118 80 10MB
English Pages 226 [244] Year 1987
Londen: Meihematical Society Lecture Note ReneS nO
CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY
PRESS
CTC ae oe ef wt as R
wi a
va
eRe
Sethe:
Kf
y
tee eat
ba: ae
=
Mn >
og SP
ey Ae
SUBJECT JO. LTE FINE
JISUARDED-LIBRAR\ LAY Ohi)
DEMCO
38- 297
oe
LONDON MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY LECTURE NOTE'SERIES Managing Editor: Professor J.W.S. Cassels, Department of Pure Mathematics and Mathematical Statistics, University of Cambridge, 16 Mill Lane, Cambridge CB2 1SB, England The books in the series listed below are available from booksellers, or, in case of difficulty,
from Cambridge University Press.
4 Algebraic topology, J.F. ADAMS 5 Commutative algebra, J.T. KNIGHT 16 Topics in finite groups, T.M. GAGEN 17 _ Differential germs and catastrophes, Th. BROCKER & L. LANDER 18 A geometric approach to homology theory, S$. BUONCRISTIANO, C.P. ROURKE & B.J. SANDERSON 20 Sheaf theory, B.R. TENNISON 21 Automatic continuity of linear operators, A.M. SINCLAIR 23
24 25 27 29 30 31 34 36 38 39 40
41
~_—~Parallelisms of complete designs,
P.J. CAMERON
= The topology of Stiefel manifolds, I.M. JAMES _ Lie groups and compact groups, J.F. PRICE Skew field constructions, P.M. COHN ~~ Pontryagin duality and the structure of LCA groups, S.A. MORRIS Interaction models, N.L. BIGGS Continuous crossed products and type III von Neumann algebras, A. VAN DAELE Representation theory of Lie groups, M.F. ATIYAH et al Homological group theory, C.T.C. WALL (ed) Surveys in combinatorics, B. BOLLOBAS (ed) = Affine sets and affine groups, D.G. NORTHCOTT Introduction to Hp spaces, PJ. KOOSIS
Theory and applications of Hopf bifurcation, B.D. HASSARD, N.D. KAZARINOFF & Y-H. WAN Topics in the theory of group presentations, D.L. JOHNSON Graphs, codes and designs, P.J. CAMERON & J.H. VAN LINT
42 43 44 2Z/2-homotopy theory, M.C. CRABB 45 _ Recursion theory: its generalisations and applications, 46 48 49
F.R. DRAKE & S.S. WAINER (eds) p-adic analysis: a short course on recent work, N. KOBLITZ Low-dimensional topology, R. BROWN & T.L. THICKSTUN (eds) Finite geometries and designs, P. CAMERON, J.W.P. HIRSCHFELD &
D.R. HUGHES (eds) 50 51 52
Commutator calculus and groups of homotopy classes, Synthetic differential geometry, A. KOCK Combinatorics, H.N.V. TEMPERLEY (ed)
54 55 56 57 58 59 60
Markov processes and related problems of analysis, E.B. DYNKIN Ordered permutation groups, A.M.W. GLASS Joumees arithmetiques, J.V. ARMITAGE (ed) Techniques of geometric topology, R.A. FENN Singularities of smooth functions and maps, J.A. MARTINET Applicable differential geometry, M. CRAMPIN & F.A.E. PIRANI Integrable systems, S.P. NOVIKOV et al
61
Thecore model,
H.J. BAUES
A. DODD
Economics for mathematicians, J.W.S. CASSELS 62 Continuous semigroups in Banach algebras, A.M. SINCLAIR 63 64 _ Basic concepts of enriched category theory, G.M. KELLY Several complex variables and complex manifolds 1, M.J. FIELD 65 Several complex variables and complex manifolds II, MJ. FIELD 66 Classification problems in ergodic theory, W. PARRY & S. TUNCEL 67 Complex algebraic surfaces, A. BEAUVILLE 68 Representation theory, ILM. GELFAND et al 69.
Stochastic differential equations on manifolds,
Groups - St Andrews 1981,
K.D. ELWORTHY
C.M. CAMPBELL & E.F. ROBERTSON (eds)
Commutative algebra: Durham 1981,
R.Y. SHARP (ed)
Riemann surfaces: a view towards several complex variables, A.T. HUCKLEBERRY Symmetric designs: an algebraic approach, E.S. LANDER
New geometric splittings of classical knots, L. SIEBENMANN & F. BONAHON Spectral theory of linear differential operators and comparison algebras, H.O. CORDES Isolated singular points on complete intersections,
EJ.N. LOOJENGA
A primer on Riemann surfaces, A.F. BEARDON Probability, statistics and analysis, J.F.C. KINGMAN & G.E.H. REUTER (eds) Introduction to the representation theory of compact and locally compact groups, A. ROBERT
Skew fields, P.K. DRAXL Surveys in combinatorics, E.K. LLOYD (ed) Homogeneous structures on Riemannian manifolds,
Finite group algebras and their modules, Solitons,
F. TRICERRI & L. VANHECKE
P. LANDROCK
P.G. DRAZIN
Topological topics, I.M. JAMES (ed) Surveys in set theory, A.R.D. MATHIAS (ed) FPF ring theory, C. FAITH & S. PAGE
An F-space sampler,
NJ. KALTON, N.T. PECK & J.W. ROBERTS
Polytopes and symmetry, S.A. ROBERTSON Classgroups of group rings, M.J. TAYLOR Representation of rings over skew fields, A.H. SCHOFIELD Aspects of topology, I.M. JAMES & E.H. KRONHEIMER (eds) Representations of general linear groups, G.D. JAMES Low-dimensional topology 1982, R.A. FENN (ed) Diophantine equations over function fields, R.C. MASON Varieties of constructive mathematics,
D.S BRIDGES & F. RICHMAN
Localization in Noetherian rings, A.V. JATEGAONKAR Methods of differential geometry in algebraic topology, M. KAROUBI & C. LERUSTE Stopping time techniques for analysts and probabilists, L. EGGHE Groups and geometry, ROGER C. LYNDON Topology of the automorphism group of a free group, S.M. GERSTEN Surveys in combinatorics 1985, I. ANDERSON (ed) Elliptic structures on 3-manifolds, C.B. THOMAS A local spectral theory for closed operators, I. ERDELYI & WANG SHENGWANG
Syzygies, E.G. EVANS & P. GRIFFITH Compactification of Siegel moduli schemes, C-L. CHAI Some topics in graph theory, H.P. YAP Diophantine Analysis, J. LOXTON & A. VAN DER POORTEN (eds) An introduction to surreal numbers, H. GONSHOR Analytical and geometric aspects of hyperbolic space, D.B.A.EPSTEIN (ed) Low-dimensional topology and Kleinian groups, D.B.A. EPSTEIN (ed) Lectures on the asymptotic theory of ideals, D. REES Lectures on Bochner-Riesz means, K.M. DAVIS & Y-C. CHANG An introduction to independence for analysts, H.G. DALES & W.H. WOODIN
Representations of algebras, P.J. WEBB (ed) Homotopy theory, E. REES & J.D.S. JONES (eds) Skew linear groups, M. SHIRVANI & B. WEHRERITZ Triangulated categories in the representation theory of finite-dimensional algebras, D. HAPPEL Lectures on Fermat varieties,
T.SHIODA
Proceedings of Groups - St Andrews 1985, E. ROBERTSON & C. CAMPBELL (eds) Non-classical continuum mechanics, R.J. KNOPS & A.A. LACEY (eds) Surveys in combinatorics 1987, C. WHITEHEAD (ed)
Lie groupoids and Lie algebroids in differential geometry, K. MACKENZIE Commutator theory for congruence modular varieties, R. FREESE & R. MCKENZIE
London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series. 123
Surveys in Combinatorics 1987 Invited papers for the Eleventh British Combinatorial Conference
Edited by C. WHITEHEAD Department of Mathematical Sciences, Goldsmiths' College, London
The right of the University of Cambridge to print and sell all manner of books was granted by Henry VIII in 1534.
The University has printed and published continuously since 1584.
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge e New York New Rochelle Melbourn
Sydney
Published by the Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge CB2 1RP ~ 32 East 57th Street, New York, NY 10022, USA 10, Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia
© Cambridge University Press 1987 First published 1987 Printed in Great Britain at the University Press, Cambridge Library of Congress cataloging in publication data available British Library cataloguing in publication data British Combinatorial Conference (11th: 1987: Goldsmiths’ College) Surveys in combinatorics, 1987: Invited papers for the Eleventh British Combinatorial Conference. —- (London Mathematical Society lecture note series, ISSN 0076-0552; 123).
1. Combinatorial analysis I. Title 511'6
ISBN
I. Whitehead, C. QA164
0521 34805 6
III. Series
CONTENTS Preface Barlotti, A. Finite geometries and designs
Cameron, P.J. Portrait of a typical sum-free set
13
Chvatal, V. Perfect graphs
43
Erdés, P. My joint work with Richard Rado
53
Frankl, P. The shifting technique in extremal set theory
81
Graham, R.L. & Rédl, V. Numbers in Ramsey theory
111
Milner, E.C. & Prikry, K. Almost disjoint sets
155
graphs Thomason, A. Random graphs, strongly regular and pseudo-random graphs
173
y Winkler, P. The metric structure of graphs: theor and applications
197
Index of names
223
‘
oe
7 ORE,
2
Mi
=
a
9
:
i
~—s
, »
ix
4 fi
J
rs
= 7 “¥
~
oa
=”
=
Tess
7
: i
ee
e~
ea =.
LS
smsiae
eG Li
\
ite Sealeaeeeotdadpee
ai
eee)
Es, 7
Ss Ler
;ee =
Cerise:
ee
£see
r
eae
erik e
aadieniad adi,
ae
af
-
Ps
2
as
faze
ee
“ «
;
L_Belinea
OA pet 2
and
through
an
see
A
and
new
passes
a ana
exactly
following
incidence
is
longer
(when
are
by simply
a
plane
To
Finite
modification
the
lh
The
the
The
affine
S-spaces.
points
through
satisfied.
through in
is
line
an
of dimension
in
and
satisfied.
space
lie
of
points,
is
I'
way:
of
suitable
incidence
of
is not
L,
which
through
are
a
and
notion
of
example
S(P,
the
one
parallelism.
two
a line
to
from
following
AB),
with
Z
lines
pass
S-spaces
but
the
number
space
in
the
class
affine
S-space
the
or
easy
special
simple
ordinary
exactly
a.
arise
@
exists
generalizes a
very
a plane
A
Veblen
a through
A
in
change,
in
may
relation
for
and
of
axioms:
number
there
designs
an
Similarly
It postulates
be
to
form
S-spaces
2 except
B.
exactly
consists
elements
PXxL
with
2-(v,k,1)
an
through
in
of
following
a finite
obtain
a
L
the
with
spaces.
through
set
cardinal
a)
S-space
S-spaces
called
not
A with
(A,
spaces
can
in
pair
affine is
incidence
a
S,
relation;
an
Consider
2%, we
S-space,
defined
same
of
affine
s>3.
the
notion
Ete ae, Bh)
From
with
equivalence
A
Proper
order
I
incident
parallel
structures
Let
are
and
that
ordinary
and
satisfying
points
an
with
The space,
L,
point-line
incident
points
an
5S;
3) Parallelism
4) For
shortly
relation
L*
incident
of
or
called
in
distinct
order
space
incidence
defined
1) Any
the
affine
be
two
the
desarguesian
affine r
line
of
2),
Then
lines
space
bea
a line A.
four
rand
of
8 not
Barlotti: Finite geometries and designs
through In
A
the
and
which
S-space,
u.
the
Thus
satisfied.
the
Barlotti
& Nicoletti
may
1968)
spread
be
very
and
of
construction
of
planes
in
use
a later
Z and
Let
q.
2 be
two
of
= .
plane
am
intersection
A-points
them.
represented
than
by the
and
s
represented
Q , and
A
avoid
to
A-lines
by
the
in
useful
high
the
to
also
may
products
Similar
other
of
types
several
of
the
as a natural
arises
and
1979).
geometry
(see,
construction
of
structures.
given
in Bose &Barlotti
Dembowski
e.g.
non-desarguesian
the
here
recall
We
incidence
are
and
A-points
points them
confusing
three
of
are
of
planes
planes
and
£
¥!
contained passing
of type
Q
and
.
The
lines
with
shall
1971,
which
we
4-dimensional
space
of order
which
in
to be
plane
will
5
of
line
constructed
A-points
type
A-points
of
pass
through
a line
Eu
A—points:jof
s
and
represented
not
lying
by the
of
“type
(1) S
(2)
in either
points
will
and
represent
which
2!
a
in the
contained
be called of
by S
denote
and
%'
of
elements
types.
through
(3) are
the
s
by
Denote
its
not
3-spaces
distinct
of
finite
a
be
PG(4,q)
=
lines
by
e.g.
(see
section.
of
denoted
S-spaces
orthographic
the
to
1977).
Halder
1978,
projective
a
of
A-planes
spread
be
in
non—desarguesian
extended
be
construction
Glynn
other
"
the
choosing
in
a
classes
has
designs
of
order
a and
the
allows
semitranslation
of
the
over
their
spread
constructed
other
spreads
in if
a
line.
contained
ring
only
in AM
of
(1)
and
“A—point.”
ternary
or
1s
this
a
plane
& of
in
PG(2n,p)
from
(Krier
has
“to be
been
way of
is
dimensional
A
given
in
of
linear
Heft
of
the
27.
the
design. of
1971
and
in)
classes spaces
obtain
different
X'
flats
By
planes
1974).
a divisible
various
we
shear
hyperplanes
(n-1)-dimensional
in this
high
Q
generalizations.
derived
A
constructions in
is
various
kernel
of
2 and
Galois
of type
A-point
“the®
of
planes
construction
PG(2n,q), a
a
as
1971.
way
2
defined
intersect
A-line
representing
dimension
be
using
12!
with
is
A-point
them
the
the
than
given
of
& Smith
structure
also
incident
suitable
i=
incidence
is
A
of
to
representing
of
generalization
so
planes
construction
greater
taking
is incident
representing
plane
in Bose
(2)
A-line
element
The
spread
the a
is obtained
by
if
case
semi-translation
degree
type
other
contains
other
of
between
Heft
partial
ani on
certain
quadrics.
4.
a
variety
Well
known
Geometrical
in
a
1981,
briefly
unital
the
arc)
have
examples
Ray-Chaudhuri Holz
space
1962,
properties
are
in
1965.
Pellegrino
the
plane
used
Bose
Other
1973,
construction
in
been
of
A
a
curve
for
the
1958,1961,
examples
1974, a
of
(Barlotti
of
Bose
&
given
1978.
lines
finite
construction
are
1977,
unital
ina
We
plane
of
or
of
designs.
Chakravarti
1966,
in
1968,
Barlotti
shall
recall
here
U*
(i.e.
the
dual
& Lunardon
1979).
The
existence
of
a
Barlotti: Finite geometries and designs
of,
1%
implies
consists
of
of
U*.
the
The
s
in
§ 3.
2
in
two
A
there
points
of
A
which
A
Let
Q
of
is
_ Barlotti
& Lunardon
In Biscarini
designs.
is
other
Among be and
is
for
used vifs.
also
For
proved
6.
the
is
E'
in
the
plane
U*
of
P and assume
with
two
of
U*.
Let
in P.
from
by
the
set
(1)
type
possible
all
and
Consider
A
is a unital
A-lines
consider
to
2%
obtained
passing
incident
and
and
of
points
&
that
1
q+
only
of
of
&
different
cone
the
line
1976.
points
V
lines
A-point
every
exactly
a Laguerre
design
with
the
construction of
how
2-designs
Another
but not
structures
incidence
designs
of
geometric
we
be
associated
way
which
plane
do
C which
the
through
q+1
and
lines
it
A-lines
of
of
not
is
This
(cf.
cases
in the
point
out
see
Glynn
to
of
to
of
q
order
PG(3,q)
PG(3,q).
finite the
designs.
interesting
of odd
parameters
isomorphic
which
structures
these
can
same
class
construct
to
from
and planes)
theory
used
1980
& Conti
the
be
may
known
a well
are
planes
planes
Benz
of points
(as a structure
prove
to
order
the
only
q
qe -
of
in
A
planes
the
by
or
w
intersects
by
either
%'
in
,
P
Consider
V.
2
with
(3-dimensional)
point
,
respectively.
(clearly
&
with
p
p
that
way
a
w
one
intersects
incident
symmetric
a
constructed
which
S
line
exactly
Z'
of
the
inversive
finite
of
types
2'
which
1979).
Finite
5.
using
of
arc
in Buekenhout
and
requires
and
difficult
Other
with
incident
is
U*
constructed
given
oO
the
that
prove
to
enough
in
(2),
type
of
lines
that
to
consists
U*
Since
VR.
line
to
with
is tangent
of
,
XYUQ
to
belong
not
incident
unital
and
represented
lines
of
a
oOo
such
the
from
also’
denoted
be
C
by
Q
projecting U*
p
in
are
a hyperplane
planes
Let
denote
and
P),
be
exists
analogous
plane
intersection
the
be
V
A
chosen
is
A
the
A _ which
respectively.
that
is
be
distinct
ovoid
R
in
construction
Let
an
that
case
may
half-planes
1985,
where
leads
to
it
them.
sometimes
the
Barlotti: Finite geometries and designs
construction
covering chosen A
or
in
and
of
B
families
of
a
a proper
the
designs
partition way.
of
We
respectively,
design,
of
incidence
fix
the
in
be
based
a geometric
may
as
may
two
set
of
the
on
structure
particular blocks
design
the
and
being
knowledge
with
set
given
a
substructures
families the
of
of
of
by
elements,
points
a
of
a
particular
relation. We
1984.
The
plane
in
a
present
here
author
first
Lemma:
Consider
tangent
to
PG(3,q) \\%=
one
proves
Q
of
the
in
nice
point
aset
examples
given
in
Vecchi
following.
PG(3,q)
ina
AG(3,q)
the
V.
D
(q
odd),
Then
it
of
a is
Re
wee
possible
Qs
to
anda
construct
q _ disjoined
fa cae
such
a
of
points
that
(i) gN\tvie bp (ii)
the
caps
of
D
form
partition
the
of
AG(3,q). From
PG(3,q) as
this
(q odd)
points
the
a block
are
meet
two
in
Cofman
Ebert
set
if
and
only
PG(3,q)
using
examples are
The
it
indefinite
of
When
Combinatorics
and
thinking
of
are
in
(q+1)-arcs
I since I
was at
another
a design
time
in
can
a,
a point
and
and
line
a family 428-429
pp.
planes
and
other
obtained
obtained
1986
designs
and
3-designs.
recently:
by
of
in
partitioning
are
constructed
odd).
this
busy free
for
with
1969
be
I was
possibility
to
ees
Bruck
present
remain
that
of
parameters:
of a line
constructions
to
lines
» A =a° (+1) (q-3)/4.
in PG(2,q)(q
to
with
the
belonging
corresponding
Kestenband
that
those
the
a covering
designs
invited
wanted
and
blocks
establishing
inversive
nice
as
and
obtain
on
how
and
if
V_
considered
two
shown
ovoids,
title
also
those
D,
Taking
r=q°(q°-1)/2
based
recall is
properties
7.
we
results
will
into
points,
» ke(q-1)/2-,
points
we
through
the
distinct
1985
those
of
1973.
Finally
Theorem:
incident
Other of
the
Sees
v=q ; b=q°(q+1) sets
follows
, except
lecture
with to
this
I
gave
problems
decide.
lecture
far
Then
in
an from
I
was
order
to
Barlotti: Finite geometries and designs
of
keep topic
class
of
know
everything
here
the
1982,
following
Piper
divisible
of
1985.
Schulz
cf.
designs
translation
to
classified
be
classification
a
For
principles.
different
wish
1983,
Kelly
good
I present
designs
may
designs
of
types
Other
1967.
Schulz
1983,
who
those
For
a,b,1985,
1984
Butler
information:
necessary
a particular
symmetric
of
classification
the
on
designs.
symmetric
, the
g.
e.
designs,
in
designs,
of
types
choose
to
have
we
classification
a nice
have
of
variety
large
the
to
due
Clearly, to
the
for
above.
presented
order
to
better
was
I decided
and
anniversary
50-th
the
for
celebration
the
it
that
thought
I
later
However
planes.
projective
a classification
of
birth
second
the
of
anniversary
30-th
the
celebrate
REFERENCES
Barlotti,
A.
Alcuni
(1965).
di
generalizzati
Barlotti,
pp.
A.
(1968).
and
planes
Periodico
Barlotti,
A.
(1985).
designs.
Barlotti,
A. from
&
geometric
affini
Univ.
Padova
and
Geometric
Ars
Combin.
J.
46 pp.
(4)
77
la
costruzione
(1975),
for procedure pp. 7-14.
from
pp. the
projective
of
28-38.
(1974). and
40,pp.
231-241.
Finite
affine
Sperner
spaces.
Abh.
spaces
constructed Sem.
Math.
nei
unitals A. & Lunardon, G. (1979). Una classe di 5. 781-78 Riv. Mat. Univ. Parma (4) 5, pp.
Barlotti,
G. (1976). On a geometric procedure A. & Nicoletti, r spaces. Abh. Math. Sem. Univ. Sperne of on constructi 251-255.
of
construction
19-A,
projective
pp.
spaces.
projective
Barlotti,
45,
di
59-68.
construction
structures
Math.-Verein.
Cofman,
Hamburg
di Mat.
Representation other
Deutsch.
Jber.
spazi
Mat.
per
geometrici
Procedimenti
(1975).
A.
Rendiconti
Sperner.
degli
Sem.
18-46.
35,
PBIB-—disegni.
Barlotti,
studio
nello
risultati
Univ.
A-piani.
for
the
Hamburg
Barlotti: Finite geometries and designs
Barnabei,
M.
&
Brini,
A.
Beth,
Th.,
(1980).
Jungnickel,
D.
&
A.
(1982).
Lenz,
A.
(1983).
P.
&
Bose,
R.
C.
(1947).
The
Bose,
R.
C.
(1958).
deriving
ts.
The
Soc. Bose,
R.
On
for
C.
die
in die
(1980).
Sem.
Fis.
design
of
the
Design
endliche
endliche
Piani
Univ.
di
Modena
Theory.
Geometrie
Geometrie
Laguerre 2opepp.)
experiments,
application
a certain
golden
pp.
R.
C.
B.I.
II.
B.I.
Proc.
e
disegni
LO1=107i
34th
Indian
of
finite
projective
geometry
series
of balanced Kirkman arrangemen— commemoration volume, Calcutta Math.
jubilee
Lecture
& Barlotti,
projective
Bose y Rn
Ccn
18
di
Notes.
A.
Dept.
(1971).
planes Mat.
Pura
Chakravarti,
finite
of
Statistics.
in
a
e Appl.
I.
projective
Linear four
Chapell
M.
representation
dimensional
88,
pp.
(1966).
space
PG(N,q
Rie
iC
ak
Smiths,
yKey
JieeeC
(1971).
representable
Convegno
Geometria
(1969).
planes,in pp.
Buekenhout,
F. planes pp.
Construction Univ.
(1976). of
189-194,
varieties
Canadian
Ternary
order
of
J.
in
Math.
q
problems
with
of
Carolina
unitals
a kernel
of
of
of
finite its
in order
class
In
Universita
and Press,
a
planes.
Perugia
Mathematics
North
Existence
rings
semi-translation
Combinatoria,
"Combinatorial
426-514.
of
space.
a 18,
;
linearly
R. H.
of a class
projective
Hermitian ).
69-101.
Bruck,
Hill,
9-32.
pp.1161-1182. Bosies
Sci.
341-354.
(1961).
Annali
B.I.
I.
NiciCes
Bose,
from
1-25.
pp.
Congress,
obtained
13-17.
pp.
Mannheim.
F.
Atti
29,
(1985).
in
Einfiihrung
Conti,
simmetrici.
PBIB-designs
Mannheim.
Wissenschaftsverlag,
Biscarini,
H.
Einfiihrung
Wissenschaftsverlag,
Beutelspacher,
of
Math.
Mannheim.
Wissenschaftsverlag,
Beutelspacher,
A class
Discrete
geometries.
projective
pp.
projective
applications",
Chapel
finite q,
of
atti
Hill,
N.C.
translation Geom.
Ded.
5;
Barlotti: Finite geometries and designs
Butler,
N.
T.
(1984a).
pp.
Butler,
N.T.
(1984b).
Giessen,
Butler,
N.T.
Clatworthy,
W.
(1954).
On
combinatorics Projective
Halder,
Hedayat,
5S.
Ph.D.
An
(1985).
309-342.
H.-R.
(1979).
A.
J.
M.
G.
type
V and
Math.
Sem.
VI.
J.
Statist.
configuration Am.
Math.
finite
Soc.
projective
pp.
59-70,
which
is
pp.
47-55.
5,
a
spaces.
Proc.
Washington
State
Heidel-
Berlin
caps.
into
geometries
projective
1163-1175.
of Adelaide.
Paralle-
mit
von Inzidenzrdiumen Produktbildung Angew. Math. 305, pp. 82-88.
19A,
Combin.
Ars
planes,
half
to
introduction
combinatorial
and related
planes
Univ.
Thesis,
S.
Spreads
Ph.D.
The
(1980).
(1971).
Inference
projective
in
Chapel
Thesis,
von
Konstruktion
projektiven
pp.
Hill,
t-designs
of
family 4,
Part
-
Il.
173-212.
and
geometry
associated
N.C.
Spernerraumen
Math.
Sem.
Ebene.
Abh.
of
designs
which
(1985).
Design
aus
einer
Univ.
vorge-
Hamburg
46,
25-54.
(1981).
D.
of
Springer-Verlag,
projective
Plann.
Arch.Math.
Hughes,
pp.
Statist.
(1977).
pp.
Mitt.
Reine
& Kageyama,
gebenen
Holz,
37,
Finite
(1978).
pp.
A.
16,
Wash.
Partitioning
Math.
designs. Herzer,
Dedicata
York.
(1985).
J.
Heft,
of
Geometries,
lismus.
III.
Planes,
Finite
D.G.
type
Proc.
P.(1968).
systems,
Glynn,
of
geometrical
design.
Pullman,
G.
D.
A
Press,
Can.J.
Glynn,
Geom.
355-361.
University
L.
G.
designs pp.
Conf.
berg—New
Ebert,
11,
balanced
(1973).
designs
Symmetric
H.
Intern.
Dembowski,
blocks.
1-24.
Inference
partially
J.
semi-translation
Symmetric
pp.
(1985).
Plann.
Cofman,
On
279-290.
Construction
37,
pp.
contain
a
unital.
179-183.
F. Piper, & R. University Press.
Cc.
Theory,
Cambridge
Barlotti: Finite geometries and designs
Kageyama,
S.
& Hedayat,
Statist.
Kelly,
G.
S.
A.
(1983).
Lecture
Kestenband,
N.
pp.
pure
with
M.J.
and
of t-designs
- Part
I1.J.
257-287.
Designs
Johnson,
in
family
7,
elations.
Kallaher,
applied
In
C.T.
"Finite
Long.,
mathematics
82,
eds.)
M.
Dekker
pp.263-272.
B.
C.
(1986).
elements.
Krier,
(N.L.
Notes
The
Inference
Symmetric
geometries" Inc.
(1983).
Plann.
J.
(1974).
Balanced
Statist.
Linear
incomplete
Plann.
block
Inference
representation
of
13,
derived
designs
pp.
on
q+l
45-50.
shear
planes.
Boll.
UMI (4) 9, pp. 709-720. Pellegrino,
G.
(1973).
4 3
e
su
Sulle
un
proprieta
BIB-disegno
della
ad
essa
11-calotta
collegato.
completa
Bollettino
di
UMI
(43°7, pp. 463-470. Pellegrino,
G.
(1974).
associazione
Costruzione
e di
di
una
PBIB-disegni.
classe
Atti
di
Accad.
schemi
Naz.
Modena
di
(6),
16, pp. 5-17. Pellegrino,
G.
(1977).
finiti.
Pellegrino,
Piper,
Piper,
F.
F.
G.
Schemi
Rend.
di
(1978).
in
a
25
Pps
plane
On
Math..15,
axial
(1983).
On "Finite
Long,
Raghavarao,
associated odd
negli
spazi
lineari
645-656.
order.
with J.
non
degenerate
Statist.
Plann.
conics
Inference
D.
(1971). of
D.K.
automorphism
of
symmetric
designs.
Ann.
S33—340).
pp.
designs which admit axial automorphisms geometries" (N.L. Johnson, M.J. Kallaher, C.T.
Dekker
design
for
pp.
symmetric
eds.),
M.
Ray-Chaudhuri,
of
9,
=sO0/—3ii2
(1982).
82,
associazione
(4)
t-designs
Galois
Disgrete
in
di
Mat.
Lectures
Notes
pp.
Inc.,
in
Constructions
experiments.
(1962).
constructing
pure
and
applied
mathematics
391-400.
J.
and
Wiley
Applications PBIB-designs.
combinatorial & Sons,
of
New
the
Ann.
problems
in
York.
geometry Math.
of
Stat.
quadrics 33,
pp.
1175-1186.
Ray-Chaudhuri, spaces
D.K. and
(1965).
Some
partially
configurations
balanced
incomplete
in
finite block
projective
designs.
Can.
11
Barlotti: Finite geometries and designs
J. Schulz,
Math.
R.-H.
R.-H.
Sperner,
B.
M.
114-123.
Uber
Zeit.
(1985).
sible
Segre,
pp.
(1967).
gruppe.
Schulz,
17,
On
designs.
Blockplane
98,
the
pp.
mit
classification
Europ.
J.
(1965).
Istituzioni Disegni.
Roma:
Istituto
Affine
Rdume
mit
(1960).
algebraische
Dilatations-—
of translation
Combinatorics
si,Reti,
E.
transitiver
60-82.
di
Geometria
Strukturen.
pp.
group-—divi-
369-374.
Superiore
III:
Comples-
Matematico.
schwacher J.
6,
Reine
Inzidenz Angew.
und
zugehorige
Math.
204,
pp.
205-215.
Vecchi,
I.
(1984). ovoids
10,
Some and
results
related
pp.219-225.
on
coverings
BIB-designs.
J.
of
Galois
Statist.
spaces
Plann.
with
Inference
.
1
+, 29474 oe poirening oti T iproieg
a.oe |
edotem
> 6
"/ Litt
SE ARO OWS
ary JO ar
oe64,-
yt eh Acne Pre 2
:
7 o i}
‘parautl ae? »[¢0es) 8 a Aree _ ch» teapot sh af) a
(pameigd. £m, seibak, “inet
wiegye -t
1
name
‘poe
os
“pats Spats 6 dab, KisSOLID? aii abla cous itt *we
Fetes
ah
PUREMDRETS
onal a isgin hasta
oC) Chak
We
aig
aE
coe
semen
a:
BO Sy eenteelden ty and Ele i RS Meet, ae eh ipomeeps te heya, Dea Mt oii
Nest
is ee
fut cone
mean a
as as
3
PORTRAIT
P.J.
OF A TYPICAL
SUM-FREE
SET
Cameron
School of Mathematical Queen Mary College University of London Mile End Road LONDON El 4NS
Sciences
INTRODUCTION A set
y € S, we
have
x+y
The
history
(homogeneous
relational
of
are
results
and
defining
among
dimension possess
tools
be
their
extremal
theory,
theory
model
and
that
I think be
won’t
built
a
of
used
find
the
"typical"
the
do
not
I
remarkable
methods
used
sum-free
set
these
until
on
our
we
areas
may
problems,
and
another’s
one
learn
in
are
Hausdorff
and
in
specialists
its
of
Firstly,
a
probability
effectively
out
life
a
on
such
until
section
first
reasons.
by
here
reported
takes
main
Secondly,
topology,
-_
could
we
from
(or
counter-intuitive;
and be
can
notion
the
them.
which
two
for
topic
surprising
areas
but
versa;
vice
analysing many
from
taken
date cannot
detail in the
quickly
understood.
better
is
case
special
all x,
vertex-transitive
to
planes,
in more
subject
theory
general
a
that
believe
to
They
investigations
the
to
the
quite
often
said
rise
projective
I describe
this
chosen
I have
own.
if, for
numbers
in Ramsey
applications
in
be
sets.
give
groups),
led
However,
paper.
the
can
natural
sum-free
many
which
applications,
these
sum-free
structures).
first
was
I
sets the
that
sets
blocking
theory,
graph
sum-free
yielding
graphs,
triangle-free
of
abelian
finite
in
is called
5S.
finitely
into
partitioned analogues
numbers
proved
Schur
when
1916,
S of natural
language.
A Many on
of the
the
basis
experimental
time
but
subsidiary conjectures of
stage.
reason were
computation.
Moreover,
little memory,
and
are
involves formulated Indeed,
typical
best
the
collection
(and
a few
the
subject
computations
performed
on
evidence.
of
of them is
require
still
proved) at
a lot of
a microcomputer.
an
Cameron: Portrait of a typical sum-free set
Readers
are
encouraged
to
try
their
hand
at
further
data-gathering!
1
ORIGINS
1.1
AND
Schur,
van
I have cannot
be
first
result
is
what
theorem
arbitrarily
(1936)
must
superior are
density
and
equal,
was
upper
(1927) sets,
the
This
density
led
numbers
exists,
years.
Ramsey:
must
Erdos
if
contain
and
Turan
of positive
upper
progressions.
of a subset
respectively,
limit
them
N the
(excluding
predates
of
long arithmetic
lower
theory
was
by fourteen
also
one
of natural
inferior,
later,
hard.
But
theory.
he in
was
proved 1977,
of
the
S of N are
|SN
the
{1,....n}|/n;
common
value
if
is
the
such
numbers
analogy
suggests
the
sum-free
density set have
1.2
the
progressions
general
enriched
(1952)
a
proved
arithmetic
The
nicer
that
a set
progressions.
by Szeméredi
conjecture.
gave
both
result
(1969);
proof
is
six
quite
proof
using
ergodic
and
ergodic
theory.
combinatorics
is possible
is obviously a problem
we
consider
set?
and
graphs
and
isomorphism
between
finite induced
extends
be
6.
has
sets.
The
density
detail:
In particular,
what
set
of
%
But
the
can
be
said
does
a "typical"
is it?
cyclic graphs.
finite or countable
is said
of [ which
in
if so, what
graph T
to
sum-free
and
consider
of a sum-free a density,
for
sum-free
A
automorphism
Roth
three-term
Furstenberg
Homogeneous We
contains
for discussion.
(1983)
No all odd
slow.
to four-term
His methods
See Petersen
initially
density
improved
years
graphs.
Ramsey
that
This
of S).
of positive
about
and
that
Progress
This
Ramsey
arbitrarily
limit
so
as
many
(1916)
sets.
pre-dating
Waerden
a set
theorem
sum-free
progressions.
that
contain
limit
der
and ‘Furstenberg
Schur’s
many
known
finitely
(The upper they
now
arithmetic
to conjecture
density
is
into
long
finitely
priciple),
of van
partitioned
Szeméredi
mentioned
into
pigeonhole
A similar N
in
Waerden,
already
partitioned
Dirichlet’s
APPLICATIONS
der
simple
homogeneous
subgraphs
Thus
undirected if, whenever
of [, there
"homogeneity
6 is an
is an
of [" means
Cameron: Portrait of a typical sum-free set
"transitivity
of the
non-edges,
Gardiner
etc." The
finite The
non-trivial
by
Henson
(1971)
(i)
homogeneous
graphs
(iii)
of m complete
m,
finite
or
countable;
(i)
(complete
n are
of
where
n,
the pentagon;
of K3 33
graph
(v)
for
each
n > 3, a graph Gp containing
and homogeneity
Types are
finite
=
(n
G,
automorphism
3)
graphs
Let
isomorphism:
Furthermore,
vertices
S = { nin x;
is
and Rényi
are
of [T as
joined
« up
to
Xj
x,
(iv)
in
the
interested
observed
cyclic
what
R and
that
graph
(n € Z) so that « maps
and
to conjugacy
Gg
not.
of a countable
to X,}. if
(iii) and
question:
the
Henson
automorphism
3 0, Xp joined
S determines
we
so
consider
have?
while
interest,
no
but Gy, (n ® 4) does
Let « be a cyclic
the
it);
graph R (Erdos
here;
We
R.
and
cyclic automorphisms,
number
of
(ii) are
relevant
do these
characterise
or "random"
(i) and not
(these
subgraphs
(1964)).
Rado
(1963),
having
no K, but
induced
as
(v)3
of
"universal"
the
(vii)
graphs
free
K, -
finite
complements
(vi)
Xn + 1°
The
graphs);
multipartite
line
can
and
earlier);
of size
graphs
the
graphs
by were
graphs
complete.
is
list
(iv)
being
determined
found
one
the
that
unions
properties
to
were
homogeneous
from
(apart
edges,
condition.
graphs
disjoint
all
We
strong
are
complements
(ii)
of [ on vertices,
countable
proved
(1980)
Woodrow
&
homogeneous
admit
group
this is a very
(1976).
discovered Lachlan
automorphism
Clearly
Then only
S determines if
in Aut([).
lj
-
il
(More
I.
xy, to [T up €
S.
Cameron: Portrait of a typical sum-free set
precisely,
if x, and
the associated
«3 are
subsets
cyclic
automorphisms
of N, then
«, and
&> are
of [, and conjugate
S, and
Sz
in Aut(I)
if
and only if S, = S>). The
I recall finite
that,
for
A subset
oO =
zeros
and
to R if and
includes
in
Clearly
no
sum-free
the
only
restriction.
elements
there
differ
k apart So
exist
ej-re4
(ii)
every
S is isomorphic of the
senses
universal.
exist,
of
G3,
if and
so
we
that
in
that
S, is sf-universal
if S
if k € S and
occur
say
begin
only
by k, and
can
we
it is not
too
to
than
i, j withl
the what
sum-free
Finite
What
«i
= 1 and j — i € 8;
© is a subsequence
is isomorphic
1.3
words,
(This
R admits
so
S.
a
finite
But
this
sum-free any
the
sum-free.
S is sum-free,
no
if, given
with
is
sequence should
set finite
S,
be with
zero-one
O = (e,,...,e,), either
(i)
typical
is
such
sequence
contains
by
in either
sets
be universal:
of S can
function
infinite
if S
set
any m
automorphisms).
set can
in positions
questions:
universal
is triangle-free
ones
trivial
2%o
exists
(In other
an
determined
typical
[(S)
with
Now
a
there
only
(1984);
if, given
if e; = 1.
Moreover,
automorphisms
no
characteristic
paper,
ones,
function,
[(S)
in Cameron
universal
and
if and
cyclic
then
sequence
graph
that
in detail
only
universal
the
cyclic
that
two
is
this
assertion
For
S if and
if S is universal.
non-conjugate
observation
S
Now
later
the
of zeros
its characteristic
ones,
only
described
m+i€
S with
sequence).
considered
of N is called
(€4 s0005@y))
1 ¢ i =n,
identify
finite
ao
[ = R was
results.
sequence
if we of
the
case
hard
Gg
analogous do
with
or
of S.
to show
if and
< Jj
vertices
Set o(i) = 1 if vo is joined to vj, 0 otherwise, for
Proof. i=
Let
3.4.
{Vo, V4} an
Vy}>
Hamiltonian
The cycle
result follows is obtained
on
by homogeneity.
by choosing
n = 2
edge.
al subset of Sf It is not difficult to show that a residu In particular, many density zero. consists of sequences with lower is not This zero. density lower have sequences sf-universal long uces in Proportion 3.3 introd surprising; the implicit construction are lacking: But results in the other direction blocks of zeros.
Cameron: Portrait of a typical sum-free set
28
Problem
(i)
Is it true zero
(ii)
Prove
An affirmative
more
interesting.
next
chapter
about
general
obvious
way.
members
of which
is true
of 3Pf).
of 2N
+1
of this
For
function
surely bounded
density
give
upper
of n,
bounds
Proposition
3.6.
density
at most
Proof.
By the
then
from
on
is not
zero.
provide
is much
typical.
this
The
section
has
However,
function the
0.
lower
In some
by Roth’s union
that
4;
it is an
e,(n)
density cases,
easy
as
this
and, all members
exercise
above
Sf,
sets
member
set
of members such
X, all
of the power
almost
is bounded
set
theorem,
a random
in the first
density
of the
in the most
a perfect
(disjoint)
checked
a version
generalise
(In fact,
the
surely %.
to which
to define
6/, of lying
expansion
away
space
of introduction,
It cannot
It is easily
have
if the
that,
also
of Schur’s
Sf as measure
extent
it is easy
consider
almost
show
of
By way
is the
density
this,
set
linear
example,
Also,
the second
and would
version
sf-universality
holds.
probability
on
(i),
Measure
to this.
Numbers
have
set has
any sf-universal
considerations.
and of 4N.
conditional
density
1.
question
Law of Large
settle
the structure
is devoted
that
of a "density"
In particular,
A natural Strong
lack
in Section
Generalities
some
in Sf with
zero.
(ii) would
the
By contrast,
contains
of sequences
the conjecture
density
to
for
discussed
3.3
has
answer
replacement
theorem,
the set
or refute
sequence
some
that
is residual?
of
to
by a
of X is almost one
can
also
density
A random
member
of Sf almost
surely
has
upper
yd
Strong
Law,
given
€ \ 0, at
least
1 - € of the
inputs
large
length
n have between
(4 - €)n and(% + €)n ones,
the first
which
occurs
not
position
with
later
than
€n.
But
an
input
this
of
of
29
Cameron: Portrait of a typical sum-free set
property bits
generates
of input
position
output
output
copied
m, then
x + m, where
the
an
are
at least
the
most
It
a
at least
output,
and
(9/2 -
if the
have
has
in position
x.
-
2€), and
the
to
prove
a one
(% + €)/(°/2
2€)n;
first
(% - €)n - m positions
output
is at
of length
to the
for
one
the
n
occurs
in
density
of
the form
Thus
the
limit
superior
is at
most 1/3. Odd
and
Fib
elaborate
The
following
result.
Theorem
4.1.
entirely
specific
...
method given
bounds
that
probability can
3[%n] terms.
This
« 33; it turns Py
to
is given
of proof
- P can
paragraph,
giving
consists
set
sum-free
upper
obvious
that
bound
of Sf satisfying Py
from
s(2i)
a
of the
closed
this condition.
smaller
of py;
= 0 for all i 2k, A; C S,1 2. By using a ramification
system
we obtained
(r—1)-times iterated exponential.
an upper
bound
for f (n;k,r)
as an
In fact we proved
f (nsksr)'™ < k®
ae
r-1.
Hajnal, Rado and I [XII] later showed that in fact f (n;k,r) is greater than an
(r—2)-times iterated exponential. exponential gives the correct bound.
It seems likely that the (r—1)-times iterated Let us restrict ourselves for the moment to
r = 3. The probability method gives without any difficulty
f (52,3) > 26"
(8)
and Hajnal proved more than 20 years ago that (see [XVIII]
f (n;4,3) > 2¢°2”
(9)
63
Erdés: My joint work with Richard Rado
Hajnal and I have a slightly better upper bound then (8) for f (m;3,3). Probably
f (n;2,2) > 2?"
(10)
but, unfortunately, on this no progress has been made.
This is one of the outstanding open problems of the subject.
I offer 500 pounds
If (10) holds then it would follow from our
for a proof or disproof of (10).
methods that f (n;k,r) increases as an (r—1)-times iterated exponential. Hajnal and I have a forthcoming new paper on f (n;k, 3) which will show that
in many ways f (n;k,3) behaves differently then f (m;k,2) which perhaps will further increase the interest in the fundamental conjecture (10). In [III] we give the first non-trivial lower bound for the van der Waerden
function W(n).
W(n) is the smallest integer for which if we divide the integers
an not exceeding W(n) into two classes then at least one of the classes contains
arithmetic
progression
of m terms.
The
only known
increases as fast as Ackermann’s function.
upper
bound
for W(n)
We easily showed by the probability
method that
W(n) > 2"? This was
improved
by Wolfgang
Schmidt
to W(n) > gito())n | Berlekamp
[3] showed that if n =p is a prime then W(p+1) > p2?. Lovdsz and I noticed c2"/n. that the local Lemma of Lovdsz gives, for every n, W(n) >
In some of my
As far as | papers I somewhat carelessly stated that in fact we get W(n) > c2".
64
Erdés: My joint work with Richard Rado
know it has never been proved (see e.g.,the survey paper of Graham which appears in the same volume as this paper.)
and Rodl
The first task would be to prove
W(n) > c2”
(11)
W(n)/2" — 0
(12)
and then to prove
(11) and (12) will perhaps not be difficult and I offer 25 pounds for a proof.
It
seems very likely that in fact W(n)!“ — , but perhaps the proof will require a significant new idea. For a long time all of us believed that W(n) certainly increases much slower
than Ackermann’s function. doubts about this.
W(n)
is much
The large majority still believes that the order of magnitude of
less than Ackermann’s
Paris and Harrington functions
which
As far as I know Solovay was the first who expressed
showed
increase
much
function.
The very surprising results of
that simple combinatorial
problems
faster than Ackermann’s
function.
can lead to Denote
by
f° (n;k,r) the smallest integer for which if we divide the r-tuples of the integers not
exceeding
f*(n;k,r)
into
k classes
then
there
always
is a
sequence
a, < a2 2r+1
and we also proved that every graph of chromatic
number 2X; contains a k (n;8} but does not have to contain a k &o, Xo) Unfortunately Walter cardinal
Taylor. m
all of us missed the beautiful and fundamental Let G be any graph of chromatic
there is a graph G,, of chromatic
number &:.
number
m
conjecture of
Then for every
for which
all finite
subgraphs of G,, are subgraphs of G too. Hajnal, Shelah and I have a triple paper on this subject where we prove some partial results and recently Hajnal and Komjath [10] have a paper in which they
prove many
further interesting results on finite and denumerable
graphs of chromatic number
subgraphs of
2 &:. In a triple paper of Hajnal, Szemerédi and
myself [11] we prove many interesting theorems and raise many problems which I
- hope will lead to further interesting results. Thus our old paper with Richard leads to many developments and I am sure will continue to do so.
In [XII], many results are proved and very many unsolved problems are posed
but their discussion on the one hand would lead too far into set theory and also a proper discussion of them would need a better knowledge of the many results on undecidable problems with which I am not so well acquainted.
recent Hajnal,
Shelah and many others could do a better job of this than I. Thus I will restrict
74
Erdos: My joint work with Richard Rado
myself to a very small sample.
Hajnal often observed that to prove positive results
in partition calculus we essentially use only two tools. and the canonization Lemma.
The ramification systems
In its most general form the canonization Lemma is
stated in XVIII p. 164 (see also [XII]). This Lemma was one of our most original contributions to set theory and it was very useful in many applications. Shelah has a very significant improvement of our Lemma
for r = 2 (see p. 159 of [XVIII]).
To avoid a complicated formalism we state our Lemma in only a special case: @ be a regular cardinal. of cardinals.
Let
Let Sg, 1 < 6 < wy, be a rapidly increasing sequence
Split the r-tuples of
(J Sg into fewer than w, classes (each r-tuple B 0 and
PG
F C |,| then for n > no(k, t), t
lAl < |,_,|
holds.
To see that the inequality (1) is best possible, ie., max|F¥| > [z7p consider
82
Frankl: The shifting technique in extremal set theory
the family consisting
all k-subsets
of X which
contain
¢ fixed elements.
For
n < (k—t+1) (t+1) a larger t-intersecting family was constructed in [F1] and [EKR]. (See next page). Denote by mg (k,t) the Jeast integer such that (1) holds. For n < 2k any two k-subsets
have nonempty
intersection,
that is A
is
intersecting; and it was shown in [EKR] that mo (kK, 1) = 2k. Hilton and Milner [HM] proved that for t = 1 and n > 2k the optimal family is unique.
In fact we have ng (k, t) = (k—t+1) (t+1) for all ¢ and k as it was proved for t > 15 in [F1], and for all t by Wilson [W].
Moreover for n > no (k, t) there is
only one optimal family. However, for t 2 2 one may ask, what is the maximum size of a f-intersecting
family
F,
FC
fl for 2k —t
Clearly, s/; is t-intersecting.
n=
One can also check that |.,| = |Ao| = a
15 and 0.8(k —t +1) +1) t, we may assume |4; N Ao| < |B, N Bo|. This implies FEB, NB, and fi, j} M.A; NMAp=. Say j ¢ Ay. Then A; =S;;(B,) = (B, — {j}) U fi). On the other hand A, = B,. Why did we not shift B, when i ¢ B» and j € By?
The
only
possible
|4; 9 A2|=|B,
reason
is
1 B3| >t8
B3 = (B,-— {j}) U {i} € F
Consequently,
It is not hard to see that if we keep on shifting then finally we end up with a stable or shifted family G, ie. S;;(G) = G for all 1 a
k-cascade 2>t DZ.
a;
a
fee é
(where
b
is
understood to be zero for b < 0). We leave the easy proof to the reader.
Theorem 3.2. |F| =m
(Kruskal-Katona
and
Then for all 2,1
3.1)
(3.2)
k
m=
cE +ese
theorem) a; +
t
Suppose
¥
is a family
is the k-cascade
of k-sets,
representation
of m.
|0e(Ak, m))| .
Because of the k-cascade representation, Theorem 3.2 is often clumsy for applications. Lovdsz proposed the following weaker, but handier version. Recall that
A
x(x —1)-..:G-a+t+1)
k is
i} Then for all 1 < @ < k one has
(3.3)
x hae
|, (F)| 2
Following [F2] we give a unified argument yielding both results.
Proof of Theorems 3.2 and 3.3. First we note that it is sufficient to settle the case £=1
(and
then
iterate
the
result
¢-times)
—
this
is, in fact, trivial
from
: i Proposition 3.1(ii) and the monotonicity of q| for x 2 a, respectively. Our next observation is that for all 1 < i < j one has
HS;(P) C S,;(P) —
a fact which can be proved by a simple but somewhat tedious case by case
analysis. Therefore, in proving (3.1) and (3.3) we may assume that F is stable (i.e., Sij(A) = F for all 1
not
true
|Fo| >
then
contradicting
—']
a feiand (3.4) would imply that if (3.6) were
:
In fact, |F| =
k=1
(3.5).
, so Therefore
that (3.6)
by induction is
true.
|@F| > Ree b¢ —
oF
CF, U {{I}
f-1-
note _ that
UG:G € 9A}. By induction |@F,| > |, _.], and thus
88
Frankl: The shifting technique in extremal set theory
aaa
|aF| >
r—-11
Xe
+
|e—21
x
=
;
[e—1)>
Proving (3.3).
To prove (3.1) we first show that one can assume that
LP plain
(3.7)
(|
a,—1
3
Porsche
lypal
ale
If this were not the case then (3.4) would imply that
(3.8)
a,—1 k
|Fo| >
foes
a;—1 t
+
+ bs
If a; — 1 > t, then we can forget about the +1 in (3.8) and deduce from the induction hypothesis that an
|AFo| >
1
ken
Henk
a,—1
Lathes
lapreay | , contradicting (3.5) .
If a, = ¢ then let s be the largest integer so that a, = s holds,
k
2s 2 t. Then
(3.8) can be rewritten as a,—1
| Fol >
A541) —1
Ey
PRG, Se
Ry
WE 5
From the induction hypothesis we infer that =
|9Fo| >
a,—1
a4,
Baie
es
a,—1
2
PTA
Pag)
S
PM
is—T
as4,—1
LSA i
ay—1 =
—1
s i
+ (+3)
a,—1 +
Crh
+
‘a
:
again in contradiction to (3.5). Therefore we can assume that (3.7) is true. We conclude the proof of (3.1) as that of (3.3), i.e., S laF| > |aF| a,|\F,|. By ar k
the induction hypothesis and (3.7), |@F,| > | beni
a; —
tbo”
|
t—2
|Adding
this inequality to (3.7), (3.1) follows. @
Proposition 3.4. Suppose that F is a family of k sets, |F| =m > 1 and x > kis defined by m =
x kI:
Suppose further that |d,(A)| =
x ce‘l holds for some @,
Frankl: The shifting technique in extremal set theory
Xo
< @
k-1|°
y>x,
then
ahsg|> 2 contradiction.
Theorem 3.3
implies
™ Let us mention
that
recently Furedi-Griggs [FG] and Mérs [M] characterized those triples (m, k, @) for which #@(k, m) is the unique optimal family in the Kruskal-Katona Theorem.
Corollary 3.5. (Sperner [S])
WANA Proof.
>
Suppose
that
@+*xFC
n n es |/ | Aholds with equality if and only if F =
Note that
x
X
|,.
Then
| Al
x
eo) (i=kiMk — 2x —k+@)+..-—k
+1)
is
monotone decreasing and apply Theorem 3.3 together with Proposition 3.4. @ Note that this corollary can be easily proved by a direct double-counting argument, too.
4. SHADOWS OF t-INTERSECTING FAMILIES Xx If one assumes that ¥ C
Katona
theorem
for
| iis t-intersecting then the bound of the Kruskal-
|, F| can
ld,F| > |Al for & < t. Let. us
first consider
beat = ie
o/ =
be improved.
[1,2k —¢]
| :
In particular,
| Clearly
we
shall
so is t-intersecting
show
and
. The next theorem shows that o/ is the “worst example”.
Theorem 4.1 (Katona [Ka2]) Suppose that ¥ is a k-uniform, t-intersecting family. Then forl 1+i holds. value of i for which this holds, ie. IF N[1,t+2j]| i(F) one has |F A [1,1+2i(F)]| =1+i(F).
define
for
[2¢+i+1,n]
ket-i
A€E
F
Fy ={F € F:i(F) =i,
[(2t+i+1,n] = A}. Then we have the partition F=
va
U
U
0
Define pF, ={G U A:G € 0,4}. It is immediate that 0%, C a¢Fz4 holds.
“We claim that for A, A' distinct 0,F%4 N Oe F4, = @. Suppose |A| =k —t —i, |A'|_ =k —t —i',i i — t + 1. Thus to have equality, one
Ae
must have f, = Ofori t
is
equivalent
Thus the Katona Theorem can be restated as follows.
Suppose that
F C 2* satisfies for all F, F' € F,
b |. i=0
and |Al
5
O0 2k there is a unique optimal family in the Erdos-Ko-Rado Theorem, as well.
6. THE HILTON-MILNER THEOREM. As we saw in the preceding section, the Katona Theorem implies the ErdésKo-Rado Theorem together with the uniqueness of the optimal families for n > 2k. Hilton and Milner described the next two optimal families. Define
A=
Clearly,
HO
G=iGE
[1,n]
+H E is
k
intersecting
and
we welU (ak,
NH = @.
Define
also
By : |G 9 [1,3]| > a Note that @ is intersecting, NG = @
and for k =2,
G=
Theorem 6.1.
(Hilton-Milner
intersecting,
6.1)
1eH. Dk+a
H# holds.
n > 2k and
Theorem
NF =.
([HMI))
Suppose
that
¥C
k
is
Then
-1 —k-1 IAI < [oA= i) - fre
Galas
Moreover, equality holds in (6.1) if and only if F is isomorphic to #, or k = 3
and F is isomorphic to G.
The original proof of this theorem
is rather involved.
For other proofs cf.
Mors [M] and Alon [A]. The present proof is due to [FF]. Proof. We start by applying the (i, j)-shift to ¥ Then either Si;(F) satisfies the
assumptions of the theorem or i is contained in every member of S;;(F). In the first case we keep on shifting until, eventually, we obtain a shifted family satisfying the assumptions.
Suppose now that at some point the second possibility occurs.
Without loss of
generality suppose i = 1, j = 2. Since 1 € F for all F € Si;(F), {1, 2} intersects
all members of ¥. Taking
(6.2)
Since
¥ of maximal size we may assume that
(6[12IcGe
few.
xX p
N ¥ = @, we may assume that {1,3,4,..,kK +1} €F
S'\2 we keep applying the (, j)-shift for 3 < i < j
O with IF N[1,ri + £]| > & —1)i + 4. Clearly, (7) >0. In the geometric
language, @ is the largest integer such that no walk w(F), F € F, lies entirely under the line y = (r — 1)x + @. The next proposition extends Proposition 7.2 in another way.
100
Frankl: The shifting technique in extremal set theory
Proposition 8.3. Suppose intersecting. Then
(8.5) Proof.
that
F,, ...,
F C 2* are
MF,) + +--+ +F,) Set dj =\(¥F;).
By stability for
stable
101
and
cross-wise
t-
2B rt holds. 1 [@ apr] holds
In view of Proposition 8.1 we can choose ¢ 2 0 such that
(8.7)
Dil zl— Fl ZI-Fl>° yp [@-rr] >e- Br. 1t+2s—3]A|.
o
Theorem 9.4. The following equality and inequality hold.
(9.3)
fm, 3,t) =2""
for i 2, n > 2s and
Then
- |
if and only if either xX ) :G
on
G =
rf
| | for some
for some Z €
xX Poet
Proof (Akiyama-Frankl [AF]). In proving (10.1) we may suppose again that @ is stable. Since Y contains subsets is not in G.
no s pairwise disjoint edges, one of the following s
G; = {i, 2 +1-i},
i=1,..,5.
However, if G; ¢ G, then the stability of G implies
xX
:-GN[1,i-1]#@
orG C [1,25 —i}}
Note that actually G; contains no s pairwise disjoint edges. from
gmax IG:l=19,|
Now
(10.1) follows
or |g,|
and equality holds only if
G=G,
or
G=@G,.
Finally, note that if @ contains no s pairwise disjoint edges and Sij(F) isomorphic to Gy for some 1 < ¢ < 5, then @ is isomorphic to Gy as well. @ The families corresponding to G, and @, for k-graphs with k > 3 are:
n= fre
xX
k :Fn
peel
ie-ile oland F,= |
is
Frankl: The shifting technique in extremal set theory
x K\>”
Conjecture 10.2 (Erdos [E]) Suppose that ¥ C
105
> ks and ¥ contains no
S pairwise disjoint sets. Then
(10.2)
|F| < max | 4~
—
" ih
1
=
ks — 1 k
Erdos [E] proved this conjecture for n > ng(k,s).
‘holds .
The bounds on no(k, s)
were improved by Bollobds, Daykin and Erdés [BDS] who showed that (10.2) holds for n > 2k3s. Firedi and the author (unpublished) proved (10.2) for
n > 100ks”, but to prove (10.2) in full generality appears to be a very difficult problem.
Let us prove an upper bound, which is not too far from (10.2) and holds for all n2ks. Theorem 10.3.
Suppose that
¥ C
xX k\> ” 2 ks and ¥ contains no s pairwise
disjoint edges. Then
-1 lIFl < (s-1) a
(10.3) Proof.
holds.
Note that for s = 2, (10.3) reduces to the Erdés-Ko-Rado Theorem.
fact, our proof will be similar to that.
First we prove (10.3) for n =ks.
ema O Gs Ul yer UNG. be an arbitrary IG;| = --- =|G,| =k. Out of these s sets at most Averaging over all partitions gives
eel]
In
Let
partition with s—1 can be in F.
Now we apply induction on 71 and prove the statement simultaneously for all k with ks < n.
Again, we may assume that ¥ is stable. Consider F(n) = {F € ¥:n ¢ F} and An) = {F— {n}:n € F € F. We claim that neither of them contains s pairwise disjoint sets. Indeed, this is trivial for F(n) C F. As to F(n), note that if H,,...,H, € Alm)
are pee
disjoint then choosing s distinct elements
n—s(k—-1) 25, DP avycetsse “from [1.n]—(H, U --- U A,), which has size the stability of F implies F; = (H; U aN € ¥. However, Fj, ..., F, are pairwise disjoint, a contradiction. Now using the induction hypothesis we infer that
)| < oo) + |F)| |F| =|Fa
als
1)
Frankl: The shifting technique in extremal set theory
106
11. ON r-WISE INTERSECTING FAMILIES Recall that
F C 2% is called r-wise intersecting if
for all Fy,...,F,€F F,
++:
F, N --:
N F, # @ holds
If |F,| + --- +|F,| > @—1)n,
then necessarily
1 F, # @ holds.
This shows that the assumptions of the next result
are necessary.
Theorem 11.1
([F8])
rk < (r —1)n.
Then
Suppose
that
xX k
FC
is
r-wise
intersecting,
-1 IF < lea
(11.1) Moreover,
F={FE
excepting
the case r= 2, n = 2k equality
holds
if and
only if
be € X} holds for some x € X.
Neither the original nor the present proof uses shifting. However, the present proof uses the Kruskal-Katona Theorem, which we proved by shifting. First we prove a proposition which is due to Kleitman. Proposition
11.2
(IKL)
Suppose
_ that
xX
FC
A;
Fe dines
T
Nara cine ate al so
F, U-+::
If
(11.2) Moreover,
X=G,U
are
no
n
IlFil/|,| ,..., A, are events in a probability space having dependence graph I’, and there exist positive y;, y2,..., y, satisfying
logy;
>
>
yjPr(A;) + y,Pr(A,)
jer
for 1
ck?/(log k)? for a suitable c > 0. The following result gives the sharpest known bound currently known.
Theorem 2.4 (Sp77]
(2.3)
r(k, 3) 2
ees (1) |x0og k)?. 7
Proof: The proof is a modification of that of Spencer [Sp77]. Let the edges of K, be independently 2-colored red and blue with the probability that an edge is colored red always being p. To each 3element subset of vertices S associate the event As that all the edges spanned by S have been colored red. Similarly, to each k-element subset K associate the event Bx that all the edges
spanned by K have been colored blue. Observe that
r(k,3) >n if Pr(Q) As N (1) Bx) > 0. Ss
K
Let I’ denote the graph with [i] ar (7] vertices corresponding to all possible As and Bx, where
{As, Bx} is an edge of I if and only if |SNK| > 2 (i.e., the events Ay and Bx are dependent), and the same applies to pairs of the form {As, As} and {Bx, Bx}. Let N44 denote the number of vertices
of the form As for some S joined to some other vertex of this form (so that Naa = 3(n — 2)), and let Nag, Ng4 and Ngg be defined analogously. In this case, Corollary 2.3 implies:
If there exist positive p, y, z such that:
113
Graham & R6édl: Numbers in Ramsey theory
114
p yPr(As)(Na4 + 1) + zPr(Bx) Nap , log z > yPr(As)Npga + zPr (Bx) (Nop + 1)
then r(k,3) >n. Now, k
Pr(As) =
p>, Pr(Bx) = (1 — p) f) < exp |-o(8]
Also, we have the bounds
n < ne Nan< (f} [2]met < neel, k
k
Naa+1 0 and k sufficiently large. 2.2 Constructive lower bounds
In the preceding sections, all of the bounds given were based on the use of the probability method. As a consequence, the proofs do not produce any explicit colorings but rather, they only prove that such colorings exist. To remedy this not entirely satisfactory state of affairs, attempts have been made over the years to construct good colorings, unfortunately without much success. For
the case of r(k, 3), Erdés [E66] has given a construction which shows that rk, a)"> Kato)
where
Sawer log 2 af ar metas | 13139 eels improving an breakthrough Frankl [F77], this section,
earlier construction of his which gave a somewhat weaker result (cf. [E57]). A for r(k,k) finally occurred several years ago, however, with the result of who gave the first Ramsey construction which grew faster than any polynomial. In we will outline a more recent theorem of Frankl and Wilson [FW81] on set
intersections which yields the best constructive bound for r(k, k) currently available.
Theorem 2.7 [FW81] Suppose Fis a family of k-sets of {1, 2,...,m} such that for some prime power q,
115
Graham & R6édl: Numbers in Ramsey theory
F,F'€ FEF #F'
116
> |FNF'| #k (modq).
Then
(2.10) Proof:
lA < (,"4}Let A;, Az... Ain) be all the j-element subsets and B;, B>,...,B (")be all the i-element Jj
I
subsets of {1,2,...,n}, where i < j. Define the ("| by ("] matrix N(@, j) as follows:
(u, v)-entry of N(ji,j) is 1 if B, C A,, and Oif B, ¢ A,, forl 0. Further, f satisfies
fd) + d* -— d)f'(d) . Therefore,
1+ (mi -—d,-Df@)
21+ M-d,-
21+(M—d,-—
Df)
+ @—-d,- 1)’ - a)f'(d)
If (ad) + dd, +d — 2d,d,)f'(d)
2 (n — d, — 1)f (da) + (a, + 1)f d)
by (2.18)
= nf (d) .
Thus, a 2 nf (d) as required, and the theorem is proved. @ As an immediate consequence, we have: Theorem 2.10
(2.19)
r(k, 3) < k?/log (k/e) .
Proof. Let G be a triangle-free graph on n vertices and suppose a(G) < k. Since the neighbors of any vertex v form an independent set then we must have degree (v) < k. Thus, the average degree
d in G is at most kK. Therefore, by (2.16)
(2.20)
k > alG) 2 nf d) 2 nf (k).
Hence, if n > k/f(k) then G must contain an independent set of size k + 1. This implies
(2.21)
Rk + 1,3)
n/(100d log d) for any triangle-free graph G with n vertices and average degree d. If 3 is replaced by an arbitrary but fixed value ?, then the best bound on r(k, @) is given by the following result of Ajtai, Komlds and Szemerédi:
Theorem 2.11 [AKS80]
(2.22)
r(k, £) < (5000)%k*'/(log k)*-?
for k sufficiently large (depending on ¢).
Graham & R6dl: Numbers in Ramsey theory
120
It will be convenient for the next result to define the related quantity r°(k, @), the largest value of n such that there is a red-blue coloring of the edges of K, having no red K;, and no blue Ky. Thus,
rik O=r(kK+1,2@+0)—-1. For arbitrary k and @ (not satisfying k >> ¢ required by Theorem 2.11), the best current upper bound is given by a recent result of the second author:
Theorem 2.12 [R]
(2.23)
rk, O 0.
Because of space limitations, we will not give the proof of (2.23). method used in proving it by proving the following weaker result.
Rather, we will illustrate the
Theorem 2.14
(2.25)
r(k, 2) @+a-p [7]-ea-p (2). Let d,, dz, ...,dy be the degrees of the vertices of G. Then
7G) + 7G) = [5-5 Bea, - vay - (5) - 3Be
Da - ap
> + (n(n — 1)(n — 2) — 36n(n — 1)?+36°n(n — 1)2)
- @
+0 -—) [%]-sa-a) [R}. =
Graham & Rédl: Numbers in Ramsey theory
121
Lemma 2.16 Suppose m and n satisfy m > e2n > 0. Then
(2.27)
r°(m,n) EA" s(s — 1)
te
s-1
jem,
1+ «| Pe jromn). sj s-—1
Proof: Set N: = r*(m, n) and let Ky be 2-colored so that no red K+, and no blue K,4; is formed. Let d,” denote the number of red edges incident to the ith vertex of Ky, with d,” denoting the analogous quantity for the blue edges.
If d;” > = 1+ + N for some i, then by considering the
“red” neighbors of this vertex we get (i). Similarly, if d,{“) > e 1+ feN then (ii) must hold. Hence, we can assume that
d?
B= Hli+E|[r+—ti}y
we
now
indicate
how
to
do.
First,
observe
that
by
(2652)
N ted @= - 26()]> 22m_ - ent S}-y so
that
(2.35) Thus
B >
it will
(2.36) |B o
be
enough
to
show
that
egen + © - 2 - 1)/ (i-1)
>
sept eeeler ar
for N> 16s? We will not carry out all the details of this computation, relatively straight forward (but unenlightening).The basic that the important term of (2.36) is
(2.37)
[2 r 8 s
which
can
(2.38)
be
y mec)
“sg?
In
turn
the
(2.39)
by the The
main
e7]
s(s-1)
definition
value
assigned
of to
s-1
€ a cet
¥ 1.) (< ms =i
n? st
m(m-1) }} s*(s-1)2
contribution
m2 —m(n-1)
s*
s
as
m2 m(m-1) iS = gla-t)
+
are is
1+ £|ie+ =
s(s-1)
rewritten
which point
_*
to
(2.38)
ut) a(n-1)]
turns
out
to
be
an
87(s-1)
s. € now
guarantees
(2.36), and
therefore
(2.34), holds.
124
Graham & R6dl: Numbers in Ramsey theory
The
case
that
way (using the to yield (iv). We
need
there
are
B blue
trinagles-:follows
in
exactly
symmetry of 8 and 1 - 8 in the expressions This completes the proof of Lemma 2.17.
one final
observation
before
proceeding
to
the
proof
Fact.
= he aS : i=r+1
(2.40)
Proof:
The
n
n 2 1/i
Siok i=
>log
m=k,
+ 1)
r WG
=log(s
Set
log(n
Consequently
s
HAN i=r+1
Proof of Theorem We will consider
-
“
i=i
increasing.
s
1.
s + 2 ie Gweall
sequence
a_=
is monotone
Sy wilioyee
coe oh wael =
+ 1) + es
Siiet naar
log(r
t=k+2&
*
i]
a
al EL
2.14. Let G be a graph with the following algorithm.
n=,
+ 1) -
and
log t Co|log
log t
ang
F
the
same
involved)
r*(k, 2) vertices.
of
(2.25).
Graham & Rédl: Numbers in Ramsey theory
2.
3.
If max{m/n, n/m} > x then halt; otherwise go to 3. Ifr‘G@n, n) < 16(m +n)? then halt; otherwise go to 4.
4.
Select a pair (m*,n*)
m'+n*=m+n—-—1 m=m’',n
for which
or
125
one of the possibilities of Lemma
m+n—2.)
2.17 occurs.
(Thus,
Let G* be a graph with r°(m'‘, n°) vertices.
=n’, G =G‘ and go to 2.
Set
Suppose now that the algorithm halts at some graph G’ of size r* (k', é’). Let t': = k'+ @' and
p=t-—t'. of e=
Note that if y: = dog lent then at each pass through step 4 of the algorithm, the value fon
min(m, n) 8Gn + a)
satisfies
ea (2.41)
Bi
:
8(m +n)
> 8(1 + m/n) 1 > ———
80x)
2
=).
Hence, by the time we have reached G’, we have (by Lemma 2.17) accumulated the “gain factors” to obtain the estimate
epee
ele
(2.42)
py
ke
Ue
aoa Tiel Ta
+ 2)
GAG
(EE
IS
+ 2). (ser)
Gee
y
Derr rr
2
Lee
ke
r°(k, @)
= a! 1+ oe r(k, @).
We now consider several cases, depending on how soon the algorithm halts, and why.
Case 1. t'> Vt +2. Subcase (a). r°(k', 2.) < 16 t ?. Since ¢ is large then so is t’. Thus, by (2.7) we must have min(k', 2’) = 2, say (by symmetry) é'=2.
Thus,
r(k', 2) =r°(k', 2) < (k'+ 1)*/logtk'+ 1)/e) (2.43)
< (k' + 1)?fog(Vt /e) = 2(k' + 1)?flog(t/e”) .
Therefore, by (2.42)
.
rk,
be
eee
t e< (+3) r°(k',£') 2
(2.44)
fort = k + @ large.
li) < —— “4 nip
. 2(k + 1)?
log (t /e?)
s|k+é | |og(k + £)
Graham & R6dl: Numbers in Ramsey theory
1 ee logt Ip! > x Sor Leer ORE Subcase (b). k'/£'
126
ie
Thus, by Lemma 2.16,
re’, e) (26 + p — 48"!
(where m-+> (k) indicates that m —>
(k) does not hold).
This together with Theorem 4.2
implies Theorem 4.4 For p 2 3,
(4.5)
Logy-2(rp(é)) > cp'é? .
The asymptotic behavior of r,(¢) is not known for p 2 3. However, because of the SteppingUp Lemma, any improvement on the lower bound of r3(¢) would yield a corresponding improvement on the lower bounds for r,(¢), p > 3. The major open problem here (and indeed, one of the main unsolved problems in Ramsey theory) is the determination of the order of growth of r3(é). P. Erdés is currently offering $500 for an answer to the following problem. Problem 4.5.
Is there an absolute constant
(4.6)
c > 0 such that
loglogr3(¢) > cé ?
It is interesting to note that if four colors are allowed (rather than two), then the analogue to (4.6) is valid, i.e.,
(4.7)
loglogr3(¢,4) > cé.
This is a consequence of the next result.
Theorem 4.5 (Hajnal; cf. [EHMR84], Th. 26.3)
If n-+> (2)3 then 2"-+> (¢ + 12. Proof: Let [n]?=C, U C2 be a 2-coloring with no monochromatic ¢-set, and let < be the lexicographic order on An), the power set of [n], given by: a, < az iff max(a; — (a, Nay) < max(az — (a, Na,)) . For a, ¥ a2 € An), we also define
8(a,,a2) = max{i: i € (a; — a2) U (a, —a))}.
For a1,a2,a;
€ An) with a; < az < a;, let 6; = 6(a,,a) ’ 62 = 5(a,a3)
Finally, set
.
Graham & R6édl: Numbers in Ramsey theory
{a),a>,a3}
E Sy iff {5,55}
136
€ Ci and 6;
62, {a},a,a3}
€ S3 iff {5,59} € Cz and 6; < 6,
{a},a2,a3}
€ S4 iff {5,55} € C2 and 6; >
6.
Suppose now that there is a family ¥ € An), |X| = ¢ + 1, which is monochromatic. [X}? C S, (the other three cases are similar). Write X= and let 6;: a
5(a;,a;+1),
{a),a>, wien e +4ea1},
1 < i < £.
Fori
ay,
S(é,m +1). For a fixed r, let M'=N(é,1,7™) and suppose x: [MM"]—>TIr] is given. Define the
x': [M'] —>
I[r™] s0 that x(k) =x'(k')
By the induction
x €[0, 2-1].
M=N(Z, m,r), induced coloring
hypothesis,
if x(kKM — j) =x(k'M -j) there
exist a’ and d’ such
for
O< jf 1 +> S(€+1,1).
For a fixed r, let x: [2N(¢,r,7r)] —>
Ir] be
arbitrarily given. Thus, there exist a, d,,...,d, such that for x; € [0, 2], a + > x;d; is bounded r
above by N(¢,r,r) and x(a + > x;d;) is constant on ¢-equivalence classes. i=l
i=l By the pigeon-hole
principle there exist u, v € [0, 7] with u < v such that
x(a + > fd;) =x(a + > d;) . i=l i=l Therefore,
x(a + Sed +10 SD d)) i=t
imutl
is constant for ¢ € [0, 2]. This proves S(¢ + 1, 1). Since S(1, 1) clearly is true then the theorem holds by induction.
&
Of course, Theorem 6.1 is the special case m = 1 in Theorem 6.2.
The upper bound on W(k,r) resulting from this proof is quite large.
Essentially, it is given
inductively by a function in two variables, and grows like the Ackermann function (cf. [Sp83]). In fact, no proof is known which yields an upper bound on W(k, r) which is even primitive recursive!
The same also applies to the special case W(k): = W(k, 2).
On the other hand, the strongest lower bounds for W(k) are much more modest, namely, just exponential in k (cf. Theorems 6.3, 6.4). What the truth really is here represents a central open question in this whole area.
Theorem 6.3 [Ber68] If p is prime, then
(6.1) Proof:
Wep+l1)>p-2. For simplicity, we only prove a slightly weaker result:
(6.2)
W(p +1) > p(2? - 1).
Let GF (2?) denote the finite field with 2? elements, and fix a primitive element a € GF (27). Let V1, +++» Vp bea basis for GF (2?) over GF (2). For any integer j, set a
=
41jV1 + arjvo t+. oe + apjVp
»
ay € GF (2) ‘
Graham & Rédl: Numbers in Ramsey theory
143
Let
Com (ji: aj =0,
1 x; (2d + 1)', 0 < x; < d, which are all at most n. i
There are essentially n2~* such integers.
Thus, for some s
n v3(n) > |Xn.a.s| > Fak Setting d = exp(vViog n) we deduce \Xn,d,s| 2 1 exp(—c Vlog n) for some c > 0, as required.
Instead of the upper bound in (6.8), we only show here that v3(n) = o(n). There are other relatively simple proofs of this fact (cf. [RS78], [G81]). The proof give here, based on ideas of Ruzsa and Szemerédi, is taken from [EFR86]. Theorem 6.7
(6.9) Proof:
v3(n) =o(n). Let G = (V, E) denote a graph and let A, B C V be a pair of disjoint non-empty subsets
of V. The density of the pair (A, B) is defined to be the ratio
d(A, B): = e(A, B)/|A||B| where e(A, B) denotes the number of edges {a, b} with a € A, b €B. The pair (A, B) is called e-uniform if for all A' © A, B' © B with |A'| > «|A|, |B'| > «|B| we have
|d(4', B') —d(A, B)| ,A,;#’,v)-Family.
Since
there
+
this
is a
cardinal
contradicts
# cf,
< \} and
it
follows
almost
2"
P is directed
is
a
disjoint axioms
we give
if there
1.2}
false,
there
is an elewent pair
2” + @_.
is an almost
question
theory.
introduction
be a partially
if every
that
natural
set
with
and
SETS
{#1,@,a)-family.
of
a brief
is consistent
DISOINT
(Corollary
that both the Sxistence,
ordered
r € P such of elements
to
This
To discuss to Martin's
set.
that
Two
ask
disjoint
is
turns
whether
out
this,
to be
and
axiom.
elements
P,q
Psranqir.
in P are
some
compatible.
eP
Whe The
Milner & Prikry: Almost disjoint sets partial
order
elements
is
a
ccc
if
on
the
a set
MA(x)
is
a
It
is easily
family
However,
“countable
size
of
MA(w)
is
axioms
of
ZF,
it
However,
it
the
order
to
appiy
principle
with
In fact
it
not
of fewer Clearly
does
is equivalent
CH
fundamental
as
MA,
an
result
A
and
subset
FnG
? is a CCC
partially
of
there
?,
then
D
but
it
¢ P
is
subsets of
¥ @ for every ordered
an
is
(G can be chosen
quite
same
set
F €
and
¥
set.
f-generic
to be an w-chain).
so MA(k) implies x ¢
naturally
turns
to
algebra,
the
many
the
of SOLOVAY
dense
out
CH,
appeal
the
to be
theory
sets
of of
other
forcing.
forcing
in
combinatorial
and
set
point
open
a compact
sets
(see e.g.
is
KUNEN
of
MA
is
which
is
important
% TENNENBAUM
the
a poverful
assertion:
disjoint
as
context
the
analysis
usefulness to
in
with
topological
nowhere
alternative
intuitive
familiar
which
to
but
the
to be
uncountably
2° closed
implies
employed
have
arise
axiom,
containing
incompatible
is true for every x, w < « ¢ 2°,
applications
than
if G is directed
is true
not
necessary
the
of
condition",
statement
does
is not
sets).
(see e.g. KUNEN [1980],p.54),
MA: MA(x) axiom
set
chain
If F is a family of cofinal
subsets
axiom
this
< d.
¢ x cofinal
that
unebuntable
incompatible
whenever
seen
Martin’s
for
assertion:
MA(2°) is false
Although
be
nod
stands
G C P F-generic
the
of
is
Space
P Banta lee
in P if (vpeP)(SdeD)p
P, we call
rs
is
historically
condition
cofinal a
?
(CCC
161
that
[1971]:
it
It
not
topology.
Hausdorff the
union
[1980],p. can in
65).
frequently view
of
is consistent
the
that
MA holds and 2”)0,. Many
For
example
TENNENBAUN
outstanding
MA(#,)
[1971],
problems
can
implies
the
easily
see also KUNEN
“more concerned
with
the
in particular
with
the way MA
subsets
of x (( a) by subsets
in MARTIN & SOLOVAY immediate
interplay
consequence
[1970] of
the
[1980], between
is used
be
settled
Suslin
p74}. MA and
of w (a technique
following
important
the
hypothesis
However, almost
(see Theorem
and JENSEN & SOLOVAY
with
aid
of
MA.
(SOLOVAY
&
here we shall be
disjoint
2.4 below)
families
,
to encode
due to Solovay described [1970]}.
This
will
be an
result.
If A, B ¢ P(w) are such that |4u2| < « and Assume MA(k). THEOREM 2.1. JB \ ua’| = @ whenever B € B and A’ is a finite subset of A, then there is set a
€ &.
C € w such that
CoA is finite and CoB is infinite
for all AE
A and B
Milner & Prikry: Almost disjoint sets
PROOF.
Let
=
(P,)
be
the
partial
162
order
on
the
set
P of
(s,F), where s€ [a], F € [a] and (s1,F,) < (S2,F2) F, and UFjns, in P if and
© 5,.
only
Note
that
(sus’,fuF’)
subset
which
first
the
same
For A € A,
let
Ban = {(5,F):
each which
has
holds
with
a
=
that
CnB
is
immediately is,
is
(5’,F’}
€ 5,
compatible
and
the
MA
are
with
for
all
€ G
is
n € a,
that each D, and
sets.
For,if
is
compatible.
a directed
these
A
compatible
is finite.
(s,F’)
B € & and
to check
there
F}.
so AnC
therefore
and
is easy
(s,F) and
set,
The
theorem
€ A,
there
with
(s,F),
If BE
&,
G,
is
then,
it for
and so CoB \ n 2? snB\n # @, and
oO
2.1
More
2.2.
are
? is clearly CCC since
two elements
AEF},
some
€ GE, has
mwany
question
consistent
(#,,,0)-family. THEOREM
any
is infinite.
ansvers it
are
by MA(x)
for
(s,F)
Theorem
that
(s’,F’})
extension.
It
so
intersection
€ UFns’
any n € w, there therefore
51 © S25 Fi ©
€ gs’,
and which
(s,F)€G
since
Ans’
UF'’ns
Da = {(s,F):
\ n # 9}.
U{s:
(s,F) € GoD, and, follows
component,
in P and
non-enpty
C
and
of ? there
let
soB
aoe is cofinal
Cs
is a common
in any uncountable have
{s,F),
pairs
if UFns'
in which case
two elements
all
applications.
raised
that
at
there
the
is
For
beginning
no
example,
of
this
it
section
maximal
almmst
disjoint
maximal
almost
disjoint
generally,
implies
that
there
is
no
(x,w,w)-family for w < x ¢ 2", PROOF.
Given
an
alwost
{with B = {w}), there
AEA.
is an infinite
(x,w,w)-family
,A,
set C C w almost
by
Theorem
disjoint
2.1
from each
o We
also
disjoint
should
consistent
Waximeal
mention
that:
almost
for
disjoint
that,
each
in
contrast
cardinal
(x,w,w)-family
x
-
to
Theorem
(w,< x
see
the
¢
2.2,
2”)
rewark
it
there
is
is
following
a
3.6
below. We
subsets
Obviously, length THEOREM
shall
A,B of there
w,. 2.3.
o,
use
write is no
However, MA
the
APB
following
consequence
if A \ B is
strictly
decreasing
infinite sequence
of
Theorem
and of
2.1.
For
B \ A is finite. subsets
of
w
of
... implies
subsets of w of length 2°.
that
there
is
a
bh-decreasing
sequence
of
Milner & Prikry: Almost disjoint sets PROOF.
Let
that
as,
Aa}
and
a
¢ 2” and
holds
B =
for
{Ag
a.
B
*
~
" a
'
a
‘
-
‘
4
’
-
— a)
=
a*
ie
ry
=
.
cae 7 »
-_
i
-
> = -
a
aaah
> >
-
the
’
-
-
THE METRIC STRUCTURE
OF GRAPHS: Theory and Applications
Peter Winkler Emory University, Atlanta, Georgia 30322 U.S.A.
Abstract. The "path metric" on the vertices of a connected graph G is given by defining the distance between two vertices u and v to be the minimum over all paths P from u to v of the number of edges in P. Over the past 20 years a structure theory has emerged whose
aim is to simplify the path metric by means of isometric embedding in cartesian products of graphs. Although the theory is peculiar to graphs, it looks like a typical algebraic structure theory and the analog of representation by subdirect products works out nicely. Development of the theory was motivated by a problem from computer science and has contributed to the solution of several others. These problems, which arise in complexity theory, network design and data structures, will be described briefly and their connections with the structure theory explained.
Introduction
The general aim of a structure theory is to break down a complex object into simpler components, the object in this case being the path metric on a graph. The approach taken is a familiar one to algebraists, namely representation by embedding
in a product; it turns out that this
approach works quite well here, despite the apparent absence of category-theoretic underpinnings. There are a variety of applications of the structure theory to computer science, some of which
will be briefly presented below. By a graph G = we shall mean a finite set V(G) of vertices together with a
collection E(G) of unordered pairs of vertices called edges, that is, a finite, simple graph. For definition of basic terms such as "path" or “connected” the reader is referred to any elementary text on graph theory or combinatorics.
The distance dg(u,v) between two vertices of a con-
nected graph G is defined to be the number of edges in a shortest path from u to v; the resulting "path metric” turns V(G) into a metric space. is a map a: V(G)—V(H)
An isometric embedding of G in another graph H
such that dy (o(u),a(v)) = dg(u,v) for all vertices u and v of G; the
image of G is then a subgraph of H isomorphic to G.
198
Winkler: The metric structure of graphs
The Cartesian Product
There are at least three natural graph products definable on the cross product of the vertex sets of two graphs; a clever notation scheme due to J. Nesetrtil assigns a symbol to each which looks like the corresponding product of two edges. Although the "weak product” (denoted by x)
and the "strong product" (@) are universal products in the category of graphs (as non-reflexive and reflexive relational structures, respectively), the "cartesian" product (C1) has turned out to be extremely versatile and is the product of choice in metric theory, for reasons which will become plain. The cartesian product GOH
of graphs G and H is defined as follows. The vertices of
GOH
are ordered pairs (g,h) with geV(G)
GOH
iff either {g,g’} is an edge of G and h=h’, or {h,h'} is an edge ofH and g=g’. It
is
easily
seen
that
the
and heV(H), and {(g,h),(g’,h’)} is an edge of
cartesian
product
{(1,82 --- »8k)(81.82)---»8e’)} is an edge of GAGA
is
associative
and _ that
-- - OG, just when {g;,g;"} is an
edge of G; for some i and g;=g;’ for all 7, in which case we say that the edge "belongs to the ith factor." Note that the product of k copies of K2, which we denote by K§, is just the "Boolean k-cube,” i.e. the graph given by the vertices and edges of a (unit) cube in k-space; its metric is of course the k-dimensional Hamming metric. The cartesian product of K3 and the three-point path P; is illustrated in Fig. 1 below. Sabidussi (1960), and later Vizing (1963), showed that the cartesian product enjoys unique
prime factorization for connected graphs.
The proofs were difficult and did not provide an
efficient method for finding the prime factorization---a point which we will address again later. Unique prime factorization fails for disconnected graphs, for which Zaretskii (1965) gave the fol-
lowing example: K}+K7+K}+K2+K>+K, = (K3+K,0O(K3+K2+K) = (K2+K))O(K}+K}+K;)), where "+" denotes disjoint union and all the graphs in parentheses can be shown to be prime. Since each step of a path in a product []G; moves in only one factor, any path in a pro-
duct breaks down into paths in the factors. Thus we have that
Winkler: The metric structure of graphs
199
Oo
eee
©)
3 fe)=4
Fig. |
Winkler: The metric structure of graphs
Are (Sa + - Be)(81's- - - 8k’) = Lido,(81081) It follows that if G is a product of simpler graphs, or if it is an isometric subraph of such a product, then its metric can be broken down into simpler components.
Isometric Embedding in Products
In representing
the metric on a graph G, the best result one can reasonably hope to
encounter is an isometric embedding of G in K*; equivalently, a description of G as a subspace
of Hamming space. Such embeddings were sought by Firsov (1965) for the purpose of investigating "the closeness of various linguistic objects," but only preliminary results were obtained at that
time. In the early ’70’s Graham & Pollak (1971, 1972) highlighted the problem in the process of designing addressing schemes for computer communications networks. Information is sent from
computers in "packets" only microseconds long, and efficiency requires that many of these be on a network simultaneously. Each packet is augmented with the address of its destination, and must somehow find a short route to that destination through the network.
Graham and Pollak’s idea was to represent the network by a graph and provide addresses for the vertices in such a way that the distance between two vertices (number of edges in a shortest path) can be easily recovered by comparing their addresses. Then when a packet reaches a
vertex it can compare its destination address with the local address, discovering, ~~ that it is presently at distance k from its destination. It then checks the addresses of neighboring vertices until it finds one at distance only k—1 from the destination, and moves there. Thus using local information only, it finds a shortest path to its destination.
The most obvious way to realize Graham and Pollak’s objective is to address the vertices by binary strings whose Hamming distances match the graph distances; that is, to embed the
graph isometrically in a Boolean cube. Unfortunately, as noted already by Firsov, there are graphs which are resistant to such embeddings even when made bipartite by edge-subdivision. Graham
200
Winkler: The metric structure of graphs and Pollak then turned to the addition of a "don’t care" symbol c"*") to the binary strings, whose distances to the other symbols 1 and 0 are both defined to be zero. Even though the space of all such strings (of a given length) is no longer a metric space, the new scheme worked beautifully;
later Winkler (1983) was able to show that any graph on 7 vertices could be addressed by strings
of this sort having length at most n—1. The question of which graphs could be addressed by the {0,1} scheme, however, remained open until Djokovic (1973) gave a complete characterization. If {x,y} is an edge of a connected graph G, let Nxy = {veV(G): dg(v,.x) = dg(v,y}-1}, ie. the set of vertices nearer to x than to y, and xNy = {ve V(G): dg(v,x) = dg(v,y)}. Further, any set S of vertices of G is deemed convex if every shortest path in G between vertices of § is contained completely in the subgraph
induced by S.
Theorem (Djokovic 1973). A connected graph G can be isometrically embedded in a Boolean cube if and only if G is bipartite and for every edge {x,y} of G, both Nxy and Nyx are convex.
We omit the proof of Djokovic’s theorem since it will follow from more general results below.
If more symbols are allowed in the addressing scheme, with the distance between distinct symbols still always 1, then the problem becomes one of embedding G isometrically in some power K* of a complete graph. This also cannot generally be done, as can be seen for example
by examining the complete bipartite graph K2, or the cycle Cs. A polynomial-time characterization of the graphs which can be embedded in a power of a complete graph (equivalently, in a product of complete graphs) was obtained by Winkler (1984), who also made the (then) surprising
observation that all irredundant isometric embeddings of this sort were unique up to symmetries
of the product graph. By 1984 it was beginning to look like some much more general pleasantnesses concerning isometric embedding in products lay behind the previous results. Let us define a metric represen-
tation of a connected graph G to be an isometric embedding of G in a product H,O ::- OW,
201
Winkler: The metric structure of graphs
which is "irredundant" in the following sense: (1) each H; is a connected graph with at least two
vertices, and (2) every vertex of each factor appears as a coordinate in the image of at least one vertex of G. (It is not hard to show that any isometric embedding in a product can be made irredundant by discarding unused vertices and trivial factors.) Two (metric) representations are equivalent if there is a bijection between the factors of one and the factors of the other, together with isomorphisms between corresponding factors for which the obvious diagram commutes. A graph G is said to be irreducible if all of its representations are trivial, that is, equivalent to the identity map from G to itself. All of this is of course a parody, in a sense, of subdirect products in algebra, but as far as we know no algebraic interpretation is available. Nonetheless everything one could hope to be true actually is.
Theorem
(Graham & Winkler (1984,1985)). Every connected graph G has a unique canonical
representation tion
G — G,O :-- OG, in which every factor is irreducible. For any other representa-
G > H,O---OH,,
there is a surjection ¢: {1,...,4} — {1,...m]} between the index sets
and representations H; —-> []{G;: (j)=i} for which everything commutes; that is, the canonical
representation can be factored through any other. Furthermore, the canonical representation of G can be obtained by a polynomial-time algorithm.
Proof: Fix a representation
G + H,O ---OH,
of G and denote by (v;,...,V,_) the image of
a vertex v of G. Let e={x,y} be an edge of G with Nxy, xNy and Nyx (defined above) partitioning V(G). (See Fig. 2.) If e belongs to the ith factor, that is, if x;#y,;, then of course Xj=)j for all j# so for any vertex v,
dg (vx )}-de (vy) = dy. (vii -dy,(¥i,¥i) It follows that the location of v in the above partition depends only on v;. If f ={u,v} is an edge which crosses the partition, e.g. ueNxy and vexNy, then u;#v; and therefore f and e belong to the same factor.
Define the relation 6 on E(G) as follows: if e={x,y} and f ={u,v} are edges then
202
Winkler: The metric structure of graphs
Fig. 2
203
Winkler: The metric structure of graphs
eOf iff d(x,ujtd(y,v)
204
#d(x,v}+d(y,u) .
In that case f indeed crosses the partition induced by e, so e and f belong to the same factor. The relation @ is reflexive and symmetric but not generally transitive; let 6 be its transitive closure. Then e bf again implies that e and f belong to the same factor. If the equivalence classes of 6 in E(G) are E,,E,,...,E, then we already know that m1.
On the other hand, let G be the complete graph on vertices a,b,c,d with the edge {a,d}
Winkler: The metric structure of graphs
removed. If Player I is sitting on vertex b and sees c,a,d,a ,d,...,a,d in the window, he must go to c if the first unseen request is c but Stay at b if that request is a b. Hence this graph has infinite windex. It is not surprising, in view of previous comments, that the property of having windex