were still com pelled to urge that their representation carried the authority of a nonfictional discourse. As the pseudofactual novel attained currency as a fictional mode in the eighteenth century, it gained more secure status as a mode of cog nition. In novels as diverse as Henry Mackenzie' s The Man of Peeling, Tobias Smollett' s Humphrey Clinker, Denis Diderot's La religieuse, and Choderlos de Laclos ' s Les liaisons dangereuses, the implication of pretended veracious discourse served to enhance the text's claims to generality rather than to suggest its possible authenticity. Thus Mackenzie' s claims that the manuscript of his tale was discovered be ing used as wadding for the local curate' s fowling piece and that the text' s fragmented plot is attributable to hiatuses in the manuscript are belied by the story's patently didactic intent. "It is no more a history than it is a sermon, " declares the curate. 49 Smollett pretends that the letters constituting: Humphrey Clinker were gathered by one Jonathan Dustwich, who, in the first of a prefatory p air of letters , assures his bookseller, Henry Davis, that the letters do not " contain any matter Selected Essays, ed. Gordon Hall Gerould (Boston: Ginn, 1905), 30. The Man of Feeling ( 1 77 1 ; N e w York: Norton, 1 9 5 8) , x i v . The novel, Mackenzie wrote in the Lounger, should " aid the cause of virtue, and . . . hold out patterns o f the most exalted benevolence" (June 1 8, 1 7 8 5 ; reprinted in loan Williams, Novel and Romance, 3 29) . 48Henry Fielding,
49Henry Mackenzie,
I28
The Pseudofactual Novel which will be held actionable in the eye of the law. "50 The tongue in-cheek nature of this ruse is made explicit in Davis' s reply; "There have been so many letters upon travels lately published - what between Smollett' s , Sharp's, . . . The public seems to be cloyed with that kind of entertainment . . . . Nevertheless, I will . . . run the risque of printing and publishing. " Diderot's guarantees about the truth of his tale of cloistral incarceration pale beside the text' s more powerful thematic assertions . The banning of a movie version of La religieuse in France j ust twenty years ago suggests that the novel's satirical thrust resides more in its generalized critique of clerical corruption than in its exposure of certain individuals engaged in nefarious acts . 51 Laclos ' s "editor' s" that he simply selected and com pronouncement piled the letters that make up Les liaisons dangereuses is subverted by his "publisher's " remark that "we do not guarantee the authenticity of this narrative, and have even strong reasons for believing that it is but a romance. "52 In these and many other instances, ironizing coventions of fiction ality enable the novelist to move beyond those constraints that, in the earlier forms of pseudofactual fiction, restricted the range of the text's interpretive commentary to the perceptual vantage point of its speak ing voice (or voices) . The later novelists are clearly offering general ized s tatements about ethical principles and social realities, and irony is directed toward the referent as much as toward the manner of rep resentation. As Laclos ' s "publisher" notes, " Several of the personages whom [the editor] brings on his stage have minds so sorry that it were impossible to believe that they lived in our century, in this cen tury of philosophy, where the light shed on all sides has rendered, as everyone knows, all men so honourable, all women so modest and reserved. " But the eighteenth-century novelist's adherence to the 50Tobias Smollett, The Expedition of Humphrey Clinker (1 771), ed. Lewis Knapp (London: Oxford University Press, 1 966) , r . The passage quoted below is from pp. 2 - 3 . 51As Jean-Luc Godard commented regarding Andre Malraux's suppression of the movie, "It's really sinister to see a Gaullist minister in 1 966 afraid of an Enclyclopedist of 1 789" (quoted in Denis Diderot, The Nun, Eileen B. Hennessey [Los Angeles : Hollo trans . way, 1 968], l ) . 52Choderlos d e Laclos, Dangerous Acquaintances, trans. Ernest Dowson (London: None such, 1 940) , xiii. The passage quoted below appears on the same page. In pointing up a general similarity between the uses of pseudofactual imposture in English and French nov els of the eighteenth century, I am not asserting that novelistic developments in these two countries were parallel in many other respects. For more on the differences between the ev olution of prose fiction in England and France, see Williams, The Idea of the Novel.
I29
Practice pseudofactual mode of narration also enforces a separation between the speaking voice and the informing ideological abstraction pro j ected by the author: in many pseudofactual novels, from Moll Flanders to Les liaisons dangereuses, it is difficult to determine exactly what the author thinks . The author has not yet achieved the transcen dental subj ectivity afforded by full-fledged realism, which would posit an Archimedean position outside the text, from which a plural ity of ideological stances could be counterposed, reconciled, and as similated to a governing perspective. The business of interpreting and judging social reality therefore remains the province of fictional characters who have not yet been as similated to a fictional representation that appears to emanate from a position beyond ideology. Each text projects characters with differ ent conceptions of that reality, of course, and each signals a uniquely contradictory way of appropriating it. Les liaisons dangereuses suggests a contradiction between Laclos's aversion to and fascination with his decadent wordmongers , while La religieuse suggests a contradiction between Diderot's radical polemic against the church and his uneasy identification with the social system that sustains that institution. My main point, however, is that these documentary novels of the eigh teenth century tend to play out their ideological contradictions by proj ecting some sort of disparity between the text's divergent claims to cognition. As analogous configuration, the text makes certain generalizing propositions about its referent; as a putative true docu ment, the text implies that its pretensions to reference are confined to the opinions and speculations of memoirists and letter-writers . Pseudofactual novels of the eighteenth century routinely proj ect a certain hesitancy, not about whether to make fictional assertions , but about how to make them in a convincing way. This hesitancy, I sug gest, reflects the contradictory epistemological stance of the contem poraneous bourgeois subj ect, who is in the process of achieving he gemony but has not yet consolidated for itself a position from which the relation of perception to cognition can be taken as self-evident and unproblematic.
The Pseudofactual Novel and Empiricism The primary conceptual abstraction shaping the representational strategy of the pseudofactual novel in its various phases is the episte mology of nascent empiricism. The somewhat cavalier attitude toIJ O
The Pseudofactual Novel ward factuality characterizing ancient, medieval, and, to a lesser ex tent, Renaissance discourse, both fictional and historical, suggests that the verifiability of particular assertions was not necessarily taken as the most important criterion of their value. If a text purported to be telling the truth, that truth generally was moral or religious not empirical. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, however, the view emerges that facts are meaningful in their own right and func tion as reliable indices to truth-an empiricist credo that visibly sets in motion the mechanics of a corroborative apparatus that distin guishes the conventions of the pseudofactual novel from those of the romance. For the pseudofactual novel routinely features in its protag onist a consciousness engaged in the activity of perceiving and under standing its world. In Jack Wilton's conclusion that Surrey's helmet resembles a garden waterpot, in H . F . 's voyeuristic speculations about the exp eriences of Thomas and John, in Pamela's subconscious ma nipulation of Mr. B . , we see a series of Lockean selves busy in the procedure of codifying perception into cognition. Experience, they proclaim, is that from which, as Locke said, "our knowledge . . . de rives itself" : "Our observation, employed either about external sensi ble obj ects, perceived and reflected on by ourselves , or about the internal operations of our minds, perceived and reflected on by our selves, is that which supplies our understanding with all the materials of thinking. These two are the fountains of knowledge, from whence all the ideas we have, or can naturally have, spring. "53 The fictional characters' ambition to know the lineaments of their worlds also ar ticulates the insurgent epistemological program of Descartes, who as pired to liberate philosophy from the "infirm foundation" of scholas tic speculation and to formulate a "knowledge highly useful in life, " by means of which, "knowing the force and the actions of fire, water, air, the stars, the heavens, and the other bodies that surround us . . . as distinctly as we know the various crafts of our artisans, we might also apply them in the same way to all the uses to which they are adopted, and thus render ourselves lords and possessors of nature. "54 53John Locke, An Essay concerning Human Understanding ( 1 690) , in The English Philoso phers.from Bacon to Mill, ed. Edwin A. Burtt (New York: Modern Library, 1939), 248 . 54Rene Descartes, A Discourse on Method and Selected Writings, trans. John Veitch, Every man's Library (New York: Dutton, 1 9 5 1 ) , 5 3 - 54. For the view that Descartes's Discourse constitutes "an ur-novel in which we can trace the coming to be of the space the novel will be assigned , " see). M. Bernstein, The Philosophy ofthe Novel: Lukacs, Marxism, and the Dia lectics ofForm (Brighton: Harvester, 1 984) , 1 6 5 , 166-84. IJ I
Practice Portraying an ego cogitans who takes the res extensa of the social world as his or her obj ect of inquiry, the pseudofactual novel repre sents an exploratory consciousness attempting to be "lord and posses sor" of its environment. 55 Just as empiricism mounted a challenge to the old idealism of medi eval science, the narrative strategy of the pseudofactual novel implied a criticism of the aprioristic abstractions of the romance. Indeed, any subversive impact of the pseudofactual novel derives primarily from its insurgent epistemology; in The Unfortunate Traveller and Pamela, in Robinson Crusoe and La religieuse, cognition is insistently scruti nized as the activity of determinate individuals confronting concrete social situations. A bstraction does not mean the invocation of eternal truths, but instead designates the procedure whereby, as Locke de fines it, "ideas taken from particular beings become general repre sentatives of all the same kind. "56 Conclusions are shown to be the result of the represented subject's inquiry into the res extensa, rather than as the quod semper quod ubique ab omnium creditum est implicit in the romance and codified in the normative universals of neoclassical aesthetic theory. Defoe's foregrounding of a highly individualized and exploratory voice in Moll Flanders thus runs completely counter to Shaftesbury's prescription that "the variety of Nature is such, as to distinguish every thing she forms by a peculiar character; which, if strictly observed, will make the subj ect appear unlike to anything ex tant in the world besides . But this effect the good poet and painter seek industriously to prevent. They hate minuteness, and are afraid of singularity . "57 Moll is preeminently singular, and the effect of Defoe's portrayal of her is to make the reader wonder whether she re sembles "anything extant in the world besides . " The pseudofactual 551 am not alone, of course, in claiming that the eighteenth-century novel is profoundly shaped by empiricism. Watt, for one
( The Rise of the Novel,
chap .
1),
argues for a close cor
relation between empiricist epistemology and fictional form. But Watt takes more or less at face value the empiricist pretension to a neutral and precise replication of the objection of perception.
I
am clearly indebted to Watt, but
I
am more interested in empiricism as an ide
ological paradigm, one that is shaped primarily by changes in the forces of production. For the alternate view that the pseudofactual apparatus of the early novel is attributable princi pally to the Puritans' distrust of the imagination, see Sidney J. Black, "Eighteenth-Century
Boston University Studies in English, 1 ( 1 9 5 5 ) : 3 3 - 44. Human Understanding, 28 1 .
'Histories' as a Fictional Mode, " 56Locke,
S7Anthony, Third Earl o f Shaftesbury, "Essay on the Freedom of Wit and Humour, " in
Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times, Etc., Grant Richards , 1 900) ,. 1 :9 5 - 96. IJ2
ed. John M. Robertson (London:
The Pseudofactual Novel
novelist's very hesitancy about incorporating the speaking voice fully into the text serves to highlight all the more the provisional nature of any discourse's claim to cognition. The documentary materials ac companying the text thus serve not to validate a posteriori the asser tions of the text' s narrative voice but to authenticate its sincerity. Even when, as in later pseudofactual fiction, these documentary ma terials ironize the speaker's discourse, they do not furnish determinate judgments, for to do so would involve a totalizing activity alien to the empiricist proj ect. ''judgment, " Locke reminds us, " is the presuming things to be so, without perceiving it. "58 The pseudofactual novel's empiricist epistemology constitutes its primary challenge to aristocratic hegemony. This is not to say, how ever, that it lacks an expressly political propositional content. On the contrary, the "singular" voices that we hear in the pseudofactual novel frequently pose dear challenges to received notions of decorum or social order. Oroonoko, it is true, may not in some respects occupy a particularly subversive relation to dominant ideology (despite its bold treatment of the slavery issue) , but The Unfortunate Traveller, Robinson Crusoe, and Pamela provide a discursive terrain where distinctly bourgeois viewpoints and aspirations receive a hearing. Jack Wilton, after all, delivers a devastating satire on courtly tourna ments and love rhetoric; Crusoe celebrates the bourgeois entrepre neur; Pamela the servant marries her master. The individualism em bedded in the epistemology of the pseudofactual novel thus readily aligns itself with the premises of Lockean political economy, which posits a Homo economicus, unburdened by tradition, as the autono mous center of its contractual relations . In their very freedom from the constraint of performing an assigned function fully controlled from outside the text, the protagonists of pseudofactual fiction enact a version of Locke's definition of radical independence- that is, that "state of perfect freedom" where people may "order their actions and dispose of their perceptions and persons as they think fit, within the bounds of the law of nature, without asking leave, or depending upon the will of any other man. " 59 Just as Locke' s atomistic ego in dependently contracts his social relations in the state of nature, the memoirist or letter writer contracts to be understood on discursive 58Locke, Human Understanding, 3 77 . 59Locke, An Essay Concerning the True Original, Extent and End of Civil Government ( 1 690) , in The English Philosophers, ed. Burtt, 404. 13 3
Practice terms presumably uninfluenced by inherited conventions . As N . W . Visser points out, the pseudofactual novel's " marginal standing i n the prevailing hierarchy of kinds" enabled it to be "a vehicle through which an emergent class could explore and codify its sense of itself and the world. " 60 While pseudofactual fictions of the seventeenth and eighteenth cen turies express the revolutionary aspects of early bourgeois empiri cism, however, they also reflect its limitations as an oppositional pro gram. For in its confrontation with the res extensa, the ego cogitans denies the dialectical- and hence historical- relation between sub j ect and obj ect, taking as an ontological given its own empyrean posi tion in relation to material reality. Locke, who described the mind as a " closet wholly shut from the light, with only some little openings left to let in external visible resemblances or ideas of things with out, "61 concluded that "the mind, in all its thoughts and reasonings , hath n o other immediate obj ect b u t its own ideas, which i t alone does and can contemplate. " Descartes decided that " except our thoughts , there i s nothing abs olutely i n our power; so that, when w e have done our best in respect of things external to us, all wherein we fail of suc cess is to be held, as regards us, absolutely impossible. "62 While Descartes prided himself on his investigations in physics and anatomy and celebrated the value of experimentation, he also proclaimed the radical unreliability of sensory data and continually returned to the cogito ergo sum that constituted, for him, the "first principle of philos ophy . " The ego cogitans is therefore a peculiarly abstract identity, never altering through its participation in the world of things, and never contemplating, as Descartes remarked of himself, " anything higher than the reformation of my own opinions, and basing them on a foundation wholly my own. " For the early empiricists, nature was to be known by contemplation but not by intervention; the explor atory consciousness that aspired to be "lord and possessor" of nature also took as an operative premise its own alienation from, and lack of determination by, its obj ect of inquiry. In the pseudofact:ual novel, this empiricist failure to discern the his torical connection of subj ect and obj ect manifests itself in the pecul60N. W. Visser, "The Novel as Liberal Narrative: The Possibilities of Radical Fiction, " unpublished essay (Rhodes University, Cape Town, 1 9 8 5 ) , 6. 61Locke, Human Unders tanding, 282. The passage quoted below is from p . 3 1 7. 62Descartes, 2 1 -22. The quotations below are from pp. 28 and 1 2 . I J4
The Pseudofactual N ovel
iarly abstract relation of character to the represented social world. Jack Wilton's interaction with his historical world is beset with anachronisms. Oroonoko, with his courtly speech and Caucasian fea tures, is not especially plausible as an African ruler of the early colo nial period. Moll rolls through her environment with the freedom of a billiard ball in a Newtonian experiment: she may be hauled off to Newgate, but her character remains an emanation of her own nature. Even Pamela's psychology partakes of a mechanistic quality, for she responds to stimuli with unfailing consistency, forms a minimum of inductive generalizations, and readily abandons even these when the stimuli emanating from Mr. B. alter in their social content. Pamela's inability to bear a grudge is not simply a function of her unacknowl edged ambitions ; it is also intimately linked to her shallow contextu alization in social relations, which take shape as background rather than as formative context . Where the realist Twain was to portray his character Chambers in Pudd'nhead Wilson as permanently and irre vocably stamped by his experience as a slave, Richardson makes his servant girl infinitely adaptable to her radically altered social sta tus : speech and manners - the material expressions of class- are strangely irrelevant to Pamela's experience. The pseudofactual novel ists ' unwillingness to drop the imposture of veracity and to incorpo rate their characters fully into the stories they tell implies a static view of the text's social referent: historical actuality consists not in pro cesses but in obj ects , and the perceiving subj ect discovers identity in opposition to, rather than in conjunction with, its environment. The documentary strategy of the pseudofactual novel thus medi ates the central ideological contradictions characterizing early empiri cism. The text represents discourse as an activity of particular indi viduals. The act of perception leads to cognition, but cognition is not imposed- at least, not overdetermined-by the configuration of the text. The text's avoidance of interpretive totalization thus signals a critical relation to the apriorism of dominant aesthetic and social ide ologies . "Historicity" is retained in a residual apparatus of documen tary authentication to the extent that "history" - as the totalizing field of force informing that referent-is not recognized as the pri mary determinant of the activities of perception and cognition. If characters have not attained full credibility as objects of perception, they must inhabit a realm as subjects of perception that is (or at least claims to be) coterminous with that of the reader. IJ 5
Pr a c ti c e
The Pseudofactual Novet and Merchant Cap italism To posit that the pseudofactual novel mediates the contradictory conceptual abstractions of nascent empiricism does not tell the whole story, however. For empiricism itself constitutes a quintessential ar ticulation of the new form of the exchange relation accompanying the emergent capitalist social formation. On one level, the connection be tween empiricism and capitalism is obvious and was in fact perceived and articulated by philosophers of the time. Bacon drew an explicit connection between the advancement of scientific knowledge and the voyages of discovery. Crossing the Atlantic had replaced the search for Atlantis, he declared, and "These times may j ustly bear in their motto . plus ultra - further yet-in precedence of the ancient non ul tra - no further . . . in respect of our sea-voyages, by which the whole globe of earth has, after the manner of the heavenly bodies, been many times compassed and circumnavigated. "63 Similarly, Descartes' s desire to make man the "lord and possessor of nature" ex pressed the ideological imperatives of a class that needed to abolish the mystifications of feudal apologetics in order to attain its political and economic ends . Descartes, we will recall, aimed to produce a "knowledge highly useful in life" that would enable man to apply the elements to " the uses to which they are adopted, " thus bringing the knowledge of nature into the same sphere as the knowledge of " the various crafts of our artisans . " The postulation of an ego cogitans tak ing the res extensa as its obj ect was therefore linked to the commer cial proj ect of the bourgeoisie; Descartes's regulatory and proprietary language is hardly an accidental construct. As Engels rather grudg ingly admitted, in the early phases of the bourgeois era .
.
the bounds of the old
orbis terrarum
were pierced, only now for the first
time was the world really discovered and the basis laid for subsequent world trade and the transition from handicraft to manufacture, which in its tum formed the starting-point for modem large-scale industry. The dictatorship of the Church over men's minds was shattered . . . .
63Francis B acon, Works (London: 1 8 5 7 - 74) , 4: 1 69 . For more on the influence of the oce anic voyages on Elizabethan writing, see Robert Ralston Cawley, Unpathed Waters: Studies in the Influence of the Voyagers on Elizabethan Literature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1 940) . 13 6
Th e P s e u do fa c t u a l N o ve l It was the greatest progressive revolution that mankind had so far ex perienced. 64
· As part of this process of global exploration, the revolution in scien tific method, with its necessary dismantling of older forms of specu lative philosophy, was for Engels clearly founded in the economic imperatives of the rising bourgeoisie. It has been pointed out, however, that the utility of the empiricist platform was ultimately more ideological than pragmatic and that the theory of the empiricists was in actuality greatly advanced beyond their practice. Christopher Caudwell, for example, proposes that early bourgeois natural philosophy tells us a good deal more about property relations than it does about methods that were used in scien tific inquiry: "Man is the subj ect; Nature is the obj ect. Therefore in bourgeois society, the obj ect appears solely as 'things' over which man has rights , and whose laws or 'necessity' he discovers in order to satisfy his desires . " According to Caudwell, empiricism, in spite of its p retensions to experimentalism, is an intrinsically noninterven tionist philosophy. "Nature is always known as a passive obj ect- as something not subj ect to man's activity nor the antagonist of his striving, but as something self-contained and shut in by its necessi ties . Hence Man's whole relation to Nature bears the stamp of the property relation, in which his right over it is the reward of his con sciousness or cleverness - never of his activity. "65 The empyrean stance of the ego cogitans is therefore primarily an ideological pos ture, one that transposes a relation of ownership into an epistemolog ical category. Sohn-Rethel has further developed the connections between the epistemological and political premises of Cartesian dualism and the "real abstraction" of early capitalist relations of production and ex change. The gradually increased division of mental from manual la bor, Sohn-Rethel argues, determines the cognitive procedures of bourgeois science, from the time of Galileo to the present. "It is . . . not science but ideology, " he declares, "when, in the seventeenth century, philosophers like Descartes and Hobbes looked upon the 64Frederick Engels, Dialectics of Nature (Moscow: Progress, 1 974) , 2 1 - 2 2 . 65Christopher Caudwell, "The Crisis in Physics, " i n The Concept of Freedom (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1965), 205 . IJ 7
Practice outer world as a whole and in all its parts , organic no less than inor ganic, as self-operating mechanisms. "66 According to Sohn-Rethel, the empiricist compulsion to conceptualize the material world as ob j ect of inquiry expresses above all else the increasing need of capital to impose upon produ ction the abstraction of a self-regulating mecha nism : conceptual appropriation takes as its model the appropriation of an abstracted and transferable exchange value. The growing influ ence of empiricist paradigms is a crucial signal of the development of bourgeois hegemony, but the significance of this influence resides more in the realm of ideology than in that of technology. The principal historical development that sustained- and was ra tionalized b y - empiricist epistemology was therefore not the devel opment of the applied sciences needed for expanding commerce and industry but the gradual subordination of the social relations and the forces of production to the automatism of capital. This process would attain its full development only in the nineteenth century, when workers relinquished their tools and became appendages to machines propelled by nonhuman sources of energy. From the late sixteenth through most of the eighteenth century, however, changes in the so cial formation were initiated that would render capitalist production virtually a self-regulating phenomenon. The primitive accumulation of the capital necessary for the developments Engels described consis ted primarily in the accumulation of a fund of labor power. The early capitalists embarked upon their enterprises, not by amassing wealth from trade or even by discovering p recious metals in the Americas, but primarily by separating laborers from their means of produc tion- a process of social compulsion. In the era of handicraft indus try, the social division of labor was moved from the society at large to the workshop, where wage laborers possessing specialized skills were b rought together under one roof. In the era of manufacture, workers were trained to perform segmented tasks requiring less knowledge and expertise: manufacture was , in Marx's words , "a pro ductive mechanism whose p arts are human beings . "67 With the sub jugation of workers to the discipline of wage labor, capital gradually b rought the entire social fo rmation under the hegemony of the ex change relation . Where in precapitalist modes of production s ocial re66Alfred Sohn-Rethel, intellectual and Manual Labor: A Critique of Ep istemology, trans. Martin S ohn-Rethel (Atlantic Highlands, N .J . : Humanities, 1 978), 1 2 3 . 67Karl Marx, Cap ital, r : 3 3 8 . The passage quoted below is from p. 7 3 7 . IJ B
The P s e u d o fa ctu al N ov el
lations took the form of visible, personal dependencies , in the era of handicrafts, and especially of manufacturing, relations among per sons increasingly became obj ective dependency relations, character ized by growing economic abstraction and by the apparent neutrality of the market. Marx caustically remarked, It is not enough that the conditions of labour are concentrated in a mas s , i n the shape of capital, at the o n e pole of society, while a t the other are grouped masses of men, who have nothing to sell but their labour power. Neither is it enough that they are compelled to sell it volun tarily. The advance of capitalist production develops a working-clas s , which by education, tradition, habit, looks upon the condition o f that mode o f production as self-evident laws of Nature .
But the era of merchant capital and manufacture was beset by con tradictions, for capitalist hegemony was by no means consolidated or complete. For one thing, the capitalist class encountered continual opposition from the landed aristocracy, who, while assimilating a good deal of agricultural production to the capitalist model, still re tained control of the state and the economy. Furthermore, the capital ist class itself was hardly the monolithic presence that it would be in the era of industrialism. As Elizabeth Fox-Genovese and Eugene Genovese have recently argued, Although [merchant capital] provided a powerful s olvent to feudal and seigneurial relations and contributed mightily to the emergence of a world market, it could not create capitalist social relations or a new sys tem o f production. To the extent that it remained commercial and money-dealing capital - to the extent that it escaped becoming an agent of industrial capital -it eventually became an impediment to the emer gence of the capitalist mode of production. 68
Merchant capitalist enterprises often served as financial auxiliaries to the entrenched landed aristrocracy; even the "historic overseas expan sion, " Fox-Genovese and Genovese argue, was "a desperate if heroic effort to shore up a crisis-ridden feudal mode of production. " In addition, the owners of manufacturing enterprises experienced 68Elizabeth Fox-Genovese and Eugene Genovese, Fruits of Merchant Cap ital: Slavery and Bourgeois Property in the Rise and Expansion of Capitalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1 9 8 3 ) , 6 - 7 . The statement quoted below is from p. ro. I J9
Practice continual- if, to be sure, largely spontaneous - oppos1tlon from their workers, who maintained a modicum of control over the condi tions and terms of p roduction. " Since handicraft skill is the founda tion of manufacture, " remarked Marx, " and since the mechanism of manufacture as a whole possesses no framework, apart from the labourers themselves, capital is constantly compelled to wrestle with the insubordination of the workmen. "69 The early phases of the capi talist era thus witnessed a tremendous expansion in commodity ex change but they were not completely regulated by it; the principle of equivalence characterized emergent tendencies in the social synthesis but did not extend to the labor process itself. The "interior of the commodity , " as Marx put it, was not yet dominated by the exchange relation. Marx defined the intermediary nature of merchant capital in this way: The quantitative ratio in which products are exchanged is at first quite arbitrary. They assume the form of commodities inasmuch as they are exchangeables , i . e . , expressions of one and the same kind. Continued exchange and more regular reproduction fo r exchange reduces this arbi trariness more and more. But at first not for the producer and con sumer, but for their go-between, the merchant, who compares money p rices and p ockets the difference. It is through his own movements that
Merchant's cap ital is originally merely the inter vening movement between extremes which it does not control and between prem ises which it does not create .70
he establishes equivalence.
The important idea here is that the principle of equivalence is situated between "uncontrolled" and "uncreated" processes of production and consumption. Merchant capital played a growing role in regulating the market, but it co uld not yet propose itself as a " self-evident law of nature. " The Cartesian hypostatization of the ego cogitans and the res extensa. I suggest, mediates this "intervening movement" b etween uncontrolled and uncreated extremes and premises . " Descartes , " Marx wryly remarked, " saw with the eyes of the manufacturing pe riod. "71 Disj unctions would necessarily exist between the theory and 69Marx, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, ed. Frederick Engels, trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (New York: International Publishers, 1 967) , 1 : 3 67. 70Marx, Cap ital, 3 : 3 24. 71Marx, Capital, 1 : 3 90.
140
The Pseudofactual Novel the practice of the sovereign bourgeois ego that aspires to take the material world as its obj ect and to appropriate to itself the fruits of production. That obj ect possesses, after all, a contradictory social na ture: it is characterized by the universal equivalence accompanying a highly developed market economy, but it has not yet been subdued to the imperatives of those industrial capitalist forces of production that will extend the principle of abstract equivalence to the totality of the labor process. To the extent that the abstraction of the exchange relation has not fully penetrated the social relations of production, the epistemological paradigms articulating early capitalist development will be highlighted as ideology - conceptual abstractions necessary for appropriating the configuration of nature and society, perhaps , but hardly cognitive structures that can be said to emanate from the na ture of the obj ect itsel£ " Our knowledge, " Locke observed, " comes not only short of the reality of things, but even of the extent of our own ideas . . . . It would be well with us if our knowledge were but as large as our ideas , and there were not many doubts and inquiries con cerning the ideas we have, whereof we are not, nor I believe, ever shall be in this world, resolved. "72 As long as "abstraction" is seen as a generalizing activity of the perceiving subj ect, and not experienced as the pervading atmosphere of a reified daily life, such " doubts and inquiries " will continue to enforce a separation between perception and cognition . The historical contradictions characterizing the development o f bourgeois economic and political hegemony, I speculate, reproduce themselves in the fundamental contradictions informing the ironic strategy of documentary representation in the pseudofactual novel. History per se also enters the pseudofactual novel, of course. Moll tells us a good deal about the brutality of the primitive accumulation of capital in the early eighteenth century, and the Vicomte de Val mont reveals a good deal about the proclivities of the leisure class that lived off the surplus created by peasants before the French Revolu tion. But historical actuality enters the text through various levels of mediation and permeates not only its referent but its strategy of rep resentation as well. The pseudofactual novel's insistent inclusion of an authenticating documentary apparatus reveals a hesitancy about engaging in a procedure of analogous configuration that will assert 72Locke, Human Understanding, 3 2 8 .
I4 I
Practice the generality of the text' s representation of life. It is, paradoxically, only when the reifying tendency of industrial capitalism effects the full severance of mental and manual labor that the sense of the real is decisively supplanted by realism and that the documentary novel un dertakes a totalizing representation of the very historical process that produces the text' s alienation from its referent .
142
6 The Historical No vel
Through the plot [of the historical novel], at whose centre stands [the typical hero], a neutral ground is sought and found upon which the ex treme, opposing social forces can be brought into a human relation with one another. - Georg Lukacs
In the nineteenth century, the "sense of the real" has been su perseded by "realism, " and the dominant mode of the documentary novel becomes the historical novel. The term "historie" now disap pears from the title pages of novels , since they no longer aspire to in voke what Richardson called " that kind of Historical Faith which Fic tion itself is generally read with, tho ' we know it to be Fiction. "1 Banished from the manner of representation, however, history resur faces in the referent. Where pseudofactual novelists represented an abstract and undialectical relation between character and environ ment, and even the realist Fielding declared his lawyer in Tom Jones to have been alive for four thousand years, documentary novelists of the nineteenth century are historical novelists, for they view historical process as the crucible in which character and destiny are formed. Even those texts that recapitulate certain features of the pseudofactual novel's documentary strategy- such as Dickens's David Copperfield or Charles Reade' s The Autobiography ofa Thief- incorporate the speak ing "I" into a novelistic frame that locates the character's identity in a historically specific fictional realm, rather than in a speciously authen tic mode of discourse. Other modes of documentary fiction enj oy 1 Samuel Richardson, Selected Letters, ed. John Carroll (Oxford: Clarendon, 1 964) , 8 5 . 1 43
Practice residual status in the nineteenth century, but the historical novel emerges as the paradigmatic mode of the genre. The shift from pseudofactuality to realism marks a maj or trans formation in the conceptions of history that guide the practice of nineteenth-century novelists. When the novel's referent comes to be seen as possessing a dynamis in its own right, historicity need no longer be invoked to guarantee the text's representation of that refer ent. By a curious paradox, mimesis is empowered to interpret and . j udge historical actuality when it finally acknowledges its own dis tinctness as a mode of discourse: the novel loses its hesitancy about its propositional status when it admits that its assertion is fictional. The historical novel's separation from nonfictional kinds of writing such as history and j ournalism thus signals its adoption of a new view of the historical process shaping the relation of character to event. As Raymond Williams points out, it is only in the nineteenth century that the term "history" comes to denote not merely a mode of dis course or.a universal process of change, but a crucial context for un derstanding the present. 2 This altered notion of historical process, we shall see, profoundly influences historiography of the time as well. From the Romantic history of Bancroft and Michelet to the "scien tific" history of Ranke and Taine, nineteenth-century historical narra tives take as their premise a view of history as the formative context of the present that sharply differentiates them from histories written during the century before. The historical novel thus participates in a broader transformation of historical consciousness . Its emergence as an unabashedly fictional kind of writing signals not its abandonment of the claim to represent historical actuality but its reformulation of this claim in accordance with a changing conception of that actual ity. 3 The representational strategy of the historical novel differs in three respects from the practice of earlier documentary fiction. First, the text now proposes cognition through an undisguised adoption of analogous configuration. Characters make their claim to truthfulness 2Raymond Williams, Kt'ywords: A Vocabula ry of Culture and Society (New York: Oxford University Press, 1 976) , u 9 - 20. 3for the view that the m ajor transformation in modern historical consciousness occurred in the eighteenth century--and hence manifests itself in the eighteenth-century novel - see Leo Braudy, Narrative Fo1m in Histo ry and Fiction : Hume, Fielding, and Gibbon (Princeton: Princeton University Pres:;, 1970) . r 44
The Historical Novel not through their imposture of veracity but through their function as representative types; hence they convey cognition of the referent through their relationality. Moll compels interest by her billiardlike movement through a static world, but Cooper's Harvey Birch, in The Sp y , gains credibility only as he is embedded in the context of a revolutionary crisis. Second, the plot of the historical novel relin quishes the historical probabilities accompanying the pseudofactual novel and directs its narrative energy to the elaboration of a pattern of complication and resolution that interprets and evaluates the social world. The historical novel posits complication as an essential com ponent of the historical dialectic; resolution becomes a teleological necessity, and totalization emerges as the principal strategy for repro ducing the lineaments of historical actuality. Third, empirical data enter the historical novel not to validate the author's honesty but to reinforce the text's claim to offer a persuasive interpretation of its ref erent. Where details in the pseudofactual novel could be outrageous and anomalous so long as they purported to be true (we recall Mme d ' Aulnoy's fantastic tales of intrigue) , factual references in the histori cal novel must be plausible, yet they need make no pretension to a lit eral retelling of events. When a figure from world history enters the fictional world, he or she verifies the traj ectory of the plot; when a corroborative preface or footnote is attached to the text, it authenti cates the propositionality embedded in the analogous configuration. Telling the truth has become a matter of accurate generalization. The representational strategy of the historical novel bespeaks, in short, a new epistemological program. In the closing section of this chapter, I shall argue that this epistemological program points to the qualititative alteration taking place in the relations of production characteristic of an emergent industrial capitalist society. Realism, I shall propose, articulates the triumph of reification; the historical novel's powerful synthesis of the dialectics of social change mediates the emergence of capital itself as the supreme social subj ect. Industrial capitalism is thus in one sense the hero of my tale here. Following the lead of Marx, who grudgingly admired the achievement of nine teenth-century capital in drawing the economy of the entire globe into a universal market, I acknowledge the higher level of mimetic ab straction made possible by the more fully developed abstraction of the exchange relation in the era of the mechanically powered ma chine. But the very abstraction that derives from the increased com1 45
Practice plexity in the realm of the concrete makes it increasingly difficult to return to the realm of the concrete; by rendering capital the supreme social subj ect, reification posits the equivalence of the different sub j ects who are subordinated to capital's hegemony. In most nine teenth-century historical novels, the vantage point of the authorial subj ect thus presents itself as interchangeable with that of the reader. The ideological coloration of the consciousness that shapes the text is no longer foregrounded for critical consideration, as it was in the pseudofactual novell. Instead, the text's goal of rendering empirically grounded representation readily lapses into positivism, and totaliza tion threatens to become self-evidence. In its contradictory blend of disability and empowerment, the historical novel mediates the reifi cation that both expands and limits the epistemological horizons of nineteenth-century discourse. It should be apparent that the representational strategy of the his torical novel creates new problems at the same time that it solves old ones . The historical novel indeed makes possible a comprehensive portraiture of past events that was unavailable to the pseudofactual novel. But where the empirical self-consciousness of the pseudofactual novel continually called attention to the epistemological relation be tween fact and generalization, the more confident empiricism of the historical novel tends to simplify this relation. The historical novel's "facts " appear to anchor the text's analogous configuration in histori cal actuality by proposing that particular corroborative data bear an unmediated reference to the public historical record. Actually, how ever, these data function to validate a posteriori the text's particular ideological construction of its referent. Documentation in the histori cal novel is intrinsically tautological; rather than confirming the text's assertions about social reality, it corroborates a reality assumed to be self-evident. This documentary practice was bound to recoil upon it self. In the course of the century, the historical novel's empiricist claims enter into a state of crisis , ultimately issuing in the profound epistemological skepticism characterizing modernist documentary fiction. 4 4The debate over the meaning of the term "realism" is heated and never-ending. In re cent years, of course, the notion that nineteenth-century realism aims at transparent "reflec tion" has been widely challenged. See, for example, Leo Bersani's A Future for Astyanax: Character and Desire in Literature (Boston: Little, Brown, 1 976) . Bersani argues, '"fhe or-
The Historical Novel
The Classical Historical Novel Lukacs's writings on nineteenth-century realism remain the locus classicus of the theory of the historical novel, and any Marxist discus sion of the genre should take them as the point of departure. The cen tral critical category in Lukacs's theory of realism is the "type, " who, as fictional protagonist, provides a peculiar synthesis which organically binds together the general and the particular both in characters and situations . What makes a type a type is not its average quality, not its mere individual being, however pro foundly conceived; what makes it a type is that in it all the humanly and socially essential determinants are present on their highest level of devel opment, in the ultimate unfolding of the possibilities latent in them, in extreme presentation of their extremes , rendering concrete the peaks and limits of men and epochs . 5
dered significances of realistic fiction are presented as immanent to society, whereas in fact they are the mythical denial of that society's fragmented nature. . . . The formal and psy chological reticence of most realistic fiction makes for a secret complicity between the nov elist and his society's illusions about its own order. Realistic fiction serves nineteenth century society by providing it with strategies for containing (and repressing) its disorder within significantly structured stories about itself" (6 1 , 62) . There is much of value here; as I shall argue throughout this chapter, realism does entail ideological operations of con tainment and repression. But we should not los-e sight of the empiricist goals - and achievements -of nineteenth-century realism, which did in fact manage to capture the to tality of social relations with a new degree of precision. As Harry Levin observes, "Etymo logically, realism is thing-ism. . . . Platonic idealists and scholastic 'realists' - and let us not be confused by the misnomer-had believed in the priority of universals, universalia ante rem. Specific obj ects were mere accidents, or at best symbolic correspondences with the actualities of a transcendent otherworld. That they should be valued for their own sake, that things should have meaning in themselves, marked the triumph of empiricism, materi alism, and worldliness" ( The Gates ofHorn : A Study ofFive French Realists [New York: Ox ford University Press, 1963]). For the various formulations o f " realism" that have been in fluential in writing this chapter, see George Levine, The Realistic Imagination: English Fiction .from Frankenstein to Lady Chatterley (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 9 8 1 ) ; Taylor Stoehr, "Realism and Verisimilitude, " Texas Studies in Language and Literature, r r ( 1 970) : 1 269 - 8 8 ; loan Williams, The Realist Novel in England: A Study in Development (London: Macmillan, 1 9 74) ; Robert Alter, "Mimesis and the Motive for Fiction, " TriQuarterly, 42 (Spring 1 978) : 224-49; Everett W. Knight, The Novel as Structure and Praxis : From Cervantes to Malraux (Atlantic Highlands, N.J . : Humanities, 1 980) ; Mary Louise Pratt, Toward a Speech-Act Theory of Literary Discourse (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1 977) , 201 - 2 3 ; and of course Lukics's many writings on realism. 'George Lukacs, Studies in European Realism, Universal Library (New York: Grosset & Dunlap, 1 964) , 6. r4 7
Practice The fate of the typical hero thus embodies in microcosm the essential traj ectory of the historical dialectic: "Through the plot, at whose cen tre stands the hero, a neutral ground is sought and found upon which the extreme, opposing social forces can be brought into a human rela tionship with one another. "6 Moreover, the complications and reso lutions constituting the plot of the historical novel represent what the author sees as the essential dynamic of historical process. The world historical hero here plays a necessarily subsidiary role. As Lukacs says of Scott's novels, the great representatives of the age "can never be central figures of the action . . . . The important leading figure, who embodies an historical movement, necessarily does so at a certain level of abstraction . Scott, by first showing the complex and in volved character of popular life itself, creates this being which the leading figure then has to generalize and concentrate in an historical deed. " Articulating the lesson of the French Revolution- that his tory is the product of mass activity, rather than of the subj ective in tentions of kings and generals -the world-historical hero functions, in Hegelian fashion, as an index to the unconscious strivings of the masses of people. But the real "struggles and antagonisms of history" are best represented by "mediocre" heroes who, "in their psychology and destiny, always represent social trends and historical forces . " In this context, "it matters little whether individual details, individual facts are historically correct or not . . . . Detail . . . is only a means of achieving historical faithfulness, for making concretely clear the his torical necessity of a concrete situation. " In many ways Lukacs offers an accurate and penetrating descrip tion of the ideological premises of the historical novel. Certainly Scott's novels, which Lukacs repeatedly invokes as pure instances of the form, fulfill Lukics 's criteria for realistic representation. In Ivan hoe, for example, fictional characters such as Cedric the Saxon and Front-de-Boeuf act out the historical contradiction between Saxons and Normans; historical personages such as Robin Hood and Richard the Lion-Hearted assume ancillary roles that emphasize the primary function of the anonymous populace in effecting historical change. In Waverley; or, ' Tis Sixty Years Since, the typical hero emerges as the dialectical embodiment of vast social forces . Thus Waverley's alter nating attraction to Rose Bradwardine and Flora Mac-Ivor sets forth 6Lukics, The Historical Novel, trans. Hannah Mitchell and Stanley Mitchell (London: Merlin, 1 962) , 36. The statements quoted below appear on pp. 39, 3 4, and 59.
The Historical Novel in microcosm the contrary appeals of Lowland concession and High land rebellion; his initial rej ection of, and ultimate reconciliation with, his own aristocratic status illustrate Scott's melioristic view of the path of historical change. When Bonnie Prince Charlie enters the tale, he furnishes a specific link with the historical record, but it is rel atively unimportant whether or not the real Pretender followed the exact circumstantial course that Scott outlines for his fictional coun terpart. What matters most is that Bonnie Prince Charlie' s quixotic actions validate Waverley's eventual decision to repudiate the Stuart rebellion; the world-historical hero is a catalyst, not a cause. Lukacs pays little attention to the question of documentary corrob oration, but we can expand upon his analysis by noting the ways in which Scott's testimonial materials are intended to reinforce the propositional claims of his novels . In the various prefaces and the postscript to Waverly, for example, Scott announces his departure from Gothic antiquarianism and his ambition to represent the histori cal forces that have proj ected Scotland into modern times . His goal is, indeed, to use fiction to delineate the trajectory of history: "The change, though steadily and rapidly progressive, has, nevertheless, been gradual; and, like those who drift down the stream of a deep and smooth river, we are not aware of the progress we have made until we fix our eye on the now distant point from which we have been drifted. "7 While Scott is careful to point out that his novel is based on historical research and the testimony of participants in the Highland Rebellion, he openly admits that his narrative is a "romance" and that he has "embodied in imaginary scenes, and ascribed to fictitious char acters, a part of the incidents which I then received from those who were actors in them. " The difference between this statement and Behn's claim to be relating neither "novel" or "story" is striking, and it bespeaks a qualitative shift in the cognitive capacities attributed to mimesis . Romance, imagination, and fiction are now means, rather than barriers, to assertion. Moreover, Waverley 's apparatus of footnotes testifies to the novel's presumption to be a reliable guide to the characteristic features of eighteenth-century Scottish history and culture. Thus one note tells us that " the sanguine Jacobites, during the eventful years 1 74 5 - 46, 7Sir Walter Scott, Waverley; or, ' Tis Sixty Years Since ( 1 8 14; London: Nelson, n . d . ) , 5 5 3 . The passages quoted below appear o n p p . 5 54, 234, and 1 5 4.
I49
Practice kept up the spirits of their party by the rumour of descent from France on behalf of the Chevalier St. George. " Another, referring to Fergus Mac-Ivor's regaining the estate that had been forfeited after his father' s participation in the insurrection of 1 7 1 5 , remarks that "it was not till after the total destruction of the clan influence, after 1 745 , that purchasers could be found, who offered a fair price for the estates forfeited in 1 7 1 5 , which were then brought to sale by the creditors of the York Buildings Co. , who had purchased the whole or greater part from the government at a very small price. " Unlike the docu mentary materials in the pseudofactual novel, which testify to the text' s authenticity but not necessarily to its truth, these documentary materials establish the verifiability of the text's generalized portrai ture of customs and historical movements . The text must present a valid analogy to hilstory, these notes imply, if the author has taken such pains to resea1rch his subj ect. (Indeed, one might note, even the typographical presence of the notes serves to anchor the text in an au thenticated reality. The very act of leaving the story and moving one's eyes to the small print at the bottom of the page has the effect of invoking an extratextual source of information. ) Cooper's novels,, which Lukacs also praises as exemplars o f classi cal historical fiction, adopt a comparable strategy in their proj ect of narrating and explaining the early years of the Republic. In The Spy : A Tale of the Neutral Ground, for example, the battle over war-torn Westchester County proj ects in microcosm the collision of opposed historical forces . JEven the rather insipid lovers, D unwoodie and Frances, take on the status of historical actors, in that the b arriers to their romantic fulfillment are thrown up by the contention of rebels and loyalists. And the omnipresent figure of the double agent, Har vey Birch, points to the shifting nature of political allegiances: his in teractions with both camps give full play to the attractiveness of the British cause (Cooper is something of an Anglophile) at the same time that they mobilize the reader' s sympathies on the side of the reb els . In this context, the text' s documentary apparatus serves an im portant validating function. Cooper's preface, which informs us that the novel is based on a story he was told about the experiences of an actual double agent during the Revolutionary War, parades the narra tive's fictionality and openly asserts the generalization encoded in the text: " [My] theme, " he declares, "is patriotism, " and " the hero of the 1 50
The Historical Novel anecdote just related is the best illustration of this subject. "8 More over, the mysterious figure who turns out to be George Washington corroborates the nationalistic theme. "That Providence destines this country for some great and glorious fate I must believe, " beams Washington, " while I witness the patriotism that pervades the bo soms of her lowest citizens. " The novel ends , indeed, with a " docu ment" that directly links the world-historical hero to the fate of Har vey Birch, who, having died fighting for his country once again in the War of 1 8 1 2 , is found clutching to his bosom a paper that reads : " Circumstances of political importance, which involve the lives and fortunes of many, have hitherto kept secret what this paper now re veals. Harvey Birch has for years been a faithful and unrequited ser vant of his country. Though man does not, may God reward him for his conduct! " The Spy most clearly shows Cooper as a self-consciously historical novelist. 9 It bears noting, however, that even the Leatherstocking novels, which do not portray world-historical heroes, introduce doc umentary materials in strategically similar ways . In the largely auto biographical The Pioneers, for example, Cooper includes a set of cor roborative statements that reverse the role assigned to documentation in the pseudofactual novel. The preface, informing us that the novel replicates many personalities from the Cooperstown of Cooper's youth, makes the peculiar claim that generalization is superior to pre cise historicity. In response to inquires about "how much of [the nov el's] contents is literal fact, and how much is intended to represent a general picture, . . . the author is very sensible that, had he confined himself to the latter, always the most effective, as it is the most valuable mode of conveying knowledge of this sort, he would have made a far better book" (italics added) . He later adds, "The incidents of this tale are purely a fiction. " 10 The role of the corroborative preface, it now seems, is to reclaim the authorial role that was previously disavowed; 8.James Fenimore Cooper, The Spy : A Tale of the Neutral Ground ( 1 8 2 1 ; New York: Putnam's, n . d . ) , vi. The passages quoted below appear on pp. 42 1 and 429 - 3 0. 'For a thorough discussion of Cooper's strategy as a historical novelist, see "Cooper: The Range of the American Historical Novel, " in Harry B. Henderson III, Versions of the Past: The Historical Imagination in American Fiction (New York: Oxford University Press, 1 974) . 50 - 90. 10Cooper, The Pioneers; or, The Sources of the Susquehanna: A Descriptive Tale ( 1 8 2 3 ; New York: Putnam's, n. d. ) , ii. IjI
Practice we have come a long way from Mme d'Aulnoy's denial that she composes " novel . . . or story. " All the same, the text contains a number of footnotes that verify the fiction' s grounding in personal experience. Thus , describing the bass-seining episode, Cooper re marks, " O f all the fish the writer has ever tasted, he thinks the one in question the best";. recounting Judge Temple's munificence to the pi oneering poor (presumably a fictive rendition of the activities of Cooper's own father, William Cooper) , the author assures us that " all this was literally true. " The unmediated assertion of something "liter ally true" nestles in the bosom of a narrative that is "purely a fiction, " providing personal corroboration that a text that does " represent a general picture" does indeed tell the truth. In some ways, then, the above analysis of the uses of documenta tion in S cott and Cooper confirms and even extends Lukacs' s discus sion of the representational strategy of the realistic historical novel. But my analysis also challenges Lukacs's contention that, by virtue of its obj ectivist episitemology, the realistic historical novel is therefore privileged to portray from a neutral standpoint " all the humanly and socially essential determinants . . . present on their highest level of de velopment. " According to Lukacs, writers like S cott and Cooper could transcend the limitations of their class perspectives and present obj ectively valid portrayals of historical process because of their stra tegic location in that process . In the wake of the French Revolution, but before the proletarian upheavals of 1 8 4 8 , the bourgeoisie were still a residually progressive class, engaged in the process of consoli dating their victory over feudalism. Their interest was not yet inalter ably opposed to that of the masses with whom they had marched under the b anner of liberty, equality, and fraternity; they could, therefore, pose themselves as exemplars of universal humanity . As a result of the presumably nonantagonistic contradiction shaping the historical dialectic,. writers of this period could view the emergence of national destiny from a nonpartisan position: for Lukacs, realism is the fruit of the privileged ideological stance made possible by the po litical configuration of pre- r 848 Europe. The early nineteenth century historical novel is therefore beyond ideology. Lukacs stipu lated, we will recall, that the plot of the historical novel constitutes a "neutral ground . . . upon which the extreme opposing social forces can be brought into a human relationship with each other" (italics added) . The echo of Cooper's subtitle to The Spy is not entirely acci1 52
The Historical Novel dental: both writer and critic see historical process as affording a posi tion of political- and epistemological- obj ectivism. But a close scrutiny of both literary and political modes of repre sentation in this era produces, I believe, quite a different conclusion: the works of Scott and Cooper are saturated with ideology, at no time more so than when they seem to be engaging in an unmediated transposition of historical realities into fiction. The choice of an Edward Waverley or a Harvey Birch as typical hero, to begin with, hardly affords the author an empyrean view of political conflict. Waverley functions as a prescriptive rather than a neutral norm; Scott proffers a generic contract that requires the endorsement of a number of ideological assumptions, foremost among which is the notion that an Englishman, by virtue of his accession to the "steadily and rapidly progressive . . . change" through which the Highlanders were de feated, is a better index to historical process than is a member of the race that "has now almost entirely vanished from the land. " Were Fergus Mac-Ivor presented as the typical hero, and the plot's reso lution centered around his tragic fate, Waverley would bear a very dif ferent relation to the raw materials constituting its referent. 1 1 Simi larly, Cooper's delegation of typical status to Harvey Birch carries a number of implications. Birch's position as a figure marginal to the very society he is trying to liberate suggests that the revolutionary process that relies upon the participation of such outsiders need not incorporate them into its postrevolutionary resolution. Birch re mains, fortunately, celibate, requiring no marital denouement to his personal destiny; he therefore is freed from any permanent associa tion with lower-class characters speaking crude English, yet also kept from too close a contact with the Whartons and Dunwoodies who in herit the reins of power. Birch's glad acceptance of Washington's fa"In arguing that Scott commits himself to a certain view of progress by positing Waver ley as the typical hero, I am not claiming that Scott's portrayal of the supersession of the Highlanders is free of ambivalence. As Avrom Fleishman has noted, Scott absorbed from Scottish speculative history-particularly Adam Ferguson's Essay on the History of Civil So ciety ( 1 767) and the teachings of Dugald Stuart-a highly contradictory view of the rela tion of tradition to progress in historical development. Fleishman declares , "One of the rea sons . . . the historical novel begins with Scott is that the tension between tradition and modernity first achieved its definitive form in Scotland. " The Scottish speculative histori ans were, Fleishman maintains, "scientific Whigs" who viewed the course of Scottish his tory as a combination of tragedy, melodrama, and above all historical necessity ( The Eng lish Historical Novel: Walter Scott to Virginia Woolf [Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1 9 7 1 ] , 3 8, 46) .
153
Practice vor, moreover, obscures the fact that he does not belong to the class that will (if Washington has anything to say about it) be enfranchised after the war is over. In short, the heroes of Waverley and The Spy project anything but a neutral typicality signaling essential historical truths . Rather, typical ity becomes coterminous with synecdoche: the bourgeois protagonist "stands for" the dynamic totality of society in a way that sloughs over very real historical contradictions among very real social groups. En closing social conflicts within the apparently benign framework of a representative fictional microcosm, the classical historical novel artic ulates the rationale of representative government, which masks the reality of class conflict and social inequality by positing a pluralistic social order in which all antagonisms are presumably voiced, consid ered, and then reconciled. The politically synecdochic status of the classical historical novel's protagonist is reinforced by the ways in which the text characteristic ally marshals its documentary apparatus. The world-historical hero, pace Lukacs , does not simply "grow out of the being of the age"; rather, he corrobates a myth of nationalistic progress that is quintes sentially class-bound. Scott's Pretender illustrates the folly of mon archical rebellion that would turn back the clock of history; he pre pares the reader for the text's endorsement of Waverly's accession to English hegemony, even as he allows full play to the attractiveness of the Highland cause. Cooper's Washington acknowledges the energy and integrity of the anonymous Harvey Birches who guarantee the success of the Revolution, even as he lays the basis for their later marginalization. The historical novel gives play to the historical dia lectic, to be sure, but this historical dialectic is mediated by the ideo logical contradictions internal to each writer, and it is synthesized in accordance with the dominant aspect of that ideological contradic tion. The world-historical hero characteristically enters the plot in its final phases, but this does not therefore imply (or exclusively imply) the author's fascination with the purposive agency of the rank and file makers of history. The maneuver also glosses over the covert nature of bourgeois rule, which equates class interest with popular national ism. Moreover, the use of prefaces and footnotes in classical historical novels can be seen as further evidence of the text's embeddedness in various political premises . When Scott tells us that it was only after 1 74 5 that "fair" prices could be obtained for the chieftans' forfeited 1 54
The Historical Novel lands by the creditors of the York Building Co . , he is endorsing a distinctly partisan view of equity. When Cooper reassures us that the account of Judge Temple's kindness to his tenants is "literally true, " he espouses a landholder' s view on class relations in the United S tates at the end of the eighteenth century: these were, after all, also the years of Shay ' s Rebellion. 1 2 Lukics 's theory of realism thus offers only a partial account of the referential activities of the classical historical novel. Lukacs quite cor rectly points to the historical circumstances that gave historical novel ists the confidence to position themselves above and outside the his torical process they described, but he gives far too much credence to their posture of neutrality. 1 3 The classical historical novelist's im plicit claim to stand above ideology is itself an ideological position, one positing the equivalence of essence and phenomenon, cognition and perception . The text' s representation of its referent is, quite sim ply, offered as equivalent to the referent itself; its configuration pro poses itself as not only analogous but in fact homologous with that of historical actuality, and the empirical corroboration it provides is tau tological. 14 In the shift from pseudofactual to historical modes of documentary mimesis, ideological abstraction has been transferred from the represented subj ect to the representing author. Where the pseudofactual novel reinforced a disj unction between the asserting . 12Shari Benstock, in an analysis of the rhetorical function of footnotes in fiction, argues that " the notational system implies an extrareferentiality that does not exist in fiction (where all is fiction, even the notes), so that the notes can only extend the authority of the text by seeming to enlarge the context in which the fiction takes place" ("At the Margin of Discourse: Footnotes in the Fictional Text, " PMLA, 98 [March 1 9 8 3 ] : 2 1 9- 20) . Benstock's remark may well be applicable to such writers as Fielding, Joyce, and Sterne, but it offers an inaccurate account of works residing squarely in the realistic tradition-which, when they use footnotes, insistently refer beyond the text to corroborate the explanatory paradigm of the text. 13In a chapter of my "The Politics of Criticism: Historical Contexts of Marxist Literary Theory " (forthcoming) , I explore the connection between Luk:ics 's theory of realism, his advocacy of nationalism, and the politics of the United Front against Fascism endorsed by the Third International in 1 93 5 . 14By the distinction between " analogy" and " homology" in relation t o the problem of fictional reference, I mean that the former implies a correspondence in function, while the latter implies a correspondence in structure, origin, and development as well as function. Homology involves a contractual agreement that the world of the novel replicates its refer ent in a totalizing way: every particular is drawn into a configuration that purports to repli cate reality diachronically as well as synchronically. For more on the distinction between analogy and homology, see Raymond Williams, Marxism and Literature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1 977) , 1 04-6.
I55
Practice speaker and the d:isavowing author, the historical novel proposes a transcendental standpoint outside the text from which the text' s competing ideological voices can be j uxtaposed and then reconciled. As Heidegger commented of the epistemological transition from Descartes to Kant, " 'I think" becomes 'I bind together. ' " 1 5 To read a classical historical novel is to be invited to participate in a generic con tract with an authorial presence that " binds together" the text, empy rean in its pretensions to autonomy but in fact implicated in every shade of characterization and turn of plot.
From Typicality to Anachronism: The Historical Nouel as Genre Scott's influence on mimetic p ractice was enormous, and by mid century the historical novel was established as a genre in its own right. Leslie Stephen voiced a prevalent nineteenth-century fasci nation with historicism when he praised S cott for his ability to " describe no charader without assigning to it its place in the social organism which has been growing up since the earliest dawn of his tory. "16 S tephen's echo of Darwin' s phrase " the earliest dawn of his tory" (from the conclusion to On the Origin of Species) is by no means accidental, even if it was perhaps unintentional. Where the model of mechanistic atomism provides a metaphor for the informing episte mological assumptions of the pseudofactual novel, the model of bio logical organism articulates those of the historical novel. But Scott's legacy, as we have seen, was contradictory - capable of a totalizing , dialectical synthesis of the particular and the universal, but prone to an empiricist overdetermination that simply renders self-evident the relation between fact and generalization, text and ref erent. Both tendencies are visible in the novels of Scott's descendants. In some novels, the interest in the historical genesis of the "social or ganism" involved the reader in a sophisticated and self-critical mi15Quoted in J . M. Bernstein, The Philosophy of the Novel: Lukacs, Marxism, and the Dialec tics of Form (Brighton: Harvester, 1 984) , 1 8 r . 16Leslie S tephen, " Sir Walter Scott, " in Hours in a Library ( 1 8 7 1 ; London, 1 907) , 1 :22r . The point that Stephen echoed Darwin was first made by John Henry Raleigh, "What Scott Meant to the Victorians , " in Time, Place, and Idea: Essays on the Novel (Carbondale: South ern Illinois University Press , 1 968), I 1 9 . 156
The Historical Novel metic contract. The documentary apparatus accompanying such works as Hen ry Esmond and War and Peace, for example, expresses a complex awareness of history as both process and discourse; the tau tological footnote is abandoned, world-historical figures are treated with a skeptical irony, and the authorial v reface calls attention to the ideological perspective that shapes the text's totalizing portraiture of past events. Even in the early decades of the nineteenth century, however, Scott's model had prompted some novelists (for example, W. H. Ainsworth and G. P. R. James) in the direction of a florid cos tumery that left out the material pre mises of Scott's representation of past events . Increasingly, then, historical novels substituted psycho logical anachronism or superfluous detail for historically concrete specificity, and the Hegelian "identical subj ect-obj ect of history" be came either the transcendental subject of the antiquarian historical novel or the nonpurposive obj ect of the naturalistic novel. The use of documentary materials reflects this shift in consciousness : data that would presumably anchor the text in an extratextual reality becomes absorbed into the fictional representation, with the result that the analogous configuration, while more densely concretized than ever, loses the possibility of formulating a critical relation to its referent. Much of the self-critical historicism of Hen ry Esmond and War and Peace derives from the conj unction of authorial commentary with the mimetic representation of historical events . Where Scott and Cooper tend to offer their plots as self-propelling mechanisms and to present the authorial preface as a discourse external to the plot, Thackeray and Tolstoy, as conscious authorial presences, explicitly theorize the views of historical process that their narratives imply. Thus the very marginality of the world-historical hero becomes a thematic proposi tion. In War and Peace, for example, Kutuzov and Napoleon continue to fulfill the ancillary function described by Lukacs; clearly it is the Rostovs and Betzukovs who embody the dynamis of historical pro cess . But, in his two epilogues to War and Peace, Tolstoy explicitly dis cusses the theory of history that shapes his portraiture of the two generals. Confronting the " specialist historians, " the "universal his torians, " and the "historians of culture, " Tolstoy declares the inade quacy of any philosophy of history that locates the springs of histori cal causality in the subj ective wills of "heroes and rulers " : " S o long as histories are written of separate individuals, whether Caesars, Alex anders, Luthers, or Voltaires, and not the histories of all, absolutely 15 7
Practice
all those who take part in an event, it is quite impossible to describe the movement of humanity without the conception of a force com pelling men to direct their activity toward a certain end. " 17 In de picting the divergent fates of Napoleon and Kutuzov, Tolstoy refutes the fervid nationalism that envisions the leader as a repository of the " collective will of the people " : Kutuzov succeeds where Napoleon fails precisely because he understands his own subsidiary role in the historical proces s . Authorial commentary thus asserts the accuracy of its mimetic representation ("wherever in my novel h istorical persons speak or act, I have invented nothing, but have used historical material of which I have accumulated a whole library during my work") , at the same time that it acknowledges the text itself to be the product of a theory of history that takes issue with other theories of history. D ocumentation vali dates not by effacing the relation between evidence and generalization but by arguing for the text' s particular construction of that relation. Henry Esmond, while less expressive of a formulated theory of his torical process than War and Peace, also comments explicitly on its lampoon of the Great Man theory of history . "Why shall History go on kneeling to the end of time?" Thackeray wonders in the opening chapter. "I am for having her rise up off her knees, and take a natural posture: not to be for ever performing cringes and congees like a court chamberlain, and shuffling backwards out of doors in the pres ence of a sovereign. In a word, I would have History familiar rather than heroic. "18 Marlborough, Addison, and Swift are thus memora ble in Henry Esmond mainly for their pettiness , while the P retender is enshrined in his torical absurdity for his lustful " dangling after Trix" - a propensit y that, in Thackeray's version of historical affairs , loses him the throne. Indeed, Thackeray i s , o f all the nineteenth century historical novelists, perhaps the most audacious in his tamp ering with the historical record; he enacts a daring extension of Her bert Butterfield' s suggestion that "sometimes a wrench has to be given to history in order to subdue it to the demands of the novel. " 19 Scott ' s Pretender is at least plausibly a participant in the rebellion that 17Leo Tolstoy, War and Peace ( 1 865 - 69) , trans. Louise Mande and Aylmer Mande (New York: Simon & S chuster, 1 947) , r 3 2 r . The passage quoted below appears on pp. 1 3 5 8 - 5 9 . 18William M akepeace Thackeray, The History of Henry Esmond, Esq . ( 1 8 52; New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1 962) , 2. The statement quoted below is from p. 487. 19Herbert Butterfield, The Historical Novel: An Essay (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer sity Press, 1 924) , 3 2 . r5 8
The Historical Novel Waverly j oins; Thackeray' s entirely flouts the canons of historical probability. The text' s pseudomemoiristic form, moreover, com pounds its satire upon the authority of received historical discourse. Presenting itself as the memoir of Henry Esmond, "written by him self, " the novel is introduced by a preface supposedly composed by Esmond's daughter Rachel in 1 77 8 ; as Thackeray admits in the dedi cation preceding this preface, the text " copies the manners and lan guage of Queen Anne's time. " 20 While Henry Esmond operates squarely within the conventions of realism-it is written in the third person �nd possesses little of the sense of the real characterizing fic tions in " Queen Anne' s time" - the effect of this documentary over determination is to direct attention to the question of narrative au thority. The text offers a generalized interpretation of a past epoch without posing that interpretation as a neutral replication of that ep och; the author's privileged epistemological stance proposes totality, but not tautology. Tolstoy's and Thackeray' s awareness of history as both a series of past events and a mode of inquiry proved the exception rather than the rule, however; most nineteenth-century historical novels adopted a relatively unproblematic and naturalized formulation of the relation between text and referent. In Barnaby Rudge, for example, Dickens proposed an analogy between his microcosmic fictional world and that in which the actual Gordon riots occurred. Thus Ga briel Varden exemplifies the stable and nonalienated craftsman; Sim Tappertit, the borderline lumpenproletarian; the older Chester, the decadent gentility; the idiot Barnaby, all the nameless victims of aris tocratic brutality and social disorder. The George Gordon who enters the book is a thoroughly despicable creature. Employing a bolder sa tiric pen than Scott or Cooper, Dickens stresses the tragic social con sequences of the pride and greed of the declining aristocracy. But, even in its partiality toward the popular forces typified by Varden, Barnaby Rudge effects an ideological resolution fully assimilable to bourgeois liberalism. The enormity of Gordon' s historical crimes is muted by Dickens's attribution of the novel's key historical acts to Gordon' s fictitious accomplice George Gashford, who is depicted as manipulating the anti-Papist riots - and Gordon himself- in order to satisfy his own hunger for power. The marginalization of the ac20Thackeray,
xxxv.
I 59
Practice tual historical figure thus lessens the burden of historical blame: docu mentation mutes the force of historical assertion at the same time that it anchors the text :[n a known public actuality. Dickens thus success fully encompasses social contradictions within the framework of a petty bourgeois meliorism. Joe Willett marries D olly Varden, re ceives from the king a silver snuff box as a reward for his role in con taining the riots, and assumes proprietorship of the Maypole Inn, which, nodding in its sleep at the end as at the start of the narrative, symbolizes the accommodation of England's most venerable institu tions to the incursions of struggle and change. In one historical novel after another, this paradigm repeats itself. Characters constitute a microcosmic portrayal of representative social types; they experience complications and conflicts that embody im portant tendencies in historical development; one or more world historical figures enters the fictive world, lending an aura of extra textual validation to the text' s generalizations and j udgments; the conclusion reaffirms the legitimacy of a norm that transforms social and political conflict into moral debate. When the novel addresses do mestic crises, as in Barnaby Rudge, the depiction of warring historical forces takes on real urgency, for the author must acknowledge the full dimension of the conflict that precedes resolution and synthesis . Heightened ideological contradiction mediates an intensification of social contradiction in the referent. In The Pioneers and Waverley, the authorial conscience reluctantly accedes - but accedes nonetheless - to the defeat of the Highlanders or the extermination of the Indi ans; in Barnaby Rudge, it can less readily come to terms with the sub ordination of a proletarian class that can hardly be seen as a vanishing race. Nonetheless , in all these novels the informing ideological per spective is that of an emergent and then consolidated liberalism, which claims to encapsule universal human aspirations and needs in the synecdochic figure of the bourgeois hero. The text' s documentary apparatus, presumably providing from extratextual sources an empiri cal validation for the generalizations the fiction implies, lapses into a positivist invocation of factuality that legitimates the text's informing assumptions . The tendency toward this sort of empiricist rubber-stamping be came especially pronounced in the later part of the century, when the historical novel came to assume stature as a quasi-official genre in its own right. An early instance of this development is contained in I60
The Historical Novel George Eliot's Romola, which serves as a kind of bridge b etween fictions deriving from the tradition of Scott and later antiquarian fictions abandoning the classical historical novelist's aspiration to portray historical processes as what Lukacs called "the concrete pre condition of the present. "21 In Romola, Eliot grapples with the criti cal shifts in consciousness that accompany a transitional historial mo ment; the decaying marriage of Romola and Tito illustrates the deeply divisive nature of the debate over the religious and secular ba sis of ethics, a debate articulating the contradictory tendencies toward medieval asceticism and Renaissance individualism in fifteenth century Florence. Eliot's morbid Savonarola effectively shapes the terms of this debate, for his initial appeal to Romola' s moral nature is superseded by her- and the reader' s - realization of the social cost that his fanaticism entails . Despite its careful re construction of fifteenth-century backdrops and debates , however, Romola 's historicity is in many ways superfi cial. As Eliot comments in the introductory "Proem, " the "eternal marriage of love and duty" is her principal theme; "We still resemble the men of the past more than we differ from them, "22 she declares . As more than one critic has noted, there is something anachronistic about Eliot's protagonist: despite her situation in a carefully etched environment, her consciousness is peculiarly modern, more akin to that of Browning's Victorianized Renaissance people than to a plausi ble fifteenth-century psychology. 23 It is therefore significant that, in formulating her protagonist's final endorsement of a Comtian "reli gion of humanity, " Eliot finds it necessary to leave behind the histori cal world of Florence, transporting Romola to a village suffering from the plague, where the problems of humanity appear sub specie aeternitatis and Savoronola is suddenly strangely irrelevant. Noting that these closing episodes were "by deliberate forecast adopted as ro mantic and symbolical elements, " Eliot was apparently aware that the analogous configuration constructed around Romola's Florentine ca21Lukacs, The Historical Novel, 2 1 . 22George Eliot, Romola ( 1 86 3 ; London: Oxford University Press, 1 9 7 1 ) , 2 , 9 . 23See, fo r example, Fleishman, 1 24, and Andrew Sanders, The Victorian Historical Novel, r840- r880 (London: Macmillan, 1 968), 168 - 96. Sanders declares, " [Eliot) is not concerned to show how the past has moulded the present, but that history can be alive to us, through our awakened awareness of the 'internal conditions' of the men of the past. " She plants "a nineteenth-century seed in a fifteenth-century soul" ( 1 74, 1 76- 1 77). The statement by Eliot that I quote below appears in Sanders, 1 9 1 .
I 6I
Practice reer could not bear the weight of the text' s moral resolution; hence the critical determination of her fate apart from historical proces s . The transcendental subj ectivity that, i n the classical historical novel, is restricted to the author's vantage point, now becomes a property of the protagonist. Despite her dense contextualization, Romola is an essentially private being, and her discovery of moral order constitutes a peculiarly modern "separate peace. " The departure from historical imagination implied in the conclu sion to Romola becomes a headlong retreat from the historical process in most later nineteenth-century historical fiction. In the last decades of the century, the historical novel dons a flamboyant costumery . While it appears still committed to the concrete representation of a past actuality, its conception of historical development has become increasingly abstract. In Lew. Wallace' s Ben Hur: A Tale of the Christ and Gustave Flaubert' s Salammbo, for example, there is little attempt to present character and event as issuing from the contradictions of the historical dialectic; history is no longer the " concrete precondition of the present, " but a remote and exotic ground for the incarnation of religious truths and timeless human passions . The text's referential relation to historical actuality is thus undergirded by what might be termed a "pseudoempiricism" : the corroborative " facts" make no pretense to verifiable factuality. Ben Hur bristles with photographs of the modern Holy Land, but these only enhance the reader' s sense of the text' s separation from the referent. A nineteenth-century Bedouin standing by a camel in front of a ruined Crusader castle provides a cu rious sort of corroboration for the text' s propositional claim that Je sus Christ actually walked the earth and performed miracles . In Salammbo, Flaubert undertakes a similarly " archaeological" (the phrase is Sainte-Beuve's)24 representation of the past. Flaubert repu diates the one ancient source detailing the Punic war upon which the novel is based: "Hanna' s Periplus is hateful to me, " he declared; it is "a subj ect for [dissertation] theses . " Flaubert thus engages in a recon struction of past events that is patently invented from beginning to end. Replying to Sainte-Beuve' s complaint that Salammb8 was too " fantastical, " Flaubert remarked that his "empirical" reconstruction 24Quoted in Gustave Flaubert, Salammbo (1 862), trans. J. S. Chartres (Lou'don: J. M. Dent, 1 9 3 1 ) , 305. Flaubert's responses appear on pp. 3 1 1 - 1 9. The quotation from Flaubert appears on p. 3 1 2 . 1 62
The Historical Novel of physical details was as accurate as possible. Hanno 's account was , however, too close to the events it described to provide an obj ective basis for historical reconstruction. Apparently the novelist's transcen dental presence is best able to tell the truth about the Punic wars if it frees itself entirely from the trammels of documentary testimony. Flaubert's mode of historical reconstruction mystifies the past and closes it off from the present. Usually such antiquarianism does not imply a particular political agenda. The plantation novels of Thomas Nelson Page and Thomas Dixon, however, exemplify one kind of particularly distasteful polemic that could be veiled in historical costumery. Portraying the defeat of Reconstruction as the triumph of those who, Page tells us in his preface, "reconquered their section and preserved the civilization of the Anglo-Saxon , "25 Page sets his Red Rock in a peculiarly mythic environment, "somewhere in that vague region partly in one of the old Southern States and partly in the yet vaguer land of Memory" -a realm where "sincerity dwells and the heart still rules - the realm of old-time courtesy and high breeding . " In Red Rock, nostalgia constitutes an apology for slavery. The docu mentary preface makes no pretension to anchor the text in a continu ing historical dialectic but instead asserts the superiority of a vanished past. In the preface to The Clansman, which makes a more decisive claim to historicity (the abolitionist father of the pure white heroine is a veiled representation of Thaddeus Stevens) , Dixon testifies to the veracity of his tale: "The men who enact the drama of fierce revenge into which I have woven a double love-story are historical figures, " he declares . "I have merely changed their names without taking a lib erty with any essential historic fact. "26 He follows this empiricist claim with a peculiar sort of corroborative argument: In the darkest hour of the life o f the South, when her wounded people lay helpless amid rags and ashes under the beak and talon of the vulture, suddenly from the mist of the mountains appeared a white cloud the size of a man's hand. It grew until its mantle of mystery unfolded the stricken earth and sky. An " Invisible Empire" had risen from the field o f Death and challenged the Visible to mortal combat.
25Thomas Nelson Page, Red Rock: A Chronicle of Reconstruction, in The Works of Thomas Nelson Page (New York: Scribner's, 1 908), 4:vii, ix, xi. 26Thomas Dixon, The Clansman: An Historical Romance of the Ku Klux Klan (New York: Doubleday, Page, 1 90 5 ) , v-vi. 1 63
Practice When references to rags and ashes, beaks and talons, and white clouds from the realm of the Invisible authenticate a text' s claim to historicity, we cleady have come some distance from the mode of the classical historical novel. Where Scott used corroborative detail to re inforce the explanatory claims of his text, Page and Dixon repudiate even the pretense of empiricism. Where Scott at least attempted to delineate the contradictory social and political forces informing his referent, Page and Dixon confine their representations of the South to selected sets of characters whose claims to typicality rest on a patently spurious racial stereotypicality. 27 Waverley signals the discursive con cerns of a progressive liberalism that envisions in pluralism a genuine resolution to contradiction. Red Rock and The Clansman, by contrast, treat historical dialectic as coterminous with racial destiny. The "In visible Empire" of the "vanished race" becomes the locus of all value, and the "visible" realm of an emergent historical race is assaulted with all the weapons that pseudoempiricism can muster. If some novelists in the late nineteenth century directed their atten tion to a mythical past, others - ordinarily of a much more progres sive p olitical inclination- postponed the assignation of historical sig nificance to a distant future. The late nineteenth century witnessed a revival of utopian novels, in which authors came to terms with the harsh realities of their time by constructing ideal worlds in which these difficulties had been overcome. For example, Edward Bellamy, in Looking Backward: 2000 - r 887, reacted to the strikes and financial panics of his day not by exploring their roots in the configuration of past class struggle but by positing a world in which such occurrences would be no longer conceivable. Indeed, in one sense Bellamy achieved an apotheosis of the liberal conception of progress , since his utopia is attained without the loss of a drop of blood, through the ex ercise of reason and parliamentary democracy. Yet the labor pro cess - the battleground of the old society- is hidden from view in the new society, and commodities magically pop out of tubes from central warehouses. Moreover, the exemplary citizens of the future, the Leete family, are distinctly anachronistic proj ections, since their undisturbed, middle-class gentility negates the transformation of hu man personality that would accompany any genuine transformation 27For more on the relation of racism to typicality and stereotypicality, see below, Chap ter 8 .
The Historical Novel of the social relations of production. For all its socialist proclivities , Looking Backward proj ects a fundamental fear o f the actual nature of historical change; its exhaustive descriptions of industrial armies and communal kitchens lack grounding in a commensurate grasp of the dynamics of class conflict. Indeed, Bellamy closely resembles the "Socialistic bourgeois " whom Marx and Engels ridiculed in The Communist Manifesto - that is, those reformers who " want all the ad vantages of modern social conditions without the struggles and dan gers necessarily resulting therefrom. They desire the existing state of society minus its revolutionary and disintegrating elements. They wish for a bourgeoisie without a proletariat. " 28 Posing itself as an exemplary fiction written for the enlightenment of citizens of the twenty-first century, Looking Backward occupies a peculiar relation to the tradition of the documentary novel. Knowing that his readers cannot possess an experience to which the text can correspond by analogy, Bellamy somewhat playfully posits this read ership in the future. Presenting his text as Julian West's autobiograph ical reminiscence, Bellamy remarks in an "author's" preface: Living as we do in the closing year of the twentieth century, enj oying the blessings of a social order at once s.o simple and logical that it seems but the triumph of common sense, it is no doubt difficult for those whose studies have not been largely historical to realize that the present organization of society is, in its completeness, less than a century old. The obj ect of this volume is to assist persons who, while desiring to gain a more definitive idea of the social contrasts between the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, are daunted by the formal aspect of the histo ries which treat the subj ect. 29
This strategem circumven\s but cannot finally avoid the question of historical reference. Bellamy carefully avoids reference to events in the class struggle of the I 8 8os that would locate his utopia in a con tinuing historical dialectic; the novel's reconcretization of its referent eschews any documentary invocation of extratextual actualities of Bellamy' s own time. 30 28Marx and Engels , "Manifesto of the Communist Party, " in The Marx-Engels Reader, 2d ed. , ed. Robert C. Tucker (New York: Norton, 1 978), 496. 29Edward Bellamy, Looking Backward, 2000 - 1 887 (1 888; New York: New American Li brary, 1 960), xxi. 301 do not mean to imply that all the time-traveling novels of the l 8 8os and l 89os - uto pian or otherwise- were as fetishistic and idealist as Looking Backward. Mark Twain's A
Practice
The Naturalistic Novel There is a peculiar paucity of documentary references to actual his torical persons and events in the historical novel of the late nineteenth century. Curiously enough, this sort of nonspecific referentiality is also a distinctive feature of the exhaustive reportage of the naturalistic novel. At first, this may seem an anomalous claim, since the natural istic novel, with its passion for encyclopedic portraiture, would seem to exemplify the documentary novel in its purest form. If, however, we take " documentary" as denoting a specified invocation of data known to exist in an extratextual reality, we see that the naturalistic novel in fact participates in the same reluctance to anchor fiction in a known actuality that characterizes contemporaneous works of histor ical fiction. Edmond de Goncourt made a revealing statement of purpose in his preface to Les .freres Zemganno. "The novel, " he advocated, should be "made with documents narrated or selected from nature, j ust as his tory is based on written documents . "31 Working-class people, he continued, " can be captured only through an immense storing up of observation, by innumerable notes taken through a lorgnette, by the amassment of a collection of human documents, like those heaps of pocket sketches which, assembled at a painter's death, represent his life-time of work. " There is a curious logic here. First, the writer as serts that fiction must possess a " documentary" base; he is supremely conscious of his sociological mission. But Goncourt does not specify exactly what the naturalistic novelist's "documents " actually are, nor how these are to be differentiated from the "written documents" on which the historian relies . And yet these "human documents " consist of " an immense storing up of observations, by innumberable notes" (italics added) . How can these " documents " be both unwritten and written? The answer is , of course, that his "documents " are written Connecticut Yankee in King Arthur's Court ( 1 8 89) undertakes a fairly earthy and concrete ex amination of the theme of historical progress, and William Morris's News from Nowhere ( 1 89 1 ) does not shy away from representing the role of class struggle in producing "vision ary" change. Nonetheless, even these novels evade a direct confrontation with the historic ity of the present and the recent past: historical process is, significantly, displaced to distant centuries . 31Edmond d e Goncourt, Preface t o Les freres Zemganno (1 879) , reprinted i n George Becker, ed. , Documents in Modern Literary Realism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1 963), 245 -46.
166
The Historical Novel by the author; they are not borrowed from the public fund from which historians draw their data. This invocation of an absent au thority points to the peculiar nature of the naturalistic novel's empiri cist claims . The naturalistic novel purports to replicate and expose social conditions with scientific obj ectivity, yet it offers no docu mentary guarantee that the text's mediation between referent and analogous configuration is validated by extratextual realities . The di alectic between evidence and generalization informing the epistemol ogy of the classical historical novel- however tautological this rela tion may be- has been superseded by a positivist epistemology positing the unmediated equivalence of document and fact, extratex tual reality and intratextual representation. Despite its frequently rad ical commitment to demystifying and exposing existing social and economic relations (in the preface to Germinie Lacerteux, the Gon court brothers " ask . . . whether what one calls ' the lower classes' have no right to the novel") , 32 the naturalistic novel is guided by a distinctly conservative epistemology. Naturalistic novelists thus generally repudiated any kind of testi monial apparatus and offered their texts as authoritative representa tions . There are no prefaces, postscripts, or footnotes accompanying texts such as The Pit, Germinal, The Red Badge of Courage, Sister Carrie, and The Financier, even though these texts are grounded in personal experience or careful research and could very easily be an chored in extratextual reality. These texts are intended to represent their referents by analogous configuration, and analogous configura tion alone; even within the totalizing framework of fictionality, in deed, they characteristically avoid reference to specific historical events . In The Red Badge of Courage, for example, Crane omits all mention of the actual Battle of Chancellorsville, on which his narra tion is based. His intent is to reveal the biological roots of human be havior, and Henry Fleming's heroic aspirations have no historical specificity. They reenact, indeed, the futile attempt of human con sciousness to escape from the trap of biological instinct (poor Henry Fleming is, all within one page, a "j aded horse, " a "rabbit, " and a "proverbial chicken")33 from the time of the ancient " Greek-like 32Edmond de Goncourt and Julius de Goncourt, quoted in Alan Swingewood, The Novel and Revolution (London: Macmillan, 1 975) , 59. 33Stephen Crane, The Red Badge of Courage, in Great Short Works of Stephen Crane ( 1 89 5 ; New York: Harper & Row, 1 965) , 39-40.
Practice struggle" to the present. In Germinal, Zola even goes so far as to dis tort nineteenth-century political developments in order to enhance his representation of the emergence of the revolutionary proletariat as a Darwinian necessity. Proj ecting back into class struggles of the I 86os a political battle between anarchism, evolutionary socialism, and Marxist revolutionism that acquired significance only in the 1 8 80s, Zola attained sociological exactitude only at the expense of historical anachronism. 34 For all its apocalyptic force, then, there is a strangely timeless quality in Zola's closing prophecy: " Men were springing forth, a b lack avenging army, germinating slowly in the furrows , growing towards the harvests of the next century, and this generation would soon overturn the earth. "35 Class struggle is, it seems, a natural force, having little to do with the political course that the proletariat will choose to follow. In The Financier, Dreiser omits all reference to the actual Charles Yerkes, on whose career Dreiser based his saga of Frank Cowperwood. Even though, as with the Gillette case in An ilmerican Tragedy , whole pages of the Yerkes trial transcript have been incorporated into the narration, these materials are presented as part of the analogous configuration; the text provides the reader with no signal that its reconcretized materials replicate the p articulars of the referent. 36 The generic contract accompanying the naturalistic novel thus re quires the reader to focus on the configuration of the events por trayed, even when the reader may sense that many details of the text also possess an independent referential power of their own. The novel insists upon the pervasiveness of the conditions it represents , and the reader is not permitted to dismiss the story as a retelling of events that may be bizarre or atypical, with no broader social signification. At times, the naturalistic novel's denial of its grounding in particular lives powerfully reinforces its generalized assertions . The protagonist of Sister Carrie, for example, is not simply a fictional replication of D reiser's sister but a wholly plausible character whose fate necessiZola 's "Germinal ": A Critical Study of Its Prima ry Sources 1 972) , 1 4 3 -4 4 . Zola, Germinal (1 8 8 5) , trans. Havelock Ellis (New York: Knop£ 1 92 5) , 472.
34See Richard H. Zakarian,
(Ge
neva: Droz, 35Emile
36For more on Dreiser 's incorporation of documentary materials into his novels, see
Naturalistic Triptych: The Fictive and the Real in Zola, Mann, and Dreiser (New 1 970) , 54- 77. Even though Dreiser placed about thirty pages of trial testimony and letters in the final portion of An American Tragedy, Block argues , " the Haskell Block,
York: Random House,
poignant and arresting portrayal of character in moments of crisis forcefully asserts the dominance of the fictive over the real in Dreiser's art" (67) .
I 68
The
Historical
Novel
tates a trenchant judgment on the economics of sexual morality. The commodity fetishism pervading Carrie's world would reduce her, like the other shop girls, to the status of a thing: Dreiser' s totalizing portraiture of her fate and his insistence upon her typicality constitute a compelling critique of capitalist dehumanization. At the same time that it emphasizes the broad application of the truth it tells, however, the naturalistic novel runs the risk of presenting social conflicts as nat ural phenomena and therefore of denying the historical specificity of its referent. If the Battle of Chancellorsville is all wars , if the struggle between miners and capitalists exemplifies the germination and har vest of a natural necessity that will " overturn the earth, " if Cowper wood' s career enacts the struggle of the fittest to survive, then what is the possible role of conscious agency in the historical process ? Is there a particularity to the configuration of natural necessity at any given historical j uncture? The lack of any documentary apparatus presum ing to ground the naturalistic novel's assertions in an extratextual re ality provides a telling index to the mechanistic determinism guiding the process of mimetic abstraction and reconcretization, for the inclu sion of references to public figures and events is a constant reminder to the reader that history is the product of human acts . Even if it simplifies and distorts these acts by positing the embodiment of na tional destiny in the typical hero, the historical novel treats the inter section of individual praxis with forces beyond individual agency. By contrast, the naturalistic novel's omission of historically specific doc umentation:-- particularly in novels representing actual public events and personages , such as The Red Badge of Courage and The Finan cier-produces a curiously static effect. The view of history as na ture, which departs through the front door of the historical novel in the early decades of the nineteenth century, reenters through the back. In short, the many sociological particulars in the naturalistic novel do not produce historically specific cognition. Rather, they re pro duce re-cognition of a reality that, in its underlying laws and epi phenomenal features , is assumed already to be known.
Emp iricism and Positivism in Nineteenth-Century Historiography As it moves through the various phases I have described here, the documentary novel of the nineteenth century mediates the conceptual 169
Practice abstractions of a now-confident empiricism. Speaking of the assump tions guiding the practice of nineteenth-century realism, George Levine remarks, "In requiring the validation of imagination in the visible world, . . . realism posits a tension between imagination . . . and reality. Values are reversed in that the realistic method proceeds to what is not visible- the principles of order and meaning through the visible; the a priori now requires validation. "37 Where the pseudofactual novel only partially signals "principles of order and meaning" through the documentary " validation" of the " visible, " the historical novel invokes a contract presupposing the reader's endorse ment of an empiricist epistemology. As even the best historical nov els move toward costumery in the last decades of the century, how ever, and the task of documenting quotidian realities passes to the naturalistic novel, the " tension between imagination . . . and reality" collapses . The hypostatization of subj ect and obj ect mediates the transition of empiricism into positivism: fact becomes coterminous with law, and the transcendental observer is absorbed into the obj ect of perception. E mpiricist assumptions permeated many areas of nineteenth century intellectual activity, but perhaps few as fully as historiogra phy. If we seek to understand the conceptual abstractions shaping the representational strategy of the historical novel, it is useful to analyze the paradigms guiding contemporaneous historical writing, particu larly since historians and novelists of the time were quite explicit about their mutual ilnfluences . Macaulay, for instance, acknowledg ing his indebtedness to S cott, stated that the perfect his torian is he in whose work the character and spirit of an age is
[sic]
exhibited in miniature . . . . By j udicious selection, rej ection,
and arrangement, he gives to truth thos e attractions which have been usurped by fiction . :Sir Walter Scott, in the same manner, has used those fragments o f truth which historians have scornfully thrown behind them in a manner which may well excite their envy . . . . But a truly great historian would reclaim those materials which the novelist has appropriated. 38
Thackeray modeled Hen ry Esmond on Macaulay' s historical narratives and enviously exclaimed, "It takes as much trouble as Macaulays [sic] 37Levine, The Realistic Imagination, 1 8 . 38Thomas B abington Macaulay, "History , " i n Critical and Historical Essays (Boston: Houghton Miffiin, 1 900) , 1 :2 3 6 . I 70
The
His t o ri c al N o v e l
History almost and he has the vast advantage of remembering every thing he has read, whilst everything but impressions I mean facts dates & so forth slip out of his head. "39 Parkman constructed his frontiersman after the model of Natty Bumppo, who, he remarked, seems "so palpable and real" that "the reader might in some moods of mind . . . easily confound" Cooper's hero with "memories of his own experiences . "40 Carlyle' s depiction of the French Revolution as a fiery moral drama was clearly a central subtext for A Tale of Two Cities; his writings on the role of "representative men" exercised a widespread influence upon Victorian novelists treating historical themes . Yet Carlyle, in turn, drew much of his inspiration from Scott: "Bygone ages of the world were actually filled by living men, not by protocols, state-papers, controversies, and abstractions of men. " Carlyle wrote: Not abstractions were they, not diagrams or theorems; but men, in buff or other coats and breeches , with colour in their cheeks, with passions in their stomach, and the idioms, features, and vitalities of very men. [History's] faint hearsays of " teaching by experience" will have to ex change themselves everywhere for direct inspection and embodiment; this , and this only, will be counted experience . . . . It is a great service, . . . this that Scott has done; a great truth laid open by him. 41
Interestingly, writers in each genre seem to value in their counter parts in the other the ability to clarify the experiential relation be tween fact and generalization. Macaulay lauds Scott for his seizing upon abandoned "fragments and truth" and calls upon his t ori ans to 39William Makepeace Thackeray, The Letters and Private Papers of William Makepeace Thackeray, ed. Gordon N. Ray, 4 vols. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1945-46) , 3 :38. 40Francis Parkman, "James Fenimore Cooper, " i n Essays from the North American Review, ed. Allan Thorndike Rice (New York, 1 879) , 3 5 8-62. "Thomas Carlyle, " Sir Walter Scott, " in Critical and Miscellaneous Essays (London, 1 8 8 8 ) , 3 :2 1 4- 1 5 . Carlyle was, however, very much biased toward historical forms of dis course. As he exclaimed in his "Biography, " "Consider but the whole class of Fictitious Narrative; from the highest category of epic or dramatic Poetry, in Shakespeare and Ho mer, down to the lowest of froth Prose, in the Fashionable Novel. What are these but so many mimic Biographies? . . . Let anyone bethink him how impressive the smallest histori cal.fact may become, as contrasted with the grandest fictitious event; what an invaluable force lies for us in this consideration: The Thing which I here hold imaged in my mind did actu ally occur; was, in very Truth, an element in the system of the All, whereof I too form a part; had therefore, and has, through all time, an authentic being; is not a dream, but a real ity ! " ( mo, r n6) . 1 71
Practice use "selection, rej ection, and arrangement" of their materials so as similarly to exhibit ''in miniature" the "spirit of an age. " P arkman praises Natty Bump po for seeming "so palpable and real. " Carlyle praises Scott for his " direct inspection and embodiment" of experi ence. Thackeray chides himself for losing track of the "facts dates and so forth" that render Macaulay' s "impressions" so valuable. It would seem that novelists and historians are engaged in comparable empiri cist enterprises; interestingly, when the novel has staked out its claim as a distinctive mode of cognition, it then can grant its indebtedness to- rather than simply simulate - other kinds of writing. If S cott is most frequently mentioned as an influence by novelists and historians, Hegel' s writings most clearly set forth the assump tions guiding both fictional and historical depictions of historical process in the nineteenth century. Rej ecting the dominant eighteenth century notion that history is governed by either universal " un changing laws " or "providence, " Hegel argued that "World-history . . . represents the rationally necessary course of the World Spirit, the Spirit whose nature is indeed always one and the same, but whose one nature unfolds in the course of the world. "42 The universal thus manifests itself in the succession of distinct particulars : "Every age has conditions of its own and is an individual situation; decisions can and must be made only within, and in accordance with, the age it self. " History' s actors exercise a freedom generated by the contradic tions internal to the historical moment, but they work within the lim its of a necessity external to subj ective will. The " manifestations of vitality on the part of individuals and peoples in which they seek and satisfy their own purposes are, at the same time, the means and tools of a higher and broader purpose of which they know nothing, which they realize unconsciously. " In Hegel's philosophy of history, people are at once the subj ects and the obj ects of historical proces s . Where the Cartesian ego cogitans contemplated the world from a detached and ahistorical vantage point, the Hegelian subj ect is dialectically in volved with a changing obj ect of contemplation. The Spirit hovers over historical actuality, then, but its " manifestations of vitality" are necessarily concretized in agents who follow its dictates of their own volition. Hegel's conception of the dialectical emergence of Reason had both 42Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Reason in History: A General Introduction to the Philos ophy ofHistory ( 1 822) , trans. Robert Hartman (New York: Liberal Arts, 1 9 5 3 ) , 1 2 . The pas sages quoted below appear on pp. 8, 3 1 , 39, and 54.
The Historical Novel revolutionary and conservative implications . On the one hand, the "inner development of the Idea" generates "momentous collisions be tween existing, acknowledged duties , laws , and rights and those pos sibilities which are adverse to this [established] system, violate it, and even destroy its foundations and existence. " The state of nature posited by eighteenth-century philosophers was, he declared, " one of those nebulous images which theory produces . . . . Freedom . . . does not exist as original and natural. It must first be acquired and won . " Attacking the atomistic and static presuppositions of early bourgeois political theory, Hegel posited the necessity of struggle and change. On the other hand, Hegel's conception of the Idea was read ily assimilable to the hegemony of the bourgeois world order. Pro posing that the stages in the development of Spirit are embodied in "world-historical national Spirits, " he argued that national spirit was in turn embodied in the state, which he designated as "the externally existing, genuinely moral life. " The recognition that the Spirit must be concretized in order to be Real meant, in practical terms, a very premature concretion in the self-evident - that is, the Prussian state. The motion within essence is, for Hegel, "the moment of becoming and of transition which remains within itself " Describing the tension of the historical dialectic as a feature of pure Spirit, Hegel thus sub dued the potentially revolutionary aspects of his dialectic to the politi cal imperatives of bourgeois nationalism. Calling upon philosophers to grant the contradictoriness of natural and social processes , Hegel himself proj ected a contradiction that locates him squarely within the ideological nexus of emergent capitalism. Hegel's dialectical conception of history profoundly influenced the narratives of Romantic and Victorian historians . First, they recog nized the centrality of conflict to historical process and celebrated the role of the masses . Thus Michelet declared that the history of human kind was the history of "interminable struggle" and stressed the sub ordinate role of "brilliant, powerful speakers " in the "drama" of his tory . Probing into the archives of the Commune, he concluded, "The chief actor is the people. In order to find and restore the latter to its proper position, I have been obliged to reduce to their proportions those ambitious puppets whom they have set in motion and in whom till now, people have fancied they saw . . . the secret transactions of history. "43 Carlyle warned that "hunger, nakedness and righteous 43Jules Michelet, History of the French Revolution ( 1 847 - 5 3 ) , trans . Charles Cocks, ed. Gordon Wright (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 967) , 1 : 12. I 7J
Practice oppression lying heavy on 25 million hearts; this, not the wounded vanities or contradicted philosophies of philosophical advocates, rich shopkeepers, rural noblesse, was the prime mover in the French revo lution; as the like will be in all such revolutions , in all countries . "44 Bancroft, in his History of the United States, treated D aniel Boone as a prototype of the whole class of woodsmen, rather than as an isolated heroic agent. Motley declared of William of Orange that " the whole nation thought with his thoughts, and spoke with his words . "45 Second, nineteenth-century historiography often crossed the fine line between the argument that historical process creates its heroes and the proposition that history' s powerful are the chosen arbiters of national destiny . Just as Hegel' s Idea found its concrete apotheosis in the nationalist design of the Prussian state, Macaulay complacently envisioned the reign of Victoria as the culmination of England's de velopment toward liberty, an interpretation that merely codified the Whig interpretation of history . "The history of our country during the last hundred and sixty years is eminently the history of physical, of moral, and of intellectual improvement, " he declared. "No man who is correctly informed as to the past will be disposed to take a mo rose or desponding view of the present. "46 Motley believed in the "inexorable law of Freedom and Progress " ;47 Prescott and Bancroft characterized as politically- even biologically- retrograde all those nations and peoples that presumably retarded the fulfillment of the Teutonic or Anglo-Saxon historical mission. Thus , in The Conquest of Mexico, Prescott saw an irresistible march of destiny in Cortez' s de feat of the decadent civilization of Montezuma, while Bancroft stated that it was the " strong tendency to individuality and freedom" that allowed the " Teuto nic race" to " become the master from the Gulf of Mexico to the poles . "48 Even Carlyle, despite his sympathetic de44Thomas Carlyle, The French Revolution: A History ( 1 8 3 7; London: Chapman & Hall, I 8 8 8 ) , p 40.
45John Lothrop Motley , The Rise of the Dutch Republic ( 1 8 5 5) , quoted in David Levin, History as Romantic Art: Bancroft, Prescott, Motley, and Parkman (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1 95 9) , 50. 46Macaulay, The Life and Works of Lord Macaulay (London: Longmans, Green, 1 898) , 1 :2 . 47Motley, "Historic Progress a s American Democracy, " in ]ohn Lothrop Motley : Repre sentative Selections, ed. C. P. Higby and B. T. Schantz (New York: American Book, 1 9 3 9) , rn5. 48George Bancroft, History of the United States _from the Discovery of the American Continent (Boston: Little, Brown, 1 862 - 75 ) , 4:456.
I 74
The Historical Novel scription of the class oppression that erupted in the French Revolu tion, eventually favored the side of bourgeois right. As Engels re marked of Carlyle in disgust, All real class conflicts, for all their variety in various periods, are finally resolved into the one great, eternal conflict, between those who have fathomed the eternal law of nature and act in keeping with it, the wise and noble, and those who misunderstand it, distort it, and act against it, the fools and the rogues . . . . The trump card in all [Carlyle's] attacks on bourgeois relations and ideas is the apotheosis of the bourgeois individual. 49
It should be evident that historical novelists and historians of the nineteenth century founded their narratives on certain common ideo logical presuppositions. The novel was constructed around the typi cal hero, whereas the history focused upon the activities of "great men " ; yet both held that "representative men" could successfully em body the contradictions of their historical moments . Scott's depiction of Waverley's hesitation between Rose and Flora thus has its analogue in Bancroft's assertion that " the trials of Washington are the dark, solemn ground on which the beautiful work of his country's salva tion was embroidered. "50 Moreover, the novelist's treatment of the formal problems of resolution and closure bore a marked resem blance to the historian's narrative rendition of the theme of progress: Scott's marriage of Waverley to Rose has its counterpart in Motley's celebration of the defeat of Spanish decadence by Dutch resourceful ness. The novelist generalized upon the private, whereas. the historian personalized the public, but the effect is the same: character emerges as a Hegelian concrete universal, but it also takes on inevitably class bound qualities. Antagonistic historical forces were not so opposed, it seemed, that they could not be incarnated in the career of a single synecdochic individual, and the unfolding of national destiny super seded the conflict of opposed classes . As David Levin shrewdly re marks of the American Romantic historians, "Whatever value facts had for their own sake, it was the story, and the kind of story, that counted. "51 The "story" was the triumph of liberal nationalism, and 49Marx and Engels, On Literature and Art (Moscow: Progress, 1 976) , 3 3 3 , 3 3 6. 50Bancroft, 9 :2 1 8 . 51Levin, 22. 1 75
Practice the "facts" chosen to validate it a posteriori were carefully subordi nated to its informing teleology. The so-called scientific historians of the later nineteenth century castigated their forebears for what Homer Hockett called the "appe tite for literary effects . " s2 "The substance of all science, " wrote Taine, consists in "little facts that are well chosen, important, and significant. "53 Taine''s little significant fact became almost as notori ous as Ranke's dictum that the historian's task is to recount "what really happened" (wie es eigentlich gewesen) . George Burton Adams echoed Ranke when he urged his colleagues to "ascertain as nearly as possible and to record exactly what happened. " s4 Frederic Harrison envisioned the accurate collocation of data as the supreme accom plishment of the historian: " If there is one thing which, more than an Qther, is the mark of Oxford today, it is the belief in contemporary documents, exact testimony of authorities, scrupulous verification of citations, minute attention to chronology, geography, paleography, and inscriptions . When all these are right, you cannot go wrong. " ss This description contrasts sharply with Parkman's declaration that " the task of exploring archives and collecting documents" was "re pulsive at best. " S6 The positivist orientation of the scientific historians is unmistaka ble: facts speak for themselves, laws emerge from the dispassionate survey of facts, and the historian's task is to be a neutral facilitator of the connection between the two . It seems obvious to us now that this proj ect was doomed in advance. It was, of course, impossible for his torians to eliminate their own perspectives . Taine may have de clared that " the movements of the spiritual automaton which is our being are governed by laws to the same extent as those of the material world in which it is contained, "57 but this proclamation of neutrality did not prevent him from branding the leaders of the French Revolu52Homer Hockett, "The Literary Motive in the Writing of History, " Mississipp i Valley Historial Review, 12 ( 1 926) : 476. 53Hippolyte Taine, De !'intelligence, 1 6th ed. (Paris: Hachette, n. d. ) , 1 : 2, my translation. 54George Burton Adams, quoted in Richard Hofstadter, The Progressive Historians: Turner, Beard, Parrington (New York: Random House, 1 968) , 3 8 . 55Frederick Harrison, The Meaning of History ( 1 89 3 ; London, 1 902) , 1 1 8 - 3 8 . 56Francis Parkman, quoted i n Charles H . Farnham, Life of Francis Parkman (Boston: Lit tle, Brown, 1 900), 3 3 m. 57Taine, quoted in Edmund Wilson, To the Finland Station: A Study in the Writing a nd Act ing of History ( 1 940; New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1 972) , 6 3 , 59.
The Historical Novel tion as a "race of crocodiles. " In fact, the scientific historians' posture of objectivity routinely masked a complacent conservatism. Michelet freely admitted that his Introduction to Universal History had been com posed "on the burning pavements" of Paris . 58 Comte, by contrast, suppressed the personal voice in his disourse but proclaimed that "the positive spirit tends to consolidate order, by a rational develop ment of a wise resignation to incurable political evils . A true resigna tion . . . can proceed from a deep sense of the connection of all kinds of natural phenomena with invariable natural laws . "59 As Charles Beard noted of Ranke, "Written history that was cold, factual and ap parently undisturbed by the passions of the time served best the cause of those who did not want to be disturbed. "60 The positivist epistemology upon which the scientific historians relied did not simply mask political conservatism in a specious obj ec tivity; it also ultimately mystified the very historical processes that it set out to describe with scientific rigor. Comte conceded that there was an epistemological limitation to the enterprise of the scientific in vestigator, who "recognizes the impossibility of reaching an absolute understanding, and abandons the search for the destination of the uni verse and the inmost caqses of phenomena. "61 Where Marx saw in the greasy sausages distributed by Louis Napoleon both the actual ev idence of bribery and the ironic symbolic embodiment of the bour geois bid for imperial grandeur, Taine consigned to metaphysics "re search into first causes . " Phenomena have only an apparent reality, concluded Taine. "Basically, there exist only abstractions, universal principles of general cases that appear to us as particulars . "62 Renan argued that his scientific approach to the history of religion would simply replace religious faith with a "faith which believes in the ideal without the need of belief in the supernatural, and which . . . sees the divinity better in the immutable order of things than in derogations from the eternal order. "63 John Stuart Mill posited that the "phae58Quoted in ibid. , 8 . 59Auguste Comte, quoted i n Swingewood, 9n. 60Charles Beard, "Written History as an Act of Faith, " in The Philosophy ofHisto ry in Our Time, ed. Hans Meyerhoff (Garden City: Doubleday/ Anchor, 1 9 5 9 ) , 142. 61Comte, Cours de la philosophie positive (Paris: J . Bailliere, 1 864) , 1 : 9 , my translation. 62Taine, Hippolyte Taine: Sa vie et sa correspondance, 1902 -07, quoted in D. G. Charlton, Positivist Thought in France during the Second Empire, r 852 - 70 (Oxford: Clarendon, 1 959) , 148, m y translation. 63Emest Renan, Studies ofReligious History (London: Heinemann, 1 89 3 ) , xxvi. I 77
P r ac ti ce
nomena" that furnish the obj ect of scientific inquiry are opaque and static, precluding any access to determinate knowledge: We have no knowledge of anything but Phaenomena; and our knowl edge of phaenomena is relative, not absolute. We know not the essence, nor the real mode of production, of any fact, but only its relations to other facts in the way of succession or of similitude. These relations are constant; that is, always the same in the s ame circumstances . The con stant resemblances which link phaenomena together, and the constant sequences which unite them as antecedent and consequent, are termed their laws . The laws of phaenomena are all we know respecting them. Their essential nature, and their ultimate causes, either efficient or final, are unknown and inscrutable to us. 64
For all its aspiration to render a materialist description of phenomena, the positivist program led to a new metaphysics of essence. The positivist epistemology that shapes the practice of the scientific historians is the same one that shapes the picture of social reality in documentary novels of the late nineteenth century. Like the scientific historians, the antiquarian historical novelists and the naturalists fetishized the " little significant fact . " The detailed description of Flor entine life in Romola and the dizzying succession of battle sequences in The Red Badge of Courage furnish fictive counterparts to Renan' s com pendious research in The Origins of Christianity: presumably the reader can never learn, and the writer never tell, too much about the subj ect at hand, which is in fact defined as the sum of its component data. Totality is imagined to be an additive entity, so that the writer' s j ob i s to pile u p enough data until the working of a law becomes ap parent. In both scilentific histories and documentary fictions, how ever, the laws that the data are supposed to supply bear a highly prob lematic relation to their empirical base. In Romola , for example, the presence of Savonarola suggests a specific link between the dilemma facing the typical hero and larger world-historical forces . In the plot, however, his relatilon to Romola's moral development remains am biguous; her endorsement of a Comtian pragmatic humanism pro vides an anachronistic ideological resolution, one distinctly at odds with her represented historical experience. But if essence consists, as Renan and Mill proposed, in immutable laws, then the imposition of 6".John Stuart Mill, Auguste Comte and Positivism, 2d ed. (London: Routledge, 1 866) , 6 - 8 .
The Historical No v el moral categories in vogue some four hundred years later is of little ac count: ultimate realities are, after all, timeless . Similarly, Crane's reli ance upon an elaborate sequence of zoological metaphors to desqibe Henry Fleming suggest that the laws regulating Henry' s behavior stem from an intrinsic biological mechanism. The particulars of the plot, in order words, assert Taine' s "abstractions, universal principles of general cases . " Phenomenon recapitulates law, and law springs forth from the dispassionate observation of phenomenon. The con crete is only concrete in appearance: its essence is abstract. The empir icism that would probe the meaning of the thing (the res) has become the positivism that affirms the structure to which the thing belongs (reification) .
Automatism and Alienation: The Historical Novel and Industrial Cap italism The empiricism and positivism shaping the altering representa tional strategy of the documentary novel in the nineteenth century are themselves conceptual mediations of changes in the nature and degree of abstraction characterizing the social world at large. The principal development here is the emergence of industrial capitalism, which signaled the complete subordination of the production process to the automatism of capital. In the era of manufacture, we will recall, la borers still retained a residual control over the process of production, for the instruments of production, while owned by the capitalists, required deployment at the initiative of the laborer. According to Sohn-Rethel, As long as [the artisan producer's] means of production had not actually been taken from him, no matter how heavily they were pledged to the capitalist, we still move in the era of the production relations of arti sanry . . . . The manner of production and of its physical conditions were still conceived in terms of artisanry and these were basically the
t e rm s
of the unity of head and hand
of the artisan in person. 65
With the institution of steam-powered machinery, however, the tool no longer serves to link laborers with the raw materials upon which they work. Marx observed, 65Sohn-Rethel, Intellectual and Manual Labor, 68. 1 79
Practice Labour no longer appears so much to be included within the production proces s ; rather, the human being comes to relate more as watchman and regulator to the pro duction process itself. (What holds for machinery holds likewise for th e combination of human activities and the develop ment of human intercourse . ) No longer does the worker insert a modi fied natural thing as middle link between the obj ect and himself; rather, he inserts the process of nature, transformed into an industrial process , as a means between himself and inorganic nature, mastering it. He steps
to the side of the production process instead of being its chief actor. 66
Accordingly, the machine enforces the complete hegemony of capi tal. Every kind of capitalist production, in so far as it is not only a labour process , but also a process of creating surplus-value, has this in com mon, that it is not the workman that employs the instruments of la bour, but the instruments of labour that employ the workman. But it is only in the factory system that this inversion for the first time acquires technical and palpable reality. By means of its conversion into an auto mation, the instrument of labour confronts the labourer, during the labour-proces s , in the shape of capital, of dead labour, that dominates, and pumps dry, living labour-power. The separation of the intellectual powers ofproduction .from the manual labour, and the conversion of those pow ers into the might of capital over labour, is . . . finally completed by modem in dustry erected on the foundation of machinery . [Italics added]
This " 'postulate of automatism' presents itself as a feature of tech nology , " Sohn-Rethel observes, yet "it does not spring from technol ogy, but arises from the capitalist production relations and is inherent in the capital control over production. It is, as it were, the condition controlling this control. " 67 Thus, the machine removes the last bar rier between the abstractness of the exchange relation and the labor process. When workers themselves have become interchangeable parts in a production process controlled by machines and when their labor power itself has become a commodity that facilitates their inser tion in this production process, then the abstract second nature of the commodity form has clearly achieved a new position of dominance. 66Marx, Capital: A Critique on Political Economy, ed. Frederick Engels, trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (New York: International, 1 967) , 1 :422 . The statement quoted below is from p. 42 3 . 67Sohn-Rethel, 1 2 r . 1 80
The Historical Novel Indeed, it is a dominance so complete as to obscure the fact of its dominance. Since all exchanges -including the exchange of labor power for a wage- are now equivalents in quality as well as quan tity, the process of exploitation itself, based upon the nonequivalence of wages and labor, is shrouded in the abstractness of the exchange relation. The concepts generated by the development of this self-regulating automatism in the "real abstraction" assume, accordingly, an added degree of abstraction. Marx' s parenthetical aside ("What holds for machinery holds likewise for the combination of human activities and the development of human intercourse") has direct epistemological implication . Marx's own anatomy of capital, indeed, could be seen as the fullest exemplification of the connection between material and in tellectual abstractions : it was only when capital itself had achieved the automatism of its industrial phase that it could genereate a theory of itself possessing corresponding abstraction. Such a hypothesis need not, of course, negate the political and historical importance of Marx's theory of class struggle. The automatism of capital would create a rebellious proletariat and a recalcitrant bourgeoisie at the same time that it subordinated the labor process to its structural im peratives . Nor does this hypothesis need to relativize the validity of Marx's own discourse, which, as an abstraction, might be seen as in trinsically a prioristic and bound by ideology. As Sohn-Rethel has noted, Capital is not only a description of actual relations of produc tion and circulation but also a critique of prevailing views of these re lations; as such, it provides a critique of prevailing abstractions . Its partisan position in the class struggle need not therefore imply a di minished explanatory power. As Marx repeatedly argued, abstrac tion is a necessary consequence of the development of the forces and social relations of production, but it does not in itself necessarily im ply alienation and fetishism. Indeed, abstraction of social relations is a precondition to the development of explanatory abstraction: As a rule, the most general abstractions arise only in the midst of the riches t possible concrete development, where one thing appears as com mon to many, to all . Then it ceases to be thinkable in a particular form alone. On the other side, this abstraction of labour as such is not merely the mental product of a concrete totality of labours . Indifference toward specific labours corresponds to a form of society in which individuals
181
Practice can with ease transfer from one labour to another, and where the spe cific kind is a matter of chance for them, hence of indifference. 68
It is only to the bourgeois economists, Marx noted, that "the objectifi cation of the powers of social labour appears . . . as inseparable from the necessity of theilr alienation vis-a-vis living labour. " The very pro cess of consolidating production and exchange into an increasingly complex social division oflabor also created the class that, constituted by abstraction alone (at least from the point of view of capital) , would abolish the conditions of alienation (and of its own existence as a class) altogether. Marx's theory of capital confronts and criticizes the nature of capi talist abstraction directly, in the realm of political economy . The rep resentational strategy of the nineteenth-century documentary novel, I propose, more indirectly expresses the increasing complication and opacity characterizing the realm of production. Despite its circum stantial concreteness , the documentary novel at this time achieves a new level of abstraction. Again, to quote Marx: "The concrete is con crete because it is the concentration of many determinations, hence unity of the divers e. It appears in the process of thinking, therefore, as a process of concentration, as a result, not as a point of departure, even though it is the point of departure in reality and hence also the point of departure: for observation and conception. " The apparent autonomy of the fictive realm, its liberation from the cumbersome apparatus of pseudofactuality, its implicit claim that the text' s recon cretized particularS; replicate the concrete features of the referent- all these constitutive aspects of the generic contract of the historical novel mediate the "unity of the diverse" in nineteenth-century soci ety . In one sense, then, the totalizing strategy of the historical novel - particularly in its classical phase- can be seen as an attempt to outline the vanishing lineaments of a world being rendered increas ingly opaque by the hegemony of capital. The text's immersion in the dynamics of historical process and its insistent depiction of the work ings of a society in its entirety involve an implicit rej ection of reifica tion and fragmentation. The totalizing strategy of the historical novel thus signals the epistemological achievement of a transcendental sub68Marx, Grundrisse: Foundation of the Critique of Political Economy, trans. Martin Nicolaus (New York: Random House/Vintage, 1 9 7 3 ) , 1 04. The passages quoted are from pp. 8 3 2 and I O I . I 82
The Historical Novel j ectivity which (like the transcendental subj ectivity that "steps to the side" of the labor process) comprehends and describes the workings of the mechanism from which it is alienated. As Lukacs noted in The Theory of the Novel, the nineteenth-century novel "is the epic of an age in which the extensive totality of life is no longer directly given, in which the immanence of meaning in life has become a problem, yet which still thinks in terms of totality. "69 Even as the automatism of capital generates abstractions that possess increased explanatory power, it at the same time threatens to sever al together the historical connection between subj ect and process, anal ogous configuration and referent. Alienation and commodity fetish ism blur the configuration of the social formation and further distance the " second nature" of the exchange abstraction from the " first na ture" of use values. Alienation- or, estrangement, as Marx termed it in the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of I 844 - means the separa tion of wage laborers from the products of their labor, from their life activity as productive beings, from their fellow laborers, and from themselves . 70 In alienating laborers from the totality of the labor process, the abstraction of the wage relation thus creates material, so cial, and conceptual fragmentation. Commodity fetishism thus dis places alienation onto the products of labor. Marx concluded in Cap i tal, "A commodity is therefore a mysterious thing, simply because in it the social character of men' s labour appears to them as an obj ective character stamped upon the product of that labour; because the rela tion of the producers to the sum total of their own labour is presented to them as a social relation, existing not between themselves , but be tween the products of their labour. "71 When alienation and com modity fetishism exert dominant influence upon the epistemological 69Georg Lukacs, The Theory of the Novel, trans. Anna Bostock (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1 9 7 1 ) , 56. The view of totality as a rejection of reification provides the epistemological basis for Lucian Goldmann's theory of realism . "The [realistic] novel of the problematic hero " arose, Goldmann declares, "from precisely the traits analyzed by the theories of reification dealing with commercial and nineteenth-century liberal capitalism. The novel form was founded precisely on the opacity of social life, and the individual's difficulty in orienting himself and giving his life meaning" (Cultural Creation in Modern Society, trans. Bart Grahl [Oxford: Blackwell, 1 976] , 43 ) . Goldmann sees the realistic novel as intrinsically critical and adversarial; as is clear from the preceding discussion, I see the realistic novel as primar ily incorporating dissent and reproducing dominant ideology. 70Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1 844, trans . Martin Milligan, ed. Dirk ) . Struik (New York: International, 1 969) , r o6- 1 9 . 71Marx, Capital, 1 : 72. 1 83
Practice matrix within which consciousness confronts material reality, phe nomena that are the products of purposive human activity appear nat ural and ahistorical; stasis takes the place of process; the self becomes privatized, hypostasized as an essence apart from, and antagonistic to, its actual embeddedness in the social world. At the same time that the automatism of capital enables the formu lation of increasingly comprehensive explanatory models (fictive, historical, or economic) for social processes, it also fosters a disj unc tion between these conceptual abstractions and their referents in his torical actuality. Just as the exchange relation fetishizes the products of human labor, rendering equivalent those expenditures of labor power that in fact create widely varying use values , the nineteenth century documentary novel - particularly in its later phases - fetish izes the very procedure of analogous configuration, suggesting an uncritical and unmediated equivalence between the represented social world and the contradictory complex of social processes for which the text purports to offer an explanatory account. The implicitly ad versarial epistemological stance of the pseudofactual novel-its que rying of the relation between perception and cognition, its fore grounding of the problem of ideological perspective- has been superseded by a mimetic strategy that presents as inevitable the epis temological and political hegemony of the industrial capitalist class . Authenticating documentation functions primarily t o promote the il lusion that the generalizations proj ected in the mimetic text possess an unproblematic legitimacy; authority replaces testimony. The very capacity for synthesizing totalization that constitutes the strength of the nineteenth-century historical novel also signals its crucial fragil ity. As the automatism of capital presses to its limits the principle of equivalence in the monopolist era, it is inevitable that the representa tional procedures of classical liberalism will also be pressed to their limits, ultimately producing qualitatively new kinds of documentary mimesis . Empiricist documentation is no longer a means to cogni tion, but a barrier that must be overcome if the text is to assert its ap propriation of reality.
7 The Modernist Documentary Novel
Pure essential truths do not make the slightest assertion concerning the facts. - Edmund Husserl
In the early decades of the twentieth century, the empiricist and positivist epistemologies that sustained historical and natural istic fiction of the nineteenth century enter into a state of crisis . The modernist documentary novel makes few of the pretensions to total izing representation that accompany fictions of the previous century. Rather, in its use of documentary materials it parades its status as in terpretation but calls into question the very necessity of offering de terminate j udgments of a concretely historical referent. As Michael Zeraffa has noted, "The historical development of the novel com prises two opposite tendencies : the novel was born and established it self as a genre on account of, and to account for, historical and social phenomena; it attained the status of art when it set itself over against them. " 1 This does not mean that documentary fiction of the early twentieth century had less assertive power than before. As we shall see, the assertion of indeterminacy in the referent or of impotence in the authorial subj ect carries as much propositional force as does the assertion that the text transparently replicates its referent. The docu mentary procedures used in modernist fiction, however, bespeak a profound skepticism about the capacity of analogous configuration to effect a valid reconcretization of the text's referent. Ideological ab straction presents itself as not merely involved in, but constitutive of, 1Michael Zeraffa, Fictions: The Novel and Social Reality, trans . Catherine Burns and Tom Burns (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1 976) , r I .
Practice the representational process; the generic contract requires that the reader participate in a deconcretization of the text' s historical referent. The modernist documentary novel is as preoccupied with telling the truth as were its forebears, but it questions whether this truth has much to do with " the facts . " In the modernist era, the documentary novel splits into two strands . 2 First, the historical novel continues as a distinct fictional subgenre, but it becomes the metahistorical novel . The linear progres sion and univocal causality of nineteenth-century realism are sup planted by the postulation of cyclicality and indeterminacy in the ref erent. D ocumentation serves either to highlight the epistemological problem of historical inquiry or to affirm a truth transcending the realm of the concrete altogether; it no longer reinforces the self evidence of the text' s representation of a particular moment in the historical dialectic. Second, the pseudofactual novel reappears in the modernist era, this time in the new guise of the fictional autobiogra phy. Invoking a generic contract that requires the reader to see the text' s characters and actions as replications of real persons and events , the fictional autobiography emphasizes , paradoxically, that i t i s nev ertheless a fiction and cann ot be other than a fiction, rendering cogni tion of its referent by means of analogous configuration. The sense of 2ln the discussion that follows, I shall focus upon texts produced after the First World War and shall implicitly extend the definition of modernism into the 1 940s : Warren' s All the King's Men appeared in 1 946, and Toynbee's A Study of History spanned the mid- 1 93os to the mid- 1 95os. I am aware that this procedure shifts the definition · of modernism into a somewhat later temporal framework than is customary . Bradbury and Mcfarlane, for in stance, call the years 1 890- 1 9 3 0 the modernist epoch, arguing that the reaction against pos itivism predates the turn of the century and that the return to more explicitly political and historical concerns in the: literature of the 1 9 3 0s excludes the Depression era from the rubric of modernism . I do not quarrel with their stipulation that the modernist era begins in the l 89os - I simply find the most interesting instances of modernist documentary fiction ap pearing in later decades --but I would disagree with their argument that some literature of the 1 9 3 0s, and even some of that of the 1 940s, is not, properly speaking, " modernist. " The representational strategies adopted in many fictions of the 1 9 3 0s manifest some quintessen tially modernist features, and as we shall see, the uses of modernist technique in the work of Brecht and Dos Passos signal one crucial aspect of modernist literary production - that is, its harnessing to an explicitly radical propositional content. For more on the definitive fea tures of modernism, see Modernism, 1 890- 1930, ed. Malcolm Bradbury and James Mcfar lane (Atlantic Highlands, N .J . : Humanities, 1 978), esp . the editors' introductory essay, "The Name and N ature of Modernism, " 1 9 - 5 6 . See also Renato Poggioli, The Theory of the Avant-Garde, trans . Gerald Fitzgerald (New York: Harper & Row, 1 9 7 1 ) ; and Eugene Lunn, Marxism and Modernism : An Historical Study of Lukacs, Brecht, Benjamin, and Adorno (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1 982) . 1 86
The Modernist Documentary Novel the real accompanymg the modernist fictional autobiography is therefore very different from that characterizing its pseudofactual forebear. Where the eighteenth-century pseudofactual novel featured a clear disjunction between the perceptual stances of author and char acter, the fictional autobiography poses a differentiated but essentially nonironic relation between the two discourses . The protagonist is obj ectified without being j udged; his or her subj ectivity is regarded as the only possible lens through which to perceive historical actuality, rather than featured as one among many possible perceptual vantage points . Though the metahistorical novel and the fictional autobiography use very different representational strategies, they share some com mon ideological premises . Central among these is an emphatic cri tique of the notions of subj ect and obj ect that sustain empiricism, positivism and novelistic realism. Novelistic mimesis can no longer be presumed to convey authoritative generalizations, nor can the author presume to validate his or her private vision by invoking authenticating references to an extratextual reality. This skepticism about the cognitive range of the perceiving subj ect is routinely ac companied by the notion that historical process, the obj ect, is in any case beyond the reach of individual agency or comprehension. The private self may inhabit a domain more real than that of public affairs , but this reality is largely a function of its refusal to try to make sense of these affairs . Epistemological indeterminacy thus frequently co habits with a pronounced historiographical determinism. For San tayana, life consists of "two concomitant, yet strangely different streams " - one, " the vast cosmic flood of cyclic movements and sud den precipitations, in which man has his part, like the other animals " ; the other, " the private little rivulet o f images , emotions and words babbling as we move, and often hidden in sleep or forgetfulness . "3 The modernist documentary novel- like much philosophy and historiography of the early twentieth century, as we shall later see - takes as its point of departure a critique of the reification that would render unproblematic the relation between datum and law, particularity and generality. But it often reproduces the very reifica tion that it attacks. If history is a flux beyond purposive agency or de'George Santayana, quoted in John Henry Raleigh, Time, Place, and Idea: Essays on the Novel (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1 968), 43 .
Practice terminate interpretation and if the transcendental subj ect can repre sent a reality beyond itself only through a procedure of patently subj ective aesthetic intervention, then the modernist text replicates - indeed, reinforces - the very separation of consciousnss from con text that its antipositivist epistemology seeks to overturn. Though some writers manage to make use of modernist defamiliarization as a powerful tool in the critique of reification, most accede to the thor oughgoing fetishization of social relations that characterizes what Lukacs called the "problem of commodities" in the early twentieth century.
The Fictional Autobiography In the fictional autobiography, the validation of personal testimony attaches to one of the central concerns of modernist fiction, namely, the artist-hero's odyssey to self-knowledge. Focusing upon the pro tagonist's efforts to formulate a coherent representation of an evasive historical actuality, the fictional autobiography gives a specifically referential urgency to its depiction of the protagonist's discovery of the redemptive powers of art. For the fictional autobiography pro poses that its reader apprehend its central characters and incidents as real entities rather than as mimetic constructs - filtered through the consciousness of the protagonist and thereby endowed with shape and significance, but real nonetheless . The fictional autobiography is therefore founded on a paradox: a discursive activity that privileges the transcendence of historical actuality is insistently anchored in a felt historicity . Joyce's A Portrait of the Artist as a Young Man can be taken as a para digmatic illustration of this paradox. The plot of Portrait is peculiarly indeterminate. Its resolution depicts the hero' s adoption of a matur ing aesthetic- and thus completes the bildungsroman pattern of the plot- but also suggests the open-endedness of "real-life" experience. The novel's shift into a first-person, diaristic form in its final pages signals its abandonment of those patterns of decisive closure that had characterized most novels written in the preceding century. Where the bildungsroman obj ectifies its hero as part of its analogous config uration, Portrait limits its explanatory claims to the perception of the hero, whose vantage point becomes the only position from which to I 88
The Modernist Documentary
Novel
view and j udge social reality. Stephen is both a fictional character and, in his own words, an image of "life purified and reproj ected from the human imagination. "4 The other characters are both com ponents of a fictional construct and possessors of what Rader calls a " mysterious outwardness . . . independent of perceiving S tephen and . . . independent of Joyce also. "5 The Stephen who addresses the reader as " I " in the novel's closing pages is thus in a peculiar way exempt from controlling authorial judgment: the powerful valoriza tion attached to his status as artist derives not so much from any heroic action or moral stance as from his position as the center of con sciousness who "author-izes" the existence of the narrative itself. Thus the heated debate that surrounds Joyce's depiction of S te phen's aesthetic (does the author intend this manifesto as a serious statement of his own artistic principles or as a sophomoric credo that the reader is to view ironically?) can be seen to derive largely from the ambiguity of the protagonist's ontological status . If S tephen is to be seen as a wholly fictive construct, then we may expect that Joyce would provide a framework of authorial j udgment inviting us to evaluate Stephen' s beliefs in a certain light. If, however, Stephen is a reproj ection ofJoyce, then we may anticipate that we, not Joyce, pro vide the final court ofj udgment upon Stephen's stated artistic goals . The author communicates the immaturity of his hero' s theory of art and yet withholds signals ofirony that would decisively imply the in adequacy of this theory. Accordingly, a crucial disj unction exists be tween S tephen's aesthetic and the actuality for which it presumably offers a symbolic account- a rupture that signals both Joyce's privi leging of the transcendent vision available in art and his skepticism re garding its ultimate explanatory power. Variants upon Joyce's documentary strategy in Portrait are discern ible in other fictional autobiographies that focus upon the prophetic figure of the modernist artist-hero. In The Autobiography of Alice B . Toklas, fo r example, the text's invocation o f a sense o f the real en ables S tein to project her own " monumental egotism" by presenting ".J ames Joyce, A Portrait of the Artist as a Young Man, ed. Chester A. Anderson (New York: Viking, 1 964) , 2 1 5 . 5Ralph W . Rader, " Defoe, Richardson, Joyce, and the Concept o f Form in the Novel, " in Autobiography, Biography, and the Novel, ed. William Matthews and Rader (Los Angeles : William Andrews Clark Memorial Library, 1 97 3 ) , 5 1 . I am indebted to Rader for my cen tral argument about Stephen' s aesthetic. r 89
Practice herself as a " character" in Alice B . Toklas's presumed memoir. 6 Thus Toklas, the putative author, repeatedly refers t o her friend a s a "genius" ; the arrogance of the real author is transmuted into an obj ec tive feature of the character about whom Toklas naively writes . Yet Stein also retains for herself the final rights of authorship . As she re marks in the final chapter, still speaking through the voice of Toklas, "About six weeks ago Gertrude Stein said, it does not look to me as if you were ever going to write that autobiography . You know what I am going to do. I am going to write it for you. I am going to write it as simply as Defoe did the autobiography of Robinson Crusoe. And she has and this is it. "7 The reference to Defoe is revealing : abandon ing her original plan to close the book in the style of Huck Finn (" Sin cerely, Alice B. Toklas") , S tein disrupts both realism and the sense of the real by openly admitting her own identity as the transcendental subj ectivity that has framed a novel about itself. In playing with the Gestalts of antecedent modes of mimesis, how ever, S tein does not impede her novel's proj ection of fictionality. Defoe did not, after all, admit to having composed his pseudomem oir; The Autobiograp hy ofAlice B. Toklas is, by contrast, undisguisedly by Gertrude S tein. Stein thus avoids the generalizing claims implicit in realism - her text makes no pretensions to typicality or to totaliza tion in its proj ection of Toklas's patently subj ective perspective- at the same time that it retains its status as a fictional representation. Through Stein's collapse of the obj ect into the agent of perception, the voices of Alice B. Toklas and Stein are merged rather than differ entiated; indeed, the two women become, in the reading experience, virtually interchangeable identities . The text's ironic tone thus serves not to query the ideological stance endorsed by the pervasive Stein/ Toklas voice but to assert the unquestioned superiority of that voice, which permits the reader access to the community of privileged sensi bilities constituting the modernist movement. Henry Miller, by contrast, presents himself in propria persona throughout Trop ic of Cancer; there is no ambiguity about the identity 6Michael Hoffman, Gertrude Stein (Boston: Twayne, 1976) , l 1 6 . For more on Stein's changes in the manuscript, as well as on the factual discrepancies contained in the Autobio graphy, see Richard Bridgman, Gertrude Stein in Pieces (New York: Oxford University Press , 1 970) . Apparently Matisse, Tzara, and Braque attacked the Autobiography for what they felt were serious errors in factual representation. 7Gertrude Stein, The ilutobiography of Alice B. Tok/as (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1 9 3 3 ) , 3 10 .
The M o dern ist D o cumen tary
N o v el
of the text's narrative voice. He b ares his soul so readily, however, that the reader is invited to view his " confession" as the proj ection of an invented personality who should be obj ectified within the evalua tive conventions of a mimetic contract. Like Moll Flanders, " Henry Miller " conveys a " confessional increment" that makes it possible fo r the reader to ironize his discourse. B u t where Defoe, i n his preface t o Moll Flanders, indirectly invites the reader to engage i n such a j udg ment, Anais Nin, in the testimonial preface included in the first and all subsequent editions of the book, openly celebrates the regenerative power of Miller' s candor and vouches for the prophetic insight of the narrative voice: Here is an artist who re-establishes the potency of illusion by gaping at the open wounds , by courting the stern psychological reality which man s eeks to avoid through recourse to the oblique symoblism of art . The gross caricatures are perhaps more vital, more " true to life" than the full p ortraits o f the conventional novel for the reason that the indi vidual today has no centrality and p ro duces not the slightest illusion of wholenes s . The characters are integral to the false cultural void in which we are drowning; thus is produced the illusion of chaos, to face which requires the ultimate courage. 8
The text engages in the fictional representation of historical actual ity- it "re-establishes the potency of illusion" - but it rej ects the strategy of a realism embodied in " the conventional novel" that would posit a false typicality and resolution. Miller's often outrageous flaunting of his ego is therefore to be construed as an artistic strategy necessary for countering the per ceived fragmentation of mass society. As in The Autobiography of Alice B . Toklas and Portrait, the text' s valorization of an artistic ego courageously facing the "illusion of chaos" involves a foregrounding of the sense of the real. But the novel lays bare the ideological precon ceptions of its narrative voice only to reaffirm that voice' s privileged epistemological stance; irony is directed more toward inherited con ceptions of the explanatory role of mimesis than toward the p articular discursive assertions of the artist-hero. What Nin's testimonial p ref8Anais Nin, preface, in Henry Miller, Tropic of Cancer ( 1 934; New York: Grove Press, 1 96 1 ) , xxxii. 19 1
Practice ace authenticates , we note, is not the text's veracity but its fidelity to its self-appointed mission. Christopher Isherwoo d and Thomas Wolfe examine the figure o f the artist-hero i n a more concretely specified historical context; their tendency to transcendentalize the ego cogitans enters into contradic tion with their acute awareness of the historical situation within which the subj ect p roduces its discourse. Isherwood, in Goodbye to Berlin, frames his mimetic rendition of pre- W odd War II B erlin be tween two diaristic excerpts putatively composed in 1 9 3 0 and 1 9 3 2 3 3 , thereby enclosing his representative fictional microcosm within a comparatively nonteleological, pseudofactual discourse. One effect of this device is to historicize the text's fictional claims and to locate S ally Bowles and the other boardinghouse characters within the per ceptual framework of a specified consciousness . The fiction does not self-evidently represent the social tensions of prefascist Berlin from an Archimedean vantage point; it is the product of a subj ectivity that is itself implicated in these tensions . Another effect is to indicate the terrifying alterations taking place during the historical period spanned by the fictional s tories : the Isherwood who watches the anti-Semitic persecutions and street b attles on the eve of Hitler's rise to power discerns a fatalistic traj ectory only partially visible in the fictional narratives . But the ego cogitans who both authors and narrates Goodbye to Berlin is a self who is practicing the strategy of self-effacement and insisting on the diarist's prerogative to offer only fragmentary re marks on the wodd passing before his eyes. "I am a camera, " he states in 1 9 3 0, " with its shutter open, quite passive, recording not thinking� . . . S ome day all this will have to be developed, carefully printed, fixed. "9 Writing in 1 9 3 2 - 3 3 , he concludes, "Even now I can' t altogether believe that any of this has really happened. " S uch passivity is quite different from the detached consciousness recorded in the earlier pseudofactual novel. When H. F . and Jack Wilton take the world as their obj ect, they do not hesitate to formulate analyses and j udgments of it- even if these are put into relief by the framing strategy of the text. Isherwood's " camera eye, " by contrast, hesitates to offer explanatory accounts of the phemonena that come before his 9Christopher Isherwood, Goodbye to Berlin (New York: Random House, 1 9 3 9) , 1 3 . The passage quoted below appears on p . 3 1 7 . 1 92
The Modernist Documentary Novel open lens . As a result, his work does not project the forceful auton omy of personality that would enable the reader to ironize the ideo logical perspective of his pronouncements , even though that per spective emerges as a patently subj ective intervention in historical process. In a peculiar combination of assertion and passivity, the doc umentary effect authorizes moral and political impotence. In You Can 't Go Home Again, Thomas Wolfe presents a fiction nar rated by a still more self-conscious authorial presence. His autobio graphical hero, George Webber, is himself depicted as being obsessed with the problematics of autobiographical mimesis . Pondering the difficulties accompanying an effective transformation of life into fic tion, Webber declares that the weakness of his previous work was that it was "not autobiographical enough. " He exclaims, " [I must] use myself to the top of my bent . . . use everything I have . . . milk the udder dry, squeeze the last drop, until there is nothing left. And if I use myself as a character . . . withhold nothing, try to see and paint myself as I am- the bad along with the good, the shoddy alongside of the true-j ust as I must try to see and draw every other charac ter. " 10 This fictional protagonist's dilemma clearly mirrors the dis cursive activity of his creator, who also attempts to use subj ectivity as a means of exploring a totalized range of human experience. Webber announces, "I'm looking for a way . . . I think it may be something like what people vaguely mean when they speak of fiction . . . . Not the facts, you understand- not j ust the record of my life- but some thing truer than the facts - something distilled out of my experience and transmitted into a form of universal application. " Where other modernist fictional autobiographers attribute the artist's prophetic in terpretive stance to a privileged particularity with which the reader is not permitted fuller identification, Wolfe posits in his ego cogitans a stubborn embodiment of typicality, "a form of universal applica tion . " A strongly democratic and romantic impulse distinguishes Wolfe's delineation of the artist. Interestingly, however, this typical ity rests upon a notion of representation far removed from the prem ises of nineteenth-century realism. Where the bourgeois hero lays claim to universality on the basis of a specified position in the social 10Thomas Wolfe, You Can 't Go Home Again (New York: Harper, 1 940) , 3 8 5 - 86. I quote below from pp. 3 86- 8 7. For a discussion of the hybrid generic nature of Wolfe's fiction, see Richard Kennedy, " Thomas Wolfe's Fiction: The Question of Genre, " in Thomas Wolfe and the Glass of Time, ed. Paschal Reeves (Athens : University of Georgia Press, 1 9 7 1 ) , l - 44. I 9J
Practice formation, Webber insists upon an intersubj ective essence that is "truer than the facts, " one that transcends concretion in the historical moment . Despite their many differences in outlook and sensibility, these he roes of fictional autobiography share their alienation from the very historical process that invests them with immediacy . In Ulysses, Stephen frankly sees history as a nightmare from which he is trying to awake . For Stein, the Great War is principally an uncomfortable gap between two p hases of the modernist movement in the arts. For Miller, history is defined as " the women I've known . . . like a chain I've forged out of my own misery . " 1 1 Social relations threaten to strip him of all identity, leaving him in the narcissistic " dead center" of a " constant flux" where "you slowly rot, slowly crumble to pieces, get dispersed again. Only your name remains . " Webber, witnessing a Jew being seized by the Gestapo, seeks not to probe the roots of Na tional Socialism (much less to interfere in the arrest) but to compre hend " the atavistic yearnings in himself. " He concludes , "The dark ancestral cave, the womb from which mankind emerged into the light, forever pulls us back. " 12 Isherwood's "camera eye" responds to the mounting oppression of prefascist Berlin by assimilating its metropolitan alienation to his own dispersed ego : "Berlin is a skele ton which aches in the cold; it is my own skeleton aching. I feel in my bones the sharp ache of the frost in the girders of the overhead rail way, in the ironwork of b alconies, in bridges, in tramlines, lamp standards, latrines . The iron throbs and shrinks , the stone and the bricks ache dully, the plaster is numb . "13 Whether the artist-hero of modernist fictional autobiography encounters the horror of contem porary history by evasion, denial, or self-flagellation, the effect is similar: the referent may be an obj ect of cognition, but the knowl edge that it yields is either transhistorical or ahistorical. The modernist fictional autobiography thus reproduces features of both p seudofactuall and realistic fiction, but it produces a synthesis qualitatively different from either. The text abandons both the men dacious sense of the real (which posits a subj ect undetermined by its obj ect) and the privileged omniscience of realism (which posits an ob j ect undetermined by its subj ect) . Instead, its generic contract asks the " Miller, 2 8 7 . 12Wolfe, 706. 13lsherwood, 287. 1 94
The Modernist D ocumentary Novel
reader to consign the task of interpretation to the artist-hero who, as the central ego cogitans, produces cognition of historical actuality by proclaiming its alienation from that actuality. The documentary in vocation of a residual sense of the real guarantees the authenticity of a self who discovers essence and identity apart from any historical con cretion. The sense of the real in the pseudofactual novel mediated the exploratory energy of an emergent bourgeois subj ect. The residual sense of the real in the modernist fictional autobiography, by con trast, mediates the tenuous epistemological stance of a subj ect who attempts to combat the reification of an alien realm of fact by denying the relevance of this realm of fact to the task of interpreting and j udging social reality. The text asserts the supremacy of the realm of the aesthetic, but it denies this realm any further propositional power. It should be clear that there are important connections between this peculiar valorization of impotence and the nonassertive theories of mimesis formulated by twentieth-century literary theorists .
The Metahistorical Novel Where the fictional autobiography foregrounds the discursive op erations of a transcendental subj ectivity, the metahistorical novel (as I shall call it) directly confronts the problem of historical process. In contradistinction to the nineteenth-century historical novel, how ever, it abandons altogether the proj ect of representing historical specificity, positing instead that recurrence constitutes the essence of historical movement. The metahistorical novel continues to invoke a number of the representational conventions of earlier historical fic tion, but it no longer assumes that historical actuality constitutes a self-evident obj ect of cognition. The artist-hero of fictional autobio graphy resurfaces here as the creative historian, who, as part of the text's referent, insistently calls attention to the ideological abstrac tions that mediate the text's reconcretization of that referent. The text submits Taine's "little significant fact" to critical scrutiny, for the documentary apparatus now directs attention to the process by which the little fact acquires its significance. In Virginia Woolf' s Orlando, documentary materials "testify " not to the validity of the text' s interpretation of historical process but rather to the necessity of forging an aesthetic that will transcend that 1 95
Practice p rocess altogether. Thus the references to Addison, Swift, and Pope function very differently than do the analogous appearances of Marl borough and S wift in Henry Esmond. Where Thackeray introduced his world-historical characters to delineate- and to validate his delin eation of- the mo ral (or immoral) features of Esmond's environ ment, Woolf draws in the great artists of past ages in order to affirm the power of mimesis in synthesizing the fragmentary nature of lived time: The most successful practitioners of the art of life . . . s omehow con trive to synchronize the sixty o r seventy different times which beat si multaneously in every normal system s o that when eleven s trikes , all the rest chime in unison, and the present is neither a violent disruption nor completely forgotten in the past . . . . Indeed it is a difficult business - this time-keeping ; nothing more quickly disorders it than contact with any of the arts. 1 4
The text' s playful presentation of itself as a " biography, " moreover, reinforces its implication that fictionality constitutes a privileged mode of cognition. When " O rlando" and "Louise" appear in the in dex alongside " Victoria, Queen" and "Tennyson, the late Lord, " and pictures of Vita S ackville-West are j uxtaposed with Renaissance and eighteenth-century portraits of O rlando the ambassador and the gen tleman, it becomes clear that " contact with . . . the arts" has trium phantly asserted its victory over the clock of linear historical time. In one sense, Orlando could be said to embody the final flowering of nineteenth-century progressivism . The protagonist's historical alterations in style and ethos illustrate the Hegelian principle of con cretion ; the text' s play with changing typicalities signals its easy as similation of the historical novel's convention of representative char acterization. But the present, rather than seeming to be the logical product of the historial dialectic represented in the novel, possesses a " terror, " a "nondescript character. " And O rlando is above all a quick-change artist: her/his alterations in personality articulate merely alterations in phenomenon; her/his essence is that of the writer, which remains unchanged over the centuries. It is no accident, then, that the text' s resolution occurs with O rlando ' s completion of 14Virginia Woolf, Orlando: A Biography (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1928), 3 0 5 - 6. I quote below from p. 3 22 .
The Modernist Documentary Novel the poem "The Oak Tree, " which, like its referent in nature, has ex perienced a slow and consistent growth over the centuries . Typical ity, in Orlando, involves the valorization of a new type- the artist conceived apart from his or her embodiment of a changing essence in the social formation; resolution signifies not the working out of a dynamis embedded in the materials of the plot but the affirmation of aesthetic completeness . Historical particulars thus function to cor roborate a conception of essence fundamentally alien to Hegelian concretion. Despite their conventional cameo appearances, Woolf's world-historical figures in Orlando have far less in common with Thackeray' s Great Men than they do with E. M. Forster' s great nov elists of the past, who are pictured in Aspects of the Novel as being "seated together in a room, a circular room, a sort of British Museum reading-room- all writing their novels simultaneously. " 15 In Robert Penn Warren's All the King 's Men, by contrast, docu mentary particulars are more insistently grounded in a localized real ity, and Warren clearly intends the reader to perceive a close resem blance between his Willie Stark and the historical Huey Long . Yet Warren's extended historical parallel ultimately implies the universal ity and recurrence of unchanging ethical choices . For, in recognizing Huey Long in Willie Stark, the reader perceives essential human qual ities that transcend any given historical concretion; the veiled histori cal reference functions not to anchor the work in a verifiable historical actuality so much as to abstract the prototype itself from history. As Warren has noted of the novel, I do not mean to imply that there was no connection between Governor
S tark and Senator Long. Certainly it was the career of Long and the atmostphere of Louisiana that suggested the play that was to become the novel . But suggestion does not mean identity
.
.
.
.
I did have some
notions about the phenomenon of which Long was but one example, and I tried to put some of these notions into my book . . . . The book, however, was never intended to be a book about politics . Politics merely provided the framework story in which the deeper concerns,
whatever their final significance, might work themselves out. 1 6
15E. M. Forster, Aspects of the Novel ( 1 927; New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, Har vest, n . d . ) , 9 . 16Robert Penn Warren, quoted in Russel B. Nye, "History and Literature: Branches of the Same Tree, " in Essays on History and Literature, ed. Robert Bremner (Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1 966) , 1 5 r . See also Robert Penn Warren, "All ihe King's Men: The 1 97
Practice The shadowy presence of an actual historical model behind the fic tional portraiture produces an undeniably powerful confluence of narrative elements ; the text's resolution is rendered inevitable by both its represented dynamis and its external reference to the actual assassi nation of Huey Long . But even if "politics " are merely an epiphe nomena! feature of social organization, never equivalent to "final sig nificance, " the dense tissue of documentary references cannot help signaling precisely the historical concretion that the tale must tran scend if it is to represent its " deeper concerns . " In its replication of its referent, All the King 's Men asserts that es sence is transhistorical; in its manner of telling its story, the novel implies that historical reconstruction is a matter of intuition and hypothesis, aspiring mor � toward coherence than toward determi nacy. Jack Burden, the narrator, is a historian whose intellectual and moral development implies a trenchant critique of positivism. His progression- from a dispassionate graduate student unsuccessfully attempting to garner facts about Cass Mastern to an ethically com mitted detective successfully piecing together information that estab lishes the guilt of his own father-is clearly presented as the triumph of a superior philosophical method. Yet this development in method ology is offset by the parallel that Burden discovers in the substance of his two inquiries ; presumably, Cass Mastern's implication in the cruelties of slavery in the nineteenth century is ethically equivalent to Judge Irwin' s shady business dealings in the twentieth. While probing the difficult relation between fact and meaning, then, Jack Burden ends up bypassing appearance- which is merely historical- to get at a timeless ethical essence. His final decision (to "go into the convul sion of the world, out of history into history and the awful responsi bility of Time")17 takes the novel not into the crucible of protofascist populism in the Louisiana of Huey Long but into that of a curiously abstract and ahistorical condition humaine . Warren's relativistic con ception of the pro cess of historical reconstruction thus converges with his implication that the story he is telling is simultaneously real and invented. Essence consists in metaphysical equivalence; differMatrix of Experience, " Yale Review, 53 (December 1 963): 1 6 1 - 67. Warren states, "The [di alectic between myself and ' Huey'] was . . . far less important, in the end, than that deeper and darker dialectic for which the images and actions of a novel are only language. " Louisi ana, he continues, was less crucial than "my acquaintance with another country . . . even more fantastic than was Louisiana under the consulship of Huey" ( 1 67) . 17Robert Penn Warren, All the King's Men (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1 946) , 464.
The Modernist Documentary Novel ences in historical specificity are merely variants upon an opaque and unchanging facticity. William Faulkner's Absalom, Absalom! is perhaps the prototypical modernist historical novel. In its representation of the pre- and post Civil War South, the text invokes a contract in some ways similar to that accompanying the realistic historical novel. Sutpen is a type carrying a powerful generalized reference, and through Sutpen's in teractions with the microcosm of fictional characters surrounding him, Faulkner conveys a series of judgments upon the course of Southern history. Yet Faulkner subordinates this historically specific representation to an informing cyclical pattern: the novel's extended network of allusions to Greek tragedy and the Old Testament points to repeating patterns of parental rej ection, fratricide, and revenge througho ut Western history and leg end The concreteness of Faulk ner's proj ections of the historical specificity of Sutpen's tale is thus countered by an insistence upon mythic recurrence; as in Orlando and All the King 's Men, historical parallels primarily serve to minimize the importance of the novel's embeddedness in a particular time and place. Faulkner's treatment of the problem of documentary validation re inforces his premise that historical process transcends comprehension or purposive agency. The historical record is revealed to be discrep ant and confusing: the appended '' chronicle" of the Sutpen dynasty contains notable inconsistencies, and even the headstones in the Sutpen family burial ground yield information conflicting with pre sumably reliable sources. 1 8 Moreover, Mr. Compson, who plays the role of the positivist historian, proves unable to discover in his doc uments the "chemical formula" that will yield up the meaning of the Sutpen myth. "You bring [the letters] together in the proportions called for, " he complains, "but nothing happens. "19 Given the capac ity and intractability of "the facts, " then, Quentin's and Shreve's nar rative is ultimately valued above that of Miss Rosa or his father, not because it is more objective (all equally play out the teller's fantasies) , but because i t openly asserts its own patently subj ective nature. Ob.
18Gerald Langford, Faulkner's Revision of "Absalom, Absalom! " A Collation of the Manu script and the Published Book (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1971), r r - 1 2. For much of this discussion of Faulkner's historiographical method, I am indebted to an unpublished es say by my colleague Harriet Gilliam entitled "Overpassing to Love: Phenomenological Truth in Absalom, Absalom! " (Northwestern University, 1 976) . 19William Faulkner, Absalom, Absalom! ( 1 936; New York: Random House/Vintage, 1 964) , I O I . 199
Practice sessed with the problem of reconstructing a mythic past that pos sesses greater concreteness and vitality than the "cold, New England dark" of the abstract present, Quentin willingly invents crucial "facts " - such as the conversation where Bon reveals to Henry that they are brothers - in order to penetrate to the essence of the Sutpen tragedy . His criterion for validity in historical reconstructiOn is, fi nally, internal or imaginative coherence rather than external corre spondence; he makes no claim that the patterns he uncovers inhere within the obj ect of his inquiry. In one sense, Absalom, Absalom! renders a reconcretization of history; in another sense, its insistent fo cus on the procedures of ideological abstraction queries the very real ity of that history. To tell the truth about Thomas Sutpen is to ques tion whether he ever existed. Clearly the metahistorical novel sets out to refute the empiricist il lusion of neutral subjectivity and the positivist illusion of neutral ob jectivity, as well as the complacent liberal progressivism that these il lusions sustain. It brings in documentary "facts " only to question their ontological status rather than to assume a priori their value as registers to truth. It is questionable, however, whether the meta historical novel actually frees itself from the positivist paradigm that it takes as its adversary. Comte, we will recall, despaired of discover ing the "inmost causes " of the "phenomena" that he studied so ex haustively; Mill posited a fundamental dualism between "facts" and the "essence . . . the real mode of production, of any fact . " In the metahistorical novel , this dualism is not eradicated but instead inten sified. Not only are the "inmost causes " more remote than ever, but the "little significant fact" assumes a chimerical quality. Narration is still undertaken from the vantage point of a transcendental subj ectiv ity, although no longer that of the author, standing outside the analo gous configuration, but of a character, haunted by the problem of penetrating the opaque historical world of which he is now a repre sented part. The present is the product of historical processes, but its peculiar unreality i[s not a historical problem. As Lukacs remarks in History and Class Consciousness, "The unexplained and inexplicable facticity of bourgeois existence as it is here and now acquires the pa tina of an eternal law of nature. " 20 20Georg Lukacs, History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics, trans. Rod ney Livingstone (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1 9 7 1 ) , 1 57· The locus classicus of Lukacs's attack on modernism remains "The Ideology of Modernism, " in The Meaning of Contemporary 200
The Modernist Documentary Novel
Ra1 ical Modernism: The Examples of Brecht and Dos Passos The fictional autobiographies and metahistorical novels we have examined could be said to contain a symptomatic critique of reifica tion. Certain modernist texts, however, offer an intentional challenge to fetishized ideological abstractions, not through their denial of the possibility of concrete totalization per se, but through their construc tion of a critical totalization, one that purports to render determinate explanations and judgments while foregrounding the political nature of their own epistemological frameworks . The politics of these texts are ineluctably radical: they can engage in their acts of critical totaliza tion precisely because they view reification as a problem and as a product of capitalism, and they can also view their own critical per spectives as the articulation of a class outlook, rather than as an iso lated protest. This leftist modernism was expressed in a variety of mimetic genres, from the theater of Meyerhold to the cinema of Eis enstein. For the purposes of our discussion here, its most significant theorist is Bertolt Brecht; its most significant documentary practi tioner, John Dos Passos. 2 1 Brecht polemicized both against the representational strategies of bourgeois realism and against the aesthetic theory of Lukacs, which prescribed a return to typicality and totalization as the cure for the maladies of both naturalism and modernism. Plots constructed Realism, trans . John Mander and Necke Mander (London: Merlin, 1 962) . Luk:ics's descrip tion of " concrete typicality" and " abstract particularity" in this essay is highly relevant to the preceding discussions of both fictional autobiographies and metahistorical novels . Throughout "The Ideology of Modernism, " however, Lukacs frequently succumbs to nos talgia for a bourgeois realism that is, by his own logic, irrecoverable. See above, Chapter 3 , n. l I. 21The link between Dos Passos and Brecht is probably best understood in their discov ery of a common ancestor in cubism as well as in their common admiration for Eisenstein. For a discussion of the politically radical implications of cubism, see Lunn, 48 - 54. For the argument that all modernism- even the fascist modernism of Wyndham Lewis- consti tutes a rejection of reification, see Fredric Jameson, Fables ofAggression: Wyndham Lewis, the Modernist as Fascist (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979) . For example: " Mod ernism not only reflects and reinforces [the J fragmentation and commodification of the psy che as its basic precondition, but . . . the various modernisms all seek to overcome that re ification as well, by the exploration of a new Utopian and libidinal experience of the various sealed realms or compartments to which they are condemned, but which they also rein vent" (r4). Jameson's argument here is based on the Althusserian premise that literature un dermines ideology. 20I
Practice around the exemplary careers of typical individuals might have proven adequate to represent the configuration of social relations in the progressive era of the bourgeoisie, Brecht remarked, but they had little value in the present. "Those close interactions between human beings in struggle were the competitive struggles of developing cap italism, " he commented. "But time flows on, and if it did not it would be a bad prospect for those who do not sit at the golden ta ble. "22 As a result, It is absolutely false . . . it leads nowhere, it is not worth the writer's while, to simplify his problems so much that the immense, compli cated, actual life-pro cess of human beings in the age of the final s truggle between the bourgeois and the proletarian class , is reduced to a " plot , " setting, or background for the creation of great individual s . Individuals should not o ccupy much more space in books and, above all not an other space, than in reality.
. Altered mimetic strategies were needed to encompass and interpret the altered nature of social reality in the era of monopoly capitalism: " Methods become exhausted; stimuli no longer work. New prob lems appear and demand new methods . Reality changes; in order to represent it, modes of representation must change. " Brecht thus argued strenuously against the ideological premises of bourgeois dramatic realism, which, he claimed, substituted recognition for cog nition, catharsis foir inquiry, and resolution for the sharpening of con tradictions. "Realism, " Brecht declared (interestingly, he retained the term) , consists in the enactment of an essentially Leninist epistemol ogy: " discovering the causal complexes of society I unmasking the prevailing view of things as the view of those who rule it I writing from the standpoint of the class which offers the broadest solutions for the pressing difficulties in which human society is caught I em phasizing the element of development I making possible the con crete, and making possible abstraction from it. " In Brecht' s aesthetic, concrete and abstract are not coterminous with one another; the con crete, indeed, is made possible only by freeing it from the reified ab stractions by which it is confined. Neither, however, are concrete 22Bertolt Brecht, " Against Georg Lukacs, " trans . Stuart Hood, New Left Review, 84 (March- April 1 974) : 47. The passages quoted below are from pp. 47, 5 1 , 40, 5 1 , 44, and 47. 202
The Modernist Documentary
Novel
and abstract ontologically separate. They are dialectically related, and the essence of representing this dialectical relation is not obj ectivism but partisanship . Brecht posed a theory of representation that could harness the epis temological self-consciousness of the modernist program to a revolu tionary political praxis . He was passionate in his indictment of the ideological presuppositions coded into typicality, totalization, and resolution; he mocked the specious proj ection of neutrality and self evidence in the traditional realistic text. Even the most radical mi metic representation, Brecht argued, could not present its ren dition of reality as self-evident: in order to mobilize the critical awareness of the audience- a crucial element in the promotion of communist consciousness - the text must produce cognition by altering conventional habits of perception. Yet Brecht also sharply criticized those avante-garde artists who indulged in " an almost unbearable narrowing of perspective" and therefore "merely freed themselves from grammar, not from capitalism. " His " alienation ef fect" sought instead to use defamiliarization as a way of producing revolutionary cognition of the referent. Lukacs's fetishization of the productive forces tended to equate representation with the re-presen tation of contradictions already defined and determined in their pri mary and secondary relations by the configuration of the productive forces and the class struggle. Conceiving of literary production as one of the "social forces of production, " Brecht broke decisively with Lukics 's productive forces determinism when he stressed the role of representation in shattering the synecdochic equation of the totality of society with one of its parts . For Brecht, Lukics 's theory of typi cality served merely to legitimate those conceptions of the "norma tive" that reinforced the hegemony of the capitalist class. The solu tion, Brecht wryly remarked, lay "not in the good old days, but in the bad new ones . " I do not wish to argue that Dos Pas sos was following Brecht's ad vice when he wrote U. S . A . Most of Brecht's theorizing postdated the trilogy and was in any case published only after a delay of many years . Dos Passos 's letters and j ournals reveal no signs that he even knew of the German playwright's existence. Moreover, B recht's openly communist politics would have been quite distasteful to the American author, who, even at his most radical, never abandoned his allegiance to " our storybook democracy. " Nonetheless, Dos Passos's 203
Practice proj ect in U. S . A . constitutes , in my view, the most successful, sus tained instance of Brechtian realism - "making possible the concrete, and making possible abstraction from it" - in modernist prose fic tion. Dos Passos managed, first, to retain much of the generalizing and interpretive force of the nineteenth-century historical novel without falling into its characteristic fetishization of the " representative" bourgeois hero or of the transcendental vantage point of the author. Accordingly, the totalization afforded by U. S . A . is not self-evident but critical. No single individual in all of U. S . A . is taken to typify the complex interconnection of historical forces in the early decades of the twentieth century; as a group , the fictional characters proj ect in microcosm the central contradictions shaping American life. The word-mongering empire of J. Ward Moorehouse functions as a cohering center around which many of the characters move. But it cannot furnish a hegemonic principle of structural unity, and Moore house himself is a shadowy parody of the typical tycoon. The inter secting lives of the characters thus fail to produce a fully overdeter mining representation. Mac is lost in Mexico; Joe Williams and D aughter die and le:ave no appreciable mark on the lives of the others; Mary French drifts toward an uncertain future on the fringes of the left . Although they are grouped into a concretely historical micro cosm, these characters do not constitute an analogous configuration transparently rendering the conflicts and tendencies of the historical moment. Class contradiction shapes the fictional plot of U. S . A . but it demands cognition, not recognition; types are represented in mu tual relations that s ettle many questions but leave others unresolved. Yet these unresolved questions do not point towards the routine modernist conclusion that history involves either obj ective determin ism or subj ective indeterminacy; rather, they simply remind the reader that concretion is always richer and more various than any conceptual abstraction that would claim correspondence with it. Second, the documentary elements in U. S . A . reinforce this proj ec tion of a critical totalization . The historical events and cultural trends referred to in the newsreels provide data validating the text' s implicit generalizations about the various material and ideological abstrac tions shaping the lives of Americans in the early twentieth century. But Dos Passos locates the foundation of personal and social experi ence in the class struggle without posing his data as a posteriori em2 04
The Modernist Documentary Novel pirical corroboration; many newsreel fragments resist ready assimila tion into any of the patterns ofjudgment accompanying the different characters' lives . The references to the Florida land boom clearly contextualize the tragic arc of Charley Anderson's destiny; the docu mentary references to the Hall-Mills murder trial suggest the voyeur istic sensationalism of the mass culture in which Margo Dowling will achieve her apotheosis . But the many references to scandals, strikes, and society gossip that remain unincorporated into any specific the matic matrix point to a realm of historical event that exists - and signifies- beyond the interpretive configuration of the text. The contradictions informing the referent are at once equivalent to and greater than their representation in discourse, since the "known obj ect" can only approximate, but never fully delineate, the " real obj ect. " The short biographies also function simultaneously to reinforce and highlight Dos Passos's dialectical view of the relation between evidence and abstraction. These sketches reassert the subordinate sta tus of the world-historical hero inherited from classical historical fic tion: emphatically, it is the Eleanor Stoddards and the Joe Williamses who , in their largely unconscious pursuit of self-interest, make his tory. Yet Dos Passos's world-historical heroes and villains also pos sess a being apart from their validation of the text' s ideological per spective. On the one hand, Henry Ford's institutionalization of the assembly line intervenes directly in Charley Anderson's career; Ford's decision to extract cash payments from his dealers in February 1 92 1 precipitates the financial crisis in Charley's family . Ford here is not simply a concretion of the Hegelian World Spirit; he is, even more than the world-historical heroes of Cooper and Tolstoy, a figure whose actual deeds have direct impact upon the historical process represented in the text. On the other hand, Ford also inhabits the his torical reality that surrounds the mimetic microcosm; the fictional stories come to a halt around 1 92 8 , but we are told that in 1 9 3 2 Ford ordered his guards to machine-gun unemployed workers demanding j obs at his D earborn plant. 23 The world of Henry Ford thus inter23For more on the manipulation of fictional time in U. S.A . , see my " From U. S.A. to Ragtime: Notes on the Forms of Historical Consciousness in Modern Fiction, " American Lit erature, 50 (March 1 978) : 8 5 - 1 0 5 , and "The Treatment of Time in The Big Money: An Ex amination of Ideology and Literary Form, " Modern Fiction Studies, 26 (Autumn 1980): 447 - 67.
2 05
Practice sects and overlaps with the world of the fiction, but the two are never asserted to be one and the same. Ford helps to ground the novel in a verifiable actuality, but his peculiar intractability as a character warns the reader that fictional analogy and reconcretization cannot presume to encompass or exhaust the totality of the referent. The use of the Camera Eye, however, most decisively signals Dos Passos ' s departure fro m the ideological p remises of nineteenth-cen tury realism and demonstrates his affinity with a B rechtian program. In some ways the Camera Eye bears a genetic relation to the ego cogitans recorded in both the pseudofactual novel and the fictional autobiography; indeed Dos Passos often expressed his admiration for both Defoe and Joyce, especially the Joyce of Portrait. But Defoe' s protagonists routinely take for granted the relation between percep tion and cognition; even when their vantage point is ironized by the author, a particular ideological formulation is foregrounded, not the intrinsically ideological nature of all discourse. By contrast, the Cam era Eye, as modernist artist-hero, is painfully aware of his own pre conceptions, and he continually scrutinizes the "upsidedown image on the retina, "24 a phrase surely intended to echo Marx's and Engels' s famous description of ideological thought in The German Ideology . But where the hero of modernist fictional autobiography ordinarily assimilates historical actualities to the dimensions of a problematized self-consciousness, Dos Passos's C amera Eye strug gles to bring both his experience and his writing into alignment with historical processes objectively existing beyond the bounds of con sciousness . Moving from a stance of Joycean spectatorship to one of engaged partisanship ( "all right we are two nations") , the Camera Eye grapples with the historical p rocess that shapes his own shaping of A merican history. Consciously confronting his own tendencies to ward aestheticism and privatization, he repudiates a stance of tran scendental subj ectivity and acknowledges his own embeddedness in the reality he describes; at the same time, he retains the option to de lineate, interpret, and j udge. Partisanship, for Dos Passos, means a political stance in material reality, rather than an admission of the intrinsic - and equivalent2".John Dos Passos, The Big Money (New York: Modem Library, 1 93 7) , 1 96. The pas sa g e quoted belo w is from p. 462 . 206
The Modernist Documentary Novel subj ectivity of all angles of perception. Totalization is undertaken from a position involving neither specious neutrality nor solipsism but rather explicit grounding in the social contradictions of the his torical moment. Dos Passos's praxis as author is inseparable from his view of history as the praxis of class struggle, which molds both in ner states of consciousness and external historical events . At the trilo gy's moment of climax, then, it is significant that subj ective and ob j ective realities , previously kept separate in the different segments of the narrative, are j oined. Mary French' s singing of the Internationale when she is arrested at the protest rally for Sacco and Vanzetti blends into the newsreel that follows the fictional narration, and Vanzetti' s prison meditations are then excerpted i n the midst of the Camera Eye's impassioned thoughts on the bankruptcy of the American judi ciary. While both Isherwood and Dos Pas sos use the term " camera eye" to designate a privileged authorial lens, there is a crucial differ ence in the functions of these alter egos . Isherwood's affirms the tran scendental vantage point of a subj ectivity that cannot locate its own anguish in dialectical relation to its causes ; Dos Passos's delineates the abandonment of detached subj ectivity as a result of political activity affirming the necessarily social essence of individuality. While asserting the primacy of a radical politics and epistemology in U. S.A., we cannot say that the text is in any sense free of ideolog ical contradiction. On the contrary, D os Pasos repudiated many fea tures of liberal ideology and mimetic practice, but his work also bears certain traces of the reification it exposes. The text's structural separa tion of public from private experience, while enabling Dos Passos to avoid the ideological effect of positing either the cast of fictional char acters or the author's own subj ectivity as exhaustively representative, also runs the risk of hypostasizing the personal and the historical as separate realms of experience. The text also proposes only an incom plete rendition of the pro cess whereby the informing authorial con sciousness has reached its stance of committed partisanship . The Camera Eye's apocalyptic recognition of class warfare emerges from a minimum of directly represented experience; it is significant that the Camera Eye disappears for over three hundred pages before its sud den appearance in the midst of the movement to save Sacco and Vanzetti. Accordingly, the Camera Eye's achievement of historical insight seems like a Joycean epiphany; even the text' s powerful struc20 7
Practice tural conj unction of fiction, newsreel, and autobiography in the Sacco and Vanzetti episode effects a certain mystification of historical process , although it also persuasively draws together the text' s vari ous strands of narration and commentary. Despite its powerful im plied critique of empiricism and positivism, then, U. S . A . retains a privileged autonomy for the consciousness of its artist-hero . The text reproduces a certain fetishization of subjectivity, even as it describes truthfully the social and historical forces producing the isolation and alienation that lead to such subj ectivity.
The Assault on Positivism in Philosophy and Historiography The contradictory blend of protest and acquiescence that characterizes the modernist documentary novel's response to reification re ceives its full theoretical articulation in the reaction to positivism in much contemporaneous philosophy and historiography. As H. Stu art Hughes has pointed out, early twentieth-century theorists pur sued various paths, but they were generally united in their antipathy to, and yet their curious reliance upon, the nineteenth-century philophical heritage that they variously termed " mechanism, " "ra tionalism, " "materialism, " or "intellectualism. "25 We shall now con sider certain paradigmatic conceptual abstractions that guide a range of early twentieth-century philosophers and historians. As we survey modernist thinkers as diverse as Bergson and Husserl, Spengler and Collingwood, I shall suggest correlations between their principal theses and the abstractions shaping the fictional reconcretizations we have j ust examined. I am not arguing, of course, that Woolf was di rectly influenced by Bergson (though this may have been the case) , or Faulkner by Husserl. My concern is with mediation rather than with influence as such. My goal is to outline the recurring features of con ceptual abstraction in key texts of the modernist epoch, in order to link these features plausibly to the "real abstraction" from which they anse. 25See H . Stuart Hughes, "The Decade of the 1 890s: The Revolt against Positivism, " in his Consciousness and Society: The Reorientation of European Social Thought, 1 890- 1930 (New York: Knopf, 1 9 5 8 ) , 3 3 - 66. 208
·
The Modernist Documentary Novel Transcendental Conceptions of Time and Essence in Modernist Philosophy Henri Bergson's attempt to relate relativity theory to the problem of temporal perception and experience constituted a critical response to the positivist obj ectification of time and matter in the natural and physical sciences. For Bergson, both "empiricism" and "rationalism" had isolated the perceiving self within arbitrary boundaries that leave it confronted only with "empty space. " A "true empiricism" he urged, "is one which purposes to keep as near to the original itself as possible, to probe more deeply into its life, and by a kind of spiritual auscultation, to feel its soul palpitate; and this true empiricism is the true metaphysics . "26 The key to this "true metaphysics, " Bergson believed, was a renewed perception of time. Dissatisfied with the ab stract conception of chronology inherited from Newtonian mechan ics, Bergson proposed a radical distinction between simultaneite, or clock time, and duree, or experienced time: "We . . . call two external flows that occupy the same duration "simultaneous " because they both depend upon the duration of a like third, our own; this duration is ours only when our consciousness is concerned with us 'alone, but it becomes equally theirs when our attention embraces the three flows in a single indivisible act. "27 "Why must we speak of an inert matter into which life and consciousness would be inserted as in a frame?" he asked . "By what right do we put the inert first?"28 He urged, "Let us become accustomed to see all things sub specie durationis: immediately in our galvanized perception what is taut becomes relaxed, what is dormant awakens, what is dead comes to life again. "29 The recovery of multiple temporal perspectives "in a single indivisible act" prom ises to revive the deadened isolation of reified consciousness, which is otherwise confined to itself alone. Bergson's exploration of the epistemological implications he saw in relativity theory was clearly meant to liberate the subject from the old trap of Cartesian dualism. His favoring of duree over simultaneite 26Henri Bergson, The Creative Mind, trans. Mabelle L. Andison (New York: Philosophi cal Library, 1 946) , 206. 27Bergson, Duration and Simultaneity: With Reference to Einstein's Theo ry, trans. Leon Jakobson (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1 965), 5 2 . "Bergson, The Creative Mind, ro8. 29Bergson, Duration and Simultaneity, ix. 209
Practice can be seen, however, as substituting a "metaphysics of temporality" (the phrase is Horkheimer' s) for the positivist metaphysics of obj ec tivity.30 Bergson absolutized existential time as thoroughly as the positivists had absolutized the abstract time of Newtonian mechanics and-for all his celebration of the subject's newfound freedom- de fined a new determinism. "It is time which is happening, " he de clared, "and, more than that, which causes everything to happen. "31 Moreover, the phenomena caught up in the flow of time become less real than time itself " There are changes, but there are underneath the change no things which change: change has no need of a support. "32 Berg son's attack on empiricism and rationalism, then, amounted to an at tack on any analytical system that would presume to discern princi ples of order in facticity: "Disorder is simply the order we are not looking for. " The j oys of experienceing life sub specie durationis are available only to the metaphysical soul; otherwise life is condemned to the positivist realm of the inert, which will always " come first. " Where Bergson carefully avoided any rigorous systemization of the lessons he drew from his intuitive explorations of the realm of dun�e, Hans Vaihinger, in The Philosophy of "As If, " attempted to found a neo-Kantian theory of knowledge upon his critique of positivism. Curiously, however, he harnessed positivism itself in this critique, referring to his own theoretical stance as, alternately, "positivist ide alism" and "idealistic positivism. "33 Conceding that "objective" real ity is ruled by "an absolute, unchangeable necessity, " Vaihinger grafted onto the positivist conception of a brute reality regulated by unswerving laws a neo-Kantian formulation of the inaccessibility of the " thing-in-itself" -a formulation that would, presumably, liber30Max Horkheimer, "Zu Bergsons Metaphysik der Zeit" ( 1 9 3 4) , quoted in Martin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute for Social Re search, r923 -50 (Boston: Little, Brown, 1973 ) , 5 1 . "Bergson, Duration and Simultaneity, x. "Bergson, The Creative Mind, 1 7 3 . I quote below from p . u6. 33Hans Vaihinger, The Philosophy of "As If": A System of the Theoretical, Practical, and Reli gious Fictions ofMankind, trans . C. K. Ogden (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1 92 5 ) , 5 8 - 59. The quotations below are from pp. lvii and viii. Although Vaihinger is a relatively obscure figure of the modernist period, his philosophical formula, Hughes argues, "came the closest to providing social thought with the highly flexible criterion of investigation it required: his notion of a fiction in science was approximately identical to Weber's 'ideal type. ' But Vaihinger's work remained unknown for the greater part of his academic life" (Hughes, uo) . Vaihinger completed the first edition of The Philosphy of "As If" in 1 8 77, but it was first published in German in 1 9 1 I . 2 IO
The Modernist Documentary Novel ate the ego cogitans from the constraints of a correspondence theory of knowledge. The world of ideas , he declared, is a "network of fic tions" that claim explanatory power only on the level of abstraction. Indeed, Vaihinger could barely disguise his contempt for the realm of the concrete: " What we usually term reality consists of our sensa tional contents which press forcibly upon us with greater or lesser ir resistibility and as ' given' can generally not be avoided. " Vaihinger' s description of the relation of thought to actuality thus reveals an alienation of essence from phenomenon even more pro nounced than that articulated by Comte or Mill. Materiality is im penetrable, opaque, and ruled by laws that can be reliably quantified but never fully understood; the subject can ultimately know only its own heuristic fictions and is in fact further implicated in the separa tion of appearance and essence that it seeks to overcome. Vaihinger attempted to avoid the fully idealist implications of his formulation by offering a central distinction between "hypotheses " and "fictions , " the former being "natural" and "probable, " the latter merely provid ing a dispensable intellectual scaffolding. But this strategic distinction was virtually impossible to maintain in practice. Presumably directed against the epistemological hegemony of the crude positivist equation of perception with cognition, Vaihinger' s theory in fact codified the unknowability of the thing-in-itself as a necessary feature of all ex planatory enterprises . Indeed, Vaihinger maintained, truth is not even a necessary criterion of the value of a " fiction, " which might be demonstrably false but still possess "great practical importance. " His theory of "as if, " intended to free philosophy from the trammels of a reductionist materialism, ended up fetishizing the "unchangeable, ab solute necessity" of brute facticity by rej ecting the only potential vir tue of positivism- namely, its insistence upon a world beyond con seiousness that philosophy was to understand and interpret. Husserl's proj ect of redefining essence by means of "phenomeno logical reduction" also constituted an attack upon the positivist fetish ization of the "little significant fact. " "Individual Being of every kind is, to speak quite generally, 'accidental. ' It is so-and-so, but essentially it could be other than it is . " 34 Such accidental facticity is limited, however, because it is "correlative to a necessity which does not carry 34Edmund Husserl, Ideas: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology ( r 9 r 3 ) , trans . W. R. Boyce Gibson (London: Allen & Unwin, r93 r ) , 5 3 . I quote below from pp. 54, 5 5 , 57, and r 50.
2 II
Practice the mere actuality-status of a valid rule of connexion obtaining be tween spatio-temporal facts , but has the character of essential necessity, and therewith a relation to essential universality . In order to grasp this "essential universality, " " empirical or individual intuition" must be "transformed into essential insight, " since ''just as the datum of individual or emp irical intuition is an individual object, so the datum of essential intu ition is a pure essence . " But, as with Vaihinger, "fact" and "truth" therefore come to in habit mutually incompatible realms . " The positing of essence, " declares Husserl, "does not imply any positing of individual existence whatsoever; pure essential truths do not make the slightest assertion concerning facts. " Ac cordingly, the subj ect who seeks to understand essences reduces facts to the status of " exemplars . " All merely factitious data occupy equiv alent status, and, finally, "absolute consciousness " is the "residuum after the nullifying of the world. " The ego cogitans who, in the for mulation of Descartes , at least insisted upon the embeddedness of the subj ect in historicall actuality, is now endowed with an absolutized trancendental status. For Husserl, Descartes's cardinal error was to anchor the subj ect in " absolute evidence" and to treat it as a "primary, indubitably existing bit of the world. "35 While phenomenology cer tainly did not base itself in transcendental presuppositions (Husserl emphatically denied the charge of "subjective idealism") , 36 it led to such presuppositions, as Marcuse points out, for identity, in isolation from facticity, becomes the source of cognition. 37 It should be apparent that many of the assumptions guiding these philosophical rej ections of positivism also shaped the representational strategy of the modernist documentary novel in both its triodes . Orlando' s peculiady relativized process of aging, for example, is a kind of mimetic p roj ection of the Bergsonian opposition between dun�e and simultaneite. On the more obvious level of plot, Orlando's time-traveling suggests Bergson's notion that "there are changes, but . . . underneath the change no things which change. " More signifi cantly, however, Orlando' s very identity derives from her/his im plicit repudiation of the rational quantification of the clock of linear 35Husserl, Formal and Transcendental Logic, trans . Dorion Cairns (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1 969) , 227. 36Husserl, Ideas, l 6 8. 37See Herbert Marcuse, "The Concept of Essence, " in Negations: Essays in Critical The o ry , trans. Jeremy J. Shapiro (Boston: Beacon, 1 968) , 5 5 - 5 8 . 2 I2
The Modernist Documentary Novel
historical time and endorsement of a view of history in which all mo ments of time are simultaneously present: beyond the achievement of "The Oak Tree, " it is, as in Bergson's ontology, "time which is hap pening, and which causes everything to happen. " Even Woolf' s par ody of biography suggests a Bergonsian alienation from any explana tory scheme that would purport to affix identity by a measurable diachronism. Orlando's play with its own status as a historical docu ment thus ironizes not simply the linear conception of history but also the explanatory claims of any discourse presuming to invoke "in ert matter" as a "frame" for comprehending "life and conscious ness. "38 Similarly, Vaihinger's postulation of a realm of "absolute, un changeable necessity" and of the intrinsic fictionality of all explana tory abstractions .bears a distinct similarity to the epistemology guid ing Goodbye to Berlin. Like Vaihinger's maker of fictions, Isherwood's "camera eye" inhabits an opaque historical world (a " 'given' that can not be avoided") that leads him to postpone the time when all this will have to be developed, carefully printed, fixed. " The privileged status of the artist thus hinges upon the provisional nature of any propositional schemes that he would impose upon the raw facticity of historical actuality. " 'Christopher Isherwood, ' " Isherwood tells us in his preface, "is a convenient ventriloquist's dummy, nothing more. "39 His statements about prefascist Berlin are thus to be taken as fictive hypotheses; even when he describes the mounting vigilante terror in Berlin, he " can't altogether believe that any of this has really happened. " In addition, Husserl's notion that facts are mere "exemplars " artic ulates a conception of phenomenological interchangeability that sur faces frequently in modernist fictions - whether in Stein's conjunc tion of the subj ectivities of herself and Alice B. Toklas, in Faulkner's undifferentiated blending of the voices of Quentin and Shreve, or in Warren' s suggestion of transhistorical ethical parallelism in the crimes of Cass Mastern and Judge Irwin. In these texts, indeed, the Husser38While I am not arguing that any of the philosphers mentioned here directly influenced any of the novelists in question, a case can be made for Bergson's influence on Wool£ See James Hafley, The Glass Roof Virginia Woolfas Novelist (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1 954) , 43 -44. See also, however, J. W. Graham, "A Negative Note on Bergson and Virginia Woolf, " Essays in Criticism, 6 (June 1956) : 70- 74. 39lsherwood, 7.
2 13
Practice lian equivalence of factitious obj ects of perception even implies an equivalence in the subj ects of perception: " Whatever belongs to the es sence of the individual can also belong to another individual . " In their aban donment of a historically based typicality that would mediate be tween the individual and the social, Stein, Faulkner, and Warren portray historical agents who partake of both a unique particularity and a collective being that supersedes individual identity altogether. Husserl's description of all empirical data as "facts of consciousness" also illuminates the treatment of documentary particulars in these mi metic texts . Quentin can undertake his bold imaginative extrapola tions because all the data available to him are, it seems, equally verifi able and fallible: the "essential universality" of the Sutpen story is therefore unrelated to the " connection obtaining between spatio temporal facts" and, indeed, need not make " the slightest assertion concerning the facts . "40 Relativism and Determinism in Modernist Historiography Historians and philosophers of history in the early decades of the twentieth century also participated in a critical reassessment of the positivist heritage-- in particular, they took as their target the obj ec tivist pretensions of " scientific history . " Alfred Bushnell Hart voiced the new skepticism when he declared in 1 899 that " the analogy of the natural sciences may be pushed too far . . . . Facts as facts, however carefully selected, s cientific treatment in itself, however necessary for the ascertainment of truth, are no more history than recruits arranged in battalions are an army . 41 Pursuing the methodological impli cations of this insight, some modernist historiographers became rel ativists , engaging in a self-conscious reflection upon their own epistemological assumptions and proclaiming the limitations of their conclusions . Others, going in the opposite direction, proposed grand 40For the argument that Faulkner historicizes his referent and defetishizes the specious obj ectivity of the " reifiecl reader, " see Carolyn Porter, Seeing and Being: The Plight of the Participant Observer in Emerson, James, Adams, and Faulkner (Middletown: Wesleyan Univer sity Press, 1 9 8 1 ) , 24 1 - 76 . 41Alfred Bushnell Hart, "Imagination in History, " American Historical Review, 1 5 (Janu ary l 9 I O) : 2 3 4, 2 3 6 - 3 7 . For more on the shifts in American historiography early in the twentieth century, see History, by John Higham, with Leonard Krieger and Felix Gilbert (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1965), 87- 1 3 I . 2 14
The Modernist Documentary Novel schemes of historical development that turned speculative history away from the task of scientific description and toward the goal of philosophical meditation. While the relativist and the speculative his torians wrote very different kinds of narratives, they each rej ected a heritage that they saw as linear and progressive in its conception of historical process and as positivist in its assumptions about historical mqmry. Croce was to modernist historiography what Hegel had been to the historiography of the previous century. Launching a broadside against the methodological and philosophical presuppositions of the positivist historians, Croce declared that scientific method was intrin sically antithetical to the enterprise of the historian; historical recon struc tion, he argued, is a "spiritual act. " Science, for Croce, could yield only an "external" perception of data, whereas history necessi tated an "internal" comprehension, an imaginative reenactment of the motives o f historical agents. The historian's own subj ectivity was therefore the key to effective historical narration; the scientific method could produce only dead history, or " chronicle, " whereas the . intuitive intervention of the historian produced "living " history, nec essarily written from the standpoint of the present. "The deed of which history is told, " stipulated Croce, " must vibrate in the soul of the historian. "42 If the scientific method violated the creative nature of historical discourse, however, the attempt to write comprehensive or speculative philosophies of history of the Hegelian sort was , for Croce, equally bankrupt . Because of the inherently inventive and provisional nature of historical reconstruction, the historian could never hope to generate totalizing explanatory systems, which were simply " metaphysical constructs " invoking a superficially empirical methodology. The historian, declared Croce, is limited to exploring only "proximate causes . " In the hands of Croce, then, the Hegelian conception of history as the unfolding of reason underwent a crucial transformation. Croce retained the i d ealist aspects of Hegel's formulation: The spirit itself is history, maker of history at every moment of its exis tence, and also the result of all anterior his tory. Thus the spirit bears with it all its history, which coincides with itself. . . . The spirit, so to
42Benedetto Croce, History : Its Theory and Practice, trans . Douglas Ainslie (New York: Russell & Russell, 1 960) , 1 2 . I quote below from pp. 65 and 2 5 . 2IJ
Practice speak, lives upon i ts o wn history without those external things called narratives and documents ; but thos e external things are instruments that it makes for itself, acts prepatory to that internal vital evocation in whose process they are resolved.
Croce abandoned the Hegelian requirement that Spirit is manifested only in its concretions, asserting instead that history is thought, an "internal vital evocation, " to which the "facts " of history stand in merely an illustrative relation. Hegelian totalization could therefore be, for Croce, only a hubristic venture, for there were no empirical standards for evaluating the relative adequacy of any causal analysis of past events . Croce explicitly repudiated relativism and irrational ism (he continually dissociated his proj ect from that of Bergson, to which it was often linked) , but his theory logically implied the sub j ective idealism that: it claimed to disdain. His formulation of the pro cess of historical reconstruction required that the historian rely cen trally upon intuition- what he called the "lightning-flash" of insight. Aprioristic imagination thus emerged as the ultimate source of histor ical knowledge; as in Husserlian phemonenology, identity furnished the basis of cognition, and historical discourse became an " act of faith. " Croce' s contemporaries in the United States, the " New Histori ans , " were confronting their positivist heritage in a somewhat less hostile manner, but: they eventually endorsed a relativistic stance that was readily compatible with Crocean idealism. James Harvey Robin son, author of the seminal The New Histo ry, mounted an assault on the followers of Ranke. "What onlookers call 'impartial history' and the professionals call 'obj ectivity, ' " he quipped, "is merely history without an obj ect. '"43 Yet Robinson also denigrated the tradition of novelistic narration exemplified by Bancroft and favored some of the " s cientific" aspirations that Croce deplored. The historian " is at lib erty to use only h:is scientific imagination, which is quite different from a literary imagination, " he declared. Charles Beard, whose An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution of the United States exemplifies the achievement of the New History at its most rigorous, answered Robinson's call for a history that would be both "present-minded" and "scientific. " In this study, Beard called explicit attention to his 43J ames Harvey Robinson, The New History ( 1 9 1 2; New York: Free Press, 1 96 5 ) , xxi. The quoted passage below appears on p . 52. 2I6
The Modernist Documentary Novel own methodological procedures . In his preface to the 1 9 1 3 edition, Beard distinguished his own work from the three dominant historio graphical traditions in the United States - the romantic nationalism of Bancroft, the chauvinsim of the racialist historians, and the neu tralist pretensions of the scientific historians . 44 Yet Beard did not re strict himself to a Crocean exploration of "proximate causes . " In his exhaustively documented study of the economic interests of the Founding Fathers, he offered a compelling analysis of the class nature of the Constitution that retains its influence to this day. Like Dos Passos's U. S . A . , Beard's study defamiliarizes the course of American history, submitting it to a subversive critique that is itself aware of its own ideological premises. It is perhaps no accident that Dos Passos was a great admirer of Beard. While the New Historians corrected the errors of scientific history in important ways, they hardly disowned all its guiding assumptions . Beard declared that his highly partisan stance in An Economic Interpre tation was " coldly neutral " ; Robinson celebrated the liberation of his tory from its "long servitude to philosophy. "45 The New Historians did not wish to resolve the contradiction between " science-minded ness" and "present-mindedness " by positing that historical truth can be both obj ective and partisan at the same time: a Brechtian theory of discourse and a Leninist theory of politics were alien to their liberal temperament. By the 1 93 0s, they had abandoned their obj ectivist posture and had come to endorse Croce's notion that all history is " contemporary history. " Thus, Beard, who became Croce's most ar dent apostle and popularizer on this side of the Atlantic, remarked in his 1 93 5 preface to An Economic Interpretation that his study was " merely what it professes to be-a version, not the absolute truth - of history. " It " does not 'explain' the Constitution, " he conceded. "It does not exclude other explanations deemed more satisfactory to the explainers . "46 44Charles Beard, An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution of the United States ( 1 9 1 3 ; . New York: Macmillan, 1 944) , 1 - 4. I quote below from p . ix. 45Robinson, 99. 46Beard, ix. For the later Beard, Robinsonian "present-mindedness" came to mean rela tivism, not relevance. "The pallor of waning time, if not of death, " he lamented in the 1 930s, "rests upon the latest volume of history, fresh from the roaring press. " Quoted iri Richard Hofstadter, The Progressive Historians: Turner, Beard, Parrington (New York: Ran dom House, 1968) , 3 08 . For more on the changes in Beard's view of history, see Hofstadter, 3 04 - 1 7 . 2I7
Practice From the explicit relativism of the later Beard it was only a step to the acknowledged idealism of R. G. Collingwood, the most impor tant British practitioner of Crocean historiography. Collingwood as serted, like Croce, that history is the " reenactment" of past experi ence, " requiring imaginative empathy and identification on the part of the historian. History therefore comprises - in his famous phrase - an immense " web of imaginative construction , " 47 in which not merely the lacunae and the connections, but the " fixed points " them selves, are determined by an essentially autonomous cognitive proce dure. The historian, said Collingwood, builds up a " picture of the past, the product of his own a priori imagination, that has to j ustify the sources used in its own construction. " In Collingwood's hands , Croce's conception of history as "internal vital evocation" received its fullest theoretical articulation. The criterion for validity in historical discourse is, emphatically, coherence rather than correspondence; like the Husserlian subj ect, the Collingwoodian historian posits identity (that is , reference to subj ective insight) as the source of knowledge and seeks from facticity only secondary corroboration. In Colling wood' s philosophy of history, the attack on positivism comes full cir cle, and we meet again Comte's despair of ever knowing the " inmost causes of phenomena. " While in the early decades of the century analytical philosophers of history were moving toward a narrowing and a qualification of the historian's explanatory claims, speculative philosphers of history were launching the attack upon positivism from another direction. Spengler exemplified the most conservative tendency in this ideolog ical opposition, for his attack upon scientific history was , fundamen tally and explicitly, an attack upon rationalism as such. Indeed, Spengler resisted primarily the residually progressive aspect of posi tivism - its insistence upon the possible obj ectivity and determinacy of knowledge and upon the uses of empiricism in historical recon struction . Rej ecting the search for causal uniformity, laws, and " measurability" in history, Spengler declared that "causality has noth ing whatever to do with Time . . . Real history is heavy with fate but (ree of laws . "48 The historian thus explicitly repudiates the regulative .
47R. G. Collingwood, The Idea of History ( 1 946; New York: Oxford University Press, 1 9 56) , 242. I quote below from p . 245. 480swald Spengler, The Decline of the West: Form and Actuality ( 1 9 1 8) , trans. Charles Francis Atkinson (New York: Knopf, 1 926) , 1 20, r r 8 . 218
The Modernist Documentary Novel principle of reason in favor of an irrationalist vitalism: "Only the in sight that can penetrate into the metaphysical is capable of experienc ing in data symbols of that which happened, and so of elevating an In cident into a Destiny . . . . Life is the alpha and omega, and life has no system, no programme, no rationality; it exists for itself and through itself, and the profound order in which it realizes itself can only be in tuited and felt- and then perhaps described. " Spengler's charged fa talism thus coexisted with a peculiar methodological relativisim: de terminism in the sphere of events is clearly linked with indeterminacy in the sphere of contemplation. Spengler may have denigrated the "scientific" or "empirical" method, but he asserted nonetheless that history does indeed realize itself in a "profound order. " He called for a "morphology of world history" that would discover the essence of historical movement in cyclical recurrence and in the appearance of " contemporaneous" phe nomena in separate ages. Spengler thus associated "fate" with the rise and fall of peoples and nations . In his disturbingly Europocentric view of the "great" civilizations and his glorification of great auto crats and military leaders, Spengler reasserted the teleological nation alism of many historians in the century before- with the difference that national destiny, in Spengler's hands, is a grim proposition in deed, divested of the enlightenment association of progress with rea son and democracy that had energized the pronouncements of a Michelet and even a Bancroft. "The genuine Internationale, " he de clared, "is imperialism. "49 Spengler thus proclaimed the irrelevance of scientific method at the same time that he invested his own vitalis tic philosophy with a fatalistic authority. This charged combination of irrationalism with apocalyptic nationalism accounts for the easy assimilation of the major tenets of Spenglerian thought to Nazi ideology . Spengler articulates an overtly reactionary version of the modernist critique of positivism. But even liberal speculative historians like Arnold ). Toynbee and H. G. Wells reached comparable conclusions . Toynbee insistently differentiated his own Anglo-American "empir icism" from Spengler's Germanic idealism and proclaimed hope where Spengler saw only decline. He argued that the study of his49Quoted in Georg Lukacs, The Destruction of Reason, trans. Peter Palmer (Atlantic Highlands, N.J. : Humanities, 1 9 8 1 ) , 464. 2 19
Practice tory demonstrates the succession of rising and falling civilizations , whereby each one experiences a similar pattern of "rally and rout, " "challenge and response. " He claimed that release from cyclical recur rence was possible, however, not by the working out of a progressive principle in human affairs, but by a repetition of the divine interven tion first illustrated in the coming of Christ. "Inasmuch as it cannot be supposed that God's nature is less constant than man's , " he hy pothesized, "we may and must pray that the reprieve which God has granted to our society once will not be refused it we ask for it again in a humble spirit and with a contrite heart. "50 Wells, in the 1 92 1 edi tion of his An Outline ofHistory, sadly concluded that " there has been a slipping off of ancient restraints; a real decivilization of men's minds . " He prophetically noted, "New falsities may arise and hold men in some unrighteous and fated scheme of order for a time, before they collapse amidst the misery and slaughter of generations . "51 Despite his liberal faith in progress, Wells, like Toynbee, ultimately placed his hopes for world salvation in the religious spirit: "Religious emotion - stripped of corruptions and freed from its last priestly entangle ments- may prese:ntly blow through life again like a great wind, bursting the doors and flinging open the shutters of the individual life and making many things possible and easy that in these present days of exhaustion seem almost too difficult to desire. " While Well's vi sion of a collectivist future "flinging open the shutters of the individ ual life" has little in common with Spengler' s grim conclusion about the "genuine Internationale, " he, like Toynbee, appears to have aban doned the Hegelian notion that change is generated by contradictions internal to the historical process itself. All three look to a telos be yond human agency or scientific formulation. It should be apparent that many of the conceptions of historical process and inquiry guiding analytical and speculative historiography furnish the epistemological premises to modernist documentary fic tion. Faulkner' s Quentin Compson in Absalom, Absalom! can be seen as a prototype of the Collingwoodian historian, for he boldly con structs a "web of ilmaginative construction" in his "a priori imagina tion" and evaluates the explanatory power of facts on the basis of dis50Amold J . Toynbee, A Study ofHistory, reprinted in Theories ofHistory, ed. Patrick Gar diner (New York: Free Press , 1 9 5 9) , 205 . 51H. G . Wells, The Outline of Histo ry: Being a Plain History of Life ana Mankind, 3 d ed. (New York: Macmillan, 1 92 1 ) , 1089, u oo . 220
The Modernist Documentary Novel cursive coherence rather than referential correspondence. In his futile attempt to wrest a meaning from the accumulated data about Cass Mastern, Warren's Jack Burden dramatizes the dilemma of a historian trained in the positivist method; his intuitionist discovery of patterns of historical recurrence- personalized instances of "rally and rout, " as it were-is treated as the discovery of a more adequate method of historical inquiry. Thomas Wolfe's attribution of fascist violence to an unconquerable atavism embedded in all of humanity represents a horrified liberal's surrender to the primitive irrationalism that Speng ler celebrates with hearty gloom. The extreme alienation and despair of Isherwood's camera eye bear an affinity to the disillusionment voiced by Wells at the termination of his tour of world history. Even Orlando's succession of historical reincarnations blends into a cyclical pattern similar to those described by Spengler or Toynbee: her/his diachronic roles are hardly identical in appearance, but they constitute a "morphology" signaling a synchronic essence. Historians and nov elists alike rej ect the use of empiricist documentation to support linear theories of historical development which the events of the early twen tieth century seemed to belie. In so doing, however, they relinquish the search for a determinate interpretation that would enable them to see their own reified present as the product of concrete historical de velopments. Their crisis is the crisis of liberalism in the era of monop oly capitalism.
The "Problem of Commodities " in the Modernist Era The modernist era spanned the period when capital underwent the transition from its competitive to its monopolist phase. Because com petition forced it constantly to modernize its technological base, capi tal became increasingly concentrated in its fixed component (raw materials, machinery, and overhead) , as opposed to its variable com ponent (wages) . This process- designated by Marx as the "increase in the organic composition of capital" - resulted in a number of im portant changes in capital's social role. Sohn-Rethel states , Firms where . . . part of the cost is high in relation to the direct costs , in the main of materials and wages which vary according to the volume of output, cannot easily respond to the market regulatives of social econ omy controlling the play of the law of value. When demand recedes and
22 I
Practice prices tend to slump , production should be cut down and supplies be di minished. But heavy overheads will cause unit costs to rise with less ened output, and we obtain the contradiction that adaptation of supplies to receding ·demands forces the cost to rise when prices fall. In other words the rising organic composition of capital makes production in creasingly inadaptable to the market regulatives . The reaction to the contradiction on the part of the firms affected can only be to force them, as a matter of life arnd death, to try to obtain control of the movements of the market. This is how they become " monopolists . "52
Where capitalists formerly had adapted production more or less to the demands of the market and had expanded or contracted their la bor pool as they chose, now they were compelled to keep their plant functioning at all times in order to offset the tendency toward a fall ing rate of profit that accompanied their large-scale investment in fixed capital. As a result, the imperatives of production and con sumption and the imperatives of exchange entered into a highly con tradictory and often antagonistic relationship, in which the second nature of commodities (as embodiments of abstract labor) stood in open opposition to their fi r st nature (as use values embodying con crete labor) . Two central consequences of this development- one highly visible, one more covert - are of importance to our inquiry here. Imperialism The more palpable effect of the movement toward monopolism was the growing necessity to open up new markets and resume colo nial expansion-in other words , imperialism. The last quarter of the nineteenth century witnessed apparently uncontrollable cycles of boom and bust, in which the limited markets of the industrialized na tions were unable to absorb the flow of commodities produced by the rapidly expanding industrial base. Imperialism was the necessary solution to the economic and social dislocations generated by this development. Lenin, in his Imperialism: The Highest Stage of Cap italism, quoted Cecil Rhodes's frank admission of the "importance of imperialism": 52Sohn-Rethel, Intellectual and Manual Labor: A Critique of Epistemology, trans . Martin Sohn-Rethel (Atlantic Highlands, N .J . : Humanities, 1978), 1 44- 4 5 . 222
The M o derni s t
D o cu m ent ar y N o vel
I was in the East End of London yesterday and attended a meeting of the
unemployed. I listened to the wild speeches, which were just a cry for " bread, bread ! " and on my way home I pondered over the scene and I became more than ever convinced of the importance of imperialism . . . . My cherished idea is a solution for the social problem, i . e . , in order to save the 40, 000, 000 inhabitants of the United Kingdom from
a bloody
civil war, we colonial statesmen must acquire new lands to settle the surplus population, to provide new markets for the goods produced in the factories and mines . The Empire, as I have always s aid, is a bread and butter question. It you want to avoid civil war, you must become imperialists . 53
Imperialist expansion did postpone civil war-at least in the Western nations - and it temporarily offset the worst of the periodic crises in overproduction. The state intervened more unabashedly than before in the affairs of capital, and cartels were formed to control the vagar ies of the market. These measures, however, could only delay the in evitable consequences of sharpened interimperialist rivalry. As Lenin pointed out, these cartels would inevitably collapse, involving the monopolists in a war to partition the markets and resources of the globe. The spiraling of presumably enlightened nations toward the Great War and the unprecedented carnage and horror of the combat thus resulted from the inevitable contradictions within both produc tion and exchange in the monopolist era. To Lenin, who saw the "problem of commodities " at the root of early twentieth-century historical developments, the causes of the Great War were transparent. In his preface to the 1 9 1 7 edition of Im perialism, he noted the prophetic character of the analysis of imperial ism he had published the year before and urged that "unless the ques tion of the economic essence of imperialism is studied, it will be impossible to understand and appraise modem war and modem poli tics . " But to Western bourgeois intellectuals reared on evolutionary liberalism in what Dos Passos called the "peaceful afterglow of the nineteenth century, " Lenin's answer was by no means apparent. Tak ing the organization of production based upon the sale and purchase of labor power as a self-evident premise, a metaphysical axiom, bour geois intellectuals generally failed to penetrate the opacity of the com53Quoted in Lenin, Imperialism: The Highest Stage of Capitalism, in Collected Works, trans. George H. Hanna, ed. Robert Daglish (Moscow: Progress, 1 967) , 22:2 5 6 - 5 7 . I quote be low from p. 1 94. 22 3
Practice modity form or to question the legitimacy of the exchange of wages for labor power- hence their tendency to reify the very phenomenon of reification. In the time of Adam Smith, Marx noted, " the interior of the commodity" was only partially penetrated by the contradiction between use value and exchange value, concrete and abstract labor. 54 One hundred years :later, however, the visibility of production pro cesses in the object of production had been blurred, for the entire economy was organ:ized around the commodification of wage labor. As the normative self-evidence of the market economy gave way to uncontrollable cycles of boom and decline, therefore, bourgeois intellectuals experienced a crisis in ideology. Instead of attempting to penetrate the opacity of the social relations of production, they tended to resort to causal explanations that presupposed the legiti macy (or at least the fixity) of the mode of production that was caus ing the uncontrollable- and seemingly irrational- course of modern history. A phenomenon that was political to the core assumed the sta tus of an epistemological dilemma. The pressures of urbanization and economic depression appeared to signal the automatism of industrial ization and technology per se, rather than the historically specific or ganization of the social relations of production necessitated by finance capital. And subj ectivity was advanced to supply the locus of mean ing that social reality lacked. Husserl proclaimed, " There are only two escapes from the crisis of European existence: the downfall of Europe in its estrangement from its own rational sense of life, its fall into hostility and into barbarity; or the rebirth of Europe from the spirit of philosophy through a heroism of reason that overcomes nat uralism once and for all. "55 The postulation of a heroic, reasonable self transcending the naturalistic nightmare of fragmentation and chaos was thus an ideological mediation of monopoly capital's in creased need to subordinate the entire social synthesis to the impera tives of the exchange relation. In the context of this crisis in self-evidence, the Great War appeared to corroborate either the uncontrollable cyclicality or simply the unpredictability of historical processes . Where the French Revolution 54Marx, Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique ofPolitical Economy, trans. Martin Nicolaus (New York: Random House/Vintage, 1973), 169. 55Edmund Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology ( 1 9 5 4) , trans. David Carr (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1 970) , 299 . 224
The Modernist Documentary Novel
and the Napoleonic wars had shattered the ahistorical abstractions of Nature and Providence and had signaled the power of the masses in making history, the Great War signaled the omnipotence of History over the acts of individual participants and once again appeared to subordinate history to Nature- only this time to a Nature consti tuted by an odd admixture of indeterminacy and determinism, con tingency and fatality. Confronted with the imperialistic consequences of the "problem of commodities " in its most naked form, most nov elists, philosophers, and historians took the commodity itself as an aprioristic foundation rather than as an object of analysis . As Lukacs remarked in History and Class Consciousness, bourgeois society, " unable to comprehend [its] reality and [its] origin . . . as the product of the same subj ect [i. e. , capital] that has ' created' the comprehended total ity of knowledge, " will espouse an "ultimate point of view, decisive for the whole of its thought, . . . of immediacy. " 56 The contradictory response to reification in modernist thought thus articulates not any failure of nerve or intellect but the inadequate ideological premises upon which this response was founded. The assault upon fetishism and obj ectification was carried out with the artillery of conceptual ab stractions that took as axiomatic the second nature of the commodity form. Taylorism The growth of imperialism was the most obvious result of the in crease in the organic composition of capital, but equally significant consequences were manifested in the process of production itself. C apital was compelled to engage in a greater degree of exploitation of the work force and, consequently, to exercise a greater degree of con trol over production. When the capitalist had invested so great a pro portion of his financial resources in machinery and overhead, he could not afford to let his plant be underutilized through the ineffi cient use of variable capital; not simply a greater or lesser amount of profit but his very survival as a capitalist depended upon his ability to extract maximum productivity from his laborers . Earlier phases of capitalist development had witnessed the subjugation of the proletar iat as a class to the autonomism of capital and the harnessing of pro56Luk:ics, History and Class Consciousness,
I
56.
225
Practice
duction to the machine. But only in the era of monopoly capital did the entire labor process become segmented and quantified in accor dance with the dictates of Taylorism, or "scientific management" ; la bor did not merely confront and direct, but was actually incorporated into , the functioning of the machine. With production fragmented into components measurable by stopwatches and slide rules, human labor became, as Sohn-Rethel puts it, " directly adaptable and could be inserted or transferred into [the machinery] without any difficulty of conversion. "57 In the era of Taylorism and flow production, then, the split be tween mental and manual labor entered into the arena of production itself, and reification emerged as a self-evident feature of both the labor process and the social relations of production. 58 Braverman notes, Both in order to ensure management control and to cheapen the worker, conception and execution must be rendered separate spheres of work, and for this purpose the s tudy of work processes must be reserved to management and kept from the workers , to whom its results are com municated only in the form of simplified j ob tasks governed by simpli fied instructions which it is thenceforth their duty to follow unthink ingly and without comprehension of the underlying technical reasoning or data . . . . In the setting of antagonistic social relations, of alienated la bor, hand and brain become not just separated, but divided and hostile, and the human unity of hand and brain turns into its opposite, some thing less than human . . . . The separation of hand and brain . . . is inherent in the [capitalist] mode of production from its beginnings, and it develops, under capital ist management, throughout the history of capitalism, but it is only during the past century that the s cale of production, the resources made available to the modern corporation by the rapid accumulation of capi tal , and the conceptual apparatus and trained personnel have become available to institutionalize this separation in a systematic and formal fashion. 59
57Sohn-Rethel, 1 5 5 · 58For the alternate view that reifi.cation i s attributable mainly t o the shift toward produc tion for Department II (consumer goods) , and hence derives principally from the realm of consumption, see Michael Spindler, American Literature and Social Change: William Dean Howells to Arthur Miller (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1 9 8 3 ) , esp. 97- 1 20. 59Harry Braverman, Labor and Monopoly Capital: The Degradation of Work in the Twenti eth Century (New York: Monthly Review, 1 974) , 1 1 8, 1 2 5 - 26. 226
The Modernist Docu mentary Novel
It is arguable whether Taylorism represented a qualitative alter ation in capitalist forces of production or simply a tremendous quan titative expansion of the reifying tendencies noted by Marx. In either case, however, it involved a new level o f abstraction in production relations. Now, from the perspective of both the capitalist and of the worker, the telos of production in its first nature (that is, the produc tion of use values) became entirely subordinated to its second nature telos (that is , the production of surplus value) . The residual quality of labor that Marx specified as distinctly human- that is, that " at the end of every labour process , we get a result that already existed in the . imagination of the labourer at its commencement" - was finally eradicated. 60 The worker was increasingly dependent upon the capi talist, for not only the equipment and raw materials but also every as pect of engineering and planning were the property of the capitalist. "The power of capital is magnified in monopoly capitalism, " Sohn Rethel remarks, " because in the size of the modern system the work ers are more powerless than they ever have been since slavery, owing to the minuteness of each individual contribution. "61 Accordingly, the "fair exchange" of wages for labor power gained in legitimacy, or least in apparent naturalness , for the worker was divested of the ca pacity to plan production or even to control the machine to which la bor was attached. Reification and Representation It is interesting to speculate about the ways in which the conceptual abstractions guiding the characteristic representational strategies of the modernist documentary novel mediate the distinctive form of the exchange relation in the era of imperialist war and Taylorism. The modernist postulation of autonomous subj ectivity, for example, can be seen as articulating the full divorce of mental from manual labor in the production process. In one sense, of course, the modernist text' s empyrean positioning of a transcendental subj ect simply signifies an increased implication in the fetishistic epistemological paradigms that had been fostered by capitalist production in its earlier phases. In the modernist novel, however, the transcendental subj ect is fully tran60Marx, Captial: A Critique of Political Economy, ed. Frederick Engels, trans. Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling (New York: International, 1 967) , 1 : 1 7 8 . 61Sohn-Rethel, 1 5 8 . 22 7
Practice scendentalized, for the res extensa cannot provide a locus of signifi cance or value in which the ego cogitans may meaningfully define it self. The ego cogitans now constitutes a dualism: an authentic self that discovers identity apart from production, history, and social re lations, and a public self that merely plays a role in the social collec tivity. As George Simmel noted in his The Philosophy of Money , in a society characterized by universal commodity exchange and the uni versal commodification of labor power, "every material content of life" becomes " more and more material and impersonal so that the non-reifiable remnant may become all the more personal and all the more indisputably the p roperty of the person. "62 The modernist novel's abandonment of typicality and totalization thus reveals a dis enchantment not only with realism's epistemological naivete but als o with the notion that any social definition of individuality can success fully embody the intersection of personal and extrapersonal realities . The isolation of the perceiving self is now a priori: S antayana' s "pri vate little rivulet" of personal experience is separated from the " vast cosmic flood" of history by the severence of conception from execu tion, of abstract from concrete, right within the process of produc tion itself. If the perceiving self takes as a premise not merely its separation but also its ontological isolation from the obj ect of perception, it follows that the subj ect's attempts to account for that obj ect will be corre spondingly divested of power. The artist-hero' s proclamation of the inadequacy of his discourse to explain specific historical phenomena can be seen as further testimony to the pervasiveness of the second nature abstraction at the material base of consciousness. To offer a de terminate account of causality is, implicitly, to associate oneself with a degrading positivist rationalism that subsumes discourse to the province of exchange: if the use value of labbr p ower to capital is the expansion of surplus value and if the use value of reason is the more efficient quantification and control of production, then the use value of mimesis will be its lack of use. This conclusion does not represent a concession to the theoretical position (for which the foundation is laid in the modernist: period) that modernist documentary novels ac tually lack cognitive: power: the very affirmation of indeterminacy 62Georg Simmel, The Philosophy of Money, quoted in Lukacs, History and Class Con sciousness, 1 56-57. 228
The
Modernist Documentary Novel
and impotence is itself a proposition carrying assertive force. A ven triloquist's dummy does, after all, express the ventriloquist' s words, even if the authorial self appears committed to a mysterious silence. Nonetheless , the modernist novel's elevation of aesthetic sensibility over instrumental reason constitutes a capitulation to the monopolist divorce of conception from execution, since it relegates the protest against reification to a fictional realm that denies its own explanatory relation to its referent. One response to reification in modernist fiction is to valorize the apparently nonpropositional operations of the transcendental subj ect; another response is to propose an undifferentiated equivalence of subj ectivities . By divorcing thought from practice, Taylorism en forces a series of equivalences - between the various products of ab stract labor, between humans and machines . This abstraction of par ticularities in the realm of production manifests itself in the modernist documentary novel's paradoxical treatment of narratorial identity: the text celebrates the uniqueness of the autonomous self whose iden tity is the source of insight, but it also proclaims the peculiar inter changeability of this self with alternate subj ectivities . Ironically, the subsumption of commodities to the abstraction of their second nature effects the abstraction of the very subj ect who presumes to hold itself apart from the dehumanization it beholds . Henry Miller' s " women I have known" - as women, of course, easily obj ectified as abstrac tions - blur in his attempts at recall; Cass Mastern and Judge Irwin signal, by their Spenglerian " contemporaneity, " the accidental nature of their individual historical concretions; Quentin and Shreve treat all empirical data as equally valuable and fallible. But the Gertrude Stein who is valorized as a prophet of revolutionary modes of perception also blends imperceptibly into Alice B. Toklas; Quentin and Shreve lose their individual articulation and merge into a single undifferenti ated Faulknerian voice. The Husserlian subj ect who finds the source of cognition in identity, once divested of the social contextualization that would provide a concrete historical definition of self, is finally assimilated to the very undifferentiated abstraction to which it sets it self in opposition. Finally, the kinds of documentation that appear in modernist fic tion can be understood as mediations - at once critical and conces sionary- of the dominant form of the exchange abstraction in the monopolist era. The p seudofactual ambience surrounding the fie229
Practice tional autobiography testifies to the isolation of the perceiving sub j ect: the sense of the real anchors the subj ect's discourse in a felt histo ricity while avoiding the sorts of authorial j udgments that would imply - indeed, necessitate- the subj ect's contextualization in social experience. Hence the significance of Isherwood's decision to frame the fictional parts of Goodbye to Berlin within the documentary frame of a personal diary. The camera eye ruminating in isolation provides an insight into the terrors of the metropolis that the character featured in the fictions cannot hope to signal through his analogizing role. Yet by virtue of their very historicity, the protagonists of modernist fic tional autobiography are denied the capacity fully to enforce their views upon the reader. The peculiar rhetorical status of S tephen ' s aes thetic, for example, derives not merely from the questionable worth of the aesthetic itself but also from the etiolated interpretive force of the fiction in which it is presented. Where the eighteenth-century sense of the real proj ected a hesitant empiricism, its counterpart in the modernist fictional autobiography denies the epistemological prem ises of empiricism altogether, since the abstracting activity of the sub j ect now possesses only an incidental relation to the realm of the con crete. In the pseudofactual novel, the foregrounding and ironizing of the p erceiving subj ect's discourse reflected the configuration of a so ciety in which capital only partially controlled the labor proces s . In the modernist fictional autobiography, the position of the ego cogni tans is valorized, but as a locus of sensibility rather than as one of comprehension: capital is the social subj ect, and individual perceiving subj ects question their ability to propose cognition on the b asis of the empirical data they perceive. The uses of documentation in the metahistorical novel can also be seen as signaling the mediation of reification in the " real abstraction . " Where the realistic historical novel introduced empirical data to cor roborate its thematic statements , the metahistorical novel brings in historical documentation to highlight the provisional and indetermi nate nature of historical knowledge. Jack Burden thus is initially hampered by his obj ectivist desire to "know" Cass Mastern through "facts" rather than intuitive identification. Quentin and Shreve, de spite their superior imaginative synthesis, finally produce a version of the Sutpen story that is only a superior " fiction, " in Vaihinger's sense of the word. The realm of historical concretion is related only inci23 0
The Modernist Documentary Novel dentally to the abstractions by which historical processes can be de scribed. The introduction of historical data in the metahistorical novel thus serves to dislocate, rather than to reinforce, the reader' s perception of the protagonist a s a synecdochic type. Orlando i s de fined as a consciousness who discovers in aesthetic production a sta bility and continuity of ego denied by the fluid and peripheral nature of her/his particular historical incarnations. The Hegelian dialectic between abstraction and concretion that undergirded the representa tional strategy of the realistic historical novel has collapsed. Abstrac tion now supersedes a fragmented concretion, j ust as the telos of production as conception is severed from its execution as practical ac tivity. Telling the truth becomes difficult indeed when the teller sees all particular truths as variants on an undifferentiated facticity and sees the activity of telling itself as a praxis lacking a determinate sub j ect. In most documentary fiction of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, reification enables a new level of totalization, but it also pressures that totalization toward increasing autonomy and ahistoric ity. The documentary novel invokes facts to buttress its propositional claims, but these facts become more and more incidental to the gen eral truths that the text asserts . Abstraction is a curious phenomenon, however, for it is constituted by a contradiction between empirically based synthesis and fragmentation, between explanatory adequacy and opacity. The documentary novel routinely exemplifies this con tradiction, and its varying and conflicting claims to assertive power can thus be seen as signaling divergent tendencies within reification it self When the text does not simply take abstraction as an epistemo logical premise but instead treats it as an epistemological (and politi cal) problem (as in U. S . A . ) , the contradictory nature of abstraction is foregrounded, and empiricism becomes a means rather than a barrier to the representation of social reality. Ordinarily such oppositional texts are the exception rather than the rule. When a group of writers find themselves confronting abstraction in a particularly intrusive form, however, they generally cannot avoid its contradictory impli cations, and they together constitute an adversarial tradition that for mulates and practices distinct conventions for asserting mimetic truth. Racism constitutes one such form of abstraction, and Afro2J I
Practice American documentary novelists one such group of writers� In the closing chapter of this book, we shall consider the Afro-American documentary novel as an oppositional tradition that uses empiricism as a weapon against the abstractions that empiricism ordinarily vali dates.
23 2
8 The Afro-A merican Documentary Novel
Just as one sees when one walks into a medical research laboratory jars of alcohol containing abnormally large or distorted portions of the hu man body, just so did I see and feel that the conditions of life under which Negroes are forced to live in America contain the embryonic emotional prefiguration of how a large part of the body politic would react under stress. -Richard Wright
In the preceding chapters, I have set forth a model describing the principal changes in the documentary novel over the past three centuries and relating these changes to fundamental shifts in the mode of production. In this closing chapter, I shall treat a body of fiction, the Afro-American documentary novel, that invites me to test and reformulate - though not basically alter- my theoretical model. In my discussions of pseudofactual, historical, and modernist documen tary fiction, I have suggested that writers choose modes of documen tary corroboration that both articulate and confirm existing types of abstraction, both economic and conceptual- that, in short, writers reinforce dominant ideology. In my discussion of the Afro-American documentary novel, however, I shall argue that specific social and historical circumstances can set writers in opposition to dominant ideology. The generic contract accompanying most Afro-American documentary novels is situated in social circumstances that affect in far-reaching ways the procedures by which reality enters the fictional text. Even as writers use familiar strategies of fictional representation, they call into question various of the ideological premises routinely associated with these strategies of representation. Accordingly, the 23 3
Practice conceptual abstractions shaping the process of fiction-making repro duce but also query the " real abstraction" that the text represents . The Afro-American documentary novel continues to adopt the fa miliar representational strategies of realistic and modernist documen tary fiction, but it introduces documentation in ways that subvert rather than reinforce certain aspects of bourgeois hegemony. 1 In the Afro-American documentary novel, the two main types of documen tary validation - veracious and verifying - are characteristically blended. The effect of this documentary synthesis is a p owerful historicizing of the referent. Novels in the realistic mode proj ect ad ditional assurances that they tell a truth to which the author directly attests, and novels written in the modernist mode- both fictional autobiographies and metahistorical fictions - insistently remind us that their referents are historically specific. In the hands of the Afro A merican realistic novelist, the text' s claim to typicality ordinarily takes on oppositional force, for the bourgeois hero ' s status as a repre sentative of the key contradictions informing historical actuality is re placed by the Afro--American protagonist , who clearly possesses no favored status in the mind of the implied (usually white) reader. The empiricist claims of realism are therefore challenged even as they are employed: documentation functions not to authenticate an interpreta tion of reality that the reader is assumed to share but to probe certain assumptions - about race, history, social order- that the reader might hold to be self-evident. Similarly, the pseudofactual proj ection of a veracious voice takes on a distinctly adversarial quality in much Afro-American documentary fiction, since the reader's attention is continually fo cused upon the historical conditions that render its authenticating presence an apparent necessity. The text' s flouting of nonfictional discourse carries added significance when the reader is led to question whether the text's putative factual model could ever have been composed. The generic contract of the Afro-American documentary novel in its various modes is thus characterized by - to recall Rabinowitz's useful terms - a cautious amount of " assump tion" and a considerable amount of "assertion. " The proliferation of documentary materials testifies to the text's denial of an ideological a 1lt will be noted that, in the discussion that follows, I have cited a few white authors that is, Stowe, Tourgee, and Fast. I have included these writers because they directly con front the problem of racism and its representation, which is my central concern here. I do not mean to imply that they become honorary Afro-Americans by virtue of this fact. 234
The Afro-American Documentary Novel priori and to its insistence that its reconcretized analogous configura tion does indeed correspond to a real historical referent. The reasons for the documentary overdetermination of much Afro-American fiction are apparent: racism denies full subj ectivity to the black protagonist and full authority to the black author, so any text affirming such a subjectivity or such an authority necessarily requires the reader to engage in a (willing or unwilling) abolition of disbelief. The Afro-American documentary novel is vehement in its assertion of propositionality. I am not saying, of course, that the text therefore possesses an ideology-transcending propositional force. Recalling the Leninist conception of ideology as partisan discourse outlined in Chapter 4, I contend that the procedures of analogous configuration and ideological abstraction are as embedded in counter hegemonic mimetic works as they are in texts that proj ect proposi tions assimilable to dominant systems of belief. Both racism and anti racism, in other words, constitute ideological positions. Nor am I claiming that Afro-American documentary novels are in any sense contradiction-free; indeed, they frequently incorporate some aspect of dominant ideology as a secondary - at times, even, a primary aspect of ideological contradiction. I am simply asserting that, as a group , these documentary works are distinguished from the broader Anglo-American tradition by their persistent- and intentional foregrounding of contradiction in the referent. They continually p oint to the disj unction between theory and practice in A merican de mocracy; their own representational contradictions and constraints express limitations upon " representation" in social reality. In both re alistic and modernist works of Afro-American fiction, then, docu mentary validation calls attention to the epistemological relation be tween generalization and evidence, even as the texts purport to tell the truth about a reality that has too frequently been misrepresented or simply ignored. It is this insistent stress upon contradiction, rather than any supersession of contradiction, that enables us to speak of Afro-American documentary fiction as an adversarial tradition.
Racism, Emp iricism, and Representation In order to grasp the significance of the testimonial strategies pecu liar to Afro-American documentary fiction, it is necessary to establish 23 5
Practice the essential features of American racism as a social and historical phenomenon and to examine its relation to the epistemological and p olitical paradigms accompanying the growth of American capital ism . Racism is situated, I shall argue, in both the superstructure and the base of society;. it denotes attitudes and cultural practices , and it also denotes economic activities and political imperatives . The empir ical mode of thought has thus historically provided an important but tress to racist theory and practice, and democratic theories of p opular representation have posed no insuperable b arriers to the institutional operations of racism, either before or after the abolition of chattel slavery . Racism is a quintessential mode of abstraction, embodying both the imperatives of the real abstraction in capitalist society, as well as the conceptual formulations of human essence and p otential to which this real abstraction gives rise. Racism arid Empiricism Precapitalist social fo rmations had numerous ways of reinforcing and j ustifying social hierarchy, to be sure, and slavery flourished for thousands of years before the coming of capitalism. Racism as such is a creation of the capitalist epoch, however, originating in the colonial activities of mercantile capitalism . "At first the Spaniards and Portu guese j ust took over whatever kingdoms they could, and looted them , " Richard Popkin notes . " Then, when they were challenged, racial theories were worked out to j ustify the conquest and rape of America, and later the enslavement of Africa. "2 As Indians died off by the tens of thousands in the gold and silver mines of the New World, racial theorizing abandoned its "ideal speculations about the curious diversities of mankind" and took on increased practical im p ortance. The ensuing dispute over the morality of slavery o ccurred mainly in the domain of theology. When the more humanistic argu ments of De Las Casas and De la Vera Cruz lost out to those of Sepulveda, however, it is significant that the latter invoked nature as well as religion to j ustify the Spaniards' enslavement of the Indians . " Because of the gravity of their sins , " declared Sepulveda, and "be2Richard Popkin, " The Philosophical Bases of Modern Racism, " in Philosophy and the Civilizing Arts, ed. Craig Walton and John P . Anton (Athens: Ohio University Press, 1 974) , 1 2 8 . 23 6
The Afro-American Documentary Novel cause of the rudeness of their heathen and barbarous natures, " the In dians were obliged "to serve those of more elevated natures , such as the Spaniards possess. "3 As recent research into the history of slavery has shown, this sort of argument was distinctly characteristic of the emerging capitalist epoch. Various kinds of ethnocentrism and reli gious doctrine provided ideological j ustification to earlier forms of bondage, but the biological notion of race first supplements and later supplants these as colonial expansion makes it possible to enslave masses of peoples of color. 4 When capitalism shifted from its mercantile to its manufacturing and then to its industrial phase, the African slave trade figured promi nently in the primitive accumulation of capital. 5 "It was a common saying , " Eric Williams remarks, " that several of the principal streets of Liverpool had been marked out by the chains , and the walls of the houses cemented by the blood, of the African slaves. "6 The labor power that yielded up surplus value may therefore have been pur chased from white proletarians , but the capital that enabled the con struction of the factories and mills was largely drawn from the ex ploitation of slave labor. As Marx noted, The discovery of gold and silver in America, the extirpation, enslave ment and entombment in mines of the aboriginal population, the begin ning of the conquest and looting of the East Indies , the turning of Africa into
a warren
fo r the commercial hunting of black-skins , signalised the
'Gaines de Sepulveda, cited in Oliver C . Cox, Caste, Class, and Race: A Study in Social Dynamics (New York: Monthly Review, 1959), 3 3 4. 4For more on the relation of slavery to different ideological paradigms, including mod ern notions of race, see D avid Brion Davis, The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1 964) , and William McKee Evans, " From the Land of Canaan to the Land of Guinea: The Strange Odyssey of the ' Sons of Ham, "' American Historical Re view, 85 (February 1 9 80) : 1 5 - 43 . 'There is a heated debate among scholars of slavery about the precise nature of the rela tion b etween the institution of chattel slavery in the Americas and the political economies of merchant and industrial capitalism. Williams argues that slavery was crucial to the primi tive accumulation needed for industrialization and that merchant capital actively aided in this process. Elizabeth Fox-Genovese and Eugene Genovese, by contrast, agree that "the slaveholders arose on the foundations of merchant capitalism, " but they argue that mer chant capital was a "parasitic" and "passive" phenomenon that actually impeded the devel opment of industrial capitalism. See Fruits ofMerchant Capital: Slave ry and Bourgeois Property in the Rise and Expansion of Cap italism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1 9 8 3 ) , 1 5 - 1 6 and passim. 6Eric Williams, Cap italism and Slavery ( 1 944; New York: Capricorn, 1 966) , 63 . 23 7
Practice rosy dawn of the era of capitalist production. These idyllic proceedings are the chief momenta o f p rimitive accumulation . 7
As capital modernized its methods of exploitation, the grounds of the arguments j ustifying bondage on the basis of race were unabashedly shifted from the Bible to biology. In the seventeenth century the term " A frican" denoted merely geographical origin, similar to " Irish" or " S co ttish" ; in the eighteenth, it came to denote physical traits and ra cial essence. 8 Various Enlightenment thinkers produced elaborate taxonomies linking "higher" and "lower" racial types to various en vironmental determinants. Linnaeus , for example, decided that the climate had produced in Africans an "indolent, negligent" nature that was "governed by caprice, " and in Europeans an " acute and inven tive" nature that was " governed by laws . "9 Hume, who claimed that he was applying " the experimental method of reasoning to moral subj ects , " p roclaimed that " there never was a civilized nation of any complexion other than white. "10 On the basis of this incontroverti ble evidence - gleaned, it would seem, from an " experiment" per formed in his own " reasoning" mind- Hume concluded that " such a uniform and constant difference could not happen in so many coun tries and ages, if nature had not made an original distinction betwixt these breeds of men . " George Fredrickson has shown that in the eighteenth century such blatantly racist pronouncements were gener ally adduced to j ustify an essentially paternalistic view of race rela tions . The more " a cute" were the keepers of the "indolent . " Even the mechanistic materialism of the environmentalist theories of race pro vided a kind of safety valve: presumably changes in climate would produce changes in phenotype, since these were not coded into the genes . 1 1 7Marx, Cap ital: A Critique of Political Economy, ed. Frederick Engels, trans . Samuel Moore and Edward Avel.ing (New York: International, 1 967) , 1 :75 r . 8See Lerone Bennett, The Shaping of Black America (Chicago: Johnson, 1 97 5 ) , and Gary Nash, Red, White, and Black : The Peoples ofEarly America (Englewood Cliffs : Prentice-Hall, 1 974) . 9Linnaeus (Karl von Linne) , A General System of Nature through the Three Grand Kingdoms of Animals, Vegetables, and Minerals ( 1 7 5 8 ; London, 1 806) , 1 : " Mammalia . Order I, Pri mates . " 10David Hume, "Of National Characters, " in The Philosophical Works, ed. T . H. Greer and T . H . Grose (London, 1 8 82) , 3 :2 5 2n. 1 1George Fredrickson, The Black Image in the White Mind: The Debate on A.fro-American Character and Destiny, 1 8.r 7- I9I4 (New York: Harper & Row, 1 9 7 1 ) , chap . 3 , passim. 23 8
The Afro-American Documentary Novel Europeans developed the initial j ustifications for modern racism . In the United States , however, racist practice gained the surest foothold and biological theories of racial difference received the fullest articula tion; the compulsion of African slave labor provided the foundation of fortunes accumulated in the American colonies . Originally uti lizing the labor of both black and white indentured servants, the planters found it difficult to control their workers in a territory where labor was in such great demand. "The Americas presented entrepre neurs not only with their greatest opportunities, " remarks William McKee Evens, "but also with their most acute problem: how to per suade people to work for bare subsistence in mines and on plantations located in a country of ' open resources, ' where there was an abun dance of land often free for the taking? How could entrepreneurs control other people's impulse to ' get ahead' in a land of boundless opportunity? " 12 The plantation owners went a long way toward solving this problem when they designated for permanent servitude one segment of the work force that was readily identifiable on the ba sis of color. Not only did this measure guarantee them a supply of controllable labor, but it also blunted the edge of white rebellion. White servants, apprentices and laborers had to be taught that blacks were not their natural allies (as Lerone B ennett has pointed out, it took one hundred years of legislation, religious exhortation, and cor poral punishment to get the message across) , 13 but once taught, these whites could prove a valuable buffer for the plantation class . Even though N orth American chattel slavery was an anachronism and an anomaly, then, for many decades it was compatible with the growth of capitalism in the United States and in fact became increasingly im plicated in the global market of the nineteenth century . As H. Bruce Franklin notes, slavery successfully changed " from a predominantly small-scale, quasi-domestic institution appended to hand-tool farm ing and manufacturing" into the productive base of "an expanding agricultural economy, utilizing machinery to process the harvested crops and pouring vast quantities of agricultural raw materials, prin cipally cotton, into developing capitalist industry in the Northern states and England. "14 12Evans, 42. 13Bennett, 6 1 - 80. 14H. Bruce Franklin, " Animal Farm Unbound; or, What the Narrative of the Life of Frederick Douglass, An American Slave, Reveals about American Literature, " New Letters, 43 (April 1 977) : 3 1 - 3 2 . 23 9
Practice With the expansion of slavery to the vast cotton plantations of what was then the Southwest, the planters abandoned their earlier stance of protective paternalism and invoked more aggressive argu ments of biological superiority. Thomas Jefferson, whose Notes on the State of Virginia exemplifies the transitional phase between patriarchal and biological theories of race, declared, "I advance it therefore as a suspicion only, that the blacks, whether originally a distinct race, or made distinct by time and circumstances, are inferior t o whites in the endowments both of body and mind. "15 The founders of the new pseudosciences of ethnology and craniology were not so hesitant in their proclamations , particularly when slavery apologists were faced with the threat of abolition . The famous biologist Louis Agassiz en dorsed a p olygenetic theory of human development, holding that blacks had a racial origin wholly separate from that of whites. George Gliddon, in his Cmnia Americana and Crania Aegyp tica, "proved" by means of skull measurements that the ancient Egyptians had been white and that Caucasians had a demonstrably larger cranial capacity than Africans. Josiah Nott, who explicitly set forth the connection between racist pseudoscience and the cause of the plantation holders, said that " ethnology" was really "niggerology . " Samuel Cartwright diagnosed the slave's tendency to run away as " drapetomania. " When skull measurements and charts of genetic origin could be adduced as empirical evidence, how could anyone question whether the enslaved Africans were suited for their condition? By the mid-nineteenth century, the anomalous features of Ameri can chattel slavery p roved incompatible with modern industrial capi talism, and the Civil War ensued. But when, after Emancipation, the entire national economy came under the sway of Northern business, racism remained central to the expansion of capital and the control of the work force. For decades, Black laborers were restricted to sharecropping, domestic labor, and the most menial industrial j obs; whatever multiracial movements of resistance arose among rank and file farmers and wage laborers were viciously suppressed. 16 Contem p orary studies of the economics of racism reveal that even in the af termath of the Civil Rights movement, the further exploitation of racial minorities continues to yield high profits, to hold down the 15Thomas Jefferson, Notes on the State of Virginia (Baltimore: Pechin, 1 800) , 1 5 5 . 16See C . Vann Woodward, The Strange Career ofJim Crow, 3d rev. ed. (New York: Ox ford University Press, 1 974) .
The Afro-American Documentary N o vel wages of whites, and above all to create social and political divisions that seriously impair the possibility of united working-class opposi tion to monopoly capital. 17 Evans has commented, Wherever color prej u dice has been reinforced by the profit motive, wherever relations with the blacks have been conditioned not only by face to face contact but also by the pressure of distant and impersonal markets , white prej udices have taken on such an immediacy, a consis tency, a neurotic intensity that a number of s cholars have understanda bly mistaken this attitude for an " irrational" psychological phenome non, rather than a discrete historical one. 18
Furthermore, ethnology and skull measuring have passed into the ar chives of myth, but contemporary racist ideology, invoking the " data" of IQ tests, continues to cloak itself in the mantle of empiri cism. In short, racism is systematically integral to the social relations of capitalism and cannot be examined as a sociological or psychologi cal phenomenon without attention to its foundation in the production and exchange for profit. It should be argued that, rather than being an unfortunate stain upon the record of bourgeois liberalism, racism has furnished a - if not the-principal means by which the American rul ing class has gained and maintained its position of dominance. Racism and Representation Racism enj oys a paradoxical relation to the basic premises of bour geois theories of representation. It would appear that a social system founded upon the principle that all men are created equal could only with difficulty enforce practices and espouse theories aiming at the systematic subjugation of entire portions of the human species . Surely, it would seem, the Homo economicus is sufficiently abstract to allow for variations in pigmentation of the skin. B ourgeois politi cal theory has proven quite resourceful in confronting this dilemma, however. Locke, for example, held that " the NATURAL liberty of man is to be free from any superior power on earth, and not to be under the will or legislative authority of man, but to have only the law of nature for his rule. " 19 He also contended, however, that, if a man has 17See, for example, Victor Perlo, The Economics of Racism U. S . A . : The Roots of Black Ine quality (New York: International, 1 975) . 18Evans, 43 . 19Locke, An Essay Concerning the True Original Extent and End of Civil Government ( 1 690) ,
24 I
Pra c ti c e "by his own fault forfeited his own life by some act that deserves death, he to whom he has forfeited it may . . . make use of him in his own service. " Such positions may not seem compatible with the mass enslavement of Africans, who were, surely, hardly accountable for heinous crimes deserving death. In his capacity as drafter of the con stitution of the Carolinas, however, Locke produced a theory that would j ustify the peculiar relation of freedom to unfreedom in the colonies . Popkin observes that Locke saw the Indians and Africans as failing to mix their labors with the land, and thus failing to create property as an extension of their persons . Hence they had no property as their natural right due to their own fail ing s . The y also had properly lost their liberty " b y some Act that de serves Death" (presumably opposing the Europeans) and hence could be enslaved. Their lands were wastelands . The E uropeans were there fore j u s tified in turning them into property and enslaving the resis
tors . 20
Apparently the Homo economicus did not enter into the social con tract on an equal basis with all comers ; certain assumptions about property, nationality, and social custom were a prerequisite to partic ipation in the contract- and, when it became necessary, these could very conveniently be linked with race. The republican egalitarianism of the colonial ideologists could therefore readily encompass the institution of slavery; it is, indeed, one of the ironies accompanying the contradictions of American his tory that colonial democratic political platforms took as their opera tional premise the forced bondage of Africans . As Edmund Morgan has argued, it is no accident that Virginia, which had outstripped the other colonies in extending property rights to former indentured ser vants and in color-coding the division of labor, articulated the most radically democratic platform for independence: Aristocrats would more easily preach equality in
a slave society than in a
free one. Slaves did not become unruly mobs , because their owners would see to it that they had no chance to . . . . [Slavery] was . . . the so-
in The English Philosophers .from Bacon to Mill, ed. Edwin A . Burtt (New York: Modern Li brary, 1 9 3 9) , 409. The pacssage quoted below is from p. 4 1 0. 20Popkin, l J J .
The Afro-American Documentary Novel lution to one of society ' s most serious problems , the problem of the poor. Virginians could outdo English republicans as well as Northeast ones , partly because they had solved the problem: they had achieved society in which most of the poor were enslaved. 21
a
D emocracy for some necessitated bondage for others . Doctor John son should not have been so shocked when he exclaimed, "How is it that we hear the loudest yelps for liberty among the drivers of ne groes?"22 Even since the Civil War, racism has continued to justify limitations on representation, and biological theories of inequality have proven especially suited to the democratic form of the state prevalent in the capitalist era. In precapitalist social formations, rulers adduced such overtly idealist j ustifications as church doctrine or the chain of being to legitimate their own positions of hegemony. In the capitalist era, however, the realities of economic compulsion are masked by the " freedom" of the marketplace, and inequality in social relations is ob scured by " equality" before the law. In order to account for the ensuing contradiction between economic hierarchy and political de mocracy, capitalist apologists have been compelled to resort to causal accounts that would locate an individual's- or a group 's- failure to succeed in intrinsic physical essences, rather than in the structural in equities of capital itself. Racist ideology thus constitutes a logical extension and refinement of the conceptual abstractions embedded in classical bourgeois episte mology and political theory: in invoking "factual" validation, racist ideology points to the entrapment of empiricism within the apriorism of its unexamined social presuppositions . Where Locke and Hobbes take nature as a metaphysical point of departure, ignoring the histori cal process that leads the Homo economicus to be constituted by property as an emblem of human essence, racist theory develops the implications of this attribution of social position to an inborn nature. The notion that some people are "other" is indeed the epitome of ob j ectification, revealing how one person's (really, one group 's) self hood hinges upon the abolition of another' s humanity. Racism offers a self-fulfilling prophecy: a people's position within the social forma21Edmund S . Morgan, American Slavery, American Freedom : The Ordeal of Colonial Vir ginia (New York: Norton, 1 9 7 5 ) , 3 80- S r . 22Quoted in Davis, 3 . 243
Practice tion is construed to be founded in that people' s nature, and " data " from that nature are then offered as proof of their suitability for their condition. People become things - literally so, when commodified as slaves- and the conceptual paradigms describing their nature posit their necessary status as obj ects rather than subj ects of historical pro ces s .
Documentation in A.fro-American Realism If racism reduces the subj ect to an exemplar of a degraded collectiv ity, antiracism proclaims the integrity of both the individual and the group . Indeed, individual identity cannot be secured without a for mulation and a defense of group identity. As William Fischer notes, Wh ereas the traditional expectation of the novel reader is, in general, the representation of one or a few characters whose unique personal qualities are gradually revealed in an extended fictional dramatization - the concept of the
bildungsroman
is the critical basis for this expecta
tion- the most striking Afro-American [novels] place the emphasis upon a representa tive man, one whose singular identity is less impor tant to the author's purpose than the protagonist's representative or composite identity. 23
In Afro-American realism, this conception of " the protagonist ' s rep resentative or composite identity" produ ces two traits that distin guish Afro-American texts from the mainstream tradition. First, the postulation of typicality assumes a subversive quality: instead of con firming, analogous configuration disputes deep-seated assumptions about the nature of the social totality and who is eligible to represent it. Second, the text frequently assumes a picaresque quality, for its goal of rendering an encyclopedic portraiture of its referent comes into conflict with realism' s tendency to resolve and defuse the contra dictions informing its referent. The episodic format of the fugitive slave narrative thus enj oys an enduring popularity in novels from Martin Delany's Blake to Ralph Ellison's Invisible Man. Totalization involves a recognition of the irreconcilability of some of the text ' s 23William C . Fischer, "The Aggregate Man i n Jean Toomer's Cane, " Studies i n the Novel, 3 (Summer 1 9 7 1 ) : 7.
2 44
The Afro-American Documentary Novel represented conflicts, and resolution is achieved when such irrecon cilability has been exhaustively depicted. Abolitionist Documentary Fiction
.
Abolitionist novelists invoked the generic contract of the realistic novel for expressly political purposes: the typical hero was intended to stand at the center of social forces representing the key issues facing the abolitionist movement. For example, William Wells Brown, the first Afro-American novelist, centered the plot of Clotel; or, The Pres ident's Daughter around the fate of the supposed slave daughter of Thomas Jefferson and introduced a range of characters who encapsule different types of slave experience. Although Brown ascribed some heroic features to his dark-skinned male protagonist, he gave central significance to the tragic figure of his female mulatto, indicating his own preoccupation with the particular oppression suffered by the light-skinned offspring of slave owners. Harriet Beecher Stowe, in Uncle Tom 's Cabin; or, Life among the Lowly , delineated a vast social canvas also intended to encompass the entire institution of slavery, from its most benign case in the St. Clare household to its most brutal enact t?.ent on the plantation of Simon Legree. Her designation of Uncle Tom as a typical protagonist articulated her belief that the cause of the slaves was best represented by a hero combining stoical dignity with Christian forbearance. Directing realistic typicality and comprehensiveness toward more radical ends than either B rown or Stowe, Martin Delany, in Blake; or, The Huts of America, took his hero on a tour of the Southern states and Cuba to outline for the reader the seething unrest of the antebellum South. In contrast with Stowe's Uncle Tom, Delany' s rebellious hero, Blake/Henry, stub bornly rej ects passive stereotypes in his claim to typical status. In deed, Blake/Henry was constructed in explicit contradistinction to Stowe's portraits of blacks; as one critic has noted, D elany openly " resented Mrs . Stowe's prominence as an interpreter of the Afro-American slave experience to both whites and blacks, " and he offered the fate of his protagonist as " the antithesis to Mrs. Stowe ' s picture of . . . slave docility, Christian endurance and Liberia a s the destination of the successful fugitive slave. "24 24Floyd J . Miller, introduction to Martin D elany, Blake; or, The Huts ofAmerica (Boston: Beacon, 1 970) , xx. 24 5
Practice Where most contemporaneous works of realistic social cnt1c1sm (for example, Bleal� House) invoked generic contracts hinging upon straightforward fictional representation, the abolitionist novelists routinely underlined their claims to truthful representation b y includ ing corroborative materials that testify to the texts' verifiability . B y appending this apparatus, the abolitionist novelists were n o t simply aping the practice of S cott or Cooper, nor were they mobilizing con ventions of pseudofactual truth-telling from the century before. Rather, they were grafting onto their novels a convention peculiar to the slave narrative, namely, the practice of prefacing the accounts of escaped slaves with testimonials to the texts' accuracy as portraits of the evils of slavery. Thus , Lydia Maria Child began Linda Brent' s In cidents in the Life of a Slave Girl with the assurance that the author of the following autobiography "is personally known to me, and her conversation and manners inspire me with confidence . . . . Those who know her will not be disposed to doubt her veracity, though some incidents in her story are more romantic than fiction. " 25 Wen dell Phillips declared that Frederick Douglass's Narrative of the Life of an A merican Slave, Written by Himself gives " a fair specimen of the whole truth , " representing "no incidental aggravations, no individual ills, but such as must mingle always and necessarily with the lot of every slave. " 26 S towe was invoking this kind of authority when, in her preface to the European edition of Uncle Tom 's Cabin, she re sponded to attacks on the book's accuracy: It has b een said that the representations of this book are exag gerations ! and oh would that this were true! Would that this book were indeed a fiction; and not a close wrought mosaic of facts ! but that it is not a fic tion the proofs lie bleeding in thousands of hearts - they have been at tested and confirmed by thousands of witnesses in the slave s tate s ; they have b een endorsed b y slaveholders themselves ! with express reference to this book. 27
25Lydia Maria Child, preface to Linda Brent, Incidents in the Life of a Slave Girl, ed. Lydia Maria: Child ( 1 8 6 1 ; New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1 9 73 ) , xi. 26Wendell Phillips, preface to Frederick Douglass, Narrative of the Life of Frederick Doug lass, An American Slave, Written by Himself, ed. Benj amin Quarles (Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1 960) , 1 8 - 1 9 . 27Harriet Beecher Stowe, Uncle Tom 's Cabin; or, Life among the Lowly, e d . John A . Woods ( 1 8 5 2; Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1 96 5 ) , !xi. F o r more on Stowe's sources - especially her use ofJosiah Henson's autobiography- see Robin Winks's preface to Four Fugitive Slave Narratives (Reading : Addison-Wesley, 1 969) .
The Afro-American Documentary Novel In addition, in 1 8 5 3 Stowe published a collection of documentary ma terials entitled "A Key to Uncle Tom's Cabin . . . Presenting the Original Facts and Documents Upon Which the Story Is Founded, " in which she made available to the reader the " mosaic of facts" that validated the truth-telling claims of her narrative. Apparently Stowe felt that analogous configuration alone could not convey the text' s propositions . I f the novel could not assume full powers o f generaliza tion, the author would introduce the empirical materials that would ground its assertions in a reality to which the reader would be com pelled to give assent. Delany rejected such a testimonial procedure in Blake, which as serts its analogous configuration with a good deal more confidence. Nonetheless, he conceded something to the reader's presumed need for verification when he sprinkled the text with footnotes testifying to the sociological accuracy-at times , indeed, to the exact historical truth-of the incidents recorded in the text . Thus, one note informs the reader that the footnoted episode describes "a real incident which took place between a slave and a free black. "28 Another note states that a presumably fictional character "had really $2, 000 in gold, se curely hid away unknown to any person but his wife, until showing it to the writer. " The effect of Delany' s notes is to anchor the text's propositions in an actuality that is vouched for by personal testi mony. To be sure, this mode of authentication somewhat resembles that practiced by Cooper in The Pioneers . But Cooper, who comes from the landholding family that gave its name to Cooperstown, is in a position very different from Delany's when he declares that his ac count of Judge Temple's (William Cooper's) beneficence is "literally true. " Cooper provides a private assurance, but it carries public reso nance; Delany, by contrast, speaks from a position of anonymity when he assaults the legitimacy of William Cooper's Southern ana logues . He must validate the very facts that would validate his novel's generalized assertions about brutalities in the antebellum South. Brown's mode of documentation highlighted the problems that Delany kept literally to the margins of his text. In the first edition of Clotel, Brown prefaced the text with a lengthy "Narrative of the Life and Escape of William Wells Brown, " in which the author not only cited book reviews testifying to the favorable reception of his previ28Delany, 8 5 , 84. 24 7
Practice ously published slave autobiography but also related a number of fac tual episodes that reappear in the fictional tale that immediately fol".' lows . The result is a curious sort of dej a vu: the text provides the reader with the raw materials utilized in its own construction, and the correspondence of mimesis to historical actuality is unmistakably as sured. Brown's documentary materials thus constantly signal the au thor's need to guarantee the credibility of his description of slave life. "I have personally participated in many of these scenes, " Brown sol emnly attests . " Some of the narratives I have derived from other sources; many from the lips of those who, like myself, have run away from the land of bondage. "29 Brown's claim-omitted in later edi tions of the novel- that Jefferson was indeed the father of Clotel thus takes shape as a charge possessing more than typical appropriateness; the reader is led to query the possible historicity of the assertion, since so many of the tale's propositions carry the ring of authority. 30 Abolitionist novels also reveal their indebtedness to the model of the fugitive slave narrative by their frequent replication of its seg mented and rambling structure, which conveyed the text's indict ment of slavery by the unrelenting accumulation of its vignettes. The rather sprawling plot sequence of Uncle Tom 's Cabin enabled a many fronted assault upon the institution of slavery; what the novel lost in tightness of plot and character development it recovered in the breadth of its social survey. Blake, which features an even more dis j unctive story line, surveyed quite a remarkable number of locales, from Mississippi to Arkansas to Cuba. Clotel illustrates the extent to which the abolitionist documentary novelist utilized the picaresque structure of the slave autobiography more than the standard plot structures of realism. In the novel's final revised version, published after the Civil War (Clotelle; or, The Coloured Heroine), Brown de cided to rescue Clotelle from Clotel's tragic suicide, appending in stead four final chapters that take his preserved heroine through the Civil War and deposit her in a Freedman's School, where she happily 29William Wells Brown, Clotel; or, The President's Daughter: A Narrative of Slave Life in the United States ( 1 8 53 ; New York: Arno, 1 969) , 244. 30For more on Brown's allegations concerning Jefferson and on the different versions of Clotel, see W. Edward Farrison, "Clotel, Thomas Jefferson, and Sally Hemings, " College Language Association Journal, 1 7 (December 1 973 ) : 1 47- 74; W. Edward Farrison, William Wells Brown, Author and Reformer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 969) ; and). Noel Heermance, William We.lls Brown and Clotelle: A Portrait of the Artist in the First Negro Novel (Hamden, Conn. : Archon, 1 969) .
The Afro-American Documentary Novel presides as an "Angel of Mercy. " Clearly, Clotelle's life was intended to encompass as broad a range of significant social experience as pos sible. When this experience needed to be altered in accordance with historical changes in the text's referent, Brown felt no qualms about tailoring his narrative to suit new ideological requirements . One ver sion' s tragic traj ectory was another version's path to comic fulfill ment; Aristotelian dynamis was less important than externally di rected social commentary. The unremittingly episodic structure of most abolitionist docu mentary novels reveals something about the premises of the generic contract that the abolitionist author invoked. The hero's destiny was intended to illustrate social trends and conflicts, but it was not con ceived as a synecdochic reconciliation of these trends and conflicts. Rather, in the frequent arbitrariness of its conclusion, the abolitionist novel proposed that the conditions for formal completeness and clo sure were dictated by extratextual as well as textual considerations: the text's attempt to construct an analogy to the historical world was constrained by the very intensity of the contradictions informing that world. These contradictions urgently required mimetic representa tion , yet they tested the limits of realism; the explanatory require ments of totalization found themselves at odds with the conventional gravitation toward resolution. 31 The text could not proj ect a concre tion of the Hegelian World Spirit when such a concretion had not occurred in historical actuality: the very real limitations upon resolu tion in the referent carried structural consequences for the strategy of representation. Realism takes as its referent the fate of a bourgeois hero whose career encapsules the arc of national destiny; even when that career calls into question the integrity of that destiny, the generic contract assumes their representational equivalence. Clearly such a generic contract would be invoked only ambivalently by abolitionist novelists, who were treating both a historical experience that belied the most fundamental principles espoused in bourgeois political the ory and a people whose very existence in the nation was acknowl edged by the legal designation of " three-fifths . " 31The extant text of Blake is incomplete; the closing chapters, which presumably follow the rebellion to its termination, have yet to be discovered. This circumstance does not alter my argument, however; no imaginable resolution could alter the essentially picaresque structure of the novel, whidt achieves a sense of fullness primarily through the additive ac cumulation of rhetorically powerful episodes. 2 49
Practice While some works of abolitionist documentary fiction exhibit at times a tenuous control over their extensive testimonial apparatus, Herman Melville's "Benito Cereno" exemplifies the powerful rhetor ical effects that were possible for the writer working with heavily overdetermined documentary materials . 32 Based upon the actual memoir of one Captain Amasa Delano, who encountered off the coast of Chile a slave ship that had been commandeered by bondsmen in revolt, Melville' s microcosmic fictional representation presents a trio of characters who together set forth the central ideological and political contradictions informing a society based upon slavery. Thus Delano - alternately confused, condescending, and frightened stands forth as an exemplar of the Northern liberal racist whose imagination cannot admit the selfhood, much less the typicality, of the captured Africans . The decadent Cereno, with his pale mien and artificially stiffened scabbard, typifies the self-pitying Southern aris tocrat, who is ultimately destroyed by his own irrational fear of the abstracted specter of "the Negro . " The inscrutable Baba, whose un usually large skulll implicitly refutes the craniological arguments to which the naive Delano half-consciously subscribes, emerges as both the obj ect and the subj ect of racist abstraction: deprived of a voice in 32The determination of Melville's stance on racism and slavery in "Benito Cereno" has occasioned extensive co ntroversy. For the argument that Melville adopts a racist perspec the tive, see Sidney Kaplan, " Homer, Melville, and American National Sin: The Meaning of 'Benito Cereno,"' Journal of Negro History, 4 1 (October 1 956): 3 u - 3 8 , and 42 (January 1 9 5 7) : l r - 3 7 . For the opposing argument, see Sterling Stuckey and Joshua Leslie, "Babo -Th e Negro a s Hero , ' ' forthcoming, and Carolyn K. Karcher, Shadow over the Promised Land: Slavery and Violence in Melville 's America (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1 980) . Stuckey and Leslie have recently recovered from a Chilean archive further documents relating to the historical incident upon which Melville's tale was based. Some of these letters and court transcripts reveal that, in response to the Africans' takeover of the Tryal (the San Dominic!: in "Benito Cereno"), greater security precautions were legislated on all Spanish slave ships. Others contain the quite significant information that Amasa Delano agreed to rescue the Tryal from the Africans only after Cereno promised him half the value of the ship ' s cargo and that Cereno subsequently reneged on his end of the deal. Only after a bitter controversy, in which members of the crew of the Perseverance (Bachelor's Delight) testified to the brutality - and financial desperation-of their captain, did Delano finally secure some compensation, although not all that he had demanded. It is interesting to speculate about the way in which Melville may have used these materials in his character izations of the Spanish and Yankee captains; it is certainly possible that he saw the docu ments, since he clearly had access to the trial transcript. An excerpted version of these docu ments is forthcoming in Modern Philology, with a preface by Stuckey and Leslie. For further evidence that Melville :;atirizes racist pseudoscience in "Benito Cereno, " see also his short story, "The ' Gees , " in Great Short Works of Herman Melville (New York: Harper & Row, 1 966) , 3 5 5 - 6 1 . 250
The Afro-American Documentary Novel the narration, he nonetheless controls the majority of the action and emphatically represents an explosive potentiality. As a parable pro phetically prefiguring the historical conflicts of the 1 8 50s, "Benito Cereno" incorporates its characters into an analogous configuration inviting determinate evaluation; Melville's tale may be based upon the first-person account of Delano, but it transforms this raw material into an interpretive fiction requiring decisive judgment on the part of the reader. Melville invited scrutiny of the evidence by which dominant ideol ogy justifies itself, moreover, by appending to the main portion of his narrative a detailed testimony derived in large part from the actual transcript of the rebels' trial; a posteriori, the mimetic representation is grounded in an empirically specified historical reality. This docu mentary material- does not simply corroborate the text' s status as a replication of real historical events, however; it also provides a satiric commentary upon the very pretense of legal-and empirical- neu trality, since the testimony accepted by the court is, of course, that of Benito Cereno. The authenticating voice of the corroborative appara tus designs the official version of the "facts" that will constitute the historical record; the self-evidence of the data proclaims not the legiti macy but the savagery of the Africans ' revolt. Melville's use of cor roborative materials not only reinforces the felt historicity of the ref erent (as in the works of Stowe, Delany, and Brown) but also shows how empiricism reconstructs that referent for political purposes . His tale is true, but not neutrally so; to tell Babo's story is not to tell Benito Cereno's story, much less that of Captain Delano. Afro-American Documentary Realism since the Civil War In treating Reconstruction and the new forms of racism that fol lowed in its wake, documentary novelists continued to make use of an extensive testimonial apparatus. In A Fool's Errand, for example, Albion Tourgee adopted an anonymous posture and presented his radical account of the attack upon Reconstruction as the discourse of a quixotic fool. He ironically declared in his preface, "The one merit which the story claims is that of honest, uncompromisi ng truthful ness of portraiture. Its pictures are from life. And even in this which he boasts as a virtue may be found, perhaps, the greatest folly yet 25 1
Practice committed by ONE OF THE FOOLS . "33 Faced with the barrage of criti cism that greeted the first edition of the novel, Tourgee included in subsequent editions a lengthy appendix entitled " The Invisible Em pire. " Here, citing eyewitness accounts and the records of senatorial investigations, he meticulously corroborated his historical allegations about the Ku Klux Klan's plot to undermine Reconstruction. Perhaps significantly, in these later editions Tourgee cast aside the mantle of anonymity and acknowledged his authorship; the full irony of his self-designation as "one of the fools " who supported Reconstruction was reinforced by his careful documentation of the forces of reaction aligned in opposition. He apparently felt comfortable with claiming authorship only when his novel presented itself as more than a gener alized interpretive commentary. Where in most realistic fictions, as we have seen, the sense of the real is incompatible with the strategy of realism, here verifiability underlines rather than undermines the text's attempt to tell the truth. Frances Harper, less bent upon either political education or precise verification than was Tourgee, included a note at the end of her Iola Leroy in which she� reinforced the moral of her Civil War romance: From the threads of fact and fiction I have woven a story whose mission will not be in vain if it awakens in the hearts of our countrymen a stronger sense of justice and a more Christlike humanity in b ehalf of those whom the fortunes of war threw homeless , ignorant and poor upon the threshold of a new era. Nor will it be in vain if it inspire the children of those upon whose brows God has poured the chrism of that new era to determine that they will embrace every opportunity, devote every faculty, and use every power God has given them to rise in the scale of character and condition, and to add their quota of good citizen ship to the best welfare of the nation. 34
Harper' s decision to append this guarantee of truthfulness reveals a certain anxiety about the generic contract she has invoked. She in33Albion Tourgee, ii. Fool's Errand, ed. John Hope Franklin (Cambridge: B elknap, 1 96 1 ) , 6 - 7 . 34Frances E. W. Harper, Iola Leroy; or, Shadows Uplifted, 2d e d . ( 1 892; College Park, Md. : McGrath, 1 969) , 282. For more on authenticating devices in late nineteenth-century and early twentieth-century Afro-American fiction, see Arlene A. Elder, The Hindered Hand: Cultural Implications of Early African-American Fiction (Westport: Greenwood, 1 978), esp. 4 1 - 43 .
252
The Afro-American Documentary Novel tends her story to convey highly moral generalizations, generaliza tions that will instruct both whites and blacks about their ethical re sponsibilities in the new era, yet she lacks confidence in the power of analogous configuration to persuade her readers of their duties hence her hortatory use of the testimonial apparatus . Presumably her assurances that there are " threads of fact" in her fictive fabric will in crease the probability that her readers will attend to her plea. In Hanover; or, The Persecution of the Lowly, Jack Thorne (David Bryant Fulton) exposed the brutal racism that still prevailed nearly half a century after Stowe had subtitled her Uncle Tom 's Cabin "Life among the Lowly. " Thorne presented a ' fictionalized retelling of the Wilmington massacre of 1 8 9 8 (when the entire black population of Wilmington, North Carolina, was attacked by racist vigilantes incited by local Democratic politicians) and added a battery of doc umentary materials . He first cited the Associated Press Market Re port that gave the official version of the facts: "With the killing of the Negroes yesterday the backbone of the trouble seems to have been broken. The authors of the tragedy have gone to their homes and the mob has disbanded as if in contempt of the gangs of Negroes who still hang about in the black quarters growling and threatening the whites . "35 Taking issue with this description of the "authors of the tragedy, " Thorne composed a prefatory protest: It h a s always been the rule with mobs t o vilify their victims, assail their characters in the most shameful manner in justification of their murder. But an attack upon the character and integrity of the Negroes of Wil mington, in order to jus tify the massacre of November 1 0th, shall not go unchallenged. If what I write should raise a howl of protest and call another ex-Governor Northern to Boston to brand it as a lie, it is never theless a truthful statement of the causes that led up to the doings of the 1 0th of November, and although I shall fictitiously name some of the star actors in this tragedy and the shifters of the scenes , I can call them all by their names
and point them
out. It will be proven that the massa
cre of November 1 0th, 1 89 8 , had been carefully planned by the leading wealthy citizens of Wilmington.
Thorne' s documentation serves an interesting function. On the one hand, Hanover is clearly a fiction, with its scenic dramatization and 35Jack Thome, Hanover; or, The Persecution of the Lowly (New York: Amo, New York Times, 1 969) , 3. I quote below from p . r o . 2 53
Practice psychological interiorization, and its factual apparatus reinforces the text's generalized status as a challenge to the Associated Press ' s " at tack upon the character and integrity of the Negroes of Wilmington. " On the other hand, Thorne proposes that his reconcretization is an unmediated replication of its referent: it is a "truthful statement. " Thorne assigns a privileged veracious status to his mimetic represen tation because the j ournalism of the dominant class denies the truth: fictive discourse must step in to tell the truth when nonfictional dis course lies . Sutton Griggs, also writing in the grim years of the Jim Crow era, explored the limits of documentary overdetermination in his The Hindered Hand; or, The Reign of the Repressionist. In his preface, he re marked that "in no part of the book has the author done violence to conditions as he has been permitted to view them";36 in his " Notes for the Serious " at the end of the text, he cited the factual basis for various fictionalized characters and incidents . Like Tourgee, Griggs clearly felt it necessary to point out that his typical characters did in deed represent a broad range of experience, unknown as this experi ence may have been to most readers . In the third edition of the novel, moreover, Griggs went so far as to remove a debate between fictional characters and to append it instead as "A Hindering Hand, Supple mentary to The Hindered Hand: A Review of the Anti-Negro Crusade of Mr. Thomas Dixon, Jr. " In Griggs's eyes , no purely fictional rep resentation could respond to the racist representations in The Leop ard 's Spots with sufficient polemical force; factual authentication was required. The Hindered Hand signals in both its referent and its strat egy of representation the continuing pressure of many of the issues that had motivated the abolitionist novelists. Clearly the legal exten sion of certain aspects of "universal humanity" had hardly produced the sorts of social transformations that would permit a writer such as Griggs to proj ect his generalized fictional assertions from a position of assumed ideological authority. Subsequent realistic writers addressing the issues of slavery and racism have introduced documentary materials in a less intrusive manner, but th �y have continued to rely upon explicitly extratextual 36Sutton E . Griggs, The Hindered Hand; or, The Reign of the Repressionist ( 1 905; Miami: Mnemosyne, 1 969) , 5. Also see Imperium in Imperio, in which Griggs uses a complicated testimonial apparatus to v ouch for the truth of a rather implausible account of a black sepa ratist movement. 2 54
The Afro-American D o cumentary N ovel
proof and argument. Thus Howard Fast, in his depiction of multira cial unity during Reconstruction, attached a postscript attesting to his novel's recovery of a past that had been deliberately erased from the historical record: "There was not one Carwell in the south at that pe riod, but a thousand, both larger and smaller, " he declares . "When the eight-year period of Negro and white freedom and cooperation in the South was destroyed, it was destroyed completely. Not only were material things wiped out and people slain, but the very mem ory was expunged. "37 Richard Wright had similar purposes in mind when he attached authenticating prefaces to the naturalistic narratives contained in Uncle Tom 's Children and Native Son . He introduced the second edition of Uncle Tom 's Children with an autobiographical sketch, "The Ethics of Living Jim Crow, " in which he reinforced the generalizing power of his fictional tales by anchoring their gruesome events in the writer's own experience. He prefaced the second edition of Native Son with an explanatory essay, "How Bigger Was Born, " in which he argued that the character of Bigger Thomas was a com posite of many youths the author himself had known and that it em bodied a grim symbol of American social reality: "Just as one sees when one walks into a medical research laboratory j ars of alcohol containing abnormally large or distorted portions of the human body, j ust so did I see and feel that the conditions of life under which Negroes are forced to live in America contain the embryonic emo tional prefiguration of how a large part of the body politic would re act under stress. "38 In p ositing Bigger as an " abnormally large" and " distorted" native son, Wright thus highlights the contradictory ide ological abstractions of American democracy: the very individuals to whom it denies representation become, ironically, the synecdochic representatives of its social essence. Even Margaret Walker' s Jubilee, which proffers its narrative largely as a transparently realistic replica tion of its referent, contains a brief preface informing the reader that the text has its foundation in a verifiable historical actuality: "I have a true photograph of my great-grandmother, who is the Vyry of this tale, " Walker remarks. "The picture was made approximately one hundred years ago . " 39 Documentation reminds us that the text is not the product of a transcendental subj ectivity standing outside or above 37Howard Fast, Freedom Road (New York: World, 1 944) , 262. 38Richard Wright, Native Son (New York : Harper & Row, 1 940) , xxi. 39Margaret Walker, Jub ilee (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1 966) , x. 255
Practice the historical process that constitutes the text' s referent. It is b ased in family history; oral tradition provides the text with a determinate lo cus of narrative consciousness .
Modernism i n the Aft·o-American Documentary Novel A pronounced concern with extratextual verification and veracity also characterizes the Afro-American documentary novel when it enters the domains of modernism and postmodernism. Even as it participates in the relativism and skepticism characterizing many twentieth-century metahistorical novels and fictional autobiogra phies, the text doggedly insists upon its status as a purveyor of histor ically specific cognition.
The Afro-American Metahistorical Novel The novels ofJohn A. Williams proj ect a peculiar blend of paranoia and prophecy that situates them in the strain of metahistorical mod ernism extending into the tradition of Pynchon and B arth. In The Man Who Cried I Am, Williams 's Harry Ames - a barely disguised version of Richard Wright- is assassinated when he discovers an interimperialist plot to exterminate all the earth's people of color. In Captain Blackman, \1\Tilliams 's Orlandoesque protagonist p articipates in all the maj or military experiences of the United S tates Army, from the American Revolution through the Vietnam War to some name less neocolonial war of the future in which blacks seize the arsenal and threaten genocidal retaliation. In both novels , history is guided by conspiratorial forces that threaten glob al holocaust: the free-floating anxiety of Isherwood and Wolfe has become a vision of global con spiracy. Also in both novels , a series of documentary devices enforces the notion that the history we have learned is a text constructed by nefarious powers . Williams' s suggestion, in The Man Who Cried I Am, that Richard Wright was killed by the C J . A . challenges the offi cial account of his death; the novel's inclusion of thinly veiled coun terparts to Martin Luther King, Malcolm X, and James B aldwin only intensifies its implication that the entire course of modern black his256
The Afro-American Documentary Novel tory may have b een misreported. 40 In Captain Blackman, Williams's prefacing of each of his hero 's lives with quotations from such sources as the New York Times, the Congressional Record, and official military documents reveals the mendacity and double-dealing that masquerade as legitimacy . When Williams invents his own docu ments, (as when C aptain Blackman receives a discharge signed by George Washington) , the reader is thus forced to agree that Wil liams' s lying is no worse than that of the powers that be. If one fiction is contained in the military archive, another will be set forth in the novel. Williams clearly identifies with those who proclaim that reality is a fiction. His works cannot simply be dismissed as solipsistic, however, for they insist that their suspicions constitute a justifiable response to very concrete historical circumstances. The government plan for de tention and genocide depicted in The Man Who Cried I Am, for in stance, b ears a chilling resemblance to certain actual provisions of the McCarren Act and of the Internal S ecurity Act of 1 9 5 0 . As C. W. E . Bigsby notes , The suggestion that Harry Ames (Richard Wright) died at the hands of a C . l . A . assassin is, in a way, no more absurd than the black comedy of the events which followed President Kennedy' s assassination. Those suspicious o f the existence of a vast political and even cosmic conspir acy no longer seem so paranoid as once they did . To Williams , the con spiracy which the novel proposes as being responsible not only for Lu mumba ' s death but also for the disproportionately high level of black casualties in Viet Nam, is at least as plausible as the public fictions ad vanced as explanations o f those event s . 41
Pynchon's postal conspiracy in The Crying of Lot 49 is ominous enough, but it lacks a specific historical referent. Williams ' s represen tation of a plan for massive racist suppression, by contrast, replicates features - perhaps not widely publicized- of a referent that is in some respects all too real. In Captain Blackman, Williams' s elaborate documentary apparatus invests his metahistorical prophecy with a strange aura of historicity . 40Williams has also set forth his theory that Wright was killed by the C . I . A . in The Most Native of Native Sons: A Biography of Richard Wright (Garden City: Doubleday, 1 970) . 41C. W. E. Bigsby, "Judgment Day Is Coming ! " in Black Fiction: New Studies in the A.fro American Novel since r945, ed. A . Robert Lee (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1 980) , 1 64. 25 7
Practice The hero may undergo a Bergsonian asymmetrical aging, but his es sence is anything but the transcendental subj ectivity of a modernist artist-hero . If there is, to echo Woolf, a " terror" in the represented "present" of the novel's final scene, it by no means derives from the " nondescript character" of that present: the horror of historical pro cess is real. If the novel's final s cenario seems beyond plausibility, it is only a little less plausible than the novel's representation of the Tombolo massacre -- a little-known episode in World War II when s cores of black Gl's were murdered by the American military in the Italian swamp s . Williams ' s fictionalized account of the Tombolo massacre is followed. by a reference to Eisenhower's letter to the Al lied Expeditionary Porces, in which the commander in chief offers " colored troops who have had infantry training " the " opportunity to fight shoulder to shoulder" with white troops " to deliver the knock out blow" to the Germans. 42 Public documentation from the ar chives reverses the truth of what actually happened: the " fighting shoulder to shoulder" at Tombolo, rather than contributing to the defeat of fascism, revealed the fascist tendencies within the United States military itself Thus, in both The Man Who Cried I Am and Cap tain Blackman, the closing prediction of genocide is given an aura of horrific possibility by the invocation of a factual apparatus that calls into question received versions of the historical record. Indeter minacy has a determinate adversary, and apocalyptic determinism is grounded in a historical traj ectory that, it can be demonstrated, al ready characterizes the development of American history. Ishmael Reed, in Mumbo-Jumbo and Flight to Canada, engages in a p arodic play with narrative forms that have supposedly encoded the essential truths of Afro-American experience. In Mumbo-Jumbo, Reed asserts that Haitian folk rituals are at the heart of the maj or s trands in modern American popular culture- a movement that he terms "Jes Grew , " in an ironic sideswipe at S. t owe's Topsy, who is presented in Uncle Tom 's Cabin as a typical exemplar of black folk experience. Intersplicing his narrative with such materials as a photograph from Mark Sullivan's Our Times, an advertising poster from the Cotton Club, and, anachronistically, a photograph of Attorney General John Mitchell, Reed paro dies historical chronicle by demonstrating that the evidence that can be used to validate one version of the past can be 4john A . Williams, Cap tain Blackman (Garden City: Doubleday, 1 972) , 273 .
258
The Afro-American Documentary Novel creatively rearranged to prove another. He even adduces what looks like documentary proof when, to substantiate his assertion that Woodrow Wilson was stricken down by an act of "Voo Doo ven geance, '' he footnotes as his source Robert K. Murray' s The Harding Era - a book which, of course, makes no such claim. 43 In Flight to Canada, Reed parodies the classical historical novel, in viting the reader to flout the very generic contract he has invoked. The world-historical heroes of cultural mythology receive a severe drubbing: Lincoln and Stowe, for example, enter the text not as a posteriori validation of the historical dialectic embodied in Raven Quickskill's career but as real impediments to the hero's aspiration to represent supposedly universal democratic ideals . Stowe emerges as a particularly villainous presence, for she pillages Uncle Robin's Oo siah Henson's) slave autobiography in her Uncle Tom 's Cabin and thus strips him of "his story . . . his gris-gris . . . his Etheric Double. "44 The text's numerous anachronisms underline its critique of compla cent liberal progressivism. When house slaves watch TV on water beds in the quarters and fugitive slaves travel by j et, the text' s preten sion to depict and resolve historically specific social contradictions is lampooned. The struggle for freedom may have been "resolved" in 1 8 63 , Reed implies, but clearly new forms of enslavement (to the commodity form, to the mass media) have emerged. In both Mumbo-jumbo and Flight to Canada, Reed attaches a specific historical urgency to the Collingwoodian enterprise, for the story that he would understand and reconstruct from within- even if he has to create his own "fixed points " -is nothing less than the histori cal experience of black Americans . In one sense Reed identifies clearly with the tradition of idealist historiography. In both novels, he valor izes "hoo doo" as a privileged discourse that can, through mystical insight, penetrate the opacity of a racist and consumerist culture. Moreover, he posits the radical indeterminacy of all historical dis course, including his own; Raven Quickskill muses, "Who is to say what is fact and what is fiction?" This proclivity toward a highly sub43Ishmael Reed, Mumbo:fumbo ( 1 972; New York: A von, 1 978), 1 67. 44Reed, Flight to Canada (New York: Random House, 1 976) , 8 . The statements quoted below are from pp. 7 and 89. For an indication of how easily Reed can be assimilated to the postmodernist celebration of self-conscious textuality, see Frank McConnell's treatment of Raven Quickskill as an artist-hero in "Ishmael Reed's Fiction, " in Black Fiction, ed. Lee, 1 4 5 - 47 .
259
Practice j ectivist epistemology accompanies an often dubious critique of the content of historical process: chattel slavery somehow becomes a Husserlian equivalent to consumer fetishism, and freedom becomes abstracted as, again in Raven Quickskill' s words, a " state of mind. " Reed's ideological stance differs from that of much contemporary writing, however, in his insistence upon the specifically historical as sertive power of discourse. He would not pose a cultural alternative to Our Times if he did not think Sullivan's chronicle had significant powers of misrepresentation; he would not direct such ire toward Stowe if he did not think that she in some way distorted a referent ex isting beyond the borders of Uncle Tom 's Cabin . In his novels, Reed invokes a generic contract similar to that accompanying Barth's mirthful lampoon in The Sot- Weed Factor. The difference is , however, that, as "poet, " he does not wonder "whether the Course of Human History Is Progress , a Drama, a Retrogression, a Cycle, an Undula tion, a Vortex, a Right-or-Left-Handed Spiral, a Mere Continuum, or What Have You. "'45 Rather, he asks the reader to anchor the text's analogous configuration in a historical actuality that requires determi nate judgment, even if it evades determinate codification. History is never simply "What Have You, " if only because it has the power to destroy. Afro-American Fictional Autobiography Just as the metahistorical novel retains a connection to concrete and specific historicity in the hands of Afro-American practitioners, the fictional autobiography retains a power of generalized interpretation and commentary. Where much modernist fictional autobiography, as we have seen, repudiates its roots in nineteenth-century realism, invoking a sense of the real that evades controlled evaluation and judgment, the Afro-American fictional autobiography typically pro j ects a veracious narrative voice, but it mobilizes its sense of unme diated historicity to reinforce the text' s larger claims about the his torical world in which this veracious voice is situated. The speaker does not simply become a character in a first-person realistic narra tion; on the contrary, as in the pseudofactual novel of the eighteenth century, the text proj ects a discrepancy between its speaking voice as 45John Barth, The Sot- Weed Factor (Garden City: Doubleday, 1 960) , 7 1 8 . 260
The Afro-American Do cumentary No v el
an agent and as an obj ect of perception. The character is only partially incorporated into the text's representation of events , for his or her voice asserts an authority superseding that of the absent author. This irony is directed, however, not toward fissures and contradictions in the ideological discourse of a given speaker but toward the social and discursive practices that would deprive the speaking voice of its claim to typicality- that would, in effect, reduce it to either stereotypical ity or anonymity. The Afro-American fictional autobiography as serts a critical totalization of historical actuality; its pseudo factual pos ture primarily serves to reinforce the felt presence of a subj ect refusing obj ectification within the paradigms of racist ideology. James Weldon Johnson's The Autobiography of an Ex-Coloured Man poses a complex and contradictory overdetermination of historicist claims, for the text purports to represent a voice that is at once ac tual, anonymous, and typical. It proposes itself as the true confession of a light-skinned artist-hero who has made the decision to pass for white but finally concludes bitterly that, like the biblical Esau, he may have sold his birthright for a mess of pottage. Johnson so effec tively simulated the " double consciousness" of a member of the " tal ented tenth" that, when the work first appeared under a pseudonym, it was widely accepted as a genuinely factual document . "Even after Johnson revealed his identity, " Robert Bone remarks, "he was so be set by readers who thought it was the story of his life that he was forced to write a real autobiography in self-defense. "46 Indeed, Johnson himself made the interesting assertion that the text, while wholly invented, was to be seen as a "human document, " rather than as a "piece of fiction. "47 Instead of ironizing the text' s generalized claims, however, this pseudofactual posture greatly enhanced the text 's interpretation and j udgment of American society, since the speaker's derogatory assessment of the cost of whiteness becomes the dominant ideological perspective that guides the text's entire com mentary on social reality. The hero' s veracious insistence upon his anonymity reinforces the veiled threat contained in his discourse: no 46Robert Bone, The Negro Novel in America (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1 9 5 8 ) , 46. 47James Weldon Johnson to Carl Van Vechten, March 25, 1 9 2 5 . The statement quoted below is from Johnson to Carl Van Doren, December 28, 1 922, in Eugene Levy, James Weldon Johnson: Black Leader, Black Voice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1 9 7 3 ) , 1 3 2 , 1 2 8 - 29 .
Practice doubt the notion that this speaker might be enj oying the status of the very whiteness he scorned - including even marital prerogatives disturbed the equanimity of a number of readers when the novel ap peared in 1 9 1 2 . At the same time, the hero' s stubborn assertion that he has no name places his pseudomemoir in ironic j uxtaposition with the entire tradition of the fugitive slave autobiography, which cele brated the subj ect' s emergence from anonymity to membership in universal humanity. The Autobiograph y of an Ex-Coloured Man thus grafts a compelling sense of the real onto the broader propositional assertions of realism. John ' s nameless hero is, like Ellison's invisible man four decades later, a figure whose very anonymity constitutes not an idiosyncratic destiny but a composite experience. Accordingly, the situations that the hero encounters render a microcosmic depiction of early twenti eth century racist practices and beliefs : the forms of picaresque and bildungsroman intersect. Yet the hero ' s rej ection of the role of the tragic mulatto reveals the radicalism of his claim to composite status : if he does not represent a type comfortably familiar to the conventions of assimilationist fiction , whom does he then represent? Could there be substantial numbers of equally cynical black men, secretly im planted in the bosom of white society? I propose that the text' s impli cation of a new typicality, one refusing equation with conventional sterotypes, accounts for the ambiguous generic reception of the Auto biography . The contradictions in the text's representational strategy thus direct attention toward contradictions in the referent: the name less hero is difficult (at least for many contemporaneous white read ers) to grant as a type precisely because of the real limitations placed upon the recognition of such types in social reality. The sense of the real thus operates to foreground the text' s problematic relation to the representational clailms of realism; if recognition cannot be assumed, then cognition must be highlighted. The artist-hero' s insistence upon the integrity of his own voice opposes the discursive and social con ventions that would not permit this voice recognition as an interpre tive presence. Published a good sixty years after Johnson's cynical mock autobio graphy, Ernest Gaines ' s The Autobiography of Miss Jane Pittman in vokes a generic contract that reflects a cautious optimism: the protag onist can and does claim a universal selfhood. This proposition is asserted, however, not through the p roj ection of a transparent real2 62
The Afro-American Documentary Novel ism but through the simulation of a transcribed oral history. Al though the text is classed as a novel in the Library of Congress and carries Gaines 's name on its title page, it contains a preface in which a nameless editor claims that the text consists of a series of taped inter views that he has simply condensed and selected. Since this " editor" is not definitively identified with Gaines, Miss Jane herself enj oys the status of a possible real person, rather than of a patently fictional construct . This editorial posture is not entirely a ruse, either: Miss Jane Pittman is indeed based to a large extent upon the oral accounts of former slaves similar to Miss Jane, for the novel owes much to Gaines' s own childhood on a Southern plantation during the Depres sion, when he listened to the lengthy stories about slavery told by elders of his grandparents' generation. 48 As in Jubilee, this invoca tion of the authenticating apparatus of oral history has the effect of enhancing the protagonist's status as an active historical subj ect. The documentary procedures that would rescue the protagonist from anonymity also assure her typicality. Nonetheless, Miss Jane Pittman is primarily a mimetic work de signed to proj ect a composite portrait of an aged former slave. As the editor obliquely indicates in his preface, "others" filled in the hiatuses in Miss Jane's narrative, and they deserve inclusion in his acknowl edgments, since "this is not only Miss Jane's autobiography, it is theirs as well. " 49 Through the blended voices that attest to the histo ricity of a single individual, Gaines thus manages to convey much of the totalization ordinarily accompanying realism; the self is, emphat ically, a type, and consciousness is, emphatically, a social phenome non. Indeed, Gaines' s careful orchestration of realistic and pseudofac tual representational strategies enables him to incorporate into his text the lengthy saga of Mary Agnes and Tee Bob (an interracial cou ple meeting a predictable S outhern Gothic end) , without violating the pseudofactual posture that frames the text. In certain structural re spects, this miniature parable of racial tragedy resembles the interpo lated narratives about Thomas and John in A Journal of the Plague Year and of Henry and Bon in Absalom, Absalom! But the three interpo lated narratives perform very different formal and ideological func48Ruth Laney, "A Conversation with Ernest Gaines, " Southern Review, n . s . IO ( 1 974) : 1 - 14. 49Ernest J . Gaines, The Autobiography of Miss Jane Pittman (New York: Dial, 1 9 7 1 ) , x . The statement quoted below is from p . 192.
263
Practice tions . In Journal, the fictional account of Thomas and John's escape from London is incorporated into the text' s memoiristic frame and enhances H. F. 's authority as a presumed witness to the plague. In Absalom, Absalom! the imagined interactions of Henry and Bon assume the status of Collingwoodian constructed " facts , " and they reinforce the authority of Quentin and Shreve as practitioners of an idealist historiographical method. In Miss Jane Pittman, the tale of Mary Agnes and Tee Bob augments the authority of Miss Jane as a composite type privileged to witness, interpret, and even dramatize the experience of subj ectivities exterior to her own. Sitting with Jules Raynard, the white lawyer, after their j oint reconstruction of the final episode of the story, Miss Jane reports : "But ain' t this specalatin?" I said. "It would be specalatin if two white people was sitting here talking, "
Jules Raynard s aid . . . . "But it's u s ? " I said. " And that makes it gospel truth, " he said.
Miss Jane' s claim to typicality clearly hinges upon her status as a col lective historical subj ect, which enables her to articulate " gospel truth" where others may be only " speculatin . " The final meaning of the Mary Jane/Tee Bob episo de may be a matter of conj ecture, but it is not radically indeterminate, and Miss Jane is, by virtue of her social and historical situation, the most reliable teller of its probable truth.
Conclusion
The preceding analysis of the uses of documentation in Afro American fiction shows that empiricism does not always function in the same way when it is incorporated into fiction' s claim to render cognition. Most writers working in the realistic tradition have as sumed a good deal of ideological congruence between their own be liefs and those held by their readers; accordingly, extratextual corrob oration serves to validate these beliefs a posteriori. Most writers working in the modernist tradition, by contrast, have been hostile to ward the neutralist pretensions of realism, but they have responded by postulating a radical indeterminacy: accordingly, their invocation of documentary materials has asserted the prophetic (but impotent) status of the artist-hero and has enhanced the view of history as a realm of alien and undifferentiated facticity. Writers grappling with the phenomenon of racism, however, have started from quite differ ent premises . Realistic writers have had to confront the ignorance of much of their audience- and the skepticism of some of it- regard ing the text's presumption to be rendering a generalized portraiture of its referent. Indeed, empirical "proof" often seemed to rest with the opposition. Empiricism thus serves for these writers as both antago nist and polemical ally: they do not abandon empirical documenta tion as a means of conveying cognition but instead use it in ways that will disturb fixed assumptions and augment the text's propositional claims . Similarly, modernist writers addressing the issue of racism have altered the conventions of the fictional autobiography and the metahistorical novel in significant ways, for they have directed their hostility to empiricism toward a critique of the specific ideologies 265
Conclusion. that empiricism routinely sustains. If there is an incomprehensible destiny guiding historical processes , its strangeness and irrationality are concretized in practices that would either subj ugate or margin alize an entire group of historical subj ects. And if historical knowl edge seems radically indeterminate, its explanation is the vested in terest that the powers who formulate and disseminate historical information have in distortion and obfuscation. In the hands of the Afro-American documentary novelist, then, the invocation of an extratextual reality does not constitute a pretension to unmedi ated propositionality. Rather, it foregrounds the relation between evidence and generalization and calls attention to the ideological na ture of any discourse-itself included- purporting to represent reality. The Afro-American documentary novel, by virtue of its privi leged- or, one might say, embattled- social and historical situation, highlights the definitive features of documentary mimesis . Indeed, it focuses attention on the strategies of representation and reference commonly used in nondocumentary fiction as well. In closing, I shall reexamine the theoretical theses set forth in Part 1 in the light of my readings of Afro-American documentary fiction. First, the Afro-American documentary novel reveals that fictional representation entails a social contract between author and reader and that this contract is an intrinsically historical phenomenon. The em piricist overdetermination accompanying Clotel points to William Wells Brown's uneasiness about his audience's ability to accept the novel's incidents as valid generalizations about the conditions of chat tel slavery; the strongly felt autobiographical presence in The Autobio graphy of an Ex-Coloured Man reveals James Weldon Johnson's desire to convince his audience that the novel's protagonist is both a plausi ble social type and an authentic artist-hero . My point is not simply that these novels address issues of contemporaneous concern. I am arguing, rather, that the very decision to read these novels as works of fiction involves a series of other decisions that are constitutively historical and ideological. To read Clotel as a realistic novel is to par ticipate in many assumptions about typicality and representation political as well as artistic- that are definitively characteristic of the mid-nineteenth century. To read The Autobiography ofan Ex-Coloured Man as a fictional autobiography is to ground modernist conceptions of the artist's relation to reality in the particular context ofJim Crow 2 66
Conclusion racism. As works of fiction, these novels mobilize conventions of ab straction and reconcretization that are historically specific, and their acts of mimesis cannot be fully understood without reference to the contracts they proffer to their readers . Second, the foregoing analysis of the Afro-American documentary novel demonstrates that the problem of reference is central to the act of mimetic communication. The documentary novel, it is true, ex hibits what might be called an "anxiety of reference" : as a genre, it is preoccupied with convincing its readers that its reconcretized particu lars of character and event have close links with the original concrete entities to which the text refers . Thus Melville's incorporation of the transcript of the Africans' trial into "Benito Cereno " assures the reader that his tale of rebellion and revenge is not a speculative flight of fancy. Wright's prefacing of Native Son with the sketch "How Big ger Was Born" requires the reader to recognize that Bigger's apparent deviance contains a trenchant commentary on everyday realities . But the documentary novel's distinctive concern with verifiable reference should not be taken as a concession that the text would lack referen tial power if it did not assert its particular links with actual persons and events . Rather, the invocation of a documentary apparatus oper ates to guarantee that the generalizing powers of fiction do indeed have applicability to the particulars the text contains. Rather than implying that fiction ordinarily lacks the capacity to assert a view of the world, the use of documentation suggests that a particular charac ter or episode, presumably so terrifying or abnormal, recreates essen tial features of the world inhabited by the reader. Documentation thus testifies not only to the reality of a specific cluster of represented materials but also to the formidable referential power of fiction. Finally, the very empiricist overdetermination of much Afro American documentary fiction affirms that, as a mode of cognition, fiction possesses a distinct and separate status. The documentary novel approaches the frontier between fictional and nonfictional dis course, but it does not transgress or blur that borderline. Sutton Griggs appends his "Notes for the Serious" to The Hindered Hand not to turn his novel into an undifferentiated amalgam of mimesis and so ciological commentary but to underline the generalized portraiture of race relations that his fictional tale proj ects . Even Ishmael Reed, whose protagonist explicitly asks where fiction leaves off and fact be gins, brings Lincoln and Stowe into the domain of the novel not to 267
Conclusion suggest that they are fictional constructs but to validate his parodic commentary on liberal conceptions of progress. From the most me ticulous naturalism to the most far-flung fantasy, fiction renders knowledge of the world by means of analogous configuration. As we have seen, factual particulars may enter the text in a variety of ways to suit a variety of ends, but they frame and highlight the text' s gen eralized propositions . The documentary novel's insistence that it has a particular truth to tell thus reinforces rather than undermines fic tion's distinct status as a means of telling the truth.
268
Index
Abercrombie, Nicholas, 90 n. l I Abolitionist novel. See Afro-American documentary novel Abstraction, 98-I0 3 , 1 79-84, 229- 3 2 Adams, George Burton, 1 76 Afro-American documentary novel: abolitionist novel, 245-5 1 ; defined, 2 3 3 - 3 5 , 244; fictional autobiography, 260-64; metahistorical novel, 2 5 6-60; Modern ist novel, 2 3 4- 3 5 , 256-68; post-Civil War novel, 2 5 1 - 56; realistic novel, 2 3 43 5 , 244- 56 Agassiz, Louis, 240 Ainsworth, W. H. , 1 5 7 Alexander, Edward, 1 2- 1 3 Alienation. See Reification Althusser, Louis, 82- 8 3 , 92 Althusserian school, 1 8- 1 9, 66-67, 79- 8 3 , 92-94, I 02 Amyot, Jacques, I I O Analogous configurations , 64-65, 67-74 Apuleius, I 08-9, l I O Aristotle, 5 0 , 75-77, 78 Assertion and mimesis, 42-6 3 , 74 Auerbach, Erich, I 09 Austin, J. L . , 56 Autobiography. See Fictional autobiography Automatism. See Reification Bacon, Sir Francis, 1 3 6 Bakhtin, M. M. , 96-97 n . 2 3 , 1 1 8 Balibar, Renee, 93 n. 1 7 Bancroft, George, 1 44, 1 74-75, 2 1 6- 1 7, 219 Barth, John, 260 Barthes, Roland, 3 3 -34, 3 5 Bateson, Gregory, 3 6-3 8 Beard, Charles, 1 77, 2 1 6- 1 8
Beardsley, Monroe, 44 Beattie, James, 127 n. 46 Behn, Aphra, 1 7, 1 1 3 - 1 7, 1 3 3 , 1 3 5 Bellamy, Edward, 1 64-65 Bennett, Lerone, 2 3 9 Bennett, Tony, 8 1 n. 1 7, 93 n . 1 7 Benstock, Shari, 1 5 5 n . l 2 Bergson, Henri, 208- 10, 2 1 2, 2 1 3 n . 3 8 , 258 Bernstein, J . M. , 1 3 1 n. 54 Bersani, Leo, 1 46 n.4 Bigsby, C. W. , 257 Black, Sidney J . , 132 n. 5 5 Bleich, David, 54- 5 5 Block, Haskell, 168 n. 3 6 Bone, Robert, 26 1 Bradbury, Malcolm, 1 86 n . 2 Brandy, Leo, 1 44 n . 3 Braverman, Harry, 226 Brecht, Bertolt, 20 1 -4 Brent, Linda, 246 Bridgman, Richard, 1 90 n . 6 Brooke-Rose, Christine, 1 4 Brooks, Cleanth, 7 5 Brown, Robert, 5 7, 6 1 Brown, William Wells, 1 9 , 2 4 5 , 246-49, 251 Bruss, Elizabeth, J 2 n . 9 Butterfield, Herbert, 1 5 8 Camden, William, 1 I O Cameron, J . M. , 44 Capitalism, 1 3 6-42, 22 1 -27. See also Industrial capitalism Carlyle, Thomas, 1 7 1-75 Cartwright, Samuel, 240 Caudwell, Christopher, 54, 1 3 7 Champigny, Robert, 48-49
Index Child, Lydia Maria, 246 Chomsky, Noam, 3 8- 3 9 Cognition and mimesis, 64- I 0 3 Collingwood, R . G. , 208 , 1 8 3 , 220-2 1 , 259, 264 Comte, Auguste, 1 6 1 , 1 77-78, 200, 2 1 1 , 218 Cooper, James Fenimore, 56, 1 50-5 5 , 246; The Pioneers, 1 5 1 - 5 2 , 1 5 5 , 1 60, 247; The Spy, 1 7, 1 4 5 , 1 5 0- 5 1 , 1 52-54 Cooper, Thomas, 1 I O Coward, Rosalind, 9 7 11. 24 Crane, Stephen, 1 67-68, 1 69, 1 7 8 , 1 79 Croce, Benedetto, 2 1 5-- 1 8 Culler, Jonathan, 5 7 n . 3 5 Darwin, Charles, 1 56 d'Aulnoy, Marie Catherine, 1 1 3 - 1 6, 1 24, 1 2 8 , 145 Davis, David Brion, 2 3 7 n.4 Davis, Lennard ) . , 1 3 , 26, I I 2 , u 4- 1 5 Davys, Mary, 1 1 8- 1 9 Defoe, D aniel, I 0 8 , u 8 , 1 1 9-24, 206; Journal of the Plague Year, u 9-2 1 , 1 3 I , 192, 263 -64; Moll Flanders, 1 7 , I 0 8 , 1 2224, 1 3 2-3 3 , 1 3 5 , 1 4 1 , 1 4 5 , 1 9 1 ; Robinson Crusoe, 1 2 1 -22, 1 3 2--3 3 , 1 89 Delany, Martin, 244-45, 247-48 , 2 5 1 Deloney, Thomas, 1 09, u 2- 1 3 Derrida, J acques , 1 3 , 3 4-3 5 Descartes, Rene, I O I , 1 3 1 - 3 5 , I J 6, 1 40, 1 56, 2 1 2 Dickens, Charles: Barnaby Rudge, 1 59-60; Bleak House, 68-69, 7 0- 7 1 , 7 3 , 74, 24'6; David Coppeljield, 143 Diderot, Denis, 1 28-30, 1 3 2 Dixon, Thomas, 8 8-89, 1 6 3 , 2 5 4 Doctorow, E . L . , 9 - rn , 1 4- 1 5 , 1 7 Documentary novel: defined, 25-29. See also Afro-American documentary novel; Historical novel; Modernist documen tary novel; Pseudofactual novel Dolozel, Lubomir, 59 n. 3 9 Dos Passos, John, 1 4, 1 6 , 47, 67, 20 1 , 2038 , 2 1 7, 223 , 2 3 I Douglass, Frederick, 246 Dreiser, Theodore, 1 67-69 Eagleton, Terry, 80- 8 1 , 93 Eisenstein, Sergei, 20 1 Elder, Arlene, 2 5 2 n . 3 4 Eliot, George, 1 7, 1 6 1 -62, 1 7 8 Ellis, John M . , 3 3 n. IO , 9 7 n 24 Ellison, Ralph, 244, 262 Empiricism, 1 00- 1 0 1 ; and the historical novel, 1 44-46; and nineteenth-century .
2 70
historiography, 1 69-70; and the pseudo factual novel, 1 3 0-3 5 ; and racism , 2 3 4-41 Engels, Frederick, 8 7- 8 8 , 89, 1 3 6, 1 3 8, 1 6 5 , 1 7 5 , 206 Eschenbach, Wolfram von, 1 09, I I I Evans , William McKee, 2 3 9 , 242 Exchange relation, 98- 1 0 3 , 1 79-84, 22932 Family resemblance definitions o f mimesis, 30-3 3 . See also Qualitative definitions of mimesis Fantasy, 69, 7 1 -72 Farrell, James T . , 45, 68-72 Farrison, W. Edward, 248 n. 3 0 Fast, Howard, 2 5 4 Faulkner, William, 1 99-200, 2 0 8 , 2 1 3 - 1 4 , 220-2 1 , 229, 263 -64 Federman, Raymond, I I Fiction. See Mimesis Fictional autobiography: defined, 1 86-8 8 , 1 8 8-9 5 ; Afro-American, 260-64 Fielding, Henry, 1 2 1 , 1 26-28 Fischer, William, 244 Fish, Stanley, 46 n. 8 Flaubert, Gustave, 1 62-63 Fleishman, Avrom, 1 5 3 n. I I Footnotes: in Afro-American realism , 247; in the historical novel, 1 49-50, 1 5 3 , 1 5456 Forster, E . M., 197 Foucault, Michel, I 3 Fox-Genovese, Elizabeth, 1 3 9 , 2 3 7 n. 5 Franklin, H. Bruce, 2 3 9 Fredrickson, George, 8 8 Froissart, u o , 1 1 1 Frye, Northrop , 75 Gaines, Ernest, 262-64 Gale, Richard, 59-60 Gallie, W. B . , 5 1 Gaus, Helmut, 5 3 Gearhart, Suzanne, 3 4 n . I Genovese, Eugene, 1 3 9, 2 3 7 n. 5 Geoffrey of Monmouth, l I O Gestalt psychology, 3 6-40 Gilliam, Harriet, r 9 9 n. I 8 Gliddon, George, 8 8 , 240 Godard, Jean-Luc, 1 29 n . 5 1 Goffman, Erving, 36-37, 3 9 Goldknopf, David, 1 2 3 Goldmann, Lucien, 90-92, 1 8 3 n . 69 Gombrich, E. H. , 3 6 Goncourt, Edmond de, 1 66; and Julius Goncourt, 1 67
Index
Graff, Gerald, 62, 45-46 n. 7 Griggs, Sutton, 254, 267 Hafley, James, 2 1 3 n. 3 8 Hamburger, Kate, 48, 49 Hardison, 0. B . , 50 n. 1 7 Harper, Frances, 252-53 Harrison, Frederic, r 76 Hart, Albert Bushnell, 2 1 4 Hawthorne, Nathaniel, 69, 7 1 , 74 Heermance, J. Noel, 248 n . 3 0 Hegel, G. F. W. , I OO, 1 72-73 , 1 74, 2 1 5- 1 6 Heidegger, Martin, 1 56 Hellmann, John, 1 2 Henderson, Harry B . , 7 1 -72 n . 6 Hernadi, Paul, 29 Herodotus, 1 I O- 1 1 Historical novel, 143 -84; a)l tiquarian his torical novel, 1 56-57, 1 60-64, 1 78-79; classical historical novel, 1 47-56; defin ing features of, 143 -46; mid to late nine teenth-century historical novel, 1 56-6 5 ; Utopian historical novel, 1 64-65 Historiography: Ancient and Renaissance, I 09- u ; Modernist, 2 1 4 - 2 1 ; Nineteenth century, 1 69-79; Romantic and Vic torian, I 69-76; Scientific, I 76-79 Hockett, Homer, 1 76 Holland, Norman, 5 3 Hollowell, John, 1 2 Homology: and analogy, 1 5 5 n. 1 4 ; and Goldmann's theory, 90-92 Huet, Pierre Daniel, Bishop, r u - 1 2 Hughes , H . Stuart, 208, 2 I O n. 3 3 Hume, David, 3 7, 62, 23 8 Husserl, Edmund, 47, 50, 208, 2 u - 1 2 , 2 1 3 - 1 4, 2 1 6, 2 1 8 , 224, 229 Ideology, 80- 8 3 , 8 5- I 03 ; Althusserian definition, 92-94; as apologia, 88-89; definitions of ideology, 87-95 ; as false consciousness, 86-90; ideological contra diction, 95-98; Leninist definition, 949 5 , 23 5 Imperialism, 222-2 5 . See also Monopoly capitalism Industrial capitalism, 145-46, 1 79-84; and racism, 243 - 44 Ingarden, Roman, 48-49 Intentionalist definitions of mimesis, 5 5-62 Irony: as defining the pseudofactual novel, 1 1 8- 1 9, 1 2 3 -24 Iser, Wolfgang, 54- 5 5 , 83 Isherwood, Christopher, 1 7, 1 92-93 , 1 94, 207, 2 1 3 , 230, 256
Jakobson, Roman, 45 Jakubowski, Franz, 89 James, G. P. R., 1 5 7 James, Henry, 69-70 Jameson, Frederic, 79- 80, S r , 201 n. 2 1 Jefferson, Thomas, 240, 245, 248 Johnson, James Weldon, 261 -62, 266-67 Johnson, Samuel, 243 Journalism: and the pseudofactual novel, I I 4- 1 5 Joyce, James, 1 8,8-89, 1 9 1 , 1 94, 206 Kant, Immanuel, I O I , 1 56 Kaplan, Sidney, 250 n. 3 2 Karcher, Carolyn, 2 5 0 n. 3 2 Kellogg, Robert, 29, 3 2 Kennedy, Richard, 1 9 3 n . I O Klinkowitz, Jerome, 1 1 Krieger, Murray, 50- 5 1 Kristeva, Julia, 80 Kuhn, T. S . , 3 8 Lacan, Jacques, 92, 9 7 n. 24 Laclos, Choderlos de, 1 28-30, 1 4 1 Lange, Victor, 3 9 Langer, Lawrence, 1 2 Laporte, Dominique, 93 n. 1 7 Laudan, Larry, 3 8 n . 2 1 Lenin, 94-95 , 23 5 ; definition o f ideology, 1 8 , 65, 66, 77, 222-23 Leslie, Joshua, 250 n. 3 2 Lesser, Simon, 5 3 Levin, David, 1 75-76 Levin, George, 1 70 Levin, Harry, 1 46-47 n . 4 Lewis , Thomas, 8 1 - 82, 93 Linnaeus (Karl von Linne) , 23 8 Locke, John, 1 3 1-36, 1 4 1 , 241-42, 243 Lodge, David, 44 n . 3 Lodge, Thomas, I09 Lukacs, Georg, 1 8- 1 9, 52 , 66-67, 77-79, 90, 92, 93 -94, I O I n . 28 , I02, 1 47-56, 1 8 3 , 1 8 8 , 200-203 , 225 Macaulay, George Babington, 1 70-7 1 , 1 74 McCarthy, Mary, 7 1 McConnell, Frank, 2 5 9 n . 44 MacDonald, Margaret, 44-45 Mcfarlane, James, 1 86 n . 2 Macherey, Pierre, 9 2 , 9 3 Mackenzie, Henry, 1 2 8 Mailer, Norman, I I , 14, 1 5 n . 20 Mandelbaum, Maurice, 3 I n. 8 Marcuse, Herbert, 2 1 2 Marx, Karl, 4 5 , 5 2 , 87- 8 8 , 89, 99- I OO, I03, 1 3 9, 1 40, 165, 1 77, 1 79-84, 206, 22 1 , 224, 227, 237-38 2 7I
Index
Mediation, 98-ro3 Melville, Herman, 2 5 0--5 1 , 267 Mentalist definitions of mime s is, 52- 5 5 ; Affective definitions, 52-54; Reader response definitions, 54- 5 5 Merchant capitalism, r 3 6-42 Metahistorical novel: Afro-American, 2 5 6-60; defined, 1 86-87, 1 95-201 Metscher, Thomas, 65--66 Michelet, Jules, 1 44, 1 7 3 , 1 77, 2 1 9 Mill, John Stuart, 1 7 8-·79, 200, 2 I I Miller, Henry, 1 90-92,. 1 94, 229 Mills, Nicolaus, 72 n . 6 Mimesis: definition o f terms, 2 8 n. 3 . See also Assertion and mimesis; Cognition and mimesis; Family resemblance defini tions of mimesis; Intentionalist defini tions of mimesis; Mentalist definitions of mimesis; Qualitative definitions of mimesis; Textual de finitions of mimesis Mink, Louis, 5 l Modernist documentary novel: Afro American modernist novel, 2 5 6-64; defined, 1 8 5-8 8 ; ficti.onal autobiography, 1 8 8-95; metahistorical novel, 1 95-20 1 ; and modernist histoiriography, 2 1 4-2 1 ; and modernist philosophy, 209- 1 4 ; and radical modernism, 200-208 Monopoly capitalism, 2 2 1 -27 Morgan, Edmund, 242-43 Morris, William, 1 6 5 -66 n . 3 0 Motley, John Lothrop, 1 74, 1 7 5 Nashe, Thomas, I I 2- r 7 , 1 20, 1 3 I , 1 3 2 , 1 3 3 , 1 3 5 , 1 92-93 Naturalism, 68-7 1 , 1 66-69 Neumann, Manfred, 86 n . 4 N e w History, 2 1 6- 1 7. See also Historiography, Modernist New Journalism, I I - I 2 , r s Nin, Anals, 1 9 1 -92 Nott, Josiah, 88, 240 Novak, Maximilian, I 2 I n. 3 3 Ohmann, Richard, 45-46, 5 8- 5 9 , 6 r , 8687 Olsen, Stein Haugom, 45, 5 8 , 6 r Osborne, Harold, 8 6 Page, Thom a s Nelson, 1 6 3-64 Palmer, Melvin D . , I I 4 n . 2 1 Parekh, Bhikhu, 87- 8 8 n. 5 Parkman, Francis , 1 7 1 , 1 72 , 1 76 Pascal, Blaise, 62 Pascal, Roy, 68 Phelan, James, 45
2 72
Phillips, Wendell, 246 Philosophy of science. See Qualitative definitions of mimesis Plato, 62 Polanyi, Michael, 3 8- 3 9 Popkin, Richard, 2 3 6 , 242 Popper, Karl, 3 8 Porter, Carolyn, 7 7 n . I I , 2 1 4 n . 40 Poststructuralism, I O- I I , 1 3 - 14, 1 7- 1 8 , 28, 33-35 Pratt, Mary Louise, ro7 Prescott, Orville, r 7 4 Primary framework, defined, 3 7 Pseudofactual novel, ro7-42; defined, ro78; in eighteenth century, I I 8- 30 ; emer gence of, r I I - r 8 ; and empiricism, 1 3 03 5 ; and merchant capitalism, 1 3 6-42; precursors of, ro8- I I Pynchon, Thomas, 2 5 7 Qualitative definitions o f mimesis, 1 4 - 1 6, 27-42; family resemblance definitions, 3 0- 3 3 ; poststructuralist definitions, 3 3 3 5 ; spectrum definitions, 29, 3 1 - 3 2 Rabinowitz, Peter J . , 5 4- 5 5 n. 29, 2 3 4 Racism: and the Afro-American documen tary novel, 2 3 3 - 3 5 ; and empiricism, 2 3 5-4 1 ; and representation, 241 -44 Rader, Ralph W. , 5 1 , I I 9, 1 89 Raleigh, John Henry, 1 56 n. r 6 Raleigh, Sir Walter, r r o Ranke, Leopold von, 1 44, 1 76-77, 2 1 6 Reade, Charles, 143 Realism: Afro-American, 23 3 -3 4, 244- 56; and analogous configuration, 68-69, 707 1 ; and the historical novel, 143 -69; Lukacs's theory of, 1 47-48; and the sense of the real, 1 26-3 0 Reed, Ishmael, 2 5 8-60, 267-68 Reeve, Clara, 1 26-28 Reference in mimesis: and abstraction, r o 1 -2 ; and cognition, 64-84; and language, 44-47 Reflectionism, 77-79, 90-92 Reification: critique of, in Brecht and Dos Passos, 20 1 - 8 ; and industrial capitalism, 1 45-46, 1 79-84;and the modernist docu mentary novel, 227-3 1 ; and monopoly capitalism, 2 2 1 -27 Renan, Ernest, 1 77-79 Rhodes, Cecil, 222-23 Richardson, Samuel, ro8, 1 24-26, 1 3 1 , 1 3 2, 1 3 3 , 1 3 5 , 143 Roberts, Thomas, 5 5-56, 60, 6 1 Robinson, James Harvey, 2 1 6- 1 7
Index Romance: and analogous configuration, 69, 71 _72; and the p seudo factual novel, I I 5 - 1 7 , 1 26 - 2 8 Roth, Philip, I I
Thackeray, William Makepeace, 1 5 7-59, 1 70-7 1 , 1 72 , 1 96-97 Thome, Jack, 2 5 3 Thu cy di des , r o9 Tolstoy, Leo, r o 8 , 1 2 1 , 1 5 7- 5 8 , 1 5 9
Sacks , Sheldon, 3 9 n . 24, 1 2 3 Said, Edward, 79 n . 1 2 .S ainte-Beuve, Charles, 1 62-63 Sanders, Andrew , 1 6 1 n . 2 3
Santayana, George, 1 8 7, 22 8 Scholes Robert, I I , 1 3 , 29, 3 2
fi
S cienti c history. See Historiography, nineteenth-century Scott, Sir Walter, 46-47, 60, 1 50, 1 5 2- 56 , 1 5 7,
1 60, 1 64, 1 70-72, 1 7 5 , 246
S criven, Michael, 47
Searle, John, 3 3 , 56, 5 9-6 1 , 8 3 Seneca, r o9 Sense of the real, r r 8- 3 0 Sepulveda, Gaines d e , 2 3 6 - 3 7 Shaftesbury, Anthony, Third Earl of, 1 J 2 Si dney , Sir Philip, 1 7, 1 I I
S i m m el, Ge o rg , 2 2 8 Slave narrative, 246-49, 2 5 9 . See also Afro-American documentary novel Smith, B arbara Herrnstein, 3 2 , 5 6-57, 5 9-
6 1 , ro8 Smollett, Tobias , 1 2 8 -2 9
Sohn-Rethel, Alfred, 7 6 , 99- r o 3 , 1 3 7 - 3 8 , 1 79 - 8 1 , 2 2 1 -22, 226, 227 Speech-act theory, 56-62. See also Textual
definitions of mimesis Spengler, Oswald, 2 0 8 , 2 1 8 - 1 9 , 220, 22 1 , 229
Spin dl er, Michael, 226 n . 5 8
Stein, Gertrude, 1 8 9-90, 1 9 1 , 1 94, 2 1 3 - 1 4 , 229 S teinmann, Martin, 5 7, 6 1 S tephen, Leslie, 1 5 6
S tern, Laurent, 4 8
Stevenson, Charles , 3 l Stowe, Harriet Beecher, 245 -47, 24 8 , 2 5 1 , 2 5 8 -6o, 2 6 8 Stuckey, Sterling, 2 5 0 n. 3 2 Subj ect, problem o f the. See Ideology
Sukenick, Ronald, 1 1 - 1 2
Tomashevsky, Boris , 50 Tourgee, Albion, 2 5 1 - 5 2 , 2 5 4 Toynbee, Arnold ] . , 2 1 9- 2 1 Twain, Mark, 1 3 5 , 1 65-66 n. 3 0
Typical hero: defined, ! 47-48 . See also Realism; Afro-American documentary novel Vaihinger, Hans, 2 I O- I I , 2 1 3 Van Dijk, Teun A . , 5 4 - 5 5 n . 7 Vergil, Polydore, I I O
Visser, N. W. , 1 3 4
Vonnegut, Kurt, 69, 7 1 -72, 7 3 Walker, M a rga ret, 1 9 , 2 5 5- 5 6 Wallace, L e w , 1 62 Walton , Kendall, 3 7 n . 1 6 , 49- 5 0
Warren, Austin, 44 Warren, Robert Penn, 1 97-99, 2 1 3 - 1 4 , 22 1 , 229
Watt, Ian, I I 9, . 1 3 2 n. 5 5 Weimann, Robert, 6 1 Weitz, Morris , 3 0 - 3 1
Wellek, Rene, 44 Wells , H . G. , 2 1 9- 2 0 White, Hayden, 5 1 Williams, Eric, 2 3 7
Williams, Joan, 129 n . 5 2 Williams , J o h n A . , 2 5 6- 5 8 Williams, Raymond, 90, 1 44 . 1 5 5 n. 1 4
Wimsatt , Will iam K. , 7 5 Winks , Robin, 246 n . 27
Wittgens tein, Ludwig, 3 0- 3 3 , 5 7 Wolfe, Thomas, 1 92-94, 22 1 , 2 5 6
Woodmansee, Martha, 6 2 n . 4 8 Woolf, Virg in i a, 1 7 , 1 9 5-97, 1 99 , 2 0 8 , 2 1 2- 1 3 , 2 2 1 , 2 5 8 . World-historical hero : in Afro-Amencan
metahistorical fiction, 2 5 6-60; in Mod ernist metahistorical fiction, 1 97-9 8 ,
205-6; i n nineteenth-century fiction, 1 4 5 , 1 4 8 - 5 6 , 1 5 7-62 Wright, Richard, 46, r o 8 , 2 5 5 , 2 5 6 - 5 7
Taine, Hippolyte, 1 44. 1 76-77, 1 9 5
Taylorism, 2 2 1 -22, 2 2 5 27, 22 9 - 3 1 -:Textual definitions of m1mes1s; 43-52;
Zavarzadeh, Mas'ud, I O , 1 2 Zeraffa, Michael, l 8 5
linguistic, 44-47; ontological, 4 7 -
Zimmerman, Everett, 1 2 1 n. 3 3
5 0 ; structural, 50- 5 l
Zola, Emile, 1 67-68
2 73