Skepticism: From Antiquity to the Present 1472507711, 781472507716

Skepticism: From Antiquity to the Present is an authoritative and up-to-date survey of the entire history of skepticism.

287 78 4MB

English Pages xvi+752 [769] Year 2018

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Table of contents :
General Introduction by Baron Reed and Diego E. Machuca
**PART I: ANCIENT SKEPTICISM**
Introduction by Diego E. Machuca
1. The Cyrenaics and Skepticism by Richard Bett
2. Pyrrho and Timon by Casey Perin
3. Arcesilaus by Anna Maria Ioppolo
4. Carneades by Harald Thorsrud
5. Aenesidemus by Luca Castagnoli
6. Philo of Larissa by Harold Tarrant
7. Cicero by J. P. F. Wynne
8. Menodotus and Medical Empiricism by James Allen
9. Middle Platonism and Skepticism: Plutarch and Favorinus by Carlos Lévy
10. Sextus Empiricus by Tad Brennan and Cliff Roberts
11. Skepticism in Classical Indian Philosophy by Matthew R. Dasti
**PART II: MEDIEVAL AND RENAISSANCE SKEPTICISM**
Introduction by Diego E. Machuca
12. Augustine and Skepticism by Stéphane Marchand
13. John of Salisbury’s Skepticism by David Bloch
14. Skepticism in Classical Islam: The Case of Ghazali by Paul L. Heck
15. Nicholas of Autrecourt and John Buridan on Skepticism by Christophe Grellard
16. Divine Deception by Henrik Lagerlund
17. Michel de Montaigne by Gianni Paganini
18. Pierre Charron by Gianni Paganini
19. Francisco Sanchez: A Renaissance Pyrrhonist against Aristotelian Dogmatism by Damian Caluori
**PART III: MODERN SKEPTICISM**
Introduction by Baron Reed
20. François de La Mothe Le Vayer by Sylvia Giocanti
21. Gassendi on Skepticism by Antonia LoLordo
22. Descartes and the Force of Skepticism by David Cunning
23. Varieties of Modern Academic Skepticism: Pierre-Daniel Huet and Simon Foucher by Michael W. Hickson
24. Spinoza on Skepticism by Alison Peterman
25. Pierre Bayle by John Christian Laursen
26. Berkeley and Skepticism by Margaret Atherton
27. A Pyrrhonian Interpretation of Hume on Assent by Donald L. M. Baxter
28. Thomas Reid’s Engagement with Skeptics and Skepticism by Renévan Woudenberg
29. Johann Georg Hamann by Gwen Griffith-Dickson
30. Kant and External World Skepticism by Georges Dicker
31. Hegel: Philosophy as a Kind of Skepticism by Dietmar H. Heidemann
32. Friedrich Nietzsche by Andreas Urs Sommer
33. Russell’s Logical Construction of the External World by Peter J. Graham
34. Moore and Mooreanism by Annalisa Coliva
35. Wittgenstein and Skepticism: Illusory Doubts by Michael Williams
36. Richard Popkin on the History of Skepticism by José R. Maia Neto
**PART IV: CONTEMPORARY SKEPTICISM**
Introduction by Baron Reed
37. Regress Arguments and Skepticism by Richard Fumerton
38. The Problem of the Criterion by Andrew D. Cling
39. Neo-Pyrrhonism by Markus Lammenranta
40. Disagreement and Skepticism by Bryan Frances
41. Skepticism and the Internalism-Externalism Debate by Matthias Steup
42. Skepticism and Fallibilism by Stephen Hetherington
43. Skepticism and Contextualism by Michael Blome-Tillmann
44. External World Skepticism by Ram Neta
45. Disjunctivism and Skepticism by Duncan Pritchard and Chris Ranalli
46. Inductive Skepticism: A Functional Investigation by Ruth Weintraub
47. Skepticism about A Priori Knowledge by Otávio Bueno
48. Skepticism about Other Minds by Anil Gomes
49. Moral Skepticism by Richard Joyce
50. Religious Skepticism by J. L. Schellenberg
Recommend Papers

Skepticism: From Antiquity to the Present
 1472507711, 781472507716

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

SKEPTICISM

Also available from Bloomsbury The Bloomsbury Companion to Analytic Philosophy, edited by Barry Dainton and Howard Robinson The Bloomsbury Companion to Epistemology, edited by Andrew Cullison A Critical Introduction to Skepticism, Allan Hazlett

SKEPTICISM FROM ANTIQUITY TO THE PRESENT

Edited by Diego E. Machuca and Baron Reed

Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc

LON DON • OX F O R D • N E W YO R K • N E W D E L H I • SY DN EY

Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square London WC1B 3DP UK

1385 Broadway New York NY 10018 USA

www.bloomsbury.com BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2018 © Diego Machuca and Baron Reed, 2018 Diego Machuca and Baron Reed have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as the Editors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury or the editors. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN: HB: 978-1-4725-0771-6 ePDF: 978-1-4725-1436-3 ePub: 978-1-4725-1149-2 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Machuca, Diego E., editor. Title: Skepticism: from antiquity to the present / [edited by] Diego Machuca and Baron Reed. Description: New York : Bloomsbury, 2018. | Includes bibliographical references and index. Identifiers: LCCN 2017030623 (print) | LCCN 2017043043 (ebook) | ISBN 9781472511492 (ePub) | ISBN 9781472514363 (ePDF) | ISBN 9781472507716 (hardback) Subjects: LCSH: Skepticism–History. Classification: LCC B837 (ebook) | LCC B837 .S53 2018 (print) | DDC 149/.7309–dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2017030623 Cover design: Clare Turner Cover image © Bridgeman Images Typeset by Deanta Global Publishing Services, Chennai, India

CONTENTS

L ist

of

C ontributors

ix

L ist

of

A bbreviations

xi

General Introduction  Baron Reed and Diego E. Machuca

Part I: Ancient Skepticism

xiii

1

Introduction  Diego E. Machuca 3 1 The Cyrenaics and Skepticism  Richard Bett

14

2 Pyrrho and Timon  Casey Perin

24

3 Arcesilaus  Anna Maria Ioppolo

36

4 Carneades  Harald Thorsrud

51

5 Aenesidemus  Luca Castagnoli

67

6 Philo of Larissa Harold Tarrant

81

7 Cicero J. P. F. Wynne

93

8 Menodotus and Medical Empiricism James Allen

102

9 Middle Platonism and Skepticism: Plutarch and Favorinus Carlos Lévy

114

vi

CONTENTS

10 Sextus Empiricus  Tad Brennan and Cliff Roberts

125

11 Skepticism in Classical Indian Philosophy  Matthew R. Dasti

145

Part II: Medieval and Renaissance Skepticism

163

Introduction  Diego E. Machuca 165 12 Augustine and Skepticism  Stéphane Marchand

175

13 John of Salisbury’s Skepticism  David Bloch

186

14 Skepticism in Classical Islam: The Case of Ghazali  Paul L. Heck

196

15 Nicholas of Autrecourt and John Buridan on Skepticism  Christophe Grellard

209

16 Divine Deception  Henrik Lagerlund

222

17 Michel de Montaigne  Gianni Paganini

232

18 Pierre Charron  Gianni Paganini

247

19 Francisco Sanchez: A Renaissance Pyrrhonist against Aristotelian Dogmatism  Damian Caluori

260

Part III: Modern Skepticism

271

Introduction  Baron Reed 273 20 François de La Mothe Le Vayer  Sylvia Giocanti

283

21 Gassendi on Skepticism  Antonia LoLordo

295

22 Descartes and the Force of Skepticism  David Cunning

306

CONTENTS

23 Varieties of Modern Academic Skepticism: Pierre-Daniel Huet and Simon Foucher  Michael W. Hickson

vii

320

24 Spinoza on Skepticism  Alison Peterman

342

25 Pierre Bayle  John Christian Laursen

355

26 Berkeley and Skepticism  Margaret Atherton

369

27 A Pyrrhonian Interpretation of Hume on Assent  Donald L. M. Baxter

380

28 Thomas Reid’s Engagement with Skeptics and Skepticism  René van Woudenberg

395

29 Johann Georg Hamann  Gwen Griffith-Dickson

407

30 Kant and External World Skepticism  Georges Dicker

419

31 Hegel: Philosophy as a Kind of Skepticism  Dietmar H. Heidemann

430

32 Friedrich Nietzsche  Andreas Urs Sommer

442

33 Russell’s Logical Construction of the External World  Peter J. Graham

454

34 Moore and Mooreanism  Annalisa Coliva

467

35 Wittgenstein and Skepticism: Illusory Doubts  Michael Williams

481

36 Richard Popkin on the History of Skepticism  José R. Maia Neto

506

Part IV: Contemporary Skepticism

521

Introduction  Baron Reed 523

viii

CONTENTS

37 Regress Arguments and Skepticism  Richard Fumerton

535

38 The Problem of the Criterion  Andrew D. Cling

550

39 Neo-Pyrrhonism  Markus Lammenranta

565

40 Disagreement and Skepticism  Bryan Frances

581

41 Skepticism and the Internalism-Externalism Debate  Matthias Steup

592

42 Skepticism and Fallibilism  Stephen Hetherington

609

43 Skepticism and Contextualism  Michael Blome-Tillmann

620

44 External World Skepticism  Ram Neta

634

45 Disjunctivism and Skepticism  Duncan Pritchard and Chris Ranalli

652

46 Inductive Skepticism: A Functional Investigation  Ruth Weintraub

668

47 Skepticism about A Priori Knowledge  Otávio Bueno

685

48 Skepticism about Other Minds  Anil Gomes

700

49 Moral Skepticism  Richard Joyce

714

50 Religious Skepticism  J. L. Schellenberg

727

N ame I ndex

739

S ubject I ndex

742

LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

James Allen, University of Toronto, Canada Margaret Atherton, University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee, United States Donald L. M. Baxter, University of Connecticut, United States Richard Bett, Johns Hopkins University, United States David Bloch, University of Copenhagen, Denmark Michael Blome-Tillmann, McGill University, Canada Tad Brennan, Cornell University, United States Otávio Bueno, University of Miami, United States Damian Caluori, Trinity University, United States Luca Castagnoli, University of Oxford, United Kingdom Andrew Cling, University of Alabama in Huntsville, United States Annalisa Coliva, University of California, Irvine, United States David Cunning, University of Iowa, United States Matthew Dasti, Bridgewater State University, United States Georges Dicker, SUNY College at Brockport, United States Bryan Frances, University of Tartu, Estonia Richard Fumerton, University of Iowa, United States Sylvia Giocanti, Université de Toulouse Le Mirail, France Anil Gomes, University of Oxford, United Kingdom Peter Graham, University of California, Riverside, United States Christophe Grellard, EPHE, PSL Research University, France Gwen Griffith-Dickson, King’s College London, United Kingdom Paul Heck, Georgetown University, United States Stephen Hetherington, University of New South Wales, Australia Dietmar Heidemann, Université du Luxembourg, Luxembourg Michael Hickson, Trent University, Canada Anna Maria Ioppolo, Sapienza - Università di Roma, Italy Richard Joyce, Victoria University of Wellington, New Zealand Henrik Lagerlund, Stockholm University, Sweden

x

LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS

Markus Lammenranta, University of Helsinki, Finland John Christian Laursen, University of California, Riverside, United States Carlos Lévy, Université Paris-Sorbonne, France Antonia LoLordo, University of Virginia, United States Diego E. Machuca, Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas, Argentina José Raimundo Maia Neto, Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais, Brazil Stéphane Marchand, École Normale Supérieure de Lyon, France Ram Neta, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, United States Gianni Paganini, Università del Piemonte Orientale, Italy Casey Perin, University of California, Irvine, United States Alison Peterman, University of Rochester, United States Duncan Pritchard, University of Edinburgh, United Kingdom Baron Reed, Northwestern University, United States Cliff Roberts, University of Victoria, Canada J. L. Schellenberg, Mount Saint Vincent University, Canada Matthias Steup, University of Colorado Boulder, United States Harold Tarrant, The University of Newcastle, Australia Harald Thorsrud, Agnes Scott College, United States Andreas Urs Sommer, Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg, Germany Ruth Weintraub, Tel Aviv University, Israel Michael Williams, Johns Hopkins University, United States René van Woudenberg, VU University, The Netherlands J. P. F. Wynne, Northwestern University, United States

LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

3D Berkeley, Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous Acad. Cicero, Academica Ad Att. Cicero, Epistulae ad Atticum Adv. Col. Plutarch, Adversus Colotem AM

Sextus Empiricus, Adversus Mathematicos

Apol. Plato, Apology of Socrates AT  Œuvres de Descartes, 11 vols., edited by C. Adam & P. Tannery. Paris: Vrin, 1996. Bibl. Photius, Bibliotheca C. Acad. Augustine, Contra Academicos Chronic. Can. Eusebius, Chronicus Canon Conf. Augustine, Confessiones CSM  The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vols. 1 & 2, edited by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984/5. CSMK  The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. 3, edited by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D. Murdoch, and A. Kenny. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991. De Alex. fort. Plutarch, De Alexandri Magni Fortuna Comp. med. gen. Galen, De compositione medicamentorum per genera De E Plutarch, De E apud Delphos De Or. Cicero, De Oratore De Prim. Frig. Plutarch, De Primo Frigido De rep. Cicero, De re publica De sect. ingred. Galen, De sectis ingredientibus De ut. cred. Augustine, De utilitate credendi Div. Cicero, De Divinatione DL

Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers

EHU Hume, An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding Fat. Cicero, De Fato

xii

LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

Fin. Cicero, De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum Gorg. Plato, Gorgias Met. Aristotle, Metaphysics MM Galen, De methodo medendi Mur. Cicero, Pro Murena ND Cicero, De Natura Deorum NA

Aulas Gellius, Noctes Atticae

Off. Cicero, De Officiis Opt. Doct. Galen, De Optima Doctrina PH

Sextus Empiricus, Pyrrhonian Outlines

PHK Berkeley, The Principles of Human Knowledge Praep. evang. Eusebius, Praeparatio evangelica Proem. Celsus, Proemium Prot. Plato, Protagoras QNS Sanchez, Quod nihil scitur Rep. Plato, Republic St. Rep. Plutarch, De Stoicorum Repugnantiis Subfig. emp. Galen, Subfiguratio empirica T Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature Theaet. Plato, Theaetetus Tusc. Cicero, Tusculanae Disputationes Vit. Soph. Philostratus, Vitae Sophistarum

General Introduction BARON REED AND DIEGO E. MACHUCA

Skeptical concerns arise in a variety of cultures. Most famously, the possibility that our experiences of the world are merely a dream is explored by many different thinkers, including by the Chinese sage, Zhuangzi: Last night Zhuang Zhou dreamed he was a butterfly . . . and did not know about [Zhuang] Zhou. When all of a sudden he awoke, he was Zhou with all his wits about him. He does not know whether he is Zhou who dreams he is a butterfly or a butterfly who dreams he is Zhou. (Quoted in Raphals 1994: 501) By a Nahuatl tlamatinimi (poet-sage) in pre-Conquest Mexico: Do we speak the truth here, oh Giver of Life? We merely dream, we only rise from a dream. All is like a dream . . . No one speaks here of truth . . . . (León-Portilla 1963: 7) And, in the history of Western philosophy, by Plato: The question I imagine you have often heard asked—what evidence could be appealed to, supposing we were asked at this very moment whether we are asleep or awake, dreaming all that passes through our minds or talking to one another in the waking state? (Plato, Theaetetus 158b) By Cicero: But you quite miss the point when you refute the false impressions of the insane or dreamers by their own subsequent recollection. The question isn’t what recollection dreamers or the insane have when they are awake or their fits subside, but what kind of impression they had at the time. (Acad. II 90) By al-Ghāzalī: Do you not see how, when you are asleep, you believe things and imagine circumstances, holding them to be stable and enduring, and, so long as you are in that dream-condition, have no doubts about them? And is it not the case that when you awake you know that all you have imagined and believed is unfounded and ineffectual? Why are you confident that all your waking beliefs, whether from sense or intellect, are genuine? They are true in respect of your present state; but it is possible that a state will come upon you whose relation to your waking consciousness is analogous to the relation of the latter to dreaming. In

xiv

SKEPTICISM

comparison with this state your waking consciousness would be like dreaming! (From al-Ghazālī’s Deliverance from Error, quoted in Watt 1953: 23.) And, of course, by Descartes: How often, asleep at night, am I convinced of just such familiar events—that I am here in my dressing-gown, sitting by the fire—when in fact I am lying undressed in bed! . . . As I think about this more carefully, I see plainly that there are never any sure signs by means of which being awake can be distinguished from being asleep. (Descartes 1984, CSM II 13; AT VII 19) Although this curiosity about how and whether our minds are properly fitted to reality is widely shared, perhaps even universal, it is also important not to lose sight of the differences in how that concern has been shaped and answered. Skepticism has been many things in its long history: a puzzle, a paradox, a challenge, an argument, an attitude, a way of life. Adopting a broad perspective allows us to see that it has also been a tradition, linking philosophers across the centuries who have been impelled to ask, why do we believe what we believe? and do we know what we take ourselves to know? These questions are as old as philosophy itself—and perhaps essential to it. Understanding skepticism in its full variety is of particular importance in the present philosophical age, as the predominant reactions to it have been attempts at refuting or solving it (see, e.g., Klein 1981 and DeRose 1995). The skeptical tradition is marked by a pair of dualities. The more obvious contrast is between skepticism and anti-skepticism. Some philosophers, like the Pyrrhonists and Montaigne, put forth skeptical arguments because they think skepticism is true, or rational, or part of a good life, or leads us toward faith instead of knowledge, or perhaps simply because they find it unavoidable. Others, like Descartes and G. E. Moore, take up skeptical arguments because they think skepticism is a useful challenge, or an obstacle to be overcome, or a deep and possibly dangerous philosophical problem. And some philosophers, like Wittgenstein, have a more ambiguous relationship to skepticism, both resisting it and articulating new forms of it. The second duality was submerged through most of the twentieth century, though it is perhaps now becoming more visible. The contrast here is between radical and mitigated skepticism. Where radical skeptics take most or all of our beliefs to be without epistemic legitimacy, mitigated skeptics do allow for the possibility that some beliefs are better than others, though most or all of them fall short of certainty. Both forms of skepticism appear throughout the history of philosophy, with the radical sort being championed by the Pyrrhonists in the ancient world and used methodologically by Descartes in the early modern period. Mitigated skepticism is associated with some of the later Academic skeptics, with Cicero, and with Charron and Gassendi. More common, especially in the modern world, are philosophers like Montaigne and Bayle who draw on both varieties as it suits their own needs. Hume is the best-known skeptic of this sort, as he favors a “more mitigated skepticism or academical philosophy,” which results when Pyrrhonism is “corrected by common sense and reflection” (Hume 2000, XII 24).1

GENERAL INTRODUCTION

xv

Like philosophical views of every sort, the various developments of skepticism— including in present-day philosophy—must be understood in the context of wider concerns. Some philosophers have been drawn to skepticism as a broadly ethical way of life—for example, the Pyrrhonists, Cicero, and Charron—while others, like Descartes, have used it in the service of scientific certainty or, like al-Ghazālī and perhaps Bayle, have thought that skepticism clears the way for a purer religious faith. The aims for which skeptical arguments can be mustered often determine the force and value of those arguments. To borrow an image from Sextus Empiricus, skepticism is like the color of a dove’s neck, changing as one’s perspective on it shifts (PH I 120). If that makes it difficult to come to grips with skepticism, it also makes the effort all the more rewarding. The present collection aims to provide an up-to-date critical survey of both the entire history of the various skeptical traditions and the systematic discussion of skeptical problems and arguments in the current philosophical scene. Although its scope could perhaps be expanded even further, the ground covered in the fifty chapters collected here is much more extensive than anything found in other scholarly works on skepticism, making it the first of its kind. The book is chronologically divided into four parts— ancient, medieval and Renaissance, modern, and contemporary skepticism—each preceded by an introductory chapter. Each chapter provides an authoritative overview of its topic, advances ongoing debates, and indicates new directions of research. We are grateful to Colleen Coalter, the philosophy senior commissioning editor at Bloomsbury, who approached us with the project of putting together an anthology on skepticism and later accepted the proposal to edit instead a book of newly written chapters. She has been patient and supportive through a variety of vicissitudes, including the tragically early death of Tony Brueckner, one of the very first people to join the list of contributors. His passing was a grievous loss both to this book and to the entire community of philosophers who work on skepticism. We are also grateful to the authors, some of whom overcame injury and illness in the writing of their chapters, and all of whom have greatly enriched our understanding of skepticism as it has been, as it is, and as it might yet become.

NOTE 1. It is perhaps worth noting here that the editors disagree with each other over the most fruitful way to think of skepticism. One favors a mitigated approach, while the other prefers his Pyrrhonism uncorrected by common sense and reflection.

REFERENCES Cicero. 2006. On Academic Scepticism, translated by C. Brittain. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. DeRose, Keith. 1995. “Solving the Skeptical Problem,” Philosophical Review 104: 1–52. Descartes, René. 1984. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. II, translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hume, David. 2000. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, edited by T. Beauchamp. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

xvi

SKEPTICISM

Klein, Peter. 1981. Certainty: A Refutation of Scepticism. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. León-Portilla, Miguel. 1963. Aztec Thought and Culture, translated by J. E. Davis. Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma Press. Plato. 1961. The Collected Dialogues of Plato, edited by E. Hamilton and H. Cairns. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Raphals, Lisa. 1994. “Skeptical Strategies in the Zuangzhi and Theaetetus,” Philosophy East and West 44: 501–526. Sextus Empiricus. 2000. Outlines of Scepticism, edited by J. Annas and J. Barnes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Watt, W. Montgomery. 1953. The Faith and Practice of Al-Ghazālī. London: George Allen and Unwin.

PART ONE

Ancient Skepticism

2

Introduction Ancient Skepticism DIEGO E. MACHUCA

As noted in the General Introduction, we have aimed to offer a comprehensive picture of both the history of the various skeptical traditions and the contemporary philosophical discussions of skeptical views, problems, and arguments. Consequently, this first part devoted to ancient skepticism includes chapters not only on the two main Western traditions, namely Pyrrhonism and Academic skepticism, but also on the skeptical aspects of two schools with which they bear close historical and philosophical connections, namely Cyrenaicism and medical Empiricism. Likewise, we have decided to include chapters not only on the chief representatives of Pyrrhonism (Pyrrho, Timon, Aenesidemus, and Sextus) and the skeptical Academy (Arcesilaus and Carneades), but also on less important figures (Menodotus, Philo, Cicero, Plutarch, and Favorinus). Finally, in order not to focus exclusively on Western thought, we have included a chapter devoted to the skeptical strands within classical Indian philosophy, which exhibit remarkable richness and sophistication. Some scholars have argued that there exist both historical and philosophical connections between Pyrrhonism and classical Indian thought. While the evidence for the historical link is both meager and problematic, we do find certain philosophical similarities—particularly in the skeptical argumentative strategies used by members of the two traditions—as anyone can realize by reading the chapter on Indian skepticism.1 The reader will also find significant parallels with skeptical views and arguments discussed in contemporary analytic epistemology. It should be observed that the authors covered by that chapter (Nāgārjuna, Jayarāśi, and Śrīharṣa) range from the second to the twelfth century CE, a timespan that falls within the classical period of Indian philosophy. Although this span of time goes, in the periodization of the history of Western philosophy, from the Imperial period to the Middle Ages, it did not make much sense to split the chapter into two and place the second portion in the part on medieval and Renaissance skepticism. Until not long ago, most scholars of Greco-Roman philosophy undervalued or neglected the skeptical traditions of the Hellenistic and Imperial periods, the main reason being the widespread view that any form of skepticism is of no intrinsic philosophical significance. The voluminous extant corpus of a Pyrrhonist like Sextus Empiricus was read almost exclusively as a key source of information about the views of non-Pyrrhonian thinkers and schools. The powerful skeptical

4

SKEPTICISM

argumentative armory expounded therein was either ignored or regarded as a collection of sophisms. This tendency began to recede particularly in the early 1980s, and at present scholarship on ancient skepticism has reached a high degree of development, rigor, and sophistication. Scholars have not only addressed complex historical and exegetical issues, but also examined the consistency and livability of the distinct strands of ancient skepticism as well as assessed the scope and soundness of the skeptics’ arguments. This reevaluation of ancient skepticism has no doubt been essential to a better understanding of Hellenistic and Imperial philosophy and medicine. But it has also had a much broader effect inasmuch as the form of Pyrrhonism described in Sextus’s writings has exerted a strong influence on contemporary philosophy, primarily in the field of epistemology. As a result, hardly anyone familiar, first- or second-hand, with ancient skepticism would today question its philosophical import. As already observed, ancient Western philosophy knew two major and closely related skeptical traditions, the Pyrrhonian and the Academic, both of which originated in the Hellenistic era and continued into the Imperial age. Even though in pre-Hellenistic philosophy one can find skeptical inclinations, themes, and arguments, it is only at the beginning of the Hellenistic age that the possibility of knowledge and justified belief was called into question in a systematic way by means of elaborate argumentative strategies. Those approaching ancient skepticism for the first time should be aware that it was not uniform, not only because there were different traditions but also because there were significant transformations within each of them. This is also a cautionary reminder to those already familiar with ancient skepticism. For there is sometimes a tendency to neglect especially the differences between the members of a single tradition, ascribing to earlier figures a stance or an argument that was arrived at only at a later stage. Keeping in mind the heterogeneous character of ancient skepticism not only prevents historical and interpretive mistakes, but also allows one to appreciate its richness and to make sense of some of the discrepancies between our sources or within a single source. This is not to say that it is easy or in all cases possible to provide a precise account of the distinct skeptical traditions or the various brands of skepticism within the same tradition, and of how they influenced each other or diverged from each other. The main reason for such a difficulty is that some key figures like Pyrrho, Arcesilaus, and Carneades wrote nothing, and that the works of most of those who did are lost to us. Most of the time we must therefore content ourselves with fragments, reports, and summaries that are usually meager, sometimes of doubtful reliability, and on occasion hard to reconcile.2 Pyrrhonism is no doubt the most prominent and influential form of skepticism in the history of Western philosophy. Not only was it an important philosophical movement in the Hellenistic and Imperial periods, but, as we will see in the other three parts of this book, it also had a profound impact on Renaissance and modern philosophy and is a topic of discussion in contemporary epistemology. Pyrrhonism was thus named after its eponymous figurehead, Pyrrho of Elis (360–270 BCE), whose stance is known primarily through the poems and prose works of his leading disciple Timon of Phlius (320–230 BCE), parts of which survive in fragments and

INTRODUCTION

5

second-hand reports. What we know of Pyrrho’s thought, however, differs in key respects from our current conception of Greek Pyrrhonism, which derives from the works of the later Pyrrhonists. The later ancient Pyrrhonian tradition, sometimes called “neo-Pyrrhonism” by ancient philosophy scholars,3 began in the first century BCE with Aenesidemus of Cnossos and culminated with Sextus Empiricus (probably late second century CE) and his immediate successors. Succinctly put, by the standards of the later representatives of the tradition, Pyrrho should be regarded as a “Dogmatist,” since he made assertions, even if negative in kind, about what things are like by nature. In describing Pyrrho’s stance in terms of the suspending of judgment, the refraining from dogmatic determinations, and the following of that which appears (DL IX 62, 106), Aenesidemus was actually projecting onto Pyrrho his own skepticism. It could likewise be argued that the picture of Pyrrho painted by Timon was molded by the latter’s own skeptical stance. Timon is close to the later Pyrrhonists in refraining from affirming that things are as they appear and in taking that which appears as a guide in practical matters (DL IX 105). For this reason, it has even been claimed that the epistemological views ascribed to Pyrrho by Timon are actually the latter’s, who should therefore be considered the first Pyrrhonist.4 As for Sextus, he cautiously explains the connection between Pyrrho and the skeptical philosophy in relative terms: the skeptical way of thought is called “Pyrrhonian” because “Pyrrho appears to us to have attached himself to Skepticism more tangibly and more conspicuously than his predecessors” (PH I 7). One should therefore refrain from assuming that the type of skepticism expounded in great detail in Sextus’s substantive extant writings, which are our chief source for ancient Pyrrhonism, is nothing but a more developed version of Pyrrho’s stance. Nonetheless, it is not arbitrary that Pyrrho was taken as a forerunner or an inspiration by the later Pyrrhonists, for it can be explained by his having claimed that the state of tranquility or undisturbedness (ἀταραξία), which the later Pyrrhonists took as their aim, is attained by mistrusting our sensations and opinions as a guide to determining the nature of things.5 The preceding remarks may give the misleading impression that the later Pyrrhonian tradition was homogeneous. In fact, there appear to be considerable differences between what we can reconstruct of Aenesidemus’s outlook and the skeptical stance expounded in at least most of Sextus’s surviving works.6 For Aenesidemus seems to have made both negative and relativized claims that would have been viewed by Sextus as violating suspension of judgment in that they amount to assertions about non-evident matters.7 It should also be noted that even within Sextus’s own corpus there seem to coexist differing varieties of Pyrrhonism that cannot always be reconciled and that can at least in part be accounted for by his drawing on different sources to compose his works. One of the tensions between distinct forms of skepticism that is detectable in his works concerns the sets of modes by means of which the Pyrrhonist seeks to induce suspension of judgment. In book one of PH, Sextus expounds the Ten Modes (PH I 36–163) and the Five Modes (PH I 164–177). These two sets of modes differ in nature: whereas each of the Ten Modes applies to a particular conflict of perceptual appearances or opinions,8 the Five Modes are thematically neutral and of universal application, since they can

6

SKEPTICISM

be employed in relation to any assertion or doctrine.9 In this case, it is possible to identify Sextus’s sources. First, at PH I 36 he ascribes the Ten Modes to “the older Skeptics,” and at AM VII 345 he speaks of “the Ten Modes of Aenesidemus.” We also know from Diogenes Laertius that Aenesidemus made use of the Ten Modes (DL IX 87).10 Second, Sextus ascribes the Five Modes to “the more recent Skeptics” (PH I 164), whereas Diogenes attributes them to Agrippa (DL IX 88), of whom we know nothing, except that he probably lived in the first century CE.11 Now, both the fact that the Aenesideman and the Agrippan modes differ in character and the fact that they were proposed by Pyrrhonists belonging to different phases of the Pyrrhonian tradition indicate that they correspond to differing types of skepticism. It should be remarked, however, that although the Ten Modes and the Five Modes differ in their scope and force, they are not incompatible and their joint presence in Sextus’s work does not actually threaten the coherence of his Pyrrhonism.12 As regards the Academy, most scholars agree that its skeptical phase arose out of both the epistemological debate between Academics13 and Stoics and the return to Socrates’s dialectical style of philosophizing, but they also think it possible that the figure of Pyrrho played a part in the origin of Academic skepticism. It should be noted that, while the Pyrrhonists were in general reluctant to recognize forebears or to acknowledge similarities between Pyrrhonism and other philosophies, the Academics believed that their skepticism was the culmination of a gradual development commencing with the Presocratics and that it was perfectly in keeping with the tradition of Socrates and Plato. The skeptical phase of the Academy ranges from Arcesilaus (316/5–241/0 BCE), through Carneades (214–129/8 BCE) and his student Clitomachus (187– 10 BCE), to Philo of Larissa (159/8–84/3 BCE) and Antiochus of Ascalon (130–69/8 BCE), to name only the main representatives. Arcesilaus adopted a radical form of epistemological skepticism characterized by universal suspension of judgment.14 In Carneades, skepticism was extended to other domains such as ethics and theology, but it may also have been mitigated by the espousal of a kind of fallibilism. There is, however, much dispute about what his stance was and even whether he adopted any stance in propria persona.15 For his part, Clitomachus defended a strong form of skepticism that he ascribed to Carneades, but after him Academic skepticism began to soften. Philo first defended a radical skepticism but later held that it is possible to have knowledge, albeit not of the type proposed by the Stoics.16 This decline of Academic skepticism was followed by a total departure from it on the part of Antiochus, who after espousing his teacher Philo’s skeptical outlook returned to what he took to be the position of the Old Academy, embracing what most scholars describe as a Stoicizing form of Platonism. With Antiochus begins the period known as “Middle Platonism,” which extends to the early third century CE.17 The influence of Academic skepticism did not however cease, since it is still present in Cicero (106–43 BCE), a student of both Philo and Antiochus, who considered himself to belong to that philosophical tradition. In relation to skepticism, Cicero is generally studied only as a major source of information on the skeptical Academy; his own moderate skeptical outlook is not usually discussed in companions and general introductions to ancient skepticism. For this reason, we decided to include a chapter

INTRODUCTION

7

entirely devoted to him.18 The presence of a mitigated form of Academic skepticism is also found in Favorinus of Arles (80–160 CE), who claimed to be an Academic skeptic, although he was also influenced by Pyrrhonism. In On the Best Method of Teaching, which is our most important source for Favorinus’s philosophical stance, Galen (129–210 CE) attacks the “younger” Academics, among whom was Favorinus.19 Thus, even though the Academy as an institution ceased to exist in the first century BCE, in the second century CE there was a group of Academics who were skeptical and prominent enough to merit Galen’s attack. It should also be noted that Plutarch (ca. 50–120 CE), Favorinus’s teacher, was sympathetic to Academic skepticism, albeit of course not in its radical form. Not only did he seek to defend Academic skepticism from the attacks of rival schools, but he also viewed it as part of a unitary tradition that extended from Plato to himself. He thought that the skeptical interpretation of Plato did justice to the aporetic aspect of the latter’s dialogues, but did not take it to be incompatible with the fact that Plato held doctrines.20 It is rather surprising that what may be called the “epistemological” position of the Cyrenaic school (late fifth to mid-third centuries BCE) is not generally discussed in presentations of Greek skepticism. It is true both that the Cyrenaics were not interested in epistemological issues per se, but only insofar as these were relevant to their ethical theory, and that they did not draw all the skeptical consequences of their epistemology that they could have drawn. Nonetheless, their epistemological stance seems to be more elaborate and subtle than those of the pre-Hellenistic philosophers in whom one may detect skeptical elements, and it bears close relations with both Academic and Pyrrhonian skepticism. The Cyrenaics claimed that we have knowledge of our own “affections” (πάθη),21 but not of the properties of the external objects that cause them because they are inapprehensible, and that we cannot know the content of other people’s affections. They even coined curious neologisms (“being whitened,” “being sweetened,” “being darkened”) so as to restrict themselves to talking about the various ways they are affected and to avoid any reference to the causes of the affections. Such neologisms are occasionally used by Sextus. In short, the Cyrenaic epistemological stance should be taken into careful consideration by anyone seriously interested in ancient skeptical thought.22 Another current in ancient skepticism was that of medical Empiricism, which stretched from the third century BCE to the second century CE and was one of the three main medical sects of the Hellenistic and Imperial ages, the other two being the Rationalist or Dogmatic and the Methodical. Medical Empiricism did not in fact constitute an independent skeptical tradition, since it was in intimate relation with Pyrrhonism. Not only are there significant philosophical similarities between the two outlooks (as the testimonies in Galen and Celsus attest), but we also know that several Pyrrhonists were Empirical doctors, the first of whom being probably Menodotus of Nicomedia, who flourished in the first part of the second century CE. Sextus Empiricus himself was an Empiricist, as both the external evidence and his sobriquet indicate, even though he explicitly distinguishes Pyrrhonism from medical Empiricism and expresses more sympathy for medical Methodism (PH I 236–241).23 It has been suggested that medical Empiricism contributed to the revival of the

8

SKEPTICISM

Pyrrhonian philosophy in the first century BCE. The Empirical doctors also seem to have been heavily influenced by the skeptical Academy, which is not in any case strange given the close similarities between Pyrrhonism and Academic skepticism and their mutual influence.24 I would like to conclude this brief introduction by making a few remarks about the application of the words “skeptic” and “skepticism.” While Aenesidemus did not probably use “skeptic” but only “Pyrrhonist,” Sextus prefers to employ “skeptic” and “skepticism” (or “the skeptical way”) when talking about the Pyrrhonist and his stance. Diogenes Laertius (third century CE) too uses “skeptic” and “Pyrrhonist” as synonyms. As is widely known, the Greek σκεπτικός means “inquirer” and σκέψις “inquiry.” It is commonly agreed that only in the early second century CE did those words come to be generally used as a designation of the Pyrrhonist and his stance. Now, the application of such terms in their technical sense to medical Empiricism is plainly legitimate, given its intimate historical and philosophical connection with Pyrrhonism. Their use in relation to Cyrenaicism, and to certain strands in Indian philosophy, is grounded on the fact that in such positions one can identify points of similarity with Pyrrhonism—and even with contemporary versions of skepticism. As for the Academics, it is sometimes remarked that, unlike the Pyrrhonists, they did not call themselves “skeptics,” nor did they describe their stance as “skepticism.” Some of our sources, however, indicate that “skeptic” was also applied to the Academics. For instance, in his Attic Nights (XI v 1), the second-century CE antiquarian Aulus Gellius tells us that Pyrrhonists are referred to as “skeptics,” but he later remarks that both Pyrrhonists and Academics are so designated (XI v 6). Note in addition that, since Favorinus is likely the source of Gellius’s text, one might infer that at least he and other Academics of the second century CE did actually call themselves “skeptics”—which may be accounted for by their having been influenced by Pyrrhonism. Be that as it may, the application of the label “skeptics” to figures such as Arcesilaus, Carneades, Clitomachus, Philo, Cicero, and Favorinus is grounded on the close similarities between their outlooks and the Pyrrhonian stance: for example, the advocacy of suspension of judgment, the practice of arguing on both sides of a question, and the dialectical style of argumentation. Such similarities explain, at least in part, why in the second-century CE authors like Seneca, Epictetus, Galen, Lucian, and even Favorinus tended to assimilate Academic skepticism to Pyrrhonism. There is also a historical connection between the two traditions, since it is almost unanimously accepted that Aenesidemus was a former member of the Academy whose desertion seems to have been motivated by Philo’s abandonment of the rigorous skepticism of the earlier Academics. It seems clear that the source of Aenesidemus’s argumentative practice is to be found in the dialectical method of the skeptical Academy, and our sources state that both Arcesilaus (PH I 232, cf. Acad. I 45) and Aenesidemus (DL IX 107, cf. PH I 30) conceived of suspension of judgment as their aim (τέλος). For such reasons, some have suggested that Aenesidemus’s revival of Pyrrho’s outlook was actually a return to radical Academic skepticism. In this connection, it must also be borne in mind both that it is possible that Arcesilaus was influenced to some extent by Pyrrho (PH I 234, DL IV 33) and that Aenesidemus viewed Pyrrho as a proponent of suspension of judgment (DL IX 62).

INTRODUCTION

9

NOTES 1. On the historical and philosophical connections between Pyrrhonism and Buddhism, besides Matthew Dasti’s chapter in this book, see e.g. Frenkian (1957), Flintoff (1980), Bett (2000: 169–178), Kuzminski (2008), and Beckwith (2015). 2. For useful book-length general presentations of ancient skepticism, see Hankinson (1998), Brochard (2002), Thorsrud (2009), and Bett (2010). For a shorter overview, with extensive bibliographical references in the main European languages, see Machuca (2011a,b,c). 3. This usage is common among French and Italian scholars. In English, the term “neoPyrrhonism” is employed in contemporary analytic epistemology to refer to presentday versions of Pyrrhonism or to the application of Pyrrhonian argumentative strategies to current debates. 4. This is the view defended by Brunschwig (1994, 1999). 5. On the early Pyrrhonism of Pyrrho and Timon, besides Casey Perin’s chapter in this book, see e.g. Ausland (1989), Brunschwig (1994), Conche (1994), Bett (2000), Long (2006), Clayman (2009), and Svavarsson (2010). 6. Bett (1997) claims that in AM XI one detects traces of the Aenesideman variety of skepticism. 7. See Woodruff (1988, 2010) and Bett (2000: ch. 4). On these and other aspects of Aenesidemus’s philosophical stance, including his so-called Heracliteanism, see, besides Luca Castagnoli’s chapter in this book, Polito (2004, 2014), Pérez-Jean (2005), and Schofield (2007). 8. The Aenesideman modes are also expounded by Diogenes Laertius (DL IX 78– 88) and Philo of Alexandria (On Drunkenness 169–205). On these arguments, see especially Annas and Barnes (1985); also Striker (1996) and Woodruff (2010). 9. The Agrippan modes are also expounded by Diogenes (DL IX 88–89). On these modes, see especially Barnes (1990). It should be noted that those modes have been the focus of much attention among contemporary epistemologists, who have recognized the seriousness of the challenge posed by the so-called “Agrippa’s trilemma” and proposed different ways to cope with it. On this issue, see Klein (2008), Lammenranta (2008), and Machuca (2015). 10. Scholars have usually thought that Aenesidemus was not strictly the author of the Ten Modes, but their compiler. 11. Sextus also expounds Two Modes of suspension of judgment (PH I 178–179), but they actually work by the application of three of the Five Modes and most likely derive from Agrippa. 12. See Machuca (2008: 51–57) for an overview of the varieties of skepticism found in Sextus’s corpus and the tensions between them. For book-length studies on Sextus’s Pyrrhonism, see especially Bailey (2002) and Perin (2010). 13. Following a usage found in some of our sources, I employ “Academics” to refer to the Academic skeptics. 14. On the skepticism of Arcesilaus, in addition to Anna Maria Ioppolo’s chapter, see Ioppolo (1986, 2000), Cooper (2004), and Vezzoli (2016). 15. On Carneades’s skepticism, besides Harald Thorsrud’s chapter in this book, see e.g. Bett (1989, 1990), Thorsrud (2002, 2010), and Obdrzalek (2006).

10

SKEPTICISM

16. On Philo’s skepticism, besides Harold Tarrant’s chapter in the present book, see Brittain (2001) and Glucker (2004). 17. On the philosophy of Antiochus and Middle Platonism in general, see, in addition to Carlos Lévy’s chapter, Glucker (1978), Tarrant (1985), and Sedley (2012). 18. On Cicero’s skepticism, see also Thorsrud (2009: ch. 5), Woolf (2015), and Nicgorski (2016). 19. On Favorinus’s skeptical views, besides Carlos Lévy’s chapter, see Ioppolo (1993, 1994, 2002) and Holford-Strevens (1997). 20. On Plutarch and skepticism, besides Lévy’s chapter, see De Lacy (1953) and Bonazzi (2014). 21. It should be noted that a πάθος is that which happens to someone or something as a result of being affected by an agent in the broad sense of this term. It refers to the physical and/or psychological state or condition in which the affected person or thing is. Although in ordinary English “affection” does not have this meaning anymore, it has become in the specialist literature a technical term to translate πάθος because it shows the connection that πάθος bears with the Greek verb πάσχειν (to affect). 22. On the skepticism of the Cyrenaic school, besides Richard Bett’s chapter, see Tsouna (1998) and O’Keefe (2011, 2015). 23. On Sextus’s relationship with the medical schools, see Machuca (2008: 40–50). 24. On Menodotus and medical Empiricism more generally, besides James Allen’s chapter in this book, see e.g. Edelstein (1967), Mudry (1982, 1990), Frede (1987, 1988, 1990), Hankinson (1987), and Perilli (2004).

REFERENCES Annas, Julia and Jonathan Barnes. 1985. The Modes of Scepticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ausland, Hayden. 1989. “On the Moral Origin of the Pyrrhonian Philosophy,” Elenchos 10: 359–434. Bailey, Alan. 2002. Sextus Empiricus and Pyrrhonean Scepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Beckwith, Christopher. 2015. Greek Buddha: Pyrrho’s Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Bett, Richard. 1989. “Carneades’ Pithanon: A Reappraisal of its Role and Status,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 7: 59–94. Bett, Richard. 1990. “Carneades’ Distinction between Assent and Approval,” Monist 73: 3–20. Bett, Richard. 1997. Sextus Empiricus: Against the Ethicists. English translation with an introduction and commentary. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bett, Richard. 2000. Pyrrho, His Antecedents, and His Legacy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bett, Richard (ed.). 2010. The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

INTRODUCTION

11

Bonazzi, Mauro. 2014. “Plutarch and the Skeptics.” In M. Beck (ed.), A Companion to Plutarch, 121–134. Malden and Oxford: Blackwell. Brittain, Charles. 2001. Philo of Larissa: The Last of the Academic Sceptics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brochard, Victor. 2002. Les Sceptiques Grecs. 4th ed. Paris: Le livre de poche. (First published in 1887.) Brunschwig, Jacques. 1994. “Once again on Eusebius on Aristocles on Timon on Pyrrho.” In his Papers in Hellenistic Philosophy, 190–211. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brunschwig, Jacques. 1999. “The Beginnings of Hellenistic Epistemology.” In K. Algra, J. Barnes, J. Mansfeld, and M. Schofield (eds.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, 229–259. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Clayman, Dee. 2009. Timon of Phlius: Pyrrhonism into Poetry. Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter. Conche, Marcel. 1994. Pyrrhon ou l’apparence. 2nd ed. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. (First published in 1973.) Cooper, John. 2004. “Arcesilaus: Socratic and Sceptic.” In his Knowledge, Nature, and the Good: Essays on Ancient Philosophy, 81–103. Princeton: Princeton University Press. De Lacy, Phillip. 1953. “Plutarch and the Academic Sceptics,” The Classical Journal 49: 79–85. Edelstein, Ludwig. 1967. “Empiricism and Scepticism in the Teaching of the Greek Empiricist School.” In his Ancient Medicine: Selected Papers of Ludwig Edelstein, 195– 203, edited by O. Temkin and C. Temkin. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Flintoff, Everard. 1980. “Pyrrho and India,” Phronesis 25: 88–108. Frede, Michael. 1987. “The Ancient Empiricists.” In his Essays in Ancient Philosophy, 234– 260. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Frede, Michael. 1988. “The Empiricist Attitude Towards Reason and Theory.” In R. J. Hankinson (ed.), Method, Metaphysics and Medicine: Studies in the Philosophy of Ancient Medicine, special volume of Apeiron 21, 79–97. Edmonton: Academic Printing and Publishing. Frede, Michael. 1990. “An Empiricist View of Knowledge: Memorism.” In S. Everson (ed.), Companions to Ancient Thought I: Epistemology, 225–250. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frenkian, Aram. 1957. “Sextus Empiricus and Indian Logic,” The Philosophical Quarterly (India) 30: 115–126. Glucker, John. 1978. Antiochus and the Late Academy. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. Glucker, John. 2004. “The Philonian/Metrodorians: Problems of Method in Ancient Philosophy,” Elenchos 25: 99–152. Greco, John (ed.). 2008. The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism. New York: Oxford University Press. Hankinson, Robert. 1987. “Causes and Empiricism: A Problem in the Interpretation of Later Greek Medical Method,” Phronesis 32: 329–348. Hankinson, Robert. 1998. The Sceptics. 2nd ed. London and New York: Routledge. (First published in 1995.)

12

SKEPTICISM

Holford-Strevens, Leofranc. 1997. “Favorinus: The Man of Paradoxes.” In J. Barnes and M. Griffin (eds.), Philosophia Togata II: Plato and Aristotle at Rome, 188–217. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 1986. Opinione e scienza. Il dibattito tra Stoici e Accademici nel terzo e secondo secolo a. C. Napoli: Bibliopolis. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 1993. “The Academic Position of Favorinus of Arelate,” Phronesis 38: 183–213. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 1994. “Accademici e pirroniani nel II secolo D.C.” In A. Alberti (ed.), Realtà e ragione: Studi di filosofia antica, 85–103. Firenze: Olschki. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 2000. “Su alcune recenti interpretazioni dello scetticismo dell’Academia. Plutarch. Adv. Col. 26, 1121F–1122F: una testimonianza su Arcesilao,” Elenchos 21: 333–360. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 2002. “Gli accademici neōteroi nel secondo secolo d.C.,” Méthexis 15: 45–70. Klein, Peter. 2008. “Contemporary Responses to Agrippa’s Trilemma.” In Greco 2008, 484–503. Kuzminski, Adrian. 2008. Pyrrhonism: How the Ancient Greeks Reinvented Buddhism. Lanham: Lexington Books. Lammenranta, Markus. 2008. “The Pyrrhonian Problematic.” In Greco 2008, 9–33. Long, Anthony. 2006. “Timon of Phlius: Pyrrhonist and Satirist.” In his From Epicurus to Epictetus: Studies in Hellenistic and Roman Philosophy, 70–95. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (First published in 1973.) Machuca, Diego. 2008. “Sextus Empiricus: His Outlook, Works, and Legacy,” Freiburger Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Theologie 55: 28–63. Machuca, Diego. 2011a. “Ancient Skepticism: Overview,” Philosophy Compass 6: 234– 245. Machuca, Diego. 2011b. “Ancient Skepticism: Pyrrhonism,” Philosophy Compass 6: 246– 258. Machuca, Diego. 2011c. “Ancient Skepticism: The Skeptical Academy,” Philosophy Compass 6: 259–266. Machuca, Diego. 2015. “Agrippan Pyrrhonism and the Challenge of Disagreement,” Journal of Philosophical Research 40: 23–39. Mudry, Philippe. 1982. La préface du De medicina de Celsus. Lausanne: Imprimerie des Arts et Métiers. Mudry, Philippe. 1990. “Le scepticisme des médecins empiriques dans le traité De la médecine de Celse: modèles et modalités.” Le scepticisme antique: perspectives historiques et systématiques, 85–96. Cahiers de la Revue de Théologie et de Philosophie 15. Genève: Lausanne & Neuchâtel. Nicgorski, Walter. 2016. Cicero’s Skepticism and His Recovery of Political Philosophy. Basingstoke: Palgrave. Obdrzalek, Suzanne. 2006. “Living in Doubt: Carneades’ Pithanon Reconsidered,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 31: 243–80. O’Keefe, Timothy. 2011. “The Cyrenaics vs. the Pyrrhonists on Knowledge of Appearances.” In D. Machuca (ed.), New Essays on Ancient Pyrrhonism, 27–40. Leiden: Brill.

INTRODUCTION

13

O’Keefe, Timothy. 2015. “The Sources and Scope of Cyrenaic Scepticism.” In U. Zilioli (ed.), From the Socratics to the Socratic Schools, 99–113. New York: Routledge. Pérez-Jean, Brigitte. 2005. Dogmatisme et scepticisme: L’héraclitisme d’Énésidème. Lille: Septentrion. Perilli, Lorenzo. 2004. Menodoto di Nicomedia: Contributo a una storia galeniana della medicina empirica. München and Leipzig: Saur. Perin, Casey. 2010. The Demands of Reason: An Essay on Pyrrhonian Scepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Polito, Roberto. 2004. The Sceptical Road: Aenesidemus’ Appropriation of Heraclitus. Leiden and Boston: Brill. Polito, Roberto. 2014. Aenesidemus of Cnossus: Testimonia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Schofield, Malcolm. 2007. “Aenesidemus: Pyrrhonist and ‘Heraclitean’.” In A. M. Ioppolo and D. Sedley (eds.), Pyrrhonists, Patricians, Platonizers: Hellenistic Philosophy in the Period 155–86 BC, 269–338. Napoli: Bibliopolis. Sedley, David (ed.). 2012. The Philosophy of Antiochus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Striker, Gisela. 1996. “The Ten Modes of Aenesidemus.” In her Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics, 116–134. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (First published in 1983.) Svavarsson, Svavar. 2010. “Pyrrho and Early Pyrrhonism.” In Bett 2010, 36–57. Tarrant, Harold. 1985. Scepticism or Platonism? The Philosophy of the Fourth Academy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Thorsrud, Harald. 2002. “Cicero on His Academic Predecessors: The Fallibilism of Arcesilaus and Carneades,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 40: 1–18. Thorsrud, Harald. 2009. Ancient Scepticism. Stocksfield: Acumen. Thorsrud, Harald. 2010. “Arcesilaus and Carneades.” In Bett 2010, 58–80. Tsouna, Voula. 1998. The Epistemology of the Cyrenaic School. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Vezzoli, Simone. 2016. Arcesilao di Pitane: l’origine del Platonismo neoaccademico. Analisi e fonti. Turnhout: Brepols. Woodruff, Paul. 1988. “Aporetic Pyrrhonism,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 6: 139–168. Woodruff, Paul. 2010. “The Pyrrhonian Modes.” In Bett 2010, 208–231. Woolf, Raphael. 2015. Cicero: The Philosophy of a Roman Sceptic. New York: Routledge.

CHAPTER ONE

The Cyrenaics and Skepticism RICHARD BETT

1  SHOULD THE CYRENAICS COUNT AS SKEPTICS? The Cyrenaics are regularly described as having a skeptical epistemology.1 But some would say that the Cyrenaics do not belong in a book on skepticism. Prominent among them would be the Pyrrhonist skeptic Sextus Empiricus. At the end of the first book of his Outlines of Pyrrhonism, Sextus discusses several philosophies that were thought to be equivalent or at least similar to skepticism. It is not clear who thought so; were they skeptics themselves, or adherents of some other philosophical outlook? But Sextus is opposed to the whole project, arguing in each case that there are central differences between skepticism as he understands it and the philosophy in question. And one of these philosophies is that of the Cyrenaics (PH 1.215). Sextus points to two differences. First, the Cyrenaics posit pleasure as the end or aim (τέλος) of life, whereas the skeptic’s end is ἀταραξία, freedom from worry; referring to his earlier chapter on the skeptic’s end (PH 1.25–30), Sextus counters that a firm conviction that pleasure is the end will (whether or not one actually achieves it) lead to a great deal of trouble—that is, the opposite of ἀταραξία. The earlier chapter did not actually mention the specific case of pleasure, but argued that taking anything to be by nature good or bad, and thereby caring intensely about its presence or absence, will lead to turmoil; the same point can be found elsewhere (PH 3.235–238, AM 11.110–140). There are really two distinct issues here: the identity of the ends posited by each school, and the ways in which they are posited. First, pleasure and ἀταραξία are two different things, so the Cyrenaics do not have the same end as the skeptics. But second, holding to one’s view of the end (whatever one takes it to be) as a matter of firm conviction (in the present passage, διαβεβαιούμενος) will lead to results that are actually contrary to the skeptic’s end. The Cyrenaics are assumed to adopt their end in this committed way. By contrast, when Sextus states the skeptics’ own end, he is careful to put it much less decisively. He says: “Up to now we say that the skeptic’s end is freedom from worry” (PH 1.25).2 Rather than being posited, as ends usually are, as the end for human beings in general—as what humans as such should, or naturally do, strive

THE CYRENAICS AND SKEPTICISM

15

toward—it is explicitly restricted to the skeptics themselves; and it is put forward tentatively, as a matter of their experience “up to now,” rather than definitively. In both respects it conforms to the suspension of judgment (ἐποχή) that Sextus regularly identifies as the centerpiece of his skeptical attitude. The centrality of suspension of judgment for the Pyrrhonist skeptic is also the basis of the second contrast Sextus draws between his school and the Cyrenaics. Here and elsewhere, Sextus distinguishes between the way objects strike us and the objects themselves, and says that concerning the latter, here referred to as “the external underlying things” (τῶν ἐκτὸς ὑποκειμένων), the skeptics suspend judgment,3 whereas the Cyrenaics “declare that they have an inapprehensible nature.” The Cyrenaics, then, assert that these objects are inherently unknowable, and that is an intellectual commitment, just as much as if one were to claim that they could be known; in modern scholarship, though Sextus does not use this terminology himself, such a position is generally called “negative dogmatism,” and Sextus is clear that this is different from skepticism. Now, the other side of this distinction— what I referred to as “the way things strike us”—is what led, as Sextus reports it, to the claim that the Cyrenaic position is the same as skepticism; the reason given is that “it too [i.e., skepticism] says that only the ways we are affected [πάθη] are apprehended,” just as the Cyrenaics did.4 Sextus does not necessarily endorse this characterization of skepticism; it is presented simply as the support offered by those who claim the identity. In fact, as I shall suggest in closing, he would be well advised not to endorse it; even here, the Cyrenaic and the skeptical positions are not identical. But his point in drawing this second contrast is that, even if we accept the supposed point of similarity, the Cyrenaics differ importantly from the skeptics in what they are prepared to say about the objects themselves. So Sextus, a card-carrying skeptic, explicitly repudiates the idea that the Cyrenaics are skeptics. Why, then, should we treat them as skeptics? The answer is that skepticism has taken numerous different forms in the history of philosophy. Although the Cyrenaic position may differ in crucial ways from skepticism as understood in the ancient period—the hallmark of which, both in Sextus’s hands and elsewhere, was suspension of judgment of one form or another—anyone approaching the Cyrenaics with a background in reflections about skepticism in the modern period will immediately see their philosophy as having a strong skeptical component. For skepticism in the modern period has generally been regarded as centering around the denial of the possibility of knowledge in some domain: about the “external world,” about other minds, about induction, and so on. As we have already noted, the Cyrenaics, if Sextus is right, hold something that clearly has at least a family resemblance with external world skepticism; we shall also see hints of a position resembling other minds skepticism. So to the extent that the Cyrenaics qualify as skeptics, it is in an anachronistic fashion, because of the resemblance of some of their views to views that would now be called “skeptical,” not because of anything that would have been recognized as skepticism in the ancient world. How close the Cyrenaic position is even to varieties of skepticism discussed today is an interesting and subtle question; I shall suggest in what follows that we should be careful not to try to assimilate them too closely. If I am right about this last point,

16

SKEPTICISM

then the Cyrenaics serve as an illuminating foil to skepticism in both the ancient and the modern periods. In order to develop this line of thought, however, we need to look more closely at what the Cyrenaic position actually was. I shall say no more about their ideas on pleasure, nor will I address the very interesting questions surrounding their picture of the relation between pleasure and happiness,5 except to say that this side of their thought seems to reveal the same tendency to restrict their concerns to what is immediately accessible to experience as we find in their epistemological ideas. It is the latter on which I shall concentrate from now on.

2  THE VIEW IN MORE DETAIL The passage of Sextus referred to in the previous section attributes to the Cyrenaics the view that only the πάθη, and not the objects causing them, are or can be apprehended (PH 1.215). We find the same attribution in another, considerably longer passage of Sextus in which the Cyrenaic view is summarized (AM 7.191–200—on the present point see especially 191, 195); this is a section of Sextus’s lengthy review, in the first book of Against the Logicians, of positions, positive and negative, concerning the criterion of truth. Several other authors also cite them as holding that only the πάθη can be apprehended: the Anonymous Commentator on the Theaetetus (on 152b, col. 65, 29–39), Aristocles of Messene in a passage on the Cyrenaics quoted by Eusebius (Praep. evang. 19.1–2), Eusebius himself in introducing this passage (Praep. evang. 18.31),6 and Diogenes Laertius in his life of Aristippus (DL 2.92). Despite the close verbal agreement among all these passages, there is room for some doubt as to whether the terminology of apprehension (κατάληψις) goes back to the Cyrenaics’ own original formulation of the position. As far as we can tell, this terminology was first given an epistemological connotation by Zeno of Citium, the first Stoic (Cicero, Acad. 2.145). Now, there is an unresolved debate (and the evidence may be insufficient to settle this) over whether the Cyrenaics’ epistemology was part of their position from its beginning with the older Aristippus, a disciple of Socrates, or was added later—probably by his grandson, also named Aristippus.7 But although the older Aristippus’s precise dates are uncertain, and those of his grandson even more so, it is clear that both must have predated Zeno, whose birthdate is generally placed in the later 330s BCE.8 Hence, if the report that Zeno invented κατάληψις as a philosophical term is correct, the Cyrenaic view is likely to have been developed too early to make use of it. By the time of the authors who are our sources, it was no longer restricted to Stoicism, but was common philosophical parlance for any kind of secure cognitive awareness; and this would explain why it became standard in describing the Cyrenaic position, even if the Cyrenaics themselves did not use this language. However, this need not trouble us, since what is clearly the same position is also reported to us without the language of apprehension.9 Plutarch tells us that the Cyrenaics saw each πάθος as “having its own evidence [ἐνάργειαν] within itself, which is not to be challenged” (Adv. Col. 1120E). In Hellenistic and later philosophical contexts, ἐνάργεια regularly indicates something’s being a matter of plain and incontrovertible experience, and hence it plays a role equivalent to that

THE CYRENAICS AND SKEPTICISM

17

of apprehension in the other passages: it specifies that there is no room for doubt or dispute about how these πάθη come across to us.10 By contrast, Plutarch says that they “thought that the assurance [πίστιν] coming from them [i.e., from the πάθη] was not sufficient for firm declarations about the objects”—that is, the objects causing those πάθη (1120D); examples are whether honey is sweet, an olive-shoot bitter, hail cold, wine warm, the sun bright, or night dark (1120E). Similarly, Cicero tells us that the Cyrenaics held that “they do not know what has which color or which sound, but only sense that they are affected in a certain way” (Acad. 2.76.).11 The outlines of the view, then, are clear enough: we can have a certain kind of secure grasp of something about the πάθη themselves, but the objects that caused them are not amenable to any such grasp. It is now time to get clearer about what this amounts to. First of all, what is a πάθος? Most generally, it is something that happens to someone or something, or that someone or something undergoes. Most often, but certainly not always, it is human beings who are described as having πάθη, and this is clearly true for the Cyrenaics; it is our own πάθη of which we are said to have apprehension. In human contexts the word is frequently translated “emotions,” “passions,” or “feelings”; these can often be appropriate, but in the present case they are too narrow. From the texts already adduced, it is clear that the πάθη include cases of ordinary sense-perception, with no particular affective component; this is suggested by the frequent talk of the external objects (the character of which we cannot apprehend) versus our πάθη of them, and is confirmed by the examples from Plutarch and Cicero in the previous paragraph. Indeed, these appear to be the cases of most immediate interest for our purposes, although pleasure and pain are also included by the Cyrenaics among the πάθη (Sextus, AM 7.199, DL 2.86, Cic. Acad. 2.76). Above, in an attempt to capture this diversity, I translated πάθη as “ways we are affected”; it is not clear that any single English word will do.12 From now on I will simply use the Greek word. What, then, is apprehended on the Cyrenaic view, and what cannot be apprehended? On the side of the objects, it seems clear enough that we cannot apprehend the objects’ real or intrinsic character; we can know how we are affected by these objects, but not how they are in themselves.13 And it may seem that the answer on the side of the subject having the πάθη is equally clear: one apprehends, or has infallible access to, one’s own subjective experience of these objects. This may also seem to be supported by Sextus’s talk of the πάθη as “apparent” (φαινόμενα) to us (AM 7.194, 197).14 But the other sources do not use this language, and it may well be that Sextus is translating the Cyrenaics’ position into language with which he himself and his assumed audience are familiar (so Tsouna 1998: chapter 4.V). Sextus also reports the Cyrenaic view using a different form of language; the same form of words also appears in Plutarch’s report, and Plutarch explicitly claims to be giving the view as the Cyrenaics themselves present it—by contrast with the Epicurean Colotes, whom he criticizes for misrepresenting it (Adv. Col. 1120D–E). According to these sources, in characterizing the πάθη the Cyrenaics said that we are “sweetened,” “whitened,” “reddened,” “chilled,” “heated,” etc. (AM 7.192– 193, Adv. Col. 1120E); in what appears to be interchangeable terminology, Sextus

18

SKEPTICISM

also has them saying that we are “affected [or “activated,” κινεῖται] yellowly,” “redly,” etc. (AM 7.192, 198). Now, to say that we are “sweetened” or “whitened” does not seem the most natural language to use if one wanted to talk purely about experiencing something as sweet or white. Rather, it sounds as if something in us is being said to turn sweet or white.15 And this recalls another, roughly contemporary account of sense perception—at least as some scholars have read it. On one interpretation of Aristotle’s account of sense perception,16 the sense organs actually acquire, when one perceives, the sensory qualities belonging to the objects of senseperception; for example, the interior of one’s eye turns red when one sees a red tomato. Whether or not this is right about Aristotle, it seems a natural reading of the Cyrenaic terminology—thinking now, of course, about the perceiver’s side alone. For someone to be “reddened” is for something in that person to become red, the sense organ for vision being the obvious candidate; and the same would be true, mutatis mutandis, for “sweetened,” “chilled,” and the rest. The other language in Sextus (“affected redly,” etc.) does not point so clearly in this direction, but seems at least compatible with the reading just suggested. This reading might be challenged on the ground that the peculiar verbal forms reported in our sources extend considerably beyond the kind of basic sensory properties considered so far. Plutarch’s report includes the claim that the Cyrenaics also spoke of being “walled,” “horsed,” or “manned” (Adv. Col. 1120D). Now it would be hard to understand these other than as shorthand for “experience a perception as of a wall/horse/man”; that perceiving subjects in any sense become walls, horses, or men during these perceptions would surely be absurd. However, there is good reason not to accept this account of what the Cyrenaics said. Plutarch presents these terms as coming from Colotes’s portrait of the Cyrenaic view, which he says was offered in a spirit of mockery (κωμῳδῶν, 1120D) and which, as noted above, he explicitly rejects, contrasting it with his own account of what the Cyrenaics actually said, where only sensory properties are included. No other evidence includes these outlandish terms, which one would expect to have excited broader ridicule if they had really been part of the view.17 Sextus’s summary does say that “the person who presses on his eye is activated as if by two things,” and goes on to use the verb “doubled” to express this (AM 7.192–193); here is another purported Cyrenaic coinage outside the range of sensory properties, and given Plutarch’s evidence we may find this suspect as well. But, unlike in the case of “walled,” etc., it is not hard to understand “doubled” as referring to an actual change in the sense organ; pressing on your eye might well be thought to divide the material inside into two. Indeed, the reference to pressing on the eye may even support the general reading of these verbs as referring to physiological changes rather than to subjective experiences. If this is indeed what the Cyrenaics mean, we need not deny that they are interested in the experience of tasting something as sweet or seeing it as white; in speaking of the πάθη as apprehensible (or whatever equivalent terms they actually used), they clearly have in mind our grasp of something of which we are subjectively aware.18 Rather, the point is that they do not have a sharp distinction, such as is taken for granted in Descartes and much early modern philosophy, between mental and physical occurrences. One tastes something as sweet, and that thing turns one’s

THE CYRENAICS AND SKEPTICISM

19

tongue sweet. Are these the very same event described in two different ways? There is no indication in the sources that the Cyrenaics have any concern to distinguish them. And if not, then our πάθη, the ways we are affected by objects, are not purely mental events; they are also effects on our bodies. By the same token, they are not purely subjective, but also things happening in the world, describable from a thirdperson perspective.19 And this is one reason why one should not try to assimilate the Cyrenaics too closely to the typical figure of “the skeptic” in modern philosophy. While it is not false that the Cyrenaics deny that we can know about the external world, “external” in this case means “external to our bodies,” not “external to our subjective awareness.”20 Another reason why it is hazardous to assimilate the Cyrenaics to the modern skeptic is that they do not seem to question the existence of the external world (in any sense of “external”). Instead, the question is consistently whether we know what the objects causing our πάθη are like. Their answer is that we do not know this; but that there are objects out there, to which our πάθη are somehow a response, is taken for granted. For example, Sextus tells us that, on the Cyrenaic view, “that we are whitened and we are sweetened, it is possible to say . . . irrefutably; but that the thing productive of the effect is white or sweet, it is not possible to assert” (AM 7.191). And Aristocles reports that “they said that, when being burned or cut, they knew that they were affected in some way; but whether the thing burning them was fire or the thing cutting them was iron, they were not able to say” (in Eusebius, Praep. evang. 14.19.1). Sextus’s report once seems to show them inching toward a question about existence; he says that “the external thing productive of the effect is perhaps (τάχα) a being, but it is not apparent to us” (AM 7.194). But there is no indication that they ever followed through on that suggestion and explicitly raised the question.21 One might say that this is simply a failure to see where the logic of their position was leading them. But if, as I have suggested, the πάθη are physiological events as much as experiences, it is not perhaps surprising; a view according to which there were human bodies, but maybe no world for them to inhabit, would be a strange view indeed. So if it is true that “external” means something different for the Cyrenaics from what it means for a Cartesian, this is not unconnected with their focus on the nature of external objects rather than their existence. In addition to doubts about our knowledge of the world around us, Sextus’s report includes doubts about our knowledge of the πάθη of others, which seems to anticipate what is today called “skepticism about other minds.” No other source mentions this, but it is hard to see why Sextus would simply invent it in the course of a description of what the Cyrenaics say. It appears to be introduced as part of the argument for external objects being inapprehensible; the idea seems to be that we cannot tell what objects are like because we cannot compare our πάθη with those of others and confirm that they are qualitatively the same (AM 7.196–197). One may wonder why, even if we could do this, it would give us knowledge of the way things are; might not all humans see things distortedly?22 But I am not sure the argument has to deny this; the idea may be that, since we cannot even tell whether we see things the same way as others—which, even if we could, might not be enough— the prospects for getting to a secure grasp of the nature of those things are truly

20

SKEPTICISM

hopeless. In any case, Sextus says that according to the Cyrenaics, “each person grasps the πάθος that is his own,” but that since we do not grasp each other’s πάθη, “it is rash to say that what appears a certain way to me also appears that way to the next person.” If our own πάθη are all we can be sure about, it is indeed not hard to see how the πάθη of others might be judged just as elusive as the character of the objects that produce them. But again, just as the existence of the external world does not seem to be an issue for the Cyrenaics, nor is there any hint of solipsism. Nothing in this passage suggests any doubt that there are other minds; what goes on in them is the question. Again, part of the reason for this may be that the πάθη are, as I put it earlier, not purely mental,23 but the connection is not as obvious as in the case of the external world. So the Cyrenaics interestingly anticipate what in modern times has been called skepticism about the external world, and also, if Sextus is to be believed, skepticism about other minds. There are also interesting and important differences. But certainly they are much closer to these modern forms of skepticism than are any other ancient thinkers—including, to return to my opening point, the ancient thinkers who called themselves skeptics. Finally, we can now see why Sextus ought to distinguish himself from the Cyrenaics not only, as he says, on the inapprehensibility of external things, but also on the apprehensibility of the πάθη, which was the point on which those who wished to assimilate the two schools were said to rely (PH 1.215). Sextus does not question the way things appear to him; indeed, he says that this is not a topic for discussion (PH 1.22). But this is not the same as asserting that a whole class of items, the πάθη, can be infallibly known about—which is what the claim of apprehensibility amounts to; that would be a theoretical claim.24 The Cyrenaics have an epistemological doctrine of which apprehensibility of the πάθη and the inapprehensibility of their objects are interconnected parts; both should equally be anathema to Sextus. True skeptics in the ancient sense are not philosophers, in any usual sense of the term; the Cyrenaics are.

NOTES 1. See, e.g., Matson (2006) and Taylor (2012), both in standard reference works. 2. Translations are my own. 3. The sentence also contains the difficult phrase ὅσον ἐπὶ τῷ λόγῳ: “as far as the argument goes,” “as far as reason is concerned.” However precisely one translates it, the point seems to be that the skeptic makes no attempt to theorize about the nature of these “external” objects. See Brunschwig (1994: 250). 4. I shall return to the question of what the πάθη are and how the word should be translated; the somewhat cumbersome translation “ways we are affected” is intended as a place-holder until that point. 5. On this, see especially DL 2.87–88, and for two partially differing interpretations, see O’Keefe (2002) and Tsouna-McKirahan (2002). 6. On this division of the text between Eusebius and Aristocles, see Chiesara (2001: fragment F5 and Introduction, section II, especially xxvi–xxviii).

THE CYRENAICS AND SKEPTICISM

21

7. In this chapter, for reasons of space, I do not attempt to address the history of the school or possible differences among individual members. Our sources in any case consistently report Cyrenaic epistemology as adopted by the school in general (unlike their ethics, where we hear of a number of individual differences—see especially DL 2.93–100); the only question is whether it was part of their philosophy from the start. 8. The evidence on the older Aristippus’s chronology is conflicting and hard to interpret; see Giannantoni (1990: Note 13, vol. 4, 135–140), and for the ancient sources, Giannantoni (1990: vol. 2, section IV-A). There are no precise chronological indications for the younger Aristippus. But someone who was an adult in Socrates’s lifetime must have been born no later than the 420s, which almost certainly puts the younger Aristippus at least a generation earlier than Zeno. 9. Here (as on almost every other point in this section) I am in agreement with Tsouna (1998); see chapter 4.I on the present issue. This book is an essential resource for anyone wishing to pursue this subject further. 10. Hence ἀπερίσπαστος can confidently be translated (as above) “not to be challenged,” not merely “not challenged.” Adjectives ending in –τος routinely have this descriptive/prescriptive ambiguity, but the occurrence of ἐνάργεια shows that the prescriptive translation is not misleading. (Incidentally, ἐνάργεια is an emendation. But the mss. reading ἐνέργεια, “activity” makes no sense, and the correction is an easy one.) 11. In the same section, Cicero says that “they deny that anything external can be perceived, and that they perceive only those things that they sense with internal touch.” But “perceive” (percipi) in Cicero’s Academica is used as equivalent to the Greek καταλαμβάνειν, “apprehend,” even though his actual translation of καταλαμβάνειν is comprehendere (2.145–146); since my present interest is in evidence independent of the notion of apprehension, I leave these words aside. 12. The translation “affections” is still sometimes used, presumably intended as shorthand for “ways we are affected”; but in contemporary English the word “affections” has connotations that are hopelessly misleading in the current context. In the past I have used “effects,” but this fails to bring out the fact that a πάθος is something that happens to a subject (be that subject animate or inanimate). 13. Zilioli (2012) has argued that this is because, according to the Cyrenaics, there is no way things are in themselves; things are indeterminate in their nature. On this reading the Cyrenaics would resemble Pyrrho, on some interpretations of his thought. I have argued against this in Bett (2015); see also O’Keefe (2013). 14. See, however, Everson (1991), which argues that even the category of the apparent, in the hands of the Pyrrhonists, should not be construed in subjectivist terms. For some well-founded doubts about this, see Fine (2003), especially section 6. 15. Diego Machuca commented that the point may simply be to put the focus on the ways in which one is affected, and to avoid any reference to the causes. I quite agree that this is the intention. But what are the ways in which one is affected? This peculiar form of language suggests that the Cyrenaics mean to identify something other than pure subjective experience. The account that I go on to sketch seems to me the most natural way to make sense of this idiosyncratic terminology; given the state of our evidence, it would be rash to claim anything stronger.

22

SKEPTICISM

16. E.g., Ross (1923: 137), Sorabji (1974). 17. Here I follow Kechagia (2011: chapter 8.2). Tsouna (1998: chapter 6.III) also rejects Colotes’s picture. 18. My account is thus not inconsistent with that of Fine (2003: section 5) Fine’s focus is on the subjective aspect of the Cyrenaics’ πάθη; her concern is to rebut the idea, stemming from Burnyeat (1982), that ancient Greek philosophy does not recognize a category of the subjective that is anything like that which we find in philosophy since Descartes. I think that she is successful in this aim. But Fine does not deny that these πάθη are also physical states, though she is not particularly interested in their character. 19. Of course, whether these events could ever be reliably observed from a third-person perspective is put in doubt by the other side of the Cyrenaic position, that the objects causing the πάθη are not apprehensible. That you are “reddened” may be apprehensible to you, and this may have an objective aspect (your eye’s turning red) as well as a subjective one (something’s looking red to you). But your being reddened is not apprehensible to anyone else, because to everyone else your eye’s turning red is not a πάθος, but an external event. 20. That the conception of one’s body as “external” originates with Descartes is not a new idea; it was first made prominent in Burnyeat (1982). 21. Another passage of Sextus (AM 6.53) claims that the Cyrenaics thought that only the πάθη exist, which sounds like an outright denial, not just a questioning, of the existence of the external world. But this is in a polemical context in which some highly dubious claims are also made about Plato and Democritus; it should almost certainly be discounted. See Tsouna (1998: 80–81) and Bett (2013: 177–178). 22. Tsouna (1998: chapter 7) raises this objection and then explores alter­ native interpretations. 23. Tsouna (1998: 93–95) has some suggestions in that direction. 24. On this, see further O’Keefe (2011). Perin (2010) argues that Sextus takes us to have noninferential knowledge of how things appear to us. (Fine (2003: 209) also considers this possibility, but is uncertain.) But, first, this is an inference from other things that he says; he certainly does not say anything that could be translated by these words. What we think an ancient philosopher was committed to holding may not always correspond to what that ancient philosopher actually held. Second, even if we accept Perin’s view, it does not follow that Sextus would or should be comfortable with the dogmatic notion of apprehension; one can claim in a commonsense way to know things (even noninferentially, as in “I just know it”), without having or wishing to have any precise commitments concerning what that amounts to. Both Perin (2010: 160) and Fine (2003: 208) draw attention to the fact that Sextus reports the view of those who would assimilate the Cyrenaics to the skeptics with the words “it too says that only the πάθη are apprehended,” and does not reject the implication that this is the skeptic’s view. However, as I noted earlier, he also does not endorse this implication; and my claim here is that he is well-advised not to do so.

THE CYRENAICS AND SKEPTICISM

23

REFERENCES Bett, Richard. 2013. “A Sceptic Looks at Art (but not Very Closely): Sextus Empiricus on Music,” International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 3: 155–181. Bett, Richard. 2015. “Pyrrho and the Socratic Schools.” In U. Zilioli (ed.), From the Socratics to the Socratic Schools, 149–167. London: Routledge. Brunschwig, Jacques 1994. “The ὅσον ἐπὶ τῷ λόγῳ Formula in Sextus Empiricus.” In his, Papers in Hellenistic Philosophy, 244–258. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Burnyeat, Myles. 1982. “Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw and Berkeley Missed,” Philosophical Review 91: 3–40. Chiesara, Maria Lorenza. 2001. Aristocles of Messene: Testimonia and Fragments, edited with translation and commentary. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. Everson, Stephen. 1991. “The Objective Appearance of Pyrrhonism.” In S. Everson (ed.), Companions to Ancient Thought 2: Psychology, 121–147. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Fine, Gail. 2003. “Subjectivity, Ancient and Modern: The Cyrenaics, Sextus, and Descartes.” In J. Miller and Brad Inwood (eds.), Hellenistic and Early Modern Philosophy, 192–231. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Giannantoni, Gabriele. 1990. Socratis et Socraticorum Reliquiae, 4 vols. Naples: Bibliopolis. Kechagia, Eleni. 2011. Plutarch Against Colotes: A Lesson in the History of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Matson, Wallace. 2006. “Cyrenaics.” In D. M. Borchert (ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd ed., vol. 2, 619–620. Farmington Hills, MI: Thomson Gale. O’Keefe, Tim. 2002. “The Cyrenaics on Pleasure, Happiness, and Future-Concern,” Phronesis 47: 395–416. O’Keefe, Tim. 2011. “The Cyrenaics vs. the Pyrrhonists on Knowledge of Appearances.” In D. Machuca (ed.), New Essays on Ancient Pyrrhonism, 27–40. Leiden and Boston: Brill. O’Keefe, Tim. 2013. Review of Zilioli (2012), Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2013.04.14. Perin, Casey. 2010. “Scepticism and Belief.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 145–64. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ross, David. 1923. Aristotle. London: Methuen. Sorabji, Richard. 1974. “Body and Soul in Aristotle,” Philosophy 49: 63–89. Taylor, C. C. W. 2012. “Cyrenaics.” In S. Hornblower and A. Spawforth (eds.), The Oxford Classical Dictionary, 4th ed., 405. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Tsouna, Voula. 1998. The Epistemology of the Cyrenaic School. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tsouna-McKirahan, Voula. 2002. “Is there an Exception to Greek eudaimonism?” In M. Canto-Sperber and P. Pellegrin (eds.), Le style de la pensée: receuil de texts en hommage à Jacques Brunschwig, 464–489. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. Zilioli, Ugo. 2012. The Cyrenaics. Durham: Acumen.

CHAPTER TWO

Pyrrho and Timon CASEY PERIN

1  PYRRHO THE OBSCURE We know remarkably little about the life of Pyrrho. Born sometime around 365 BCE in Elis on the Peloponnesos, he was, according to Antigonus of Carystus by way of Diogenes Laertius, a failed painter turned philosopher. Several ancient authors report that Pyrrho traveled to India as part of Alexander’s expedition. There he is said by Diogenes Laertius to have encountered certain “naked wise men” (γυμνοσοφισταί) and, as a result, to have developed certain philosophical views. However, he did not record these views in writing as he appears to have written nothing. He died sometime around 275 BCE. It is arguable that we know even less about Pyrrho’s philosophical views than we do about his life. There is a consensus among scholars that the most important text for understanding Pyrrho’s philosophical position is a passage from the latefirst-century BCE or early-first-century CE Peripatetic philosopher Aristocles’s On Philosophy. This and other passages from Aristocles’s treatise are preserved in Eusebius’s (260–340 CE) Praeparatio evangelica. Aristocles reports a number of claims he attributes to Pyrrho’s disciple and publicist Timon of Phlius (c. 325–c. 235 BCE). Timon, in turn, attributes at least one of these claims to Pyrrho. It is not easy to tease out just what in the passage comes from Aristocles, what from Timon, and what, if anything, from Pyrrho. Few scholars think Aristocles is quoting Timon directly. Many, though, think his paraphrase of Timon is, at least for the most part, accurate. And many of these scholars think the text by Timon that Aristocles accurately paraphrases itself accurately reports Pyrrho’s views. Hence, these scholars think we can read back through Aristocles via Timon to Pyrrho. Other scholars are less optimistic and think that what we get in Aristocles’s passage is either mostly the views of Timon or, worse, the views of a Timon badly distorted by Aristocles.1 I see no way to settle these issues. However, unless we assume that what Aristocles tells us about Timon, and what Timon tells us about Pyrrho, is accurate, then Pyrrho as a philosopher is more or less lost to us. For this reason, I will proceed on the assumption that the Aristocles passage tells us something about Pyrrho and Timon if only we can make sense of what it is.2

PYRRHO AND TIMON

25

2  THE PASSAGE FROM ARISTOCLES Here, in as neutral a translation as I think possible, is the Aristocles passage in full. (For ease of exposition I have divided the passage into six sections [A] through [F].) A. It is necessary above all to consider our own knowledge; for if it is our nature to know nothing, there is no need to inquire any further into things. There were some among the ancients, too, who made this statement, whom Aristotle has argued against. Pyrrho of Elis was also a powerful advocate of such a position (ἴσχυσε μὲν τοιαῦτα λέγων καὶ Πύρρων ὁ Ἠλεῖος). B. He himself has left nothing in writing; his pupil Timon, however, says that the person who is to be happy must look to these three points: first, what are things like by nature (ὁποῖα πέφυκε τὰ πρὰγματα)? Second, in what way ought we to be disposed toward them (τίνα χρὴ τρόπον ἡμᾶς πρὸς αὐτὰ διακεῖσθαι)? And, finally, what will be the result for those who are so disposed? C. He [Timon] says that he [Pyrrho] reveals that things are equally indistinguishable/indifferent (ἀδιάφορα) and unmeasurable/unstable (ἀστάθμητα) and indeterminable/indeterminate (ἀνεπίκριτα); D. for this reason (διὰ τοῦτο) neither our sensations nor our opinions (μήτε τὰς αἰσθήσεις ἡμῶν μήτε τὰς δόξας) tell the truth or lie (ἀληθεύειν ἢ ψεύδεσθαι). E. For this reason, then (διὰ τοῦτο οὖν), we should not trust them, but should be without opinions (ἀδοξάστους) and without inclinations and without wavering, saying about each single thing that it no more (οὐ μᾶλλον) is than is not or both is and is not or neither is nor is not. F. Timon says that the result for those who are so disposed will be first an inability to say anything (ἀφασία), but then tranquility (ἀταραξία); and Aenesidemus says pleasure. These, then, are the main points of what they say. (Eusebius 14.18.1-5)3 The passage has the following structure. In [A] Aristocles attributes to Pyrrho the view that in virtue of our nature we can’t know anything. However, Aristocles himself notes that Pyrrho wrote nothing. Hence, when he attributes this view to Pyrrho, Aristocles must by relying on what someone else has said or written about Pyrrho. So in [B] Aristocles either quotes or paraphrases Timon. But the connection between the quotation from or paraphrase of Timon and the view attributed to Pyrrho in [A] is not obvious. Pyrrho is said to have held the view that we can’t know anything. Timon is said to have made a claim about what is required for someone to be happy. Specifically, Timon is reported as saying that to be happy a person must consider, and presumably answer correctly, three questions. Then, in [C], we get the only claim clearly and explicitly attributed to Pyrrho by Timon. And, apparently, this claim constitutes an answer, and is understood by Timon to be Pyrrho’s answer,

26

SKEPTICISM

to the first of the three questions relevant to happiness. In [D] an inference is made, either by Pyrrho or Timon or both, from the claim attributed to Pyrrho in [C]. A second inference is made in [E] and generates the answer given by either Pyrrho or Timon or both to the second of the three questions relevant to happiness. Finally, in [F], Aristocles reports the answer Timon gives, and may implicitly attribute to Pyrrho, to the third of the three questions relevant to happiness. Aristocles then claims to have presented the “main points” of what “they” (Pyrrho and Timon? and Aenesidemus?) say.

3  TWO READINGS OF PYRRHO The claim attributed to Pyrrho by Timon in section [C] is supposed to be an answer to the first of the three questions relevant to happiness. Hence, it is supposed to be a claim about what things are like by nature. The initial, and perhaps most fundamental, interpretative problem with the passage is how to understand the trio of adjectives by which Pyrrho describes what things are like by nature. Here there are two general interpretative options: the so-called subjective versus objective or, better, the epistemic versus the metaphysical reading of the adjectives. According to the former, Pyrrho’s fundamental claim is that things are indeterminable by us (as, on this reading, ἀνεπίκριτα is taken to mean), that is, we can’t determine, and hence can’t know, what things are like.4 More precisely, Pyrrho’s is the minimally informative claim that (α) Things by nature are such that we can’t know what they are like. A problem arises if, as appears to be the case, (α) falls within its own scope. (α) is a claim about what things are like by nature (otherwise it fails to answer the first of the three questions relevant to happiness). But (α) says that we can’t know what things are like. A fortiori we can’t know what things are like by nature. Hence, we can’t know that things by nature are such that we can’t know what they are like. And if that is so, we can’t know that (α) is true. So if (α) falls within its own scope, and if Pyrrho asserts (α) as something he knows, Pyrrho’s assertion of (α) is self-refuting. If (α) is something Pyrrho knows, it is false; if (α) is true, it is not something Pyrrho knows. Pyrrho can avoid these problems if he thinks that somehow (α) does not fall within its own scope. He would then think, for reasons we can only guess, that the one thing we can know about what things are like is that they are by nature such that we can’t know what they are like. On the metaphysical reading, Pyrrho is making a more substantial claim about what things are like by nature. This is the strange, almost paradoxical, claim that (as Richard Bett formulates it) “things in themselves have no fixed and definite character” (Bett 2000: 20).5 That is, things are “indifferent” in the sense that any one thing lacks properties that would distinguish it from any other thing; things are “unstable” in the sense that their natures change; and things are “indeterminate” in the sense that that they have no determinate features or properties. On the metaphysical reading, Pyrrho’s answer to the question “What are things like by nature?” is that there is nothing at all that things are like by nature.

PYRRHO AND TIMON

27

4  ZELLER’S EMENDATION Partisans of the metaphysical reading have argued, and many partisans of the epistemic reading have agreed, that the epistemic reading of Pyrrho’s claim wrecks the logic of Aristocles’s text as we have it. Either Pyrrho or Timon or both make an inference from the claim attributed to Pyrro in section [C] to the claim in section [D] that “neither our sensations nor our beliefs tell the truth or lie.” Most, though not all, scholars take the latter claim to mean that our sensations and beliefs neither constantly nor consistently tell the truth nor constantly nor consistently lie, that is, they are unreliable. Suppose the claim in section [D] is understood in this way. Suppose, further, that Pyrrho’s claim in section [C] is equivalent to or at least clearly implies that we can’t know what things are like.6 In Aristocles’s text as we have it, either Pyrrho or Timon or both would be making an inference from (1) We can’t know what things are like. to (2) Our sensations and beliefs are unreliable. Yet, as commentators regularly note, the inference ought to go the other way: at best (1) is a consequence of (2), not (2) of (1). Since this is so, partisans of the epistemic reading of Pyrrho’s claim have been thought to have only one option, namely, to emend Aristocles’s text so that either Pyrrho or Timon or both infer (1) from (2) rather than (2) from (1).7 Hence, partisans of the epistemic reading have accepted an emendation first proposed by the nineteenthcentury German scholar Eduard Zeller. Sections [C] and [D] of Aristocles’s text as we have it read (in the translation favored by the epistemic reading): [C] He [Timon] says that he [Pyrrho] reveals that things are equally indistinguishable and unmeasurable and indeterminable; [D] for this reason, (διὰ τοῦτο) neither our sensations nor our opinions tell the truth or lie. Zeller altered the italicized phrase so that the emended text reads: [C] He [Timon] says that he [Pyrrho] reveals that things are equally indifferent and unstable and indeterminate [D] on account of the fact that (διὰ τό neither our sensations nor our opinions tell the truth or lie. Zeller’s emendation reverses the direction of the inference made in sections [C] and [D]. Now either Pyrrho or Timon or both make an inference from (what they take to be the fact that) our sensations and beliefs are unreliable to the conclusion that we can’t know what things are like. And, the partisans of the epistemic reading of Pyrrho’s claim insist that inference is at least intelligible. Moreover, and importantly, there are linguistic and paleographic considerations that independently support, even if they do not strictly require, Zeller’s emendation.8

5  PYRRHO THE METAPHYSICIAN Partisans of the metaphysical reading of Pyrrho’s claim resist Zeller’s emendation as unnecessary. In their view, once Pyrrho’s claim and the claim made in section [D]

28

SKEPTICISM

are properly understood, the logic of Aristocles’s text as we have it is clear. On the metaphysical reading, the claim Pyrrho makes in section [C] is that (1) Things are indeterminate, that is, things do not have any determinate property. Now the inference from (1*) to (2) Our sensations and beliefs are unreliable. is not promising. But Bett argues that (2) does not capture the meaning of the claim reported in section [D] of Aristocles’s text. That claim is not (2) but (2) Our sensations and beliefs are neither true nor false. And, Bett insists, the inference from (1*) to (2*) is perspicuous. According to him, a sensation or belief is either true or false only if there is “some definite state of affairs” that the sensation or belief “either correctly or incorrectly represents” (Bett 2000: 23). The import of (1*) is that there are no definite states of affairs at all. So there is no state of affairs of, for example, lemons being yellow. Why? Lemons, like any other thing, have no determinate properties. Hence, they have no determinate color properties. Since this is so, the sensation or belief that lemons are yellow is not true. Nor, Bett argues, is it false. For it is false that lemons are yellow only if there is a state of affairs of lemons being not yellow but some other color. But, given their lack of determinate color properties, there is no color lemons are. Bett’s argument turns on two points, one linguistic and the other philosophical. First, it isn’t clear that the claim made in section [D]—that “neither our sensations nor our beliefs tell the truth or lie”—is best, or even plausibly, interpreted as (2*). We might think that in section [D] Aristocles preserves in its original formulation a claim made by Timon (and we might think this regardless of whether we think Timon, in turn, preserves in its original formulation a claim made by Pyrrho). But we might also think that what Aristocles gives us in section [D] is not unadulterated Timon but rather his—that is, Aristocles’s—explication of a claim made by Timon. If the words in [D] are not Timon’s but Aristocles’s, then the context in which they occur might give us some clue about how to understand them. That context is Aristocles’s treatise On Philosophy. Eusebius transcribes five sections of this treatise in his Praeparatio evangelica. Tad Brennan has shown in convincing detail that in this context the claim in section [D] is best understood as a claim about the general reliability of our sensations and beliefs and so as (2) rather than (2*) (Brennan 1998: 426–429). Second, Bett’s claim that the inference from (1*) to (2*) is perspicuous depends on a particular view about the conditions under which a proposition is false. On his view, a proposition of the form ‘x is F’ is false just in case some proposition of the form ‘x is G’ (where being G is incompatible with being F) is true. That is, ‘x is F’ is false just in case some determinate state of affairs contrary to x’s being F obtains (Bett 2000: 22–23 and n.19). Call this the strong conception of falsehood. Since, on the metaphysical reading of Pyrrho’s claim that Bett favors, no determinate state of affairs obtains, no proposition of the form ‘x is F’ is false. However, there are

PYRRHO AND TIMON

29

two problems with any version of the metaphysical reading of Pyrrho that relies on the strong conception of falsehood. First, as several scholars have noted, this conception of falsehood is neither mandatory nor standard.9 We might reject it in favor of the weak conception of falsehood according to which ‘x is F’ is false if the state of affairs specified by that proposition—x’s being F—fails to obtain. On the weak conception of falsehood, that is, a proposition’s being false requires only that a certain state of affairs does not obtain and not, as on the strong conception, that some other state of affairs does obtain. Given the weak conception of falsehood, the inference from (1*) to (2*) is invalid. If, as (1*) says or implies, no determinate states of affairs obtain, then it follows that every proposition of the form ‘x is F’ is false. Hence, every sensation or belief whose propositional content is of this form is false. So Bett must show that there is reason to think that either Pyrrho or Timon, or both, accepted the strong rather than the weak conception of falsehood. Even if he can do so, however, there is a second and even more serious problem. For it appears that the metaphysical reading can’t attribute the strong conception of falsehood to Pyrrho or Timon, or both, without undermining itself.10 On this reading they reject as false the claim that things are determinate where that just is or implies the claim that there are no determinate states of affairs. But this they can’t do if they accept the strong conception of falsehood. For on that conception of falsehood, it is false that (3) There are determinate states of affairs. only if some determinate state of affairs contrary to (3) obtains. But if any determinate state of affairs obtains, then (3) is true. So if Pyrrho or Timon, or both, accept the strong conception of falsehood, they can’t reject (3) as false. Hence, on pain of inconsistency, they must reject (1*) as false. If they do so, however, then the metaphysical reading is false. Alternatively, if they accept (1*), then, again on pain of inconsistency, they must reject the strong conception of falsehood. There is another option open to those inclined to favor a metaphysical reading of Pyrrho’s claim and to read the claim in section [D] as (2*) rather than (2). Again, the claim attributed to Pyrrho in section [C] is, on the metaphysical reading, that “things (πράγματα) are equally indifferent and unstable and indeterminate.” Jacques Brunschwig has argued, ingeniously, that the inference from (1*) to (2*) is perfectly acceptable if we make two assumptions. First, we assume that our sensations and beliefs are themselves “things” and so fall within the scope of Pyrrho’s claim. And, second, we assume that the way in which sensations and beliefs are “equally indifferent and unstable and indeterminate” is that they are neither true nor false (Brunschwig 1994: 199–202). It is not clear, though, that we have good reason to make either of these assumptions, especially the first. Brunschwig seems to think that the claim in section [D] must be part of the answer being given to the first of the three questions relevant to happiness, and so must be a claim about what things are like by nature. This is so only if our sensations and beliefs, and not just the things in the world they are of or about, are things (πράγματα). But why think that everything said in sections [C] through [F] of the passage must be part of an answer to one or another of the three questions relevant to happiness? Why not think, as

30

SKEPTICISM

Bett does, that [D] is the conclusion of an inference made from the answer given in [C] to the first of the three questions concerning happiness?

6  A LIFE WITHOUT BELIEFS In section [E] we get the answer either Pyrrho or Timon, or both, give to the second of the three questions relevant to happiness (“In what way ought we to be disposed toward things?”). We are told that we should not trust our sensations or beliefs or even have any beliefs at all. This claim is inferred from the claim made in section [D]. If that claim is construed as (2), the inference is easy: the claim that our sensations and beliefs are unreliable is the basis for the recommendation not to trust them but to suspend judgment. Bett has argued that if the claim in section [D] is construed as (2*), the inference is no less easy. But here we should ask why the fact that our sensations and beliefs are neither true nor false (the claim made in section [D] as Bett reads it) is a reason not to trust them and to avoid having any beliefs at all. According to Bett, we are subject to a misconception if we trust, and so accept as true, a sensation or belief that purports to be true but in fact is neither true nor false. Now I can think of only two possible conceptions of a misconception. It is, or consists in, either (a) a belief that isn’t true or (b) a belief that is false. (a) is the more capacious conception of misconception because the class of propositions that aren’t true (including, as it does, those propositions that are neither true nor false as well as those propositions that are false) is wider than the class of false propositions.11 Consider first (a). In this case Bett would be claiming that the reason to avoid having beliefs that are neither true nor false is that by having them we are thereby subject to a misconception. But, given (a), that misconception just is, or consists in, a belief that is neither true nor false. So Bett’s claim would then be that the reason not to have beliefs that are neither true nor false is that by having them we thereby have a belief that is neither true nor false. But, that, obviously, is no reason at all. It does not tell us what is wrong, in the first place, with having beliefs that are neither true nor false. Consider, next, (b)—the conception of a misconception as consisting in one or more false beliefs. What might be the false belief I acquire by trusting, and so accepting as true, a sensation or belief? On Bett’s own reading of the claim made in section [D] as (2*) rather than (2), it can’t be a false belief about the world. For (2*) says that our beliefs about the world are neither true nor false. So it must be a false belief about the particular sensation or belief I accept as true, namely, that that sensation or belief is true. This higher-order belief is false if my sensation or belief is either false or (as on Bett’s reading of the claim in section [D]) neither true nor false. Bett must think that if I trust, and so accept as true, the sensation or belief that p, then I believe not only that p but also, at least implicitly, that my sensation or belief p is true and so the kind of thing that is either true or false. These implicit beliefs are the content of the misconception to which, according to Bett, I am subject if I trust my sensations and beliefs. It seems to me just possible that this line of thought underwrites the inference from section [D] to section [E]. But, if it does, it makes that inference much less straightforward than it is on a reading of the claim in section [D] as (2) rather than (2*).

PYRRHO AND TIMON

31

In section [E] we are told that, in addition to not having any beliefs, we should be “without inclinations and without wavering” (καὶ ἀκλινεῖς καὶ ἀκραδάντους). It’s plausible to think that we are being told here that the doxastic state or condition we are told we should be in—not having any beliefs—should itself be stable in certain ways. We should be “without inclinations” in the sense that we should lack not only beliefs but also any inclination to believe anything or to accept any sensation as true or to reject it as false. If this is so, then there is a sense in which we will be, as we are told we should, “without wavering.” In the absence of any inclination to believe, we won’t vacillate between doxastic options by first believing one thing and then rejecting it in favor of another. Moreover, we won’t vacillate between having and not having beliefs. The state or condition in which we do not have any beliefs will be (to borrow terminology from Aristotle) firm and unchanging.12

7  MAKING UTTERANCES WITHOUT MAKING ASSERTIONS In section [E] we are also told that we should say “about each thing that it no more is than is not or both is and is not or neither is nor is not.” Either Pyrrho or Timon or both recommend that we take a certain disposition or stance toward things. This disposition consists not only in lacking beliefs but also, perhaps surprisingly, in making utterances. And, crucially, these utterances contain the locution ‘no more’. Here it is important to distinguish two questions we might ask about these utterances. The first question is syntactic: it concerns the scope of the locution ‘no more’. The second question is semantic: it concerns the meaning of that locution and so of the utterances in which it occurs. These utterances will seem slightly less baffling if we assume, as commentators frequently do, that some predicate is understood to follow the occurrences of ‘is’ and ‘is not’ in them (e.g., Bett 2000: 30). So to say that something no more is than is not is to say that it no more is than is not, for example, yellow or round or sweet. Now there are two ways to construe the syntax of the utterance we are told to make about each thing (Stopper 1983: 272–274; Bett 2000: 30). That utterance has three disjuncts. One possibility is that the locution ‘no more’ is embedded in and so governs only one of these disjuncts. On this reading (call it R1), we are being told to say about each thing that it A. no more is than is not; or B. both is and is not; or C. neither is nor is not. This complex disjunctive utterance has a ‘no more’ statement (A) as one and but only one of its disjuncts. Moreover, we might understand disjuncts (B) and (C) as alternatives to disjunct (A). We would then be saying about each thing that one of three things is true of it: either it no more is than is not F (for some predicate ‘F’), or it both is and is not F, or it neither is nor is not F. But we might understand the disjuncts (B) and (C) not as alternatives to (A) but as equivalent formulations of it.

32

SKEPTICISM

On this version of R1, to say about each thing that it no more is than is not F is just to say that it both is and is not F or that it neither is nor is not F. The other syntactic possibility is that the locution ‘no more’ is not embedded in any of the disjuncts but governs all three. On this reading (call it R2), we are being told to utter about each thing one complex ‘no more’ statement. That is, we are to say about each thing that it is no more than A. it is not, or B. it both is and is not, or C. it neither is nor is not. On R2 we would be saying about each thing that it is F no more than it is not F or it both is and is not F or it neither is nor is not F. As far as I can see, no independent consideration (i.e., no consideration independent of the interpretative commitments one has already made in reading the Aristocles passage) gives us good reason to favor R1 over R2, or vice versa. In this context, it is worth nothing that in section [F] Aristocles reports Timon as saying that anyone who adopts the disposition toward things described in section [E] will experience ἀφασία. Since this disposition consists in part in making meaningful utterances of a certain type, ἀφασία can’t be speechlessness or quietude. What might it be then? One plausible suggestion is that ἀφασία is a condition in which one refrains from making not utterances but assertions or at least sincere assertions that express beliefs. We are told in section [E] that we should be disposed toward things in such a way that we have no beliefs. And if we are so disposed, then we have no beliefs we can express in our assertions. Hence, we are in a state in which we refrain from making sincere assertions because we are incapable of making them. However, on either reading R1 or R2, the disjunctive utterances we are told we should make about each thing seem to constitute assertions. We are asserting that one of three disjuncts is true of a thing, or that something of which the three disjuncts are equivalent formulations is true of a thing (versions of reading R1), or that a thing has a certain property or feature no more than it lacks it or both has it and lacks it or neither has it nor lacks it (reading R2). So the prohibition on assertions does not give us reason to favor one syntactical reading of the utterances over the other.13 But how can we respect this prohibition (and so be in a state of ἀφασία) while also making utterances that, regardless of the way we construe their syntax, seem to constitute assertions? The answer we give to this question will depend on the answer we give to the question about the meaning of the locution ‘no more’. And here, again, there are two options that correspond to the epistemic and metaphysical readings of Pyrrho’s claim in section [C]. Partisans of the former will take their cue from the way Sextus Empiricus (PH 1.192) uses the locution ‘no more’ and understand it as expressing suspension of judgment. To say something of the form ‘x no more is than is not F’ is not to make any assertion about x, but rather to express one’s suspension of judgment about whether x is F. Utterances of this sort do not violate the prohibition on assertions. Now suppose we understand the meaning of ‘no more’ in this way. Suppose, further, that we accept reading R2 of the syntax of the utterances that contain this locution. We will then think that in section [E] we are being told that one part

PYRRHO AND TIMON

33

of the disposition we should take toward things consists in making utterances that do nothing more than express the attitude or state of mind (having no beliefs, but suspending judgment, about things) that constitutes the other part of that disposition.14 But suppose, instead, that we accept the metaphysical reading of Pyrrho’s claim and interpret it as the claim that things have no determinate properties. We will think that, unlike Sextus Empiricus, either Pyrrho or Timon or both uses ‘no more’ to assert about some particular thing x that it no more has than lacks a particular property F-ness (see Bett 2000: 32–33). We will also think that, for one reason or another, the prohibition on assertions does not apply to either assertions of this kind or Pyrrho’s more general assertion that things have no determinate properties. Finally, in section [F], Aristocles records Timon’s (if not also Pyrrho’s) answer to the third of the three questions relevant to happiness. Timon claims that those who adopt the correct disposition toward things—where that is a matter of living without beliefs and making utterances of a certain kind—will experience tranquility (ἀταραξία). And this tranquility just is, or at least is a principal component of, happiness.

8  PYRRHO THE SKEPTIC There is, then, little that is clear or uncontroversial about the passage from Aristocles that constitutes our best evidence for Pyrrho’s philosophical views. I have tried to sketch the range of difficult interpretative questions that passage raises. The answers we give to these questions (if we are confident enough to answer them at all) will determine what sort of skeptic, if any, we take Pyrrho and his apparently faithful student Timon to be. On the epistemic reading of his central claim in section [C] of the passage, Pyrrho is a skeptic in the following sense. He, unlike the skeptic described by Sextus Empiricus, has the view that nothing can be known. Moreover, he, or at least Timon, has the view that since this is so, a person ought not to have any beliefs. Hence, Pyrrho, or at least Timon, is also a skeptic in the sense that he adopts the attitude of suspension of judgment toward things. On the metaphysical reading, in contrast, there is little sense in which Pyrrho is a skeptic. He holds the general metaphysical view that things have no determinate properties. This view, in turn, commits him to the view that there are an indefinitely large number of truths we can know. These are truths of the form ‘x is no more F than not F’—for example, “the lemon is no more yellow than not” or “the honey is no more sweet than not.” Yet his general metaphysical view also commits him to the view that we know little of what we ordinarily take ourselves to know, for example, that the lemon is yellow or that the honey is sweet. And this is because, on that view, lemons are not yellow and honey is not sweet. So if, on the metaphysical reading, Pyrrho is less a skeptic than a dogmatic metaphysician, his metaphysical view still has skeptical implications.15

NOTES 1. For the former view, see Brunschwig (1994: 193–195), for the latter, Brennan (1998: 431–432). 2. For an extended defense of this assumption, see Bett (1994).

34

SKEPTICISM

3. The Greek text is most easily found in Long and Sedley (1987: II 5, text 1F). 4. For versions of the epistemic reading of Pyrrho’s claim, see especially Stopper (1983: 274 and 292 n.50), Brennan (1998), and Castagnoli (2002: 447). If we give “indeterminable” an epistemic reading, then we will feel pressure to read the other two adjectives in Pyrrho’s claim epistemically as well. Hence, we’ll take ἀδιάφορα to mean “indistinguishable” by us and ἀστάθμητα to mean “unmeasurable” by us. One possibility is that, on either the epistemic or the metaphysical of the adjectives, both occurrences of καί in Pyrrho’s claim are epexegetical. If this is so, then ἀστάθμητα gives the meaning of ἀδιάφορα, and ἀνεπίκριτα gives the meaning of ἀστάθμητα and so of ἀδιάφορα. 5. See also Long and Sedley (1987: I 16–17). Bett’s book offers the most extensive presentation and defense of the metaphysical reading of Pyrrho’s claim. It is, by some wide margin, the most important book on Pyrrho published in several decades. Some scholars have objected that the Greek adjective ἀνεπίκριτα can’t bear a metaphysical reading and can only mean, as on the epistemic reading, “indeterminable” by us. I assume here that a metaphysical reading of each of the trio of adjectives in Pyrrho’s claim is at least linguistically possible. 6. Even if Pyrrho’s claim is one about what things are like, on the epistemic reading it is a claim about what things are like in relation to us and, more precisely, our cognitive abilities. Moreover, it is reasonable to think that Aristocles at least understands Pyrrho’s claim as equivalent to, or at least as clearly implying, the claim he attributes to Pyrrho at the outset of the passage, namely, that our nature is such that we can’t know anything. 7. But see Svavarsson (2004) for what I take to be a version of the epistemic reading that does not rely on emending the text in this (or any other) way. 8. First, the phrase Zeller emends (διὰ τοῦτο) occurs again in section [E] of Aristocles’s text. That fact might explain the corruption from διὰ τὸ to διὰ τοῦτο. (Though, as Bett (2000: 25) notes, there is no trace of this corruption in the manuscript tradition. All manuscripts have διὰ τοῦτο here.) Second, the phrase Zeller emends appears to be asyndotic, that is, it lacks a particle where it is thought it should have one. Third, the forms of the negatives employed in section [D] are thought to be incorrect given the grammatical construction in which they occur. Bett (2000: 25–26) claims that these linguistic considerations do not constitute reasons to emend Aristocles’s text. I’m inclined to agree with Brennan (1998: 432–433) that Bett shows only that the text as we have it is linguistically possible, but not that it is correct or that the linguistic considerations in question aren’t good reasons to emend. 9. See especially the useful remarks in Castagnoli (2002: 447) and Brennan (1998: 421–22). 10. Thanks to Baron Reed for making this point clear to me. 11. Thanks, again, to Baron Reed for suggesting this conception of a misconception to me. 12. For this way of reading the injunction, see Bett (2000: 30). Brunschwig (1994: 209), following Ausland (1989), reads the injunction more broadly to cover practical as well as doxastic inclinations. He thinks we are being told to have no inclination to choose or pursue anything as choiceworthy or to reject or avoid it as not choiceworthy.

PYRRHO AND TIMON

35

13. See Stopper (1983: 274) for the claim that ἀφασία is non-assertion. (In making this claim he appeals to the gloss Sextus Empiricus gives the term at PH 1.192.) 14. That is, for any x and any predicate F, we suspend judgment about whether x is F or not F or both F and not F or neither F nor not F. 15. Many thanks to Diego Machuca and Baron Reed for their comments on the initial version of this chapter.

REFERENCES Ausland, Hayden. 1989. “On the Moral Origin of the Pyrrhonian Philosophy,” Elenchos 10: 359–434. Bett, Richard. 1994. “Aristocles on Timon on Pyrrho: The Text, Its Logic and Its Credibility,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12: 137–181. Bett, Richard. 2000. Pyrrho, His Antecedents, and His Legacy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brennan, Tad. 1998. “Pyrrho on the Criterion,” Ancient Philosophy 18: 417–434. Brunschwig, Jacques. 1994. “Once Again on Eusebius on Aristocles on Timon on Pyrrho.” In his Papers in Hellenistic Philosophy, translated by J. Lloyd, 190–211. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Castagnoli, Luca. 2002. “Review of Pyrrho, His Antecedents, and His Legacy.” Ancient Philosophy 22: 443–457. Long, Anthony and David Sedley. 1987. The Hellenistic Philosophers. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stopper, M. R. 1983. “Schizzi Pirroniani,” Phronesis 28: 265–297. Svavarsson, Svavar Hrafn. 2004. “Pyrrho’s Undecidable Nature,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27: 249–295.

CHAPTER THREE

Arcesilaus ANNA MARIA IOPPOLO

1 INTRODUCTION Arcesilaus of Pitane (316/5–241/0) became the head of Plato’s Academy in 268 or 266 BCE and oriented the school toward skepticism. Since he did not write any philosophical work, we have to rely on secondary sources to reconstruct his philosophy. The ancient sources are not unanimous on the nature and origin of Arcesilaus’s skepticism, but offer conflicting testimonies. Arcesilaus himself claimed Socrates, Plato, and certain Presocratics as his predecessors. Some sources attribute his skepticism to the influence of Pyrrho of Elis, while others maintain that he only posed as a skeptic in order to conceal the true doctrine of Plato that he was secretly teaching. The main extensive sources, Cicero and Sextus Empiricus, are not unbiased and innocent. Both have a philosophical perspective they wish to defend, and both inform us about Arcesilaus’s philosophy by closely connecting it to his epistemological dispute with the Stoic, Zeno. Since the debate between the Academic skeptics and the Stoics did not end with Arcesilaus and Zeno in the third century BCE but raged through the following centuries down to Cicero’s day, the reconstruction of Arcesilaus’s philosophy is rather controversial, for the positions of individual representatives of the two schools would inevitably have changed in the course of this epistemological debate. The risk, then, is that Arcesilaus’s philosophy may have been distorted by the way that his successors elaborated on it. In order to produce a coherent account of Arcesilaus’s doctrine, we need to examine the testimonies, not in isolation, but by setting them within the philosophical and argumentative context of the sources recording them. We must take account of their date, philosophical preferences, and—last, but not least—of their polemical aims.

2  THE DIALECTICAL METHOD OF “ARGUING THE OPPOSITE” AT THE CORE OF ARCESILAUS’S PHILOSOPHY The most ancient testimonies trace Arcesilaus’s philosophy back to two opposing traditions, which in a way imply one another: one, originating with Arcesilaus himself, claims a strong link with his forerunners, Socrates and Plato, as well as with

ARCESILAUS

37

other illustrious philosophers of the past; the other, which is favored by Arcesilaus’s contemporaries, accuses him of plagiarizing other philosophers’ doctrines. In his Life of Arcesilaus, Diogenes Laertius states: “It seems that Arcesilaus admired Plato, whose books he possessed. Some say that he emulated (ἐζηλώκει) Pyrrho as well. He was very keen on dialectic and made use of the arguments of the Eretrians” (DL IV 32– 33, trans. Long and Sedley 1987 modified).1 The philosophical continuity between Arcesilaus and Plato was questioned by the philosophers of his day, and in particular by Aristo of Chios2 and Timon of Phlius, who both accused him of being a plagiarist. This charge was based on Arcesilaus’s own admission that he was “not saying anything new,” as he simply wished to refer to his predecessors’ doctrines (Plut. Adv. Col. 1121 F). Arcesilaus thus became a target for Aristo’s and Timon’s witty remarks: while exploiting Arcesilaus’s own claim not to be an original philosopher, they did not see in his teaching a conformity to Plato’s doctrines but instead attributed Pyrrho’s views to him. Timon implied that Arcesilaus lacked any originality as a thinker, since he made use of Menedemus’s eristic, and sought refuge under Diodorus’s dialectic and Pyrrho’s philosophy (“all flesh”). In a parody of a famous Homeric verse—“Plato in front, Pyrrho behind, Diodorus in the middle”—Aristo described Arcesilaus’s philosophy as a chimera: an eclectic monstrosity that seeks to reconcile what is irreconcilable, to wit Plato and Pyrrho via Diodorus.3 Arcesilaus’s detractors also included the Epicurean Colotes, who accused him “of rubbing off his doctrines about suspension of judgment and non-cognition (ἀκαταληψία) on Socrates, Plato, Parmenides, and Heraclitus, who did not need them” (Plut. Adv. Col. 26, 1121 F; trans. Long and Sedley 1987).4 It is clear, then, that the charge of unoriginality, if not of downright plagiarism, leveled against Arcesilaus by his contemporaries stemmed in particular from his use of philosophers of the past: Arcesilaus sought to “rub off” his own doctrines on others with the aim of strengthening them. By proclaiming the identity between his own philosophy and that of his predecessors, Arcesilaus sought to lend credit to his skepticism, which in the eyes of his contemporaries represented a betrayal of his teachers, Socrates and Plato. Timon, Aristo, Colotes, and other unnamed detractors agreed in challenging Arcesilaus’s attempt to attribute his own “doctrines” to his forerunners5; in doing so, they also disputed his claim to be carrying on the philosophical tradition of his school. Aristo’s verse sums up his contemporaries’ refusal to grant Arcesilaus’s philosophy the legitimation it aspired to, on the grounds that through dialectical arguments Arcesilaus used Plato as a screen to conceal his Pyrrhonism.6 Still, given Colotes’s silence with regard to Pyrrho, we may rule out any connection between Arcesilaus and this philosopher; otherwise Colotes would no doubt have included Pyrrho among the authorities invoked by Arcesilaus. The lack of any philosophical connection between Arcesilaus and Pyrrho is further confirmed by the fact that Cicero knew nothing about Pyrrho’s role as a skeptic and presented him simply as a moralist.7 More generally, the whole Academic tradition, both dogmatic and skeptical, ignored Pyrrho completely. In order to understand the reason why Aristo attributed Arcesilaus’s skeptical turn to his plagiarism of Pyrrho’s philosophy, we must examine how Arcesilaus justified his connection with his predecessors in the school, and especially Socrates, whom both Zeno8 and Aristo9 claimed to be following.

38

SKEPTICISM

What is most revealing in this respect is the fact that, according to the tradition of the skeptical Academy (Acad. I 44–46), an antecedent for Arcesilaus’s skepticism is to be found in Socrates’s confession of ignorance, based on the idea that all things are hidden in darkness—an approach also common to the Presocratic philosophers Heraclitus, Democritus, Anaxagoras, and Empedocles.10 By drawing upon the aporetic Socrates of Plato’s dialogues, Arcesilaus saw Socrates’s practice of ἔλεγχος (refutation) as the chief instrument for purifying the mind of false beliefs. The central role he attributed to Socrates’s dialectical method enabled him to justify his own particular interpretation of Platonic philosophy, as well as to claim a degree of continuity between his own teaching and that of Plato (Acad. I 46; cf. De or. III 67). The ἔλεγχος was able to bring people who wrongly imagined that they possessed knowledge to realize their own ignorance. Unlike Socrates, however, Arcesilaus even denied that he could claim to know that he did not know: he therefore turned the aporetic stance against itself, yet without discarding it: [Arcesilaus] used to act consistently with this philosophy, and by arguing against everyone’s opinions he led most of them to his own, so that when reasons of equal weight were found on opposite sides on the same subject, the easier course was to withhold assent from either side. (Acad. I 45, trans. Long and Sedley 1987 modified)11 Arcesilaus would allow his interlocutor to speak first and only afterwards put forward the argument opposite to the one already advanced. The result was that he would speak in such a way as to present a counterargument, but without appearing to be involved in any assertion or denial (see Fin. II 2; De or. III 67; ND I 11). For Arcesilaus, arguing on the opposite side—that is, by opposing the thesis put forward by one’s interlocutor—represented the very essence of philosophizing, which fulfills itself and comes to a conclusion through this process, since the ἰσοσθένεια (equipollence) of contrary arguments can never be overcome: the suspension of judgment simply emerges from their opposition. From Diogenes Laertius we learn that “Arcesilaus was the first to suspend his assertions owing to the contrarieties of arguments, he was also the first to argue pro and contra and the first to change the traditional Platonic discourse, and by question and answer, to make it more of a debate contest” (DL IV 28, trans. Long and Sedley 1987). One may question whether the method of arguing pro and contra was first used by Arcesilaus, given that this method may be traced back to Protagoras—as Diogenes Laertius himself records (DL IX 51)—and it constituted an integral part of the dialectical training offered in the Peripatos.12 Arcesilaus was certainly the first to practice it in a different way from that common in the philosophical schools of his day, such as the Peripatos and the early Academy. In a sense—especially at a superficial glance—Arcesilaus’s dialectical method might have seemed little different from that of arguing pro and contra, given that the interlocutor would always be the first to state his view, with Arcesilaus then offering a counterview. A more in-depth philosophical analysis, however, reveals that Arcesilaus’s method of argument sharply differs from that of arguing for and against a given thesis, as witnessed by Chrysippus, who had carefully studied Arcesilaus’s arguments in an attempt to refute them.13

ARCESILAUS

39

Plutarch informs us that, according to Chrysippus, “arguing the opposite” (πρὸς τὰ ἐναντία διαλέγεσθαι) is only useful for those who suspend all judgment, with the aim of turning people away from cognition (κατάληψις).14 Chrysippus had thus developed a strategy to neutralize the effectiveness of the method of arguing the opposite. First of all, he warned his disciples not to let themselves be diverted by the persuasiveness of the arguments of those who suspend judgment; secondly, he encouraged his disciples to overturn the dialectical method of those suspending all judgment by presenting a counterargument without defending it, but only weakening it as a lawyer in a courtroom might do (see Ioppolo 1986: 109–120). Chrysippus’s words clearly confirm the idea that Arcesilaus’s dialectical method consisted in arguing against the thesis presented by one’s interlocutor, rather than arguing pro and contra a given thesis. Plutarch further informs us that Chrysippus feared this method because it has the power of turning away from cognition even the kind of people who base their knowledge on common sense.15 The aspect of Arcesilaus’s dialectical method that Chrysippus feared the most was not its capacity to make one argument prevail over another, but the fact that, by presenting two opposite arguments on a given thesis that have the same weight, so that neither can prevail, it prevents listeners from understanding the solutions.16 Chrysippus’s testimony thus agrees with Cicero’s view of Arcesilaus’s dialectical procedure, as presented in Academica I 45: faced with the equipollence of opposite theses on the same argument, the interlocutors will fail to find any solution and fall into aporia. Hence, the suspension of judgment does not dialectically depend upon the Stoic premises but rather invariably follows the aporia as a conclusion, due to the mutual contrariety of the arguments.17 In other words, ἐποχή is not the goal toward which Arcesilaus strives—for this would make it the preset aim of his dialectical method—but constitutes the unavoidable manifestation of aporia at an epistemological and linguistic level.18 In his Academica, Cicero records that the τέλος for Arcesilaus is not ἐποχή, but verum invenire velle (Acad. II 76). It is in the light of the search after truth that Cicero interprets the dispute with Zeno: “Arcesilaus did not fight with Zeno for the sake of criticizing him but from a wish to discover the truth” (Acad. II 76, trans. Long and Sedley 1987). With these words Cicero clears Arcesilaus of the charge of wishing to argue with Zeno simply for the sake of competitiveness or a taste for victory (see Acad. I 44, II 16). Cicero also tells us: “None of Zeno’s predecessors (nemo umquam superiorum) had clearly expounded, or even stated, that a human being can refrain from opining and that a wise man not only can but must do so. To Arcesilaus this idea seemed true and honorable and worthy of a wise man” (Acad. II 77, trans. Long and Sedley 1987). Cicero’s emphasis in presenting the agreement between the two philosophers on the thesis that “the wise man must absolutely never formulate opinions” suggests that this thesis played a pivotal role in the debate and at the same time that Arcesilaus’s agreement was sincere.19 Arcesilaus used this, however, as the premise for an argument from which he then drew a completely opposite conclusion. Cicero recounts the debate between Zeno and Arcesilaus in dialogue form. Arcesilaus asks Zeno what would happen if the wise man could cognize nothing at all and were absolutely required not to formulate any opinions. Zeno replies that he will not opine because there exists

40

SKEPTICISM

something cognitive, namely the presentation (φαντασία).20 He defines this as that which is “stamped and reproduced from something which is, exactly as it is” (Acad. II 77, trans. Long and Sedley 1987). But Arcesilaus gets Zeno to admit that if a true presentation does not possess that mark whereby it can be told from a false one, then, since it is indistinguishable therefrom, it cannot be grasped. Arcesilaus then focuses his criticism on the third clause (“such as could not arise from what is not”), which raises the problem of establishing how it is possible to distinguish a cognitive presentation from a noncognitive one, given that, in terms of cognizance, a person can have access only to his own presentation.21 Once Zeno has been forced to accept the third clause, Arcesilaus establishes the nonexistence of the Stoic criterion. This is not enough to conclude, however, that Arcesilaus upheld the opposite thesis to Zeno’s, that “nothing can be known”—that is, that he was a proponent of ἀκαταληψία. In this regard, it will be useful to compare Cicero’s account of the debate between Zeno and Arcesilaus to Sextus’s version.

3  ἈΚΑΤΑΛΗΨΊΑ AS A DIALECTICAL THESIS AGAINST THE STOICS Sextus’s testimony on Arcesilaus is rather problematic. Sextus speaks of Arcesilaus at AM VII 150–158 and PH I 232–234, but at first sight the two accounts appear to paint two different pictures of Arcesilaus. In PH I Sextus represents Arcesilaus as a philosopher close to Pyrrhonism: he does not assign him to any of the three currents into which he has divided philosophy (see PH I 3–4), nor in the course of his exposition does he ever refer to him as an “Academic”; rather, he includes Arcesilaus’s philosophy in his discussion of so-called neighboring philosophies. Moreover, although Sextus’s professed aim is to bring out the differences between Pyrrhonian skepticism and its neighboring philosophies, he personally undertakes to associate Arcesilaus with the Pyrrhonists (PH I 232). In AM VII, by contrast, when distinguishing skeptics and dogmatists in relation to the criterion of truth, Sextus includes not just Carneades but also Arcesilaus among those dogmatists who posit the criterion (AM VII 1, 46). Sextus introduces Arcesilaus’s criticism of the criterion by stressing that he did not determine any criterion, and does so through the use of a rather loaded and typically Pyrrhonian verb, ὁρίζειν (AM VII 150).22 However, he then reduces Arcesilaus’s perspective to his dialectical counterarguments, without explaining why Arcesilaus did not “determine” any criterion. Sextus maintains that the main difference between Academic and Pyrrhonian skepticism is to be found in the use of language: for the Academics it expresses a commitment to the truth of their assertions, whereas for the skeptics it simply means speaking without holding opinions, ἀπαγγέλλειν.23 Consequently, the terminology used is particularly significant. The procedure Sextus adopts in his account is also peculiar: before illustrating Arcesilaus’s criticism of the criterion, he presents the Stoic doctrine; this is followed by Arcesilaus’s arguments, which are clearly distinguished from the former in such a way as to bring out their dialectical and ad hominem character (AM VII 151–155).24 This procedure is

ARCESILAUS

41

perfectly in line with the dialectical method of arguing the opposite, which the most ancient and reliable sources attribute to Arcesilaus. The arguments that Arcesilaus raises against the Stoic epistemological doctrine are of Platonic inspiration in form as much as substance; hence, they are quite independent of the Stoic premises.25 The argument that κατάληψις is not a μεταξύ, since it is a mere name without any real determination, is not the dialectical reversal of a Stoic thesis, but a counterargument; and the same is true of the objection that κατάληψις does not exist if, as the Stoics argue, it means “assent to a cognitive presentation”: for the assent is given to the proposition, whereas presentation, according to Zeno’s definition, is a τύπωσις, which is to say simply an affection of the soul. After attacking the role of assent as a constitutive part of the definition of κατάληψις by questioning its existence, Arcesilaus questions the existence of the cognitive presentation that is claimed to be its object (AM VII 154). Once the Stoic has been forced to accept the thesis that alongside any purported cognitive presentation another false one may be found that is indistinguishable from it, Arcesilaus establishes the nonexistence of the Stoic criterion. Note that Arcesilaus infers ἀκαταληψία from his demonstration of the nonexistence of the Stoic criterion, not of a criterion in general. So the thesis that all things are non-cognitive does not concern him, but only the Stoics, according to whom κατάληψις exists. After having demonstrated the nonexistence of κατάληψις, Arcesilaus concludes: “If cognition does not exist, everything will be noncognitive. And if everything is noncognitive, it will follow that according to the Stoics too (καί), the wise man suspends judgment” (AM VII 155, trans. Long and Sedley 1987). Up until this point, Arcesilaus has only been disputing against, opposing Stoic arguments by counterarguments, according to the dialectical method of arguing the opposite. Arcesilaus’s argument is structured in such a way as to lead the Stoic sage to accept the thesis of ἀκαταληψία, which is precisely the opposite thesis to the Stoic one; yet he does not positively establish its truth. So, if ἀκαταληψία is a dialectical thesis, what still remains to be determined is whether ἐποχή is a conclusion to which Arcesilaus is committed, or whether he is resorting to the demonstration of ἀκαταληψία merely as a reductio ad absurdum of the stance of the Stoic wise man, in such a way as to lead him to universal suspension of judgment. In the latter part of his refutation (AM VII 156–157), starting from a reversal of the Stoic theses, Arcesilaus then turns them into their contradictory opposites. It is in this latter section that he demonstrates that, if the Stoic sage does not wish to opine, he must withhold assent, that is, that he is forced to ἀσυγκαταθετεῖν. If Arcesilaus merely wished to provide a reductio ad absurdum of the Stoic position, it would be enough for him to demonstrate that, since everything is non-cognitive, the only option the Stoic wise man has is to opine. Arcesilaus does not ignore this argument: in fact, he adopts it as an intermediate step before leading the Stoic sage to ἐποχή. Arcesilaus forces the sage to acknowledge that “assent to the non-cognitive is opinion,” drawing this definition from a reductio ad absurdum of Zenonian cognition. Hence, the above definition of opinion holds only against the Stoics. “But the wise man is certainly not one of those who opine”: this is the premise that Arcesilaus shares with Zeno and that they had agreed upon before engaging in the debate, as Cicero makes clear in his account (Acad. II 76–77). Sextus does not mention the two philosophers’

42

SKEPTICISM

agreement with regard to this premise, as he is not interested in presenting Arcesilaus’s point of view. If “assent to the non-cognitive is opinion” and “the wise is certainly not one of those who opine,” then the Stoic sage has no other option but to withhold assent. Yet, “to withhold assent (ἀσυγκαταθετεῖν) is no different from suspending judgment (ἐπέχειν)” (AM VII 157). From the shared premise that “the wise is certainly not one of those who opine,” two consequences follow: the Stoic sage is forced to withhold assent because κατάληψις does not exist, whereas in the face of the equipollence of two opposite theses—the Stoic thesis of the existence of cognition and the demonstration of its nonexistence—the Academic is forced to suspend judgment, since he finds himself in aporia, that is, incapable of asserting or denying that there is knowledge. The ἐποχὴ περὶ πάντων (universal suspension of judgment), that is, the attitude of the Academic wise man, is thus what the Stoic sage is left with, too—where “too” stresses the fact that it is the Stoic sage who must conform to the behavior of the Academic sage, if he wishes not to formulate any opinions. If “to withhold assent” (ἀσυγκαταθετεῖν) had the same meaning as “to suspend judgment” (ἐπέχειν), there would be no point in Arcesilaus forcing the Stoics to accept the equivalence of the two terms, since the Stoics themselves would be treating them as synonyms. Moreover the verb ἀσυγκαταθετεῖν is composed of α-privativ + the verb συγκαταθετεῖν, clearly referring to the Stoic concept of assent, to which Arcesilaus is not committed, as has been shown before, while the verb ἐπέχειν does not need necessarily assent as its object.26 The introduction of the two verbs makes sense only if we admit that they describe two attitudes that differ fundamentally, not just linguistically. The use of a different term to denote the attitude of the Stoic sage compared to that of the Academic sage reveals that ἐποχή is Arcesilaus’s own point of view, and cannot be reduced to a dialectical thesis. If then, as it seems, Arcesilaus does not infer ἐποχή from the nonexistence of the Stoic criterion, but upholds it as his own view, this must be on the basis of other considerations that are not mentioned here by Sextus.

4  UNIVERSAL SUSPENSION OF JUDGMENT AS THE “NATURAL” AND UNAVOIDABLE OUTCOME OF THE EQUAL STRENGTH OF OPPOSITE ARGUMENTS It remains to be established whether the previous considerations are compatible with skepticism. Sextus himself in PH I provides the considerations that he omits in AM VII: “[Arcesilaus] seems to me to have very much in common with the Pyrrhonian discourses, so that his school is practically the same as ours” (PH I 232, trans. Long and Sedley 1987).27 Sextus justifies his assertion in the following terms: Arcesilaus “is not found making assertions about the existence or nonexistence of anything, nor does he prefer one thing to another by way of credibility or incredibility, but suspends judgment about everything. He also says that suspension of judgment is the end” (PH I 232, trans. Long and Sedley 1987). Sextus provides two more possible interpretations of Arcesilaus’s suspension of judgment. According to one interpretation, attributed to an anonymous “someone” (τις), Arcesilaus, unlike

ARCESILAUS

43

the Pyrrhonists, speaks of suspension of judgment with regard to the real nature of things. But while Arcesilaus does not speak in favor of either the existence or nonexistence of things, there is no evidence for the idea that the expression “in reference to nature” (ὡς πρὸς τὴν φύσιν) may refer to a cognitive-ontological pronouncement on the nature of the external world. The third interpretation, again drawn from an anonymous source, presents Arcesilaus as being covertly Platonic. Yet Aristo’s parody of the Homeric verse, which is quoted in support of the esoteric interpretation, suggests the very opposite of what the charge of esotericism directed against Arcesilaus implies: for πρόσθε Πλάτων indicates that Arcesilaus was openly Platonic, not Pyrrhonian.28 While Sextus’s discussion of Arcesilaus’s philosophy is certainly based on διαφωνία (disagreement)—Arcesilaus is presented as a genuine skeptic first, then as a negative dogmatist, and finally as a covert Platonist—ultimately the three accounts are not set on the same level: not just because the account that assimilates Arcesilaus within Pyrrhonism is explicitly endorsed by Sextus himself,29 but also because the other two are only weakly justified. It is noteworthy, moreover, that Sextus does not ground Arcesilaus’s skepticism on his polemic against the Stoics, but rather presents ἐποχή as Arcesilaus’s point of view, in agreement with the most ancient sources, predating Sextus himself—from Chrysippus30 to Cicero. But if ἐποχή emerges from the opposition between two contradictory theses, neither of which prevails over the other (Acad. I 45; DL IV 28), then it simply describes the state of mind in which the Academic finds himself; as such, it cannot be the τέλος of Arcesilaus’s philosophy, as Sextus would have it. Besides, in his account on the criterion of conduct at AM VII 158, Sextus himself argues that according to Arcesilaus the goal of life is happiness, thus leaving open the possibility that the identification of ἐποχή as the τέλος may simply be a polemical expedient. In order to grasp the meaning of Arcesilaus’s ἐποχή, it is worth dwelling on the words with which Cicero ends his account of the debate between Zeno and Arcesilaus. He states that the thesis that “the wise man will assent to nothing” was no longer taken into consideration in the dispute, since the wise man “might ‘grasp nothing and yet opine’—a thesis Carneades is said to have accepted” (Acad. II 78). Indeed, the thesis of the opinionless31 sage may only be upheld provided one practices universal ἐποχή, as Arcesilaus did. However, this thesis has serious implications with regard to the issue of conduct, so much so that later Academics abandoned it.32 In Clitomachus’s day, Academics were still debating how to practice universal suspension of judgment. Clitomachus distinguishes between two ways of conceiving suspension of judgment: “one, when it means that he assents to nothing at all; the other, when he checks himself from responding in such a way as to accept or reject something with the result that he neither denies nor asserts something” (Acad. II 104; trans. Long and Sedley 1987).33 The latter way of conceiving suspension agrees with the meaning of ἐποχή that other sources attribute to Arcesilaus, as ἐπέχειν τὰς ἀποφάσεις. On Clitomachus’s account the action does not require assent: the skeptic may react positively or negatively provided he does not assent (dum sine adsensu).34 This means that Clitomachus, by distinguishing two modes of suspension, is offering not so much a theory of qualified assent as a theory of “qualified non-assent” (see

44

SKEPTICISM

Burnyeat 1997). Clitomachus rejects the notion of suspension as checking oneself from responding “Yes” or “No” to questions, which was implied by Arcesilaus’s ἐποχή περὶ πάντων, since it does not allow one to provide a rational justification for one’s actions, and hence to answer the charge of ἀπραξία (inaction) leveled against skeptics by dogmatists, as is illustrated by Arcesilaus’s difficulty in defining a criterion of conduct.

5  THE CRITERION OF CONDUCT AND THE LANGUAGE OF “NON-ASSERTION” Sextus focuses on the criterion of conduct in the last section of his account on Arcesilaus at AM VII 158. The first thing one notices here is the sudden change of tone compared to the previous section. Sextus directly presents Arcesilaus’s position, without first introducing the Stoic view, in open contrast to the dialectical procedure he has attributed to Arcesilaus so far. Furthermore, the criterion of conduct is presented as something that the person suspending his judgment must “investigate” after the criterion of truth has been abolished. Most importantly, the language used by Arcesilaus undergoes a shift of tone, as attested by the fact that all the finite verbs are expressed in the future tense to indicate that the philosopher is delivering an exhortation rather than arguing dialectically: Since after this it was necessary (ἔδει) to investigate (ζητεῖν) the conduct of life too, which is not of a nature (πέφυκεν) to be explained without a criterion, on which happiness too, i.e., the end of life, has its trust dependent, Arcesilaus says that one who suspends judgment about everything will regulate (κανονιεῖ) choice and avoidance and actions in general by the reasonable (εὔλογον); and by proceeding in accordance with this criterion, he will have success (κατορθώσει). (AM VII 158, trans. Long and Sedley 1987 modified.) It is significant that the expression οὐδὲν ὁρίζειν that Sextus had used to introduce the criterion of truth is matched here by the verb ζητεῖν, which introduces the criterion of conduct. Sextus’s stress on language, as a way of distinguishing Pyrrhonian skepticism from Academic skepticism, makes it unlikely that the choice of the two verbs, both belonging to the jargon of Pyrrhonian skepticism (see PH I 1–3, 7), is merely a casual one. The verb “to investigate” emphasizes that Arcesilaus is suggesting the adoption of a criterion of conduct, the εὔλογον, as an open, temporary solution, compatible with the universal suspension of judgment.35 The argument by which Arcesilaus recommends the εὔλογον is based on three premises: (1) happiness is attained through prudence; (2) prudence resides in successes (κατορθώματα); and (3) a success is whatever, once it has been done, has a reasonable defense. Arcesilaus concludes: “Therefore one who attends to the reasonable will have success and be happy.” This argument draws upon some concepts that are apparently of Stoic origin, such as εὔλογον, καθῆκον, and κατόρθωμα: what is especially crucial is Arcesilaus’s definition of κατόρθωμα, which is identical to Zeno’s definition of καθῆκον.36 And since the term καθῆκον is used in Stoic

ARCESILAUS

45

doctrine to refer to the action of the ordinary man, as opposed to κατόρθωμα, which describes the wise man’s action, the supporters of the dialectical interpretation have concluded that Arcesilaus was being ironical: that he sought to prove that once deprived of his knowledge, the Stoic sage is forced to act as an ordinary man, which is to say as a fool. We would be compelled to accept this interpretation if Arcesilaus had borrowed his notion of εὔλογον from the Stoa. But apart from the fact that the concept of εὔλογον was far from new in Greek thought, having previously been widely employed by Aristotle, in the debate between the Stoa and the skeptical Academy, it is not always easy to ascertain which school borrowed certain technical terms and concepts from the other (Glucker 1978: 33 with n.78; Görler 1994: 817). The use of a common technical terminology, therefore, is not enough in itself to prove Arcesilaus’s dialectical reading, unless evidence is found for the Stoic use of the same notions. Moreover, if Arcesilaus had wished to suggest the idea of an ironic exchange between καθῆκον and κατόρθωμα, he ought to have made at least some allusion in his arguments to the difference between the two kinds of actions according to the Stoics and to have recalled Zeno’s position—as he had indeed done in order to refute the criterion of truth. But unlike in the first section, where the noun “Stoics” occurs twice between 155 and 157, highlighting the ad hominem nature of the reply, in the section on the criterion of conduct that noun does not appear at all. Nor does Arcesilaus mention it in the three arguments by which he establishes the εὔλογον as the criterion to be adopted by the person who suspends his judgment in order to regulate (κανονιεῖ) his actions. The choice of the verb κανονίζειν likewise suggests a regulatory norm, a κάνων, with an epistemological and justificatory function, rather than a prescriptive one. The definition of κατόρθωμα—identical to Zeno’s definition of καθῆκον—is a formal one, since it stresses the a posteriori justification of action, yet without enunciating the principles on which this action is based. The past participle πραχθέν is used to emphasize that “rational defense” comes after the action has been performed, not before.37 Hence, the εὔλογον cannot be identified with the judgment “It is reasonable that p,” if this is expressed before performing the action, since the εὔλογον is not taken in this sense in the definition of κατόρθωμα. Either Arcesilaus had expressed himself unclearly, or Sextus has omitted some details, to shorten his account. Favoring the latter hypothesis is Sextus’s complete silence with regard to Arcesilaus’s answer to the charge of ἀπραξία. It is rather strange that Sextus ignores it, not just because the εὔλογον acquires a far clearer meaning when viewed in its light, but especially because this accusation represents a problematic issue that we know for sure Arcesilaus had to address, since it concerns the very credibility of skepticism, as witnessed by the accusation raised by his contemporary Colotes (see Adv. Col. 1121F–1124B). Faced with the charge leveled by Stoics and Epicureans that by removing assent the Academic can neither act nor avoid committing absurd or random actions, Arcesilaus replies that neither the Academic’s faculty of presentation nor his impulsive faculty are impaired. His impulse will thus naturally (φυσικῶς) lead him toward what is appropriate (οἰκεῖον), without assent ever coming into play. For error derives from opinion and hence from assent. Following nature means being guided by impulse without assenting to the presentations by which one is involuntarily affected. It is nature that ensures

46

SKEPTICISM

both the possibility of action and the possibility of not committing any errors. The importance of nature in providing guidelines for one’s conduct links the Academic’s description of the mechanism of action to the rational justification suggested by the εὔλογον, since the conduct of life “‘is not of a nature’ (οὐ πέφυκεν) to be accounted for without a criterion on which happiness too, i.e., the end of life, has its trust dependent.” Plutarch’s account, which explains how Arcesilaus describes the mechanism of action, not only answers the charge of total inaction,38 but also gives meaning to the εὔλογον, which otherwise could not be accounted for—be it as a dialectical reversal of a Stoic view or as a criterion of conduct. Only by integrating Plutarch’s testimony with Sextus’s is it possible to answer both objections contained in the charge of ἀπραξία, and—most importantly—to grasp the connection drawn by Arcesilaus between the criterion of conduct and nature, as asserted in both accounts. Sextus himself, in PH I as well as in AM XI, provides an explanation for the Pyrrhonist’s action without assent, which stresses the crucial role of nature and is very similar to Arcesilaus’s explanation for action without assent.39 What is also suspicious is Sextus’s silence with regard to Arcesilaus’s criterion of conduct in PH I, since he discusses and refutes the criterion of conduct of Carneades and Clitomachus at PH I 231, distinguishing it from the Pyrrhonists’ criterion of conduct, yet makes no reference to Arcesilaus’s formulation of a criterion. It cannot be ruled out that Sextus sought to conceal the role played by nature in Arcesilaus’s philosophy, as Pyrrhonian skepticism was greatly indebted to it. A comparative analysis of the sources shows that Arcesilaus’s skepticism does not involve any commitment to the doctrine of ἀκαταληψία but is compatible with universal ἐποχή. The latter is not the final goal for Arcesilaus, and hence does not represent a substantive belief. Rather, it is the practical expression of the theoretical difficulty that the Academic experiences in the face of aporia, which invariably emerges from the equipollence of opposite theses. The problem that Arcesilaus must address is one common to all forms of skepticism, namely: whether it is legitimate for the skeptic to communicate his own non-position to others by drawing upon concepts such as reason, opinion, and truth. The only way of communicating without making assertions that will concern oneself is to develop a language that is distinct from that of dogmatists, but that at the same time does not reject the use of their concepts. Traces of this reflection on language are to be found in various accounts of Arcesilaus’s philosophy, ranging from Cicero (Acad. I 45) to Diogenes Laertius (DL IV 36)40 and Sextus Empiricus himself. The quest for a language of “non-assertion” indicates that Arcesilaus foreshadowed Pyrrhonian skepticism in his awareness that every assertion, by implying the presence of a subject, can ultimately be turned against itself. Sextus himself, who chiefly perceives the difference between Pyrrhonian skepticism and Academic dogmatism as a matter of language, goes so far as to admit that Arcesilaus does not assert anything διαβεβαιωτικῶς,41 while at AM VII 150 he claims that Arcesilaus and his followers οὐδὲν ὥρισαν κριτήριον. More generally, both accounts, in PH I and AM VII, suggest that Arcesilaus employed not just a dialectical terminology drawn from a refutation of Stoic theses—which, as such, cannot be attributed to him—but also a language of his own to convey his skeptical attitude.

ARCESILAUS

47

NOTES 1. Cf. Antigonus of Carystus apud Philodemus, Academicorum Historia col. 19, 11–16 (154 Dor.= fr. 20A). As Long (2006: 96–114) has persuasively suggested, Diogenes’s Life of Arcesilaus almost certainly derives from Antigonus of Carystus—a reliable source, since he was a contemporary of Arcesilaus and “was still being read as late as the second century AD” (Long 2006: 101). 2. On the epistemological dispute between Aristo of Chios and Arcesilaus, see DL VII 162–163, as well as Ioppolo (1980: 26–33; 2013: 188–190) and Long (2006: 106–108). 3. See DL IV 33; PH I 234; Numenius apud Eusebius, Praep. evang. XIV 6, 4–5 = fr. 25 Des Places. 4. As Colotes’s work—Plutarch’s source—was written around 260 BCE, its doctrinal and polemical context can only coincide with the height of Arcesilaus’s career. On the reliability of Adversus Colotem as a source for Arcesilaus’s philosophy, see Ioppolo (1986: 121–156; 2000: 333–360; 2009: 123 n. 98); also Warren (2002: 333–360). 5. The same charge is leveled against Arcesilaus at Acad. II 15. 6. PH I 234 quotes the verse by intentionally interpreting it as meaning the very opposite (see below). 7. Cf. Acad. II 130; Fin. II 35, III 31, 43, IV 40, etc. 8. See DL VII 2; 31; Cicero, De or. III 61. On the Stoics’ claim to be following Socrates, see Philodemus, De Stoicis XIII 3. 9. See Ioppolo (1980: 78–90). 10. Some scholars interpret Acad. I 44–45 as evidence that ἀκαταληψία (noncognition) was endorsed by Arcesilaus. See Maconi (1988: 246–247). As Brittain and Palmer (2001: 44) note, however, “It is not clear . . . how Arcesilaus’s appeal to the Presocratics supports the akatalepsia premise because his appeal is susceptible to both a ‘dialectical’ and a ‘non-dialectical’ reading.” 11. huic rationi quod erat consentaneum faciebat, ut contra omnium sententias dicens, in eam plerosque deduceret ut cum in eadem re paria contrariis in partibus momenta rationum invenirentur, facilius ab utraque parte adsensio sustineretur. I follow Madvig’s reading dicens in eam, as this explains how Arcesilaus would lead his interlocutors to share his point of view, that is, to suspend all judgment. This controversial passage is crucially important for any attempt to understand Arcesilaus’s philosophy. 12. Cicero first attributes the method of in utramque partem disserere to Aristotle at Tusc. II 9. Cf. Fin. V 10–11 and De or. III 80. Arcesilaus had been a pupil of Theophrastus (DL IV 29). 13. See Plutarch, St. Rep. 1037A, ironically noting with regard to Chrysippus: “in the ambition to outdo Arcesilaus” (ὑπερβαλέσθαι φιλοτιμούμενος τὸν Ἀρκεσίλαον). This confirms the hypothesis formulated by Long (2006: 97): “Traces of Arcesilaus’s actual words, we may presume, were transmitted in writing through the Academy’s Stoic opponents, especially Chrysippus (DL 7.183), who was his student for a time.”

48

SKEPTICISM

14. St. Rep. 1036A: τοῖς μὲν γὰρ ἐποχὴν ἄγουσιν περὶ πάντων ἐπιβάλλει, φησί, τοῦτο ποιεῖν. Regardless of which of Chrysippus’s works the quotation may be taken from, it confirms that the πρὸς τὰ ἐναντία διαλέγεσθαι method was at the core of Arcesilaus’s philosophy. 15. St. Rep. 10, 1035F–1037C, faithfully records Chrysippus’s words, as well as the titles of his works. 16. St. Rep. 1036 D–Ε: οὐχ ὡς ἔτυχεν δ’οὐδὲ τοὺς ἐναντίους ὑποδεικτέον λόγους . . . ἀλλ’εὐλαβουμένους μὴ καὶ περισπασθέντες ὑπ’αὐτῶν τὰς καταλήψεις ἀφῶσιν, οὔτε τῶν λύσεων ἱκανῶς ἂν ἀκοῦσαι δυνάμενοι καταλαμβάνοντες τ’εὐαποσείστως. 17. DL IV 28: ἐπισχὼν τὰς ἀποφάσεις διὰ τῆς ἐναντιότητας τῶν λόγων (suspending his assertions owing to the contrarieties of arguments). 18. The dialectical procedure cannot be cut off from its aim, which according to Platonists consists in the “search after truth”: see Plat. Apol. 21 B–23 B, 38 A; Gorg. 505 E. 19. The words vera . . . honesta . . . digna sapienti reveal that Arcesilaus shared this premise. It is worth recalling that the precondition for Socratic ἔλεγχος is to be found in the sincerity with which the two interlocutors express their views: see Plat. Gorg. 457D–458B; Prot. 331C–D; Rep. 346A; Theaet. 167D–168C. 20. In Ioppolo (1989: 232–233), I explain why I prefer to translate φαντασία as “presentation” instead of “impression.” 21. This is the problem that Carneades was to formulate more clearly by drawing a distinction between the two σχέσεις of presentation: see AM VII 168–169. 22. προηγουμένως μὲν οὐδὲν ὥρισαν κριτήριον. On the various possible ways of translating this passage, see Ioppolo (2009: 81–82). 23. See PH I 15; also PH I 197, 203, and Spinelli (2005: 114–126). 24. See AM VII 159–166, on the different dialectical procedures that Sextus adopts in his account on Carneades. 25. For a detailed analysis of Arcesilaus’s arguments, partly drawn from Plato’s Theaetetus, see Ioppolo (2009: 82–93). 26. See Arcesilaus’s explanation of how action is possible in the absence of assent in Plut. Adv. Col. 1121F-1124B. 27. The importance of this κοινωνία with Arcesilaus, acknowledged by Sextus himself, is further witnessed by the limits he sets to the κοινωνία with Protagoras at PH I 217. 28. Note that in the transition from his enunciation of ἐποχή as a good to that of its interpretation from a dogmatic perspective—ὡς πρὸς τὴν φύσιν—Sextus switches from the first person to the third person of his anonymous source: πλὴν εἰ μὲν λέγοι τις (PH I 233). Sextus mentions the charge of esotericism in even more hypothetical terms: εἰ δὲ καὶ τοῖς περὶ αὐτοῦ λεγομένοις πιστεύειν, φασίν (PH I 234). See also Ioppolo (2009: 42–52). 29. Note that Sextus uses the first person very rarely and usually only when his own view is not subject to διαφωνία: see PH I 237, 239; II 9, 10, 22, 98, 204, 212. 30. See Plutarch, St. Rep. 1036A. See also Colotes in Plut. Adv. Col. 1120C: τοὺς περὶ Ἀρκεσίλαον Ἀκαδημαικούς. Οὗτοι γὰρ ἦσαν οἱ περὶ πάντων ἐπέχοντες.

ARCESILAUS

49

31. See Acad. II 67 on the divergence between Arcesilaus and Carneades with regard to the thesis nihil opinari sapientem. See also Ioppolo (2007: 238–241). 32. Numenius apud. Eusebius, Praep. Evang. XIV 7, 15 (fr. 26 Des Places) distinguishes Arcesilaus’s position from that of Carneades precisely with reference to the ἐποχὴ περὶ πάντων, which Carneades does not maintain, since it abolishes the distinction between “uncertain” (ἄδηλον) and “noncognitive” (ἀκατάληπτον). Regarding ἄδηλον as a technical term of Arcesilaus’s philosophy, see Ioppolo (2009: 193–208). 33. Note that the verb ἐπέχειν does not always require συγκατάθεσις as its object: see Cicero, Ad Att. XIII 21, 3. Cicero discusses the matter in relation to the dispute between Chrysippus and Carneades on the sorites paradox at Acad. II 93 (see also Ioppolo 2007: 227–267). 34. I have discussed this topic extensively; see Ioppolo 2007. 35. The practice of ζητεῖν is a distinguishing feature of Arcesilaus’s philosophy, which was modeled after that of Socrates: see Plat. Apol. 21B–23B, 38A; DL II 22. Cf. Acad. I 44–46, II 76–77 on verum invenire velle. 36. See DL VII 107–108. On the peculiar meaning of Arcesilaus’s κατόρθωμα, see Ioppolo (2009: 118–124). 37. With regard to the word κατόρθωμα, Tsekourakis (1974: 121) observes: “Terms in -μα . . . seem to have presented the act as a whole, as finished and with its results present. . . . We often find a perfect tense in the definition of the concepts expressed by these terms.” 38. See Plut. Adv. Col. 1122B: ὥσπερ Γοργόνα τὴν ἀπραξίαν ἐπάγοντες. 39. See Adv. Col. 26 1122B–1122 F and PH I 23–24. See also AM XI 162–168 and Spinelli (1995: 325–335). Cf. AM VII 158 with AM VII 30. 40. Φυσικῶς δέ πως ἐν τῷ διαλέγεσθαι ἐχρῆτο τῷ Φημ᾽ἐγώ, καί, οὐ συγκαταθήσεται τούτοις ὁ δεῖνα, εἰπὼν τοὔνομα. Φημ᾽ἐγώ. “I say” translates “Yes” in the context of an ordinary exchange during a discussion and may be explained as a natural impulse that would drive him to speak, even though this did not imply any claim to truthfulness with regard to the content of his words, thereby freeing the expression from any assertive meaning. 41. From the very opening of PH I 4 Sextus uses two specific verbs in order to distinguish dogmatic διαβεβαιοῦσθαι from the ἀπαγγέλλειν. Note that Sextus does not name Arcesilaus among the Academics, implicitly including him among the anonymous skeptics.

REFERENCES Brittain, Charles and John Palmer. 2001. “The New Academy’s Appeal to the Presocratics,” Phronesis 46: 38–72. Burnyeat, Myles. 1997. “Antipater and Self-Refutation: Elusive Argument in Cicero’s Academica.” In B. Inwood and J. Mansfeld (eds.), Assent and Argument: Studies in Cicero’s Academic Books, 277–310. Leiden. Glucker, John. 1978. Antiochus and the Late Academy. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

50

SKEPTICISM

Görler, Woldemar. 1994. “Älterer Pyrrhonismus. Jüngere Akademie. Antiochos aus Askalon.” In H. Flashar (ed.), Die Philosophie der Antike 4: Die hellenistische Philosophie, 717–989. Basel: Schwabe. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 1980. Aristone di Chio e lo Stoicismo antico. Napoli: Bibliopolis. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 1986. Opinione e scienza. Il dibattito tra Stoici e Accademici nel terzo e secondo secolo a.C. Napoli: Bibliopolis. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 1989. “Stoici e Accademici sul ruolo dell’assenso,” Elenchos 10: 231–246. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 2000. “A proposito di alcune recenti interpretazioni dello scetticismo dell’Accademia,” Elenchos 21: 333–360. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 2007. L’assenso in Clitomaco:un problema di linguaggio? In A. M. Ioppolo and D. Sedley (eds.), Pyrrhonists, Patricians, Platonizers. Hellenistic Philosophy in the Period 155–86 B.C., 225–267. Napoli: Bibliopolis. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 2009. La testimonianza di Sesto Empirico sull’Accademia scettica. Napoli: Bibliopolis. Long, Anthony. 2006. “Arcesilaus in His Time and Place.” In his From Epicurus to Epictetus: Studies in Hellenistic and Roman Philosophy, 96–114. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Long, Antony, and David Sedley. 1987. The Hellenistic Philosophers, 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Maconi, Henry. 1988. “Nova Non Philosophandi Philosophia,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 6: 251–253. Spinelli, Emidio. 1995. Sesto Empirico: Contro gli Etici. Napoli: Bibliopolis. Spinelli, Emidio. 2005. Questioni scettiche: Letture introduttive al Pirronismo antico. Roma: Lithos. Tsekourakis, Damianos. 1974. Studies in the Terminology of the Early Stoa. Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner Verlag. Warren, James. 2002. “Socratic Scepticism in Plutarch’s ‘Adversus Colotem,’” Elenchos 23: 333–356.

CHAPTER FOUR

Carneades HARALD THORSRUD

1 INTRODUCTION Carneades of Cyrene (214–129/8 BCE) became head of the Academy sometime before 155 BCE, a little more than one hundred years after Arcesilaus initiated a skeptical movement in the school. Inspired by his reading of Plato’s dialogues, Carneades adopted a version of Socrates’s dialectical project—recognizing his own ignorance and the supreme importance of knowledge, he set about testing, and ultimately refuting, others.1 Carneades followed in Arcesilaus’s footsteps, continuing and strengthening this method.2 Like his predecessors, he wrote nothing,3 and was formidable if not unconquerable in debate.4 And as head of the Academy, he too must have acknowledged some connection with Socrates. So even though he focused on the refutation of the Stoics (see DL IV 62, St. Rep. 1035F), we should not lose sight of the Platonic or Socratic context for his argumentative practice. According to one version of the history of the Academy, Socrates initiated a dialectical method aimed at (i) relieving others of falsely believing they know what they don’t, and (ii) revealing the most probable solutions to the problems discussed, while (iii) concealing his own opinion so as not to interfere with the rational autonomy of the participants (Tusc. V 11).5 There is no doubt that Carneades devoted himself to the first of these three aims. He produced powerful objections to the Stoic view of divination,6 to both Stoic and Epicurean views of freedom and determinism,7 and he argued forcefully against Stoic theology.8 He also expanded the range of targets in ethics and epistemology, arguing not only against all the actual views held on the ethical τέλος and on the criterion of truth, but against all possible views, given certain restrictions on the candidates (Fin. V 16, AM VII 159).9 Whether, or in what sense, Carneades embraced (ii) and (iii) is controversial.10 He is credited with developing an account of living in accordance with the probable or persuasive impression11 to explain how, while suspending judgment, one might remain active and even attain wisdom and happiness. But it is not clear whether he himself relied on such impressions in day-to-day life and in the pursuit of truth, or whether this account was merely part of a dialectical strategy aimed exclusively at refuting the Stoics. In either case, the proper understanding of Carneades’s view of probability must still be determined.

52

SKEPTICISM

While the question about the content of his view should be kept distinct from the question about his attitude toward it, they are related in at least one important way. If Carneades’s theory successfully shows how one may live well in the absence of certainty, then it shows this for everyone, not just the Stoics; and in that case he too would have a powerful motive to accept his own account and live accordingly (Obdrzalek 2006: 253).

2  THE DIALECTICAL CONTEXT Like Arcesilaus before him, Carneades focused a great deal of effort on refuting the Stoic view of wisdom and its epistemic foundation in apprehension (κατάληψις). If the Stoic sage is to be infallible, there must be something worthy of his assent. Zeno defined such an apprehensible, or kataleptic, impression (καταληπτικὴ φαντασία) as (i) one that arises from what is, (ii) is stamped, impressed, and molded just as it is, and (iii) is of such a kind as could not arise from what is not (Acad. I 42, II 77; AM VII 252). One of the arguments Carneades deployed against the third, modal condition is an epistemological sorites. We begin with a false impression that is persuasive, for example, that some counterfeit is genuine. Suppose this initial impression is relatively easy to correct by careful examination. We may next imagine an impression of a more skillful counterfeit whose deceit is more difficult to discern. And we may increase this difficulty until we arrive at a false impression that is, for us, indistinguishable from an impression of the genuine article. For any level of skillful detection we care to name, we can always imagine an even more skillful counterfeit. In the end, two equally persuasive impressions, one false and one true, differ in nothing but number (Acad. II 47–49; AM VII 415–422). The consequences of Carneades’s arguments, if successful, would be devastating for the Stoics. For if there is no apprehension, the sage will either have to withhold assent or assent to what is not apprehended. Neither is acceptable: the former would render the sage inactive since the Stoics claimed assent is necessary for intentional action, and the latter would render the sage fallible (Acad. II 67). Without the possibility of apprehension, it seems the Stoics must choose between an infallible but inactive sage and an active but fallible one. In an attempt to remove the source of this dilemma, the Stoics provided some reductiones of the Academic denial of κατάληψις (i.e., ἀκαταληψία). These are referred to as apraxia arguments since they are supposed to show that if the Academic attack succeeds, certain sorts of action would be impossible.12 If there might be no discernible differences between true and false impressions, we can have no confidence in the truth of any of our impressions, and the worldviews we construct might always be systematically deceptive. We would be right in that case to withhold judgment, but that would paralyze us. Since it is absurd to claim that it is right to render ourselves utterly inactive, we must reject ἀκαταληψία. Similarly, if we suppose there is no apprehension, the sage can have no confidence in his moral judgments. This is especially problematic when morality demands we make

CARNEADES

53

a great sacrifice (Acad. II 23). So if there is no apprehension, there is no wisdom. But there is (or at least may be) wisdom according to the Stoics, so again we must reject ἀκαταληψία. Why would Carneades bother to respond to these apraxia objections? From a dialectical standpoint, ἀκαταληψία is not his view, and thus he should feel no need to defend it. But if the Stoics also maintained that no account other than their own could adequately explain wisdom, then Carneades may have developed a view in response to that challenge (Allen 1994: 87). In fact, Carneades is supposed to have offered two distinct alternatives. First, the sage might follow a persuasive impression without assent and the resulting opinion, and thus without committing himself to the truth, or even probable truth, of the impression (radical skepticism). And second, the sage might assent to the truth of persuasive impressions with the appropriate modesty or caution due to recognizing the possibility of error (mitigated skepticism). While it might be the case that neither of these is Carneades’s view, I will argue that the evidence strongly favors mitigated skepticism. First, note that there are two major problems with attributing radical skepticism to him. In order for the radical skeptic to be free from opinion, he takes no stand on the truth of what strikes him as probable (or better: plausible). On this view, Carneades’s radical skeptic appears no different from Sextus’s Pyrrhonist, who follows appearances without any commitment as to whether things really are as they appear. By suspending judgment the Pyrrhonist expects that the tranquility he desires will follow fortuitously. But since there is no reason to think Carneades’s radical skeptic has a similar expectation, or even prizes tranquility in the way the Pyrrhonist does, it is hard to see why such a life would be thought worth living. As a Socratic, he might cherish his intellectual integrity, but that alone seems an unacceptably thin account of wisdom and happiness. Without the payoff of tranquility, radical skepticism does not provide Carneades with an effective response to the apraxia objection in its entirety. At a minimum, his Stoic interlocutors would reject the claim that one may live a flourishing life in the absence not only of knowledge, but even reasoned opinion.13 The second problem arises from the incompatibility of radical and mitigated skepticism: one maintains that the sage is infallible (by holding no opinions), and the other that the sage is fallible. And yet Cicero appears to endorse both of these as the proper interpretation of Carneades in the Academica, one of our most important and detailed sources. Since Cicero explicitly intends to explain his Academic allegiance in this work (ND I 11), and since he consistently endorses and practices a mitigated skepticism in every other philosophical dialogue, we should seek an interpretation of the Academica that is consistent with such a mitigated skepticism (Thorsrud 2002, 2012). To the extent that we succeed, much of the support for Carneades’s radically skeptical proposal will vanish, and we will be left with the mitigated variety, even if the possibility remains that Carneades endorses nothing.14 In the remainder of this chapter, I will pursue this approach by discussing Carneades’s distinction between kinds of impression, the kinds of assent given to each, the varieties of cognitive state, or opinion, that arises from such assents, and the compatibility of wisdom with opinion.

54

SKEPTICISM

3  VARIETIES OF IMPRESSION Carneades argued that no impression could serve as the criterion of truth. Generalizing on the Academic arguments against Stoic epistemology, he claimed that for any true impression, an indistinguishable false one could be found. And he argued that impressions cannot reveal both themselves and their objects or states of affairs in such a way that we can grasp the correspondence between them with certainty. So all such criteria will “consist in an appearance [impression] that is common to both true and false. But the appearance that is common to these two is not apprehensive, and not being apprehensive, neither will it be a criterion” (AM VII 164).15 So it is surprising to find that, after refuting his predecessors, Carneades introduces the probable impression as yet another account of the criterion of truth, especially since he admits that what is probably, or persuasively, true is common to both what is in fact true and false. It appears that his earlier argument preemptively refutes this new proposal.16 But this will only be the case if he agreed with his Stoic opponents that a criterion of truth must infallibly indicate truth. Carneades’s innovation is to reject that view. “We should not,” he says, “because of the rare occurrence of this [an apparently and vividly true impression being false] distrust the one that for the most part tells the truth. For both our judgments and our actions are, as a matter of fact, regulated by what applies for the most part” (AM VII 175). Obviously there is no sophisticated or mathematical appeal to frequency in the notion of what happens for the most part. But it is just as clear that it is an appeal to an ordinary understanding of frequency—we can comfortably rely on such persuasive impressions because they have a good track record, they typically get things right. Carneades is proposing, apparently for the first time, the notion that probability is the very guide to life.17 In the absence of certainty, we are not left with the desperate and impractical view that everything is equally uncertain (Acad. II 99, 103), as if there were no basis whatsoever to prefer one impression to another.18 Such a view would undermine life in the way the Stoics objected. But this is not Carneades’s position. He holds that some impressions are persuasive because they appear to be true (AM VII 169), and that among these some are more persuasive and vivid than others, even though the most vivid may still turn out to be false (AM VII 173, PH I 227). Furthermore, he seems to have more than a purely dialectical interest in providing this account. Sextus reports that “since he [sc. Carneades] too requires some criterion for the conduct of life and for the achievement of happiness, he is in effect compelled for his own part to take a stand on this” (AM VII 166). Sextus does not tell us why he was so compelled. But insofar as there was broad agreement that happiness (εὐδαιμονία) is the proper specification of our τέλος, we may plausibly suppose that all Hellenistic philosophers would have been expected to offer guidance in attaining it (see Hadot 1995; Cooper 2013). There are additional distinctions to be made among persuasive impressions. In trivial matters, or when we simply don’t have the time or opportunity for further scrutiny, we rely on the merely persuasive impression without further ado. But

CARNEADES

55

in more important matters we examine the neighboring impressions, looking for confirmation or disconfirmation. For the extent to which an impression is convincing is, in part, a function of the coherence and mutual support provided by related impressions. So, for example, a good physician will not diagnose a patient on the basis of one symptom, but will rather look for corroborating evidence. And in matters of the greatest importance, that is, those pertaining to our happiness, we subject each of the associated impressions to additional scrutiny, rather than taking them at face value (AM VII 176–189; cf. PH I 227–229). But what might be the content of a persuasive impression pertaining to happiness? The examples typically involve some proposed course of action: for example, whether to avoid the object on the floor because it appears to be a snake, whether to set out on a sea voyage, sow crops, get married, etc. (Acad. II 109, AM VII 176–189, PH I 227). Successfully avoiding coiled snakes or safely crossing the sea is certainly important, but in what sense, if any, do these actions pertain to my happiness? It might turn out, unlikely though it seems, that I will be happier as a result of snakebite, shipwreck, failed crops, or a ruined marriage. If Carneades intended to limit persuasive impressions to those revealing expected outcomes, it would provide only the barest minimum of guidance with respect to attaining happiness. For living in accordance with such impressions will only make it more likely that we satisfy our desires, and not that we are more likely to be happy by doing so. Fortunately, there is good evidence that persuasive impressions extend well beyond the merely perceptual and predictive.19 According to Sextus, members of Carneades’s Academy affirm that what persuasively appears to be good is really good (PH I 226). Whether or not this claim is entirely accurate, it does suggest the existence of persuasive, evaluative impressions—for example, that it would be good to do something and not merely that the proposed action will succeed. Furthermore, Cicero tells us that when the sage is “asked about what it is appropriate to do [de officio]. . . . He won’t say he doesn’t know, as when asked about whether the number of the stars is even or odd” (Acad. II 110).20 This allows for deontic impressions, which we should expect given that “the wise person will use whatever strikes him as persuasive . . . and the whole structure of his life will be governed in this way (omnis ratio vitae gubernabitur)” (Acad. II 99; see also Acad. II 104, PH I 231).21 But since it would be frivolous to act on the basis of whatever happens to strike one as plausibly worth doing or as what one is plausibly required to do, the sage’s moral judgment must be informed by rational principles (Acad. II 35–36). Now if, as the Stoics think, the sage can have no principles (decreta = δόγματα) that he fails to securely grasp as true, Carneades would have to admit that his Academic sage securely grasps this much: that nothing is apprehensible. Cicero responds, on behalf of Carneades: “As if the wise person has no other principles and could live his life without principles! But just as he holds those as persuasive rather than apprehended principles, so with this one, that nothing is apprehensible” (Acad. II 109–110; see also Acad. II 29, PH I 226). Accordingly, Carneades seems to allow for philosophical impressions as principles governing the life of the sage.22 The only plausible explanation of how Carneades’s sage could arrive at such principles is philosophical investigation: the sage “will deliberate about what to

56

SKEPTICISM

do or not to do on the basis of [persuasive] impressions” (Acad. II 100). Indeed, Carneades and his followers are said to have been especially inspired by their claim that persuasive or truth-like impressions provide them with a rule for both conducting their lives and for philosophical investigation and disputation (regula et in agenda vita et in quaerendo ac disserendo) (Acad. II 32).23 Cicero tells us that the whole point of Carneades’s refutative practice was to discover the truth, or what is most like the truth, the most probable solution (ND I 11–12, Tusc. V 10–11; see also Acad. II 7–9, ND I 4, Div. II 150).24 If Carneades develops his account of persuasive impressions to show not only how we may navigate through the world but also how we may achieve wisdom, there will have to be a wide variety of persuasive impressions for the sage to rely on. And his dialectical practice of arguing for and against must, as Cicero repeatedly insists, be aimed not only at refutation but also at revealing which position is most truth-like, or rationally defensible; otherwise Carneades’s wisdom will merely enable the sage to navigate through the world and satisfy his desires. But how then can the method of subjecting sense-impressions to increasing degrees of scrutiny and the method of arguing pro and con both rely on the same criterion? The ordinary sense of frequency invoked in the former seems entirely out of place in the latter—our philosophical judgments aren’t regulated by what happens for the most part. While none of our sources address this problem, there is a ready solution. In both cases the reigning assumption is that truth is what survives refutation.25 When we subject an impression to closer scrutiny by first checking for overall coherence with its associated impressions and then by examining each of those impressions independently, we are seeking to falsify the target impression. If we fail to do so, the target impression becomes even more persuasive—it has survived refutation. The Academics do not deny that some impressions are in fact true, but only that we can be certain of which are true (Acad. II 73, 111). And the possibility that what is true can, at least in some cases, constrain our judgments is implicit in a remark that Carneades used to make: the sons of the wealthy and sons of kings do learn to ride on horseback, but they learn nothing else well and properly; for in their studies their teacher flatters them with praise, and their opponent in wrestling does the same by submitting to be thrown, whereas the horse, having no knowledge or concern even as to who is private citizen or ruler, or rich or poor, throws headlong those who cannot ride him. (Plutarch, Adulator 58f5, tr. Babbit 1927) Similarly, only life itself may correct those philosophical views that are left untouched by overly polite or incompetent interlocutors. In the dispute over Stoic epistemology, where we have competent opponents, the extent to which the claim that nothing is apprehensible survives refutation is the extent to which we will, and should, find it persuasive. The dialectical testing of philosophical impressions is thus analogous to the scrutiny of perceptual impressions. And while the notion of dialectical survival is admittedly vague, it does show how one might reasonably think that τὸ πιθανόν provides a rule for both the conduct of life and philosophical investigation.

CARNEADES

57

4  VARIETIES OF ASSENT Just as Carneades offers the persuasive impression as an alternative to the kataleptic impression as the sage’s guide to life, he also provides an alternative to the Stoic view of assent. According to the Stoics, strong assent is given only to kataleptic impressions (or more precisely, only to the true propositions that articulate the content of kataleptic impressions) and in such a way as to be irreversible. To be capable of assenting strongly requires the virtue of dialectic, which “conveys a method that guards us from giving assent to any falsehood or ever being deceived by specious probability, and enables us to retain and defend the truths that we have learned about good and evil” (Fin. III 72, tr. Rackham 1914). This dialectical virtue is also described as freedom from precipitant or rash judgment: “knowledge [of] when to give or withhold the mind’s assent to impressions,” or “the disposition not to assent in advance of apprehension” (DL VII 46–48; see also Plutarch, St. rep. 1056F, 1057B–C). Having this virtue, the Stoic sage never believes a falsehood, and never assents to anything that is not apprehended (Stobaeus, Anthologium II 7, 11m). By contrast, a weak assent is one that would not have been given had the circumstances been even slightly different. The foolish are too easily swayed by factors that are irrelevant to the truth or falsity of the proposition in question; when they get things right, it is to some extent just a matter of good fortune. The foolish lack the systematic knowledge that secures each individual piece of knowledge, so even when they assent to a true proposition, the assent is weak because changeable. These distinctions rest squarely on the possibility of apprehension. If there are no impressions worthy of strong assent, then all assent will be weak and rash on the Stoic view, and we will be back once again at the conclusion that we must withhold all assent. To avoid this conclusion, Carneades offers a very different distinction: The wise person is said to suspend assent in two senses: in one sense, when this means he won’t assent to anything entirely; in another, when it means he will restrain himself even from giving responses showing that he approves or disapproves of something, so that he won’t say “yes” or “no” to anything. Given this distinction, the wise person accepts the suspension of assent in the first sense, with the result that by following what is persuasive wherever that is present or deficient, he is able to reply “yes” or “no.” Since the person who keeps himself from assenting to anything nevertheless wants to move and act, Clitomachus maintained there are still impressions of the kind that excite us to action; and likewise, there are still responses we can use when questioned on either side, by just following our impressions on the matter, provided we do so without assent (Acad. II 104).26 Despite the lack of any explicit reference to the Stoics in this passage, it is reasonable to expect that, having eliminated kataleptic impressions, Carneades would finish the job by forbidding the sort of assent that is only properly given to such impressions— this is nicely captured by the expression “assenting entirely.” If so, we may take Carneades’s first kind of assent to correspond to the Stoic’s strong assent. Only now the point is that the sage refrains from such assent since there is nothing worthy of that absolute degree of confidence.

58

SKEPTICISM

The description of the second type of assent is brief and obscure—replying “yes” to what is persuasive and “no” to what is not. But if the distinction is offered by way of contrast, it will be a matter of not assenting entirely, but rather to a lesser degree, yet still with enough confidence to motivate action and provide guidance. The notion that such assent comes in degrees of confidence correlates perfectly with the degrees of persuasiveness among impressions. So we may say that, since no impression is apprehensible, the sage does not assent entirely to anything, but that he does assent to the extent that the persuasive impression has been thoroughly examined and is not contradicted by associated impressions. This amounts to a consciously fallible judgment of truth.27 Unlike the Pyrrhonists, Carneades holds that some impressions are more convincing than others (PH I 227). Since what we are convinced of, typically, is that something is the case, this amounts to saying that some impressions appear true to a greater degree than others. So the reason Carneades prefers persuasive impressions that have been subjected to the highest degree of scrutiny is that they are more likely to get things right and provide good guidance (PH I 229). It is precisely on this point that Sextus differentiates Carneades’s New Academy from Pyrrhonism.28 Academics assent in the way a dissolute man agrees with someone who urges extravagant living. What Carneades actually desires is not extravagance, of course, but truth.29 So the charge is that Carneades knows better than to assent to the apparent truth of merely persuasive impressions, but cannot resist doing so. The Pyrrhonists, by contrast, yields to some impressions, not because they are apparently true, but simply because they move him. What Sextus probably finds objectionable about the former sort of assent is that, unlike the Pyrrhonist’s yielding, it leaves one vulnerable to rational challenges and the disturbance that follows when those challenges are not met. To reply on behalf of Carneades, we may say that it would be truly blameworthy only if one were to assent entirely. This provides a good way to understand his almost Herculean labor of driving “assent—i.e., opinion and rashness—from our minds, as one would drive out a wild and savage monster” (Acad. II 108). Since it would be flagrantly inconsistent to insist that one should never assent to anything whatsoever and that one should assent in a more qualified manner to persuasive impressions, we may conclude that what Carneades drives out is assenting entirely. And we should provide this qualification as needed in Cicero’s discussion of the rashness of assent or the view that the sage withholds assent. For example: “Even if anything is apprehensible, the very habit of assent [i.e., assenting entirely] is slippery and dangerous. Hence, since it’s agreed that it is extremely vicious to assent [entirely] to anything false or unknown, it’s better to restrain all assent [i.e., assenting entirely] so the wise person doesn’t go awry by advancing rashly” (Acad. II 68). Similarly, what is most shameful is to approve of something false in place of the truth, or as if it were true [pro veris probare false] (Acad. II 66). By supposing that what we are assenting to is true, rather than probably true or persuasive, we give our assent entirely. Likewise, it is rash to assent to the unknown in place of, or as if it were, known (ne incognita pro cognitis habeamus iisque temere assentiamur) (Off. I 18).30 Once again, by supposing that what we are assenting to is securely known, we give our assent entirely—and this is rash.

CARNEADES

59

Consequently, the error Carneades seeks to eliminate is not simply assenting to what is false, but rather being credulous or gullible, especially with respect to the rational support of our own convictions. He would in that case be seeking, in good Socratic fashion, to relieve us of the rashness of thinking that we know what we do not and of obstinately defending the views we have grown attached to (Acad. II 9).

5  VARIETIES OF OPINION AND THE FALLIBLE SAGE There are, however, a number of passages in which both Carneades and Cicero seem to reject the view that it is ever wise to hold mere opinions. For example, Cicero openly approves of Zeno’s view that the sage will hold no opinions (Acad. II 113). On the basis of what I have argued so far, we may take him to mean that the sage never has the blameworthy mental state that arises from assenting rashly, that is, entirely, in the absence of apprehension. The fact that he chooses to call this “opinion” is potentially misleading since it may be confused with the cognitive state that guides the life of the Academic sage. Both sorts of opinion involve assenting to what is, or may be, false. The crucial difference is that from the Stoic perspective any such assent is necessarily a moral and epistemic failing, while from Carneades’s Academic perspective only assenting entirely is blameworthy.31 This explains why Carneades would not vehemently combat the Peripatetics when they affirm the sage will hold opinions. For the Peripatetics similarly think that fulfilling one’s epistemic obligation does not make one infallible, so assenting to what turns out to be false is not necessarily a transgression (Acad. II 112). This also illuminates Carneades’s dialectical strategy in combating the Stoics. When Carneades proposes, for the sake of argument, that the sage will sometimes have opinions, he is relying on the Stoic view of opinion. This is why the Stoic spokesman in the Academica describes his strategy this way: “Carneades was occasionally liable to sink so low as to say that the wise person would have opinions, i.e. that he would err” (Acad. II 59, see also II 67). In order to drive the Stoics to the unacceptable conclusion that the (Stoic) sage would transgress, Carneades had to rely on their own views of assent and opinion.32 Finally, we also find that the Academics identify rashness as either assenting to what is false or to what has not been sufficiently examined or comprehended.33 The disjunction is puzzling. Is it blameworthy to assent to what is false because it is shameful to have false opinions? Or is it blameworthy, as I have been arguing, to assent to what has not been adequately examined because this is contrary to what wisdom demands? These two options are potentially at odds. Suppose one assents to an adequately examined persuasive impression that turns out false. It would then be both rash to assent to it (because false) and not rash (because sufficiently examined). On the other hand, suppose one assents to a true impression that has not been sufficiently examined. Now it will be both rash to assent to it (because not sufficiently examined) and not rash (because true).34

60

SKEPTICISM

We may avoid this problem by taking the second disjunct as an emphatic alternative. In that case, the claim would be that it is rash to assent to what is false, or at least (since we are often not in a position to know whether the proposition in question is false) to what has not been sufficiently examined.35 In any case, we must maintain the fundamental point that, since Carneades’s sage assents to persuasive impressions and since such impressions may always turn out to be false, it necessarily follows that the sage will sometimes assent to what is false. So the Academic sage’s wisdom must be constituted by the distinctive manner in which he gives his assent. In particular, he will proportion the strength of his assent to the persuasiveness of the impression, whether through systematic scrutiny of his perceptual impressions or through argument pro and con in the case of philosophical propositions, and he will remain perpetually open to being corrected by subsequent experience and additional argument. On those rare occasions in which a thoroughly examined persuasive impression turns out to be false, or dialectically defeated, the sage’s opinion that it was probably true is not blameworthy.36

NOTES 1. See Cicero, De Or. III 67, Cooper (2004: 92–95), Ioppolo (1986), and Thorsrud (2010: 58–62). 2. See De Or. III 68, ND I 11, Acad. II 16. See also Acad. II 46, and Eusebius, Praep. Evang. 14.7.15. 3. See DL I 16, IV 65; Plutarch, De Alex. fort. 328A–B; Gellius, NA 17.15.1–3. Carneades’s student Clitomachus wrote over 400 books documenting the arguments of his teacher (DL IV 67; see Acad. II 16, Or. 51). None of these survive except in the form of quotations and paraphrases, which are collected by Mette (1985). Cicero and Sextus are the most important sources; however, Cicero is more sympathetic and closer in time, and over half of the lines of text collected by Mette are his or derive from his writing. Many of the central texts are also collected and translated in Long and Sedley (1987: 438-460). 4. See De Or. I 45, III 68; Fin. III 41; DL I 16, IV 65; De Alex. fort. 328A–B; Gellius NA 17.15.1–3; Praep. Evang. 14.8. Carneades, along with two other philosophers acting as Athenian emissaries in 155, convinced the Romans to reduce a fine levied against Athens for having sacked the city of Oropus. Powell (2013) has convincingly shown that the famous arguments for and against justice that Carneades is reported to have delivered on this occasion are likely to be a fabrication of Cicero’s. Had he really sought to show the Romans that they did not know what justice is, he would likely have betrayed his diplomatic charge. 5. Since it was common practice among Academic philosophers to locate the origin of their views in Plato and Socrates, there were a number of competing histories of the Academy—see Brittain (2001: 169–254). I am not presupposing that this is the correct account. I mention it here because it neatly contains the major features that one might find exemplified by Carneades, as indeed Cicero did. 6. See Cicero, Div.; also Hankinson (1988). 7. See Cicero, Fat.; also Bobzien (2002) and O’Keefe (2005: 138–149, 153–162).

CARNEADES

61

8. See Cicero, ND III; Sextus, AM IX. See also Burnyeat (1982a) and Long (1990). 9. On Carneades’s epistemological arguments, see Frede (1987b), Schofield (1999: 338–344), and Perin (2006). On his ethical arguments, see Long (1967), Algra (1997), and Annas (2007). 10. The current consensus is that he did not—see n. 32 below. 11. The proper translation of the property expressed by these impressions, τὸ πιθανόν, is also controversial. Cicero renders it probabile and veri simile (Acad. II 7–8, 99, 107; Tusc. I 17, II 5). See Glucker (1995). 12. Vogt (2010) illuminates the variety of apraxia arguments. 13. Obdrzalek (2006: 257) convincingly argues that in order for Carneades’s response to the Stoic apraxia charge to succeed, it must show how one can lead a coherent and happy life while refraining from dogmatic assent. 14. It is clear that there was some dispute among Carneades’s students regarding his position (Acad. II 78). I maintain that whatever the nature of that dispute, Cicero’s testimony does not support a radically skeptical Carneadean alternative. Görler (1994: 816–819) also rejects the view that Carneades was a radical skeptic insofar as he shares some basic convictions with the Stoics—for example, that sense-impressions exist and that some are true. For more on the extraordinarily complicated history of the post-Carneadean Academy, see Tarrant (1985), Glucker (1978), Brittain (2001), and Lévy (2010). 15. All translations of AM VII are from Bett (2005). 16. Ioppolo (2009) argues that Sextus relies on inconsistent accounts of Carneades’s criterion: on the one hand, exclusively practical, having no connection to truth, and on the other, epistemic. 17. This is hardly a novel proposal. Indeed, Cicero seems to have understood Carneades this way, as does Reid (1885) in his notes to the text of the Academica. More recently, see Stough (1969: 50–64) and Grundmann (2003). Jeffrey (1984: 73–75) and Niiniluoto (1984: 594) find in Carneades the historical precedent for their favored views of probability. In opposition, Burnyeat (1982b) argues, with reference to Hacking (1984), that Carneades does not, and in fact could not, share or even anticipate our contemporary view of probability (that X is good evidence for Y in proportion to the frequency with which X and Y go together). But even without any mathematical or statistical interpretation of frequency, one may still think that we are habituated by the regularity of experience to anticipate a certain effect from a certain cause. Furthermore, the fact that the Academic sage is guided by probable impressions indicates that it plays a normative role, showing not merely how people live, but also how they should live. 18. The one key issue on which Carneades is said to have departed from Arcesilaus is in claiming that it is impossible to suspend judgment on everything, but that fortunately while all things are inapprehensible, not all things are uncertain (Praep. Evang. 14.7.15; cf. Acad. II 59). 19. Görler (1994: 874–879) argues to the contrary that Carneades’s probable impressions are exclusively sensory and that the approval of philosophical views as probable is Cicero’s distinctively Roman innovation. 20. All translations of the Academica are from Brittain (2006).

62

SKEPTICISM

21. Compare ND I 12: persuasive impressions direct or regulate the life of the sage (sapientis vita regeretur). 22. Cicero reports that the Stoics and Peripatetics used to choose Carneades to adjudicate their disagreement over the proper understanding of the τέλος (Tusc. V 120), presumably because of his great oratorical skill. If so, they would have wanted him to judge which side was more persuasively argued, which suggests a straightforwardly philosophical application of Carneades’s skeptical criterion. 23. Brittain (2001: 95–96, 103–108) accounts for such passages as an intrusion of mitigated skepticism into Carneades’s real position of universal ἐποχή and an exclusively dialectical engagement with dogmatists. But see Glucker (1994: 147–152). 24. If Carneades really did argue pro and con for the sake of drawing out the most probable philosophical views, we may reasonably ask why there is no record of what he judged to be the dialectical winners. Cicero provides the answer: Academics conceal their views so that students may be guided by their own reason rather than by authority (Acad. II 60, Tusc. V 11, de Or. I 84). This would explain why Clitomachus used to say that he had never been able to understand what Carneades did accept (quid probaretur, Acad. I 139); it would make no sense for him to try to figure out what Carneades accepted if he had been confident that he accepted nothing. 25. Waterfield (1989) makes a persuasive case for attributing to the Socrates of Plato’s Socratic dialogues the view that truth is what survives refutation. 26. I have made a slight but crucially important modification to Brittain’s (2006) translation. For omnino eum rei nulli adsentiri he provides, “[The sage] won’t assent to anything at all,” whereas I follow Reid (1885: 300) in taking omnino as an adverb: “[The sage] won’t assent to anything entirely.” 27. For a very different interpretation see Bett (1990), and similarly: Frede (1987c), Striker (1996; 2010: 200), Schofield (1999: 334–337), and Ioppolo (2007). Bett argues that Carneades’s response to the apraxia objection involves distinguishing between an impression being convincing from our taking it to be true. On this view, Carneades proposes we may act in accordance with former while withholding assent to the latter. I believe, however, that finding something convincing is inextricably connected with taking it to be true, in some sense. 28. It is interesting to note that this is virtually the same argument that Sextus makes against those who would count Plato as a skeptic (PH I 222–223). 29. Carneades argued against Stoic theology “in such a manner as to arouse in persons of active mind a keen desire to discover the truth” (ND I 4; see also Acad. II 7, 66, 76). 30. For similar uses of pro, see Acad. II 53, Part. 44, ad. Brut. 1.5.2. 31. Similarly, when Cicero admits that he cannot resist assenting to some persuasive impressions and thereby holding opinions (Acad. II 66, 113), we should not suppose that he is sincerely convicting himself of foolishness—see Görler (1997). For if he sincerely believed that wisdom is incompatible with opinion, he could not endorse his Academic method, the whole point of which is to draw out the most probable views, that is, the most rationally defensible opinions. Elsewhere, he is quite happy to insist on the compatibility of wisdom and mere opinion (e.g., Mur. 63).

CARNEADES

63

32. However, we might also seek to explain Carneades’s rejection of the compatibility of wisdom with opinion by claiming, as some have, that the mitigated skeptic is merely a dialectical invention, which was later attributed to Carneades as his own positive view. With the inspiration of Couissin (1929), this has been developed and employed in a variety of ways by Burnyeat (1982b), Sedley (1983), Frede (1987c), Bett (1989; 1990), Allen (1994; 1997), Striker (1996; 2010), Schofield (1999), and Brittain (2001). Perhaps the most important piece of evidence in support of this view of Carneades is a reported dispute between his students: “[That the sage] could fail to apprehend anything and yet still have opinions … is said to have been the position approved by Carneades—although, since I [sc. Cicero] trust Clitomachus rather than Philo or Metrodorus, I consider it a position he argued for rather than approved” (Acad. II 78; see Brittain 2001: 76–82). For an interpretation of this passage that is consistent with the position I take here see Thorsrud (2012). 33. There are no texts that attribute this sort of disjunction explicitly to Carneades. The following three, however, could plausibly be linked to him. At Acad. II 68, Cicero, on behalf of the New Academy is describing our view. And Div. I 7 and ND I 1 are general descriptions and justifications of Cicero’s Academic methodology, which he does identify explicitly as Carneades’s elsewhere (Tusc. V 11). 34. Augustine explores some similar possibilities in C. Acad. III xv 34. 35. A prime example of this is Acad. II 7: the sole purpose of the Academics’ arguing on both sides is to draw out that which is either true or at least the closest approximation to the truth (aliquid quod aut verum sit aut ad id quam proxime accedat). See also Off. III 54, Tusc. V 51. 36. The inspiration for this view may have come from the Stoics themselves. In order to maintain the sage’s infallibility, some Stoics argued that, when the sage assents to some proposition p that turns out false, we should suppose that what he assents to is the proposition that it is reasonable that p. Regardless of whether p is true or false, it will still be the case that it was reasonable that p, and the sage will not have made a mistake (see DL VII 177, Brennan 1996). Similarly, when Carneades’s sage assents to the proposition that it is probable that p, he is probably right in doing so, and again even if p turns out to be false, he will not have made a mistake.

REFERENCES Algra, Keimpe. 1997. “Chrysippus, Carneades, Cicero: The Ethical Divisions in Cicero’s Lucullus.” In B. Inwood and J. Mansfeld (eds.), Assent and Argument: Studies in Cicero’s Academic Books, 107–139. Leiden: Brill. Allen, James. 1994. “Academic Probabilism and Stoic Epistemology,” Classical Quarterly 44: 85–113. Allen, James. 1997. “Carneadean Argument in Cicero’s Academic Books.” In B. Inwood and J. Mansfeld (eds.), Assent and Argument: Studies in Cicero’s Academic Books, 217– 256. Leiden: Brill. Annas, Julia. 2007. “Carneades’ Classification of Ethical Theories.” In A. M. Ioppolo and D. Sedley (eds.), Pyrrhonists, Patricians, Platonizers. Hellenistic Philosophy in the Period 155–86 BC, 187–223. Naples: Bibliopolis. Babbit, Frank. 1927. Plutarch: Moralia, vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

64

SKEPTICISM

Bett, Richard. 1989. “Carneades’ Pithanon: A Reappraisal of Its Role and Status,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 7: 59–94. Bett, Richard. 1990. “Carneades’ Distinction between Assent and Approval,” Monist 73: 3–20. Bett, Richard. 2005. Sextus Empiricus: Against the Logicians. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bett, Richard (ed.). 2010. The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bobzien, Susanne. 2002. Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brennan, Tad. 1996. “Reasonable Impressions in Stoicism,” Phronesis 41: 318–334. Brittain, Charles. 2001. Philo of Larissa: The Last of the Academic Sceptics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brittain, Charles. 2006. Cicero: On Academic Scepticism. Indianapolis: Hackett. Burnyeat, Myles. 1982a. “Gods and Heaps.” In M. Schofield and M. Nussbaum (eds.), Language and Logos: Studies in Ancient Greek Philosophy, 315–338. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Burnyeat, Myles. 1982b. “Carneades Was No Probabilist,” unpublished manuscript. Cooper, John. 2004. “Arcesilaus: Socratic and Sceptic.” In his Knowledge, Nature, and the Good, Essays on Ancient Philosophy, 81–103. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Cooper, John. 2013. Pursuits of Wisdom: Six Ways of Life in Ancient Philosophy from Socrates to Plotinus. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Couissin, Pierre. 1929. “Le stoicisme de la nouvelle Academie,” Revue d’historie de la philosophie 3: 241–276. Translated and reprinted as “The Stoicism of the New Academy.” In M. Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition, 31–63. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983. Frede, Michael. 1987a. Essays in Ancient Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Frede, Michael. 1987b. “Stoics and Sceptics on Clear and Distinct Impressions.” In his Essays in Ancient Philosophy, 151–178, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Frede, Michael. 1987c. “The Sceptic’s Two Kinds of Assent and the Question of the Possibility of Knowledge.” In his Essays in Ancient Philosophy, 201–224, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Glucker, John. 1978. Antiochus and the Late Academy. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht. Glucker, John. 1995. “Probabile, Verisimile, and Related Terms.” In J. Powell (ed.), Cicero the Philosopher: Twelve Papers, 115–143. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Glucker, John. 2004. “The Philonian/Metrodorians: Problems of Method in Ancient Philosophy,” Elenchos 25: 99–153. Görler, Woldemar. 1994. “Ältere Pyrrhonismus, Jüngere Akademie, Antiochos aus Askalon.” In F. Ueberweg (ed.), Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie, Die Philosophie der Antike, Bd. 4. Die hellenistische Philosophie, 732–989. Basel: Schwabe. Görler, Woldemar. 1997. “Cicero’s Philosophical Stance in the Lucullus,” B. Inwood and J. Mansfeld (eds.), Assent and Argument: Studies in Cicero’s Academic Books, 36–57. Leiden: Brill.

CARNEADES

65

Grundmann, Thomas. 2003. Der Wahrheit auf der Spur. Eine Verteidigung des erkenntistheoretischen Externalismus. Paderborn: Mentis. Hacking, Ian. 1984. The Emergence of Probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hadot, Pierre. 1995. Philosophy as a Way of Life, translated by M. Chase. Oxford: Blackwell. Hankinson, Robert James. 1988. “Stoicism, Science and Divination,” Apeiron 21: 123–160. Inwood, Brad and Jaap Mansfeld (eds), 1997. Assent and Argument: Studies in Cicero’s Academic Books. Leiden: Brill. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 1986. Opinione e Scienza. Naples: Bibliopolis. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 2007. “L’assenso nella filosfia di Clitomaco; un problema di linguaggio?” In A. M. Ioppolo and D. Sedley (eds.), Pyrrhonists, Patricians, Platonizers. Hellenistic Philosophy in the period 155–86 BC, 225–267. Naples: Bibliopolis. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 2009. La testimonianza di Sesto Empirico sull’accademia scettica. Naples: Bibliopolis. Ioppolo, Anna Maria and David Sedley (eds.). 2007. Pyrrhonists, Patricians, Platonizers. Hellenistic Philosophy in the period 155–86 BC. Naples: Bibliopolis. Jeffrey, Richard. 1984. “De Finetti’s Probabilism,” Synthese 60: 73–90. Lévy, Carlos. 2010. “The Sceptical Academy: Decline and Afterlife.” In R. Bett The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 81–104. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Long, Arthur Anthony. 1967. “Carneades and the Stoic telos,” Phronesis 12: 59–90. Long, Arthur Anthony. 1990. “Scepticism about the Gods in Hellenistic Philosophy.” In M. Griffith and D. J. Mastronarde (eds.), Cabinet of the Muses, 279–91. Atlanta, GA: Scholars Press. Long, Arthur Anthony and David Sedley. 1987. The Hellenistic Philosophers, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mette, Hans Joachim. 1985. “Weitere Akademiker heute Von Lakydes bis zu Kleitomachos,” Lustrum 27: 39–148. Niiniluoto, Ilkka. 1984. “The Significance of Verisimilitude,” PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 2: 591–613. Obdrzalek, Suzanne. 2006. “Living in Doubt: Carneades’ Pithanon Reconsidered,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 31: 243–80. O’Keefe, Tim. 2005. Epicurus on Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Perin, Casey. 2006. “Academic Arguments for the Indiscernibility Thesis,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86: 493–517. Powell, Jonathan 2013. “The Embassy of the Three Philosophers to Rome in 155BC.” In C. Kremmydas and K. Tempest (eds.), Hellenistic Oratory: Continuity and Change, 219–248. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rackham, Harris. 1914. Cicero. De finibus bonorum et malorum. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Reid, James. 1885. M. Tulli Ciceronis Academica. London: Macmillan. Schofield, Malcolm. 1999. “Academic Epistemology.” In K. Algra, J. Barnes, J. Mansfeld, and M. Schofield (eds.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, 323–354. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

66

SKEPTICISM

Sedley, David. 1983 “The Motivation of Greek Skepticism.” In M. Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition, 9–29. Berkeley: University of California Press. Stough, Charlotte. 1969. Greek Skepticism. Berkeley: University of California Press. Striker, Gisela. 1996. “Sceptical Strategies.” In her Essays in Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics, 92–115. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Striker, Gisela. 2010. “Academics versus Pyrrhonists, Reconsidered.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 195–207. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tarrant, Harold. 1985. Scepticism or Platonism? The Philosophy of the Fourth Academy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Thorsrud, Harald. 2002. “Cicero on His Academic Predecessors: The Fallibilism of Arcesilaus and Carneades,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 40: 1–18. Thorsrud, Harald. 2010. “Arcesilaus and Carneades.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 58–80. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Thorsrud, Harald. 2012. “Radical and Mitigated Skepticism in Cicero’s Academica.” In W. Nicgorski (ed.), Cicero’s Practical Philosophy, 168–192. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press. Vogt, Katja. 2010. “Scepticism and Action.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 165–180. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Waterfield, Robin. 1989. “Truth and the Elenchus in Plato.” In P. Huby and G. Neal (eds.), The Criterion of Truth, 39–56. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press.

CHAPTER FIVE

Aenesidemus LUCA CASTAGNOLI

1 INTRODUCTION Unlike many other philosophers who flourished at the dawn of the Hellenistic age, Pyrrho did not found a school. Probably as a result of this and of his choice not to write, his philosophy, and the fascination that his personality exercised during his life, failed to outlive his pupil Timon and to produce any lasting legacy beyond the third century BCE.1 In line with their standard practice, some post-Hellenistic doxographers reconstructed an uninterrupted “succession” of philosophers seamlessly linking Pyrrho and Timon with the later Pyrrhonian tradition (see, e.g., DL IX 116). But on the basis of other sources (e.g., Aristocles apud Eusebius Praep. Evang. 14.18.29) scholars tend to agree that this is a largely fictional construction, and that the history of Pyrrhonism actually lapsed after Timon and resumed only in the first century BCE. That is the time when Aenesidemus appropriated, revived, and (in some measure to be determined) reinterpreted and developed Pyrrho’s ideas and attitudes, thus initiating a new brand of skepticism that he chose to baptize after him. The terms σκέψις (“skepticism”) and σκεπτικοί (“skeptics”) were not yet in currency at Aenesidemus’s time, nor do they seem to have been introduced in his works either. Later on, however, others, both within and outside the Pyrrhonian school, adopted these terms to refer to the whole tradition from Pyrrho onwards and (but only outside the Pyrrhonian school) to the skeptical phase of Plato’s Academy between the third and first centuries BCE, that is, from Arcesilaus to Philo of Larissa.2 As we will see, Aenesidemus’s Pyrrhonian revival set itself in overt opposition to what he took to be contemporary forms of positive (e.g., Stoic) and negative (e.g., Academic) “dogmatism.” According to the scholarly vulgata, Aenesidemus was himself a member of the Academy before defecting (but see Decleva Caizzi 1992 and Polito 2004), and perhaps founded his own school precisely in reaction to the unacceptable slackening of skepticism under the two leading first-century BCE Academics, Philo and Antiochus. Although we can establish with a certain degree of confidence that he lived in the first century BCE, virtually nothing else is certain about Aenesidemus’s dates and life, except for the fact that at some point he worked in Alexandria. According

68

SKEPTICISM

to Diogenes Laertius (DL IX 115), he was originally from Cnossos in Crete, but, according to Photius (Bibl. 212, 170a41), he was from Aigai in Asia Minor.

2  PYRRHO’S DISPUTED LEGACY Because of Aenesidemus’s appropriation of Pyrrho, who was by his time a rather obscure figure, as the “noble father” of his newly founded school, any reconstruction of his brand of skepticism should not dispense with the question of how exactly it was related to Pyrrho’s original outlook. But since antiquity Pyrrho has been an exegetical puzzle, and especially within the last three decades, since fully informed research on Pyrrho has become possible thanks to the publication of a complete collection of testimonies (Decleva Caizzi 1981), the number of rival reconstructions has proliferated. Of these, the two most plausible and influential, and also most directly relevant to our study of Aenesidemus, are (1) the “epistemological” and (2) the “metaphysical” interpretations: (1) According to the former interpretation, which used to be the standard one, Pyrrho was essentially a skeptic in the same mold as Sextus Empiricus (second century CE),3 our key source for later Pyrrhonism. Having witnessed the weakness and unreliability of our senses and reason, which had led others, before him, to despair of the possibility of human knowledge, Pyrrho concluded that the correct attitude toward reality was withholding assent from any belief and claim, whether positive or negative. While registering how things appear to us, he suspended his judgment on how things really are (for defenses of this traditional interpretation, see, e.g., Stopper 1983; Thorsrud 2009; and Castagnoli 2013). (2) According to the latter interpretation, Pyrrho was impressed by the metaphysical insight of some earlier thinkers, like the Eleatics and Plato, who had made stability and absoluteness the mark of reality and truth, relegating change and relativity to the realm of appearance and mere opinion. He thus concluded that things cannot really be in any of the ever-changing ways in which they manifest themselves to our senses and minds. Because of the pervasiveness of the phenomenon of variability, that conclusion amounted to a nihilist metaphysics according to which reality itself, beneath the appearances, is completely indeterminate, and we should thus deny that things really are how they appear to be (see, e.g., Long-Sedley 1987; Hankinson 1995; and Bett 2000).4 The deep sensitivity to the pervasiveness of conflict and disagreement was Pyrrho’s starting point on both interpretations, but his diagnoses of the phenomenon would have been different, and indeed incompatible, on either interpretation. Finally, the two interpretations agree in attributing to Pyrrho the view that a correct understanding of reality, or of our prospects of knowing it, will transform our lives for the better: both (1) suspension of judgment and (2) recognition of the intrinsic indeterminacy of reality were supposed to induce in us a desirable state of psychological “tranquility”

AENESIDEMUS

69

or “peace of mind” (ἀταραξία).5 This tranquility was presumably the result of relinquishing any positive commitment to the good and the truth, thus avoiding the anxiety, frustration, and fear related to the pursuit and preservation of them.

3  AENESIDEMUS: APPROACHES AND SOURCES While the number and divergence of the interpretations of Aenesidemus is not as wide as for Pyrrho, attempts to reconstruct his philosophy face analogous and related methodological issues. Unlike Pyrrho, Aenesidemus wrote several works, but none of them is preserved, and our later sources on Pyrrhonism, whether Pyrrhonian or hostile, tend either to be silent on Aenesidemus’s own distinctive position or to conflate it with Pyrrhonian skepticism as represented by later exponents like Sextus. The identification of original Aenesidemean fragments within our secondhand testimonia on his philosophy, or on Pyrrhonian philosophy as a whole, is often impossible or deeply conjectural. In light of the nature of the scant information available, it is difficult to establish the exact nature of the connection with Pyrrho’s earlier thought and to disentangle Aenesidemus’s position from the later Pyrrhonian (or “Neo-Pyrrhonian”) tradition which he initiated. Most interpreters have focused on the task of identifying and explaining those contributions that appear to be more distinctively Aenesidemean, especially on the basis of important evidence provided by Photius’s late (ninth century CE) summary of Aenesidemus’s Arguments of the Pyrrhonists (in eight books), but also by examining several passages scattered in book 9 of Diogenes Laertius’s Lives of Philosophers (see Barnes 1992); in excerpts of Aristocles of Messene’s On Philosophy, preserved by the father of the church Eusebius of Caesarea (see Chiesara 2001); in Sextus Empiricus’s extant corpus; and in Tertullian’s On the Soul.6

4  AENESIDEMUS AGAINST THE ACADEMICS From our sources a decidedly polemical focus against the Academics emerges clearly as an Aenesidemean trait: their position is singled out from the beginning of the first book of the Arguments of the Pyrrhonists as the polemical foil against which it is possible to define the correct Pyrrhonian attitude. The question of how the Academics and the Pyrrhonists differ would become a topos in the first and second centuries CE (see, e.g., Gellius, NA 9.5.6), but it was clearly put on the map already by Aenesidemus. At the end of the first book of his Outlines of Pyrrhonism, Sextus will also include various Academics in his long list of “neighboring” philosophies not to be conflated with Pyrrhonian skepticism (PH I 220–235). While Sextus’s discussion is extensive, its position does not however show the same level of urgency originally displayed by Aenesidemus. Even the choice of expounding his philosophy in writing poses Aenesidemus in contrast with some of the leading Hellenistic Academics, such as Arcesilaus and Carneades, who had adopted the Socratic stance of not writing (Polito 2014). The point should not be overstated, however, since that choice also marks an interesting discontinuity with Pyrrho himself.

70

SKEPTICISM

According to Aenesidemus, the Academics are barely disguised dogmatists: far from being aporetic and suspending judgment about everything, they have all kinds of opinions. They confidently affirm certain things—for example, when they admit that some views or arguments are more persuasive than others (clearly a reference to the Carneadean doctrine of the πιθανόν)7—and unambiguously deny others—for example, when they claim, against the Stoics, that “nothing can be apprehended,” that is, grasped with infallible certainty. Contemporary Academics, like Philo and Antiochus, sometimes are even in agreement with Stoic doctrines, and are essentially “Stoics fighting against Stoics.” Moreover, they are guilty of contradicting themselves: they give their assent to a number of things, while denying the possibility of knowledge as firm apprehension (κατάληψις) of reality (Bibl. 212.169b36–170a17). Aenesidemus’s polemics against the Academy might have had not only a clear philosophical rationale, but also “political” roots: as we have seen, it is possible that Aenesidemus was himself an Academic renegade, and certainly he placed his school as a form of genuine anti-dogmatism in competition with it (see Decleva Caizzi 1992; Mansfeld 1995). Aenesidemus’s anti-Academic spin might also be reflected in his predilection for the Socratic/Platonic language of aporia to describe the Pyrrhonian stance, and in the quasi-Socratic flavor (cf. Plato, Apol. 21b4–5) of his claim that “he who philosophizes after Pyrrho is happy not only in general but also, and especially, in the wisdom of knowing that he has no firm cognition of anything,” as reported by Photius (Bibl. 212.169b28–29).8 We are also informed that Aenesidemus took a position on whether Plato was a skeptic, something which had become a focus of controversy within the late Hellenistic Academy. Unfortunately, textual corruption in our source (PH I 222) makes that position impossible to determine with full certainty, but it seems more likely that Aenesidemus, like Sextus after him, rejected the skeptical credentials that some Academics had attributed to the founder of their school (Spinelli 2000).

5  AENESIDEMUS’S “HERACLITEANISM” Aenesidemus’s so-called Heracliteanism is another distinctive, and more puzzling, aspect of his thought, and as such has attracted ample scholarly attention (in recent years, Polito 2004; Pérez-Jean 2005; and Schofield 2007). Sextus reports, reproachfully, that “Aenesidemus and his followers said that the skeptical way is a path which leads to Heraclitean philosophy, since the idea that contraries appear to hold of the same thing leads to the idea that they actually hold of it” (PH I 210). In other words, the Pyrrhonian epistemological awareness of the pervasiveness of conflicting appearances would lead, somehow, to the Heraclitean metaphysical tenet of the unity of opposites. On a few occasions Sextus and other sources also mysteriously attribute dogmatic views—for example, about the soul or time—to “Aenesidemus κατά Heraclitus” (Aenesidemus “citing Heraclitus”? Aenesidemus “in accordance with Heraclitus,” that is, following him? Aenesidemus “in his Heraclitean mode”?). Although these testimonies have been taken by some scholars to attest to the existence of an early or late Heraclitean phase in Aenesidemus’s thought, this reading has been convincingly shown by others to be implausible. Aenesidemus’s

AENESIDEMUS

71

interest in Heraclitus is more likely to have been instrumental in his dialectic with contemporary philosophical rivals: in particular, we know that the Stoics, who are with the Academics one of Aenesidemus’s primary targets, had appropriated Heraclitus as a precursor, and Aenesidemus could have engaged in Heraclitean exegesis to show that the Stoic interpretation of Heraclitus was tendentious, and that un-Stoic consequences actually followed from his doctrines. The exegesis might have gone as far as to claim that, if anything, Heracliteanism had more affinities with Pyrrhonism than with Stoicism—for example, in the measure in which the Pyrrhonian emphasis on the all-pervasive existence of conflicting appearances (and possibly on the undecidability of conflict: see below) is logically prior to, and explanatory of, the Heraclitean postulation of the unity of opposites (see Polito 2004).

6  AENESIDEMUS’S “MODES” OF SUSPENSION OF JUDGMENT The “invention” or compilation of the ten “modes” (τρόποι) of suspension of judgment (ἐποχή),9 which form the backbone of the Pyrrhonian argumentative strategies along with the “five modes” later introduced by Agrippa, is Aenesidemus’s most celebrated contribution to the history of Western skepticism (see, e.g., Striker 1983; Annas and Barnes 1985). A large body of conflicting appearances, observations, beliefs, and arguments was collected by Aenesidemus and arranged into ten broad groups. The material often derived from the previous philosophical tradition, but Aenesidemus systematized its collection and put it to a specific use within his skeptical project (for the scholarly controversy surrounding this use, see below). Following the order in which the modes appear in Sextus’s report (PH I 35–163), things appear in different ways relative to (1) different animals: for example, sea water is unpleasant and poisonous for human beings, but not for sea fish; (2) different human beings: for example, most human beings die if they drink hemlock, but some do not; (3) different sense organs: for example, perfume is pleasant to smell, unpleasant to taste; (4) different circumstances: for example, honey tastes sweet to the healthy, bitter to the sick; (5) different positions, distances, and places: for example, the same tower will appear round from far off, square from nearby; (6) different mixtures: for example, smells are pungent in the warm and humid air of a bath-house, faint in the cold air outside; (7) different quantities and constitutions: for example, a single grain of sand feels rough to the touch, but as part of a heap grains of sand feel smooth; (8) relativity: the mode, not exemplified, can be seen as a “super-mode” encompassing all the others;

72

SKEPTICISM

(9) different frequencies of experience: for example, the sun is not striking because we see it daily, while a comet appears impressive because it is observed only very rarely; (10) different ways of life, customs, laws, mythical beliefs, and philosophical views: for example, some people believe that the soul is immortal, some believe that it is mortal. The modes are presented in a slightly different way, number, and order in other reports by Philo of Alexandria (On Drunkenness 169–202), Aristocles of Messene (Praep. Evang. 14.18.11), and Diogenes Laertius (DL IX 78–88).

7  AENESIDEMUS’S MODES AGAINST CAUSAL EXPLANATIONS Aenesidemus argued extensively against dogmatic theories of causation and introduced eight “causal modes” specifically tailored to expose the weakness and inconclusiveness of any possible causal explanation (αἰτιολογία) devised by the dogmatists (Barnes 1983; Hankinson 1999). According to Sextus’s presentation of these modes (PH I 180–185), a causal explanation can be rejected on the grounds that (1) it is not itself evident and is not corroborated by agreed-upon evidence; (2) it is arbitrarily selected from a number of possible explanations available; (3) it is too simple to account for the order and complexity of the explanandum; (4) it extends without warranty to the non-evident what has been observed as evident; (5) it is based on “hypotheses,” that is principles or assumptions, which are not universally agreed upon; (6) it fails to take into due account opposite hypotheses; (7) it is incompatible with the hypotheses of its own proponents; (8) it is no less puzzling than the explanandum.

8  AENESIDEMUS AS A SEXTAN-STYLE SKEPTIC Apart from the distinctive views and contributions which can be attributed directly to Aenesidemus in the four areas mentioned above, traditionally interpreters have tended to presuppose that we should credit Aenesidemus with essentially the same form of skepticism as that presented in detail in Sextus Empiricus’s extant corpus. From the limited and second-hand evidence available in our sources, we know that Aenesidemus put forward a battery of arguments against all the main theories of dogmatic schools, systematically, along the lines of the standard Hellenistic division of philosophical discourse into physics, logic, and ethics, just as Sextus would later do (although in a different order). According to Photius (212.170b3–36), for example, in books 2 to 8 of his Arguments of the Pyrrhonists, Aenesidemus attacked dogmatic

AENESIDEMUS

73

theories concerning first principles, passions, change, generation and corruption, thought, sensation and their properties (i.e., presumably, truth and falsehood), signs, nature, the world, gods, causal explanations (see above), what is good and bad, what is choiceworthy and to be avoided, virtue, happiness, and the goal of life. The assimilation of Aenesidemus’s skepticism with Sextus’s would also seem to be justified by those testimonies according to which Aenesidemus “determined absolutely nothing, not even this very claim, that nothing is determined” (Bibl. 212.170a11–12). Moreover, it seems that Aenesidemus was aware of the problem of self-refutation which the Pyrrhonian pronouncements risk incurring, a problem later addressed extensively by Sextus, when he explained that the Pyrrhonists utter the apparently assertoric formula “Nothing is determined” simply “because [they] have no other means of blurting out what [they] have in mind” (Bibl. 212.170a12–14). On this standard interpretation, Aenesidemus suspended judgment about everything. Suspension of judgment resulted from the realization that “there is no firm basis of cognition,” presumably as the result of Aenesidemus’s “collection of appearances or thoughts, of any kind,” which are “brought into confrontation with each other and, when compared, are found to present much disparity (ἀνωμαλίαν) and confusion (ταραχήν)” (DL IX 78), clearly a reference to the ten modes. From ἐποχή a happy state of tranquility will follow “like a shadow.” According to Aristocles’s report at Praep. Evang. 14.18.4, Aenesidemus somehow identified this state as “pleasure” (ἡδονή), but this need not be taken as a sign that he espoused a form of philosophical hedonism over and above the pursuit of ἀταραξία itself. That various forms of skepticism and other similarly unorthodox philosophical stances should lead to ἀπραξία (“inaction”), in the form of either vegetable-style paralysis or random, crazy, or self-destructive behavior, was a standard criticism in antiquity (see Vogt 2010). The targets of such criticism devised a variety of strategies to defend the “livability” of their position. Aenesidemus made “appearances” (φαινόμενα) the Pyrrhonists’ “criterion of action”: while suspending judgment on whether things are as they appear to be, they noncommittally “went along with” appearances in their dayby-day life, thus living an outwardly ordinary existence despite their alternative frame of mind (PH I 21–24). It is probable that for Aenesidemus the scope of appearances was broad and included cultural conventions and social norms (DL IX 107–108), just as for Sextus. Addressing criticism leveled at his teacher, Timon had claimed that Pyrrho “did not depart from normal practice” (DL IX 105), in contrast with several ancient anecdotes which depict Pyrrho’s behavior as wildly eccentric, unattractively non-humane, and dangerously erratic. Aenesidemus too offered a “normalizing” picture of Pyrrho, and maintained that “although he practiced philosophy on the principles of suspension of judgment, [Pyrrho] did not act carelessly in the details of daily life” (DL IX 62), because he “determined nothing dogmatically on account of opposite arguments, but followed appearances instead” (DL IX 106). A typical trait of late Hellenistic and late-antique philosophy is that formulating and clarifying one’s philosophical position was part and parcel of offering the correct interpretation and explication of the thought of the founders of the tradition or school to which one declared one’s allegiance. Aenesidemus was no exception, although in his case the interpretation could not be, of course, a matter of textual exegesis.

74

SKEPTICISM

No source reports Aenesidemus’s reasons for maintaining that the conflict of appearances, views, and reasons should induce us to apply the skeptical formula “no more” (οὐ μᾶλλον) to everything, and produce a mental state of ἐποχή.10 The idea that the conflict is not decidable (or, at least, has not been decided) because of the “equipollence” (ἰσοσθένεια), that is, the equal persuasive force, of the opposites is pivotal in Sextus’s account (PH I 8–10) and has traditionally been imported into the equation for Aenesidemus, too: (1) x appears F relative to S.

[Material provided by the ten modes.]

(2) x appears F* relative to R.

[Material provided by the ten modes.]

(3) We cannot prefer S and F to R and F*, or vice versa, because of equipollence. (4) We can neither affirm nor deny, neither believe nor disbelieve, that x is F, or that x is F* (i.e., we suspend judgment): x is no more F/F* than it is not.11

9  AENESIDEMUS AS A NEGATIVE OR “APORETIC” SKEPTIC The Sextan-style interpretation of Aenesidemus sketched above is by no means the only one on the market. It would be impossible to present here all of the available interpretations. I will focus on an alternative reconstruction of Aenesidemus’s outlook that has recently gained currency. It rejects the assumption that what we know from Sextus can be safely used to fill the gaps in our picture of Aenesidemus’s original Pyrrhonism. Woodruff (1988) and Bett (2000: 189–222), the two most notable supporters of this approach, have maintained that unprejudiced reassessment of our evidence will reveal that Aenesidemus’s brand of Pyrrhonism differed substantially from Sextus’s. Aenesidemus’s arguments did not aim to induce ἐποχή on the basis of the undecidable equipollence of conflicting appearances and arguments; they were meant to establish, for any object x and predicate F, the negative conclusion that x is not really or “by nature” F, on the basis of an “invariability condition” ultimately equivalent to the one endorsed by Pyrrho, according to some supporters of the metaphysical interpretation (see Section 2 above), and having the same Platonic pedigree: For an object to be a certain definite way “by nature,” it should be and appear that way invariably or without qualifications.12 Hence, something that manifests itself as F only to some people (but not to others), or only in some circumstances (but not in others), or only in certain respects (but not in others), cannot be F “by nature.” In virtue of this principle, and of the widespread conflict and variability catalogued in the ten modes, Aenesidemus concluded that not only should we refrain from making positive dogmatic claims determining how things are, but we should deny that anything really is any particular way: (1) x appears F relative to S.

[Material provided by the ten modes]

(2) x appears F* relative to R.

[Material provided by the ten modes]

AENESIDEMUS

75

(3) Unless x appears invariably F (F*), x cannot be F (F*) “by nature.” [Invariability condition] (4) x is “by nature” neither F nor F*. On this reading, Aenesidemus’s negative or “aporetic” conclusions about the nature of things had as their counterpart a form of phenomenal relativism: he allowed relativized claims such as “x is F at time t,” “x is F for y,” or “x is F in circumstances C,” which, exactly because relative (or “ambiguous”), do not purport to determine the intrinsic, essential nature of things (Bibl. 212.169b38–170a11). Such claims would have qualified in Aenesidemus’s own terms as assertions about appearances and would have been allowed as objects of non-dogmatic belief and, perhaps, even (a mundane form) of knowledge, and not only as a practical criterion.13 The revisionary interpretation promoted by Woodruff and Bett was prompted by the observation that, in several reports of Pyrrhonian views and arguments which either are directly attributed to Aenesidemus or could have an Aenesideman pedigree (e.g., Sextus’s Against the Ethicists: see Bett 1997), we often find unqualified negative conclusions (e.g., signs do not exist at all, the various goals of life celebrated by dogmatic philosophers do not exist [Bibl. 212.170b12–14], nothing is good or bad by nature [AM XI 71]) and apparent formulations and uses of the invariability condition.14 These occurrences are insufficient, however, to establish conclusively that there must have been a form of Aenesidemean “aporetic” Pyrrhonism essentially distinct from Sextan “ephectic” (i.e., suspensive) Pyrrhonism. In Sextus’s works there are plenty of cases in which, although the context unequivocally shows that inducing ἐποχή on the basis of the equipollence is the goal, Sextus limits himself to providing only evidence and arguments for the negative conclusion that something is not the case or does not exist. This is typically explained by the fact that the equipollent positive evidence and arguments require no rehearsing, since they represent the default commonsense or philosophical position. That sources like Photius could have misinterpreted and misrepresented these typical Pyrrhonian strategies is not implausible; after all, Photius himself also attributes to Aenesidemus views to the effect that truths, causes, affections, motion, generation, destruction, nature, the world, gods, good, and bad are beyond our grasp or impossible to know. If taken as the ultimate conclusions of Aenesidemus’s arguments, these views would clearly be different from, and possibly inconsistent with, the negative conclusions of “aporetic” Pyrrhonism (although still unacceptable from the point of view of Sextan Pyrrhonism) and would be surprisingly at odds with Aenesidemus’s criticism of the Academics’ inapprehensibility conclusion.15 As for the invariability condition, we can conjecture that Aenesidemus used it only dialectically, to establish a negative antidogmatic conclusion starting from a dogmatic principle to which the Pyrrhonists themselves had no commitment, following, again, an argumentative trope pervasive in later Pyrrhonism (Thorsrud 2009: 102–122; Hankinson 2010).16 If not imposed by our evidence, is the revisionary reading of Aenesidemus at least consistent with it? Something especially problematic to account for on this reading is Aenesidemus’s vocal attitude toward contemporary Academics: how could he criticize Plato’s heirs for making negative and positive claims, and then

76

SKEPTICISM

adopt a position which, on the basis of positive adherence to a dogmatic principle with a clear Platonic pedigree, committed him to countless negative conclusions? One could also object that stressing Aenesidemus’s relativistic tendencies is difficult to reconcile with the therapeutic vocation of Pyrrhonism as a route to ἀταραξία, explicitly attested for Pyrrho and Sextus. If Pyrrhonian arguments conclude that nothing is good or bad in its own nature, while admitting that things can be correctly judged to be good or bad in relation to certain individuals, at certain times, and in certain circumstances, then the disturbing psychological effects of the dogmatic belief that certain things are good or bad “by nature” will be replaced by the no less disturbing effects of the Pyrrhonian belief that certain things are good or bad for me, at this time, and in my present circumstances. At the same time, however, a different objection can be leveled against Sextus’s own adoption of suspension of judgment as a route to ἀταραξία: the awareness of the possibility that there are truths about what is good and bad, which can in principle be known but which we have failed to grasp so far, could be thought to engender a psychological state of constant anxiety and fear rather than ἀταραξία (see Striker 1990).

10 CONCLUSION Any satisfactory interpretation of Aenesidemus must take into account the individual and cumulative force of arguments focusing on the terminology and logic of specific passages, on the nature and reliability of the relevant sources, on issues of intrinsic philosophical consistency, and on how to account for the dialectical relationship between Aenesidemus and his philosophical sources and targets. Hopefully, the recent publication of the first commented edition of Aenesidemus’s testimonia (Polito 2014) will give fresh impetus to the re-examination of such arguments and their relative weight. However, no satisfactory reconstruction of Aenesidemus’s thought can sidestep the additional question whether and how it can make sense of its pivotal position within the Pyrrhonian tradition as a whole. After all, Aenesidemus adopted Pyrrho as the noble father of his philosophy and was seen by later Pyrrhonists like Sextus as a bona fide representative of the “Pyrrhonian way.” As I have explained, the question is complicated, however, by the fact that Pyrrho’s outlook is itself subject to deep scholarly controversy, and thus our equation contains two variables. While Pyrrho is never attacked as a skeptic in pre-Aenesidemean sources, this argument from silence appears less urgent than the objection that, on the metaphysical interpretation, Pyrrho would seem to have little in common with what is supposed to be his tradition as represented to us by Sextus. For those who assume that Aenesidemus was himself a Sextan-style skeptic, the challenge would then be to explain why he appropriated the obscure metaphysician Pyrrho in the first place. Coordinating the metaphysical Pyrrho with the “aporetic” Aenesidemus would appear to offer an easy way out of the impasse: their philosophical core is essentially identical, despite the fact that the consequence of the “invariability condition” is cashed out slightly differently, in the former as a claim of indeterminacy of reality, in the latter as a series of definite denials concerning the nature of things. But while

AENESIDEMUS

77

this exegetical move would make Aenesidemus’s adoption of Pyrrho as a figurehead easy to explain, the transition from Aenesidemus to Sextus would turn out to look problematic. According to Bett (2000), it originated from Sextus’s decision to drop Aenesidemus’s invariability condition. It is clear why a Sextan-style Pyrrhonist should have rejected as intolerably dogmatic that condition and its consequences: it is harder to imagine how he could still have thought to belong to the same school as someone who had made that condition the foundation of his philosophy. One would expect that the “aporetic” Aenesidemus should have deserved a place in the list of philosophers whom Sextus discards as bona fide skeptics (this consideration applies, of course, to the metaphysical Pyrrho as well). Was Sextus hypocritical, saving Aenesidemus (and Pyrrho) from well-deserved bashing? The aporetic reading also requires us to postulate that Aenesidemus understood and used most of the key Pyrrhonian concepts and terminology differently from Sextus. Έποχή cannot, on that reading, be a “standstill of the intellect, owing to which we neither deny nor affirm anything” (PH I 10, emphasis added). Consequently, all the skeptical slogans must carry different meanings than in Sextus (Bett 2000: 198–199). As we have seen, the concept of equipollence would have been extraneous to Aenesidemus’s strategy (just as to Pyrrho’s on the metaphysical reading), but the suggestion that this key concept might have been such a late addition is perplexing and possibly contradicted by the Anonymous commentary on Plato’s Theaetetus (61.26–30), whose dating is uncertain, but perhaps not much later than Aenesidemus. Moreover, as Polito (2014) suggests, the reference to the “equal persuasiveness” of the opposed positions at DL IX 79 might be part of the report of Aenesidemus’s account of the Pyrrhonian logos which begins at DL IX 78. I have also explained how the ten modes would themselves have had different functions and conclusions in Aenesidemus and Sextus according to the revisionary interpretation of the former. It has been suggested that the “aporetic” reading of Aenesidemus dovetails neatly with the moderate or “urbane” reading (see Burnyeat and Frede 1997) of the scope of Sextus’s skepticism (Hankinson 2010: 110), but this too is only partially correct. For the two agree on the target of the skeptical arguments, that is, dogmatic declarations about the non-evident nature of things, but not on the attitude adopted toward them: the “aporetic” Aenesidemus resolutely “refutes” the claim that x is F by nature, while the “urbane” Sextus suspends judgment on the very same claim. From this point of view, the label σκεπτικός (literally, “inquirer”), and Sextus’s emphasis on the fact that Pyrrhonism is an open-ended inquiry after the truth, which has not been shown to be inexistent or ungraspable by Pyrrhonian argument (see, e.g., PH I 1–4), would have also been difficult to retroject onto Aenesidemus. That such radical changes may have occurred at some point after Aenesidemus, in the later Pyrrhonian tradition preceding Sextus, despite our lack of any ancient record of this doctrinal earthquake, is not impossible but appears at first sight implausible. Someone might object that this impression is the result of our weighing plausibility anachronistically, on the basis of our own standards and expectations. The ancients could be much more flexible than we tend to be in their way of appropriating and interpreting philosophical antecedents, emphasizing continuity,

78

SKEPTICISM

and passing over differences within those traditions they constructed, whether for themselves or others. The shared core insight that happiness, as tranquility, will come from abandoning any positive belief (and not—as many other philosophers had suggested—from knowledge of reality) might be just enough to explain why Aenesidemus looked back at Pyrrho, and Sextus was comfortable in calling himself a “Pyrrhonist,” even if we decided that Sextus’s route to the abandonment of belief was very different from that traveled by Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, or both. But before we decide to stretch ourselves in such a way, and to reach for the very boundaries of plausible exegesis, we will need extremely compelling reasons to accept that this is the best way of making sense of the extant evidence on Aenesidemus (and Pyrrho) in its own right. It is questionable whether revisionary interpretations have succeeded in providing such reasons.

NOTES 1. On Pyrrho and Timon, see Casey Perin’s chapter in this book. 2. On the skeptical phase of the Academy, see the chapters in this book on Arcesilaus, Carneades, Philo, and Cicero. 3. On Sextus Empiricus, see chapter 10 of this book. 4. For discussion of these two interpretations, see chapter 2 of this book. 5. For the influence of the Democritean tradition on Pyrrho’s adoption of ἀταραξία as a desirable goal, see Warren (2002). 6. For very useful discussion of the nature and reliability of all these sources, see Polito (2014). 7. See Harald Thorsrud’s discussion of this topic in chapter 4. 8. On the question whether this and other pronouncements by Aenesidemus show awareness of the dangers of self-refutation, see below and Castagnoli (2010: 329–352). 9. The term ἐποχή, which probably had never been used by Pyrrho, was central in Academic skepticism. 10. For the ancient philosophical history of the formula οὐ μᾶλλον, see De Lacy (1958). 11. For a different, unorthodox interpretation of the logic of Sextus’s use of the Aenesidemean tropes, see Morison (2011). 12. This principle could also be connected to Aenesidemus’s “Heraclitean” definition of the true as that which appears to all in common at AM VIII 8. 13. Some narrower kind of “phenomenalism” restricted to perception has been associated by some (e.g., Polito 2007) with a possible influence of medical empiricism upon the development of Aenesidemus’s skepticism: the ancient reconstruction of the whole succession of Pyrrhonists conjoining Timon to Sextus’s pupil, Saturninus, however fanciful, is interesting in that it includes several Empiricist doctors and makes the Empiricist Heraclides of Tarentum Aenesidemus’s teacher. On medical Empiricism, see Allen (1993) and chapter 8 in this book.

AENESIDEMUS

79

14. E.g. AM VIII 8: “Aenesidemus says that . . . the things that appear in common to everyone are true, while the ones not like this are false”; XI 69–71: “If there is anything good by nature, this is good in relation to all men, and if there is anything evil by nature, that is evil in relation to all.” 15. Some interpreters (e.g., Stough 1969; Hankinson 1995: 120–128; and Polito 2004) have suggested that from phenomenal variability Aenesidemus did draw the conclusion that the underlying nature of things is beyond our grasp. 16. For a different interpretation, which attributes to Aenesidemus some qualified commitment to a version of the condition, but relativized to ordinary experience, see Polito (2004: 40–101).

REFERENCES Allen, James. 1993. “Pyrrhonism and Medical Empiricism.” In W. Haase (ed.), Aufstieg und Niedergang der Römischen Welt II 37.1, 646–690. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter. Annas, Julia and Jonathan Barnes. 1985. The Modes of Scepticism: Ancient Texts and Modern Interpretations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Barnes, Jonathan. 1983. “Ancient Skepticism and Causation.” In M. Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition, 149–203. Berkeley: University of California Press. Barnes, Jonathan. 1992. “Diogenes Laertius IX 61–116: The Philosophy of Pyrrhonism.” In W. Haase (ed.), Aufstieg und Niedergang der Römischen Welt II, 36.6, 4241–4301. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter. Bett, Richard. 1997. Sextus Empiricus: Against the Ethicists. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bett, Richard. 2000. Pyrrho, His Antecedents, and His Legacy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bett, Richard (ed.). 2010. The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Burnyeat, Myles and Michael Frede (eds.) 1997. The Original Sceptics. Indianapolis: Hackett. Castagnoli, Luca. 2010. Ancient Self-Refutation: The Logic and History of the Self-Refutation Argument from Democritus to Augustine. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Castagnoli, Luca. 2013. “Early Pyrrhonism: Pyrrho to Aenesidemus.” In F. Sheffield and J. Warren (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Ancient Philosophy, 496–510. London and New York: Routledge. Chiesara, Maria Lorenza. 2001. Aristocles of Messene. Testimonia and Fragments. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Decleva Caizzi, Fernanda. 1981. Pirrone: Testimonianze. Napoli: Bibliopolis. Decleva Caizzi, Fernanda. 1992. “Aenesidemus and the Academy,” Classical Quarterly 42: 176–189. De Lacy, Phillip. 1958. “οὐ μᾶλλον and the Antecedents of Ancient Scepticism,” Phronesis 3: 59–71. Hankinson, Robert. 1995. The Sceptics. London and New York: Routledge. Hankinson, Robert. 1999. Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

80

SKEPTICISM

Hankinson, Robert. 2010. “Aenesidemus and the Rebirth of Pyrrhonism.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 105–119. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Long, Anthony and David Sedley. 1987. The Hellenistic Philosophers. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mansfeld, Jaap. 1995. “Aenesidemus and the Academics.” In L. Ayres (ed.), The Passionate Intellect: Essays on the Transformation of Classical Tradition, 235–248. New Brunswick, NJ and London: Transaction Publishers. Morison, Benjamin. 2011. “The Logical Structure of the Sceptic’s Opposition,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 40: 265–295. Pérez-Jean, Brigitte. 2005. Dogmatisme et scepticisme: L’héraclitisme d’Énésidème. Lille: Septentrion. Polito, Roberto. 2004. The Sceptical Road: Aenesidemus’ Appropriation of Heraclitus. Leiden and Boston: Brill. Polito, Roberto. 2007. “Was Skepticism a Philosophy? Reception, Self-Definition, Internal Conflicts,” Classical Philology 102: 333–362. Polito, Roberto. 2014. Aenesidemus of Cnossus: Testimonia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Schofield, Malcolm. 2007. “Aenesidemus: Pyrrhonist and Heraclitean.” In A. M. Ioppolo and D. Sedley (eds.), Pyrrhonists, Patricians and Platonizers: Hellenistic Philosophy in the Period 155–86 BC, 271–338. Naples: Bibliopolis. Spinelli, Emidio. 2000. “Sextus Empiricus, the Neighbouring Philosophies and the Sceptical Tradition.” In J. Sihvola (eds.), Ancient Scepticism and the Sceptical Tradition (Acta Philosophica Fennica 66), 35–61. Helsinki: The Philosophical Society of Finland. Stopper, Malachi Rudolph. 1983. “Schizzi Pirroniani,” Phronesis 28: 265–297. Striker, Gisela. 1983. “The Ten Tropes of Aenesidemus.” In M. Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition, 95–115. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Striker, Gisela. 1990. “Ataraxia: Happiness as Tranquillity,” The Monist 73: 97–110. Thorsrud, Harald. 2009. Ancient Scepticism. Durham: Acumen. Vogt, Katja Maria. 2010. “Scepticism and Action.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 165–180. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Warren, James. 2002. Epicurus and Democritean Ethics: An Archaeology of Ataraxia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Woodruff, Paul. 1988. “Aporetic Pyrrhonism,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 6: 139–168.

CHAPTER SIX

Philo of Larissa HAROLD TARRANT

1  LIFE AND EVIDENCE Philo of Larissa was an adherent of the so-called New Academy, that is, one of those who saw themselves as philosophizing in the tradition of Arcesilaus as well as of Plato. Born between 159 and 153 BCE,1 he had apparently developed an interest in current Academic philosophy while still in his native town and set off to study at the Academy in Athens at the age of about twenty-four. His mentor for fourteen years was Clitomachus, apparently the strictest of the followers of Carneades, whose arguments against the criterion of knowledge were the most comprehensive and wide-ranging. While there is no evidence that the terms “skeptic” and “dogmatic,” so familiar from Sextus Empiricus, were yet in regular philosophical use, it is clearly appropriate for us to regard the Academy under which Philo had studied, and his teacher Clitomachus, as “skeptical” in important ways—as deserving of that description as any school up until that time. Philo became the scholarch (Head) himself on the death of Clitomachus in 110/109 BCE, and the evidence (Numenius fr. 29 = T. XXIII) suggests that there was at first little change in the official activities or stance of the school. It is therefore generally agreed among his interpreters that in the first instance Philo continued to philosophize in a manner compatible with his Carneadean heritage as normally interpreted. Ultimately, however, after the dispersal of the school in 88 BCE following the second Mithridatic War, Philo left for Rome where he already had admirers, and may have lived there for four to five years before his death. At any rate, soon after his arrival there, he wrote his two so-called Roman Books, which rapidly provoked considerable controversy among others who had studied with his school.2 That controversy is an important part of the background of Cicero’s Academica and, through Cicero, of Augustine’s work Against the Academics. It is important to realize that virtually the whole of the evidence for Philo is colored by this controversy, and that there are almost no neutral reports. Cicero himself was writing a dialogue, and in extant parts of it he may represent himself as speaking either for Philo or for the traditional Academic position attributed to Carneades; the anti-skeptical position is defended by his character Lucullus in the first version of the work (Academica Priora or Lucullus) and by Varro in a revised

82

SKEPTICISM

version (Academica Posteriora).3 The controversy was led by Antiochus of Ascalon, a former pupil of Philo who had begun to attract pupils of his own while the Academy still functioned at Athens, and who then claimed to teach the doctrines of the Old Academy, and particularly of Xenocrates and Polemo, the third and fourth scholarchs, respectively.4

2  ACADEMIC FREEDOM The Old Academy had been quite open about offering positive teaching and embracing doctrine, though given the variety of doctrine that one might claim to trace in Plato, it is not surprising that the early Academy seems to have been very flexible in its beliefs. Indeed, Cicero (Acad. II 7–9), in offering his own account of continuing Academic ideology, does not give a picture of a system of tenets, but of the acknowledgment that much is unclear and that human beings are consequently fallible, leading to the habit of giving every point of view a hearing and arguing both for and against positions. Philosophy’s ultimate goal will still be the truth or the closest possible approximation to it (Acad. II 7), but one that gives them the freedom to judge what is “probable” without fear that their judgments will be seen as involving disloyalty to their teacher and their school (Acad. II 8). While this position is not openly attributed to Philo, Cicero had been strongly influenced by his studies with Philo after he had come to Rome (Brutus 306 = T. II), and it would be surprising if the picture had differed greatly from that which Philo had painted when in Rome.5 It is vital to note two things in this account. First, the Academic is given the freedom to make judgments that appear to conflict with his loyalties to his school or to his personal teacher. Much is made by Philo’s enemies of his change(s) of stance, and disloyalty to what they saw as the Academic tradition (Acad. II 11–12 = T. XXIX, Acad. II 18 = XXVII). It is here clear that his own picture of the Academic tradition imposes no obligation of philosophical loyalty, disloyalty involving anything that approached a school doctrine. No doubt it would not excuse him if he were guilty of historical disloyalty involving the willful misrepresentation of earlier Academic positions, but it did excuse deviations from those positions. The Academy’s identity was determined by its culture of philosophic investigation, not by anything to be believed or provisionally accepted. Secondly, the Academic is expected to search without obstinacy for what can be maintained with most consistency (constantissime, Acad. II 9). It looks almost as if there is a kind of criterion for tentative assent being proposed here, whether it concerns the agreement of the claims with the facts, agreement among the claims themselves, or the wider agreement of trustworthy human beings. We know that the term “probable” here refers to the Greek πιθανόν that Carneades had employed as his basis for choice of action, that is, rather to what is capable of being believed or approved rather than to anything whose probability could be calculated objectively. A link between the Carneadean criterion and consistency may be intended, but if so the focus has shifted from trying to find single “presentations” (φαντασίαι) that have such startling clarity that they must be totally reliable, and toward having

PHILO OF LARISSA

83

presentations that cohere with all other pertinent presentations that may occur either to the individual or indeed to any human being who examines the relevant considerations objectively. Has the single cognitive act lost its overriding importance in epistemology at this time? Can systems of knowledge be built on aggregations of cognitive experiences that are legitimately convincing when taken together, but not wholly convincing when taken singly?

3  PHILO’S FINAL EPISTEMOLOGY At this point, we should consider the position that is attributed to Philo regarding the Stoic criterion of truth, the “cognitive presentation” (καταληπτικὴ φαντασία). Sextus Empiricus (PH I 235 = T XXVIII) tells us that Philo’s adherents “say that things are non-graspable as regards the Stoic criterion, but graspable as regards the nature of things themselves.” It seems that the established New Academic theme that things were non-graspable (ἀκαταληψία) was being blamed not upon nature itself but upon a Stoic requirement that was so rigorous that no cognitive act could conform with it. Human beings simply do not have cognitive presentations such that there could not be another that was identical in all respects except insofar as it did not correctly present what had given rise to it. Since Sextus does not mention human beings here, it seems that Philo’s intention was to blame the lack of such presentations on the Stoics, who devised such a requirement, rather than on serious cognitive incapacity on the part of human beings in general.6 As if to confirm this, Sextus goes on to accuse Antiochus of introducing Stoic doctrine into the Academy, and Cicero presents the whole epistemological debate between Philo and Antiochus as being centered on the need for a criterion of truth such as the Stoics had conceived it, tracing accordingly the New Academic endeavor to Arcesilaus’s genuine problems with Zeno’s concept of a cognitive presentation (Acad. I 44). Sextus does not seek to limit his report to Philo’s final years in Rome, and taken together with what he had just said about the multiplicity of Academic positions, with Philo allegedly introducing a Fourth Academy and Antiochus a Fifth (PH I 220 = T V), it seems clear that he thought this position on the Stoic criterion had been shared by Philo’s Academic colleague Charmadas, who died three years before Philo came to Rome. Brittain agrees that this is what Sextus thought but claims that “he must have been mistaken” (2001: 54), since it does not agree with Brittain’s view of three clearly delineated phases of Philo’s thought. Yet Charmadas’s name here needs some explanation, for he is being treated as if he were virtually a coscholarch; perhaps it indicates that Philo had himself controversially made appeal to Charmadas, who as a former pupil of Carneades might have commanded greater authority regarding Academic traditions. In that case, it seems strange that Cicero did not give any hint that Charmadas had anticipated Philo’s position, except in one rather important respect. There have been various explanations of how the Roman Books had been doctrinally innovative. All of them face the difficulties that neither version of Cicero’s Academica has survived complete, the position of Philo is not explained in the extant parts, and Cicero himself seems to have found it unconvincing.

84

SKEPTICISM

Tarrant (1981 and 1985) was perhaps over-reliant on Numenius’s evidence (fr. 28 = T XXIII), where it was claimed that Philo was swayed “by the agreement and perspicuity of our experiences,” suspecting that Philo found little reason to doubt the evidence of the senses (and ultimately of empirically derived concepts), even if attempts to prove what is perspicuous were doomed to fail.7 Striker (1997: 274) appears uncertain that Philo ever specified how cognition might be possible without the existence of a cognitive presentation. She considers the possibility that Philo had claimed Carneades’s maximally probable presentations, which had been thoroughly tested, were enough to justify the inference to a proposition’s truth; but this is rejected in favor of the view that Philo distinguished, in his own mind at least, between (i) the belief that one has a reliable sensory indication that p (which he could allow) and (ii) the inference from that presentation that p is true (which he would have resisted). This would have given him “what could be called a criterion of truth,” but not an infallible one (1997: 274–275). Agreement between presentations would surely have been pertinent to the rejected possibility, while perspicuity would have been pertinent to the one chosen. Brittain (2001: 18–19) thinks that Philo simply dropped the Stoic requirement that a presentation should be such that it had to be true of its object in the relevant way. It seems to me that this option makes disappointingly little attempt to make Philo sound convincing. It seeks to understand Philo very much in terms of the traditional debate between Academics and Stoics, and seems not to consider something fundamental: that the traditional debate, which privileged the discussion of Stoic concepts in particular, had worked itself out (cf. Augustine, C. Acad. III 41 = T XXXI), and stood like an obstacle in the way of those who thought that philosophy had a salutary role to play in the shaping of human life—too important to be neglected because epistemological issues remained unsolved. In a briefer discussion, albeit informed by decades of working on these texts, Lévy (2010: 88) affirms that Philo’s originality was not in affirming an alternative to the Stoic criterion, but “in affirming that epochê, in a restricted version, could be put in the perspective of a knowledge rooted in the very nature of things.” While the claim seems to embody contradictions (affirmation and ἐποχή, ἐποχή and firmly grounded knowledge), it has the merit of conveying a little of the complexity of Philo’s project. Titles embody something of the different conceptions of what Philo’s contribution was like. In Lévy’s the key word seems to be “decline,” Brittain’s still calls Philo an “Academic skeptic,” Striker’s a “dogmatist fighting dogmatists,” while Tarrant (1985) preferred to ask whether he was a “skeptic” or a “Platonist.” If I had answered this directly I would perhaps have said “both, in some sense,” but “neither” might have been equally appropriate.

4. THE ONE-ACADEMY THESIS Stating an epistemological position was almost certainly not the principal purpose of the Roman Books. It was in fact not normal for Academic scholarchs to record their epistemological views in writing.8 Cicero announces what seems to have been the main function of these two books at the commencement of his Academica

PHILO OF LARISSA

85

(I 13 = T XXX), where he says that they maintained the same thesis as Cicero had heard from him orally, that there was only one Academy, attacking those who believed in two separate schools, an Old and a New Academy. This may reflect the actual title of the books, given that a similar title was also employed by Plutarch,9 who, of the various Platonists of the Roman Imperial period, was certainly one of the most accommodating toward Arcesilaus and the so-called New Academic heritage. The books must have been aimed at Antiochus, who had already apparently acquired followers of his own (Acad. II 69–70),10 and whose raison d’être appears to have been the promotion of the “Old Academy” as it had functioned until the death of Polemo. Any scholarch of the school that Plato founded must have been offended at the suggestion that its allegiance to Plato had ceased with Arcesilaus, but Antiochus seems to have assumed, like Gerson (2013: 13–14), that anti-skepticism was a defining characteristic of Platonism proper. Antiochus’s offense at the content of the Roman Books when he read them in Alexandria in 87/6 BCE (Acad. II 11–12 = T XXIX) all but guarantees that they were written in direct opposition to him. In the course of arguing against the idea of a gulf between Old and New Academies, Philo made claims that were unfamiliar to all Academics present to the extent that they might not have believed these to be Philo’s books if it could not be confirmed by the presence of some who had heard him in Rome. The passage accuses Philo of telling “lies” (II 12: mentitur), a word usually used of historical rather than philosophical claims, and the topic obviously required an account of why Plato and the Academy had once seemed so much more willing to embrace their preferred theses than Arcesilaus and his successors. Somehow the gulf between Plato and the recent Academy had to be bridged, and there needed to be a single approach to epistemology that could plausibly be credited to both. In this way Philo was forced to reveal his current position on the criterion of truth, a position that he had not revealed before, even though he might long have been leaning in this direction. It is here that I must resist Brittain’s distinction between Philo’s Metrodoran phase and his Roman Book position; I think it more plausible that Philo moved toward his final position over a period of many years, which could better explain why Antiochus’s “Old Academic” teaching had initially been tolerated. It is quite possible that Philo’s One-Academy thesis was not a simple construction, especially given that it was expounded in a two-book work. It seems likely that the Academics had long had some kind of story to tell about Socrates and Plato being authorities for skepticism, and chapter 10 of the anonymous Prolegomena to Plato’s Philosophy lists five arguments designed to show that Plato was a “suspensionist” (ἐφεκτικός, i.e., a champion of suspension of judgment), which appealed to the Theaetetus and several other dialogues. Some such arguments were discussed earlier, in Cicero and others.11 In Cicero (Acad. I 44–45, cf. II 74) Socrates is supposed to have been led by the obscurity of certain matters to his profession of ignorance (at least in the course of any given investigation),12 in which only the knowledge of his own ignorance was made an exception. What Cicero’s character Varro says about Socrates at Acad. I 15–16 shows that even a spokesman for Antiochus’s side would have no great quarrel with this picture of Socrates, and that it could

86

SKEPTICISM

never be described as a “lie.” Correspondingly, Plato’s dialogues are supposed to have affirmed nothing, argued for both sides of many questions, inquired on all subjects, and resisted certainty (Acad. I 46). Such claims might easily have been used to support a more orthodox Academic skepticism that privileged argument on both sides of the question and the suspension of judgment, but it cannot have been new since it has Plato himself go beyond the requirements of the “Fourth Academy” position as stated by Sextus. This position accepts that things are not naturally shrouded in obscurity after all (as Socrates had allegedly thought), and that they would in fact be graspable as long as one does not make cognition depend on the Stoic cognitive presentation.13 In order to align Plato (and preferably Plato’s Socrates, too) with Academic thought and practice as Philo was now depicting it, there were really only two requirements: 1. Neither Plato nor Socrates could be depicted as accepting the Stoic cognitive presentation, though they did not need to be disowning every explanation of a cognitive grasp (κατάληψις); 2. Both should be seen as resorting on occasions to such Academic practices as suspension of judgment and argument on both sides of the question. Both of these requirements are easily met, given the variety of Platonic dialogues and the variety of the representation of Socrates therein. No great effort had to be made to present either Plato or Socrates as a genuine skeptic, for genuine skepticism was now no longer being attributed to the Academy (cf. Striker 1997: 276). If Philo was lying, it was not about the school’s founder but about his successors. Here two possibilities present themselves: either he gave a false account of the Old Academy after Plato, presumably including Xenocrates and Polemo whom Antiochus had appeared to favor, or he misrepresented the New Academy from Arcesilaus. The former alternative would have the advantage of tackling Antiochus’s new authorities for the true Academic discipline. Cicero’s Varro, speaking for Antiochus at Acad. I 17, claims that not only Aristotle but also Xenocrates had complete doctrinal systems, following Plato in the essentials, and abandoned the Socratic style of inquiry with its widespread doubts and resistance to final conclusions; later he claims that Polemo, Crates, and Crantor had defended diligently the tradition that they inherited (Acad. I 34). The overall picture is one of increasing certainty, to which Zeno would apply the final touches with his theory of a cognitive presentation, laying the ground for certain knowledge (Acad. I 41–42). Yet there is no suggestion in what survives that Philo had tried to argue over any of these Old Academics, and “Cicero” at I 46 simply judges the proper “Old Academic” position from what Plato seemed to have believed. But how could Philo have “lied” about the New Academy? There was nothing novel in the view that Arcesilaus devised his armory for an ad hominem attack against the Stoics, as that had been Metrodorus’s view; likewise Metrodoran was the view that the sage might on occasion “opine” owing to the lack of a secure cognitive act such as the Stoics demanded (Acad. II 78 = T XXV, cf. II 59, 148). Furthermore, Brittain (2001: 104–108) would assign the acceptance of “perspicuous” presentations

PHILO OF LARISSA

87

at Acad. II 34 to the Philonian/Metrodoran position, that is, the one preceding the Roman Book position, so that the suggestion that Academics accepted “perspicuity” could not have been the Roman Book lie. Could he have attributed to the New Academy the acceptance of presentations that are true and “caused by the object in the relevant way,” dismissing only the clause that requires them to be true in such a way that a similar false one could not exist? This is the Roman position that Brittain would attribute to Philo (2001: 18–19, 129–168), but, though Philo himself may well have been thinking along such lines, it is most unlikely that he would have sought to attribute it to Academics from Arcesilaus to Clitomachus as anything like their official view (i) because they did not espouse official views and (ii) because Cicero explicitly regards this position as Peripatetic (Acad. II 112),14 suggesting perhaps that the Old Academy too might not have resisted it (Acad. II 113), but giving not the slightest hint that it had been attributed to any New Academic—or even openly adopted as his own by Philo. Philo’s “lies” resided neither in the attribution of New Academic doctrine to Plato and the Old Academy, nor in the attribution of Platonic, Old Academic, or even Peripatetic doctrine to the New. Rather, it lay in a theory of two strands always (or almost always) coexisting. That does not require a theory of esoteric dogmatism, as usually believed.15 The evidence sometimes understood as pointing to claims of esoteric dogmatism is as follows: 1. Augustine (C. Acad. III 43 = Cic. Acad. fr. 21) reports that according to Cicero “the Academics had been in the habit of concealing their view, and of only revealing it to those who had lived with them until old age”; 2. Sextus (PH I 224) mentions that some thought Arcesilaus, when he used to test aporetically whether his colleagues were well suited to the reception of Platonic doctrine, appeared to remain aporetic himself, but was still putting the teaching of Plato into the hands of the gifted among his colleagues; 3. Cicero’s Lucullus (Acad. II 60), presumably responding to some claim already made before the beginning of book II concerning the Academics’ practice of concealing the truth that they discover, asks “What are those mysteries?” One looks in vain for any word for teaching, or for anything indicating doctrine in texts 1 and 3. Text 1 seems to refer to no more than one’s preferred option on a given issue, but the long qualifying period agrees well with the esoteric doctrine of [Plato] Epistle VII 342c5–d2 (cf. II 314a5–7);16 text 2 suggests no commitment on Arcesilaus’s part to Platonic doctrines or writings, but rather an openness to communicating them so that suitable persons were entrusted with Plato’s written views17; text 3 perhaps seems sarcastic, and uses “mysteries” in part because of the claim that any fruits of Academic searches were not to be revealed, but it remains possible that Philo had somewhere used this term, whose application to Platonic studies is attested in early imperial Platonism (Theon of Smyrna, Expositio rerum mathematicarum ad legendum Platonem utilium XIV 18). However, mysteries typically involve not only a revelation for the initiate, but also some kind of ritual

88

SKEPTICISM

in the course of which that private revelation takes place. One was guided through the mysteries, not taught them. For the Platonist the model would be the revelation that is presented by Socrates at Theaetetus 155d–157c, where Socrates remains uncommitted and regards himself as a partner in Theaetetus’s search for a hidden truth—for ideas that are presented as “mysteries” such that they must be kept from the uninitiated and uncultured materialists. In both text 2 and text 3, the Academic teacher is being assimilated to “Socrates” in the Theaetetus.18 These texts suggest the existence of a view of the Academy that allowed individuals to hold more beliefs and to discover more truths than could be made public, but they still did not prescribe what beliefs might be held, provisionally or otherwise. Text 2 in particular suggests that Plato continued to be taught, not as scripture or dogma, but in the sense that he is taught today. Indeed, we find Charmadas teaching the Gorgias in the Academy close to the time when Philo took over as scholarch.19 We do not find Philo himself teaching Platonic writings, and those who had most to do with Plato’s writings under the Old Academy included Philip of Opus and Crantor; this last a figure of comparable stature with Polemo in the Old Academy just as Charmadas had comparable stature with Philo in the New. Plato was kept alive, but there may have been a separation of roles, so that the scholarch would not be constrained by the need to defend Plato.20 At any rate, the high regard in which Plato was held at that time cannot easily be disputed. It is entirely possible that Philo, in attempting to close the gap between Plato and the Academy’s recent past, had exaggerated the ongoing commitment of the school to its founder and the significance of the kind of Platonic “teaching” that was now being undertaken.

5 ETHICS There is only one substantial testimony about moral philosophy, which concerns the division of the types of discourse that it requires. The fragment is preserved in Stobaeus (Eclogues II 7 = T XXXII), via some intermediary21 who clearly admired Philo greatly and considered this contribution valuable. It pursues an analogy between philosophy and medicine. Like the doctor, philosophy must persuade the student to take the cure and argue against contrary advice, and this comes under the heading “protreptic.” At stage two the therapy will be introduced, involving the removal of false opinions, which have a deleterious effect on our faculties of judgment, and the imparting of healthy opinions. This requires discourse on the topic of things good and bad. A further stage will require discourse on the end or goal, that is, happiness, analogous to health in the case of medicine. This discourse involves discussion of types of life and many moral and political questions that will assist the preservation of one’s psychic health. Since the goal is essentially the privilege of the wise, Philo also demands ethical writings of a more summary kind for those of more modest ability. The obvious presence of a presumption that philosophical progress may be made and the talk of imparting opinions make it difficult to regard this division as the work of anybody who should be called “skeptic.” Rather, it bears out the view that Philo was anxious for philosophy to move on.

PHILO OF LARISSA

89

6 RHETORIC The ethical testimony just discussed, insofar as it discusses types of discourse, has a link with rhetorical theory. It is clear from Cicero (Tusc. II 9, 26, = T XXXV– XXXVI) that Philo taught rhetoric as a separate discipline from philosophy and also had special skills in the recitation of poetry. None of this has much bearing on his relation to skepticism.

7 INFLUENCE In Tarrant (1985) my primary concern had been to further weaken the evidence that Antiochus was the force behind the Platonic revival, which followed under the early Roman Empire, by showing that his opponent Philo was producing an epistemological position that granted one considerable latitude and was closer to being something that could be used by subsequent generations of Platonists. The Stoic theory of knowledge and the Stoic cognitive presentation were not something that were taken up and used by those known as Middle Platonists, whereas Philo’s stance was not inimical to constructive philosophical inquiry in the Plato tradition. Dealing with those I thought to have been influenced by Philo, particularly the anonymous Theaetetus-commentator and Plutarch,22 both of whom seem to have held some kind of One-Academy thesis, I perhaps blurred the lines that separated them from Philo, thus giving somewhat too “Platonist” a picture of Fourth Academic activity—especially given uncertainty over when various Platonic themes were reintroduced as Platonist doctrine. Opsomer (1998) has clarified many of the issues involved. Antiochus is still looked upon by some as a key figure in the transmission of Platonic doctrine (see Bonazzi 2012), though there is an increasing feeling that no single re-inventor of Platonism should be sought. The version of Philo described by Brittain (2001) would certainly not have had much influence, either on Platonism or on skepticism, though however we describe Cicero it is clear that Philo, if not his Roman Books, did influence him greatly, and as a result Augustine and the western tradition have become more familiar with the issues surrounding Academic skepticism than they otherwise would have been.23

NOTES 1. According to T. I, i.e., testimony I in Brittain (2001), which is now more convenient to use for the testimony than Mette (1986), Philo was born in the archon-year of Aristaechmus, and accordingly Brittain (2001: 41) and Lévy (2010: 85) offer ca. 159/8 BCE. Dorandi (1999: 34) had given 154/3 BCE. Discrepancies arise from many uncertainties regarding the reconstruction of numbers of years in col. XXXIII of our papyrus source (Philodemus’s Academic Index from his Syntaxis Philosophorum). 2. Glucker (1978) was a seminal work in modern scholarship on this controversy. 3. It is important to note that, since an earlier part of the second version and a later part of the original version are extant, Acad. I conventionally refers to the later version and Acad. II to the earlier version.

90

SKEPTICISM

4. Sedley (2012) is an important and wide-ranging collection of articles on Antiochus, but the contributors are by no means agreed on several controversial issues. On Antiochus’s life, see particularly Hatzimichali (2012). 5. We are told by Cicero (ND I 59 = T XXII) that Cotta was advised by Philo to hear Zeno the Epicurean, a notable instance of the Academic policy of giving everybody a hearing. 6. To this extent I may be in disagreement with Sedley (1981: 72), who speaks of “human cognitive incapacity,” though he too sees that “incapacity” in terms of the lack of a Stoic criterion. 7. See Tarrant (1985: 52–53). Note particularly anonymous in Theaetetum, LXX, a work best consulted in Bastianini and Sedley (1995), on Academic attacks on growth, allegedly designed to demonstrate the inability to improve on perspicuity by rational proofs that growth happens. 8. Rather, versions of the lectures of Arcesilaus and Carneades were recorded by others (Philodemus Acad. XX 3–4, XXII 37–XXIII 6); the accusation that Philo’s position in the Roman Books was novel does not seem to have been supported by reference to any earlier epistemological text that he had written, so that I do not find it “probable that Philo wrote at least one work on the Philonian/Metrodoran position” (Brittain 2001: 71). Stobaeus Ecl. 2.7 (= T XXXI) gives his division of ethical discourse, and the verb πεπραγματεύεται suggests that this was laid out schematically, and hence probably in writing, though what we are told does not necessarily reflect its title. Nothing gives the impression that writing came naturally to Philo. 9. Lamprias Catalogue no. 63: On There Being One Academy since the Time of Plato. Nos. 64 and 134 seem also to testify to his Academic interests, and the extant Against Colotes defends Arcesilaus. 10. There is some discussion about when this happened, and how formal Antiochus’s group of followers was; I follow Hatzimichali (2012: 12–16) rather than Polito (2012: 32–34), and feel that Antiochus may well have taken over the role that Charmadas had been playing in 91 BCE. 11. One argument appeals to the repeated use of words like “perhaps” in the dialogues, and is found also in the anonymous Theaetetus-commentator (col. LIV). 12. This important qualification is proposed by Burnyeat (1997: 299). 13. Augustine (C. Acad. III 41 = T XXXI) adds that Metrodorus had previously denied that the Academics had adopted as their own position the theme that knowledge was impossible, but that it had emerged rather from their dispute with the Stoa (cf. Acad. I 44). On Metrodorus, see Lévy (2005). 14. “If I were dealing with a Peripatetic, who stated that this thing can be perceived that has the impression of something true, but doesn’t [append]* that important extra ‘in such a manner that it could not come from something false.’” The verb marked * cannot reliably be ascertained. 15. In Tarrant (1981: 70), I failed to recognize the limited nature of such reports, influenced perhaps by the One-Academy thesis of anon. in Tht. LIV–LV. Brittain (2001: 34) sees no merit in the theories of esoteric Platonism but wrongly attributes what I had said to Tarrant (1985).

PHILO OF LARISSA

91

16. It would be perverse to tackle the vexed question of the authorship of this passage here; Cicero seems to be extending this idea of “living with” philosophers to living with their heritage at Acad. II 74: “I seem to have lived with them [Socrates and Plato].” 17. The passage needs careful translation. The aporetic testing referred to, in which suitable persons are given a taste of the doctrines of Plato, is reminiscent of Platonic midwifery in the Theaetetus, particularly 150b–151b for testing, the suspension of judgment by the tester, and the rejection of unsuitable candidates, and 157c–d for testing, continued suspension of judgment, and the offer of a taste of the thoughts of the wise. For a new study of Arcesilaus’s use of midwifery, see Snyder (2014). 18. On the early importance of this dialogue, see Tarrant (2013). 19. Evidence in Cicero, de Oratore I 47 where Crassus says: “Then at Athens I read the Gorgias rather carefully with Charmadas”; the influence of Plato’s Gorgias and Phaedrus is evident in Charmadas’s arguments against non-philosophical rhetors at De Or. I 84–94, though Charmadas did not of course openly reveal his own views in the course of these arguments (De Or. I 84). For a view of Charmadas as a conservative Carneadean, see Lévy (2010: 84–85). 20. I suspect that Arcesilaus became an exception, and that he had taken over his close friend Crantor’s role, “acquiring Plato’s books” before unexpectedly becoming scholarch, too. 21. Stylistically, the passage that we have resembles other material that follows, at least some of which derives from Eudorus of Alexandria. 22. Plutarch refers to Philo in his Lucullus (42 = T XIV), where he praises Cicero’s Lucullus highly, and his Cicero (3, 4 = T XX, XV), in which the praise of Philo’s character contrasts with the suggestions that Antiochus was swayed rather by ambition than by any genuine perspicuity that he discovered through the senses. 23. For some account of the “afterlife” of the Academy, see Lévy (2010: 89–102).

REFERENCES Bastianini, Guido and David Sedley (eds). 1995. Edition of anonymous In Theaetetum in Corpus dei papiri filosofici greci e latini, iii: Commentari, 227–562. Firenze: Olschki. Bonazzi, Mauro. 2012. “Antiochus and Platonism.” In D. Sedley (ed.), The Philosophy of Antiochus, 307–333. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brittain, Charles. 2001. Philo of Larissa: The Last of the Academic Sceptics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Burnyeat, Myles. 1997. “Antipater and Self-refutation: Elusive Arguments in Cicero’s Academica.” In B. Inwood and J. Mansfeld (eds.), Assent and Argument: Studies in Cicero’s Academic Books, 277–310. Leiden: Brill. Dorandi, Tiziano. 1999. “Chronology: The Academy.” In K. Algra, J. Barnes, J. Mansfeld, and M. Schofield (eds.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, 31–35. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gerson, Lloyd. 2013. From Plato to Platonism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

92

SKEPTICISM

Glucker, John. 1978. Antiochus and the Late Academy. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht. Hatzimichali, Myrto. 2012. “Antiochus’ Biography.” In D. Sedley (ed.), The Philosophy of Antiochus, 9–30. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lévy, Carlos. 2005. “Les petits Académiciens: Lacyde, Charmadas, Métrodore de Stratonice.” In M. Bonazzi and V. Celluprica (eds.), L’Eredità Platonica: Studi sul Platonismo da Arcesilao a Proclo, 51–77. Naples: Bibliopolis. Lévy, Carlos. 2010. “The Sceptical Academy: Decline and Afterlife.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 81–104. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mette, Hans-Joachim. 1986. “Philon von Larisa und Antiochos von Askalon,” Lustrum 28: 9–63. Opsomer, Jan. 1998. In Search of the Truth: Academic Tendencies in Middle Platonism. Brussels: Koninklijke Akademie voor Wetenschappen, Letteren en Schone Kunsten. Polito, Roberto. 2012. “Antiochus and the Academy.” In D. Sedley (ed.), The Philosophy of Antiochus, 31–54. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sedley, David. 1981. “The end of the Academy,” Phronesis 26: 67–75. Sedley, David (ed.). 2012. The Philosophy of Antiochus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Snyder, Charles E. 2014. “The Socratic Benevolence of Arcesilaus’ Dialectic,” Ancient Philosopy 34: 341–361. Striker, Gisela. 1997. “Academics Fighting Academics.” In B. Inwood and J. Mansfeld (eds.), Assent and Argument: Studies in Cicero’s Academic Books, 257–276. Leiden: Brill. Tarrant, Harold. 1981. “Agreement and the Self-Evident in Philo of Larissa,” Dionysius 5: 66–97. Tarrant, Harold. 1985. Scepticism or Platonism: A Study of the Fourth Academy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Tarrant, Harold. 2013. “L’importance du Théétète avant Thrasylle.” In D. el Murr (ed.), La Mesure du savoir: Études sur le Théétète, 243–266. Paris: J. Vrin.

CHAPTER SEVEN

Cicero J. P. F. WYNNE

1  CICERO’S SKEPTICISM The Roman orator and politician, Marcus Tullius Cicero (106–43 BC), earned his place in this book with a sequence of skeptical dialogues he wrote late in life (Hortensius, Academica, On ends, Tusculan disputations, On the nature of the gods, On divination, On fate). These dialogues pioneered attractive writing about the whole of philosophy in Latin, and they did so from a skeptical perspective. For Cicero, who had met, and often studied with, most of the leading philosophers of his day, had been won over to the skeptical “new” Academy at about the age of twenty by the visit of Philo of Larissa to Rome, and he was to retain his Academic affiliation throughout his life.1 But he was not, I shall argue, a follower of Philo’s brand of skepticism. When we study Cicero’s skepticism in these writings, we face a complex task of interpretation. For from his dialogue dedicated to Academic philosophy (the Academica), we learn that the recent history of the skeptical Academy had been tangled.2 Usually, then, to characterize Cicero’s own skepticism, we must first offer an interpretation of the historical background he describes, and then try to place him in it.3 But in this book the first stage would duplicate the preceding chapters.4 So I shall simply give my answer to the controversial question of where Cicero suggests that his affiliation lay.5 In the Academica, it is plain that Cicero follows Clitomachus’s interpretation of Carneades, the dominant figure in the later skeptical Academy. Clitomachus was by birth a Carthaginian who moved to Athens to pursue a philosophical career. He became Carneades’s student and successor as the head of the Academy, and was succeeded by Cicero’s teacher, Philo, in turn.6 Like the Academics in general, Clitomachus argued against the Stoic “cognitive” or “grasping impression,” the sort of impression the Stoics claimed could not be false. He argued that for any impression at all, even one which seems to offer a cognitive “grasp” on its content because it seems that it cannot be false, there could be an identical, but false, impression (Acad. II 40, 83). A further Stoic premise was that a wise person would never opine, that is, would never assent to impressions which could be false (Acad. II 66–67). Thus,

94

SKEPTICISM

if the Academics were right and there were no such impressions, a Stoic would have to conclude that the wise person would never assent—and that neither should anyone else. Now sometimes Carneades seemed to depart from the Stoic premise, and said that the wise person might assent, but sometimes he seemed to endorse it and conclude that the wise person would never assent. His own thoughts on the matter were therefore open to interpretation. Clitomachus’s interpretation was to take Carneades’s deployment of the Stoic premise to heart, and to conclude that indeed, Stoic or not, one should never assent (Acad. II 59, 67, 78). By contrast, other, “mitigated” skeptics, including Cicero’s teacher Philo, thought Carneades was rightly not in earnest about the sage’s universal suspension of assent. They decided that we may assent to an impression—take it to be true—even though it might be false (Acad. II 78, 112, 148). Clitomachus faced the “inactivity” objection to his skepticism: how could he act if he never took anything to be true? Clitomachus replied that commitment to the truth of any impression does not seem necessary to act. For impressions differ in how plausible or persuasive they seem or, as Cicero often puts it in Latin, how “like the truth.”7 Clitomachus says that a wise Academic will live by “following” or “accepting” the impressions that seem plausible, rather than by “assenting” to them, that is, rather than rationally committing himself to them by taking them to be true (Acad. II 103–105). In the Academica, Cicero follows Clitomachus on both points: he interprets the proper recommendation of the skeptical Academy he follows to be the avoidance of mere opinion, and aims to follow what is plausible instead.8 He says, “I trust Clitomachus when he writes that Carneades endured a Herculean labor because he dragged assent, which is to say opinion and rashness, from our souls as though it were a wild and savage monster. . . . [W]hat keeps somebody from acting, who follows things plausible, so long as nothing impedes him?”9 Cicero’s and Clitomachus’s skepticism, by contrast with the mitigated kind, is sometimes called “radical.”10 But it might seem not so radical. For, you might say, if someone does philosophy in order to encounter and delight in what seems like the truth, is she so radical a skeptic? But notice that, epistemically speaking, what seems like the truth is a world away from the truth. For example, what seems like the truth can be false, as what is true cannot. It seems like the truth that the Earth does not move—at least, it seems so when I look out my window—but it moves. To have found only what seems like the truth, then, is to have made no progress toward finding the truth, so far as you can tell. Again, you might say, a radical skeptic would not consider the goal of philosophy to be the truth, or what seems like the truth, or discovery, at all. She would take as her goal (you might say) suspension of judgment and emancipation from the tyranny of the truth. Yet notice how little Cicero’s pursuit of the truth commits him to. He takes to be true no theory of truth, nor any scheme of logic. He has no idea what, in truth, discovery would be like. He shares the dogmatist’s conception of the goal of the philosophical enterprise only in the vaguest and most abstract way. Nevertheless, he shares that conception of the goal: discovery. On this interpretation, Cicero has no way to tell when, if ever, he has encountered the truth. You might ask, then how can he tell which impressions are like the truth,

CICERO

95

when he has no truth with which to compare them? The answer must be that the phrase “like the truth” is potentially misleading. When Cicero accepts that something seems like the truth, he neither accepts that it approximates the truth nor that it is likely to be true, for he has no way to assess such claims. Rather, some impressions seem to him such that he is inclined to accept them, in ways that are presumably familiar: they seem perceptually clear and distinct, for example, or their content seems to follow from a seemingly sound argument. It seems to Cicero that this is what the truth would be like, if he found it. But he has no way to tell if he is right about that. It is my view that Cicero presents himself in all his skeptical dialogues, and not just in the Academica, as an occupant of Clitomachus’s position.11 (Where he stood earlier in life is harder to say.)12 I shall say more to support this thesis in the next section.

2  CICERO AND THE ETHICS OF BELIEF In Section 1, I sided Cicero with Clitomachus in the internal debates of the skeptical Academy. I shall now try to bring Cicero’s skepticism to life: why did Cicero choose to be a skeptic of this kind, when his charismatic teacher, Philo, was not? In answer to this question, I shall suggest that Cicero reports a strong intuition about what we call today the ethics of belief debate, an intuition for which he found a theoretical model in some Stoic psychology. A focus of the debate over the ethics of belief is this question: ought we, or may we, ever form a belief in the absence of sufficient evidence for its truth? For example, suppose that there is insufficient evidence for the truth of the proposition that God exists. But suppose also that those who believe in Him act more justly and have a unique source of comfort. In such circumstances, would we be permitted, or obliged, to form the belief that God exists? The contemporary version of this debate was begun by W. K. Clifford, who held firmly the “evidentialist” line that we ought never to form a belief in the absence of sufficient evidence (Clifford 1877). I wish to suggest that Cicero describes a similar evidentialist intuition. To see this, let us look first at a passage where he tells his friends about his personal attitude to skepticism. Cicero begins his defense of skepticism in the second book of the Academica as follows: So I shall get on with it, if I may first say a few things about my reputation, so to speak. For if I was led to apply myself to this philosophy in particular by some sort of need to show off, or by eagerness to pick a fight, I think that not only my stupidity should be condemned, but also my character and nature. For if we reprove stubbornness in small matters and punish misrepresentation, would I wish, when the condition and design of my whole life is at stake, to contend with others just for the sake of the fight, and to cheat them, and myself too? Thus, if I didn’t think it unfitting to do in this speech what it is sometimes customary to do in political debate, I would swear by Jupiter and by the gods of the city, both that I am aflame with zeal to discover the truth, and that I state my own views. For how could I not desire to find the truth, when I rejoice if I find something like

96

SKEPTICISM

the truth? But just as I judge that this is most beautiful—to see the truth—just so it is most vicious to accept falsehoods in place of truths. Nevertheless, I am not the sort of person who never approves anything false, who never assents, who opines not at all. But we are inquiring about the wise person. I am indeed a great opiner, for I am not wise. I steer my thoughts not by the little Cynosure [the constellation of the Little Bear] . . . but by Helice [the Great Bear], that is, by reasons that are bigger in the mind’s eye, not filed down to a fine point.13 Thus it comes about that I err and wander more widely. But as I said, our inquiry is about the wise man. For I accept those impressions that strike the mind or the sense sharply, and sometimes I even assent to them—but I do not grasp them, for I judge that nothing can be grasped. I am not wise, thus I yield to impressions, nor can I resist. (Acad. II 65–66) Cicero’s latter point is that he does not conduct his mental life according to the skeptical standard he accepts, in that he sometimes assents. But he says that a wise person would never assent. To be wise is to have succeeded at philosophy, to be the ideal for one who pursues wisdom. Thus I think it is clear that Cicero regrets his frequent lapses into assent, even while he is proud that what skeptical discipline he manages to maintain affords him some measure of guidance.14 Why does Cicero wish to be the sort of wise man who does not assent? The key to this question is in the sentence I have underlined in Acad. II 66 above. Cicero desires to find the truth. But, crucially, his desire is discriminating. The difference is like that between somebody who is looking for love and thus is ready to go on a date with anybody promising, and somebody who is already in love and thus wishes to date his beloved and to avoid dating anybody else. Cicero’s burning desire for the truth is of such a sort that he judges it “most vicious to accept falsehoods in place of truths.” To “accept in place of truths” is to take to be true, to assent. “Most vicious” translates the superlative of Cicero’s term of art turpe, which in everyday use means “foul.” Cicero uses turpe for what is ethically repulsive, the opposite of what is virtuous.15 Thus Cicero says here that it is ethically vicious to assent to what is false. Now, this particular ethical judgment of Cicero’s is not Clifford’s evidentialist judgment: Cicero says that it is vicious to assent to what is false, Clifford to assent where there is insufficient evidence. Clifford’s judgment is more stringent, because it rules out assent even to what is true when there is not enough evidence. But in fact Cicero is prone to deliver Clifford’s judgment, too. For example, in On Divination I 4, he says, “rashness and error in assent are vicious in all matters.”16 So, does Cicero’s judgment that assent to what is false is vicious motivate his further view that rash assent, assent to what might be false, is vicious? I think so, as follows. The truth, if it were available, would be available to Cicero through his impressions. To find the truth would involve the recognition of the truth of a true impression, that is, assent to the impression. But the Academics have made it seem to Cicero that he cannot tell which, if any, of his impressions are true. Now one reaction—even for somebody repulsed at the thought of assent to what is false—would be to assent to everything, or, more realistically, to any impression that seemed like the truth.

CICERO

97

For in so assenting one might expect to have assented to some truths, albeit perhaps at the repulsive cost of assent also to some falsehoods. Cicero rejects this wager. Thus he must see some asymmetry between the gain of assent to the truth and the loss of assent to the false, such that the risk of the latter trumps the chance of the former. I suggest that, for Cicero, to assent to a truth which one cannot tell is true is not to find the truth, but rather to fool oneself that an impression is true which, coincidentally, happens to be true. Thus there is nothing virtuous in having a true impression, or in taking it to be true.17 For either thing can happen to any fool. By contrast, assenting to what is false in place of what is true is most vicious, because that is precisely the wage of foolishness: taking to be true what might, so far as she could tell, be false, the fool has taken to be true what was false. Thus we have found Cicero’s asymmetry. Where there are no cognitive impressions, to assent to what is true is not ethically virtuous, but to assent to what is false is ethically vicious. Thus the risk of assent to what is false trumps the chance of assent to the truth. In this way, Cicero’s judgment that it is vicious to assent to what is false, combined with his skepticism, leads to his judgment that rash assent, assent to what might be false, is itself vicious, the equivalent of Clifford’s contention. But why does Cicero think that rash assent is an ethical failing? Why is it not merely a stumbling block in the pursuit of knowledge or wisdom? It is easy to see why a mistake in the pursuit of truth is ethically vicious for thinkers like the Stoics, who hold that virtue is identical with knowledge. But why so for Cicero, who was not a Stoic? We can answer this, and make better sense of many of Cicero’s pronouncements quoted in this chapter, if Cicero cherished an aspect of human psychology described theoretically in a text on Stoic ethics he wrote for his son, On Duties. Cicero there presents four basic drives in the human soul, each of which is the basis for one of four cardinal virtues. One of these is the natural drive for truth or knowledge, which is the basis for the virtue of wisdom (see also Off. I 15–16; cf. Fin. III 17–18): The search for and inquiry into the truth, above all, are proper to humanity. Thus when we are free of pressing business and care, we yearn to see something, to hear, to learn, and we suppose that the grasp of matters hidden or wonderful is necessary for the happy life. (Off. I 13) Of these four topics, it is the one that has to do with the grasp of the truth that most of all gets at human nature. For we are all dragged about and led on to a desire for cognition and knowledge, in which we think it beautiful to excel, but we say that to slip, to err, to be ignorant, to be deceived is both bad and vicious. While this kind of drive is both natural and virtuous, we must avoid two flaws in it. One is that we might hold what we have not grasped in place of what is grasped, and assent to these impressions. Anyone who wishes to escape this flaw—and everyone should wish to—must use both time and care in pondering matters. The second flaw is that some people bestow too much enthusiasm and effort on subjects difficult, obscure and indeed not necessary. (Fin. 1.18–19) It is the former of these two flaws that Cicero worries about in his skepticism: the desire to grasp can itself lead one to assent to what one does not grasp. The point, I imagine, is that faced with a plausible but possibly false impression, we

98

SKEPTICISM

wish to decide that it cannot be false, so that we may assent to it. If we yield to this temptation, we placate our desire for a grasp of the truth, but only by gulling ourselves with a counterfeit. Cicero reports similar views of his own in the Academica. First, on the point that we have a natural urge for the truth, here Cicero concludes his arguments against dogmatism in physics with the remark that physical inquiry should continue: Investigation into these most important but most hidden matters holds a delight of its own. If something turns up which seems like the truth, the soul is filled with the most human of pleasures. Thus both your [dogmatic] sage and our own [skeptical sage] inquire into these things, but yours with the result that he assents, he trusts, he makes sure, ours with the result that he fears that he might rashly opine, and so that he thinks he has done famously, if he has found something like the truth in matters of this kind. (Acad. II 127–128) The pleasure that a skeptic feels on finding something even like the truth is the “most human of pleasures.” Both dogmatist and skeptic, it appears, are responding to the sort of drive we saw Cicero describe in On duties. Second, on the point that dogmatists yield to a sort of temptation to assent, here is the conclusion to Cicero’s arguments against dogmatism in ethics: So do you gentlemen think that, when I hear these things and countless others like them, I am entirely unmoved? I am moved just as you are, Lucullus, nor should you think me less human than you. The difference is only that when you are moved, you give in, you assent, you agree, you wish it to be true and sure and grasped and perceived and reasoned and firm and fixed, and you cannot be moved nor pushed out of it by any argument. But I judge that nothing is of such a sort that, should I assent to it, I would not often assent to something false, since truths are distinguished from falsehoods by no mark, especially since there are no criteria of logic. (Acad. II 141) Cicero’s diagnosis of dogmatism here is that dogmatists wish to grasp that their views are true, and give in to this temptation, while the skeptic holds firm against it. Thus in the Academica Cicero shares views with the sorts of Stoics he was to describe in On duties, that humans have a natural and laudable drive for the truth but that this very drive tempts people into rash assent. I suggest this explains why Cicero considers rash assent to be an ethical failure. To allow the most distinctive aspiration of our rational and valuable nature to trip itself up is to betray that nature. In this light, we can understand the whole sequence of thought in Cicero’s remarks on his attraction to skepticism (Acad. II 65–66, quoted above). Cicero’s love for the truth leads him to despise assent as ethically vicious, just as the same love leads people at large to despise mendacity as ethically vicious.18 I shall now return to the question of Cicero’s affiliations. For you might see in Cicero’s repeated declaration of his devotion to the truth a sign that he is a mitigated skeptic, aligned with Philo, after all.19 At times, you might point out, he even says that in skeptical discourse, “[his] goal is to speak both for and against all philosophers, for the purpose of discovering the truth” (N.D. I 11, emphasis added).20

CICERO

99

But I have shown that, on the contrary, it is exactly Cicero’s discriminating love of the truth that leads him to disagree with the mitigated skeptics, because it leads him to think that assent to what might be false is always vicious. While discovery of truth is indeed his fond hope in skeptical inquiry, a more realistic statement of his goal is to find, “either what is true or what approaches as closely as possible to the truth” (Acad. II 7).21 So far he has found at best the latter, to which he must not assent because it might not be true. We might see tragedy in Cicero’s situation. He is the man who loved truth so faithfully that he lost it altogether. But Cicero does not seem downcast. On the contrary, he presents himself as confident and content in his skepticism. He is free to navigate away from danger, while the dogmatist clings to whatever rock life’s storms drove her onto (Acad. II 8). As Cicero remarks when challenged in the Tusculans that he has contradicted one of his own arguments in On Ends, “We live for the day. We say whatever strikes our minds as plausible. Thus only we are free” (V 33).

NOTES 1. For Cicero’s philosophical studies see, e.g., Cicero’s Brut. 306309, Fam. XIII 1.2, N.D. I 6–7, and Plutarch, Life of Cicero IV 24. For his attraction to Philo, see Brut. 306, De Inv. II 10 (cf. De Or. I 5), N.D. I 11–12 and 17. See also n. 11. 2. For an accessible translation, with help on the work’s confusing history, see Brittain (2006). 3. I substantially follow the interpretation of these debates in Brittain (2001; 2006: xxii–xiii). For some recent alternatives, see Glucker (2004) (a critical review of Brittain), Thorsrud (2009: chs. 4–5; 2010), and Lévy (2010). 4. See the chapters on Arcesilaus, Carneades, and Philo of Larissa in this book. 5. For different conclusions about Cicero’s skepticism from much of the same material as I examine in this chapter, see Thorsrud (2009: ch. 5; 2010: 76–78) and Görler (1997). 6. Diogenes Laërtius, Lives of the Philosophers IV 67; Cicero, De Or. I 45. There is also information about Clitomachus in a papyrus discovered at Herculaneum, the Index Academicorum. A synthesis of the evidence on Clitomachus’s life, in German, is Görler (1994). See also the chapters on Carneades and Philo in this book. 7. “Like the truth” translates veri simile and “plausible” probabile, both of which reflect Carneades’s term. For the data on what these various terms might mean, see Glucker (1995), who draws different conclusions than I do. 8. Here I alert readers to a difficulty thrown up by the form in which Cicero writes, narrated conversations in which “he” plays a part as a character. It is possible that what “Cicero” in the drama says is not meant to express the views of Cicero the author. But for simplicity’s sake I shall refer to both Cicero the author and “Cicero” the character as Cicero in this chapter. Readers who rightly wish to be wary on this point should consult the context of each quotation. 9. Acad. II 108. For Cicero’s other Clitomachean pronouncements in the Academica, see II 65–66, 78, 127–128, 141. 10. See Brittain (2006: xxvii).

100

SKEPTICISM

11. Some passages in other dialogues which support my view are: Fin. II 43; Tusc. I 8, IV 47, V 32–33; N.D. I 12, III 95; Div. I 4, II 150. Brittain (2016) is an example of how one might interpret a dialogue other than the Academica as radically skeptical. Woolf (2015) gives an extended and accessible picture of a more radically skeptical Cicero. 12. Cicero seems to have been a skeptic at about the age of twenty, after his encounter with Philo (see On Invention II 10; cf. De Or. I 5). But at Leg. I 39, written about a decade before the skeptical dialogues, Cicero’s character invites the skeptical Academy to step aside from the discussion, which could ground an argument that Cicero was then in a dogmatic phase (see Glucker 1988). But the latter passage does not require that interpretation, and arguably does not support it (see Görler 1995). 13. In Cicero’s day, there was no pole star, because the north celestial pole lay in a dark part of the sky between the “backs” of the Great and Little Bears. The Little Bear was thus a useful guide to true north and more precisely so than the Great Bear, because the Little Bear swept a circle of smaller radius around the pole. Navigation by the Little Bear was associated with the seafaring Phoenician peoples, of whom Clitomachus, as a Carthaginian, was one (ND II 105–106, translating Aratus, Phaenomena 39). 14. Thorsrud (2010: 77) and Görler (1997: 38, 56) think Cicero is proud that he has mere opinions. Thorsrud interprets Cicero as a mitigated skeptic and thus supposes that Cicero means that his opinions are the result of responsible inquiry. 15. See, e.g., Fin. III 38, Tusc. V 27, Off. I 10. 16. See also: N.D. I 1, Acad. I 45, Off. II 8. Cicero acknowledges the Stoics as allies in this: Fin. III 72. 17. You might object: Cicero says it “is most beautiful to see the truth,” so must he not think it is virtuous to see the truth? But I do not think Cicero means that it is virtuous to see the truth. He uses the adjective pulcher, “beautiful,” which he habitually keeps distinct from honestus, “ethically attractive” or “noble” (for pulcher see, e.g., Tusc. IV 31, for honestus, e.g., On Ends III 27–28). Certainly, the beauty of “seeing the truth” cannot be something distinctive of the experience of having or assenting to true impressions, because then true impressions would offer to us a mark of their own truth, the beauty of having or assenting to them, and thus true impressions would be cognitive, such that they could not be false. The beauty of somebody “seeing the truth,” whether this means having or assenting to a true impression, must either be a beauty that is also to be had from false impressions, or, if distinctive of an encounter with the truth, it must be something Cicero imagines from the outside: it is fitting that a rational mind should encounter, perhaps even take to be true, the truth that it desires, even though it cannot tell that it has done so. But if so, this is a beauty that both wise men and fools could exemplify. 18. In On Ends, Cicero makes this sort of parallel explicit in a related argument against Epicurean ethics: “Since [n]ature has implanted in humanity a desire to see the truth, as is easily apparent when, once freed from care, we wish to know what happens even in heaven, we are drawn on by these first stirrings to love everything true, i.e. what is trustworthy, simple and consistent, while we hate what is empty, false and deceptive, like fraud, perjury, malice and injustice” (Fin. II 46).

CICERO

101

19. See Thorsrud (2010: 76–78). 20. For the discovery of truth as Cicero’s goal in skeptical inquiry, see also Fin. I 13. 21. See also: Acad. I 45; Off. II 8. Cicero acknowledges the Stoics as allies: Fin. III 72.

REFERENCES Bret, Richard. 2010. The Cambridge Companion to Scepticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brittain, Charles. 2001. Philo of Larissa. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brittain, Charles (trans.). 2006. Cicero: On Academic Scepticism. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Brittain, Charles. 2016. “Cicero’s Sceptical Methods: The Example of De finibus.” In J. Annas and G. Betegh (eds.), Cicero’s De Finibus: Philosophical Approaches, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 12–40. Clifford, W. K. 1877. “The Ethics of Belief,” Contemporary Review 29: 289–309. Glucker, John. 1988. “Cicero’s Philosophical Affiliations.” In J. Dillon and A. A. Long (eds.), The Question of “Eclecticism”. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 34–69. Glucker, John. 1995. “Probabile, Veri Simile, and Related Terms.” In J. G. F. Powell (ed.), Cicero the Philosopher: Twelve Papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 115–143. Glucker, John. 2004. “The Philonian/Metrodorians: Problems of Method in Ancient Philosophy,” Elenchos 25: 99–152. Görler, Woldemar. 1994. “Die Akademie zwischen Karneades und Philon.” In H. Flashar (ed.), Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie v. 4.2, 898–914. Basel: Schwabe. Görler, Woldemar. 1995. “Silencing the Troublemaker: De Legibus 1.39 and the Continuity of Cicero’s Scepticism.” In J. G. F. Powell (ed.), Cicero the Philosopher: Twelve Papers, 85–113. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Görler, Woldemar. 1997. “Cicero’s Philosophical Stance in the Lucullus.” In Brad Inwood and Jaap Mansfeld (eds.), Assent and Argument, 36–57. Leiden: Brill. Inwood, Brad and Jaap Mansfeld (eds.) 1997. Assent and Argument. Leiden: Brill. Lévy, Carlos. 2010. “The Sceptical Academy: Decline and Afterlife.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Scepticism, 81–104. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Powell, J. G. F. (ed.). 1995. Cicero the Philosopher: Twelve Papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schofield, Malcolm. 2002. “Academic Therapy: Philo of Larissa and Cicero’s Project in the Tusculans.” In G. Clark and T. Rajak (eds.), Philosophy and Power in the Graeco-Roman World: Essays in Honour of Miriam Griffin, 91–109. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Thorsrud, Harald. 2009. Ancient Scepticism. Durham: Acumen. Thorsrud, Harald. 2010. “Arcesilaus and Carneades.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Scepticism, 58–80. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Woolf, Raphael. 2015. Cicero: The Philosophy of a Roman Sceptic. London: Routledge.

CHAPTER EIGHT

Menodotus and Medical Empiricism JAMES ALLEN

1 INTRODUCTION Menodotus of Nicomedia was a physician and philosopher, who probably flourished in the first half of the second century CE (cf. Capelle 1931: 901–902). The Empirical school of medicine to which he belonged arose in the third century BCE, defining itself in opposition to the rationalist tendency then dominant in the profession. Though our sources often speak of a rationalist “school” or “sect” (a logikē hairesis), rationalism was not a proper school in the way Empiricism was, that is, a collective with common doctrines and/or projects and methods, leaders or recognized authorities, and a felt group identity (cf. von Staden 1982). The term was applied polemically by the Empiricists to members of different schools—properly so-called—who were often sharply at variance with each other. The contrast between reason and experience on which the opposition is based is an old one. In Plato’s Gorgias, citing medicine as an example, Socrates maintains that the practitioner of a genuine art (technē) selects the measures he will employ on the basis of an understanding of the nature of the object upon which he acts, and he insists that a true artist must be able to give an account (a logos) of his actions in the light of this understanding by specifying the causes because of which that object is as it is and those because of which the measures he applies will have the desired effects (501a; cf. 465a, Phaedrus 270b, Laws IV 720b ff.; cf. 857c). In the terminology favored by later rationalist physicians, who accepted Plato’s view, the pathological condition indicates its own treatment. From the perspective of Socrates and those sharing his outlook, mere experience can by contrast never constitute an art because it is confined to recording conjunctions and sequences among observed events without grasping the nature of the beings that act or are acted on in them, and therefore without being able to get at the cause or explanation, which must refer to the underlying nature of what is observed. According to Galen’s testimony, in the view of the rationalists, reason was above all a faculty that enables us to grasp natural or rational relations of consequence (akolouthia) and exclusion (machē) (Subfig. emp. 87, 7; 89, 12, 15 Deichgräber).

MENODOTUS AND MEDICAL EMPIRICISM

103

The grasp of indication is one application of this faculty, which also explains one of the distinctive marks of rationalist medicine: its reliance on (alleged) truths about so-called non-evident matters, which, because they are forever beyond the reach of observation, can become objects of knowledge only with the aid of such a power (cf. Galen, De sect. ingred. SM III 11, 16–19; Subfig. emp. 62, 24–31 Deichgräber; On Medical Experience 100, 102, 103, 104–105, 107, 111, 132–133, 135, 136, 137, 139, 141, 153 Walzer). In effect, medical Empiricists came to the defense of the position attacked in the Gorgias. Though they developed their position with an eye on medicine, they held that it applied to other arts as well (Celsus, Proem. 31–32; Galen, MM X 126, 15–127, 1 K; Subfig. emp. 86, 23–87, 4 Deichgräber). They strove first to show that experience, which had its origin in observation and was confined to objects accessible to observation, was equal to the task of constituting an art without the aid of reason and the unobservable entities allegedly discovered by it. But the Empiricists also took the battle to their opponents by trying to show that the difficulties in which the rationalists and their theories were entangled undermined the claims they made for reason.

2  SKEPTICISM AND EMPIRICISM Menodotus owes his place in the history of skepticism, and his presence in this book, to the intriguing fact that, like several other Empiricists, he was also a Pyrrhonian skeptic.1 The list of Pyrrhonists in Diogenes Laertius includes at least three more Empiricists apart from Menodotus: his fellow student, Theodas, Sextus Empiricus, who is identified by his surname as an Empiricist, and Sextus’s student Saturninus (IX 115 = fr. 9 Deichgräber). Others on the list and Pyrrhonists not mentioned in it may also have been Empiricists. Sextus and Menodotus are also included in the list of Empiricists in the pseudo-Galenic medical work, Introductio seu Medicus (9, 23–24 Petit = XIV 683, 11 Kühn = fr. 6 Deichgräber). Like the Academics, the Pyrrhonists were dogged from the outset by the charge that their philosophy, which was expressed in skeptical slogans like “Everything is inapprehensible” and “Suspension of judgment about all things,” made life impossible. Sextus stoutly rejects this charge, maintaining that skeptics live and act under the guidance of a criterion, namely what appears (to phainomenon), which amounts to living in accordance with everyday observance, one of whose four elements is the teaching of the arts (PH I 21–23). Like the members of other medical schools, Empirical physicians diagnose, make prognoses, and prescribe and administer treatments and regimens—all of which would seem to require a high level of discrimination and judgment. Yet they, or those of them who were also Pyrrhonists, plainly thought they could discharge their responsibilities as doctors without compromising skeptical suspension of judgment. An understanding of the art practiced by so many Pyrrhonists may give us some insight into the skeptical form of life they claimed to lead or at the very least, by affording us a fuller picture of such a life, give us a better understanding of the explanandum.

104

SKEPTICISM

Sextus wrote a work on Empirical medicine, which has not survived (AM I 61).2 The extant philosophical works contain expressions of sympathy for the Empiricists and their ideas (PH II 246, 254; AM V 104, VIII 288, 291; cf. Spinelli 2010). At one point, Sextus even treats Empiricists and Pyrrhonists as allies who join forces to argue that non-evident matters are not apprehended (AM VIII 191), and at another, without mentioning the Empiricists, he presents the skeptics as disagreeing not only with dogmatic philosophers, but also with the Empiricists’ principal opponents, rationalist physicians (AM VIII 157).3 When he tackles the question whether as “some people say” medical Empiricism is the same as skepticism, however, Sextus takes Empiricism severely to task for dogmatic tendencies unacceptable to true skeptics, and he suggests that Pyrrhonists interested in medicine might be better advised to practice as members of the socalled Methodist school of medicine (PH I 236–241). Although it can be argued that Sextus did not intend to condemn Empiricism, but to criticize tendencies in it (cf. Frede and Walzer 1985: xxv–xxvi; Allen 2010), we must look elsewhere in order to learn how someone could be both a Pyrrhonian skeptic and an Empirical physician. Attention to Menodotus is likely to prove especially rewarding. Owing to Galen’s interest, we know a good deal about his views on the issues that divided the Empiricists from their rivals in medicine as well as the stands he took in controversies internal to Empiricism.

3  ART AND EXPERIENCE The form the Empiricists’ positive account of their art took was shaped in part by a challenge put to them by their rationalist opponents: experience, based as it is on observation, is available to laypeople as well as to experts; therefore, it cannot be the art that sets the latter apart from the former. The Empiricists acknowledge that the capacity for observation that is the basis of experience and a certain amount of experience itself are common to everyone, but insist that there is such a thing as expert experience (cf. Galen, On Medical Experience 98–99 Walzer; MM 126, 10 ff. K = fr. 45 Deichgräber). And it is experience conceived in this way, they maintain, that constitutes an art worthy of the name. Galen devotes much attention to the Empiricists’ ideas about this issue, especially in the Subfiguratio empirica.4 Two terms, peira and empeiria, which are translated as “experience,” both derived from the verbal root, peirān, meaning “to put to the test.” They are not always kept apart, and the latter especially has several related senses that must be clearly distinguished. Peira is typically used to mean the knowledge one gains from a single episode of observation (Subfig. emp. 44, 6 ff. Deichgräber). Such episodes can be by chance; result from an intervention by an observer, who tries something to see what will happen; and they can be the result of efforts to reproduce a previous observation. Individual episodes like this or the pieces of knowledge one has as a result of each taken singly do not qualify as experience strictly so-called. Experience (empeiria) in this privileged sense is knowledge or memory of what has been observed to happen many times in the same way, which can now be formulated as a theorem, which specifies, whether, for example, bleeding is followed by the

MENODOTUS AND MEDICAL EMPIRICISM

105

cessation of fever always, for the most part, roughly half the time, or rarely (Subfig. emp. 45, 24–46, 14; 50, 23 Deichgräber). In another sense, “experience” means the art composed of such theorems as a whole (47, 26; 54, 10–13; cf. De sect. ingred. SM III 3). Experience has its origin in observation, but as the Empiricists acknowledge, we can profit not only from our own observations, but also from those of others. Hence they distinguish two sources of empirical knowledge, autopsia, one’s own observation, and historia, the experience of others as preserved in books or oral teaching—one practitioner’s autopsy becomes history for another (De sect. ingred. SM III 3, 17–20). So much was common ground, but two related issues especially were subject to controversy in the school and figured in important developments in the school’s position. One concerned the status of the so-called transition to the similar, the other, how the Empiricists understood the kind of reason that they reject. Over the course of their school’s history, Empiricists adopted different stances toward reason. Some, especially early on, took a very hard line, while other, mostly later, Empiricists admitted that there was a place in the art for something they were willing to call reason, but they insisted that it did not qualify as reason as the rationalists understood it, and to mark the difference they employed two terms, epilogismos for the form of reason they found acceptable and analogismos for the kind peculiar to rationalism (Subfig. emp. 62, 22–63, 1 Deichgräber). Theodas maintained that the method through similarity was a form of rational experience (Subfig. Emp. 50, 2–4). The transition to the similar is the Empiricists’ response to an obvious challenge, namely, what will the Empirical physician do when faced with a case of a new type? The answer is that he will use the transition to the similar by applying a therapy that has already been effective when applied to one part of the body to another part similar to it, or by applying the same therapy to diseases that are similar to one against which it has proven effective (and if the disease is familiar from experience but the known remedy is unavailable, he will use a similar remedy). But what part can be played in an empirical art by the transition to the similar, whose point of departure is, to be sure, something that has been observed and remembered by the practitioner, but that leads him beyond his experience? A difficult passage in the Subfiguratio empirica reviews some of the opinions held by Empiricists (49, 23 ff.; cf. Perilli 2004: 154–157). It begins with a scholarly question about what an early Empiricist, Serapion, may have thought and becomes—though it is unclear precisely where—a discussion of the merits of different views about the issue itself. “Did Serapion judge that transition to the similar is a third constitutive part of medicine [together with autopsy and history]?” Menodotus is cited for his view: “No, he only uses it.” Probably still following Menodotus, Galen says: “There is a difference between using something and using it as a part.” Menodotus, then, appears to have held that Serapion used transition to the similar without using it as a constitutive part of medicine, that is, as a reliable source of medical knowledge. Others, Galen notes, held that it was better viewed as an instrument (organon). It seems that an Empiricist cannot put the results of the transition on a level with those of autopsy and history without compromising his empiricism. When Galen returns to the subject, he again appeals to the authority of Menodotus, who held that the

106

SKEPTICISM

transition to the similar is not a true criterion, but rather a criterion of the possible (69, 33 ff., 70, 7) and “a road to experience” (70, 6). Experience remains the ultimate authority. Nonetheless, the distinction between two moments that is implicit in this account of the nature and value of the transition to the similar is noteworthy. On the one hand, there is the task of testing or confirming the potential theorems suggested by the transition; on the other, that of inventing or “thinking up” what is submitted to the test of experience. An empirical account of the latter is not impossible, and there are traces of one in Galen’s testimony. In past experience similarities in certain respects, for example, in the taste and smell of remedies, have proved more reliable predictors of therapeutic efficacy than in others, for example, color. But it is also easy to see how the choice of similarities to which to attend could provide scope for reasoning.

4  THE ROLE OF REASON IN THE DEBATE Everything depends on what counted as reason in the debate. There are three relevant ways of understanding reason, which can be roughly ordered in terms of logical strength, so that it is fair to speak of three degrees of rationalist commitment to which correspond three levels of antirationalism. What is entailed by the first and weakest degree of commitment is revealed in an argument brought against the Empiricists by Asclepiades of Bithynia, a prominent physician and medical theorist active in Rome in the first century BCE. He espoused a paradigmatically rationalist theory, according to which health is ultimately the flow at the proper rate of microscopic bodies through passages in the body and diseases are due to their excessive or deficient flow. According to Asclepiades, the finite number of types under which infinitely various experiences can be classified are not given in experience, but discovered by reason. He gives as an example the twenty-four letters of the Greek alphabet, with the aid of which infinitely various verbal sounds can be apprehended (On Medical Experience 88 Walzer). And he argued that the observation of what happens many times in the same way cannot begin without the prior contribution of reason—the reason exercised in concept-formation (Galen Subfig. emp. 88, 25 Deichgräber; De sect. ingred. SM III 9, 9–13; On Medical Experience 85 ff. Walzer). The argument is ingenious and touches on important issues. The problem is that this is not what the Empiricists, or most of their opponents, meant by reason. And it begs the question to assume that it is impossible to possess the capacities that Asclepiades counts as rational for the purpose of his argument without also having the rational faculties that the Empiricists claimed to do without. The second degree of rational commitment covers reasoning as inference, the drawing of a conclusion on the basis of grounds or evidence, arguably a practice in which, in some form or to some degree, almost all human beings engage. The third and last degree of commitment is reason as characterized in the account of the debate between rationalism and Empiricism, namely, as a power to apprehend relations of consequence and exclusion, which is the peculiar property, at least in its refined and developed form, of highly trained experts and whose most striking

MENODOTUS AND MEDICAL EMPIRICISM

107

and distinctive manifestation is the discovery of non-evident entities and processes beyond the reach of observation and unknown to laypeople. Whether and how this power is related to reasoning corresponding to the second degree of rational commitment could be a matter of controversy. No Empiricist embraced reasoning of the last kind. None rejected reason of the first degree, though they may have questioned how useful it is to speak of “reason” in connection with it. It was the second degree of rational commitment about which there was controversy and their attitude to which seems to have undergone development over time. How far some Empiricists were willing to go in their rejection of reason is plain from Galen’s summary of the account some of them gave of the discovery of the “cephalicum” drug (MM X 163, 14 ff. Kühn = fr. 105 Deichgräber; cf. Comp. med. gen. XIII 366, 2 ff. Kühn = fr. 106 Deichgräber; cf. Frede 1990: 233). It is a mixture of ingredients that have been effective treating the same ailment when applied singly to different patients. Some Empiricists, Galen maintains, say that discoveries of this sort could be suggested by a dream, or that, after the ingredients had been mixed by chance, someone might have ventured to try the mixture. This, says Galen, is so much nonsense, and he contrasts this account with the epilogistical method employed by other Empiricists. In his words, a physician employing this method, having experience of the curative effect of each of the simple uncompounded ingredients, may discover that not every one of them suits every patient’s nature. He will then use epilogismos to conclude that he should mix together as many simple remedies for the affliction as he can in order that each nature will be supplied with the remedy that suits it. It is not easy to see how a human being can lead a life, let alone practice an art, without doing anything of the kind that we or the Empiricists who countenance epilogismos would describe as inferring, drawing a conclusion, and the like. Yet it seems that radically “anti-rational” Empiricists refused to agree to the second degree of rational commitment and tried to explain as an exercise of the faculty of memory what others would call reasoning. According to this way of thinking, repeated observation of occurrences that coincide, precede, or follow one another, supplemented by history based on the experience of other people, forms dispositions in us to be reminded of one thing by another. When one sees smoke, on this account, one does not infer that there must be fire by appreciating the grounds that favor this conclusion, let alone by apprehending relations of consequence and exclusion imposed by the nature of fire. Rather, one is simply put in mind of fire. It would not be wrong to borrow talk of custom from Hume and like-minded philosophers and regard the Empiricists’ view as a variety of associationism. A contrast like this one is the basis for the distinction between indicative and commemorative signs, to which Sextus Empiricus devotes two lengthy discussions (PH II 97–133; AM VIII 141–299). The former signify that of which they are signs by their own nature and constitution; the latter by reminding us or recalling to mind matters with which they have been co-observed in past experience, as, for example, smoke signifies fire. Though the matter remains controversial, it has been argued that the conception of commemorative signification is due to the Empiricists.5

108

SKEPTICISM

We can trace the progress in the Empiricists’ attitudes toward reason through the way in which they handled certain oppositions. As part of his discussion of the transition to the similar in the Subfiguratio empirica, Galen compares two ways of understanding the term “transition” (metabasis). It looks as if metabasis is being presented as a genus whose two main species are inference or rational inference, on the one hand, and the Empiricists’ alternative, on the other: Rational transition derives knowledge indicatively from the nature of the matter; Empirical transition follows matters that are known from experience, not because it is plausible that like things are productive of like effects, or that they stand in need of like measures or are similarly affected—it is not for this reason that [the Empiricists] insist on using the transition, but because we have experienced like things behaving in this way. (Subfig. emp. 70, 10 ff. Deichgräber) Note that “rational,” and by implication “reason,” belong on the rationalist side of the opposition between two varieties of transition. “Rational” also attaches to the “consequence” (assecutio, akolouthia) that figures in Galen’s characterization of indication (Subfig. emp. 44, 9; 64, 7 Deichgräber), and as we have seen consequence together with conflict are the objects grasped by the special faculty of reason, commitment to which was in Galen’s view the defining characteristic of medical rationalism (Subfig. emp. 87, 4–7).

5  EMPIRICAL REASONING: EPILOGISMOS A different picture emerges from the work that has the most to say about epilogismos, On Empirical Medicine. Though we are fortunate to have it, apart from two short fragments, it survives only in an Arabic translation of a Syriac translation of the Greek, edited and translated into English in 1944 by Richard Walzer (reprinted in Frede and Walzer 1985). My interpretation is based on Walzer’s English translation, and the reader should be aware of the layers standing between the lost original and the present author. Galen first presents the anti-Empirical polemic due to Asclepiades mentioned above and then an extended response from the Empiricists. In the part relevant to our present purpose, the spokesman for Empiricism takes the opportunity afforded by the rationalists’ charge that “[the Empiricists] have no method of drawing a conclusion, with the help of which inferences are drawn from the visible to the invisible” to expound “[his] opinion [that] there are two kinds of logoi: the one called epilogismos, the other called analogismos” (On Empirical Medicine 131– 132). The extent to which the Empiricist is willing to take over the language of his rationalist opponents is remarkable. Thus we find: “The conclusion from visible to visible that is known as epilogismos,” which is contrasted with “the conclusion from the visible to the invisible” (141); “the method of reasoning from visible to visible” (149); “Epilogismos is an inference from common and universally used by all mankind” (133); “the conclusion and logos known as epilogismos” (135, 139); and “in affirming what is necessitated by something that is said or done, you will find two kinds of affirmation, one after the manner of the logos known as epilogismos,

MENODOTUS AND MEDICAL EMPIRICISM

109

the other after the manner of the logos known as analogismos” (135–136). And there is no missing the fact that the battle lines in the case made by Galen’s Empiricist have been redrawn. The dispute is no longer simply between the partisans of reason and those of memory and observation, but between advocates of two kinds or two understandings of rational inference. According to the Empiricists, epilogismos is confined to evident matters; it does not, as analogismos purports to do, extend the reach of human knowledge beyond the realm of observable items. Unlike analogismos, it is not the possession of a few specialists but common to all humankind. And in sharp contrast to analogismos, it yields results on which all can agree instead of giving rise to endless and apparently irresolvable controversy (De sect. ingred. SM III 11, 8; Subfig. emp. 62, 24–31 Deichgräber; On Medical Experience 133–135, 140 Walzer). It covers what we call inference based on empirical generalizations (cf. De sect. ingred. SM III 10, 23–24; 11, 9–10), but it also seems to cover the invention or thinking-up of new ideas that I mentioned earlier in connection with the transition to the similar. It is perfectly clear that a difference exists between each logos and conclusion used by the dogmatists [i.e., rationalists] and the logos and conclusion known as epilogismos, which is universally used by everybody, namely that epilogismos seeks the guidance of visible things—and it is from this that it seeks confirmation of its truth and rightness. (On medical experience 139, cf. 133–134 Walzer) The specimen of epilogistical reasoning about the cephalicum discussed above may furnish an example (MM X 163, 14 ff. Kühn = fr. 105 Deichgräber; cf. Comp. Med. gen. XIII 366, 2 ff. Kühn = fr. 106 Deichgräber). Although it appeals to the “natures” of the patients’ bodies, it does so in a completely general way: in effect “the nature, whatever it is, that responds to an ingredient in the drug,” and the upshot must of course be submitted to the test of experience. Most controversial is the use of reason by the Empiricists in anti-rationalist polemic. They argued plausibly that the conflicting results reached by the rationalists, using their version of the rational method, undermined the claims they—the rationalists—made for it. This and the attempts by some Empiricists to show where the rationalists’ anti-Empirical arguments go wrong may invite the charge that the Empiricists were more invested in reason than they allowed or than can be explained as simple epilogismos. Menodotus stands accused of yet another offense, however. According to Galen, he contradicts himself: Menodotus often introduces something third, in addition to memory and perception; he calls this third thing “epilogism”; often though, he does not posit anything in addition to memory except perception. (Subfig. emp. 87, 25–88, 1) According to one attractive suggestion, in taking different and incompatible positions at different times, Menodotus was acting as a skeptic (cf. Frede 1990: 248– 249). Academics like Carneades were known to argue for incompatible positions about, for example, the question whether the wise person will have opinions, at most one of which can have been their real view (cf. Cicero, Acad. II 67, 78).6

110

SKEPTICISM

By arguing in this way, they could show that their dogmatic opponents were not entitled to certain conclusions even granted certain concessions. Following this strategy, Menodotus could, for example, have argued that an art of medicine was possible on the basis of experience even if, contrary to fact, they foreswore the use of reason, including epilogismos. A close look at the polemical context of this charge, leveled in the twelfth and last chapter of the Subfiguratio, suggests another possibility, however. The favorable attitude toward Empiricism on display in most of the Subfiguratio is conditional: provided they stick to what—in Galen’s view—they did best. In chapter XI, to which we shall return because it faults Menodotus for failing to live up to the ideal of Pyrrho, Galen says that the account so far covers Empirical medicine that is sufficient for the good treatment of patients. He turns now to the criticism of superfluous additions made by leaders of the Empirical school (Subfig. emp. 80, 16–81, 20 Deichgräber). In Galen’s view, the ideal Empiricist is a man of deeds and very few words, who makes his mark by curing patients, not by engaging in disputes. Chapter XII, which belongs to the same polemic, rejects the view, apparently held by some Empiricists, that medical experience includes parts that resolve the difficulties raised against Empiricism by its opponents and furnish arguments against the opponents’ own positions (Subfig. emp. 86, 15–23 Deichgräber). Galen maintains that people who claim to base an art solely on evident perception and memory have no business attempting to show what is wrong with the rationalists’ case against Empiricism, let alone arguing against their theories. To do this, one would have to accept that human beings have a faculty capable of evaluating and judging relations of consequence and exclusion, that is, the rational faculty as Galen and the rationalists understood it (Subfig. emp. 87, 4–12; cf. 89, 5–23, 44, 9–10, 63, 23–26 Deichgräber). To accept this, however, places one under an obligation to develop the power by the study of logic according to Galen. Only then will one have earned the right to participate in the debates from which he thinks Empiricists should otherwise remain aloof. This is the occasion for Galen to mention the Empiricists who found a place for reason. “[Heraclides] knows that there is [such a faculty] and is seen to use it on many occasions” (Subfig. emp. 87, 19–21). The problem is that he never did what he needed to do to develop it. For this reason, “he is as much worse a doctor than Hippocrates as he is a better one than Menodotus” (Subfig. emp. 87, 22–25), who is now accused of contradicting himself. Galen, then, is looking for the thin end of the wedge, evidence that some of the Empiricists were committed to the existence of a faculty of reason, which he can then use to fault them for failing to develop this faculty as they would have to have done to make their arguments against the rationalists worthy of serious consideration. His evidence is Heraclides’s self-conscious use of reason and Menodotus’s acceptance of a form of reasoning that he styled “epilogismos.” The argument would surely have seemed tendentious to the Empiricists, however. They were at pains to distinguish the form of reasoning they accepted from the rationalists’ alternative. There is no reason to think that they would have agreed that the use of epilogismos committed them to accepting the existence of a special rational faculty answering to the description supplied by Galen or to

MENODOTUS AND MEDICAL EMPIRICISM

111

acknowledging the attendant obligation to study logic. It may be doubted, then, whether they viewed the adoption of epilogismos as a sharp break with the past. The interpretation of Serapion’s views about the transition to the similar shows that, in the manner of other long-established schools, many of them wanted to see themselves as in fundamental agreement with their distinguished predecessors. Despite his wholehearted endorsement of epilogismos, the Empirical spokesman in On Medical Experience describes Empiricists as proponents of memory and observation and recognizes a sense of “reason” in which it is the exclusive possession of the rationalists (138, 154 Walzer). If this proposal is on the right lines, Menodotus will have regarded the acceptance of epilogismos as compatible with a commitment to memory and observation as the sole ultimate bases of knowledge. Epilogismos, as he conceived of it, is reasoning based on and not departing from what we know through these powers. The innovation, if it amounted to that, will simply have been to describe better what the Empiricists had been doing all along.

6  WAS MENODOTUS AN INCONSISTENT PYRRHONIST? In chapter XI of the Subfiguratio, Galen levels another charge of inconsistency. He tells us that as the Pyrrhonist is in the whole of life so the Empiricist is in the medical sphere; he informs us that Menodotus had held up Pyrrho as a model for his fellow Empiricists to follow; and he faults him for failing to live up to the ideal that Pyrrho represented. This is powerful evidence that Menodotus, together with at least some other Empiricists, was a Pyrrhonist and regarded himself as one. Galen’s criticism of Menodotus contains two charges that are not clearly distinguished. The first, that unlike Pyrrho, Menodotus is a man of many words (multiloquus) and that, far from avoiding disputation, he is constantly engaged in it, is easily answered. The evidence furnished by Sextus Empiricus about the Pyrrhonian tradition to which both he and Menodotus belonged shows that disputation was the life blood of Pyrrhonism and that the Pyrrhonists were aware that they likely differed from Pyrrho in important ways while they continued to find aspects of his life exemplary (see PH I 7). According to Galen, Menodotus’s too many words were also often vituperative and buffoonish, and worst of all—this is the second main charge—he was guilty of making rash and dogmatic assertions. Thus according to Galen, in his writings against Asclepiades of Bithynia, Menodotus declares that he knows certainly that all of his doctrines are false—despite the fact that “in many of his writings, he has demanded that one should approach everything non-evident as if perhaps it is true and perhaps it is not” (Subfig. emp. 84, 18–31)—the true Pyrrhonian attitude. If Menodotus did really claim to know for certain that Asclepiades’s theories were false, he was guilty of the second inconsistency of which Galen accuses him. Galen’s charge bears some resemblance to Sextus’s complaints about the unskeptical firmness with which Empiricists speak about non-evident matters, with the difference that Sextus thinks Empiricists are too ready to pronounce non-evident matters to be inapprehensible while, if Galen is right, Menodotus claimed to know that one theory was false.

112

SKEPTICISM

Nonetheless, this shows not that Menodotus was not a Pyrrhonist, but at worst that he was an inconsistent one. We do not have the evidence on which Galen based his charge, but in view of his penchant for uncharitable interpretations of his opponents, it is at least possible that it might support a different and lesser charge: in his impatience with Asclepiades, Menodotus so far forgot himself as to say, or to say things that imply, that he knew Asclepiades was all wrong. Though Galen may have been too hard on Menodotus, that there could be a tension between Empiricism and Pyrrhonism is undeniable. The Empirical position, stated simply and without qualifications, is dogmatic. The denial that knowledge of non-evident matters is possible, of which Sextus complains, can be combined with the equally unskeptical conviction that knowledge of evident matters is. According to Galen, Empiricists hold that the fact that “each thing has appeared as it is confirms the correctness of those who are right and refutes those who are not [about evident matters by contrast with non-evident ones]” (De sect. ingred. SM III 1120–1112, 4; cf. On Medical Experience 103, 133–135 Walzer). Pyrrhonists acknowledge that things appear a certain way, to be sure, but of course “investigate whether the real object is such as it appears” and cannot “be sure regarding the phenomena whether they are as they appear” (PH I 19; AM VIII 142, cf. 357). If some Pyrrhonists embraced Empiricism, they will not have endorsed the conviction about the phenomena or appearances that Galen ascribes to the Empiricists. This will not have prevented them from following the same appearances as the Empiricists. They will have done so with the proviso that things may not be as they appear, however. Such a person would be a skeptical Empiricist, differing from his dogmatic colleagues not necessarily by following appearances with a different content, but in the character of his attitude to them. Empiricism will most likely have recommended itself to a Pyrrhonist of this kind because of the way in which it purported to be nothing more than a refinement of everyday observance and so a form of artistic teaching that had a place in the Pyrrhonists’ criterion. Even if Menodotus is guilty of the lapses of which Galen accuses him, he likely was, or strove to be, a Pyrrhonian Empiricist of this kind.7

NOTES 1. If a corrupt passage in Sextus (PH I 222) contains a reference to Menodotus, he may have taken an interest in the much debated question whether Plato was a skeptic. See Spinelli (2000), who favors this view, and Perilli (2005), who rejects it. 2. Thought by scholars to be the same as the “Medical Commentaries” cited at AM VII 202. 3. Consider, however, AM VIII 327–328, where the Empiricists are pitted against dogmatic philosophers and rationalist physicians as parties to a dispute—about the existence of demonstration—regarding which skeptics suspend judgment. 4. Latin text in Deichgräber (1965); English translation in Frede and Walzer (1985). 5. See Allen (2001: 106–139), with references to the literature on page 107 n. 19. Ebert (1987) argues for an entirely different origin of the theory of signs discussed in Sextus.

MENODOTUS AND MEDICAL EMPIRICISM

113

6. On Carneades, see Harald Thorsrud’s chapter in this book. 7. Medical Empiricism is discussed in standard histories of skepticism: Brochard (1923: book IV, ch. 1), Robin (1944: part IV, ch. 1), and Hankinson (1995: ch. XIII). Menodotus is the subject of specialized monographs: Favier (1906) and Perilli (2004).

REFERENCES Allen, James. 2001. Inference from Signs: Ancient Debates about the Nature of Evidence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Allen, James. 2010. “Pyrrhonism and Medicine.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 232–248. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brochard, Pierre. 1923. Les sceptiques grecs, 2nd edn. Paris: Vrin. Capelle, Wilhelm. 1931. s.v. “Menodotos (2).” RE XXIX, cols. 901–916. Deichgräber, Karl. 1965. Die griechische Empirikerschule: Sammlung der Fragmente und Darstellung der Lehre. 2nd edn. Berlin and Zürich: Weidmann. (First published in 1930). Ebert, Theodor. 1987. “The Origin of the Stoic Theory of Signs in Sextus Empiricus.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 5: 83–126. Favier, Albert. 1906. Un médecin Grec du II siècle ap. J.-C. précurseur de la méthode expérimentale moderne: Ménodote de Nicomédie. Paris: Jules Rousset. Frede, Michael and Richard Walzer. 1985. Galen: Three Treatises on the Nature of Science. Indianapolis: Hackett. Frede, Michael. 1990. “An Empiricist View of Knowledge: Memorism.” In S. Everson (ed.), Epistemology, 225–250. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hankinson, Robert James. 1995. The Sceptics. London and New York: Routledge. Perilli, Lorenzo. 2004. Menodoto di Nicomedia: Contributo a una storia galeniana della medicina empirica. Leipzig: Saur. Perilli, Lorenzo. 2005. “Quantum coniectare (non) licet: Menodotus between Sextus Empiricus (P 1.222) and Diogenes Laertius (9.116),” Mnemosyne 58: 286–293. Robin, Léon. 1944. Pyrrhon et le scepticisme grec. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Spinelli, Emidio. 2000. “Sextus Empiricus, the Neighbouring Philosophies and the Skeptical Tradition (again on Pyr. 220–225).” In J. Sihvola (ed.), Ancient Scepticism and the Sceptical tradition. Acta Philosophica Fennica 66: 36–61. Spinelli, Emidio. 2010. “Pyrrhonism and the Specialized Sciences.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 249–264. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. von Staden, Heinrich. 1982. “Hairesis and Heresy: The Case of haireseis iatrikai.” In B. F. Meyer and E. P. Sanders (eds.) Jewish and Christian Self-Definition, vol. III: Selfdefinition in the Graeco-Roman World. 76–100, 199–206. London: Fortress Press.

CHAPTER NINE

Middle Platonism and Skepticism: Plutarch and Favorinus CARLOS LÉVY

1 INTRODUCTION The concept of skepticism has at least two different meanings. The first is general (M1), the second is more restricted (M2). A tendency to doubt the things commonly considered as clear was present in many ancient philosophical doctrines (M1). That was the reason why the neo-Academics were so eager to show that their absolute ἐποχή, far from being an invention of their own, was the result of a long tradition that included thinkers as different as Democritus, Xenophanes, and Socrates (Cicero, Acad. II 72–74). But generally the term “skepticism” is used in studies on ancient philosophy to designate only two schools (M2), the New Academy, inaugurated by Arcesilaus, and neo-Pyrrhonism, which was the creation of Aenesidemus in the first century BCE.1 One of the reasons for this duality is that skepticism as a technical concept did not appear before Aenesidemus. For example, Arcesilaus, scholarch of the Academy in the third century BCE, never used this concept. He defined his own philosophical identity as that of an Academic practicing a radical suspension of judgment (ἐποχὴ περὶ πάντων), not as that of a skeptic belonging to the Academy. Inside these two schools, the problem of continuity versus rupture was a permanent one, with a complex net of strategies to differentiate themselves from each other, as we will see in the case of Plutarch. Academics seem to have ignored contemptuously Aenesidemus, and two centuries later, Sextus Empiricus, defining himself as a skeptic and Pyrrhonist, worked hard in his Outlines of Pyrrhonism to demonstrate that the neo-Academics were not authentic skeptics (see Bonazzi 2011). The problem I will tackle in this chapter is how to understand the presence of skeptical terms and themes in Middle Platonism, a rich and confused period between the Hellenistic systems and Neo-Platonism, focusing my analysis on Plutarch and Favorinus.2

MIDDLE PLATONISM AND SKEPTICISM: PLUTARCH AND FAVORINUS

115

2  THE MIDDLE PLATONIC BACKGROUND 2.1  Problems of Method There are two possible interpretations of the presence of skeptical terms and themes in Middle Platonism. First, one may consider skepticism and dogmatic Middle Platonism as radically different. On this interpretation, the skeptical themes are only traces, without any essential meaning, of the previous period. Second, Platonism may be deemed a paradoxical product of the evolution of skepticism, as the response to some of its aporias; and so there would be no deep rupture between the two periods. When examining the history of the New Academy, one realizes that skepticism seems to have become more and more moderate from Arcesilaus to Philo of Larissa, who, while continuing to fight Stoic dogmatism, asserted that things were knowable by nature, but without saying what the criterion of such a knowledge could do (see Brittain 2001: 138–145). Philo opened the door to an interpretation of Platonic thought that would not be entirely determined by the traditional Academic hostility toward Stoicism. The best example of this continuity can be found in the Commentary on the Theaetetus, the date of which is still at the center of many discussions.3 The author criticizes the Stoic idea that justice has a natural foundation. In order to demonstrate the falsity of this doctrine, he uses an example found in the famous antilogy of the third book of Cicero’s De re publica. In his dialectic refutation of the Stoic ethical immanentism, Carneades said that if a ship was wrecked and two shipwrecked sailors had to compete for holding on to a board, the struggle for life would be stronger than any ethical concern (Cicero, De rep. 3. 26). The solution to this Stoic aporia was, in the opinion of the author of the Commentary, the return to a dogmatic version of Platonism. It was based on the famous so-called digression of the Theaetetus 176B, namely, the view that justice could not be founded on the idea that the world is the city of gods and mankind, but in the φυγή, the flight away from the world of sensation. The difference between the position of Carneades and that of author of the Commentary is clear. For the former, at least from what we can deduce from the complex Ciceronian metaphrasis, the essential thing was to demonstrate that the premises of Stoic ethics lead to the exact opposite of what they pretended to prove, but he did not offer any alternative solution of his own. The Theaetetus, and more precisely the concept of ὁμοίωσις κατὰ τὸ δύνατον, indicates the way to avoid the difficulties inherent in naturalistic ethics. It is likely that the Theaetetus, a dialogue certainly frequently read in the New Academy that was aporetic and contained a digression with an assertive tone, was the best means to try a kind of conciliation between Carneadean skepticism and a much more dogmatic form of Platonism.

2.2  A Pioneer: Transcendence and Skepticism in Philo of Alexandria Plutarch was not the first philosopher of the Middle Platonic period to have interpreted skepticism as both an access road to transcendence and a consequence of it. In the first decades of the first century CE, Philo of Alexandria, who certainly

116

SKEPTICISM

was not a philosopher in the technical sense of the word but had an excellent knowledge of the philosophical milieu and texts, opened this way. He was the first, at least in our testimonies, to have expounded the tropes of Aenesidemus, not in order to affirm his own skeptical affiliation, but as a path to his rather fideistic theology. In Philo’s treatises, there are some quite interesting allusions to Academics and skeptics of his time, but their interpretation is complex, both because the allusion that seems to have been the most explicit one has reached us in an Armenian translation and because Philo has a tendency to transform the skeptics in an allegory of the resurgence of Sophistic (Lévy 2008: 105–110).4 But we find in De fuga et inventione (136), in the exegesis of the sacrifice of Isaac, an articulation between the concept of ἐποχή and the almightiness of God, which is not only interesting from the perspective of Biblical studies, but as the sign of a change in the intellectual climate, making it possible to create a strong link between doubt and transcendence. Above all, Philo’s De ebrietate has been considered by prominent scholars like von Arnim and Bréhier as being probably the closest to the classification elaborated by Aenesidemus (von Arnim 1888: 79; Bréhier 1907: 210). More recent scholars expressed a different opinion about Philo’s testimony, but without convincing evidence.5 In any case, it is important to notice that in about 30 CE, the approximate date of the redaction of most Philo’s treatises, a quite learned man with a real philosophic formation was able to bring together Academic concepts (ἐποχή, πιθανόν, εὔλογον), neo-Pyrrhonian modes, and, last but not least, the motto of Middle Platonic thought, the Platonic recommendation to become “like God so far as it is possible” (Theaet. 176b). The conditions under which this mixture took place are far from clear, but it is important that some decades before Plutarch the structures of the intellectual environment in which he was going to write his own philosophical treatises were already present.

3 PLUTARCH 3a  General Remarks John Glucker (1978: 257–279) demonstrated, rather convincingly in my opinion, that the claim that Plutarch of Chaeronea (ca. 45–120 CE) studied in an organized Academy lacks evidence. The passages in which he mentions the Academy do not allow us to say firmly that, after having been Ammonius’s pupil, he went to the Platonic school, where he would have received all his knowledge about Academic skepticism. One of the most interesting elements about Plutarch’s relation to skepticism is that he had a precise knowledge not only of the tradition represented by Arcesilaus, Carneades, and Clitomachus, but also of the neo-Pyrrhonian tradition. He wrote books in the anti-dogmatic, and especially anti-Stoic tradition of the New Academy, such as On the Contradictions of the Stoics and Against the Stoics on Common Notions, but he was also the author of On the difference between the Pyrrhonists and the Academics and of On the Pyrrhonian Ten Tropes. Plutarch’s literary and philosophical production is enormous, and any attempt to give a complete account

MIDDLE PLATONISM AND SKEPTICISM: PLUTARCH AND FAVORINUS

117

of it in a few pages is impossible. However, it seems that Plutarch’s relation to skepticism has different aspects that it is necessary to present separately.

3b  The Critique of Stoicism The first aspect is his anti-Stoicism, or more exactly his hostility toward the Hellenistic dogmatisms, since he did not spare Epicureanism, against which he wrote many treatises (see Hershbell 1992). However, since the refutation of Stoicism was much more fundamental in the history of the New Academy than that of Epicureanism, I will focus on this aspect of Plutarch’s thought. In fact, his relation to Stoicism is quite complex, as Daniel Babut (1967) showed, but that does not prevent him from carrying on and extending the long tradition of criticism of the Stoic doctrine elaborated by Arcesilaus and his successors in the New Academy. In the Catalogue of Lamprias, an exhaustive list of the titles of Plutarch’s books, eight explicitly anti-Stoic treatises are mentioned, three of which have reached us, the third one being a short and polemic treatise in which Stoics are accused of saying things more absurd than those said by the poets. However, many other treatises are attacks against particular aspects of the Stoic doctrine, even if neither the name of this school nor any specific Stoic concept are present in the title. As an example, the treatise “Is rhetoric a virtue?” was certainly anti-Stoic, since these philosophers were those who had defined true rhetoric as a component of wisdom. The two main treatises, On the Contradictions of the Stoics and Against the Stoics on Common Notions, though being rich in references and often explicit about sources, are full of mysteries. It is probable that these anti-Stoic treatises were written more or less at the same time as the anti-Epicurean ones, when Plutarch was still influenced by his Platonic formation under the direction of Ammonius. Babut’s argument that these treatises are full of too much philosophical information to have been written by a young scholar is not entirely convincing, given that Plutarch could have used material carefully elaborated in the New Academy.6 Von Arnim remarked that no Stoic philosopher later than Antipater, who was more or less contemporary with Carneades, is quoted in the On the Contradictions of the Stoics. He deduced from this terminus ante quem that Plutarch used a book of the prolific Clitomachus, the successor of Carneades at the head of the Academy, as a source for his own treatise (von Arnim 1903: XI–XIV). In my opinion, it is quite probable that this neo-Academic material was the basis of the refutation by Plutarch of his main adversary, Chrysippus. However, the idea of a single source must be rejected, since his deep knowledge of the Stoa allowed him to use his own material, at the risk of creating a great deal of disorder in the composition of these treatises. Plutarch remains in the dialectical tradition of Carneades, about whom the testimonies are fewer and often more difficult to understand.7 Indeed, in many places Carneades says that he does not want to bring a dogmatic response to the philosophical problems tackled by the Stoics, just to highlight the contradictions inherent in their argumentation. Actually, his purpose was somewhat more perverse than he declares, since Stoicism argued that it was impossible to remove one element

118

SKEPTICISM

(Cato says one letter) without destroying the whole system (Cicero, Fin. 3.74). What Jacques Brunschwig (1995) called “the conjunctive model” was both the structure and the essence of the doctrine. To highlight contradictions was not only a dialectical ploy inside the Stoic system, it aimed to demonstrate that Stoicism had no legitimacy to give satisfactory responses to any philosophical problem. In the Contradictions, Plato is never presented as the holder of the truth. At the same time, Plutarch wants to show how unfair was Chrysippus’s criticism of many aspects of Plato’s dialogues. This βοήθεια, this effort to protect Plato against inequitable attacks was already present in the ancient Academy, though there were many differences between Speusippus or Xenocrates and the founder of their school. There is no conclusive part in the Contradictions. The last paragraphs are a discussion of Chrysippus’s dogma that it is impossible to act and to follow impulse without assenting to it, a problem involving concepts like liberty, God, and the wise, but without any attempt to go outside of the anti-Stoic debate. The same polemical context characterizes the Common Notions. Though Stoic texts can seem nowadays quite difficult to understand, even for a learned reader, Zeno or Chrysippus did not want to write abstruse treatises. On the contrary, they intended to build their system on common notions, formed from representations of reality that are the same for everyone. For example, Plutarch says that it is contrary to common sense to have two τέλη, two supreme goals in life (Common Notions 1070F). That would be true if the Stoics had really asserted the existence of this duality. In fact, by saying that the τέλος was to be found in doing one’s best for reaching the goods that conform to nature, they tried to avoid the intrusion of Fortune in the field of ethics (Soreth 1968). Plutarch resumes here in a rather confused way Carneades’s polemics against Diogenes of Babylon’s and Antipater’s teleological theories, which tried to render precise Zeno’s definition of the τέλος, namely, to live in harmony. Indeed, if we only knew the On the Contradictions of the Stoics and the Against the Stoics on Common Notions, we would consider Plutarch as a philosopher in the tradition of the New Academy, differing from Carneades by his ability to openly defend Plato, without however giving a dogmatic interpretation of his thought. This could lead us to identify him as a thinker in the tradition of Philo of Larissa’s Roman Books. But things are more complex. Plutarch is not only the defender of Academic skepticism, someone who highlights the contradictions of the Stoics in their attacks against Plato, but also someone with positive Platonic beliefs.

3c  Plutarch and Plato What Jan Opsomer (1998: 127) called the “interplay between Academic and Platonic themes in Plutarch” is a very complex problem. Plutarch wrote a treatise On the Unity of the Academy from Plato Onwards, a theme developed by Philo of Larissa at the end of his life (Boys-Stones 1997: 55 n. 2), but it did not reach us. If we knew with some precision the chronology of the Moralia, it would perhaps be easier to interpret this articulation as the result of an intellectual evolution. Plutarch tackled the controversial question of the origin of Academic skepticism in the Adversus Colotem, his reply to a highly polemical work written by a disciple

MIDDLE PLATONISM AND SKEPTICISM: PLUTARCH AND FAVORINUS

119

of Epicurus against both Socrates and Arcesilaus. One of the main elements of Plutarch’s argumentation is that, far from being a foolish invention of Arcesilaus, Academic skepticism was continuous with the philosophy of doubt practiced by prestigious thinkers such as Socrates, Plato, Parmenides, and Heraclitus. Actually, Plutarch says to be grateful to Colotes and to everyone showing, though in a hostile way, that the Academic outlook came to Arcesilaus as an ancient tradition. Plutarch’s position is not fundamentally different from the one we find in Cicero, when he evokes at length the quite honorable genealogy of Academic skepticism.8 Colotes charged Socrates with being a Sophist who criticized the senses while acting in contradiction with this criticism, especially when he said that he was seeking to discover what human nature is (Plutarch, Adv. Col. 1118C). Plutarch’s reply to the Epicurean attacks against Socrates and Plato does not refute the interpretation of them as skeptics. One of the main arguments developed at length in the treatise and attributed to Arcesilaus is that which aims to demonstrate that assent is not necessary for action. The interpretation of this argument is too controversial to be discussed here. Was it defended by Arcesilaus in propria persona or only dialectically? Be that as it may, Plutarch seems to consider it a fully convincing argument. The real problem is to determine how he, the author of a treatise aiming to demonstrate the unity of the Academy throughout its complex history, could be both a Platonist and a skeptic. Plutarch, who actually defined himself as an Academic, never as a Platonist, knew about the many differences between philosophers who all referred to Plato as the inspirer of their thought. What could be for him the logic of this unity? If one accepts the concept of “metaphysical skepticism,” coined by Pierluigi Donini, it is possible to say that Plutarch’s position presents three main aspects (see Donini 1986 and Bonazzi 2016). The first is the refutation of all the doctrines proclaiming the truth of all sensations (Epicureanism) or of most of them (Stoicism). The second is that truth must be searched for in the principles identified with God, a frequent feature of Middle Platonism. The third attributes the truth only to God, so that men are reduced to looking for it carefully, without ever yielding to the temptation of asserting, as the Stoics did, that a human sophia was exactly the same as that of God, and even greater than the divine perfection, since conquered by free will. Dualism and the perfection of God are for Plutarch principles about which doubt is not allowed. That is one of the reasons why Babut suggests that his thought can be defined as a kind of fideism, speaking of “a conscious tension between the need of rationality and the divine transcendence whose manifestations go beyond the capacity to understand of our reason” (Babut 2007: 93). This is very close to the conclusion of the On the E at Delphi, where Ammonius shows that the eternity of God and human weakness, despite seeming to be contradictory, are in reality complementary (Plutarch, De E 393BC). An alternative to Babut’s fideist interpretation is Boys-Stones’s, for whom “Plutarch felt himself able to draw positive conclusions from his skepticism, and even his most Academic works—as notably the de Stoic. rep.—should still be read as vehicles for an expression of his Platonism” (Boys-Stones 1997: 55). In any case, scholarship now seems to be unanimous in having a unitarian interpretation of Plutarch’s thought, even if the formulations of this unity are different.

120

SKEPTICISM

3.4  Plutarch and Pyrrhonism The third aspect of Plutarch’s relation to skepticism is his attitude toward Pyrrhonism, a subject about which the loss of his treatise on the differences between Pyrrhonists and Academics leads us to a quasi-silence. It can seem quite strange that he could have written his anti-Stoic and anti-Epicurean treatises without any reference to neo-Pyrrhonism, though this doctrine was much closer to him from a chronological point of view. This only means that the strength of a philosophical affiliation was so compelling that discussions that were almost four centuries old could seem to Plutarch of a greater topicality than a skeptical doctrine that appeared less than two centuries earlier. He did not ignore Pyrrhonism, but he was not interested in it; he seems to want to use it as an instrument of his own reflection. In his extant writings at least, there is no allusion to the modes elaborated by Aenesidemus, though they were certainly extensively diffused at the beginning of the second century CE. The only reference to a specifically major Pyrrhonian concept—since ἐποχή was common to the Academics and the Pyrrhonists—namely, that of ἀφασία, is in the Adversus Colotem, without any precise reference to Pyrrhonism (Plutarch, Adv. Col. 1123C; see Ioppolo 1994, 2004; Bonazzi 2016). Plutarch says that the Epicurean claim that all sensations are true leads to the claim that sensation has the same degree of reliability as that ascribed to dreams and illusions. Here he establishes an implicit link between Epicureanism and Pyrrhonism, considering the later as a sort of consequence of the former. It seems that for an Academic philosopher, as he perceived himself, this intra-Hellenistic link between two forms of philosophy that rejected all forms of transcendence was of no interest.

4  FAVORINUS AND THE ACADEMY 4a  A Strange Personality Favorinus (ca. 80–160 CE) was not unknown to Plutarch, who dedicated the treatise on the principle of cold to him (Plutarch, De Prim. Frig. 945F–946A). He wrote a book on the Academic method, the title of which was Plutarch. He seems to have been an interesting, contradictory, and somewhat mysterious person. He said himself that there were three contradictions in his life (Philostratus, Vit. Soph., I, 8=test. 6 Barigazzi): (i) despite having been born in Arles, in the South of Gaul, he lived in a Greek way; (ii) despite being an eunuch, actually an hermaphrodite, he was accused of adultery; and (iii) despite having been hostile toward the emperor Hadrian, he was still alive. The testimonies about his philosophical identity are of two kinds. First, the Suda says that he was a very learned man (πολυμαθής), but more interested in rhetoric than in philosophy (Suda s.v. Favorinus = Barigazzi 1). It must be added that Eusebius evokes a polemic between him and Polemo the rhetor (Chronic. Can. 166 Schöne = Barigazzi 2). Second, Philostratus presents him as a philosopher who was considered a sophist because he was very eloquent (Vit. Soph. 1.8.1 = Barigazzi 2). He never says that Favorinus was a Pyrrhonist but affirms that his best writings were

MIDDLE PLATONISM AND SKEPTICISM: PLUTARCH AND FAVORINUS

121

his Pyrrhonian speeches, in which, despite saying that Pyrrhonists were ephectics, he allowed them to assume the functions of judges (Vit. Soph. 1.8.6). For Lucian, too, he was a philosopher, if Favorinus is the Celtic eunuch belonging to the Academic tradition who is mentioned in the Eunuch (Eun. 7 = Barigazzi 4). Gellius, who was his disciple, mentions him many times and describes him as a philosopher, without giving any precision on his philosophical affiliation. However, in a passage of the Noctes Atticae (20, 1, 10), Favorinus presents himself as belonging to a sect that preferred research over decision (inquirere potius quam decernere), a motto quite close to the definition of the Academic attitude given by Cicero.

4b  Favorinus as Platonist Favorinus was quite interested in Plato. He wrote Memorabilia, a book on the history of philosophy in which evidently Plato had a great role, a treatise on Plato (Περὶ Πλάτωνος) and another one on Forms (Περὶ ἰδεῶν), which some scholars think was a writing about rhetoric, but which could as well have been a philosophical writing. If that was the case, Barigazzi’s (1966: 171) thesis that he had criticized idealism from a skeptical point of view is merely speculative. There is no evidence that, despite being a friend of Plutarch, he thought that it was impossible to find any kind of conciliation between Platonism and skepticism. The most extensive account of his philosophical position is given by Galen, who says that like other “recent Academics” he was sometimes so fiercely ephectic that he said that even a representation (φαντασία) of the sun could not be said to be certain, and sometimes so dogmatic that he transmitted doctrines to his disciples without having a critical approach to the criteria of knowledge (Opt. Doct. 40 = Barigazzi 28–31). Galen also says that he changed his mind between his writings, since he said in his Plutarch that something could be known with certainty, while in the Alcibiades he asserted the contrary. But if we read carefully what Galen wrote, we realize that, in fact, Favorinus always spoke in a prudent, that is, probabilistic way. He never went beyond what seemed probable to him, practicing a kind of disputatio in utramque partem (antilogy) between the possibility and the impossibility of knowledge.9 Despite being a probabilist, Favorinus had a special interest in Pyrrhonism, since he wrote a treatise in ten books about the Pyrrhonian tropes, devoting one book to each of them.10 In front of so many philosophical attitudes, Eugenio Amato (2005) has defined Favorinus as a brilliant eclectic. I am not sure that was the case. Actually, Favorinus is in my opinion an extremist of what could be named “Platonocentrism,” that is to say, the Academics’ tendency to think that their school was not a school among others, but the source of philosophy as a whole. In the famous excursus of book 3 of the De oratore, Cicero affirms that Socrates and Plato were at the origin of most philosophical schools: “Many people virtually took their origin from Socrates, since different followers seized upon different aspects of his discussions, which had been varied and diverse and had branched out in all directions” (De or. 3.61, transl. May and Wisse). It is likely that for Favorinus to be close to Pyrrhonism was not to adopt a new doctrine but to display

122

SKEPTICISM

an interest in what he thought to be a variant of Academic skepticism, itself a variant of Platonism. This genetic conception of philosophy is perhaps the key to what otherwise could appear as a patchwork.

5 CONCLUSION Is the problem of the relation between skepticism and Platonism in the Middle Platonist period artificial? What seems strange to us was considered normal by many prominent philosophers of that time. From a methodological point of view, we are not bound to study ancient authors with concepts of their time. But at the same time, we cannot ignore that some of the concepts we use, and especially that of Middle Platonism, did not exist at their time. To analyze concepts is of course an essential task of historians of philosophy, but one should realize that these concepts were elements of dynamic processes of identification, implying quite a number of factors that are not all explicitly conceptualized. In ancient philosophy, as Foucault and Hadot argued, there was no clear separation between thought and life. What the subject of this chapter has shown us is that the life of traditions, often so disconcerting, is a topic at least as fascinating as the static analysis of the elements that compose them.

NOTES 1. On the outlooks of Arcesilaus and Aenesidemus, see Ioppolo’s and Castagnoli’s chapters in this book. On the controversial question of Aenesidemus’s dating, see Decleva Caizzi (1992). 2. Dillon (1977) chronologically defines this period as the one between 80 BCE and 220 CE. Other delimitations are possible, since such a dating includes Antiochus of Ascalon, which is controversial. On this, see Sedley (2012). 3. On this point, see Tarrant (1985) and Bonazzi (2003: 79–212). It seems difficult to adopt for the Commentary a date later than the first century BCE. 4. The text that has reached us in an Armenian version is Quaestiones in Genesim 3.33. 5. See Striker (1983: 97), who considers it likely that Philo was a contemporary of Aenesidemus, a quite improbable hypothesis in my opinion. The absence of “the skeptical framework” in Philo’s exposition of the modes is not a convincing argument, since we have no proof that Aenesidemus’s framework of the tropes was the same as the one found in Sextus. 6. See Babut (2004: 18), for whom the most probable date of composition is ca. 80 CE. 7. On Carneades, see Thorsrud’s chapter in this book. 8. The main difference between Cicero and Plutarch is that the former does not mention Heraclitus. 9. On Favorinus’s use of antilogy, see Amato and Julien (2005: 180–181). 10. On Favorinus and the Pyrrhonists, see Ioppolo (1993).

MIDDLE PLATONISM AND SKEPTICISM: PLUTARCH AND FAVORINUS

123

REFERENCES Amato, Eugenio. 2005. “L’éclectique.” In E. Amato and Y. Julien (eds.), Favorinos d’Arles: Œuvres, Tome 1. Introduction générale. Témoignages. Discours aux Corinthiens sur la Fortune, 167–176. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. Amato, Eugenio and Yvette Julien. 2005. Favorinos d’Arles: Œuvres, Tome 1. Introduction générale. Témoignages. Discours aux Corinthiens sur la Fortune. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. Babut, Daniel. 1967. Plutarque et le stoïcisme. Paris: PUF. Babut, Daniel. 2002. Plutarque: Œuvres morales. Traité 72: Sur les notions communes contre les Stoïciens. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. Babut, Daniel. 2004. Plutarque: Œuvres morales. Traité 70: Sur les contradictions des Stoïciens. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. Babut, Daniel. 2007. “L’unité de l’Académie selon Plutarque. Notes en marge d’un débat ancien et toujours actuel.” In M. Bonazzi, C. Lévy, and C. Steel (eds.), A Platonic Pythagoras: Platonism and Pythagoreanism in the Imperial Age, 63–98. Turnhout: Brepols. Barigazzi, Adelmo. 1966. Favorino d’Arelate. Opere. Introduzione, testo critico e commento. Florence: Le Monnier. Bonazzi, Mauro. 2003. Academici e Platonici. Il debattito antico sullo scetticismo di Platone. Milano: LED. Bonazzi, Mauro. 2008. “L’offerta di Plutarco. Teologia e filosofia nel De E apud Delphos (capitoli 1–2),” Philologus 152: 205–211. Bonazzi, Mauro. 2011. “Again on Sextus on Aenesidemus and Plato.” In D. Machuca (ed.), New Essays on Ancient Pyrrhonism, 11–20. Leiden: Brill. Bonazzi, Mauro. 2012. “Plutarch on the Difference between the Pyrrhonists and the Academics,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 43: 271–298. Bonazzi, Mauro. 2016. “Le platonisme de Plutarque de Cheronée entre scepticisme, théologie et métaphysique.” In A.-I. Bouton-Touboulic and C. Lévy (eds.). Scepticisme et religion: Constantes et évolutions, de la philosophie hellénistique à la philosophie médiévale, 75–88. Turnhout: Brepols. Boys-Stones, George. 1997. “Thyrsus-Bearer of the Academy or Enthusiast for Plato? Plutarch’s De Stoicorum repugnantiis.” In J. Mossman (ed.), Plutarch and His Intellectual World, 41–58. London: Duckworth. Bréhier, Émile. 1907. Les idées philosophiques et religieuses de Philon d’Alexandrie. Paris: Picard. Brittain, Charles. 2001. Philo of Larissa: The Last of the Academic Sceptics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brunschwig, Jacques. 1995. “Le modèle conjonctif.” In his Études sur les philosophies hellénistiques, 161–187. Paris: PUF. (First published in 1978.) Decleva Caizzi, Fernanda. 1992. “Aenesidemus and the Academy,” Classical Quarterly 42: 176–189. Dillon, John. 1996. The Middle Platonists: 80 B.C. to A.D. 220. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. (First published in 1977.) Donini, Pierluigi. 1986. “Lo scetticismo accademico, Aristotele e l’unità della tradizione platonica secondo Plutarco.” In G. Cambiano (ed.), Storiografia e dossografia nella filosofia antica, 203–214. Torino: Tirrenia stampatori.

124

SKEPTICISM

Frazier, Françoise. 2008. “Philosophie et religion dans la pensée de Plutarque. Quelques réflexions autour des emplois du mot πίστις,” Études platoniciennes 5: 41–62. Glucker, John. 1978. Antiochus and the Late Academy. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. Hershbell, Jackson P. 1992. “Plutarch and Epicureanism.” In W. Haase (ed.), Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt 36 (5), 3353–3383. Berlin: de Gruyter. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 1993. “The Academic Position of Favorinus of Arelate,” Phronesis 38: 183–213. Ioppolo, Anna Maria. 1994. “Accademici e Pirroniani nel II secolo d.C.” In A. Alberti (ed.), Realtà e ragione. Studi di filosofica antica, 85–103. Florence: L.S. Olschki. Isnardi Parente, Margherita. 1988. “Plutarco contro Colote.” In I. Gallo (ed.), Aspetti dello stoicismo e dell’epicureismo in Plutarco, 65–88. Ferrara. Lévy, Carlos. 2005. “Deux problèmes doxographiques chez Philon d’Alexandrie: Posidonius et Énésidème.” In A. Brancacci (ed.), Philosophy and Doxography in the Imperial Age, 103–120. Florence: Leo S. Olschi. Lévy, Carlos. 2008. “La conversion du scepticisme chez Philon d’Alexandrie.” In F. Alesse (ed.), Philo of Alexandria and Post-Aristotelian Philosophy, 103–120. Leiden: Brill. Lévy, Carlos. 2009. “Favorinus et les Academica,” Revue des Études Anciennes 111: 45–54. Lévy, Carlos. 2013. “Plutarque juge et partie: à propos des débats entre l’Académie, le Jardin et le Portique,” Aitia 3. May, M. James and Jakob Wisse. 2001. Cicero on the Ideal Orator. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. Opsomer, Jan. 1998. In Search of the Truth. Academic Tendencies in Middle Platonism. Bruxelles: Koninklijke Academie voor Wetenschappen. Sedley, David. 2012. Antiochus of Ascalon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Soreth, Marion. 1968. “Der zweite Telosformel des Antipater vor Tarsos,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 50: 48–72. Striker, Gisela. 1983. “The Ten Tropes of Aenesidemus.” In M. Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition, 95–116. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Tarrant, Harold. 1985. Scepticism or Platonism? The Philosophy of the Fourth Academy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. von Arnim, Hans. 1888. Quellenstudien zu Philon. Berlin: Weidmann. von Arnim, Hans. 1901. Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta. Leipzig: Teubner.

CHAPTER TEN

Sextus Empiricus TAD BRENNAN AND CLIFF ROBERTS

1 INTRODUCTION There is no evidence that, in his own day, Sextus Empiricus was a figure of any great prominence. If we look to sources outside his writings, we find only a few contemporaries who mention him, in lists of teachers and students, and they credit him with no philosophical innovations (DL IX 116; Ps-Galen 14.683). If we look inside his writings, we find a clever and competent compiler of other people’s arguments, who claims no originality for either the structure or contents of his works. For all that we know, it may be that in his own day Sextus was a very minor figure. But accidents of transmission have led to his becoming a very major figure indeed for the modern era. In the history of skepticism in the West, Sextus is central and indispensable: he is the conduit through which the most copious streams of Ancient Greek skepticism flooded into Renaissance Europe, with effects both cataclysmic and fertilizing.1 In St. Paul’s Cathedral in London, a modest plaque marks the tomb of Christopher Wren, its architect. It reads “Lector, si monumentum requiris, circumspice.” So too, the reader looking for a fitting monument to the influence of Sextus Empiricus may look around this book as a whole, and see something of his influence in nearly every chapter. In the present chapter, we devote Section 2 to an overview of the life and works of Sextus Empiricus. We then introduce the problem of how to characterize the philosophical project of Pyrrhonism, and in particular its claim to offer practical guidance in living (Section 3). This problem has been discussed extensively in the literature, and we focus on two especially influential proponents of opposing viewpoints, Michael Frede and Myles Burnyeat (Section 4). In Section 5, we consider controversies about how to understand Sextus’s use of Modes of Skeptical argumentation.

126

SKEPTICISM

2  OVERVIEW OF THE LIFE AND WORKS OF SEXTUS EMPIRICUS The evidence for Sextus’s life is “frightfully meager,” as Burnyeat (1984: 242) put it—estimates of his dates range anywhere within a century on either side of 200 CE. His location can be specified with comparable imprecision—he probably lived in a major city somewhere in the Mediterranean basin. Scholarly arguments for locating him in Rome or Alexandria turn out to be tissue-thin, as House (1980) has shown. He is clearly a follower of the Neo-Pyrrhonian School of Aenesidemus. He is very well informed about the main philosophical schools of the period from 300 BCE to 100 BCE, but he seems curiously unaware of philosophical developments in the centuries closer to him. We must imagine that he or his sources had access to a good library, given the many texts that he quotes; but nothing about his works suggest that he is in daily contact with a community of philosophers, whether of his own school or opponents. The reasons to think he was a medical doctor begin with the name “Empiricus,” attached to him in his own manuscripts and in the two contemporary references, which suggest that he was connected with the Empiricist school of medicine. The picture is somewhat confused by his stated preference for the Methodical school of medicine, but not in a way that speaks against his having been a trained physician (PH I 237–241). He also refers at two points to treatises that he wrote on medicine2; these and a treatise “On the Soul” have not survived (ΑΜ X 84). The works that have survived are three: a treatise in three books called Outlines of Pyrrhonism (cited as PH from the initials of its Latin title); a treatise in six books called Against the Professors (AM, likewise from its Latin title), and a treatise in five books of the same name (AM VII–XI), but composed independently of the second, six-book treatise. The Outlines begins with an overview of the Skeptical system (PH I), before turning to the detailed refutations of dogmatic theories of logic and epistemology (PH II), and physics, theology, and ethics (PH III). In AM I–VI, Sextus offers arguments against the advocates of the liberal arts, sc. grammar, rhetoric, geometry, arithmetic, astronomy, and music (in that order). In AM VII–VIII, he investigates theories of logic and epistemology; in AM IX–X he investigates physics and theology; and in AM XI he investigates ethics. As that brief account indicates, Sextus gives us two separate treatments of each of the main topics in philosophy: logic and epistemology are discussed both in AM VII–VIII and in PH II; physics in AM VIII–IX and in PH III, and ethics in AM XI and PH III. Much material is reused, though seldom through verbatim copying from one treatise to another. And indeed, scholars disagree about which of the two sources was written earlier. Janáček (1963) argued that the shorter, more summary treatments in PH were written before the fuller treatments in AM, but Bett (commentary to Sextus 1997) has argued for the opposing view. Most of the material in these treatises is, by design, quoted from dogmatic philosophers. Sextus begins his investigation of a given dogmatic tenet by presenting the view at length before arguing against it. Often his counterarguments, too,

SEXTUS EMPIRICUS

127

are drawn from dogmatic sources. As a result, his works are a treasure-trove of dogmatic arguments, as well as skeptical arguments. His reporting of earlier schools is generally fair and accurate, so far as we are in a position to judge the matter, and accordingly his evidentiary value is very high. However, precisely because so much of his work consists in quotations, it is also not directly useful for understanding his own Skeptical outlook. Sextus had no philosophical dogmata—so he claims—but he did practice a way of life. And he does offer us a variety of comments and explanations about what he does as a Skeptic.

3  SEXTUS’S SKEPTICAL OUTLOOK: SKEPTICAL VERSUS DOGMATIC ASSENT The clearest and most direct statement of his own understanding of the Skeptical outlook and life is given by Sextus in the first book of PH, in particular, §§1–35. The outlook there portrayed is a (perhaps turbulent) marriage of two separate aspects. The first aspect captures our familiar contemporary view of skepticism as exclusively destructive.3 Sextus defines the Skeptic as someone who possesses the ability, when faced with any claim, to generate an equally strong case for its contrary. The Skeptic, and anyone else exposed to the competing arguments and considerations pro and con, then has no better reason to assent to the given claim than to its contrary. Since the Skeptic cannot assent to both claims (they are, after all, contraries), her most natural recourse is the suspension of assent (ἐποχή) with respect to claims: to assent neither to the claim nor to its contrary. Yet a virtue can be made of what appears, at first, to be mere rational necessity, for the Skeptic discovers, upon suspending belief, that she has achieved some measure of peace of mind, what the Skeptic calls “quietude” or “freedom from disturbance” (ἀταραξία), which is the final end of the Skeptical philosophy. It is no wonder, then, that Sextus devotes the lion’s share of the first book of PH to characterizing the elaborate and various forms of argument—called “Modes” (τρόποι)—by means of which ἐποχή is to be secured; for without a sufficiently robust armory of such arguments, there is little hope of securing ἐποχή, and beyond it, the grail of ἀταραξία.4 Neither ἐποχή nor ἀταραξία makes a life; the former, in particular, is a merely negative stance of withholding assent. Yet the Skeptic, in Sextus’s words, “cannot help but be active” (PH I 23), and a distinctively human life, one given structure and content by reasons, seems to demand assent. Without assent a human is reduced to a merely vegetative life, a life without action. This apparent conflict need not perturb the Skeptic, for the Skeptic’s commitment to ἐποχή is fully consistent—so Sextus insists—with the Skeptic’s giving assent, when this assent is limited to the standard or criterion of “appearances” or “what is apparent.” This is the second or positive aspect of Sextus’s Skepticism, which is less familiar to contemporary readers (PH I 19–24, 29–30). It is appearances to which the Skeptic assents in living her life, and it is appearances that determine a quite ordinary life lived in light of the natural human capacities for thought and sensation, the constraint of feelings (e.g., of thirst and hunger), the familiar customs and laws, and the teachings of the crafts (PH I 23). While it is true that these appearances are objects of Skeptical

128

SKEPTICISM

assent, her assent on these matters is consistent with her advocacy of ἐποχή, since she withholds assent only to the “things underlying” (ὑποκείμενα) appearances, not to the appearances themselves. These ὑποκείμενα are precisely the objects of that form of assent, dogmatic assent, which the Skeptic avoids at all costs. Thus the Skeptic aspires to navigate the twin perils of inaction and dogmatic assent. Whether this aspiration can be realized has been the subject of much scholarly controversy. A verdict on this issue presupposes answers to specific questions about the difference between dogmatic and Skeptical assent: is it a difference in the object of assent or a difference in the kind of assent? Is Skeptical assent to be understood, like dogmatic assent, as assent to the truth of a claim? Does it constitute what we would now think of as belief? What are the “apparent” or “evident” matters to which the Skeptic may assent, and how are they to be distinguished from the topics about which the Skeptic suspends? Very different answers to these questions have been given by interpreters, and it is to those answers that we now turn.

4  INTERPRETING SEXTUS ON ASSENT: FREDE AND BURNYEAT For the last four decades, philosophical discussions of how the Pyrrhonist lives have been dominated by the work of Michael Frede and Myles Burnyeat, and the reactions that their work has provoked. In two papers, Frede (1979, 1984) argued for a radical revision of the standard understanding of Sextus’s philosophy and accompanied this rereading of Sextus with a novel account of the development of ancient skepticism as a whole. In two other papers, Burnyeat (1980, 1984) argued for a more traditional, Humean understanding of Sextus. These papers are brilliant examples of how to write the history of philosophy, engaging with questions of the broadest philosophical scope as well as the most minute philological detail. They deserve and repay repeated study. That said, they can be frustrating because of their difficulty and obscurity.5 In the next two sections, we will discuss the work of Frede and of Burnyeat.

4a  Frede’s Sextus Empiricus In his first paper on skepticism, Frede (1979) drew attention to the fact that Sextus claims not to eschew all beliefs in general, but only dogmatic beliefs, that is, beliefs about “non-evident” or “non-apparent” matters, matters of dogmatic investigation. Frede proposed that the scope of the “evident” is very inclusive; Sextus possesses an extensive collection of beliefs that are quite ordinary in their character and subject matter. The Pyrrhonian Skeptic goes through his or her day believing most of the things that anyone else believes about the ordinary objects and events in their world. What the Pyrrhonist feels no inclination either to accept or to deny are the theories of the Dogmatic schools, and their elaborate, non-evident stories about Democritean atoms, Platonic forms, Aristotelian entelechies, and so on. Believing in those things is what makes one a Dogmatist. But through his investigations of these theoretical posits, and through his ability to construct arguments in opposition to the Democritean, Platonic, and so on arguments for special entities and theories, the

SEXTUS EMPIRICUS

129

Pyrrhonist has come to feel that the case for and against all of these things is perfectly equipollent. As a result, he suspends judgment about their existence. But doing so is fully compatible with believing all of the ordinary things that non-philosophers believe about the world around them. And since the Skeptic has very nearly the same number and kind of beliefs that any ordinary person has, the traditional question of how a Skeptic can live without any beliefs simply never arises. So far as their ordinary interactions with tables, chairs, food, cliffs, and the other people in their lives, the Skeptic lives just as anyone else lives. That, in broad outline, is the reading that Frede advanced. When we move to the details of Frede’s reading, however, it becomes more complex and obscure. The complexity is not in itself a defect in Frede’s reading; any adequate interpretation of a complex philosophical text will have to be a complex interpretation. The obscurity, however, is a lamentable artifact of Frede’s own failure to make his views clear. The crux of the problem is his characterization of the difference between the beliefs that Pyrrhonists may have (about “evident” or “apparent” matters), and those that they reject as dogmatic (concerning the “non-evident”). At first sight, it may seem that the difference is one of content—the Pyrrhonist may believe in the evident chairs around them, but not in the non-evident Form of the Chair. But it is fairly clear that this could not have been what Sextus meant, and that it is not what Frede thought he meant. We can see this because Sextus sometimes attacks beliefs as dogmatic even when they have the same content as beliefs he elsewhere accepts. As Frede says, “it is not the content of theoretical views . . . that makes them dogmatic views; it is, rather, the attitude of the dogmatist” (1979: 195). So it is clear that Frede did not think that the difference between evident and non-evident matters is one of disjoint subject matters. However, it can be very difficult to tell where precisely Frede does locate the crucial difference. In parts of his first paper, he suggests that the difference between the Skeptic’s beliefs and the Dogmatist’s beliefs consists in the difference between believing that P and believing that it is true that P; or passively believing P and actively believing P; or implicitly and explicitly believing P; or unconsciously and consciously believing P. Fine (2000) does a thorough and excellent job of showing insurmountable problems with all of these glosses. In his second paper, Frede distinguished between “holding a view” that P and “taking a position” that P. Frede clearly wanted these phrases to convey some distinction, but on their own they get us no further toward understanding what he meant. We are inclined to find the core of Frede’s view in a different set of glosses that he sometimes uses, according to which the Dogmatic beliefs present themselves as part of an ultimate scientific theory of the world: [Dogmatic beliefs claim to contain] deeper insights into the true nature of things. (Frede 1979: 179) [I]t is characteristic of the dogmatists that they believe it is possible to go behind the surface phenomena to the essence of things, to the nature of things, to true reality. (Frede 1979: 187) [The Skeptic does not think that his impressions are] such that they will come out true on the true theory of things. (Frede 1984: 210)

130

SKEPTICISM

[In dogmatic assent, one] commits oneself to a belief about what will come out as true on the true theory of things, about what would turn out to be true if one really knew what things are like. (Frede 1984: 215) Dogmatists think that the philosophical project, the ζήτησις that they began along with the Pyrrhonists, aims at the ultimate possession of a deep, explanatory, comprehensive, rationally justified theory of the world; a scientific knowledge of the nature of things, expressed in the language of science, whose nouns name the real entities and whose predicates map the real properties of the world. This is the kind of theory whose possession will purge our lives of anomaly and disturbance. Once one has it, one will be able to say individual true things, of course, but far more than that: one will have scientific knowledge of the true things one says and be able to show, for any truth one utters, exactly how one’s grasp of it counts as knowledge, how it is justified by its place in the total system. It is possible that the Pyrrhonists share or shared (in the beginning) some parts of this characterization of the project, the ultimate aim of their ongoing ζήτησις. But the Dogmatists think that their school already has attained it, or some large coherent fragment of it, and that the pronouncements they make as members of that school are already deliverances of that ultimate theory. They are not merely true; they are a part of the ultimate true theory, and so inherit from it those features of consistency, coherence, explanatory adequacy, ideal vocabulary, and so on. This, so far as we can tell, is the reason that Frede sometimes wrote as though the essence of the Dogmatic stance was the additional belief that P is true; he was using “true” as a shorthand for “is a deliverance of the ultimate true, explanatory, rationally justified, etc. theory,” or as he says, “is true on the true theory.” “For them [sc. Dogmatists], those things count as truths which on the true account of things would come out as truths” (1984: 210, 215). In the modest sense of “true” in which every belief that P entails believing that it is true that P (which we take to be the normal sense of “true,” as well as the normal account of belief), it is clearly not the case that “taking something to be true” means “committing oneself to its being explanatory, expressed in the ideal vocabulary, and so on”—that is, the whole long range of properties that Frede abbreviates by calling them “true.” Fine (2000) raised a number of decisive points against the idea that a Skeptic can believe P without believing that P is true, in the ordinary sense of “believe” and “true.” We think that Frede’s best response would be simply to concede that she is right, and that he was using “true” and “truth” in a nonstandard sense. It is a sense with some parallels among ancient Dogmatists—for example, Parmenides’s “Way of Truth” or the Stoic idea that only the Stoic Sage has “truth”—but it is certainly not the normal sense of “truth.” This is how Sextus understands what it is to be a Dogmatist and what it is to assent to something dogmatically: to assent to something dogmatically is to arrogate to one’s belief the status of ultimacy, to present it as part of the ultimate theory of everything. When one reflects on the writings of actual Dogmatists such as Plato, Aristotle, or Chrysippus, this characterization of them may seem unfair. There is much that is tentative and provisional in their work, places where one can see that their thoughts

SEXTUS EMPIRICUS

131

are still developing and will continue to develop. If Frede’s Sextus characterizes dogmatic belief in terms of granting something the status of ultimacy, it seems that Plato, Aristotle, and Chrysippus turn out not have been uniformly dogmatic after all, and this outcome may look like an objection to Frede’s characterization of Sextus’s position. But it is not. For the same mismatch between the figure of the Dogmatist in Sextus and the actual schools that Sextus opposes is clear from the opening lines of the work. The Dogmatists of PH I 1 are figures whose searching has terminated, because they claim to have discovered the truth. It is clear to us as sensitive readers of Plato (e.g.,) that this misrepresents his attitude toward many of his own doctrines; his own searching was by no means at an end when he wrote his dialogues. But Sextus clearly characterizes Plato and other Dogmatists as people who believe that their answers have put an end to searching. Frede is not misrepresenting Sextus on this point; but is Sextus misrepresenting his opponents? Is “the Dogmatist” in Sextus merely an idealization or projection rather than an accurate report of people whom Sextus had met or whose writings he had read? The answer is presumably mixed, inasmuch as the historical figures themselves had mixed attitudes toward their own views. Plato, for instance, seems to have been willing to try a number of competing characterizations of the “participation-relation” between Forms and particulars; nothing in his writing suggests that he thought he had worked out that part of his doctrine in a final form. By contrast, his attitudes toward such statements as “There are gods” and “Virtue is good” look to be clear cases of Dogmatism, whether by Sextus’s characterization in the opening trichotomy of PH I 1, or by Frede’s criterion of ultimacy: Plato thought his search with respect to those questions had ended with the successful discovery of truths that would form parts of the ultimate true theory of everything. Whatever else might change as his doctrine evolved, these claims would remain unaltered. If Plato’s own attitude toward his doctrine was a mixture of the tentative and the dogmatic, Epicureanism featured an even higher proportion of the dogmatic, and even less invitation to future revision or innovation. Finally, when we consider the Stoics, it is worth remembering that, according to their own theory of assent (which formed the structural basis for the Skeptic doctrine of assent and suspension), one should assent to an impression only when it is cataleptic, that is, true, guaranteed to be true by its content, and of such a sort that if a Sage were to assent to it, her assent would be unshakeable by any rational argumentation. No future findings of philosophy or science could give the Sage reason to reverse their assent or revise their views on this topic. Here the Skeptical equation of dogma with ultimacy is entirely justified. So the Skeptic conception of dogmatic assent is not a gross distortion of the ambitions of Sextus’s opponents, though it also does not apply to all of their practices. Many of his opponents put forward many of their views as though they were the deliverances of the final, ultimate theory, which would be vindicated by any future perfected version of philosophy. Such views are the Skeptic’s lawful prey. True, some Dogmatists put forward some of their views as provisional or tentative hypotheses awaiting development. But it is not unfair for Sextus to attack these views, either, given that the attack simply culminates in a request that the Dogmatist not assent to them in a dogmatic way. And if the view in question was advanced by

132

SKEPTICISM

the Dogmatist in a merely provisional or tentative way, then the Dogmatist does not need to do anything new in order to comply with the Skeptic’s request. Because the Skeptic rejects only dogmatic pronouncements, that is, assertions that arrogate to themselves the status of ultimacy, the Skeptic can consistently have and use a wide range of other beliefs about ordinary life. The non-philosopher thinks it is day, and thinks that it is true that it is day, but does not have any view about whether the ultimate theory of the world will make reference to “days” or eliminate them in favor of some purified vocabulary. The Pyrrhonists do the same, both about days and about the rest of their ordinary practical life. This expansion in the range of the Pyrrhonist’s beliefs leads directly to a contraction in the range of the Pyrrhonist’s ἀταραξία. All interpretations of Sextus must agree that he promises tranquility with respect to the prohibited dogmatic opinions and moderated disturbance with respect to what is necessary.6 But this boundary or surface between the necessitated things and the realm of dogmatic opinion shifts a great deal between rival interpretations. The classic Humean reading has the surface shrink to a minuscule bubble inside the Pyrrhonist’s own mind; within that bubble, Skeptics will necessarily have appearances and suffer the moderate affections of being appeared to in various ways. But they can attain tranquility outside that bubble by refusing to believe that there is a war on, not assenting that their family was just captured by the enemy, suspending judgment about whether they are being trussed up for execution, and so on. On Frede’s reading, the realm of moderate affections moves outward to encompass ordinary life, including families and wars, and the realm of tranquility shrinks to a sphere around the doctrinal posturings of the Dogmatic schools. The Pyrrhonist has little choice but to suffer the ordinary injuries, both physical and mental, that ordinary people are prey to; and they are content if they can share only moderately in the frailties of flesh. But they can achieve one important kind of tranquility: they can resist adding on to their inevitable injuries the voluntary and self-inflicted disturbance that comes from fanatical devotion to a speculative creed. Much less is being promised by the Pyrrhonist on this reading; they can offer little advantage over ordinary life. But, as they have learned, no other school can credibly offer any great advantage, either. And the Skeptic can offer a huge advantage over the rival Dogmatic schools: they can show you how not to worsen your life with dogma. They offer no miracle cure for ordinary suffering—injuries, worries, grief, and pain are all necessary concomitants of life. It is the Dogmatists who offer miracle cures, and the Pyrrhonists can show you that they are all charlatans and quacks, whose remedies give you a new disease you did not have before. That, in outline, is the picture that Frede offers. It allows Sextus to give a very robust answer to the traditional charge that the life of the Skeptic is not livable: the Skeptic in this view can live a very ordinary life indeed, with the same beliefs, actions, attitudes, desires, and so on that the ordinary person has.

4b Burnyeat’s Sextus Empiricus Burnyeat’s first article was written largely without reference to Frede’s work; only the sixth of its seven sections (“Controversial Interlude”) acknowledges Frede’s reading

SEXTUS EMPIRICUS

133

of Skepticism, and it does so in order to consider it as a possible objection to the paper’s main conclusions and then dismiss it. Otherwise, the paper advances a view of Skepticism that is traditional in its verdicts (inspired by Hume, a long quotation from whom begins the paper), although brilliantly sophisticated in its methods. Those main verdicts are two: first, that if it were possible to live the life that Sextus describes, it would be horrible, repellent, and sub-human: “The life without belief is not an achievement of the will, but a paralysis of reason by itself” (Burnyeat 1980: 42). Second, Burnyeat argues that the description of the life is incoherent in any case: it claims to be a life without belief, but the central elements of the Skeptic’s life—opposing arguments, equipollence, suspension, and tranquility—all require to be explained in terms of belief. This is the burden of the last section of the paper. Burnyeat’s article, too, contains some puzzles. To begin with, he claims early in the paper that the word “true” in Ancient Greek philosophical contexts means “‘true of a real objective world’ . . . as distinct from mere appearance . . . . Statements which merely record how things appear . . . are not called true or false” (1980: 25–26). He then notes that belief involves “the accepting of something as true,” and then concludes that there can be no beliefs about how things appear, since there is no truth about such matters. In line with this distinction, Burnyeat argues that assents to matters of real existence constitute beliefs, and are contrasted with assents to appearances, which are not beliefs and do not have truth-values (1980: 26–27). It is quite unclear how Burnyeat intended to establish or argue for his claim that truth in Greek philosophical contexts is restricted to beliefs about “matters of real existence.” This is not something that one can look up in a dictionary, nor are there ancient statements to this effect. Barnes (1982: n. 21) and Fine (2000) have both rejected this line of argument, and in the article Burnyeat does little more than assert it. It is unsurprising, therefore, that later interpreters such as Fine (2000) and Perin (2010a,b) have accepted Burnyeat’s claim that Skeptical assent pertains only to subjective matters of appearance (not objective matters about the world), while rejecting his further claim that such assent cannot be viewed as belief, that is, as assent to the truth of the subjective matters. The claim that “truth” cannot apply to appearances plays a central role in Burnyeat’s arguments. It leads immediately to the conclusion that the Skeptic cannot have any beliefs. For Sextus says he assents only to appearances, but (according to Burnyeat) appearances have no truth-values, and things without truth-values cannot be beliefs (Burnyeat 1980: 26). Since Burnyeat takes the Pyrrhonist to have no beliefs whatsoever, he assumes that Pyrrhonian suspension and tranquility must also occur without beliefs, on pain of inconsistency. Accordingly, he imagines that the Pyrrhonist will claim, not that they believe that opposed arguments are equipollent, but that the opposed arguments merely appear to them to be equipollent, without their believing that they are. (This sort of appearance claim is called by both Frede and Burnyeat a “non-epistemic” appearance claim, but we agree with Fine (2000: 83 fn. 11) that it is more useful and more accurate to call it a “non-doxastic” appearance claim, since the speaker disavows even the correlative belief, much less the correlative knowledge). And here Burnyeat protests: “this appearance, so called, being the effect of argument, is only

134

SKEPTICISM

to be made sense of in terms of reason, belief, and truth—the very notions the sceptic is most anxious to avoid” (1980: 50). Furthermore, he argues that no tranquility can be produced by suspension unless the Skeptic is “in some sense satisfied . . . that no answers are forthcoming, that contrary claims are indeed equal . . . How can Sextus then deny that this is something he believes?” (1980: 52). So Burnyeat’s Skeptic is committed to beliefs at two stages in the process: “[b]oth the causes (reasoned argument) . . . and the effects (tranquillity) are such as to justify us in calling it a state of belief” (1980: 52). In pressing the argument against the first stage, Burnyeat anticipates that the Pyrrhonist will claim that opposed arguments merely appear equipollent. But he denies they can do so coherently: “In the philosophical case, the impression, when all is said and done, simply is my assent to the conclusion of an argument, assent to it as true” (Burnyeat 1980: 53). This argument is rather mysterious. Why can it not appear to someone that two arguments are of equal weight, without her believing that they really are? And what does it mean to say that “the impression . . . simply is my assent”? This last phrase, although it makes an attractive slogan, is surely a category mistake, given the terms of Hellenistic epistemology. An impression is a sort of state, a static configuration of one’s soul; an assent is a movement of one’s soul.7 No state can be a movement. And in particular, no impression can ever be anything more than a possible object for some psychic action such as entertaining, assenting, rejecting, investigating, and so on. Impressions stand to assents as propositions stand to propositional attitudes, and to say “the impression just is an assent” is no more sensible than saying “the proposition just is a wondering whether.” Burnyeat seems to be aware that he has overstated his case, since in the next sentences he talks more carefully of the impression “presupposing” or “including” assent, and of its being not “independent of” assent. So presumably what he meant was not that the impression at issue “simply is” an assent, but rather that it somehow presupposes one or more assents. Since the impression at issue is an impression that two arguments are of equal weight, then perhaps this is his thought: if I have the impression that A and B are both equally probative arguments, then I must have assented, previous to having this comparative impression, to the two earlier impressions that A is a probative argument and B is a probative argument. But that simply raises a second round of questions: why can I not have the impression that A is a probative argument, without assenting to that impression (and likewise for B)?8 Here Burnyeat’s response might be: the impression that A is a probative argument is not (of course) itself an assent, but it depends, in turn, on earlier assents, as for instance my assenting to the impressions that A is formally valid, and that the premises of A are cogent and plausible. So my impression of equipollence “includes” and “presupposes” my assent to impressions of probative force, and my impressions of probative force “include” and “presuppose” my assents to impressions of validity and cogency. The impressions at every higher level presupposes assents to the impressions at lower levels. But do they? Why cannot the form appear valid and the premises cogent, without my assenting to those appearances? Why cannot the entire practice of Skeptical argument build up from the lowest level with nothing but a sequence of impressions,

SEXTUS EMPIRICUS

135

to which no assents are forthcoming? I have the impression that certain premises are cogent, and that certain forms are valid; as to whether they are or not, I suspend judgment. I have the impression that the argument they constitute is probative, but I do not assent to its being so. I have the impression that a pair of such forms, filled out with such premises, is roughly balanced in its force; nonetheless no assent eventuates. Burnyeat does not seem to have a way to rule this out. Perhaps at this juncture he switches to the second stage of the argument and appeals to the “effects” of suspension, instead of its “causes”: if I am not “convinced by the argument[s]” on both side, and then convinced of their equality of weight, then I will not be “in some sense satisfied . . . that contrary claims are indeed equal,” and thus no tranquility will ensue (Burnyeat 1980: 53). Nothing short of assent can alleviate my worries. Perhaps this was Burnyeat’s thought in this passage. But if so, then he could have convicted the Skeptic of having beliefs in much easier ways. Nothing especially philosophical needs to be introduced; we may simply suppose the Skeptic is sitting comfortably in a chair. The Skeptic will claim to suspend judgment about whether the chair will continue to hold him up or will disappear and drop him abruptly to the floor—there are arguments on both sides, after all. But the comfortable Skeptic will also manifest no concern about the possibility of being dropped abruptly to the floor. If, according to Burnyeat, nothing short of assent can alleviate the Skeptic’s worries, then the unworried chair-sitter must be “in some sense satisfied” that the chair will not disappear. And how can he then deny that this is something he believes? Our point is that this problem of tranquility is perfectly general, and has no special connection to philosophical impressions. There is a general question, applicable to both chairs and equipollence: “how can you be tranquil about danger D, when you suspend judgment about whether D impends?” If the Skeptic cannot answer it for chairs, then Burnyeat can make his point without the complexities of arguments and equipollence and philosophical impressions. If the Skeptic can answer it, then the answer will serve just as well for equipollence as for chairs. And put in terms of chairs, the Skeptic answer should be familiar. When asked why “someone who suspends judgment does not rush away to a mountain instead of to the bath,” Plutarch answers on behalf of the Academic Skeptics, “because, of course, it is not the mountain but the bath that appears a bath to him” (1122E, trans. LS). The Skeptic is careful around cliffs and comfortable in chairs because it is the cliff, not the chair, that appears dangerous to him. In the same way, the Skeptic can be comfortable with equipollence because the arguments appear equipollent. Assent is not a precondition of tranquility. So the claim that the Skeptic’s suspensive practice commits him to beliefs, either in its causes or its effects, does not strike us as successful. And the claim that the life without belief is a “paralysis of reason” is based on the idea that the Skeptic can have no beliefs of any sort, which in turn is based on an idiosyncratic claim about Greek theories of “truth.” It also does not take account of Frede’s suggestion that the Skeptic has a wide variety of beliefs that can be employed in life. Burnyeat’s second article “The Skeptic in his Place and Time” is presented as a direct response to Frede’s reading (1984: fn. 13). He argues that Frede is attributing

136

SKEPTICISM

to Sextus a strategy of “insulating” some areas of discourse from other areas of discourse. If one “insulates” the claims of ordinary life from the claims of philosophy, then they cannot clash or contradict; we may claim philosophically that there is no such thing as time, while claiming in ordinary life that there is enough time to catch the train, without either claim “affecting or being affected by” the other (Burnyeat 1984: 227). No ancient Skeptic, Burnyeat argues, ever practiced insulation. Thus Frede’s reading of Sextus is anachronistic, attributing to him a view he could not possibly have had. That is a rough outline of Burnyeat’s strategy in the article. But in detail it goes slightly differently. He introduces at least two kinds of “insulating” readings of skepticism, one derived from Gassendi and Montaigne that he calls “insulation by subject matter,” or the “Country Gentleman’s Interpretation,” the other derived from Kant, which he refers to as “insulation by level,” or “transcendental skepticism” (Burnyeat 1984: 233, 252). On the Country Gentleman’s Interpretation, a Skeptic scrutinizes such philosophical posits as Platonic Forms and Epicurean atoms but accepts as evident our ordinary talk of tables and chairs. On the transcendental reading, there is no distinction of subject matter, but rather “two ways of understanding a statement like ‘The stove is warm,’ the plain way and the philosophical way, and it is only the philosophical claim to an absolute knowledge that the sceptic wants to question” (Burnyeat 1984: 252). Burnyeat’s comments about “insulation by level” are clearly intended to be a sympathetic presentation of Frede’s reading, in which Skeptical enquiry is restricted to “the dogmatist’s belief that he can achieve a further or deeper kind of knowledge and truth than the plain man requires for the purposes of ordinary life” (Burnyeat 1984: 233). He spends the bulk of the article (§§III–IX) looking closely at arguments in Sextus about the concept of “place” (τόπος) in order to show that Sextus did not insulate by subject matter in that discussion, and (by implication) that he did not insulate by subject matter in the rest of his work. He then argues (§§X–XI) that no one ever insulated by level until Kant. He concludes that it is anachronistic to suppose that Sextus insulated by level. But evidently there is a problem here: Burnyeat never examines Sextus directly to see whether he insulated by level (rather than by subject matter). He has no argument to that conclusion, other than the claim that no one prior to Kant insulated by level. And this indirect argument from anachronism simply begs the question against Frede: Kant was not the first person to insulate by level if Sextus did it before him. This gap in Burnyeat’s argumentative strategy could be closed if it could be shown that anyone who insulates by level must also insulate by subject matter. In that case, the demonstration that Sextus does not insulate by subject matter in his discussions of place would go some way toward showing that he could not be insulating by level, either. But in fact, insulation by subject matter does not follow from insulation by level. Quite to the contrary: the hypothesis on which Sextus insulated by level actually presupposes that Sextus did not insulate by subject matter. Here is why. The hypothesis on which Sextus insulated by level claims that he directed his skeptical scrutiny toward statements and assertions only when they

SEXTUS EMPIRICUS

137

are read or understood in one way (as dogmatic pronouncements), and not when they are understood in another way (as claims in ordinary life). But it is also part of this hypothesis that Sextus is confronting Dogmatists who themselves refuse to insulate by subject matter. These Dogmatists—idealized rather than historical, as noted above—think that their dogmatic philosophies are so coherent, so complete, so all-embracing, that every statement that they make is a deliverance of some part of the correct ultimate science of nature, the final Theory of Everything. And this applies just as much to their statements about practical affairs and medium-sized objects as it does to their more abstruse proclamations. So the Dogmatist does not insulate by subject matter. Accordingly, the Skeptics who insulate by level must treat any Dogmatic statement, on any subject matter, as a theorem of the Dogmatist’s favorite candidate for the Theory of Everything. If uttered by a Dogmatist, the statement—no matter what its subject matter may be—is inextricably bound up with the Dogmatist’s favored theory. If the Dogmatist says “my house is some miles west of here,” then they are staking a claim that the ultimate theory will vindicate the existence of substances like houses, locations like “here,” the coherence of directions like “west of,” of metrics like “some miles,” and so on. The Skeptic who insulates by level is exactly responding to Dogmatists who refuse to insulate by subject matter: the Skeptic attacks all of the Dogmatist’s claims as philosophical claims, no matter what their subject matter may be, because the Dogmatist’s own ultimate theory is meant to apply to practical affairs as well as theoretical ones. Accordingly, the Skeptic distinguishes two levels of discourse about, for example, stoves, one outside and one inside the Dogmatist’s discourse. But for this very reason, the Skeptic will not want to distinguish two types of subject matter within the Dogmatist’s discourse. And this is what Burnyeat shows in the central part of this paper: the Skeptic does not insulate some kinds of Dogmatic pronouncements about place from other kinds of Dogmatic pronouncements about place. Both kinds of Dogmatic talk occur at the same level. But that means that the paper misfires as a refutation of the claim that the Skeptic practices insulation by level; that hypothesis is simply never tested. And the results of the test that is conducted (on insulation by subject matter) are perfectly compatible with the hypothesis that Sextus himself insulated by level.

5  THE MODES AND THEIR INTERPRETATION As mentioned earlier, the bulk of PH I (§§36–186) is devoted to a survey of the Modes (τρόποι) or argument forms essential to generating the opposition among claims that rationally compels ἐποχή. Sextus considers various collections of Modes: the Ten Modes of Aenesidemus (§§36–163), the Five Modes of Agrippa (§§164–177), the Two Modes (§§178–179), and the “Causal” Modes (§§180–186). The first two collections are most important, not only because they figure prominently in Sextus’s arguments throughout his work and have exerted a profound influence on the subsequent history of philosophy

138

SKEPTICISM

after Sextus, but also because they seem to capture the essential character of Skeptical argument. The Ten Modes depend upon the familiar fact that things ostensibly the same will appear differently either to different observers or in different circumstances or when other factors differ. When these appearances are incompatible, the argument concludes that one must suspend assent with regard to how the object is. There seems to be an important connection between the Five Modes and the Ten, since one of the Five Modes—the Mode from “Relativity” (πρός τι)—seems to capture the basic form of the Ten Modes as a whole and, indeed, Sextus suggests precisely that (PH I 167).9 A similar point can be made with regard to the Mode from Disagreement (διαφωνία), which, while perhaps not as closely related to the Ten Modes, nevertheless seems to share a similar structure. The remaining three Modes, by contrast, look to be quite different. Each of them—the Modes from Infinite Regress, Reciprocity, and Hypothesis—involve showing that a line of argument for a claim is vitiated either by regress, by circularity, or by lack of any support beyond bare assertion. It is quite clear that Sextus conceives of the Five Modes as forming a “loose system”10 (PH I 170–177), and this suggests that both the Five and the Ten Modes might be used together, though whether this “togetherness” is more loose collection or genuine system is a matter of dispute. Indeed, in the next section we will consider a recent attempt to precisely articulate both the structure of the Ten and the Five Modes and the nature of their connection with a view to deepening our understanding of both.

5a  Morison’s Understanding of the Modes Recently, Ben Morison (2011; 2014)11 has argued that all of the Skeptic’s arguments against some dogmatic thesis P must take the form of arguments in favor of ~P.12 In line with this proposal, Morison argues that the Ten Modes are best analyzed as “devices for generating an equal and opposing argument in response to a dogmatist’s attempt to show how things are” (Morison 2014: §3.5.1). When the Dogmatist argues that P, the Skeptic who has mastered the Ten Modes will be able to respond with an argument that ~P. Morison’s discussion of his proposal, and his rejection of the earlier understanding of the Ten Modes, is thoroughly convincing. Morison has also suggested that we cannot understand the Five Modes of Agrippa as they have been traditionally construed. Traditionally, critics have assumed that the point of showing that a Dogmatist’s proof of P rests on an infinite regress or a reciprocity is to persuade the Dogmatist that their argument for P is a “bad argument,” and so should be abandoned as a reason for believing P.13 Morison thinks that this cannot be the correct construal of Sextus’s practice, because showing a Dogmatist that their argument for P is a bad argument does not give them a reason to believe ~P. And if the Skeptical argument does not give the Dogmatist a reason for believing ~P, then it is not an opposed argument of the kind that is essential to the Skeptic’s practice. In conformity with his thesis that the Skeptic responds to Dogmatic arguments for P only by producing positive arguments for ~P, Morison has suggested that

SEXTUS EMPIRICUS

139

the Five Modes should also be understood as “devices for generating an equal and opposing argument.” So, for instance, when the Dogmatist has argued that P, and the Skeptic shows the Dogmatist that her argument is guilty of an infinite regress, that diagnosis of regress is not itself the Skeptical response to the argument for P. Rather, the Skeptic counters the Dogmatist by constructing a symmetrical argument for ~P, using the same method: infinite regress is to be used constructively to provide an infinitely regressive argument for ~P in order to counter the infinitely regressive argument for P that the Skeptic finds in the Dogmatist’s system.14 This looks like a very perverse and laborious way for the Skeptic to argue, and such a construal is certainly not suggested by the text. But more importantly, this understanding of how the Skeptic sets out to produce oppositions is unjustifiably narrow, as can be seen by looking at what Sextus says about equipollence, in his gloss on the definition of Skepticism in PH I 10: By “equipollence” we mean an equality in respect of credibility and incredibility (ἰσότης κατὰ πίστιν καὶ ἀπιστίαν), so that none of the conflicting arguments will stand out from the others as being more credible. Morison’s thesis gives a good account of what it means to say that the conflicting arguments have “equality in respect of credibility” (ἰσότης κατὰ πίστιν): there is as much positive reason to believe P as there is positive reason to believe ~P. But what is ἰσότης κατ’ ἀπιστίαν, that is, equality in respect of incredibility? This equality, presumably, is the result of producing reasons not to believe P (as well as reasons not to believe ~P, should they be needed for balance). Now, one sort of reason not to believe P is any positive argument in favor of ~P. But that case has already been covered in the ἰσότης κατὰ πίστιν clause. So the ἰσότης κατ’ ἀπιστίαν must be a distinct kind of reason to lose faith in P, or to find one’s P-credences diminished. And undermining arguments are the obvious candidates. Sextus’s idea of “incredibility” (ἀπιστία) is thus a matter of having a proposition’s credibility reduced or undermined. P is ἄπιστος when it lacks support, or has its support weakened or undermined, even if this does not involve an improved position for ~P, or any active increase in the credences for ~P. So the text which gives Sextus’s official account of how Skeptical opposition is supposed to work clearly shows that undermining arguments are envisioned as playing a role in the production of equipollence. But the same result emerges when we turn to the texts in which Sextus exercises his own antithetical powers. For instance, we can see the clear use of undermining arguments in his discussion of demonstrating P by means of P at PH I 61. If P is used to demonstrate P, Sextus says, then P will be at once πιστός and ἄπιστος: πιστός insofar as it is being used as a premise in the demonstration, but ἄπιστος insofar as it is being treated as a conclusion in need of demonstration. In a related sense, Sextus will call a method or a source of testimony ἄπιστος in order to undermine its credibility. So for instance, at PH I 98, the philosophers disagree about what nature is. Who can decide the question? Not the philosophers, since they are the parties to the disagreement. But not a layman, either, since he is ἄπιστος (according to the philosophers). To say that the layman is ἄπιστος does not do anything to

140

SKEPTICISM

establish the contradictory of his account of nature. Instead, it takes away from the credibility of his testimony, it increases its incredibility: it undermines what he says. Similarly, at PH I 117, Sextus argues that we cannot sort out the problem of the criterion without a good account of demonstration, and we cannot settle the problem of demonstration without an adequate account of the criterion: “And thus both criterion and demonstration collapse into the reciprocal mode (διάλληλος τρόπος), in which both of them are found to be incredible (ἄπιστα). For, since each of them is dependent on the credibility of the other, each of them is just as incredible [ἄπιστος] as the other.” The Skeptic here counters demonstrations of P not by arguing for ~P, but by undermining the credibility of the grounds for P, that is, by undermining the demonstration directly. These examples are only the first few of many in Sextus, in which ἀπιστία is invoked in the course of bringing about equipollence. Sextus’s use of undermining arguments should not surprise us, since his thoughts about equipollence are at least in part modeled on the dynamics of a weighing-scale in which arguments on each side are thought of as “weighty” or “light” (ἐμβριθές, κουφότερον, PH III 281). If the Dogmatists put a kilogram of sand into one pan of the scale, the Skeptic can bring the pans to a balance by subtracting some of the sand from the Dogmatist’s pan as well as by adding some sand to the opposite pan. Thus, in order to bring the Dogmatist to equipollence, Sextus may well use—as we see he often does use—a multiplicity of arguments, some of them directly arguing for ~P, and some of them undermining the Dogmatist’s case for P. This means that the notion of an argument (λόγος) is doing slightly different work in different passages of Sextus. It can sometimes refer to a particular piece of evidence (e.g., the evidence of the sun’s motion, against Zenonian denials of motion) or a particular sequence of premises and a conclusion (PH I 202). Or, it can refer to the portfolio or suite of arguments on either side, the total cumulative case that the Skeptic makes in bringing a question to equipollence. In this sense of “argument,” the cumulative “argument” against motion will contain many particular “arguments.” It is only in the cumulative sense that Sextus can declare that, “to every argument there is an equal argument opposed.” This utterance (φωνή) sums up the state of affairs that emerges after Sextus has presented a multiplicity of arguments against the Dogmatist’s position: after a series of particular moves which have supported ~P or undermined P or done both, the net result is an equality in respect of credibility and incredibility. For this reason, then, we can be sure that the Skeptic slogan that “to every argument there is an equal argument opposed” cannot mean that every particular Skeptical argument against the Dogmatic advocacy of P must take the form of an argument advocating ~P. Instead, it must refer to an equality between the accumulations of particular arguments on either side, that make up the aggregate cases pro and con. Among the particular arguments, there is no reason why each one must be an argument directly opposed to the Dogmatic argument as ~P to P, and indeed there is good reason why each one cannot be of equal and opposite weight to the Dogmatist’s argument.

SEXTUS EMPIRICUS

141

It may help to distinguish two claims: (a) Every equipollence is an equipollence between P and ~P. (b) Every argument used to produce equipollence is an argument in favor of P or an argument in favor of ~P. (a) is correct, but (b) does not follow from it. The equipollence between P and ~P may be brought about both by arguing for ~P and also by confronting Dogmatic arguments that raise the credibility of P with Skeptical undermining arguments that lower the credibility of P. It is also worth noting that several of the cases cited above, in which Sextus uses the word ἄπιστος or ἀπιστία in the context of undermining, involve tropes that Agrippa gathered into the Five Modes. At PH I 117, we saw an invocation of the Mode of Reciprocity (διάλληλος τρόπος) leading to a verdict of ἀπιστία. At PH I 61, the allegation of ἀπιστία followed on the charge that the Dogmatist was attempting to ground P in P, which Sextus may have attacked through the Mode of Hypothesis.15 This evidence that Agrippan modes produce ἀπιστία supports the picture above: the Five Modes are intended to undermine the Dogmatist’s case for P, not to provide constructive arguments for ~P. Moreover, if this picture of the Five Modes is correct, then we can see a further way in which the Five Modes complement the Ten. Morison’s picture of the Ten Modes presents them as means to generate arguments for ~P in response to the Dogmatist’s arguments for P, while we have argued the Five Modes are meant to undermine the arguments for P.16

6  CONCLUSION ABOUT VARIOUS INTERPRETATIONS In our opinion, the view of Frede is still an open interpretive option, although faced with many difficulties of formulation—its friends find it suggestive and stimulating, its critics complain that it has escaped definitive refutation only by remaining amorphous and underspecified. The more traditional view according to which Sextus assents to nothing more than his own internal appearances—which Burnyeat, Fine, and Perin all endorse in various forms—has an easier time with some of the evidence for Sextus’s epistemic stance but offers very little hope of vindicating Sextus’s claims to be describing a livable life.17 The aspirations of philosophical interpretation—either to produce a reading that consistently verifies the whole of Sextus’s system, or a refutation that clearly shows the conceptual fissures between its parts—remain to be achieved by future critics, unless they are permanently frustrated by the limitations of Sextus’s own writings.

NOTES 1. See Popkin (1979), Schmitt (1983), Floridi (2002; 2010). 2. “Medical Notes” (AM VII 202) and “Empirical Notes” (AM I 61). These may have been alternate titles for one treatise.

142

SKEPTICISM

3. For evidence of this aspect, see PH I 7–10, 12, 26–30. 4. Detailed discussion of the Modes is provided in Section 5 below. 5. Barnes (1982), reprinted along with the two by Frede and the two by Burnyeat, in Burnyeat and Frede (1997), is equally good and far less obscure than the others—its laudable clarity perhaps leading to less subsequent literature. Its central polemical contention, that “urbane” skepticism inevitably collapses into “rustic” skepticism because of the need for a criterion, was challenged by Brennan (1994), and definitively rebutted by Schwab (2013). 6. The same phrase, τὰ κατηναγκασμένα, that is, “the necessitated or compelled things,” is used both to mark out the sphere of things to which the Pyrrhonist will give their assent in PH I 13 and the sphere of things in which the Pyrrhonist must be content with “moderate disturbance” in place of total tranquility, in PH I 26 and 30. 7. These are standard claims in Stoic theory, which gave the Skeptics the machinery of impressions and assent. 8. Fine (2000: 84) gives the example of my considering an argument propounded by a notorious logical trickster: it appears sound to me, but because of my previous experience with its author, I do not assent to its really being sound. 9. Whether or not Sextus is referring to the Ten Modes at PH I 167 is something of a vexed question. For discussion, see Barnes (1990). One of us has argued elsewhere (Brennan and Lee 2014) that the Agrippan “Mode of Relativity” was originally intended as a prohibition on epistemic self-grounding and had nothing to do with the kind of relativity that features in the Ten Modes. That paper also argues that Sextus conflated the two issues through his own failure to understand Agrippa. Sextus’s reference at PH I 167 was indeed intended to refer back to the Ten Modes, but Agrippa would not have assimilated his Relativity to the earlier relativity. The revisionist proposal of Brennan and Lee has not (yet?) become the standard view, so in this paper we take the more conventional view about Agrippa’s Mode of Relativity. 10. In the words of Powers (2010: 157). 11. We are grateful to Morison for discussions about these topics. 12. More precisely: in favor of ~P, or of some other proposition opposed to and incompatible with P. Sextus explicitly notes in PH I 10 that the opposition is not restricted to the case of contradiction. What is important is simply that both cannot be true together. In the main text we use “~P” as a sort of abbreviation for “some proposition incompatible with P.” 13. Morison (2014) quotes Barnes (1990) for the phrase “bad arguments” as a summation of the verdict that Sextus intends to convey with the Five Modes. 14. Morison (2011: 293–294): “I take it that all the sets of modes [including the Five Modes just mentioned] can be made to work in the way the Ten Modes do: that is, all the sets of modes are devices to be deployed by the sceptic in forming opposing arguments to the arguments they encounter in the course of their philosophical investigations.” 15. Brennan and Lee (2014) argue that Agrippa himself would have brought this under the Mode of Relativity, which (we argue) prohibits grounding a proposition reflexively in itself.

SEXTUS EMPIRICUS

143

16. For a different view of the relation between the Five and Ten, see Powers (2010). 17. Fine (2000) adduces one philosopher who thinks that internal appearances may be sufficient for action. Perin argues that internal appearances allow the Skeptic to rebut the charge of being reduced to total inaction, but he also concludes that they are insufficient to provide the Skeptic with actions that are fully human in any richer sense (see Perin 2010: 113).

REFERENCES Barnes, Jonathan. 1982. “The Beliefs of a Pyrrhonist,” Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society N.S. 28: 1–29. Barnes, Jonathan. 1990. The Toils of Scepticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bett, Richard (ed.). 2010. The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brennan, Tad. 2000. “Criterion and Appearance in Sextus Empiricus,” Acta Philosophica Fennica 64: 63–92. Brennan, Tad and Jongsuh James Lee. 2014. “A Relative Improvement,” Phronesis 59: 246–271. Burnyeat, Myles. 1980. “Can the Sceptic Live His Scepticism?” In M. Schofield, M. Burnyeat, and J. Barnes (eds.), Doubt and Dogmatism: Studies in Hellenistic Epistemology, 20–53. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Burnyeat, Myles. 1983. The Skeptical Tradition. Berkeley: University of California Press. Burnyeat, Myles. 1984. “The Sceptic in His Place and Time.” In R. Rorty, J. Schneewind, and Q. Skinner (eds.), Philosophy in History, 225–254. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Burnyeat, Myles and Michael Frede (eds.). 1997. The Original Sceptics: A Controversy. Indianapolis: Hackett Press. Fine, Gail. 2000. “Sceptical Dogmata: Outlines of Pyrrhonism I 13,” Méthexis 13: 81–105. Floridi, Luciano. 2002. Sextus Empiricus: The Transmission and Recovery of Pyrrhonism. New York: Oxford University Press. Floridi, Luciano. 2010. “The Rediscovery and Posthumous Influence of Scepticism.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 267–287. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frede, Michael. 1979. “Des Skeptikers Meinungen,” Neue Hefte für Philosophie, Actualität der Antike, Heft 15/16: 102–129. (First appeared in English as “The Skeptic’s Beliefs.” In his Essays in Ancient Philosophy, 179–200. Oxford: Oxford University Press.) Frede, Michael. 1984. “The Sceptic’s Two Kinds of Assent and the Question of the Possibility of Knowledge.” In R. Rorty, J. Schneewind, and Q. Skinner (eds.), Philosophy in History, 255–278. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frede, Michael. 1987. Essays in Ancient Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. House, D. K. 1980. “The Life of Sextus Empiricus,” Classical Quarterly 30: 227–238. Janáček, Karl. 1963. “Die Hauptschrift des Sextus Empiricus als Torso erhalten?” Philologus 107: 271–277. Morison, Benjamin. 2011. “The Logical Structure of the Sceptic’s Opposition,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 60: 265–295.

144

SKEPTICISM

Morison, Benjamin. 2014. “Sextus Empiricus,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sextus-empiricus/ Perin, Casey. 2010a. The Demands of Reason: An Essay on Pyrrhonian Scepticism. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. Perin, Casey. 2010b. “Scepticism and Belief.” In R. Bett (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism, 145–164. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Popkin, Richard. 1979. The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza. Berkeley: University of California Press. Powers, Nathan. 2010. “The System of the Sceptical Modes in Sextus Empiricus,” Apeiron 43: 157–172. Rorty, Richard, Jerome Schneewind, and Quentin Skinner (eds.). 1984. Philosophy in History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Schmitt, Charles. 1983. “The Rediscovery of Ancient Scepticism in Modern Times.” In M. Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition, 225–251. Berkeley: University of California Press. Schwab, Whitney. 2013. “Skepticism, Belief, and the Criterion of Truth,” Apeiron 46: 327–344. Sextus, Empiricus. 1997. Against the Ethicists (Adversus Mathematicos XI), translation and commentary by Richard Bett. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

CHAPTER ELEVEN

Skepticism in Classical Indian Philosophy1 MATTHEW R. DASTI

1 INTRODUCTION There are some tantalizing suggestions that Pyrrhonian skepticism has its roots in ancient India. Of them, the most important is Diogenes Laertius’s report that Pyrrho accompanied Alexander to India, where he was deeply impressed by the character of the “naked sophists” he encountered (DL IX 61). Influenced by these gymnosophists, Pyrrho is said to have adopted the practices of suspending judgment on matters of belief and cultivating an indifferent composure amid the vicissitudes of ordinary life. Such conduct, and the attitudes that it embodied, became inspirations to later skeptical thinkers. It is a fact that practices of the sort attributed to Pyrrho are richly evident in a number of ancient Indian philosophical and ascetic movements. On this basis, attempts have been made to determine the identity of these gymnosophists and, further, to pinpoint the dialectical tropes within Pyrrhonism that may have their basis in Indian thought. But despite these attempts, and in the absence of any new discoveries, these suggestions will likely remain just that. The paucity of the historical data and the problematic nature of the data itself prevent us from reconstructing a solid bridge between ancient India and Greek skepticism that may serve as the basis of robust historical theorizing.2 Classical India does, however, lay claim to a sophisticated and diverse culture of epistemological reflection, which includes a number of innovative skeptical thinkers deserving study on their own merits. This chapter is meant to provide such a study, or perhaps more accurately, a prolegomena for such. After some initial groundlaying, I will discuss three leading Indian skeptics and situate them historically and conceptually within the network of competing schools that comprise classical Indian philosophy. They are Nāgārjuna (c. 150 CE), the founder of Madhyamaka Buddhism, Jayarāśi (c. 800), associated with the Indian materialist tradition, and Śrīharṣa (c. 1150), a thinker connected to the school of Nondual (Advaita) Vedānta.

146

SKEPTICISM

2  SKEPTICAL ELEMENTS OF THE PROTOPHILOSOPHICAL PERIOD The proto-philosophical period in Indian thought spans roughly from 700 BCE to100 CE. The most ancient body of literature in India is the Vedas (c. 1500 BCE for their earliest portions). Though they contain occasional moments of philosophical, and indeed skeptical, reflection,3 the Vedas are centrally concerned with the performance of sacrifice and the ritual culture that surrounds it. The seeds of classical Indian skepticism were laid at a time of departure from the Vedas, during the middle of the first millennium BCE, amid the tumult associated with the śramaṇa movement. This was a broad social development connected to the rise of urban centers and characterized by itinerancy, asceticism, and bold philosophical speculation. It was motivated by a search for the ultimate solutions to life’s problems and dissatisfaction with the religious orthodoxy embodied in the culture of Vedic sacrifice. A number of later traditions, including Buddhism, Jainism, and Upaniṣadic Hinduism,4 developed out of the śramaṇa milieu. Certain features of this period lent themselves to skeptical attitudes. Many of its thinkers express acute concern with our basic cognitive abilities and their limitations, arguing that whatever the ultimate reality is, it transcends our ordinary conceptual apparatus. This led naturally to deep strains of apophatic theorizing, often coupled with the view that meditative gnosis is the only access available to such higher realities. Two traditions we will consider below, Madhyamaka Buddhism and Nondual Vedānta, incorporate these ideas into a notion of “two truths,” the conventional and the ultimate. They do, however, unpack this concept in very different ways. Tied to such concerns with the limitations of our basic cognitive abilities was a further contention that the objects identified as the real, mediumsized dry goods of common experience tend to fall apart under scrutiny. For many Upaniṣadic thinkers who pave the way for Hinduism, this manifests as a skepticism about the reality of ordinary objects coupled with an affirmation of unqualified being itself (the locus classicus for this is the sixth book of the Chāndogya Upaniṣad). For Buddhists, this manifests in a variety of ways, including a reduction of macro-objects to sensation-instances that are said to be reified and conceptually constructed into the objects of ordinary experience.

3  CLASSICAL INDIAN EPISTEMOLOGY AND THE CENTRALITY OF PRAMĀṆAS The classical period of Indian philosophy begins soon after the start of the Common Era and lasts until roughly 1800 CE. On one side, the classical period is bracketed by the proto-philosophical period, and on the other side, by the modern period, which is centrally preoccupied by the confrontation with the West and by the problems of modernity more generally. (Even today, learned pandits carry the classical traditions onward, though it is an increasingly marginalized feature of Indian intellectual culture.) In the classical period, we find the coalescence of specific schools and

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL INDIAN PHILOSOPHY

147

sub-schools of thought that have their roots in the proto-philosophical period. A number of Buddhist, Jaina, and Hindu schools of thought may be traced to various earlier cultural and religious movements, but they become distinctly philosophical in the classical period as they become explicitly concerned with both system-building and defending their holdings through dialectical engagement with rivals. Classical philosophers typically work within a school, developing their own innovations through commentaries or sub-commentaries on the foundational texts of their particular tradition. Another characteristic of the classical period, of great importance to this study, is the centrality of pramāṇas, “knowledge sources.” Epistemology in classical India largely consists in the identification and analysis of irreducible sources of knowledge (e.g., perception, inference, testimony). Competing schools and thinkers articulate different lists of fundamental pramāṇas as well as analyses of specific pramāṇas, and extensive debate over knowledge sources is a key feature of Indian philosophy.5 These knowledge sources are not only taken to be the cognitive resources by which we as individuals guide our lives. They are also the basis of philosophical argumentation. Illustrating that my belief or the holding of my school is supported by genuine pramāṇas places it on firm ground. Indeed, the early history of pramāṇa theory is intertwined with a robust culture of formal public debate,6 and some of the first systematic Indian treatments of epistemology are integrated with manuals on debate theory and dialectics. The very survival of a school typically depended on patronage, and the primary way to win support was public discourse and debate with rivals. A particular style of debate, the “purely destructive” mode (vitaṇḍā), was explicitly recognized in works on dialectics and appropriated by philosophical skeptics. One arguing in this mode disavows any personal thesis to defend and sets himself only to destroy other views. This method was controversial and an object of concern for realists, some of whom argued that it involves an inherent selfcontradiction of some kind or other.7 The skeptics we will study were acutely aware of this charge and defended themselves against it. In summation, pramāṇa discourse, as well as an allied culture of formal debate, provide the conceptual landscape for classical Indian epistemological reflection, and skeptical attacks on the possibility of knowledge presuppose this landscape.

4 NĀGĀRJUNA AND MADHYAMAKA BUDDHISM The first Indian skeptic we will consider is the founder of Madhyamaka Buddhism, Nāgārjuna (c. 150 CE). To understand Nāgārjuna’s project, we need to take note of some features of Buddhist thought traceable to the historical Buddha himself (Siddhārta Gautama, fifth century BCE). At the time he began his career as a philosophical and religious teacher, the Buddha was merely one participant in the śramaṇa movement. After years of self-abnegation and meditative practice, he became convinced that he found a solution to the fundamental problem of life, which he expressed within the Four Noble Truths: life is pervaded by suffering, we suffer because of our desires, we may uproot suffering by uprooting desire, and

148

SKEPTICISM

there is a way of life (the Eightfold Path) that allows us to do so. Expressing and developing this simple formula, the Buddha became one of the most influential thinkers in ancient India and, eventually, much of the Asian world. A few features of the Buddha’s approach to philosophy are relevant to this study. In short, it tends to be therapeutic, pragmatic, and anti-metaphysical. Philosophy is not meant to capture the right theory about the world, but rather to remove problematic misconceptions. The Buddha thus treats human beings’ natural tendency to schematize the world as an intellectual analogue of desire: an attempt to harness the world, a clinging of sorts, which perpetuates suffering. We may notice the way in which these elements of the Buddha’s thought lead him, and later Buddhist skeptics, to dismiss elaborate philosophical systematizing as a massive unwholesome distraction. Moreover, the Buddha is sensitive to the way in which our conceptual and linguistic frameworks dictate our experiences and understandings. This leads to a general antirealist sensibility. Finally, he problematizes the commonsense notion of the world as populated by enduring, self-standing macro-objects of common experience. These aspects of the Buddha’s teachings collectively set the stage for various tendencies in mature philosophical Buddhism, including empiricism, reductionism, idealism, and skepticism. And with the last, we may now consider Nāgārjuna. Nāgārjuna flourished while the classical period of Indian philosophy was taking shape and various systems of thought, Buddhist and otherwise, were being constructed.8 He opposed what is, from the Madhyamaka9 perspective, a common practice of philosophers: the enshrinement within philosophical argumentation of our pre-theoretical tendency to project a world of independent, self-standing objects. His philosophical opponents are those who espoused various sorts of realism, including Buddhist scholastics and Hindu realists like the Nyāya (“Logic”) and Vaiśeṣika (“Particularism”) schools. The central theme of Nāgārjuna’s most important work, The Fundamental Verses of the Middle Way (MMK), is emptiness (śūnyatā), the lack of intrinsic existence (svabhāva, “self-nature”), which, he argues, holds for all phenomena. The term svabhāva takes on various related meanings within Madhyamaka thought. Fundamentally, it refers to something whose existence is independent of other conditions or factors. 10 Emptiness, the denial of intrinsic existence, is taken by Nāgārjuna to be equivalent to dependent co-origination (pratītyasamutpāda), the inexorable interdependence of all phenomena.11 In short, Nāgārjuna argues that nothing has an ontologically stable identity independent of other phenomena. This interdependence is not merely causal, in the sense that we can never separate an entity’s existence from the rich network of conditions upon which it depends and which it in turn influences. More radically, it is conceptual: the nature of any particular thing under scrutiny is determined by the conventions, concerns, linguistic practices, etc. of those doing the scrutinizing. Any attempt to isolate a certain moment or node within the rich causal, conceptual, and linguistic networks that constitute life as experienced, while claiming that this node has a nature existing independently from such networks, is mere reification and projection. The notion of emptiness is thus not merely a report on our own cognitive limitations, that we have no cognitive access to what lies beneath the phenomena-

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL INDIAN PHILOSOPHY

149

as-experienced, as Locke speaks of substance in general or as Kant speaks of the thing in itself. Nor is it merely semantic, in that there are limits to the capacity of language to capture extra-linguistic reality. It is ultimately ontological. There is nothing there beneath the appearances. The notion of underlying, independently existing real entities that undergird the contents of phenomenal awareness is simply incoherent. We should underscore that this is not merely a kind of idealism, since there are no enduring, intrinsically existing minds that ground the world either. Subjects are as empty as the phenomena they experience.12 Nāgārjuna’s primary method to advance this point is argumentum ad absurdum: positing intrinsically existing entities leads to inescapable contradictions. He provides a wide array of arguments to the effect that various phenomena championed by philosophers (e.g., causation, motion, indwelling selves, substances that bear properties) lack svabhāva.13 One of his major lines of argumentation may be summarized as follows14: 1. x enters into relations with other nodes within causal, conceptual, and linguistic networks. 2. x possesses intrinsic existence (svabhāva). 3. If something possesses intrinsic existence, then its fundamental identity is isolated from the networks of conditions (causal, conceptual, linguistic) within which it is embedded. 4. If something’s fundamental identity is isolated from the networks of conditions (causal, conceptual, linguistic) within which it is embedded, then it does not enter into relations with other nodes of such networks. 5. Therefore, x does not enter into relations with other nodes of causal, conceptual, and linguistic networks. The contradiction between premise 1 and the conclusion leads to the rejection of premise 2. This lack of independent existence further entails that precisely discriminating some real entity, independent from the conditions within which it is embedded, is impossible.15 At best, we merely select certain features of the causal/ cognitive nexus as most relevant to our concerns. The fact that Nāgārjuna preserves premise 1 underscores the fact that, despite the claims of his opponents, he does not intend his imputation of emptiness to be nihilistic. In fact, he argues, it is the very opposite: emptiness is a condition for something’s being part of the common world of causal interaction.16 Nāgārjuna’s arguments in support of emptiness are meant to undermine realists’ attempts to gain purchase on a substantial external world and are thus skeptical in spirit. But they are not distinctively epistemological in form. In his Dispeller of Disputes (VV), however, Nāgārjuna takes direct aim at pramāṇa (knowledgesource) epistemology. The context of his attack is a response to Nyāya realists. Naiyāyikas (Nyāya philosophers), as far back as the original Nyāya-sūtras (c. 200 CE), have taken the Madhyamaka position to be a kind of skeptical nihilism that is guilty of the self-referential incoherence mentioned above. They take emptiness to mean insubstantiality and claim that the Buddhist must either accept that there

150

SKEPTICISM

are non-empty pramāṇas, which support his assertions, or give up the attempt to prove his point. Nāgārjuna’s response is twofold. First, he denies that he advances a robust thesis about the nature of a real external world, claiming “I have no thesis” (VV 29).17 Because of this, he claims to be innocent of the charge of self-contradiction. Second, and more aggressively, he turns the argument back on the realist, by arguing that the notion of pramāṇas as foundational sources of knowledge is unsustainable (31–51): If you hold that the various objects are established by pramāṇas, then again, you must explain how it is that the pramāṇas are themselves established (31).18 If the pramāṇas were established by other pramāṇas, then there would be an infinite regress. Then, neither the beginning, middle, nor end would be established (32). But if you think that the pramāṇas are established without need for other pramāṇas, then your position (that claims about an object’s existence or nature must be supported by appeal to pramāṇas) has been abandoned. There is inconsistency in this, and you must provide a specific reason for it. (33) So far, Nāgārjuna has presented two lemmas: an infinite regress of pramāṇas and the mere positing of pramāṇas without epistemic grounding, both of which are undesirable for the reasons he cites. Next, he presents a third lemma, beginning with the idea that the pramāṇas may be self-established. As opposed to being ungrounded, this option suggests that pramāṇas have the special power to provide epistemic support for themselves by dint of their own functioning. From our perspective, this option seems closest to a classical formulation of foundationalism: there are cognitive states that are both self-supporting and able to support other states. Nāgārjuna’s interlocutor suggests that this may be akin to the way that a fire not only illuminates various objects but also itself. After finding fault with the details of the fire analogy, Nāgārjuna argues: If the pramāṇas are self-established, then the objects of knowledge are also independent (of the pramāṇas). For self-establishment is independent of any other thing (40). If the pramāṇas are established independently of their objects, then they would be the pramāṇas of nothing at all. (41) If the pramāṇas were truly self-established, this would exclude us from accounting for the veracity of, for example, perception by appeal to the objects it normally reveals. Track-record arguments, familiar to reliabilist theories, would be off the table. The very notion of self-establishment would rule out such an appeal. Putting aside the practical question of how we could then discriminate legitimate knowledge sources from flawed imposters (perception vs. mere hallucination), Nāgārjuna highlights the way in which this approach would sever the intimate tie between knowledge sources and their proper objects. I would suggest that this argument may be placed within the family of arguments directed against “the given” and, more precisely, against strong versions of foundationalism. Nāgārjuna’s contention is that, if foundational cognitive states were truly walled off from the support of other inputs, this wall would be impassable in both directions. The

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL INDIAN PHILOSOPHY

151

very act of insulating these foundational cognitive states makes them impotent as sources of epistemic support for any particular domain of putative objects or truth claims. His argument may be understood in two distinct, but complementary ways. Epistemically, as we have seen, we would be unable to support the veracity of, for example, perception by appealing to its track record of success. I could no longer say that perception reliably provides me cognitive access to “this tree right here” as I point to a tree in my backyard. Conceptually, if self-establishment is taken as a kind of logical atomism, then the concept of perception could not include its capacity to provide cognitive access to a distinct domain of physical objects. In his auto-commentary, Nāgārjuna remarks: “If they are to be pramāṇas of something, they cannot be independent of their objects.” Given the way in which this lemma instantiates Nāgārjuna’s general attack on intrinsic existence, we now see a close connection between his critique of pramāṇa epistemology and his general philosophical project. The fourth and final lemma is acceptance of the interdependence of pramāṇas and their objects: If, conversely, you accept that “establishment of pramāṇas always occurs in reference to their proper objects,” there would be the establishment of what is already established. (42) If the realist opts for a more holistic approach to the establishment of pramāṇas, allowing the objects of knowledge to play a role, then, in the course of justifying his views, appeal to knowledge sources would merely serve the purpose of reiterating what he already accepts. The existence of knowledge sources is presupposed, as they are what provide cognitive access to their proper objects. The existence of objects of knowledge is also presupposed, as they are what we appeal to in order to establish the existence and nature of knowledge sources. In succeeding verses, Nāgārjuna argues that there is no way to escape this circularity in a way that salvages the realists’ project. They would have to hold that the objects of knowledge are established independently of the pramāṇas to use them as a non-circular ground for establishing the pramāṇas (43). But if this is the case, what need is there for appealing to pramāṇas in order to ground knowledge of the objects (44)? This strategy would, further, reverse the putative dependence relation between the sources and objects of knowledge (45). Proposing a complete circularity between them ends up establishing nothing (46). In conclusion, “the pramāṇas cannot be self-established, nor established by other pramāṇas, nor established by appeal to the objects of knowledge, nor established without reason” (51). And thus, they are unsuitable to play the foundational role assigned to them by the systembuilding realist philosophers. It is important to see that Nāgārjuna’s purpose here is not to refute commonplace epistemic practice, the use of perception, inference, testimony, and the like in navigating our daily lives (see Siderits 1980: 320). It is rather to refute the contention that the pramāṇas have the capacity to justify metaphysical realism.19 And this refutation, in consonance with traditional Buddhist attitudes, is meant to support a life aimed at enlightenment. The affirmation of emptiness, supported by

152

SKEPTICISM

skeptical argumentation, provides an ideative support for meditative praxis, meant to dislodge the tangled knots of reification and desire, and ultimately terminate in peace and freedom from suffering.20

5 JAYARĀŚI AND THE MATERIALIST TRADITION The materialist tradition (Lokāyata, Cārvāka) is a noteworthy exception to the typically ascetical flavor of classical Indian philosophy.21 Most of the original works of the materialists are unfortunately lost to us. We tend to find bits and pieces preserved by their rivals, who often represent them as interlocutors worthy of contemptuous dismissal. The materialists themselves dismissed the religious ambitions of other Indian schools (sometimes with quite humorous rhetoric), and their skepticism stems from their anti-religious and anti-speculative approach to the good life. There is no immortal soul. We have one life to live, and the best that life can offer is pleasure; all else is vanity. In a corresponding movement, personal experience is all that we can take seriously in matters of knowledge, while inference and testimony—the primary means to bolster claims about transcendent realities— are never sources of knowledge proper.22 Against inference, materialists note that it relies on a recognized connection between an inferential sign and that which is signified (e.g., between smoke and fire). But for this sign to underwrite knowledge of the signified, it must be known to be invariably and non-accidentally connected to it. How do we acquire this knowledge? Not by perception, as it operates upon particulars in the present moment. Nor by inference, as this would trigger an infinite regress. Nor testimony; since it too relies on a connection between sign and signified, it would mirror the problems of inference. Furthermore, we can never be sure that apparently secure inferential relata are not merely accidentally and “locally” connected. Our ability to know is limited in scope. We lack the resources to refute the possibility of unknown causal factors that would engender deviation at some time or place. Jayarāśi (c. 800 CE) is connected to the materialist tradition, though he seems willing to develop his own conclusions.23 One sign of his independence is that he takes the deep skeptical strand within materialism and expresses it across the board, attempting to refute leading analyses of knowledge and knowledge sources, including perception. He abandons the somewhat clumsy materialist formulation that “perception is the only legitimate knowledge source,” fraught with the potential for easy refutation, and devotes his work to a more sophisticated, skeptical vindication of ordinary life: “The philosophers’ technical categories being subverted, ordinary linguistic practices are appropriate, and should not be subject to critical examination” (my translation of text in Solomon 2010: 228). In the Tattvopaplavasiṁha (The Lion that Subverts all Philosophical Categories), his method is straightforward “destructive” argumentation. For any technical view put forth by a philosopher (typically analyses of the major knowledge sources or key metaphysical tenets), he tries to illustrate that it is either patently false or inadmissible given the interlocutors’ own set of truth commitments.

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL INDIAN PHILOSOPHY

153

By way of example, below is a summary of one his arguments against the analysis of testimony given by Nyāya: “testimony is an assertion by an authoritative speaker” (āpta-upadeśa śabdaḥ; Nyāya-sūtra 1.1.7), where “authoritative” is meant to convey a speaker’s own veridical cognition of some fact and an honest willingness to convey it to another. 1. Granting provisionally that there is a property, authoritativeness, possessed by some persons, it would underwrite the positive epistemic status of testimonial beliefs either by (a) its mere existence, devoid of any particular production of testimonial knowledge, or (b) its actual production of testimonial knowledge. 2. Option (a) cannot be the case, since authoritativeness cannot be a cause of positive epistemic status if it is causally unproductive. 3. Regarding (b), authoritativeness would have to produce knowledge either (c) by itself or (d) with the help of auxiliary causal factors.

(3a) Option (c) is not appropriate, as you (Nyāya) do not accept it. And in any case, it would contradict the experience of causal fluctuations that are attributed to the influence of auxiliary causal factors.



(3b) If you hold (d), then authoritativeness is neither necessary nor sufficient for the production of veridical testimonial cognition. Consider the statement “the boy has nava blankets” (the Sanskrit term nava could be understood to mean “new” or “nine”). Seeing a boy with a new blanket, an authoritative person may utter the above statement. Owing to auxiliary causal factors that beset the listener, however, his statement produces the false cognition “the boy has nine blankets.” Similarly, a person intent on deception may say “the boy has nine blankets,” but owing to auxiliary causal factors, his statement produces for a listener the true cognition “the boy has a new blanket.” 4. Therefore, the Nyāya analysis “testimony is an assertion by an authoritative speaker” fails.

This is but one example. But Jayarāśi’s contention is that such destructive argumentation is possible for any and every technical definition put forth by dogmatic philosophers.

6  ŚRĪHARṢA AND NONDUAL VEDĀNTA The final skeptic we will consider is Śrīharṣa (c. 1150), a thinker within the school of Advaita (“Nondual”) Vedānta, living roughly four centuries after Śaṅkarācārya, the figure who gave definitive form to the school and whose works serve as its systematic foundation.24 Vedānta is a Hindu school, or rather a large family of subschools, devoted to interpreting the Upaniṣadic scriptures as well as articulating a coherent, defensible metaphysics that makes sense of the Upaniṣadic view of the world. The Upaniṣads are heterogeneous and unsystematic in nature, but a common theme that emerges is that the various objects of ordinary experience are

154

SKEPTICISM

ontologically dependent upon and find their ultimate value as derivative of the fundamental ground of being, Brahman. Realizing Brahman—in large measure, realizing our own intimate relationship with it—is considered the key to achieving supreme felicity and liberation from the cycle of rebirth. The various sub-schools of Vedānta fall into two major (and hostile) camps, realism and nondualism, based on their interpretation of the nature of Brahman and the dependence relation between Brahman and the world. The realists affirm the existence of a mind-independent world but suggest that, without reflection upon Upaniṣadic teachings, we remain ignorant of the way in which it is sustained and pervaded by Brahman, which is understood as a God-like being. Nondual Vedānta is contrastingly a monist idealism. For the nondualists, Brahman is a homogeneous, unified, self-aware consciousness. The world of common experience, which presupposes multiplicity, is ultimately unreal, a persistent illusion, as is the notion of a creator God. The world is grounded in Brahman in the sense that everything, even illusion, is grounded in awareness. The difference between the two camps may also be understood in their interpretation of Brahman’s totality. The Upaniṣads hold that Brahman is everything. For realists, this means that Brahman undergirds, unifies, and makes coherent the multiplicity of real objects in the world; for nondualists, this means that the only real thing is homogeneous conscious awareness; all else is ultimately illusion.25 While it is outside the scope of this study, we should also note there are historical and conceptual continuities between Madhyamaka Buddhism and Nondual Vedānta in spite of the fact that the former is anti-Vedic and the latter is among the more orthodox of the Vedic Hindu traditions. This nondualist view is sometimes advanced through sophisticated epistemological arguments that combine a notion of cognitive sublation (bādha) with the selfillumination/justification of conscious awareness. A cognitive state is sublated when it is defeated or undermined by a contrary awareness (e.g., an illusion of a man in the distance is sublated by expert testimony that the thing in question is a tree stump). A key nondualist contention is that all contentful awareness is in principle capable of being sublated, but unqualified awareness simpliciter is not. This is because all sublation takes place within the domain of awareness. To put it slightly differently, while any particular cognitive presentation may be doubted, the fact of conscious awareness cannot. And such unqualified awareness is taken to be identical to Brahman, the ultimate ground of being.26 This argument provides a helpful way to conceptualize Śrīharṣa’s project in his dialectical masterpiece, the Khaṇḍanakhaṇḍakhādya (The Sweets of Refutation): while Descartes’s skepticism is the first half of a two-part movement that erodes conviction in the external world, pivots on the indubitability of conscious self-awareness, and rediscovers the world on more secure footing, Śrīharṣa simply stops at the end of the first movement. He seeks to undermine any positive, contentful cognition (belief, proposition, etc.), such that the only thing left standing is unqualified, homogeneous conscious awareness itself (again, equated with Brahman, the ground of being revealed in the Upaniṣads). As Phillips (1995: 88) puts it, he would “back into success” by refuting any view that asserts the reality of multiplicity. In support of this objective, Śrīharṣa argues against a wide variety of philosophical views, commitments, and theses (including, for example, a scathing attack on

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL INDIAN PHILOSOPHY

155

universals). Like Jayarāśi, he often sets the views of a philosopher or school against themselves, in support of his contention that that systematic realism cannot be maintained.27 He succinctly expresses this in the claim that “all technical analyses are untenable (sarvāṇi lakṣanāṇi anupapannāni)” (see Granoff 1978: 23, and Jha 1986: 82). Harkening back to our discussion of the purely destructive mode of debate (vitaṇḍā), Nicholson (2009: 94) suggests that it “achieves its most developed expression” in the work of Śrīharṣa, who contends that any understanding of reality, pre-theoretic or philosophical, which considers distinctness (bheda) real, collapses under philosophical scrutiny. Śrīharṣa explicitly states that the basic form of his arguments may be modified in order to attack against positions that he doesn’t directly address, and thus used as modes, so to speak, in the continued refutation of realism.28 We my recall that Indian realists contend that a complete denial of knowledge sources is impossible, as any thesis put forth (including the skeptical hypothesis) must derive its probative force from somewhere (see note 6). One way to express this contention is that one cannot engage in philosophical debate without at least tacitly accepting that there are knowledge sources that determine the legitimacy of argumentative moves and provide for the rules by which defeat and victory may be objectively recognized. This would, of course, undermine Śrīharṣa’s program from the start. Naturally, he tasks himself with deflecting this charge.29 In short, his response is as follows: it would be misleading for the realist to cast Śrīharṣa’s own position as starting from a denial of knowledge sources. He is, rather, uncommitted to the truth of their existence. All he claims to possess, and all that that is needed to debate their legitimacy, is an idea or notion of knowledge sources, and indeed, not prior knowledge of their existence. He need no investment in their reality or in a theory that ties them to an external world of causal conditions. Clearly, those who attack the legitimacy of knowledge sources (identified by Śrīharṣa as Mādhyamika Buddhists, Cārvāka materialists, and Advaita Vedāntins) participate in philosophical discussion and debate. This gives the lie to the notion that accepting knowledge sources is a prerequisite for dialectical engagement. And further, the realists themselves engage in vigorous, extensive debate with skeptics! Clearly they themselves do not in fact accept the rule that debate must require a preliminary acceptance of knowledge sources. How then, is the debate between the skeptics and the realists to be prosecuted? What undergirds what we take to be the standards of success and failure in debate? Śrīharṣa argues that it is simply a set of agreed-upon rules. This is the only thing that both sides must accept for debate to occur. And such rules are a matter of convention and nothing more; certainly they need not be objects of knowledge. Accepting those debate-governing conventions that have passed the test of time and seem to function effectively is the baseline requirement for two parties to engage in debate effectively. Śrīharṣa deftly supports this line of argumentation by reflection on our general epistemic condition: our action-guiding cognitive resources are as a rule usually far below the standards of ultima facie justified knowledge. All of us, realists included, must rely on cognitions that are themselves unverified and therefore, provisional, on pain of infinite regress. And relying on these, without any

156

SKEPTICISM

sense of deep conviction or pretense to knowledge, is all the skeptic needs to engage in debate and, indeed, to leverage his attack on knowledge itself.30

NOTES 1. This chapter was generously supported by a grant from Bridgewater State University’s Center for the Advancement of Research and Scholarship. I would also like to thank Diego Machuca and Baron Reed for helpful comments and suggestions. 2. See Frenkian (1957) and Flintoff (1980) for arguments that Pyrrho was indeed influenced by Indian philosophers. McEvilley (1982) identifies a number of remarkable similarities between dialectical tropes within Pyrrhonism and Madhyamaka Buddhist thought, though he ultimately remains dubious of Indian influence. For concise appraisals of the issue see Hankinson (1995: 58–64) and Bett (2000: 169–178). 3. The famous creation hymn (Nāsadīya sūkta) of the Ṛg Veda (10.129) contains a delightfully skeptical conclusion regarding the ultimate nature of the cosmos. 4. “Hinduism” is a problematic term for various reasons, including the fact that it refers to hundreds of philosophical and religious movements under a single heading. For our purposes, it refers to persons and traditions that accept the authority of the Vedas—if only nominally—along with allied texts, cultural norms, and practices. It primarily serves the purpose of distinguishing these groups from those which explicitly rejected the authority of the Vedic tradition, including Buddhists, Jainas, and Cārvāka materialists. By “Upaniṣadic Hinduism” I refer to an influential strain of Hindu thought that takes many of the motivations and concerns of the śramaṇa period and incorporates them into the Vedic ritual tradition, in the spirit of reformation and not outright rejection. 5. See Matilal (1986) and Mohanty (2000: 11–40) for introductions to pramāṇa theory. 6. See Solomon (1976: chs. 1–3) for evidence of the primacy of debate within a number of ancient Indian traditions of thought. Matilal (1998: 32) suggests that debate was “a preferred form of rationality” in classical India. See Matilal (1986: 80–93; 1998: 32–59) for further discussion. 7. Considerations of space prevent us from extensively considering responses to skepticism by Indian realists. This short aside will have to suffice: the selfcontradiction alleged may be couched in various ways, including self-referential incoherence and pragmatic self-contradiction. In simpler versions, dating at least to the earliest commentary on the Nyāya-sūtra, the realist argues that since views cannot be advanced without reliance upon knowledge sources, the skeptic’s position is abandoned in the very act of making his case. Likewise, one proffering an argument must have some objective or concern that he holds to be normatively binding. The skeptic must either admit this, betraying his skepticism, or be dismissed as a purposeless madman (see Matilal 1986: 87 and Ganeri 2001: 11). In more sophisticated versions, the realist argues that the very concept of falsehood is parasitical on truth and therefore doubt cannot be motivated without an acknowledged background of true cognition (see Dasti 2012). Other anti-skeptical arguments are pragmatic in tone: we appeal to

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL INDIAN PHILOSOPHY

157

knowledge sources (and engage in epistemological reflection upon them) because we want to be guided well in support of our goals in life. A priori skepticism would stultify us from the outset, undermining this very project (see Phillips 2012: 18–19). 8. Phillips (1995: 15) suggests that Nāgārjuna was a catalyst for the “professionalization within all Indian schools” of this time, as his dialectical attacks provoked them into “rethinking [their core positions] and tighter argumentation.” 9. The terms mādhyamika and madhyamaka refer to an individual or group devoted to the “middle way,” a term commonly used by Buddhists to describe the Buddhist lifestyle. It has come to be specifically identified with the tradition that traces itself to Nāgārjuna. In his earliest sermons, the Buddha characterizes his path as a middle way between excessive renunciation and excessive hedonism. Elsewhere, he describes his attitude toward the reality of the world as a middle way between the complete affirmation of being and its complete denial. Nagarjuna (MMK 15.7) directly cites the sermon where this latter notion is put forth, and, as Garfield (1990: 223) notes, this usage sets the stage for Nāgārjuna’s rejection of both metaphysical realism and nihilism in favor of the “middle way” of conventionalism. See Huntington (1989), Siderits (2007: 180–207), and Westerhoff (2009), for philosophically oriented introductions to the school. See Garfield (1995), Siderits and Katsura (2013), and Westerhoff (2010) for translation and commentary on the texts that are central to this study. 10. MMK 15.2 holds that svabhāva is unconstructed (akṛtrimaḥ) and not dependent on something else (nirapekṣaḥ paratra). See Westerhoff (2009: 19–52) for a study of the primary Mādhyamika understandings of svabhāva. A helpful characterization that Westerhoff borrows from Tibetan commentators on Nāgārjuna is that something possessing svabhāva would have to exist “from its own side” and thus independently of our conceptual engagement with it. Tillemans (2001: 9) argues that for Nāgārjuna, the two central aspects of svabhāva, “findability under analysis” (something like conceptual irreducibility) and causal independence, are mutually entailing. 11. Dependent co-origination was originally put forth by the Buddha as an account of the factors that collectively perpetuate a personality stream’s continued misconception and suffering, binding it to continued rebirth in saṁsāra. According to this notion, there is no original, fundamental cause of our existence, but a self-perpetuating cycle of mutually dependent causes. We should underscore that while Nāgārjuna’s usage is tied to the original notion, he clearly develops it according to his own philosophical understanding. 12. This is the primary concern of Chapter 8 of MMK. 13. Westerhoff (2009) catalogues a number of these arguments. 14. For examples of the reasoning captured in this argument, see MMK 13.4–6; 15.2; 20.17; 21.17; 22.22; 24.38. 15. MMK 18.10 therefore states: “Whatever comes into being dependent on another is not identical to that thing. Nor is it different from it” (translation by Garfield 1995: 252). This theme is developed in Chapter 10 of MMK. 16. MMK 1.10; 15.8–9; 24.7–20, 36.

158

SKEPTICISM

17. I will cite specific passages of this text by verse number. See Westerhoff (2010: 63–65) for a concise discussion of this enigmatic disavowal. 18. Translations are mine unless otherwise noted. I have used the Sanskrit manuscript of the Dispeller of Disputes by Yonezawa (2008). Note that derivations of the verbal roots sidh and sādh are used in this passage, conveying the notion of accomplishment or establishment. Here they convey a sense of epistemic establishment or proof. 19. On these grounds, Siderits (1988; 2003: 150–153) argues against using the label “skeptic” for Nāgārjuna and that he is better understood as an anti-realist devoted to undermining correspondence theories of truth and foundationalist epistemologies. Without disagreeing with his cogent analysis of Nāgārjuna’s motivations or antirealist sensibility, I would contest that the convention of calling Nāgārjuna a skeptic (e.g., Matilal 1986 passim) is appropriate, so long as it is understood within the context of his philosophical project. In defense of this, a few remarks are in order. I would suggest that the definition Siderits provides of a paradigmatic skeptic is too narrow. To paraphrase, he defines the skeptic as one who agrees with the realists that there is a theory that best captures reality, but denies that we are capable of achieving it. As an anti-realist conventionalist, Nāgārjuna would then reject the very realist pretentions that give rise to skepticism. But given Siderits’s definition one could even call into question whether Sextus Empiricus is a skeptic. By modus tollens, then, the definition must be too narrow. To elaborate: like Nāgārjuna, Sextus seeks to undermine confidence that an objective theory of reality is even possible as he repeatedly calls attention to the fact that particular phenomena are experienced in radically different ways according to the presuppositions and cognitive backgrounds of the subject. Anyone arguing in favor of her own perspective would do so from within it and thus still be part of the dispute (PH 1.112). Sextus further deploys argumentative tropes akin to those of Nāgārjuna (e.g., the two modes; PH 1.78–79) that are meant to undermine any standard by which the nature of the world may be definitely adjudicated. We may, therefore, speak of Nāgārjuna as a skeptic as we do of Sextus, insofar as he argues that pretentions to objective knowledge of a mindindependent reality are unjustifiable, fruitless, and incoherent. Knowledge of that sort is not possible. In this way, just as Sextus allows for individuals to adopt conductgoverning standards while disavowing opinions regarding the true nature of things (PH 1.21–24), Nāgārjuna would allow for a limited sort of appeal to “knowledge sources” for the needs of common life, while explicitly denying that he maintains any thesis about the real nature of the world (VV 29). I would conclude, therefore, that given the range of meanings associated with “skeptic,” it is not misleading, and is indeed, appropriate for Nāgārjuna, as long as it is understood in the context of his broader project. For a more developed comparison between Madhyamaka and Pyrrhonian skepticism, see Dreyfus and Garfield (2011). 20. Huntington (1989: 78–83) and Westerhoff (2009: 13) underscore the fact that in Madhyamaka thought theoretical reflection must be conjoined with contemplative practice. 21. The first chapter of the Sarvadarśanasaṃgraha, a medieval Indian doxography, is devoted to a reconstruction of the materialist view: see Agrawal (2002). For translations of Jayarāśi’s central work, see Franco (1994) and Solomon (2010). For article-length studies of Jayarāśi, see Balcerowicz (2011) and Mills (2015).

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL INDIAN PHILOSOPHY

159

22. While this is a common characterization of the materialist view, examining extant fragments of commentaries on the Cārvākasūtras (Sūtras on Materialism), Bhattacharya (2011) illustrates that some materialists are willing to allow inference to stand as a source of knowledge, so long as it is entirely grounded upon and derivative of perceptual experience. 23. See Balcerowicz (2011: sect. 1.4) for a succinct summary of available evidence regarding Jayarāśi’s relationship to the materialist school. 24. See Granoff (1978) and Phillips (1995) for influential studies of Śrīharṣa. See Jha (1986) for a translation of his central work. Ram-Prasad (2002) has a number of insightful essays on Śrīharṣa. See Potter (1981) for an introduction to early Advaita Vedānta. See Ganeri (2011: 127 n. 12), however, for a suggestion that the evidence for Śrīharṣa’s connection to the Nondualist school is weaker than often claimed. 25. The use of “ultimate” is important here. Classical Nondualism tends to speak of the objects of ordinary experience as conventionally real, but ultimately unreal. As opposed to a married bachelor, which is unequivocally false, the computer in my office is conventionally real, even if ultimately illusory. Nondualists therefore tend to use a third category (other than “real” or “unreal”) for objects that are merely conventionally or phenomenally real; they are “indeterminate” (anirvacanīya). See Ram-Prasad (2002) for a study of this notion, which deftly ties its development to Indian debates over epistemology and metaphysical realism. 26. Deutsch (1969: 15–26) provides a clear explication of this notion. Phillips (1995: 78–81) discusses its development in Śrīharṣa. For translation of the relevant passages, see Jha (1986: 25–57). 27. Given this project (and with noteworthy affinities to Nāgārjuna), a central target of Śrīharṣa’s attacks is the Nyāya school. Phillips (1995) illustrates the way in which Śrīharṣa’s criticisms were a primary catalyst for the rise of “New Nyāya,” which defends traditional Nyāya positions with increased analytic rigor and refinement. 28. See Jha (1986: 704). For Śrīharṣa’s explicit appeal to the legitimacy of vitaṇḍā, see Jha (1986: 30–31). Extended discussion of this feature of Śrīharṣa’s argument is not possible in this paper, but see Granoff (1978: 1–69) for an example and analysis of his method, applied to the analyses of knowledge provided by his interlocutors. 29. See Jha (1986: 3–24). Also see Granoff (1978: 71–83). 30. Considerations of space preclude discussion of Śrīharṣa’s use of Gettier-style counterexamples to undermine Nyāya definitions of knowledge. This would, of course, be a natural point of resonance with contemporary epistemology. For further discussion, see Matilal (1986: 135–137) and Ganeri (2011: 127–130).

REFERENCES Agrawal, Madan Mohan (trans.). 2002. The Sarva-Darśana-Saṃgraha of Mādhavācārya. Vrajajivan Indological Studies, Vol. 7. Delhi: Chaukhamba Sanskrit Pratishtan. Balcerowicz, Piotr. 2011. “Jayarāśi,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/ entries/jayaraasi/.

160

SKEPTICISM

Barnes, Jonathan and Julia Annas (ed.). 2000. Sextus Empiricus: Outlines of Scepticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bett, Richard. 2000. Pyrrho, his Antecedents and his Legacy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bhattacharya, Ramkrishna. 2010. “Commentators on the Cārvākasūtra: A Critical Survey,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 38: 419–430. Dasti, Matthew R. 2012. “Parasitism and Disjunctivism in Nyāya Epistemology,” Philosophy East and West 62: 1–15. Deutsch, Eliot. 1969. Advaita Vedānta: A Philosophical Reconstruction. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. Dreyfus, Gorges and Jay L. Garfield. 2011. “Madhyamaka and Classical Greek Skepticism.” In The Cowherds (ed.), Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy, 115–130. New York: Oxford University Press. Flintoff, Everard. 1980. “Pyrrho and India,” Phronesis 25: 88–108. Franco, Eli. 1994. Perception, Knowledge and Disbelief: A Study of Jayarasi’s Scepticism. 2nd ed. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. Frenkian, Aram. 1957. “Sextus Empiricus and Indian Logic,” The Philosophical Quarterly (India) 30: 115–126. Ganeri, Jonardon. 2001. Philosophy in Classical India: The Proper Work of Reason. London and New York: Routledge. Ganeri, Jonardon. 2011. The Lost Age of Reason: Philosophy in Early Modern India 1450– 1700. New York: Oxford University Press. Garfield, Jay L. 1990. “Epoche and Śūnyatā: Skepticism East and West,” Philosophy East and West 40: 285–307. Garfield, Jay L. 1995. The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way: Nāgārjuna’s Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. New York: Oxford University Press. Garfield, Jay L. and Graham Priest. 2003. “Nāgārjuna and the Limits of Thought,” Philosophy East and West 53: 1–21. Granoff, P. E. 1978. Philosophy and Argument in Late Vedānta: Śrī Harṣa’s Khaṇḍanakhaṇḍakhādya. Dordrecht: D. Reidel. Hankinson, Robert J. 1995. The Sceptics. London and New York: Routledge. Huntington, C. W. 1989. The Emptiness of Emptiness: An Introduction to Early Indian Mādhyamika. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. Jha, Ganganatha (trans). 1986. The Khaṇḍanakhaṇḍanakhādya of Śrī-harṣa: An English Translation. 2 Vols. Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications. Matilal, Bimal Krishna. 1986. Perception: An Essay on Classical Indian Theories of Knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Matilal, Bimal Krishna. 1988. The Character of Logic in India, edited by Jonardon Ganeri and Heeraman Tiwari. Albany. SUNY Press. McEvilley, Thomas. 1982. “Pyrrhonism and Madhyamika,” Philosophy East and West 32: 3–35. Mills, Ethan. 2015. “Jayarāśi’s Delightful Destruction of Epistemology,” Philosophy East and West 65: 498–541. Mohanty, J. N. 2000. Classical Indian Philosophy. Janham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL INDIAN PHILOSOPHY

161

Nicholson, Hugh. 2009. “The Shift from Agonistic to Non-agonistic Debate in Early Nyāya,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 38: 75–95. Phillips, Stephen H. 1995. Classical Indian Metaphysics: Refutations of Realism and the Emergence of “New Logic.” Chicago: Open Court. Phillips, Stephen H. 2012. Classical Indian Epistemology: The Knowledge Sources of the Nyāya School. New York and London: Routledge. Potter, Karl H. 1981. Advaita Vedānta up to Śaṁkara and His Pupils. The Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, vol. 3. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers. Ram-Prasad, Chakravarthi. 2002. Advaita Epistemology and Metaphysics: An Outline of Indian Non-Realism. London: RoutledgeCurzon. Siderits, Mark. 1988. “Nāgārjuna as Anti-realist,” Journal of Indian Philosophy 16: 311– 325. Siderits, Mark. 2003. Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy. Hampshire: Ashgate Publishing. Siderits, Mark. 2007. Buddhism as Philosophy: An Introduction. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. Siderits, Mark and Shoryu Katsura. 2013. Nāgārjuna’s Middle Way: Mulamadhyamakakārikā. Somerville, MA: Wisdom Publications. Solomon, Esther A. 1976. Indian Dialectics. Vol. 1. Ahmedabad: B. J. Institute of Learning and Research. Solomon, Esther A. (trans.). 2010. Jayarāśi Bhaṭṭa’s Tattvopaplavasiṃha, edited by Shuchita Mehta. Delhi: Parimal Publications. Tillemans, Tom J. F. 2001. “Trying to Be Fair to Mādhyamika Buddhism.” The Numata Yehan Lecture in Buddhism. Calgary, Canada: University of Calgary. Westerhoff, Jan. 2009. Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Westerhoff, Jan. 2010. The Dispeller of Disputes: Nāgārjuna’s Vigrahavyāvartanī. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Yonezawa, Yoshiyasu. 2008. “Vigrahavyāvartanī: Sanskrit Transliteration and Tibetan Translation,” Journal of Aritasan Institute of Buddhist Studies 31: 209–333.

162

PART TWO

MEDIEVAL AND RENAISSANCE SKEPTICISM

164

Introduction Medieval and Renaissance Skepticism DIEGO E. MACHUCA

It is at present widely acknowledged among historians of Western philosophy that the Renaissance was a key period for both the recovery of ancient skeptical texts and the revitalization of the Western skeptical tradition. There has been much less recognition that skeptical problems and arguments were discussed fairly extensively in Western Europe during the Middle Ages. The limited awareness of the role of skepticism in medieval philosophy partially explains why historical scholarship on this topic is still scarce compared to that devoted to skepticism in ancient, Renaissance, or modern philosophy. The situation has started to change, though, particularly in the last few years.1 And fortunately so, since the widespread ignorance of the part played by skepticism during the Middle Ages has prevented most scholars from realizing that medieval discussions of various forms of epistemological skepticism must be taken into account in order to fully understand the history of Renaissance and modern skepticism. For instance, new light is shed on Descartes’s evil genius and deceiving god arguments, and their differences, when one becomes aware that the question of the possibility of divine deception and the question of the extent of this deception in comparison to that of the devil were topics of considerable discussion among medieval theologians and philosophers.2 Given this background, in Descartes’s time the mere reference to deception by an evil demon or by God vividly evoked in his interlocutors and readers a topic with a long and rich history of philosophico-theological debates. But leaving aside this instrumental value, medieval discussions of skepticism—particularly skepticism about our knowledge of the nature and existence of the external world—may be of intrinsic philosophical interest to, for example, those present-day epistemologists concerned with understanding and refuting skepticism. If we consider the influence of the two main ancient skeptical traditions on Western medieval thought, it must first be said that the role played by Pyrrhonism was minor in relation to other forms of skepticism and insignificant in comparison with the part it has had from the sixteenth century until the present day. Knowledge of Pyrrhonian skepticism was extremely limited in the Middle Ages because direct acquaintance with ancient Pyrrhonian texts was rare. Although three manuscripts

166

SKEPTICISM

of an early-fourteenth-century Latin translation of Sextus Empiricus’s Pyrrhonian Outlines, probably by Niccolò da Reggio (ca. 1280–1350), survive, this translation seems to have exerted no influence whatsoever.3 One of these manuscripts also contains a partial Latin translation of Sextus’s Adversus Mathematicos III–V, probably by the same author.4 Likewise, a manuscript remains that contain a fifteenth-century Latin translation, by Giovanni Lorenzi, of the first four books of the Adversus Mathematicos, but it does not appear to have had any circulation.5 It does seem, however, that in the fourteenth century there was some knowledge of Sextus, since it has been argued that, in Nicholas of Autrecourt’s treatment of the infinite regress argument, it is possible to identify certain Pyrrhonian elements (see Grellard 2007a). As for other philosophical traditions, it should be noted that Greek/Byzantine and Arabic scholars continued to read Pyrrhonian texts during Late Antiquity and the Middle Ages. For instance, in his Myriobiblon (Library), Photius, the ninth-century Patriarch of Constantinople, offers a detailed and relatively extensive summary of Aenesidemus’s lost Pyrrhonian Discourses that is our main source for the latter’s own brand of Pyrrhonism. By contrast, Academic skepticism was well known in Western Europe during the Middle Ages especially through Augustine’s Contra academicos, but also through Cicero’s Academica, De natura deorum, and Tusculanae.6 In general, when medieval authors engaged with skepticism, they referred to the position of the “Academics.” For instance, in the thirteenth century, Academic skepticism figures in the works of Henry of Ghent (ca. 1217–1293) and John Duns Scotus (1265/6–1308). While Henry mentions the Academics in his analysis of the ancient skeptical challenges to certain knowledge or cognition, Scotus does so in the attack he mounted against Henry’s theory of illumination: he argued that Henry’s arguments in favor of divine illumination led in the end to the position of the Academics. The debate between them revolved around the question whether human knowledge is possible and, if so, how. To put it in rather simplistic terms, they both agreed that humans can have knowledge, but while Henry put forward arguments to the effect that we are unable to attain certain knowledge without divine illumination, Scotus claimed that the natural use of our cognitive faculties is sufficient to attain such knowledge.7 Setting aside the transmission and influence of ancient skeptical arguments, it should be remarked that medieval philosophico-theological discussions gave rise to original skeptical arguments, the most important of which is that which appeals to the notion of a God who, being all-powerful, could easily deceive us. In its most radical form, this argument—versions of which were discussed by such figures as William of Ockham (ca. 1287–1347), Robert Holkot (ca. 1290–1349), Gregory of Rimini (ca. 1300–1358), Nicholas of Autrecourt (ca. 1299–1369), John Buridan (ca. 1300–1361), and Peter of Ailly (1351–1420)—targets all of our knowledge of the nature and the very existence of the external world, and even logical principles such as the principle of non-contradiction. Thus, as medieval philosophy scholars sometimes remark, it is a mistake to think that external world skepticism was first formulated by Descartes. However, it is also noted that medieval authors did not in fact draw the radical skeptical implications of their arguments concerning

INTRODUCTION

167

divine omnipotence, the reason being that, unlike Descartes, their project was not the examination of the reliability of our cognitive capacities in order to determine whether infallible or certain knowledge is possible. They were interested in exploring the implications of the theological thesis about God’s absolute power, but did not doubt that our cognitive capacities are reliable whenever nature follows its normal course.8 Unlike what happened before and after the Middle Ages, during this period there were no skeptics, with the probable exception of John of Salisbury (ca. 1120–1180), who was influenced by Cicero and considered himself an Academic skeptic. Salisbury sought to adapt the skeptical stance he found in Cicero to Christianity. According to him, by means of the sole use of reason, certain ancient philosophers came close to the divine mysteries, but failed to recognize that their rational capacity was a gift from God and even dared to rival Him. As a result, God punished them by concealing the truth from them, which accounts for the plurality of the philosophical sects and their entrenched disputes. Academic skepticism was the humble recognition that the truth is beyond our reach. Salisbury claimed, however, that even though only God has certain knowledge of all things, we have a natural desire for truth that cannot be vain because it is implanted in us by Him: truth exists and we can gradually approach it, but without ever being able to fully attain it. Salisbury was not therefore a radical skeptic advocating universal suspension of judgment or denying the possibility of all knowledge. Rather, embracing a form of probabilism, he took skepticism to be a stance of prudence and modesty that avoids rash judgments concerning all the issues that admit of no definite resolution, and that is compatible with the holding of reasonable and fallible beliefs that are formed through dialogue and debate and that can serve as both a guide to life and the foundation of natural science. Moreover, Salisbury took certain propositions to be immune from doubt and the basis of the critical and open-minded examination of truth: logical and mathematical propositions, those concerning immediate perceptions, and those concerning the foundations of faith.9 Even though a number of medieval thinkers adopted what might be regarded as a skeptical stance on specific issues, when skepticism was the topic of discussion, in most cases the aim was either to refute the skeptical argument being considered or, following a reductio ad absurdum strategy, to refute one’s opponent’s position by showing that it led to skepticism. With regard to the former aim, one could cite, for example, the various thirteenth-century strategies to refute the skeptical argument based on the illusion of the senses (see Grellard 2004). As for the latter aim, one could mention, in addition to Scotus’s attack on Henry’s theory of divine illumination referred to above, that Nicholas of Autrecourt argued that Bernard of Arezzo’s view on the intuitive cognition of non-existents had skeptical implications that were more absurd than those which followed from the Academics’ position, and that John Buridan, in turn, argued that Nicholas’s foundationalist anti-skeptical reply actually led to skepticism while his own fallibilist strategy did successfully answer the skeptical challenge.10 Bernard of Arezzo was a Franciscan whom Nicholas had met when they were both theology students in Paris and to whom he wrote nine letters, only two of which

168

SKEPTICISM

survive.11 According to these letters, Bernard held that, in those circumstances in which God intervenes in the normal course of nature, there may be an act of cognition even if its object does not exist. In Nicholas’s view, this meant that it is not possible to determine when our awareness of the existence of external objects is true or false, and hence that we can never be certain of their existence, for it is not possible to determine when the act of cognition is produced by a supernatural or a natural cause, that is, by God or by the perceived object itself. Bernard also claimed that we do not have direct intuitive cognition of our own mental acts. In response, Nicholas argued that, if one cannot be certain of the existence of those things of which one has a clear cognition (viz., external objects), neither can one be certain of the existence of those things of which one has a less clear cognition (viz., one’s own mental acts), and so one cannot be certain of one’s own existence as an intellect. Although he offered replies to different skeptical arguments—such as the argument from sensory illusion and the dream argument—Nicholas’s general reply to skepticism consisted in maintaining both (i) that there are evident basic beliefs, both perceptual and intellectual, on which the justification of other beliefs ultimately rest, and (ii) that “evidentness” (evidentia),12 which admits of no degrees, is not a necessary condition for knowledge, since there is also probable knowledge, that is, knowledge of that which cannot be demonstrated but can be defended by means of rational arguments—for example, inductive and causal knowledge is probable, not evident. Buridan’s own reply to skepticism about the external world consisted in distinguishing, pace Nicholas, between two degrees of evidentness that can ground knowledge: evidentness properly so called and natural or relative evidentness. The former type of evidentness, which commands our assent immediately, is that of the propositions that are true by virtue of the semantic relation between their terms (e.g., “Every horse is an animal”) or that exemplify the principle of non-contradiction. Natural evidentness is that of the propositions expressing that which appears to be the case and which cannot appear to be otherwise for any human reason—except for sophistical ones. This type of evidentness cannot properly be so called because the intellect may be deceived with regard to those naturally evident propositions owing to a supernatural cause, that is, when God intervenes in the normal course of nature, causing the appearance of an object that is not really present. Buridan therefore conceded the possibility of divine deception with regard to our knowledge of external objects, but argued that the skeptic placed an unreasonable demand for absolute evidentness—and hence for absolute certainty—on our knowledge of the world. For, even though naturally evident knowledge is fallible, it suffices for the principles and conclusions of natural science whenever nature follows its normal course. Just as one should bear in mind that there were (almost) no real skeptics during the Middle Ages, so too should one bear in mind that medieval refutations of skepticism were not produced in the context of a serious skeptical crisis, unlike what later occurred in the Renaissance and modern periods. Rather, at least a considerable number of medieval authors made a methodological use of skeptical arguments, which consisted in using such arguments either to undermine a given conception of knowledge that was then replaced by another one immune from the challenges posed

INTRODUCTION

169

by those arguments, or to distinguish between types of knowledge and to determine the kind of certainty proper to each one of them.13 Skepticism seems to have been a logical construction independent for the most part of the skeptical tradition, which explains why it was understood as a reservoir of arguments to the effect that knowledge is impossible (Grellard 2004: 113; 2007a: 328). The skeptic was a fictional character whose radical stance could teach us something about the nature and limits of human knowledge. The medieval conception of skepticism is thus analogous to the way in which skepticism is conceived of by most contemporary analytic epistemologists, who take for granted that there are not, and there cannot be, any real skeptics, and who therefore regard skeptical arguments as ingenious and enlightening heuristic devices. I noted at the outset that many historians of philosophy are still unaware that discussion of skeptical problems and arguments is well attested in Western medieval philosophy. Still less known is the fact that skepticism played a central part in philosophico-theological discussions in classical Islam—a period that ranges from the ninth to the thirteenth centuries CE—even though in the Islamic tradition there were no flesh-and-blood skeptics. Skepticism arose in a dialectical context in which incompatible views were defended concerning such subjects as the anthropomorphic nature of God, the nature of belief in Islam, and religious pluralism. Skepticism was conceived of as an attitude of perplexity and doubt in the face of conflicting and equipollent assertions, and was hence clearly distinguished from the attitude of disbelief. Even though the writings of Sextus and Cicero were not available in Arabic, Islamic scholars made use of concepts that remind us of Greek skeptical notions such as ἀπορία (aporia) and ἰσοσθένεια (equipollence). Given the significant role played by skepticism during Islam’s classical period, the present book includes a chapter on this topic that focuses primarily on al-Ghazālī (1058–1111), a philosopher and theologian of Sunni Islam. al-Ghazālī made use of skeptical arguments in order to show that philosophy is unable to attain any kind of true knowledge unless it is combined or supplemented with mystical insight, for God is the ultimate guarantor of truth. al-Ghazālī is an interesting figure for historians of modern Western philosophy due to the striking similarities between the skeptical arguments he formulated and those found in Descartes (e.g., the argument from sensory illusion or the dream argument) and Hume (the arguments against causation), as well as between his and Descartes’s autobiographical records of their skeptical crises, their rejection of traditional beliefs, and their quest for certain knowledge.14 As for the part that skepticism played in the Renaissance, it should first be mentioned that in 1562 Henri Estienne published a Latin translation of Sextus’s Pyrrhonian Outlines, and in 1569 Gentian Hervet published a Latin translation of Adversus Mathematicos and of Adversus Dogmaticos, which made widely available what we today know as Sextus’s corpus. It is safe to say that most historians of ideas accept at present that the Renaissance rediscovery of those Pyrrhonian texts exerted a strong influence on the European intellectual life in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, playing a key role in shaping philosophical thought in particular. Richard Popkin was the first to maintain that the revival of Pyrrhonism

170

SKEPTICISM

triggered a “Pyrrhonian crisis.”15 According to Popkin, this crisis first arose in the religious sphere, and then spread to cover philosophy, the sciences, and the pseudosciences. In his view, the history of Renaissance and modern philosophy should to a large extent be construed as the history of the various strategies that Renaissance and modern thinkers devised to deal with that crisis. What is of note about the rediscovery and dissemination of Sextus’s writings is the fact that his Pyrrhonism was put into the service of very different, and sometimes incompatible, aims. Some scholars have argued that Popkin overstated the part played by Pyrrhonism in shaping Renaissance and modern thought (Ayers 2004; Perler 2004). However that may be, it seems incontestable that Pyrrhonism was one of the intellectual forces that molded Renaissance and modern philosophical discussions. This is to be explained, at least in part, by the fact that those philosophers who took an interest in Sextus found in his substantive surviving writings several sophisticated batteries of arguments that call into question the epistemic justification of our beliefs in a more systematic and compelling way than anything contained in the other available ancient sources. The Pyrrhonism expounded in the recovered Sextan writings will then become an integral part of Renaissance discussions of skepticism. Academic skepticism, already known from the works of Augustine and Cicero, will of course continue to be taken into consideration in such discussions, but now with the additional invaluable information on the Pyrrhonian brand of skepticism provided by Sextus’s works. In this second part of the book, the reader will find three chapters dealing with the most important figures of Renaissance skepticism, namely, Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592), Pierre Charron (1541–1603), and Francisco Sanchez (1550/51–1623). Unlike the medieval authors who engaged with skepticism (again, with the possible exception of John of Salisbury), Montaigne, Charron, and Sanchez were skeptics, even if of a mitigated stripe. As in medieval philosophy, skepticism was discussed by Renaissance skeptics in close connection with religious and theological matters. In fact, both Montaigne and Charron have been considered as fideists (Popkin 2003), embracing a type of skepticism according to which reason by itself is useless for the attainment of truth or the justification of our beliefs, faith being the only means to the acquisition of knowledge and certainty. Montaigne, whose Essays heavily rely and expand on Sextus’s works, is the central figure both in the dissemination of those recently recovered works and in the impact of Pyrrhonism on Renaissance and modern philosophy, to the extent that he may be considered the first non-ancient Pyrrhonist. His importance is seen, for example, in his being the first author to have translated Sextus’s technical skeptical terms into a modern language. Montaigne’s own form of Pyrrhonism presents some key differences from Sextus’s. For instance, he interpreted Pyrrhonism as a form of phenomenalism according to which our knowledge is restricted to appearances (understood narrowly as perceptual appearances), since objective reality is unknowable. Besides the fact that Sextus’s notion of appearance included both perceptual and intellectual appearances, the main problem with Montaigne’s view concerns, from an ancient Pyrrhonist’s point of view, his claim about the unknowability of reality, which would gain him the accusation of negative meta-dogmatism that Sextus leveled against neoAcademics, Cyrenaics, and Empirical doctors. In addition, Montaigne conceived of

INTRODUCTION

171

the skeptic as someone who is in a state of doubt, which is a state of uneasiness or discomfort, radically different from the state of undisturbedness that the ancient Pyrrhonist fortuitously attained by suspending judgment. Montaigne also associated the Pyrrhonian fourfold observance of everyday life with Catholic traditionalism as a way of avoiding adherence to the Reformation.16 Charron adopted a more positive stance on the epistemic value of reason than did Sextus and Montaigne. Unlike Sextus, he regarded suspension of judgment as the voluntary decision of the inquirer and also allowed the skeptic to have weak opinions, in line with what he took to be Academic skepticism. His own skeptical stance is closer to this form of skepticism than to Pyrrhonism, even though he did not in the end distinguish between them. Charron introduced a sharp distinction between the internal and the external spheres that may sometimes be in strong tension: the Charronian skeptic behaves in accordance with the social norms and confines his doubt to the private sphere, where the sole authority is reason, and preserves his intellectual autonomy from the external requirements by bringing everything under critical scrutiny.17 As for Sanchez—the author of That Nothing is Known—he seems to have been a skeptic of a Pyrrhonian stripe, although he has also been characterized as defending Academic skepticism—this latter understood either as the view that knowledge is impossible or as the view that less-than-certain knowledge is achievable but always revisable in the face of new evidence. Sanchez’s Pyrrhonism can be seen, for example, in his portrayal of his search for truth: though he has not yet found it, he keeps seeking it, and though he does not claim that the search for truth is doomed to failure, he cannot assure that it will ever be found. The target of his skeptical assault was the scholastic Aristotelianism of his day: following an ad hominem argumentative strategy, he claimed that, if either of the two dominant Aristotelian metaphysical views were true, then knowledge would be impossible. It should finally be noted that Sanchez, who was also a physician, seems to have been influenced by the skeptical approach to the practice of medicine adopted by ancient medical Empiricism, a school with close ties with Pyrrhonism.18

NOTES 1. See especially Perler (2006), Lagerlund (2010), Grellard (2013), and Denery, Ghosh and Zeeman (2014). 2. For medieval authors, while the devil’s deception is restricted to knowledge that originates in perception—i.e., to the realm of external material objects that act upon our senses—God is also able to act directly upon the intellect by creating a false proposition and inducing the intellect to assent to it. On this difference, see Gregory (1992c). 3. See Schmitt (1983: 227) and Porro (1994: 230–235). For a detailed analysis of these manuscripts, see Cavini (1977: 1–8) and Floridi (2002: 63–69). 4. See Cavini (1977: 4, 8–9) and Floridi (2002: 79–80). 5. See Schmitt (1976), Porro (1994: 236), and Floridi (2002: 80–84). 6. See Schmitt (1983: 227), Porro (1994: 242–251), and Grellard (2004: 114–115).

172

SKEPTICISM

7. On Henry’s position and Scotus’s attack on it, see especially Perler (2006: ch. 1). It should here be pointed out that a chapter devoted to this topic and to skepticism in the thirteenth century in general was commissioned, but its author never fulfilled his commitment and publication of the book could not be further delayed. 8. On the deceiving God argument in the Middle Ages, and some comparisons with Descartes’s, see, besides Henrik Lagerlund’s chapter in this book, Perler (2010a) and especially Tullio Gregory’s two seminal studies: Gregory (1992b,c). 9. On the skepticism of John of Salisbury, in addition to David Bloch’s chapter in this book, see Grellard (2007b, 2013). 10. On Nicholas of Autrecourt’s and John Buridan’s replies to skepticism, besides Christophe Grellard’s chapter in this book, see Zupko (1993), Thijssen (2000), Grellard (2007a, 2010), Karger (2010), and Klima (2010). 11. A critical edition and English translation of Nicholas’s extant correspondence is provided in de Rijk (1994). 12. I render the Latin evidentia as “evidentness” in lieu of “self-evidence” because the former translation has become a technical term in scholarship on medieval philosophy. 13. See especially Perler (2010b); cf. Grellard (2004: 128–129; 2007a: 342). Of course, whether an author considered it necessary to answer a given skeptical argument or merely made a methodological use of is not always easy to establish. 14. On al-Ghazālī, besides Paul Heck’s contribution to this book, see Halevi (2002) and Kukkonen (2010). On skepticism in classical Islam in general, see Heck (2014). On the comparison of al-Ghazālī with Descartes and Hume, see Menn (2003) and Moad (2009). 15. Popkin (1960) is the pioneering work on the impact of ancient skepticism (especially in its Pyrrhonian variety) on Renaissance and modern philosophy, covering the period from Erasmus to Descartes. Popkin (1979) extends the analysis to Spinoza, and Popkin (2003) reaches back to Savonarola and forward to Bayle. 16. On Montaigne’s skepticism, besides Gianni Paganini’s contribution, see e.g. Brahami (1997), Giocanti (2001), Popkin (2003: ch. 3), and Paganini (2008: ch. 1). 17. On Charron’s skepticism, besides Gianni Paganini’s contribution, see e.g. Popkin (2003: ch. 3) and Maia Neto (2014: ch. 2). 18. On Sanchez’s skepticism, besides Damian Caluori’s chapter, see Limbrick (1988), Popkin (2003: 38–43), Caluori (2007) and Paganini (2016).

REFERENCES Ayers, Michael. 2004. “Popkin’s Revised Scepticism,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12: 319–332. Brahami, Frédéric. 1997. Le scepticisme de Montaigne. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Caluori, Damian. 2007. “The Skepticism of Francisco Sanchez,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 89: 30–46. Cavini, Walter. 1977. “Appunti sulla prima diffusione in Occidente delle opere di Sesto Empirico,” Medioevo 3: 1–20.

INTRODUCTION

173

Denery, Dallas, Kantik Ghosh, and Nicolette Zeeman (eds.). 2014. Uncertain Knowledge: Scepticism, Relativism, and Doubt in the Middle Ages. Turnhout: Brepols. de Rijk, L. M. 1994. Nicholas of Autrecourt: His Correspondence with Master Giles and Bernard of Arezzo. Leiden: Brill. Floridi, Luciano. 2002. Sextus Empiricus: The Transmission and Recovery of Pyrrhonism. New York: Oxford University Press. Giocanti, Sylvia. 2001. Penser l’irrésolution: Montaigne, Pascal, La Mothe Le Vayer. Trois itinéraires sceptiques. Paris: Honoré Champion. Gregory, Tullio. 1992a. Mundana Sapientia: Forme di conoscenza nella cultura medievale. Roma: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura. Gregory, Tullio. 1992b. “La tromperie divine.” In Gregory 1992a, 389–399. (First published in 1982.) Gregory, Tullio. 1992c. “Dio ingannatore e genio maligno. Nota in margine alle Meditationes di Descartes.” In Gregory 1992a, 401–440. (First published in 1974.) Grellard, Christophe. 2004. “Comment peut-on se fier à l’expérience? Esquisse d’une typologie des réponses médiévales au problème sceptique,” Quaestio 4: 113–135. Grellard, Christophe. 2007a. “Scepticism, Demonstration and the Infinite Regress Argument (Nicholas of Autrecourt and John Buridan),” Vivarium 45: 328–342. Grellard, Christophe. 2007b. “Jean de Salisbury: un cas médiéval de scepticisme,” Freiburger Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Theologie 54: 16–40. Grellard, Christophe. 2010. “Nicholas of Autrecourt’s Skepticism: The Ambivalence of Medieval Epistemology.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background, 119–143. Leiden: Brill. Grellard, Christophe. 2013. Jean de Salisbury et la renaissance médiévale du scepticisme. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. Halevi, Leor. 2002. “The Theologian’s Doubts: Natural Philosophy and the Skeptical Games of Ghazālī,” Journal of the History of Ideas 63: 19–29. Heck, Paul. 2014. Skepticism in Classical Islam: Moments of Confusion. New York: Routledge. Karger, Elizabeth. 2010. “A Buridanian Response to a Fourtheenth Century Skeptical Argument and its Rebuttal by a New Argument in the Early Sixteenth Century.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background, 215–232. Leiden: Brill. Klima, Gyula. 2010. “The Anti-skepticism of John Buridan and Thomas Aquinas: Putting Skepticism in their Place Versus Stopping them in their Tracks.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background, 145–170. Leiden: Brill. Kukkonen, Taneli. 2010. “Al-Ghazālī’s Skepticism Revisited.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background, 29–59. Leiden: Brill. Lagerlund, Henrik (ed.). 2010. Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background. Leiden: Brill. Limbrick, Elaine. 1988. “Introduction.” In E. Limbrick and D. Thomson (eds.), Francisco Sanches: That Nothing is Known, 1–88. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

174

SKEPTICISM

Maia Neto, José. 2014. Academic Skepticism in Seventeenth-Century French Philosophy: The Charronian Legacy 1601–1662. Dordrecht: Springer. Menn, Stephen 2003. “The Discourse on the Method and the Tradition of Intellectual Autobiography.” In J. Miller and B. Inwood (eds.), Hellenistic and Early Modern Philosophy, 141–191. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Moad, Omar. 2009. “Comparing Phases of Skepticism in al-Ghazālī and Descartes: Some First Meditations on Deliverance from Error,” Philosophy East and West 59: 88–101. Paganini, Gianni. 2008. Skepsis: Le débat des modernes sur le scepticisme. Paris: Vrin. Paganini, Gianni. 2016. “Sanches et Descartes. Subjectivité et connaissance réflexive au temps des sceptiques,” Bulletin de la Société internationale des amis de Montaigne 64: 173–185. Perler, Dominik. 2004. “Was There a ‘Pyrrhonian Crisis’ in Early Modern Philosophy? A Critical Notice of Richard H. Popkin,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 86: 209–220. Perler, Dominik. 2006. Zweifel und Gewissheit: Skeptische Debatten im Mittelalter. Frankfurt: Klostermann. Perler, Dominik. 2010a. “Could God Deceive us? Skeptical Hypotheses in Late Medieval Epistemology.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background, 171–192. Leiden: Brill. Perler, Dominik. 2010b. “Skepticism.” In R. Pasnau (ed.), The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy, 384–396. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Popkin, Richard. 1960. The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Descartes. Assen: van Gorcum. Popkin, Richard. 1979. The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza. Berkeley: University of California Press. Popkin, Richard. 2003. The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle. New York: Oxford University Press. Porro, Pascuale. 1994. “Il Sextus latinus e l’immagine dello scetticismo antico nel medioevo,” Elenchos 15: 229–253. Schmitt, Charles. 1976. “An Unstudied Fifteenth-century Latin Translation of Sextus Empiricus by Giovanni Lorenzi.” In C. H. Clough (ed.), Cultural Aspects of the Italian Renaissance: Essays in Honor of Paul Oskar Kristeller, 244–261. Manchester: Manchester University Press. Schmitt, Charles. 1983. “The Rediscovery of Ancient Skepticism in Modern Times.” In M. Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition, 226–251. Berkeley, Los Angeles and London: University of California Press. Thijssen, Johannes. 2000. “The Quest for Certain Knowledge in the Fourteenth Century: Nicholas of Autrecourt against the Academics.” In J. Sihvola (ed.), Ancient Scepticism and the Sceptical Tradition (Acta Philosophica Fennica 64), 199–223. Helsinki: Philosophical Society of Finland. Zupko, Jack. 1993. “Buridan on Skepticism,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 31: 191–221.

CHAPTER TWELVE

Augustine and Skepticism STÉPHANE MARCHAND

1 INTRODUCTION Augustine (354–430 CE) was certainly not a skeptic. He nevertheless played a crucial role in the history of philosophical skepticism. Three main reasons place Augustine at a strategic point in relation to skepticism. First, he is the author of Against the Academics (Contra Academicos), a philosophical dialogue entirely devoted to the refutation of skepticism, where he discusses the arguments of the New Academy in order to go beyond skepticism. But, secondly, Augustine’s contribution to skepticism is not limited to this work, for he never ceased in considering skepticism a problem of the highest order. His conception of belief in the Christian faith can also be interpreted as a response to the skeptical contention that one should live without belief. Finally, through his reflections on the problem of skepticism, Augustine conceived of a new form of it: skepticism as a thought experiment of the inner self, which exhibits a metaphysical and epistemological strength that from Descartes onward has remained vibrant.1

2 THE CONTRA ACADEMICOS Augustine is a witness of great importance in the history of ancient skepticism under its Academic guise. First of all, his reading of Cicero played a crucial role in the education he received.2 Augustine was probably the most important reader of Cicero’s Academica in antiquity (Schmitt 1972: 29): he took the arguments put forward by Cicero in that book very seriously, to the point that he confessed having temporarily endorsed the skepticism of the New Academy in 383 CE, after giving up Manichaeism and before his conversion to Christianity (see Confessiones V x 19; cf. De beata vita 4).3 Therefore, for Augustine skepticism was not just a theoretical hypothesis, but a real (albeit false) philosophical alternative for those who are disappointed by how difficult it is to find the truth. Since he felt that skepticism was a genuine problem, he wrote an entire dialogue with the sole purpose of refuting it, the Contra Academicos, written in 386, just after his conversion to Christianity.

176

SKEPTICISM

Contra Academicos is presented as a dialogue in the style of Cicero and is composed of three books. The global aim of the work is to demonstrate, in countering skepticism, that certain knowledge is possible and that happiness cannot be attained without believing that it is possible to find the truth (C. Acad. I ii 5). At the end of the dialogue, Augustine distinguishes between the real intention of the Academics, who according to him were not true skeptics, and their arguments, which were genuinely skeptical. Augustine was convinced that the so-called skeptical Academy represented, in reality, an esoteric form of Platonism that used skepticism to hide its dogmatism during the Hellenistic period, when materialism was flourishing (see C. Acad. III xvii 37–xx 43; see also Letter 1).4 Therefore, when Augustine criticized the New Academy, he was not attacking the Academy as an institution (indeed, he shared their Platonist conviction that spirit is superior to matter). Rather, he was trying to inoculate against skepticism anyone who might be tempted to take it as a serious philosophical option. Because there were people who believed the Academy’s skeptical arguments to be valid, he considered it not only necessary to respond to those arguments, but to restore a genuine relationship to truth. Augustine’s line of argument in the Contra Academicos is somewhat tortuous.5 However, it is possible to distinguish between two levels of refutation: (i) an epistemological and (ii) a moral level.6 The epistemological level (i) is a direct response to the arguments presented in Cicero’s Academica. Augustine purported to prove that it was possible to offer a rational response to the New Academy. Among the numerous arguments, Augustine made use of analytic or a priori knowledge: even if one doubts a proposition, this doubt cannot remove the true knowledge that this proposition is either true or false (C. Acad. III ix 21). Similarly, every disjunctive proposition is necessarily true (C. Acad. III ix 23: the world is organized either by a divine providence or by a body, it either has a beginning or does not, etc.; see also III xiii 29). These arguments function as counterexamples, showing that it is easy to have access to certainty and, therefore, that there is no reason to despair of knowing the truth: Augustine’s contention against skepticism is that some things can be known.7 We can focus on a set of arguments that are similar to the dream argument in Descartes’s First Meditation: Therefore, I call the whole that contains and sustains us, whatever it is, the “world”—the whole, I say, that appears before my eyes, which I perceive to include the heavens and the earth (or the quasi-heavens and quasi-earth). If you say nothing seems to be so to me, I’ll never be in error. It is the man who recklessly approves what seems so to him who is in error. You do say that a falsehood can seem to be so to sentient beings. You don’t say that nothing seems to be so. Every ground for disputation, where you Academicians enjoy being the master, is completely taken away if it is true not only that we knew nothing, but also that nothing seems to be so to us. However, if you deny that what seems

AUGUSTINE AND SKEPTICISM

177

so to me is the world, then you’re making a fuss about a name, since I said I call this “world.” You’ll ask me: “Is what you see the world even if you’re asleep?” It has already been said that I call “world” whatever seems to me to be such. (C. Acad. III xi 24–25)8 Thus, whatever we might think about the existence of an external world (the knowledge of which is mediated by our senses and can actually be false), it remains indubitable that there is something in one’s mind (even if I am dreaming or suffering from a hallucination) that I can call “world” and about which I can form true knowledge. Admittedly, Cicero’s Academica (II 47–48) already planted the seeds of this argument. But Cicero glanced over that hypothesis without any clear formulation of a world composed only of inner states. Augustine’s own reflection on the Academic arguments produced a clearer formulation of the hypothesis of external world skepticism which will be a fundamental feature of modern skepticism.9 As for the moral level of refutation (ii) as Heil (1972: 109) has claimed, in Contra Academicos the core of the refutation is not epistemological. Augustine was aware that the truth and certainty he was looking for was not of the kind we find in mathematics or analytic knowledge (see C. Acad. II iii 9), but concerned instead knowledge of the soul and of God, the sole objects of worth for Augustine (see Soliloques I 7). Indeed, this skepticism is dangerous because it can discourage anyone from being on the path of the truth, i.e., on the path of God. Hence, the real danger of skepticism is moral, and it becomes essential to demonstrate that skepticism as a philosophy is essentially defective. This demonstration consists in showing that skepticism is not what it seems to be for Cicero, namely, an open-minded stance that earnestly seeks the truth (see, e.g., Acad. II iii 7), but rather a renunciation of truth and philosophy: “Therefore,” I continued, “don’t you know that up to now there is nothing I perceive to be certain? I’m prevented from searching for it by the arguments and debates of the Academicians. They somehow persuaded me of the plausibility—so as not to give up their word just yet—that man cannot find the truth. Accordingly, I had become lazy and utterly inactive, not daring to search for what the most ingenuous and learned men weren’t permitted to find. Unless, therefore, I first become as convinced that the truth can be found as the Academicians are convinced that it cannot, I shall not dare to search for it. I don’t have anything to defend.” (C. Acad. II ix 23) Here is the danger: by their arguments, the Academics deviate from the natural path that leads from the desire for truth to knowledge and then to God. And since the knowledge of God is the only means of achieving our natural desire to be happy, the moral refutation of skepticism consists of demonstrating that it cannot be considered a serious philosophical option to achieve happiness. Rather, for Augustine, the skeptics’ excessive prudence hides existential despair (the despair of truth, the desperatio veri: see Letter 1, 3; C. Acad. II i 1; Confessiones VI i 1). In fact,

178

SKEPTICISM

the skeptic is frightened by the possibility of error. By privileging the criterion of plausibility (as King translates the Latin probabile, which is itself a translation of the greek word πιθανόν), he is trying to avoid risk. But, as Augustine shows, this position cannot provide any quietude and does not prevent anyone from error: I seemed to see an entrance through which error would rush in upon those who felt safe. I think that a man is in error not only when he follows the false path, but also when he’s not following the true one. (C. Acad. III xv 34) Therefore, a person can avoid giving his assent, follow the criterion of what is probable—in sum, a person can act exactly as Carneades recommended—and still be wrong: being guided by the criterion of what is probable does not prevent anyone from sinning, and therefore can lead them to err from a moral point of view (C. Acad. III xvi 35–36). Rashness can be useful and necessary in order to allow an individual to believe something doubtful that will nevertheless lead to truth. Even if to doubt can prevent many of our errors, one cannot find the true path without having a belief.

3  HERMENEUTICS AGAINST SKEPTICISM If something skeptical remained in Augustine’s position, it should be sought in connection with his thoughts on the weakness of pure reason.10 Indeed, Augustine was an acute critic of the arrogance of philosophers, who claimed that it was possible to know everything through the use of reason alone. Against this claim Augustine insisted, in a skeptical manner, on the difficulty of finding any indubitable truth by itself through reason, at least on any theological or metaphysical level. Thus, Augustine tried to find an escape path between two excesses: an excessive rationalism that claims to know God by reason (as the Manicheans claimed: see De utilitate credendi I 2) and an excessive skepticism that will lead to the despair of truth. Augustine frequently agreed that it is reason—or intellect—whose function it is to understand the truth; but the problem is knowing whether such an understanding can begin with reason alone or must instead begin with belief and, more precisely, with faith. To introduce the necessity of faith (fides) as a condition for understanding, Augustine made frequent use of Isaiah 7.9: “Unless you believe, you will not understand.” Hence, Augustine’s position did not entail fideism in the sense that faith should replace reason, but rather stressed the necessity of believing in order to understand and know theological truths, according to the principle crede ut intelligas: you must believe to understand (see e.g., De libero arbitrio I 4). As Augustine said, “Faith prepares the ground for understanding” (De ut. cred. XVII 35)11; in the end, it is reason that understands, but reason needs to begin with some form of belief (Rist 2001: 27). Hence, to attain knowledge of the truths that really matter to Augustine, knowledge of God and of our soul, it is impossible to rely on pure reason; unlike formal knowledge, this kind of knowledge concerns objects that are hidden and requires one to begin with belief. Since there is no direct access to this knowledge,

AUGUSTINE AND SKEPTICISM

179

it is necessary to believe in some authority in order to be on the path of truth. This contention does not entail, as fideism does, the confusion between knowledge and faith, but rather the distinction between two epistemological processes: “We must hold what we understand as coming from reason, what we believe as coming from authority” (De ut. cred. XI 25).12 Actually, it seems that, in Augustine’s view, belief is necessary not only in theological or metaphysical matters, for almost all aspects of the human condition are determined by our confidence in propositions that we cannot verify through scrutiny; propositions about our relation to the world and to other men, even to our own history, rely on belief. Belief is a necessary feature of the human condition: without believing witnesses, we could know nothing of history or about the thoughts and feelings of another mind13: So it was, Lord, that you began little by little to work on my heart with your most gentle and merciful hand, and dispose it to reflect how innumerable were the things I believed and held to be true, though I had neither seen them nor been present when they happened. How many truths there were of this kind, such as events of world history, or facts about places and cities I had never seen; how many were the statements I believed on the testimony of friends, or physicians, or various other people; and, indeed, unless we did believe them we should be unable to do anything in this life. With what unshakable certainty, moreover, did I hold fast to the belief that I had been born of my particular parents, yet I could not have known this without believing what I had heard. (Conf. VI v 7; Boulding’s translation in Rotelle 1997) Augustine offers a rationalist approach to the problem of believing. To believe (credere) is not necessarily to be credulous. On the contrary, Augustine (again at De ut. cred. XI 25) stresses the difference between believing and having an opinion (opinari). To have an opinion consists of having a belief without the consciousness that it is a mere belief. To opine entails the ignorance of the difference between the things we can know (intelligere) and those we can only believe (credibilia); in sum, opinion is rash belief. But to believe is not wrong per se. We can have true belief, if we keep in mind that this very belief remains a mere belief, and if we have good reasons to believe. Hence, the quality of the belief depends on the awareness that belief is not certain knowledge and on the authority followed for believing. Thus, just as reason needs faith, so too does faith need reason. More precisely, faith is the belief in an authority that has—by rational means—been recognized as being reliable. In the end, this is the very reason that compels us to decide whether to believe or not: If, then, it is reasonable that faith precede reason with respect to certain great truths that cannot yet be grasped, however slight the reason is that persuades us to this, it undoubtedly also comes before faith. (Letter 120, 3; Teske’s translation in Ramsey 2004; see also De vera religione XXIV 45) This rationalistic approach to faith is based on reflection on the authority of the Bible as a holy book that defines what it is to believe. This view makes it possible to

180

SKEPTICISM

differentiate between Christian faith and credulity: if faith is not blind and irrational assent, it is necessary to have reasons to assent to facts that are, for the most part, unbelievable, such as the resurrection of Christ. For Augustine, the Bible gives an account of God’s manifestations in the world, which are signs to be interpreted. In this sense, the Bible is like a history book that requires the evaluation of the reliability of the witnesses and their idiosyncrasies, etc. Since there can be no direct knowledge of history, we have to rely on accounts and testimonies, and Augustine tries to offer some sort of method to acquire a rational approach to the Bible as God’s book, by defending its reliability and overall coherence, despite the fact that God has chosen different prophets who use a variety of styles and images to pass on the testimony of his actions on men. The Bible therefore contains, on the one hand, reasons to believe its contents, and on the other, truths enabling readers to understand once a method to read and to interpret it has been provided.14 Hence, there is a connection between Augustine’s reflection on belief and his thoughts on reading and hermeneutic theory, and this reflection shares some common features with the problem of skepticism, and more precisely with the problem of understanding someone else’s thought.15 This feature of Augustine’s thought has been related to the hermeneutic circle. Augustine’s reflection on belief shows that, in many things, understanding entails, firstly, making the hypothesis that there is something to understand (a kind of principle of charity, cf. De ut. cred. VI 13), and secondly, holding preliminary beliefs in order to be on the path of understanding (or a pre-understanding principle). This circle comes from Augustine himself (Conf. I i 1; De Trinitate XV ii 2) and is perhaps one of the most important theses of Augustinian thought (see, for instance, Pascal Pensées Laf. 919): we cannot seek God (or truth) without having already found him. Thus, neither the excessive rationalism of the Manicheans nor any skeptical reading of the Bible is able to understand the truth of Christianity, because both lack faith. Augustine conceived this circle through his thinking on the mysteries of the Bible and the search for a method to read and understand it against the skeptical objections. As he said in the Confessions, the Bible—and especially the Old Testament— appeared to him a weak and poor book in comparison with the sophisticated prose of Cicero (Conf. III vi 9). The comprehension of the full sense—or at least of a true sense—of the text supposes giving credit to its author and to his intention by way of some belief. This circle helps us to understand more precisely Augustine’s stance on faith: although he emphasized the fact that there are reasons to believe, his stance was not purely rationalistic. Faith and religious belief can be fed by reason and intellectual reflection on the meaning of the Bible and, more generally, on God’s manifestations in the world. But faith does not depend on the sole decision of the will. More precisely, the will itself is not the result of a purely individual decision, but presupposes the grace of God without which nobody can really find the path of truth. This feature takes on great significance given that Augustine was at that point involved in the debate with the Pelagians, who defended the possibility for men to save their souls by themselves. For this reason, even if it remains true that faith is

AUGUSTINE AND SKEPTICISM

181

conditioned by rational reasons, the very fact of believing relies on a movement that originates in God himself. Contrary to what the skeptic seems to believe, assent is not a completely voluntary act; rather, it is influenced by God’s love and concern for us.16

4  AUGUSTINE AND THE COGITO An overview of the relationship between Augustine and skepticism would be incomplete without a survey of Augustine’s texts that anticipate Descartes’s famous experience of the cogito. We saw that as early as the Contra Academicos, Augustine presented arguments that are similar to those employed by Descartes in his First Meditation, where he showed that some kinds of knowledge (such as mathematical knowledge) resist the dream argument. But Augustine also deployed some thought experiments that can be compared to Descartes’s discovery, in the Second Meditation (AT VII 25), of the indubitable truth of the proposition “ego sum, ego existo.” In opposition to skepticism, Augustine emphasized the certainty of the existence of the individual’s own thought as a fundamental experience. It is worth noting that this very experience is mentioned in the first dialogues (see De vita beata II 7, Soliloques II 1, De libero arbitrio II iii 7) and appears in later masterpieces like De Trinitate (e.g., XV xii 21) and De civitate dei (XI, 26). Putting aside the highly debated question of whether Descartes took his inspiration from Augustine,17 what is important is determining in what sense Augustine’s stance is connected to solipsism, which is nowadays deeply connected to skepticism. In the De civitate dei, the indubitable fact of the existence of the individual’s own thought takes the form of an anti-skeptical argument—the Academics cannot affirm that men are always mistaken because there is something indubitable: the very fact that one does exist, and that one does know that he exists—“for if I am mistaken, I exist” (si fallor, enim sum, XI 26).18 Accordingly, as in Descartes, doubt cannot be universal because something within the inner experience of my mind provides resistance to all skeptical scenarios. Yet, Augustine’s aim is not to use the skeptical hypothesis in order to reconstruct knowledge, for one can see that such a methodological doubt does not appear in Augustine. And, as we saw, as far as knowledge is concerned, he considered rather the necessity of relying on an external authority. Nevertheless, the discovery of the inner knowledge of the individual’s own existence as a mind is also fundamental in Augustine, not in the sense that it could have the function of a first principle, but rather in the sense that it reveals the distinctive nature of human thought. Not only does the inner knowledge discovered by Augustine offer a formal criterion of truth and an instance of an indubitable truth (cf. De Trinitate XV 21), but it also, and more fundamentally, gives us knowledge of the individual’s own substance: Now properly speaking a thing cannot in any way be said to be known while its substance is unknown. Therefore when mind knows itself it knows its substance, and when it is certain of itself it is certain of its substance. But it is certain of itself, as everything said above convincingly demonstrates. Nor is it in the least

182

SKEPTICISM

certain whether it is air or fire or any kind of body or anything appertaining to body. Therefore it is not any of these things. The whole point of its being commanded to know itself comes to this: it should be certain that it is none of the things about which it is uncertain, and it should be certain that it is that alone which alone it is certain that it is. . . . But if it were one of these things [sc. if mind were a material thing] it would think that thing differently from the others, not that is to say with a construct of the imagination as absent things are thought that have been contacted by one of the senses of the body, either actually themselves or something of the same kind; but with some inner, nonsimulated but true presence (nothing after all is more present to it than itself), in the same way as it thinks it is living and remembering and understanding and willing. It knows these things in itself, it does not form images of them as though it had touched them with the senses outside itself, as it touches any bodily things. If it refrains from affixing to itself any of these image-bound objects of its thoughts in such a way as to think it is that sort of thing, then whatever is left to it of itself, that alone is what it is. (De Trinitate X x 16; translation by Hill 1991) Thus, for Augustine, a special knowledge comes from the mind: the mind is present to itself in a totally different way from that in which other things can be present to it. Book X of the De Trinitate precisely demonstrates this distinctive characteristic: by knowing itself, the mind knows that it lives, that it exists—it knows itself entirely (De Trinitate X iv 6). In this work, references to similar skeptical arguments probably no longer refer to the skepticism of the New Academy; Augustine has extracted from this skepticism a new picture of skepticism as an inner experience,19 the experience of solipsism through which he discovered the peculiarity and the substance of an inner world. Hence, skepticism is not only something that any rational thinker should refute for the sake of argumentation; it has also become a gateway to a crucial feature of knowledge in Augustinian philosophy: interiority. Skeptical scenarios show that knowledge of external reality is not of the same character as knowledge of the inner self. But even in this context, this experience cannot be understood as a kind of solipsism that is an experience where one is alone (solus ipse) and where each thing can be reduced to a subjective representation. It is for this reason that Augustine perceives this experience revealed in the individual as the presence of the “interior master”—the presence of God in each of us—thanks to whom any propositional content can be recognized as a truth.20 The inner self has the privilege of being an image of God; accordingly, skeptical scenarios are an efficient means of going inside and finding an inner world. Skepticism remains a means (however, not the only means) of revealing the inner self and performing Augustine’s advice: “Do not go outside, come back into yourself. It is in the inner self that Truth dwells” (De vera religione XXXIX 72, translation by Hill in Ramsey 2005). Thus, even though Augustine was not a skeptic and devoted a part of his work to refuting skepticism, in reality it seems that skepticism played a significant role in the constitution of his philosophy. And despite the fact that skepticism entered

AUGUSTINE AND SKEPTICISM

183

Augustine’s work through his knowledge of the Academic skeptical tradition, the vivid discussion he entertained with this philosophical tradition gave rise to new skeptical problems and to new functions of and uses for skepticism.

NOTES 1. Augustine’s view of skepticism has also had an important influence on the medieval conception of Skepticism: see Grellard (2011; 2018) and Bouton-Touboulic (2013). 2. On Augustine’s life and education, see Marrou (1939) and Brown (2000). 3. Some scholars have doubted that Augustine earnestly espoused skepticism: see Alfaric (1918: 352–358), Testard (1958: 129), and Besnier (1993: 91). However, there is no doubt that Augustine considered skepticism a very serious problem. 4. That hypothesis is already mentioned by Sextus, PH I 234. For a critical approach to this hypothesis, see Lévy (1978). 5. For a precise analysis of the argumentation in Contra Academicos, see Mosher (1981), Kirwan (1983), and Curley (1997). 6. For this distinction, see Catapano (2006), who also provides useful references. 7. For an accurate analysis of the function of those analytic counterexamples in Augustine’s strategy, see Heil (1972: 108–111). 8. All translations of the Contra Academicos are taken from King (1995). 9. See Burnyeat (1982: 28). This paper has been recently challenged by scholars who denied that Augustine entertained the hypothesis of an external world skepticism: see Bolyard (2006). One can also consider that the medieval interpretations of Augustin’s treatment of skepticism were a crucial influence on the modern form of skepticism: see Grellard (2011: 18; 2018). 10. It is worth noting that Augustine was confronted by accusations of skepticism: see Contra litteras Petiliani III xxi 24. Cf. Bermon (2009). 11. For the De ut. cred., I follow the translation of Kearney in Ramsey (2005). 12. Quod intellegimus, debemus rationi: quod credimus auctoritati. Cf. also Revisions XIV 3. 13. Cf. De fide rerum quae non videntur II 4; De ut. cred. XII 26. 14. The definition of such a method is the goal of the second book of De Doctrina Christiana. 15. According to Stock (1996: 283), the reading theory building upon the experience of the Bible is an “adaptation of scepticism.” 16. For an accurate analysis of this point, see Koch (2013). 17. Descartes himself was forced to explain the differences between both arguments: see Bermon (2001: 9–15). The bibliography on the topic is extensive, see Gilson (1930), Gouhier (1978), Taylor (1989), Matthews (1992), Menn (1998), and Marion (2008: 87–98). 18. For an accurate explication of this argument, see Matthews (1972; 1992: 29–34). 19. Scholars question whether this new picture should be connected with the Plotinian treatment of skepticism that can be found in Plotinus’s Ennead V 3 [49].

184

SKEPTICISM

20. On this crucial doctrine, see the De Magistro and De Trinitate XII. An accurate explanation of the doctrine of illumination can be found in O’Daly (1987: 199–207).

REFERENCES Alfaric, Prosper. 1918. L’évolution intellectuelle de Saint Augustin: Du manichéisme au néoplatonisme. Paris: E. Nourry. Bermon, Emmanuel. 2001. Le cogito dans la pensée de saint Augustin. Histoire des doctrines de l’Antiquité classique. Paris: Vrin. Bermon, Emmanuel. 2009. “‘Contra academicos vel de academis’ (retract. I, 1): saint Augustin et les Academica de Cicéron,” Revue des études anciennes, 111: 75–93. Besnier, Bernard. 1993. “La Nouvelle Académie selon le point de vue de Philon de Larisse.” In B. Besnier (ed.), Scepticisme et exégèse: Hommage à Camille Pernot, 85–163. Fontenay-aux-Roses: ENS Fontenay/Saint-Cloud. Bouton-Touboulic Anne-Isabelle. 2013. “Scepticism (up to Descartes).” In K. Pollmann (ed.), The Oxford Guide to the Historical Reception of Augustine, vol. 3, 1694–1697. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brown, Peter. 2000. Augustine of Hippo: A Biography. London: Faber. Burnyeat, Myles. 1982. “Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw and Berkeley Missed,” Philosophical Review 90: 3–40. Catapano, Giovanni. 2006. “Quale scetticismo viene criticato da Agostino nel Contra Academicos?” Quaestio 6: 1–13. Curley, Augustine. 1997. Augustine’s Critique of Skepticism: A Study of Contra Academicos. New York: Peter Lang. Gilson, Étienne. 1930. Études sur le rôle de la pensée médiévale dans la formation du système cartésien. Paris: Vrin. Gouhier, Henri. 1978. Cartésianisme et augustinisme au XVIIe siècle. Paris: Vrin. Grellard Christophe. 2011. “Academicus.” In I. Atucha, D. Calma, C. König-Pralong, and I. Zavattero (eds.), Mots Médiévaux offerts à Ruedi Imbach, 7–8. Porto: Fédération internationale des instituts d’études médiévales. Grellard Christophe. 2018. “Le scepticisme au Moyen Âge, de saint Augustin à Nicolas d’Autrécourt. Réception et transformation d’un problème philosophique.” Cahiers Philosophiques. Heil, John. 1972. “Augustine’s Attack on Skepticism: The Contra Academicos,” The Harvard Theological Review 65: 99–116. Hill, Edmund. 1991. Augustine: The Trinity. Volume I/5. New York: New City Press. King, Peter. 1995. Augustine: Against the Academicians and The Teacher. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. Kirwan, Christopher. 1983. “Augustine against the Skeptics.” In M. Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition, 205–223. Berkeley: California University Press. Koch, Isabelle. 2013. “Représentation et assentiment dans la définition augustinienne de la croyance.” In L. Jaffro (ed.), Croit-on comme on veut? La controverse classique sur le rôle de la volonté dans l’assentiment, 47–62. Paris: Vrin. Lévy, Carlos. 1978. “Scepticisme et dogmatisme dans l’Académie: l’ésotérisme d’Arcésilas,” Revue des études latines 56: 335–348.

AUGUSTINE AND SKEPTICISM

185

Marion, Jean-Luc. 2008. Au lieu de soi: l’approche de Saint Augustin. Paris: PUF. Marrou, Henri-Irénée. 1939. Saint Augustin et la fin de la culture antique. Paris: De Broccard. Matthews, Gareth. 1972. “Si Fallor, Sum.” In G. Matthews (ed.), Augustine: A Collection of Critical Essays, 151–162. New York: Doubleday. Matthews, Gareth. 1992. Thought’s Ego in Augustine and Descartes. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Menn, Stephen. 2002. Descartes and Augustine. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mosher, David L. 1981. “The Argument of St. Augustine’s Contra Academicos,” Augustinian Studies 12: 89–113. O’Daly, Gerard James Patrick. 1987. Augustine’s Philosophy of Mind. London: Duckworth. Ramsey, Boniface (ed.). 2004. Augustine: Letters 100–155, translated by R. Teske. Volume II/2. Hyde Park and New York: New City Press. Ramsey, Boniface (ed.). 2005. Augustine: On Christian Belief, translated by E. Hill, R. Kearney, M. Campbell, and B. Harbert. Volume I/8 of The Works of Saint Augustine: A Translation for the 21st Century. Hyde Park, NY: New City Press. Rist, John. 2001. “Faith and Reason.” In N. Kretzmann and E. Stump (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Augustine, 26–39. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rotelle, John (ed.). 1997. The Confessions, translated by M. Boulding. Hyde Park, NY: New City Press. Schmitt, Charles Bernard. 1972. Cicero Scepticus: A Study of the Influence of the Academica in the Renaissance. The Hague: M. Nijhoff. Stock, Brian. 1996. Augustine the Reader: Meditation, Self-Knowledge, and the Ethics of Interpretation. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Testard, Maurice. 1958. Saint Augustin et Cicéron : Cicéron dans la formation et dans l’œuvre de Saint Augustin. Paris: Études Augustiniennes.

CHAPTER THIRTEEN

John of Salisbury’s Skepticism DAVID BLOCH

1 INTRODUCTION “The Latin world has had nothing greater than Cicero!” (Orbis nil habuit maius Cicerone Latinus), said John of Salisbury (c. 1115/20–1180) in his Entheticus Maior (van Laarhoven 1987: 185). John spent most of his life as a diplomat and had only limited time for philosophical studies. However, he had studied no less than twelve years in Paris (1135/36–1147/48) with practically all the great masters, and he knew much about philosophy, theology, and literature. We may disagree with him concerning the evaluation of Cicero, but he was certainly qualified to make the claim. For the history of philosophy, John is also important as one of the first medieval thinkers who had access to most if not all of Aristotle’s works on logic. Thus, he had the resources and was naturally inclined to combine the philosophies of Cicero and Aristotle, a fact that contributed immensely to his views on skepticism.1 Thus, John was, for better and worse, a peculiar kind of skeptic: an Academic, Ciceronian skeptic, but (perhaps) not truly so. He set forth his views in two major works in particular: the Policraticus (on political theory) and the Metalogicon (on logic and education), both finished in or around 1159. The former relies primarily on examples and quotations from authoritative authors (although book 7 in particular contains important arguments), whereas the latter presents arguments in favor of the positions he adopts. I will focus on the Metalogicon.2 In this work, John makes the claim that the basic texts in education should be those that constitute Aristotle’s Organon (along with Porphyry’s Isagoge), and the Stagirite was certainly no skeptic but the founder of modern science and scientific theory and methodology. At first glance, then, John seems to be in danger of holding contradictory views. Furthermore, skepticism was not a common position in the twelfth century.3 In fact, John is apparently the only westerner of that century who claims to be a skeptic, although the Academic type of skepticism was well known in the first half of the century, in particular from Augustine’s Against the Academics (Contra Academicos).4 None of his teachers, who were practically all

JOHN OF SALISBURY’S SKEPTICISM

187

the great masters of his time, were skeptics, and John usually followed their lead in philosophical matters. But in the Metalogicon he seems to embrace skepticism contrary to almost all the science and philosophy of his time. I will argue that John’s desire to be both Ciceronian and Aristotelian makes him a rather fascinating kind of Aristotelian skeptic. Even if one is sometimes puzzled by the results of John’s efforts, he deserves our respect for taking such a controversial and independent stance based on arguments and for his willingness to take both Cicero and Aristotle seriously.

2  THE THREE KINDS OF ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM In book 4 of the Metalogicon, John distinguishes three kinds of Academic skeptics: The Academician is in doubt, and he dares not lay down what is true in each and every case. But this sect is divided into three groups. The adherents of the first group claim that they know nothing at all, and as a result of this extreme caution they have lost the right to be called philosophers. The adherents of the second group accept as knowledge only things that are necessary and known per se, that is, things that one cannot fail to know. The third kind comprises those of us who do not venture to state an opinion in cases that are doubtful to the wise man. (Metalogicon 4.31, Hall 1991: 168; all translations are mine)5 The first group comprises those who doubt everything, and John quickly dismisses them. It is, John says elsewhere, ridiculous and absolutely unphilosophical to doubt everything (Policraticus 7.2, Webb 1909: 96). The second group is surprising in this context; for without the further premise that they themselves do not think that “things that are necessary and known per se” are knowable (a premise that is not made explicit), its adherents are not really skeptics but rather philosophers who put too much trust in demonstrative science. John’s evaluation of the second group seems to reflect his own views on knowledge and science. John himself prefers the third kind of skepticism. The position is noteworthy for at least two characteristics. First, “holding opinions” is not as such wrong, but doing so rashly or without proper consideration is problematic. John himself often held opinions of his own (see below on the problem of genera and species). Second, in some cases you should hold opinions; it is only when even those who are best qualified have to give up that one should suspend judgment. This, stated in positive terms, would seem to mean that John’s kind of Academic skeptic has every right to state opinions if (1) he examines and considers the matter carefully beforehand, (2) he is suitably qualified to do so in the relevant area of knowledge, and (3) the subject matter allows one to hold qualified opinions. John does not state these requirements explicitly, but they are supported by the discussions in which he takes his own positions and by his use of Aristotle’s dialectical method in the Topics. I will illustrate both points in the following parts of this article. Probably the most famous of John’s discussions in which he voices and evaluates many arguments and opinions is the extended treatment of the genus-species

188

SKEPTICISM

problem in book 2, chapters 17 and 20 of the Metalogicon. This and many other subjects can be discussed with positive results, and skepticism is the best way of obtaining such results (Policraticus 1.prologus, ed. Keats-Rohan 1993: 25), but there are also many subjects where rational analysis and argument will provide nothing useful. In such matters, John says, the only acceptable tool is faith (fides).6 However, philosophically speaking, another turn in his development is equally interesting, namely, his Aristotelianism.

3  DIALECTIC AND ARISTOTLE’S TOPICS It has been argued, then, that John is a rather liberal skeptic. Opinions resulting from rational analysis and argument are in many cases not only permissible but even strongly recommendable. On the other hand, he strongly and consistently believes that one cannot know anything with absolute certainty (Metalogicon 1.prologus, ed. Hall 1991: 11; Policraticus 7.1, ed. Webb 1909: 93–95). Having learned from, and adjusted his teaching to, Cicero, what this kind of skeptic needs to do is to find the best possible source of rational and coherent argument, and John was fortunate. For the very best had recently become available in full. Parts of Aristotle’s Organon (i.e., his works on logic) had been known for some time, and Aristotle was known as the philosopher. However, it was only in the second quarter of the twelfth century that the texts of the Organon really entered the schools of Paris (Bloch 2012: 27–44), and John is one of the first to take advantage of these new sources of learning. Thus, his overall view naturally becomes the result of his combined reading of Cicero and Aristotle. Through Aristotle and later Aristotelian sources (Boethius in particular), the medievals had learned that there were at least two different kinds of knowledge and methods of obtaining knowledge: demonstration (demonstrative science) and dialectic. Aristotle’s Organon had been structured—albeit probably not by Aristotle himself—in part to reflect this division by including a treatise on deductions (Prior Analytics), which serves as a tool for both a treatise on demonstrative science (Posterior Analytics) and one on dialectic (Topics). But, according to Aristotle, the only real understanding comes from demonstrative science, whereas dialectic is equally rigid in the deductions but much less strict when it comes to the principles (i.e., the basic premises) of the deductive process. So, although the precise nature of the Posterior Analytics is a much disputed topic in contemporary Aristotelian scholarship, Aristotle’s views on knowledge, understanding, and science are nowadays usually gathered and deduced primarily from this text.7 But for John the most important text by far is the Topics. For whereas the former is concerned with the kinds of knowledge and understanding that are necessary and based upon clear and distinct principles that cannot be disputed (i.e., demonstrative science), the latter is concerned with what is probable and open to debate (i.e., dialectic). Consequently, when John learns from Cicero that “a mere human being” (homunculus) should be “striving for the probables” (probabilia sequens) (Tusculanae disputationes 1.9), he naturally seeks out the Aristotelian work concerned with probable arguments and knowledge. His introductory account of

JOHN OF SALISBURY’S SKEPTICISM

189

the Topics illustrates the importance that John assigns to that work, but it is also a somewhat surprising passage: The Topics comprises eight books, and each book brings more coherence and force to the subject than the preceding ones. The first gives a rough outline, so to speak, of the subject matter of the other books and establishes some fundamentals of logic as a whole. For it teaches what a deduction is; what a demonstration is, and from which sources it is established; what the principles of the arts are, and the principles of the faith that we gain from the arts; what the dialectical deduction is, and the contentious . . . . (Metalogicon 3.5, ed. Hall 1991: 120) Aristotle’s Topics is certainly the natural tool of a man with moderate skeptical views, and fittingly John also stresses the fact that Aristotle is particularly good at demolishing other people’s theses and arguments (Metalogicon 3.8, ed. Hall 1991: 125). But John’s account of the purpose and content of the Topics show that he believes it to be much more than just a useful tool for skeptics. It is rather a text on logic and how to gather knowledge in general to the extent possible. Aristotle’s Topics is traditionally divided into eight books. The first is introductory and establishes the fundamentals of dialectic, books 2–7 treat “accident,” “property,” “genus,” and “definition,” and book 8 is concerned with rules and procedures for dialectical debate. John’s use of the Topics goes far beyond logic and dialectic proper contributing, as it does, to the other kinds of knowledge as well. This comes out clearly in his careful exposition of the text, which takes up most of book 3 of the Metalogicon (3.5–10, ed. Hall 1991: 118–139). For instance, in the exposition of book 3 on accidents, he says: Since only “accident” admits of comparison, the third book [scil. of the Topics] explains the power inherent in “comparables” [scil. the value of understanding what may and may not be done in comparisons]. Pursuing the nature of accidents, it shows by general rules the reasons for choosing and avoiding, and among the things to be chosen, it shows which should be preferred over the others, and among the things to be avoided it shows which should be avoided more than the others. Consequently, it is evident how much this discipline benefits studies of natural science and ethics; for this part of the discipline is very effective in instances where one has to choose and avoid, and generally in every situation where comparison must be made. Clearly this book [scil. the Topics] has much to commend it, and earlier scholars were wrong to neglect it, as it is of outstanding utility, written in a pleasant style and extremely beneficial in the study of both ethics and natural science. (Metalogicon 3.6, ed. Hall 1991: 123) Two of the claims made in this passage are particularly important for understanding John’s position: (1) Aristotle’s Topics was, according to John, not highly regarded in the twelfth century and thus little used, and (2) the utility of the Topics is great even in matters of ethics and natural science. Claim (1) is probably somewhat exaggerated, but it is not completely wrong.8 We have no extant commentaries on Aristotle’s Topics from the twelfth century, and scholars were most often perfectly happy with Manlius Boethius’s (c. 480–524/25)

190

SKEPTICISM

version of the Topics. Thus, John was one of the very first thinkers to use the newly recovered Aristotelian text, and it provided a solid basis for his skepticism. Skepticism is, according to John, the right approach to things about which we can expect to learn something by our own faculties, but since extreme skepticism is unreasonable, we need a positive philosophy as well, which is provided by the dialectical approach of the Topics. Thus, John is in accordance with Cicero’s description of Carneades, who is described as a thinker who mastered both proof and demolishing proof (De oratore 2.38.161). Claim (2) is based on the view that both natural philosophy and ethics have basic principles that are by nature probable at most. Nature is defined by movement and ethics by action, neither of which allows the philosopher the luxury of certainty. Thus, there will be two possible responses: complete suspension of judgment or use of a method that is especially designed to treat such cases. This is the dialectical procedure that is described and analyzed in Aristotle’s Topics. In favor of this view, John perhaps appealed to the much discussed passage in the Topics, book 1, chapter 2, in which Aristotle can be construed as saying that dialectic is one of the most basic tools of all philosophical inquiries. Not only does it work on the basis of probable principles, but it is also the discipline that enables philosophers to examine the principles of other sciences. Ethics is particularly important in this context. John is apparently not much interested in natural science, even though the principles of nature are not necessary, in the Aristotelian tradition, but only probable like the principles of ethics. Aristotle himself used several examples from natural philosophy in his Posterior Analytics to illustrate demonstrative science, and other texts of the twelfth century clearly show that John’s contemporaries had the option of defending a demonstrative science of nature despite the apparent conflict between probable principles and a demonstration.9 However, John focuses on ethics, which he considers by far the most important discipline (Metalogicon 2.11, 2.13; ed. Hall 1991: 73, 74–76). Thus, like many of his contemporaries, John thought that ethics was the goal for which all the sciences were servants, as it were. This view he could have learned from Cicero himself or from some of his most esteemed teachers, most notably Peter Abelard (1079–1142),10 and a strongly “ethical” approach to logic is found in the Latin translations of Arabic scholars.11 The kind of philosophy that interested John most was the one that would eventually lead to practical results, and such results could, as Aristotle would also say (Nicomachean Ethics 1.3, 1094b: 12–27), never attain the degree of precision and necessity required for demonstrative science. Thus, it seems that John is led both by his regard for Cicero and by his intellectual inclinations to his mild Ciceronean-Aristotelian skepticism.

4  A SKEPTIC ON DEMONSTRATIVE SCIENCE Still, since John has such respect for Aristotle and his writings, and since he recognizes that Aristotle should be the foundation of all proper education, one would have expected him to take the full step and also embrace Aristotelian demonstration and demonstrative science. For he is well aware that Aristotelians consider them the

JOHN OF SALISBURY’S SKEPTICISM

191

crown jewel of the Philosopher’s theory of knowledge (Metalogicon 4.7, ed. Hall 1991: 145–146). However, he has, first, his own, very simple—and amusing—skeptical argument against demonstrative science: It was long thought that it was impossible to cut diamonds, since their matter did not yield to sharpened iron or sharpened steel. But when they were eventually cut using lead and goat’s blood, it became apparent that it was actually quite easy to do what had previously seemed impossible. (Metalogicon 3.9, ed. Hall 1991: 130)12 Demonstrative science is impossible, he claims, because we can never know for certain that we actually know what we think we know. The same argument applies to the more serious case of virgin births (Metalogicon 2.13, ed. Hall 1991: 75). In fact, this kind of argument could be countered—and was countered by Robert Grosseteste less than 100 years later—by reference to the Augustinean theory of divine illumination, a theory which twelfth-century thinkers including John knew well.13 Understanding and knowledge start by the passive reception of phenomena through the faculties given by nature, but in order to transform the phenomena into knowledge human beings need “internal light” (interior lux) provided by divine grace; without this human beings have no possibility of cognizing the real and universal truths. John would, however, embrace this description as one that illustrates his point: human beings have limited cognitive powers when left to themselves, and divine illumination does not really belong in a theory of demonstration, but in faith. Second, the state of demonstrative science in the twelfth century was somewhat unclear. Scholars and philosophers simply did not always know how to use it. John’s chapter on this issue is important: The science/knowledge (scientia) found in the Posterior Analytics is a subtle one and penetrable only for few intellects. There are evidently several reasons for this. First, the work contains the art of demonstration, and this art is more difficult than the other systems of argumentation. Second, this art has practically fallen into disuse as a result of the rarity of practitioners, since the mathematicians are the only ones to use demonstration, and they too barely use it; even among them, it is used almost exclusively by the geometers. However, this discipline is not one that is frequently cultivated among us either, except perhaps in the Iberian region and in the confines of Africa. For these people, for the sake of astronomy, practice geometry more than other people. The same is true of the Egyptians and quite a few of the Arabic peoples. In addition to these observations, the book in which the demonstrative discipline is transmitted is much more confused than the others, both because of the transpositions of words and letters and the out-dated examples that have been borrowed from different disciplines; and finally—which is not the author’s fault—the work has been so much distorted by scribal errors that it contains almost as many obstacles, as it contains chapters. And actually, it is good when there are no more obstacles than chapters. Thus, many blame the translator for the difficulty and claim that the work has not been correctly translated. (Metalogicon 4.6, ed. Hall 1991: 145)

192

SKEPTICISM

This rather exotic description shows that the main problems are the limited usefulness of demonstration and the difficulty of the Posterior Analytics. Demonstrative science is not completely invalidated; it is simply limited to mathematics. One would think that John will then comfortably discard any talk of demonstrative science as a valid method of inquiry, but surprisingly that is not the case.

5  THE METHODOLOGY OF JOHN OF SALISBURY’S SKEPTICISM In his only sustained chapter on demonstrative science, John writes: One must have prior knowledge of the principles, and from these one must gather the sequence of truths by coherent reasoning based on necessity; and one must progress by working very hard to place the argument on solid ground, so to speak, in order that the lack of necessity would not result in the appearance of a gap in the argument, a gap that would jeopardize the otherwise resulting demonstrative knowledge. Certainly, not every science/knowledge is demonstrative, but only those that are based on true, primary, and immediate principles. For just as not every deduction is a demonstration but every demonstration is a deduction, so also knowledge/science comprises the demonstrative but not conversely. (Metalogicon 4.8, ed. Hall 1991: 146) This remarkable passage is basically a general methodological description that can be systematized as follows: 1. When one strives to obtain some kind of knowledge, one must recognize the principles of the knowledge in question as carefully as possible. 2. Conclusions must ultimately be deduced from these principles. 3. The deductions must be necessary, that is, the conclusions must follow by necessity, every step of the argument must be clear, and there can be no exceptions. 4. Every effort must be made to ensure that there are no gaps in the argument. This means that every single step of the argument must be clear and convincing. The most surprising thing about this procedure is Step 4. Step 1 is a problem that Aristotle himself apparently never solved for demonstrative science, and whereas he would presumably accept that a number of scientific disciplines have strictly necessary and primary causal principles, John would not (except for mathematics). Steps 2 and 3 apply to both demonstration and dialectic, but Step 4 is purely dialectical. The knowledge produced by demonstrative science cannot be disputed, and thus there can be no reworking of the argument afterwards. If the argument is truly demonstrative, it is complete. But the skeptic part of John maintains that even the process of demonstrative science is never complete; there will always—or almost always—be more gaps to close.

JOHN OF SALISBURY’S SKEPTICISM

193

This leaves John with a quasi-demonstrative approach to knowledge. It maintains that necessity is essential in the deductions from principles to conclusions, and it also incorporates substantial dialectical elements that have been gathered from Aristotle’s Topics, not least the fact that the deductions and the arguments can—and must—always be tested further. Thus, John has combined methods that would not seem easily compatible. The reason might be that he believes that all knowledge is somehow connected: All things have a way of contributing to each other, so that one will become more proficient in any proposed branch of learning to the extent that he has mastered neighboring and related branches. (Metalogicon 3.5, ed. Hall 1991: 119; cf. Cf. Metalogicon 4.1, ed. Hall 1991: 140) Different sciences do not, according to John, have completely separate domains. Instead, each somehow contributes to one’s understanding of other sciences. A scholar needs to be able to use both demonstrative and dialectical methods, and supposedly “neighboring and related branches” will easily incorporate elements of both kinds. This further explains how John can say that the Topics also teaches demonstration (Metalogicon 3.5, ed. Hall 1991: 120, quoted above). The differences are simply reconcilable, according to John. For a skeptic, John is strangely obsessed with, and optimistic about, establishing the proper methods for actually obtaining knowledge.

6 CONCLUSION In some ways John is then perhaps the least skeptical of all the thinkers discussed in the present book. He himself sums up his views on how to obtain knowledge, and to what extent it is possible, as follows: Divine perfection is to know all things completely, angelic perfection is to avoid errors in all cases, and human perfection is to have a good perception of most things. (Metalogicon 3.3, ed. Hall 1991: 110) This by itself is hardly skepticism. At the very least, it is skepticism with a prominent Christian superstructure, and thus inherently a rather optimistic kind of skepticism. In particular, it still leaves room for the intervention of a God who provides the necessary principles in the Augustinean fashion. But still, if one combines the view that some subjects are in fact beyond human knowledge and that opinions should not in these matters be stated as facts with the view that, even when opinions can—and should—be stated, human beings can never have certain knowledge, one has a respectably skeptical stance. It is in this sense that John of Salisbury can be considered a skeptic.14

NOTES 1. For general and more thorough information about John of Salisbury’s life and works, see Liebeschütz (1950), Nederman (2005), and Bloch (2012).

194

SKEPTICISM

2. For analyses of the Policraticus and its use of examples, see von Moos (1988) and Grellard (2013). 3. For skepticism in the Middle Ages, see Perler (2006), Lagerlund (2010a), Grellard (2013), and the other articles in Part 2 of the present book. 4. On the lack of knowledge of Cicero’s Academica, see Rouse and Rouse (1978) and Grellard (2011). 5. Cf. Lagerlund (2010b: 10–11) and, in particular, Grellard (2013: 50–53). 6. Metalogicon 3.10, ed. Hall (1991: 138): “There are many things that do not admit of discussion, the ones that transcend human reason/argument and are consecrated only to faith.” Cf. Policraticus 7.1, 7.7, ed. Webb (1909: 95–99, 114–117). 7. See, e.g., Wians (1989) for a summary of the discussion. It is, however, uncertain whether John really knew this text, and he certainly did not know it well (see Bloch 2012). 8. See further Metalogicon 4.24 (ed. Hall 1991: 162). For the early tradition of Aristotle’s Topics, see Stump (1982) and Green-Pedersen (1984). 9. Texts and sources are described and analyzed in Bloch (2012: 27–82). 10. Cicero, Academica 1.9.34 (stating that Strato was no philosopher, because he did no work on ethics); Abelard, Collationes §§ 2, 67–69 (ed. Marenbon and Orlandi 2001: 82–86). 11. Al-Ghazali, Tractatus de Logica, Prooemium (ed. Lohr 1965: 241–242). It is, however, unlikely that John knew this particular text. 12. The story is actually much older and found in Pliny the Elder, Augustine, and Isidore, but lead is not mentioned by any of them. 13. See Policraticus 8.25 (ed. Webb 1909: 418–425). Cf. Entheticus Maior, ed. van Laarhoven 1987: verses 223–250, 273–278, 629–654, pp. 121, 123, 147–149. 14. I do not here have the space to discuss Grellard (2013), which is now undoubtedly the most important work on John of Salisbury’s skepticism. I merely note that the present article is much more focused on John’s Aristotelian inclinations, which I consider essential to our understanding of John’s skepticism. However, this approach to John’s work is at the expense of a number of important topics treated by Grellard.

REFERENCES Bloch, David. 2012. John of Salisbury on Aristotelian Science. Turnhout: Brepols. Green-Pedersen, Niels Jørgen 1984. The Tradition of the Topics in the Middle Ages. The Commentaries on Aristotle’s and Boethius’ “Topics”. München and Wien: Philosophia Verlag. Grellard, Christophe. 2011. “La seconde acculturation chrétienne de Cicéron: la réception des Académiques du IXe au XIIe siècle,” Asterion 11. URL: http://asterion.revues. org/2350. Grellard, Christophe. 2013. Jean de Salisbury et la renaissance médiévale du scepticisme. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.

JOHN OF SALISBURY’S SKEPTICISM

195

Hall, John B. (ed.). 1991. Ioannis Saresberiensis Metalogicon. Corpus Christianorum, Continuatio Mediaevalis 98. Turnhout: Brepols. Keats-Rohan, K. S. B. (ed.). 1993. Ioannis Saresberiensis Policraticus I-IV. Corpus Christianorum, Continuatio Mediaevalis 118. Turnhout: Brepols. Lagerlund, Henrik (ed.). 2010a. Rethinking the History of Skepticism. The Missing Medieval Background. Leiden and Boston: Brill. Lagerlund, Henrik. 2010b. “A History of Skepticism in the Middle Ages.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism. The Missing Medieval Background, 1–28. Leiden and Boston: Brill. Liebeschütz, Hans 1950. Mediaeval Humanism in the Life and Writings of John of Salisbury, Studies of the Warburg Institute 17. London: University of London. Lohr, Charles H. 1965. “Logica Algazelis. Introduction and Critical Text,” Traditio 21: 223–290. Marenbon, John and Giovanni Orlandi (eds.). 2001. Peter Abelard: Collationes. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nederman, Cary J. 2005. John of Salisbury, Medieval and Renaissance Texts and Studies 288. Tempe and Arizona: Arizona Center for Medieval and Renaissance Studies. Perler, Dominik 2006. Zweifel und Gewissheit. Skeptische Debatten im Mittelalter. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann. Rouse, Richard and Mary Rouse. 1978. “The Medieval Circulation of Cicero’s Posterior Academics and the De finibus bonorum et malorum.” In Malcolm B. Parkes and Andrew G. Wilson (eds.), Medieval Scribes, Manuscripts and Libraries: Essays Presented to N.R. Ker, 333–367. London: Scolar Press. Stump, Eleonore 1982. “Topics: Their Development and Absorption into Consequences.” In N. Kretzmann, A. Kenny, and J. Pinborg (eds.), The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy. From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600, 273–299. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. van Laarhoven, Jan (ed.). 1987. John of Salisbury’s Entheticus Maior and Minor, 3 vols. Leiden: Brill. von Moos, Peter 1988. Geschichte als Topik. Das rhetorische Exemplum von der Antike zur Neuzeit und die historiae im Policraticus Johanns von Salisbury. Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag. Webb, C. C. J. (ed.). 1909. Ioannis Saresberiensis Episcopi Carnotensis Policratici sive De Nugis Curialium et Vestigiis Philosophorum Libri VIII. Recognovit et prolegomenis, apparatu critico, commentario, indicibus instruxit, 2 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wians, William. 1989. “Aristotle, Demonstration, and Teaching,” Ancient Philosophy 9: 245–252.

CHAPTER FOURTEEN

Skepticism in Classical Islam: The Case of Ghazali PAUL L. HECK

1 INTRODUCTION The question of skepticism in Islam invariably prompts mention of the name of Abū Ḥāmid Muḥammad al-Ghazālī (d. 1111 CE, henceforth Ghazali), but it would be wrong to limit skepticism during Islam’s classical period (ninth to thirteenth centuries) to single—and apparently anomalous—cases. To be sure, skepticism did not coalesce into a distinct school (madhhab), although hints of a tendency in that direction exist in the literature of the ninth and tenth centuries. Also, the sources of ancient skepticism, notably Cicero and Sextus Empiricus, were not translated into Arabic, but Islam’s scholars were familiar with the writings of Plato, Aristotle, and John Philoponus, and writings such as these included material on sophistical strategies of argumentation. It is therefore best to speak of the phenomenon of skepticism in classical Islam as part of the overall scholastic dynamic where dogmatic assertions were always met with reservations and counterarguments, making contradiction a regular feature of the practice of the art of disputation. The fact that skepticism in Islam emerged in close relation to the process of defending beliefs may offer insight for the study of skepticism in other contexts. Are skeptical objections ever fully separable from contestation over belief? At the same time, Islam’s scholars used precise language to describe the skeptical outlook. Nevertheless, while skepticism existed largely within, rather than apart from, the arena of theological reasoning, it can also be said to have its own distinct features within that arena. To note some of the specific terminology used in relation to skepticism: “perplexity” (ḥayra), approximating aporia in ancient skepticism; “the equivalence of arguments” (takāfu’ al-adilla), approximating isostheneia in ancient skepticism; and “the inability to know is knowledge” (al-‘ajz ‘an al-idrāk idrāk), recalling learned ignorance—docta ignorantia—from the Latin West. As will be seen, it is this last concept (learned ignorance) that best describes Ghazali’s brand of skepticism. It is also worth noting that Islam’s scholars distinguished the terminology for skepticism from that used to designate atheism, which in this context does not mean

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL ISLAM: THE CASE OF GHAZALI

197

denial of God’s existence but rather rejection of Islam’s revelation as a source of truth, a position that has been traced to only a handful of savants and satirists, dubbed as “freethinkers” (Stroumsa 1999). Islam’s scholars recognized that to say that one does not know (lā adrī) or is perplexed (mutaḥayyir) or doubtful (shākk) in the face of mutually opposing but equally compelling arguments on elusive theological issues is not the same as denying (inkār) or rejecting (juḥūd) the religion of Islam. Skepticism, then, had a place within, not apart from, the fold of Islam’s scholastic life. Indeed, the point in advancing doubts was to establish Islam’s beliefs on a firmer basis, and yet the process never failed to generate as much confusion as clarity. A number of problematic questions drove the dynamic of skepticism in classical Islam. For example, the Qur’an implies that God is corporeal in some fashion, describing God as having eyes, hands, a face, and as seated on his throne, suggesting spatial limitation. And prophetic sayings (hadiths) speak of God as beardless, with curly hair, and clothed in a green garment (Williams 2002). Such revealed texts stood in contradiction to the conclusions of discursive reasoning (both philosophical and theological, the two being deeply interwoven during this period) that sought to preserve the transcendent unity of God from anthropomorphist resemblance to his creation. In the end, faced with the contradiction that God has a body and that God does not have a body, one could only admit, “I do not know.” Indeed, according to the celebrated rationalist scholar of the ninth century, al-Jāḥiẓ (d. 869), those who adhered to God’s bodily self-description in scripture (anthropomorphism) over against the demands of rational discourse only encouraged doubts about Islam’s beliefs, ultimately casting suspicion on the legitimacy of its political mandate. His opponents, of course, made similar accusations against him for refusing to read divinely revealed texts in their literal sense. Were humans to question statements that God had clearly revealed about his corporeal features? A second factor driving the dynamic of skepticism, in addition to such contradiction-generating questions, was the very nature of belief in Islam. Was belief a matter of unquestioning faith—or was it knowledge, that is, compelling and comprehensible to the mind? The Qur’an, perhaps more so than other scripture, claims that its message amounts to knowledge (‘ilm), revealed by God to guide human beings to a favorable outcome on Judgment Day. This would eventually be understood in a scholastic sense—belief as rationally demonstrable—and thus raised questions about the status of the masses of believers without skill in scholastic argumentation by which to show that they actually had knowledge of what they professed. The issue was particularly troubling within the dominant school of theology, Ash‘arism, which held that in principle it is not enough for Muslims to accept their beliefs on hearsay (as handed down on the authority of others, a concept known as taqlīd) (Frank 1989). If the masses simply believed what scholars told them to believe, did that qualify as belief? In other words, if they could not offer rational argumentation for their beliefs, did it constitute genuine belief? However, the first step in the process was to doubt what one had come to believe by hearsay. Only after knocking down such “blind belief” could one begin to know it through rational argumentation. In short, to be a true believer, one had to doubt. To others, the idea that doubt was essential to belief was absurd. In his critique of Ash‘arism,

198

SKEPTICISM

the great scholar of Andalusia, Ibn Ḥazm (d. 1054) mockingly noted that for that school, to be a believer, one had to be a skeptic! A third driver of skepticism was the existence of multiple sects (firaq, sing. firqa) and religions (Judaism, Christianity, and Zoroastrianism, among others) within the Abode of Islam. All had their advocates who could defend their doctrines persuasively. Where did religious truth lie? The plurality of truth claims led diversely affiliated scholars to pursue skeptical strategies in their debates with one another, seeking to highlight contradiction (tanāquḍ or ta‘āruḍ) in their opponents’ arguments rather than common ground upon which all could agree. Such theological wrangling only suggested that mutually contradictory beliefs could be equally compelling, leading some to conclude that religious truth is unascertainable. The literary virtuoso of the eleventh century, Abū Ḥayyān al-Tawḥīdī, inspired by his own deep piety, mocks the craft of disputation (kalām, lit. speech), citing a number of cases of scholars who opted for religious skepticism as the logical outcome of theological debate (‘Abbās 1966; Van Ess 1968). More mystically inclined, al-Tawḥīdī is essentially implying that theological disputation is a waste of time that only produces a cacophony of contradictory claims, thereby putting religious truth itself in jeopardy. All of this made it seem that the practice of disputation only ended in the suspension of belief. Some therefore rejected it as a threat to Islam, opting for adherence to the literal wordings of scripture. Others, also rejecting it, looked to philosophy, not as a self-standing method to attain certain knowledge (although some did make such a claim) but as a means to clean up the theological morass in Islam. Surely, it was felt, all parties would accept what could be apodictically demonstrated, and Islam’s scholars, beginning from the ninth and tenth centuries, sought to formulate the claims of Islam in philosophical categories, a process that reached a zenith with al-Fārābī (d. 950) and Ibn Sinā (Avicenna, d. 1037) and also less clearly but no less significantly with al-‘Āmirī (d. 992) and al-Juwaynī (d. 1085). This, however, only led to new dilemmas. The idea that truth is to be established by philosophical method rather than by a message from God had the effect of downplaying scripture at least for the learned elite. The wordings of revelation— the gardens of paradise and fires of hell—were at best a distant imitation of the philosophical categories of ultimate happiness and ultimate wretchedness, at worst merely images useful for controlling the unlearned masses that had no hope of obtaining certain knowledge philosophically. But philosophical circles were also not free of taqlīd (Griffel 2005), the practice of accepting beliefs on the authority of others, the very issue that had encouraged use of the philosophical method in the first place! Just because Aristotle said something does not mean it is to be uncritically accepted. How was philosophy to be held to its own standards?

2  GHAZALI, PHILOSOPHICAL SKEPTICISM, AND THE TURN TO MYSTICAL SCHOLASTICISM Those conundrums all left their mark on the thought of Ghazali who is best remembered for the skeptical crisis he faced at the height of his teaching career. However, it is important to consider carefully the nature of his skepticism, which,

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL ISLAM: THE CASE OF GHAZALI

199

generally speaking, involves reservations about the prevailing scholastic methodology of his day. Arguing on the basis of the heritage of scholastic philosophy, which he had mastered, Ghazali made use of a kind of skepticism to counter the claims of philosophers to have surer knowledge of God than prophets. In other words, he was not at all opposed to philosophical reasoning but rather used it to expose its own limits. Several studies in recent years underscore his debt to Avicenna (Frank 1994; Griffel 2009; Treiger 2012). However, it has also been shown that even in his most philosophical writings, likely addressed to his elite disciples, Ghazali remained sensitive to the doctrines of Islam: for example, God’s knowledge of particulars in addition to universal concepts, which philosophers were inclined to deny (Al-Akiti 2009). In the end, Ghazali is keen to show the limits of the philosophical method even if accepting it as path to certain knowledge. He departs from philosophers, as will be seen, in his claim that the philosophical method, if properly pursued, ends in the recognition that the philosophical method itself only begets ignorance of the reality of God and, in turn, of all things, which, after all, have their existence in God. In other words, the philosophical method alone is not enough to establish certain knowledge of the reality (or quiddity) of things (what they truly are rather than what they seem to be). How is one to know the true nature of things by the philosophical method if one must admit—by the very same method—ignorance of the reality (or quiddity) of their creator? The point is that knowledge of the reality of things requires knowledge of the reality of their creator, but philosophy has been shown unable to attain certain knowledge of the creator. Another method is needed, still philosophically sound but now, for Ghazali, enhanced by mystical insight. This features in the way he views syllogistic reasoning. In The Just Balance (al-Qisṭās al-Mustaqīm), he shows that Aristotle’s categories of logic are derivable from the Qur’an, establishing consistency between knowledge attained by syllogistic reasoning and knowledge revealed by God. However, while generally committed to Aristotle’s categories of logic, Ghazali has a tendency to conduct his argumentation on the basis of a mystically informed grasp of the spiritual realm as much as by syllogistic reasoning. This is not to say that such a pursuit of logic took hold in scholastic circles. The logic of Avicenna remained dominant. Rather, by grounding scholasticism in mystical insight, Ghazali was able to dull the challenge of philosophy. This, however, does not mean that Ghazali’s goal was a simple restoration of Islam’s revealed message to a place of prominence over philosophy. Ultimately, he sought to establish a sounder basis for knowledge of the realities of things, a task that in his view the philosophical method alone failed to accomplish. This is clear in The Incoherence of the Philosophers (Tahāfut al-Falāsifa), written not in condemnation of the philosophical method, but rather as a challenge to the supremacy of its claims to yield certain knowledge, as seen notably in its discussion of causality. There, Ghazali argues against philosophers who mistakenly assume a quasi-deist view of the world. His issue with them is not so much the idea of efficient causality, whereby things happen according to their own natures apart from direct intervention by God, but rather with their failure to see that such a claim belongs to the realm of possibility rather than necessity; efficient causality must therefore be qualified as custom, not as necessity. That is, any causal relation between things—fire making

200

SKEPTICISM

cotton burn—is not due to any necessity. It is simply a custom. Thus, while today cotton burns because fire is applied to it, tomorrow it might cool as a result. There is no necessary connection. That would be to limit God’s power over the way things work. This, of course, was Ghazali’s way of maintaining the sense of miracles, which would be impossible in a world run by efficient causality rather than by God. Indeed, as is his wont, Ghazali shows that the arguments of philosophers who argue for efficient causality fall short of their own method (Marmura 1989). The fact that philosophical arguments for efficient causality have their flaws is reason to doubt the philosophical method, casting suspicion on the sufficiency of syllogistic reasoning. Again, Ghazali is not dismissing philosophy. For him, it is necessary for the establishment of certainty. Rather, his point is that while necessary, alone it is not sufficient. Given its flaws, there needs to be a higher authority by which to adjudicate the claims of philosophy—a higher and thus meta-rational but not contradictory or anti-rational authority. For this reason, Ghazali turns to mystical insight, not to replace but rather in order to enhance—more precisely to adjudicate—knowledge claims reached by the philosophical method. In other words, he does not view mystical insight as foreign to scholasticism. But what does he mean by mystical insight? Ghazali was not claiming that individual mystical experience was a source of knowledge. (After all, a madman could claim such experience.) Rather, he sought to introduce mystical insight of a kind into the scholastic process in order to buttress what he saw as its methodological deficiencies. For this reason, we can speak of Ghazali’s system of thought as a mystical-philosophical scholasticism. Born toward the middle of the eleventh century in what is today northeastern Iran, Ghazali was a towering scholar in his own age, writing works in various disciplines, including philosophy, theology, jurisprudence, and ethics. He was appointed in 1091 to the post of chief teacher at the Niẓāmiyya Madrasa in Baghdad, then the leading center of learning in the Abode of Islam, where upwards of 300 students at a time studied under his tutelage. According to his own testimony, Ghazali’s crisis began in 1095 at the height of his professorial career, when he came to the realization that he was no longer sure of his own scholarly convictions. Excusing himself on the pretext of making the pilgrimage to Mecca, he departed Baghdad and made his way first to Damascus, where he would spend the bulk of the next two years in contemplative retreat. From there, he would visit the holy sites in Jerusalem, Medina, and Mecca. By 1097, he was back in Baghdad, but he did not remain long. He would resume teaching, this time in Nishapur, where he had earlier studied under the direction of al-Juwaynī. He spent his last years there, consolidating his ideas, teaching them to disciples, and fending off accusations, only to return to his hometown of Tus not long before his death in the year 1111. It is in The Deliverer from Error (al-Munqidh min al-Ḍalāl) that Ghazali records his skeptical crisis, but what exactly is the nature of his skepticism? This question, which has not gone untreated (Halevi 2002; Kukkonen 2010; Garden 2013), can only be answered by looking at this quasi-autobiographical work (Menn 2003) in the context of his overall oeuvre. The Deliverer from Error opens with notice of the prevailing doctrinal confusion (iḍtirāb al-firaq) and divergence (ikhtilāf) in Islam, each sect claiming to be the saved sect. Ghazali clears the deck of such discordance,

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL ISLAM: THE CASE OF GHAZALI

201

noting how it had always been his habit to inquire into the beliefs of the varied schools on his own, apart from the pronouncements of scholarly authorities. In this way he disassociates himself from taqlīd (i.e., belief on the authority of others), but he goes further, noting another source of skepticism, namely, the existence of other religions. His observation that Jewish, Christian, and Muslim youth are all raised according to family tradition—and tend not to leave it as adults—is meant to show that his pursuit of knowledge will start from original human nature prior to a person’s exposure to teachings handed down by parents and teachers (i.e., prior to taqlīd). Such traditional teachings are not necessarily wrong but cannot be counted as knowledge if received on the authority of others. Ghazali’s record of his own life thus reflects the key factors that encouraged doubts about a single religious truth in the Abode of Islam as outlined in the first section above. This skeptical posture leads him into crisis. He wants to know things as they really are, but having begun by rejecting traditional beliefs, he is unsure where to turn for sources of knowledge. He even doubts the senses. The sun looks small to the naked eye, the oar bent in the water, but the mind corrects such misperceptions. If not the senses, then, can he trust the mind and first principles that the mind says are necessarily true, such as the claim that ten is greater than three or that the same thing cannot be both true and false? If the senses err, perhaps the mind does, too. Just as the mind has to correct misperceptions of the senses, perhaps there is a meta-rational realm where even the conclusions of the mind are judged to be right or wrong. Dreaming, Ghazali explains, offers a concrete analogy for such a metarational realm; it does not operate contrary to the workings of the senses or the mind but offers evidence of a cognitive state above and beyond them. Ghazali, it should be noted, is not looking to dreaming to resolve his dilemma but introduces it only as evidence for the existence of a cognitive state comparable to mystical insight, setting the stage for him to reestablish the entire scholastic project on the basis of a combination of mystical insight and syllogistic reasoning. In the end, as he relates, he was healed of his skeptical disease, not as a result of a renewed confidence in first principles (on the basis of which he might build compelling arguments about the reality of things) but rather by a light (nūr) that God had cast into his breast. This light, it will be seen, can be taken as intuition of a kind that is at once meta-rational and the fruit of the philosophical method. What exactly was this light? It was not a personal or individual mystical experience. Ghazali was too committed to the scholastic project to rely on personal or individual experience, which he did not deny but did view as dangerous, since it offered grounds for individuals to claim to embody God. The light cast into his breast was, rather, a way of undertaking the scholastic project with mystical insight—that is, not seeing God (as in a personal or individual mystical experience) but seeing things in this world only insofar as they exist with God their creator. In other words, he discovered that rather than limiting himself to the philosophical method in the traditional sense (i.e., by trying to understand the causal nature of things and building from there to higher conclusions), he could amplify it by acquiring knowledge of things not solely in terms of what was rationally comprehensible but also from a meta-rational perspective. If the scholastic method begins with observation of things

202

SKEPTICISM

and ends with knowledge of their nature (or causality, e.g., the nature of fire being to cause things to burn), the mystical-philosophical approach involves seeing things— even the smallest of creatures such as a gnat—not simply as part of a rationally comprehensible order in which everything is known according to its nature, but rather first and foremost as part of God’s existence. The philosophical method, it turns out, is limited, only able to yield knowledge of things according to their nature, whereas mystical-philosophical scholasticism yields that and more, namely, knowledge of things as they exist with God—and thus as they truly are. Ghazali saw this as surer knowledge of the reality of things, following logically from his view that all things other than God only have existence in a metaphorical sense, that is, insofar as they receive it from God. In contrast, God alone has existence in reality. Thus, if God is the only thing with real existence, the surest knowledge of the reality of things comes not from inquiry into their nature per se but rather by seeing them insofar as they exist in the singular reality of God. He thus turned to Sufism, not for a personal mystical experience, but for a cognitive state of a meta-rational kind as referee for philosophical (rational) claims, just as the mind is referee for sense-based perceptions. One might argue whether Ghazali is talking about mysticism in a traditional sense of a direct and ineffable communion with God in which one might see God, but he is speaking of the meta-rational (what cannot be reached by syllogistic reasoning alone) and thus, at least in that sense, the mystical. However, since, as we will see, he reaches this conclusion (the limits of philosophy) by the scholastic method, he never departs from scholasticism but is, rather, driven to ground it anew not solely in the scholastic method in the traditional sense but in awareness (albeit indirect) of God as everywhere present, making it impossible to know things in their true reality (or quiddity) except insofar as they exist with God as the singular reality, as we will see. The rest of The Deliverer from Error is largely devoted to explaining the shortcomings of other approaches to knowledge. Theology (i.e., disputation), designed for the defense of the faith, has nothing to say to those who do not already believe; and its practitioners (ahl al-kalām), having left the bounds of apologetics for more obscure forms of speculation beyond their ken, fail to dispel the doubts that arise from differences in belief. Philosophy, for its part, has much to offer, but its leading figures (Ghazali singles out al-Fārābī and Ibn Sinā) are declared infidels, particularly for their rejection of three doctrines: bodily resurrection, God’s ignorance of particulars in addition to universal concepts, and the created status of the world, which they hold to have existed from eternity as a necessary effect of God’s eternal knowledge. They may or may not be right in these views, but their method is not sufficient to establish their claims as certain. Also, in general, Ghazali expresses concerns about the impact of philosophy on the masses of believers. The assumption that Islam is opposed to philosophy makes it seem that a believer has to choose between the life of the mind and obscurantist forms of Islam. As for those who claim to follow the instructions of the infallible imam (Ismā‘īlism, which makes the imam the infallible source of truth—in contrast to papal infallibility, which is limited to the preservation of inherited teachings), Ghazali sees them as the most illogical of all for their claim that the mind is not to be trusted since people invariably disagree, necessitating the existence of the infallible

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL ISLAM: THE CASE OF GHAZALI

203

imam to resolve all disputes. He repeatedly charges them with perplexity (ḥayra), that is, with encouragement of obscurantist belief (and thus of skepticism) for their distrust of syllogistic reasoning, which, Ghazali asserts, can resolve disagreement among Muslims, obviating the need for the infallible imam, if people would only take the time to learn it properly! Finally, he comes to Sufism, which he sees as the method to attain certain knowledge. He speaks of it in close conjunction with demonstrative proof (burhān), that is, in terms of the philosophical method, but also as something meta-rational. His point is that knowledge can be reached apodictically but that certain knowledge of the reality of things is known only through taste (dhawq), by which he means mystical insight (based on spiritual consciousness, wijdān, rather than analogical reasoning, qiyās). In other words, metaphysical realities can be known of through syllogistic reasoning, but they can only be really known through a mystical seeing that takes place not with the physical eye but with the mind’s eye. This eye has the capacity to see metaphysical realities, thereby acquiring certain knowledge of them, but it needs a light by which to see them clearly, namely, the light that comes from the niche of prophecy (mishkāt al-nubūwa). Islam’s revealed message—prophecy— is thus the means to mystical insight into metaphysical realities, allowing for certain knowledge of the reality of things. In other words, mystical insight as a meta-rational phenomenon needs a grounding in a meta-rational source (revelation); those who draw from this source by frequent recollection of the names of God as revealed by prophecy will be able to cultivate the cognitive state that allows them not only to know of metaphysical realities with certainty but also to see (know) them directly as the prophets did. Ghazali is not suggesting that mystically minded scholars can become prophets, but rather that they can enjoy prophet-like knowledge by cultivating a life in conformity to that of Muhammad, especially his ritual activity. Here, Ghazali is influenced by Avicenna, speaking of prophecy not simply as a message from God, authenticated by a prophet’s performance of miracles, but as an internal cognitive state that all have the potential to cultivate, allowing them to acquire prophetic knowledge of the realities of things. And it’s also worth noting that Ghazali is not claiming that philosophers and prophets disagree. Quite the contrary! What he is saying is that philosophy, to be true to its own method, requires meta-philosophical adjudication if it hopes to establish its claims as certain. It is best to speak of Ghazali’s brand of skepticism as a kind of learned ignorance: the philosophical method, on its own terms, only yields ignorance of the reality of God. Ghazali states this clearly in The Highest Goal in Explaining the Most Beautiful Names of God (al-Maqṣad al-Asnā fī Sharḥ Asmā’ Allāh al-Ḥusnā). There, he shows that there is no way to reason to the infinite God by analogy to finite creatures (ex creaturis), making it impossible to acquire certain knowledge of God’s reality, both essence and attributes (powerful, knowledgeable, living, speaking, seeing, hearing, etc.), by the philosophical method in the traditional sense. The following passage captures the gist of his thinking: If you said: what is the endpoint of the knowledge of the knowers of God the Exalted [nihāyat maʿrifat al-ʿārifīn bi-llāh taʿālā]? We would say: the endpoint

204

SKEPTICISM

of the knowledge of the knowers is their inability to know [ʿajzuhum ʿan almaʿrifa]. Their knowledge in truth is that they do not know him; that it is completely impossible to know him; that it is impossible that anyone but God the Mighty and Majestic know God with true knowledge encompassing the essence [kunh] of the attributes of lordship [ṣifāt al-rubūbiyya]. If that is disclosed to them by demonstrable proof [inkishāf burhānī], as we noted, they would know it, that is, they would reach the endpoint that it is possible for creation [humanity] to know. This is what the great righteous one Abū Bakr, God be pleased with him, meant when he said: “The inability to grasp comprehension is a kind of comprehension.” (Ghazali 1971: 54) The last line of this passage, a quote attributed to one of the leading companions of Muhammad and his first caliphal successor, indicates that learned ignorance is not the end of knowledge but yields “a kind of comprehension.” This becomes, for Ghazali, a new point of departure for scholasticism. This point of departure is a monistic vision of existence, allowing for knowledge of the reality of things not simply according to their nature as determined by the philosophical method but as they exist with God. In short, learned ignorance teaches that God has no definition, no limit by which to be defined and therefore no opposite. Thus, while God is not the world, God is also not other than the world. In sum, Ghazali’s skepticism about the philosophical method—as demonstrated by the philosophical method— leads him to a monistic vision of existence that requires mystical insight alongside syllogistic reasoning as proper basis of the scholastic enterprise. Everything that exists is a light from God’s lights and a trace of God’s pre-eternal power, and just as one claims to see only the sun when beholding its rays stretching over mountains, similarly, one can say, “I know only God and I see only God” (Ghazali 1971: 59). This monistic vision of existence, curious byproduct of his philosophical skepticism, features across Ghazali’s oeuvre, notably in The Niche of Lights (Mishkāt al-Anwār) but also in a number of places across his magnum opus, The Revivification of the Religious Sciences (Iḥyā’ ‘Ulūm al-Dīn). God is now in sight, at least for mystically minded scholars who see God as manifest without limit (via the light of the mind’s eye in conjunction with the light of revelation, just as the physical eye needs the sun to see). Again, mystical insight here is not personal experience. Indeed, it remains within the realm of scholasticism, enhancing its methodology with awareness of God’s unbounded existence, everywhere manifest in the effects of his actions. This yields certain knowledge of the reality of things, since it takes God’s existence as starting point. In turn, it begets a sound love for God, as seen in the following passage from The Revivification of the Religious Sciences: Those with strong insight [baṣīra] and endowment [minna] that is not weakened, when in a state of inner balance, see only God the Exalted, are not aware of anything but him, and know there is nothing in existence except God. His acts are a trace of his power [qudra] and are subject to him. They have no existence in reality [bi-l-ḥaqīqa] apart from him. Existence belongs to the One, the Truth. Through him is the existence of all his actions. Those in this state look at actions only to see in them the agent [God]. . . . The entire world is the composition of

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL ISLAM: THE CASE OF GHAZALI

205

God the Exalted. Those who look at it as God’s action, are aware of it as God’s action, and love it as God’s action—look only at God, know only God, and love only God. (Ghazali 2003: vol. 2, 1680–1682, passim) It is worth noting that this idea of human love for God, which is dependent on Ghazali’s monistic vision of existence (itself the curious by-product of his skepticism) and the possibility it affords of meta-rational knowledge obtained through mystical insight in conjunction with syllogistic reasoning, does not imply any ontological likeness between creation and creator. The idea of such human-divine affinity did feature in some circles of Sufism, where spiritual masters claimed to reflect God’s existence in their very own human being. Rather, for Ghazali, human love for God—he is more ambiguous about the possibility (and criteria) of divine love of humans—is the fruit not of ontological affinity but of the knowledge (maʿrifa) of God’s unbounded existence that results from his system of mystical-philosophical scholasticism, as seen in the following passage from The Revivification of the Religious Sciences: All that exists in relation to the power of God the Exalted is like shade in relation to the tree, light in relation to the sun; all things are the traces of his power [āthār qudrathi], and the existence of all belongs to his existence [tābiʿ li-wujūdihi]. . . . Kindness from people can only be conceived metaphorically, for the one who is kind is God the Exalted [that is, God is the singular source of all qualities that are loved]. . . . My goodness! Who can deny that it is really possible to love God the Exalted [in a way other than simple obedience to his commands and prohibitions]? . . . Who denies that these descriptions are the descriptions of beauty, perfection, and goodness . . . and that they describe God? . . . The closeness of the slave [that is, the human] to his Lord the Mighty and Majestic is in terms of attributes [not in terms of physical closeness], attributes which he is commanded to follow and the characteristics of lordship: knowledge, righteousness, goodness, kindness, mercy, guidance, and so on, which he is commanded to emulate. . . . All regions of the realm [malakūt] of the heavens and the earth are the domain of the knower, who takes his place therein as he wishes. . . . Whoever has awareness [maʿrifa] of God the Praiseworthy will have disclosed to him the mysteries of the realm [mulk] of God, even a little, and upon this disclosure, he will be struck in his heart with joy that will almost make him fly. . . This is something comprehended only by taste [dhawq, the method of mystical-philosophical scholasticism]. (Ghazali 2003: vol. 2, 1658–1668, passim) Here, the call to scholarly emulation of God’s attributes shows the ethical climax of Ghazali’s thought. He had first sought to get the learned elite (i.e., philosophers) to admit their own ignorance of the reality of things, and that by their own method, compelling them, if truly learned, to turn to mystical insight—made possible by the light of prophecy—for certain knowledge of the reality of things. He now seeks to put them in the position of having to emulate the attributes of God (as known by revelation and not solely by the philosophical method) in the manner of the prophets—and to do so because that is what the philosophical method demands

206

SKEPTICISM

in the end! Thus, what began as skepticism of a kind ends with the claim that the philosophical method, when properly pursued, should convince the learned of the necessity of living like the prophets! In other words, the call to emulate God’s attributes is not simply a devotional matter. It actually serves as evidence that those who claim to have knowledge actually possess it. A scholar who does not live a prophetic ethics as modeled by Muhammad is therefore scholastically deficient—his claim to possess knowledge (especially but not only of God) is suspect. Of course, the emulation of God’s attributes that Ghazali has in mind does not transgress the ontological divide between creator and creation, as earlier noted. In The Highest Goal in Explaining the Most Beautiful Names of God, he shows how it is possible to identify with the attributes of God in appropriately scholastic fashion. Since God has made these attributes (or names) known by revelation to humanity, he must have intended them to be comprehensible to humans in some fashion. In other words, if humans are to identify with them, they have to be able to grasp their conceptual meaning beyond their literal wordings. Ghazali proceeds to explain in detail how this is to be done in the case of each of God’s revealed names. Indeed, for him, it is possible to identify even with the primary name of God—Allah—through a kind of theosis (ta’alluh), where one immerses one’s heart and aspiration wholly in God: not seeing other than God, not heeding other than God, not having hope in—or fear of—other than God. However, in line with his scholastic approach, which preserves the philosophical method while going beyond it, Ghazali turns to the philosophical categories of the day to explain the conceptual meaning of God’s names, thereby allowing human identification with them. In the end, human emulation of God’s names serves as ethical balance for the human soul, giving the rational faculty mastery over the soul’s lower appetitive and irascible faculties. In this way, Ghazali distinguishes between the way in which the names or attributes are applied to God and the way in which they are applied to humans, demonstrating the scholastic sense of emulating God’s names or attributes. For example, when explaining the divine name, “king” (malik), he begins by describing “king” as one who needs nothing where everything needs him. In this sense, the name applies exclusively to God. The human being cannot be king in this fashion but does have a kingdom in his heart and soul where his soldiers are his appetite, anger, and passion, and his subjects his tongue, eyes, hands, and all his bodily members. If he rules them and they do not rule him, he attains the rank of king in his world. Thus, Ghazali’s monistic vision of existence has resulted in a corresponding monistic vision of ethics whereby humans are able to imitate the attributes of God in a way that is both grounded in Islam’s revealed message and philosophically compelling. To conclude, it is now possible to understand the nature of Ghazali’s skeptical crisis and its resolution as described in The Deliverer from Error. His skepticism is skepticism about the knowledge that comes from the philosophical method. He is not against the philosophical method, but rather seeks to put it in its proper place. It may yield knowledge of the reality of things, but such knowledge is not supreme, existing only as fruit of a rationally comprehensible order in which the nature of things can be determined. Such knowledge requires adjudication by a meta-rational

SKEPTICISM IN CLASSICAL ISLAM: THE CASE OF GHAZALI

207

cognition, just as our sense perceptions need to be adjudicated by the mind. Thus, for certain knowledge of the reality of things, one must incorporate mystical insight into one’s scholastic inquiry. This mystical insight, the fruit of learned ignorance, is the light that Ghazali says God cast in his breast, allowing for the cultivation of a prophet-like knowledge—that is, certain knowledge—of the reality of things. He thus forges a close connection between skepticism and (a kind of) mysticism, both of which remain within the scholastic world to which he belonged. At the same time, he is led by his own scholastic commitments to raise questions, not of the efficacy of the philosophical method but of its sufficiency, leading him to doubts, albeit not outright rejection, of some of the philosopher’s conclusions that are at odds with Islam’s beliefs. It is worth noting that Ghazali’s skepticism does not come out of the blue but builds upon a history of doubt in Islam that questioned the claims of discursive reasoning (both theological and philosophical) to certain knowledge of the reality of God (Heck 2014). At the same time, he wrote at a time when such reasoning, particularly the legacy of Avicenna, was becoming more fully integrated into the scholarly life of Islam. Ghazali is thus faced with the challenge of both affirming the philosophical method but also putting it in its place, drawing upon a long heritage of skeptical stratagem to best philosophy at its own game. In sum, he made the philosophical method more palatable to Islam’s scholarly milieu by raising doubts about its supremacy. While helping to consolidate the place of Avicenna in the scholastic curriculum, he also established grounds for scholars to attack Avicenna (Shihadeh 2013) and arguably helped set the stage for doubts to be raised about the sufficiency of the logic of Aristotle as basis of knowledge (Ibrahim 2013).

REFERENCES ‘Abbās, Iḥsān 1966. “Abū Ḥayyān al-Tawḥīdī wa-‘Ilm al-Kalām,” al-Abḥāth 19: 189–207. Al-Akiti, Afifi M. 2009. “The Good, the Bad, and the Ugly of the Falsafa: Al-Ghazālī’s Maḍnūn, Tahāfut, and Maqāṣid, with Particular Attention to their Falsafī Treatments of God’s Knowledge of Temporal Events.” In Y. Tzvi Langermann (ed.), Avicenna and his Legacy: A Golden Age of Science and Philosophy, 51–100. Turnhout, Belgium: Brepols. Frank, Richard, M. 1989. “Knowledge and Taqlīd: The Foundations of Religious Beliefs in Classical Ash‘arism,” Journal of the American Oriental Society 109: 37–62. Frank, Richard, M. 1994. al-Ghazālī and the Ash‘arite School. Durham: Duke University Press. Garden, Kenneth. 2013. The First Islamic Reviver: Abū Ḥāmid al-Ghazālī and his Revival of the Religious Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press. al-Ghazālī. 1967. al-Munqidh min al-Ḍalāl, eds. Jamīl Salībā and Kāmil ‘Ayyād, 7th edition. Beirut: Dār al-Andalus. al-Ghazālī. 1971. al-Maqṣad al-Asnā fī Sharḥ Asmā’ Allāh al-Ḥusnā, ed. Fadlou A. Shehadi. Beirut: Dār al-Mashriq. al-Ghazālī. 1993. al-Qisṭās al-Mustaqīm, ed. Maḥmūd Bījū. Damascus: al-Maṭba‘a al-‘Ilmiyya. al-Ghazālī. 1997. Tahāfut al-Falāsifa, ed. and trans. Michael E. Marmura. Provo, Utah: Brigham Young University Press.

208

SKEPTICISM

al-Ghazālī. 1998. Mishkāt al-Anwār, ed. and trans. David Buchman. Provo, Utah: Brigham Young University. al-Ghazālī. 2003. Iḥyā’ ‘Ulūm al-Dīn, 2 vols. Cairo: Dār al-Salām. Griffel, Frank. 2005. “Taqlīd of the Philosophers: al-Ghazālī’s Initial Accusations in his Tahāfut.” In S. Günther (ed.), Ideas, Images, and Methods of Portrayal: Insights into Classical Arabic Literature and Islam, 273–296. Leiden: Brill. Griffel, Frank. 2009. Al-Ghazālī’s Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Halevi, Leor. 2002. “The Theologian’s Doubts: Natural Philosophy and the Skeptical Games of Ghazālī,” Journal of the History of Ideas 63: 19–29. Heck, Paul L. 2014. Skepticism in Classical Islam: Moments of Confusion. London: Routledge. Ibrahim, Bilal. 2013. “Fahr al-Dīn al-Rāzī, Ibn al-Haytam and Aristotelian Science: Essentialism Versus Phenomenalism in Post-Classical Islamic Thought,” Oriens: 379–431. Kukkonen, Taneli. 2010. “Al-Ghazālī’s Skepticism Revisited.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background, 2–59. Leiden: Brill. Marmura, Michael E. 1989. “al-Ghazālī on Bodily Resurrection and Causality in the Tahāfut and the Iqtiṣād,” Aligarh Journal of Islamic Thought 2: 46–75. Menn, Stephen 2003. “The Discourse on the Method and the Tradition of Intellectual Autobiography.” In J. Miller and B. Inwood (eds.), Hellenistic and Early Modern Philosophy, 141–191. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Shihadeh, Ayman. 2013. “A post-Ghazālian Critic of Avicenna: Ibn Ghaylān al-Balkhī on the Materia Medica of the Canon of Medicine,” Journal of Islamic Studies 24: 135–174. Stroumsa, Sarah. 1999. Freethinkers of Medieval Islam: Ibn al-Rāwandī, Abū Bakr al-Rāzī, and their Impact on Islamic Thought. Leiden: Brill. Treiger, Alexander. 2012. Inspired Knowledge in Islamic Thought: Al-Ghazālī’s Theory of Mystical Cognition and its Avicennian Foundation. London: Routledge. Van Ess, Josef. 1968. “Skepticism in Islamic Religious Thought,” al-Abḥāth 21: 1–18. Williams, Wesley. 2002. “Aspects of the Creed of Imam Ahmad Ibn Hanbal: A Study of Anthropomorphism in Early Islamic Discourse,” International Journal of Middle East Studies 34: 441–463.

CHAPTER FIFTEEN

Nicholas of Autrecourt and John Buridan on Skepticism CHRISTOPHE GRELLARD

1 INTRODUCTION After John Duns Scotus’s radical criticism of Henry of Ghent, the skeptical challenge becomes more and more central to medieval epistemology.1 The reduction of a theory to skepticism, by showing its skeptical consequences, is used as a kind of ad hominem argument (see Grellard 2011b). Moreover, the development of the argument of a deceiving god, in the Scotist and Ockhamist traditions, urges every philosopher and theologian to answer the skeptic.2 Hence, a kind of ideal skeptic, who absolutely denied the possibility of knowing anything with certainty, emerges as an unavoidable adversary. It becomes necessary for any epistemological system to justify the mere possibility of knowing. This kind of attitude to the skeptical challenge is key to understanding Nicholas of Autrecourt’s and John Buridan’s epistemologies. The two philosophers were colleagues at the Faculty of Arts of the University of Paris, during the 1330s.3 Both tried to refute skepticism, but their solutions are radically different and even opposed. Indeed, Autrecourt’s answer to skepticism can be labeled as foundationalist, whereas Buridan’s can be labeled as externalist. Moreover, Buridan seems to think that Autrecourt’s foundationalism may lead to a form of skepticism, and he partly targets him in his general criticism of skepticism. In this chapter, I will first examine Nicholas’s attempt to answer skepticism and its failure. Such a failure may explain why Nicholas has been usually considered to be skeptic by most historians of medieval philosophy. Then, I will turn to Buridan’s solution and clarify his relation to Autrecourt.

210

SKEPTICISM

2  NICHOLAS OF AUTRECOURT’S UNWILLING SKEPTICISM In a letter to the Franciscan friar, Bernard of Arezzo, Nicholas of Autrecourt explicitly claims that he wants to avoid any form of skepticism: And, as it seems to me, from your position there follow things that are more absurd than follow from the position of the Academics. And, therefore, in order to avoid such absurdities, I have upheld in disputations in the Aula of the Sorbonne that I am evidently certain of the objects of the five senses and of my own acts. (Autrecourt 1994: 55–57) Clearly, to answer skepticism means to preserve the cognitive value of external (viz., sensible) and internal perception. Therefore, Autrecourt’s solution will consist in using some kind of perception, along with some intellectual principles, as the foundations of our knowledge. But before examining his foundationalism, we have to individuate the kind of skepticism Autrecourt is targeting.

2a  The Invention of Modern Skepticism In the first letter to Bernard of Arezzo, Nicholas is involved in a controversy about the intuitive knowledge of a non-existent object. In the Scotist tradition to which Bernard belongs, God, by his absolute power, may destroy an object but preserve a clear perception of it in the spirit of a man (see Autrecourt 1994: 46–47).4 Nicholas tries to show how such a position leads to several skeptical absurdities. By this reductio ad absurdum, Autrecourt wants to disqualify Bernard’s epistemology. But he also builds a new picture of the skeptic, different in some respects from the skepticism inherited from Augustine. First, if it is logically possible for the act of cognition to exist without its object (since we can have a clear idea of an object that does not exist), we have to conclude that it is impossible to distinguish the true from the false, since truth consists in the correspondence between an object and an idea of it. Then, we cannot have evident knowledge of external objects (Autrecourt 1994: 46–47). To this first objection, Bernard replies by distinguishing between the natural and the supernatural order of knowledge. In the common course of nature, there is no knowledge of a non-existent object. As we shall see, Buridan defends a very similar view. So, if we add the clause “God is not intervening in the course of nature,” such an inference as “a whiteness is seen, therefore a whiteness exists” is evident. But Nicholas cannot accept such a reply since, according to him, we are unable to identify the cases in which God is intervening and those in which He is not (Autrecourt 1994: 50–51). It is therefore impossible to escape a general doubt about the existence of things outside the mind. The second step of the reduction to skepticism concerns our mental states. According to Bernard himself, we don’t have a direct knowledge of our mental states. Therefore, our perceptions of external things are clearer than the perception of our inner states. Against the Franciscan, Nicholas uses an a fortiori argument: if we can’t have an evident perception of external things (as has just

NICHOLAS OF AUTRECOURT AND JOHN BURIDAN ON SKEPTICISM

211

been shown), a fortiori we can’t have an evident perception of things we perceive less clearly, as is the case with our mental states (Autrecourt 1994: 52–53). From this, Nicholas concludes that Bernard is a complete solipsist: he does not know whether external things exist, he does not know whether he himself exists as a body, and he does not know whether he has mental states, in such a way that he cannot say that he thinks or has an intellect: “Moreover you will not have certitude about your own mind either and thus you do not know whether it exists” (Autrecourt 1994: 54–55). This reductio ad absurdum clearly shows that, according to Autrecourt, radical skepticism is strongly linked to the extension of God’s absolute power. Indeed, such a power leads to a general doubt about the existence of the external world and to a strong form of solipsism. As Nicholas explains, Bernard’s position is much more absurd than the Academics’ (see the quotation at the beginning of Section 2). We probably reach here the first clear distinction between ancient and modern skepticism. Indeed, in Against the Academicians Augustine explained, in arguing against Carneades, that the Academics never dared to question the existence of the external world.5 For this reason, we may consider the problem of the external world (and the solipsism strongly connected to it) as a touchstone for distinguishing between ancient and modern skepticism, and such a touchstone explicitly appears for the first time in Autrecourt’s criticisms of Bernard of Arezzo.

2b  A Foundationalist Answer to Skepticism In order to avoid skepticism, Nicholas claims, we need to accept some self-evident basic beliefs as the foundation of all our knowledge. These beliefs are of two kinds: immediate perceptions and analytic propositions: The following are evident, properly speaking: sensible objects, and the acts which we experience in ourselves. These refer to what is incomplex. As regards what is complex, there are principles which are known from their terms, and conclusions depending on them. (Autrecourt 1971: 235) Propositional (or complex, in scholastic terms) evidentness includes the first principle, namely, the principle of non-contradiction,6 and every analytic proposition that can be used as a premise in an inference. The first principle plays the role of a general condition of possibility for every discursive truth, since on the one hand no truth can be contradictory, and on the other the first principle cannot be falsified by God’s absolute power. The first principle allows us to secure a first level of evidentness against the skeptics. The warrant of this first level can be extended to other propositions by a reduction to the first principle. To reduce means “to show the foundations” in such a way that the first principle functions as a sort of metaprinciple with regard to analytic propositions, whose main property is the inclusion of the predicate in the subject (see Autrecourt 1971: 102; Grellard 2005: 69). Since these propositions may be used in their turn as premises in a syllogism, every proof contains the first principle virtually, that is, can be reduced to it by a process of

212

SKEPTICISM

regress. Nevertheless, to warrant the transfer of evidentness from the principle to the conclusion, Nicholas introduces two principles for our inferences: P1: An inference is evident if and only if the signification of the consequent is included in, or identical to, the signification of the antecedent. P2: An inference is evident if and only if it is impossible that the antecedent and the contradictory of the consequent are true at the same time.7 On these two principles depend two rules of inference: R1: The inference “if a exists, then b exists” is not evident if and only if (1) “a” and “b” are two absolute terms; and (2) a is different from b. R2: The inference “if a exists, then b exists” is evident if and only if (1) “b” is a term relative to “a”; or (2) if “a” and “b” are two absolute terms, the signification of “b” is included in the signification of “a.” (see Autrecourt 1994: 64; Grellard 2005: 83–89) According to R2, we may conclude: “If a house exists, a wall exists,” or “If every animal is running, every man is running,” but according to R1 we have to exclude inferences such as: “If an accident exists, a substance exists,” or “If A is produced, something is producing A” (Autrecourt 1994: 181).8 Therefore, it clearly appears that, by warranting our knowledge against skepticism, Nicholas excludes from the realm of science a large part of the Aristotelian natural philosophy and metaphysics. Such a philosophy, according to Nicholas, is at best only probable, as we shall see. The second kind of evidentness is perceptual evidence. In order to avoid the problems of the intuition of non-existent objects, Nicholas claims that a veridical perception demands a relationship of conformity between the mental act and the external thing. Such a relation must be necessary (habitudo necessaria) and occurs when the thing really exists in se and is perceived by the external senses. Such a perception is called a “complete appearance” (apparentia plena) (Autrecourt 1971: 108; see Perler 2006). Of course, the problem for Nicholas, if he really wants to answer the skeptic, is to explain how we may know when we have such an appearance and be sure that the external thing exists. Facing this objection, Nicholas answers on a twofold level. First, he claims that there is a qualitative difference between real and fictitious perceptions, that is, a difference of clarity such that the perception naturally compels the intellect to assent. Second, we have to assume as probable that everything that appears in a clear way is true. This probable assumption means that we may generally trust our senses and accept that our direct perceptions are usually true. With this assumption, I am allowed to use some clear perceptions to correct the other less clear perceptions. The complete appearances function as judgments that allow us to correct a posteriori some misleading perceptions. For example, if I see a broken stick in the water, I may touch it to correct my vision and confirm my judgment, “The stick is not broken.” Therefore, Nicholas thinks he may answer skepticism by developing a foundationalist theory of knowledge, where two kinds of principles, propositional and perceptual, may warrant the evidentness of some basic beliefs, and from which we may infer other beliefs. Nevertheless, in some respects, we may think that Nicholas has failed to reach his goal and is led to an unwilling form of skepticism.

NICHOLAS OF AUTRECOURT AND JOHN BURIDAN ON SKEPTICISM

213

2c  Nicholas’s Failure to Avoid Skepticism Most scholars usually consider Nicholas as the best example of medieval skepticism, even if he himself claims not to be a skeptic.9 We may identify three reasons that explain why Autrecourt is often considered a skeptic: his probabilism, his attitude toward the truth of principles, and the limits of his defense of sensible perception. Let us consider briefly these three points. First, as we have seen, Nicholas sharply criticizes Aristotelian philosophy by claiming that it is at best only probable. Indeed, every philosophy that cannot satisfy the condition of evidentness can be only probable, that is, rationally grounded. For example, Nicholas thinks that his own atomistic physics is only probable, but more probable than Aristotelian natural philosophy, since it can give a better explanation of natural phenomena.10 A theory is more probable than another if one is more justified in assenting to it, that is, if one has more and better arguments for it. Autrecourt’s conception of what is probable is linked both with an evolving conception of knowledge conceived of as a quest for justification and with a conception of the history of philosophy as the refutation of previous systems.11 But the consequence is the weakening of the scholastic model of scientia as evident knowledge. Finally, the realm of science is strongly limited, and most of our knowledge is not science at all but only more or less justified opinions. For Nicholas, that is enough, but as we shall see in the case of Buridan, for most of the scholastics it is not acceptable. For example, Nicholas’s theory of knowledge leads him to exclude inductive knowledge from the realm of science. First, induction cannot be evident since causal connections are not. Indeed, a causal connection cannot satisfy R2, and our experience of causality gives us nothing more than a mere contiguity. Second, since we cannot enumerate all the possible causes, we can never exclude absolutely the possibility of counterexamples. Third, the notion of a cause does not guarantee the constant production of an effect. We are inclined to accept that similar causes produce similar effects because of a conjectural habit (habitus conjecturativus), that is, a natural disposition to generalize, but such a habit gives us no certitude (see Autrecourt 1994: 72; 1971: 119). The skeptical scope of Nicholas’s probabilism is reinforced by his attitude toward the principles. For Nicholas, as we have seen, all certitude comes from the first principle by reduction to it. At the same time, Nicholas claims that, despite its primacy, the first principle cannot warrant the truth of our other principles or of our conclusions. Such truths are only useless hypotheses. He first shows that we have an indirect proof of the truth of evident knowledge, by the following argument: Accordingly, I shall lay down as a first conclusion that, if the intellect can say of something “this is true,” there cannot coexist the opposite of what is known clearly and evidently. Hence, what is clear and evident to the intellect is true—a statement universally valid and convertible. This conclusion is proven for, when something is known to be true, if it were possible for its opposite to be true, it would follow that the intellect could be sure of nothing. But the opposite of this was maintained in our hypothesis. The reasoning is proven because we have no certitude concerning first principles of anything else knowable except because we know them clearly and evidently. (Autrecourt 1971: 116)12

214

SKEPTICISM

Second, he shows that there is no direct proof of the truth of a proposition. If we want to demonstrate the truth of p by the means of premises q and r, we have to show that q and r are either true or evident. To show the first point, we need other premises whose truth has to be demonstrated, etc., and we have an infinite regress. If we say that p is true because q and r are evident, we have a petitio principii. Hence, the combination of skeptical modes allows Nicholas to say that truth is only a hypothesis (Autrecourt 1971: 117). Therefore, there is a primacy of evidentness over truth. The first point is that we cannot prove the truth of our principles, but we should assume it as following from their evidentness. But, in the same way, we have no proof for this evidentness except an indirect one: we need to posit the first principle if we want to escape the infinite regress argument in our syllogisms. Undoubtedly, this is a strong concession to the skeptics. Third, and finally, the strongest concession to skepticism appears in Nicholas’s solution to the problem of perceptual illusions. Even if Nicholas’s probabilism is very close to a form of mild skepticism, Nicholas goes even further by acknowledging some limits to his answer to skepticism. As we explained, against the traditional skeptical arguments against perception, like the dream argument, Nicholas appeals to the clarity or self-evidence of complete and veridical perceptions. But we may ask: how are we able to discriminate complete and partial appearances and to explain the incompleteness of some appearances? Indeed, in situations involving dreams or illusions, we do think that we have a complete appearance, which often compels the will to assent to it as strongly as a complete appearance. The skeptical dream argument, for example, presupposes a qualitative identity between wakefulness and sleep. On this point, Nicholas is much more embarrassed. He admits that if our dreams, and more generally our illusions, were as clear as complete appearances, we could never make any distinction between them and reality, and we could not have any certitude at all. We would be reduced to complete skepticism or absolute relativism: It is evident that in sleep the appearance is not clear. For, no matter how vividly it appears to someone in sleep that he has seen a camp, the light of heaven, etc., nevertheless everyone experiences when awake that the appearance he gets through sight is clearer and different in kind, and so he is more attracted by this. For, if they were equally clear, he would have either to say nothing is certain for him or to admit that in both appearances what appears to be true is true. (Autrecourt 1971: 107) Of course, this is an important concession from Nicholas since the skeptical dream argument makes two assumptions: the qualitative identity of true and false appearances and a slippery-slope reasoning of the form, “If I am once deceived, I could always be deceived.” Nicholas tries to escape the problem by claiming that we have to assume as probable that every clear appearance is true, that is, that our sensations are usually correct, but, of course, a skeptic would never accept such an assumption.13 The attempt to give a foundationalist answer to skepticism seems to lead Nicholas of Autrecourt to a dead-end. His position involves too many concessions to a more or less strong form of skepticism, in such a way that he could not avoid

NICHOLAS OF AUTRECOURT AND JOHN BURIDAN ON SKEPTICISM

215

the accusation to be himself a kind of skeptic. Such an accusation seems to appear in Buridan’s discussion of Nicholas’s epistemology.

3  JOHN BURIDAN’S ANTI-SKEPTICAL STRATEGY John Buridan confronts skepticism in several texts. In most of these texts, Nicholas of Autrecourt is one of his targets, but he is far from being the only one.14 Nevertheless, due to the radical gap between Autrecourt’s foundationalism and Buridan’s externalism, the latter clearly uses the process of reduction to skepticism in order to underline how foundationalism leads to skepticism. For Buridan, skepticism is mainly a problem for perceptual cognition, and he assumes that an externalist epistemology can sufficiently answer the skeptical challenge.

3a  Who Is Buridan’s Skeptic? In two questions of his commentaries on Metaphysics and Posterior Analytics, Buridan directly faces the skeptical challenge by asking: is it possible to know something with evidence?15 In both questions, the arguments quod non (i.e., the arguments against the thesis Buridan wants to defend) draw the portrait of the skeptic Buridan wants to refute. This skeptic mainly uses arguments against perception, which culminate with the hypothesis of divine deception. In the Questions on Metaphysics, Buridan introduces ten arguments against perception, most of which are linked to the relativity of perception. The last one relies on the possibility of illusion, which is grounded in God’s absolute power. He then introduces seven arguments against intellectual knowledge. The first four rely on the subordination of intellectual knowledge to perceptual knowledge. The fallibility of our perception contaminates intellectual knowledge. Next follows the argument of the Meno,16 the argument of the infinite regress, Nicholas’s rule of inference (R1) used to criticize causality, and a “Heraclitean argument” according to which there is no science of contingent and mutable things. The general structure of the arguments quod non is the same in the Questions on the Posterior Analytics. Buridan only adds two arguments against causality and an argument against induction that could be inspired by Autrecourt’s criticisms. Therefore, for Buridan, the skeptical challenge mainly pertains to perceptual knowledge and indirectly to intellectual knowledge. It is clear that, on this point, Autrecourt is not his target. It is highly implausible, contrary to De Rijk’s (1997) assumption, followed by Zupko (2003) and Klima (2009; 2010), that Autrecourt would be one of the theologizantes Buridan criticizes in his Summulae de demonstrationibus (Buridan 2001: 112–113). Indeed, Autrecourt never deals with the question of the deceiving God, except in his controversy with Bernard, when he uses Bernard’s own terms and theory to underline their skeptical consequences. For his part, Bernard seems very close to Franciscan theologians like Walter Chatton or John of Rodington. Then it is much more plausible that Buridan targets some aspects of the post-Scotist theology that gave an impulsion to the question of the deceiving god.17 On the other hand, it cannot be denied that Autrecourt’s criticisms of our knowledge of substance, along with his criticisms of induction and causality,

216

SKEPTICISM

are mixed with skeptical arguments, which would make it possible to reduce his epistemology to a form of skepticism. But the problem here is much more the question of the nature of our principles and of epistemic justification, and only secondarily, of skepticism.18 To sum up, Buridan’s skeptic is someone who endangers the possibility of knowing through perception and making inferences from perceptions. Buridan only partly targets Autrecourt, and the opposition between the two colleagues at the Arts Faculty rather concerns their respective conceptions of epistemic justification.

3b  Buridan’s Externalist Answer to Skepticism Buridan’s answer to skepticism first relies on a twofold distinction of evidentness, and second on the idea of a natural inclination to the truth. For Buridan, to avoid mere fallible opinion, the firmness of our assent must depend not only on subjective factors (like appearances and dialectical arguments) but also on an objective factor he calls evidentness (evidentia). This evidentness can be either absolutely infallible or relatively infallible.19 The first occurs when it can be falsified by no means, either natural or supernatural. Hence, such evidentness avoids the problem of divine deception. It is exemplified by the evidentness of mathematics and logic. In this case, it is almost impossible to refuse to assent to the proposition. For example, the principle of non-contradiction can be denied verbally (ore), but not sincerely (corde). The other kind of evidentness is only relatively evident (secundum quid or ex suppositione), since it depends on the supposition that we are in a strict natural context (the common course of nature), in which God by definition does not intervene to modify natural causality. This kind of evidentness is enough for natural science; that is, we do not need to be certain that just now our knowledge is preserved from divine deception, but only that, usually, God does not intervene, in such a way that natural science is true: In another way, we consider evidentness as relative or hypothetical (accipitur euidentia secundum quid siue ex suppositione). For example, we claimed before that we observe it in every being according to the common course of nature, and in this way it is evident for us that every fire is hot and that the heavens are moved, even if the contrary is possible by the power of God. Such evidentness is enough for the principles and conclusions of natural science. (Buridan 1518: Bk II, q. 1, f. 8vb–9ra) For Buridan, even if it is always theoretically possible that God may intervene in the common course of nature and temporarily suspend the causal laws He established, such a theoretical possibility is nevertheless practically insignificant. In other words, we may practice natural science as if God would never intervene, but keeping in mind that He could falsify our knowledge. The scientist can never be absolutely certain that his natural knowledge is entirely true, since some parameters could remain unknown, as exemplified by the possibility of divine intervention. This first level of the answer to skepticism is completed by a second one: the natural inclination of the intellect toward the truth. For Buridan it is as natural for

NICHOLAS OF AUTRECOURT AND JOHN BURIDAN ON SKEPTICISM

217

the intellect to know the truth as for fire to burn or for wheat to fruit. There is a natural tendency, due to the biological constitution of these beings, to perform such an action. Generally speaking, for Buridan the natural power (potentia) of being, that is an ability to act, will produce its effect if there is no impediment. For example, a magnet attracts iron, and the body moves toward its proper place. The ideal action of the intellect is exemplified by the grasping of the first principles. Such a grasping cannot be erroneous, but there are of course impediments. Since the intellect is a power determined by many external factors, it is not a strictly natural power, but a habitual one, which depends on the repetition of the act. Therefore, it is possible for an intellectual power to be habituated to the contrary of its natural tendency. By custom, bad education or habits, or by the repetition of false perceptions, I can be trained to give my assent to the false. Therefore, the skeptic relies on this bad intellectual education to dismiss all our knowledge. But Buridan thinks we may correct a posteriori our defective knowledge by identifying the punctual causes of error. These punctual errors may not be a sufficient reason for rejecting our natural ability to grasp the truth. In other words, for Buridan, true knowledge is the rule and error the exception. Indeed, according to him, our knowledge depends on causal relations that could theoretically fail, but that succeed in most cases (see Grellard 2014). Usually, I do know the truth, and my knowledge does not fail. This natural inclination of the intellect toward the truth is the key to explain inductive inference. The problem consists in explaining how we can jump from a partial enumeration of singular cases to a general law subsuming each of these singulars. A complete enumeration is, of course, impossible. But, according to Buridan, if we have discovered, after careful examination, no counterexamples, we are allowed to add the clause et sic de singulis (“and so with each token”). This clause cannot rely on a principle of the uniformity of nature, otherwise we would have a petitio principii (the uniformity of nature warrants the inductive process but is itself known by induction). According to Buridan, we have to assume that the absence of any counterexamples is sufficient to claim that the process is reliable enough and depends on our natural inclination to the truth, even if it is theoretically possible that our inductive principle may be falsified. Of course, induction provides only a hypothetical or relative evidentness, but it is nevertheless evidentness.20 The way Buridan answers the skeptical challenge allows him to maintain a definition of science where evidentness (even of a weaker kind) and truth are still necessary conditions of knowledge in a strong sense (whereas Autrecourt dismissed truth as a mere hypothesis and evidentness as the ideal higher level of knowledge). Indeed, Buridan’s strategy against skepticism is to circumscribe it, to reduce it to a very exceptional case that very rarely occurs, in order to maintain the high standards of science. But could Buridan satisfy a skeptic with such an answer? Probably not. This answer relies on the assumption of some principles the skeptic cannot accept (e.g., error occurs rarely) and on the possibility of correcting our error a posteriori. But none of these two assumptions may satisfy the skeptic who asks for an a priori warrant for the truth of his belief.

218

SKEPTICISM

4 CONCLUSION What is the general teaching of this medieval debate on skepticism? Two conclusions may be drawn. First, from a philosophical point of view, the debate between Autrecourt and Buridan on the best way to avoid skepticism shows that it is impossible to give a satisfactory answer to the skeptical challenge. Either you accept the terms of the debate the skeptic calls for, or you try to bypass them by refusing the skeptical formulation of the problem of knowledge. The first solution is Nicholas’s choice and leads to a failure since in the end he has to acknowledge some cases where the skeptic cannot be refuted. The second solution is Buridan’s, but it cannot satisfy the skeptic since it does not fulfill his demand to meet a high standard of knowledge that could a priori warrant each instance of our knowledge. In this case, there is no real dialogue between the dogmatist and the skeptic. Second, from a historical point of view, the case of Nicholas of Autrecourt clearly shows that all the necessary conditions for the rise of modern skepticism are present in the fourteenth century. A mix of institutional and intellectual factors inhibited the development of such skepticism before the following centuries. From an institutional point of view, the condemnation of Autrecourt in 1346 (for reasons alien to skepticism) prevented any positive influence on late medieval philosophy. From an intellectual point of view, we may assume that Scotus’s radical criticisms of Henry of Ghent probably made it much more difficult to explicitly adopt a skeptical position. Nevertheless, the claim that the translation of Sextus’s writings was the only cause of the development of modern skepticism should be revised.

NOTES 1. See Perler (2006: 33–115). 2. On this point, see Lagerlund in this book, Gregory (1984), and Perler (2010). 3. Nicholas of Autrecourt was born around 1300 and died in 1369. Due to his condemnation in 1347, he left the philosophical stage and had little influence on late medieval Parisian philosophy. John Buridan was also born around 1300 and died between 1358 and 1361. Throughout his life, he was a teacher at the Arts Faculty, and he had a wide influence not only in Paris but also in Italy and Central Europe. On Autrecourt’s life, see Kaluza (1995); on Buridan’s, see Faral (1950). On Autrecourt’s skepticism, see Thijssen (2000) and Grellard (2010). On Buridan and skepticism, see Zupko (1993) and Klima (2010). 4. Bernard’s position is very close to Walter Chatton’s. On this point, see Kaluza (1991). 5. Augustine (1995, 74): “‘How do you know that the world exists,’ replies the Academician, ‘if the senses are deceptive?’ Your arguments were never able to disown the power of our senses to the extent of clearly establishing that nothing seems to be so to us. Nor have you ever ventured to try to do so.” 6. In some texts Nicholas seems to claim that the first principle includes both the principle of non-contradiction and the principle of identity. On this topic, see Grellard (2005: 69–70), also Krause (2009).

NICHOLAS OF AUTRECOURT AND JOHN BURIDAN ON SKEPTICISM

219

7. On P1, see Autrecourt (1994: 64); on P2, see Autrecourt (1994: 60). P2 is very common among medieval logicians. P1 is less common and clearly aims to exclude material implications. For this reason, it can be said that it belongs to the prehistory of relevance logic. 8. On Autrecourt’s criticisms of the possibility of knowing a substance, see Robert (2006). 9. As I point out elsewhere (Grellard 2010), Autrecourt’s epistemology is very close to that proposed in the twelfth century by John of Salisbury, who explicitly claimed to be a skeptic (see Bloch’s chapter in this book and Grellard 2013a). We may assume that some historical changes forbade such a claim in the fourteenth century. A plausible explanation is the following: Scotus’s accusation that Henry of Ghent was a skeptic made it impossible for anyone to claim to be a skeptic because he took Henry’s skepticism to be a form of irrationality. 10. On Autrecourt’s atomism, see Grellard (2002; 2009). 11. See Autrecourt (1971: 41): “For although in my opinion they appear far more probable than what Aristotle said, yet, just as for a long time Aristotle’s statements seemed to be probable, though now perhaps their probability will be lessened, so someone will come along and undermine the probability of these statements of mine.” On Autrecourt’s probabilism, see Grellard (2005: 93–118). 12. The structure of the argument is not very clear, and seems to suffer from some logical flaws, but we can propose the following reconstruction (I would like to thank Baron Reed for improving my understanding of the argument): (1) Kp (assume) (2) not-p (assume for reductio) (3) Kp & not-p (conjunction introduction: 1, 2) (4) if Kp & not-p, then not-Kp (the knowledge of p excludes the truth of not-p) (5) not-(Kp & not-p) (modus tollens: 1, 4) (6) not-Kp or p (equivalent to 5) (7) p (disjunction elimination: 1, 6) (8) p (reductio ad absurdum: 2, 7) (9) if Kp, then p (conditional proof: 1, 8) 13. This failure to plainly answer to skepticism may partly explain why Autrecourt adopts a phenomenalist theory of perception in the second part of his treatise. See Grellard (2015a). 14. The claim that Buridan is mainly attacking Autrecourt’s so-called skepticism is found in Zupko (1993; 2003) and Klima (2009; 2010). This claim is not entirely false, as we shall see, but it should be formulated in a more cautious way. 15. Buridan (1518: Bk II, q. 1, f. 8rb): utrum de rebus sit nobis possibilis comprehensio veritatis? (Whether it is possible for us to grasp the truth about things?) and Buridan unpublished, Bk I, q. 2: utrum possibile sit nos aliquid scire? (Whether it is possible we know something scientifically?). 16. On the status of Meno’s argument in the Middle Ages, see Grellard (2011a). 17. See Lagerlund’s chapter in this book. 18. Buridan also seems to target Autrecourt on induction in the Questions on Ethics, Bk. VI, q. 11, but without any mention of the skeptical problem. See Grellard (2005: 270–271).

220

SKEPTICISM

19. I leave aside a third level, the moral evidence that is much closer to mere opinion. On this point, see Grellard (2013b; 2015 b). 20. On this topic, see Buridan (1518: II, q. 2, f. 9vb; unpublished: I, q. 19 & 20) Grellard (2005: 264–273), and Economos (2009).

REFERENCES Augustine of Hippo. 1995. Against the Academicians and The Teacher, translated by P. King. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett. Autrecourt, Nicholas of. 1971. The Universal Treatise, translated by L. Kennedy. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. Autrecourt, Nicholas of. 1994. Nicholas of Autrecourt: His Correspondence with Master Giles and Bernard of Arezzo, critical edition and English translation by L. M. de Rijk. Leiden, New York and Köln: Brill. Buridan, John. 1518. Quaestiones in Metaphysicen Aristotelis. Paris: Josse Bade. Buridan, John. 2001. Summulae de demonstrationibus. Groningen and Haren: Ingenium. Buridan, John. Unpublished. Quaestiones super Posteriora analyticorum. Typescript by Hubert Hubien. De Rijk, Lambert Marie. 1997. “Foi chrétienne et savoir humain. La lutte de Buridan contre les theologizantes.” In A. Elamrani-Jama, A. Galonnier and A. De Libera (eds.), Langage et philosophie. Hommage à Jean Jolivet, 393–409. Paris: Vrin. Economos, Ariane. 2009. Intellectus and Induction: Three Aristotelian Commentators on the Cognition of First Principles, Including an Original Translation of John Buridan’s Quaestiones in duos Aristotelis libros Posteriorum Analyticorum. PhD Dissertation. New York: Fordham. Faral, Edmond. 1950. Jean Buridan, maître ès arts de l’université de Paris. Paris: Imprimerie nationale. Gregory, Tullio. 1984. “La tromperie divine.” In Z. Kaluza and P. Vignaux (eds.), Preuve et raisons logiques à l’université de Paris. Logique, ontologie et théologie au xive siècle, 187–195. Paris: Vrin. Grellard, Christophe. 2005. Croire et savoir: Les principes de la connaissance selon Nicolas d’Autrécourt. Paris. Vrin. Grellard, Christophe. 2010. “Nicholas of Autrecourt’s Skepticism: The Ambivalence of Medieval Epistemology.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Medieval Skepticism. The Missing Medieval Background, 119–142. Leiden and Boston: Brill. Grellard, Christophe. 2011a. “Peut-on connaître quelque chose de nouveau? Variations médiévales sur l’argument du Ménon,” Revue philosophique de la France et de l’étranger 201: 37–66. Grellard, Christophe. 2011b. “Academicus.” In I. Atucha, D. Calma, C. König-Pralong, and I. Zavaterro (eds.), Mots médiévaux offerts à Ruedi Imbach, 5–16. Turnhout: Brepols. Grellard, Christophe. 2013a. Jean de Salisbury et la renaissance médiévale du scepticisme. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. Grellard, Christophe. 2013b. “L’âne et les petites vieilles: psychologie de l’action et logique de l’assentiment chez Jean Buridan.” In L. Jaffro (ed.), Croit-on comme on veut? Histoire d’une controverse, 79–101. Paris: Vrin.

NICHOLAS OF AUTRECOURT AND JOHN BURIDAN ON SKEPTICISM

221

Grellard, Christophe. 2014. “How is it Possible to Believe Falsely? John Buridan, the vetula and the Psychology of Error.” In K. Gosh, D. Denery, R. Copeland, and N. Zeeman (eds.), Uncertain Knowledge: Interdisciplinary Conversations about Doubt and Scepticism in the Middle Ages, 91–113. Turnhout: Brepols. Grellard, Christophe. 2015a. “The Nature of Intentional Objects in Nicholas of Autrecourt’s Theory of Knowledge.” In G. Klima (ed.), Intentionality, Cognition and Mental Representation in Medieval Philosophy, 235–250. New York: Fordham University Press. Grellard, Christophe. 2015b. “Probabilisme et approximation du vrai au xive siècle (Jean Buridan, Nicole Oresme, Jean Gerson).” In J-Ph. Genet (ed.), La vérité. Vérité et crédibilité : construire la vérité dans le système de communication de l’Occident (xiiie– xviie siècle), 65–79. Paris: Publications de la Sorbonne. Kaluza, Zénon. 1991. “Serbi un sasso il nome: une inscription de San Gimignano et la rencontre de Bernard d’Arezzo et Nicolas d’Autrécourt.” In B. Mojisch and O. Pluta (eds.), Historia philosophiae medii aevi. Festschrift für Kurt Flasch zu seinem 60 Geburstag, 437–466. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: Grüner. Kaluza, Zénon. 1995. Nicolas d’Autrécourt, ami de la vérité. Paris: Imprimerie nationale. Klima, Gyula. 2009. John Buridan. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Klima, Gyula. 2010. “The Anti-Skepticism of John Buridan and Thomas Aquinas: Putting Skeptics in Their Place Versus Stopping Them in Their Tracks.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Medieval Skepticism. The Missing Medieval Background, 145– 170. Leiden and Boston: Brill. Krause, Andrej. 2009. “Nikolaus von Autrecourt über das erste Prinzip und die Gewißheit von Sätzen,” Vivarium 47: 407–420. Lagerlund, Henrik (ed.). 2010. Rethinking the History of Medieval Skepticism. The Missing Medieval Background. Leiden and Boston: Brill. Perler, Dominik. 2006. “Relations nécessaires ou contingentes? Nicolas d’Autrécourt et la controverse sur la nature des relations cognitives.” In C. Grellard and S. Caroti (eds.), Nicolas d’Autrécourt et la Faculté des Arts de Paris (1317–1340), 85–111. Cesena: Stilgrad editrice. Perler, Dominik. 2010. “Does God Deceive Us? Skeptical Hypotheses in Late Medieval Epistemology.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Medieval Skepticism. The Missing Medieval Background, 171–192. Leiden and Boston: Brill. Robert, Aurélien. 2006. “Jamais Aristote n’a eu de connaissance d’une substance: Nicolas d’Autrécourt en contexte.” In C. Grellard and S. Caroti (eds.), Nicolas d’Autrécourt et la Faculté des Arts de Paris (1317–1340), 111–51. Cesena: Stilgrad editrice. Thijssen, Hans. 2000. “The Quest for Certain Knowledge in the Fourteenth Century: Nicholas of Autrecourt against the Academics.” In J. Sihvola (ed.), Ancient Scepticism and the Sceptical Tradition (=Acta Philosophica Fennica 66), 199–223. Helsinki: Philosophical Society of Finland. Zupko, Jack. 1993. “Buridan on Skepticism.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 31: 191–221. Zupko, Jack. 2003. John Buridan: Portrait of a Fourteenth Century Arts Master. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.

CHAPTER SIXTEEN

Divine Deception HENRIK LAGERLUND

1 INTRODUCTION Perhaps one of the most fascinating arguments that one encounters as a firstyear philosophy student is the argument for skepticism about the external world. Entertaining the tantalizing thought that the world as I know it might not exist or that I am stuck in the Matrix, but unable to take the red pill to find out what the world is really like, meets the fancy of many undergraduates. The argument itself is often presented using Descartes’s First Meditation, and the position the meditator finds herself in at the end of the meditation is captured well by Barry Stroud in The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. He writes: We are confined at best to what Descartes calls “ideas” of things around us, representations of things or states of affairs which, for all we know, might or might not have something corresponding to them in reality. We are in a sense imprisoned within those representations, at least with respect to our knowledge. Any attempt to go beyond them to try to tell whether the world really is as they represent it to be can yield only more representations. . . . This can seem to leave us in the position of finding a barrier between ourselves and the world around us. There would then be a veil of sensory experience or sensory objects which we could not penetrate but which would be no reliable guide to the world beyond the veil. If we were in such a position, I think it is quite clear that we could not know what is going on beyond the veil. . . . I have described Descartes’s sceptical conclusion as implying that we are permanently sealed off from a world we can never reach. (Stroud 1984: 32–33) Now, Descartes himself is not a skeptic, of course, since we are only in the first meditation and by the end of the third, when he has proved the existence of a benevolent God, he is in a position to claim that our ideas reach beyond the veil and hook up with things in the world. The arguments Descartes uses to cast doubt on our ideas of the external world are famous, but certainly the most spectacular is that of an evil demon deceiving us. Descartes uses a demon because he does not think God could deceive us; in fact, he thinks it goes against God’s nature to do so, and once the existence

DIVINE DECEPTION

223

of an all-powerful God is established, there is no reason for the original doubt, and the methodological skepticism is overcome. Even though Descartes finds it problematic to think of God as a deceiver, it was in the early fourteenth century commonly thought that he could deceive human beings, and it generated similar worries about the existence or nature of the external world as it did for Descartes 300 years later. The late medieval debate about divine deception ranges from the early fourteenth to the seventeenth century. Descartes himself was most likely aware of it, particularly since he was reminded of it by Mersenne in his objections to the Meditations (AT VII 125; CSM I 89–90). It was a debate with very high stakes, which had an impact on all parts of philosophy and theology. It represented a new wave of skeptical thought that went well beyond anything in the earlier history of philosophy. In this chapter, I will look closer at the origin of the idea of God as a deceiver and the debates about skepticism that it led to. I will also outline some of the reasons why it never led philosophy to global skepticism.

2  A NEW MODAL THEORY In his very instructive article “Does God Deceive us?” Dominik Perler starts by looking at thirteenth-century views about God as a deceiver. Thomas Aquinas’s view was, for example, very similar to Descartes’s. Aquinas argued that you have to have a bad intention in order to deceive someone and that this is contrary to God’s nature or rather to his benevolence. Demons can deceive, of course, but their power is limited, and although they can pull tricks on our senses, they are not powerful enough to fiddle with our intellectual capacities. Aquinas developed a very particular view of perception according to which we can, despite possibly being deceived by demons, grasp the essences and gain knowledge (Perler 2010: 173–178). It is foremost through the metaphysical underpinnings of his theory of cognition that any skepticism due to deceiving demons is prevented. This metaphysics, as well as the metaphysics of modality, went through fundamental changes in the late thirteenth and early fourteenth centuries, which changed philosophy fundamentally, and as a result new epistemological problems also emerged (see Lagerlund 2010b). The starting point for a discussion of divine deception has to be a discussion of God’s omnipotence. The changes that took place in the fourteenth century began with the development of a new modal theory underlying a new conception of divine omnipotence. The background for these developments was, as so often, set by Aquinas. In Summa Theologiae I, q. 25, art. 3, he writes: God is said to be omnipotent, because he can do everything that is absolutely possible. . . . It must be said that something absolutely possible or impossible derives from the nature of the terms [in a proposition], in the way that something is possible if the predicate [term] is not repugnant to the subject [term], like in “Socrates is sitting.” Something is, however, impossible, because the predicate [term] is repugnant to the subject [term], like in “A human being is a donkey.”

224

SKEPTICISM

This view of modality takes as fundamental what is or what is not repugnant to the essence to which the subject term refers. It assumes the essence to be and then asks what is or is not repugnant to it. It is, for example, not repugnant to the existing essence of Socrates that he sits or stands, hence it is possible for Socrates to sit and the corresponding proposition: “Socrates is sitting” is possible. It is repugnant to the essence of Socrates, and indeed every other human being, that he be a donkey. Such a genus-species arrangement cannot occur. Likewise, it is not possible, that is, it is impossible, that Socrates is not rational, since it is repugnant to the essence of Socrates that he not be rational. He would simply not be what he is, namely, a human being, if that were the case. Hence, on Aquinas’s view of omnipotence, God can do anything that is absolutely possible, but he does not have the power to bring about something that is absolutely impossible. This view of possibility is obviously limited in the sense that it starts from what is actual. John Duns Scotus, who is mainly responsible for the radically new view of modality that emerged in the early fourteenth century, retains some of the terminology used by Aquinas. He even accepts that God’s omnipotence should be explained in terms of what is absolutely possible. He, however, changes the notion of what is absolutely possible. For him, it must instead be equated with what he calls “logical possibility” (possibile logicum). Scotus is the first to use this terminology (see Knuuttila 1993, 2012; Gelber 2004). Scotus explains logical possibility by a thought experiment. If we assume that neither God nor the world exists, but that the proposition “The world will be” exists in some intellect, then this proposition is possibly true, as is the proposition “The world is possible”; that is, they are logically possible or true (Scotus, Lectura I, d. 7, n. 32). This is also what he means when he modifies the so-called positio rule in obligations logic and explains what he means by contingency. He writes: I do not call something contingent because it is not always or necessarily the case, but because the opposite of it could be actual at the very moment when it occurs. (Ordinatio I, d. 2, p.1, q. 1–2, n. 86) What both these examples illustrate is that for Scotus possibility is not tied to, or have anything to do with, what actually exists. The subject term, to follow Aquinas’s example, is not assumed to pick out an actual being anymore, but it is instead assumed to range over all possible beings. Hence, what is possible might not ever be actual. The best way to understand this is in terms of possible worlds, even though it is a bit anachronistic to borrow terminology from the seventeenth century. On Scotus’s view, there are an infinite number of possible worlds or possible combinations of things. The actual world is merely one among these. On this view, a proposition like “Every human being is an animal” is not necessarily true, since there are possible worlds where there are no humans and hence the proposition is false there. Instead, it is contingent. Scotus thinks that a proposition like “God exists” is necessarily true, since God exists in all possible worlds. He is thus a necessary being, unlike humans, who are contingent beings. A proposition like “A Chimera exists” is impossible, because there is no possible world where Chimeras exist.

DIVINE DECEPTION

225

As mentioned, Scotus continues to associate God’s omnipotence with absolute possibility, but on his view what is absolutely possible is a much larger class than what Aquinas had in mind. God’s omnipotence is associated with what is logically possible, and as a result God’s power has vastly increased since what he cannot do is now only what is logically impossible; for example, he cannot make Chimeras exist and he cannot make the principle of non-contradiction false, but otherwise his power has very few limitations. To fully see how medieval philosophers expanded this view, we must have a look at the famous distinction between God’s absolute power and his ordained power.

3  ABSOLUTE VERSUS ORDAINED POWER The way medieval philosophers, at least after William Ockham in the early fourteenth century, explained God’s power was through a distinction between his absolute and his ordained power. A representative example of how this distinction was used in the late fourteenth century can be found in Peter of Ailly’s Sentences commentary (for more about him see Oakley 1964). He explains: What God can do is understood in two ways. In one way, in accordance with his absolute power, and in another in accordance with his ordained power. It is not the case that there are two powers in God, one absolute and one ordained, but that God can do with his absolute power (absolute potest) what he simply and absolutely can do. And in this way we have to understand God’s absolute power. (Commentary on the Sentences I, q. 13, art. 1) The use of “absolute potest” above is, of course, a reference to the idea of absolute possibility as used by Aquinas and modified by Scotus to mean logical possibility. The notion of ordained power is explained in a twofold way by Ailly in the continuation of the passage just quoted: What God can do in accordance with his ordained power can be understood in two ways. In one way and strictly speaking, it is what God can do when he holds to what he ordained, which he wills eternally to be such and such, and then he can only do what he ordained to be the case. In another way, this can be understood more widely so that it means what God can do when he holds to the true law and the divine scripture. And as such it is possible to say that God can do with his ordained power what is absolutely possible but only as long as he does not take away some already ordained true law or sacred scripture. Once God had created the world in a certain way or, to follow the spirit of Scotus’s view, once God had chosen to make one possible world actual, he has committed himself to it and does not change his mind. This act of God’s will binds him, and whatever is in line with this initial choice or does not contradict it is within God’s ordained power, but he still can act contrary to this through his absolute power. This is a straightforward way of explaining miracles, for example, which are contrary to the normal causal interactions in the created world. When fire does not have any effect on the bush or the bodies of the children, God is intervening in the ordained

226

SKEPTICISM

order through his absolute power. From the way Ailly outlines the distinction, it follows a distinction between absolute or logical possibility and ordained or natural possibility. Natural possibility or necessity is what is possible or necessary given the actually created world, while logical possibility or necessity is what is possible or necessary over all possible worlds.

4  DIVINE DECEPTION It is this view of God’s power put in the particular context of the new modal theory that generates the skeptical hypothesis of divine deception. God is so powerful that the mere possibility of deception threatens to cast philosophy into global skepticism and undermine any knowledge of the external world. John Buridan, an important figure in this debate a generation before Ailly,1 puts it succinctly in his commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics: As is commonly said, the senses can be deluded, and it is certain that the species of sensible things can be preserved in the organs of sense in the absence of sensibles, as is mentioned in De somno et vigilia. And then we judge about what does not exist as if it existed, and so we err through the senses. And the difficulty is greatly augmented by the fact that we believe on faith that God can form sensible species in our senses without the sensible things themselves, and preserve them for a long time. In that case, we judge as if there were sensible things present. Furthermore, since God can do this and greater things, you do not know whether God intends to do this, and so you have no certitude and evidentness [regarding the question] whether there are men before you while you are awake or while you are asleep, since in your sleep God could make a sensible species as clear as—indeed, a hundred times clearer than—what sensible objects could produce. And so you would then judge formally that there are sensible objects before you, just as you do now. Therefore, since you know nothing about the will of God, you cannot be certain about anything. (Buridan, Quaestiones in Aristotelis Metaphysicam, II, q. 1, fol. 8rb-va) Buridan is very clear in his response to the skeptical argument that our intellects have the ability to correct for sensory illusion and that our senses are overall reliable. Under any natural circumstance we can thus trust our senses and realize when they are deceiving us, but in the case of divine deception this is obviously not possible, as he explains. If God deceives us, we have no way of knowing it, and hence we cannot be certain about anything. The kind of argument presented by Buridan swept over fourteenth-century philosophy and theology, and we find all major thinkers of the time commenting on it. Even though the doctrine of divine deception had the potential to cast medieval philosophy into complete skepticism, it did not do so. With only one exception, there were no skeptics in the fourteenth century, but it did force thinkers to change their views of the conditions under which we can achieve knowledge, and it also ultimately changed their view of knowledge.

DIVINE DECEPTION

227

Ockham, Robert Holkot, and Adam Wodeham were all very influential philosophers and theologians before Buridan and Ailly in the early to midfourteenth century who all agreed that God could be deceiving us. Holkot writes in his Sentences commentary that God can deceive a rational creature, both in an immediate way, namely by himself, and in a mediate way, through good human beings and angels. (Commentary on the Sentences III, q. 1, BBB; see also Perler 2010: 179) Wodeham adds to this the following observation about the consequences of the doctrine of possible divine deception: “We cannot know of any external thing— more precisely, of any thing other than our own mind—that it exists” (Karger 2004: 229). There is hence no doubt that they were all aware of the implications of that doctrine. It has even been argued that Ockham’s famous doctrine that we can have intuitive cognition of things that do not exist is an attempt to get away from the implications of divine deception (see Karger 2004 and the response to this in Panaccio and Piché 2010), though it seems very unlikely that this was what it was intended for. The only thinker of the fourteenth century who ends up defending a kind of skepticism was Nicholas of Autrecourt.2 He develops his position in an attempt to refute the skeptical views of the otherwise unknown Bernard of Arezzo, an earlyfourteenth-century follower of Scotus. The issue at hand was whether we can have an intuitive cognition of non-existent things. Nicholas argues that Bernard’s position implies Academic skepticism since one can have intuitive cognitions without any object that they are about. If this were the case, it would therefore be impossible to be certain about the existence of external objects. Bernard responded to this objection by introducing the distinction between God’s absolute and ordained power, and then claimed that there is no intuitive cognition of non-existent things without divine intervention. Nicholas then replies that, if we must qualify all our knowledge claims by saying “unless God is intervening,” then we can never be sure about anything, since we cannot know whether God is deceiving us or not. On this view, we cannot be certain about the existence of sensible things, he argues. In fact, he argues further that Bernard’s position implies what we now would call solipsism, and claims that Bernard cannot even be certain about the existence of his own mind. Based on these arguments against Bernard, Nicholas presents himself as an antiskeptic, but, as Grellard (2010) shows, his views actually imply a new form of skepticism. Nicholas proposes a kind of foundationalism as an answer to Bernard. The one thing that cannot be doubted in the face of divine deception, he argues, is the principle of non-contradiction, and hence anything based on it can be said to be certain. His position is somewhat similar to Leibniz’s in the sense that all certain knowledge is reducible to the principle of non-contradiction. All other knowledge is merely probable, according to Nicholas. This view was an anomaly in the fourteenth century, but it motivated powerful reactions and led ultimately to a reformulation of the concept of knowledge.

228

SKEPTICISM

5  ARGUMENTS AGAINST DIVINE DECEPTION As already mentioned, the doctrine of divine deception did not lead the fourteenth century into skepticism. One might ask, why? There are at least three reasons for this. First of all, some thinkers argued that divine deception is simply not possible, since it would contradict God’s benevolence. Second, although God can deceive, he will not do so because of a covenant between God and humankind laid down at the moment of creation. The third and the most philosophically interesting view consists in revising the concept of knowledge and relativizing the concept of evidence. Gregory of Rimini, another early-fourteenth-century philosopher, argued that God cannot be a deceiver since this would go against his benevolence. Gabriel Biel in the fifteenth century and Francisco Suárez in the sixteenth century defended a similar view. This seems to be the view that Descartes falls back on in the Meditations and the Objections and Replies (Rimini and Biel are mentioned by Mersenne). Rimini’s argument is that God cannot deceive, since it would imply saying or making someone believe something false. He writes: “God cannot say something false to someone, willing thereby that the person, to whom he says it, assents to what is said” (Lectura I, d. 42–44, q. 2; see Perler 2010: 182 for this quote). As Perler (2012: 183) analyzes Rimini’s position, he holds that God cannot say something false or make someone else say something false, if that means that what is said is said in a meaningful way, without irony, and in an assertive mode. Saying something false in this way amounts to lying, argues Rimini, and God cannot lie even given his absolute power. Rimini is thus limiting God’s omnipotence by saying that, given his benevolence, he cannot be a deceiver. A second reason for why divine deception did not have the implications for philosophy it could have had was the appeal to a contract or covenant between God and humankind. This was a very common view, particularly among certain theologians following Ockham, and all the main thinkers who were concerned with divine deception adhered to this view. We find it in Ockham, Holkot, Rimini, Ailly, and Biel. The notion of a covenant governs both the natural and the moral order established by God in the creation of the world. It takes its starting point in the idea that what is, is determined by God’s will, and whatever natural or moral laws there are, are also determined by an act of God’s will. These laws are hence not absolute but decided on or chosen by God. God had infinite possibilities from which to choose in creating this world, but he chose to establish this particular moral law and this particular causal order, which, of course, make them special and necessary in the relative or natural sense discussed above. As someone like Ailly understands the notion of a covenant, which we could already see indicated in the above discussion of ordained power, there are two covenants, corresponding to the two kinds of ordained power. The first covers the world in general and is made with all humans. The second is made with the church (see Courtenay 1971). According to the first covenant, God has promised to uphold his creation and all the laws that govern it. According to his absolute power, God could act in whatever way he wanted toward his creation: change it, deceive us, etc. However, according to his ordained power, he will not and instead he acts in

DIVINE DECEPTION

229

accordance with the established laws. This view does not limit God’s omnipotence in any way, since God is not limited by the laws he has put down, but given the covenant he will abide by them. As humans, we can hence trust that God will not make changes and that he is not deceiving us. The doctrine of a covenant plays an important role in late medieval and early modern thought, but perhaps the most important aspect of the theory is that it did not allow divine deception to take hold of philosophy. The third way to deal with divine deception is philosophically the most interesting. Buridan is generally credited with coming up with this approach, but after him it was repeated by almost everyone well into the sixteenth century (see Karger 2010). I will here present the view as defended by Albert of Saxony, a slightly later contemporary of Buridan, and Ailly. It takes as its starting point the assumption that, in the face of possible divine deception, knowledge can no longer be assumed to be infallible. Given God’s omnipotence, as we saw Buridan explain above, we can no longer be certain of anything and hence, if we hold on to the idea that knowledge is infallible, we will have to accept skepticism. Buridan’s way out is to say that knowledge is fallible and that we must relativize the concept of evidence to the domain of inquiry we are concerned with. Albert of Saxony explains this very clearly. He writes: It must be noted that evidence is used in two ways, namely maximal and natural evidence. Maximal evidence is used for propositions in accordance with which the intellect by its nature cognizes with assent to the proposition, and cannot dissent from it. In this way, we say that the principle of non-contradiction is evident, and, similarly, it is by this evidence that it is evident that I know that I exist. Natural evidence, however, is such evidence that nothing opposite appears through human reasoning unless by sophistry. And in this way natural principles and conclusions are said to be evident. It must be noted that [such principles] are not strictly speaking evident, since the intellect that holds this to be evident can be deceived by a supernatural power.3 Albert goes on to explain that God may have changed the appearances so that Socrates who appears human to me is in fact a donkey or that fire is hot when it in fact is cold, and hence it is not maximally evident that “Socrates is a human being” or that “Fire is hot.” These are only naturally evident, which means that there is no natural counterevidence to them. It is true given that we are not being deceived by God. Ailly explains this distinction in a very similar way. He, however, couches it in terms of absolute versus conditional evidence. For the second he also uses secundum quid and ex suppositione. Natural evidence on Albert’s view is conditional in Ailly’s terminology, since it assumes that God is not deceiving us, that is, it puts God aside so to speak. He notes as well that whatever is absolutely evident is infallible (infallibilis), and the examples he gives are the principle of non-contradiction and that I know that I am alive. He also adds to this list truths like that one cannot be made cold by warmth (Sentences I, q. 1, art. 1, O, fol. 48r). Ailly also adds a distinction between what is conditionally evident and what is merely probable. Something is probable if it is possible to conclude the opposite, but if something is

230

SKEPTICISM

evident, on the other hand, then there is no counterargument to it, save, of course, divine deception (Sentences I, q. 3, art. 3 DD, col. 78r). Mainly through Ailly this concept of knowledge and the new account of evidence that followed from it had an enormous influence on later philosophy. We can see its influence well into the sixteenth century (see Karger 2012). It very elegantly shortcircuited the global skeptical threat of divine deception and, although it ultimately moved from a view of knowledge as infallible to a view of it as fallible, it allowed philosophy and natural science to develop without the threat of skepticism.

NOTES 1. On Buridan, see further Christophe Grellard’s chapter in this book. 2. On Autrecourt, see further Christophe Grellard’s chapter in this book. 3. Albert of Saxony, Quaestiones subtilissime super libros Posteriorum Analyticorum Aristotelis, I, q. 3, fol. 4rb–va, transcribed in Fitzgerald 2002: 348–349.

REFERENCES Ailly, Peter of. 1968. Quaestiones super libros sententiarum cum quibusdam in fine adjunctis. Frankfurt: Minerva. Aquinas, Thomas. 1952. Summa Theologiae, edited by P. Caramello. Turin and Rome: Marietti. Buridan, John. 1518. Quaestiones in Aristotelis Metaphysicam: Kommentar zur Aristotelischen Metaphysik. Paris. Courtenay, W. 1971. “Covenant and Causality in Pierre d’Ailly,” Speculum 46: 94–119. Descartes, René. 1984–1991. Oeuvres, edited by P. Tannery and Ch. Adam. Paris: Vrin. Descartes, René. 1984–1985. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Duns Scotus, John. 1950. Ordinatio I, d. 1-2. Opera Omnia 2. Vatican City: Typis Poliglottis Vaticanis. Duns Scotus, John. 1960. Lectura I, prologus, d. 1-7. Opera Omnia 16. Vatican City: Typis Poliglottis Vaticanis. Duns Scotus, John. 2010. “A Buridanian Response to a Fourteenth Century Skeptical Argument and Its Rebuttal by a New Argument in the Early Sixteenth Century.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background, 215–232. Leiden: Brill. Fitzgerald, M. 2002. Albert of Saxony’s Twenty-Five Disputed Questions of Logic, Leiden: Brill Gelber, Hester. 2004. It Could Have Been Otherwise: Contingency and Necessity in Dominican Theology at Oxford, 1300–1350. Leiden: Brill. Grellard, Christophe. 2010. “Nicholas of Autrecourt’s Skepticism: The Ambivalence of Medieval Epistemology.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background 119–144. Leiden: Brill.

DIVINE DECEPTION

231

Holkot, Robert. 1967. In quatuor libros Sententiarum quaestiones. Frankfurt: Minerva. First published in 1518. Karger, Elizabeth. 2004. “Ockham and Wodeham on Divine Deception as a Skeptical Hypothesis,” Vivarium 42: 225–236. Knuuttila, Simo. 1993. Modalities in Medieval Philosophy. London: Routledge. Knuuttila, Simo. 2012. “Modality.” In J. Marenbon (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Medieval Philosophy, 312–341. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lagerlund, Henrik (ed.). 2010a. Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background. Leiden: Brill. Lagerlund, Henrik. 2010b. “Skeptical Issues in Commentaries on Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics: John Buridan and Albert of Saxony.” In J. Marenbon (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Medieval Philosophy, 193–214. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Oakley, Francis. 1964. The Political Thought of Pierre d’Ailly: The Voluntarist Tradition. New Haven: Yale University Press. Panaccio, Claude and David Piché. 2010. “Ockham’s Reliabilism and the Intuition of NonExistents.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background, 97–118. Leiden: Brill. Perler, Dominik. 2010. “Does God Deceive Us? Skeptical Hypotheses in Late Medieval Epistemology.” In H. Lagerlund (ed.), Rethinking the History of Skepticism: The Missing Medieval Background, 171–192. Leiden: Brill. Rimini, Gregory of. 1979–1984. Lectura super primum et secundum Sententiarum, edited by A. D. Trapp and V. Marcolino. Berlin: de Gruyter. Stroud, Barry. 1984. The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

CHAPTER SEVENTEEN

Michel de Montaigne GIANNI PAGANINI

1  LIFE AND WORKS Michel de Montaigne was the first European intellectual to fully realize the strong impact of the rebirth of ancient Pyrrhonism on early modern philosophy. Widely known as a skeptical student of philosophy and as a painter of himself as well as of mankind, he used a new literary form, the essay, in which he tends to digress into anecdotes and personal meditations, according to his motto: “I am myself the matter of my book.” At the same time, the apparently loose form of the essay permitted him to adopt an approach of free doubt and inquisition toward any matter: the essayist is the modern incarnation of the “seeker” (zētētikos) or the “inquirer” (skeptikos) as it was depicted by ancient Pyrrhonism, some sort of “researcher” who practices the skeptical art of zētēsis (free research). Montaigne was born on February 28, 1533, in the Château de Montaigne, close to Bordeaux.1 His father, Pierre Eyquem, Seigneur of Montaigne, was a French Catholic soldier in Italy for a time and had also been the mayor of Bordeaux. His mother, Antoinette López de Villanueva, converted to Protestantism, whereas his maternal grandfather came from a wealthy Spanish-Jewish family who had converted to Catholicism. The oldest of eight surviving children, Montaigne had a brother and a sister who became Protestants. It is very probable that the presence of these different religious allegiances in the family history stimulated Montaigne to be open-minded with regard to problems of faith and pushed him to adopt an approach of wide religious toleration. To this effect, the experiences deriving from the fierce religious war in France between Catholics and Calvinists that raged during the sixteenth century also contributed in a strong way. Montaigne’s education followed a pedagogical plan sketched out by his father and refined by the latter’s humanist friends. The objective was for Latin to become his first language, as it in fact was. He also learned Greek, though without becoming as fluent in it as in Latin. Around the year 1539, Montaigne was sent to study at a prestigious boarding school in Bordeaux, the Collège de Guyenne, then under the direction of the greatest Latin scholar of the era, George Buchanan. Afterward, the young Montaigne studied law in Toulouse; then, he entered a career in the local legal system, becoming a counselor of the Court des Aides of Périgueux and, in 1557, counselor of the Parlement in Bordeaux. From 1561 to 1563, he was a

MICHEL DE MONTAIGNE

233

courtier at the court of King Charles IX, obtaining the highest honor of the French nobility, the collar of the Order of St. Michael. During this period at the Parlement in Bordeaux, he became very close friends with the humanist poet Étienne de la Boétie, by whose death in 1563 he was deeply affected. It has been argued that after losing in Étienne his best conversation partner, Montaigne sought for a different interlocutor who could take the place of the dead friend. It was thus that he started writing the Essais (Essays) as his means of communication and expression: this time he would aim not at a friend but at a reader. In 1565, Montaigne married Françoise de la Cassaigne, basically under pressure from his family, who encouraged him to accomplish marriage as a sort of social duty. The couple had six daughters, though only the second-born, Léonor, survived childhood. Following the recommendation of his father, Montaigne started to work on the first translation of Raymond Sebond’s Theologia naturalis, which he published a year after his father’s death in 1568. Then he inherited the family’s estate, the Château de Montaigne, to which he moved back in 1570, thus becoming the Lord of Montaigne. Another literary accomplishment was Montaigne’s posthumous edition of his friend Boétie’s works, among which Discours de la servitude volontaire was prominent. In 1571, Montaigne retired from public life to the tower of his castle, where he almost totally isolated himself. Locked up in his library, he had several Greek maxims (some of skeptical intonation) sculpted on the beams of the ceiling and finally began to work on his Essays. During the Wars of Religion, being still a Roman Catholic, he acted as a moderating authority and obtained the esteem of both the Catholic King Henry III and the Protestant Henry of Navarre (Henry IV). From 1580 to 1581, he traveled in France, Germany, Austria, Switzerland, and Italy, partly in search of a cure for the painful kidney stones from which he was suffering. To this effect, he established himself at Bagni di Lucca, a place famous for the healing power of its waters. During this travel Montaigne kept a fascinating Journal, which was published only posthumously, in 1774. While traveling through Rome in 1581, he experienced the strong pressure of the Inquisition. Actually, he was detained in order to have the text of his Essays examined by Sisto Fabri who served as Master of the Sacred Palace under Pope Gregory XIII. After Fabri’s close scrutiny, the Essays were returned to its author on March 20, 1581. The main objections concerned references to the pagan notion of “fortuna” and praise for the emperor Julian the Apostate and some heretical poets. Eventually, the author was released with a strong recommendation to make some emendations to the text (which he followed only partly). Being elected mayor of Bordeaux, Montaigne returned to France and took up office. He was reelected in 1583 and served until 1585, again trying to moderate between Catholics and Protestants. In 1586, he left his castle for two years, because of the plague that had broken out and the Wars of Religion that were raging. Montaigne continued to extend, revise, and oversee the publication of the Essays. The first two books were published in 1580 and included 94 chapters. The earliest were short, impersonal, more akin to a collection of anecdotes with

234

SKEPTICISM

brief conclusions. The following chapters were deeply influenced by the Stoic ideal of resisting the ills of life by means of reason and will. However, the chapters of 1574–1575 already show a stronger discontent with Stoical solutions, until the chapter that is the longest by far, the Apology for Raymond Sebond, results in a strong attack on Stoicism, and more generally on any sort of dogmatism, both philosophical and theological. In this chapter, Montaigne drew heavily upon Greek skepticism, especially that of Pyrrho of Elis as presented in the works of Sextus Empiricus and in the detailed Life of Pyrrho contained in the philosophical biographies of Diogenes Laertius. In 1588, Montaigne supervised the fifth edition of the Essays, the first to contain the thirteen substantial chapters of Book III. He also met the writer Marie de Gournay, who became his literary executrix. He attended the Estates-General in Blois, where Henry III had Henri de Guise (the Catholic leader of the League and the instigator of the revolt against the king) assassinated. After King Henry III’s murder (1589), Montaigne helped to keep the city of Bordeaux loyal to the Huguenot Henry of Navarre, who would go on to become King Henry IV.2 Montaigne died of quinsy at the age of fifty-nine, on September 13, 1592, at the Château de Montaigne. Remaining in possession of all his other faculties, he requested mass and died during the celebration of that mass. Since 1588 Montaigne had not written new books or chapters of his Essays; however, he kept adding a thousand passages that reveal a bolder and bolder awareness of his independent thought. Deeply considering the harsh experience of religious wars, he sharpened his views on the state of religion in France, blaming both Catholics and Protestants for their fanatical and intolerant behavior. He became extremely conscious of the necessity of man’s moral autonomy; thus, he criticized any conception of morality that would rely on external authorities, such as religion and law. Furthermore, Montaigne wrote indignantly against the cruelty and hypocrisy of the civil wars, condemning torture and inquisition as means that do not fit any sense of humanity; finally, he developed his plan to portray himself as a way to penetrate the universal human form. His rejection of the Stoical rigor became sharper in the late Essays, whereas his view of death changed completely. At the twilight of his life, he considered death as the end, and not the goal, of the entire existence.

2  THE INTRODUCTION OF SKEPTICISM INTO MODERNITY As we have already said, Montaigne introduced the genuine Pyrrhonian philosophy into early modern philosophy by giving it wide circulation. Before him it was mostly a topic of study for philologists or was used to give support to apologists. The immediate background of Montaigne’s position was the revival of skepticism caused by the recovery of the works of Sextus in Renaissance European culture.3 The rediscovery, the publication, and finally the Latin translation of Sextus’s works allowed Montaigne two great achievements that influenced the aftermath of the skeptical trend during the seventeenth century. First of all, by reading Sextus’s

MICHEL DE MONTAIGNE

235

Pyrrhoniae Hyptyposes, Montaigne became able to grasp the profound originality of Pyrrhonism in comparison not only to the other ancient philosophies, but also to its “false friends,” such as Academic skepticism. Secondly, by having access to Pyrrhonian sources, Montaigne could appreciate the full philosophical substance of skepticism and grasp its principal aims, epokhē and ataraxia (suspension of judgment and imperturbability or peace of mind). Even though he realized the possible religious utility of skepticism as an introduction to naked faith, nevertheless he avoided identifying it with a pure apologetic instrument, as was the case in the Renaissance interpretations. Pyrrhonism was the last ancient philosophy rediscovered by humanists, a resurrection that occurred nearly at the end of the Renaissance. While Academic sources—mainly Cicero’s Academica and the polemical work by Augustine, Contra Academicos—were available during the Western Middle Ages, the few manuscripts of Sextus’s works that were still extant in European libraries apparently passed unnoticed before the sixteenth century. In early humanism, Florence and Rome were the main centers of the renascent interest in those works. Giovanni Pico (1463–1494) used it for his polemic against the astrologers (Disputationes adversus asrologiam divinatricem) while his nephew, Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola (1469–1533), was the first to make extensive use of Sextus’s philosophical works in order to support his own fideistic apologia for Christianity. In his Examen vanitatis doctrinae gentium (1520), Gianfrancesco Pico presented Pyrrhonian skepticism as the best preparation to religion, which was completely alien to the true ancient sources (cf. Cao 2007). His main target was to demolish the “pagan” dogmatism of the Aristotelians and the other philosophical schools, not in order to achieve the sheer suspension of judgment like a true Pyrrhonist, but in order to reach the superior and transcendent certitude of religion. The heavy recourse to the Pyrrhonian tropes (amply displayed and paraphrased from Sextus’s Hypotyposes) was in Pico closely connected to the idea that Christian revelation would be better set up on the ruins of philosophical reason. According to Pico, it is up to skepticism to display its corrosive effect on the body of all dogmatic philosophies, so as to open the way to the transcendent authority of religion and church. From then on an understood alliance was consolidated in European culture between skepticism and apologetics. In the seventeenth century, this typically modern blending of skepticism and strong religious belief took the name of “Christian Pyrrhonism,” finding a fervent supporter in Blaise Pascal in the second part of the century, and a more controversial representative in Pierre Bayle, at the end of the century. In the same vein one can read the long invective contained in Henricus Cornelius Agrippa’s De incertitudine et vanitate scientiarum (1530), which blatantly counterpoised the ignorance of simple believers with the pride of knowledge displayed by dogmatists, which was considered by Agrippa as a “veritable plague” to be fled. Apart from the circulation of manuscripts, which became significant at the end of the fifteenth century, a wider first-hand knowledge of Sextus’s work was first made possible thanks to the printing of Henri Estienne’s Pyrrhoniae Hypotyposes (1562) and Gentian Hervet’s Adversus mathematicos (1569) Latin translations. Another primary source for Pyrrho’s life and doctrines was available in an edition of Diogenes

236

SKEPTICISM

Laertius’s Lives of philosophers (1570) but one had to wait until 1621 to have the editio princeps of Sextus’s Greek text printed (cf. Floridi 2002). The importance of this hard philological work should not be underestimated; yet, it was not just an episode inside the studia humanitatis tradition. Once rediscovered, ancient skepticism was immediately exposed to a subtle enterprise of reinterpretation, in which fidelity to the original meanings was the least of concerns. We will give just two conspicuous examples to show that even the first editions provided the occasion for free reinterpretations. The first editors, the Catholic Gentian Hervet and the Calvinist Henri Estienne, were both worried about giving to the modern reader the right key to understand the works they had edited and translated. In their respective prefaces, the two humanists highlighted the antidogmatic character of Sextus’s arguments, even while emphasizing the religious utility that could possibly derive from skepticism. Of course, their theologies were different and the religious advantages were accordingly different, too. The Huguenot Estienne presented the usefulness of skeptical teaching in terms of moral reform and the improvement of knowledge, whereas the Counter-Reformist Hervet presented Sextus’s tropes and his devastating attack on reason as a confirmation of his own objections to Protestant positions, which he had interpreted as a fresh example of renewed dogmatism. It is with Montaigne’s reappraisal that ancient skepticism in general comes to be appreciated anew in its own original features and as a true philosophical point of view, not only as an apologetic weapon. It is nearly impossible to underestimate Montaigne’s importance as an expounder of this “new” skepticism. Besides drawing on a whole new corpus of Pyrrhonian texts, he clearly marked the difference between the real “skeptics”—namely, the Pyrrhonians—on the one side, and on the other both “dogmatists” and negative dogmatists—these latter being neo-Academics who positively and conclusively affirmed the impossibility of knowing, instead of merely the need to suspend judgment. Furthermore, the author of the Essays rethought and popularized fundamental notions such as phenomenon, criterion, epochē, equipollence between contrary arguments (isostheneia), ataraxia or apathy, vicious circle (diallelos), and “infinite regress.” For the first time, Montaigne translated the entire Pyrrhonian technical terminology into a modern language and, what is more, redirected the ancient notions to suit modern needs. With this reworking, Pyrrhonian skepticism passed from the register of philology (or, in certain cases, apologetics) to that of philosophy.

3  PHENOMENA AND APPEARANCES In order to achieve this result, that is, to reinstate skepticism as one of the major trends of early modern philosophy, the first step had to be to resurrect the basic notion of phenomenon, which was at the very heart of Pyrrhonian philosophy. In reality, Montaigne never used the word “phenomenon,” which was perceived at the time as a Greek word and not accepted either as a Latin or a French term until the age of Descartes and Leibniz (the latter was the first to use this word extensively both in his Latin and in his French writings). If not the word, however, the meaning

MICHEL DE MONTAIGNE

237

was already present in Montaigne. Instead of the term “phenomenon,” Montaigne usually spoke of “appearance” (apparence), which is a calque of the Latin apparentia (plural) used by Henri Estienne in his translation and commentary of Sextus’s Hypotyposes. In Estienne’s work apparentia and phainomena are strictly equivalent.4 This is not the only influence of Estienne’s philological work on Montaigne’s vocabulary. Another, no less important, concerns the notion of phantasia, which Estienne considered as equivalent to phenomenon. Estienne’s Latin interpretation actually renders phantasia as “persuasionem et coactam passionem” (“assent and involuntary affection”), which largely overlaps the definition of phenomenon. The two influences (the one regarding phainomenon, the other connected to phantasia) tightly intertwine. In a crucial passage of the Apology for Raymond Sebond (in fact, a synthesis of PH I 72–78), Montaigne explains what a phenomenon is by appealing to the appearance, at the same time connecting it closely to the notion of fantasie (in French), which means to him “imagination,” or more precisely “sensitive representation.”5 Both choices are not merely lexical; in reality, they deeply characterize Montaigne’s understanding of Pyrrhonian skepticism. Montaigne adopts an epistemologically weak version of phantasia or fantasie, which is no longer a phantasia katalēptikē (the apprehensive representation that, according to the Stoics, can provide a sure criterion for distinguishing between false and reliable representations of reality). Montaigne’s skeptical fantasie is not able to fulfill this function, and that situation clears the way for the study of the subjective states of the mind in themselves and disconnected from reality. These subjective states of the mind are now rather connected to the organic equipment of the senses and are relative to circumstances, conditions, locations, frequency or rarity, habits, etc. In the Apology Montaigne closely follows the famous Ten Modes of Aenesidemus that had been expounded by Sextus. However, unlike the relativistic readings that betrayed the authentic skeptical meaning of these tropes,6 the author of the Essays really grasps their original content, which was calling into question the paradigm of normality on which Aristotelian epistemology was founded. According to Aristotle and the Aristotelians, any man, put in a “normal” situation, with senses and intellect well-tuned according to nature, is able to get an adequate and true representation of external reality. The traffic of species, which come from the object to the subject bearing forms, is supposed to provide a reliable bridge between representation and what is represented. On the contrary, in the Essays not only are species (both sensible and intelligible) banished7—the words species and espèce literally disappear from Montaigne’s lexicon—but the entire complex Aristotelian psychology, which is the basis of his fundamentally realistic theory of knowledge, is abandoned. In a crucial passage of the Apology, Montaigne compares dreaming and being awake, being sober and being drunk, youth and old age, jaundiced and correct perception, health and illness (Montaigne 1999: 595 ff.). Far from being a sheer rhetorical device, this comparison plays an important role in Montaigne’s argumentation. The real meaning of these comparisons consists in showing that, from the epistemological or ontological points of view, normal and abnormal representations are on the same foot: despite all of their differences, they are all simply phenomena or appearances mediated by the internal constitution of the subject, the particular nature of the

238

SKEPTICISM

medium, the complex of circumstances in which both the subject and the object are placed. There is neither direct nor privileged access to reality in itself. Considering their causes and features, “normal” and “abnormal” representations depend on the same natural processes that produce both. Unlike the Aristotelian species, skeptic’s “images” or fantasies are not copies that contain the same forms as their patterns, but just indirect, remote, and complicated effects of distant causes. Starting from these principles, Montaigne can now include all subjective states within the skeptical category of phenomena or appearances. In this light one should read his apparently paradoxical claim: “We are always with some sickness” (Montaigne 1999: 569). For him, to perceive an object always means to be in a subjective state that reflects the quality of the subject rather than the nature of reality itself; or, better, any state of mind reflects a peculiar mixture of both. When perceiving a thing, says Montaigne, we accommodate it to ourselves, transforming the thing according to the self. This process of assimilation is at the same time a process of falsification that prevents us from judging what the thing is in and of itself: Now, because our state accommodates things and turns them according to itself, we do not know what the actual things are any more; as nothing comes to us but falsified and altered by our senses. (Montaigne 1999: 600; cf. 562, 587, 592, 599, 603) In reality, the person “who judges by appearances judges on the basis of something different from the thing itself” (Montaigne 1999: 601), relying on phenomena that belong to the subject and its states—and not strictly to the object. These appearances or phenomena are not part of the object, not even in a formal sense. As a consequence, for a Pyrrhonist such as Montaigne is at least in the Apology, perceptions and any sort of mental representations are not warranted either epistemologically or ontologically, as was the case in the Aristotelian model of “normal knowledge.”

4  MONTAIGNE’S INNOVATIONS: SKEPTICISM AS PHENOMENALISM AND PHILOSOPHY OF DOUBT Montaigne’s interpretation had a strong impact in leading early modern philosophers to seeing Pyrrhonian skepticism as a sort of phenomenalism.8 The foundations of this reading can be summarized in two points. (a) The main scene of skepticism becomes the dichotomy between appearance and reality. The first is knowable. The second—which includes both formal essences and real substances—is unknowable.9 (b) About reality we know only the way in which the external object perceptually appears. “Phenomenon” and “perception” become synonymous expressions in Montaigne and in his followers, whereas, according to Sextus, there was also a kind of phenomena that were disclosed only to the intellect; they did not have sensible features but were rather like noumena (intelligible objects). Nowadays, we might wonder whether Montaigne’s interpretation is philologically and exegetically correct, in comparison with the ancient Pyrrhonian sources. We might also ask whether this kind of dichotomy between appearance and reality does not end up

MICHEL DE MONTAIGNE

239

reinstating some sort of negative dogmatism, proclaiming that the latter is impossible to know and imagining a mysterious metaphysical substructure behind phenomena. This would be an outcome absolutely at odds with the sheer anti-dogmatic effort displayed by Pyrrhonists. Our judgment, however, must be changed when we place ourselves in the perspective either of Rezeptionsgeschichte or of Wirkungsgeschichte. Both of them include the history of misunderstandings and unfaithful traditions, sometimes much more than the sheer history of faithful transmission. Very often the former results in sterile repetitions, whereas the latter produces interesting novelties. In this connection, it is historically true that Montaigne’s phenomenalistic version of ancient skepticism became the prevailing reading in early modern philosophy and deeply influenced the entire epistemological debate. The adoption of the skeptical pattern based on this phenomenalistic approach permitted Montaigne to break the link between reality and appearances and to narrow all of our knowledge to the latter. The clearest statement of this break can be read in the so-called Socrates’s portrait dilemma: how can we be certain that the portrait is a picture of Socrates if we only have access to his representation, namely, to appearances (phenomena), and not to the original model? The Pyrrhonian problem of the criterion is tightly connected to this new scenario, which is the coherent result of abandoning the Aristotelian notion of species (the bearer of the form) as a link between reality and its sensible or intellectual representation. Since appearance and reality are now split, it is necessary to appeal to a “third” term (the criterion) that could guarantee the relation between the two. However, this criterion should in turn require a new one, so raising a sort of infinite regress in the search for further criteria that can guarantee the previous ones. The attempts made in order to stop this aporia fall into two possible traps: the diallelos, or vicious circle, and the dogmatic pretense to allegedly objective and uncontroversial evidence. In reality, both of these aporias result in the impossibility of overcoming the basic dilemma of the criterion (Montaigne 1999: 600–601). Besides these epistemological considerations, which brought all the strength of Pyrrhonian skepticism into the European culture, already weakened by the crisis of Aristotelian scholasticism, the Apology for Raymond Sebond also contains the critical examination of a wide range of dogmatic conceptions belonging to the special fields of metaphysics, theology, politics,10 morals, and even religion.11 Criticism of perceptual representations, contradictions between philosophical schools on their great topics of knowledge (God, soul, immortality, ontological foundations of reality, laws of nature, the divide between the so-called wild peoples and the civilized ones, etc.): all these are the themes of Montaigne’s skepticism, which rejuvenates old Pyrrhonian topics in close contact with modern problems, thus marking the beginning of a rather lively version of the “life without dogmatic beliefs.” Montaigne elaborates also a new concept of belief, emphasizing its emotional and practical character12 and giving prominence in the field of religion to that particular instinct from above that is divine grace. This was also for him the way to distinguish between “true” religion, which is mysterious and supernatural, ultimately an indisputable gift coming from God, and the real religions, which are purely human since they are historical and sociological phenomena. Unlike the former (transcendent revelation),

240

SKEPTICISM

these latter (historical phenomena) can be fully submitted to critical analysis, and this close examination takes in Montaigne the form of tough disenchantment. In spite of his overtures to grace and supernatural revelation,13 the author of the Essays present in other chapters a realistic depiction of the all-too-human forms taken by religions when they are transformed into blind belief, absurd superstition, intolerant fanaticism, or simply traditional conformism. Another major novelty brought about by Montaigne concerns his transforming a philosophy based on epochē and ataraxia into a philosophy of doubt. In the Greek tradition, ataraxia or peace of mind flowed from suspension of judgment—namely, from epochē—rather than from knowledge and judgment about things. Montaigne maintains the basic avowal of ignorance concerning moral laws, no matter whether they are conceived as natural laws or as prescriptions connected to the particular settlement of every society. However, he eventually ends up by making doubt, instead of epochē and ataraxia, the climax of skeptical approach. This is not without consequences for the entire conception of Pyrrhonism, all the more so since doubt is perceived by Montaigne as a state of restlessness and discomfort rather than of calm and moderation of emotions.14 In this connection, Montaigne’s position is defined by a double move: first, he identifies skepticism with the activity of doubting; second, he stresses the discomfort involved in the attitude of doubting. Thus, skepticism and doubt become co-extensional and synonymous, which was not the case in the ancient sources. Once again, the contribution made by Estienne’s translation to this shift is considerable. Following Cicero, Estienne rendered the Greek verb aporein, with its multiple meanings, with the much more univocal Latin verb dubitare (cf. Mates 1996: 30). Under this influence, Montaigne is the first modern writer to stick to the idea that the main activity of the skeptic should be doubting, in the exact meaning that this term takes in the theory of knowledge: an activity fundamentally concerning thoughts whose truth one evaluates. The main activity of the modern skeptic turns out to be a mental exercise, whereas the ancient Pyrrhonist does a discursive practice: the former brings up doubts in his mind, the latter utters opposite statements, balancing each other until he reaches isosthenia. In the Greek Pyrrhonian tradition, doubting or wondering was not the main activity of the inquirer. In fact, the ancient skeptic used to compare conflicting propositions, so as to show that they were no more (ou mallon) asserted than denied. The proper stance of the Pyrrhonist was the suspension of judgment, rather than a fluctuating state of mind, like incertitude and hesitation. After Montaigne and under his influence, these mental and psychological aspects of skepticism, which are represented mostly by the activity of doubting, decidedly prevailed over the original Pyrrhonian linguistic formulations, and it contributed to render extremely problematic the ideal of living comfortably following appearances, according to the original Pyrrhonian project. This relation of synonymy established by Montaigne between the activity of doubting and skepticism is found especially in a crucial passage of the Apology, where the primacy of doubt overlaps a wider panoply of ancient formulations. At first, the author correctly mentions all of the main phonai (phrases) typical of Pyrrhonism, showing how they intertwine, converging into epochē (Montaigne

MICHEL DE MONTAIGNE

241

1999: 505). However, when he needs afterwards to narrow the outlook and focus on a few main points, Montaigne drastically reduces the wider range of skeptical prescriptions, limiting them to two basic propositions: he stresses the formula of Socratic ignorance (J’ignore), which actually is neither properly Pyrrhonian nor exclusively skeptical, and he puts forward the very activity of doubting (Je doubte) as the main activity of skepticism. “I doubt” becomes thus the true motto of the skeptic (Montaigne 1999: 527). Needless to say, both formulas betray the genuine meaning of epochē, since they imply a state of mind quite different from the mere suspension of judgment. “I ignore” and “I doubt” substitute the balanced neutrality of the suspension of judgment with either a dogmatic denial (“I do not know”) or a statement of wavering perplexity (“I doubt”). Despite this true misunderstanding of the original skeptical approach, Montaigne’s interpretation had a strong impact on his posterity and deeply influenced seventeenth-century presentations of Pyrrhonism. It is only in the second edition of the Essays that Montaigne reformulates his approach to skepticism as a kind of interrogation (Que sçay-je?, i.e., “What do I know?”) rather than of a positive or negative assertion.15 He thus intends to avoid the danger of falling into the logical inconsistency represented by the liar paradox, according to which a proposition like “I do not know anything” or “I doubt everything” should apply to itself, with the paradoxical and unacceptable result of being at the same time true and false.

5  THE SKEPTICAL SELF Montaigne has constantly been celebrated as the first inventor of the modern self, or as the father of modern subjectivity. Self-knowledge and self-control play a great role in the Essays, indeed. Montaigne studied himself more than any other subject; he was convinced that the attempt to depict the most faithful portrait of an individual life could lead also to a better knowledge of humanity (Montaigne 1999: 379, 665, 806). He clearly stated this very conviction: “Each man bears the entire form of man’s estate. Authors communicate themselves to the people by some peculiar and strange mark; I am the first to do that by my universal being, as Michel de Montaigne, and not as a grammarian or a poet or a lawyer” (Montaigne 1999: 805). Self-study was for him a school of human nature. This is also the reason why he shared with Socrates full allegiance to the Delphic precept: “Know thyself” (Montaigne 1999: 1001). This is in accordance with the notion of a phenomenon as an internal state of mind, to which the subject has direct access. Furthermore, even when he seems to look at others, in reality it is just to better understand himself: “I tell the others, but I do that in order to recount more myself”; “I watch my life in that of the others” (Montaigne 1999: 1076). Montaigne was in a good position to develop this art of self-portrayal. Self-study led him to practice the art of self-description. Nearly all of the Essays practice this kind of technique, in style as well as content. Furthermore, the portrait must follow the variability, the contingency of its subject; thus, the topic of the essay changes as the subject changes, according to its multiplicity and variability (Montaigne 1999: 378, 805, 818, 964, 1095). The closing of the Apology argues that man cannot

242

SKEPTICISM

have firm knowledge of being, because he is rather a creature of flux, according to the Heraclitean interpretation of the skeptical diatribe; therefore, man cannot participate in full being, which must be stable. Thus, the only real being that does not become is God. The very conclusion of the Apology is against Stoicism, considered as the supreme form of dogmatism, inasmuch as it holds that man can achieve by himself the highest degree of wisdom and natural perfection. According to Montaigne, it is rather the reverse: God alone can rescue man from the perpetual flux of becoming and raise him above humanity (Montaigne 1999: 601–603). The depiction of the self is evident and extremely enlivened in the Essays. For all the appreciation that deserves, we must nevertheless distinguish between, on the one hand, the artistic practice of subjectivity, of which Montaigne is a master, reaching absolutely outstanding results, and on the other the philosophical theory of the subject, for which he still lacks the main conceptual premises and in which he is not really interested. No trace of a proper philosophical theory of the subject can be found in the Essays, despite all his concern about knowledge of his internal and external states. In this regard, the Pyrrhonian model turned out to be more an obstacle than a real help to any theoretical formulation of subjectivity: the more it helped him to an experimental description of the self, the less it contributed to elaborating a theory of the subject. It is true that, according to Montaigne, the “sacramental formula” of the skeptics is epechō (“I suspend [judgment]”), which is a first-person point of view. In reality, this does not imply that Pyrrhonism relies on a deep reflection on the role of the subject. Actually, Pyrrhonism can be defined more as an impersonal philosophy than as a first-person view. Thus, skeptical phenomena are usually described by Sextus using the impersonal form of phainetai, that is, “it seems,” “it appears.” Even though phenomena are connected in practice to the peculiarities of the perceiving subject, from the theoretical point of view there is no need to make explicit the role played by this perceiver; or rather, the perceiver is put at the same level as the perceived and the natural medium that connect each other. Even in Aenesidemus’s Ten Modes, in which the common topic is the relation connecting subject and object, the tone of the treatment is openly naturalistic and very far from any hint of the primacy of the human subject. This latter is mostly considered as a piece of nature plunged into a material world. The knowledge process itself is explained as a “combination” of strongly naturalistic elements (sense organs, humors, particles, and membranes). If we have a look at the psychological section of Montaigne’s Apology, we can immediately realize that the approach of this modern skeptic is also extremely objectivistic. He examines the main different schools of philosophical psychology, showing their hopeless clash, according to the skeptical method of diaphonia (disagreement). Treating this topic is like being in the middle of the “Babel tower” (Montaigne 1999: 553). In his extensive doxology, Montaigne depicts the subject and the soul as parts of nature. Far from grounding the esprit’s prerogative, centrality, and activity in a theory of the autonomy of the soul, Montaigne draws especially on Stoic and Epicurean crude materialism, while considering Platonism, with its complex doctrine of the psychē, to be a fairy tale and poetic philosophy. About Aristotle, he thinks that he was intentionally obscure with regard to his psychology,

MICHEL DE MONTAIGNE

243

willing to hide his attitude toward the thesis of the intellect’s mortality (Montaigne 1999: 552). At the end of this harsh examination of all the psychological theories, the intellect itself is described as “an instable, dangerous, and daring instrument” (“un outil vagabond, dangereux et temeraire”), upon which one should not rely too much. It would be better to assign to it “the tightest possible constraints” (“les barrieres le plus contraintes qu’on peut”) (Montaigne 1999: 559),16 so as to control its extreme fickleness. The full awareness of man’s mutability, inconstancy, and inconsistency was another cause that prevented Montaigne from outlining a strong doctrine of subjectivity. It was up to Descartes to resume from Montaigne the new characterization of skepticism and, at the same time, to overcome the aporias in which the author of the Essays remained trapped.17

NOTES 1. On Montaigne’s life, see Frame (1965). 2. On Montaigne’s political involvements, see Desan (2006). 3. Popkin (2003) is still a useful work about modern skepticism. For a more in-depth and up-to-date analysis, see Paganini (2003; 2008b). On Renaissance skepticism in general, see Popkin and Maia Neto (2004) and Paganini and Maia Neto (2008). For a wider look at recent research on early modern skepticism, see Moreau (2001), Charles and Bernier (2005), and Maia Neto, Paganini, and Laursen (2009). 4. For this interpretation of Montaigne’s skepticism and its drawing on Estienne’s translation of Sextus, see Paganini (2008b: 15–60). On the difference with Sanches’s case, cf. Paganini (2004). For example, when translating Sextus’s main chapter about epochē’s limitations (“Whether skeptics reject phenomena,” PH I 19–20), Estienne felt it necessary to interpolate the text to explain better the sense of the Greek word phainomena. To this aim, he used all the variations on the verb “to appear” in the lexicon. In the next chapter (PH I 21–23), Sextus established an equivalence between the phenomenon—Estienne’s apparentia—and the phantasia. 5. As was first pointed out by Dumont (1972: 44–45), the entire long passage from the Apology for Raimond Sebond (Essays, II, 12) is a brilliant paraphrase of Sextus Empiricus’s text. Cf. Montaigne (1999: 600–601). 6. The reasons why skepticism is not relativism have been correctly illustrated by Annas and Barnes (1985: 96–98, 144): instead of suspending judgment, relativism leads to the affirmation that the object is neither this nor that, or more precisely, it is one thing when it stands in one relation, another when it is in another relation. 7. For a sharp criticism of the Aristotelian pattern of knowledge by similarity, which is at the basis of the notion of species, see Montaigne (1999: 601). 8. For this impact, especially on Hobbes, see Paganini (2003: 3–35). 9. In some famous passages, Montaigne contrasts the perception of the quality of a thing (often varying among subjects) with the thing itself (Montaigne 1999: 587). In other places, he contrasts observable qualities with the essence of the object, which is unknowable (Montaigne 1999: 598–599). Sometimes Montaigne attributes “l’ignorance de la vraye essence de telles choses” to the lack of faculties apt to grasp the “hidden” properties of things (Montaigne 1999: 590).

244

SKEPTICISM

10. On Montaigne’s skeptical political thought, see Laursen (1992). 11. On this last topic, see Panichi (2010: 45–96, 119–152). 12. This aspect is at the heart of the recent French interpretation: see Brahami (2001: 167–234); Giocanti (2001: 91–140). 13. See, for example, the end of the Apology, where the absolute transcendence of the divine is openly proclaimed (Montaigne 1999: 601–604; cf. 927–928). On these topics, see Carraud and Marion (2004), Desan (2008). 14. To characterize modern skepticism, most scholars have focused on the abandonment of the conception of happiness as ataraxia. This is an important feature in itself, but it is secondary compared to what we are dealing with here. For more details, see Paganini (2008a: 166–169). 15. Montaigne (1999: 527): “Cette fantasie est plus seurement conceüe par interrogation: Que sçai-je? comme je la porte à la devise d’une balance.” Clearly, it is an allusion to the medal Montaigne had made to engrave with this symbol, and, at the same time, a reference to the skeptical theme of the equal balance of two opposite assertions, or isostheneia. 16. On the problems raised by Montaigne’s naturalism, see Gontier (1998). 17. On Montaigne’s influence, besides the classical study by Brunschvicg (1942), see Marchi (1995), Melehy (1997), Gessmann (1997), Paganini (2008b: ch. 1), Panichi (2009), Hartle (2013), and Panichi and Spallanzani (2013).

REFERENCES Annas Julia and Jonathan Barnes. 1985. The Modes of Scepticism: Ancient Texts and Modern Interpretations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brahami, Frédéric. 2001. Le travail du scepticisme: Montaigne, Bayle, Hume. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Brunschvicg, Léon. 1942. Descartes et Pascal lecteurs de Montaigne. Neuchâtel: La Baconnière. Cao, Gian Mario. 2007. Scepticism and Orthodoxy: Gianfrancesco Pico as a Reader of Sextus Empiricus. Pisa and Roma: Fabrizio Serra Editore. Carraud, Vincent and Jean-Luc Marion (eds.). 2004. Montaigne: scepticisme, métaphysique, théologie. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Charles, Sébastien and Marc André Bernier (eds). 2005. Scepticisme et modernité. SaintÉtienne: Publications de l’Université de Saint-Étienne. Desan, Philippe (ed.). 2006. Montaigne politique. Paris: Honoré Champion. Desan, Philippe. 2008. Montaigne: Les formes du monde et de l’esprit. Paris: PUPS. Desan, Philippe (ed.). 2008. Montaigne et la théologie: “Dieu à nostre commerce de société”. Genève: Droz. Dumont, Jean-Paul. 1972. Le Scepticisme et le phénomène: Essai sur la signification et les origines du pyrrhonisme. Paris: Vrin. Eva, Luiz. 2004. Montaigne contra a Vaidade: Um estudio sobre o ceticismo na Apologia de Raimond Sebond. São Paulo: Humanitas.

MICHEL DE MONTAIGNE

245

Faye, Emmanuel. 1998. Philosophie et perfection de l’homme: De la Renaissance à Descartes. Paris: Vrin. Floridi, Luciano. 2002. Sextus Empiricus: The Transmission and Recovery of Pyrrhonism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Frame, Donald. 1965. M. Montaigne: A Biography. London: Hamilton. Gessmann, Martin. 1997. Montaigne und die Moderne. Zu den philosophischen Grundlagen einer Epochenwende. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag. Giocanti, Sylvia. 2001. Penser l’irrésolution: Montaigne, Pascal, La Mothe Le Vayer. Trois itinéraires sceptiques. Paris: Honoré Champion. Gontier, Thierry. 1998. De l’homme à l’animal (Montaigne et Descartes). Paris: Vrin. Green, Felicity. 2012. Montaigne and the Life of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hartle, Ann. 2013. Montaigne and the Origins of Modern Philosophy. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Laursen, John Christian. 1992. The Politics of Skepticism in the Ancients, Montaigne, Hume, and Kant. Leiden, New York and Köln: Brill. Maia Neto, José R., Gianni Paganini, and John Christian Laursen (eds.). 2009. Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the Work of Richard Popkin. Leiden: Brill. Marchi, Dudley. 1995. Montaigne Among the Moderns: Receptions of the Essais. Providence: Berghahn. Mates, Benson. 1996. The Skeptic Way: Sextus Empiricus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism. New York: Oxford University Press. Melehy, Hassan. 1997. Writing Cogito: Montaigne, Descartes, and the Institution of the Modern Subject. New York: State University of New York Press. Montaigne, Michel de. 1999. Essais, edited by P. Villey. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Moreau, Pierre-François (ed.). 2001. Le scepticisme au XVIe et au XVIIe siècle. Paris: Albin Michel. Paganini, Gianni. 2003. “Hobbes Among Ancient and Modern Sceptics: Phenomena and Bodies.” In G. Paganini (ed.), The Return of Scepticism: From Hobbes and Descartes to Bayle, 3–35. Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer. Paganini, Gianni. 2004. “Montaigne, Sanches et la connaissance par phénomènes. Les usages modernes d’un paradigme ancien.” In V. Carraud and Jean-Luc Marion (eds.), Montaigne: scepticisme, métaphysique, théologie, 107–136. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Paganini, Gianni. 2008a. “The Quarrel over Ancient and Modern Scepticism: Some Reflections on Descartes and His Context.” In J. Popkin (ed.), The Legacies of Richard Popkin, 173–194. Dordrecht: Springer. Paganini, Gianni. 2008b. Skepsis: Le débat des modernes sur le scepticisme. 2nd edition, 2017. Paris: Vrin. Paganini, Gianni and José R. Maia Neto. 2008. Renaissance Scepticisms. Dordrecht: Springer. Panichi, Nicola. 2004. I vincoli del disinganno. Per una nuova interpretazione di Montaigne. Firenze: Olschki. Panichi, Nicola. 2010. Montaigne. Roma: Carocci.

246

SKEPTICISM

Panichi, Nicola (ed.). 2009. Montaigne et les philosophes, Montaigne Studies 21. Panichi, Nicola and Maria Franca Spallanzani. 2013. Montaigne and Descartes: A Philosophical Genealogy. Special issue of Montaigne Studies 25. Popkin, Richard. 2003. The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Popkin, Richard and José R. Maia Neto (eds.). 2004. Skepticism in Renaissance and PostRenaissance Thought. New Interpretations. Amherst: Humanity Books. Sève, Bernard. 2008. Montaigne: Des règles pour l’esprit. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

CHAPTER EIGHTEEN

Pierre Charron GIANNI PAGANINI

1  LIFE AND WORKS Pierre Charron was born in Paris in 1541, one of the twenty-five children of a bookseller. After studying law, he took his degrees in Montpellier (1571) and afterward practiced as an advocate, for a few years, before deciding to study theology, still in Montpellier, where he resided from 1565 to 1566 and again from 1570 to 1571. He then entered the church and soon was a popular priest, rising to become a canon. He moved to the southwest of France, invited by Arnaud de Pontac, Bishop of Bazas. He was appointed priest in ordinary to Marguerite de Valois, wife of Henry IV of Navarre. In about 1588, Charron decided to become a monk, but, being rejected by both the Carthusians and the Celestines, he returned to his old profession. He delivered a course of sermons in Angers, and the next year he moved to Bordeaux where he formed a famous friendship with Michel de Motaigne. On July 2, 1586, Montaigne presented him with a copy of Catechism by Bernardino Ochino (the famous Italian monk who fled his native country and religion to adopt Protestant ideas), with the annotation liber prohibitus (“forbidden book”). According to La Rochemaillet, Charron, residing in Bordeaux from 1589 to 1593, had many opportunities to visit Montaigne during the last four years of the latter’s life. On Montaigne’s death, in 1592, Charron was requested in the will to bear the Montaigne arms.1 In many circumstances of his life and during his activity as a preacher, Charron got involved in the events of the French religious wars, first in the struggles between the Catholic League and the Huguenots, and afterwards in the difficult procedures aiming to enforce the Edict of Toleration (Nantes Edict). Indeed, Charron directly experienced the fierce troubles provoked by religious intolerance: in Montpellier he was imprisoned and taken hostage by the Protestants (1565–1566). In 1588, in Angers, he was reached by the news of the assassination of the leader of the League, the Duke of Guise, by order of King Henry III, against whom he had rebelled. In the Discours chrestien, qu’il n’est permis au subjet pour quelque cause et raison que ce soit, de se liguer, bander et rebeller contre son Roy (written in 1588 and published in 1606), Charron remembers to have been caught then by a “strong fit of anger

248

SKEPTICISM

and disdain,” but to have been quickly “cooled,” definitely abandoning his previous attachment to the League. This Discours contains a complete refutation of the ideas held by the monarchomachs, preaching instead absolute fidelity to the sovereign, even when he is “bad.” Charron spent from 1594 to 1600 under the protection of Antoine Hérbrard de Saint-Sulpice, Bishop of Cahors, who appointed him grand vicar and theological canon. In 1595, he was chosen deputy to the general assembly of the clergy, for which he became chief secretary. For the occasion he preached also in the church of Saint Eustache, one of the most populous parish churches in Paris. In 1601, Charron published in Bordeaux his main work, De la Sagesse, a system of moral philosophy that develops some ideas from Montaigne, realizing a peculiar synthesis of skeptical wisdom and a strong Stoic sense of human autonomy. In this work, Charron also connected Montaigne’s skepticism to the anti-rational strand in Christianity, underlining the narrow limits that constrain human knowledge in theological matters. He worked afterwards on a new revised edition but died suddenly of a stroke on November 16, 1603. This new edition appeared in 1603, just after the author’s death. It contains numerous changes in comparison with the first one; in particular, Charron modified the plan of Book I: he added six chapters and modified several passages that were considered scandalous by theologians.2 Despite these changes, the work was condemned by the Faculty of Theology in Paris (1603) and was after included in the Index of Forbidden Books (1605). De la Sagesse was also attacked by the Jesuit François Garasse (1585–1631), who described Charron as an atheist; yet the work was defended by Duverger de Hauranne, the abbot of Saint Cyran, one of the leading personalities within the Jansenist movement. A summary and defense of the book, written shortly before his death, appeared in 1606 (Traicté de Sagesse). In 1604, Charron’s friend Michel de la Rochemaillet prefixed a “Life” to an edition of De la sagesse, which depicts Charron as an amiable man of good character. His complete works, with this contribution by de la Rochemaillet, were published in 1635.

2  SKEPTICISM AND THE RISE OF MODERN SUBJECTIVITY In his treatise De la Sagesse, Charron tried to summarize and rearrange Montaigne’s thought, bringing forth that handbook of wisdom that was already implicit in the Essays but still needed to be explicitly and systematically expounded.3 In so doing, Charron made of De la Sagesse a cornerstone for the new culture of the honnête homme that spread all over the seventeenth century, influencing both the skepticallibertine milieux and Cartesian morals. In Charron’s book various philosophical trends converge and cooperate: the Stoic reevaluation of the autonomy of virtue goes together with an argument against superstition and subordination of morality to faith. At the same time, the drive to an entirely mundane preud’homie (“human wisdom”) appears to be full of Epicurean suggestions and contains daring references to an unscrupulous political prudence.

PIERRE CHARRON

249

From the point of view of the history of skepticism, Charron’s work is a landmark that separates modern forms from the ancient ones. De la Sagesse uncovers a new face of skepticism, which had deep impact on the common image of this movement during the seventeenth century and after. In Charron’s work, the skeptical sage is not only an active and important character, but, what is more, also is someone who breaks away from the classical Pyrrhonian pattern as well as from its more recent reenacting in Montaigne’s Essays. As regards the ancient pattern, the attainment of epochē was basically the result of a process of “detachment from the self,” the fruit of an “accentuated passivity” of sensations and thoughts, “a paralysis of reason by itself,” as Myles Burnyeat has put it (1983: 133). According to Jonathan Barnes, epochē was a pathos, some sort of passivity or passion, that happened to inquirers (skeptikoi) at the end of their investigations. In other words, for the ancient Pyrrhonians, even the suspension of judgment was less a voluntary effort than the product of a causal sequence impacting on them (the sequence included: investigation (zētēsis)—disagreement (diaphōnia)—equipollence (isostheneia)—and finally suspension of judgment (epochē) (Barnes 1983: 7)). Nearly the same can be said about Montaigne, except that this latter added a sense of pessimism and human frailty that was unknown to the ancient skeptics. When one reads Montaigne, it seems that skepticism inflicts a heavy blow not only to human arrogance, but also to the value of the intellect and the senses themselves. Not by chance, reason is defined in the Essays as “an instrument of lead and wax, which one can lengthen, bend, and adapt to any direction and extent” (Montaigne 1999: II xii 565). From this point of view, Charron’s skepticism is quite different. First of all, the author of De la Sagesse does not hesitate to stress the strength of reason, emphasizing at the same time the positive feature of skeptical examination. It is true that reason, and mostly skeptical reason, does not have “jurisdiction” on all subject matters: for example, Charron proclaims that skepticism makes no metaphysical claims and that it relies on revelation in theological matters. Nevertheless, in the mundane domain of “human wisdom,” reason preserves its complete right “to judge about everything” and to “restrain assent” when faced with inadequate reasons (Charron 1986: 399). In his own field, the sage shows full “universality of spirit”; he is not narrowed by the “municipal law” (1986: 406) that rules closed systems of beliefs, whether these beliefs be the elementary, sociological beliefs of the village or the more sophisticated beliefs of nations, philosophical schools, religions (i.e., actual religious rites and behaviors), and churches. For the first time in the modern age, Charron’s skeptical sage is someone who fights against an entire corpus of beliefs, someone who decides to doubt and seeks for arguments to this effect. This is the main Charronian achievement: epochē or suspension of judgment becomes now a vigorous and voluntary liberating move from a system of beliefs rather than an imponderable point of balance between different opinions, as it was before in the ancient idea of equipollence. Far from being the passive effect produced by the unresolved diaphōnia of appearances that are simply registered by the observer, Charron’s art of doubting requires a conscious and voluntary decision from the subject. Skepticism demands a whole set of epistemic virtues that preserve the wise from precipitancy, prejudices, and

250

SKEPTICISM

mistakes. Modern skepticism, as it is reworked by the author of De la Sagesse, needs a discipline of the intellect and its judgments. After Charron, the modern skeptic is someone who wants to cast into doubt almost everything whereas the ancient Pyrrhonian was cast in doubt by different phenomena. With this work, one can see the author initiate the typical modern attitude of negative suspicion against any belief whose sole justification is habit, authority, or tradition. From passive, skepticism becomes active; it is no longer the position of an impartial observer but the pose of a conscious protagonist who does not want to be enslaved to prejudices or opinions devoid of any rational justification.4 This is also the reason why Charron’s philosophy, probably more than Montaigne’s, and certainly more than ancient Pyrrhonism, is one of the birthplaces of modern subjectivity (cf. Paganini 2008). One major contribution to this achievement is the sharp separation between externality and interiority in the attitude of the sage. Whereas external appearances can be given up to social conformity, so that the skeptic would not challenge laws, common opinions, and public offices, interiority, that is, private judgment, becomes in Charron the domain of free “jurisdiction” that acknowledges no authority but reason. The external sphere is the field in which particularity and municipality rule, whereas the internal becomes the reign of “universality of spirit.” The “free spirit” or the esprit fort, to which Charron recognizes the right to judge about everything, is the antecedent of the modern intellectual to whom the right to criticize established values and conventions is attributed, without any other commitment, except to reason and morality. All these innovations, along with the clear influence of Stoicism, converge in Charron’s philosophy into the discovery of man’s autonomy: autonomy that means firstly selfgovernment according to the lead of reason, and secondly disentanglement toward any external, traditional, social, and political constraint. This profound split between internality and externality runs along the line dividing the private and the public spheres. After Charron, modern skepticism develops in the sage’s interior region, while actions are confined to exterior conformism. This is a major innovation in comparison to the ancient Greek sources that ignored this dramatic divide. In a much clearer way in Charron than before in Montaigne, this radical split is not only a matter of personal reservation; indeed, it stretches to the extremes of simulation and dissimulation. Faced with the constraints imposed by external requirements, the modern Charronian sage feels free to recur to pretense and reticence in order to keep his own interiority safe and free. We should not understand this attitude as a kind of overt rebellion; on the contrary, the skeptic does not shirk his own duties and responsibilities, in line with the Pyrrhonian precept that recommends following the rules, customs, and laws of one’s country. Nevertheless, and despite this apparent conformism, the modern skeptic becomes the bearer of a new sense of intellectual emancipation that was unknown to the ancients. Actually, the relationship between the sage and society has completely changed with respect to antiquity. The moderns are confronted with schools of thought, political and religious bodies of beliefs that are organized, and compelling systems requiring from the subject the performance of precise behaviors, but also requiring him to take sides in the course of the ideological struggles that tear the commonwealth, the church,

PIERRE CHARRON

251

and their institutions. Thus, the modern skeptic has to experience the strength and the coercion of ideological systems that were almost unknown to antiquity. In order to face this new and troubling situation, the modern skeptical sage, according to Charron, should adopt a cold and detached conception of acting that is tightly connected to the distinction between the external and the internal. The skeptic must give to the institutions just the minimum of his external commitment, the minimum that is absolutely necessary for the needs of praxis and for the functioning of the social body. By contrast, he ought to preserve for the internal and individual sphere his intimate beliefs. The modern skeptic can feel free to criticize in his internal sphere the common wisdom and the values of the city, which were not cast into doubt by the ancient skeptic. The main target of the criticism of the latter were not so much the beliefs and the rites of the city, but only the moral and political theories elaborated by the dogmatic philosophers (cf. Charron 1986: 411–415). Furthermore, and despite all of Charron’s caution in keeping different fields and their respective prerogatives sharply separated, one must admit that with this modern skeptical scrutiny the foundations for an uncompromised assent to the public institutions are at least implicitly undermined. The least one can say is that, in comparison to those of ordinary people, the skeptic’s choices become more pragmatic and independent of any partisan dogmatism. Even though he conforms to the beliefs and rules that are in force and displays his profession of conformity, whenever he can withdraw into “the forum of consciousness,” the skeptical sage refuses to abdicate the freedom of his own judgment; his external obedience is completely disentangled from any internal orthodoxy. According to Charron, abiding by a law does not necessarily involve the duty of considering it true, right, or rational. All this has an evident impact on the holding of the skeptic’s beliefs. By practicing the skeptical scrutiny of any dogma, including those that constitute morals and politics, the sage is now able to denounce the “mystical ground” of laws and customs: “mystical” in the sense of being obscure, mysterious, and ultimately arbitrary or unjustified. Echoing one of Montaigne’s famous statements, Charron declares that “laws and customs keep their credit not because they are right and good, but for being laws and customs: this is the ground of their authority” (1986: 498).5 This sentence overtly expresses skepticism regarding the official motivations that are given to support ethics and politics. This split between the internal and the external can sometimes result in a plain contradiction, as Charron himself recognizes: “enjoying his own right to judge and examine everything, it will often happen to the sage that his judgment and his hand, the spirit and the body contradict themselves, and he will act outside in one way and judge inside in another way” (1986: 393). This is the effect of the new protagonist pose that the sage takes, at least in his internal sphere, toward the whole body of public opinions. Whereas the ancient Pyrrhonians usually stressed the perfect conformity of the skeptic to the customs and beliefs that make up not only ordinary life but also political life, Charron emphasizes the complete autonomy of the sage, who conceives himself as an independent subject, even while seeking refuge in the sphere of private consciousness. We can understand now why the value of isostheneia is no longer central in this new perspective. By challenging the cautious advice of “general indifference,”

252

SKEPTICISM

Charron sticks much more to the rational basis of skepticism. He declares that “the search for truth” is the real and explicit aim of any skeptical investigation, and that its instrument (outil) is reason. This free use of reason, which is not only allowed but also recommended by skepticism, becomes the new standard for the conception of being truly human. Human dignity is now based on using reason in order to “judge” about everything: The real prerogative of humans, their proper and more natural practice, their worthier activity, is that of judging. Why are humans beings that speak, reason, and intend? Because perhaps they have minds in order to build castles in the air or to fill to bursting with silliness and trifles, like most people? Who ever had eyes for darkness? Certainly, humans are made to see, to understand, to judge all things to such a point that they are called the guardian, supervisor, controller of nature, world, God’s works. To deprive them of this right is the same as willing them not to be anymore humans but beasts. (Charron 1986: 389–390) This recourse to the prerogative of judging is all the more crucial, since humans are immerged in that condition of uncertainty that the skeptical crisis has revealed. This situation of doubt demands from the sage the most attentive practice of rational discernment: Since there is only one truth among a thousand lies and of a thousand opinions about the same subject only one is the true one, why shouldn’t I investigate which one is best, the most reasonable, good, useful, and convenient using reason? Is it possible that among so many laws, habits, beliefs, different and opposite customs, only those we practice are the good ones? (Charron 1986: 387) Charron’s conclusion is univocal: “The sage will judge everything. Nothing will escape him that he lays on the table and on the scale to investigate” (Charron 1986: 392). It is essential to notice that this kind of “judging” is neither dogmatic nor Pyrrhonian. As to the former, Charron explains that the sage does not “judge” in the sense of “establishing, affirming, determining,” but in the sense of a continuous quest that has no end (“to examine, evaluate, weigh and balance reasons on one side and on the other, and thus search for truth”). As to the latter, Charron admits that the sage can opine (contrary to the Pyrrhonian injunction against neo-Academics), even though “without any determination, decision, affirmation.” This is a kind of having “weak” opinions, according to Academic probabilism (Charron 1986: 386–387). It must be added, however, that this right of doubting and judging, which is at the heart of Charron’s active interpretation of skepticism, is not the business of everyone but just of those who are well equipped for it, namely, “spirits well born, strong, and vigorous” (“esprits bien nez, forts et vigoureux”). These peculiarities depend on the prerogative of reason, and do not derive from any privilege of nobility. According to Charron, an esprit fort is someone who is capable of using reason and conducting his own life according to this kind of rational examination, which is the basic procedure of skepticism. The Charronian sage is well aware that social, political, and religious institutions rely on passivity, and yet that they are absolutely necessary for ordinary

PIERRE CHARRON

253

people. What is more, Charron is overly pessimistic about the possibility that most people could act according to his ideal of self-determination. The large majority is made of “not too well talented men”; these latter strongly support the character that laws and conventions impose upon them. Unlike ancient skepticism, which did not explicitly make any difference between various kinds of persons, modern skepticism, as it was shaped by Charron in the wake of Montaigne, is intrinsically hierarchical. Charron divides human beings according to intellectual capacity and correlates with this their ability to suspend judgment, not giving their assent to what is doubtful or simply plausible. Most people are on the lowest degree of this tripartite hierarchy (“weak spirits, of low and little ability, born to obey, to serve, and to be conducted”); in the middle are “pedants,” who are perfect models of the “dogmatist”; on top are the few who “would rather doubt and suspend their judgment” than enter the rush of dogmatic and unjustified affirmations. This tripartite classification of spirits was already present in Montaigne, but it is only with Charron that it enters as a constituent point into the construction of a skeptical anthropology (Charron 1986: 291–292).6 On the whole, it can be said that the main aim of Charron’s skepticism is no longer the Pyrrhonian ataraxia. The importance of this rather passive value is superseded now by the exercise of a triad made up of much more active practices: “judging of everything” (juger de tout), “retaining the assent” (sursoir la determination), keeping “the universality of spirit” (universalité d’esprit) (Charron 1986: 406). Even though he still draws on Montaigne for illustration of the details in which this practice of doubting ultimately consists,7 it is only in Charron that this practice takes the form of an emancipatory program supported by a deliberate education and exercise of the spirit.8

3  CHARRON’S SKEPTICISM COMES BACK FROM PYRRHONISM TO NEO-ACADEMICISM Since the theory and praxis of epochē are largely common to the two main skeptical traditions, Pyrrhonism and neo-Academic philosophy, Charron feels authorized to draw on both of them. He often puts Pyrrhonism and Academicism on the same level (Charron 1986: 405), equating the ataraxia of the former to the “neutrality and indifference” of the latter (Charron 1986: 410). In so doing, he inaugurates the typical modern koinē of skepticism, which is some sort of eclecticism in the art of doubting. Blending together these two trends, Charron goes much further than Montaigne, who had rather stressed the novelty of Pyrrhonism and rejected probabilism. The author of De la Sagesse opens the way to considering both traditions as belonging nearly to the same body of philosophy, which meant, for some “dogmatic” opponents of skepticism like Descartes, rejecting Pyrrhonism and Academicism altogether, and for some sympathizers of skepticism like Hume, allowing them to shift from the one form to the other, always keeping allegiance to the skeptical approach.

254

SKEPTICISM

From the strictly epistemological point of view, Charron does not take up the precise characterization of Pyrrhonism that was contained in Montaigne’s Apology for Raymond Sebond. This marks a major shift in his own description of skepticism, which turns out to follow in the wake of the neo-Academic revival that preceded Montaigne’s turn toward Sextus’s texts. Among the neo-Academic features that are recognizable in De la Sagesse,9 there is first the emphasis on the ideal of intellectual integrity, which comes from Cicero (Acad. II. 7–9), and the insistence on the necessity of studying and neutralizing the internal and the external causes of any strong attachment to uncertain, false, and precipitant opinions. “Retaining the assent” (surseance) is the first condition for keeping the freedom of one’s spirit (Charron 1986: 404). Avoiding precipitancy and error ends up being more important than attaining truth: whereas this latter usually is extremely difficult to reach, the former always stays within our range. The second major Academic influence on Charron consists in an overt profession of Socratic ignorance. The device of the wise man, which figures in the frontispiece of De la Sagesse, is the famous Socratic motto “je ne sais” (“I do not know”). The affirmation of akatalēpsia was blamed by Pyrrhonians as an example of negative dogmatism. By contrast, it is taken up by Charron, despite all of its logical inconsistencies (one could object that at least the sage knows one thing, that he knows nothing). Nor is the author of De la Sagesse interested in Montaigne’s reform of skepticism, which had transformed the profession of ignorance into an interrogation (“que sçais-je?”). Charron seems inclined to give to his sage a stable intellectual and moral position (which is made of intellectual integrity, rejection of errors, refusal to hasten his judgments, emendation of prejudices, etc.). To this effect, he does not like the kind of Pyrrhonian irresolution that was practiced by his master Montaigne. The assured position of the neo-Academic sage seems to him steadier than the passive and indifferent pose typical of the Pyrrhonian philosopher.10 The third Academic feature is the emphasis put on the value of self-knowledge. Moving in the wake of his beloved predecessors, Socrates and Montaigne, the author of De la Sagesse gives a systematic form to what in the Essays was much more a matter of practice than of theory. In Charron, self-observation and selfinquisition develop in a true anthropological doctrine, without losing all of his skeptical approach: in reality, this whole corpus of knowledge that starts from the self and ends with humanity is basically aimed at fighting dogmatic presumption and ignorance; skeptical anthropology is mainly a doctrine about the moral and epistemic limits of anyone’s self (Charron 1986: 28, 33, 37, 44–46, 376). Finally, the fourth positive influence of the Academic tradition on Charron makes him more open than Montaigne to Carneades’s notion of probability as a guide to the complex world of opinions, most of all practical opinions.11 In this regard, Charron clearly breaks off from both Sextus, who denied any significant difference in opinions concerning probability, and Montaigne, who saw in probabilism a challenge not only to Pyrrhonian indifferentism but also to his Catholic traditionalism. By contrast, Charron thought that there was a way of taking a doctrine as probable that was compatible with a true skeptical approach, provided that one adopted Carneades’s and Cicero’s point of view.

PIERRE CHARRON

255

4  THE SKEPTICAL IMPACT ON MORALS AND RELIGION The consequences for morals and religion of this new conception of wisdom, in which skeptical themes play a crucial role along with a Stoic inheritance, are extremely important. The comparison with Montaigne is still useful in order to appreciate the novelty of Charron’s position. Whereas the former blended the Pyrrhonian fourfold rule of life with modern Catholic traditionalism, which prevented him from adhering to the Reformation, Charron, even while remaining apparently faithful to his religious confession, used skepticism to go beyond the limits of Montaigne’s cautious conformism, even in the field of morals and religion. As to the former (morals), Charron took up the Platonic and Stoic topic of the “inborn seeds,”12 willing to emphasize the autonomy of morals from any external constraints, such as those of religions and laws. The origin of this topic is still classic, coming basically from Cicero and Seneca; however, Charron’s reinterpretation is new in that he stresses its possible polemical meaning, which is now clearly directed against the overwhelming burden of religious eternal norms (see Kambouchner 2008; Gaiu 2010). This is a radical turn in comparison to the traditional ethics that relied on a transcendent foundation and not on a “natural” tendency of man, appealing much more to the threat of natural rewards and the promise of supernatural punishments than to the intrinsic value of virtue.13 In contrast with an entire millennial religious tradition, Charron wants men to be good even “without hell and paradise” (1986: 464). Nor do original sin and theological grace have any importance in the philosophical ethics of De la Sagesse, even though the author will be compelled in the second edition to mitigate his views, adding (in Book III, Ch. III) a paragraph about “grace as a perfection of nature,” which would be taken up again in the Traicté de sagesse with the title: “warning about the necessity of the divine grace” (1986: 846–847; cf. Faye 1998: 270–271). However, and despite this softening of the original thesis, it is still true that in the first version of De la Sagesse, human wisdom (preud’homie) is considered by the author as antecedent and independent with regard to religion. Charron continually emphasizes the difference between “probity” on the one side and “piety” on the other, claiming that “religion is posterior, a special and particular virtue, distinguished from the other virtues” (1986: 464).14 At the same time, the traditional conception of wisdom related to metaphysics and speculative theology is completely abandoned, whereas the emphasis is put on its practical and humanistic import. Charron stresses the narrow borders of human reason: while restraining philosophy to what lies within the natural reach of the human mind, he polemically reacts to the excessive pretensions of the metaphysicians who aim at delivering the first principles and causes. The object that is naturally adequate to human reason is not knowledge of essences or substances, or dogmatic physics, but human morals and life (Charron 1986: 25–32). In the expanded preface to the second edition of De la Sagesse, Charron explicitly distinguishes between divine wisdom and human wisdom, leaving to the theologians the former and adopting the latter as his own subject. In so doing, he appeals to his qualification as a philosopher and not as a theologian. It is on

256

SKEPTICISM

religion that this skeptical-stoical sort of wisdom had the greatest and the most influential impact. In principle, true religion and true wisdom should converge, since—says Charron—when someone is really a sage, he “acts according to God, according to himself, to law, to nature” (1986: 424). In reality, when one examines religions in their historical and actual substance, leaving out of consideration the supernatural pretensions that they unanimously claim, rightly or wrongly, it is easy to recognize that all of them counterpoise true wisdom. Consequently, one basic distinction that De la Sagesse draws is that between “true piety” and “superstition.” The superstitious man is dominated by fear and makes God to be like men, thereby running into “blasphemy.” He reduces the relation with the divinity into a utilitarian trade, some sort of “trafficking” in which the expectation of rewards and the fear of punishments end up being more important than reason and virtue. Noticing how much superstition is natural among men, Charron draws from Montaigne a whole web of considerations that develop, in the text of De la Sagesse, into a true philosophical anthropology of religious behaviors (see Kogel 1972: 90–104). In Book II Ch. V, Charron opposes “vraye pieté” to actual religions: these latter, however various and strange, have many features in common, such as sacrifices, humiliation of the spirit, credulity, multiplication of miracles, and some sort of illusory reversal in the human relations to the divinity. While aiming at propitiating gods, these religions end by annihilating human nature. “What overturning of sense, when one thinks to appease the divinity by inhumanity, to gain divine goodness by our affliction, to please his justice by cruelty?” (1986: 449). Even though Charron would like to carry out “true wisdom and true piety,” joining them and “blending together,” it is still true that, even in the most favorable hypothesis of a mutual concord, one should keep them sharply distinguished: “[I want it to be so] that each of them subsists and stands alone, without the help of the other, and acts by its own strength” (Charron 1986: 466). Wisdom must be “already born in you, with you, planted by nature”; by contrast, religion cannot but be “posterior,” “learnt” through revelation and instruction. In the relation between religion and wisdom, the latter comes first and is the cause of the former, not the reverse (1986: 466–467). Because of his official commitments in ecclesiastical institutions as a preacher and a teacher,15 Charron had the opportunity to write many theological works, some of which preceded De la Sagesse. The first was Les trois vérités contre les athées, idolatres et juifs (1593), an apologetic treatise aimed at demonstrating the existence of God and the truth of Christian religion. It is interesting to see how these apologetic aims developed in such a way as to connect with skeptical themes that would be treated at a later point in De la Sagesse. The main points in common with this latter work concern the polemic against superstition and the adherence to the themes of negative theology, on the basis of the idea that “God is impossible to know” (1635: II 12). Combining the skeptical thesis about the inadequacy of human knowledge with the theses of mystical and apophatic theology grounded on God’s ineffability, Charron goes so far as to write statements that only seldom could be found in any apologetic work. The “Discourse on God’s knowledge” is particularly explicit, stating that “every divinity, which is proven and established by reason, is a false divinity, not a true one,” since “there is no passage from

PIERRE CHARRON

257

the finite to the infinite” (1635: II 13). In this same Discourse, Charron declares every theological representation to be absolutely relative and therefore devoid of any effective content. After describing with mystical overtones the soul that rises “abstracting itself from everything” and “merging into a vague and infinite void,” Charron concludes that every “image” or representation of the divinity is “always false, that is faulty and defective,” even though man cannot but try to fabricate one. Despite the tone filled with compunction, the ultimate result is a strong skepticism about the value of any discourse about God. Charron states so: “The last and highest degree to which everyone can rise and reach by the extreme effort of his imagination is for him his own God” (1635: II 19–20). In reality, every definition, every positive statement about God is at the same time some sort of restriction of the infinite, which is unacceptable. This apophatic method (according to which we can say of God what he is not but not what he really is) also serves Charron’s strategy against atheism because he sustains that even a negation of God, being as dogmatic as the affirmation, would intend to set a limit to divine nature; therefore, atheism also falls into the defect of restricting the infinite to the finite. Like the dogmatic theologian, the atheist is guilty of an “abuse,” since both try to submit the infinite to the limits of finite human reason (1635: II 13). This propensity of Charron toward negative theology, as opposed to “dogmatic” theology, is strongly emphasized in the Discours chrestiens (1601). In this work, he appeals to the label of “learnt ignorance” and declares that his work aims at arousing “admiration” rather than offering “knowledge” about God. Religious discourse should be simply a way of “honoring” God (“without any affirmation, determination, prescription”), and not an effort to describe Him (1635: I 12–13). When it is applied to theological discourse, skepticism encourages some sort of transvaluation of the attributes of God. In the wake of this tendency, Charron does not just emphasize the absolute transcendence of the divinity; he even goes much further than supporting the traditional distinction between ordained and absolute power in God, stating that He can do everything that is not contrary to Himself, that is, to being and truth (1635: I 23). The most daring statement by Charron in this direction is that, even though we cannot “conceive goodness, wisdom, power except in a human way,” nevertheless one should remove all the bounds from these notions, going as far as to imagine a kind of “superwisdom” (sursagesse) in God (1635: I 8).

NOTES 1. The main source for Charron’s life is still La Rochemaillet in Charron (1635), reprinted in Desan (2009: 273–286). 2. A bibliography of Charron’s works can be found in Charron (1960: 147–151) and in Dini and Taranto (1987: 419–435). 3. Referring to his sources in general, Charron claims that his work is the product of his readings; however, he says, “the form and the order are mine” (1986: 34). 4. On this peculiar feature of Charron’s skepticism, see Popkin (1954; 2003: 57–63, 68–70, 100–107) and Paganini (1991: 201–214).

258

SKEPTICISM

5. This is an echo of a famous passage by Montaigne (1999: III xiii 1072). 6. See Montaigne (1999: II xvii 657). For this tripartition, see Paganini (1987). 7. See e.g. Charron (1986: 406–411) for the considerations on barbarism, universality of nature, variety of religions, etc. 8. Another important source of this emancipatory program can be traced to the secularization of some ideas related to the movement of “free spirit” or “libertinism,” typical of the sixteenth century and condemned by John Calvin. From this heritage probably comes—even though from far—the continuous hints made by Charron to the Pauline motto “spiritualis omnia iudicat et a nemine iudicatur” (1 Cor. 2: 15), by which he tries to legitimate his appeal to freedom of judgment and universality of spirit (Charron 1986: 41, 389). 9. For the emphasis on neo-Academic features in Charron’s work, see José Maia Neto’s interpretation (Maia Neto 2003, 2014). 10. It is significant that, when it is a matter of describing the grounds of epochē, Charron recurs much more often to neo-Academic formulations that to the truly Pyrrhonian ones (Charron 1986: 399–400). Also when characterizing the result of epochē, Charron emphasizes active more than passive features of the spirit (see Charron 1986: 404). 11. On the issue of whether Carneades’s stance is a sort of probabilism, see Harald Thorsrud’s contribution in Part One of this book. 12. On this crucial topic, see Horowitz (1971; 1974; 1998). 13. For the novelty represented by Charron in this field, see Gregory (1986: 71–113), translated in Gregory (2000: 115–155). 14. For the originality of Charron’s notion of “wisdom,” see Rice (1958: 178–207) and Abel (1987: 187–208). 15. On this activity, see Belin (1995: 7–205).

REFERENCES Abel, Günher. 1978. Stoizismus und Neuzeit. Berlin: De Gruyter. Barnes, Jonathan. 1983. “The Beliefs of a Pyrrhonist,” Elenchos 4: 5–43. Belin, Christian. 1995. L’Oeuvre de Pierre Charron (1541–1603): littérature et théologie de Montaigne à Port-Royal. Paris: Honoré Champion. Burnyeat, Myles. 1983. “Can the Skeptic Live His Skepticism?” In M. Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition, 117–148. Berkeley: University of California Press. Charron, Pierre. 1593. Les trois vérités contre les athées, idolatres, juifs, mahumétans, hérétiques, schismatiques par Charron. Bordeaux: S. Millanges. Charron, Pierre. 1601. Discours chrestiens. Seconde partie. Bordeaux: S. Millanges. Charron, Pierre. 1635. Toutes les Œuvres de Pierre Charron…. Paris: Jacques Villery. (Reprinted in 2 vols. Genève: Slatkine Reprints, 1970.) Charron, Pierre. 1986. De la sagesse. Paris: Fayard. Desan, Philippe (ed.). 2009. Pierre Charron. Special issue of Corpus 55. Dini, Vittorio and Domenico Taranto (eds). 1987. La saggezza moderna. Temi e problemi dell’opera di Pierre Charron. Napoli: Edizioni Scientifiche Italiane.

PIERRE CHARRON

259

Faye, Emmanuel. 1998. Philosophie et perfection de l’homme. De la Renaissance à Descartes. Paris: Vrin. Gaiu, Claudiu. 2010. La Prudence de l’homme d’esprit. L’éthique de Pierre Charron. Bucuresti: Zeta Books. Gregory, Tullio. 1986. Etica e religione nella critica libertina. Napoli: Guida. Gregory, Tullio. 2000. Genèse de la raison classique de Charron à Descartes. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Horowitz, Maryanne. 1971. “Pierre Charron’s View of the Source of Wisdom,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 9: 443–457. Horowitz, Maryanne. 1974. “Natural Law as Foundation for an Autonomous Ethics: Pierre Charron’s De la Sagesse,” Studies in the Renaissance 21: 204–227. Horowitz, Maryanne. 1998. Seeds of Virtue and Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Kambouchner, Denis. 2008. “Descartes et Charron: prud’homie, générosité, charité,” Corpus 55: 193–208. Kogel, Renée. 1972. Pierre Charron. Genève: Droz. Maia Neto, José. 2003. “Charron’s Epoché and Descartes’ Cogito: The Sceptical Base of Descartes’ Refutation of Scepticism.” In G. Paganini (ed.), The Return of Scepticism: From Hobbes and Descartes to Bayle, 81–131. Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer. Maia Neto, José. 2014. Academic Skepticism in Seventeenth-Century French Philosophy: The Charronian Legacy 1601–1662. Dordrecht: Springer. Montaigne, Michel de. 1999. Les Essais, edited by Pierre Villey. Paris: PUF. Paganini, Gianni. 1987. “‘Sages,’ ‘spirituels,’ ‘esprits forts.’ Filosofia dell’ ‘esprit’ e tipologia umana nell’opera di Pierre Charron.” In V. Dini and D. Taranto (eds.), La saggezza moderna. Temi e problemi dell’opera di Pierre Charron, 113–156. Napoli: Edizioni Scientifiche Italiane. Paganini, Gianni. 1991. Scepsi moderna. Interpretazioni dello scetticismo da Charron a Hume. Cosenza: Busento. Paganini, Gianni. 2008. Skepsis: Le débat des modernes sur le scepticisme. 2nd edition, 2017. Paris: Vrin. Popkin, Richard. 1954. “Charron and Descartes: the Fruits of Systematic Doubt,” Journal of Philosophy 51: 831–837. Popkin, Richard. 2003. The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rice, Eugene. 1958. The Renaissance Idea of Wisdom. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

CHAPTER NINETEEN

Francisco Sanchez: A Renaissance Pyrrhonist against Aristotelian Dogmatism DAMIAN CALUORI

1 INTRODUCTION Francisco Sanchez (1550/51–1623) was a well-known skeptic in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. His one skeptical work, That Nothing is Known (Quod nihil scitur), first published in 1581, was widely read and went to four editions.1 Pierre Bayle praised him in his Dictionnaire historique et critique as “a great Pyrrhonist” (Bayle 1740: vol. IV, 133), and Gabriel Naudé recommended in 1644 that Sanchez’s skeptical work should be part of every learned library—next to that of Sextus Empiricus (see Jolly 1990).2 Even as late as 1702, Leibniz declared in a letter to the French mathematician and physicist Pierre de Varignon that he had often thought a reply to Sanchez would be a very useful thing indeed (Gerhardt 1859: 94–95). After this, Sanchez’s influence waned. He no longer seems to have been discussed much in the eighteenth century. In what follows, I will first discuss what kind of skepticism Sanchez adhered to: whether he was an Academic or a Pyrrhonian skeptic. Then I will consider Sanchez’s critique of the scholastic Aristotelians, the dogmatists of his day. Finally, I will ask where Sanchez stands in relation to modern Cartesian skepticism and whether his skepticism is purely theoretical or whether it also has implications for the practical affairs of life.

2  SANCHEZ, THE PYRRHONIST There is a traditional view of skepticism—a view found, for example, in Hegel’s influential Lectures on the History of Philosophy—according to which the skeptic

FRANCISCO SANCHEZ

261

claims that nothing can be known or that nothing can be known for certain (Hegel 1979: 253). Sometimes this version of skepticism is called “dogmatic” skepticism since it dogmatically claims that nothing can be known (or that nothing can be known for certain). Already in antiquity, Academic skepticism was sometimes interpreted in this way.3 Thus, Sextus Empiricus criticizes Academic skepticism for asserting that nothing can be known and considers this a mark distinguishing Academic from Pyrrhonian skepticism: while the Academic skeptic dogmatically states that nothing can be known, the Pyrrhonist continues his search (PH I 3, 226).4 It is easy to see how the title of Sanchez’s work, That Nothing is Known, can be understood as defending a dogmatic skepticism. In order to counter this misunderstanding right from the start, Sanchez begins his work with the following words: “Not even this do I know, that I know nothing. I suspect, however, that neither I nor anyone else knows anything”5 (QNS 1, LT 172).6 Further elaborating on this, Sanchez denies that he can prove the truth of the claim that he knows nothing. This incapability of proving his ignorance, he thinks, confirms his suspicion that he does not know that he knows nothing. If, however, he had proof of his total ignorance, then he would know that he knew nothing. He could then assert that he knew nothing. Pursuing this hypothetical alternative a little further, Sanchez has an imaginary opponent state: “If you know how to prove that you know nothing, the contrary follows, namely, that you already know something” (QNS 1, LT 172). Sanchez, not being a dogmatic skeptic, can easily reply that he knows of no such proof and since he has no such proof, he does not commit himself to any claim to knowledge. Rather, like an ancient Pyrrhonist, Sanchez does not know that nothing can be known. He is just not aware of any knowledge that has so far been established. Thus, it seems to me that Sanchez’s own words rule out an interpretation such as that of Richard Popkin who states in his History of Scepticism: “Sanchez’s totally negative conclusion is not the position of Pyrrhonian skepticism, the suspense of judgment as to whether anything can be known, but rather the more full-fledged negative dogmatism of the Academics” (Popkin 2003: 41). That Sanchez was not a skeptic of the sort Popkin believes him to be does not as such imply that he was a Pyrrhonian skeptic. There seems to be at least one further possibility. Elaine Limbrick, for example, shares Popkin’s view that Sanchez was an Academic skeptic. Yet she understands Academic skepticism as advocating, not a negative dogmatism, but “a system of methodological doubt which would free the human mind of the fetters of the past and enable the skeptical enquirer to reestablish knowledge on a firmer empirical basis” (Limbrick 1988: 88). According to her interpretation, the knowledge that Sanchez seeks to establish is not firm or certain knowledge (and thus not the sort of knowledge that the dogmatists believe themselves to have achieved). Rather, it is revisable knowledge based on the best evidence we have. Should new evidence show that our knowledge is inadequate— and it is perfectly conceivable that such new evidence can be found—our knowledge should be revised. Sanchez’s skepticism becomes, according to this interpretation, a methodical skepticism in the sense that, although we assume that knowledge is achievable, we never assume it to be definitely achieved but always continue to question and test it. In allowing for revisable knowledge, Sanchez’s skepticism would

262

SKEPTICISM

be distinct from the radical Pyrrhonian skepticism that doubts that knowledge is achievable at all. If this interpretation is correct, Sanchez becomes, thus understood, a profoundly modern thinker. What makes this view nevertheless Academic, in Limbrick’s interpretation, is the idea that we base our knowledge claims on the Academic notion of what is persuasive or probable (probabile): we are justified in believing ourselves to know something if we have better reasons to believe it than not to believe it.7 On the basis of this justification, the skeptic of this ilk believes that the truth of her beliefs is more likely (probabilius) than their falsehood. Thus, while a skeptic of this sort does not commit herself to any firm or certain knowledge, she nevertheless believes that it is possible to achieve knowledge in the sense of a set or system of justified beliefs that remains open to reform. While this is doubtless a picture attractive to us moderns, it seems to me that we have no good reason to attribute it to Sanchez.8 Let us first consider two pieces of evidence adduced by Limbrick (1988: 78) for her claim that Sanchez was an Academic skeptic: he signs off a letter to the famous Renaissance mathematician Clavius with “Carneades philosophus,” using the name of one of the most famous Academics; and in his commentary on Galen’s De pulsibus ad tyrones, he claims to withhold judgment “Academicorum more.” For this to count as evidence for a Sanchezian Academic skepticism, we would have to assume that Renaissance philosophers clearly distinguished between Pyrrhonian and Academic skepticism. However, as Charles Schmitt (1972: 7, 14) has shown and as the studies of Emmanuel Naya (2009: 24) have confirmed, they often used the words “skeptic,” “Academic,” and “Pyrrhonian” more or less synonymously. Thus, these two pieces of evidence show only that Sanchez considered himself a skeptic. Yet they do not show that he considered himself an Academic, as opposed to Pyrrhonian, skeptic. In That Nothing is Known Sanchez uses the term “persuasive” or “probable” (probabile) only three times. As I have argued elsewhere (Caluori 2007: 34–36), he nowhere uses it unambiguously in the epistemic sense relevant to Limbrick’s interpretation. Moreover, if Sanchez wanted to establish a science based on the notion of what is persuasive or probable, we would expect him to explain this notion and how it forms the foundation for his new science. Yet none of this can be found in his writings. So it seems to me that we have no good reason to believe that the notion of the probabile played a key role in Sanchez’s skepticism. Finally, we may be inclined to believe that Sanchez is about to establish a foundation for a new (revisable) science because he refers four times to a method of knowing (methodus sciendi) as if he was dealing with it in another book.9 At the end of That Nothing is Known, for example, he states: If you know anything, teach me. For I shall be very grateful to you. In the meantime, I prepare myself for the examination of things and I shall put forward in another book whether anything is known and [if anything is known] how, a book in which I shall expound, as far as human frailty allows, the method of knowing. Farewell. (QNS 245, LT 290) No such book is extant nor do we have any evidence that Sanchez ever wrote it. It is thus impossible to prove that such a book would (or would not) have contained

FRANCISCO SANCHEZ

263

a method of knowing that would allow us to build a new and revisable science. The best information we possess about Sanchez’s project is contained in the passage just quoted. But here Sanchez does not commit himself to the view that anything can be known. His promised exposition of the (or a) method of knowing presupposes the settling of the question of whether anything can be known. For if nothing can be known, developing a method of knowing is quite pointless. This passage tells us, however, that Sanchez is not giving up his pursuit of truth. He promises to continue his search for it by preparing himself for the examination of things. In the same vein, he states in the address to the reader: Yet I will not at all promise you the truth because I am ignorant of it—as of everything else. Nevertheless, I will pursue it with all my power and you for your part shall pursue it. . . . Yet do not expect ever to capture it. . . . Let the chase suffice for you, as it does for me. For this is my aim and my end—an end you too must aim for. (QNS xiii, LT 170) Now compare this passage to how Diogenes Laertius describes the Pyrrhonists: “All these were called Pyrrhonists after the name of their master, but also . . . seekers because they were ever seeking the truth; skeptics [i.e. inquirers] because they were always looking for a solution and never finding one” (DL IX 69–70). Sanchez’s description of his search for the truth is clearly modeled on the basis of what he knows about ancient Pyrrhonism.10 Sanchez is seeking the truth without ever having found it, and while he does not claim that it is impossible to find the truth, he is not certain that it will ever be found and cautions expectations accordingly.

3  AGAINST ARISTOTELIAN DOGMATISTS Aristotelians dominated Western universities throughout the sixteenth century (see Schmitt 1983). In fact, as Charles Lohr has shown, the number of Latin commentaries on Aristotle composed between 1500 and 1650 “exceeds that of the entire millennium from Boethius to Pomponazzi” (1974: 228). Aristotelianism was not, of course, a unified school or doctrine at the time (nor at any other), and there were many different strands, schools, and traditions.11 For our purposes, however, it will be sufficient to consider the epistemological consequences of two competing metaphysical views that were popular among the Aristotelians of Sanchez’s time12: first, the nominalist view in the tradition of Ockham. Nominalists claim that only particulars (as opposed to universals such as species) possess real existence; second, the realist so-called species theory that goes back to Thomas Aquinas and regained popularity with the revival of Thomism in the sixteenth century.13 Sanchez argues against them separately. His conclusion, however, is in both cases the same: if the corresponding metaphysical view is true, nothing can be known. Before discussing these two views, the following should be noted: when Aristotelians talked about knowledge (scientia), they had in mind scientific knowledge—the sort of knowledge Aristotle discusses in his Analytica Posteriora. Accordingly, Sanchez’s target is scientific and not ordinary knowledge. I will come

264

SKEPTICISM

back below to the relation of these two kinds of knowledge and what this means for Sanchez as a skeptic. Let us now look at Sanchez’s critique of the knowledge claims of the nominalists. In order to show some of the difficulties into which nominalists run, Sanchez adopts, for the sake of argument, a nominalist position. He states: Do you expect even further proof of our ignorance? I will provide it. You have already seen the difficulties with species. But you will concede that there is no knowledge of particulars as they are infinite. But there are no species—or, in any case, they belong only to the imagination. (QNS 80, LT 212–213) Sanchez uses a problem (aporia) already stated in Aristotle’s Metaphysics and turns it into a skeptical argument: we can have scientific knowledge (scientia) only of universals. But there are no universals. Therefore, there is no scientific knowledge (see Met. 999a: 24–b3).14 Now, a nominalist may be unimpressed by this argument because she does not deny the existence of universals tout court but only the real existence of universals. So she would reply to Sanchez that there are universals, namely, species, but that these species have no real existence. Instead, they exist only as mental entities. To which Sanchez replies: You will say that you are not studying particulars, as they are not objects of scientific knowledge (scientia), but rather universals such as human being, horse, and so on. This is indeed the case and I have already said it before: your knowledge is knowledge, not of real human beings, but of a fiction that you invent. Hence, you know nothing. (QNS 46, LT 196)15 According to the nominalist position understood thus, universals are mental entities with no real existence. But if we understand them in this way, then according to this argument, mental entities, rather than really existing things, become the objects of knowledge. But if so, then we are incapable of acquiring any knowledge about things in the external world. Nothing is known if the nominalists are right.16 Now, in order to avoid the conclusion that species are purely mental (and perhaps even fictitious) entities, we may want to give up nominalism and claim that species are in some way part of extramental reality. The so-called species theory was perhaps the most sophisticated version of this view in the sixteenth century. According to Aquinas, with whom the species theory originates, all our knowledge derives from the senses. Yet even though all sensory objects are particulars, we are capable of arriving at the cognition of universals—and this in roughly the following way. When I see a particular human being, the sensible part of my soul receives through my eyes an impression of this particular human being. What the soul thus receives is a sensible form. Now my active intellect abstracts the universal form (i.e., the intelligible species) from the sensible form. As a result of this process of abstraction, the soul possesses an intelligible species, which is the essence of the object: in our example the essence human being.17 What is crucial for our purpose is the view that the species (the universal) is not simply a representation of the external object: it is not an internal object somehow representing the essence of the external object. Rather, it is formally identical with it. This makes it possible for the

FRANCISCO SANCHEZ

265

intellect (or so defenders of this view claimed) to grasp the essence of the external object itself. In this way, the species theory is a realist theory and distinct from the nominalist view considered above. Sanchez’s first argument against the species theory is a classic Pyrrhonist attack on the reliability of the senses (through which all knowledge is acquired according to the Aristotelians). When examining the reliability of sense perception, Sanchez quite reasonably assumes that, in order to have normal sense perception (i.e., sense perception presenting the things the way they are), certain criteria must be fulfilled. One of them concerns the medium through which we perceive the object. For depending on the medium, things appear differently to us. So the medium must be such as to allow for normal sense perception. But how can the mind be certain that the medium is such as to allow for normal sense perception? Well, certain criteria will need to be fulfilled so that the medium is such as to allow for normal sense perception. How does the mind know that these criteria are fulfilled? Sanchez sums up: “There is no conclusion, only endless doubt” (QNS 172, LT 254). Even if we assume for the sake of argument that sense perception works properly and that we possess normal sense perception, Sanchez sees further problems with the species theory. I will restrict the discussion to one of them. Defenders of the species theory claim that all knowledge is based on sense perception. What our senses perceive, however, are only accidental features of particulars—not their essence. Accordingly, the sensible form must exclusively consist of accidental features. But if this is the case, the essence cannot get abstracted from the sensible form. For the essence is neither part of the sensible form nor can it be inferred from a thing’s accidental features: The whole thing would be bearable, if we had images from the senses of all things we wish to know. Yet the contrary is the case: we do not possess images of the most important things but only of accidental features which do not, as they say, contribute anything to the essence of a thing. But the essence is the source of true knowledge; and accidental features are the most useless of all things. (QNS 127, LT 237) Sanchez here assumes that species are only images of extramental objects and implicitly denies that species are formally identical with the objects whose species they are.18 Now, even if the species theorist rejects this representationalist interpretation, the main argument still stands. The active intellect is incapable of deriving the essence of a thing from sensible forms. For sensible forms, being the only material from which the active intellect can abstract intelligible forms, exclusively consist of accidental features. And no matter how many accidents of a thing we are aware of, by no process of abstraction can an essence be distilled out of them. Hence, Sanchez concludes, if the species theory is true, we will not be capable of cognizing essences. And since essences, according to the Aristotelians, are the only objects of scientific knowledge of the world, nothing can be known if the realists are right. I have only discussed two of the arguments Sanchez presents against the dominant Aristotelian positions of his day. But I hope Sanchez’s strategy has become clear. He shows that both nominalists and realists fail to ground their knowledge claims

266

SKEPTICISM

within their own respective dogmatic frameworks. In his arguments, Sanchez only uses premises either granted by his opponents or derived from claims granted by them. Thus, in line with both forms of ancient skepticism, he commits himself neither to nominalism nor to realism nor to any other dogmatic framework.

4  SANCHEZ AND CARTESIAN SKEPTICISM In a classic paper, Myles Burnyeat shows in what ways Cartesian and ancient skepticism are distinct. Ancient skeptics doubted that we possess knowledge about the world as it really is. No ancient philosopher, however—and thus no ancient skeptic—knows “the problem of proving in a general way the existence of an external world” (Burnyeat 1982: 19). Descartes’s hyperbolic doubt is more radical in that it presents, by means of the evil demon, precisely this problem. As Burnyeat shows, this radicalization of skepticism leads to its refutation by means of the cogito. Moreover, Burnyeat follows Bernard Williams (1978) in arguing that Descartes’s project is one of pure enquiry. Ancient skepticism, by contrast, is a way of life and thus an eminently practical affair. Sextus tells us that suspension of judgment leads to tranquility and thus to a sort of life that appears desirable. Hence, the ancient skeptic offers what his dogmatic opponents promise but cannot deliver: a good and happy life. Cartesian skepticism, on the other hand, is purely theoretical. Descartes does not show us a way to a good and happy life achievable through skepticism. Burnyeat thinks that these two points (i.e., doubting the existence of the external world and seeing skepticism as a purely theoretical affair) are related. Ancient skepticism did not question, Burnyeat claims, that one can walk around in the world “because it was in fact entirely serious about carrying skepticism into the practical affairs of life” (Burnyeat 1982: 40). Descartes, by contrast, is in a position to question the existence of the external world because his skepticism is methodical and divorced from practical concerns. We have seen in Section 3 that the sort of knowledge whose attainability Sanchez doubts is scientific knowledge (scientia). So it may seem that his skepticism is also of a purely theoretical kind, detached from one’s life. But Sanchez’s doubt is not methodical and not part of a larger project of pure enquiry. It rather is a genuinely skeptical doubt as I hope to have shown in Section 2. What is more: Sanchez was a medical practitioner at the Hôtel Dieu, the hospital of Toulouse, and, later in his life, became a professor at the faculty of medicine at the town’s university. So we need an account of Sanchez’s attitude toward practical issues. Since his doubt was not methodical, we have to ask how he could be a practitioner and teacher of medicine. For we may be inclined to assume that these activities presuppose the acknowledgment of a body of scientific knowledge. The answer to this question can be found if we heed the fact that Sanchez’s skepticism was influenced by the ancient medical school of empiricism (see Caluori 2007).19 Ancient empiricists practice medicine, but they do so without reference to any theoretical framework (see Frede 1987). They reject medical theories, the use of formal inference, and the postulation of entities that (according to their dogmatic

FRANCISCO SANCHEZ

267

opponents) can be grasped only by reason. Instead, they rely on experience for their practice. A medical empiricist acquires experience in relying on what she herself perceives, on the carefully checked reports of other people, and on the transition from cases she is familiar with to cases that are similar to them. In keeping with their skeptical attitude, they do not believe themselves, however, to possess a rational justification for their procedures. Rather, it appears to them that, if they proceed in this way, they can practice medicine quite successfully. Moreover, the procedures they use seem to them to be the same as those that people use in their ordinary lives. Ordinary people live their lives without relying on theories and without the postulation of the existence of abstract entities. Sanchez makes very similar claims. Like the ancient empiricists, Sanchez does not doubt that ordinary people possess experiences and lead their lives on the basis of them. For example, he does not doubt that the farmer can distinguish his donkey from the neighbor’s ox (QNS 171, LT 254). And like the ancient empiricists he doubts the existence of theoretical entities: “For who could understand non-existent things? Thence come Democritus’s atoms, Plato’s Forms, Pythagoras’s numbers, and Aristotle’s universals. . . . In this way they [i.e. the dogmatists] entrap the unwary, claiming to have discovered unknown things and the secrets of Nature” (QNS vii, LT 168). In another passage he states: “Much experience, then, makes a person both learned and wise. This is why old people are more learned, at least in terms of experience, and thus better adapted to the conduct of human affairs than the young” (QNS 225, LT 281). We trust experts in such fields as agriculture, navigation, commerce, and medicine because of their experience. Experience appears to be a tremendously successful guide to the conduct of human affairs. Sanchez was well acquainted with ancient empiricism. One main source for this view is Galen—in the sixteenth century the medical authority par excellence. Galen’s work includes a number of treatises and passages discussing medical empiricism.20 It is true that Renaissance Galenism was rather dogmatic (Gilbert 1960; Schmitt 1985). But this does not exclude the possibility that a Renaissance skeptic could find in Galen a view opposed to dogmatic Galenism—a view that would allow him not only to live a skeptical life but also to practice and teach medicine without believing in the truth of any dogmatic theory.21 It seems to me that Sanchez was such a Renaissance skeptic, a skeptic living a skeptical life and practicing and teaching medicine in a non-dogmatic way. Sanchez thus shares with the ancient Pyrrhonists the view that a skeptic can live his skepticism and even practice an art without committing himself to any theory. Given the practical side of his skepticism, it is perhaps also unsurprising that he does not doubt the existence of the external world, the world we live and act in. However, there is one crucial difference between Sanchez and ancient Pyrrhonism. Sanchez nowhere promises that his skepticism may lead to tranquility or happiness. His view on human life is less hopeful, and he often complains about the misery of human life and laments about our epistemic situation. What motivates him nevertheless to pursue his theoretical enquiries is not the hope of tranquility but rather the desire to understand.

268

SKEPTICISM

NOTES 1. Lyon 1581, Frankfurt 1618, Toulouse 1636, and Rotterdam 1649. 2. Also Delassus, Sanchez’s first biographer and editor of the Toulouse edition of That Nothing is Known, calls Sanchez a Pyrrhonist. See Limbrick (1988: 68 n. 6). 3. This interpretation has since been refuted, as far as the major Academic skeptics of the Hellenistic period are concerned. See Frede (1997). 4. See also Photius, Bibl. 212, 169b. Another influential source for this view was Augustine, who was widely read in the Renaissance. See Augustine, C. Acad. 2.11. 5. A very similar statement is attributed to Arcesilaus by Cicero at Acad. I 12, 45. 6. When quoting Sanchez, I refer to the paragraph number of the latest critical edition of the Latin text by Howald, Caluori, and Mariev (2007) and to the page number of the English translation by Thomson in Limbrick and Thomson (1988). All translations are my own. 7. It should be noted that Limbrick’s understanding of Academic skepticism is compatible only with the Metrodorian-Philonian line and stands in contrast to the classical skepticism of Clitomachus and Carneades. For more details, see Frede (1997) and Brittain (2001). 8. I discuss this in detail in Caluori (2007). 9. In addition to the passage quoted below, see QNS 26 (margin), 215 (margin), and 221 (LT 278). The edition and translation of Limbrick and Thomson does not render Sanchez’s marginal notes. 10. As far as his sources are concerned, we do not know whether Sanchez knew Sextus’s writings, but he explicitly refers to Diogenes Laertius and to Plutarch’s works Adversus Colotem and Lucullus (see Sanchez’s marginal notes to QNS 24, 34, 130, and 164). In addition, Sanchez knew Galen, for which see below. 11. For the variety of Renaissance Aristotelianisms, see Kristeller (1974: 30–49) and Schmitt (1983: 10–33). 12. In this part, I follow Howald, Caluori, and Mariev (2007: cxxiv–cxlviii). 13. For the renewed interest in Thomas Aquinas in the sixteenth century, see Spruit (1995: 93–158). 14. In Aristotle it is, of course, an aporia to be resolved. 15. Sanchez’s argument goes back to Duns Scotus (Commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics, lib. 7, Quaest. 13). 16. Sanchez also argues against an alternative modification of the original argument a nominalist could present. For she could claim that there is knowledge of particulars. For a discussion of Sanchez’s argument against this, see Howald, Caluori, and Mariev (2007: cxxxii–cxxxvi). 17. For more details on Aquinas’s theory, see Kretzmann (1993: 138–146). 18. This argument had already been developed by Petrus Johannis Olivi and William Crathorn in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries. See Perler (2003). 19. Ancient empiricism was related to Pyrrhonism. See James Allen’s chapter in Part I of this book.

FRANCISCO SANCHEZ

269

20. See Galen’s On the Sects for Beginners; On Medical Experience; An Outline of Empiricism (all in Frede 1985); and On Therapeutic Method (in Hankinson 1991). 21. For textual parallels between Sanchez and Galen on empiricism, see Caluori (2007).

REFERENCES Bayle, Pierre. 1740. Dictionnaire Historique et Critique. Amsterdam: P. Brunel. Brittain, Charles. 2001. Philo of Larissa: The Last of the Academic Sceptics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Burnyeat, Myles. 1982. “Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw and Berkeley Missed,” The Philosophical Review 91: 3–40. Caluori, Damian. 2007. “The Skepticism of Francisco Sanchez,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 89: 30–46. Floridi, Luciano. 2002. Sextus Empiricus: The Transmission and Recovery of Pyrrhonism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Frede, Michael (ed.). 1985. Galen: Three Treatises on the Nature of Science. Indianapolis: Hackett. Frede, Michael (ed.). 1987. “The Ancient Empiricists.” In his Essays in Ancient Philosophy, 243–260. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Frede, Michael (ed.). 1997. “The Sceptic’s Two Kinds of Assent.” In M. Burnyeat and M. Frede (eds.), The Original Sceptics: A Controversy, 127–151. Indianapolis: Hackett. Gerhardt, Carl Immanuel. 1859. Leibnizens Mathematische Schriften, vol. 4. Halle: Verlag H. W. Schmidt. Gilbert, Neal. 1960. Renaissance Concepts of Method. New York and London: Columbia University Press. Hankinson, R. J. (ed.). 1991. Galen on the Therapeutic Method. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hegel, G. W. F. 1979. Vorlesungen über Geschichte der Philosophie. Werke in zwanzig Bänden. Auf der Grundlage der Werke von 1832–1845. Neu edierte Ausgabe. Redaktion Eva Moldenhauer und Karl Markus Michel, Band 19. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Howald, Kaspar, Damian Caluori, and Sergei Mariev (eds.). 2007. Franciscus Sanchez. Quod nihil scitur. Dass nichts gewusst wird. Introduction, Latin text, and German Translation. Hamburg: Meiner Verlag. Jolly, Claude (ed.). 1990. Gabriel Naudé: Advis pour dresser une bibliothèque. Reproduction de l’édition de 1644. Paris: Alain Baudry et Cie. Kretzmann, Norman. 1993. “Philosophy of Mind.” In N. Kretzmann and E. Stump (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Aquinas, 128–159. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kristeller, Paul Oskar. 1974. Humanismus und Renaissance I: Die antiken und mittelalterlichen Quellen. Munich: Fink. Limbrick, Elaine and Douglas Thomson (eds.). 1988. Francisco Sanches: That Nothing is Known. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Limbrick, Elaine. 1988. “Introduction.” In E. Limbrick and D. Thomson (eds.), Francisco Sanches: That Nothing is Known, 1–88. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

270

SKEPTICISM

Lohr, Charles. 1974. “Renaissance Latin Aristotle Commentaries: Authors A-B,” Studies in the Renaissance 21: 228–289. Naya, Emmanuel. 2009. “Renaissance Pyrrhonism: A Relative Phenomenon.” In G. Paganini and J. R. M. Neto (eds.), Renaissance Skepticisms, 13–32. Dordrecht: Springer. Perler, Dominik. 2003. “Wie ist globaler Zweifel möglich? Zu den Voraussetzungen des frühneuzeitlichen Aussenwelt-Skeptizismus,” Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 57: 481–512. Popkin, Richard. 2003. The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schmitt, Charles. 1972. Cicero Scepticus: A Study of the Academica in the Renaissance. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Schmitt, Charles. 1983. Aristotle and the Renaissance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Schmitt, Charles. 1985. “Aristotle among the Physicians.” In A. Wear, R. K. French, and I. M. Lonie (eds.), The Medical Renaissance of the Sixteenth Century, 1–15. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Spruit, Leen. 1995. Species Intelligibilis. From Perception to Knowledge. Vol. 2: Renaissance Controversies, Later Scholasticism, and the Elimination of the Intelligible Species in Modern Philosophy. Leiden: Brill. Williams, Bernard. 1978. Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. London: Penguin Books.

PART THREE

Modern Skepticism

272

Introduction Modern Skepticism BARON REED The beginning of the second great flowering in the skeptical tradition coincides with two of the major transformations in European history. First, the development of a globalized economy brought the exchange across vast distances of not only material goods but also people and ideas. Many Europeans reacted with the sort of selfinterested chauvinism that has always tended to shape human interactions, but the most perceptive recognized the intellectual, ethical, and spiritual challenges posed by these very different forms of human life. Michel de Montaigne, for example, was prompted by his encounter with a group of Tupinambá people, who had traveled from Brazil to France, to reconceive what it means to be barbaric or civilized and, a century later, Pierre Bayle punctured the almost universally accepted notion that an atheistic society couldn’t be moral by pointing to the ancient civilization of China.1 The increasingly close contact with the wider world served as an implicit critique of European beliefs, values, and customs. Second, the Reformation—together with the resistance it provoked—led to a profound change in the way moral and intellectual authority functioned in society. Religious disagreements became far more widespread, and it was no longer possible to simply treat unorthodox ideas as impermissible heresies. These disagreements also became deeper from an epistemological point of view, as Catholics and Protestants no longer shared a commitment to the same way of thinking about how these differences could be resolved. These theological conflicts, along with the rise of a new way of engaging in natural philosophy, prompted a widespread concern with intellectual methodology: what are the proper sources of human knowledge? Martin Luther, Francis Bacon, René Descartes, and John Locke, among many others, gave widely diverging answers to the question. The ancient skeptical texts were among the intellectual resources mustered to come to terms with these transformations.2 Arguments drawn from the ancient skeptics, particularly those having to do with the problem of the criterion—that is, determining which criterion is the correct one to resolve a disagreement and to judge what is true—were used by both sides in the Reformation dispute, and they also shaped the development of epistemology in early modern philosophy.3 More broadly, a skeptical outlook became a prominent thread in European culture, visible not only in the essays of Montaigne and the philosophical writings of Descartes but also, for example, in the plays of Shakespeare and the fiction of Cervantes.4 Modern skepticism is often thought to differ from ancient skepticism in a number of ways. Some scholars have argued that modern skepticism targets

274

SKEPTICISM

knowledge, while the ancients directed their arguments against belief. This picture is perhaps best exemplified in Bernard Williams’s characterization of Descartes’s methodological use of doubt as a crucial first step in a project of “Pure Enquiry,” intended to culminate in “a systematic vindication of knowledge” (1978: 20).5 Before beginning that project, Descartes adopts a “provisional moral code,” so that he will not be indecisive in his actions while his judgments are in doubt.6 He then advances skeptical arguments, “not copying the sceptics, who doubt only for the sake of doubting and pretend to be always undecided,” but only “to reach certainty” (CSM I 125; AT VI 29).7 Because these skeptical considerations are being raised only when they will not threaten the ordinary course of life, and because Descartes thinks he has a decisive response to them, the doubts he is willing to entertain can become as radical as he likes.8 What had been a way of life in the ancient world was now merely an intellectual problem to be solved. Something like this attitude, though in a more pessimistic form, is also visible in some of Hume’s remarks about skepticism. In his famous characterization of Berkeley’s arguments as skeptical, he says that this can be seen from the fact “that they admit of no answer and produce no conviction. Their only effect is to cause that momentary amazement and irresolution and confusion, which is the result of skepticism” (Hume EHU XII 122 n. 1). So, far from having any relevance to our behavior, Hume instead holds that “the great subverter of Pyrrhonism or the excessive principles of scepticism is action, and employment, and the occupations of common life” (EHU XII 126). To rid himself of his “philosophical melancholy and delirium,” he says, I dine, I play a game of back-gammon, I converse, and am merry with my friends; and when after three or four hour’s amusement, I wou’d return to these speculations, they appear so cold, and strain’d, and ridiculous, that I cannot find in my heart to enter into them any farther. (T 1.4.7 9) Although there is an element of truth in this picture, it leaves out much of what is most interesting in modern skepticism. It overlooks the way in which Descartes is concerned not only to build a body of certain knowledge but also to reform the minds of those who follow his method.9 Descartes would not have recognized a clear distinction between the theoretical and the practical, as he thought the experience of certainty itself would have a profoundly transformative effect upon those who follow his course of meditation. The evil demon hypothesis is designed to position his readers precisely so that the first-hand experience of certainty will have the greatest impact. For this reason, the meditator doesn’t simply note the possibility that he is being deceived; rather, he “will suppose” or “pretend” that this is actually happening, so that “the weight of preconceived opinion is counterbalanced” (CSM II 15; AT VII 22). This picture also ignores Hume’s efforts to articulate a way of proceeding in philosophy despite his skeptical worries. They are not abandoned, as idle and practically irrelevant; rather, he says, “A true sceptic will be diffident of his philosophical doubts, as well as of his philosophical conviction” (T 1.4.7 14). We would do well, he thinks, to adopt “a more mitigated scepticism or academical philosophy,” which brings with

BARON REED

275

it “a degree of doubt, and caution, and modesty, which, in all kinds of scrutiny and decision, ought for ever to accompany a just reasoner” (EHU XII 129). Skepticism, understood in this way, is not subverted by “the occupations of common life” but rather ought to be inextricably bound up with them. And, finally, this picture misses the wonderful variety of skeptical arguments and perspectives found in other modern philosophers. Although many of them were deeply influenced by the Academics and the Pyrrhonists, there turned out to be no single way of being a modern skeptic. Modern skepticism did not comprise a way of life as Pyrrhonism did; there was no modern Sextus, laying out a common goal and a shared sense of what the implications of the skeptical arguments might be.10 What we have instead is an endlessly fascinating, many-sided dispute by philosophers who were intrigued, worried, and sometimes delighted by human cognitive limitations. This part of the book, then, reflects the full diversity of purpose and perspective in modern skepticism, including essays on both famous and less well-known philosophers of the modern era. If ancient and modern skepticism cannot be distinguished from each other in virtue of their scope or their practical relevance, perhaps the best way to understand their differences is to look at the changing circumstances in which modern skepticism developed. We have already seen two vastly important transformations—the move toward a fully globalized world and the Reformation—but it is also worth noting another broad difference from the ancient world. Skepticism changed in the modern period, in large part, because dogmatism changed. With the rise of the major monotheistic religions, different dogmatic worldviews came to be incompatible rivals with each other. Within Christianity, in particular, salvation was thought to depend on having the correct theological beliefs. This had enormous implications not only for the individual believer but also for the shape of society at large. The consequences of dying outside the faith were terrible enough, Augustine thought, to motivate the use of coercion in matters of religion, which could be justified by Jesus’s use of the parable of the banquet, in which the master of a house tells his servant, “Go out into the highways and hedges and compel them to come in that my house may be filled” (Luke 14:23). Bayle’s Philosophical Commentary on Augustine’s view is the most direct attempt to push back against this sort of aggressively intolerant dogmatism.11 Bayle also used skeptical arguments to reconsider, in broader terms, the relation between religion and morality. Where we should be able to expect perfection in the moral order, given the nature of God, we find instead depravity and suffering. And where we should be able to expect virtue in the actions of the faithful, and vice in the behavior of the faithless, we instead find virtuous atheists and vicious Christians. Bayle concludes that “it is a mistake to believe that the moral practice of a religion corresponds to the doctrines of its confession of faith.”12 Skeptical arguments were also brought to bear on religion through a consideration of “superstition,” usually in the guise of the ancient pagan religions. One of the chief difficulties in grasping the nature of modern skepticism is that much of this work is intentionally ambiguous. Philosophers, with varying degrees of sincerity, articulated criticism of the irrational nature of paganism and “idolatry,” before remarking that this sort of criticism of course did not apply to “the true religion” (Bayle

276

SKEPTICISM

1965: 401). Where skeptical arguments do make contact with Christianity, Bayle says that “one learns of the excellence of faith” and “of the necessity of mistrusting reason and of having recourse to grace” (1965: 435). This apparent move toward fideism can be found in other early modern thinkers as well, including François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Pierre-Daniel Huet, and Johann Georg Hamann.13 Scholars are divided on how to understand Bayle’s attitude toward religion, with some taking the fideist remarks at face value and others arguing that those are intended to deflect unwelcome attention from “libertines” and freethinkers.14 Contemporaries of the early modern skeptics tended to view their fideism with suspicion; as one of them remarked, “That Method of attacking, when one seems to defend, is not new.”15 As the grip of orthodoxy relaxed later in the modern period, the need for a fideistic shield began to lessen.16 Hume’s criticisms of superstition, for example, are less ambiguous than Bayle’s, though even Hume couches some of his arguments in the form of an imagined dialogue set in ancient Athens.17 At the beginning of the early modern period, orthodoxy in religion was intimately bound up with orthodoxy in philosophy.18 Skeptical arguments proved to be a useful tool for undermining the latter as well as the former. Both Gassendi and Descartes used skepticism as a way of circumventing the well-entrenched Aristotelian Scholasticism, though Gassendi had a greater sympathy for skepticism in its own right.19 The usual Scholastic practice was to recount what had been said by earlier philosophers on a particular question before presenting one’s own view. Raising skeptical concerns from the outset allowed Descartes to avoid being needlessly involved in a thousand controversial matters before getting to a fundamentally new way of doing philosophy. For this reason, he begins the Meditations by attacking the Scholastics’ empiricist assumption that “whatever I have up till now accepted as most true I have acquired either from the senses or through the senses” (CSM II 12; AT VII 18). In doing so, he was able to set aside the entire Scholastic tradition while also posing an epistemological challenge for any potential rival view: if only the Cartesian theory can overcome skepticism, then Cartesianism must be the best of all philosophies. Other philosophers, of course, did not think that Descartes was ultimately successful in meeting this challenge. Gassendi, Huet, Foucher, and Bayle all used skeptical arguments to attack various aspects of Cartesianism.20 Skeptical considerations played a crucial role in modern philosophy, not only negatively by shaping criticism of Scholasticism, but also positively through the development of a new account of perception. Reflection on the Ten Modes of Pyrrhonism convinced many modern philosophers that material objects were not really as they seemed to our senses. Sensible qualities like colors and odors were thought to be mental items that represented objects without resembling them, while other qualities we could perceive, like motion and spatial extension, existed just as they appeared to us. This view, espoused by Galileo, Descartes, Boyle, Locke, and others, proved to be unstable. As Bayle noted, “If the objects of our senses appear colored, hot, cold, odoriferous, and yet they are not so, why can they not appear extended and shaped, in rest and in motion, though they are not so?”21 In this way, the modern account of perception, which Reid called the “common theory of ideas,”22 gave rise both to a physics that fruitfully narrowed its focus to the qualities

BARON REED

277

that most easily permit mathematical description and to the philosophical problem of skepticism about the external world. Berkeley and Reid tried to solve that problem by denying, in different ways, that perception is deceptive; where Berkeley rejected the distinction between our ideas and the objects they are purportedly of, Reid argued that we should abandon the theory of ideas altogether and take ourselves to have a direct awareness of mind-independent objects.23 Kant, by contrast, was willing to grant that our perceptions may not give us an unproblematic access to the nature of mind-independent objects as they are in themselves, but he also argued that our awareness of ourselves as determined in time is possible only if we are aware of something relatively permanent in our perceptual experiences, which can serve as a frame of reference for the temporal order of those experiences.24 Skepticism had a significant impact, not only on the work of philosophers who tried to refute it, but also on the development of some of the major philosophical systems of the modern period. Spinoza followed Descartes in placing God at the center of his epistemology, though not by invoking a divine guarantee for our cognitive faculties; rather, the certainty of which we are capable arises only in the relatively rare cases when our ideas can be properly deduced from God’s essence.25 Hume’s efforts at systematic philosophy turn toward naturalism as the only possible way of moving forward, in light of the unanswered skeptical challenges he has raised. Both aspects of his philosophy, the skepticism and the naturalism, manifest his inheritance from ancient skepticism.26 Both Hegel and Nietzsche also took skeptical modes of thought to be essential to philosophical theorizing; where Hegel thought skepticism was itself an integral part of rationality, it is for Nietzsche bound up with the “revaluation of all values.”27 Skepticism continued to be of central importance in the twentieth century. Bertrand Russell, early in his career, attempted to solve the problem of the external world by showing how everyday objects, like trees and books, are logically constructed out of sense-data. Our knowledge of the former is supposed to be secured in virtue of our unproblematic knowledge of the latter.28 Although G. E. Moore also incorporated sense-data into his epistemology, he did not regard that as necessary for a refutation of skepticism. His famous “proof of an external world” presented the skeptical challenge in the starkest possible terms: either you reject the possibility of any sort of knowledge in light of your inability to tell whether you are dreaming, or you acknowledge that you know you have hands and know you are awake. No philosophical argument sufficient to establish the skeptical conclusion could be more certain than your knowledge that you have hands, Moore contends, and so we can confidently reject skepticism.29 Ludwig Wittgenstein thinks that Moore’s way of dealing with the skeptic is implausible because it is unnatural— Moore’s proof fails because he has taken the skeptic’s doubts seriously. But doubts can be raised only in the scope of a “language-game,” where some things are taken for granted. If doubting one thing means accepting another, though, it is impossible for the sort of general skepticism Descartes raises to get a grip on us.30 As should be clear from the rich variety of ways in which it has been defended and rejected, used as an instrument and embraced as an end, skepticism is one of the most important facets of intellectual life in the modern period. Its influence

278

SKEPTICISM

can be traced in both the rise of secularism and in some of the religious reactions to rationalist critique. Skeptical arguments have played a role in the development of modern science, and skepticism has profoundly shaped every branch of philosophy, from epistemology and metaphysics to ethics and political philosophy. Encompassing everything from Descartes’s evil demon to Hume’s “just reasoner,” modern skepticism provides an indispensable framework for understanding the past several centuries and the world we inhabit today.

NOTES 1. See “Of Cannibals” in Montaigne (1958); for Bayle’s view of classical Chinese philosophy, see Israel (2006: 644 and 2007: 7–8). See also Hazard (2013: ch. 1). 2. Cicero’s Academica was published with a commentary by Omer Talon in 1547; see Schmitt (1972: 81). Sextus Empiricus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism were printed by Henri Estienne in 1562; see Popkin (2003: 18). Popkin (2003: 6) also notes that Savonarola encouraged the production of a Latin edition of Sextus’s works in 1494 while in the midst of his disagreement with the Pope, though Sextus did not become widely known until Estienne’s publication of the Outlines. More generally, Popkin (1960, 1979, 1980, and 2003) argues that the revival of skepticism in the early modern period is largely due to the rediscovery of Sextus. See Maia Neto’s chapter on Popkin in this book for an account of the profound impact his work has had on the study of modern skepticism. See Maia Neto (1997 and 2014) and Michael Hickson’s chapter on Huet and Foucher in this book for an argument that the influence of Academic skepticism was greater than has been generally recognized. 3. On the uses of the criterion argument in religious disagreement, see Popkin (2003), ch. 1, 4. Descartes says, in the Second Replies, that he has “reheated this cabbage,” namely, the arguments of the ancient skeptics; see Descartes (CSM II 94). See Fine (2000) on the relation between Descartes’s presentation of skepticism and ancient skepticism. Arnauld famously raised the problem of the “Cartesian Circle,” which is an instance of the problem of the criterion, in the Fourth Objections to Descartes’s Meditations (CSM II 150; AT VII 214). 4. See, e.g., Bell (2002) and Rescher (1993) on Shakespeare and Cervantes, respectively. 5. Cf. Williams (1986: 118). See also Gaukroger (1995: 310–321): “Epistemological doubt questions whether one’s beliefs amount to knowledge, whereas doxastic doubt questions whether one is entitled to hold the beliefs one has” (311). Gaukroger takes doxastic doubt to be a distinctive feature of Pyrrhonism (311), while epistemological doubt is “something new” in Montaigne’s work (315) and characteristic of Cartesian skepticism. See Fine (2000: 195–196) for a survey of others who draw this sort of contrast between ancient and modern skepticism and for a critical response to it. 6. Discourse on the Method, Part Three (CSM I 122; AT VI 22). In the Meditations, he begins the project only after he has arranged for himself “a clear stretch of free time” (CSM II 12; AT VII 18). 7. Diderot expresses a similar thought in his article on the “Pyrrhonic or Skeptical Philosophy” in the Encyclopédie: “Doubt is the first step toward science or truth” (1965: 294). (This passage was censored in the original version.)

BARON REED

279

8. Descartes describes the doubts as “exaggerated” (CSM II 61; AT VII 89), “very slight and, so to speak, metaphysical” (CSM II 25; AT VII 36), and ones that “no sane person” would ever have (CSM II 11; AT VII 16). 9. See Rorty (1986) and Hatfield (1986), who both emphasize the “meditational” aspect of Descartes’s work. 10. It is important to keep in mind that ancient skepticism, taken as a whole, was not a single way of life. The revival of Pyrrhonism occurred precisely because there was widespread disagreement in the Academy over the legacy of Carneades and the best way of conducting inquiry; see Brittain’s introduction to Cicero (2006). One of the unstated aims of Sextus’s Outlines may well be to create a consensus about skepticism that did not already exist. 11. See Bayle (2005), Robinson (1931: 72), and John Christian Laursen’s chapter on Bayle in this book. For the intersection of skepticism and political thought in the early modern period more generally, see Laursen and Paganini (2015). 12. “Jupiter,” remark D, in the Historical and Critical Dictionary (1965: 109). Cf. “David,” where Bayle recounts the morally questionable exploits of David, “a man after God’s own heart” (1965: 45), and asks, “is it not better to consider the interests of morality rather than the glory of a particular person?” (1965: 63). For Bayle’s reflections on the problem of evil, see “Manichaeans,” “Paulicians,” and the “Third Clarification” in the Dictionary (1965: 144–153, 166–193, and 399–408). For Bayle’s consideration of atheism, see his Various Thoughts on the Occasion of a Comet (2000) and the “First Clarification” in the Dictionary (1965: 399–408). See also Laursen’s article on Bayle in this book. As in other ways, Hume pushed to a further extreme an attitude found in Bayle—in this case, the extrication of morality from religion; as Don Garrett (2015: 309) notes, Hume’s “account of the basis of morality makes no substantive appeal to religion.” An earlier manifestation of this impulse can be found in the work of Pierre Charron; see Gianni Paganini’s chapter on Charron in Part II of this book. 13. See the chapters in this book by Sylvia Giocanti on La Mothe Le Vayer, by Hickson on Huet, and by Gwen Griffith-Dickson on Hamann. 14. See van der Lugt (2016: 37) for an overview of this dispute in scholarship on Bayle. 15. Durand (1730: 19). Durand says that it was employed by Carneades and Cicero, among others, and he hints that Bayle may also be a practitioner of the method. Cf. Allen (1964: 11), who says that, according to Voetius—the orthodox Dutch theologian who pushed the University of Utrecht to condemn Descartes’s work— “One of their cleverer tricks is to attack an atheist, fully expound his Lucianic remarks, and then, after a tepid confrontation, depart, ‘leaving certain subtle curiosities in the midst of things.’” 16. It should be noted, however, that the skeptical undermining of reason in defense of religion continued to find adherents in later thinkers, including Hamann and Kierkegaard. See Griffith-Dickson’s chapter on Hamann in this book and “Hume and Kierkegaard” in Popkin (1980: 227–236). Popkin (1980: 236) says that Kierkegaard’s religious outlook was significantly influenced by Hume via Hamann’s reflections on Hume’s chapter on Miracles (EHU X). 17. EHU XI 104110. According to Garrett, “Hume saw his age as a battleground between what he called ‘philosophy,’ on the one hand, and ‘superstition,’ on the other” (1997: 7).

280

SKEPTICISM

18. Stillman Drake (2001) argues that Galileo’s troubles with the Inquisition were caused by conflict with Aristotelian philosophers, rather than with theologians. See also Voetius’s dispute with Descartes over the challenge Cartesianism poses to “the traditional philosophy”; Descartes recounts this conflict in the “Letter to Father Dinet” (CSM II 393–397; AT VII 596–603). 19. See especially Gassendi’s first published work, Exercitationes paradoxicae adversus Aristoteleos, Maia Neto (2014: ch. 3), and Antonia LoLordo’s chapter on Gassendi in this book. On Descartes, see Rorty (1986), Hatfield (1986), and David Cunning’s chapter in this book. 20. See Watson (1987), LoLordo’s chapter in this book on Gassendi, Hickson’s chapter on Huet and Foucher, and Laursen’s chapter on Bayle. See also Bayle’s entry on “Pyrrho,” remark B, in the Dictionary (1965: 194–199). 21. See “Pyrrho,” remark B, in the Dictionary (1965: 197). Bayle attributes the argument to Foucher (fn. 11). See also Watson (1987) and Reed (2015). 22. See Reid’s Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man II.14 (1872: 298). 23. See Margaret Atherton’s chapter on Berkeley and René Van Woudenberg’s chapter on Reid, both in this book. See also Van Cleve (2015: ch. 3) on Reid’s rejection of the “way of ideas.” 24. See Georges Dicker’s chapter on Kant in this book. 25. See Alison Peterman’s chapter on Spinoza in this book. 26. See Donald Baxter’s chapter in this book for an account of how Hume adapted the sort of passive acquiescence found in Pyrrhonism to his own system. See Garrett (2015: ch. 7) for an interpretation of Hume as embodying a mitigated form of skepticism. This mitigated skepticism, which Hume calls “academical” (EHU XII 129), may derive to some extent from the ancient Academics, given his use of probability as a guide to belief. See Harald Thorsrud’s chapter on Carneades in Part I of this book for an account of how probability may have functioned in a mitigated Academic skepticism. 27. See Dietmar Heidemann’s chapter on Hegel and Andreas Urs Sommer’s chapter on Nietzsche, both in this book. See also Berry (2011) on Nietzsche’s relation to Pyrrhonism. 28. See Peter Graham’s chapter on Russell in this book. 29. See Annalisa Coliva’s chapter on Moore in this book. See also Reed (2015: 74–75). 30. See Michael Williams’s chapter on Wittgenstein in this book. See Sluga (2004) for an interpretation that takes Wittgenstein to be sympathetic in some ways to Pyrrhonism.

REFERENCES Allen, Don Cameron. 1964. Doubt’s Boundless Sea: Skepticism and Faith in the Renaissance. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press. Bayle, Pierre. 1965. Historical and Critical Dictionary, translated by R. Popkin. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill. Bayle, Pierre. 2000. Various Thoughts on the Occasion of a Comet, edited by R. Bartlett. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

BARON REED

281

Bayle, Pierre. 2005. A Philosophical Commentary on the Words “Compel Them to Come In, That My House May Be Full,” edited by J. Kilcullen and C. Kukathas. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund. Bell, Millicent. 2002. Shakespeare’s Tragic Skepticism. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Berry, Jessica. 2011. Nietzsche and the Ancient Skeptical Tradition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cicero. 2006. On Academic Scepticism, translated by C. Brittain. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Descartes, René. 1984. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. II, translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Descartes, René. 1985. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. I, translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Diderot, Denis, et al. 1965. Encyclopedia, translated by N. Hoyt and T. Cassirer. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill. Drake, Stillman. 2001. Galileo: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Durand, Denis. 1730. The Life of Lucilio Vanini, Burnt for Atheism at Thoulouse. London: W. Meadows. Fine, Gail. 2000. “Descartes and Ancient Skepticism: Reheated Cabbage?” Philosophical Review 109: 195–234. Garrett, Don. 1997. Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Garrett, Don. 2015. Hume. London: Routledge. Gaukroger, Stephen. 1995. Descartes: An Intellectual Biography. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hatfield, Gary. 1986. “The Senses and the Fleshless Eye: The Meditations as Cognitive Exercises.” In A. Rorty (ed.), Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, 45–79. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Hazard, Paul. 2013. The Crisis of the European Mind, translated by J. May. New York: New York Review Books. Hume, David. 1975. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hume, David. 2000. A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by D. Norton and M. Norton. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Israel, Jonathan. 2006. Enlightenment Contested. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Israel, Jonathan. 2007. “Admiration of China and Classical Chinese Thought in the Radical Enlightenment (1685-1740),” Taiwan Journal of East Asian Studies 4: 1–25. Laursen, John Christian, and Gianni Paganini (eds.). 2015. Skepticism and Political Thought in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Maia Neto, José R. 1997. “Academic Skepticism in Early Modern Philosophy,” Journal of the History of Ideas 58: 199–220. Maia Neto, José R. 2014. Academic Skepticism in Seventeenth-Century French Philosophy: The Charronian Legacy 1601–1662. Dordrecht: Springer. Montaigne, Michel de. 1958. The Complete Essays of Montaigne, translated by D. Frame. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

282

SKEPTICISM

Popkin, Richard. 1960. The History of Scepticism: From Erasmus to Descartes. Assen: Van Gorcum. Popkin, Richard. 1979. The History of Scepticism: From Erasmus to Spinoza. Berkeley: University of California Press. Popkin, Richard. 1980. The High Road to Pyrrhonism. Papers collected by R. Watson and J. Force. San Diego: Austin Hill. Popkin, Richard. 2003. The History of Scepticism: From Savonarola to Bayle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Reed, Baron. 2015. “Skepticism and Perception.” In M. Matthen (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception, 66–80. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Reid, Thomas. 1872. The Works of Thomas Reid, edited by W. Hamilton. Edinburgh: Maclachlan and Stewart. Rescher, Nicholas. 1993. “Quixotic Scepticism,” American Philosophical Quarterly 30: 183–184. Robinson, Howard. 1931. Bayle the Sceptic. New York, NY: Columbia University Press. Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg. 1986. “The Structure of Descartes’ Meditations.” In A. Rorty (ed.), Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, 1–20. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Schmitt, Charles. 1972. Cicero Scepticus. The Hague: Nijhoff. Sluga, Hans. 2004. “Wittgenstein and Pyrrhonism.” In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Pyrrhonian Skepticism, 99–117. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Van Cleve, James. 2015. Problems from Reid. Oxford: Oxford University Press. van der Lugt, Mara. 2016. Bayle, Jurieu, and the Dictionnaire Historique et Critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Watson, Richard. 1987. The Breakdown of Cartesian Metaphysics. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press International. Williams, Bernard. 1978. Descartes: The Project of Pure Understanding. London: Routledge. Williams, Michael. 1986. “Descartes and the Metaphysics of Doubt.” In A. Rorty (ed.), Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, 117–139. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

CHAPTER TWENTY

François de La Mothe Le Vayer1 SYLVIA GIOCANTI

1 INTRODUCTION François de La Mothe Le Vayer (1588–1672) was no doubt a skeptic, since he explicitly claimed to belong to the skeptical philosophical tradition (both Pyrrhonian and Academic) and made frequent use of the adjective “skeptical” in the title of many of his opuscules.2 It is nonetheless legitimate to ask: in what respect was he skeptical? Indeed, the reception of his oeuvre as “libertine”3 raises doubts about the sincerity of his participation in the skeptical philosophy, and particularly about the sincerity of his adherence to fideism, thanks to which skepticism could, despite the uncertainty of reason, prepare for the Christian faith. On the hypothesis that skeptical argumentation is nothing but a rhetorical tool designed to dissimulate subversive theses, skepticism would be only a cover for his libertinage. But in either case (fideism or libertinage), the skepticism of La Mothe Le Vayer would not exist in itself and by itself, but merely as a means to other ends. Thus, to wonder in what respect La Mothe Le Vayer may be skeptical is at the same time to reflect upon the possibility of the autonomy of skepticism within philosophy, as a way of thought that could have value in itself, despite the fact that it needs to feed on dogmatism either to combat it or to serve it.4 In other words, one can recognize with Pascal that “nothing fortifies Pyrrhonism more than that there are some who are not Pyrrhonian,” without thereby subscribing to what he adds immediately afterward: “If all were so, they would be wrong” (Pascal 1962: frag. 33). Reading La Mothe Le Vayer invites us to pose anew the question of the value of skepticism, independently of its polemical anchorage. In Section 2, I will show that reason, which La Mothe Le Vayer reduces to opinion (δόξα), is sanitized in its intellectual activity by the practice of paradox, substituted for the practice of equipollence (ἰσοσθένεια). In Section 3, I will argue that this critical activity introduces a novel relationship between skepticism and orthodoxy, which explains why La Mothe Le Vayer may be considered both a libertine and a skeptic, to the extent that his discourse is used to enjoy the transgression of norms.

284

SKEPTICISM

In Section 4, I will claim that the artifices employed to transgress the norms are not however offered as recipes that work mechanically, but rather as expedients that are skeptically utilized in order to calm the soul.

2  THE SKEPTICAL DISORDER OF REASONS La Mothe Le Vayer seems to run counter to the idea peculiar to the Enlightenment that skepticism is intellectually untenable, that doubt can only be provisional and is to be surpassed by knowledge, since he builds up his skepticism on the basis of the insurmountable irresolution of reason. Even if it turned out that La Mothe Le Vayer utilized the skeptical argumentation to dissimulate the audacity of his thought, it would still be clear that his skepticism cannot be entirely feigned, since his philosophy rests upon one of the characteristics of modern skepticism, namely: the observation of the irregularity of the way in which each person reasons (La Mothe Le Vayer [LMLV] 1970e: 744), which is nothing but the effect of the irregularity of reason itself. La Mothe Le Vayer radicalizes Montaigne’s view of the malleability of reason (Essays II, 12, 565),5 for he claims that, as a “shameless courtesan who, hidden under the mask of appearance, shamefully abandons herself to every sort of candidate” (LMLV 1970g: 262), reason is incapable of providing rules. To make a skeptical use of reason consists in using it in accordance with what it is, namely, “a multipurpose toy” (un jouet à toutes mains) (1970g: 262). One must bang reasons together as in a game of balls, not in order to ridicule reason in its dogmatic use—as is the case in Montaigne—but in order to exhibit its inherent uncertainty. Within the context of this “Saturnalia of opinion,” in which everyone amuses himself by changing his mind, the disorder of reasons is a real spectacle, or even a “rhapsody.”6 In this game, the discursive discontinuity is irreducible, since the game is not unified, as in Montaigne, by the project of portraying oneself as gradually constructing the subject’s identity by means of a public reflection on oneself. The author’s position cannot be determined—and in this it is clearly skeptical—for the aim of the text cannot be related to the coherence of his thought, since his ideas remain uncertain. Thus, one would be tempted to say regarding La Mothe Le Vayer what Bayle reports about Carneades in the article of his Dictionary devoted to the latter: [Clitomachus] was never able to discover what were the opinions [sentiments] that Carneades approved of. That was not the result of the obscurity of his expressions, but of the skepticism of this philosopher. He did not find anything certain, he successively held and refuted the same doctrines: that is why one could not discern whether he approved of any of them. (Remark O) In a similar way, La Mothe Le Vayer’s skeptical argumentation does not let the author’s point of view show through, because it is fleetingly discernible, blurred by other points of view adopted successively, before a final retraction. Does his skepticism really make him incapable of making up his mind one way or the other? Or does he avoid explicitly saying what he thinks, out of prudence, like the libertines of his time (on whom see Cavaillé 2002 and Gouverneur 2005)?

FRANÇOIS DE LA MOTHE LE VAYER

285

La Mothe Le Vayer may well employ skepticism to protect himself from the accusation of impiety or atheism, thus eluding religious persecution. He will nonetheless remain someone who is both committed to skepticism and a strong spirit (esprit fort), insofar as his disavowing what he writes is coherently based on the discredit of reason, and a fortiori on the discredit of the rationalism that reigns in Cartesianism. Indeed, to accuse reason of poisoning the mind at the very moment in which Cartesianism prevails does not have the same significance as in Montaigne’s time (see Giocanti 2013). Being skeptical for La Mothe Le Vayer is to take the opposing view to Descartes’s most famous claims expressing the confidence one must accord to reason, as the guarantee of the progressive acquisition of all the perfections that man is capable of. It is against the Cartesians that La Mothe Le Vayer writes his Little Skeptical Treatise on This Common Way of Speaking “To Lack Common Sense” (LMLV 1970g), where he declares that reason (or common sense) is not the thing best shared in the world, that reason is not a source of order and the construction of knowledge, but of the dissolution and corruption of the mind in fantasy and madness. In order to find a remedy for rational obstinacy, this plague of the soul that keeps reappearing in reaction to the spontaneous disorder of reasons, the skeptic suggests ceaselessly counterbalancing the claims of reason by means of the practice of equipollence, henceforth conceived of as the practice of paradox that purifies the mind. This means that so-called reason, which acts as good sense or common sense, is on the side of δόξα, and that for the skeptic it is therefore necessary to apply oneself to struggling against it, systematically taking the opposing view to what is affirmed. The claim of independence and the quest for verisimilitude peculiar to the skeptical Academy are thus reused in the context of a combat, deemed equally Herculean, both against the overly strong adherence to dominant opinions and against the fervor of beliefs.7

3  THE ACCOMPLISHMENT OF SKEPTICISM IN LIBERTINAGE By the adoption of this rebellious attitude toward the common way, and hence toward the authority of tradition—of everything that is handed down by moral, intellectual, and religious customs—the skepticism of La Mothe Le Vayer clearly differs from that of Montaigne. It is by such an attitude that his skepticism leads La Mothe Le Vayer to libertinage, in a challenge to orthodoxy that constitutes skepticism’s natural development.

3a  The Libertine Practice of Paradox Substituted for the Skeptical Practice of Equipollence The affirmation of reason’s helplessness to hold on firmly and definitively to wellfounded certainties goes hand in hand with the affirmation of its power to challenge unfounded certainties. It is this power that La Mothe Le Vayer deploys when calling into question the attitude of respect toward laws and customs and the authority of tradition in general.

286

SKEPTICISM

Such is the main difference between Montaigne and La Mothe Le Vayer in their redeployment of the Tenth Mode of Aenesidemus as preserved by Sextus Empiricus, and particularly in the practical consequences that they both draw from it. Montaigne, favorable to anything that can contribute to preventing reason from ranting, concludes his Essays by stressing the value of the aptitude for falling in with the common model.8 It is never a matter of struggling against the obstinacy of those who strive to remain in the defeated paths of the common way, but rather of using the model of animality and simplicity to correct the excesses of speculative reason. By contrast, for La Mothe Le Vayer the skeptic has the distinctive feature of taking account of opinions other than those handed down by δόξα, that is to say, by the religious and moral orthodoxy. Qua strong spirit who is against the vulgarity of common sense, the skeptic opposes to it a contrary opinion, not in order to readjust such vulgarity with the aim of disciplining himself, but in order to grant full license to his thought, making it take, like the goat, “the isolated paths.” The practice of paradox, substituted for the practice of equipollence, does not therefore have the function of neutralizing opinions via the equipollence of arguments, as is the case in ancient Pyrrhonism or in Montaigne’s skepticism. Its function is rather to promote the reverse of ordinary opinion, for “the healthiest opinions are perhaps—supposing that we possess some health in this respect—the most paradoxical” (LMLV 1970g: 271).9 Thus, whenever La Mothe Le Vayer compares pagan rites (which in his time have become extraordinary and illicit) with Christian rites (customary and licit), he does so in favor of the former, if only because the latter are considered without regard for their differences in a way that makes them lose their exclusiveness. Because of this, it is not only completely questionable, as Maia Neto (1995: 126) has remarked, to claim that La Mothe Le Vayer is the representative of a Christian Pyrrhonism, but it is also possible to advance the view that he covertly devotes himself to contesting the validity of Christianity, despite the fideist remarks that, as Popkin (1995: 137) has noted, permeate all of his works.

3b  A Singular Conjunction between Skeptical Fideism and Libertine Disrespect of the Common Way Such claims of obedience to Christianity do not actually have any credibility. But the reason is not only that, having abandoned every rational criterion, it is not possible to place Christianity beyond the scope of doubt. This argument is too weak to call into question the sincerity of La Mothe Le Vayer’s skepticism, for, as Popkin (1995: 142–143) has argued, given that one could raise the suspicion of hypocrisy against any skeptic whatsoever, there is no more reason for suspecting La Mothe Le Vayer than any other skeptic. However, as Paganini (2008: 93–94, 99) has rightly remarked, in the second part of On the Virtue of Pagans devoted to “Pyrrho and the skeptical sect” (1970f: 194–196), La Mothe Le Vayer himself denies any faith implicit in Pyrrho and condemns him to damnation on the grounds that, unlike the other pagan philosophers, this leader of the skeptical school has placed doubt at the heart of his philosophy. On this specific point, La Mothe Le Vayer adopts the same position as Bayle, according to which “faith does not accept the Academic spirit: it wants that

FRANÇOIS DE LA MOTHE LE VAYER

287

we deny, or that we affirm” (Historical and Critical Dictionary, art. “Chrysippus,” remark G).10 Religion requires an invariability that is impossible to attain without grace and that is incompatible with doubt. Now, in La Mothe Le Vayer’s skeptical anthropology, doubt is inevitable on account of the human inconstancy that is the spontaneous manifestation of the unbelief of the mind (see especially LMLV 1970d: 605). One should then conclude that skepticism leads to irreligion, and not, as Popkin believes, that it constitutes an excellent preparation for Christianity. Admittedly, La Mothe Le Vayer explicitly makes this latter claim when he presents his skepticism throughout his work. But one may wonder—taking as an indication of an attitude of dissimulation the abovementioned text on Pyrrho—if the link he establishes between skepticism and preparation for faith is sincere, if the skeptical position itself is not merely a posture that makes it possible to attack religion in an indirect way. La Mothe Le Vayer would then be neither skeptical nor Christian, but libertine. But one will retort that La Mothe Le Vayer strives to make an exception for his own form of skepticism insofar as it is “circumcised,” that is, purified because Christianized. The question is then once again: what is the credibility of this pious exception? There is a criterion that makes it possible to resolve the dispute about the credibility of La Mothe Le Vayer’s fideism in comparison with that of Montaigne, and a fortiori that of Pascal: whether one finds in him an attitude of respect toward the authority of tradition, an injunction to obey the laws and customs of one’s country. The skepticism of La Mothe Le Vayer is, in a manner quite singular in the skeptical tradition, inseparable from a monolithic criticism of customs, which are denounced as tyrannical.11 It is from this criticism that results a disrespectful treatment of religious authority. For instance, in the dialogue On Divinity, La Mothe Le Vayer defends, in the tradition of Bacon, atheism’s superiority over superstition. And this is not in favor of the Christian religion, since he adds on the same page (LMLV 1988e: 339), following Charron, that “all religions are foreign and horrible to common sense,”12 which seems to warrant the equation of all religions with the phenomenon of superstition (see Paganini 2008: 81). In this text, Christianity does not therefore seem to be an exception nor to be susceptible, as orthodoxy requires, of being in agreement with common sense, which is nonetheless fundamental in the adherence to Christianity as a preamble to faith (Maia Neto 1995: 131–132). Certainly, the claims against religion are caught in the skeptical equipollence, which, as already noted, is transformed in La Mothe Le Vayer into the practice of paradox. The reason for such a transformation is to better display the other side of the orthodox position, with a subversive aim, since by valuing the reverse of the opinion one produces a disproportion between the orthodox theses (weakened because agreed) and the heterodox ones (whose critical impact is much more striking). La Mothe Le Vayer takes pleasure in the criticism of opinions received with reverence and systematically devalues the attitude of submission that is inseparable from devotion and piety. He praises in blasphemous terms what he calls “La Divine Sceptique,” that is, the divine skeptical philosophy, in that it leads, following the “decalogue” (i.e., the Ten Modes) of “Divine Sextus” (LMLV 1988c: 83), to the ecstatic rapture of the mind of the character of Télamon, suddenly converted to beatitude by means of doubt (LMLV 1988d: 301–302).

288

SKEPTICISM

What is at issue here is not a lack of differentiation between religions that are distinct (viz., the pagan and the Christian), but rather a competition between the Christian religion and skepticism in favor of the latter. For several times La Mothe Le Vayer cedes exclusively to the skeptical philosophy the merits and satisfactions normally provided by the Christian religion (see LMLV 1988b: 61–62).13 His skepticism, insofar as it accomplishes the desire to free oneself from the rules that are authoritative, becomes an enterprise of subversion of values, an enterprise that is incompatible not only with Christian apologetics (skeptical fideism), but with a sincere profession of faith, by which he tells us one must not be duped.14 But how could one be, since far from making a virtue of obedience to the laws and customs of his country, La Mothe Le Vayer lays down a challenge to the tyrannical authority of the latter, in the context of his skeptical escapades whose unpredictable and capricious character he defends?

3c  The Skeptical Subversion of Norms as a Condition of the Libertine’s Enjoyment Contrary to what Popkin (1995: 138) maintains, La Mothe Le Vayer is not an “insipid Montaigne.” Rather, he would be a “scandalous Montaigne,” who realizes the libertine (deviant) potentialities of skepticism, by means of an unprecedented redeployment of its content, out of reach from what he calls, in the same terms as Charron (1986: 261), “the universal contagion” or “spiritual contamination” of the crowd (LMLV 1988e: 303). Even if obedience to the Christian tradition may have a value for the herd, it is not convenient to respect it in one’s heart, but rather to contest its validity and to conform to it only to “keep up appearances,” the function of religion being “to offer a rational explanation of moral phenomena” (LMLV 1988e: 330–331). The flexibility required in La Mothe Le Vayer’s skepticism, qua ethical virtue that makes it possible to adapt to the diversity of phenomena (LMLV 1988f: 365), does not therefore have the same sense as in Montaigne, who praises the sociability of a “soul of diverse stages that knows both to tense up and to dismantle itself” (Essays III, 3, 821). The flexibility of the soul in La Mothe Le Vayer is conceived of in the context of “skeptical wisdom”—which is opposed to divine wisdom—and is defined as “wandering prudence” that “is proud of changing at any moment and of turning the sail according to the wind” (1970e: 735). To be flexible means, then, to gently accommodate oneself to all the customs introduced by mores (LMLV 1988d: 273), which also means to try one’s hand at all practices, including the most debauched, after having freed oneself from every scruple. It is not a matter, as in Montaigne, of accepting one’s natural irresolution and displaying a plasticity of both mind and body in the face of social constraints that require one to adapt oneself. It is rather a matter of freeing oneself from these constraints, of enjoying the transgression of the established order, and of spreading a perfume of scandal, initiating oneself without shame into those practices that are judged to be the most extravagant and the most shameful, on the pretext that one finds examples of them in nature (see LMLV 1988c and 1997).15

FRANÇOIS DE LA MOTHE LE VAYER

289

La Mothe Le Vayer relates then the enjoyment promised by the skeptical discourse to a diversification of mores that contravenes that which is licit. He thus extends doubt to cultural norms—not only to their intrinsic value but also to the respect that is due to them—whereas in Montaigne doubt bore only on the natural limits. By so doing, not only does he subvert social norms and incite the transgression of their prohibitions, but he also establishes the transgression of social conformism as a condition of personal flourishing. The game of reason—“shameless courtesan who, hidden under the mask of appearance, shamefully abandons herself to every sort of candidate”—in which La Mothe Le Vayer indulges proves then to be more audacious than that of the “crooked, lame and wiggling” (Essays II, 12, 565) reason of Montaigne (and this despite the image associated with sexual relations with cripples at Essays III, 11), to the extent that it accomplishes skepticism in libertinage. If it is always a matter of learning how to use reason according to itself, of acquiring “the self-sufficiency to know how to circumvent it,” as Montaigne said (Essays II, 12, 565), it is remarkable that the attitude of intellectual disobedience, related to a moral anti-conformism, supposes a sophisticated and even cunning use of reason. It is now necessary to clarify in what respect La Mothe Le Vayer’s skepticism, in its strictly discursive dimension, consists in according ethical and therapeutic virtues to a sophistical use of reason.

4  THE THERAPEUTIC VIRTUES OF THE SKEPTICAL DISCOURSE Contrary to the point of view of apologists who take the sole aim of libertine discourse to be justifying a life of debauchery motivated by the passions alone, La Mothe Le Vayer’s skeptical point of view on mores shows the pleasure one finds in transgressing the proprieties within discourse above all else. This linguistic enjoyment rests upon a “poietic” (productive) conception of reason: reason is a protean faculty that molds its discourses in a hundred different ways, following its imaginative representations, as the potter models his work.16 Reason so conceived is not a faculty that naturally leads us to knowledge of the truth, but an instrument that has “more than one trick up its sleeve” as regards fantasizing and artifice, so as to “smoke out the mind.” And the first to be interested in this conjuring, in the moral domain, is the skeptic himself, who deploys his ingenuity to deceive himself (LMLV 1970c: 534). For him, to actualize the mind’s potentialities, following a penchant that leads us to lying, means to employ artifice (LMLV 1970i: 538). Like every man, the skeptic is a “philomyth” animal, that is, a lover of fables (LMLV 1970c: 539). In this respect, it should be noted that the Dialogues Made in Imitation of the Ancients are presented as fables (LMLV 1988a: 14). Unlike the other men, the skeptic dares prefer lying over truth (LMLV 1970b: 478–479) and allows himself to practice a fabulating art in the hope of experiencing pleasure or at least of overcoming anxiety. The human condition is, according to La Mothe Le Vayer, so calamitous that, without this potion of error and ignorance that nature makes us drink at birth, no

290

SKEPTICISM

one would resist the temptation to commit suicide (LMLV 1970b: 393, 409). But this observation of human misery, apparently very Augustinian, is not an invitation to search for the truth, without which we could not live at rest. For in La Mothe Le Vayer the restriction of the skeptical investigation to what is verisimilar has no other function than to guarantee the possibility of recanting. To abide by what is verisimilar does not mean to confine oneself to an adequate vision of what is true, but to adopt a point of view that would always make it possible to adopt another one that is more joyful (LMLV 1970g: 268). This is why, following an orientation diametrically opposed to that of Pascal, La Mothe Le Vayer authorizes us to lie to ourselves, trying to approach in the mode of mockery that which would afflict us if we looked at it close up. To laugh with Democritus at the miserable condition of man transfigures this condition in a way that may prove to be “salutary” for the mind’s health, for its rest. Thus, far from fighting lying and error, as did Montaigne (who values telling the truth as sincerity that authenticates his own discourse), La Mothe Le Vayer incites us to deceive ourselves and to develop the artifices that make it possible. Admittedly, Montaigne too makes use of diversion and of the powers of fantasizing of the mind (Essays III, 4), taking advantage of a deceptive reason that indistinctively tells the truth and lies (Essays II, 12, 565). But he does not go so far as to claim that reason must be employed to deceive ourselves insofar as it has more grace in lying than in telling the truth, as La Mothe Le Vayer (1970g: 262) maintains. In this respect, La Mothe Le Vayer’s skeptical ethics is not similar to the libertine naturalism of Vanini or Charron.17 Artifice is at the heart of the devices used with therapeutic aims, in order to cure the soul of the grief that often has no attributable cause, human life appearing as a chronic illness in the eyes of a mind that is compared to a “debauched stomach” (LMLV 1970c: 530). This is why it does not suffice, as in the Pyrrhonian tradition, to get rid of dogmatic opinions in order to, through the suspension of assent, recover from the quartan fever that accompanies melancholy and attain the state of undisturbedness (ἀταραξία). This purge of opinions that had such a beneficial effect on Henri Estienne, the translator of Sextus, would leave the desolate mind of someone like La Mothe Le Vayer without something to occupy itself. Such a purge would abandon him to the vacuity of other thoughts, which could turn out to be just as corrosive, since the mind is capable of turning honey into venom, of converting pleasure into sadness, under the influence of its representations. It is then the creative freedom of fantasy, productive of reasonings likened to ingenious fables, that becomes the only possible source of consolation in the context of the irrational (because imaginative) working of the mind. Because the notions of good and evil are psychological, that is to say, relative to the mind that examines them, this fantastical treatment of the emotions—within which one learns to content oneself with imaginary objects—seems more suitable than their rationalist treatment. Hence, the discourses apparently borrowed from the Stoic and Epicurean traditions are often less taken over by La Mothe Le Vayer than skeptically distorted. One can thus provide part of a reply to the question posed at the outset of this chapter: La Mothe Le Vayer’s skepticism enjoys a certain autonomy within

FRANÇOIS DE LA MOTHE LE VAYER

291

philosophy, if only because it claims to have come up with remedies capable of relieving the misfortunes of the human soul—specific remedies that draw on the inventive potentialities of the mind. In this regard, Paganini (2008: 77) is right in insisting on the “positive potentialities” of La Mothe Le Vayer’s skepticism. The development of the Tenth Mode as expounded in Sextus represents the opportunity to divert the mind from its grief, to extract it from the upsetting disparity of its reasonings, so as to make it admire the diversity of the world (even of the worlds) through the spectacle of the ἀνωμαλία (irregularity) of phenomena, thus arousing enthusiasm. When he manages to delight in the wonders of nature or of human societies, La Mothe Le Vayer does not hide the pleasure he experiences in opening his mind to a multitude of ways of thinking, far from common prejudices (Paganini 2008: 70). But this way of looking at things results from an effort of diversion. La Mothe Le Vayer’s skeptic is also a bilious spirit, who suffers from a wandering freedom that leads him to take a disenchanted and pessimistic view of men (whose obstinacy and injustice are everywhere criticized), of himself (who does not tolerate the disparity of his reasonings and his moods), of the world (the stage where the pitfalls of fortune are performed), and of human life (which he finds it difficult not to curse). La Mothe Le Vayer’s skepticism has then both positive and negative potentialities. And one should not be surprised: insofar as things are such as we represent them, they are also at the mercy of these representations.18 According to an image that La Mothe Le Vayer borrows from Montaigne (Essays II, 12, 581), each thing is like a pot with two handles, which one can take by either the right or the left (LMLV 1670: 43). From a logical point of view, that refers to the structure of equipollence, and from an empirical point of view, that refers to the combination of pleasure and displeasure in all things. It follows that, despite the therapeutic use of reason (which is likened to the imagination) in La Mothe Le Vayer’s skeptical discourse, ἀταραξία, which remains the pursued aim, is not within easy reach and is by no means guaranteed by the adoption of the skeptical stance, nor by the reading of texts written from the skeptical perspective. The skeptic, more than any other philosopher, admits that his thought is subject to conditions he does not control and that it is always possible for him to succumb to the irrationality of the working of his mind. He therefore accepts that he is not able to really enjoy the rest associated with the adoption of a given position. Because of this, La Mothe Le Vayer’s writings stand out by an awkward mode of enunciation, which nonetheless manages, more or less constantly, to put to the test the intellectual, moral, and religious orthodoxy of his time. This certainly provokes perplexity in the reader. Thus, even if it frees us from the troubles caused by opinion, leading us to libertinage, La Mothe Le Vayer’s skepticism remains a genuine, non-feigned skepticism. It is so not because it leads to ἀταραξία, but paradoxically (with respect to the Pyrrhonian tradition) because it expresses, by means of its manner of exposition, an intellectual and moral discomfort that reveals a way of thinking that takes no position, a discomfort that affects both the author and the reader.

292

SKEPTICISM

NOTES 1. This chapter has been translated from the French by Diego Machuca. 2. These opuscules include On the Skeptical Philosophy, The Skeptical Banquet, Academic Homilies, Discourse to Show that the Doubts of the Skeptical Philosophy Are of Great Use in the Sciences, Skeptical Discourse on Music, Little Skeptical Treatise on This Common Way of Speaking “To Lack Common Sense,” Skeptical Problems, Skeptical Doubt, and Skeptical Soliloquies. 3. One did not have to wait until the twentieth century (Pintard 1983), for Pierre Bayle attests to this reception in the article “Le Vayer” of his Historical and Critical Dictionary (Bayle 1740) when he writes: “One suspects that he did not have any religion” (Remark B). 4. In La Mothe Le Vayer (1970g: 269–270), Samson, a “perfect figure of the skeptical philosophy,” after having killed the lion, feeds on the honey he finds in its mouth. The skeptic, then, feeds on the dogmatism he combats. But he is at the service of dogmatism when he takes up a discourse in line with the apostolic message of Saint Paul (LMLV 1988e: 308). 5. I cite Montaigne’s Essays by book, chapter, and page number in the standard VilleySaulnier edition (Montaigne 1992). 6. On the “Saturnalia of opinion,” see La Mothe Le Vayer (1988d: 365); and on rhapsody, see the “Author’s Letter” in La Mothe Le Vayer (1988a: 201). 7. The claim of independence of the skeptical Academy (Acad. II 8) and the importance of verisimilitude in the conduct of life are pointed out by La Mothe Le Vayer in his general presentation of Pyrrhonism (1970f: 192–194) and taken over on his own account especially in La Mothe Le Vayer (1970g: 268). He explicitly refers to the Herculean effort made by Carneades to combat the tendency to judge rashly (Acad. II 108) in La Mothe Le Vayer (1970h: 326). 8. Essays III, 13, 1116: “The most beautiful lives are, in my opinion, those that fall in with the common and human model, with order, but also without miracle and without extravagance.” Cf. Essays II, 12, 558–559: “All the extravagant ways anger me. … And there is no beast to which blinders are more justly to be given to keep its vision submissive and restrained in front of its steps, and to guard it from wandering here and there.” 9. In the “Author’s Letter” in La Mothe Le Vayer (1988a: 14), he announces that in this work one will find nearly nothing but paradoxes. 10. For a more general comparison between Bayle and La Mothe Le Vayer, see Giocanti (2004: 243–263). 11. In the “Author’s Letter” in La Mothe Le Vayer (1988a: 14–15), he denounces “the tyrannical authority of time, and of the customs that the [opinions of the laypeople] have established.” Unlike Montaigne (Essays III, 13, 1080), he does not praise the metamorphic power of custom, which is compared to the beverage of Circe. La Mothe Le Vayer regards one’s flexibility toward custom as an escape from the authority of the dominant customs. 12. In relation to this reference to common sense, it should be noted that, although in On Divinity La Mothe Le Vayer takes common sense as a criterion of evaluation in order to attack religion, he criticizes common sense itself in La Mothe Le

FRANÇOIS DE LA MOTHE LE VAYER

293

Vayer (1970g). On his ambiguous attitude toward common sense, see Giocanti (1996: 27–51). 13. In La Mothe Le Vayer (1970g: 265), the skeptical philosophy is presented, adapting an Augustinian slogan, as “the sole port of salvation for a mind that loves calm.” 14. In La Mothe Le Vayer (1970h: 328) one reads: “That he [the reader] not believe me unchanged by the opinions I may have, or pretend to have.” 15. As Cavaillé (1995: 135 n.320) remarks, this naturalistic argumentation, used for instance in La Mothe Le Vayer (1988c: 102–103) in favor of incest, might find its source of inspiration in Vanini (1616: 326–327). 16. On the mind as “another Proteus,” see La Mothe La Vayer (1970d: 666); and on the mind as “potter,” see La Mothe Le Vayer (1970i: 504). 17. See Gouverneur (2005: 276–290) on “fabulation as imaginary evasion” in La Mothe Le Vayer, “far from Charron’s naturalism.” 18. “Man is the measure of all things, which become such as he represents them to himself” (LMLV 1970c: 530).

REFERENCES Bayle, Pierre. 1740. Dictionnaire historique et critique. 4 vols. Amsterdam: P. Brunel et al. Cavaillé, Jean-Pierre. 2002. Dis/simulations. Cesare Vanini, François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Gabriel Naudé, Louis Machon, Torquato Acetto. Religion, morale et politique au XVIIe siècle. Paris: Champion. Charron, Pierre. 1986. De la sagesse. Paris: Fayard. Giocanti, Sylvia. 1996. “La perte du sens commun dans l’œuvre de La Mothe Le Vayer.” In A. McKenna and P. F. Moreau (eds.), Libertinage et philosophie au XVIIe siècle, 27–51. Saint-Etienne: Publications de l’Université de Saint-Etienne. Giocanti, Sylvia. 2001. Penser l’irrésolution. Montaigne, Pascal, La Mothe Le Vayer. Trois itinéraires sceptiques. Paris: Champion. Giocanti, Sylvia. 2004. “Bayle et La Mothe Le Vayer.” In A. McKenna and G. Paganini (eds.), Pierre Bayle dans la République des Lettres, Philosophie, religion, critique, 243– 263. Paris: Champion. Giocanti, Sylvia. 2010. “Le scepticisme instrument de transgression du licite. Le cas de La Mothe Le Vayer.” In A. McKenna and P. F. Moreau (ed.), Le libertinage est-il une catégorie philosophique?, 83–100. Saint-Etienne: Publications de l’Université de SaintEtienne. Giocanti, Sylvia. 2013. “La Mothe Le Vayer: un anti-cartésien?” In D. Kolesnik-Antoine (ed.), Qu’est-ce qu’être cartésien?, 77–94. Lyon: ENS Editions. Gouverneur, Sophie. 2005. Prudence et subversion libertine. La critique de la raison d’Etat chez François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Gabriel Naudé et Samuel Sorbière. Paris: Champion La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1670. Soliloques sceptiques. Paris: Billaine. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1970a. Œuvres, 2 vols. Genève: Slatkine Reprints. (This edition corresponds to the edition of Louis Billaine [Paris, 1669] as it was republished by Michel Groell [Dresde, 1756].)

294

SKEPTICISM

La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1970b. “Opuscules ou Petits Traités.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Œuvres, vol. I, 316–492. Genève: Slatkine Reprints. La Mothe Le Vayer, “Prose Chagrine.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Œuvres, vol. I, 505–542. Genève: Slatkine Reprints. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1970d. “Discours ou homilies académiques.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Œuvres, vol. I, 572–681. Genève: Slatkine Reprints. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1970e. “La promenade en neuf dialogues.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Œuvres, vol. I, 690–758. Genève: Slatkine Reprints. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1970f. “De la vertu des payens.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Œuvres, vol. II, 119–219. Genève: Slatkine Reprints. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1970g. “Petit traité sceptique sur cette commune façon de penser ‘n’avoir pas le sens commun’.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Œuvres, vol. II, 251–272. Genève: Slatkine Reprints. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1970h. “Doute sceptique.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Œuvres, vol. II, 306–328. Genève: Slatkine Reprints. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1970i. “Petits traités en forme de Lettres écrites à diverses personnes studieuses.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Œuvres, vol. II, 341–749. Genève: Slatkine Reprints. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1988a. Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens. Paris: Fayard. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1988b. “De la philosophie sceptique.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens, 17–62. Paris: Fayard. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1988c. “Le Banquet sceptique.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens, 63–113. Paris: Fayard. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1988d. “De l’ignorance louable.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens, 209–302. Paris: Fayard. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1988e. “De la divinité.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens, 303–352. Paris: Fayard. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1988f. “De l’opiniâtreté.” In François de La Mothe Le Vayer, Dialogues faits à l’imitation des Anciens, 353–386. Paris: Fayard. La Mothe Le Vayer, François de. 1997. L’Hexameron rustique. Paris: Zanzibar. Maia Neto, José. 1995. The Christianization of Pyrrhonism. Scepticism and faith in Pascal, Kierkegaard, and Shestov. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Montaigne, Michel de. 1992. Essais. Paris: PUF. Paganini, Gianni. 2008. Skepsis. Le débat des modernes sur le scepticisme: Montaigne, Le Vayer, Campanella, Hobbes, Descartes, Bayle. Paris: Vrin. Paganini, Gianni, Miguel Benitez, and James Dybikowski. (eds.). 2002. Scepticism, Clandestinity and Free-Thinking. Paris: Champion. Pascal, Blaise. 1962. Pensées, ed. Lafuma. Paris: Du Seuil. Pintard, René. 1983. Le libertinage érudit dans la première moitié du XVIIe siècle. Génève: Slatkine. (First published in 1943.) Popkin, Richard. 1995. Histoire du scepticisme d’Erasme à Spinoza. Paris: PUF. Vanini, Giulio Cesare. 1616. Les Arcanes admirables de la Nature, Reine et Déesse des mortels. Paris: Adrien Périer.

CHAPTER TWENTY-ONE

Gassendi on Skepticism ANTONIA LOLORDO

1 INTRODUCTION In note B of his Dictionary article on Pyrrho, Pierre Bayle remarked that before Gassendi, one hardly knew the name of Sextus Empiricus in our schools. The methods he had proposed so subtly for bringing about suspense of judgment were not less known than the Terra Australis, when Gassendi gave us an abridgement of it, which opened our eyes. . . . Now no good philosopher any longer doubts that the skeptics were right to maintain that the qualities of bodies that strike our senses are only appearances. (Popkin 1991: 197) This is—to put it charitably—an exaggeration.1 However, Gassendi did do a great deal to make skepticism better known. One factor was his use of skeptical techniques to attack rival systems, as in his Exercitationes paradoxicae adversus Aristoteleos and his Objections and Counter-Objections to Descartes’s Meditations (jointly, the Disquisitio Metaphysica). Another is the detailed account of ancient skepticism provided in his magnum opus, the posthumous Syntagma Philosophicum.2 In the Exercitationes, his first work, Gassendi portrays himself as a skeptic. But by the time of the Syntagma, he disavows that label, counting himself instead among those who hold that some truth can be found and that “a certain middle way between the skeptics . . . and the dogmatists should be followed” (1.79b). This via media is sometimes called “mitigated skepticism” or “constructive skepticism,” following Popkin 1979, but the term should not mislead us. The via media of the Syntagma is not a form of skepticism at all, but an epistemology that insists on three things. First, the scope of our knowledge is limited: it cannot reach all the way to the innermost nature of things. Second, knowledge does not require absolute certainty but only probability or verisimilitude. And third, knowledge does not require a justification that is accessible to the knower. When there is no real disagreement, some things count as knowledge without any such justification. Gassendi’s interest in ancient skepticism is epistemological and methodological. He is aware that skepticism originally had an ethical dimension. But this is not something he cares much about. His long discussion of ancient skepticism in the

296

SKEPTICISM

Syntagma concludes with the brief remark that “how the skeptics have attained their end—ataraxia, an imperturbable state of mind—by this withholding of assent can be passed over at this point” (1.76b).3 Nowhere else in his work, as far as I know, does the ethical function of suspension of judgment receive any real discussion.4

2  GASSENDI’S HISTORY OF SKEPTICISM Gassendi was familiar with the Pyrrhonian tradition from early on. One of his earliest surviving letters explains that in his youth, his “mind was not yet . . . thoroughly Pyrrhonist” but that “only one thing, experience, was lacking to make [him] an imitator of Sextus Empiricus” (to Henri du Faur de Pibrac, April 8, 1621: 6.1b). The sources he mentions are Cicero, Charron, and Montaigne. In the Preface to his first published work, the 1624 Exercitationes paradoxicae adversus Aristoteleos,5 Gassendi explains that although he studied the views of all the various sects of philosophers, “none of them ever pleased [him] like the akatalepsia praised by the Academics and Pyrrhoneans” (3.99). Thus, he explains, During the six years I devoted to the task of teaching philosophy, especially Aristotelean philosophy, at the University of Aix, I always made sure that my students would be able to defend Aristotle properly. But as an appendix to the course I also taught the claims that totally undercut Aristotelean dogmas. . . . In this way my students . . . saw that no proposition or opinion is so thoroughly accepted or plausible that its contrary cannot be shown to be equally probable or even more probable. (3.100) Most of the sources he lists are modern: Juan Luis Vives, Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola, Petrus Ramus, Charron again (3.99), and Cicero (3.100).6 But it’s clear, especially in Book II, that by this point Gassendi was also familiar with two important ancient sources: Sextus Empiricus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism and Book IX of Diogenes Laertius’s Lives of the Philosophers, the Life of Pyrrho. In both the Exercitationes and the Syntagma, Gassendi’s presentation of the Ten Modes of suspension of judgment follows Outlines of Pyrrhonism closely.7 In the Syntagma—where Gassendi is unusually careful (by seventeenth-century standards) about citing his sources—he also refers to the Life of Pyrrho repeatedly. But he cites a number of other ancient sources as well: Sextus’s Against the Logicians and Against the Grammarians; Cicero, especially his Academica; Augustine’s Contra Academicos; Seneca’s Letters; and many others. The Syntagma’s Logic begins with a history of logic that is designed to make the need for Gassendi’s own system clear. Because the goal of logic is the truth, Gassendi centers his history around disagreements over the criterion of truth. Much of this history deals with the philosophers who deny the existence of a criterion and insist that nothing is known (1.69b). Gassendi emphasizes that the criterion in question is supposed to be one “which is subject to no falsity and which thus gives rise to certain and infallible knowledge” (1.70a). This is parasitic on the way the skeptics’ opponents think of the criterion. If Descartes or the Aristotelians, for instance, set

GASSENDI ON SKEPTICISM

297

a very high bar for knowledge—absolute certainty—then the skeptic need only cast doubt on our ability to achieve absolute certainty. One surprising feature of Gassendi’s history of skepticism is the sheer number of people it includes. The obvious suspects are there: Pyrrho and his followers, and those “who [Sextus] Empiricus thought hardly differed from the Skeptics, namely the Academics” (1.72b).8 But it also includes Democritus, Empedocles, Euripides, Heraclitus, Hippocrates, Homer, Philo, Socrates, Xenophanes, Zeno of Elea, and more. One reason Gassendi includes such a dizzying list of figures is that he is always concerned to emphasize the diversity of non-Aristotelian traditions. But a second, more important one is that he has simply taken over much of the list from the Life of Pyrrho (1.70a–1.71b) and Against the Logicians (1.71b–1.72b).

3  THE TEN MODES Gassendi’s skeptical arguments rely heavily on the Ten Modes. In the Exercitationes, he uses familiar examples to show that “the judgments of different men concerning the things that are perceived by the senses are very different” (3.197b) and hence that “men do not know the inner natures of things” (3.203a). In the Syntagma, he explains that “one and the same thing can appear in different ways to different animals and different men, and even to one and the same man according to his various senses and his various affections (which are the first four Modes)” (1.84a). Moreover, Gassendi argues, this disagreement cannot be resolved. Consider an example. The same wine tastes sweet to some men and bitter to others (3.198a ff). How can we decide whose taste constitutes the standard? We cannot say that the way wine tastes to a healthy man is the way it really is, because healthy men disagree. We cannot say that the way wine tastes to most people is the way it really is, because there’s no clear majority verdict and no reason a mere majority should constitute the standard. And so on (3.198ff). If one considers such cases, Gassendi thinks, one will find oneself withholding assent from any opinion about the wine’s inner nature. This, Gassendi makes clear, is compatible with continuing to assent to the appearances: When [the skeptics] say that nothing can be known with certainty or that no Criterion exists, they are not talking about what things appear to be and what is manifested through the senses . . . but about what things are in themselves. (1.70a) For: If it is asked whether snow is white, honey sweet, fire hot, [the skeptics] will respond that it appears so to them, and they do not say that their vision perceives another color than white in snow or that their tongue perceives another taste than sweet in honey or that their hand perceives another quality than heat in fire. But because these are only external adjuncts and things that strike the senses, if it’s asked whether the things themselves, secundum se and from their innermost nature, are really the way they appear to be . . . this is what they will stick at. (1.13b)

298

SKEPTICISM

The disagreement between various men about the taste of wine is not a dispute over the contents of their minds. Gassendian appearances are far closer to what the ancient skeptics had in mind than to Cartesian knowledge of one’s own subjective mental states. Knowledge of the appearances includes not only claims like the claim that I am now seated rather than standing or that wine appears sweet to me, but also mathematical knowledge: Whatever certainty and evidentness there is in the discipline of mathematics, it pertains to appearances and in no way to the true causes or inner natures of things. However, I add that through mathematics, I can become more certain that, for example, the earth is round. For this can be apparent through the eclipses of the moon and the variation in the height of the poles. But why is the earth round? What is its true nature? . . . Why does it rest motionless in the centre, or if it moves, what power moves it?9 As soon as you go beyond those things which are apparent and fall under sense and experience, to inquire into things further within, both the discipline of mathematics and all other disciplines are surrounded entirely by darkness. (3.209a) Moreover, the appearances include not only what is apparent to us now but also what may become apparent later. For even in the Exercitationes Gassendi is willing to allow that we can infer to things beyond the appearances. Such inferences will not get us all the way to the true natures of things: If you say that the intellect can infer from the things that happen in experience or appear to the senses to other, much more hidden things, I will reply that nevertheless, it can proceed no farther by reasoning than to things which may again be experienced or things of which some appearance can be exhibited. But what we deny is that we can penetrate all the way to the inner natures of things. (3.207a–b) However, although Gassendi allows more knowledge than one might initially suspect, the knowledge he allows is still far more limited than Aristotelian scientia. It differs in two other ways as well.10 It lacks the absolute certainty characteristic of Aristotelian scientia, as Gassendi explains in an attempt to avoid the charge of self-refutation. The kind of knowledge the skeptic claims to have is not entirely certain or evident and does not derive from some Aristotelian cause or demonstration. But nevertheless, it does not lack its own certainty and evidentness, and hence probability, that relies on very apparent inferences and reasons that can restrain the intellect from assenting to the proposition that there is Aristotelian knowledge. So use the word “opinion” or any other term you like, this doesn’t really matter. For we say “to have an opinion” and “to know” indifferently, as the manner of speech of the vulgar shows. And if you attend properly, scientia and opinion can be considered synonyms. And one can say “certain scientia” and “certain opinion” as well as “weak [imbecillam] scientia,” and “weak opinion.” (3.206a)11 The certainty in question here is simultaneously psychological and epistemological.

GASSENDI ON SKEPTICISM

299

Finally, the justificatory structure of Gassendian probability differs from that of Aristotelian scientia or, for that matter, Cartesian clear and distinct perception. Gassendian knowledge need not be deduced from first principles, and it need not derive from a source whose epistemic bona fides we have established. It is enough, as we’ll see below, if there is no actual disagreement to provide a reason for doubt.

4  THE AGRIPPAN TRILEMMA Gassendi does recognize the existence of skeptical tropes beyond the Ten Modes. Near the end of his history of skepticism, he remarks: When Pyrrhonism was revived, some other Modes were added, but it is more than enough to recount the three principal ones. The first is what can be called regressus in infinitum, where what has been put forward to confirm something is said to require confirmation by another thing, and that again by another, so that no way out can be found. The second is diallelus . . . where it is shown that someone who is giving a proof asserts one thing in order to establish a second, and asserts the second in order to establish the first. . . . The last is hypothetical, or from supposition, where, after something has been supposed, someone asserts that he is permitted to make the contrary supposition. (1.75b) Using these modes again allows the skeptics to say that there is no criterion (1.75b). Gassendi’s interest in the Agrippan trilemma is slight in comparison to his interest in the Ten Modes. This fact requires some explanation. It’s easy to see why the Ten Modes are dominant in the Exercitationes, which attacks knowledge conceived of as Aristotelian scientia: “certain and evident cognition of some thing that comes from knowledge of a necessary cause or a demonstration” (3.192b).12 For since it is established that all of our knowledge either is sensation or proceeds from the senses, it also seems to be established that we cannot make a judgment about anything unless the senses have first given testimony of it. (3.192b) Thus, if Gassendi can eliminate the beliefs about the natures of things that are derived from the senses, he has destroyed the foundation of Aristotelian scientia. One might expect the Agrippan trilemma to play a greater role in Gassendi’s objections to Descartes. However, it does not. To see why, let’s look at three different strands in these objections. The first strand concerns Descartes’s use of skepticism. Gassendi argues, at some length, that Descartes misunderstands two crucial distinctions: the distinction between the inner natures of things and their appearances, and the distinction between the actions of life and the inquiry into truth. Failure to recognize these distinctions leads Descartes to apply skeptical techniques where they are not appropriate. Gassendi explains that the skeptics rejected indifference entirely where the actions of everyday life are concerned: But for the investigation of truth, they drew a further distinction . . . between ta phainomena, “the things which appear to the senses,” like the heat of fire,

300

SKEPTICISM

the sweetness of honey, and others; and ta noumena, “the things which are understood by the mind,” like . . . internal and proximate natures and causes, and the properties of those same things. And then, although they considered the latter kind of things uncertain, they still allowed the first kind except when their state of mind made it pleasant to take on the insolence of the dogmatics. (3.286a) This is consistent with Gassendi’s treatment of skepticism in the Exercitationes. But it does not amount to much as a critique of Descartes. Here it seems that Gassendi has simply misunderstood the purpose of Cartesian skepticism.13 A second line of objection, which concerns Descartes’s reliance on clear and distinct perception, is more interesting. Gassendi expresses the familiar worry that Descartes has argued in a circle by using clear and distinct perception to argue that God exists and then using God’s existence to argue that whatever is clearly and distinctly perceived is true. But he also worries about whether clear and distinct perception can serve as the criterion, posing a dilemma for Descartes. On the one hand, if clear and distinct perception is picked out by its psychological aspect alone, there will be conflicting clear and distinct perceptions. Different men—all of whom are honest, all of whom have thought about the matter carefully—perceive different, incompatible things with clarity and distinctness (3.315a). Moreover, Gassendi continues, he himself has clearly and distinctly perceived different, incompatible things at different times. As a youth, for instance, he clearly and distinctly perceived that two lines continually approaching each other more closely must meet. Later he learned about asymptotes and came to perceive, with equal clarity and distinctness, that they need not meet (3.314b). Hence, clear and distinct perception cannot serve as the criterion of truth. Descartes would object, of course, that not all of these conflicting perceptions are genuinely clear and distinct (AT 7.361). Gassendi is somewhat impatient with this response, replying that “the fact that men go to meet death for the sake of some opinion seems to be a perspicuous argument that they perceive it clearly and distinctly” (3.317a). But impatience aside, this leads to the other horn of the dilemma. If we build truth into the nature of clear and distinct perception, then we open up a gap between genuine clear and distinct perception and merely apparent clear and distinct perception. And once this gap is open, we cannot use clear and distinct perception as the criterion. Thus, nothing as sophisticated as the Agrippan trilemma is needed. Another reason for Gassendi to de-emphasize the Agrippan trilemma emerges when we look at the third line of objection: that the First Meditation skeptical hypotheses simply fail to produce doubt. For the fact that we make mistakes in certain circumstances does not threaten the knowledge we have in other circumstances: When we examine a nearby tower and touch it, we are certain that it is square, even though when we were further from it we had reason . . . to doubt whether it was square or round or some other figure. . . . In the same way, the sense of pain which still appears to be in a foot or hand after the limbs have been amputated can sometimes deceive . . . but those who are whole are so certain that they feel pain in the foot or hand which they see pricked that they cannot doubt it.

GASSENDI ON SKEPTICISM

301

In the same way, because while we live we are alternately awake and asleep, we may be deceived through a dream . . . but nevertheless we are not always asleep and when we are really awake we cannot doubt whether we are awake or asleep. (3.388a–b) The dream example is the most interesting one. Gassendi grants that we are sometimes deceived in dreams and that we sometimes believe we are awake when we are really dreaming. Nevertheless, he insists, when we are actually awake, we know that we are awake, and the falsity of beliefs acquired in dreams does not affect the status of beliefs acquired when awake. Our knowledge that we are awake, when we are awake, is not mere supposition and does not require further proof: it is simply obvious to all men. Gassendi returns to the Agrippan trilemma in the Syntagma, where he makes essentially the same point: The three modes added to the ten pertain to the general form of arguing and objecting. But . . .whenever someone objects that there . . . is no criterion . . . because anyone who says that there is does so either without a demonstration or with one, but that either way, etc., it can be said, first, that we have some demonstration. Although it’s not an Aristotelian demonstration or a demonstration which requires a precise investigation of some previous sign or criterion or the like, it’s the sort of demonstration that men who are prudent, intelligent, and furnished with good sense will generally accept as a proper reason and which cannot be contradicted except out of sheer contrariety [contradicendi animo]. For it seems that we should stand firm on this and not become frightened of being drawn into an infinite regress or circularity. (1.85b) He goes on to explain that demonstration . . . is not necessary when things are so evident that they just need to be proposed. Such things include not only particular things which appear to the senses and are approved by experience, but also general propositions against which no objections can be brought, such as . . . if equals are taken from equals, the remainders are equal . . . And although it is countered that someone who simply makes a declaration and does not prove it should not be believed, and that the opposite can be asserted hypothetically and claimed as true by anyone . . . wishing to maintain the other side, it is clear that this can indeed be done in doubtful matters, where neither experience nor some convincing and reasonable argument comes to our support, but it cannot be done without folly in other cases. (1.86a) The key difference between this and the way Gassendi treats the Ten Modes is that in the Ten Modes we start from actual disagreement about particular facts. But in the examples of the Agrippan trilemma Gassendi is considering here, actual disagreement plays no role. No one is actually denying that if equals are taken from equals, the remainders are equal. And hence, Gassendi thinks, there is no reason to start looking for proof in the first place. A similar point is made in the Disquisitio

302

SKEPTICISM

Metaphysica, where Gassendi argues that Descartes’s skeptical hypotheses fail to raise genuine doubt in cases where “the thing always appears in the same way, as the sun always appears round and shining, or as the crossing of two straight lines always creates two right angles or angles equal to two right angles” (3.279b).

5  GASSENDI’S VIA MEDIA By the time of the Syntagma, Gassendi thinks of skepticism as nothing more than a useful check on the pretensions of the sciences. Explaining the need for a via media between the skeptics and the dogmatists, he writes that the dogmatists do not really know all the things they suppose they know, and they do not have an appropriate criterion for judging those things. However, it does not seem that all the things which are thrown into dispute by the skeptics are so unknown that we cannot have some criterion for judging them. And because the majority of the things which the dogmatists suppose they know are really unknown, too often in physics the occasion arises for declaring that we are fortunate when we arrive not at what is true but at what is probable. (1.79b) This claim is itself, of course, merely probable (1.79b). Gassendi’s ultimate view is that there are two criteria of truth. First, the senses, which serve as the criterion for the appearances. Since even the skeptics allow knowledge of the appearances, Gassendi does not spend much time on this. The more interesting criterion is reason, by which we can know the “hidden” truth that is “lurking under the appearances” (1.80b). How exactly this works depends on why the truth in question is hidden. Here, again following Sextus, he distinguishes three categories of hidden truths. Some things are only circumstantially hidden (1.69a), and these can be known by memory. When we see smoke but no fire, we form the belief that there is a temporarily hidden fire because we remember smoke being produced by fire and nothing else. A second category of things are “entirely hidden, so that they can in no way fall under the scope of the understanding” (1.68b). These things cannot be known by any criterion. The third category contains things that are hidden by nature. These are things that cannot be evident per seipsas but can come to be known through “indicative signs,” to use the term of Sextus, who rejected their use (1.68b). Gassendi gives a number of examples. Motion signifies the void, because we observe motion and infer that it can exist only if there is empty space for moving bodies to move into (1.81a). Certain actions that could not be performed without a soul signify the existence of a soul (1.82b). The fact that iron is attracted by a magnet signifies a power in the magnet (1.82b). The orderliness of the universe signifies that God exists and created the universe (1.82b). Refraction signifies that light is a body (1.82a). And sweat signifies that there are pores in the skin (1.68b). Gassendi’s use of indicative signs is an important point of difference from the ancient skeptical tradition, and marks a clear way in which he is not a skeptic by the time of the Syntagma. The last example—the pores in the skin—is particularly

GASSENDI ON SKEPTICISM

303

interesting in this connection because pores belonged to the third category of hidden things before the invention of the microscope, and now belong to the first category. Gassendi gives other examples of this as well. We used to infer that mites have feet from the way they move, but now we can see their feet. We used to infer that the Milky Way is made up of stars, and can now see the individual stars that compose it with a telescope (1.82a). Such examples, Gassendi argues, confirm the legitimacy of inferences from indicative signs. And for all we know, many of the things which are now hidden from us and which we until now perceive only by understanding will one day, by some instrument thought up by our descendants, also become things that are perceived by the senses. (1.82a) At this point, Gassendi’s via media may seem closer to dogmatism than skepticism. I think this is right. However, he insists that there’s a big difference between claiming to know the existence of things and claiming to know their nature. We know that there is a soul and a God and a power in the magnet because we know there must be some cause of the things we perceive. What we do not—and cannot—know are the nature of the soul, of God, and of the magnet’s power (1.82b). We know that there is some cause without knowing what the cause is like in itself. This difference is crucial in Gassendi’s explanation of how to escape the Ten Modes: It seems that one and the same thing can appear in different ways to different animals and different men, and even to one and the same man according to his various senses and his various affections. . . . But although so many various Phantasiae or appearances are created, nevertheless it’s clear that there is in the thing or object some general cause which suffices for all the things which are manifest. And so, to whatever extent the effects are not like each other, nevertheless there are two things which are certain and can be proven. . . . One is that there is a cause in the thing itself, or the object, and the other is that there is a different disposition in the faculties that encounter it. (1.84a) Consider the action of the sun, which melts wax but hardens clay. We know that there is something in the sun that enables it to cause both the melting of the wax and the hardening of the clay. And we know that there is some difference between the wax and the clay that explains why the sun melts the first but hardens the second. But we can only characterize these features of the sun, the wax, and the clay relationally. Gassendi’s claim that we can know appearances but not inner natures, then, is the claim that we can know the relational properties of things but not the intrinsic properties that ground them.

NOTES 1. See Popkin (1979: chapter 2) and Floridi (2002). See also the chapters on Montaigne and Charron in this book. 2. I cite all Gassendi’s works by book, page, and (where relevant) column number in Gassendi (1964). The Syntagma occupies all of volumes 1 and 2.

304

SKEPTICISM

3. All translations are my own, but I have benefited greatly from consulting translations by Craig Brush (Gassendi 1972), whose Selected Writings contains a great deal of material about skepticism; Bernard Rochot (Gassendi 1959; Gassendi 1962); and Sylvie Taussig (Gassendi 2004). 4. Perhaps surprisingly, there is no real discussion of the skeptics in the Syntagma’s Ethics 1.1, “Quae felicitatem faciunt, meditanda.” (There’s a brief mention later, at 2.696b.) 5. Book I was published in 1624. Book II was written around the same time but not published until after Gassendi’s death. 6. All these authors are mentioned in various places in the body as well. For details, see Bernard Rochot’s extremely useful footnotes in Gassendi (1959). 7. See Exercitationes 2.6.2, 3.192b ff and, in the Syntagma, Logic 2.3, 1.72b ff. 8. This genealogy doesn’t put a lot of emphasis on the difference between Pyrrhonian and Academic skepticism, but Gassendi is aware of it. He notes, for instance, that “when Carneades founded what is called the Third Academy . . . he revived the criterion . . . not for the true but only for the probable [verisimile]” (1.72b). And in the Preface to the Syntagma, he tells us that he will follow Sextus’s taxonomy, dividing the Greeks into three categories: the Dogmatics; Arcesilaus and the Acataleptics, so called “because they reckon that all things are akatalepsa, incomprehensible”; and Pyrrho and the Skeptics (1.13b). 9. Gassendi was in fact a committed Copernican. In the preface to the Exercitationes, he says that in Book IV, “rest will be brought to the fixed stars and the sun: but motion will be given to the earth, as if it’s one of the planets” (3.102, no columns). See LoLordo (2014) for more on this. 10. These are also ways in which it differs from Cartesian clear and distinct perception. 11. In later works, Gassendi remains concerned to show how the charge of selfrefutation is avoided. But he makes clear that the skeptic need not be claiming to have a different form of knowledge than the form she is attacking. Rather, he can make skeptical suggestions without claiming any kind of knowledge at all. Gassendi’s explanation here follows Sextus: if someone objects that the skeptic refutes himself by claiming that nothing is known, the skeptic “responds that while phrases or propositions of this sort deny others, they also deny themselves, like medications which are taken into the body to purge the humors and expel themselves along with them” (1.76b). 12. Gassendi restricts himself to Aristotelian scientia for several reasons. As we’ve already seen, he wants to allow knowledge of the appearances and to avoid selfrefutation. But he also wants to exclude matters of faith—something which is grounded in both genuine personal conviction and in pragmatic considerations. 13. It also seems that he has misunderstood the Pyrrhonian notion of ta phainomena, since in Sextus appearances need not be “things that appear to the senses” but can be intellectual as well as perceptual.

REFERENCES Descartes, René. 1996. Oeuvres de Descartes. 11 volumes, edited by C. Adam and P. Tannery. Paris: Vrin.

GASSENDI ON SKEPTICISM

305

Floridi, Luciano. 2002. Sextus Empiricus: The Transmission and Recovery of Pyrrhonism. New York: Oxford University Press. Gassendi, Pierre. 1959. Dissertations en forme de paradoxes contre les Aristotéliciens (Exercitationes paradoxicae adversus Aristoteleos) Livres I et II, edited and translated by Bernard Rochot. Paris: J. Vrin. Gassendi, Pierre. 1962. Recherches métaphysiques; ou, Doutes et instances contre la Métaphysique de R. Descartes et ses réponses (Disquisitio metaphysica; seu, Dubitationes et instantiae adversus Renati Cartesii Metaphysicam et responsa), edited and translated by B. Rochot. Paris: Vrin. Gassendi, Pierre. 1964. Petri Gassendi Opera Omnia in sex tomos divisa. 6 volumes. Lyon: Laurent Anisson and Jean-Baptiste Devenet, 1658. Reprinted in facsimile with an introduction by T. Gregory. Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt: Friedrich Frohmann. Gassendi, Pierre. 1972. The Selected Works of Pierre Gassendi, edited and translated by C. G. Brush. New York: Johnson Reprint. Gassendi, Pierre. 2004. Pierre Gassendi (1592–1655): Lettres latines. 2 volumes, translated by S. Taussig. Turnhout: Brepols. LoLordo, Antonia. 2014. “Copernicus, Epicurus, Galileo, and Gassendi,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 51: 82–88. Popkin, Richard. 1979. The History of Scepticism: From Erasmus to Descartes. Berkeley: University of California Press. Popkin, Richard (ed.). 1991. Pierre Bayle: Historical and Critical Dictionary: Selections. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett.

CHAPTER TWENTY-TWO

Descartes and the Force of Skepticism DAVID CUNNING

1 INTRODUCTION In Meditations on First Philosophy, René Descartes (1596–1650) considers a number of skeptical arguments with the aim of locating beliefs that are immune from all doubt whatsoever. He writes: Some years ago I was struck by the large number of falsehoods that I had accepted as true in my childhood, and by the highly doubtful nature of the whole edifice that I had subsequently based on them. I realized that it was necessary, once in the course of my life, to demolish everything completely and start again right from the foundations if I wanted to establish anything at all in the sciences that was stable and likely to last. . . . So, for the purposes of rejecting all my opinions, it will be enough if I find in each of them at least some reason for doubt. (First Meditation, AT VII 17–18, CSM II 12)1 Descartes does not propose to abandon all of the beliefs that the skeptical arguments call into question. He will recover those that he can demonstrate to follow from new and improved grounds. This chapter will treat the skeptical arguments that Descartes unveils in the First Meditation and their eventual relation to the goal of securing results that are “stable and likely to last.” Section 2 considers both the argument from occasional sensory deception and the dream argument. Section 3 treats Descartes’s refrain that the main purpose of the skeptical arguments is to help us to detach from our senses and then recognize the truth of non-sensory (or what we today might call a priori) philosophical axioms. Section 4 highlights that in the final analysis Descartes is not just skeptical about the veridicality of waking perceptions; he thinks that there are transparent non-sensory philosophical axioms that entail that the senses hardly provide an accurate representation of reality at all. Section 5 is a discussion of the hyperbolic doubt that appears in the latter half of the First Meditation and a discussion of how Descartes thought he had the resources to overcome it.

DESCARTES AND THE FORCE OF SKEPTICISM

307

2  SKEPTICISM AND THE SENSES The initial skeptical arguments of the First Meditation call into question our beliefs about the everyday sensible objects that we presume to surround us. Descartes begins: Whatever I have up till now accepted as most true I have acquired either from the senses or through the senses. But from time to time I have found that the senses deceive, and it is prudent never to trust completely those who have deceived us even once. (AT VII 18, CSM II 12) Here he is appealing to a common experience in which a person has a sensory experience of an object but subsequently concludes that the experience was misleading or deceptive. As Descartes rehashes the argument later in the Sixth Meditation: Sometimes towers which had looked round from a distance appeared square from close up; and enormous statues standing on their pediments did not seem large when observed from the ground. In these and countless other such cases, I found that the judgments of the external senses were mistaken. (AT VII 76, CSM II 53) The initial conclusion that Descartes draws from this argument from occasional sensory deception is that we should never put our complete trust in any of our beliefs about the bodies that surround us. Descartes retreats from this far-reaching conclusion immediately, however, just as most of us would do if we were working through the argument along with him. Presumably, the reason that we would ever call into question a belief about a distant tower or any other non-ideally situated object is that we have had conflicting observations of the object in more optimal circumstances—in circumstances that we fully trust. If so, the definitive conclusion that our senses in some cases mislead us presupposes that they sometimes (and indeed often) do not. Descartes continues: Yet although the senses occasionally deceive us with respect to objects which are very small or in the distance, there are many other beliefs about which doubt is quite impossible, even though they are derived from the senses—for example, that I am here, sitting by the fire, wearing a winter dressing-gown, holding this piece of paper in my hands, and so on. Again, how could it be denied that these hands or this whole body are mine? Unless perhaps I were to liken myself to madmen, whose brains are so damaged by persistent vapours of melancholia that they firmly maintain they are kings when they are paupers, or say they are dressed in purple when they are naked, or that their heads are made of earthenware, or that they are pumpkins, or made of glass. But such people are insane, and I would be thought equally mad if I took anything from them as a model for myself. (AT VII 18–19, CSM II 12–13) This seems to be the right thing to say in response to the contention that all of our sense-based beliefs are suspect if our senses sometimes mislead us: the way that we tell that such a belief is misleading is by relying on sensory perceptions that we trust—sensory perceptions “about which doubt is quite impossible.”

308

SKEPTICISM

We tend to think that our beliefs about objects in our immediate vicinity are unimpeachable, but Descartes actually thinks that our confidence is unfounded even here. He continues the Meditation by remarking that we sometimes have dreams that are so vivid that, while we are having them, we cannot differentiate them from waking experiences. After making clear that he is not a madman, he writes: A brilliant piece of reasoning! As if I were not a man who sleeps at night, and regularly has all the same experiences while asleep as madmen do when awake— indeed sometimes even more probable ones. How often, asleep at night, am I convinced of just such familiar events—that I am here in my dressing gown, sitting by the fire—when in fact I am lying undressed in bed! (AT VII 19, CSM II13) Presumably most of us have had the experience of thinking that a dream was real, and we might have even had the experience of asking ourselves at a given moment whether or not we are in a dream and then concluding that we are not, but then we wake up. Descartes continues: Yet at the moment my eyes are certainly wide awake when I look at this piece of paper; I shake my head and it is not asleep; as I stretch out and feel my hand I do so deliberately, and I know what I am doing. All this would not happen with such distinctness to someone asleep. Indeed! As if I did not remember other occasions when I have been tricked by exactly similar thoughts while asleep! As I think about this more carefully, I see plainly that there are never any sure signs by means of which being awake can be distinguished from being asleep. (AT VII 19, CSM II 13) Here Descartes focuses on the vividness of dream experiences to secure the result that sometimes they are just as real-seeming as experiences that we have while awake. If so, then for any belief that we take ourselves to have formed in ideal viewing conditions, that belief might have for its evidence a perception that is not reflective of how things are. Descartes would appear to have found himself again at the conclusion that “it is prudent never to trust [the senses] completely.” As he did in the case of the argument from occasional sensory deception, Descartes quickly puts the reins on the conclusion that he will draw from the dream argument. We may not be able to tell the difference between waking experience and dreaming, he supposes, but for any sensory perception that we have there must exist the basic elements that are necessary for sensory perception to occur at all: Suppose then that I am dreaming, and that these particulars—that my eyes are open, that I am moving my head and stretching out my hands—are not true. Perhaps, indeed, I do not even have such hands or such a body at all. Nonetheless, it must surely be admitted that the visions which come in sleep are like paintings, which must have been fashioned in the likeness of things that are real, and hence that at least these general kinds of things—eyes, head, hands and the body as a whole—are things which are not imaginary but are real and exist. For even when painters try to create sirens and satyrs with the most extraordinary bodies, they cannot give them natures which are new in all respects; they simply jumble up the

DESCARTES AND THE FORCE OF SKEPTICISM

309

limbs of different animals. Or if perhaps they manage to think up something so new that nothing remotely similar has ever been seen before—something which is therefore completely fictitious and unreal—at least the colours used in the composition must be real. (AT VII 19–20, CSM II 13) So presumably there exist hands and faces, or at the very least things like size and shape. We might be wrong to trust any particular sensory perception, but at least we can trust that generally speaking the external world contains items that are familiar.2 Descartes does not say where it is that he is getting the assumption that we could not have sensory perceptions unless there existed basic elements out of which those perceptions are fashioned. The assumption certainly has not been demonstrated at this point in the Meditations, but one thing to note for now is that Descartes allows a number of unexamined assumptions in the First Meditation. This is to be expected, actually. The anticipated outcome of working through the skeptical arguments is that we will once and for all locate claims that are immune from any possible doubt, but that means that we are not in possession of any such claims for use in the skeptical arguments themselves (see also Curley 1978: 50–51; Larmore 2014: 55–59). One of Descartes’s objectors (Pierre Bourdin) raised this concern to Descartes explicitly— how he can trust the premises of the skeptical arguments of the First Meditation if those arguments are meant to finally locate beliefs that are completely certain and if his beliefs are otherwise unexamined (Seventh Objections and Replies; AT VII 527– 530, CSM II 358–361). Descartes’s response to the concern is dismissive: he points out that in the construction of a building, the tools that are used to remove the prior dwelling and any rubble do not need to be of the same quality as the materials that compose the new foundation (AT VII 538, CSM II 367; AT VII 544, CSM II 371; AT VII 542, CSM II 370). He adds that in the First Meditation he was “not yet concerned with establishing any truths” (AT VII 523, CSM II 355) and that “there is nothing at all that I asserted ‘with confidence’ in the First Meditation: it is full of doubt throughout” (AT VII 474, CSM II 319). As we have already seen, Descartes allows a number of unexamined assumptions in the First Meditation: for example, that what we know we know through the senses; and that the distinction between waking perceptions and dreams is a distinction between perceptions that are veridical and perceptions that are not.3 Now he is allowing the assumption that we could not have sensory perceptions at all unless there existed basic elements that constitute them. The first result of the Meditations that is worth its salt is “I am, I exist” (AT VII 25, CSM II 17), and the First Meditation skeptical arguments do a lot of work to help us to arrive at it.4 As we shall see, they help us to recognize the transparency and perspicuity of claims that are not known through the senses.

3  SKEPTICISM ABOUT THE A PRIORI The dream argument supposes that waking experience provides an accurate representation of reality, that dream experience does not, and that we are in possession of no clear sign to distinguish the two. What is striking is that in the final analysis Descartes holds that the external world is not as we know it through

310

SKEPTICISM

the senses, but is a plenum that contains no sensory qualities—no color, no sound, no taste, no light. Below we will consider his arguments for the view that sensory qualities are not literally in physical objects—not in anything like the way that we experience them—but first we must consider his methodological assumption that non-sensory axioms are the appropriate sort of premise for a philosophical demonstration. In Section 4, we will see how he attempts to appeal to such axioms to generate the result that the external world is not as we sense it. Descartes holds that, upon reflection, the clearest and most obvious results are not known through the senses. In contrast to the level of certainty that is afforded to the senses in the early moments of the First Meditation, Descartes in fact thinks that we have another cognitive faculty to which the senses pale in comparison. He writes: It is clear that we do not have [perfect] certainty in cases where our perception is even the slightest bit obscure or confused; for such obscurity, whatever its degree, is quite sufficient to make us have doubts in such cases. Again, we do not have the required kind of certainty with regard to matters which we perceive solely by means of the senses, however clear such perception may be. . . . Accordingly, if there is any certainty to be had, the only remaining alternative is that it occurs in the clear perceptions of the intellect and nowhere else. (Second Replies, AT VII 145, CSM II 105–106) Descartes then provides a list of the sorts of truth that he thinks are undeniable upon reflection—so long as we are sufficiently detached from the senses. He says: Now some of these perceptions are so transparently clear and at the same time so simple that we cannot ever think of them without believing them to be true. The fact that I exist so long as I am thinking, or that what is done cannot be undone, are examples of truths in respect of which we possess this kind of certainty. (Second Replies, AT VII 145, CSM II 106) The following are examples of [common notions or axioms]: It is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be at the same time; What is done cannot be undone; He who thinks cannot but exist while he thinks; and countless others. It would not be easy to draw up a list of all of them; but nonetheless we cannot fail to know them when the occasion for thinking about them arises, provided that we are not blinded by preconceived opinions. (Principles I 49, AT VIIIA 24, CSM I 209) Descartes thinks that there are axioms that are the most perspicuous that the human mind can ever confront, and he calls them alternately “primary notions” or “common notions or axioms.” Given how clear and obvious they are, they are preferable to claims or contentions that are much less perspicuous, or to contentions that the axioms entail are false. Still, we can fail to register the force of a primary notion if we think too much in terms of sensory pictures and images and are not practiced at thinking abstractly (Principles I 73, AT VIIIA 37, CSM I 220), or if we are wedded to opinions that entail that the primary notion is implausible or false (Principles I 72, AT VIIIA 36, CSM I 219–220). Descartes is contending with just such a meditator at the start of the First Meditation, someone who has not yet examined his opinions and who is committed to views like that what is known best

DESCARTES AND THE FORCE OF SKEPTICISM

311

is known through the senses. The skeptical arguments are then meant to help us to recognize that the senses are not the only game in town: In the First Meditation reasons are provided which give us possible grounds for doubt about all things, especially material things. . . . Although the usefulness of such extensive doubt is not apparent at first sight, its greatest benefit lies in freeing us from all our preconceived opinions, and providing the easiest route by which the mind may be led away from the senses. (“Synopsis of the following six Meditations,” AT VII 12, CSM II 9)5 If we detach from our senses and become able to recognize the clarity and force of the deliverances of the intellect, we will notice that these are much more perspicuous than the claims that we have asserted heretofore. We will revise and update our beliefs accordingly, and so long as we stay on the wagon, our former beliefs will be kept at bay: In order to philosophize seriously and search out the truth about all the things that are capable of being known, we must first of all lay aside all our preconceived opinions, or at least we must take the greatest care not to put our trust in any of the opinions accepted by us in the past until we have first scrutinized them afresh and confirmed their truth. Next, we must give our attention in an orderly way to the notions that we have within us, and we must judge to be true all and only those whose truth we clearly and distinctly recognize when we attend to them in this way. When we do this we shall realize, first of all, that we exist in so far as our nature consists in thinking; and we shall simultaneously realize both that there is a God, and that we depend on him, and also that a consideration of his attributes enables us to investigate the truth of other things, since he is their cause. Finally, we will see that besides the notions of God and of our mind, we have within us knowledge of many propositions which are eternally true such as “Nothing comes from nothing.” We shall also find that we have knowledge both of a corporeal or extended nature which is divisible, moveable, and so on, and also of certain sensations which affect us, such as the sensations of pain, colours, tastes and so on. . . . When we contrast all this knowledge with the confused thoughts we had before, we will acquire the habit of forming clear and distinct concepts of all the things that can be known. These few instructions seem to me to contain the most important principles of human knowledge. (Principles I 75, AT VIIIA 38–39, CSM I 221) This all sounds fair enough—we should locate axioms that are so obvious as to be undeniable, and then derive whatever it is that follows from them. We should also reject whatever our new results entail is false.

4  SKEPTICISM ABOUT THE SENSES IS WARRANTED UPON REFLECTION In the final analysis, Descartes does not think that waking perceptions are veridical. He thinks that our non-sensory cognitive faculties are a better guide to truth, and

312

SKEPTICISM

he appeals to primary notions to generate the result that the external world is very different from how we sense it. First, we consider a statement of the view: Now we understand very well how the different size, shape and motion of the particles of one body can produce various local motions in another body. But there is no way of understanding how these same attributes (size, shape and motion) can produce something else whose nature is quite different from their own—like the substantial forms and real qualities which many suppose to inhere in things. . . . Not only is all this unintelligible, but we know that the nature of our soul is such that different local motions are quite sufficient to produce all the sensations in the soul. What is more, we actually experience the various sensations as they are produced in the soul, and we do not find that anything reaches the brain from the external sense organs except for motions of this kind. In view of all this we have every reason to conclude that the properties in external objects to which we apply the terms light, colour, smell, taste, sound, heat and cold—as well as the other tactile qualities . . .— are, so far as we can see, simply various dispositions in those objects which make them able to set up various kinds of motions in our nerves . (Principles IV 198, AT VIIIA 322, CSM I 285) Here we have a statement of the view that sensory qualities exist as sensations in our mind and can be said to exist mind-independently only in the sense that bodies exist that are able to trigger sensations in us. The passage also includes a gesture at Descartes’s argument. First, he makes the claim that there is no way to understand how bodies with features like size, shape, and motion can produce qualities like color and taste and sound. Here he appears to be assuming without argument that bodies with features like size and shape and motion do not already have qualities like color and taste and sound. If they did, it would not be so difficult to understand how they could produce color and taste and sound yet again. In fact, Descartes is supposing a background argument—an argument that piggybacks on one of his arguments for substance dualism. In that argument, he reflects on the nature of substance and infers that every substance has a principal attribute in terms of which all of its modifications can be explained or understood: Each substance has one principal property which constitutes its nature and essence, and to which all its other properties are referred. Thus extension in length, breadth and depth constitutes the nature of corporeal substance; and thought constitutes the nature of thinking substance. Everything else which can be attributed to body presupposes extension, and is merely a mode of an extended thing; and similarly whatever we find in the mind is simply one of the various modes of thinking. For example, shape is unintelligible except in an extended thing; and motion is unintelligible except as motion in extended space; while imagination, sensation and will are intelligible only in a thinking thing. (Principles I 53, AT VIIIA 25, CSM I 210–211)

DESCARTES AND THE FORCE OF SKEPTICISM

313

To generate the result that minds are immaterial substances, Descartes supposes that there are thinking modifications that are modifications of a substance and that any substance also has a principal attribute in terms of which its modifications can be understood. Descartes also supposes that substances have only one principal attribute. This is because we recognize (he thinks) that a substance and a principal attribute constitute a complete thing—that is, they together constitute a thing in its own right that does not depend on any other creature for its existence (Fourth Replies, AT VII 223, CSM II 157). A substance with the principal attribute of thought is a substance that has only modifications that can be understood in terms of thought; the substance does not have any other kinds of modification because the substance starts and stops with the attribute of thought, and modifications of a different kind would be understood in terms of a different principal attribute, which would be the principal attribute of a different substance (see also Rozemond 1998: ch. 1). Descartes is then making a similar argumentative move in concluding that bodies do not have sensory qualities. He thinks that if we have successfully detached from our senses, we are in a position to think of three-dimensional extension as colorless, tasteless, soundless, etc., and we recognize it to be a complete thing. If so, the only modifications of an extended substance are modifications that can be understood or explained in terms of colorless, tasteless, and soundless extension— features like size, shape, and motion. Descartes performs the thought experiment more vividly in the Second Meditation when he thinks of a piece of wax as not having qualities like color or taste or sound. He says, Let us concentrate, take away everything which does not belong to the wax, and see what is left: merely something extended, flexible, changeable. . . . I would not be making a correct judgment about the nature of wax unless I believed it capable of being extended in many more different ways than I will ever encompass in my imagination. (AT VII 31, CSM II 21) He appears to hold that, as a matter of fact, when we think of something extended and flexible in isolation from any sensory qualities, we are thinking of something that on its own constitutes a substance. Since sensory qualities cannot be explained or understood in terms of that, they are not modifications of bodies. But we do have sensations, and these are modifications of our mind (see also Principles I 66–68). In the end, Descartes offers a pragmatic account of the role of the senses. They do not inform us of the details of the bodies that surround us, but instead they help us to keep track of the features of our environment that are relevant to our well-being and survival. The function of sensory perceptions is not to be veridical—and they are not veridical—but they do help us to organize our activities and to live our lives: For the proper use of the sensory perceptions given me by nature is simply to inform the mind of what is beneficial or harmful for the composite of which the mind is a part; and to this extent they are sufficiently clear and distinct. But I misuse them by treating them as reliable touchstones for immediate judgements about the essential nature of the bodies located outside us; yet this is an area

314

SKEPTICISM

where they provide only obscure information. (Sixth Meditation, AT VII 83, CSM II 57–58) It will be enough, for the present, to note that sensory perceptions are related exclusively to this combination of the human body and mind. They normally tell us of the benefit or harm that external bodies may do to this combination, and do not, except occasionally and accidentally, show us what external bodies are like in themselves. (Principles II 3, AT VIIIA 41–42, CSM I 224; see also (Principles IV 204, AT VIIIA 327, CSM I 289 Here Descartes is clear that even the most vivid of sensory perceptions is not an indicator of the details of the bodies that surround us. Instead, sensory perceptions serve as a guide to help us to preserve our mind-body union (see also Simmons 2014). This setup is presumably very wise, for we might not pay attention to those aspects of our environment that are relevant to our survival if the signals were not gripping and loud. Descartes thinks that our sensory experience of the external world is non-veridical in another respect as well. Not only does the physical universe have no color, taste, sound, or light—again, not in anything like the way that we experience them—but it is a fully dense plenum, and the “empty” spaces that we take to be separate objects in fact are brimming with being and activity. Once again the reasoning that Descartes offers here is (and presumably had better be) non-sensory: if there was nothing between two objects, they would be touching, and so any objects that appear to be separated by empty space are in fact in contact with bodies that form a continuous stretch in between (Principles II 18, AT VIIIA 50, CSM I 231). We, however, tend to think that things are real to the extent that they are sensible, and to the extent that they are relevant to our needs and well-being, so when we do not sense anything in the “space” between objects, we conclude that there is nothing there (Principles I 71, AT VIIIA 35–36, CSM I 218–219). It cannot be overemphasized just how foreign is the world of external bodies, if Descartes’s non-sensory argumentation is right. The universe is a colorless plenum, etc., and there is a lot more that is going on in our local (and our faraway) environment than we would be prepared to admit. Descartes does not highlight the drama of the result here, but a passage from one of his contemporaries does the job nicely: Though it was not the intention of God or nature to abuse us herein, but a most wise contrivance thus to beautify and adorn the visible and material world, to add lustre or embellishment to it, that it might have charms, relishes, and allurements in it, to gratify our appetites. Whereas otherwise reality in itself, the whole corporeal world in its naked hue, is nothing else but a heap of dust or atoms, of several figures and magnitudes, variously agitated up and down. So that these things which we look upon as such real things without us, are not properly the modifications of bodies themselves, but several modifications, passions, and affections of our own souls. (Cudworth 1996: 148–149)6 For Descartes, the distinction between waking and dreaming is not a distinction between perceptions that are veridical and perceptions that are not. If we converge

DESCARTES AND THE FORCE OF SKEPTICISM

315

on primary notions that are not known through the senses, we can conclude on the firmest grounds possible that the world is a plenum that is devoid of sensory qualities and that the world that appears to us is an incomplete but attention-getting snapshot by which we can notice and register what is pertinent to our survival. Descartes thus has a view of sensory faculties that is similar to the view that we find in Plato. Descartes does not just think that the senses deliver less probability or certainty than the intellect—where sensory perceptions might be exactly veridical, but we just cannot be sure. Instead, he holds with Plato that when it comes to metaphysical truth sensory perception is off kilter: Then what about the actual acquiring of knowledge? Is the body an obstacle when one associates with it in the search for knowledge? I mean, for example, do men find any truth in sight or hearing, or are not even the poets forever telling us that we do not see or hear anything accurately, and surely if those two physical senses are not clear or precise, our other senses can hardly be accurate, as they are all inferior to these. . . .Then he will [grasp knowledge] most perfectly who approaches the object with thought alone, without associating any sight with his thought, or dragging in any sense perception with his reasoning, but who, using pure thought alone, tries to track down each reality pure and by itself. (Plato, Phaedo 65a–66b; I use the translation in Plato 2002) Descartes agrees that the picture of reality that is secured through the senses is hardly accurate at all. He is using the skeptical arguments of the First Meditation, not to show that our beliefs about the external world are less probable than we thought, but to get us to practice a non-sensory kind of thinking that (on his view) reveals with full confidence that the external world is almost nothing like we experience it. He recognizes that the First Meditation skeptical arguments are not especially original (see also Fine 2000). What is original, he thinks, is how he repurposes them in order to help us to detach from our senses and arrive at non-sensory results that are the real guide to how things are.

5  HYPERBOLIC DOUBT IS UNINTELLIGIBLE UPON REFLECTION We still need to consider the remaining skeptical arguments that Descartes advances. After offering the dream argument, he introduces an even more radical worry—that perhaps we are wrong about matters that we find to be completely evident. As he says in his Sixth Meditation restatement of the worry: Since I did not know the author of my being (or at least was pretending not to), I saw nothing to rule out the possibility that my natural constitution made me prone to error even in matters which seemed to me most true. (AT VII 77, CSM II 53) In the First Meditation, he offers three versions of the worry that perhaps our minds are deceived about matters that we find completely evident. In the first, he considers that since God is omnipotent, He certainly has the power to create our minds to

316

SKEPTICISM

be defective, and since our own occasional errors are consistent with His goodness, for all we know He has reason for creating our rational faculties to be deceived all the time. Descartes does not fill in the details as to why this rationale might be compelling, but we might speculate—perhaps God wants us to recognize that our rational faculties are worthless so that we focus more of our energies on faith.7 In the second version, Descartes concedes that for all we know God does not exist, and that, if so, our minds are the product of a creator of a different kind. He says that perhaps I have arrived at my present state by fate or chance or a continuous chain of events, or by some other means; yet since deception and error seem to be imperfections, the less powerful they make my original cause, the more likely it is that I am so imperfect as to be deceived all the time. (AT VII 21, CSM II 14) As in the first version of the argument, Descartes is making an assertion to the effect that something is possible, and then he is concluding from that assertion that it is possible that our minds are mistaken about matters that are completely evident to us. In the third version, Descartes returns to the question of the motives of a fully benevolent God and allows that presumably such a being would not have created us with defective minds, but still there might exist an evil demon that is constantly at work to deceive us (AT VII 22–23, CSM II 15). Descartes supposes that this being might be so powerful and malicious that “it is not in my power to know any truth” (AT VII 22–23, CSM II 15, emphasis added).8 We recognize that two and three add to five, but perhaps a demon is tricking us into thinking that they add to five when in fact they add to something else. At this point we might want to ask whether or not Descartes is entitled to assume the various possibilities that undergird the three versions of the First Meditation skeptical argument about the reliability of our minds. The reason that we want to ask is that there are passages later in the Meditations and also outside the Meditations in which Descartes says without prevarication that God cannot deceive and is a necessary existent and the author of all reality—our minds included. For example, in the Third Meditation he concludes that God exists, is not a deceiver, and is the creator of all things in such a way that nothing is independent of Him (AT VII 45, CSM II 31; AT VII 51–52, CSM II 350). In the Fifth Meditation he argues that God exists necessarily and that deception is inconsistent with His nature (AT VII 65–71, CSM II 45–49). Outside of the Meditations, to one of his correspondents, he writes, “God is thought of as a deceiver.” This is foolish. Although in my First Meditation I did speak of a supremely powerful deceiver, the conception there was in no way of the true God, since, as he himself says, it is impossible that the true God should be a deceiver. But if he is asked how he knows this is impossible, he must answer that he knows it from the fact that it implies a conceptual contradiction—that is, it cannot be conceived. (Letter to Voetius, May 1643, AT VIII B 60, CSMK 222)9 Descartes thinks that it follows from non-sensory axioms that God is a necessary existent and that there does not exist the possibility that we are deceived about matters that are completely evident to us. That is, he thinks that it follows from

DESCARTES AND THE FORCE OF SKEPTICISM

317

non-sensory axioms that there does not exist the possibility that God created us with defective minds, or the possibility that God did not create us, or the possibility that God created an evil demon that is constantly deceiving us. If Descartes is right that all of these follow from undeniable primary notions, then he would conclude that none of the First Meditation possibilities is a possibility at all. They are unexamined; they conflict with results that are transparent and obvious; and as per Principles I 75 they should be dismissed. Descartes does not finally arrive at an Archimedean point until early in the Second Meditation, and the skeptical results of the First Meditation help him to do that. The first two skeptical arguments work to neutralize our allegiance to the senses, with the goal that we might recognize non-sensory axioms as a higher caliber point of departure. The remaining skeptical arguments turn us yet further away from the senses and begin to focus our attention on our minds and their activities and contents. We are not yet ready to conclude “I am, I exist” with the highest level of clarity, however (see also Cunning 2007). Descartes assumes that because we are so practiced at thinking in terms of sensory pictures and images, we enter the Meditations with ideas of mind and God that are highly adulterated—we think of God as a bearded man on a cloud, for example, and of mind as something that can be pictured and touched and felt.10 The hyperbolic arguments in the second half of the First Meditation help us to focus our attention on mind, and then when we finally think of mind in a way that does not involve the senses, we arrive at the sort of non-sensory result that Descartes thinks is the bread and butter of philosophical demonstration and that makes other results pale in comparison. At the start of the Second Meditation, we consider whether there is anything that is still true even if we have no senses and our minds are deceived. Descartes writes: Is there not a God, or whatever I may call him, who puts into me the thoughts I am now having? But why do I think this, since I myself may be the author of these thoughts? In that case am not I, at least, something? But I have just said that I have no senses and no body? This is the sticking point: what follows from this? . . . But I have convinced myself that there is absolutely nothing in the world, no sky, no earth, no minds, no bodies. Does it not follow that I too do not exist? No: if I convinced myself of something then I certainly existed. But there is a deceiver of supreme power and cunning who is deliberately and constantly deceiving me. In that case too I undoubtedly exist, if he is deceiving me; and let him deceive me as much as he can, he will never bring it about that I am nothing so long as I think that I am something. (AT VII 25, CSM II 16–17) Here Descartes is using the skeptical arguments to zero in on a result that can survive them. He proceeds to converge on other non-sensory results as the Meditations unfolds: that body is essentially extended, changeable, and flexible (and in ways that neither the senses nor imagination are able to capture); that something cannot come from nothing (or, as Descartes puts it in the case of ideas in the Third Meditation, that the objective reality of an idea requires a cause with at least as much formal reality)11; and that the idea of God has infinite objective reality. When we recognize the truth of these claims and others like them, then so

318

SKEPTICISM

long as we are sufficiently disciplined to trust what is clear upon reflection over what is clear at first glance, we will appreciate that the contentions of the skeptic have to be weighed against non-sensory primary notions, and Descartes thinks that the former cannot compete. Descartes did not take skeptical arguments to be threatening at all, except to beliefs that deserve to be cast aside. His own skeptical arguments might upend some of our beliefs, however. If we think that the distinction between waking and dreaming is a distinction between perceptual experience that tracks what the outside world is like and perceptual experience that does not, or if we think that there really exists the possibility that we were created by chance, or the possibility that an evil demon is deceiving us, then we have a lot of work to do. Descartes did not think that these possibilities existed. He did not take skeptical arguments to be serious. He had a much higher opinion of the non-sensory axioms that come in the Second Meditation and beyond.

NOTES 1. Translations are from Descartes (1984/5, 1991). References also specify the standard pagination in Descartes (1996). 2. Bernard Williams (1978: 54) famously remarks that the dream argument is highlighting the universal possibility of illusion, but not the possibility of universal illusion. 3. Descartes takes all of these to be false. For example, he argues at the end of the Second Meditation that a central component of any belief that we have about a body is an idea of extension that is not acquired through the senses (AT VII 30–32, CSM II 20–21). See also Cunning (2010: ch. 2). 4. See also the discussion in Broughton (2008: 97–98). Broughton also makes a number of nice connections between the skeptical arguments of the First Meditation and the argumentation in Descartes’s dialogue, The Search for Truth. 5. See also “Dedicatory Letter to the Sorbonne,” AT VII 4, CSM II 5; Second Replies, AT VII 130–131, CSM II 94; and Third Replies, AT VII 171–172, CSM II 121. 6. See also Berkeley: “It is thought strangely absurd that upon closing my eyelids, all the visible objects round me should be reduced to nothing; and yet is not this what philosophers commonly acknowledge, when they agree on all hands, that light and colours, which alone are the proper and immediate objects of sight, are mere sensations that exist no longer than they are perceived?” (Berkeley 1975: I 46, 105– 106). See also Cavendish 1655: 174, and Cavendish 1653: 44–45. 7. See, for example, the discussion of seventeenth-century views of faith versus reason in Popkin (1979: ch. 7). 8. See also the Second Meditation: “I will make an effort and once more attempt the same path I started on yesterday. Anything which admits of the slightest doubt I will set aside just as if I had found it to be wholly false; and I will proceed in this way until I recognize something certain, or, if nothing else, until I at least recognize for certain that there is no certainty” (AT VII 24, CSM II 16). 9. See also Principles I 14; AT VIIIA 8, CSM I 197–198.

DESCARTES AND THE FORCE OF SKEPTICISM

319

10. Second Replies, AT VII 130–131, CSM II 94; Fifth Replies, AT VII 365, CSM II 252; Principles I 71–73, AT VIIIA 35–37, CSM I 218–220. 11. See the Third Meditation, AT VII 40, CSM II 28; and Second Replies, AT VII 135, CSM II 97.

REFERENCES Berkeley, George. 1975. Principles of Human Knowledge. In M. Ayers (ed.), Philosophical Works. London: J. M. Dent. Broughton, Janet. 2008. Descartes’s Method of Doubt. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Cavendish, Margaret. 1653. Poems and Fancies. London: Printed by T. R. for J. Martin and J. Allestrye. Cavendish, Margaret. 1655. The Worlds Olio. London: Printed for J. Martin and J. Allestrye. Cudworth, Ralph. 1996. A Treatise Concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality, edited by S. Hutton. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cunning, David. 2007. “Descartes on the Dubitability of the Existence of Self,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 111–131. Cunning, David. 2010. Argument and Persuasion in Descartes’ Meditations. New York: Oxford University Press. Cunning, David (ed.). 2014. The Cambridge Companion to Descartes’ Meditations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Curley, E. M. 1978. Descartes against the Skeptics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Descartes, René. 1984/5, 1991. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, 3 vols, edited by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D. Murdoch, and A. Kenny. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Descartes, René. 1996. Œuvres de Descartes, 11 vols, edited by C. Adam and P. Tannery. Paris: Vrin. Fine, Gail. 2000. “Descartes and Ancient Skepticism: Reheated Cabbage?,” The Philosophical Review 109: 195–234. Larmore, Charles. 2014. “The First Meditation: Skeptical Doubt and Certainty.” In D. Cunning (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Descartes’ Meditations, 48–67. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Plato. 2002.  Phaedo. In Plato: Five Dialogues, 2nd edn., translated by G. M. A. Grube. Indianapolis: Hackett. Popkin, Richard. 1979. The History of Skepticism, from Erasmus to Spinoza. Berkeley: California University Press. Rozemond, Marleen. 1998. Descartes’s Dualism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Simmons, Alison. 2014. “Sensory Perception of Bodies: Meditation 6.5.” In D. Cunning (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Descartes’ Meditations, 263–274. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Williams, Bernard. 1978. Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. London: Penguin.

CHAPTER TWENTY-THREE

Varieties of Modern Academic Skepticism: Pierre-Daniel Huet and Simon Foucher MICHAEL W. HICKSON

1 INTRODUCTION Thanks in large part to decades of research by Richard H. Popkin, it is now beyond doubt that there was a revival of ancient skepticism in the early modern period. However, current historians have begun to doubt Popkin’s claim that the skeptical problem in early modernity was “more aptly described as a crise pyrrhonienne than as a crise academicienne” (Popkin 2003: xx). Following Popkin, the literature on the history of skepticism in the early modern period was for decades almost exclusively focused on the revival of ancient Pyrrhonism as it is outlined by Sextus Empiricus. Whether ancient Academic skepticism—that of Arcesilaus, Carneades, and Cicero for example—influenced the writings of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century skeptics was mostly ignored. While Charles B. Schmitt (1972) demonstrated that Cicero’s Academica was the focus of scholarly interest up to the Renaissance, it was not until the work of José R. Maia Neto (1997) that historians of skepticism took seriously the idea that early modern skepticism was much indebted to the ancient Academics. There may have been a crise academicienne after all. In a recent book, Maia Neto (2014) offers a broad interpretation of early seventeenth-century philosophy that, like Popkin’s work (2003), focuses on the importance of skepticism, but this time Academic skepticism. The unifying thread is Pierre Charron’s 1601 work, De la sagesse, which lays out a skeptical account of wisdom, which Charron describes as the highest excellence achievable by human beings, but one which “does not presuppose the attainment of certain knowledge as the dogmatist would claim, but only full accomplishment of its integrity” (Maia Neto 2014: 26). Charron understands integrity in the way expressed in the Academica,

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

321

where Cicero suggests that Academics “are more free and untrammeled in that [they] possess [their] power of judgment uncurtailed [integra nobis est iudicandi potestas]” (Cicero 1979: 475; Maia Neto 2014: 25). Maia Neto argues that Charronian skeptical wisdom was a central concern of philosophers in the early seventeenth century, some of whom defended the concept (La Mothe Le Vayer and Gassendi), others of whom attempted to go beyond mere integrity to the possession of certain knowledge (Pascal and Descartes). Maia Neto’s groundbreaking article continues this interpretation into the late seventeenth century, when “Academic skepticism had a spectacular comeback . . . with some of the major anti-Cartesians of the period” (1997: 203). Other scholars (Lennon 2003a, 2008; Charles 2013a, b) have added support to Maia Neto’s claims that Pierre-Daniel Huet and Simon Foucher, in particular, were greatly influenced by Academic skepticism. Even Popkin, in the last edition of his magnum opus, concedes that Foucher is better understood as an Academic than as a Pyrrhonist (Popkin 2003: 275). Classifying past philosophers with labels such as “skeptic,” “Pyrrhonist,” or “Academic” is little more than a game, however, unless the labels highlight similarities between those philosophers’ texts and ultimately help us to understand the texts better. So in this chapter I ask whether labeling Huet and Foucher Academic skeptics helps us to identify important similarities shared by these philosophers. In good skeptical fashion, I will argue “yes and no.” Both Huet and Foucher can meaningfully be called Academic skeptics. The label “Academic” applies to Huet and Foucher because both wrote histories of the ancient Academics and both tried to revive core aspects of Academic skepticism. Moreover, the common label focuses our attention on a common goal of the philosophers: to undermine dogmatic aspects of Cartesianism by means of self-styled Academic arguments. However, matters quickly become complicated because Huet and Foucher had radically different conceptions of Academic philosophy, and both explicitly rejected the label of “Academic skepticism” for their works. Moreover, while both Huet and Foucher principally attacked Descartes, Huet’s attack is complete and unrelenting, undermining Cartesian epistemology and metaphysics, while Foucher’s attack is limited to Cartesian metaphysics and, ironically, is based firmly on Descartes’s epistemology, which Foucher even sought to defend against the radical sort of skepticism advanced by Huet. In what follows, I give overviews of the lives and works of Huet and Foucher, and I present and analyze each philosopher’s interpretation of Academic philosophy. The theme of skepticism in the writings of these two figures is too broad to treat exhaustively in this chapter, so I limit my attention to the skeptical attacks of each thinker on the philosophy of Descartes, and in particular to the views of Huet and Foucher on Descartes’s criterion of truth. These are the topics that best expose the similarities, but also the differences, between these Academic skeptics.

2  PIERRE-DANIEL HUET: LIFE AND WORKS Pierre-Daniel Huet (1630–1721) was a quintessential citizen of the Republic of Letters—erudite and eloquent, well-connected and well-traveled, polymath,

322

SKEPTICISM

polyglot, and prolific.1 From his pen we have an edition and Latin translation of Origen’s biblical commentaries; a spin-off treatise on translation; scores of Latin and French poems on subjects as diverse as the reign of Louis XIV and the chemical nature of salt; a refutation of Descartes’s philosophy (Huet 1689, 1694/2003); a satirical story about the Cartesians; a novel, as well as a history of the genre of novels; a treatise on the location of the Garden of Eden; and a work that could have been called Summa skeptica but was instead entitled A Philosophical Treatise on the Weakness of the Human Mind (Huet 1723; henceforth, Treatise).2 Huet was born in the village of Caen, France, to noble parents, both of whom he lost by the age of six. The gloomy tone of Huet’s Memoirs becomes much cheerier once Huet begins his study of belles lettres and philosophy at the Jesuit College in Caen, which he later fondly remembered as his “second parent and foster mother” (Huet 1810: vol. 1, 57). A scholarly career was launched that would quickly gain the attention of Europe’s greatest minds, as well as its most renowned monarchs. Queen Christina beckoned Huet numerous times to join her in Sweden, and King Louis XIV made Huet, along with Bossuet, one of the Dauphin’s preceptors. Huet’s prestige increased in 1674 with his election to the Académie française, and then again in 1692 when he was consecrated bishop of Avranches. Precisely how, when, and why Huet became a fierce opponent of Cartesianism and a skeptic is debated (see Lennon 2008: 6–29). From Huet’s Memoirs we learn the following relevant details. Shortly after completing his study of philosophy with the Jesuits in Caen (in the mid-1640s), Huet reports that he learned about Descartes’s new system of philosophy, and that he “could not rest till I had procured and thoroughly perused his book; and I cannot easily express the admiration which this new mode of philosophizing excited in my young mind, when, from the simplest and plainest principles, I saw so many dazzling wonders brought forth” (Huet 1810: vol. 1, 29). But Huet would not remain Cartesian forever: I was for many years closely engaged in the study of Cartesianism . . . and I long wandered in the mazes of this reasoning delirium, till mature years, and a full examination of the system from its foundations, compelled me to renounce it, as I obtained demonstrative proof that it was a baseless structure, and tottered from the very ground. (Huet 1810: vol. 1, 30) To understand why Huet ultimately rejected Descartes, we need another piece of Huet’s intellectual biography. Around the time he discovered Descartes, Huet also discovered the study of ancient “Oriental” languages and literatures through his friendship with Samuel Bochart (see Shelford 2007: 35–39). The war of influence between Bochart’s antiquarianism and Descartes’s modernism in Huet’s young mind was unstable and ultimately forced Huet to take a side. Huet’s rejection of Cartesian philosophy likely dates to 1674, when he read Malebranche’s Search after Truth (1674/1997), parts of which attack the kind of erudite learning that Bochart helped Huet to appreciate and cultivate (see Lennon 2008: 21–29). Huet sided with antiquity. Not surprisingly, Huet later found himself, as a member of the Academie française, in the midst of the Battle of the Ancients and Moderns (officially begun

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

323

in 1687). Huet discusses the Battle several times in his Memoirs and indicates that those like Marets and Perrault who championed the moderns did so because of arrogance, ignorance, lack of taste, insanity, and to their “perpetual disgrace” (see Huet 1810: vol. 2, 2, 186, 189). Arrogance and ignorance are again the cardinal vices Huet identifies in Malebranche’s Search after Truth (see Lennon 2008: 23). The Cartesians are obsessed with appearing novel, yet—and this is what irks Huet more than anything else—they rarely advance beyond the ancient philosophers, and they plagiarize their best arguments (Huet 1694/2003: 214–229). Fifteen years elapsed between Huet’s reading of Malebranche and the publication of his first antiCartesian work. The impetus finally to make his objections to Descartes and the Cartesians public may have been Foucher, whose anti-Cartesian works discussed below demonstrated to Huet that Cartesianism was not only misguided but also dangerous to Christianity (see Lennon 2003a: 122–128; 2008: 32–41; Rapetti 2003: 111–142). The weapon ultimately employed by Huet against the Cartesians was skepticism, which, ironically, Huet first encountered in the writings of Descartes (see Maia Neto 2008b for the Cartesian roots of Huet’s skepticism). Huet knew only the name of Sextus Empiricus until around 1660, when he met Louis de Cormis, a former president of the Parliament of Aix, who became Huet’s close friend and who spoke of little else besides the ancient philosophers. It was Cormis who first urged Huet to peruse the works of Sextus. Later, in the 1680s, Huet recounts that he immersed himself again in the study of ancient philosophy, this time with Diogenes Laertius as his guide, along with the commentary on Diogenes by Huet’s friend, Gilles Menage. As we learn from the posthumous Treatise, Huet found through his careful study of the ancients proof after proof that “the truth cannot be known by human understanding, by means of reason, with perfect and complete certainty” (Huet 1723: xxix). Huet’s most skeptical writings—the Treatise3 (Huet 1723), Censura philosophiae cartesianae (Huet 1689; Huet 1694/2003), and Alnetanae Quaestiones (Huet 1690), all composed between 1680 and 1690—were meant to be parts of a single treatise with the sections corresponding roughly to the works just given in the order just given (see Maia Neto 2008a: 167–172). Huet’s system would establish the limits and the correct use of reason in supporting the Catholic faith. For a variety of reasons (see Maia Neto 2008a: 164), Huet abandoned the larger, unified project and the works were published separately. Together, these works elaborate a claim that Huet made at the outset of his earlier Demonstratio evangelica (Huet 1679), namely, that skepticism, which renders doubtful and uncertain everything that we know by reason and the senses, is not opposed to religion (Huet 1679: 5). Still, Huet did not wish to urge an irrational faith upon his readers. It was his contention that the careful study of antiquity—the languages, culture, times, and places when the Hebrew and Christian Revelations were given—was the best preparation for the faith, though this preparation could only ever achieve probability. However, since the time of Descartes, philosophers and even some theologians were pleased with the use of reason in the preambles of faith only if reason attained the highest degree of certainty—clarity and distinctness—as it allegedly did in

324

SKEPTICISM

Descartes’s proofs for the existence of God. But in Huet’s view, reason at its best never attains such a pitch of certainty, so if the bar is set this high, reason’s real, but humble, achievements in support of faith will be disdained. So Huet had to correct his readers’ expectations and show the value of the correct antiquarian path that reason paves toward the faith (see Quantin 1994). The Treatise deals with reason along with its limits, weaknesses, and need for the faith. The Censura is an application of the Treatise, refuting the Cartesian view of reason while attempting to repair the damage done by it to the faith. The Alnetanae Quaestiones finally treat the proper accord of faith and reason, while attempting to prove that the study of antiquity leads to the faith. There is much to say about these three works, but in what follows I limit myself to important aspects of the Treatise and Censura that clarify Huet’s relation to Academic skepticism and to Foucher.

3  HUET’S INTERPRETATION AND PRAISE OF ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM Book one of Huet’s Treatise is devoted to proving that the “truth cannot be known by the human understanding, by means of reason, with perfect and complete certainty” (Huet 1723: xxix). Huet opens the book with twelve philosophical arguments for this conclusion, derived mainly from classical skeptical tropes, such as the lack of a criterion of truth, the unreliability of the senses, and the changing nature of things. The thirteenth argument is historical and takes up the rest of book one. It involves a sweeping history of philosophy, from Pythagoras to Maimonides, which demonstrates that the inaccessibility of the truth by human reason has always been acknowledged to varying extents by the best writers. The bulk of this thirteenth argument is a lengthy treatment of the various ancient Academies, their evolution, and their relation to Pyrrhonian skepticism. Huet’s conclusion is that only the Academic and Pyrrhonian skeptics, who constitute a single sect in Huet’s view, fully appreciated the inaccessibility of absolute certainty in the human and divine sciences. From the outset of his history of the Academy, it is clear that Huet associates the school primarily with doubt and the profession of ignorance: “From [Socrates] there emerged several sects of philosophers, of which the most famous, the Academy, followed the wise method of doubting everything, and even augmented and brought this method to its fullest perfection” (Huet 1723: 107). The Academy evolved over time, but each instantiation was just another branch of a single tree, whose trunk was “this first principle, posited by Socrates, that man knows nothing” (Huet 1723: 132). After surveying historical rival attempts to enumerate ancient Academies, Huet settles on the following division: “We must agree, therefore, that properly speaking there were two Academies: the old [l’ancien] Academy, that of Socrates and Antiochus, and the new Academy, that of Arcesilaus, Carneades, and Philo; and I maintain that the new Academy was nothing other than Pyrrhonian philosophy” (Huet 1723: 138). The method of the old Academy involved doubt and the constant refutation of the views of others. It led, however, to a positive assertion that brought consolation,

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

325

namely, that a very limited wisdom is available through the recognition that “all that I can know is that I know nothing.” The new Academy followed but greatly extended the method of doubt and disagreement of the old Academy, even to the point of renouncing Socrates’s famous adage just quoted: we cannot even know that we know nothing. It was Arcesilaus who brought the Academy to this skeptical extreme: “We must consider [Arcesilaus], therefore, as not only the restorer, but also as the reformer of the doctrine of Socrates and of the old Academy. He is the one who gave birth to the new Academy, which is based on a more solid foundation than the old” (Huet 1723: 111). Arcesilaus was converted to his way of thinking by Pyrrho, and though he retained the name of the Academy, Arcesilaus turned it into a Pyrrhonian school. Although the views of the next head of the Academy, Carneades, differed from those of Arcesilaus in the particulars, fundamentally the two were of like mind because they denied the existence of any criterion of scientific truth. Huet’s only remark about the next head, Philo, is that he too taught that we cannot understand anything completely by means of reason. The new Academics were therefore all Pyrrhonian skeptics, who, according to Huet, were characterized by the facts that “they acknowledged no truth rule, no reasoning, no mark for recognizing the truth; they affirmed nothing, defined nothing, judged nothing; they did not even believe that a thing was more this than that” (Huet 1723: 125). Like the Pyrrhonists, the Academic skeptics were zetetics; the work of their philosophy involved searching for the truth, but never settling on anything in particular as The Truth, not even the assertion that the truth is unattainable. Huet considers numerous possible differences between the Academic and Pyrrhonian skeptics, but he refutes all of them, reducing the differences to mere language (Huet 1723: 139–150). Huet devotes so much attention to Academic skepticism in his Treatise that the reader is led to believe that the author of this work must himself be an Academic skeptic. But in book two of the Treatise, which is an exposition of the “surest and most legitimate way of philosophizing,” Huet denies very explicitly that he belongs to the sect of Academic skepticism, or to any sect for that matter: “Let us be especially careful never to become attached to the opinions of any particular author, or to become members of any sect” (Huet 1723: 213). True philosophers must instead follow their own philosophies, taking whatever seems best from all sects and all authors. The way to determine what is best among the competing views is to “weigh all things in the balance of our mind, reserving at all times a complete liberty to think and to speak on every philosophical subject” (Huet 1723: 213). Yet this disavowal of every sect is in fact a strong argument for interpreting Huet as an Academic skeptic, and for recognizing a distinction in Huet’s mind (malgré lui) between Academic and Pyrrhonian skepticism. According to Cicero (Acad. II 8, in Cicero 1979: 475), it is part of the nature of Academic skepticism to uphold the freedom of one’s judgment and consequently to refrain from settling in any camp and from accepting any label for one’s views: Academic skeptics must always deny that they are members of any school, including that of Academic skepticism. Sextus Empiricus, on the other hand, permitted at least a tentative commitment to the school of Pyrrhonism (PH I.16-17; Sextus Empiricus 2000: 7).

326

SKEPTICISM

After refusing to pledge allegiance to any philosophy, Huet tellingly justifies this practice by citing a number of authors who were likewise fiercely independent thinkers: Arcesilaus, Carneades, Philo, and Antiochus (Huet 1723: 213–214)— all Academics! That said, it is important always to recall that Huet’s revival of Academic skepticism is in many ways indistinguishable from a revival of Pyrrhonian skepticism. We will see this most clearly in the next section when we consider Huet’s skeptical objections to Descartes which are largely based on Pyrrhonian skeptical tropes. However, Huet’s great interest in Academic skepticism, evidenced by his lengthy history of it that was given pride of place in his Treatise; his emphasis on the Academic goal of complete freedom of judgment (noted in the paragraph above); his clear preference for the title “Academic” rather than “Pyrrhonist” based on the long list of distinguished philosophers who held the former (Huet 1723: 150); and his very explicit rejection of the goal of ataraxia for his philosophy (Huet 1723: 215), give us reasons to follow Maia Neto in classing Huet among the Academic, rather than Pyrrhonian, skeptics. Moreover, as we will see below, one of Huet’s contemporaries, Foucher, considered Huet part of a revival of the ancient Academy. Nevertheless, the ambiguity between Academic and Pyrrhonian skepticism in Huet’s works is one of the chief reasons for my own skepticism, noted in the Introduction above, about the use of the term “Academic” to denote the spirit of the French antiCartesians of the late seventeenth century.

4  HUET’S OBJECTIONS TO DESCARTES’S CRITERIA OF TRUTH Huet put his skepticism to work against the Cartesians, who claimed to possess not only some part of wisdom, but more importantly the very foundation of all wisdom: the criteria of truth. All eighteen sections of the second chapter of the Censura are devoted to undermining Descartes’s criteria of truth—criteria, not criterion, since Huet begins by observing that there are at least three criteria that Descartes employs in his philosophical works: the natural light, clarity and distinctness, and evidence [évidence]4 (Huet 1694/2003: 120). Huet observes that some Cartesians treat I think, therefore, I am as if it were itself a criterion, but Huet considers this view absurd since propositions, their truth, and the mark of their truth must be distinct things (Huet 1694/2003: 115). Thus the skeptical objections to Descartes’s criteria will focus on the natural light, clarity and distinctness, and evidence. Objections to criteria of truth are central to Huet’s Academic skepticism, for in his view “it is one of the main points of skeptical teaching that nothing is evident” (Huet 1694/2003: 111). Huet attempts to give some order to the three separate criteria before undermining them: [Descartes] plainly distinguishes [the natural light and clarity-and-distinctness] when he asserts that the natural light does not attain anything that is not true, in so far as it is attained by the natural light, that is, in so far as it is clearly and

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

327

distinctly perceived [see Descartes, Principles I 30; AT VIIIA 16; CSM I 203]. It thus follows that the natural light is what attains the object of perception, and that a clear and distinct perception is the action with which a thing is attained by the natural light. It is as if the natural light were the criterion through which [per quod], and clear and distinct perception the criterion according to which [secundum quid]. (Huet 1694/2003: 120–121) Huet’s interpretation of Principles I 30 is plausible, since Descartes refers to the natural light there as “the faculty of knowledge” itself; so it is the thing that actually grasps objects of perception, while clear and distinct perception is that faculty’s activity by means of which those objects are perceived. Huet then interprets Cartesian evidence to be a more general criterion: [Descartes] seems to take evidence to be something general that ought to be in everything we perceive that deserves to be regarded as true, whether it is perceived through the natural light, or through clear and distinct perception, or through reasoning, or through the senses, or in some other way. (Huet 1694/2003: 121) Huet’s objection to the natural light is that it is too general a criterion: Descartes defines the natural light as “the faculty of knowing given to us by God” [Descartes, Principles I 30; AT VIIIA 16; CSM I 203]. From this it follows that whatever we know through a faculty of knowing given to us by God is known to us by the natural light. But whatever we know is something that we know through a faculty of knowing that is given to us by God. Whatever we know, therefore, is known by the natural light, which is clearly absurd. (Huet 1694/2003: 121) As Huet sees it, the problem that a criterion of truth is supposed to resolve is how to distinguish genuine knowledge from merely apparent knowledge. Our faculty of knowledge is therefore being called into question. To appeal to that very faculty of knowledge to resolve this issue—which is what we do by appealing to the natural light—is to beg the question, not to resolve it. Huet employs a battery of arguments against the criterion of clear and distinct perception, but his strongest objections are his applications of the skeptical modes of Agrippa outlined by Sextus. Huet observes that clarity and distinctness is a relative concept (the third mode of Agrippa): one and the same idea can appear clear and distinct to one person, but not to another. This phenomenon gives rise to interminable rational disagreements (the first mode of Agrippa): “The Cartesians also disagree among themselves and, using the same standard of truth, maintain opposite and contradictory views” (Huet 1694/2003: 127). Either these disputing Cartesians will simply assert that their own perceptions (and not their opponents’) are clear and distinct, in which case they will fall prey to the Agrippan mode of hypothesis (the fourth mode); or they will bring in something other than clarity and distinctness to decide these disputes, which demonstrates that clarity and distinctness cannot be the ultimate criterion of truth. But whatever additional criterion they appeal to in order to decide the dispute will then be questioned, and the dispute

328

SKEPTICISM

will either go on ad infinitum (the second mode), with each further criterion being bolstered by yet another criterion, or the dispute will be circular (the fifth mode), since the disputants will support the further criterion by means of criteria posited earlier in the dispute (Huet 1694/2003: 128–129). In the Censura, the criterion of evidence gets little further attention, since Huet considers the forgoing arguments sufficient for refuting this criterion: If the senses, the mind, and the operations of the mind, the clear and distinct perceptions of things, and the natural light are all deceptive means of knowing the truth, however great the evidence attached to them, then they will not in the least be certain. (Huet 1694/2003: 129) Once the faculty of reason itself, the natural light, has been called into question, all additional criteria of truth are undermined, including evidence. However, in the Treatise Huet offers several pages of additional objections to evidence, most of which are based on Pyrrhonian skeptical tropes. One novel objection, however, is Huet’s neurological objection to evidence. All ideas and images in the understanding, Huet claims earlier (Huet 1723: 49–50), are formed by impulses on the brain and movements of nerve fibers and animal spirits. Since evidence is just a quality or modification of ideas and images, it follows that the causes of evidence are the same as the causes of ideas and images—brain impulses and various other internal motions. Once reduced to brain and other bodily activity, it is possible that evidence is accidentally caused by some physical aspect of the knower, rather than by the truth of the matter in question. In Huet’s mind, these rejections of Descartes’s criteria of truth are an indispensable preamble to receiving the faith, since they humble reason and demonstrate its need for faith. They are Huet’s most fundamental Academic skeptical exercise. I have dwelt so long on these objections because they distinguish Huet’s Academic skepticism from that of Foucher, who not only did not attack the foundations of Descartes’s epistemology, but who even tried to defend those foundations against skeptical arguments like those just outlined.

5  SIMON FOUCHER: LIFE AND WORKS Simon Foucher (1644–1696) was a historian, apologist, and systematizer of the philosophy of the ancient Academics, as well as a critic of Cartesian philosophy. His stated goal was to do for the ancient Academy what Sextus had done for Pyrrhonism and what Pierre Gassendi had done for Epicureanism (Foucher 1693: 2). Foucher’s interest in Academic philosophy was not merely exegetical; he modernized and applied that philosophy to critique the main ideas of leading philosophers of his time, especially Descartes, Malebranche, and Leibniz. Foucher was born in Dijon in 1644, received Holy Orders early in life, became the honorary canon of the Holy Chapel in Dijon shortly thereafter, then soon left any work this position entailed (but not the title) to study in the faculty of theology at the Sorbonne, after which he never left Paris. Besides these few points

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

329

and the general fact that Foucher was early on a well-connected intellectual with wide-ranging literary, philosophical, and scientific interests and abilities, most of the details of Foucher’s early life have been lost. The latter half of Foucher’s biography is indistinguishable from his bibliography. He is said to have died from exhaustion from studying and writing.5 Adrien Baillet, in his biography of Descartes, alleges that, when Descartes’s remains were returned to Paris in 1667, the notable Cartesian, Jacques Rohault, asked Foucher to deliver the funeral oration. The truth of this claim has been questioned (see Rabbe 1867: 4–5; Watson 1987: 33–34). Whether or not Foucher was given the honor early in life of eulogizing Descartes, we know beyond any doubt that Foucher’s later life was spent burying Descartes’s and his followers’ metaphysics deep in the ground. Foucher is remembered most of all for his polemic with Malebranche, which began with a coincidence. In 1673, Foucher began circulating among his closest friends several copies of a short treatise of his entitled Dissertation on the Search after Truth, or on the Logic of the Academics. The coincidence is that in the following year Malebranche published the first volume of his best-known work with a very similar title, On the Search after Truth. Foucher believed that Malebranche published his work as a response to Foucher’s call for fellow laborers in the search after truth (Watson 1987: 35), and so he felt obliged to correct Malebranche’s errors. A decades-long debate surrounding foundational elements of Cartesianism followed the publication of Foucher’s 1675 Critique of the Search after Truth (Watson and Greene 1995: 13–57). The debate with Malebranche established Foucher as one of the foremost critics of Cartesianism and brought him into dialogue and debate with a number of leading philosophers. First to respond to Foucher was the Benedictine monk and defender of Cartesianism, Dom Robert Desgabets, who published his Critique of the Critique of the Search after Truth, also in 1675. This work forced Foucher to clarify his understanding of and relation to ancient Academic skepticism, which Foucher did in his 1687 Apology on Behalf of the Academics and in his 1693 History and Principles of the Academics, which are the best sources for Foucher’s own philosophical ideas. Other orthodox Cartesians, including Louis de la Forge, Pierre-Sylvain Régis, and Antoine Arnauld, were moved by Foucher’s objections to Malebranche to revise core doctrines of Cartesianism, especially relating to the nature of ideas and their capacity to represent objects external to the mind (Watson 1987: 79–100). Foucher was also a close friend and frequent correspondent of Leibniz and was the first to publish criticisms of Leibniz’s monadology and theory of pre-established harmony (Watson 1987: 131–147). Richard A. Watson’s The Breakdown of Cartesian Metaphysics (Watson 1987, in which Watson 1966 is reprinted) is the authoritative study of Foucher’s critiques of Descartes, Malebranche, and Leibniz, and will remain so for many years. There is still much work to be done on Foucher, however, especially in relation to skepticism. In particular, there are three areas of research that deserve further attention and that will be treated below: Foucher’s interpretation of the ancient Academics; the nature and extent of Foucher’s metaphysical skepticism; and Foucher’s anti-skeptical defense of the criteria of truth attacked by Huet.

330

SKEPTICISM

6  FOUCHER’S CARTESIAN INTERPRETATION OF THE ANCIENT ACADEMY Foucher’s philosophical career is unified by his systematization and application of ancient Academic philosophy. A brief look at the titles of Foucher’s works (especially 1675, 1687, and 1693) demonstrates that he was interested in being recognized as the modern champion of the Academy, and this desire of his was not lost on contemporaries like Baillet and Leibniz, who gave Foucher the title of “restorer of the Academy” (Rabbe 1867: 22, Appendix VIII). Some of Foucher’s contemporaries, like Desgabets, saw in Foucher’s Critique of 1675 only the spirit of the most skeptical Academics. Desgabets accused Foucher of filling his mind and his book with the “old arguments” of the Academics who desired “to suspend their judgment on all things” (Desgabets 1675: 6), who claimed “not to know either body or soul, first principles or their consequences, or even the foundations of mathematics” (Desgabets 1675: 15–16), and who “made a trophy of their ignorance by banishing from the world all true knowledge” (Desgabets 1675: 27). However, other contemporaries closer to Foucher, including Huet, saw little trace of Academic skepticism in Foucher’s writings. According to Huet, who met with Foucher on a regular basis for many years, “[Foucher] hardly knew the names of Arcesilaus and Carneades, let alone anything about Pyrrhonism” (Letter to Nicaise April 19, 1697; quoted from Rabbe 1867: Appendix X). In Huet’s judgment, Foucher intended to rehabilitate Platonic philosophy, not Academic skepticism. Foucher’s last writings strike a balance between Desgabets’s and Huet’s assessments. Huet was certainly right that Plato’s Academy was the one Foucher was most interested in reviving; Desgabets was also right, however, that in Foucher’s view the Academy had an important skeptical dimension from the outset. In the opening pages of his last work, Foucher refers to himself as “Academico-Platonicus,” and vows to follow Plato, not blindly and by the letter, but in his method (1693: 2). Foucher distinguishes two kinds of followers of Plato: “The first followers make Plato affirm a number of things, while the others view Plato as continuing to doubt and to search for the truth” (1693: 2). The first followers are Platonists, while the latter followers are the Academics to which Foucher claims to belong. We must be careful when referring to Foucher as an “Academic skeptic” as many recent writers have done, not only because Foucher never used that term to describe himself, but more importantly because he considered the term confused. Foucher clarified the similarities and differences between Academic philosophy and skepticism. There are three kinds of philosophers: Skeptics, who search for the truth but who claim not to have found any truths; Academics, who search for the truth and who claim to have found many important truths; and Dogmatists, who claim to have found all the truth they were seeking (Foucher 1687: 4, 28–30; 1693: 239). Foucher’s Academics differ from Skeptics, therefore, in that they confidently assert that their search for truth has been successful; they differ from Dogmatists in that they claim that their search for truth has been only partly successful. Foucher neither claimed to be, nor wanted to be, the restorer of Academic skepticism, pace Popkin (2003: 275). Foucher was aware of earlier attempts to revive

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

331

Academic skepticism and showed disdain for them. For example, Foucher names Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (1463–1494) as a proponent of the Academics, but he condemns Pico’s portrayal of the Academics as skeptics (1693: 71). But as we will see in the next section, there is still good reason to call Foucher an Academic skeptic, at least in the realm of metaphysics, since he offered one of the most powerful and influential skeptical objections to the existence of the external physical world and did so from a self-styled Academic standpoint. In the rest of this section, I will show how Foucher’s interpretation of Academic philosophy is like a Trojan horse, carefully constructed to lure in the Cartesians so that it would be easier to destroy their philosophy on Foucher’s ground. Foucher’s Apology (1687) and History (1693) are not presented as rediscoveries of the Academics presented to the uninitiated; they are instead presented as original and carefully constructed interpretations of the Academics presented to those who already know much about that school. Foucher’s goal is not like that of the Renaissance commentators, to uncover the original spirit of the ancient Academy through painstaking exegeses of Cicero or Diogenes Laertius; his goal is to build upon key ideas first discovered by Plato and his successors in order to make use of them in critiquing the works of his contemporaries. The key to understanding Foucher’s interpretation of the Academics therefore does not lie in any author of the ancient Academy itself, but rather in the modern period, in particular in the writings of Descartes. Foucher’s Academic philosophy is not predominantly Platonic or Carneadean or Ciceronian; it is anachronistically Cartesian (see Maia Neto 1997, 2003; Charles 2013a). Foucher’s tendency to interpret the ancient Academics as proto-Cartesians has already been noted in the literature. Maia Neto (2003: 78–79) has shown that the role of doubt in Foucher’s philosophy is like the role given to doubt by Descartes in the first Meditation. Doubt is not the end of Academic philosophizing, but it is essential “[b]ecause it is necessary to remain as if at one’s post, which provides cover from preconceptions and errors, until evident truth forces one to leave” (Foucher 1693: 136). A second Cartesian element of Foucher’s reading of the Academics is his reduction of the Academic way of philosophizing to five laws,6 which were unmistakably inspired by Descartes’s rules in the Discourse on Method (CSM I 120; AT VI 18–19). Especially Descartes’s first law, “never to accept anything as true if I did not have evident knowledge of its truth: that is, carefully to avoid precipitate conclusions and preconceptions,” which is essentially Foucher’s first law, can be found everywhere in Foucher’s writings, including in the passage quoted immediately above (Foucher 1693: 136). But the most striking example of Foucher’s Cartesian reading of the Academics has yet to be noted in the literature. It occurs in the first chapter of the 1693 History in which Foucher claims to be writing as a disinterested historian of the ancient Academy. Yet if one reads Descartes’s Discourse on Method and Meditations, and then turns to Foucher’s “History of the Academics” (Foucher 1693: 1–72), it is striking how often and carefully Foucher maps the progress of Descartes’s thought onto the history of the Academy, from Socrates to Antiochus. Though Foucher never explicitly says so, each Academic is for him the personification of a stage of Descartes’s progress toward truth.

332

SKEPTICISM

According to Foucher, Socrates was the first to realize that, in order to give some order to philosophy, it was necessary to undermine the foundations of the reigning disorder, which were presumption and preconceptions. Destroying preconceived opinions was the only thing that Socrates could do in the absence of a criterion of truth (Foucher 1693: 12). The parallels with Discourse One and Two, and with the project of Meditations One, are evident here. Socrates takes us into the second Meditation as well, since it turns out that he discovered the cogito two millennia earlier than Descartes: “When [Socrates] said that he knew one thing, namely that he knew nothing, he was acknowledging that he was thinking, and that he knew he was thinking because he was doubting all other things” (Foucher 1687: 111). Plato’s method was simply that of Socrates, which Foucher suggestively describes as “meditations on first principles” (Foucher 1693: 15). These meditations led Plato to discover some basic starting points, foremost of which were that the “senses are not the proper judges of the truth of things that are outside of us,” that what we perceive by the senses are merely “modifications of our soul,” and that our souls, though initially unknown to us, are “nevertheless better known to us than our own bodies and any other bodies external to us” (1693: 16–17). In other words, Plato discovered the highlights of the second Meditation wax example. The immediate successors of Plato—Speusippus, Xenocrates, Polemon, Crates, and Crantor—strayed from the method of Socrates and Plato and rendered the Academy dogmatic. They remind us of the primary intellectual vice identified in the first Meditation: “My habitual opinions keep coming back” (CSM II 15; AT VII 22). Arcesilaus was therefore faced with the task of renewing the Academy, which he did by imitating Socrates by undermining precipitous judgments through doubt (Foucher 1693: 31). Carneades then realized that for the Academics “a provisional morality was necessary to guide their lives until they arrived at the knowledge they were seeking” (Foucher 1693: 43, emphasis mine). Like Descartes in the third Discourse (CSM II 122; AT VI 22–23), Carneades realized that, in the absence of certain moral knowledge and faced with the necessity of acting, we must follow the available probable guides, such as laws, customs, and religion. Philo of Larissa set the Academy again on the search after scientific truth. He gave the Academics hope that despite the doubts of Arcesilaus, some truths about ourselves and the external world might be discovered by reason and understanding (Foucher 1693: 54). Philo inspired his successor Antiochus to work on establishing certain truths. Antiochus’s main contribution was to establish a rational criterion of truth, which Foucher, like Descartes, calls évidence (Foucher 1687: 111). Antiochus takes the Academy into the early third Meditation. This is where the ancient Academy comes to a close in Foucher’s view. Not surprisingly, Foucher thinks that Descartes begins to go astray in the rest of the third Meditation.7 Foucher’s history of the Academics provides a historical basis for the argumentative strategy that he consistently used against Descartes’s philosophy: Eager to defend antiquity against the disdain of innovators, [Foucher] believed that it would suffice to convict the reigning philosophy of plagiarism, and to find in that same antiquity antecedents of the new philosophy. . . . Whatever Descartes

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

333

taught that was rigorous and solid was borrowed from others; if Descartes ever showed any originality, it was only to distance himself from the path of truth. (Rabbe 1867: 21) Descartes took the essentials of his first through early third Meditations from the Academics; afterwards, he went astray so that now “we must bring Descartes back to the Academy, rather than leave the Academy to join Descartes” (Foucher 1693: 113). Foucher’s history also demonstrates that Academic skepticism is just one humble part of the Academic philosophy that Foucher wished to rehabilitate. The doubts of Socrates and Arcesilaus, and the probabilism of Carneades, play a role in Foucher’s method, but doubt is not the end of his philosophy, nor does Foucher resist affirming numerous truths with the greatest certainty: “It is true that the Academics must doubt a great number of things, but this is because these things are doubtful. Nevertheless, the Academics know the principal truths, such that their doubts concern only scientific matters and dogmatic propositions about subjects of pure human speculation” (Foucher 1687: ix).

7  FOUCHER’S CRITIQUE OF DESCARTES Popkin blurs important differences between Huet and Foucher when he writes that “Huet and Foucher . . . destroyed Cartesianism at its epistemological heart” (Popkin 2003: 282). In this section and the next, I will argue that Foucher, unlike Huet, was not interested in destroying the heart of Cartesian epistemology, but in fact assumed that foundation in his skeptical writings. Foucher’s Academic skepticism is limited to the realm of metaphysics, while Huet’s Academic skepticism is allencompassing. In this section, I give an overview of Foucher’s skeptical critique of Cartesian metaphysics, while in the next I argue that Foucher’s 1693 History can be read in part as a Cartesian defense of reason against the skepticism of Huet. Foucher acknowledges that his Academic philosophy shares much in common with Descartes’s philosophy, especially relating to method. In particular, there are three important similarities: (1) “they begin to philosophize by means of doubting things in general, and by the universal examination of our judgments”; (2) “they agree that we must consider the senses incapable of judging by themselves the truth of things outside of us”; and (3) “they agree in following approximately the same method of philosophizing” (Foucher 1693: 187–188). Contained in the third similarity, that of basic method, is the shared criterion of rational evidence, which is the basis of the first law of both Descartes and of Foucher’s Academics. On the basis of this commitment to an initial position of doubt, mistrust of the senses, and a basic method of philosophizing that primarily involves assenting only to what is most evident, Foucher launches a skeptical attack on Descartes’s philosophy (though Malebranche was the occasional cause of Foucher’s objections, Foucher is clear that Descartes is his target—see Foucher 1675: 3). The skeptical argument in general is that, if Descartes had remained committed to the three points above (doubt, mistrust of the senses, method), then he would have realized that he never

334

SKEPTICISM

attained any certain knowledge of an external, physical world. Moreover, as long as Descartes remained committed to his ontological dualism, he could never hope to attain knowledge of the external world. Foucher’s main skeptical accomplishment is to have shown more rigorously than anyone before him that ontological dualism entails external world skepticism. Foucher’s skeptical strategy in particular is to break down the primary-secondary quality distinction of which Descartes made extensive use.8 The aim of Foucher’s strategy was to force Cartesians to regard the primary quality of extension, which they considered the essence of the material world, in the same way they regarded sensible secondary qualities like color, smell, and taste, namely, as mere modes of the mind that represent nothing real outside the mind. Foucher’s goal was to restrict knowledge to the mind’s ideas. According to Descartes’s ontological dualism, there are two created substances: mind, which is thinking, non-extended substance, and body, which is non-thinking, extended substance. The mind is immediately aware only of its own modes— ideas, sensations, imaginings, memories, judgments. Consequently, if the mind is to become aware of bodies, then it can do so only by the indirect way of its ideas and sensations of bodies. Cartesian philosophy of mind distinguished ideas from sensations by claiming that the former modes of the mind represent real external objects, while the latter modes are merely effects of those objects on the sense organs and ultimately on the mind (see Watson 1987: 47–53 for a concise summary of orthodox Cartesianism in Foucher’s time). It is with this distinction between ideas and sensations that Foucher begins his main attack against Descartes: These two sorts of ideas belong equally to us and are, properly speaking, nothing other than our soul disposed in such-and-such a manner. But it is always our soul, and since the soul [according to Descartes’s dualism] has nothing in itself which resembles matter and extended beings, it is difficult to conceive how it could represent anything other than its own ideas. (Foucher 1675: 45) Two important implicit premises do much of the work in Foucher’s objection: (1) that in order to represent an object, an idea must resemble the object, and (2) if ideas are essentially distinct from bodies (as Cartesian dualism posits), then ideas cannot resemble, and therefore cannot represent, bodies. Foucher defends (1) by arguing that “we understand nothing else by representing than rendering a thing present to us” (Foucher 1675: 52). Foucher is clear that no modification of our soul can make a body present to us: “It is necessary, in order to represent [bodies] as they are in themselves, for our ideas to dispose us exactly as if these things were actually in us and present to us immediately” (Foucher 1675: 53). But the Cartesian way of ideas, in conjunction with ontological dualism, renders such immediate access to physical objects impossible, since only extensionless thoughts can be immediately present to the mind. Foucher continues: All that we know by the senses [according to Descartes] are merely modes of our soul that belong entirely to us and that do not resemble anything in material objects. But we know extension also by means of sensation, from which we must

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

335

conclude that extension is nothing but a mode of our soul, and that there is nothing similar to extension in material objects. (1675: 65) Foucher reports that he first put this objection to Rohault in 1667 and that Rohault’s response was to deny that we know extension by means of sensation. Foucher claims that he was baffled by this response, which he refuted by the following argument: “When I see a red square, for example, I simultaneously perceive its shape and color, on the one hand, and its extension on the other, since I judge its size; consequently, we know the square’s extension doubly by means of sensation: for we know it by sight and by touch, whereas we know colors only by the eyes” (Foucher 1675: 66). With extension relegated to the realm of sensible qualities along with color, the real mind-independent existence of the extended world becomes as doubtful as that of colors. Rohault’s attempt to evade Foucher’s argument was just one of many that contemporary Cartesians advanced. Malebranche denied that ideas are modes of the human mind and argued instead that we perceive ideas in the mind of God, which Foucher considered to be a very pious, but hardly a very evident position to espouse (Foucher 1675: 116). More orthodox Cartesians tried to save Descartes by developing sophisticated accounts of how ideas can represent material objects without resembling them in essence (Watson 1987: 89–99).

8  FOUCHER’S DEFENSE OF DESCARTES’S CRITERIA OF TRUTH In his Apology, Foucher identifies Huet as another philosopher who believed that the Academic philosophy was the most solid and most compatible with Christianity (Foucher 1687: 36). In this same passage, Foucher expresses his hope that Huet will soon publish a book on Academic doubt. There is also an extant letter written in 1685 by Foucher, urging Huet to publish on the Academics (see Lennon 2008: 34–37). The work that would ultimately satisfy Foucher’s requests, Huet’s Treatise, would never be published in Foucher’s or Huet’s lifetime. Foucher would not have been happy with the Treatise had he read it. We can be sure of this because Foucher must have been disturbed by Huet’s earlier antiCartesian work, the Censura, which first appeared in 1689, between the publication dates of the last part of Foucher’s Apology and the first part of Foucher’s History. Foucher read the Censura (see Foucher 1693: 92), and though he never criticizes Huet by name, Foucher was clearly opposed to the radical nature of Huet’s skepticism. In Foucher’s History, there is an extended refutation of anti-Cartesian skeptical arguments that had been elaborated by Huet in the Censura and that would be offered again in the Treatise. These skeptical arguments target the foundation of both Descartes’s and Foucher’s epistemology, the natural light of reason, and the general criterion of evidence. As we have seen, Huet reduced evidence to a mere psychological phenomenon, an appearance that can be as deceptive as any sensory appearance (see Huet 1694/2003: 130; 1723: 76). There is no infallible evidence for Huet; there is only the varying

336

SKEPTICISM

subject-relative appearances of evidence. When Foucher begins to combat skeptics who are opposed to the criterion of evidence, he identifies their principal strategy as the relegation of evidence to mere persuasion (Foucher 1693: 141). Foucher describes these skeptics as “animals that trouble the world,” “rebels against the light,” “beasts,” “condemned by God and man,” “incurably sick,” “unwilling to open their eyes” (1693: 120–121). Foucher begins his response to this skepticism by noting that nobody would deny that the proposition “two plus two equals four” appears to be necessarily true. But if the skeptic can recognize the appearance of necessary truth, then the skeptic must possess a general idea of truth: “In order to know whether some proposition seems to be true, it is necessary for us to know at least in one instance what it is to be true” (Foucher 1693: 134). Ironically, the Academic Foucher takes this classic antiskeptical argument from the anti-Academic, Augustine. Foucher believes that, if the skeptic meditates on this initial idea of truth, he will see that it contains a general criterion of truth, namely, evidence (1693: 83–88, 133, 208). The skeptic will respond to Foucher by claiming that there is a difference between “true evidence” and “apparent evidence” and that we need a further criterion in order to distinguish these things (1693: 140–141). In the absence of such a criterion for the criterion, we are left merely with degrees of persuasion, from weak persuasion up to invincible persuasion, but without any guarantee that the highest degree of persuasion corresponds with the possession of truth. Foucher does concede that we lack a precise definition of the criterion of truth and an advanced art of teaching others to recognize the criterion (1693: 133–134); the first goal of Academic logic is to establish that art. But to search for a separate criterion beyond the perception of evidence would be misguided in Foucher’s view: “It would be like searching to clarify light itself” (1693: 133). Foucher apparently wants his reader to find absurd the idea of clarifying light by means of another light; however, Huet (1723: 83) demanded just that. It was probably with the obstinate skepticism of Huet in mind that Foucher attempted the task of shedding light on the criterion of evidence. Foucher does so by giving some further criteria by which to guarantee evident truths, and these criteria are not further qualities of the mind’s ideas but rather are rational capacities and incapacities. We are in possession of the “highest degree of evidence”—a state that Huet argued we cannot achieve—when we cannot conceive of a thing in any other way than we presently do (Foucher 1693: 142); when we do not hesitate in the conception that we have of the thing (1693: 142); when the conception we have is “incontestable,” that is, cannot be doubted (1693: 81, 213); when we are determined, whether against our will or in conformity with it, to believe in our conception by the evidence that we have for it (1693: 137); when we cannot even conceive that the contrary of our belief is true (1693: 141). Most of Foucher’s examples of evident truths are mathematical, such as “two plus two equals four.” The skeptic might object, however, that “two plus two equals four” can be doubted by means of the omnipotent God objection from Descartes’s first Meditation and that consequently the proposition does not count as an evident truth on Foucher’s account. But Foucher responds by arguing that Descartes’s

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

337

appeal to the omnipotence of God to cast into doubt common notions of mathematics is an example of excessive, not reasonable, doubt that ultimately undermines Descartes’s system: We should not think that piety requires us to speak in this way of divine power. For it serves only to overturn all the certainty that we can have concerning God, and to destroy not only theology, but also religion. That is what the Cartesians need to consider, they who take their master at his word rather than interpreting him charitably. (1693: 201) Foucher’s skepticism clearly has both epistemological and theological limits. Foucher’s defense of rational evidence ultimately rests on the distinction and connections between three species of reason: there is reason in itself, or divine reason, which is immutable, eternal, infallible, and necessary; there is right reason, which is reason in itself as shared by all human beings, and which is, like divine reason, infallible; and there is our reason or particular reason, which is a mode of the human mind, and is subject to error because of the interference of preconceptions and bad habits (1693: 195–199; 1687: 16). Foucher argues that right reason must be infallible using what he calls an a posteriori argument. Right reason must be infallible or else we could not explain the constancy, the accuracy, and the stability of the technical arts and sciences that are based in right reason. Buildings which outlast their architects, the invention of scientific instruments, and algebraic formulae all point to the infallibility of right reason (1693: 197–198). The unity and infallibility of right reason are the guarantors of mathematical truths: “It is true that the same Reason enlightens all men and extends to every mind in which it produces ideas that are perfectly similar. . . . It is certain that this unity of species [of reason] suffices to support the most solid demonstrations of the mathematicians” (1693: 207). Foucher’s argument against Huet’s skepticism is that human reason is based in divine reason. Moreover, evidence is more than invincible persuasion; it is the root of the fruitfulness of the sciences, which could be witnessed every day in Foucher’s time. This is also Foucher’s answer to dogmatists who complain that his insistence on contemplating basic evident truths will not get us very far: We easily perceive that if two triangles have two sides and one angle equal to each other, then they are congruent. Many people scorn this truth as if it had no importance. Yet it is by means of this truth that we discovered the art of measuring inaccessible places, of judging the sizes of the stars and their distances from the earth. (1693: 85) The experience of evident truths is, as Huet alleges, primarily psychological: evidence is perceived by individuals as an inner “torch in the fog” (Foucher 1693: 205). The goal of philosophy is to clear away the fog of preconceived notions and precipitous judgments in order to render the light of evidence even brighter. But in addition to the subjective experience of evidence, which Huet is right to criticize as potentially deceptive, there are also the incontestable triumphs of science and technology, which are based on these evident truths, and which ought to convince us that there is more to evidence than the modes of our minds. Foucher’s a posteriori

338

SKEPTICISM

argument for the infallibility of reason anticipates our own contemporary trust in reason that stems from the successes of science and technology.

9 CONCLUSION Both Huet and Foucher are notable among later seventeenth-century philosophers for their extensive interest in the ancient Academy. They each wrote a history of the Academy, carefully noting its differences from and superiority to other ancient sects. They each paid close attention, in particular, to the nature and extent of the skepticism of the Academy, and they employed skeptical arguments against their common foe, the Cartesians, whom they ultimately defeated by means of their skepticism.9 There is good reason, therefore, to consider Huet and Foucher Academic skeptics, and the label “modern Academic skepticism” is useful for referring to the skeptical revival of the late seventeenth century that undermined the system of one of Western philosophy’s greatest thinkers, Descartes. However, modern Academic skepticism was not a unified movement, which may be partly responsible for its success. Huet’s Academic skepticism aimed primarily at Cartesian epistemology, while Foucher’s aimed primarily at Cartesian metaphysics. Because of their fundamental differences, Huet and Foucher never did, and they never could, harmonize their versions of Academic philosophy or coauthor a single anti-Cartesian treatise. But this did not prevent readers familiar with the works of both authors from deriving a single conclusion from them: Descartes’s philosophy is fundamentally and fatally flawed. If Popkin is right that the seventeenth century began with a crise pyrrhonienne, should we say that the century ended with a crise académicienne? If we mean by this a rise of skepticism that took its inspiration from a careful study of the ancient Academics, then yes, we can say that the century ended with an Academic crisis. On the other hand, to Huet and Foucher, as well as to many of their contemporaries, Academic skepticism was not the problem, let alone a crisis: it was a solution. The real crisis to which Academic skepticism was the remedy was the crise cartésienne, which Huet and Foucher could agree was the twofold problem of the improper use of reason in supporting the Christian faith and of the infiltration of the Christian faith into philosophy. Malebranche’s Search after Truth epitomized this crisis in the minds of both Huet and Foucher, and herein lies the greatest source of unity in modern Academic skepticism. It is not a common ancient Academic source, or common Academic skeptical trope, but a common target that makes “modern Academic skepticism” a meaningful label worth preserving in our histories of skepticism.

NOTES 1. Huet was aware that he was a representative of the Republic of Letters; he justified the prima facie vain project of his autobiography by arguing that he was not writing about himself alone, but primarily about the history of the time in which he lived (see Shelford 2007: 17).

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

339

2. For a complete bibliography of Huet’s works, along with English summaries, see Huet (1810: vol. 2, 465–490). 3. For the reasons that led Huet not to publish the Treatise in his lifetime, see Shelford (2007: 140–141). 4. It is common, though not uncontroversial, in the English secondary literature on Huet and Foucher to translate évidence as “evidence,” which is sensible considering that it was the English word used in the seventeenth century to translate the French term évidence. A good alternative would be “evidentness,” but I have not seen the term used in works earlier than the nineteenth century, so it is not ideal for translating seventeenth-century works. “Self-evidence” has advantages, but whereas Huet and Foucher (and others, like Bayle) speak of degrees of évidence, it does not seem natural to speak of degrees of self-evidence. A final plausible alternative to “evidence” would simply be “clarity,” but this would make it impossible to distinguish, as Huet does, “évidence” and “clarité.” 5. For a complete bibliography of Foucher’s works, see Watson (1969: xxxviii–xlii). 6. (1) Proceed only by means of demonstration in philosophy; (2) do not consider questions that clearly cannot be decided; (3) admit that you do not know that of which you are ignorant; (4) distinguish the things you know from the things that you do not know; (5) always search for new truths (Foucher 1687: 5–9). 7. Descartes’s first error, however, occurs in the second Meditation when he declares that he is a thinking thing. In Foucher’s view, it is correct to acknowledge that the mind thinks, but it is precipitous to declare that the essence of the mind is thinking (Foucher 1675: 14–15). 8. In doing so, Foucher anticipates, if not provides, the foundation of George Berkeley’s idealism. Berkeley probably would have learned of Foucher’s attack on the primarysecondary quality distinction from Pierre Bayle’s Dictionaire historique et critique, in the article “Pyrrhon,” remark C. Some see Foucher’s arguments as tending, not toward metaphysical skepticism, but toward idealism (see Armour 2003). 9. See Watson (1987) for the case that Foucher is primarily responsible for the downfall of Cartesianism; see Lennon (2003a, 2008) for the case that Huet is mainly responsible.

REFERENCES Armour, Leslie. 2003. “Simon Foucher, Knowledge and Idealism: Philo of Larissa and the Enigmas of a French ‘Skeptic.’” In T. M. Lennon (ed.), Cartesian Views: Papers Presented to Richard A. Watson, 96–116. Leiden: Brill. Charles, Sébastien. 2013a. “Entre réhabilitation du scepticisme et critique du cartésianisme: Foucher lecteur du scepticisme académique.” In S. Giocanti (ed.), La réception des Academiques à l’Âge moderne. Special issue of Astérion 11 (online): http://asterion. revues.org/2382 (last consulted July 4, 2014). Charles, Sébastien. 2013b. “On the Uses of Scepticism against a Certain Philosophical Arrogance: Huet as a Critic of Cartesian Logic and Metaphysics,” Science et esprit 65: 299–309. Charron, Pierre. 1601/1986. De la sagesse, edited by B. de Negroni. Paris: Fayard.

340

SKEPTICISM

Cicero, Marcus Tulius. 1979. Academica and De Natura Deorum, translated by H. Rackham. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Desgabets, Dom Robert. 1675. Critique de la Critique de la Recherche de la Vérité, où l’on découvre le chemin qui conduit aux connaissances solides, pour servir de réponse à la lettre d’un Academicien. Paris: Jean du Puis. Foucher, Simon. 1673. Dissertations sur la recherche de la verité, ou sur la logique des academiciens. Dijon: Publisher unknown. Foucher, Simon. 1675. Critique de la Recherche de la verité où l’on examine en mêmetems une partie des Principes de Mr Descartes. Lettre par un Academicien. Paris: Martin Coustelier. Foucher, Simon. 1687. Dissertation sur la recherche de la verité, contenant l’apologie des academiciens, où l’on fait voir que leur manière de philosopher est la plus utile pour la religion, et la plus conforme au bon sens, pour servir de Réponse à la Critique de la Critique, etc., avec plusieurs remarques sur les erreurs des sens et sur l’origine de la philosophie de Monsieur Descartes. Paris: Estienne Michallet. Foucher, Simon. 1693. Dissertations sur la recherche de la verité, contenant l’histoire et les principes de la philosophie des academiciens. Avec plusieurs réflexions sur les sentimens de M. Descartes. Paris: Jean Anisson. Guellouz, Suzanne (ed.). 1994. Pierre-Daniel Huet (1630–1721): Actes du Colloque de Caen. Biblio 17. Paris, Seattle and Tübingen: Papers on French Seventeenth-Century Literature. Huet, Pierre-Daniel. 1679. Demonstratio evangelica. Paris. Huet, Pierre-Daniel. Censura Philosophiae Cartesianae. Paris: Daniel Horthemels. Huet, Pierre-Daniel. 1690. Alnetanae quaestiones de concordia rationis et fidei. Caen and Paris. Huet, Pierre-Daniel. 1694/2003. Against Cartesian Philosophy, edited, translated, annotated, and introduced by T. M. Lennon. Amherst, NY : Humanity Books. (The first English translation of Censura Philosophiae Cartesianae. The translation is of the revised 1694 edition.) Huet, Pierre-Daniel. 1723. Traité philosophique de la foiblesse de l’esprit humain. Amsterdam: Henri Sauzet. Huet, Pierre-Daniel. 1810. Memoirs of the Life of Peter Daniel Huet, Bishop of Avranches. 2 volumes, translated by John Aikin. M. D. London. (An English translation of Huet’s Commentarius de rebus ad eum pertinentibus. The Hague: 1718.) Lennon, Thomas M. 2003a. “Foucher, Huet, and the Downfall of Cartesianism.” In T. M. Lennon (ed.), Cartesian Views: Papers Presented to Richard A. Watson, 117–128. Leiden: Brill. Lennon, Thomas M. (ed.) 2003b. Cartesian Views: Papers Presented to Richard A. Watson. Leiden: Brill. Lennon, Thomas M. 2008. The Plain Truth: Descartes, Huet, and Skepticism. Brill Studies in Intellectual History 170. Leiden and Boston: Brill. Maia Neto, José R. 1997. “Academic Skepticism in Early Modern Philosophy,” Journal of the History of Ideas 58: 199–220. Maia Neto, José R. 2003. “Foucher’s Academic Cartesianism.” In T. M. Lennon (ed.), Cartesian Views: Papers Presented to Richard A. Watson, 71–95. Leiden: Brill.

VARIETIES OF MODERN ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM

341

Maia Neto, José R. 2008a. “Charron and Huet: Two Unexplored Legacies of Popkin’s Scholarship on Early Modern Skepticism.” In J. D. Popkin (ed.), The Legacies of Richard Popkin, 155–172. International Archives of the History of Ideas 198. Dordrecht: Springer. Maia Neto, José R. 2008b. “Huet sceptique cartésien,” Philosophiques 35: 223–239. Maia Neto, José R. 2008c. “Huet n’est pas un sceptique chrétien,” Les Études Philosophiques 2 (85): 209–222. Maia Neto, José R. 2014. Academic Skepticism in Seventeenth-Century French Philosophy: The Charronian Legacy, 1601–1662. International Archives of the History of Ideas 215. Dordrecht: Springer. Malebranche, Nicolas. 1674/1997. The Search after Truth, translated and edited by T. Lennon and P. Olscamp. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Malbreil, Germain. 1994. “Le Traité Philosophique de la Foiblesse de l’Esprit Humain, de Feu Monsieur Huet, ancien Evêque d’Avranches.” In S. Guellouz (ed.), Pierre-Daniel Huet (1630–1721): Actes du Colloque de Caen. Biblio 17. Paris, Seattle and Tübingen: Papers on French Seventeenth-Century Literature. Popkin, Richard H. 2003. The History of Scepticism: From Savonarola to Bayle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Quantin, Jean-Louis. 1994. “La Raison, la Certitude, la Foi: quelques remarques sur les préliminaires de l’acte de foi selon Huet.” In S. Guellouz (ed.), Pierre-Daniel Huet (1630–1721): Actes du Colloque de Caen. Biblio 17, 83–98. Paris, Seattle and Tübingen: Papers on French Seventeenth-Century Literature. Rabbe, Felix. 1867. Étude Philosophique. L’Abbé Simon Foucher Chanoine de la Sainte Chapelle de Dijon. Paris: Didier et Cie. Rapetti, Elena. 2003. Percorsi anticartesiani nelle lettere a Pierre-Daniel Huet. Florence: Leo S. Olschki. Schmitt, Charles B. 1972. Cicero Scepticus: A Study of the Influence of the Academica in the Renaissance. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Sextus Empiricus. 2000. Outlines of Scepticism, edited by Julia Annas and Jonathan Barnes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Shelford, April G. 2007. Transforming the Republic of Letters: Pierre-Daniel Huet and European Intellectual Life, 1650-1720. Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press. Watson, Richard A. 1966. The Downfall of Cartesianism, 1673–1712: A Study of Epistemological Issues in Late 17th Century Cartesianism. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Watson, Richard A. 1969. “Introduction.” In Simon Foucher, Critique de la Recherche de la verité, v–xlix. New York and London: Johnson Reprint Corporation. Watson, Richard A. 1987. The Breakdown of Cartesian Metaphysics. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett. Watson, Richard A., and Marjorie Grene. 1995. Malebranche’s First and Last Critics: Simon Foucher and Dortous de Mairan. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press.

CHAPTER TWENTY-FOUR

Spinoza on Skepticism ALISON PETERMAN

It remains now to investigate the doubtful idea—i.e., to ask what are the things that can lead us into doubt, and at the same time, how doubt is removed. I am speaking of true doubt in the mind, and not of what we commonly see happen, when someone says in words that he doubts, although his mind does not doubt. For it is not the business of the Method to emend that. That belongs rather to the investigation of stubbornness, and its emendation. (Spinoza, Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect §77)

1 INTRODUCTION The skeptic is one of Spinoza’s favorite targets of abuse. Whatever truth Spinoza might manage to discover, he complains, “Some skeptic would still doubt it.” “There is no speaking of the sciences” with skeptics; instead, “they must be regarded as automata, completely lacking a mind” (TIE 41).1 But Spinoza contrasts such mindless obscurantists, “who ha[ve] no other end than doubting,” with Descartes, who wielded skepticism instead “to free his mind from all prejudices, so that in the end he might discover firm and unshakable foundations of the sciences” (TIE 41). And Spinoza begins his geometrical reconstruction of Descartes’s Principles of Philosophy with an approving exposition of that “great man’s” methodological skepticism and its response, arguing that we can attain certainty only once we have a clear and distinct idea of the essence of God. But this agreement turns out to be superficial, because Spinoza and Descartes have deeply different stories about how the idea of God grounds certainty. I outline this story in Section 2, focusing on Spinoza’s early work, where I argue that he responds to the Cartesian skeptic by denying the very distinction between true ideas and ideas that are clearly and distinctly perceived. However, Spinoza’s characterization of truth in the Ethics as agreement of an idea with its object complicates matters, leaving it unclear whether Spinoza has responded in a way that would satisfy a Cartesian skeptic. In Section 3, I discuss Spinoza’s three kinds of knowledge, or cognition. I argue that Spinoza’s answer to skepticism vindicates only one special kind of knowledge and that he ultimately denies that empirical, mathematical, moral, and revelatory knowledge of nature are possible. In Section 4, I conclude

SPINOZA ON SKEPTICISM

343

by showing that, according to Spinoza, Descartes salvages knowledge from the Cartesian skeptic only by reducing all natural knowledge to revelation.

2 CERTAINTY In the Prolegomenon to his Principles of Cartesian Philosophy, Spinoza provides an account of Descartes’s deployment of and response to methodological skepticism. Superficially, it is a faithful account: we can have certain beliefs if, and only if, we cultivate a clear and distinct idea of God. But the demon is in the details. Spinoza starts by asking: while meditating with Descartes, why can we be certain of our own existence despite the possibility that God is a deceiver, but we cannot be certain, for example, that the angles of a triangle add to 180 degrees? In the former case, he answers: Wherever we turned our attention—whether we were considering our own nature, or feigning some cunning deceiver as the author of our nature, or summoning up, outside us, any other reason for doubting whatever—we came upon no reason for doubting that did not by itself convince us of our existence. (C 237) When entertaining the proposition that I exist (call this proposition “cogito”), no other idea furnishes me with a reason to doubt it, including the idea that God is a deceiver. Not so when I entertain the proposition that the three angles of a triangle sum to two right angles (call this “triangle”). Instead, while I am “compelled to infer” triangle when I attend to the nature of a triangle, We cannot infer the same thing from [the supposition] that perhaps we are deceived by the author of our nature. . . . So here we are not compelled, wherever we direct our attention, to infer that the three angles of a Triangle are equal to two right angles. On the contrary, we discover a ground for doubting, viz. because we have no idea of God which so affects us that it is impossible for us to think that God is a deceiver. (C 237) I can render mathematical truths like triangle certain by cultivating a clear and distinct idea of God: When we have formed such an idea, that reason for doubting Mathematical truths will be removed. Wherever we then direct our attention in order to doubt some one of them, we shall come upon nothing from which we must not instead infer that it is most certain—as happened concerning our existence. (C 237) These passages suggest that, according to Spinoza, S’s belief that p is certain if and only if all three of the following are true: (a) p is a “mathematical truth.” A “mathematical truth” in the PPC seems to be a truth that we are “compelled to infer” from a clear and distinct idea, and not necessarily one that concerns mathematics (C 238). (b) S cannot discover a “ground for doubting” p. (According to Spinoza, a “ground for doubting” p is an idea from which a doubt that p can be

344

SKEPTICISM

inferred—so ultimately we will want to know: what is a doubt that p, for Spinoza?) (c) S can infer p (or, S can “infer that p is most certain” (C 237)) from every other idea that S can attend to. Spinoza claims that these criteria are satisfied for mathematical truths like triangle if and only if we have a clear and distinct (“C&D”) idea of God’s essence, and in particular of God’s veracity (C 237). What is his justification for this? Let’s focus on (b) and first consider how Descartes guarantees it through God’s veracity. Once I have the C&D idea of God’s essence, I can conclude that God exists and that God lacks the will to deceive. That means that God has actually created me, and has created me with faculties that would not ineluctably cause me to believe what I shouldn’t. This argument is in no way open to Spinoza, and he does not make it. Spinoza denies that we have faculties at all (E IIp42), and he denies that God has a will whose quality can be evaluated (E Ip37). So he cannot rely on God’s veracity being actualized in God’s well-intentioned creation of our faculties to get us from the C&D idea of God’s essence to the claim that we cannot generate any doubts about triangle. Indeed, in the PPC, Spinoza takes pains to stress that I can be certain of triangle before I know that my author is not a deceiver—indeed, before I know that God exists. All that is required for my ideas of mathematical truths to be certain is that I have a C&D idea of God’s essence. Descartes’s claim that once I have this idea, I can become sure that I will never generate a doubt of any C&D idea, p, required first showing that I should believe that p, since a non-deceiving God created me. That is what guarantees not just that I cannot currently generate any reasons to doubt that p from my unclear and indistinct ideas but that it is impossible for me ever to generate a reason to doubt that p, if p is C&D. It is the epistemic status that, for Descartes, guarantees that certain ideas are doubt-proof—their being doubt-proof does not confer epistemic status. Given that Spinoza does not rely on God’s guarantee and the epistemic status it provides to achieve (b), there are two questions to answer: A. How does Spinoza think that we can proceed from the C&D idea of God’s essence to Spinozistic certainty? After developing the C&D idea of God’s essence, it seems like I can still come to doubt triangle on some other grounds—say, some fuzzy recollection that there are non-Euclidean geometries. According to the Prolegomenon, having any ideas that are not clear and distinct should place me in perpetual peril of doubt, since there is no telling what doubts I can infer from them—not to mention that I have ideas—even, it seems, clear and distinct ones—from which I cannot infer triangle. B. Even if Spinoza can establish Spinozistic certainty of triangle, has he established that he should believe it, or that it is true? Spinoza appears to provide an answer to (A) in the Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect (TIE), where he explains that the C&D idea of God’s essence ensures

SPINOZA ON SKEPTICISM

345

that our ideas are indubitable if they are deduced in the proper order from God’s essence, which is “the origin of all things”: If someone proceeds rightly, by investigating [first] those things which ought to be investigated first, with no interruption in the connection of things . . . he will never have anything but the most certain ideas. (TIE 80; see also TIE 44) Since “true knowledge proceeds from cause to effect” (TIE 85), if I begin with a C&D idea of God’s essence, carefully deduce what follows from it in the proper order, and populate my mind only with the resultant ideas, I will never generate a ground for doubting that I know any of those ideas. This is clearly impossible for a finite mind, which will always have unclear and indistinct ideas (see, e.g., E IIIp1d, E IVp4, TIE 44). But Spinoza seems to think that we can approximate it and that we can in some sense “insulate” this God-derived chain or network of clear and distinct ideas from the rest of our minds and, to that extent, make those ideas immune to doubt. In this picture, God’s essence guarantees that I have certain ideas in virtue of God’s being the cause and origin of all things, and not in virtue of God’s being the cause of my cognitive and epistemic faculties. On the TIE account, then, it looks like knowledge of God’s essence guarantees the Spinozistic certainty of our ideas of mathematical truths only if those ideas are deduced in the right way from the clear and distinct idea of God’s essence. This explains the third, seemingly unattainable, criterion that an idea is certain only if it is deducible from every idea in the mind. Spinoza seems to assume the further point that, if every one of a person’s ideas were certain, each certain idea would be deductively connected with every other. I have not found a place where Spinoza asserts anything that strictly entails this, so I can only offer: it sounds exactly like something Spinoza would say. In fact, I think that this third criterion is sufficient for certainty, according to Spinoza, if we add that we also have the C&D idea of God (which Spinoza, at E IIp47, claims that we all do). There are a few reasons to think this. It makes sense of the claim in the TIE that “if there should be only one idea in the soul . . . whether it is true or false, there will be neither doubt nor certainty, but only a sensation of a certain sort” (TIE 77). Certainty is not simply absence of doubt but essentially concerns the relationship of an idea with other ideas in the mind. Furthermore, Spinoza himself defines doubt in terms of certainty. At TIE 78 Spinoza writes that “doubt will arise though another idea which is not so clear and distinct that we can infer from it something certain about the thing concerning which there is doubt.” Finally, Spinoza writes that “by certainty we understand something positive, not the privation of doubt” (E IIp49). This gives us an alternative characterization of doubt: I doubt that p if I have any idea from which I fail to “infer from it something certain” about p. Although Spinoza tries to retain Cartesian language in the PPC by suggesting that the possibility of God’s deception furnishes a reason to doubt triangle, it is clear that he is really concerned there with whether or not we can “infer that [triangle] is most certain” (C 237). This is an absurdly high standard, but certainty, for Spinoza, is a matter of degree. The more C&D ideas we have deduced from God’s essence, from which we can

346

SKEPTICISM

deduce the idea in question, and the fewer unclear and indistinct ideas we have that we cannot connect up with it, the more certain the idea. The perfectly certain idea, which can be deduced from every idea in the mind, is to be found only in God’s intellect. Now the Cartesian skeptic can still ask whether our C&D ideas are true, or whether we are justified in believing them, starting with the C&D idea of God. Or as Spinoza gripes, “Perhaps . . . some Skeptic would still doubt both the first truth itself and everything we shall deduce according to the standard of the first truth” (TIE 47). Spinoza responds that this person “speaks contrary to his own consciousness” and his mind is “completely blinded” (TIE 48). Doubt must always have another idea as a reason or a cause (TIE 78). To have an idea is just to (pro tanto) believe or affirm that idea, because ideas essentially involve affirmation (E IIp49), although other ideas in the mind may undermine that affirmation. If there are no ideas in the mind other than the C&D idea of God and those deduced from it, the skeptic has nothing that could generate a doubt, and is just “saying in words” that he doubts. But this is still only a psychological diagnosis of the skeptic. Very well: being certain in the Spinozistic sense entails that someone is unable to doubt her ideas. But can it ensure that she is justified in believing them, or that they are true? Recall that, on the account of certainty that we have provided for Spinoza, that an idea is certain entails, among other things, that it is C&D. Spinoza stresses in the PPC that we can form a C&D idea of God’s essence before we know whether our author is a deceiver—a point that Descartes also clearly accepts. What does it mean to perceive something clearly and distinctly? In the case of Cartesian immutable natures, it entails that the properties that I C&Dly perceive to belong to that essence really do belong to that essence. As Descartes puts it: “The mere fact that I can produce from my thought the idea of something entails that everything which I clearly and distinctly perceive to belong to that thing really does belong to it” (CSM II 91).2 In the same place, Descartes claims that it is this sort of understanding that he has of the truths of mathematics. But then what, exactly, are we doubting when we doubt whether triangle is true? It cannot be that triangle in fact follows from the essence of a triangle—the truth of this is just exhausted by the fact that the truth of triangle can be clearly and distinctly perceived to belong to the essence of a triangle. It is not clear that Descartes can give any sense to the claim that he doubts the truth of triangle, once he grants that he C&Dly perceives the essence of a triangle and C&Dly perceives that triangle belongs to it. Descartes tries to drive a wedge between the assertion that triangle belongs to the nature of a triangle and the assertion that triangle can be truly affirmed of a triangle in the Second Replies (CSM 106) where he distinguishes between the following claims: 1. “That which we clearly understand to belong to the nature of something can be truly asserted to belong to its nature,” which claim Descartes deems “tautological,” and 2. “That which we clearly understand to belong to the nature of something can truly be affirmed of that thing,” which he seems to think is more substantive.

SPINOZA ON SKEPTICISM

347

But Descartes’s own Definition IX in the Second Replies (CSM II 74) comes close to an admission that (1) and (2) are equivalent: “When we say that something is contained in the nature of the concept of a thing, this is the same as saying that it is true of that thing, or that it can be asserted of that thing [my emphasis].”3 Descartes can try to rely on a distinction between asserting something of a thing and affirming something of a thing, but I do not see what sort of distinction he has in mind. Spinoza clearly believes that Descartes cannot maintain this distinction. All that the truth of triangle consists in is that it follows from the essence of a triangle. Spinoza applies this concept of truth even to essences that do not seem to be simple or immutable natures in the Cartesian sense: If some architect conceives a building in an orderly fashion, then although such a building never existed, and even never will exist, still the thought of it is true, and the thought is the same, whether the building exists or not. (TIE 69) This is Spinoza’s point when he insists in the PPC that I can form a C&D idea of God’s essence and deduce ideas from it, even before I know that I am not authored by a deceiver: truth does not depend on a well-intentioned creator matching up my ideas with the world. In these passages, an idea is true if it does in fact follow from a given possible essence. Sometimes it sounds like this may be a finite essence: in the case of the architect’s blueprint, Spinoza seems to suggest that “the architect’s building has a spiral staircase” is true if and only if it is in fact a feature of that blueprint. Other times, as in Spinoza’s discussion of certainty above, it sounds like this could be true only if the architect’s blueprint itself was deduced in the right way from God’s essence—the cause and origin of nature. It might look like, while this gets us an (ideally) perfectly coherent network of ideas, we have not established that anything outside of these ideas, including God, actually exists.4 But Spinoza thinks that existence claims, like claims about essences, also follow from God’s essence (E Ip25) and are independent of truths about essences (e.g., E IIp8s). It is not clear how truths about which things exist and in what order follow from God’s essence, by Spinoza’s lights, and Spinoza apparently thinks that we shouldn’t even bother trying to deduce the series of finite existences from God’s essence, since we are in no position to know it (e.g., Ep. 32). But at least in principle it can be so deduced.5 However, Spinoza also articulates a different conception of truth than this one, on which p is true, not if it can be clearly and distinctly perceived to follow from a given essence, but if it corresponds to its object. In the Ethics, it is axiomatic that “a true idea must agree with its object” (E Ia6), which axiom serves as the very definition of truth at Short Treatise II 15. How could this agreement be guaranteed by certainty, on the account of certainty we attributed to Spinoza? In the Ethics, Spinoza replaces talk of clarity and distinctness with talk of adequacy, using them interchangeably in some places (E IIp36, 38). Like clarity and distinctness, it is an “intrinsic denomination”; an adequate idea insofar as it is considered in itself, without relation to an object [objectum], has all the properties, or intrinsic denominations of a true idea . . . I say intrinsic to exclude what is extrinsic, viz. the agreement of the idea with its object. (E IId4)

348

SKEPTICISM

It seemed like Spinoza had managed to rid himself of his dreaded skeptic by denying him the required distinction between truth and what is clearly and distinctly perceived of an essence. But now Spinoza has asked for it. How do you know that what has the intrinsic denominations of adequacy has the extrinsic denominations of agreement with an object? Spinoza asks this question at E IIp43: “How can a man know that he has an idea that agrees with its object?” “He who has a true idea,” Spinoza answers, “at the same time knows that he has a true idea, and cannot doubt the truth of the thing.” The proof claims that if the human mind has an adequate idea of X, then there also is an adequate idea of the idea of X in that mind, concluding: And so he who has an adequate idea, or (by P34) who knows a thing truly, must at the same time have an adequate idea, or true knowledge, of his own knowledge. I.e. (as is manifest through itself), he must at the same time be certain, q.e.d. Spinoza’s proof that true ideas carry certainty moves from a mind’s having an adequate idea of X to its “knowing a thing truly,” which is justified by E IIp34: “Every idea that in us is absolute, or adequate and perfect, is true.”6 However, the proof’s reliance on IIp32, which in turn appeals to IIp7c, suggests that the sense of “agreement” that is being established between an idea and its object is not, prima facie, the kind of agreement with which the skeptic is concerned. It is instead the agreement of a mode of thought with its parallel mode, and while adequate ideas do agree with their objects in this sense, so do all ideas. But this is not what we want to know: to use Spinoza’s example, when we ask whether Peter’s idea of Paul is true, we want to know whether it agrees with what it represents—Paul—and not whether it agrees with its parallel object in God, which is some state of Peter’s body. This correspondence account of truth seems to be in tension with the account of truth in at least parts of the TIE; in addition to the passages above, in the TIE 69–71, Spinoza claims that “the form of the true thought must be placed in the same thought itself without relation to other things.” Spinoza means something different by “truth” here than he does in the Ethics, where he separates the intrinsic and extrinsic aspects of an idea from one another. Spinoza goes on to articulate his epistemology almost exclusively in terms of adequacy and not truth. There are a number of excellent works that treat Spinoza’s account of truth and adequacy in greater depth.7 But as long as he maintains a distinction between truth and adequacy, Spinoza’s response to the skeptic in IIp34 will strike her as a dodge and not a response, since it does not relate the intrinsic properties of the idea, like adequacy, to agreement with its object.

3 KNOWLEDGE Skepticism is usually formulated as a question about the possibility of knowledge, but we have not really talked about knowledge so far. Actually, Spinoza uses the word ‘cognitio’, which is the word that is usually translated as “knowledge,” in contexts that involve very different types of cognitive contents and in contexts that do not involve truth or even adequacy. There seem to be no special constraints on

SPINOZA ON SKEPTICISM

349

what counts as cognitio besides having an idea (in IIp20, e.g., Spinoza refers several times to “an idea, or knowledge [sive cognitio]”). Spinoza does not have a concept that plays the role of Descartes’s knowledge or of our knowledge—something that requires, say, belief, truth, evidence, or certainty. Not only does ‘cognitio’ signify a variety of kinds of perceptions or conceptions with varying degrees of adequacy, but no more is required for cognitio than having an idea. The only reason anyone would doubt this, Spinoza continues in IIp43s, is if they conceived of an idea “as something mute, like a picture on a tablet,” so that it would be possible to be in possession of a true idea without believing it. As we have seen, Spinoza denies that this is possible. Rather than a single distinction between what counts as knowledge and what fails to qualify, Spinoza proposes a hierarchy of kinds of cognitio. Our highest epistemic goal is to know the essences of particular things in nature, or to “reproduce the formal character of nature, both as to the whole and as to the parts” (TIE 91). There is only one kind of cognition that serves this goal: the kind that deduces the essence of a thing from the essence of its cause, and ultimately from the “source and origin of nature,” or God. It is about this kind of knowledge that it is fair to call Spinoza anti-skeptical. But Spinoza admits that he knows very little in this way (TIE 20). While every person does have adequate knowledge of God’s essence (E IIp47), it is difficult to see how we can get from that to knowledge either of the laws of nature or of the essences of particular things. Most cognitio is through experientia vaga, or “experience that is not determined by the intellect” (TIE 20), which includes all the ideas acquired through the senses, or what Spinoza calls imagination. But this cognition cannot give us adequate knowledge of nature “as it is in itself” (TIE 9) and never involves certainty (TIE 26). There is a kind of cognition in between these two that, according to the Ethics, gives us adequate knowledge of the properties of things in general but not of the essences of particular things. However, the most natural reconstruction of Spinoza’s account of their adequacy seems to entail that they are a kind of accidentally adequate imaginative knowledge. We think that we are perceiving the properties of external bodies, while we are actually perceiving a combination of properties of our own bodies and the ones that are affecting us. Usually this would make those ideas inadequate, but since those properties happen to be the same in certain cases, we perceive them adequately. This would seem to be precisely the kind of case where skeptical worries would arise—sometimes those ideas are adequate, and sometimes they are not, but how can we be sure which one is which? In fact, in the earlier TIE, Spinoza writes that only intuition “comprehends the adequate essence of the thing and is without danger of error” (TIE 29). So, at least early Spinoza would have denied that we know these common properties with certainty. Given Spinoza’s accounts of truth, certainty, and belief, it is difficult to evaluate Spinoza as a skeptic or an anti-skeptic in those terms. But if we redefine skepticism in Spinozistic terms, we find that Spinoza counts as skeptical about a variety of kinds of possible knowledge: those are the areas of inquiry in which we are not able, for Spinoza, to form adequate ideas. The reason is not that we cannot have certainty in these realms, or that our ideas of their subject matters are fallible. Rather, in all of these cases, Spinoza argues that there are systematic reasons why the ideas that

350

SKEPTICISM

are formed are inadequate. In this way, Spinoza denies that we can possibly have knowledge of nature of the following kinds: revealed, moral, applied mathematical, and empirical. If we understand scientific knowledge as empirical or mathematical knowledge of nature, then Spinoza seems to be a skeptic about scientific knowledge, belying the widely accepted story, as expressed by Popkin, that “if Spinoza was an irreligious sceptic, he was most un- or anti-sceptical in the areas of scientific and philosophical knowledge” (Popkin 2003: 246). Any cognition from sense experience counts as the first—inadequate—kind of knowledge, even the most carefully controlled experiments. In his exchange with Oldenburg about Robert Boyle’s experiments with niter, Spinoza argues that whatever properties of matter an experiment might make manifest to the senses, we can never know the deeper causes at play (Ep. 13). “The way in which things are really ordered and interconnected,” Spinoza admits, “is quite unknown to us” (TTP II 58). While experiments can usefully catalog the sensible properties of physical objects, such a catalog is of nature “as it is related to the human senses” and not “as it is in itself” (Ep. 6). What about mathematical physics? Spinoza does not doubt the adequacy of mathematical claims, and he identifies mathematics as a model on which all inquiry should be based (E I app). But he straightforwardly denies that applied mathematics provides us with knowledge of nature. Treating bodies in terms of their geometrical properties, Spinoza claims, involves abstraction, and abstractions do not describe “real and physical beings” (Ep. 12). Abstraction by its nature leads to confusion, since it elides particular differences, and all that exists are particulars (TIE 75–76, 93, 99). While Descartes makes a similar critique of abstraction, unlike Spinoza, he claims that our perception of bodies in terms of their geometrical properties involves a “clear and distinct intellectual operation” (First Set of Replies, CSM II 84). Spinoza makes his critique of applied mathematics explicit in his “letter on the infinite” (Ep. 12) and in E Ip15s, where he argues that “Measure, Time, and Number” are “only aids of the Imagination.” What is organized by measure, time, and number, however, are dimensionality, duration, and classes, so these latter, the passages suggest, are themselves generated by the imagination and thus do not represent nature as it is in itself. So much for the limits of natural knowledge in its sphere. Spinoza also denies that we can have natural knowledge of moral and religious truths. In the Ethics, Spinoza writes that good and evil, praise and blame, and sin and merit, understood as absolute, are “nothing but modes of imagining” that “do not indicate the nature of anything, only the constitution of the imagination” (E I app). It is possible to make sense, for Spinoza, of something’s being beneficial for another thing if it contributes to an increase in its power, but what contributes to the power of one finite thing detracts from the power of another. In fact, Spinoza identifies the reification of these beings of imagination as itself a cause of skepticism in the Appendix to the Ethics Part I, since what “seems good to one” turns out to be bad for another. Spinoza proposes defining revelation as “the sure knowledge of some matter revealed by God to man” (TTP 1). However, “all that we clearly and distinctly understand is dictated to us by the idea and nature of God,” according to

SPINOZA ON SKEPTICISM

351

Spinoza, so if by “revelation” we mean certain knowledge that comes from God, then all knowledge, including all natural knowledge, counts as revelation. “[F]or the knowledge that we acquire by the natural light of reason depends solely on knowledge of God and of his eternal decrees” (TTP 1). Prophecy and scripture, however, are divine in a different way. The prophet interprets revelation for those who cannot achieve certain natural knowledge of nature and must rely on faith instead to guide their lives toward beatitude. The goal of prophecy, then, is obedience and not genuine knowledge. This is achieved through the prophets, who are not individuals with more powerful rational insight, but with “more lively imaginative faculties.” An examination of scripture, Spinoza says, reveals that “everything that God revealed to the prophets was revealed either by words, or by appearances, or by a combination of both” (TTP 1). We saw above that imagination does not yield adequate knowledge, but Spinoza confirms in the TTP that “imagination by itself, unlike every clear and distinct idea, does not of its own nature carry certainty with it” (TTP 2). For this reason, those who rely on prophecy must demand a sign in order to be certain of what is revealed in prophecy. Miracles, also, provide us with no understanding of nature or of God: the power of God and the power of nature are identical, so an event that cannot be explained through natural causes cannot be explained at all, and so cannot provide us with any kind of knowledge (TTP 6). Insofar as there is any true knowledge in scripture, according to Spinoza, it must also be natural knowledge. Those teachings of scripture that are not have “nothing to do with philosophy” (Preface, TTP), and they do not represent “the sort of knowledge that derives from the natural light of reason.” The goal of scripture is to convey, with moral certainty, the “simple conception of the divine mind” that teaches obedience to God, justice, and charity. Such cognition is “completely distinct from natural knowledge in its purpose, its basis, and its method,” such that “these two have nothing in common.”

4 CONCLUSION As we saw in the last section, prophecy does not carry certainty with it, but, unlike natural knowledge, it requires a sign. Prophecy and natural knowledge share in common that they, like any knowledge, are “dictated to us, as it were, by God’s nature” (TTP 1). But all of our clear and distinct ideas, for Spinoza, are “dictated to us by the idea and nature of God—not indeed in words, but in a far superior way and one that agrees excellently with the nature of mind, as everyone who has tasted intellectual certainty has doubtless experienced in his own case” (TTP 1). That revelation requires a sign rather than carrying certainty with it makes it inferior to natural knowledge, according to Spinoza (TTP 3). Similarly, in the TIE, Spinoza stresses that the “true method does not consist in seeking the signs of truth after the acquisition of the idea. . . . The truth needs no sign” (TIE 61). Let us return to Spinoza’s account of Descartes’s response to the skeptical scenario. Spinoza, like Descartes, sees some kind of knowledge of God as part of the guarantee of knowledge that the demand for certainty represents. But according

352

SKEPTICISM

to Spinoza, this is knowledge of God’s essence, not of God’s existence and veracity. We saw that Spinoza appreciated Descartes’s foundational project when it was understood as an attempt to examine all of our ideas in order to clarify them, so that they either lost their power or furnished evidence for rather than against the doubted belief. But Spinoza rejected the idea that we must know our origin in order to know that our beliefs are not caused in a way that leads us into error. Now, this is not to say that Spinoza is not concerned with the causal origin of our ideas. Like for Descartes, in order for ideas to be true, they must be caused in the right way. God’s essence grounds our knowledge because knowledge of an effect, for Spinoza, is grounded in knowledge of its cause (E Iax4). Since God’s essence is the cause of everything in nature, “all our conceptions involve God’s nature and are conceived through God’s nature, thus we can accept finally, that everything that we adequately conceive is true” (TIE 63). Moreover, according to Spinoza, our true ideas involve or express that cause: “Nothing can be conceived without God” and “everything in Nature involves and expresses the conception of God in proportion to its essence and perfection; and therefore we acquire a greater and more perfect knowledge of God as we gain more knowledge of natural phenomena” (TTP 6). This suggests that just by attending to a true idea, the knowledge of its cause, God, is evident, and this is a mark of its truth. For Descartes, to treat the origin of our faculties as dependent on the will of God independently of their place in nature is, according to Spinoza, to treat them as miracles and to treat the idea of God as a sign. God’s goodness acts as a guarantee of the agreement of the idea with its object, but without making any clearer the nature of truth. This is illustrated by the fact that for Descartes to prove that our clear and distinct ideas are true because God guarantees their veracity does not at all require that we characterize or understand the nature of truth. All that is important for that proof is that God would not allow that our clear and distinct ideas were false, whatever truth or falsity might be. According to Spinoza, this turns all natural knowledge into revelation—an inferior kind of knowledge. Spinoza takes his response to make the nature of truth plain, and to relate it necessarily to God’s essence. Spinoza adopts the Cartesian skeptical method, if by that we understand that he appreciates that we must have knowledge of God to have knowledge of anything. But we also require knowledge of God to understand the nature of truth. Being able to be derived from God’s essence just is their truth, for Spinoza. He is an antiskeptic insofar as we can do that. But since we know very little in this way, he is a skeptic about many types of knowledge claims.

NOTES 1. I use the following abbreviations for Spinoza’s works: E = Ethics, where p = proposition, d = demonstration, def = definitions, c = corollary, a = axiom, app = appendix, l = lemma; KV = Short Treatise on God, Man, and his Well-Being; TIE = Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect; TTP = Theologico-Political Treatise; CM = Appendix Containing Metaphysical Thoughts; Ep. = Epistle. For quotations

SPINOZA ON SKEPTICISM

353

from the Principles of Cartesian Philosophy (PPC), I provide the page number from Curley (1985): for example, “C 237.” All quotations are from Curley (1985). I am very grateful to Baron Reed for his insightful comments on this chapter and for enlightening conversation. 2. He mentions the fact that he has shown God’s veracity, but seems to go on to suggest that their certainty predates this—equivocating, I believe, between psychological and normative certainty. 3. And see also the Seventh Replies (CSM II 310): “No matter who the perceiver is, nothing can be clearly and distinctly perceived without its being just as we perceive it to be, without being true.” 4. Della Rocca (2007) argues that Spinoza resists skepticism by identifying the truth of an idea, its intelligibility, and the existence of what it represents. I think that the account of truth and certainty I have described so far dovetails nicely with his and is inspired by many of the same considerations. However, as I go on to suggest, I do not think this can be the full story, since Spinoza seems elsewhere to suggest that there is a distinction between the intelligibility of a thing’s essence and its existence. 5. Note that all this can be done without appealing to any experience of the cogito or anything else that actually exists. But Spinoza does allow that we have an immediate knowledge of at least one finite existence—each of us has immediate knowledge of the existence of her own mind and body (E IIp2 and 4). As Perler (2018) argues, this precludes skepticism about the existence of the physical world, and also the external physical world, because we “feel [our] body to be affected in many ways” (E IIp4). Perler convincingly argues that we can develop these ideas that we get in this way about the things that actually affect us, connecting them up to some extent with the C&D ideas that we deduce from the essence of God. Given that these ideas are infinitely confused, while they give us knowledge that things exist, it is hard to know how to connect this knowledge of particular existences with the knowledge from essences that we get by deducing ideas from the clear and distinct idea of God’s essence. I see E IIp4 as Spinoza’s explanation of how we have anything approaching knowledge of finite existences in our local environment, given that there is no chance that we could deduce them from God’s essence, rather than as a response to the skeptic. 6. Not to mention that Spinoza seems to be offering a new account of certainty here— one that requires having an idea of an idea. 7. See, for example, Curley (1975) and Della Rocca (1994).

REFERENCES Bolton, Martha. (1985). “Spinoza on Cartesian Doubt,” Noûs 19: 379–395. Curley, Edwin. (1975). “Descartes, Spinoza and the Ethics of Belief.” In E. Freeman and M. Mandelbaum (eds.), Spinoza: Essays in Interpretation, 159–189. La Salle, IL: Open Court. Curley, Edwin. (1985). The Collected Works of Spinoza, Volume 1. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Della Rocca, Michael. (1994). “Mental Content and Skepticism in Descartes and Spinoza,” Studia Spinozana 10: 19–42.

354

SKEPTICISM

Della Rocca, Michael. (2007). “Spinoza and the Metaphysics of Scepticism,” Mind 116: 851–874. Doney, Willis. (1971). “Spinoza on Philosophical Skepticism,” The Monist 55: 617–635. Perler, Dominik. (2018). “Spinoza on Skepticism.” In M. Della Rocca (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza, 220–239. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Popkin, Richard. (2003). The History of Scepticism from Savanarola to Bayle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

CHAPTER TWENTY-FIVE

Pierre Bayle JOHN CHRISTIAN LAURSEN

1 INTRODUCTION The scholarship on Pierre Bayle (1647–1706) seems designed to reproduce the ancient skeptical tradition: equipollent arguments on both sides of any issue. On the one side, he has been described as a skeptic, and even a “superskeptic” (Popkin 2003: 283, 300–301). On the other side, he has been described as a thoroughgoing rationalist and dogmatic philosopher (Mori 1998; Israel 2006). He wrote so much, and returned to every issue multiple times and from different angles, that there is some justification, somewhere in his writings, for almost every possible interpretation of him. This very prolific many-sidedness may deserve its own place in the history of skepticism: the refusal to leave any issue alone, the constant return to arguments and opinions from every point of view, the prolixity which was perhaps matched by no other author in the tradition. Perhaps we should call it “zetetic” skepticism, after the ancients who kept on inquiring, as Sextus Empiricus put it (PH I 7). No issue was finished, closed, or immune to reopening as long as Bayle was alive. He was not a philosopher of closure. There are ways in which Bayle’s writings are similar to the skepticism of the Pyrrhonian and Academic traditions from Pyrrho, Arcesilaus, and Carneades through Cicero, Sextus Empiricus, and many others to Montaigne. These traditions need not be interpreted as incoherent, inconsistent, or immoral, as has often been the case, and hence Bayle’s skepticism also need not be dismissed on those grounds (Laursen 2004). And there are also times in which Bayle’s writings express dogmatic, and especially moralistic, claims. This chapter will compare and contrast these opposing positions. We shall begin with his understanding of famous philosophers such as Pyrrho, Descartes, Spinoza, and Malebranche in the entries of his Historical and Critical Dictionary (1697). A substantial part of what he wrote was history of philosophy, and, as one scholar has put it, there was “in the case of Bayle, an indissoluble link between philosophical skepticism and history as an empirical science” (Smith 2013: 30). Then we will turn to his practical philosophy. He wrote many books that were philosophical interventions into the raging issues of the day such as religious persecution and toleration, and in some of them we can detect the influence of his skepticism.

356

SKEPTICISM

2  BAYLE ON THE ANCIENT SKEPTICS There is no doubt that Bayle was aware of the skeptical traditions. In a letter of 1673 to his friend Vincent Minutoli he paraphrased Sextus Empiricus to the effect that “the most general division between all of the sects of philosophers is between those who think they have found the truth, those who think it cannot be found, and those who think they have not yet found it and keep searching,” and reviewed the teachings of the Academics and Pyrrhonians (Labrousse et al. 1999: vol. 1, 185). One of the most famous entries in his Historical and Critical Dictionary was “Pyrrho.”1 However, as we shall see, it is probably fair to say that Bayle never tried to follow closely any school of skepticism, and better to say that throughout his life he improvised his own variations on the theme of skepticism. The article on Pyrrho surveys some of the chief elements of Pyrrhonism. They can be usefully divided into the critiques of reason and the claim that custom and education determine most of what we think. Pyrrho supplied a series of underminings of reason: “the minds of men are unstable”; “the inconstancy of human opinions and passions is so great that it might be said that man is a small republic that often changes its magistrates” (Bayle 1991: 209 note F); the Pyrrhonians “were always seeking, and always unsteady, and ready at all times to reason after a new manner, according to the various occurrences they met with” (Bayle 1734–1738: vol. 4, 657 note F). On the role of custom and education, “Pyrrho maintained that there was not really any one thing that was this or that, and that the nature of things depended upon laws and customs; that is to say, that men by their laws and customs made some things good, laudable, ill, blameable &c” (1734–1738: 658 note I). So the alternative to reason was largely custom and habit. In “Jonas” he observed that “ideas of virtue depend on education and custom” (Bayle 1991: 106). Pyrrhonism is mentioned or discussed in many other articles, usually to make one of the above points about the weakness of reason and the strength of custom and education (Bayle 1734–1738: vol. 5, 103 Index). The same points are often made without reference to Pyrrhonism. In “Bunel” he quotes Cardinal Pole for saying that one should “admit that he knows nothing; that this is the non plus ultra of philosophy” and thus that one should turn to religious faith for truth (Bayle 1991: 42). In his own voice Bayle says that I find that Pole’s judgment is the most sensible one that can be made about philosophy; and I am extremely pleased that such an author gives me an opportunity of confirming what I have set down in various places, namely, that our reason is suitable for making everything perplexing and for raising doubts about everything. No sooner has it built something than it provides the means for destroying it. Reason is a veritable Penelope, unraveling during the night what she has been weaving during the day. (1991: 42) In the entry, “Manicheans,” he observes that human reason “is a principle of destruction . . . [and] is only fit to make man aware of his own blindness and weakness” (1991: 151). His critique of the Socinians in “Socinus, Faustus” is that their reliance on reason is “hardly suitable for converting the people . . . [and]

PIERRE BAYLE

357

is more appropriate for leading persons . . . into skepticism (pyrrhonisme)” than anything else (Bayle 2000a: 266). Such observations are repeated in a wide range of variations on the theme in Bayle’s vast texts. Pyrrhonism was often accused of fostering immorality and atheism in Bayle’s day, and he later added a “Clarification concerning Pyrrhonism” to the second edition of his Historical and Critical Dictionary (1702) in order to defend it against these charges. It was not subversive, he wrote, because he was saying nothing in it about religion, only about philosophy, and that Jesus himself had endeavored to “confound all philosophy and show its vanity” just like the Pyrrhonians (Bayle 1991: 423). Bayle often made a major distinction between faith and reason, which insulated religion from the inroads of reason and also insulated philosophy from the inroads of religion. His argument was that one could not know anything in philosophy—a version of skepticism—but that religious faith did not require anyone to know anything. Bayle’s article on Pyrrho sends us elsewhere for more on his understanding of skepticism. Of Pyrrho, he says: “His opinions did not differ much from those of Arcesilaus,” one-time head of the Academy and one of the founders of Academic skepticism (Bayle 1991: 194). The only difference was that the Academics affirmed the incomprehensibility of things where the Pyrrhonians suspended judgment even about that: “In every thing else they were perfectly alike” (Bayle 1734–1738: vol. 4, 653 note A). In the article “Arcesilaus,” Bayle wrote that this Academic skeptic approved of the verse of Hesiod that “the Gods keep human Understanding behind the Veil” (Hickson 2010: 561). The article on Arcesilaus’s successor, Carneades, reports that the latter “allowed of nothing but Probabilities for the use of Life; and beyond that he believed there was no Certainty or Evidence” (1734–1738: vol. 2, 326 note B). When he says of the Academics that “their Speculation hung betwixt two Contraries; but their Practice stuck fast to one of them” and observes that “It is the way of the World: Men do not live up to their Principles,” he is further undermining rationalism, which would require one to resolve which of the two contraries is right before acting on one of them, and that men should live up to their principles (1734–1738: vol. 2, 330 note G). This was one of the crucial features of Bayle’s skepticism: even if we do know something, there is a disconnect between reason and life, and we do not live by our knowledge. Based on these and other remarks, some scholars have concluded that Bayle was an Academic skeptic (Maia Neto 1999; Lennon 2002). It is possible to interpret Bayle in somewhat narrowly Pyrrhonian or Academic terms. It is also possible, to follow a remark by Thomas Lennon, that “Bayle’s approach is thus less skeptical than ‘critical’” (1999: 10). Given the prominence of this term in the title of Bayle’s Dictionary and in the titles of the three most substantial volumes of Immanuel Kant’s later philosophy, it is surprising how little historical and analytical attention that word has received. In the “Projet” or proposal for his Dictionary, Bayle claimed that “critical research” would help us avoid mistakes and give us “a true notion of the weakness of the mind, and of the nothingness and vanity of the sciences” (Bayle 2000a: 13). Bayle’s skepticism certainly included a fair measure of critical thinking. It is a remarkable paradox that, as one scholar has put

358

SKEPTICISM

it, Bayle seems to have had an obsession with the truth, a “critical obsession” which led him to test and take apart every idea in the history of philosophy, such that no truth survived his analysis (Simonutti 2011).

3  BAYLE ON THE MODERN PHILOSOPHERS The above can serve as a background for Bayle’s readings of famous philosophers such as Descartes, Spinoza, and Malebranche. They are skeptical and critical deconstructions of these thinkers. It is well known that Descartes based his answer to the hypothesis of the malin génie on the claim that God would not lie to us. In his entry “Rimini,” Bayle pointed to medieval and contemporary Socinian arguments that God did indeed have the power to lie (Paganini 2008a: 368–370). This led to all sorts of paradoxes such as, if God cannot lie, then is he not all-powerful? And if he can lie, how can we possibly tell when he is telling the truth and when he is lying? Bayle provided no answers, and the questions lingered into the eighteenth century (Laursen 1994). After Bayle, the Cartesian principle of divine veracity did not have much purchase. This was not all that Bayle had to say about Descartes. He may have begun as a Cartesian philosopher, but he moved far away. In the Dictionary he reported that Descartes was not original: he borrowed his theory of the vortices from the Greek philosopher Leucippus (Bayle 1991: 125). Bayle gave balancing counterarguments to what Descartes had said about the vacuum, noting that this favored the Pyrrhonians (1991: 136–137). He lined up the counterarguments to Descartes’s view of animals as machines (1991: 214–245). He delved into the pros and cons of Cartesian claims about the extension of spirit (1991: 280–284) and the nature of God (1991: 369–374, 385), and he found contradictions in all of the works of the Cartesians of his day. The foregoing is only a small fraction of what Bayle wrote to undermine Descartes. Much of his critique of Descartes and the Cartesians was not direct refutation, but in the classic skeptical form of providing examples of counterarguments from the history of philosophy. Spinoza fared no better with Bayle. He opposed Spinoza largely because the latter was a rationalist, and rationalism was one of Bayle’s bêtes noires. Bayle wrote that Spinoza’s doctrine of monism, that there is one substance and that it is identical with God, meant “giving the words a completely new signification” and has absurd consequences (Bayle 1991: 313, 330). He argued that religious faith was perfectly justifiable because “there is no contradiction between these two things: (1) The light of reason teaches me that this is false; (2) I believe it nonetheless because I am convinced that this light is not infallible” (1991: 298). In this and in later polemics against the rationalist theologians of his era, Bayle insisted that rationality had no place in religion (Brogi 1998; Paganini 2008b). Bayle associated Malebranche with Chrysippus, who raised more objections against his own doctrine than he could answer. In Bayle’s reductio ad absurdum, Malebranche is accused of subjecting God to fate and implied that God selfishly pursues glory at the expense of human suffering (Paganini 2008a: 371–379; 2008b: 115–118). The upshot of Bayle’s analyses of the modern philosophies is that none

PIERRE BAYLE

359

of them can stand. Assertions are met by counterassertions, arguments are shown to imply absurdities. No philosophy emerges unscathed. This surely must qualify as a combination of several sorts of skepticism.

4  BAYLE ON ATHEISM Skepticism is often associated with atheism, although they are not the same thing: atheism usually means a dogmatic theory that there is no God, which the more consistent skeptics could not admit. They are closer to the agnostics when they suspend judgment about the Gods. Bayle’s first important work, Diverse Thoughts on the Comet of 1682, was not really about comets but about the nature of belief, the effects of atheism on society, and more. He undermines those who think we can come up with reliable and true principles of behavior by pointing out, as he would often repeat, that even if we did have such principles, they would not affect our behavior. Most of the time one does not live by one’s principles, but according to one’s “temperament, the natural inclination toward pleasure, the taste one contracts for certain objects, the desire to please someone, a habit gained in the commerce of one’s friends” (Bayle 2000b: 169). People also live for their passions, their pride, and in accordance with the “mechanical constitution of their nature” (2000b: 210– 211), which track fairly closely to the first two of Sextus Empiricus’s four rules by which the skeptic lives after suspending belief (PH I 23). Showing that we live by the alternatives to knowledge and truth is one way of indicating that whether or not we have access to truth may be irrelevant. Perhaps the most notorious implication of this argument, also followed up in some of Bayle’s later works, was the case for the possibility of a virtuous society of atheists. It was widely accepted in Bayle’s time that, without religion, people would violate all of the rules of morality and kill each other. Bayle argued on the contrary that people’s actions are determined by their temperament and taste, not by their opinions about religion (Bayle 2000b: 178–180). Rewards and punishments, pride, reputation, vanity, are more than enough to keep social peace (2000b: 212–213, 223). We have records of atheists who have been good people (Bayle 2000b: 214). Bayle also noted that the record of religious people was just as bad as what was conjectured of atheists: one example was the court of Catherine de Medici, where “although they believed in God, they were capable of every sort of wickedness” (2000b: 193). Many years later, when the Dictionary was also accused of atheism, Bayle answered with a “Clarification concerning atheists” in the second edition of the work. There he pointed out that, in the absence of moral truths derived from truths about God, people might nevertheless behave appropriately on the basis of their “temperament, education, liveliness of ideas of virtue, love of glory, or dread of dishonor” (Bayle 1991: 407). He does not retract what critics perceived as a defense of atheism, but repeated his view that it could be harmless to society. And a few years after that, in some of his last works, Bayle reaffirmed the value of the example of the ancient Chinese as combining atheism with good morals and politics (Bayle 1966a: 227–229, 397; Bayle 1966b: 958, 966, 983, 988).

360

SKEPTICISM

Does the foregoing mean that Bayle was an atheist? Scholars have been divided. Ever since his own time, many have thought that he was an atheist, and many still do so today (Mori 1999, 2003; Israel 2006; McKenna 2010, 2012). Others, however, have found him to be a “fideist,” or someone whose religion is based on faith, not knowledge (Popkin 2003); a “complicated Protestant” (Bost 2006, 2008); and religious enough to write theodicy (Hickson 2010, 2011, and 2013). Mori makes the convincing argument that Bayle’s natural philosophy from the time of his early courses at Sedan leaves no room for a deity (Mori 1999). And it seems likely that, if Bayle had been an atheist, he would have concealed it for the sake of safety (McKenna 2010). But Bayle often reiterated the observation that one’s philosophy may have no connection with how one lives, what religion one follows, and other matters. Arguing that philosophy and knowledge have no effect on life and that we live by other means is a form of skepticism. And in this case, without trying to figure out what the “real” Bayle thought, we can observe that like other skeptics of the tradition, he left many clues and arguments on each side of the issue. In his time and in the eighteenth century, most readers believed Bayle was an atheist, and his influence was wide. His Dictionary was the most widely held book in French private libraries in the eighteenth century (Lennon 1999). G. W. Leibniz thought it important to refute him, David Hume took notes from Bayle while writing his Treatise of Human Nature, and virtually every other significant eighteenth-century thinker engaged with his thought. His contributions to shaping our views of the history of philosophy and of skepticism cannot be overestimated. We owe to him our understanding of much of this history as a debate between dogmatic rationalism and skepticism.

5  RATIONALISM AND SKEPTICISM IN BAYLE’S MORE PRACTICAL WRITINGS Bayle’s Philosophical Commentary of 1686, widely accepted as one of the greatest defenses of religious toleration in the history of philosophy, also contains a tension between skepticism and rationalism (Bayle 2005). It may be internally contradictory, and perhaps even incoherent. But the history of philosophy includes far more than the perfectly consistent and coherent, and even works that do not meet the highest standards of consistency have had their influence. A skeptic of Bayle’s stripe may not be too worried about this, because he is occupied with juxtaposing and analyzing all sorts of arguments, and in this case his determination to support toleration and condemn persecution means that he is willing to use any arguments, even contradictory ones. Bayle’s book is in the first instance a commentary on a parable of Jesus (Luke, ch. 14) that was used throughout the seventeenth century by both Catholics and Protestants to justify religious persecution (Marshall 2006: 201–212, 404, 465, 643–646). In that parable, a man prepares a celebration and invites his friends. They are unable to come, so he orders his servant to “go out into the highways and hedges,” find people, “and compel them to come in.” This is a story about inviting

PIERRE BAYLE

361

people to a feast, and yet it was used as early as St. Augustine to justify violent persecution of heretics. The feast was interpreted to mean the church, and the word “compel” was taken to justify the use of force to bring people into the church. Jesus is often quoted for the things he says about peace and gentleness, but he also chased the moneychangers out of the temple (Jn 2:15) and said: “I come not to send peace but a sword” (Mt. 10:34), so persecutors did not have to rely on Lk. 14:23 alone. Bayle, a French Protestant by birth who by that time was living in exile in Rotterdam, responded to Augustine and the persecutors with one of the most thoroughgoing arguments for religious toleration in the early modern Western tradition. At the beginning of the Philosophical Commentary, he asserts the priority of what he variously calls the “Light of Nature,” the “first Principles of Reason” (Bayle 2005: 65), “inward Light,” “natural Light,” and “interior Truth” (2005: 70). All theologians rely on reason whenever they make arguments. That means “That Reason, speaking to us by the Axioms of natural Light, or metaphysical Truths, is the supreme Tribunal, and final Judg without Appeal of whatever’s propos’d to the human Mind” (2005: 67). Bayle asserts that reason naturally comes up with the idea of moral equality and fairness. Thus “all moral Laws, without exception, ought to be regulated by that natural Idea of Equity” (2005: 69). There is a “Conscience of Right and Wrong imprinted on the Souls of all Men,” an “interior Light which communicates it self immediately to all Spirits” (2005: 71). This is a dogmatic, rationalist argument, with no trace of skepticism. We may begin to suspect the purity of Bayle’s rationalism when we realize that he is actually promoting Christian theology. Relying on the literal reading of the word “compel” to justify violence, Bayle asserts, would be “repugnant to the purest and most distinct Ideas of natural Reason” (Bayle 2005: 75). But it is a very specific theology that emerges as the product of reason: “By the purest and most distinct Ideas of Reason, we find there is a Being sovereignly perfect, who rules over all things, who ought to be ador’d by Mankind, who approves certain Actions, and rewards ‘em” (2005: 76). This is not pure light and reason but a Christian interpretation of religion. Bayle asserts that several of the principles of Christianity are products of reason: “Natural Light distinctly inform[s] every Soul which attentively consults it, that God is just, that he loves virtue,” etc., and everyone knows “That ‘tis honest and praise-worthy to forgive Enemys” (2005: 81). He also cites the complaints of the first Christians against violent persecution (2005: 124), but these cannot be considered universal or rationalist arguments. They are arguments from one particular religion. In Bayle’s hands, Protestant theology undermines the argument that violent conversion is justified by law: “All laws which oblige against Conscience, are made by a Person, having no Authority to enact it, and who manifestly exceeds his Power,” and are thus unjust (Bayle 2005: 113). Conscience “is the Voice and Law of God in” each “particular Man” (2005: 113). Princes have “no Power, either from God or Man, of enjoining their Subjects to act against Conscience” (2005: 114). Note that this Protestant definition of conscience is not universal, and not shared by most Catholics. Bayle also uses non-universal Christian arguments such as that allowing Christians to make forcible conversions deprives them of one of their chief

362

SKEPTICISM

objections to the Muslims. Christians always asserted that false religions relied on force where the true religion could rely on truth, and if they rely on force, they are conceding that theirs might not be true. The argument proceeds with references to “the Dictates of right Reason” (Bayle 2005: 195) and the “clearest principles of Metaphysics” (2005: 220) as if these were unproblematic. But Bayle began to undermine them by the claim that “every one’s determin’d by his own private Lights” (2005: 74). If the light of reason is not universal, but rather individual, then all of his arguments from natural light and reason are refuted. But now we get to the most interesting part: in chapters 8 to 10 of Part Two, Bayle undermines his own assertions of the rationality of religious toleration. He pursues a skeptical strategy instead of a dogmatic strategy in order to argue against the idea that Jesus intended us to persecute in order to compel people to join his church. Bayle may have no better reason for his stance than his own gut feelings, but that is an accepted Pyrrhonian justification. In a few earlier places he reminded people that they had been wrong before and might still be wrong now. But now he appeals openly to human ignorance and ineptitude in his famous analysis of the erroneous conscience (see Laursen 2001). Up until this point, Bayle has generally been relying on a strong notion of truth. Now he argues that “whatever a Conscience well directed allows us to do for the advancement of Truth, an erroneous Conscience will warrant for advancing a suppos’d Truth” (Bayle 2005: 220). But if correct and erroneous consciences cannot agree, how can we know which is the real truth? He insists that “the Law of never violating the Lights of our Conscience is such that God himself can never dispense with” it because it is an “eternal and immutable Law” (2005: 227). But clearly many people’s consciences have not recognized that law. Bayle realizes that his arguments justify conscientious persecutors. His answer is only that “it does not follow, that they act without Sin,” and that “this ought to not hinder our crying out loudly against their false Maxims, and endeavoring to enlighten their Understandings” (Bayle 2005: 242). But by his theory they are required to act on their wrong understandings. He asserts that no one would ever preach “Sodomy, Murder, and Rapine” because they are patently against “natural Rectitude” and scripture (2005: 244), but we know that many people have considered those actions justifiable, perhaps under different labels. Bayle’s epistemological arguments undermine much of what he has said before. “God has not printed any Characters or Signs on the Truths which he has reveal’d, at least not on the greatest part of ‘em, by which we might certainly and infallibly discern ‘em” (Bayle 2005: 259). If “Conscience is given us as a Touch-stone of Truth” and our consciences err, then we will not agree on truths (2005: 261). He concludes that “God in the present Condition of Man exacts no more from him than a sincere and diligent Search after truth,” not actually finding it (2005: 264). In one of his most devastating arguments, he even concludes that consciences are not very different from matters of taste: “No matter whether this Conscience presents to one Man such an Object as true, to another as false. . . . Does not one man’s Tast tell him that such Food is good, and the Tast of another tell him it’s bad?” (2005: 271). But truths and light were the foundation of his claims for toleration up to this

PIERRE BAYLE

363

point, and if they are now just like matters of taste, they cannot make a universal case for toleration. The fact is, Bayle insists, we believe what we believe based on our education. “Education is undoubtedly capable of making the Evidence of Truths of Right utterly disappear” (Bayle 2005: 275). But if education can make truths disappear, what has become of the universal truths of light and reason? The Supplement to Bayle’s book, published two years later, reinforces this side of Bayle’s argument. He demonstrates repeatedly that it is “the imperious Force of Education” (2005: 470), “Custom and Education” (2005: 471), that determines beliefs (see also 2005: 473– 474), not reason, a universal conscience, and natural light. As for reason, it emerges that there are reasons on both sides of every issue. Yet another reason to doubt the universality of reason is that we do not know why one set of reasons appeals to one person and another to another person. Bayle is reduced to saying that “naturally his Turn of Understanding is such, that he’s struck much more by one sort of Reasons than by another” (2005: 490). Anyone may be attracted to one set of reasons “by an odd Turn of Understanding” or by a “relish” (2005: 490). As Bayle puts it, “I can’t for my part see, that there must necessarily be a criminal Passion at heart, to make a Man prefer the Reasons which are alleg’d against some Points of Orthodoxy, to the Reasons which support ‘em” (2005: 490). But if “reasons” can go either way, what does that imply for the appeals to reason and natural light in the first parts of the book? If anyone thinks that Bayle might distinguish univocal philosophical truth from debatable theological truth, it is worth observing that for Bayle not only theological but also philosophical reason can be wrong. Another chapter of the Supplement, titled “Whether the Arguments for the Truth are always more solid than those for Falsehood” (Bayle 2005: 531–538), undermines any claims for philosophical reason. There, he says, “necessary truths . . . [are] so evident . . . [that they] carry their own Reason along with ’em which no one contests” (2005: 531). But if anyone does contest them, then they are not such necessary truths. Needless to say, the persecutors not only contest the ideas of the people they persecute, but they just as obviously contest the idea that persecution is wrong. So these are cases “when a necessary truth is not evident” (2005: 531). And people decide what these are according to the way “they are determin’d by Temper and Complexion to some Notions rather than others” (2005: 533). In all cases, “each have had their Patrons and Partys in different Countrys, and different Ages of the World” (2005: 533). If a person “inclines to one, ‘tis more from some Prevalence of Temper than that of the Arguments” (2005: 534). This means that, on contested issues like the value of persecution, it is not abstract and universal reason but rather temperament that determines our judgment. Bayle has been reduced to claiming that, if one wants to (and Bayle does), one may be tolerant, but there does not appear to be any way to argue conclusively and convincingly against a temperament that prefers persecution. On the one hand, Bayle has written of the clearest truths of reason and natural light. On the other, he has also raised epistemological barriers to knowing what these truths are, or if there really are any, and argued that we are captive to

364

SKEPTICISM

our consciences, whether right or erroneous, and are products of our education (Laursen 2011). Much of what Bayle says would seem to vindicate Richard Popkin’s judgment that “Bayle’s all-out attack on everything that is said and everything that is done carried scepticism to its ultimate extreme” (2003: 300). Popkin is aware of the recent reinterpretations that see Bayle as a “positive moralist” (2003: 294) relying on reason, and recognizes that he “adopted positive moral views” (2003: 297). But set in the context of recognition of the rights of the erroneous conscience, the fact that some consciences are right and some are wrong does not get much traction. Bayle may believe his reason has taught him some truths, but he also recognizes that other people’s reason teaches them different truths. This may be interpreted as a sort of suspension of judgment about the universal truth of moral ideas and amount to following the traditional skeptical reliance on customs and education in determining how to live. The foregoing makes at least a prima facie case that Bayle carried out the Pyrrhonian skeptical project in his Philosophical Commentary, even though he did not explicitly say that that was what he was doing. Later, in explicit discussions of Pyrrhonism he described, often with the same words, what he had done in the Philosophical Commentary. The upshot is that a book which starts out taking for granted universal truths and conscientious morals ends up arguing that one reason we cannot be meant to persecute the people who are wrong is the good Pyrrhonian reason that we can rarely be sure who is right and who is wrong. Pyrrhonian reasons justify this conclusion: reason is weak and works itself into paradoxes, and we are products of our education. So who is the real Bayle, the dogmatic rationalist or the Pyrrhonian who recognizes the weakness of reason and the power of education and conscience? Jonathan Israel brings out the rationalist side of Bayle in Enlightenment Contested (Israel 2006). He asserts that “for Bayle . . . philosophical reason more geometrico is the only criterion of what is true” (2006: 72). “Bayle actually bases his thought . . . on a radical Cartesian mathematico-historical rationalist foundation” (2006: 77). And “On the fundamental rationality of human morality . . . Bayle refuses to compromise and is never skeptical” (2006: 558). Israel says that Bayle’s toleration theory is “based solely on philosophical reason and notions of ‘equity,’” and he accepts Bayle’s assertion that reason must lead to “equity, equality, individual liberty, and a comprehensive toleration” (2006: 147, 680). But this means ignoring the places where Bayle says that reason may tell us other things, too. An optimistic Enlightener like Israel thinks that, if people will only reason rightly, they will agree with him on the democratic virtues. But Bayle’s Part Two, chapters 8 to 10 and the Supplement undermine that hope. If reason can be deconstructed, we are blinded by our education, and things are much more complicated: the same corrosive reason that undercuts the claims of Christianity and monarchy may also undercut equality and democracy. Israel’s interpretation requires ignoring Bayle’s critique of the rationalist theologians Jaquelot, Le Clerc, and Bernard, who argued that reason leads us to Christian principles. Bayle argued that it does not, and that from the point of view of reason there are serious paradoxes in Christianity (Brogi 1998).

PIERRE BAYLE

365

He must have realized that there are paradoxes in equality and democracy as well. Too many of Bayle’s texts undermine reason and may be fatal to Israel’s project of placing Bayle and reason at the heart of the Radical Enlightenment. Israel knows Bayle’s discussion of the erring conscience in the Supplement, but he does not see any serious implications (2006: 149–154). For him, it is all part of his argument for Bayle’s rationality: “Nothing could be less Pyrrhonist than Bayle’s system of moral, social, and political thought” (2006: 670). But notice that he has to interpret Bayle by adding something. When Israel recognizes Bayle’s view of the power of education, he adds that Bayle, “presumably, means the reader to infer, without his spelling it out, that education itself must therefore be fundamentally reformed” (2006: 569). And Bayle’s problems would be solved if all erring consciences could be educated into correct, tolerant opinions. But Bayle does not show any confidence that this can be done, and that may be why he does not supply the recommendation for educational reform that Israel suggests he should. Any attempt to harness Bayle’s Philosophical Commentary to a straightforward, one-dimensional “Enlightenment project” of reason and natural light must take into account the arguments that undermine that rationalism that we have reviewed. However, this does not mean that Bayle’s argument for toleration must fail. Bayle is unquestionably against persecution—even against persecution of persecutors; although that does not mean he endorses them—and the wide range of his arguments, even if some of them undermine others, could nevertheless have the effect of encouraging toleration. Perhaps the Pyrrhonian undermining of all sides could even prevent toleration from becoming a rigid dogma. Bayle’s analysis of toleration in the Philosophical Commentary was not his only contribution to the case of religious toleration. The Historical and Critical Dictionary also contains an arsenal of arguments for toleration. Some of them were grounded in skeptical arguments, and some of them were dogmatic. Several of his political pamphlets, such as France Wholly Catholic (1686) and Important Warning to the Refugees (1692) were strident and moralistic cries for justice without any trace of skepticism (Stanley et al. 2014). This has been called his “moral rigorism,” and it is undeniable that he has strong moral commitments (Labrousse 1964). Whether they have unequivocal rational justification is another question. They may be more the product of his education and the customs and traditions around him than of any philosophical proof, as he often put it. It is sometimes asserted that skepticism must lead to political conservatism because one cannot fight for reform or revolution without truths, or that it must lead to revolutionary politics because the established realm is not backed by truth. But Bayle allowed his gut feelings of indignation at persecutors of all stripes to drive his politics of toleration. And his skepticism helped him find a middle way between revolutionary politics and arbitrary power: his was a politics of absolute but not arbitrary power, as one scholar has put it (Simonutti 2007). He wanted the Protestants to earn an invitation to return to France by developing a reputation as loyal subjects, and he saw great value in the rule of law. So in his case skepticism implied neither radicalism nor conservatism, but a middle way.

366

SKEPTICISM

6 CONCLUSION After reviewing all of the materials above, it is not surprising that the status of Bayle’s skepticism has been much debated (McKenna 2008). There is no doubt that he is not a slavish follower of any preceding school of skepticism. There is no doubt that he was not a complete moral skeptic or relativist but held some moral positions with all possible dogmatic conviction. But on the whole, given his use of all of the tropes and practices of the ancient and modern skeptics up to his time, his industrious inquiries into every historical and philosophical issue of the ages, and given his refusal to take any philosophical issue as settled, it is at least defensible to consider him one of the more original as well as influential skeptics of all time.

NOTE 1. English translations of this entry can be found in Bayle (1734–1738) and Bayle (1991). It will be cited to the easily available 1991 abridged version unless the relevant passage is only available in the complete 1734–1738 version.

REFERENCES Bayle, Pierre. 1734–1738. The Dictionary Historical and Critical of Mr. Peter Bayle. London: Knapton et al. (Originally published as Dictionaire historique et critique. Rotterdam: Leers, 1697; second edition 1702.) Bayle, Pierre. 1966a. Continuation des pensées diverses écrites à un Docteur de Sorbonne, à l’occasion de la Comète. In Œuvres diverses, vol. 3, 187–417. Hildesheim: Olms. (First published in 1705.) Bayle, Pierre. 1966b. Rèponse aux questions d’un provincial. In Œuvres diverses, vol. 3, 449–1084. Hildesheim: Olms. (First published in 1706.) Bayle, Pierre. 1991. Historical and Critical Dictionary, edited by R. Popkin. Indianapolis: Hackett. Bayle, Pierre. 2000a. Political Writings, edited by S. Jenkinson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bayle, Pierre. 2000b. Various Thoughts on the Occasion of a Comet, edited by R. Bartlett. Albany: State University of New York Press. (Originally published as Pensées diverses à l’occasion d’une comete. Rotterdam: Leers, 1682, second edition 1683.) Bayle, Pierre. 2005. A Philosophical Commentary on the Words “Compel Them to Come In”. . ., edited by J. Kilcullen and C. Kukathas. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. (Originally published as Commentaire philosophique sur ces paroles de Jésus-Christ, “Contrain-les d’entrer.” Amsterdam: Abraham Wolfgang, 1686–1688.) Bost, Hubert. 2006. Pierre Bayle. Paris: Fayard. Bost, Hubert. 2008. “Pierre Bayle, un ‘protestant compliqué’.”In W. Van Bunge and H. Bots (eds.), Pierre Bayle (1647–1706): Le philosophe de Rotterdam: Philosophy, Religion and Reception, 83–102. Leiden: Brill. Brogi, Stefano. 1998. Teologia senza verità: Bayle contro i ‘rationaux’. Milano: Angeli.

PIERRE BAYLE

367

Hickson, Michael. 2010. “The Message of Bayle’s Last Title,” Journal of the History of Ideas 71: 547–567. Hickson, Michael. 2011. “‘Reductio ad malum’: Bayle’s Early Skepticism about Theodicy,” The Modern Schoolman 88: 201–221. Hickson, Michael. 2013. “Theodicy and Toleration in Bayle’s Dictionary,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 51: 49–73. Israel, Jonathan. 2006. Enlightenment Contested: Philosophy, Modernity, and the Emancipation of Man 1670–1752. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Labrousse, Elisabeth. 1964. Pierre Bayle. Vol. II: Hetérodoxie et rigorisme. The Hague: Nijhoff. Labrousse, Elisabeth, Antony McKenna, et al. (eds.). 1999. Correspondance de Pierre Bayle. Oxford: Voltaire Foundation. Laursen, John Christian. 1994. “The Beneficial Lies Controversy in the Huguenot Netherlands,” Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century 319: 67–103. Laursen, John Christian. 1998. “Baylean Liberalism: Tolerance Requires Nontolerance.” In J. C. Laursen and C. Nederman (eds.), Beyond the Persecuting Society: Religious Toleration Before the Enlightenment, 197–215. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Laursen, John Christian. 2001. “The Necessity of Conscience and the Conscientious Persecutor: The Paradox of Liberty and Necessity in Bayle’s Theory of Toleration.” In L. Simonutti (ed.), Dal necessario al possibile: determinismo e libertà nel pensiero angloholandese del XVII secolo, 211–228. Milan: Angeli. Laursen, John Christian. 2004. “Yes, Skeptics Can Live Their Skepticism and Cope with Tyranny as Well as Anyone.” In J. Maia Neto and R. Popkin (eds.), Skepticism in Renaissance and Post-Renaissance Thought, 201–223. Amherst: Humanity Press. Laursen, John Christian. 2005. “Skepticism, Unconvincing Anti-skepticism, and Politics.” In M. A. Bernier and S. Charles (eds.), Scepticisme et modernité, 167–188. SaintÉtienne: Publications de la Université de Saint-Étienne. Laursen, John Christian. 2011. “Skepticism against Reason in Pierre Bayle’s Theory of Toleration.” In D. Machuca (ed.), Pyrrhonism in Ancient, Modern, and Contemporary Philosophy, 131–144. Dordrecht: Springer. Lennon, Thomas. 1999. Reading Bayle. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Lennon, Thomas. 2002. “What Kind of Skeptic Was Bayle?” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 26: 258–279. Maia Neto, José R. 1999. “Bayle’s Academic Scepticism.” In J. E. Force and R. Watson (eds.), Everything Connects, 264–276. Leiden: Brill. Marshall, John. 2006. John Locke, Toleration, and Early Modern Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. McKenna, Antony. 2008. “Pierre Bayle in the Twentieth Century.” In W. Van Bunge and H. Bots (eds.). 2008. Pierre Bayle (1647–1706): Le philosophe de Rotterdam: Philosophy, Religion and Reception, 253–267. Leiden: Brill. McKenna, Antony. 2010. “Pierre Bayle et le bouclier de Charron.” In H. Bost and A. McKenna (eds.), Les ‘Eclaircissements’ de Pierre Bayle, 299–319. Paris: Honoré Champion.

368

SKEPTICISM

McKenna, Antony. 2012. “Pierre Bayle: Free Thought and Freedom of Conscience,” Reformation and Renaissance Review 14: 85–100. Mori, Gianluca. 1999. Bayle Philosophe. Paris: Honoré Champion. Mori, Gianluca. 2003. “Pierre Bayle on Scepticism and ‘Common Notions’.” In G. Paganini (ed.), The Return of Scepticism from Hobbes and Descartes to Bayle, 393–413. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Paganini, Gianni. 2008a. Skepsis: Le débat des modernes sur le scepticisme. Paris: Vrin. Paganini, Gianni. 2008b. “Bayle et les théologies philosophiques de son temps.” In W. Van Bunge and H. Bots (eds.) 2008. Pierre Bayle (1647–1706): Le philosophe de Rotterdam: Philosophy, Religion and Reception, 103–120. Leiden: Brill. Popkin, Richard. 2003. The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sextus Empiricus. 1933. Outlines of Pyrrhonism, translated by J. B. Bury. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Simonutti, Luisa. 2007. “‘Absolute, not Arbitrary, Power’: Monarchism and Politics in the Thought of the Huguenots and Pierre Bayle.” In H. Blom, J. C. Laursen, and L. Simonutti (eds.), Monarchisms in the Age of Enlightenment, 45–59. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Simonutti, Luisa. 2011. “Obsesión con la verdad: paradojas de Pierre Bayle.” In M. J. Villaverde and J. C. Laursen (eds.), Forjadores de la Tolerancia. Madrid: Tecnos. Smith, Plínio. 2013. “Bayle and Pyrrhonism: Antinomy, Method, and History.” In S. Charles and P. Smith (eds.), Scepticism in the Eighteenth Century: Enlightenment, Lumières, Aufklärung, 19–30. Dordrecht: Springer. Stanley, Charlotte and John Christian Laursen. 2014. “Pierre Bayle’s The Condition of Wholly Catholic France,” History of European Ideas 40: 312–324. Van Bunge, Wiep and Hans Bots (eds.) 2008. Pierre Bayle (1647–1706): Le philosophe de Rotterdam: Philosophy, Religion and Reception. Leiden: Brill.

CHAPTER TWENTY-SIX

Berkeley and Skepticism MARGARET ATHERTON

1 INTRODUCTION Getting a handle on the role of skepticism in the thought of George Berkeley (1685–1753) is surprisingly difficult. As is well known, Berkeley’s case for idealism includes old and familiar skeptical arguments. And since the conclusions Berkeley wants to reach themselves seem so incredible, it is sometimes thought that an important motive for Berkeley must be to show that his central theses don’t lead to skepticism. Finally, Berkeley himself presents skepticism neither as a tool nor as a potential menace to his theory but as a target. He claims we have been led into skepticism by the views of others. The task he sets himself is to dispel the pernicious skepticism these others have encouraged. Part of the difficulty in pinning down skepticism’s role for Berkeley is also that there are too many skeptical beliefs that might be the focus of his interest in skepticism. Skepticism might be expressed in the belief that there is neither heat nor cold in the water, or that we are unable to have perceptual knowledge of ordinary physical objects, or that we are unable to know the inward essences of things.1 While any or all of these beliefs might be implicated in Berkeley’s attack on skepticism, it is important to straighten out the nature of the skepticism Berkeley takes himself to be primarily concerned with. A stress on different aspects of skepticism—ordinary objects as opposed to inward essences, for example—results in different accounts of Berkeley’s overall project. My goal here is to achieve greater clarity on this issue by answering three questions: (1) What are the skeptical beliefs Berkeley wants to dispel? (2) What are the false principles that he takes to lead to these skeptical beliefs? And (3) what is Berkeley’s goal in ridding us of this skepticism? In particular, is he seeking to return us to common sense or a version of it, or is he trying to instill a better theory based on principles that do not lead to skepticism?2 A hurdle anyone must face is that Berkeley wrote two books laying out his immaterialism, books that do not follow exactly the same line of argument. Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous is conspicuously structured around the issue of skepticism. The two characters agree to debate the question, who is the greater skeptic, and they return frequently to examine the implications of what they have been saying concerning the matter of skepticism. In Principles of Human Knowledge, on the other hand, Berkeley lays out his positive doctrine (PHK: 1–33)3 without any

370

SKEPTICISM

mention of skepticism at all, and when he enlarges on this doctrine in his replies to objections (PHK: 34–85), he talks about skepticism only once.4 It is natural that commentators looking to examine Berkeley’s position with respect to skepticism have focused on the presentation in Three Dialogues.5 There is nevertheless good reason to take skepticism to be equally important to the argument of the Principles. Just as he does in Three Dialogues, Berkeley signals in the full title that skepticism is a central concern.6 More importantly, he lays out his project in the Introduction to the Principles as addressed to the issue of skepticism, and makes good on this promise in the final section of the Principles (PHK: 85–156), where he examines the consequences of what he terms his principles with respect to skepticism. Any attempt to answer the questions raised about Berkeley’s position on skepticism is going to need to start with the Principles. What we discover, I am going to maintain, is that the position against skepticism to be found in the Principles is not only interesting in itself, but provides a useful framework by which to read Three Dialogues.

2 THE PRINCIPLES In the Introduction to the Principles, Berkeley sets up the matter of skepticism as the target of his work through a contrast between ordinary people of common sense and philosophers. Ordinary people are never troubled by skepticism, whereas when we “reason, meditate, and reflect on the nature of things,” we soon fall prey to “uncouth paradoxes, difficulties and inconsistencies” until we “sit down in a forlorn skepticism” (PHK: Intro 1). In this state, we blame our faculties as not being suited to “penetrate into the inward essence and constitution of things” (PHK: Intro 2). But perhaps, Berkeley suggests, this is because we misuse the faculties God gave us. As he puts it, “We have first raised a dust, and then complain we cannot see” (PHK: Intro 3). Berkeley’s goal is to identify those principles he suspects to be false that philosophers have introduced and that have produced this belief, that our mental faculties are not capable of providing knowledge. There are some important points that emerge here from Berkeley’s account of his project. The first is obvious: Berkeley takes his task to be undoing skepticism. The second is equally obvious. Berkeley sets up a contrast between the “illiterate bulk of mankind,” who have common sense and are not prone to skepticism, and another group, philosophers, who are responsible for raising skeptical doubts. The obvious conclusion is that Berkeley is taking philosophers as his target and the skepticism he is worried about might be called “philosophical skepticism.” It is the false principles of philosophers he will expose. It is also worth observing that there is a “we” moving through these sections that clearly excludes men of common sense. Berkeley is not just taking philosophers as his target but also includes them as his audience. He is writing for those who are likely to fall prey to philosophical skepticism. The skeptical beliefs Berkeley seeks to dispel will be beliefs likely to be held by that narrow segment of mankind who might have meddled with philosophy. The final section of the Principles proves to be extremely helpful for identifying the principle that is “the very root of skepticism” (PHK: 86). It is the supposition of “a twofold existence of the objects of sense, the one intelligible, or in the mind,

BERKELEY AND SKEPTICISM

371

the other real and without the mind; whereby unthinking things are thought to have a natural subsistence of their own, distinct from being perceived by spirits” (PHK: 86). Earlier, in PHK 56, Berkeley has explained how philosophers acquire this belief in a twofold existence, so this principle leads to philosophical skepticism. True, we begin with an ordinary belief everyone shares: that they have some ideas of which they are not the cause. Everyone assumes these “ideas or objects of perception” exist mind-independently, “without ever dreaming that a contradiction was involved in those words.” This is a mistake that anyone is prone to, namely, taking our sensible ideas to exist without the mind in a kind of unreflective naïve realism.7 But, Berkeley says, philosophers see through the contradictions embedded in this widespread misapprehension and conclude that “the immediate objects of perception do not exist without the mind.” Philosophers correct the false belief of “mankind,” but then fall themselves into the false belief “that there are certain objects really existing without the mind, or having a subsistence distinct from being perceived, of which our ideas are only images or resemblances, imprinted by these objects of the mind” (PHK: 56). The troublesome twofold existence principle is introduced by philosophers to solve the same problem that led to the naïve realism of ordinary people, that of identifying a cause for ideas we do not cause. Berkeley’s account of how the philosopher’s principle of twofold existence leads to skepticism is two-pronged. The first centers on the philosophical belief that ideas resemble their causes, so that real knowledge occurs when ideas conform to real things. This principle drives philosophers to skepticism because it seems to follow that it is impossible to determine either the nature or the existence of real things. We cannot determine the nature of any real thing because “things remaining the same, our ideas vary, and which of them, or even whether any of them at all represent the true quality really existing in the thing, it is out of our reach to determine” (PHK: 87). Thus, philosophers conclude that what we see or otherwise sense, being relative to our senses, cannot inform us of the absolute nature of things. Nor can we even establish the existence of real things, inasmuch as there is no demonstrable connection between our sensible qualities and any alleged absolute qualities belonging to a thing. Philosophers are therefore left in the uncomfortable position of holding that our sensible ideas have an external cause, but unable to provide any account of that cause. Berkeley suggests that it is practitioners of natural philosophy who are driven to greater depths of skepticism. They propose that “there is in each object an inward essence, which is the source whence its discernible qualities flow, and whereon they depend” (PHK: 102). They assume there must be a cause of our sensible ideas the nature of which necessitates the nature of the properties we discern. Being unable to produce a viable account of the nature of this inward essence or of the causal process by means of which qualities are supposed to flow, it is they who proclaim that our faculties are unable to reveal the inner constitution of anything, being “amused only with the outside and shew of things” (PHK: 101). This second set of beliefs can produce what Berkeley likes to present as increasingly desperate attempts to bolster incoherent accounts of this real but inaccessible cause. And the principle this deeper form of skepticism depends on is the belief that “everything includes within

372

SKEPTICISM

itself the cause of its properties: or that there is in each object an inward essence” (PHK: 101). What Berkeley provides in the Principles is a dialectic of increasingly skeptical beliefs. From the true belief that the immediate objects of perception exist only in the mind, philosophers adopt the false belief in the twofold existence of ideas and their causes. They first maintain that ideas conform to their causes, and then, when faced with the skeptical consequences of this principle, adopt a further false principle that ideas are an outward show concealing the inward essence of real things. At this point we have achieved the complete denigration of the senses and of our intellectual faculties as well. In the way Berkeley develops his account of his skeptical target in the Principles, the real villain of his story is not just philosophers in our sense, but natural philosophers, those physicists-cum-philosophers attempting to provide an account of the order of nature. In the Principles, again, the remedy Berkeley is urging involves rethinking the nature of what we take to be a cause of sensible ideas. Berkeley explains that progress in natural philosophy is actually achieved through “a greater largeness of comprehension” (PHK: 105) that allows natural philosophers to subsume natural phenomena under laws of increasing generality. We should understand these general laws connecting ideas, not as capturing a causal relation or as grounded in an unknown cause but as “a mark or sign with the thing signified. The fire which I see is not the cause of the pain I suffer upon my approaching it, but the mark that forewarns me of it” (PHK: 65). Such explanations of phenomena derive from the orderly and hence predictive nature of our ideas, and do not require a belief in a twofold existence of ideas and their material causes. When we recognize the efficacy of such an explanatory procedure, we will forego a search for non-existent natural efficient causes. Berkeley has replaced the false principle of twofold existence with his own true principle, that the only things that exist are minds and ideas, on the basis of which he shows us how to develop a new non-skeptical science or natural philosophy. We no longer identify the reality of an idea as one that is caused in the “right” way, but locate reality within the realm of ideas displaying a lawful order.

3  THREE DIALOGUES When we turn our attention to Three Dialogues where skepticism is brought to the fore, a different picture emerges. The motivation launching the discussion is Hylas’s conviction that Philonous is a greater skeptic than he, and debating this question allows the implication that Berkeley’s own theory is as likely to lead to skepticism. Also in Three Dialogues, the problematic beliefs identified typically concern sensible things like cherries and gloves. This has led commentators to assume that the skepticism under attack in Three Dialogues concerns the sense perception of ordinary objects. As George Pappas puts it, a primary skeptical belief is that “[w]e do not gain knowledge by means of perception of either the nature or existence of ordinary objects” (Pappas 2000: 287). In Three Dialogues it looks as though the way to dispel skepticism is to show that we do indeed have perceptual knowledge of ordinary objects. Finally, the frequent references to common sense throughout Three Dialogues suggest Berkeley’s goal is to return us to commonsense

BERKELEY AND SKEPTICISM

373

beliefs, for example, about the existence and nature of cherries and gloves. Three Dialogues, with its emphasis on commonsense beliefs about ordinary objects, seems like a different enterprise than the one uncovered in the Principles. A careful reading of Three Dialogues , however, reveals that Berkeley is following the same program and reaching similar conclusions as the Principles. Undoubtedly, the issue addressed in Three Dialogues is framed differently and in a more open-ended fashion than in the Principles. In the Principles, Berkeley’s target is specifically philosophers, but is Hylas, Philonous’s interlocutor, a philosopher? The question they discuss, who denies the existence or knowledge of sensible things, sounds like an investigation into ordinary beliefs, such as, that cherries exist and I know about them. So is Hylas a person of common sense with straightforwardly realist views about the sensible things? Hylas, unfortunately, is not consistently either one. There is perhaps an explanation why Berkeley tends to present Hylas as a moving target. Berkeley is using Hylas to recapitulate the dialectic he outlined in the Principles. In order to reach his starting point, Berkeley needs Hylas to hold initially the commonsense view Berkeley identified in the Principles: that “ideas or objects of perception had an existence independent of, or without the mind” (PHK: 56). Thus, Berkeley has Hylas start by saying: “whatever degree of heat we perceive by sense, we may be sure the same exists in the object that occasions it” (3D: I 175). Hylas is asserting a commonsense conviction that in having ideas, we just are perceiving qualities in the object. But this is not Hylas’s final position. Berkeley shows Hylas becoming convinced of what in PHK 56 he had identified as the philosopher’s true belief that the immediate objects of perception exist only in the mind. Once Hylas learns to be a philosopher, we see him subsequently developing the positions that lead him further and further into skepticism. The first step in Hylas’s conversion to philosophy is accomplished in the first half of the First Dialogue, ending with Hylas agreeing “that all sensible qualities are alike to be denied existence without the mind” (3D: I 194). In reaching this conclusion, Berkeley is often supposed to be deploying skepticism to shake Hylas loose from his conviction that sensible qualities also exist mind-independently. Berkeley offers a number of different arguments based on phenomena of perceptual variability, arguments that are often identified with the Argument from Illusion. The first concerns a hoary chestnut, the vat of water that feels hot to one hand and cold to the other. “On your principles,” Philonous points out, “it is really both hot and cold at the same time” (3D: I 179) But what is this argument intended to show? The principle Hylas is often taken to be using here, “Heat is a quality of the fire,” would indeed encourage a skeptical conclusion, namely, we don’t know whether the water is hot or cold, but not the conclusion Hylas seems prepared to draw: “There is no heat in the fire.” But notice the principle Hylas initially asserted was actually: “Whatever degree of heat we perceive by sense, we may be sure that the same exists in the object that occasions it.” This is the belief Berkeley attributes to ordinary people. It is not a belief about hotness and water per se, but rather a belief about perceiving by sense, that perceiving by sense just is perceiving the quality there in the world. This belief is undermined when we realize we simultaneously perceive both hot and cold, since it would mean that both qualities exist simultaneously in

374

SKEPTICISM

the water. The purpose of this case (and others Philonous offers) is to move Hylas from the ordinary person’s position to that of the philosopher, “that the immediate objects of sensation do not exist without the mind.” Berkeley continues deploying the fleeting, variable nature of the sensible qualities to show it is not only temperature and colors that cannot be identified with a “real” quality in the object, but also the so-called primary qualities. Shape and size are subject to perceptual variation so it is equally inappropriate to identify the size now experienced with the real size of the object. The conclusion, then, of the extended discussion of sensible qualities finds Hylas abandoning his initial position for the more correct, philosophical one: “that all sensible qualities are alike to be denied existence without the mind” (3D: I 194). Hylas is no longer a person of commonsense. Converting Hylas does not instantly make him a skeptic. Nevertheless, by the end of the First Dialogue, Philonous makes this accusation: “You are therefore by your principles forced to deny the reality of sensible things, since you made it to consist in an absolute existence exterior to the mind. That is to say, you are a downright sceptic” (3D: I 206). Philonous here blames Hylas’s newfound skepticism on his “principles.” This suggests that somewhere between the passage in which Hylas gives up his old commonsense principle (3D: I 194) and the passage just quoted (3D: I 206), Hylas has acquired a new principle. What is that new principle and how did Hylas come by it? It is important to notice that, in this intervening passage, Berkeley is using the fictional Hylas to show how philosophers fall into skepticism once they become convinced that sensible qualities exist only in the mind, and distinguish between mind-dependent ideas and mind-independent real things. Hylas, who is ostensibly raising objections to Philonous, about half-way through enunciates a position of his own: To speak the truth, Philonous, I think there are two kinds of objects, the one perceived immediately, which are likewise called ideas; the other are real things or external objects perceived by the mediation of ideas, which are their images and representations. Now I own, ideas do not exist without the mind; but the latter sort of objects do. (3D: I 203) Hylas has just articulated what in the Principles Berkeley has called the two-fold existence principle and that he blamed for skepticism. Hylas is now committed to the view that immediately perceived mind-dependent ideas enable us to have knowledge of mind-independent real things. And this view will lead to skepticism if in fact such ideas cannot convey knowledge of mind-independent things. In the remainder of the First Dialogue, Philonous demonstrates that these skeptical consequences of this principle do indeed follow. Briefly, he argues that, as the experience of hearing a coach coming down the street shows, we can be said to have mediately perceived some sensible qualities of the coach, such as its familiar shape, when they are suggested by the immediately perceived sound of the coach. But we cannot be said to have mediately perceived Julius Caesar by immediately perceiving the light and colors of his statue, unless we have had the sort of experiences that would allow ideas of the statue to suggest Caesar himself. The immediate perceptions alone cannot lead

BERKELEY AND SKEPTICISM

375

us to the idea of Julius Caesar. Nor can ideas intelligibly be said to be images of the real things they are supposed to represent. Fleeting and variable ideas do not have the right characteristics to represent stable, unchanging real things. Finally, sensible ideas cannot be said to be like insensible real things. Thus, with what is now called the Likeness Principle, Berkeley concludes that Hylas’s adoption of the philosophical principle of the twofold existence of ideas and things leads to skepticism. At the end of the First Dialogue, Hylas has become a philosopher, inasmuch as he endorses the twofold existence of ideas and things, but he has not yet, despite Philonous’s charge, become a skeptic. This changes in the Second Dialogue. There, Hylas and Philonous explore what in the Principles Berkeley had identified as the motive for adopting the twofold existence principle, the recognition that not all of my ideas are caused by me. The Second Dialogue suggests that it is the search for a cause for our ideas that tumbles philosophers into deep natural philosophical skepticism. At the beginning of the dialogue, Hylas puts forward a version of the psychophysical account of the causation of sensible ideas that many philosophers of his time found appealing. He is brought up short when Philonous reminds him that all of the entities in the account, the bodies that impact on vibrating nerves that leave traces in the brain, are in fact so many sensible things or ideas. Hylas’s account is therefore an account of relations among contingently connected ideas. Confronted with the fact that he has not actually identified a cause of ideas, Hylas admits to skepticism but takes comfort in the observation that Philonous too is a skeptic. This theme, stemming from the original question about who is the greater skeptic, is now pursued to the end of Three Dialogues. Hylas is assuming that, since both he and Philonous have agreed they only perceive ideas in the mind, they are both skeptics, not capable of arriving at knowledge of real things. Philonous, however, identifies a different source of Hylas’s skepticism. “You indeed,” Philonous points out to Hylas, said, the reality of sensible things consisted in an absolute existence out of the minds of spirits, or distinct from their being perceived. And pursuant to this notion of reality, you are obliged to deny sensible things any real existence: that is, according to your own definition, you profess yourself a sceptic. But I neither said nor thought the reality of sensible things was to be defined in that manner. (3D: II 211–212) In this speech, Philonous has redefined the principle to which Hylas is committed: it is now the thoroughly philosophical principle that the reality of sensible things depends upon an absolute, that is, mind-independent existence. In the last part of the Second Dialogue, Hylas accepts the principle of independent existence that Philonous assigns to him but is gradually brought to admit that all his attempts to make sense of the notion are either contradictory or meaningless. It is at this point, when Hylas has been deprived of any meaningful version of what Berkeley believes to be the central concept of natural philosophers, independent existence, that Hylas ultimately succumbs to skepticism. At the start of the Third Dialogue, then, we find Hylas in just such a state of “forlorn scepticism” Berkeley describes in the Introduction to the Principles. Hylas

376

SKEPTICISM

has decided that “our faculties are too narrow and too few” for us to have any knowledge of sensible things, “their inner constitution, their real and true nature” lie hidden from us. Hylas now is one of those people he described in the First Dialogue who distrusted their senses, denied the real existence of sensible things, and pretend to know nothing of them. But what of Philonous? He denies he is skeptical about the existence of things, but on what grounds? He associates himself with the vulgar and says he trusts his senses. Does he think Hylas’s current forlorn skepticism can be defeated simply by showing we have immediate perceptual knowledge of things, that is, by defending a version of commonsense, or does he have something else in mind? There are many passages, particularly early in the Third Dialogue, that suggest Berkeley is indeed endeavoring to defend a kind of perceptual common sense, as when he has Philonous says: “I cannot for my life help thinking that snow is white and fire hot” (3D: III 229). Philonous might here be saying, so long as we agree that sensible things are just bundles of sensible qualities and that we immediately perceive sensible qualities, then we know the existence and nature of sensible things when we immediately perceive them. Skepticism about the existence or nature of sensible things is impossible. But when the skepticism issue is raised later in the dialogue, Philonous gives a more complicated defense. Hylas accuses Philonous of skepticism because, he says, Philonous is changing things into ideas (3D: III 244). Philonous’s retort is that he is actually changing ideas into things because he denies things have hidden essences. Hylas raises objections to this claim, that things have no hidden essence or inner constitution, relying on the observation that we are not presented with sets of stable sense qualities. The apple we experience is not a bundle of one color, one shape, and one size, but a highly variable set of shifting colors, shapes, and sizes. If this variable set constitutes one apple, it can only be because the varying sensible qualities derive from a single inner constitution. It is this stable inner constitution, too, that explains why we think microscopes give us a better view of something. Philonous endorses the variability of sensations that Hylas points to. “Strictly speaking, Hylas,” he says, “we do not see the same object that we feel; neither is the same object perceived by the microscope, which was by the naked eye” (3D: III 245). In giving this answer, Philonous is not asserting that a sensible thing is a relatively stable group of qualities, such as could be grasped immediately and at once, but is instead a highly variable set of qualities which are “observed however to have some connection in Nature either with respect to co-existence or succession” (3D: III 245). Similarly, with the microscope, we are not getting a better view of the thing, but learning more about what ideas go together. As Philonous puts it, “The more a man knows of the connection of ideas, the more he is said to know of the nature of things” (3D: III 245). What defeats skepticism for Berkeley is the recognition that the vast shifting mass of our ideas are not to be identified as real because of a relationship to some stable thing, but instead because of their relations with one another when they are regularly connected together. Berkeley concludes this section by giving Philonous a long speech in which he walks Hylas through the steps that led to his skepticism, ending with his inability to conceive an independently existing substance. Philonous concludes: “Lastly,

BERKELEY AND SKEPTICISM

377

whether the premises considered, it be not the wisest way to follow Nature, trust your senses, and laying aside all anxious thought about unknown natures or substances, admit with the vulgar those for real things, which are perceived by the senses?” (3D: III 246). It has been important throughout Three Dialogues that real things are perceived, but this is not all of importance. As in the Principles, it is equally important that real things be perceived as orderly. The point is spelled out when Berkeley revisits for the last time the issue of skepticism: Is not that opposition to all science whatsoever, that phrensy of the ancient and modern sceptics, built on the same foundation? Or can you produce so much as one argument against the reality of corporeal things, or in behalf of that avowed utter ignorance of their natures, which doth not suppose their reality to consist in an external absolute existence? Upon this supposition indeed, the objections from the colours of a pigeon’s neck, or the appearances of a broken oar in the water, must be allowed to have weight. But those and the like objections vanish, if we do not maintain the being of absolute external originals, but place the reality of things in ideas, fleeting indeed, and changeable; however not changed at random, but according to the fixed order of Nature. For herein consists that constancy and truth of things, which secures all the concerns of life, and distinguishes that which is real from the irregular visions of the fancy. (3D: III 258) In this passage, Berkeley is returning to the position of the Principles, that the reality of things lies not just in their being immediately perceived, but also in their being perceived in a fixed order, thus allowing us to know what to expect. In the oftenquoted passage at the end of the Third Dialogue, where Berkeley says he is reconciling the views of the vulgar and the philosophers, the claim that he is attributing to the vulgar, “that those things they immediately perceive are the real things,” is rendered acceptable to Berkeley only on his own notion of what it is to be real, that is, for ideas to occur in a fixed and orderly manner so that they can be connected by us. The position that Berkeley has in the end argued for in Three Dialogues is in fact that of the Principles, and his ultimate target is the skepticism that results from a belief in mind-independent essences. His solution to this skepticism again lies in the regularities among ideas understood according to the laws of nature. We are now back at the anti-skeptical position of the Principles: what enables us to have knowledge of the natural world is that our ideas occur in a stable law-governed manner, such that present ideas signify to us what to expect. It is this law-governed nature of our ideas that allows us knowledge beyond whatever commonsense objects are before us, up to and including “the whole system immense, beautiful, glorious beyond expression and beyond thought” but which is as well “linked in a mutual dependence and intercourse with each other” (3D: II 211).

4 CONCLUSION Let me now return to the questions raised at the beginning. (1) What are the skeptical beliefs Berkeley wants to dispel? These are the beliefs that he assigns to Hylas at the beginning of the Third Dialogue after he has succumbed to skepticism

378

SKEPTICISM

and that he raises in the Introduction to the Principles: that our nature and our faculties are inadequate to allow us knowledge of the nature and existence of things. Berkeley wishes to get rid of the notion that our Creator has equipped us with a limited set of cognitive faculties. (2) What are the false principles that he takes to lead to these skeptical beliefs? The false principles Berkeley identifies as the culprit in giving rise to skepticism are (a) the twofold existence of ideas and things and (b) the identification of real things with something that is independently existing and unperceiving. The principles Berkeley wants to reject like the skepticism it gives rise to are endemic to philosophy. Finally (3) What is Berkeley’s goal in ridding us of this skepticism? It is not to vindicate common sense but to build a better philosophical theory, which reveals that our God-given mental faculties are thoroughly sufficient to provide knowledge of the existence and nature of things.

NOTES 1. For a thorough discussion of the first kind of skepticism, see Dicker (2011: ch. 5), and for the second, see Pappas (2000: ch. 9). I will be defending the third possibility below. 2. The importance of common sense to Berkeley has been recently stressed by Pappas (2000) and by Roberts (2007). Their accounts have been criticized by Bordner (2011). 3. References to the Principles will be to PHK and section number, or to PHK Intro and section number. References to Three Dialogues will be to 3D, Dialogue Number and page number in the Luce and Jessop edition. 4. Berkeley (PHK: 40) denies that he is endorsing a skepticism of the senses. 5. This is the case, for example, with George Pappas, whose work has been important in calling attention to the centrality of skepticism in Berkeley’s theorizing (Pappas 2000: esp. ch. 9). 6. The full title of the Principles is: A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge wherein the Chief Causes of Error and Difficulty in the Sciences, with the Grounds of Scepticism, Atheism, and Irreligion, are inquired into. Even the shorter title of Three Dialogues introduced in the third edition stress the matter of skepticism: Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous In opposition to Sceptics and Atheists. 7. He is here presumably talking about the same strangely prevailing opinion identified in Berkeley (PHK: 4): that “houses, mountains, rivers and in a word all sensible objects have an existence, natural or real, distinct from their being perceived by the understanding.”

REFERENCES Berkeley, George. 1949a. The Principles of Human Knowledge. The Works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne, volume II, edited by T. E. Jessop. London: Thomas Nelson and Sons Ltd. (First published in 1710.)

BERKELEY AND SKEPTICISM

379

Berkeley, George. 1949b. Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. The Works of George Berkeley Bishop of Cloyne, volume II, edited by T. E. Jessop. London: Thomas Nelson and Sons Ltd. (First published in 1713.) Bordner, Seth. 2011. “Berkeley’s ‘Defense’ of Common Sense,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 49: 315–38. Dicker, Georges. 2011. Berkeley’s Idealism. New York: Oxford University Press. Pappas, George. 2000. Berkeley’s Thought. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Roberts, John Russell. 2007. A Metaphysics for the Mob. New York: Oxford University Press.

CHAPTER TWENTY-SEVEN

A Pyrrhonian Interpretation of Hume on Assent DONALD L. M. BAXTER

1 INTRODUCTION How is it possible for Scottish philosopher David Hume (1711–1776) to be both withering skeptic and constructive theorist? I recommend an answer like the Pyrrhonian answer to the question how it is possible to suspend all judgment yet engage in active daily life. Sextus Empiricus distinguishes two kinds of assent: one suspended across the board and one involved with daily living. The first—active endorsement—is an act of will based on appreciation of reasons; the second— passive acquiescence—is a causal effect of appearances. I suggest that Hume makes the same distinction, only he extends the sort of assent involved in the Pyrrhonian’s daily life to theoretical matters as well.1 He is a skeptic both in finding no reason to grant the one sort of assent and in being subject to the other. Understanding my suggested Hume interpretation requires understanding the Pyrrhonian distinction in Michael Frede’s way, which I will explain. To bring out the relevant features of Frede’s version, I defend it against the rival version of Myles Burnyeat. Next, I suggest that Hume’s version of the distinction is that between belief as an act “of the cogitative part of our natures” and as an act of the “sensitive” part (Treatise [T] 1.4.1.8).2 Hume’s version can be fleshed out in the way I suggest by regarding it, as Dugald Stewart did, to be derived from a lengthy discussion of Ralph Cudworth’s. I then summarize how Treatise 1.4.1, “Scepticism with regard to reason,” shows both that active endorsement is never merited and that passive acquiescence cannot be avoided. Julia Annas hints at an account like the one I give, but does not develop it and ends up reading Hume as a dogmatist (Annas 2000: 276, 279). Instead, I recommend reading Hume as finding no sufficiently good reason for active endorsement of any view while yet yielding passive acquiescence in even some theoretical matters. In theorizing thus concerning the science of man, Hume remains just as much a

A PYRRHONIAN INTERPRETATION OF HUME ON ASSENT

381

skeptic as Sextus does in daily life, such as when avoiding precipices or engaging in religious devotions.

2  PYRRHONIAN KINDS OF ASSENT The characterization of Pyrrhonism I will give depends heavily on the work of Michael Frede (1997a; 1997b) on kinds of assent. Frede’s interpretation is a minority view; the majority view follows the interpretation of Myles Burnyeat (1997a). It will help in understanding Frede’s difficult view to contrast it with Burnyeat’s. In explaining the key difference between them, as I understand it, I’ll focus on Sextus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism. Both Frede and Burnyeat take Sextus to have an answer to the traditional challenge to the skeptic, one famously reiterated by Hume in his Enquiry concerning Human Understanding (EHU 12.23).3 Here is the challenge: if you are utterly passive, then you will quickly perish, but if you act to preserve your life, then you must believe something, for all action requires some belief. For instance, you would not eat in response to hunger, if you did not believe that eating would relieve your hunger. This challenge is generally posed by those who assume that the Pyrrhonian eschews any kind of assent. That assumption is attacked in different ways by both Frede and Burnyeat. Their attacks rely on passages from Sextus such as these: When we say that Sceptics do not hold beliefs, we do not take ‘belief’ in the sense in which some say, quite generally, that belief is acquiescing in something; for Sceptics assent to the feelings forced upon them by appearances. . . . Rather, we say that they do not hold beliefs in the sense in which some say that belief is assent to some unclear object of investigation in the sciences; for Pyrrhonists do not assent to anything unclear. (PH I 13)4 But the main point is this: in uttering these phrases they say what is apparent to themselves and report their own feelings without holding opinions, affirming nothing about external objects. (PH I 15) As we said before, we do not overturn anything which leads us, without our willing it, to assent in accordance with a passive appearance. (PH I 19) Remember too that we say we neither posit nor reject anything which is said dogmatically about what is unclear; for we do yield to things which passively move us and lead us necessarily to assent. (PH I 193) For his interpretation, Frede distinguishes two kinds of assent. In one way, you do not assent to the view that eating relieves hunger, but in another way you do. Burnyeat does not distinguish two kinds of assent, but rather distinguishes two classes of proposition liable to assent. A rough way to make the distinction is to say that one class consists of propositions beginning with “It appears to me now that . . .,”5 where this phrase is used in the course of stating that something is appearing to you and describing how it appears. The other class consists of all the other propositions. Thus the Pyrrhonian who acts to relieve his hunger assents to the proposition “It appears to me now that eating relieves hunger” understood in this way, and not to the proposition “Eating relieves hunger.” In making their respective distinctions,

382

SKEPTICISM

both Frede and Burnyeat hold that there are assentings of a sort that is necessary to survival, and assentings of a sort that is not necessary to survival. It is this latter sort of assenting that is at issue in theoretical discussions about unclear matters and that the Pyrrhonian avoids. Thus one can be a Pyrrhonian without perishing. Four considerations incline me against Burnyeat’s view. Appreciating them helps one appreciate the nuances of Frede’s interpretation. It seems to me, first, that assent to “It appears to me now that eating relieves hunger,” used to state that one is being appeared to and to describe how, is not sufficient to motivate eating when one is hungry. It can only motivate eating if it leads to some kind of assent to “Eating relieves hunger.” One is motivated, generally, not by realizing how the world appears to one, but by taking some sort of stand on how the world is. So Burnyeat’s proposal does not solve the problem with survival. Perhaps Burnyeat need not say that assent to “It appears to me now that eating relieves hunger” motivates eating. Rather, the appearance that prompts that report also directly motivates eating.6 However, for the direct motivation to happen, the content of the appearance must be “Eating relieves hunger.” Being moved by this appearance will be just like the kind of assent necessary for survival that Frede defends. So this defense of Burnyeat would be a concession to his opponent. It seems to me, second, that the Burnyeat interpretation is not forced by the text. True, Sextus says that the skeptics will only say “what is apparent to themselves, and report their own feelings, affirming nothing about external objects.” But I think that often the phrase “It appears that . . .” is not used to state and describe, but rather is used to qualify one’s assent to the proposition in its scope. If I say, “It appears to me now that eating relieves hunger,” I am assenting to “Eating relieves hunger” with reservations. Perhaps I suspect that I have not established its truth conclusively. Or, more to the point, perhaps I am just reporting the view which is striking me now— that eating relieves hunger—without making any commitments to there being any good reason to hold that view. So, when skeptics say what is apparent to themselves, they need not be unreservedly endorsing that they are appeared to a certain way; they may rather with maximum reservation be venting the view that things are that way (PH I 13, 15).7 Thus there is a natural alternative to Burnyeat’s way of interpreting Sextus’s frequent appeals to how things appear. This alternative is not exactly what Frede terms the “epistemic sense” of “appears,” if in that sense “it appears to me” is synonymous with “I think” or “I believe.” These locutions can sometimes express assent with reservations, but do not always express that. I am reluctant to use the word “belief” to characterize assent with reservations as I elucidate it. In his earlier paper, Frede suggests that the skeptic has beliefs, though it becomes apparent that Frede is using an elastic sense of “belief” that could include even an impression we don’t object to (Frede 1997a: 10, 21–22). I think this way of putting things went too far and was corrected in his later paper. It seems to me, third, that Frede’s view makes better sense than Burnyeat’s of Sextus’s claims that the skeptical phrases “cancel” themselves (PH I 14–15, 206). Phrases such as “In no way more” or “No more this than that” mean that anything and its negation are equally convincing, and so anything is unconvincing—it leaves the judgment suspended. As Sextus says, “Everything is no more so than not so.”

A PYRRHONIAN INTERPRETATION OF HUME ON ASSENT

383

This utterance applies to itself, and so the skeptics make clear that they suspend judgment even concerning their own utterances. This is the sense in which the phrases “cancel” themselves. Each phrase says in part that it itself is unconvincing. However, if skeptical phrases implicitly have the content that Burnyeat would think they do, then there would be no self-cancelling. The sentence “It appears to me now that everything is equally convincing and unconvincing,” if true, does not entail that everything is unconvincing. So it does not entail that it itself is unconvincing. So it does not cancel itself. In a footnote, Burnyeat notices a related problem with self-canceling. He says that Sextus’s self-canceling propositions have to make a truth claim to be selfcanceling, whereas, according to Burnyeat elsewhere, reports of appearances make no truth claim (1997a: 30–31).8 Therefore, one infers, Sextus’s self-canceling phrases cannot be reports of appearances interpreted Burnyeat’s way. However, Burnyeat sees it as a problem for Sextus, not for his own interpretation (Burnyeat 1997a: 54 n. 52). Fourth, while both interpretations grant some kind of assent to what is apparent, Frede’s makes better sense of the skeptic’s practice of continuing to investigate whether what is apparent is real. If, say, “Honey sweetens” is what is apparent, then it makes sense to investigate whether “Honey sweetens” is really true (PH I 19). However, if “It appears to me now that honey sweetens” is what is apparent, understood the way Burnyeat intends, then there is nothing to investigate beyond the fact that you are appeared to in that way. Burnyeat might reply that what one investigates is whether the state or impression avowed when one says “It appears to me now that honey sweetens” conforms to reality. However, this response acknowledges my point. For a state to conform to reality is for the proposition it contains to be true. So the object of investigation is whether “Honey sweetens” is true, not whether “It appears to me now that honey sweetens” is true. Thus, I incline to Frede’s interpretation of Sextus. In any event, Frede’s approach to Sextus provides an extremely fruitful way of resolving a perennial problem in Hume interpretation—how to reconcile Hume the skeptic with Hume the scientist of man—in a way that does justice both to the power of Hume’s skeptical arguments and to the scientific aspirations of Hume’s psychological theory. So I recommend assuming that Frede has Sextus right, for the purpose of understanding Hume. Sextus distinguishes two kinds of assent. Here I will give my own understanding of the distinction rather than try accurately to represent Frede’s. Call the two kinds of assent “active endorsement” and “passive acquiescence.” The first is to actively endorse a view as true for a reason that one appreciates to be sufficiently good. The second is to passively acquiesce in a view forced upon one by appearances. “View” can mean the mental state one has in entertaining a proposition that is a candidate for being assented to, but I mean the proposition itself.9 An example of active endorsement might be the firm conviction of a mathematician in the result of a proof on which he has labored long and carefully and which has received the approbation of his peers. Another might be the unshakeable conviction of a religious zealot who considers his faith’s scriptures to be self-justifying. These

384

SKEPTICISM

examples are not conclusively examples. Active endorsement will, for Hume, turn out to be a fiction that we and his opponents often believe in, but without good reason. In any event, the examples are helpful at this stage in seeing what the contrast with passive acquiescence is supposed to be. Because of the self-conscious attempt to reason as one ought to, active endorsement has greater pretensions than everyday belief. Its natural home, if it has any, would be enterprises in which one investigates unclear matters beyond the mundane concerns of daily life. Crucially, belief is supposed to be chosen—chosen because one understands that it is what one ought to believe. In this sense it is called active. Passive acquiescence, on the other hand, has no more pretension than everyday belief, and sometimes less. In passively acquiescing one goes along with the view that strikes one without making any decision one way or the other about its legitimacy. For example, if a crowd stampedes by shouting, “The dam has broken!” you might well run along without stopping to consider whether or not this could be true. Circumstances just sweep you into acting as if the view that the dam has broken were indeed true (cf. Thurber 1942: 22). Passive acquiescence is acting as if a belief were true without deciding that it is. In this respect, it is like conjecture, pretense, supposition, and taking as a working hypothesis. When a two-year old pretends that a countertop is a sink, going through the motions of washing her hands and declaring, “This is a real sink,” no one, least of all her, is fooled. She has not decided that what she says is true, but acts as if it is true for all that. So do people taking the other attitudes I’ve listed. A member of a committee, who uncharitably suspects a fellow member of being disingenuous, might take as a working hypothesis that the other member is acting in good faith. The result might predictably be greater peace of mind for hypothesizer and a better outcome for the committee. Pursuing these practical benefits is not the same as deciding in favor of the truth of the hypothesis. Similarly, passive acquiescence in a view is a matter of acting as if the view is true. However, there is a major difference from the attitudes I just mentioned. They are chosen. Passive acquiescence, on the other hand, is not the result of willing. It is a causal effect of how things strike one. In this sense it is passive. The best examples of passive acquiescence would be the “beliefs” of animals—for instance, those of the little pig admired by Pyrrho (DL IX 68, 481). Animal beliefs are beliefs only in an analogous sense, not being governed in any way by normative considerations. Instead, they are brought about by some sort of instinctual response to circumstances. It is with respect to active endorsement that a Pyrrhonian suspends judgment. He finds that for any argument for any conclusion, he is able to find an apparently equally good argument for a conflicting conclusion. This balancing of arguments leaves him disinclined to either side, resulting in a suspense of judgment, that is, no active endorsement either way.10 After all, active endorsement is meant to be the kind of assent that results from reasoning as you ought to in the recognition that you are reasoning as you ought to. One cannot arrive at this kind of assent when one has an equally good reason to endorse something conflicting. This method of balancing conflicting arguments is central to the Pyrrhonian enterprise, even when Pyrrhonians take pains to lay out all-purpose arguments

A PYRRHONIAN INTERPRETATION OF HUME ON ASSENT

385

against any conclusion. For instance, take the argument that (i) nothing should be believed without a reason, and (ii) any conclusion is believed either for no reason, or a circular reason (which is no reason), or a vicious infinite regress of reasons (which is no reason) (cf. PH I 166, 168, 169). In giving such an “all-purpose” argument, the Pyrrhonist would be taking for granted that there would be some consideration in favor of the other side, which needed to be counterbalanced. The result is suspense of active endorsement.11 Generally, it is investigations into unclear matters, such as those investigated in philosophy, science, mathematics, and religion, in which one would seek to actively endorse a view. In such investigations one is self-reflectively trying to find good reasons for granting assent. In daily life, when one is for the most part just reacting for practical purposes to the way things appear, one does not strive to meet the high standards of active endorsement. As the Pyrrhonian continues to investigate, his ability to balance every argument with something conflicting has its effect on him. It begins to appear as if no proposition deserves active assent. As Sextus puts it, “Thus what is said is this: ‘All of the unclear matters investigated in dogmatic fashion which I have inspected appear to me inapprehensible’” (PH I 200). He, of course, does not actively endorse this view, but it governs his actions nonetheless. Now, it seems natural to say that he passively acquiesces in this view. However, it seems to me that the view concerns a theoretical matter about something that is not obvious, even if giving an appearance. Note that not all appearances are sensory appearances (Frede 1973: 809). For example, Sextus says that the Pyrrhonians accept the appearance “that piety is good and impiety bad” (PH I 23). Thus, the door seems opened to Hume’s extension of passive acquiescence into theoretical matters beyond active daily life (Popkin 1966: 95; Norton 1982: 268 n. 48).12 The skeptic’s view seems forced on him by appearances. Hume develops and extends this notion of views forced by appearances.

3  HUMEAN KINDS OF ASSENT Hume’s account echoes the Pyrrhonian’s distinction between two kinds of assent and the appeal to appearances forcing views on one. Hume (T 1.4.1.8) explicitly makes the distinction between two kinds of assent: belief as an act of the “cogitative part of our natures” or as a “simple act of the thought” versus “belief as an act of the sensitive . . . part of our natures.” It is not immediately apparent that Hume’s distinction maps onto active endorsement and passive acquiescence in the way I’m suggesting. However, evidence is provided by historical context. Dugald Stewart (2005: 219) points the way, noting that the distinction in Hume is familiar from the work of Ralph Cudworth. Cudworth spends much time developing the distinction: Wherefore it is evident from what we have declared, that there are two kinds of Perceptive Cogitations in our Soul: the one Passive, when the Soul perceives by suffering from its Body, and the Objects without; the other Active, when it perceives by its exerting its own Native Vigor from within it self. (1731: 4.1.7)13

386

SKEPTICISM

Cudworth explicitly connects the first with appearance, when he observes that “the Nature of Sense consists in nothing else but meer Seeming or Appearance” (1731: 3.4.2). In the previous section, he connects this sense of “appearance” with Sextus. He then concludes, And therefore we can have no Certainty by Sense alone either concerning the Absolute Natures of Individual Corporeal things without us, nor indeed of their Existence; but all the Assurance that we have thereof arises from Reason and Intellect judging of the Phantasms or Appearances of Sense, and determining in which of them there is an Absolute Reality, and which of them are but meerly Relative or Phantastical. (1731: 3.4.8) As opposed to the passive appearances of sense, Knowledge is an Inward and Active Energy of the Mind it self, and the displaying of its own Innate Vigour from within, whereby it doth Conquer, Master and Command its Objects, and so begets a Clear, Serene, Victorious, and Satisfactory Sense within it self. (1731: 4.1.1) Cudworth finds the origin of the distinction in Plato’s Theatetus (1731: 3.3.6). He may well have found some confirmation and development in Descartes’s Meditations: When I say “Nature taught me to think this,” all I mean is that a spontaneous impulse leads me to believe it, not that its truth has been revealed to me by some natural light. There is a big difference here. (AT VII 38)14 Three paragraphs later Descartes distinguishes the basis of belief formed by “blind impulse” from that formed by “reliable judgment.” He seems to be making a point captured by Cudworth as follows: For Knowledge is not a Knock or Thrust from without, but it consisteth in the Awakening and Exciting of the Inward Active Powers of the Mind. (1731: 3.3.5)15 Hume (T 1.4.1), in contrast, when making this kind of distinction will be taking the side of the “Knock or Thrust from without.” He contended that belief in persons is like that in animals: an instinctual effect of observation and experience given the principles of nature (T 1.3.16). The argument in section 1.4.1 supports his earlier contention. His purpose in this section is to argue that if we reasoned as we ought to, and if belief were a cogitative act, we would not assent to anything. Since we do assent to some things, there must be some other explanation for it than reasoning as we ought to. Belief is rather an act of sensation—an addition of “force and vivacity”—naturally caused in us by customary connections observed in the past (T 1.3.7). Here is Hume’s innovation. The sensitive part of our nature responds to the impulse from without not only with images, but also with a feeling of their forcefulness. In his argument, he intends “to make the reader sensible of the truth of my hypothesis, that all our reasonings concerning causes and effects are deriv’d from nothing but custom; and that belief is more properly an act of the sensitive, than of the cogitative part of our natures” (T 1.4.1.8).

A PYRRHONIAN INTERPRETATION OF HUME ON ASSENT

387

Think of it this way: judgment consists of a content plus assent (see Descartes, Meditations, AT VII 56–58). The question is, is the assent an action one does or something one suffers? Hume picks the latter. Hume’s argument begins with the Diminution Argument that all belief depends on probable reasoning,16 and after every case of probable reasoning “we are oblig’d by our reason” to weigh in a small measure of uncertainty about whether the reasoning in that case was properly done. Drawing a conclusion, by weighing considerations for and against it, always introduces an additional consideration against it—one that ought to be weighed in. That is because our faculty for weighing considerations has introduced its own errors in the past, independent of the original considerations themselves. The additional consideration needs to be weighed in. So every weighing requires a reweighing. Weighing in an additional consideration against a conclusion diminishes one’s confidence in the conclusion. So every reweighing diminishes confidence in the conclusion. But every reweighing is itself a weighing, so requires a further reweighing. So, confidence in the conclusion will be diminished to extinction during the successive reweighings. For Hume, like any skeptic, diminishment of confidence in a conclusion does not increase confidence in its negation. Nor, for Hume, is there some kind of negative assent, that is, dissent, that can begin to increase; there is no negative vivacity of ideas. So, the result will be suspense of judgment. Hume concludes, therefore, that reasoning as we ought will leave us in suspense of judgment: “all the rules of logic require a continual diminution, and at last a total extinction of belief and evidence” (T 1.4.1.6). Don Garrett argues “that Hume offers no epistemic evaluation in concluding that ‘all the rules of logic’ require a total extinction of belief.” Hume, rather, is merely explaining how our natural faculty of reason would operate if unhindered by “the imagination’s difficulty in following the ‘subtle and refin’d reasoning’ of such repeated reflections” (1997: 228). However, Hume is indeed offering an epistemic evaluation: one that it strikes him we should and would endorse if we were able to reason as we ought. The whole section, as well as the Diminution Argument itself, begins by considering how we ought to reason in our pursuit of truth. To minimize our chance of error, we ought to take our own fallibility into account when settling on the degree of assurance we should have in our conclusion. “In every judgment, which we can form concerning probability, as well as concerning knowledge, we ought always to correct the first judgment, deriv’d from the nature of the object, by another judgment, deriv’d from the nature of the understanding” (T 1.4.1.5). Note the “ought” and the ensuing “correct.” It is an epistemic “ought” because the goal is truth and avoidance of error (T 1.4.1.1). Again, Hume concludes that, if we reason as we ought to in pursuit of truth, we will lose all assurance through our repeated corrections. Many scholars think Hume’s Diminution Argument fails, but that is beside the point here.17 It strikes him forcefully that it succeeds. It is an “all-purpose” argument that can counterbalance the considerations in favor of any other view. Consequently, like the Pyrrhonians, Hume is unable to find anything that one ought to choose actively to endorse.

388

SKEPTICISM

Note that the conclusion itself is one of the propositions it applies to. The conclusion itself is subject to diminution. So even in his own conclusion Hume has found nothing one ought to assent to. Suppose that belief were active endorsement. We would believe just as we ought. So without anything we ought to assent to, there would be no belief. “If belief, therefore, were a simple act of the thought, without any peculiar manner of conception, or the addition of a force and vivacity, it must infallibly destroy itself, and in every case terminate in a total suspence of judgment” (T 1.4.1.8). However, we cannot and do not suspend all belief as we ought to. We have lots of beliefs. Among other things, Hume assents to the conclusion of the Diminution Argument, at least during T 1.4.1 and at 1.4.7.7. Still, he says he is not able to believe it “sincerely and constantly,” which may mean that sometimes he does not believe it, but more likely means that he is never able to act on it (T 1.4.1.7).18 In any event, we have beliefs, therefore belief is not an act of the cogitative part of our soul but is rather an act of the sensitive part. Belief is a matter of being caused to have lively ideas. It is a brute fact about us that, however much we might see the justice of the Diminution Argument, we cannot consistently follow it out for any given proposition. We quickly become overtaxed and almost as quickly return to belief in the convictions we were questioning. That is because “Nature, by an absolute and uncontroulable necessity has determin’d us to judge as well as to breathe and feel” (T 1.4.1.7). We cannot suspend all assent whatsoever any more than a sighted person can prevent himself from seeing his environs with eyes directed to them and open in the sunshine. In making the origin of all belief causal, Hume is echoing the Pyrrhonian view of passive assent as assent to views forced upon us by appearances. The “forcing” is a matter of finding ourselves to have the view in a way independent of the exercising of our will.19 One might wonder why Hume would propose the rules for causal reasoning in 1.3.15 if he thinks we cannot reason as we ought. Why would he propose standards for reasoning if we cannot follow such standards? The answer is that his proposed standards for judging of causes and effects are ultimately practical standards, extensions of Sextus’s standards of action (PH I 21–24). They are how we should reason given Hume’s Title Principle, as Garrett has termed it: “Where reason is lively, and mixes itself with some propensity, it ought to be assented to.” Whence the “ought”? In order not to “be a loser in point of pleasure; and this is the origin of my philosophy” (T 1.4.7.11–12). The rules for causal reasoning are meant to guide our natural propensity to use induction. But they do not address the skeptical problem that we can find no sufficiently good reason to regard the results of induction as true (T 1.3.6.11). We are able to follow standards gleaned from natural ways of reasoning in service of practical goals. These practical standards for regarding some things as true or false are the “measures of truth and falsehood” that Hume implies that we have (T 1.4.1.7). What we are unable to follow with any stable result are the epistemic standards we aspire to. Instead of losing all assurance, as we epistemically should, we retain some. As he puts it later, “After the most accurate and exact of my reasonings, I can give no reason why I shou’d assent to it; and feel nothing but a strong propensity to consider objects strongly in that view, under which they appear to me” (T 1.4.7.3).

A PYRRHONIAN INTERPRETATION OF HUME ON ASSENT

389

Thus in 1.4.1 Hume finds himself in the position of unavoidably believing things that it strikes him he wouldn’t believe if he reasoned as he ought, and so epistemically ought not believe. Readers of Hume who resist the Pyrrhonian interpretation crucially assume that no one can consistently be in such a position.20 It seems to such readers that assenting to a view is implicitly committing oneself to its epistemic merit.21 However, the distinction between the two kinds of assent is precisely intended to explain how one consistently can believe things that one realizes he epistemically ought not assent to, whether actively or passively. I’ll discuss the two possibilities in turn. First, one can passively acquiesce in things for which one finds no reason sufficiently good for active endorsement. Passively acquiescing in views forced upon one by appearances just is a way to assent without regard to whether one epistemically ought to assent. So one violates no implicit commitment to the epistemic merit of the views in recognizing that one can find none. Now, if one is to be such a “fool,” Hume observes, as are “all those who reason or believe,” he should at least be so in a way that is “natural and agreeable” as captured by the Title Principle (T 1.4.7.10–11).22 By acquiescing in the Title Principle, Hume decides for practical reasons not to try to conform to onerous epistemic requirements. He is better off ignoring such requirements for the sake of “service to mankind” and his “own private interest” (T 1.4.7.10). So, secondly, he is able to passively acquiesce in views even while also passively acquiescing in the view that he epistemically ought to lose all assurance whatsoever. The Diminution Argument with its general conclusion strikes him as successful, and yet he finds he cannot use that result to extinguish any given actual belief. He finds no practical reason why he should even make the effort. And not doing so violates no commitment implicit in his assent, as it would if he were actively endorsing. Again, active endorsement is committing oneself to following the strictures of what one epistemically ought to hold. It would be inconsistent to actively endorse a view when one thought one epistemically shouldn’t. But in passively acquiescing in views forced upon one, one does not make such commitments. So in passively acquiescing in views despite passively acquiescing in the view that he shouldn’t, Hume violates no implicit commitment. That beliefs are caused by appearances, not chosen for their merits, remains true even if we make theoretical investigations. We can voluntarily make observations, do experiments, weigh opposing considerations, etc.23 But Hume’s point is that the process will cause us to come to a conclusion. It will not be the occasion for our freely choosing which conclusion to come to. And we cannot just will away the resulting belief. Granted, our will could set in motion a process of further weighing of other considerations that could be expected to reduce our assent, or even eliminate it. But the assent itself happens to us, rather than is willed by us. In that way it is passive. To appreciate this point, the content of the proposition assented to must be distinguished from the kind of assent. Theoretical content does not entail active endorsement. Nor does normative content. Hume can even assent to propositions of the form, “It is evident that . . .,” or “It is true that . . .,” or “One ought to believe

390

SKEPTICISM

that . . .” without actively endorsing them (T 1.4.7.15). His assent is wrung from him by appearances, by how matters strike him, and so is passive acquiescence. This passive view of assent is nicely summarized, in the Treatise: We may, therefore, conclude, that belief consists merely in a certain feeling or sentiment; in something, that depends not on the will, but must arise from certain determinate causes and principles, of which we are not masters. (T Appendix 2) And also in the first Enquiry: It follows, therefore, that the difference between fiction and belief lies in some sentiment or feeling, which is annexed to the latter, not to the former, and which depends not on the will, nor can be commanded at pleasure. It must be excited by nature, like all other sentiments; and must arise from the particular situation, in which the mind is placed at any particular juncture. (EHU 5.11) Note that passive acquiescence ought not be thought of as weak assent. The assent may be normatively weak, but may well be causally “strong and steady” (T 1.3.7.5 n. 20). Hume allows, as Sextus apparently did not, that some views forced upon one by appearances may be causally hard to dislodge (PH I 230). Force and vivacity come in degrees and sometimes in a very high degree (T 1.3.13.19). I’ve said that Hume is like the Pyrrhonians in finding insufficiently good reason for active endorsement and in yielding to passive acquiescence. But where exactly is the skeptic’s suspense of judgment? It might seem trivial to claim that Hume suspends active endorsement, when he thinks there is no such thing. Why does withholding an assent impossible to grant make him a skeptic? The answer is that, when he reasons as carefully as he can with truth as the goal, he finds no sufficiently good reason why he ought to believe anything. This process leads to temporary suspension of passive acquiescence, until his natural propensities to believe reassert themselves. But it also leads to stable passive acquiescence in the view that those skeptical arguments are unanswerable, even if they produce no lasting suspension of judgment as passive acquiescence. So were active endorsement possible, Hume would find it suspended. And for those who believe in active endorsement, they either ought to suspend it or else ought to admit with Hume that their assent is really nothing more than passive acquiescence, after all. In summary, reasoning as we ought to would result in total suspense of judgment. Were there such a thing as active endorsement, we would totally suspend it, since we can find nothing worthy of it. Nonetheless, passive acquiescence is compelled in us by appearances, even appearances that result from theoretical investigation. In this way Hume can combine his radical skepticism with his constructive science, mathematics, and philosophy. He does so in a way very like the way the Pyrrhonian combined radical skepticism with the assent required to live a normal life. It is true that Hume resists calling his skepticism Pyrrhonian, and calls it mitigated. But Hume erroneously took the Pyrrhonians to recommend no assent whatsoever, which is why he thought that a true Pyrrhonian must “remain in total lethargy” and soon “perish.” As we have seen, the Pyrrhonians had a ready answer to this charge in the distinction between two kinds of assent. They found no reason to

A PYRRHONIAN INTERPRETATION OF HUME ON ASSENT

391

grant active endorsement, but yielded to passive acquiescence in order to survive. Likewise Hume. There is no mitigation of his failure to find a sufficiently good reason to actively endorse anything; there is much natural mitigation of any great loss of passive acquiescence that might result from his skeptical arguments (EHU 12.23–25). Hume’s own one-sided view of the Pyrrhonians should not prevent our seeing him as their natural successor concerning assent.24

NOTES 1. My reading follows Popkin (1966) (on Popkin on the crucial influence of Pyrrhonism on modern philosophy in general, see Maia Neto’s chapter in this book). See also Baxter (2006; 2008: ch. 1; 2009a; 2009b). Note that Hume does not follow the Pyrrhonians in their centrally important concern with tranquility. For a detailed discussion of Hume’s familiarity with Sextus’s works, see Fosl (1998). 2. I cite Hume’s Treatise by book, part, section, and paragraph. I use the text in Hume (2007). 3. I cite Hume’s Enquiry by section and paragraph. I use the text in Hume (2000). 4. I follow the translation by Annas and Barnes in Sextus Empiricus (2000). 5. Or, perhaps better, propositions perspicuously paraphrased by propositions beginning with “It appears to me now that . . . .” 6. I’m grateful to Lionel Shapiro for this suggestion. 7. Cf. Sellars (1956: sec. 16). Wittgenstein (1958: 92) says: “Don’t regard a hesitant assertion as an assertion of hesitancy.” 8. Barnes (1997: 65 n. 21) disagrees. Burnyeat uses the term “self-refuting” instead of “self-cancelling.” 9. “Belief” encompasses a similar ambiguity between mental state and its propositional content. 10. I disagree with Burnyeat’s claim that this process could happen only if the skeptic comes to the belief that “contrary claims are equal” (Burnyeat 1997a: 56) The skeptic need at most acquiesce in this appearance, and perhaps, as Barnes urges, the suspense of judgment “simply happens to us” (Barnes 1997: 58–59). 11. For a similar approach to “Agrippa’s Trilemma,” see Williams (1988: 573–583), though Williams sees the results of the modes of Agrippa as denials of specifically epistemological theses that would be held by a dogmatist, whereas I see them as in conflict with any conclusion assented to for a reason. 12. “In vain would the skeptic make a distinction between science and common life, or between one science and another. The arguments employed in all, if just, are of a similar nature and contain the same force and evidence” (Hume 1980: 9–10). 13. I cite Cudworth (1731) by book, chapter, and section. 14. I follow the translation in Descartes (1984). 15. “[T]hat all our Cogitations, are Obtruded, and Imposed upon us from without; and that there is no Transition in our Thoughts at any time, but such as had been before in Sense; (which the Democritick Atheist averrs) this is a Thing, which we absolutely deny. For, had we no Mastery at all over our Thoughts, but they were all

392

SKEPTICISM

like Tennis Balls, Bandied, and Struck upon us, as it were by Rackets from without; then could we not steadily and constantly carry on any Designs and Purposes of Life” (Cudworth 1964: 845). 16. Even beliefs not initially arrived at by reason are subject to its scrutiny. 17. For some crucial discussions of the 1.4.1 argument in addition to Garrett’s, see Morris (1989: 39–60), Owen (forthcoming), and Fogelin (1985: ch. 2). 18. Cf. the belief that one ought not believe in body, where “carelessness and inattention” prevent the opinion from being held constantly (T 1.4.2.56–57). 19. Thus I agree with Morris that Hume attacks “the intellectualist model of the rationally reflective epistemic agent” in order to replace it with a naturalistic model (Morris 1989: 56). See also Baier (1991: 59–61) and Owen (1999: 120–121). However, all three focus on a conception of reason as a discoverer of necessary connections. I take Hume to rather be arguing that an active endorser—someone who arrives at assent by choosing to reason as he ought—will not arrive at assent. Only assent that is a feeling caused by appearances can survive reasoning. Baier (1991: 96) contends in contrast that reason on Hume’s own account has normative authority because it can bear its own survey. Thus Hume discovers “which mental causes are good reasons.” I agree instead with Owen (1994: 198) that 1.4.1 precisely shows that even Humean reason cannot bear its own survey. 20. For instance, Garrett (2007: 7, 8, 11) assumes (i) that in providing psychological explanations, Hume has no reason to dispute them, (ii) that coming to believe according to the Title Principle could satisfy one’s curiosity only if it epistemically ought to, and (iii) that concluding that one’s own beliefs were not probable would undermine one’s ability to make judgments about usefulness. All these make the deep assumption that one can’t believe things without believing one epistemically ought to believe them. 21. My thinking here was sparked partly by Patrick Greenough’s lecture entitled “Pragmatics in Thought: The Case of Moore’s Paradox,” University of Connecticut, October 2010. 22. His belief in body is another example of Hume’s believing something that he realizes he epistemically ought not believe. “Carelessness and in-attention” are our only way to retain any sort of assent in the vulgar view involving “gross illusion” and the philosophical view “loaded” with an “absurdity” (T 1.4.2.56–57). Even were the Title Principle an epistemic one, it could not justify the conclusion that forgetting or ignoring a problem is a solution to it. 23. In this respect Hume is allowing for a Pyrrhonian way to accommodate the procedures of the New Academy (PH I 227–229). 24. I’m grateful to Richard Bett for penetrating comments in a symposium at the American Philosophical Association Central Division Meetings, 2012, as well as to Diego Machuca and Baron Reed for their helpful suggestions.

REFERENCES Annas, Julia. 2000. “Hume and Ancient Scepticism,” Acta Philosophica Fennica 66: 271– 285. Baier, Annette. 1991. A Progress of Sentiments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

A PYRRHONIAN INTERPRETATION OF HUME ON ASSENT

393

Barnes, Jonathan. 1997. “The Beliefs of a Pyrrhonist.” In M. Burnyeat and M. Frede (eds.), The Original Sceptics: A Controversy, 58–91. Baxter, Donald L. M. 2006. “Identity, Continued Existence, and the External World.” In S. Traiger (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Hume’s Treatise, 114–132. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. Baxter, Donald L. M. 2008. Hume’s Difficulty: Time and Identity in the Treatise. New York: Routledge. Baxter, Donald L. M. 2009a. “Hume’s Theory of Space and Time in its Skeptical Context.” In D. F. Norton and J. Taylor (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Hume, 2nd ed., 105–146. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Baxter, Donald L. M. 2009b. “Précis of Hume’s Difficulty,” Philosophical Studies 146: 409–411. Burnyeat, Myles. 1997a. “Can the Sceptic Live his Scepticism?” In M. Burnyeat and M. Frede (eds.), The Original Sceptics: A Controversy, 25–57. Indianapolis: Hackett. Burnyeat, Myles. 1997b. “The Sceptic in His Place and Time.” In M. Burnyeat and M. Frede (eds.), The Original Sceptics: A Controversy, 92–126. Indianapolis: Hackett. Cudworth, Ralph. 1731. A Treatise Concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality. London: James and John Knapton. Cudworth, Ralph. 1964. The True Intellectual System of the Universe. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Friedrich Frommann Verlag. Descartes, René. 1984. “Meditations on First Philosophy.” In J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch (eds.), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, Vol. 2, 1–90. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Fogelin, Robert. 1985. Hume’s Skepticism in the Treatise of Human Nature. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Fosl, Peter. 1998. “The Bibliographic Bases of Hume’s Understanding of Sextus Empiricus and Pyrrhonism,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 36: 261–278. Frede, Michael. 1973. Review of C. L. Stough, Greek Skepticism: A Study in Epistemology, The Journal of Philosophy 70: 805–810. Frede, Michael. 1997a. “The Sceptic’s Beliefs.” In M. Burnyeat and M. Frede (eds.), The Original Sceptics: A Controversy, 1–24. Indianapolis: Hackett. Frede, Michael. 1997b. “The Sceptic’s Two Kinds of Assent and the Question of the Possibility of Knowledge.” In M. Burnyeat and M. Frede (eds.), The Original Sceptics: A Controversy , 127–151. Indianapolis: Hackett. Garrett, Don. 1997. Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. Garrett, Don. 2007. “Reasons to Act and Believe: Naturalism and Rational Justification in Hume’s Philosophical Project,” Philosophical Studies 132: 1–16. Hume, David. 1980. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, edited by R. H. Popkin. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. Hume, David. 2000. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, edited by T. L. Beauchamp Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hume, David. 2007. A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by D. F. Norton and M. J. Norton. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Morris, William Edward. 1989. “Hume’s Scepticism about Reason,” Hume Studies 15: 39–60.

394

SKEPTICISM

Norton, David Fate. 1982. David Hume: Common-Sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Owen, David. 1994. “Reason, Reflection, and Reductios,” Hume Studies 20: 195–210. Owen, David. 1999. Hume’s Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Owen, David. 2015. “Scepticism with Regard to Reason.” In D. Ainslie (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hume’s Treatise, 101–134. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Popkin, Richard. 1966. “David Hume: His Pyrrhonism and His Critique of Pyrrhonism.” In V. C. Chappell (ed.), Hume, 53–98. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books. Sellars, Wilfrid. 1956. “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind.” In H. Feigl and M. Scriven (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1, 253–329. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Sextus Empiricus. 2000. Outlines of Scepticism, translated by J. Annas and J. Barnes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stewart, Dugald. 2005. “Dissertation on the Progress of Philosophy.” In J. Fieser (ed.), Early Responses to Hume’s Metaphysical and Epistemological Writings, II, 2nd edn. Bristol: Thoemmes Press. Thurber, James. 1942. “The Day the Dam Broke.” In his My Life and Hard Times. New York: Harper Brothers. Williams, Michael. 1988. “Scepticism without Theory,” The Review of Metaphysics 41: 547–588. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical Investigations, 3d ed., translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. New York: MacMillan.

CHAPTER TWENTY-EIGHT

Thomas Reid’s Engagement with Skeptics and Skepticism RENÉ VAN WOUDENBERG

1 INTRODUCTION Engagement with skeptical problems, as a means of resisting skepticism, may take various forms. First, one may try to convince skeptics that their skeptical conclusion is false. Second, one may try to identify certain assumptions underlying the skeptical argument that may initially seem unobjectionable but that cannot withstand close scrutiny.1 Third, one may try to take up the skeptical challenge and offer an argument for the denial of the skeptical conclusion, or for the weaker thesis that it is not irresponsible or irrational to accept the denial of the skeptical conclusion. I call these engagements convincing the skeptic, exposing the skeptical argument, and countervailing the skeptical conclusion, respectively. In this chapter, I will review Thomas Reid’s engagement with skeptics and skepticism under these three headings. Before starting out, I first provide some basic information about Reid, and next reflect on the interrelations between the three forms of engagement. After having served as a minister in the Church of Scotland, Thomas Reid (1710– 1796) became a professor of “moral philosophy” at the universities of Aberdeen and Glasgow. During his lifetime he published three books, An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense (1764), Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man (1785), and Essays on the Active Powers of Man (1788). Reid became the father of what has come to be called “the Scottish school of common sense philosophy.” His work was widely influential across the continent, but especially in the United States, where his work inspired Thomas Jefferson and other founding fathers of the New World (Redekop 2004). Over the last forty years Reid has again being recognized as a major philosopher. His work has had a lasting influence on philosophers such as Roderick Chisholm, Keith Lehrer, Alvin Plantinga, William Alston, and Nicholas Wolterstorff, along with many others.

396

SKEPTICISM

As to the interrelations between the three forms of engagement with skeptics and skepticism, one could think that one way to convince the skeptic is to expose the skeptic’s argument by laying bare at least one problematic assumption underlying the argument. But this need not be sufficient. After all, the skeptic may simply retort that though his argument is problematic, this does not entail that the skeptical conclusion is false. And here the skeptic is, of course, right. In order to convince the skeptic, it would be required to expose all arguments for the skeptical conclusion. And even this may not be sufficient for conviction. For, unfortunately, it isn’t a characteristic of good arguments that they convince everybody. Here we enter the mires of human psychology. As to the relation between convincing the skeptic and countervailing the skeptical conclusion, we should note that a skeptic may remain totally unconvinced by countervailing arguments. This is again a point about human psychology. So, there is no direct relation between convincing the skeptic, on the one hand, and exposing skeptical arguments and countervailing the skeptical conclusion on the other. Nor is there a direct relation between exposing skeptical arguments and countervailing the skeptical conclusion. For countervailing the skeptical argument, that is, advancing an argument for the denial of the skeptical conclusion, needn’t bring to light objectionable assumptions that underlie the skeptical argument. So, the three sorts of engagement are not related in any simple way. But both exposing the skeptical argument and countervailing the skeptical conclusion at least stay clear from the muddle of human psychology. These latter engagements would be meaningful even if there were no skeptics. The first engagement, by contrast, would not, for in order to convince skeptics, there must be skeptics.

2  CONVINCING THE SKEPTIC Reid relates a number of stories about supposedly real-life skeptics who profess not to believe their senses, but who nevertheless usually don’t bang their heads against posts, don’t step into ditches and fires, and generally stay out of harm’s way. About Pyrrho, the great skeptic, Reid writes, for example, that he “is said once to have been in such a passion with his cook, who probably had not roasted his dinner to his mind, that with the spit in his hand, and the meat upon it, he pursued him even into the market place” (1764: 21). Stories like these made Reid suspicious about what these skeptics tell about themselves. His comment is that such skeptics either “act the hypocrite” or else “impose upon themselves” (1764: 170). Some find this comment “shallow” and “superficial” (De Bary 2002: 7, 12). But is it? For surely someone may profess that he doesn’t believe his eyes, while in fact he does believe them. A bystander who observes that someone who professes not to believe his senses carefully stays out of harm’s way, has an excellent reason for thinking that the skeptic doesn’t believe what he professes he believes. The skeptic’s behavior betrays him; he does believe his senses. One plausible principle about belief ascriptions to others involves observed behavior. Someone who says he likes to have a drink and walks to the refrigerator should, in ordinary situations, surely be ascribed the belief that the refrigerator contains drinkable items. Reid’s comment, then, needn’t be deemed shallow at all; it can be taken to point to a rather sensible principle of belief ascription.2

THOMAS REID’S ENGAGEMENT WITH SKEPTICS AND SKEPTICISM

397

If we suppose that Reid’s comment is true, and so suppose that the skeptics who figure in the stories are misleading themselves as to what they believe, doesn’t this imply that they are not really skeptics, as they do, in fact, believe their senses? So, doesn’t his comment, if true, mean that there are no skeptics? No, but it does mean that in order to define being a skeptic, we need to move one level upwards. A skeptic should not be defined as someone who doesn’t believe his senses—for, if Reid’s remark is right, he does believe them. Rather, a skeptic should be defined as someone who professes not to believe his senses. Accordingly, the program of convincing the skeptic really is the program of convincing someone who professes not to believe his senses of the fact that he does believe them after all. Reid clearly recognized that there is a class of skeptics whom he cannot possibly convince by arguments of the wrongness of their conclusion, namely, the class of those who believe that our powers of reasoning and judgment are fallacious: If a skeptic should build his skepticism upon this foundation that all our reasoning and judging powers are fallacious in nature, or should resolve at least to withhold assent until it be proved that they are not; it would be impossible by argument to beat him out of this strong hold, and he must be left to enjoy his own skepticism. (1785: 480) Does this indicate that according to Reid total skepticism is irrefutable, as De Bary (2002: 16) claims? I think it is better to say that what this quote indicates is that in Reid’s view the total skeptic cannot, by arguments, be convinced of the falsehood of his skeptical thesis. Reid’s point here is about persons, skeptics, not about arguments or theses, skepticism. But what about skeptics who do argue for skeptical conclusions? Could they, perhaps, be convinced by an argument that Reid might bring against them? Some reasoning skeptics, as we might call them, urge us not to accept any proposition unless it is “founded upon reason.” This skeptic finds fault with those ordinary people who “believe undoubtedly that there is a sun, moon, and stars; an earth which we inhabit; country, friends, and relations, which we enjoy; lands, houses, and moveables, which we possess,” even though they have no decent argument or proof for any of this. The skeptic, however, “pitying the credulity of the vulgar,” resolves “to have no faith but what is founded upon reason” (1764: 18). He thinks it is wrong to believe what is not founded upon reason. In effect, the reasoning skeptic Reid has in mind affirms the following Principle of Belief: PoB It is wrong to believe proposition p unless p is founded upon reason. And, Reid explains, a proposition is “founded upon reason” if it can be proved by reasoning, that is, if it can be made the conclusion of a sound argument. One point that Reid makes about PoB is that there are propositions the skeptic believes in a way that violates PoB. Hume, for example, says Reid, appears to me to be but a half-skeptic. He hath not followed his principles so far as they lead him; but, after having, with unparalleled intrepidity and success,

398

SKEPTICISM

combated vulgar prejudices, when he had but one blow to strike, his courage fails him, he fairly lays down his arms, and yields himself a captive to the most common of all vulgar prejudices—I mean the belief of the existence of his own impressions and ideas. (1764: 71) Reid’s point, then, is that Hume believed that there exist such things as impressions and ideas but that this belief is not founded upon reason. Reid makes a similar point about Descartes, who also endorsed PoB. Descartes tried to prove his own existence in the Cogito argument. That argument concludes to the existence of a mind, or subject of thought, from the existence of thought. But, Reid asks, “why did he [Descartes] not prove the existence of thought? Consciousness, it may be said, vouches that. But who is voucher for consciousness? Can any man prove that his consciousness may not deceive him? No man can” (1764: 17). In effect, Descartes believes in the existence of thought even though it is not founded upon reason. So, Reid argues, the skeptic accepts at least some propositions (propositions about the existence of impressions and ideas, or thought) in a way that violates PoB. Still, he continues, the skeptic’s adherence to PoB really is an expression of his allegiance to the faculty of reason, and his fundamental distrust of other faculties, perception included. But why, Reid asks, should reason and perception be treated differently? Reason, says the skeptic, is the only judge of truth, and you ought to throw off every opinion and every belief that is not grounded on reason. Why, sir, should I believe the faculty of reason more than that of perception?—they came both out of the same shop, and were made by the same artist; and if he puts one piece of false ware into my hands, what should hinder him from putting another? (1764: 169) Reid, then, accuses the skeptic of unwarranted partiality. Will a skeptic be convinced by this line of thought? Not necessarily. For as noted, it isn’t a hallmark of sound arguments that they convince. Still, a reasoning skeptic, bothered by inconsistency, could be convinced by Reid’s charge that he actually violates a principle that he officially adopts. But even if the skeptic isn’t convinced by the charge, it does make explicit that the skeptic’s argument assumes a certain principle, PoB, that can be contested. In that sense, what we have heard Reid say so far can be viewed as an effort to expose the skeptical argument—which is the topic of the next section.

3  EXPOSING THE SKEPTICAL ARGUMENT Important strands of Reid’s thought rather naturally fit the heading exposing the skeptical argument. In the Letter of Dedication of the Inquiry, Reid says: For my own satisfaction, I entered into a serious examination of the principles upon which this skeptical system [Hume’s] is built; and was not a little surprised to find, that it leans with its whole weight upon a hypothesis . . . of which I could

THOMAS REID’S ENGAGEMENT WITH SKEPTICS AND SKEPTICISM

399

find no solid proof. The hypothesis I mean is, That nothing is perceived but what is in the mind which perceives it: That we do not really perceive things that are external, but only certain images and pictures of them imprinted upon the mind, which are called impressions and ideas. If this be true; supposing certain impressions and ideas to exist in my mind, I cannot, from their existence, infer the existence of anything else. (1764: 4) This passage indicates that Reid’s diagnosis of what is problematic in the skeptical argument for the conclusion that we can’t have knowledge of the external world is that it assumes the correctness of what he elsewhere calls the “theory of ideas.” And it furthermore suggests that Reid held that in order to dispose of the skeptical argument it is sufficient to explode that theory. Reid identifies a further assumption that underlies the skeptical argument—one that we have touched on at the end of the previous section. The assumption is that our thoughts, our sensations, and everything of which we are conscious, hath a real existence, is admitted in this system as a first principle; but everything else must be made evident by the light of reason. Reason must rear the whole fabric of knowledge upon this single principle of consciousness. (1764: 210) This assumption has been called classical, or Cartesian, foundationalism.3 Its basic idea is that the only beliefs with enough certainty to qualify as foundational are incorrigible or indubitable “ideas” about our own current mental states. All other beliefs (about the external world, for example, or the past) can be justified only if they are demonstrable from these foundational beliefs. This assumption obviously has a skeptical implication, for, as the history of philosophy between Descartes and Hume has made clear, it is impossible to prove the existence of mind-external items solely on the basis of premises about one’s current mental states. And hence, on the assumption of classical foundationalism, none of our external world beliefs are justified or warranted. Here, too, Reid is suggesting that in order to expose the skeptical argument it is sufficient to explode Cartesian foundationalism. Let us take a look at what Reid thinks is wrong with both of these assumptions and next turn to the question whether rejection of them is sufficient to dispose of all skeptical arguments. Let us start with the foundationalist assumption. As intimated in the previous section, Reid’s main objection to Cartesian foundationalism is that it is arbitrary. Why should consciousness, the faculty that generates beliefs about one’s own current mental states, and reason be trusted, while all other faculties (perception and memory, for example) should be trusted only after their trustworthiness has been vouched for by consciousness and reason? There is no relevant difference among our faculties that would warrant the preference of consciousness and reason over the others. Says Reid: The faculties of consciousness, of memory, of external sense, and of reason, are all equally gifts of nature. No good reason can be assigned for receiving the testimony of one of them, which is not of equal force with regard to the others. (1785: 463)4

400

SKEPTICISM

Reid criticizes the assumption of the theory of ideas—that ideas are the immediate objects of perception—in a number of ways. I single out one line of criticism: that there are no good arguments for the existence of ideas. Hume’s famous argument for the existence of ideas from the relativity of perception, Reid argues, is a failure. The argument is this: “The table, which we see, seems to diminish, as we remove farther from it; but the real table, which exists independently of us, suffers no alteration; it was, therefore, nothing but its image, which was present to the mind” (Hume 1902: 152). Reid criticizes this argument by drawing on the distinction between real and apparent magnitude. These two have very different natures even though both are named “magnitude.” The real magnitude of a table has three dimensions, it is measured on a linear scale, and it is an original object of touch, not of sight. The table’s apparent magnitude, by contrast, has only two dimensions, it is measured by the angle which it subtends at the eye, and is an original object of sight, not of touch. Given this distinction, Reid argues that Hume’s argument equivocates between these two magnitudes. Hume starts out by saying “that the table seems to diminish as we remove farther from it.” This, says Reid, is a claim about the table’s apparent magnitude. But when Hume continues that “the real table suffers no alteration,” he is making a claim about the table’s real magnitude. But then Hume’s conclusion that it is not the real table that we see doesn’t follow from the premises because “the syllogism has what the logicians call two middle terms” (1785: 182). In the quotation taken from the Letter of Dedication to the Inquiry given above, Reid seems to say that, since the theory of ideas is both necessary and sufficient to generate skeptical conclusions, any successful reply to skepticism must reject the theory of ideas. But, as John Greco has argued, although the theory of ideas may be sufficient to generate skeptical conclusions, it is not necessary in order to arrive at such conclusions (2004: 142–143). And this means that it is not sufficient for a successful reply to the skeptical argument that one rejects the theory of ideas, for there are skeptical arguments that do not invoke the theory of ideas at all.5

4  COUNTERVAILING THE SKEPTICAL CONCLUSION 6 To show that some problematic assumptions underlie the (or: a) skeptical argument may help to expose the argument. But it does not show that the skeptical conclusion is false. It only shows that certain arguments for that conclusion can be dispelled. Reid’s most important contribution to the project of countervailing the skeptical conclusion is his theory of First Principles. This section clarifies what Reid thinks is the nature of these principles and his reason for supposing such principles exist. This will allow us to see how Reid countervailed the skeptical conclusion. Reid thinks about first principles as true propositions that are “basic,” that is, as propositions that cannot be based on other, more fundamental, propositions that constitute grounds or evidence for them. First Principles are propositions we don’t (have to) reason to but may reason from. They don’t need support because “they support themselves” (1785: 463). They are, so to speak, “properly basic,”

THOMAS REID’S ENGAGEMENT WITH SKEPTICS AND SKEPTICISM

401

they “need no proof and . . . do not admit of direct proof” (1785: 39). The reason for this is that “their evidence is not demonstrative, but intuitive. They require not proof, but to be placed in a proper point of view” (1785: 41). First principles are propositions such that anyone whose faculties are functioning properly will accept and believe them. Reid’s argument for the existence of first principles is the following regress argument: When we examine, in the way of analysis, the evidence of any proposition, either we find it self-evident, or it rests upon one or more propositions that support it. The same may be said of the propositions that support it, and of those that support them, as far back as we can go. But we cannot go back in this track to infinity. Where then must this analysis stop? It is evident that it must stop only when we come to propositions which support all that are built upon them, but are themselves supported by none—that is to self-evident propositions. (1785: 455) As Alston has pointed out (Alston 1987: 436), Reid’s category of self-evident propositions must be understood as including propositions that are directly evident. That there is a tree in front of one (if there is one) is never self-evident; still, it can be directly evident. The examples Reid offers of first principles are of different kinds. Some have moral content (e.g., “What is done from unavoidable necessity may be agreeable or disagreeable, useful or hurtful, but cannot be the object either of blame or of moral approbation”), others are broadly metaphysical (e.g., “that there are some things that cannot exist by themselves, but must be in something else to which they belong,” 2002: 43), and still others are epistemological. I will be concentrating on examples of the last kind, since these are pertinent to the problem of knowledge of the external world. Following is an incomplete list of epistemological first principles that Reid adumbrates: Principle 1 It is a First Principle “that, in most operations of the mind, there must be an object distinct from the operation itself. I cannot see, without seeing something.” (1785: 44) Principle 2 I shall also take for granted [i.e., as a First Principle] such facts as are attested to the conviction of all sober and reasonable men, either by our senses, by memory, or by human testimony. Although some writers on this subject have disputed the authority of the senses, of memory, and of every human faculty, yet we find that such persons, in the conduct of life, in pursuing their ends, or in avoiding dangers, pay the same regard to the authority of their senses and other faculties, as the rest of mankind. (1785: 46) Principle 3 Those things do really exist which we distinctly perceive by our senses, and are what we perceive them to be. (1785: 476)

402

SKEPTICISM

Principle 4 Another first principle is, that the natural faculties, by which we distinguish truth from error, are not fallacious. If any man should demand a proof of this, it is impossible to satisfy him. For, suppose it should be mathematically demonstrated, this would signify nothing in this case; because, to judge of a demonstration, a man must trust his faculties, and take for granted the very thing in question. (1785: 480) In order to focus subsequent discussion, I start out by noting that Reid’s quest for First Principles has not always been looked upon favorably. Kant, for instance, in the Preface to the Prolegomena, says: They [namely, Reid and some others philosophers of common sense] found a more convenient method of being defiant [towards Hume’s doctrines] without any insight, namely the appeal to common sense. It is indeed a great gift of God to possess right (or as they now call it) plain common sense. But this common sense must be shown in action by well-considered and reasonable thought and words, not by appealing to it as an oracle when no rational justification for one’s position can be advanced. To appeal to common sense when insight and science fail, and no sooner—this is one of the subtle discoveries of modern times, by means of which the most superficial ranter can safely enter the lists with the most thorough thinker and hold his own. . . . Seen clearly, it is but an appeal to the opinion of the multitude, of whose applause the philosopher is ashamed, while the popular charlatan glories and boasts in it. (1783: 7) Here Kant explicitly states that appeal to first principles (he refers to them as common sense) has no justificatory power, because such an appeal is nothing “but an appeal to the opinion of the multitude,” and such an appeal is something a philosopher should be ashamed of—probably because there is no reason to suppose that the opinion of the multitude is true. In one respect Kant was right here. For Reid indeed held that there is merit in a proposition’s receiving (nearly) universal consent. He says, for example, that (A) we ought to take for granted, as first principles, things wherein we find universal agreement, among the learned and unlearned, in different nations and ages of the earth. (2002: 44) As Reid thinks of them, however, first principles have other features besides being (nearly) universally consented to. Kant does not mention these, but they are nonetheless part of Reid’s actual view. These other features are of great importance to Reid. For he does not forget to observe that “there seems to be great difference of opinion among philosophers about first principles. What one takes to be self-evident, another labours to prove by arguments, and a third denies altogether” (2002: 453). One example he offers of this is the thesis that there is an external world. Before Descartes, he notes, the existence of an external world was taken as a first principle, Descartes sought to prove it, and Berkeley and Hume, noticing the weakness of the “proofs,” denied its existence altogether. This leaves us wondering how to identify, or recognize, a genuine first principle. Reid’s answer is that they are to be identified

THOMAS REID’S ENGAGEMENT WITH SKEPTICS AND SKEPTICISM

403

by certain features. One of those we have already noticed: (A) universal agreement. Another feature is that it is almost impossible not to believe that these Principles are true; they force themselves upon us, we cannot resist believing them. Here are some statements of this point: (B) The belief which is implied in [perception] is the effect of instinct. (1764: 172) I cannot demonstrate that two quantities which are equal to the same quantity, are equal to each other; neither can I demonstrate that the tree which I perceive exists. But by the constitution of my nature, my belief is irresistibly carried along by my perception of the tree. (1764: 172) Closely related to (B) is the feature that first principles are indispensable for conducting practical life. Maybe the skeptic thinks she can dispense with giving assent to these Principles, but the practice of her life shows otherwise. First principles are such (C) that every man of common understanding readily assents to them, and finds it absolutely necessary to conduct his actions and opinions by them, in the ordinary affairs of life. (1785: 40–41) It is one thing to profess [that the testimony of sense is fallacious], another seriously to believe it and to be governed by it in the conduct of life. It is evident that a man who did not believe his senses could not keep out of harm’s way one hour of his life; yet, in all the history of philosophy, we never read of any skeptic that ever stepped into fire or water because he did not believe his senses. (1785: 99) Another feature of a first principle is (D) that no man ever pretended to prove it, and yet no man in his wits calls it in question. (2002: 474) That sense perception is reliable, says Reid, is not something that can be proved, nor something that can seriously be called into question. Feature (D) says that it is our predicament that first principles, such as Principle 3, which says that sense perception is reliable, can never be proved. Reid provides the reason why this is so (in the previous section we already touched upon this): in order to prove that perception is reliable, one has to take for granted that the faculty that is operative in the proof is reliable. Discussing the reliability of reason, Reid says: If a man’s honesty were called in question, it would be ridiculous to refer to the man’s own word, whether he be honest or not. The same absurdity there is in attempting to prove, by any kind of reasoning . . . that our reason is not fallacious, since the very point in question is, whether reasoning may be trusted. (1785: 480) The point can be generalized over all of our faculties: Every kind of reasoning for the veracity of our faculties, amounts to no more than taking their own testimony for their veracity; and this we must do implicitly, until God give us new faculties to sit in judgment upon the old. (1785: 481)

404

SKEPTICISM

We cannot prove that our faculties are reliable, without pragmatically presupposing what we try to prove. And the flipside of this is that we cannot disprove their reliability either, without pragmatically presupposing their reliability. Still another feature of a First Principle is that (E) opinions that contradict them “are not only false but absurd.” (2002: 462) Furthermore, belief in First Principles is not determined by experience or education but “by our nature.” This is a prevalent theme throughout Reid’s writings: (F) I consider this instinctive belief [that my faculties are trustworthy] as one of the best gifts of Nature. I thank the Author of my being, who bestowed it upon me before the eyes of my reason were opened, and still bestows it upon me, to be my guide where reason leaves me in the dark. And now I yield to the direction of my senses, not from instinct only, but from confidence and trust in a faithful and beneficent Monitor, grounded upon the experience of his paternal care and goodness. (1764: 170) original and natural judgments (of perception) are . . . a part of that furniture which nature hath given to the human understanding. They are the inspiration of the Almighty. . . . They are a part of our constitution. (1764: 215) First principles, then, have certain features that enable us to identify them. Kant, in the quotation given earlier, attributed to Reid the view that a proposition’s having those features (Kant, as noted, only mentions feature (A)) is evidence for the truth of the purported first principle proposition. According to Kant, Reid holds that universal agreement can be used in an argument that seeks to prove the truth of the principle. But, as we can now see, this was not what Reid actually held. First principles resist direct proof. For Reid, these features don’t prove the truth of supposed first principles but are indicators of a proposition’s being a first principle. Or, as Keith Lehrer puts it, they are “criteria . . . for determining whether something is a first principle” (Lehrer 1989: 87). And Reid, although he nowhere explicitly says so, held that the proposition that sense perception is reliable, displays all, or nearly all, the features mentioned and therefore qualifies as a first principle. Reid’s position on first principles can, then, be summarized as follows: (1) as the regress argument shows, there must exist first principles; (2) one such principle is that we can gain perceptual knowledge of the external world; (3) first principles have various features, (A)–(F), that enable us to identify or recognize them; these features cannot be used in an argument to show or prove the truth of the principles; (4) although the proposition that sense perception is reliable cannot be proven, it is nonetheless reasonable to accept it as a first principle; (5) we are justified in believing first principles until their falsehood has been established; (6) the falsehood of the proposition that sense perception is reliable (and of the belief that there is an external world) has not been established.

NOTES 1. Examples of this kind of engagement are Williams (1996) and Greco (2000).

THOMAS REID’S ENGAGEMENT WITH SKEPTICS AND SKEPTICISM

405

2. Pyrrhonist skeptics would, of course, deny what the bystander says about them. They would say that they are following appearances in the absence of having beliefs. If there appears to be some danger, they will stay out of harm’s way, but this doesn’t mean, they say, that they believe there is some danger. However, even if the bystander’s interpretation is wrong by the lights of the Pyrrhonists, this doesn’t invalidate the bystander’s point; she may still have a very good reason for thinking that Pyrrhonists do believe what they say they don’t. 3. Wolterstorff (1987) argues that when Reid spoke of the “theory of ideas” he had in mind a commitment not only to mental representationalism but also to classical foundationalism. I will discuss these assumptions separately. 4. No one, to my mind, has appreciated this point better than Alston (1993). 5. Likewise, Van Cleve (2015: 328–332) has argued that Reid’s direct realism, his alternative to the theory of ideas, by itself does not give sufficient resources for answering so-called closure-based skeptical arguments. I myself have argued for a somewhat different evaluation of the anti-skeptical power of Reid’s direct realism in Van Woudenberg (2000). 6. This section has lifted a couple of paragraphs from Van Woudenberg (2004).

REFERENCES Alston, William P. 1993. The Reliability of Sense Perception. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Alston, William P. 1986. “Thomas Reid on Epistemic Principles,” History of Philosophy Quarterly 2: 435–452. De Bary, Philip. 2002. Thomas Reid and Skepticism: His Reliabilist Response. London and New York: Routledge. Greco, John. 2004. “Reid’s Reply to the Skeptic.” In T. Cuneo and R. van Woudenberg (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Thomas Reid. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 134–155. Greco, John. 2000. Putting Skeptics in Their Place. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hume, David. 1902. Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by L. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kant, Immanuel. 1783 [1950]. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, edited by L. White Beck. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. Lehrer, Keith. 1989. Thomas Reid. London and New York: Routledge. Redekop, Benjamin. 2004. “Reid’s Influence in Britain, Germany, France and America.” In T. Cuneo and R. van Woudenberg (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Thomas Reid, 313–340. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reid, Thomas. 1764 [1997]. An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense, edited by D. R. Brooks. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Reid, Thomas. 1785 [2002]. Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, edited by D. R. Brooks. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Van Cleve, James. 2015. Problems from Reid. New York: Oxford University Press. Van Woudenberg, René. 2000. “Perceptual Relativism, Scepticism, and Thomas Reid,” Reid Studies 3: 65–90.

406

SKEPTICISM

Van Woudenberg, René. 2004. “Reid and Kant against the Skeptic.” In J. Houston (ed.), Thomas Reid: Context, Influence, Significance. Edinburgh: Dunedin Academic Press: 155–180. Van Woudenberg, René. 2013. “Thomas Reid between Externalism and Internalism,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 51: 75–92. Williams, Michael. 1996. Unnatural Doubts. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 2001. Thomas Reid and the Story of Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1987. “Hume and Reid,” The Monist 70: 398–417.

CHAPTER TWENTY-NINE

Johann Georg Hamann GWEN GRIFFITH-DICKSON

1 INTRODUCTION Johann Georg Hamann (1730–1788) was a Prussian scholar, writer, and editor, considered to be one of the most well-read scholars of his time (greatly aided by his fluency in many languages). He was born in Königsberg, the son of a midwife and a barber-surgeon, and began study in philosophy and theology at the age of sixteen. He left university without completing his studies and became the governor to a wealthy family on a Baltic estate. During this time he continued his extraordinarily broad reading and private research. He took up a job in the family firm of a friend from his Königsberg days, Christoph Berens, and was sent on an obscure mission to London, in which he evidently failed. He then led a high life until he ran out of friends, money, and support. In a garret, depressed and impoverished, he read the Bible cover to cover and experienced a religious conversion. He returned to the House of Berens in Riga, where they evidently forgave him his failure. He fell in love with Christoph Berens’s sister, Katharina, but was refused permission to marry her by his friend, on the grounds of his religious conversion; Berens was an enthusiastic follower of the Enlightenment and was nauseated by the more pious manifestations of Hamann’s new-found religiosity. Smarting from this blow and its motivations, Hamann returned to his father’s house in Königsberg, where he lived for the rest of his life until his final months. During this period in Königsberg, he lived with a woman whom he never married (despite his committed Christianity) but to whom he remained devoted and faithful, having four children on whom he doted and who occasionally feature in his writings (principally as unruly distractions to the author’s scholarship). At the end of his life, he accepted an invitation to Münster from one of his admirers, Princess Gallitzin; he died there in 1788. Hamann had a profound influence on the German “Storm and Stress” movement, and on other contemporaries such as Herder and Jacobi; he impressed Hegel and Goethe (who called him the brightest head of his time) and was a major influence on Kierkegaard. He also maintained a friendly, mutually respectful relationship with Kant despite their sharp philosophical disagreement and the several critiques of Kant’s work penned by Hamann—indeed, it was through the intercession of Kant

408

SKEPTICISM

that Hamann was able to attain employment as a civil servant in the tax office of Frederick the Great. Hamann never held an official academic post, nor an ecclesiastical one; this may in part have been due to his pronounced speech impediment, which inhibited him from either lecturing or preaching. Yet he was highly respected in his time for his scholarship and breadth of learning. His writings were notorious even in his own time for the challenges they threw down to the reader. These challenges to interpretation and understanding are only heightened today. Nevertheless, an increasing number of scholars from philosophy, theology, aesthetics, and German studies are finding his ideas and insights of value to contemporary concerns. His central preoccupations are still pertinent: language, knowledge, the nature of the human person, sexuality and gender, and the relationship of humanity to God. Meanwhile, his views, which in many respects anticipate later challenges to the Enlightenment project and to modernity, are still relevant and even provocative. Hamann is sometimes portrayed, particularly in the English-speaking world, as an opponent of the Enlightenment, an enemy of reason, and an irrationalist. Hamann studies have moved on from this interpretation. He had a complex, admittedly combative relationship to his time, but given the fundamental disjunctions of Enlightenment thought—rationalism, materialism, etc.—he could hardly be a singleminded opponent. Both these tendencies of his time displeased him. Positively put, his underlying insight and conviction was the wholeness, the integration, and above all the relations of the phenomenon in question. Hamann held that the various striking features of our experience—ourselves, others, language, the world, ultimately God—are inextricably related. It was his conviction that a true and deep understanding of any of these can only arise following consideration of its relationship to the others. So, for instance, an analysis of the philosophy of language would have to include a discussion of God, which in turn must make reference to sexuality, and vice versa; such assertions have led to some considering Hamann to be a mystic. This emphasis on relationships between the most basic and important facets of our experience must be borne in mind when exploring Hamann’s viewpoint on skepticism, for it meant that he eschewed any conventional relationship to positions on knowledge and skepticism that were held at the time. Hamann was skeptical, yet a decided anti-skeptic. He concerned himself with the limits and possibilities of knowledge, yet not in the manner of Locke or Kant: for Hamman this was not a technical or a technique question—his interest was in the human implications of knowing and not knowing. Hamann also had a very different story to tell: one in which history was best understood as “‘mythology”; one in which the cause-andeffect relationship of our ingestion and elimination had to be taken on faith, but attaining reliable knowledge of God was considered to be as easy as child’s play. Hamann does appear as a skeptic, or a so-called irrationalist, in several respects. First, he had an ironist’s delight in how certain philosophers deployed skepticism to undermine faith in reason. To an extent, this was a position he agreed with— overweening faith and confidence in our epistemological powers was for Hamann unwarranted and almost ethically dangerous. Second, he was a skeptic vis-à-vis

JOHANN GEORG HAMANN

409

“reason” and the qualities attributed to it by the typical figures of the time. Third, he was a skeptic when it came to some epistemological claims to knowledge, namely, its certainty and reliability, and its unity and systematicity. Yet Hamann was nonetheless a “True Believer” in a certain conception of knowledge, “rightly understood” as: piecemeal and iterative; relational rather than rational, where we know best by intimacy rather than by inference; inseparable from experience, tradition, and language; and as ultimately consisting in self-knowledge, which itself rests on being known. Hamann’s skepticism, then, did not come close to playing the nihilistic, ultimately destructive role it played for other philosophers of the Enlightenment.

2  “I DON’T KNOW”: THE TEST CASE OF SOCRATES Hamann’s epistemology called for a realism concerning our ability to acquire and hold information in isolation, twinned with immense positivity regarding the ability to understand our experience in a holistic fashion. This is well demonstrated by his use of Socrates to illustrate his conception of human knowledge.1 Plato portrayed Socrates, whether sincerely or disingenuously, as continually protesting his lack of knowledge—a phenomenon well known in the literature as “Socratic Ignorance.” In an act of wanton provocation, Hamann took the self-proclaimed ignorance of Socrates, the poster boy of the Enlightenment, as his strategy for asserting the limits to human knowledge. The fact that the most intelligent of individuals persistently claimed to know nothing challenges any claim to knowledge that his hearers—or eighteenth-century admirers—might have made and calls the powers of human knowledge itself into question. In Hamann’s hands, Socratic ignorance is not the foundation stone of skepticism; it was not a feigned agnosticism as a sophisticated argumentative position affected in an elenctic dispute, nor a tactic. Socrates’s ignorance was “Empfindung”: a feeling, perception, intuitive sense for what is the case;2 it is a recognition of the reality of human knowing. Hamann deploys this theme in multiple ways. In one maneuver, he portrays Socrates’s avowal of ignorance as an ethical stance, almost a renunciation, a refusal to participate in a distasteful activity. If a skilled card player responds to an invitation from a pack of cheats by saying, “I don’t play,” we recognize this, not as a lack of skill, but as a rejection of their immoral proclivities. So too with Socrates: on his lips “I don’t know” means “I don’t play the game of competitive knowing the way you Sophists do.” Hamann depicts the Athenians’ curiosity, their lust for the novelty of knowledge, as “satyriasis,” a sex addiction if you will. Socrates’s insistence on his ignorance was a rejection of their epistemological promiscuity, a refusal to join in their philosophical vices: both the lust for uncommitted knowing and the pride in conquest (76:28f.). For Hamann, knowledge properly understood is a relationship; and thus there is a way to know deeply, reverently, and ultimately deliciously. But there is also a style of snatching and quitting in a shallow exchange; and knowing something for the sake of power or even domination of the object is, in Hamann’s metaphor, akin to passing acquaintance for the purposes of bodily

410

SKEPTICISM

pleasure. Both signify greed at the expense of the other—a lack of perception, sensitivity, commitment. If there is such a thing as epistemological promiscuity for Hamann, there is also epistemological rape. Hamann describes Socrates as “indifferent” to “that which is called truth” (76:5). In personal letters at the time, Hamann portrays himself as similarly indifferent to “no other interest than the interest in knowing the truth (do not be frightened by my blunt confession)—of this hyperbolic interest I have neither a concept nor a feeling” (Letters 3, 7:12–14).3 Contemporary letters to Kant make clear that more damage can be done with truth than with falsehoods, depending on the use made with them (Letters 1, 377:10–15); and in a striking image: Truth would not let herself be approached too closely by highwaymen, she wore one garment on top of another so that one doubted being able to find her body. How frightening if they had their way and saw that frightful ghost, the truth, before them. (Letters 1, 381:8–11) Hamann’s provocative rejection of lusting for the truth should be seen of a piece with his rejection of Athenian promiscuous knowing; as knowledge is found in faithful commitment, so too truth is like a woman protecting herself from the violation and domination of a predator. In contrast, Hamann’s ideal “heroic spirit of the philosopher” possesses “thirsting ambition for truth and virtue, and a fury to conquer all lies and vice.”4 The task of knowledge confronts us, then, with the ethical choice of being a knight questing for knowledge as one in service of the truth, the fair lady he serves, while rejecting lies and vice—or being the highwayman or seducer who snatches and robs. Thus, the activity of knowing is not the acquisition and holding of information, but being in a relationship to reality and to truth. Not only can we not dominate the object of knowledge, we cannot even know our own knowing: “As our skeleton is concealed, because we are made in secret, because we are built below in the earth, how much more so are our concepts made in secret, and can be seen as the limbs of our understanding” (66:10–13). More importantly, knowledge, ignorance, and skepticism are all ultimately ethical matters to Hamann. The person closest to the truth is the one who displays fidelity, commitment, and humility—and renounces the power and pride of knowledge in favor of something else: the humbling of self-knowledge and being known. The Delphic Oracle commanded those who entered the temple to “Know Thyself.” It also, when asked who was the wisest of all, commended Sophocles and Euripides but proclaimed Socrates as the rightful bearer of this title. Hamann runs these themes together with Socrates’s frequent claim to ignorance: Sophocles and Euripides would not have become such great models for the stage without the art of dissecting the human heart. Socrates, however, surpassed them both in wisdom, because he had progressed further in self-knowledge than they, and knew that he knew nothing. (71:7–11) With this move, Hamann repositions the Enlightenment debate: what is, or should be, the real content of knowledge, the mark of wisdom? If his Enlightenment contemporaries

JOHANN GEORG HAMANN

411

prize the Greeks as much as they claim to, they ought to agree: the sign of wisdom is neither omniscience nor sophistry, but is above all found in self-knowledge. In “Socratic Memorabilia,” Hamann goes on to make what might seem an extreme declaration of the impossibility of knowledge; that is, our inability to “know” the most self-evident, experiential facts: “Our own being and the existence of all things outside us must be believed and can be made out in no other way” (73:21–22). All knowledge, whether of the unknowable Transcendent or of our own mortality (as Socrates demonstrated in a syllogism), thus rests on the same ground; not reason, but the relationship with the known that is Hume’s “belief”—or faith (the same word in German: Glaube).5 It is widely recognized that Hamann makes strategic use of Hume’s skeptical critique as an attack on reason. At the same time, Hamann has also been portrayed as a fideist. To conceive of Hamann as either a Humean skeptic or a pious fideist, however, is a simplistic misunderstanding of a complex and subtle thinker. Fundamentally, he does not oppose believing and knowing but sees them as inextricably related in our epistemological affairs, as is clear from this letter written late in his life: It is pure idealism to separate believing and feeling from thinking. Companionship is the true principle of reason and language, by which our sensations and representations are modified. This and that philosophy always separates things which by no means can be divided. Things without relationships, relations without things. There are no absolute creatures, as little as there is absolute certainty. . . If we believe our sensations, our representations, then perhaps all divisions cease. We cannot dispense with these witnesses for ourselves, but can refute no one with their agreement. (Letters 7, 174:12–18, 22–24) Recognizing the epistemological role played by belief subverts the demand for absolute certainty that triggers the Enlightenment slide into skepticism. Our senses, our existence, and the existence of all around us rest on a relationship of faith and trust. Paradoxically, this portrait of knowledge as consisting in a relationship to reality and grounded ultimately in faith or belief enables his cynicism about Enlightenment claims to knowledge, but also paves the way for his ultimate rejection of skepticism. Either way, a methodological doubt of the senses or a sophisticated philosophical position collapsing into solipsism is undermined. Hamann’s discussion of Socratic ignorance reaches its climax with a Pauline quote from I Corinthians 8, which he proclaims as the “venerable seal” and the “key to Socrates’s testimony to his own ignorance”: “If anyone thinks he knows something, he knows nothing as he should know it. But if someone loves God, he will be known by him—as Socrates was known by Apollo [the Delphic Oracle] to be a wise man” (74:20–27). This unites the two themes of Socratic ignorance and the relational basis for knowledge: to know oneself to be ignorant but a lover of God is to be known by God. Our natural wisdom will decay; but from this “death,” this “nothingness” of humble, self-knowing ignorance, “life and being sprout forth newly-created in a higher knowledge” (ibid.). Hamannian skepsis, in fact, gives way to an extraordinary optimism about knowledge. What can be known by the humble knight of philosophy is far greater than what can be known by reason: deep self-knowledge, and in so doing, knowing

412

SKEPTICISM

oneself to be in love with God, and thus to know God himself in relationship: “a truth which (lies) concealed,” “a secret wisdom.” All other forms of “knowledge” Hamann derides as “labyrinths of learned sophists” (77:6–8); and of these Socrates can disavow all acquaintance, while being the wisest of all: Thus, as all our powers of knowledge have self-knowledge as their object, so too all our inclinations and desires have self-love. The first is our wisdom, the latter our virtue. As long as it is not possible to know oneself, it remains impossible to love oneself. Therefore only the truth can set us free. . . . (from “Fragments,” Writings 1, 300:17–22)

3  REASON’S MISUNDERSTANDING Hamann then is not to be considered a skeptic regarding the possibility of knowledge—only a skeptic regarding an incorrect conception of it. One could still consider him critical, in the context of the Enlightenment, of some conceptions of reason. Yet despite some interpreters’ reading of him, he clearly was not a mere “irrationalist”; for one thing, he saw that position as ultimately self-refuting: “All forms of irrationalism presuppose the existence of reason and its misuse” (Writings 3, 191:21–27). Certainly there are passages where he sought to articulate a positive function for reasoning in relation to other phenomena: God, nature and reason have as intimate a relation to one another as light, the eye, and all that the former reveals to the latter, or like the centre, radius and periphery of any given circle, or like author, book and reader. (Letters 5, Nr. 784, 272:14ff.) Hamann subjected the Enlightenment concept to a more careful deconstruction; no mere “for or against reason,” but a more searching inquiry into the way the concept was characterized and what claims were made on its behalf. “For what is celebrated Reason with its universality, infallibility, unsurpassability, certainty and evidence? An Ens rationis, an idol, to whom the screeching superstition of irrationality ascribes divine attributes” (from “Konxompax,” Writings 3, 225:3–6). As a human activity, inseparable as he maintained from passion, language, experience, indeed from revelation, it was subject to human fallibility; his rejection was of the infallibility ascribed to it by the Enlightenment, as well as injecting a more modern, indeed postmodern insight: refuting the “universal healthy reason” that failed to take into account the role that history, culture, language, and lived experience all play in shaping and conditioning human cognition. “People talk about Reason as if it were a real being, and the good Lord as if the same were nothing but a concept” (Letters 7, 26:34–35). Reason for Hamann is not a thing, at the end of the day; it is an activity, subject to the same conditions that affect all our other undertakings. As he says in a letter to Jacobi: “Our reason must wait and hope—and desire to serve nature, not legislate it” (Letters 5, Nr. 782, 265:30). He adds: With me it is not so much the question: what is reason? but far more: what is language? and this I suppose to be the ground of all paralogisms and antinomies of

JOHANN GEORG HAMANN

413

which the former is accused. Hence, it happens that one takes words for concepts, and concepts for the things themselves. In words and concepts no evidence is possible, which is ascribed purely to things and states of affairs. (Letters 5, Nr. 782, 264:34–265:1) Hamann’s skepticism of overblown Reason, the knowledge acquired by it, and the philosophy based on them are best seen in his unpublished deconstruction of Kant’s first Critique: “Metacritique of the Purism of Reason.” Here Hamann accuses Kant (in his Critique of Pure Reason) of conducting a “threefold purification of philosophy”: purifying philosophy from tradition, experience, and finally from language itself. All three purifications are highly undesirable in Hamann’s view; and he alleges that, in so doing, reason becomes not merely the object, source, or mode of knowledge (as Kant discusses), but in fact “is the foundation of all objects, sources and kinds of knowledge; is itself none of the three.” This, however, subverts the role of experience and the senses being the ground of all knowledge in an integrated and holistic way. Once you have purged tradition, that is, human communities over history, from philosophy, and secondly have maintained that knowledge without experience is in some sense possible, you have implicitly declared that reason can function without language, “whose only credentials are tradition and use” (“Metacritique of the Purism of Reason,” Writings 3, 283:22). The first two purifications entail the third.6 Of these three purifications, the most intolerable is the “purification” of philosophy from language; for “Not only the entire ability to think rests on language . . . but language is also the crux of the misunderstanding of reason with itself” (“Metacritique of the Purism of Reason,” Writings 3, 287:7–9). Language and reason are two moments in the same activity of human knowing. This insistence on the integration of reason and language took root in his early writings: “Without language, we would have no reason; without reason no religion, and without these three essential components of our nature, neither spirit nor the bond of society” (“Two Mites on the Latest German Literature,” Writings 3, 231:10–12). This insight persisted, and deepened, through to his last personal letters. As he explained to his friend, the philosopher Jacobi, Hamann thought of reason much as St. Paul thought of the Law and its justification: as something that can give knowledge of error, but not the way to truth and life. He had eschewed investigation into reason in favor of the inquiry into language: “Without word, no reason—no world. Here is the source of creation and providence” (Letters 5, Nr. 721, 95:13–22). Similarly, then, to his view on epistemology, Hamann should not be regarded as a wholesale skeptic rejecting reason. Once again, he is merely in search of a more accurate portrayal of the role it plays in our human experience: If only I was as eloquent as Demosthenes, I would have to do no more than repeat a single word three times. Reason is language—Logos; I gnaw on this marrowbone and will gnaw myself to death over it. It is still always dark over these depths for me: I am still always awaiting an apocalyptic angel with a key to this abyss. (Letters 5, Nr. 753, 177:16–21)

414

SKEPTICISM

4  REVELATIONS AND TRADITIONS In another letter, he points out: “Our knowledge is piecemeal—no dogmatist is in a position to feel this great truth, if he is to play his role and play it well; and through a vicious circle of pure reason skepsis itself becomes dogma” (Letters 5, Nr. 833). For Hamann, belief and knowledge, indeed knowledge and skepticism, are not divided by hard boundaries. Belief and knowledge both rest on a foundation of trust; and with the rejection of absolute certainty for knowledge under any circumstances, the threat that skepticism about our epistemological powers poses is reduced: Belief needs reason just as much as the latter needs the former. Philosophy is of idealism and realism: as our nature is composed of body and soul. Qui bene distinguit, optime definire potest—. . . Only scholastic reason divides itself into idealism and realism. Correct and authentic reason knows nothing of this imagined difference, which is not grounded in the nature of things, and contradicts their unity, which lies at the foundation of all our concepts, or at least, should do so. Every philosophy consists of certain and uncertain knowledge, of idealism and realism, of sensuousness and deductions. Why should only the uncertain be called belief? What then are—rational grounds? Knowledge without rational grounds is as little possible as sensus sine intellectu. . . . Complex beings are not capable of simple emotion, still less simple knowledge. Feeling can as little be separated from reason in human nature as can reason from sensuousness. . . . Emotion must be delimited by rational grounds. Knowledge from belief is fundamentally identical to: Nil in intellectu. (Letters 7, Nr. 1060, 165:7–166:3, 10–11)7 Both idealism and realism share an undesirable picture of the human being standing over against the world, in Hamann’s view; whereas for him the knower and the known share an underlying unity. Qui bene distinguit: only one who wisely makes such distinctions can rightly define body and soul, knowledge and world. Hamann’s positive account of knowledge ultimately rests on his anthropology: a holistic epistemology is the activity of diverse yet integrated human beings, a union of the senses and understanding, reasoning and passions, Baroque gentility and Homerian lust for vengeance.8 His lament was that philosophers have always given truth a bill of divorce, separating what nature intended to be joined together, such as thinking and feeling (cf. Writings 3, 40:3f.): The understanding and experience are fundamentally the same thing: as the understanding and application are. From where do we get this distinction into opposites? Does the entire mystery of our reason, its antitheses and analogies, rest on nothing but a poetic license to separate what Nature has joined and to couple what she wanted to distinguish, to mutilate and then mend again? (Letters 6, Nr. 1011, 534:14–20) Instead, a little epistemological metaphor makes clear his preferred, holistic, and multivalent picture of human knowing: The human being therefore is not only a living field but also the son of the field, and not only field and seed (according to the system of the materialists and

JOHANN GEORG HAMANN

415

idealists) but also the king of the field, to cultivate good seed and enemy weed on his field; for what is a field without seed and a ruler without land and revenue? These three in us therefore are one. (“Philological Ideas and Doubts,” Writings 3, 40:14–20) In knowing, we passively receive, like a field receiving seed (a “materialist” epistemology); we actively generate and germinate ideas and knowledge (as the “idealists” imagine); we are the product and the result (son) of our own epistemological activity; but knowledge is also a question of wise governance (rule) with ethical implications (good seed and enemy weed).9 With this we are charged. Meanwhile, the “stamen and menstruation” of our cognition (what we germinate and what in turn flows from us) “are therefore in the truest sense revelations and traditions which we take for our own property, transform with our juices and powers and thereby fulfill our commission . . . as a political animal, partly to reveal and partly to transmit” (“Philological Ideas and Doubts,” Writings 3, 39:7–18). Hamann’s epistemology is also social, even political. Even if we come into the world as a tabula rasa—or as he prefers, “an empty wineskin”—this lack makes us “all the more able to enjoy nature through experiences and to enjoy community with [our] race through traditions. Our reason arises, at the very least, from this twofold lesson of sensuous revelations and human testimonies” (“Philological Ideas and Doubts,” Writings 3, 39:23–28). From his earliest journals, he insisted that knowledge rests on self-knowledge; and self-knowledge is ironically dependent on another: In order to make easier the knowledge of our self, my own self is visible as in a mirror in every neighbor. As the image of my face is reflected in water, so my self is reflected in every neighbor. That this self may be as dear to me as my own, Providence has sought to unite as many advantages and amenities in human society as possible. God and my neighbor are therefore a part of my selfknowledge, my self-love. (Writings 1, 302:16–23) Human knowledge begins and ends with another. “Self-knowledge begins with the neighbor, the mirror, and just the same with true self-love; that goes from the mirror to the matter” (Letters 6, 281:16–17). To know oneself, in other words, is to know oneself as existing only within a relationship. In sum, as neither a skeptic nor a rationalist, the possibilities of knowledge are both more restricted and more generous for Hamann than for many of his contemporaries. By “pure” reason, by inference and ratiocination, our knowledge is far less certain and far less ample than for other Enlightenment thinkers. But our ignorance, or lack, is the gateway for something far richer and deeper than epistemological certitude. It is the sign, and the opportunity, of our openness and need for each other. Indeed, for Hamann, knowledge ultimately opens out to the transcendent with perfect confidence; the cheerful confidence of a child certain of being known and loved. Ourselves, human history, the whole of creation is “mythology,” a “book” we read by an author who addresses us. Human knowing is

416

SKEPTICISM

thus located in the context of a fundamental relationship with the divine, revealing to us the highest knowledge, which is being known: Not Cogito; ergo sum, but vice versa, and more Hebraic: est; ergo cogito, and with the inversion of such a simple principle perhaps the whole system might receive another language and direction. (Letters 5, Nr. 840, 448:26–28)

NOTES 1. All translations of Hamann are mine. References are to Josef Nadler’s edition of his Schriften (cited hereafter as Writings) (Hamann 1949–1957) and in English translation by Gwen Griffith-Dickson (1995). The latter have been laid out such that the same numbered reference refers both to the English translation in Dickson and to the original in Nadler’s edition. Unless otherwise stated, quotations in this first section are from Hamann’s essay “Socratic Memorabilia,” Writings 2, and appear with page and line number only. 2. I argue that Hamann intends to translate Hume’s “feeling”, that which is foundational to reason and philosophy (Dickson 1995: 47). 3. The standard edition of his letters is Henkel (1955–1975). They are cited here as Letters, volume, page: line. 4. “A little vision and superstition here would not merely merit indulgence, but rather something of this leaven is necessary to start off the soul’s fermentation towards a philosophical heroism. A thirsting ambition for truth and virtue, and a fury to conquer all lies and vice, which precisely are not recognized as such, nor wish to be; in this consists the heroic spirit of a philosopher” (63:30–35). 5. Hamann was arguably the first to identify the tactical potential of Hume’s account of belief for theology. Hamann later writes of himself in a letter to Jacobi: “I was full of Hume when I wrote SM, and p. 49 of my little book refers to this,” and “I studied him before I wrote SM, and am indebted for my doctrine of faith to the same source” (Letters 7, 167:9). 6. For thorough discussions of these points, see Dickson (1995) and Piske (1989), who are in broad agreement. In the former, I argue: “The experience excepted by a workable definition of ‘a priori’ is precisely the experience in question, and precisely the experience which subverts the authority, autonomy, and universality of the Enlightenment theory of reason” (1995: 306). And also: “for reason to be as universal and as historically unconditioned as this strand of the Enlightenment maintains, it must be free of any language which is the product and embodiment of its time and place. . . If reason does always involve language while being purified of experience and tradition, and therefore able to exist as universal and autonomous, language must not be a matter of experience and tradition and sociality, but must lie within the structures of the mind, indeed, share its structure, its syntax or grammar, with the structures of judgement. . . . The possibility of discovering the true structure or form of a phenomenon from self-reflection, apperception, the analysis of our own thought, implies—or possibly requires, if one holds that thought is impossible without language—the possibility of doing the same for or with language. A priori thought,

JOHANN GEORG HAMANN

417

arising from the structuration of the mind, requires either an a priori language arising from the structure of the mind, or else no language at all” (1995: 304–305). 7. “Sensuousness” translates Sinnlichkeit (Kant’s “sensibility”). 8. In an ironic rebuttal of Rococo aesthetics of art as the imitation of beautiful nature, Hamann quipped: “A lust for vengeance (Rachsucht) is the beautiful nature Homer imitated” (Letters 2, 157:12). 9. “Good seed and enemy weed” is a reference to one of the parables of the sower (Mt. 13:24-30).

REFERENCES Alexander, W. M. 1966. Johann Georg Hamann. Philosophy and Faith. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Bayer, Oswald. 2012. A Contemporary in Dissent. Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. Bayer, Oswald and Bernd Weißenborn. 1993. Johann Georg Hamann. Londoner Schriften. Munich: C. H. Beck. Beech, Timothy. 2010. Hamann’s Prophetic Mission. A Genetic Study of Three Late Works against the Enlightenment. London: Maney Publ. Beiser, Frederick C. 1987. The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Berlin, Isaiah. 1993. The Magus of the North: J. G. Hamann and the Origins of Modern Irrationalism, edited by Henry Hardy. London: John Murray. Betz, John R. 2009. After Enlightenment: The Post-Secular Vision of J. G. Hamann. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. Brose, Thomas. 2004. Johann Georg Hamann und David Hume. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang. Dahlstrom, Daniel. 2000. “The Aesthetic Holism of Hamann, Herder and Schiller.” In K. Ameriks (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism, 76–94. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dickson, Gwen Griffith. 1995. Johann Georg Hamann’s Relational Metacriticism. Berlin: de Gruyter. Dunning, Stephen. 1979. The Tongues of Men: Hegel and Hamann on Religious Language and History. Missoula: Scholars Press. Hamann, Johann Georg. 1949–1957. Sämtliche Werken, 6 volumes, edited by Josef Nadler. Vienna: Verlag Herder. Hamann, Johann Georg. 1955–1975. Briefwechsel, 8 volumes, edited by W. Ziesemer and A. Henkel (from volume 4 on, edited by Henkel alone). Wiesbaden and Frankfurt: Insel Verlag. Haynes, Kenneth. 2007. Hamann: Writings on Philosophy and Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hegel, G.W. F. 2008. Hegel on Hamann, edited and translated by Lisa Marie Anderson. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

418

SKEPTICISM

Jørgensen, Sven-Aage. 1962. Johann Georg Hamann: Fünf Hirtenbriefe das Schuldrama betreffend. Einführung und Kommentar. Copenhagen: Ejnar Munksgaard. Jørgensen, Sven-Aage. 1968. Sokratische Denkwürdigkeiten. Aesthetica in Nuce. Mit einem Kommentar. Stuttgart: Reclam. Leibrecht, Walter. 1966. God and Man in the Thought of Hamann, translated by James H. Stam and Martin H. Bertram. Philadelphia: Fortress Press. Lowrie, Walter. 1950. Johann Georg Hamann, an Existentialist. Princeton: Princeton Theological Seminary. Nisbet, H. B. (ed.) 1985. German Aesthetic and Literary Criticism: Winckelmann, Lessing, Hamann, Herder, Schiller, Goethe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. O’Flaherty, James C. 1952. Unity and Language: A Study in the Philosophy of Johann Georg Hamann. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. O’Flaherty, James C. 1967. Hamann’s Socratic Memorabilia: A Translation and a Commentary. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press. O’Flaherty, James C. 1979. Johann Georg Hamann. Boston: Twayne Publishers. O’Flaherty, James C. 1988. The Quarrel of Reason with Itself: Essays on Hamann, Michaelis, Lessing, Nietzsche. Columbia: Camden House. Piske, Irmgard. 1989. Offenbarung, Sprache, Vernunft. Zur Auseinandersetzung Hamanns mit Kant. Frankfurt am Main: Regensburg. Schmidt, James (ed.). 1996. What is Enlightenment? Eighteenth-Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Smith, Ronald Gregor. 1960. J.G. Hamann, 1730–1788. A Study in Christian Existence. With Selections from his Writings. London: Collins. Sparling, Robert. 2008. Johann Georg Hamann and the Enlightenment Project. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

CHAPTER THIRTY

Kant and External World Skepticism GEORGES DICKER

1 INTRODUCTION There are many varieties of philosophical skepticism—skepticism about induction, about other minds, about morality, and more. But the brand of skepticism that has most preoccupied philosophers, at least since the time of Descartes, is skepticism about the external world. Ever since Descartes suggested that, for all we can tell from our perceptual experiences, all the things we seem to perceive by our senses may be parts of an all-encompassing hallucination foisted on us by God or by some powerful evil deceiver, philosophers have wrestled with the question of how we can know that we live in a world populated by objects that exist in space and time independently of our minds. Among these philosophers, Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) occupies an important but ambiguous position. The ambiguity stems mainly from his notorious doctrine of transcendental idealism, which, if taken literally, implies that space and time are nothing but forms imposed by our minds on what we perceive, and thus that at least some very basic properties of so-called physical objects have no reality apart from our minds. But even if Kant’s doctrine is interpreted less literally (for example as holding, à la Peter Strawson, that we cannot make intelligible to ourselves the notion of an experience that is not in time and space)—as I would urge it should be if we seek to find some truth in it—problems of interpretation remain. Perhaps chief among these is how to interpret the crucial section of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (hereafter CPR) commonly referred to as “the Transcendental Deduction.”1 Not only did Kant completely rewrite this section for the Second Edition of CPR, but neither version makes it clear whether Kant’s argument is “regressive” or “progressive.” According to the regressive interpretation, the argument begins by assuming that we have knowledge of the external world and seeks to explain how this knowledge is possible. According to the progressive interpretation, the argument attempts to prove that we have knowledge of the external world, by deriving that knowledge from some uncontroversial premise about purely subjective experience. Aside from the vexed matter of textually establishing either of these interpretations, both face

420

SKEPTICISM

difficulties. The regressive interpretation seems to rob the argument of any power to defeat an external world skeptic; for if the argument starts by assuming that we have knowledge of the external world, then obviously it cannot prove that we have such knowledge. The progressive interpretation faces the very difficult task of constructing a convincing argument, from some slender premise about purely subjective experience, to the weighty conclusion that we know the existence of the physical world.2 There is one section of CPR, however, where at least the question of whether Kant is arguing progressively or regressively is easy to answer, and where his argument is detachable from (some would even say incompatible with) transcendental idealism. This is the famous section entitled “Refutation of Idealism,” which Kant added to the Second Edition. In announcing this new section, Kant famously declared that it . . . remains a scandal of philosophy and universal human reason that the existence of things outside us . . . should have to be assumed merely on faith, and that if it occurs to anyone to doubt it, we should be unable to answer him with a satisfactory proof. (B xxxix note)3 Kant then proceeded, clearly taking on the progressive task, to argue that “the mere, but empirically determined, consciousness of my own existence proves the existence of objects in space outside me” (B 275–276). This chapter expounds and defends Kant’s argument. It draws on my previous work, which is strongly influenced by the writings of Paul Guyer and Jonathan Bennett.4

2  KANT’S ANSWER TO SKEPTICISM IN THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON The key passage of the Refutation in CPR is this: I am conscious of my existence as determined in time. All time-determination presupposes something persistent in perception. But this persisting element cannot be an intuition in me. For all the determining grounds of my existence that can be encountered in me are representations; and as such they themselves need something persisting distinct from them, in relation to which their change, and thus my existence in the time in which they change, can be determined. Thus the perception of this persistent thing is possible only through a thing outside me and not through the mere representation of a thing outside me. Consequently, the determination of my existence in time is possible only by means of the existence of actual things that I perceive outside myself. (B 275)5 The opening premise that “I am conscious of my existence as determined in time” requires explanation. For Kant agrees with David Hume that it is impossible to find a persisting self in introspection; as Kant says: “inner sense . . . gives no intuition of the soul itself, as an object” (A 22/B 37); “the consciousness of oneself in accordance with the determinations of our state in internal perception is merely empirical, forever variable; it can provide no standing or abiding self in this stream of inner appearances” (A 107). I shall take Kant’s premise to mean, as suggested by the third

KANT AND EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

421

sentence of his proof, that I am aware that I have representations or experiences that occur in a specific temporal order. For these experiences are the sole “determining grounds of my existence”; it is precisely and only by being aware of them, as they succeed each other in time, that I can be said to be aware of my own existence and its continuation in time. In line with this interpretation of Kant’s premise, we can formulate his proof this way: (1) I am aware that I have experiences that occur in a specific temporal order. (2) I can be aware of having experiences that occur in a specific temporal order only if there is some persisting element by reference to which I can determine their temporal order. (3) No conscious state of my own can serve as this persisting frame of reference. (4) Time itself cannot serve as this persisting frame of reference. (5) If (2) and (3) and (4), then I can be aware of having experiences that occur in a specific temporal order only if I perceive persisting objects in space outside me by reference to which I can determine the temporal order of my experiences. Therefore, (6) I perceive persisting objects in space outside me by reference to which I can determine the temporal order of my experiences. Kant does not state premise (4), but the argument requires it in order to rule out the possibility that this premise rejects, and it is a premise that he insists upon, on the grounds that “time itself cannot be perceived” (A 166/B 207, A 177/B 219, A 182/B 225, A 183/B 226, A 211/B 257). This argument, however, is open to a serious objection. The temporal order of experiences mentioned in (2) is simply the order in which I have those experiences or “representations.” So why should I need any “persisting element” or enduring thing in order to know what this order is? As Guyer puts this objection: It remains unclear why anything more than mere acquaintance with representations which in fact succeed one another in otherwise uninterpreted experience, or anything other than the mere occurrence of such representations, should be necessary for one to judge that there has been such a succession. . . . Why is the successiveness of consciousness insufficient for its own recognition? (Guyer 1987: 285–286, 298) Nevertheless, Guyer thinks that we can extract a successful version of the argument from the following “Reflexion,” written in 1790, after the appearance of the Second Edition of CPR (1787), and contained in Kant’s notes, the Handschriftlicher Nachlass: Since the imagination (and its product) is itself only an object of inner sense, the empirical consciousness (apprehensio) of this condition can contain only succession. But this itself cannot be represented except by means of something which endures, with which that which is successive is simultaneous. This enduring thing, with which that which is successive is simultaneous . . . cannot in turn be a

422

SKEPTICISM

representation of the mere imagination but must be a representation of sense, for otherwise that which lasts would not be in the sensibility at all. (Kant 1902: vol. 18, Reflection 6313, p. 614, as translated by and quoted in Guyer 1987: 305) Guyer explains the basic idea of this passage as follows: The starting point of this argument is clearly that the mere occurrence of a succession of representations is not sufficient for the representation or recognition of this succession. But Kant’s further claim that such recognition can be grounded “only on something which endures, with which that which is successive is simultaneous” can only mean that successive representations in one’s own experience can be judged to be successive only if they are judged to be severally simultaneous with the severally successive states of some enduring object. (Guyer 1987: 306) In what follows, I reconstruct and defend this version of Kant’s argument.

3  KANT’S ANSWER TO SKEPTICISM AFTER THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON We each have what might be called an “experiential history”—a series of subjective experiences or conscious states that stretches back in time. Now ask yourself: what enables you, right now, to set many of your past experiences in their proper time order, thereby giving you knowledge of your own past? After all, the only thing you have to go on right now is your present memory of the experiences, which have come and gone. Furthermore, recollections of your earlier experiences, considered purely as subjective conscious states or “seemings,” need not be fainter or come with a greater feeling of “pastness” than recollections of your more recent ones; a fortiori the recollected members of a series of increasingly temporally remote experiences need not be increasingly fainter or possess a greater sense of pastness. What then enables you to know the order in which they occurred? Kant’s answer, according to Guyer, is that you correlate the remembered experiences with successive states of an enduring reality that exists independently of the experiences—you take them to be “severally simultaneous with the severally successive states of some enduring object.” Here is a schematic way of putting the basic argument. Suppose that you have had two successive experiences, E1 that occurred at time t1, and E2 that occurred at the later time t2. Kant takes it as a datum that at a still later time, t3, you can know that you had E1 before E2. But he sees that there is a question about how you know this. For at t3, both E1 and E2 have come and gone, so that you cannot then tell by perception whether they occurred in the order E1, E2 or in the order E2, E1. In other words, your present state at t3—call it E3—does not in itself contain E1 or E2, but only the memories of E1 and of E2. But these memories could represent these states as having occurred in either order. What then prevents you from now thinking that they occurred in the order E2, E1 rather than E1, E2? Only that you correlate E1 with an objective state of affairs S1 that occurred before another objective state of affairs S2.

KANT AND EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

423

There is a possible misunderstanding that can obscure the force of this argument. It may seem that the argument assumes that knowledge of one’s own past experiences rests on memory, but that one has some kind of direct access, unmediated by memory, to past objective states of affairs. But since any knowledge of the past must rest on memory, the argument may seem to be based on a false assumption. But this is not so. Rather, the argument’s core idea is that one set of memories, namely, memories of the order of one’s subjective experiences, rests on another set of memories, namely, memories of the order of successive states of an enduring reality. This idea should not be confused with saying that any knowledge of time orders based on memory depends on some other knowledge of time orders also based on memory. Such a view would lead to an infinite regress, and it would entail that no knowledge of time orders based on memory is possible.6 Rather, the idea is that knowledge by memory of the time order of one’s subjective experiences depends on knowledge by memory of the time order of states of an enduring reality. The reasons for this dependence are complex; they include that the physical world changes in regular, “clocklike” ways, and that objects in it can be re-encountered, regardless of these changes, after intervals of time during which they were not perceived.7 By contrast, subjective experiences are fleeting and transitory; once gone they cannot be re-encountered, and even if they had certain clocklike features, the mere having of these features need not be recorded in memory (more about this later). It may be objected, however, that sometimes one can remember the order of one’s experiences “straight off,” with no appeal to an objective world. Indeed, Jonathan Bennett has identified three types of cases in which this seems to be true: (a) If Y occurred so soon after X that one can recall a specious present containing both, then one can simply recall that X preceded Y. If this were not so, one could not simply recall hearing someone say “damn” rather than “mad.” (b) From this it follows that one can simply recall that X preceded Y if one can recall a continuous sequence of happenings starting with X and ending with Y . . . . (c) One may simply recall that X preceded Y by recalling a time when one experienced Y while recalling X. (Bennett 1966: 228–229)8 As Bennett immediately goes on to note, however, These counter-examples to Kant’s thesis cover only a small fragment of all the temporal orderings we wish to establish. If I am asked “Did you clean your shoes before or after you went for a walk?”, I may be able—in the manner of (a)— to recall the moment when I straightened my back from shoe-cleaning, put the brush down and strode off into the street; or (b) to relive the detail of my day from the shoe-cleaning episode through to the walk two hours later; or (c) to recall thinking, while on my walk, that it had been a mistake to clean my shoes before going out in the mud. But it is far more likely that my answer will have to be based on my recollection that I cleaned my shoes while the sun rose and walked as it was setting, or that I heard the one o’clock news while cleaning my shoes and arranged to go for a walk at three o’clock, or something else equally

424

SKEPTICISM

dependent for its relevance on the truth of . . . statements about the objective realm. It would be—to put it mildly—a queer personal history which could be ordered solely in the manner of (a), (b) and (c). (Bennett 1966: 228–29) The argument, nevertheless, should be formulated so as to allow for such relatively rare cases, which I shall call “B-related experiences” (short for “Bennett-related experiences”).9 I offer the following reconstruction: (1′) I can correctly determine the order in time of experiences of mine that are not B-related, that is, that did not (a) occur within a specious present, and that do not (b) belong to a remembered sequence of continuous experiences, or (c) include a recollection of the sequence of all the earlier experiences within each of the later ones. (2′) When I remember two or more past experiences that are not B-related, my recollection of those experiences does not itself reveal the order in which they occurred. (3′) If (2′), then I cannot correctly determine the order of two or more past experiences of mine that are not B-related just by recollecting them. (4′) I cannot correctly determine the order of two or more past experiences of mine that are not B-related just by recollecting them. [from (2′) and (3′)] (5′) If I cannot correctly determine the order of two or more past experiences of mine that are not B-related just by recollecting them, then I can correctly determine their order only if I know that at least some of my experiences are caused by successive objective states of affairs that I perceive. (6′) I can correctly determine the order of two or more past experiences of mine that are not B-related only if I know that at least some of my experiences are caused by successive objective states of affairs that I perceive. [from (4′) and (5′)] (7′) I know that at least some of my experiences are caused by successive objective states of affairs that I perceive. [from (1′) and (6′)] The term “objective” introduced in (5′) begs no questions, since (5′) spells out a necessary condition for correctly determining the order of my past experiences, not just for assigning some order or other to them. Note, however, that (1′) does not mean that for any two experiences of mine that are not B-related, I can correctly determine their order; the premise allows that there may be cases in which I am unable to make this determination. Even so, a memory skeptic would of course object to (1′); I address this point immediately below.

4  OBJECTIONS AND REPLIES Critics have raised several interesting and challenging objections to the above reconstruction, and I have offered replies.10 There is not enough space to review this debate here, so I shall consider only two possible objections.11

KANT AND EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

425

The first is that a philosopher who adopts a radically skeptical stance, as Descartes provisionally does in his First Meditation, would not grant the argument’s first premise, for she would doubt the reliability of memory. Now it is true that Kant intended his Refutation of Idealism to refute what he called “the problematic idealism of Descartes” (B 274). It is also true that in one sentence of his Second Meditation, Descartes supposes that perhaps his memory always deceives him. Nevertheless, Descartes does not seriously doubt memory. Indeed, the reliability of memory must be assumed in order for his most severe doubt even to arise, since that doubt concerns whether conclusions that are correctly remembered to have been properly deduced from self-evident premises are true (see Frankfurt 1970: 160–62). In any case, Kant’s argument is not intended to refute a memory skeptic, any more than Descartes’s attempted proof of the physical world in his Sixth Meditation. The doubt that Kant is out to conquer in the Refutation of Idealism is not about the reliability of memory; it is a doubt arising from the contrast between the inner and the outer, appearance and reality, the subjective and the objective. This is the only kind of doubt that Kant calls “problematic idealism,” and the sole purpose of his argument is to refute it, by showing that “even our inner experience, undoubted by Descartes, is possible only under the presupposition of outer experience” (B 275). The second possible objection, which targets premise (5) of the argument, is that I could determine the order of my non-B-related experiences by reference to certain “clocklike” features of my purely inner experience. Katherine Gasdaglis puts it well: Why . . . couldn’t there be some persisting “clocklike” feature of our conscious experience that could be used to keep track of the temporal order of our states? Consider a variation on Strawson’s famous example of the “master sound.” Imagine a person who, from birth until death, hears a persistent tone that gradually increases in pitch throughout her life. She could simply refer to the sound’s pitch, a purely subjective feature of her experience, as a temporal marker of her representational states. She could recall, for example, that she saw the movie at a B and parked her car at an F. The possibility of clocklike features constitutes a counter-example to Dicker’s premise (5). His only response is that, luckily, there are in fact no such features. (Gasdaglis 2013: 25–26) In a similar vein, Andrew Chignell writes: Suppose there is a digital clock in the corner of your visual field (it remains when you close your eyes), or a “voice in your head” audibly counting off seconds throughout your conscious life . . . . The fact that, by hypothesis, these “clocklike” features of your experience count off the seconds in proper order is all that is required for them to serve as the measure for your other remembered states . . . . No external objects are necessary. (Chignell 2011: 185) Let us consider these two scenarios in turn. Even from a common sense, “empirical” point of view, the rising tone scenario is too fantastic to pose a real difficulty. Human

426

SKEPTICISM

lives normally last for years, and a tone that perceptibly rises in pitch from birth to death of a human being, without ever “reversing” course, is quite unimaginable. Further, in order for such a rising tone to serve as a temporal marker of all of one’s past experiences, it would have to be divisible into numberless distinguishable sounds, each of which would have to be remembered as a distinct tone, and in the right order. This is not possible for any human being. There are other difficulties as well. Suppose that at time t, I remember hearing both a high note and a low note: can I tell, solely on the basis of my memory of those tones, which came first? In some cases, the answer is yes. For example, if the high note and the low note are part of a melody that I have been continuously following up to t, then these are B-related experiences, since I remember an entire sequence of sounds rising from the low note to the high one. But suppose that I do not hold in memory the entire sequence of tones between the low note and the high note. Here it is important to notice that the fact that the sequence did in fact rise that way, and that I heard each segment of the sequence as it occurred, does not show that I now remember the entire rising sequence. The hypothesis of a gradually rising sound may encourage one to think that the memory was thus unbroken, but in the case that I am envisaging, which is both logically possible and realistic, the memory is not continuous. When I remember hearing the high note, I still also remember hearing the low note, but I can’t decide whether the tones that separated them, which I heard but perhaps paid scant attention to (maybe I was struggling to suppress a cough at a concert) were gradually rising, or rising and falling irregularly. How then might I know that the high note came after the low note, rather than vice versa? Well, I might know it by remembering that the low note sounded when the cellos began playing and the high note sounded when the violins began playing, and that the cellos made their entrance before the violins— objective facts about a sequence of events that I observed. The key general point here is that the mere fact that my inner experience had clocklike features does not show that these features were registered, recorded, or retained in my memory, and so cannot be appealed to in order to determine the order of the experiences. Rather, this order must be determined by the remembered order of objective events, even if the inner experiences had clocklike features. Consider next Chignell’s scenario. Suppose that there were a digital clock permanently present in the corner of my visual field. Could I order my past experiences by reference to this clock? To be able to do that, two conditions would have to be satisfied. First, the numbers on the digital display must track the passage of time; it must not be the case, for example, that the number 8:00/1/1/2015 (8:00 A.M. on January 1, 2015) appears before the number 8:00/1/1/2014. Second, I must know that the numbers on the display track the passage of time. If I have no idea whether the 8:00/1/1/2014 display annexed to a remembered experience X occurred earlier or later in time than the 8:00/1/1/2015 display annexed to a remembered experience Y, then I cannot use those displays to determine the order in which X and Y occurred. The trouble lies with this second condition: absent perceptible external objects whose states I can correlate with the numbers in the display, and given the point that memories of more remote past experiences are not necessarily

KANT AND EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

427

fainter than memories of more recent ones, I have no way of knowing that the order in which the numbers occurred does correspond to the passage of time; my ability to know this is subject to exactly the same difficulty as my knowledge of the order in which any of my other experiences occurred. For example, the number 8:00/1/1/2014, for all I can tell purely on the basis of my memory of the display, may have appeared later than 8:00/1/1/2015. Of course, I know that this reversal would not happen on a real digital clock in good working condition, but that only illustrates the need for an objective reality by reference to which I can order my past experiences. Analogous considerations apply to the voice counting off seconds in my head. It might be replied that I could know that my mental clock tracks time without appeal to external reality, by induction.12 This would work as follows. In cases of B-related experiences, as we have seen, one can determine the order of one’s past experiences “straight off.” Suppose then that during stretches of B-related experiences, my mental clock manifestly tracks time correctly: it always displays a later time after an earlier one. Then, it might be said, I can infer inductively that it also tracks time correctly when my experiences are not B-related. My reply is that such an inductive inference could at best show that the clock always tracks time correctly when our experiences are B-related. Since we necessarily can never observe it tracking time when two experiences are separated by not being B-related, we do not have a sample of similar cases from which we can infer inductively that the clock tracks time during cases of the same kind. Perhaps there is a psychological mechanism such that the clock “engages,” so to speak, only for experiences that are B-related; for other remembered experiences it just “runs freely.” Perhaps there is a constant conjunction between (a) only the clock’s readings and the awareness of temporal succession but not between (b) those readings and succession in time per se. I do not see by what good inductive argument (b) could be shown to be less probable than (a). The reason why the rising tone and the digital clock scenarios may seem plausible is that the “internality” of the auditory experiences and of the mental clock, combined with the hypotheses of a gradually rising sound and progressively increasing numerical sequence, encourages us of think of the experiences as being B-related. If we had a wholly B-related sequence of internal experiences from birth to death, then presumably we could use it to order our other experiences. But human experience is manifestly not like that. Now although some Kant scholars would disagree, I believe that Kant is concerned to state conditions under which we can order our experiences, given the kind of experience humans actually and unquestionably have. Like other so-called transcendental arguments in Kant’s philosophy, the Refutation of Idealism starts from certain very general though contingent premises about the kind of experience that humans unquestionably have, and argues that such experience is possible only under certain conditions. If all the premises of Kant’s argument had to be necessary truths, then its conclusion that I know that some of my experiences are caused by successive objective states of affairs that I perceive would have to be a necessary truth as well. I see no textual or philosophical reason to saddle Kant with such an implausible view.

428

SKEPTICISM

NOTES 1. In addition to this problem, Kant’s multifaceted approach has given rise to widely divergent interpretations of both the nature of his response to external world skepticism and its importance within his philosophy as a whole. For example, Caranti (2007) argues that while Kant was deeply concerned from the beginning of his career to refute the sort of skepticism evinced in Descartes’s evil-demon scenario, his most sustained and strongest answer to it is not to be found, as will be assumed here, in his “Refutation of Idealism,” but rather in the section of CPR entitled “Fourth Paralogism of Ideality” and, contrary to the view just implied, that it presupposes a robust version of Transcendental Idealism, found in Kant’s account of time and (especially) space in the section entitled “Transcendental Aesthetic.” By contrast, Forster (2008) argues that Kant was only marginally concerned with external world skepticism, and much more deeply interested in developing a chastened metaphysics in the wake of Pyrrhonian skepticism, Humean Skepticism, and his own Antinomies. For some critical discussion of Caranti, see Guyer (2007); for some critical discussion of Forster, see Dicker (2010). 2. I defend a progressive reading of both the first edition and the second edition versions of the Deduction in Dicker (2004: 84–144; 2013: 410–425). 3. In all references to CPR, I use “A” to refer the first edition and “B” to refer to the second edition; thus A 50 would refer to page 50 of A, B 50 to page 50 of B, and A 50/B74 to page 50 of A and page 74 of B. 4. See Dicker (2004: 24–25, 194–211; 2008: 80–108; 2011: 175–183; 2012: 191–195; 2013: 410–431, esp. 425–429). Parts of this chapter include material from these works, especially from Dicker (2008; 2012; 2013). 5. The third and fourth sentences were substituted by Kant, in a footnote at B xxxix, for a single sentence in the original B 275 text of the “Refutation of Idealism” that reads: “This persistent thing, however, cannot be something in me, since my own existence in time can first be determined only through this persistent thing.” 6. James Van Cleve alerted me to this point in correspondence. 7. The need for re-encounterability stems from this: Given that remembered experiences can be ordered only by reference to something with “clocklike” features, this item must be something that has preserved its identity over time. For it must be something, call it X, that has undergone some kind of change or alteration, and by reference to whose successive states we can date or determine the positions in time of the remembered experiences. But if X ceases to exist before it can be re-encountered, so that anything we encounter after encountering X must be an item with a different beginning of existence than X, then it cannot be numerically identical with X, since nothing can have two beginnings of existence. So, the item we then encounter cannot be something that has merely undergone some kind of change or alteration while remaining identical with X, and therefore it cannot serve as something by reference to whose successive states we can determine the positions in time of our remembered experiences (or of anything else). 8. Bennett numbers these possibilities as (1), (2), (3); I have substituted (a), (b), (c) to avoid confusion with the numbering of the steps in the argument.

KANT AND EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

429

9. This label was suggested by Mark Brown in discussion. 10. For example, for a reply to the possible objection that “correlated with,” rather than “caused by,” should be used in (5) and (6), see Dicker (2008: 94–95). 11. For a much fuller discussion of possible objections and replies, see Chignell (2009; 2011) and Dicker (2008; 2011; 2012). 12. Chignell suggested this in conversation.

REFERENCES Bennett, Jonathan. 1966. Kant’s Analytic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Caranti, Luigi. 2007. Kant and the Scandal of Philosophy: The Kantian Critique of Cartesian Scepticism. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Chignell, Andrew. 2009. “Causal Refutations of Idealism,” Philosophical Quarterly 60: 487–507. Chignell, Andrew. 2011. “Causal Refutations of Idealism Revisited,” Philosophical Quarterly 61: 184–186. Dicker, Georges. 2004. Kant’s Theory of Knowledge: An Analytical Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press. Dicker, Georges. 2008. “Kant’s Refutation of Idealism,” Noûs 47: 80–108. Dicker, Georges. 2010. “Review of Kant and Skepticism, by Michael Forster,” European Journal of Philosophy 18: 609–615. Dicker, Georges. 2011. “Kant’s Refutation of Idealism: A Reply to Chignell,” Philosophical Quarterly 61: 175–183. Dicker, Georges. 2012. “Kant’s Refutation of Idealism: Once More Unto the Breach,” Kantian Review 17: 191–195. Dicker, Georges. 2013. “Transcendental Arguments and Temporal Experience.” In A. Bardon and H. Dyke (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Time, 410–431. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. Frankfurt, Harry. 1970. Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen: The Defense of Reason in Descartes’s Meditations. New York: Bobbs-Merrill. Gasdaglis, Katherine. 2013. “The Refutation of Idealism and the Priority of Perception.” Unpublished manuscript. Guyer, Paul. 1987. Kant and the Claims of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Guyer, Paul. 2008. “Kant and the Scandal of Philosophy: The Kantian Critique of Cartesian Scepticism,” Philosophy and Social Criticism 34: 825–836. Kant, Immanuel. 1997. Critique of Pure Reason, translated and edited by P. Guyer and A. W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kant, Immanuel. 1902. Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften, 29 vols. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

CHAPTER THIRTY-ONE

Hegel: Philosophy as a Kind of Skepticism DIETMAR H. HEIDEMANN

1 INTRODUCTION Hegel is not a skeptic, although he believes philosophy to be a kind of skepticism. This view looks paradoxical, but it isn’t. Hegel, as many philosophers, holds that skepticism can take different forms. According to his account of philosophical doubt, there are untrue, misconceived forms of skepticism, that is, ordinary versions of skepticism according to which we cannot know whether our beliefs are true, and there is genuine skepticism that coincides with true philosophy itself. True philosophy realizes that skeptical doubt is to be conceived as an integral part of rationality and that, although skepticism as such cannot be overcome, it is not flying in the face of reason either, since genuine skepticism has the positive function of productively contributing to true philosophical cognition. Already in his infamous essay On the Relation between Skepticism and Philosophy (1801), Hegel distinguishes “skepticism that is one with philosophy” from “skepticism that is sundered from it.” The latter “can be divided into two forms, according to whether it is or is not directed against Reason” (Hegel 2000: 330, translation modified). For Hegel, “genuine skepticism” is “skepticism that is one with philosophy” because this form of skepticism represents, in his terminology, the “negative side” that each true philosophy has in that it is “directed against everything limited” or “the whole soil of finitude” (2000: 322–323). Genuine skepticism is allcomprising and hence not limited to doubts about the existence of the external world, sense perception, or human reasoning in general. It also has speculative reason or metaphysics as its object but, unlike skepticism that is sundered from philosophy, not as its target. Unlike ordinary kinds of skepticism, genuine skepticism does not just call into doubt arbitrary epistemic claims but takes skeptical doubt to systematically demonstrate that certain types of cognition are misconceived in principle. Further, according to Hegel, the systematic skeptical proof that certain types of cognition are necessarily untrue belongs to the idea of what true philosophy consists in because in the end skeptical doubt contributes to the constitution of the true as a whole. In what follows, I present the arguments Hegel puts forward in

HEGEL: PHILOSOPHY AS A KIND OF SKEPTICISM

431

favor of this rather challenging account of skepticism. In Section 2, I discuss the celebrated conception of “self-fulfilling skepticism” of the Phenomenology of Spirit (1807) that is supposed to overcome untrue types of cognition in order to promote “absolute knowing.” In Section 3, I debate Hegel’s more advanced view according to which genuine skepticism must be construed as dialectic.1

2  SKEPTICISM AND HISTORY OF SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS The Phenomenology of Spirit, which Hegel conceives as a systematic introduction to metaphysics as true philosophical science, deals with the problem of justifying true knowledge. The project of justifying true knowledge is directly connected with skeptical doubts because epistemic justification presupposes a criterion by means of which it can be decided whether knowledge is justified; however, for the skeptic the criterion itself is questionable. Although theories of epistemic justification like coherentism or contextualism claim to be able to do without a criterion and thereby to dissolve skepticism, Hegel, in the Phenomenology at least, explicitly affirms that a criterion of justification is indispensable. The problem of the non-justifiability of the criterion originates in ancient (Pyrrhonian) skepticism, which for Hegel is substantially more sophisticated than modern skepticism (see Hegel 1969–1971: XIX 358–403; Forster 1989: 9–35; Heidemann 2007: 117–198). The Pyrrhonist Agrippa models it as a skeptical trilemma. The general argument runs as follows: the logical “criterion of truth” serves as “the standard regulating belief in reality or unreality”; however, it is unprovable. For to settle the philosophical dispute over the existence of a criterion of truth, a criterion is required to determine whether there is one or not. Now, this criterion can (i) be proven in a circular way because the proof of a criterion already requires an accepted criterion by means of which it can be proven; or (ii) be a dogmatic “assumption” that involves simply presupposing its existence; or (iii) be proven by another criterion, which in turn will be proven by another one, and so on ad infinitum. (cf. Sextus Empiricus 1933: I 21–24, II 18–21) In any of the three cases, the justification of the criterion necessarily fails. Hegel, who was familiar with the Pyrrhonists’ writings, claims in the Phenomenology to have found a solution to it. In particular, he thinks that he has developed a procedure that justifies the criterion without making unjustified external presuppositions. According to Hegel, the aporia of the criterion, or “standard” (Maßstab) as he most frequently calls it, arises because the “investigation and examination of the reality of cognition” cannot manage “without some presupposition that can serve as its underlying criterion” (1977: sec. 81). From this there results a “contradiction” (1977: sec. 82) or an aporia. Hegel argues as follows: An examination consists in applying an accepted standard, and in determining whether something is right or wrong on the basis of the resulting agreement

432

SKEPTICISM

or disagreement of the thing examined; thus the standard as such (and Science likewise if it were the criterion) is accepted as the essence or as the in-itself (an sich). But here, where Science has just begun to come on the scene, neither Science nor anything else has yet justified itself as the essence or the in-itself; and without something of that sort it seems that no examination can take place. (1977: sec. 81) This version of the aporia essentially resembles Sextus Empiricus’s approach, even though Hegel does not explicitly mention the Pyrrhonian background here (cf. Claesges 1981: 68–74 and 77–96). Hegel’s solution to the problem is based on the analysis of epistemic consciousness. It can be outlined as follows: in order to prevent the unjustified presupposition of the criterion, in the introduction to the Phenomenology of Spirit, Hegel introduces the concept of Science as it “comes on the scene” (1977: sec. 76). Science is characterized at this stage first as an “appearance,” that is, a form of cognition emerging alongside other epistemic claims. Secondly, as an “emerging” science, it is “not yet Science in its developed and unfolded truth.” As this nascent Science competes with other concepts of cognition, due to skeptical equipollence it cannot simply declare its superiority since this would be nothing but a dogmatic “assurance” (1977: sec. 76). Therefore, Hegel’s strategy is to show that the emerging Science develops into true Science by turning against the mere appearance of knowledge and thereby abandoning its provisional status in order to overcome untrue modes of cognition. However, to the extent that the “exposition of how knowledge makes its appearance” (1977: sec. 76) is nothing but the “examination of the reality of cognition” (1977: sec. 81), the Phenomenology obviously cannot avoid relapsing into the aporia, since that examination presupposes a “standard” of its own. In other words, Science must provide the standard of truth although it is just about to emerge and is not yet true and real, that is, justified. Hegel now argues that a standard of justification is indispensable but cannot be dogmatically presupposed as an external criterion. It therefore must fall into the sphere of consciousness itself. The standard is an internal factor of consciousness, for “truth” and “knowledge” prove to be “abstract determinations” that “occur in consciousness” itself (1977: sec. 82). Examination of the relation between these determinations yields the insight that “[c]onsciousness provides its own criterion from within itself” by performing nothing more than a “comparison” with itself (1977: sec. 84). Hegel conceives of this as the self-creation of the standard for the distinction between knowledge and truth, between that which is for consciousness and that which is in itself outside the relation, for that very distinction is one that is made within the epistemic structures of consciousness itself. Whenever consciousness “knows” an object, this object is both for it and at the same time in itself or true, since consciousness regards the object as given outside of the cognitive relation. The in itself, however, is a determination that consciousness “affirms” within its knowledge. For Hegel these epistemic structures generate the standard: “Thus in what consciousness affirms from within itself as being-in-itself or the True we have the standard that consciousness itself sets up by which to measure what it knows” (1977: sec. 84). Thus, according to Hegel’s solution to the skeptical trilemma, the examination of knowledge consists in a comparison of consciousness with what it takes to be true.

HEGEL: PHILOSOPHY AS A KIND OF SKEPTICISM

433

If consciousness corresponds to what it takes to be true, that is, if it is in accordance with itself, then its knowledge meets the standard of true knowledge, produced by itself. This stage is achieved by consciousness at the level of true self-consciousness or subjectivity, that is, “absolute knowing.” In the course of its development toward fully fledged subjectivity, consciousness is already following the path of science and hence does not have to presuppose an external standard. It is the “history of self-consciousness” in terms of self-fulfilling skepticism by means of which Hegel explains how consciousness proceeds through that development. In the Phenomenology, Hegel conceives of the “history of self-consciousness” as the “history of the education of consciousness itself to the standpoint of Science” (1977: sec. 78).2 The purpose of the history of self-consciousness is not to describe the empirical coming into being of self-consciousness on the basis of the natural, cultural, or social development of mankind. Rather, the conception of the history of self-consciousness, as Fichte and Schelling have developed it, is about the ideal or systematic genesis of cognitive capacities in the human mind. The idea is to show how the human mind develops such capacities starting with primitive forms of epistemic consciousness or knowledge, which in the sequel is enriched by more complex forms until they finally culminate in the fully developed self-conscious cognitive subject. The Phenomenology is arranged as an interconnected “series of forms” of consciousness (1977: sec. 79). Hegel presents it as a development of epistemic claims. A form of consciousness is an idealized epistemic shape or structure of consciousness within a specific field like sense certainty, perception, reason, or spirit. The exposition of forms of consciousness is not, however, about the way consciousness has sense-impressions, perceptual representations, etc. Rather it deals with the specific epistemic claims involved in sense certainty, perception, etc., and the question whether consciousness meets these claims so as to acquire true cognition. According to this method, each form of consciousness must have its own standard that makes it possible to decide whether an epistemic claim is satisfied. For example, the standard of sense certainty as a form of consciousness is “immediacy” (1977: sec. 90–93), that is, non-inferentiality is the standard that natural consciousness sets up as the criterion for the examination of the truth of its knowledge claims. So at the level of sense certainty, consciousness examines whether its epistemic claim, that is, beliefs based on sense-impressions, meet the standard of immediacy. The examination of this form of consciousness then proves that sense certainty does not meet its standard since it turns out to be inferential knowledge after all and hence, according to its own standard, one of “the forms of the unreal consciousness” (1977: sec. 79). Thus sense certainty as the form or claim of immediate knowledge has to be given up, because all knowledge based on sense-impressions is conceptually mediated. The standard as such is not just an external presupposition since it is intrinsic to each form of consciousness and set up by consciousness itself.3 This seems to be a legitimate conception to the extent that it is possible to typify different classes of epistemic claims according to different criteria of epistemic justification. However, the systematic interconnection of these claims in the Phenomenology does generate a problem. According to Hegel, with the exception of

434

SKEPTICISM

absolute knowing, no shape of consciousness meets its standard as the fully developed form of self-consciousness or self-knowledge. However, the series of the “formative stages” (1977: sec. 28) of consciousness is not arbitrary but is said to be complete as well as necessary (1977: sec. 29, 77–80). Hegel tries to guarantee this on the basis of the following argument: the skeptically motivated non-satisfaction of a specific standard not only leads to a modification of the epistemic claim of consciousness but also “the criterion for testing is altered,” so that the examination of consciousness is also an examination of “the criterion of what knowledge is” (1977: sec. 85). From this alteration, Hegel claims, “the new true object issues” by a “dialectical movement that consciousness exercises” (1977: sec. 86). This new object is the new epistemic claim of consciousness, including its new standard. That is to say, with the exception of sense certainty as the first form of consciousness, each of the ensuing forms of consciousness necessarily (logically) follows from the preceding one and hence always contains what consciousness has learned from its previous shape. By this “historical” or, to be more precise, developmental and skeptical process, natural consciousness continuously develops into true “absolute knowing” or the completed subject, encompassing the entire experience consciousness has made before. Although subjectivity constitutes the unity of the entire development and is thus the thread of this process, from beginning to end, the question of how the developing consciousness itself can have knowledge of the logical interconnection and epistemic features of the different stages remains an open one. Indeed, the developing consciousness does not have such knowledge. This is due to the fact that the conception of a history of self-consciousness presupposes the methodological differentiation between the developing consciousness at the first level and the phenomenological philosopher who establishes the theoretical links between the forms of consciousness at the second level. The developing consciousness ignores the logical relations between its different epistemic claims since the theoretical assessment takes place from the already fully developed philosophical standpoint. This is the reason why Hegel maintains that the Phenomenology as “the way to science is itself already Science” (1977: sec. 88) and therefore does not lay claim to unjustified external standards of epistemic examination.4 Consequently, the history of self-consciousness shows, first, how the standard is generated by the skeptically self-examining consciousness, secondly, what the standard is in each particular case, and thirdly, that Hegel’s solution does not come down to mere subjectivism since the philosophical evaluation of the “pathway” is “something contributed by us” (1977: sec. 87), the knowing philosopher, and therefore made from an objective standpoint. Nevertheless, this argument as a whole can be reproached with circularity because the conclusion, the standpoint of philosophical truth, is a constitutive element needed to make sense of the premises, that is, the history of self-consciousness. For, on the one hand, the history of selfconsciousness constitutes the skeptical justification of true philosophical knowledge, but, on the other hand, the theory already makes use of it prior to the completion of the whole developmental process before it is itself justified. The history of self-consciousness is forced to make the external presupposition of philosophical knowledge that explains what is going on within the skeptical process of justifying

HEGEL: PHILOSOPHY AS A KIND OF SKEPTICISM

435

the sequence of epistemic claims that consciousness raises. This difficulty might be the reason why Hegel in his later work further developed his account of skepticism by accommodating it with skepticism.

3  SKEPTICISM AND DIALECTIC The place of true philosophy in Hegel’s system is logic conceived as metaphysics. Unlike the Phenomenology, logic, as depicted in the Science of Logic (1812–1816) and the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1817–1830), does not operate on the basis of self-fulfilling skepticism. In the logic, skepticism rather appears in connection with dialectic. Hegel makes two crucial claims with respect to the relation between skepticism and dialectic: (a) “philosophy . . . contains the skeptical moment as a moment within itself—specifically as the dialectical moment” (1991: §81) and (b) “skepticism” as “the dialectical moment itself is an essential one in the affirmative Science” (1991: §78). Both of these claims have to be understood in light of the problem of “total presuppositionlessness” (1991: §78). This problem is subsequent to the problem of a systematic introduction to metaphysics or logic. For Hegel acknowledges the skeptic’s claim that the demonstration of “Science” (1991: §78), that is, philosophical science, must not make any unjustified presuppositions. However, employing skeptical doubt as the method of a systematic introduction to science would be question-begging since “Science” itself is supposed to be selfreliant, that is, it cannot depend on a preceding justification through skepticism. Hence, it cannot be legitimate to construe the demonstration of “Science” as a procedure of skeptical justification. This, of course, means that Hegel can no longer hold onto the conception of the Phenomenology as a systematic introduction to metaphysics or “Science.”5 The fact that skepticism, particularly Phenomenology’s “self-fulfilling skepticism,” cannot perform the function of a systematic introduction to “Science” raises two questions: First, is there an alternative way of obtaining access to “Science,” a systematic way that does not violate the claim of “presuppositionlessness”? Second, if skepticism cannot accomplish the task of a systematic introduction, wouldn’t skeptical doubt be independent of, and therefore a fundamental threat to, “Science”? Hegel’s answer to the first question is that we can obtain access to “Science” without making presuppositions “by the freedom that abstracts from everything, and grasps its own pure abstraction, the simplicity of thinking—in the resolve to think purely” (1991: §78, translation modified). It is by no means clear what the “resolve to think purely” consists in, not least because Hegel does not further explain this concept. But he seems to believe that this concept represents the appropriate methodological procedure that enables an individual to get immediate access to the proper content of “Science” by pure thought. Let us assume, for the sake of argument, that “Science” can indeed be grasped by this procedure. How then does Hegel respond to the second question? He clearly denies that independent skepticism is threatening to “Science” since according to his theory skepticism is contained within philosophy as “the dialectical moment” (1991: §81). In order to see Hegel’s point, one has to recall his conception of “Science” or logic as metaphysics. In Hegel’s speculative idealism,

436

SKEPTICISM

logic represents “the pure truth itself” (1991: §19). As such, it contains “objective thoughts” that “express the essentialities of things,” though not as a collection of abstract terms but as dialectically evolving “thought-determinations.” Since Hegel’s logic is therefore to be construed in the traditional terms of ontology, it “coincides with metaphysics” (1991: §24). In order to demonstrate that truth can be cognized through pure thought, it first has to be shown that the one-sided, finite “forms of cognition,” as represented, for example, through Kant’s transcendental account of cognition, are deficient, for otherwise logic or metaphysics wouldn’t represent the only possible “Science” of “the pure truth itself” (1991: §19). This is compatible with Hegel’s idea of the nullification of the finite “forms of cognition” by means of skeptical doubt. However, this does not conflict with the view that skepticism cannot function as an introduction to metaphysics. For here Hegel explicitly refers to the destructive role of skepticism with regard to the finite “forms of cognition” beyond any kind of introductory function as in the Phenomenology: “The high skepticism of antiquity accomplishes this by showing that every one of those forms contained a contradiction within itself” (1991: §24, Addition 3). As we shall shortly see, “showing that every one of those forms contained a contradiction within itself” indicates the point of intersection between dialectic and skepticism. In On the Relation between Skepticism and Philosophy, Hegel has already argued that skepticism is innocuous “[s]ince every genuine philosophy has this negative side” (Hegel 2000: 325). The “negative side” of “every genuine philosophy” is a positive, systematic component “implicit in every genuine philosophical system.” In Hegel’s eyes, Plato’s Parmenides along with Spinoza’s Ethics are ideal representatives of this skeptical, “free side of philosophy,” since these works exhibit antinomies according to “the principle of skepticism: panti logôi logos isos antikeitai” [to every argument an equal argument is opposed] (Hegel 2000: 324f).6 The presentation of skepticism as the “negative side” of true philosophy indicates Hegel’s mature view of positively integrating skepticism into philosophy by assimilating it with dialectic. By means of this integrative strategy Hegel intends to immunize metaphysics or, more broadly, philosophy against skeptical attacks. This connection between skepticism and dialectic is not at all arbitrary, but rather systematically motivated. For according to Hegel, the dialectical, taken separately on its own by the understanding, constitutes skepticism, especially when it is exhibited in scientific concepts. Skepticism contains the mere negation that results from the dialectic. (1991: §81) The connection of skepticism and dialectic is justified by means of “negation,” that is, in Hegelian terms, through contradiction. However, skepticism is not identical with dialectic. Dialectic shows the “one-sidedness and restrictedness of the determinations of the understanding” (1991: §81), and this means their “negation.” This is also accomplished by skepticism in that the skeptic raises doubts and therefore negates epistemic claims by opposing them according to the aforementioned principle, “panti logôi logos isos antikeitai.” Unlike dialectic, skepticism does not go any further than demonstrating the “negation” of the “determinations of the understanding.”

HEGEL: PHILOSOPHY AS A KIND OF SKEPTICISM

437

However, skepticism is capable of recognizing the positive content of its “negation.” For this reason skepticism and dialectic coincide only inasmuch as both reveal finite understanding’s intrinsic negativity. Nonetheless, finite understanding cannot be aware of dialectic itself but exclusively of the skeptical negation of epistemic claims. Since finite understanding is incapable of reaching dialectical insights, it must accept skepticism as a fundamental threat to its epistemic claims, for without the help of dialectical means finite understanding cannot escape from its natural skeptical doubts and contradictions. By contrast, “genuine philosophy” itself is not affected by skeptical doubts: Skepticism should not be regarded merely as a doctrine of doubt; rather, it is completely certain about its central point, i.e., the nullity of everything finite. . . . Philosophy, on the other hand, contains the skeptical as a moment within itself— specifically as the dialectical moment. But then philosophy does not stop at the merely negative result of the dialectic, as is the case with skepticism. (1991: §81, Addition 2) Hence, skepticism and dialectic accord with respect to “negation” while being vitally distinct at the same time. Although both likewise rely on “negation,” skepticism performs “abstract negation” by simply doubting, that is, nullifying epistemic claims, whereas from the point of view of dialectic the “result” of the “negation” preserves the positive content which it “resulted from.” Here Hegel draws on the Phenomenology’s distinction between two kinds of negation. Skepticism’s, that is, finite understanding’s (“abstract”) negation merely “wait[s] to see whether something new comes along and what it is, in order to throw it too into the same empty abyss” (1977: sec. 79). By contrast, true, “determinate negation” realizes that, nothingness is, in a determinate fashion, specifically the nothingness of that from which it results. For it is only when it is taken as the result from which it emerges, that it is, in fact, the true result; in that case it is itself a determinate nothingness, one which has a content. (1977: sec. 79, translation modified) Consequently, it is the method of counter-position or negation that makes skepticism dialectical and thereby a positive element of rationality. From the immanent point of view of human understanding, skeptical counter-position or negation of epistemic claims has devastating consequences for rationality since finite understanding’s cognitive performances lead naturally and inescapably to skeptical doubt. For finite understanding it therefore looks as if the skeptic, by means of counter-position or negation, is able to prevent the human mind from successfully achieving positive metaphysical knowledge. Hegel does not deny the negative consequences that skepticism has for finite understanding. However, he criticizes this destructive view of skepticism as one-sided. For him the true positive meaning of skepticism is the “dialectical moment,” that is, skepticism’s ability to nullify finite reflection by means of skeptical doubt in order to promote all-comprising metaphysical cognition of the true. It is important to see that Hegel is not operating with two distinct types of skepticism, negative skepticism on the one hand and positive philosophical

438

SKEPTICISM

skepticism on the other. On the contrary, negative and positive philosophical skepticism are identical. It is one and the same skeptical doubt that—on the level of finite understanding—nullifies reflection while—on the level of dialectic—it promotes metaphysical knowledge. This distinction itself is, of course, made from a philosophical point of view, that is, it is an insight that cannot be achieved from within finite reflection. However, from a dialectical angle, skeptical doubt has to be taken as the documentation of true philosophical knowledge.

3  PHILOSOPHY, SKEPTICISM, AND EVERYDAY LIFE Hegel’s account of skepticism is a philosophical challenge in many ways. First of all, self-fulfilling skepticism claims to be a methodological construction of a series of skeptical doubts that promotes true philosophical knowledge. Although one can grant Hegel that he is aware of one of the most fundamental problems of epistemology, that is, the problem of the criterion, it is hard to see how the construction of a series of skeptical doubts is able to face this problem. For the skeptic might still question the objectivity of the systematic connections between the forms of skeptical doubts that supposedly lead consciousness necessarily to the standpoint of true cognition. On the other hand, within the systematically evolved forms of skeptical doubts, Hegel discusses many of the skeptical arguments that are still debated in the present, like skeptical doubts concerning external world beliefs, cognition a priori, identity, first-person beliefs, morality, or realism, and offers astute critical analyses of these arguments.7 Secondly, with respect to the account of skepticism in Hegel’s later work, one might question whether “dialectical” skepticism is at all a kind of skepticism. For Hegel’s assimilation of skeptical doubt and dialectic seems to violate our ordinary understanding of skeptical doubt. Whereas skeptical arguments are supposed to support the claim that we cannot know whether our beliefs are true, dialectic is designed to bring about metaphysical knowledge. Hence, the skeptic would insist that doubt and dialectic are intrinsically incompatible. Hegel would respond that the skeptic’s insistence is symptomatic of finite understanding’s incapacity to judge metaphysical truth, that is, that true philosophy and skepticism coincide. Accordingly, “Science” shows that this kind of criticism is limited to a one-sided finite perspective that is to be overcome in the direction of all-comprising true philosophy. From the Hegelian angle, to repudiate skeptical doubts would even be inefficacious since skepticism is a natural, inescapable problem for human cognition, a problem that can never be eliminated from our philosophical examination of the question of knowledge. This is a point of intersection between Hegel’s and the more recent discussion of skepticism. According to Michael Williams’s interpretation, contemporary “New Skeptics” like Stroud and Nagel follow Hume in that they “are rightly impressed by the simplicity, brevity and seeming transparency of typical skeptical arguments” (Williams 1996: xv), that is, they take skepticism to be a natural problem. However, the crucial question to be asked is: “Is skepticism really a natural or intuitive problem?” For Williams it isn’t since, if it is, “then Hume is right, and we will never reconcile everyday attitudes with the results of philosophical reflection”

HEGEL: PHILOSOPHY AS A KIND OF SKEPTICISM

439

(Williams 1996: xv). In this case, from the point of view of everyday life, philosophy would be irrelevant since what we commonsensically believe to be true in everyday life does not carry the heavy burden of fundamental skeptical doubt. The best way to deal with this situation is, Williams argues, to offer a “theoretical diagnosis” of skepticism that identifies “theoretical ideas” the skeptic holds “that we are by no means bound to accept” (Williams 1996: xvii). If we do so, we have a good chance to overcome skepticism by an alternative account of cognition. Hegel’s strategy is similar to Williams’s since, according to his view, skeptical doubts arise from a misconceived conception of cognition, that is, one-sided finite cognition that is to be overcome by true philosophical “Science.” Philosophical “Science” then prevents us from accepting those “theoretical ideas” that naturally force us into skepticism. That is, according to Hegel, skeptical doubts are natural as long as we reflect within the theoretical framework of, for example, Kantian subjectivism. For Kant’s restriction of cognition to appearances as ordinary objects of everyday life leads naturally into skepticism about things in themselves, that is, about things as they really are. In order to escape this kind of skepticism and to therefore eliminate unnatural doubts, Hegel asks us to give the theoretical framework that like Kantian subjectivism makes skepticism unavoidable. With respect to the claim that skeptical doubts are unnatural as long as we subscribe to certain kinds of theoretical frameworks, Hegel therefore concurs with Williams’s theoretical diagnosis. However, unlike Williams, Hegel argues that skepticism itself makes indeed a positive contribution to this insight in that skeptical doubts should be understood as the flipside of true philosophical “Science.” Skeptical arguments like Agrippa’s trilemma or Kant’s antinomies of pure reason point to the finiteness of ordinary human cognition that Hegel aims to overcome by absolute idealism, according to which true philosophical cognition is possible. For absolute idealism skeptical doubts are unnatural, on the one hand, but they remain everlasting historical facts on the other. Although as historical appearances they are unnatural as such, they are at the same time manifestations of the shortcomings of the human mind and hence move rationality toward true philosophy. In this sense true philosophy is a kind of skepticism.

NOTES 1. This article will not be concerned with Hegel’s early views of the relation between logic and metaphysics that pave the way for his later account of skepticism. For more details, see Heidemann (2011: 81–84), from which I draw in my current interpretation of Hegelian skepticism. For the broader context, see Düsing (1995: chs. 2 and 3). 2. On the “history of self-consciousness,” see also Breazeale (2001), Düsing (1993), and Heidemann (2009: 16–19). 3. For a more detailed analysis of the skeptical argument in “Sense certainty” and “Perception,” see Heidemann (2011: 88–92). 4. On the methodological differentiation between the standpoint of consciousness in process and the standpoint of the philosopher, see Heidemann (2007: 245–271).

440

SKEPTICISM

5. Hegel, after 1807, in fact gives up the view that the Phenomenology serves as such an introduction, although he does not give up the Phenomenology itself. On Hegel’s later reappraisal of the relation between the Phenomenology of Spirit and the Science of Logic, see Heidemann (2007: 327–339). 6. By “principle of skepticism” Hegel alludes to Sextus Empiricus (1933: I 12). The use of “antinomy” not only refers to the antinomies of the Parmenides but also to the antinomies of pure reason in Kant’s first Critique and possibly to the antithetical structure of the principles in Fichte’s Doctrine of Science. 7. I cannot elaborate here on Hegel’s worthwhile discussion of these arguments, but I have done so in Heidemann (2007).

REFERENCES Breazeale, Daniel. 2001. “Fichte’s Conception of Philosophy as a Pragmatic History of the Human Mind and the Contribution of Kant, Platner, and Maimon,” Journal of the History of Ideas 62: 685–703. Claesges, Ulrich. 1981. Darstellung des erscheinenden Wissens. Systematische Einleitung in Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes. Bonn: Bouvier. Düsing, Klaus. 1993. “Hegels Phänomenologie und die idealistische Geschichte des Selbstbewußtseins,” Hegel-Studien 28: 103–126. Düsing, Klaus. 1995. Das Problem der Subjektivität in Hegels Logik. Systematische und entwicklungsgeschichtliche Untersuchungen zum Prinzip des Idealismus und zur Dialektik. 3rd ed. Bonn: Bouvier. Forster, Michael N. 1989. Hegel and Skepticism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1969–1971. Theorie-Werk-Ausgabe, edited by E. Moldenhauer and K. M. Michel, 20 vols. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1977. Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A. V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1991. The Encyclopaedia Logic. Part I of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences with Zusätze, translated by T. F. Gerates, W. A. Suchting, and H. S. Harris. Indianapolis: Hackett. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 2000. “On the Relation between Skepticism and Philosophy. Exposition of His Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One,” translated by H. S. Harris. In G. di Giovanni and H. S. Harris (eds.), Between Kant and Hegel. Texts in the Development Of Post-Kantian Idealism, 311–362. Indianapolis: Hackett. Heidemann, Dietmar H. 2007. Der Begriff des Skeptisismus. Seine systematischen Formen, die pyrrhonische Skepsis und Hegels Herausforderung. Berlin and New York: De Gruyter. Heidemann, Dietmar H. 2008. “Substance, Subject, System: The Justification of Science and the History of Self-Consciousness in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit.” In D. Moyar and M. Quante (eds.), Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. A Critical Guide, 1–20. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

HEGEL: PHILOSOPHY AS A KIND OF SKEPTICISM

441

Heidemann, Dietmar H. 2011. “Hegel on the Nature of Scepticism,” Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 63: 80–99. Sextus Empiricus. 1933. Outlines of Pyrrhonism, translated by R. G. Bury. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Williams, Michael. 1996: Unnatural Doubts: Epistemological Realism and the Basis of Scepticism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

CHAPTER THIRTY-TWO

Friedrich Nietzsche ANDREAS URS SOMMER

1 INTRODUCTION Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) is generally labeled as a “skeptic” because he attacked traditional (Christian) religion vigorously and declared God to be dead, but also as a thinker frequently transgressing traditional intellectual and political boundaries (Shaw 2007). Beyond this widely accepted point of view, however, he seems to defend in his experimental philosophy strong skeptical assumptions, not only a “mitigated skepticism” (as Magnus 1980 claims). Recent research has shown that Nietzsche does not hold hard philosophical propositions or doctrines (Sommer 2012; 2013). Instead, he uses such propositions or doctrines—like the Übermensch (“overman”), the Ewige Wiederkunft des Gleichen (“eternal recurrence of the same”) or the Wille zur Macht (“will to power”)—as instruments to subvert traditional (not only philosophical) knowledge and beliefs. Nietzsche might be a skeptic as someone who never has enough reason to believe that something is true. His doubts about the knowability of truth should not be ignored: skepticism, which often has a positive connotation in Nietzsche’s writings, can easily result in a suspension of belief in reality altogether. However, the skeptical refutation of knowledge does not imply an apodictic denial of the moral order of reality, although Nietzsche’s concept of extreme nihilism in his later writings appears to indicate such a form of moral skepticism. This type of nihilism is postulated by the motto of the Assassins: “Nothing is true, everything is permitted” (Nietzsche 1999: IV 340, V 399), but it is neither free of negative dogmatism nor reflects Nietzsche’s very own position. Even when he promulgates his so-called main doctrines (“overman,” “eternal recurrence,” or “will to power”), a Pyrrhonian tendency is evident, namely, taking these pretended truths only as situational assertions, expressing ephemeral perspectives (see Kain 1983: 283–287; Sommer 2000: 524–541; Wotling 2006). It has also been remarked that Nietzsche’s aphoristic style, often avoiding a final decision between contradictory conceptions, resembles the skeptical mode of speaking developed by Sextus Empiricus and Montaigne: a mode full of reservations, aware of the fact that silence would perhaps be more adequate (Bett 2000: 83). Nietzsche is, similar to Montaigne, an ardent traveler and an ardent philosophical traveler, detesting any definite positions or goals. Skepticism is one of Nietzsche’s means of avoiding final systematization, and it helps to neutralize existential ambiguities.

FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE

443

However, Nietzsche’s singular type of skepticism significantly deviates from ancient and modern approaches: in the late 1880s, he argues in favor of an experimental form of skepticism that is heroic, active, and after all judgment-friendly. Skepticism is prevalent in the whole of Nietzsche’s writings, from his first years in Basel in the early 1870s to the last months of his conscious life in Torino in 1888. The understanding of truth in its metaphoricity established in Nietzsche’s unpublished early work Ueber Wahrheit und Lüge im aussermoralischen Sinne (On Truth and Lie in the Non-moral Sense) may already be interpreted as a neoPyrrhonian attempt to subvert one’s own speech in speech itself (cf. Berry 2006). Thus, truth appears as a mere product of speech, “the laws of speech provide the first laws of truth” (Nietzsche 1999: I 877).1 In this text, the “aporia of the missing epistemological place of a critique that has turned self-referential” (Kaiser 1994: 71) becomes obvious. This aporia can be seen as a metamorphosis of the Pyrrhonian aporia subverting its own point of view. Yet in the following, this article will focus on Nietzsche’s later, more decided, and explicit statements about skeptics and skepticism. First, I shall review Nietzsche’s knowledge of historical types of skepticism (Section 2), then investigate the character and forms of skepticism in Nietzsche’s writings (Section 3), and finally evaluate the consequences of skepticism for religion, morality, and the “revaluation of all values” (Umwerthung aller Werthe) according to Nietzsche (Section 4).

2  NIETZSCHE’S VIEW OF HISTORICAL SKEPTICISM Nietzsche was well aware of the ancient skeptical traditions.2 A major part of his early philological work was devoted to the prominent doxographer of Greek philosophy, Diogenes Laertius. He certainly knew very well the chapters on Pyrrho and Timon in the Vitae philosophorum (DL IX 11 and 12). Nevertheless, his knowledge of ancient philosophy and skepticism was also based on comprehensive overviews of Greek literature and philosophy. Nietzsche read, for example, Rudolf Nicolai’s Geschichte der gesammten griechischen Literatur, Friedrich Ueberweg’s Grundriß der Geschichte der Philosophie von Thales bis auf die Gegenwart, and Eduard Zeller’s Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen Entwicklung.3 Beyond this second-hand reading, there is no evidence that Nietzsche ever studied the main source of Greek skepticism, namely, the oeuvre of Sextus Empiricus.4 Nietzsche did also read contemporary philosophy, although it was not his predominant field of occupation. In the books of Friedrich Albert Lange, Afrikan Spir,5 and Gustav Teichmüller,6 he found different skeptical reflections that presented him with deep challenges. Apart from Arthur Schopenhauer, Lange’s Geschichte des Materialismus, first published in 1866, was the most influential philosophical book for young Nietzsche and also important for his knowledge of classical skeptical positions (Tongeren 1999). It proposes a radicalized criticism with some skeptical aspects, but it also extensively discusses recent philosophers of the skeptical tradition: Michel de Montaigne, Pierre Bayle, and David Hume. Nietzsche also came across other modern skeptics while reading several volumes of Kuno Fischer’s Geschichte der neuern Philosophie.7 He recurred to the original

444

SKEPTICISM

texts of Montaigne, Blaise Pascal,8 François de La Rochefoucauld, and other more or less skeptical French moralists, yet continued to frequently consult secondary surveys of the French history of ideas. Nietzsche even urged Ida Overbeck, the wife of his closest friend, Franz Overbeck, to translate—for him and for the general public—some selected Causeries by Sainte-Beuve on major exponents of the French Enlightenment, particularly on the skeptic Diderot.9 As a skeptic of language, Georg Christoph Lichtenberg and his collected works were well present in Nietzsche’s intellectual horizon (Lichtenberg 1867; see Stingelin 1996). The same applies to Gustav Gerber’s Die Sprache als Kunst in Nietzsche’s early writings (Gerber 1871–1874; see Meijers and Stingelin 1988). Nietzsche could find skepticism about religious claims to truth in Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, of which he possessed a German translation (Hume 1781); in William Edward Hartpole Lecky’s History of the Origin and Influence of the Enlightenment in Europe (Lecky 1873)—a book he studied intensively; in JeanMarie Guyau’s L’irréligion de l’avenir (Guyau 1887); and in Eugène de Roberty’s L’ancienne et la nouvelle philosophie (Roberty 1887). In the same year Guyau’s and Roberty’s books were published, Nietzsche also bought a copy of Victor Brochard’s Les sceptiques grecs (Brochard 1887; see Bett 2000, and Busellato 2012). Nietzsche expressly praises this study and its author (Nietzsche 1999: VI 284). Some posthumous fragments from 1888 are linked to Brochard’s work: they deal with the founding father of ancient philosophical skepticism, Pyrrho of Elis (cf. Brobjer 1997). Before Nietzsche reads Brochard, the skeptics of Antiquity barely appear in Nietzsche’s writings (Brobjer 2001: 14). Certainly Heraclitus, the exemplary philosopher of becoming, is a central figure of reference already for young Nietzsche, but he is not primarily seen by him as a protoskeptic. It is an ongoing dispute in Nietzsche studies whether the Sophists, Gorgias, Hippias, Callicles, and Protagoras had any philosophical importance for Nietzsche (Mann 2003) or not (Brobjer 2001, 2005). According to a draft periodization of Greek philosophy from 1872/73, Socrates is expressly classified as skeptic (1999: VII 540) and anti-dogmatic (1999: VII 544): “Socratic skepticism is a weapon against the traditional culture and knowledge” (1999: VII 555). According to Nietzsche, there is also both skepticism in early Plato, who saw everything in “flux” (1999: VII 550; see Ghedini 1999: 272–273), and a skepticism reloaded in the refutation of Plato’s doctrine of ideas in the dialogue Parmenides. Several years later, in 1885, Nietzsche distinguishes an exoteric and an esoteric point of view in Plato. No other philosopher, he claims, cultivated such an “absolute skepticism towards all given concepts” as Plato, although he “taught the opposite” (Nietzsche 1999: XI 147). Incapable of art, the Academic skeptic Arcesilaus stands in this tradition (1999: VII 97; see Zeller 1880: 496–497 n. 4). Pyrrhonian skepticism is very rarely mentioned in Nietzsche’s early and middle oeuvre. In the second part of Menschliches, Allzumenschliches, a figure named Pyrrho appears in a dialogue with an “old man.” He is presented as someone who wants to promulgate mistrust of “everything and everyone,” because this seems to be the “only path to truth” (1999: II 645). In the dialogue, Pyrrho has to admit that he is forced to silence if he wants to be mistrustful of all words, but that he

FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE

445

also has to tell people that he must keep silent: “Saying nothing and laughing—is that your whole philosophy? Pyrrho: it would not be the worst” (1999: II 646). According to Diogenes Laertius (DL IX 61 and IX 76), aphasia—the wordlessness, the silence in light of the impossibility of making a decision—is typical of Pyrrhonian skepticism. A better informed approach to the historical Pyrrho can be traced after Nietzsche’s reading of Brochard in 1887/88. Under this influence, Pyrrho is now presented as a “Greek Buddhist” (1999: XIII 264), even as “Greek Buddha” (1999: XIII 347), performing a fundamental criticism of a philosophy unsuitable for life (1999: XIII 311). In another note, Pyrrho’s own philosophy looks like “decadence,” defending itself against “science and mind,” denying the “importance of all things” and leading to a “final self-overcoming, final indifference” (1999: XIII 276–278). Nietzsche compares Pyrrho to another décadent, Epicurus, yet finds the former “more travelled, more worn out, more nihilistic,” perhaps more radical. In Nietzsche’s view, he challenged the very bases of philosophy: “His life was a protest against the great doctrine of identity.” Pyrrho even gave up the pursuit of happiness (1999: XIII 276–278). Not primarily interested in happiness was also René Descartes. His methodological doubt in the philosophy of knowledge did not seem radical enough to Nietzsche: Descartes still seeks and intends to find evidence for an absolute and evident truth. For Nietzsche, this is just “nonsense”: “cogito, ergo sum pretends that one knows what ‘thinking’ is and secondly, what ‘being’ is” (Nietzsche 1999: XI 640). However, we don’t know what these two things are. While Nietzsche does not show any particular interest in Hume,10 he holds Kant liable for translating the “Englishmen’s epistemological skepticism” to the Germans by meeting their moral and religious needs, “just as Pascal even made use of moral skepticism to excite the need for faith” (1999: XII 340). In fact, Nietzsche considers Kant a dogmatist to the core, who, “by means of a clever and mischievous skepticism,” has even tried to make Christianity irrefutable (1999: VI 176).

3  CHARACTER AND FORMS OF SKEPTICISM In his first philosophical reflections, Nietzsche is well aware that a fundamental criticism of knowledge has skeptical consequences. Typical is his early response to such a challenge: he underlines the “necessity of art and illusion” in order to reject “absolute skepticism” (Nietzsche 1999: VII 458, also XI 649). Philology in particular, Nietzsche’s original profession—he was a professor of Greek philology, never of philosophy—appears in his notes as a skeptical discipline, destroying all kinds of cultural and intellectual securities. This view, already present in 1875 (1999: VIII 37, 55), prevailed until Nietzsche opted for a philosophical “ephexis in interpretation” (1999: VI 233) in 1888: this is meant as a giving-up of all projections and premature judgments while reading texts or also the book of nature (see also Benne 2005). On the other hand, Nietzsche fights against a cheap skepticism of easy comfort connected with fatigue and feeling weak (Nietzsche 2003: V 153). While, according to Nietzsche, traditional skeptics claimed to own the truth that nothing is true, he

446

SKEPTICISM

claims for his own standpoint “that we do not have truth” (Nietzsche 1999: IX 52). Nietzsche proclaims a new form of skepticism against the skeptical attitude of the contemporary décadence and probably also against the academic skepticism of the nineteenth-century German university: “Skepticism! Yes, but a skepticism of experiments! Not the lethargy of despair” (1999: IX 287). This motif of an experimental skepticism that takes its legitimation out of non-knowledge remains dominant in several posthumous notes, although the real shape of this specific form of skepticism is not quite clear. It can also be seen as “a temptation” (1999: X 526). However, in the same context Nietzsche takes life itself as “an experiment”: its “happiness” consists “in guessing or experimenting (skepticism)” (1999: X 527). He seems to be attracted to the therapeutic effect of the assumption that things are unknowable: “Despair abolished via skepticism,” giving way to “the right to create” (1999: X 232). Such reflections in his notebooks lead to statements in his published books like: “I salute any form of skepticism to which I am allowed to reply: ‘let’s try!’” (1999: III 415). Nevertheless, Nietzsche attempts to guard himself against “skeptical randomness”: the recently gained liberty “from the tyranny of ‘eternal’ concepts” should teach us “to view concepts as experiments, with the help of which certain types of humans can be bred” (Nietzsche 1999: XI 526). This is the way Nietzsche’s own new concepts, will to power and eternal recurrence of the same, are to be understood: as intellectual, but also as existential, experiments. Existence has a “perspectivist character,” and the world “contains within itself endless interpretations” (1999: III 626–627). This endorses the inevitable perspectivism and situationism of knowledge. Taking this experimental skepticism seriously, Nietzsche’s readers have to take the seemingly dogmatic late work The Antichrist as ruled by a skeptical strategy of proclaiming certain interpretations against others.11 Undoubtedly, Nietzsche’s experimental skepticism is far away from the Pyrrhonian attitude of withholding judgment (cf. Bett 2000: 81). Instead, his skepticism has a neutralizing effect on the permanent stating of judgments. In 1873, Nietzsche noted that there were only “friends of truth,” “enemies of truth and skeptics” (1999: VII 574). Indifference toward the truth thus characterizes the skeptic. In Nietzsche’s later diagnosis, his contemporary cultural and intellectual situation is determined by the abolishment of a metaphysical idea of truth. Skepticism is therefore revealed as “the afterbirth of the pride” that had been cultivated for a long time by humanity believing in its own metaphysical worth (1999: IX 200). Given that such skepticism will first diminish human pride, Nietzsche assumes that later a period of exhaustion will follow. However, Nietzschean skepticism is confrontational: “We have become disgusted by the views of the authorities— rather we would starve!” (1999: IX 226). And this “skepticism is a passion,” too. Nietzsche uses the word “ephexis” for the Pyrrhonian epochē and postulates it as a main scientific principle (1999: XI 521).12 The ephectic keeps problems open and remains reserved toward precipitate explanations. Ephexis turns out to be no intellectual laziness, but a difficult task of disillusionment. In 1883/84, Nietzsche establishes a distinction between a “skepticism of weakness” and a skepticism of “courage,” to be connected with “heroic feelings” (1999: X 662).

FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE

447

Thus, he seems to abandon his former idea of an incompatibility of the tragic and the skeptical worldviews. In a historical perspective, “the skeptical periods, suffering from indecision” are precisely those periods tempted to adopt a “rigid faith” (1999: XII 191). Christianity became powerful in a skeptical world (1999: V 66). The “suffering from uncertainty” is seen as the very origin of systematic thought. Nietzsche’s experimental and heroic skepticism tries to withstand the temptation of systematic thought. He complains that authoritative skeptics have emerged only rarely up to the present (1999: XI 696), and he seeks for the “overcoming of the skeptic of weakness” (1999: XI 211). Particularly the sections 208 to 210 of Beyond Good and Evil articulate this search, where a strong skepticism is hailed against a weak and comfortable skepticism, a “gentle, pure, soothing opium” (1999: V 137). The new destabilization has to be “a skepticism of bold masculinity . . . that is closely related to the genius for war and plunder” (1999: V 141). While Nietzsche promulgates this skepticism as the relevant way of philosophizing in his last books (e.g. 1999: VI 178, 236), his critical views on skepticism in the ancient world influenced by Brochard remain hidden in his posthumous notes (Bett 2000: 79). In these notes, ancient as well as modern skepticism rather appears as “an effect of decadence” (Nietzsche 1999: XIII 264). Certainly, the active, experimental skepticism preferred by Nietzsche is totally different from the passive Pyrrhonism with its refusal to make a judgment and may come closer to Academic skepticism (that Nietzsche knew well from Cicero, see note 2). Brochard revitalized Nietzsche’s interest in the complexity of skepticism in general. Yet, the skepticism propagated by Nietzsche is the exact opposite of the Pyrrhonian skepticism in its approach to life.

4  SKEPTICISM ABOUT RELIGION AND MORALITY, AND THE “REVALUATION OF ALL VALUES” Challenging the possibility of knowing the truth, skepticism obviously stands in opposition to religion when understood as an institution that socially administers the truth (see, e.g., Nicolai 1867: 299). Nietzsche was well aware of this opposition when, in 1873, he defined skepticism as an “ascetic viewpoint of the thinker” (Nietzsche 1999: VII 624) who rejects the very idea of believing. Twelve years later, he focused on “the inwardly audacious skepticism in Germany” in reaction to the overly close familiarity of philosophers with Protestantism (1999: XI 473). Nietzsche could observe the way from Protestantism to skepticism personally in the example of his most loyal friend, the agnostic Franz Overbeck, professor of theology at the University of Basel (cf. Sommer 1997). Nietzsche stresses, on the one hand, that also Catholics like Pascal also used skepticism against reason—that humans cannot access truth through rational operations—for proselytism: according to them, faith alone opens the path to knowledge (1999: II 383–384). On the other hand, it was a skeptical insight that eliminated God, especially the Christian one, for Nietzsche. Thus, in The Antichrist and in the late Nachlass, Jesus is not the founder of a new religion, but a relative of Epicurus (1999: XIII 276–278) and also of

448

SKEPTICISM

Pyrrho: Jesus and Pyrrho are both akin to Buddha (see 1999: VI 202, XI 247), since both give up “all animosities, boundaries and distances in feeling” (1999: VI 200), all judgment and denial. For both, Nietzsche traces this peculiar attitude to their particular pathological, physiological conditions: Jesus and Pyrrho had to follow this way of life and thought because they suffered from decadence. In Nietzsche’s oeuvre, skepticism is not a simple epistemological exercise at all (see also Welshon 2009). His project of a genealogy of moral sentiments and of morality itself is fundamentally marked by skeptical reflections (Nietzsche 1999: IX 109 and V 252), while moralism usually rejects the skeptics (1999: II 407). Quite early, Nietzsche saw himself as a proponent of a “moralistic skepticism” through which pessimism had deepened and criticized itself (1999: II 370). In Daybreak (1881), “moral skepticism” mistrustful of man does not have to be accompanied by bad humor or weakness. The aphorism is a dialogue of two persons, A and B. According to A, “general moral skepticism” seems to be an elixir of life, making him healthier. B responds that A has ended up being a skeptic as he says “no” again. A answers that he has thus learned to say “yes” again (1999: III 284). This short text illustrates in nuce the performative pattern of Nietzsche’s experimental skepticism, which is, despite its sympathy for “ephexis in interpretation,” a judgment-friendly skepticism. It challenges and provokes “value judgments on people and things”: “one would have to overturn all values by means of a radical skepticism, to have a clear path” (1999: IX 62). Thus Socrates himself can turn out as the eminent forerunner of moral skepticism (1999: IX 363, 365). In return, Nietzsche recommends moral skeptics to subject their “mistrust of morality” to a mistrustful skepticism (1999: X 67–68), because skeptics attacking morality might simply forget how they are themselves infected with morality (1999: XI 486). Far-reaching doubt about morality can be problematic, since the reason for doubt fades away altogether as soon as the skeptic stops to believe in truth—unless “the will to know” has “a quite different root yet . . . from that of truthfulness” (1999: XI 510–511). Consequently, Nietzsche assumes that “no skepticism has arisen without ulterior motives” and that these ulterior motives have so far been moral ones (1999: XII 143–144). Even to ancient skeptics, Nietzsche argues, morality remained the highest value (1999: XIII 319–321), when they subordinated their epochē to the “herd instinct,” to “living like the ‘common man’” (1999: XIII 286). Nietzsche’s own experimental skepticism fosters an abhorrence of such subordination. His skepticism intends to create differences, not to make them disappear. A “victory of skepticism” over “morality as prejudice” may entail “a dawn-like happiness” (1999: XII 195). Of course, only hard work helps to attain it: “One should reduce and bound the realm of morality step by step” (1999: XII 476). In late Nietzsche, moral skepticism is a requirement for the emergence of nihilism. It also has a crucial part in Nietzsche’s final task of a “revaluation of all values” (Umwerthung aller Werthe). He pretends at the end of 1888 to have fulfilled this task in The Antichrist. If the revaluation of values is to avoid a new heteronomy, it cannot establish a canon of new values, to be obeyed as the former. Otherwise, the liberty to create values that Nietzsche wants to guarantee (at least to strong individuals) would be undercut again. “Revaluation of all values” aims for such liberty to shape

FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE

449

one’s self and one’s world. One instrument to attain this goal is the neutralizing of all differences through diaphoniai. Nietzsche’s conception of revaluation demands of every individual to make unavoidable personal, situational, and perspectivist decisions in order to shape his or her life and the world. This concept is radically different from the Pyrrhonian inclination to accept the given circumstances without making any decisions or alterations. Ephexis in The Antichrist is a principle of interpretation against the pretense of one absolute perspective, but it does not imply the Pyrrhonian suspension of one’s own decision. Nietzsche’s experimental skepticism forbids epochē as a basic attitude to life (see Obstoj 1985). Philosophers and skeptics should both become “givers of orders and laws” (Nietzsche 1999: V 145). Extreme nihilism and experimental skepticism are alternative names for the late Nietzsche’s strategy of revaluating all values. His alleged “main doctrines” of “will to power” and “eternal recurrence of the same” are only the means, not the ends, of this revaluation. Through extreme nihilism and experimental skepticism, humans gain radical distance from all ideas and doctrines hitherto taken for granted. Skepticism then enables intellectual and practical freedom. So is freedom for Nietzsche a value beyond all traditional values, not affected itself in a revaluation of values?13

NOTES 1. See also Hödl (1997) and Reuter (2009). 2. See Bett (2000), Sommer (2000), Brobjer (2001), Berry (2011), and Busellato (2012). Berry (2011) claims a fundamental difference between ancient and modern, (post-) Cartesian skepticism and sees Nietzsche in the tradition of classical Pyrrhonism as well as of Montaigne with his interest in the practical relevance particularly of epochē (cf. Santini 2013). On the other hand, Leiter (2014) rejects a Pyrrhonian ground for Nietzsche’s “value Skepticism.” More deeply engaged in questions of “Quellenforschung” is Busellato (2012). He documents, for example, the interest Nietzsche had in Cicero’s Academica—a text the young professor of philology used in one of his courses at the University of Basel in 1870/71. The relevance of the model of the wise in Hellenistic philosophy for Nietzsche’s Übermensch is made clear by Bertino (2007) (see already Parush 1975/76). 3. See Nicolai (1867: esp. 298–300, 489–90), Ueberweg (1867); Zeller (1880: esp. 478–527; 1881: esp. 1–69). 4. On parallels between Sextus and Nietzsche, see Conway and Ward (1992). 5. See Spir (1873; 1877). On Nietzsche’s reception D’Iorio (1993) and Small (2001: 1–20). 6. See Teichmüller (1882) and Nietzsche (1999: XIII 579). 7. Nietzsche (1999: XII 259–270) is a mainly unaltered excerpt taken from Fischer. See Sommer (2012b) on Fischer, Nietzsche, and Spinoza. 8. See Vivarelli (1998) on Montaigne and Pascal. 9. This translation has been published under Nietzsche’s protection by his publisher: Sainte-Beuve (1880), critical new edition Sainte-Beuve (2014). 10. See Beam (2001) and Kail (2009) for a different perspective on Nietzsche and Hume.

450

SKEPTICISM

11. Nietzsche (1999: VI 236) reflects this strategy of utilizing “convictions” frankly. 12. See also Nietzsche (1999: VI 232) and Sommer (2013: 244–46). 13. This text is based on Sommer (2006). I would like to thank Daniel Unger, the editors of this book, and particularly Julia Maas for many very useful corrections, comments, and suggestions.

REFERENCES Beam, Craig. 2001. “Ethical Affinities: Nietzsche in the Tradition of Hume,” International Studies in Philosophy 33: 87–98. Benne, Christian. 2005. Nietzsche und die historisch-kritische Philologie. Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter. Berry, Jessica. 2006. “Skepticism in Nietzsche’s Earliest Work: Another look at ‘On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense,’” International Studies in Philosophy 38: 33–48. Berry, Jessica. 2011. Nietzsche and the Ancient Skeptical Tradition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bertino, Andrea. 2007. “Nietzsche und die hellenistische Philosophie. Der Übermensch und der Weise,” Nietzsche-Studien 36: 95–130. Bett, Richard. 2000. “Nietzsche on the Skeptics and Nietzsche as Skeptic,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 82: 62–86. Brobjer, Thomas. 1997. “Beiträge zur Quellenforschung,” Nietzsche-Studien 26: 574–579. Brobjer, Thomas. 2001. “Nietzsche’s Disinterest and Ambivalence Toward the Greek Sophists,” International Studies in Philosophy 33: 5–23. Brobjer, Thomas. 2005. “Nietzsche’s Relation to the Greek Sophists,” Nietzsche-Studien 34: 256–277. Brochard, Victor. 1887. Les sceptiques grecs. Paris: Imprimerie Nationale. Busellato, Stefano. 2012. Nietzsche e lo scetticismo. Macerata: Edizioni Università di Macerata. Conway, David and Janet Ward. 1992. “Physicians of the Soul: Peritrope in Sextus and Nietzsche.” In D. W. Conway and R. Rehn (ed.), Nietzsche und die antike Philosophie, 193–224. Trier: WVT. D’Iorio, Paolo. 1993. “La superstition des philosophes critiques. Nietzsche et Afrikan Spir,” Nietzsche-Studien 22: 257–294. Fischer, Kuno. 1865. Geschichte der neuern Philosophie. Bd. 1: Descartes und seine Schule. 1. Theil: Allgemeine Einleitung. René Descartes. 2. Theil: Descartes’ Schule. Geulinx. Malebranche. Baruch Spinoza. Zweite völlig umgearbeitete Auflage. Mannheim: Friedrich Bassermann. Gerber, Gustav. 1871–1874. Die Sprache als Kunst. 2 vols. Bromberg: Mittler’sche Buchhandlung. Ghedini, Francesco. 1999. Il Platone di Nietzsche. Genesi e motivi di un simbolo controverso (1864–1879). Napoli: Edizioni Scientifiche Italiane. Guyau, Jean-Marie. 1887. L’irréligion de l’avenir. Étude sociologique, 2nd edn. Paris: F. Alcan.

FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE

451

Hödl, Hans Gerald. 1997. Nietzsches frühe Sprachkritik. Wien: Universitätsverlag. Hume, David. 1781. Gespräche über natürliche Religion. Nach der zweyten englischen Ausgabe. Nebst einem Gespräch über den Atheismus von Ernst Platner. Leipzig: Weygand. Kail, Peter. 2009. “Nietzsche and Hume: Naturalism and Explanation,” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 37: 5–22. Kain, Philip. 1983. “Nietzsche, Skepticism, and Eternal Recurrence,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13: 365–387. Kaiser, Stefan. 1994. “Über Wahrheit und Klarheit. Aspekte des Rhetorischen in ‘Ueber Wahrheit und Lüge im aussermoralischen Sinne,’” Nietzsche-Studien 23: 65–78. Lange, Friedrich Albert. 1866. Geschichte des Materialismus und Kritik seiner Bedeutung in der Gegenwart. Iserlohn: J. Baedeker. Lecky, William Edward Hartpole. 1873. Geschichte des Ursprungs und Einflusses der Aufklärung in Europa. Mit Bewilligung des Verfassers übersetzt von H. Jolowicz. 2 vols. Leipzig and Heidelberg: C. F. Winter’sche Verlagshandlung. Leiter, Brian. 2014. “Moral Skepticism and Moral Disagreement in Nietzsche,” Oxford Studies in Metaethics 9: 126–151. Lichtenberg, Georg Christoph. 1867. Vermischte Schriften. Neue Original-Ausgabe. 8 vols. Göttingen: Dieterich. Magnus, Bernd. 1980. “Nietzsche’s Mitigated Skepticism,” Nietzsche-Studien 9: 260–267. Mann, Joel. 2003. “Nietzsche’s Interest and Enthusiasm for the Greek Sophists,” NietzscheStudien 32: 406–428. Meijers, Anthonie, and Martin Stingelin. 1988. “Konkordanz zu den wörtlichen Abschriften und Übernahmen von Beispielen und Zitaten aus Gustav Gerber: Die Sprache als Kunst (Bromberg 1871) in Nietzsches Rhetorik-Vorlesung und in ‚Ueber Wahrheit und Lüge im aussermoralischen Sinne,’” Nietzsche-Studien 17: 350–368. Nicolai, Rudolf. 1867. Geschichte der gesammten griechischen Literatur. Ein Versuch. Magdeburg: Heinrichshofen’sche Buchhandlung. Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1999. Sämtliche Werke. Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 Einzelbänden, edited by G. Colli and M. Montinari, 3rd edn. München, Berlin and New York: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag and Walter de Gruyter. Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2003. Sämtliche Briefe. Kritische Studienausgabe in 8 Bänden, edited by G. Colli and M. Montinari, 2nd edn. München, Berlin, and New York: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag and Walter de Gruyter. Obstoj, Dietmar. 1985. Skepsis bei Nietzsche. PhD Thesis, University of Hannover. Parush, Adi. 1975/1976. “Nietzsche on the Skeptic’s Life,” The Review of Metaphysics 29: 523–542. Reuter, Sören. 2009. An der “Begräbnisstätte der Anschauung.” Nietzsches Bild- und Wahrnehmungstheorie in “Ueber Wahrheit und Lüge im aussermoralischen Sinne.” Basel: Schwabe. Roberty, Eugène de. 1887. L’ancienne et la nouvelle philosophie. Essais sur les lois générales du développement de la philosophie. Paris: F. Alcan. Sainte-Beuve, Charles-Augustin. 1880. Menschen des XVIII. Jahrhunderts nach den Causeries du Lundi, translated by I. Overbeck. Chemnitz: Ernst Schmeitzner.

452

SKEPTICISM

Sainte-Beuve, Charles-Augustin. 2014. Menschen des XVIII. Jahrhunderts. Übersetzt von Ida Overbeck, initiiert von Friedrich Nietzsche. Mit frisch entdeckten Aufzeichnungen von Ida Overbeck neu ediert von Andreas Urs Sommer. Berlin: Die Andere Bibliothek. Santini, Carlotta. 2013. “Nietzsche und der antike Skeptizismus,” Nietzsche-Studien 42: 368–374. Shaw, Tamsin. 2007. Nietzsche’s Political Skepticism. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press. Small, Robin. 2001. Nietzsche in Context. Aldershot and Burlington: Ashgate. Sommer, Andreas Urs. 1997. Der Geist der Historie und das Ende des Christentums. Zur “Waffengenossenschaft” von Friedrich Nietzsche und Franz Overbeck. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. Sommer, Andreas Urs. 2000. Friedrich Nietzsches “Der Antichrist”. Ein philosophischhistorischer Kommentar. Basel: Schwabe. Sommer, Andreas Urs. 2006. “Nihilism and Skepticism in Nietzsche.” In K. Ansell Pearson (ed.), A Companion to Nietzsche, 250–269. Malden: Blackwell. Sommer, Andreas Urs. 2007. “Skeptisches Europa? Einige Bemerkungen zum Sechsten Hauptstück: wir Gelehrten (Friedrich Nietzsche, Jenseits von Gut und Böse, Aphorismen 204–213),” Nietzscheforschung. Jahrbuch der Nietzsche-Gesellschaft 14: 67–78. Sommer, Andreas Urs. 2012. Kommentar zu Nietzsches “Der Fall Wagner”. “GötzenDämmerung” (= Historischer und kritischer Kommentar zu Friedrich Nietzsches Werken. Ed. by Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften. Vol. 6/1.) Berlin and Boston: Walter de Gruyter. Sommer, Andreas Urs. 2013. Kommentar zu Nietzsches “Der Antichrist”. “Ecce homo”. “Dionysos-Dithyramben”. “Nietzsche contra Wagner” (= Historischer und kritischer Kommentar zu Friedrich Nietzsches Werken. Ed. by Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften. Vol. 6/2.) Berlin and Boston: Walter de Gruyter. Spir, Afrikan. 1873. Denken und Wirklichkeit. Versuch einer Erneuerung der kritischen Philosophie. 2 vol. Leipzig: J. G. Findel. Spir, Afrikan. 1877. Denken und Wirklichkeit. Versuch einer Erneuerung der kritischen Philosophie. Zweite, umgearbeitete Auflage. 2 vol. Leipzig: J. G. Findel. Stingelin, Martin. 1996. “Unsere ganze Philosophie ist Berichtigung des Sprachgebrauchs”. Friedrich Nietzsches Lichtenberg-Rezeption im Spannungsfeld zwischen Sprachkritik (Rhetorik) und historischer Kritik (Genealogie). München: Wilhelm Fink. Teichmüller, Gustav. 1882. Die wirkliche und die scheinbare Welt. Neue Grundlegung der Metaphysik. Breslau: Koebner. Tongeren, Paul J. M. van. 1999. “Nietzsche’s Symptomatology of Skepticism.” In B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science. Nietzsche and the sciences II, 61–71. Dordrecht and Boston: Springer. Ueberweg, Friedrich. 1867. Grundriß der Geschichte der Philosophie von Thales bis auf die Gegenwart. Erster Theil: Das Alterthum. Dritte, berichtigte und ergänzte Auflage. Berlin: E. S. Mittler and Sohn. Vivarelli, Vivetta. 1998. Nietzsche und die Masken des freien Geistes. Montaigne, Pascal und Sterne. Würzburg: Königshausen and Neumann. Welshon, Rex. 2009. “Saying Yes to Reality: Skepticism, Antirealism, and Perspectivism in Nietzsche’s Epistemology,” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 37: 23–43.

FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE

453

Wotling, Patrick. 2006. “‘L’ultime scepticisme.’ La vérité comme régime d’interprétation,” Revue philosophique de la France et de l’étranger 131: 479–496. Zeller, Eduard. 1880. Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen Entwicklung. Dritter Theil, erste Abtheilung: Die nacharistotelische Philosophie. Dritte Auflage. Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland). Zeller, Eduard. 1881. Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen Entwicklung. Dritter Theil, zweite Abtheilung: Die nacharistotelische Philosophie. Dritte Auflage. Leipzig: Fues’s Verlag (R. Reisland).

CHAPTER THIRTY-THREE

Russell’s Logical Construction of the External World PETER J. GRAHAM

1 INTRODUCTION Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) was no skeptic. Like G.E. Moore (1873–1958), Russell agreed that we know about external, material objects like tables and trees. But Russell gave a very different explanation than Moore. In his highly influential 1914 Lowell Lectures, Our Knowledge of the External World, Russell “logically constructed” commonsense tables and trees from sense-data. In this chapter, I expound Russell’s logical construction of the external world.1 Most contemporary philosophers have only a passing knowledge of Russell’s work in metaphysics and epistemology, derived from reading his (still popular) 1912 Problems of Philosophy. That book presents a view of our knowledge of external, material objects as the result of an inference to the best explanation from awareness of the qualities and characteristics of our sensations. That is not the view of our knowledge of the external world that Russell presents in his Lowell Lectures and related papers. Instead he presents a view of sense-data that sounds odd to our contemporary ears. And instead of inferring the existence of tables and chairs, Russell will, where possible, “logically construct” external objects out of sense-data. Did Russell succeed, and thereby explain our knowledge of the external world? It will not surprise anyone to learn that the answer, as we will see, is no. Russell is then faced with a choice: abandon his view of knowledge of the external world as a logical construction out of sense-data or embrace radical skepticism. Despite its apparent failure, understanding Russell’s particular attempt is worth the effort. It has roots in the British empiricist tradition (especially Berkeley and Hume) as well as in Leibniz’s monadology. Russell’s originality then in turn had a substantial influence on Rudolf Carnap’s (1891–1970) own “logical construction of the world” (Carnap 1928) as well as a series of other “phenomenalisms.” These largely logical positivist views then set the terms of debate for W.V.O. Quine’s (1908–

RUSSELL’S LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION OF THE EXTERNAL WORLD

455

2000) explorations in “naturalized” epistemology. The spirit of Russell’s project is even still with us today, taken up by David Chalmers (2012), among others. I first present Russell’s view of sense-data. I then say what he means by a “logical construction.” I then turn to Russell’s logical construction of “things” and then of space. With his ontological machinery of sense-data and logical constructions in place, I then turn to his view of our knowledge of the external world as a logical construction of the “soft data” of tables and chairs out of the “hard data” of sensedata. I’ll then explain why Russell’s attempt falls short, for it needs to assume an unearned knowledge of other minds as well as the possibly unknowable existence of sensibilia. Though Russell’s project falls short, I conclude with a few achievements that, in the context of various debates with his contemporaries, led Russell to see value in his efforts nonetheless.

2 SENSE-DATA I begin with Russell’s view of sense-data. Suppose you and I walk up to a table in the park. We believe it existed before we saw it and will continue to exist after we walk away. We see the same thing, and any passerby would see it, too. Russell did not believe we immediately see the table. Think about your experiences as you approached and interacted with the table. From a distance it looked rather gray; you experienced a particular shade of color with a particular shape. As you got closer, you experienced a different shade of color with a larger shape. Russell believed these differing visible patches of shape and color—these differing “sensible objects”—are what we immediately sense in sense-perception: When I speak of a “sensible object,” it must be understood that I do not mean such a thing as a table, which is both visible and tangible, can be seen by many people at once, and is more or less permanent. What I mean is just that patch of color which is momentarily seen when [you] look at the table, or just that particular hardness which is felt when [you] press on it, or just that particular sound which is heard when [you] rap on it. (1914a: 83) Russell calls these “sensible objects” sense-data. Sense-data are the particular patches of color, shapes, sounds, and textures that we immediately sense, and may attend to, in sense-perception. Russell also calls them appearances or aspects of material objects.2 Russell relied upon the argument from perceptual variation to distinguish sensedata from material objects. As we move toward and around the table, our sense appearances change; from one location we are directly aware of something small and gray and from another something large and brown. But the picnic table does not change as our appearances change. Thus what we are immediately aware of in senseperception is not the same as the table. Since the material object stays the same but what we immediately sense changes, we do not immediately sense material objects (1912: ch. 2; 1914a: 76; 1959: 103).3 Russell attributed various properties to sense-data. First, sense-data have the properties they are sensed to have.4 Russell even believed “there are no such things

456

SKEPTICISM

as ‘illusions of sense’” (1914a: 85). Sensory acquaintance is a kind of direct, infallible relationship with objects of sense as they really are. To take a familiar example, if you press one finger against your eyeball you will “see double.” For Russell, this means you will sense two distinct visual sense-data where before you sensed one, and those two distinct visual sense-data have exactly the properties they appear to have; they are just as real as the data you sense when you are not pressing your eyeball. Your experience is not illusory; there really are two sense-data with just those properties.5 Secondly, sense-data are in constant flux. Outer experience is like watching a movie: we are viewing a series of distinct frames, each existing only for a brief moment before our eyes (1915: 96–97). Relatedly, Russell also rejected the view that the immediate objects of sense, though “external” to our minds, continue to exist when we shut our eyes or even turn our eyes in another direction (1915: 96). This belief is “a piece of audacious metaphysical theorizing; objects are not continually present to sensation, and it may be doubted whether they are there when they are not seen or felt” (1914a: 107). Echoes of Hume. Thirdly, Russell believed (and this may come as a surprise to contemporary readers) that sense-data are physical. “I believe . . . the immediate objects of [perception] are extra-mental, purely physical” (1914a: 71; 1914b: 111–113; 1915: 96–98). Sense-data are the objects of sensations, not sensations themselves.6 In sense-perception the mind is directly acquainted with external, non-mental, physical particulars.7 Many take the argument from perceptual variation to show that sense-data are mental; Russell did not. Sense-perception is then the perception, by sensation, of sense-data. Fourthly, Russell held that sense-data are private. (This may also come as a surprise, for if they are physical, how can they be private?) He argued as follows. First, a perceiver will perceive “an immensely complex three-dimensional world” of sensible objects at a time. (This is the subject’s complete, “perceived perspective.”)8 Second, there will always be differences, however slight, in different subjects’ points of view, and so there will always be differences, however slight, in the subjects’ immediate objects of sense-perception. Third, the places of objects “can only be constituted by the things in or around them” (for position in space is purely relative). If we see different objects, we see different spaces. Thus the three-dimensional space of one subject’s sensible objects and the three-dimensional space of another’s has no place in common. As a result, there “is absolutely nothing which is seen by two minds simultaneously” (1914a: 94–95; 1914b: 117; 1915: 103). We all perceive different “private worlds.”

3  LOGICAL CONSTRUCTIONS If we immediately perceive private, evanescent sense-data, then how do we know of public, continually existing material objects? In his 1912 Problems of Philosophy Russell argued that the commonsense hypothesis “that there really are objects independent of us, whose actions cause our sensations” best explains features of our sense-data: “every principle of simplicity urges us to adopt the natural view,

RUSSELL’S LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION OF THE EXTERNAL WORLD

457

that there really are objects other than ourselves and our sense-data which have an existence not dependent upon our perceiving them” (1912: 22–24). In 1914 Russell found this inference dubious and changed course: instead of inferring commonsense objects, Russell constructed them. Russell announced “the supreme maxim in scientific philosophizing. . . Wherever possible, logical constructions are to be substituted for inferred entities” (1914b: 115). In the case at hand, Russell was worried that if we construe material objects independently of sense-data, they will turn out to be unknowable “things-in-themselves.” So to prevent that, we must “construct” the material “things” of commonsense out of sense-data. Russell’s and Whitehead’s analysis of numbers in Principia Mathematica illustrates the idea (1910–1913). According to Russell and Whitehead, a number is a class of classes whose members bear a one-to-one relation to each other (Russell 1959: 70–71). Zero is the class of all empty classes; one is the class of all singletons; two is the class of all couples, etc. Numbers are then just “logical constructions” of equinumerous classes.9 When Russell turned to the external world, Russell’s and Whitehead’s success was his paradigm (1914b: 115–116). Just as Russell and Whitehead eliminated numbers as metaphysically distinct objects by Occam’s razor, Russell will “construct” the material “thing” of commonsense out of classes of sensible objects and thereby eliminate “things-in-themselves” (1914a: 72). Russell often put this “analysis” of material objects in terms of sense-data as a “reduction” or an “interpretation” of statements about material objects to classes of sense-data, where material objects are “functions” of sense-data (1914a: 85, 86; 1915: 97). The goal is to “reduce” commonsense “facts” to a “form in which nothing is assumed beyond sensible facts . . . to what is actually given in sense” (1914a: 85–86).10

4  THE LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION OF “THINGS” Begin with your own sense-data.11 This is your perceived perspective, your private world. Add to it any sense-data reported by testimony. Is that enough sensedata to construct material objects? Surely not, for what we know about material objects goes well beyond what you and I sense. Russell needs more sense-data. So he hypothesizes sensible objects that go beyond sense-data: sensibilia (1914a: 89). Imagine sitting next to another person in a room looking at the tables and chairs. Next imagine the perspective of a third person if a third person sat between the two of you (1914a: 95). Now imagine that no third person in fact sits between the two of you, but hold in place the “unperceived” perspective you just imagined. Russell hypothesizes the reality of this perspective and says this third perspective consists of sensibilia, not sense-data. They are not sense-data, for no one perceives them; sense-data are the relata of sense-perception. Sensibilia, on the other hand, are “objects which have the same metaphysical and physical status as sense-data without necessarily being data to any mind . . . a sensibile becomes a sense-datum by entering into the relation of acquaintance” (1914b: 110). Sensibilia are unperceived sense-data, the constituents of unperceived perspectives. Russell then hypothesizes

458

SKEPTICISM

an infinity of such unperceived perspectives to accompany perceived perspectives. Russell no longer faces a shortage of sensible objects. Russell then correlates sensible objects in one perspective with sensible objects in another. If you are looking at a table (so to speak), and I am too, then though you and I are sensing different sense-data in different three-dimensional worlds, our sense-data can be pretty darn similar for all that. And what’s true for tables is true for everything else we see. “Thus it is possible . . . to establish a correlation by similarity between a great many of the things of one perspective, and a great many of the things of another” (1914a: 95–96, emphasis added).12 (Whether this is in fact possible is an excellent question for another occasion.) Russell then constructs commonsense things out of classes of similar sensible objects:13 Given a [sensible] object in one perspective, form the [class] of all the [sensible] objects correlated with it in all the perspectives; that [class] can be identified with the momentary commonsense “thing.” Thus an aspect of a “thing” is a member of the [class] of aspects which is the “thing” at that moment. (1914a: 96) “A physical thing consists . . . of the whole set of its aspects . . . in all the different worlds; thus . . . a thing is a . . . set of aspects” (1914a: 117). What’s “really real” are all the aspects; the “thing” is merely a logical construction.14 A table is then not something over and above, or standing behind, all of its appearances; the table just is all of the appearances across perspectives. “The [table] . . . is a class of particulars, and what I see when I now look at the [table] is a member of this class” (1915: 102). Russell thereby razors away “things-in-themselves.” Russell can now explain how two people can “see” the same table (1914a: 83). When two people see two distinct but correlated aspects in their respective perspectives, they both see appearances of one thing (1914b: 118). So when two people immediately see two correlated sense-data, they “see” the same “thing” by immediately seeing distinct aspects of the same “thing.”

5  THE LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION OF SPACE If that’s how Russell constructs “things,” then how does he construct the public space, and so the public locations, of tables and trees? Russell’s idea is to construct a three-dimensional, “all-embracing” public space out of the system of perspectives (both perceived and unperceived), each with their own “internal” three-dimensional structure (1914a: 95, 97). In the all-embracing space, the perspectives are the points. The points then have a three-dimensional location within the system. Every sensedatum then has a three-dimensional location within the private perspective of which it is a part, and the three-dimensional location of the perspective within the system of perspectives. Russell here acknowledges the influence of Leibniz on his logical construction of space out of private perspectives, where each mind “looks out upon the world . . . from a point of view peculiar to itself” (1914a: 94). How does Russell spatially structure the system of perspectives? He places the perspectives near or far from one another based on their degrees of similarity and

RUSSELL’S LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION OF THE EXTERNAL WORLD

459

difference that turns on the similarity or difference of their constituent sensible objects. The more similar, the closer they are; the more different, the farther away: Suppose . . . we start from one [perspective] which contains the [circular, not elliptic] appearance of a . . . penny. We can then form a series of perspectives containing a graduated series of circular aspects of various sizes: for this purpose we only have to move (as we say) towards the penny or away from it. The perspectives in which the penny looks circular will be said to lie on a straight line in perspective space, and their order on this line will be that of the sizes of the circular aspects. (1914a: 97–98) And for any two similar perspectives, we can insert an intermediate perspective, thus making the all-embracing space continuous and three dimensional. Russell can specify the location of “things” within the space of physics. Take the line Russell just formed of circular aspects of the penny. Now take another straight line of aspects of the penny, “in which the penny is seen ends-on and looks like a straight line of a certain thickness . . . [T]hese two lines will meet in a certain place in perspective space, i.e. in a certain perspective.” Russell singles out that perspective as the location of the penny in perspective space (1914a: 98). The “thing” is located in the perspective that is at the intersection of two (or more) straight lines of perspectives that contain series of aspects of the “thing” (1914a: 98).15 A perspective in which a “thing” looks large (where the aspect of the thing perceived is large) is then closer to the “thing” than a perspective in which the “thing” looks small, for the perspective in which the “thing” looks larger is in fact “nearer to the perspective which is the place where the thing is.” “[T]he perspectives in which the penny looks big will be said to be nearer to the penny than those in which it looks small” (1914a: 98–99). Which means where you are—where “here” is, spoken in your voice—is the location of your current perspective. “Here,” spoken in my voice, is the place in perspective space occupied by my current perspective (1914a: 99–100). If the penny is located in the perspective in perspective space right next to your private perspective, then, on Russell’s view, you are in fact right next to the penny. Each aspect of a thing now has three locations (1914a: 100; 1914b: 117–119; 1959: 107–108). First, there is the “internal” three-dimensional location of the aspect in the private perspective of the perceiver. Second, there is the public location of the thing of which the aspect is a part; that place is where the aspect is at. Third, there is the public location from which the aspect is perceived. That place is the location of the perceiver’s perspective. Russell can now capture another commonsense point: we typically see material objects from a distance. The place from which I see a table (the place where I am) is distinct from the place where the table is at. If we see things by seeing aspects of things, and aspects of things have two locations in the system of perspectives, then the place from which I see a thing (the place of my perspective) is usually distinct from the place at which the thing I see resides (the perspective that is the location of the thing).16

460

SKEPTICISM

To summarize, Russell has constructed inter-subjective, public objects (things) in an inter-subjective, public space out of a plurality of subjective, private objects in subjective, private spaces, where the entire construction of material objects and locations in space turns on relations of similarity and difference among the plenum of sensible objects: “[We thereby] construct the one all-embracing space of physics” (1914a: 118–119).

6  EPISTEMOLOGY AS LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION If you have gotten this far, you are past the hard part. Now it is time to turn to epistemology. Russell adopted a largely non-skeptical methodology: he took it for granted that we know most of what we think we know; there is no point in trying to stand outside of our knowledge and evaluate all of it at once. Instead Russell claimed epistemology explains how we know what we know: our existing system of knowledge comprises the “data” that are the business of the philosopher to analyze. To “analyze” our system of knowledge, Russell distinguishes “hard data” from “soft data” by degrees of certainty. “Hard” data include instances of knowledge that resist “the solvent influence of critical reflection.” “Soft” data include instances of knowledge that, “under the operation [of critical reflection], become to our minds more or less doubtful” (1914a: 77–78). Hard data are rationally indubitable; soft data are not. Hard data need no justification; they are completely self-evident (1914a: 75, 77). Soft data, however, “though entitled to a certain level of respect,” are not “on a level with” hard data. Sorting our knowledge in two is the first step in analysis. The second step is to see to what extent the soft data may be derived from the hard data; this is the reconstructive step. Russell’s philosophical hope was that the hard data “may prove” the soft data “to be at least probable.” Sense-data fall within our hard data. “The immediate facts perceived by sight or touch or hearing do not need to be proved by argument, but are completely selfevident” (1914a: 75, 77). For Russell the “hardest of the hard data [include] . . . our own sense-data” (1914a: 78–79). “The more we reflect on these, the more we realize exactly what they are, and exactly what a doubt concerning them really means, the more luminously certain do they become” (1914a: 77–78).17 Russell also included “some facts of recent memory . . . introspective facts . . . spatial and temporal relations . . . and some facts of comparison . . . among our hard data” (1914a: 19). Among our soft data, Russell includes our knowledge of material objects. Knowledge of other minds also belongs in our soft data. And since belief in what is “reported by the testimony of others, including what we learn from books, is involved in the doubt as to whether other people have minds at all,” it too falls within our soft data (1914a: 79).18 Russell thus adopts a traditional, foundationalist ideal for our knowledge. Ideally, we start with our knowledge of sense-data and then reconstruct our knowledge of material objects, other minds, and the contents and veracity of testimony.

RUSSELL’S LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION OF THE EXTERNAL WORLD

461

7  AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL FAILURE? Pulling this off won’t be easy. “[T]he world from which our reconstruction is to begin is very fragmentary. The best we can say for it is that it is slightly more extensive than the world at which Descartes arrived by a similar process” (1914a: 79–80). Can Russell’s hypothetical construction show how we know about external objects from knowledge of sense-data? To put the issue in Russell’s words, now that we have “constructed a largely hypothetical picture of the world, which contains places and experienced facts . . . [do] we have any good reason to suppose that it is real?” (1914a: 100). Many epistemologists would love to see Russell pull the rabbit out of the hat. Russell clearly would love to do it, too.19 To do it, Russell would need to infer “the sense-data of other people, in favor of which there is the evidence of testimony, resting ultimately upon the analogical argument . . . and the ‘sensibilia’ which would appear from places where there happen to be no minds” (1914b: 116). Unfortunately, Russell does not think much of the analogical argument: “[T]he hypothesis that other people have minds . . . [is not] . . . susceptible of any very strong support from the analogical argument” (1914a: 101–103). But then Russell immediately adds: In actual fact, whatever we may try to think as philosophers, we cannot help believing in the minds of other people, so that the question whether our belief is justified has a merely speculative interest. And if it is justified, then there is no further difficulty of principle in the vast extension of our knowledge, beyond our own private data, which we find in science and common sense. (1914a: 103–104, emphasis added) If it is justified?! But we wanted to know whether it is justified. Even worse, the very idea of knowing about material bodies on the basis of testimony, and knowing testimony on the basis of other minds, puts the wrong foot forward: for we know about other minds on the basis of their behavior, and so of their bodies. If we didn’t already have some knowledge of material bodies that already goes beyond our knowledge of our own sense-data, then we’d be very hard pressed indeed to know about their behavior and so to know about their minds. (Cf. Soames (2014).) Even so, Russell does not abandon belief in other minds. Instead he retains it as a working hypothesis. For the hypothesis of other minds systematizes a vast body of facts and never leads to any consequences which there is reason to think false. There is therefore nothing to be said against its truth, and good reason to use it as a working hypothesis. When once it is admitted, it enables us to extend our knowledge of the sensible world by testimony, and thus leads to the system of private worlds we assumed in our hypothetical construction. (1914a: 103) If we hypothesize other minds, we can use their testimony to construct material objects and the space of physics. But then reconstruction as epistemology grinds to

462

SKEPTICISM

a halt, for we cannot just hypothesize other minds when reconstructing “soft data” from “hard data.” What about sensibilia? In OKEW he does not return to this question. Perhaps we know about these from experience, by knowing about what things would look like were I in a different position. But in RSDP he says the inference “raises much more serious questions” than the inference to other minds. Instead he says “I should regard these supposed appearances only in the light of a hypothetical scaffolding, to be used while the edifice of physics is being raised. . . . These ‘sensibilia’. . . are therefore to be taken rather as an illustrative hypothesis. . .” (1914b: 117). But then Russell’s epistemological optimism must grind to a complete halt indeed. Russell leaves us with two “working hypotheses” on which the entire logical construction of the external world rests. Dashed is the hope of justifying our knowledge of the external world from our sense-data, of deriving the “soft” data of “things” from the “hard data” of sense-perception. The foundationalist project in epistemology is just as disappointing as it is tempting.

8  CONCLUDING AFTERWORD: RUSSELL’S ACHIEVEMENTS? Russell’s logical reconstruction of the external world has often been read solely as an attempt to reconstruct our knowledge from more certain foundations. Russell certainly hoped that such a reconstruction might succeed, as we’ve seen. Part of the influence of OKEW was to inspire others to do just that. But Russell was clearly aware of the limitations of his own efforts. But if it so evidently fails as an epistemological reconstruction of our knowledge, a failure that invites the specter of radical skepticism, should we condemn Russell’s logical construction as a complete failure? Reconstructing our knowledge was not his sole motivation. He had at least four others. One was to explain how sense-data depend upon physiology: if the objects of sensation depend upon the state of our brains, then sense-data depend, in some sense, on physiology. Another was to reconcile physics and psychology: verification depends upon sense-data, but the world of physics radically departs from the appearances of the senses. The third was to reveal the structure of our knowledge and relations of dependence of one kind of knowledge on another, a point he emphasizes in the last lecture of OKEW. A fourth was to solve puzzles that arise from his direct realist view of sense-data as physical. Let me say a few words about this last motivation. Russell’s Cambridge teacher, G.F. Stout (1860–1944), also accepted the argument from perceptual variation. But he did not think the immediate object of perception could be physical. For one person may “see” a round sense-datum in one location, and another an elliptical sense-datum in that very same location, but it would be an impossible contradiction to suppose that an elliptical thing and a circular thing might exist in the same place at the same time.20

RUSSELL’S LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION OF THE EXTERNAL WORLD

463

Russell partly developed his hypothetical construction to avoid this problem for his direct realism21: What we call the different appearances of the same thing to different observers are each in a space private to the observer concerned. No place in the private world of one observer is identical with a place in the private world of another observer. There is therefore no question of combining the different appearances in the one place; and the fact that they cannot all exist in one place affords accordingly no ground whatever for questioning their physical reality. (1914b: 113–114) When concluding Lecture III of OKEW, Russell takes his hypothetical construction to have the advantage of dispensing with such arguments, and so rebutting arguments against our knowledge of the external world: Difficulties . . . [that arise] from the differences in the appearance which one physical object presents to two people at the same time . . . have made people doubtful how far objective reality could be known by sense at all, and have made them suppose that there were positive arguments against the view that it can be so known. Our hypothetical construction meets these arguments. (1914a: 104) Russell acknowledges that the results of his reconstructive efforts are somewhat meager, failing to achieve his ambitious foundationalist aims. But he finds his four other results worth the price of admission. For his hypothetical construction shows that the account of the world given by common sense and physical science can be interpreted in a way which is logically unobjectionable, and finds a place for all the data, both hard and soft. It is this hypothetical construction, with its reconciliation of psychology and physics, which is the chief outcome of our discussion. (1914a: 104)

NOTES 1. In preparing this chapter, I benefited in particular from reading Charles Fritz (1952), Peter Hylton (1992), Chris Pincock (2006), Gregory Landini (2011), Gary Hatfield (2013), and Scott Soames (2014). I am grateful to support from the Templeton Foundation during a visit to Oxford University where I drafted this chapter. I am also grateful to comments from the editors on the penultimate draft that led to improvements. 2. On the origins of the phrase “sense-data,” see Hatfield (2014: 951–952). The first time G.E. Moore used the phrase was in his 1905 paper “The Nature and Reality of the Objects of Perception.” 3. The argument appears prominently in Hume, Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, 1758, sec. XII. For criticisms of the argument and related arguments, see J.L. Austin (1962), Frank Jackson (1977), and Michael Huemer (2001). 4. Witness C.D. Broad: “All of the objects . . . that are directly perceived by anyone from anywhere under any conditions must certainly exist and have the qualities that we perceive them to have at least as long as we perceive them” (1914–1915: 232).

464

SKEPTICISM

5. Even dreaming involves veridical sense-perception in Russell’s sense. “Objects of sense, even when they occur in dreams, are the most indubitably real objects known to us” (1914a: 85–86). The error we make in dreaming is not that we perceive or sense things that are not there, but that we make false predictions about other sensedata we are likely to perceive. Dreams, unlike waking experience, are irregular and unpredictable from experience. Echoes of Berkeley. 6. The distinction between the act and the object of sensation was advanced by Samuel Alexander (1859–1938) and was fundamental to G.E. Moore’s paper, “The Refutation of Idealism” (1903). In his later “neutral monism” phase, Russell abandons the distinction, preferring to construct even mental acts out of sense-data (what he later calls percepts). 7. For discussion of Russell on acquaintance, see Roderick Chisholm (1977) and David Pears (1981). 8. Russell is of course aware of the other senses. And so our private worlds are even more complex: “there are several spaces for each person according to the different senses which can be called spatial” (1914a: 109). Russell emphasizes the space and the role experience plays in correlating locations in visual space with locations in tactile space. 9. Russell acknowledges Frege’s 1884 priority (1959: 70). Russell’s prime motive was ontological, to “get rid of numbers as metaphysical entities” (1959: 71). 10. Russell had a related semantic motive: in so far [as] . . . common sense is verifiable, it must be capable of interpretation in terms of actual sense-data alone. The reason for this is simple. Verification consists always in the occurrence of an expected sense-datum. . . . Now if an expected sense-datum constitutes a verification, what was asserted must have been about sense-data; or, at any rate, if part of what was asserted was not about sense-data, then only the other part has been verified. (1914a: 88–89, emphasis added)

Here Russell seems to endorse the verifiability theory of meaning. Soames (2014) makes a big deal out of this in his interpretation of Russell. And it seems to follow from Russell’s doctrine that understanding requires acquaintance. However, Russell himself doesn’t make much of this in Our Knowledge of the External World or even in RSDP or UCM. Russell seems more driven by ontological considerations. Soames also thinks this supports reading Russell as a phenomenalist, with counterfactual analyses of material object statements. See Pincock (2006) for some critical discussion of Soames. I remain agnostic. For recent scholarly discussion of Russell on logical construction, see also Bernard Linsky (2014).

11. Following Russell, for the sake of simplicity I shall restrict the discussion in what follows to visual sense-data: colors, shapes, sizes, and distances. 12. How do we know that sensible objects across perspectives are similar? We cannot sense sensible objects outside of our own private perspectives, and so we cannot know this by sense-perception. But, Russell thinks, we can know it by testimony. I shall return to this, for it raises obvious difficulties for his epistemological project. 13. I table two important issues that Russell treats at some length. The first involves unusual viewing circumstances, such as wearing blue-tinted glasses or physiological abnormalities, like being sick (1914a: 85–88). The second involves sense-data of bodily motion: when I verify a table by walking up to it, not only my visual

RUSSELL’S LOGICAL CONSTRUCTION OF THE EXTERNAL WORLD

465

sense-data change, but so do my tactile sense-data and my sensations of my bodily movement. Thus to say “that is a table” is not only to talk about visual sense-data, but correlated sense-data of muscular and bodily movement (1914a: 84–85). 14. This is how Russell constructs material objects in Lecture III of Our Knowledge of the External World. But in Lecture IV he notes that resemblance is clearly not sufficient for two aspects being members of the same thing: “as the Comedy of Errors illustrates, we may be led astray if we judge by resemblance. This shows that something more is involved for two different things may have any degree of likeness up to exact similarity” (1914a: 113). He then argues that continuity won’t do either. He then seems to settle on a different criterion altogether: conformity to the laws of physics. “Things are those series of aspects which obey the laws of physics” (1914a: 115–116). 15. For discussion, see Gary Hatfield (2014: 959–960). 16. Russell relied on these two locations to construct a six-dimensional space of perspectives: each aspect has a three-dimensional location as the place from which the aspect is perceived, and another three-dimensional location at which the aspect resides. Aspects then have six-dimensional locations within the system of perspectives. 17. Russell believed it would be “pathological” to doubt our sense-data (1914a: 78). 18. Without knowledge of other minds, “testimony heard or read is reduced to noises and shapes, and cannot be regarded as evidence of the facts which it reports” (1914b: 89–90). 19. “A complete application of the method which substitutes constructions for inferences would exhibit matter wholly in terms of sense-data, and even, we may add, of the sense-data of a single person, since sense-data of others cannot be known without some element of inference. This, however, must remain for the present an ideal. . . It would give me the greatest satisfaction to be able to dispense with it, and thus establish physics on a solipsistic basis” (1914b: 116). 20. Stout (1908–1909: 238). This debate is discussed at length in Nassim (2008). See also Hatfield (2013). 21. Russell was partly inspired here by T. Percy Nunn (1909–1910).

REFERENCES Austin, J. L. 1962. Sense and Sensibilia. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Broad, C. D. 1914–1915. “Phenomenalism,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 15: 227–251. Carnap, Rudolf. 1928. Der Logische Aufbau der Welt. Leipzig: Felix Meiner Verlag. Chalmers, David. 2012. Constructing the World. New York: Oxford University Press. Chisholm, Roderick. 1977. “On the Nature of Acquaintance: A Discussion of Russell’s Theory of Knowledge.” In G. Nakhnikian (ed.), Bertrand Russell’s Philosophy, 47–56. London: Duckworth. Hatfield, Gary. 2013. “Psychology, Epistemology, and the Problem of the External World: Russell and Before.” In E. Reck (ed.), The Historical Turn in Analytic Philosophy, 171– 200. New York: Palgrave MacMillan Press.

466

SKEPTICISM

Hatfield, Gary. 2014. “Perception and Sense-Data.” In M. Beaney (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic Philosophy, 948–973. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Huemer, Michael. 2001. Skepticism and the Veil of Perception. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Hume, David. 1758. Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Edinburgh. Hylton, Peter. 1992. Russell, Idealism, and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Jackson, Frank. 1977. Perception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Landini, Gary. 2011. Russell. New York: Routledge. Linsky, Bernard. 2014. “Russell’s Theory of Descriptions and the Idea of Logical Construction.” In M. Beaney (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic Philosophy, 407–429. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Moore, G. E. 1903. “The Refutation of Idealism,” Mind 12: 433–453. Moore, G. E. 1905–1906. “The Nature of Reality and the Objects of Perception” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 6: 68–127. Nassim, Omar. 2008. Bertrand Russell and the Edwardian Philosophers: Constructing the World. New York: Palgrave MacMillan Press. Nunn, T. Percy. 1909–1910. “Are Secondary Qualities Independent of Perception?” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 10: 191–231. Pears, David. 1981. “The Function of Acquaintance in Russell’s Philosophy,” Synthese 46: 149–166. Pincock, Chris. 2006. “Rejoinder to Soames,” Russell 26: 77–86. Quine, W. V. O. 1969. “Epistemology Naturalized.” In his Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, 69–90. New York: Columbia University Press. Russell, Bertrand. 1912. Problems of Philosophy. London: Williams and Norgate. Russell, Bertrand. 1914a. Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy. Chicago and London: Open Court. Russell, Bertrand. 1914b. “The Relation of Sense-Data to Physics,” Scientia 16. Reprinted in Russell 1918. Russell, Bertrand. 1915. “The Ultimate Constituents of Matter,” The Monist 25: 399–417. Reprinted in Russell 1918. Russell, Bertrand. 1918. Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays. London: Allen & Unwin. Russell, Bertrand. 1959. My Philosophical Development. London: Allen & Unwin. Russell, Bertrand and Alfred North Whitehead. 1910–1913. Principia Mathematica, 3 volumes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Soames, Scott. 2014. The Analytic Tradition in Philosophy, volume 1: The Founding Giants. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Stout, G. F. (1908–1909). “Are Presentations Mental or Physical? A Reply to Professor Alexander,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 9: 226–247.

CHAPTER THIRTY-FOUR

Moore and Mooreanism ANNALISA COLIVA

1 INTRODUCTION In this chapter I concentrate on G. E. Moore’s “Proof of an External World,”1 which first appeared in 1939. Since then, it has been the object of different and contrasting interpretations and is nowadays at the core of a large debate in epistemology. In Section 2, I present the paper to place it in its proper context. In Sections 3–5, I consider some influential interpretations of it. In so doing I assess all of them from a historical point of view, pointing out how they are all somewhat wanting as renditions of Moore’s strategy. Finally, in Section 6, I put forward my own interpretation of it.

2  MOORE’S PROOF OF AN EXTERNAL WORLD Moore’s proof of an external world is often presented without mentioning its original context and as if it was directed against skepticism about the external world. However, “Proof of an External World” (PEW) is a long essay divided into two parts. In the first one, Moore takes his lead from Kant’s famous observation, in the Critique of Pure Reason: It still remains a scandal to philosophy . . . that the existence of things outside of us . . . must be accepted merely on faith, and that, if anyone thinks good to doubt their existence, we are unable to counter his doubts by any satisfactory proof. (Kant 1929: B xxxix ) Moore claims that Kant was not able to give a successful proof of the existence of things outside of us and that his own proof will remedy the situation. However, before presenting it, he introduces a series of terminological distinctions, meant to clarify the meaning of the expression ‘things outside of us’. According to Moore, the philosophical tradition in general, and Kant in particular, erroneously believe that the following expressions are equivalent: A. ‘Things outside of us’. B. ‘External things’.

468

SKEPTICISM

C. ‘Things which are external to our minds’. D. ‘Things which can be met in space’. E. ‘Things presented in space’. According to Kant, all these locutions are synonymous because they make reference to phenomena as opposed to noumena. The former are necessarily presented in space—the pure form of sensibility that allows us to perceive outer things. In contrast, according to Moore, these expressions are not equivalent because he does not subscribe to Kant’s transcendentalism, either about empirical objects, or about space. According to Moore, there may be things that are presented in space and yet cannot be met within it. For instance, pains or itches are presented in a part of one’s body, yet cannot be met in space. Moreover, according to Moore, animals’ pains are external to our minds, yet cannot be met in space. Since, for Moore, ‘physical object’ means “an object which exists independently of being perceived by us (human beings),” he thinks that by giving a proof of the existence of physical objects he will ipso facto prove that there are things that can be met in space and that are external to us. However, this latter claim is prima facie problematical. For Moore himself points out that animals’ pains are external to human minds as we cannot perceive them. Still, it does not follow from this that they are what we intuitively regard as physical objects. Thus, the correct claim is that a physical object is everything that we could perceive, which, however, exists independently of the fact that we actually perceive it. With this clarification in hand, let us now turn to the proof itself. By holding up his hands in front of himself and in clear view, Moore makes a gesture with the right hand and says: (1) Here is a hand. Then, making the same gesture with the left hand, he says: (2) Here is another. He then concludes: (3) There are at present two human hands. Since the conclusion concerns the existence of objects which can be met in space, Moore claims that (3) entails (4) There are physical objects. and hence, that he has proved (5) There is an external world. Still, it is clear that an idealist could concede both premises—(1) and (2)—and the intermediate conclusion—(3)—and yet deny that that entails that there are physical objects—(4)—, if by ‘physical object’ one meant objects existing independently of being perceived by us. Hence, an idealist would not take Moore’s performance to show the truth of (5).2

MOORE AND MOOREANISM

469

Moreover, it must be noticed that up to this point nothing has been done to show that the premises are known to be true and are not merely assumed to be such; nor to show that the conclusion of the argument is known. Hence, up to now, Moore’s proof has no bearing whatsoever against skepticism. In fact, some years later, Moore himself maintained, in response to his critics, that his proof was directed merely at an idealist and not against a skeptic (1942: 668). For, in his opinion, in order to take issue with a skeptic he should have proved that he knew its premises, and therefore, that he was not dreaming. Yet, Moore himself acknowledged (1959a: 149) that he could not have proved such a thing. For all his evidence would have been compatible with the hypothesis that he might be dreaming of it. Why is it that most readers of Moore’s paper have taken his proof as directed at a skeptic?3 Furthermore, given Moore’s explicit pronouncements, is this reading legitimate? In order to answer both these questions, we have to take into consideration the sequel of Moore’s paper, where he claims that his proof is a rigorous one because: (a) The premises are different from the conclusion; (b) they are known to be true and are not merely believed to be true; (c) the conclusion really follows from the premises. For, given (b) and the fact that the inference is valid, it follows that also the conclusion of the argument is known.4 Hence, if it is true that Moore knew that there were two hands, it follows that he also knew that there was an external world, and this is clearly an anti-skeptical thesis. This, however, raises the following issue: how could Moore maintain that he knew that his premises were true, from which it follows that he also knew the conclusion of his argument, while holding that he was unable to prove that he knew them, and that that was necessary in order convincingly to oppose skepticism? The most charitable interpretation of Moore’s claim, which can also explain the interest Moore’s work stirred in other philosophers such as Wittgenstein, is as follows. If one is a philosopher of common sense, it does not matter how much a skeptic can press one to give a justification for one’s claims to knowledge. Hence, it does not matter if one does not know how one knows that here there are two human hands, or, more precisely (cf. Section 5), if one cannot prove that one knows it. For such ignorance is entirely consistent with the fact that one does know such a thing. In support of this interpretation, consider what Moore in effect writes in PEW: I certainly did at the moment [in which the proof was given] know that which I expressed by the combination of certain gestures with saying the words “There is one hand and here is another.” . . . How absurd it would be to suggest that I did not know it, but only believed it, and that perhaps it was not the case! (1959a: 146) I can know things, which I cannot prove; and among things which I certainly did know, even if (as I think) I could not prove them, were the premises of my . . . [proof]. (1959a: 150)

470

SKEPTICISM

We will come back to this issue in Section 6. Before doing so, however, let us now turn to some influential interpretations and assessments of Moore’s proof.

3  THOMPSON CLARKE AND BARRY STROUD: AT THE ORIGINS OF CONTEXTUALISM Thompson Clarke (1972) introduces a distinction between plain talk and philosophical talk. In his view, the former is what is produced within all our usual linguistic practices, with their characteristic embedment in non-linguistic activities. The latter, in contrast, is what is produced while doing philosophy. Philosophical talk extrapolates from any ordinary practice and from non-linguistic activities, to consider language in its own right. While in plain talk the conditions of meaningful discourse are subject to pragmatic constraints—such as relevance, and other forms of appropriateness (see Grice 1957)—in philosophical talk these limitations are removed and words are considered as such. Any well-formed sentence of natural language can be subject to philosophical analysis. A philosophical question, like the skeptical question about the foundations of our knowledge, is formulated within philosophical talk and, according to Clarke, is perfectly legitimate, since it satisfies a deep intellectual need that is not fulfilled by any of its counterparts in plain talk (1972: 292). Clarke then points out that if Moore’s use is taken to be part of plain talk, it reveals a philosophical lobotomy—that is, a sort of split-brain in one’s philosophical pronouncements—since Moore means to oppose philosophical theses. If, in contrast, it is taken as part of philosophical talk, it is dogmatic, since it does not face the skeptical challenge of explaining how he knows that there are two hands where he seems to see them (and consequently, that there is an external world) and simply counters “Because I do.” Barry Stroud’s interpretation of Moore’s proof closely resembles Clarke’s. However, according to Stroud, Moore’s proof is given within plain talk. If so, it is a good proof, but, obviously, it cannot have any anti-skeptical bearing, since it does not even face the skeptical challenge. From the inside, it is a good proof because it appeals to the greater degree of certainty possessed by the premises of Moore’s argument over the degree of certainty possessed by those premises, which, within plain talk, would be necessary in order to maintain that he may only be dreaming of having two hands. Still, none of this shows that a doubt about Moore’s knowledge of his premises is impossible. Hence, the proof fails to address the philosophical issue and, for this reason, when it is considered from the outside, in the way in which confronting the skeptical challenge requires, it cannot be successful. Hence, it is possible to doubt from the inside only when there are actual reasons to doubt that p, or when there are stronger reasons to doubt it than the ones one can produce in favor of one’s claim to know that p. Since, however, with respect to the premises of Moore’s proof there are no such reasons—or at any rate, they are not stronger than the ones in favor of holding those premises—any form of skepticism appears, from the inside, totally misguided.

MOORE AND MOOREANISM

471

From the outside, in contrast, any doubt is legitimate, inasmuch as it is possible or conceivable. Thus, it is perfectly right to doubt that the premises of Moore’s argument are known because one can raise hypotheses, such as the one from dreaming, that would call into question any supposed instance of sensory-based knowledge regarding physical objects. Therefore, Moore, by failing to show why a merely possible doubt—like the Cartesian one—is illegitimate or, in effect, no doubt at all, does not address the skeptic, whose challenge is raised at the purely philosophical level. According to Stroud, Moore’s strategy is wanting because it provides no account of why our knowledge from the inside is legitimate and because it offers no diagnosis and solution (or dissolution) of what, in his view, the skeptical mistake would amount to. This way, Stroud introduces a sort of evaluative lobotomy that, however, can help clarify the relationship between ordinary and philosophical discourse. This in turn is, in Stroud’s view, what is really at stake in the debate over skepticism and common sense. From such a perspective, Moore’s proof is interesting because—its failure notwithstanding—it contradicts skepticism while being compatible with it. It contradicts it because it claims that we do have knowledge both of its premises and of its conclusion. Still, it is compatible with it because such a claim is made in a context other than the skeptical one. Similar considerations would apply in the other direction too—that is, skepticism contradicts common sense, yet it is compatible with it.5 Hence, on Stroud’s view, Moore’s mistake consists in failing to appreciate that, if this is the right description of the relationship between ordinary and philosophical discourse, then his negation of the skeptical thesis cannot be a confutation of skepticism. Thus, “the price of philosophical skepticism’s immunity . . . would be the corresponding immunity of all our ordinary assertions to philosophical attack” (Stroud 1984: 127). Let us assess Clarke’s and Stroud’s interpretations. In an important letter to Malcolm (1993: 214), Moore claims that he is using the verb ‘to know’ according to its ordinary meaning. Furthermore, he maintains that his use of ‘I know’ in relation to the premises of his proof is meant to engage with his philosophical opponents, contrary to what Stroud says.6 Hence, on the one hand, according to Moore, it is with an ordinary conceptual repertoire that one enters philosophical discourse, contrary to what Clarke claims. On the other, in his view, there is no separation between philosophy and common sense, in such a way that statements respectively made in those different contexts could contradict each other yet somehow be compatible with one another, as opposed to what Stroud holds. These two claims together amount to the view that, according to Moore, the concept of knowledge is not context-sensitive.7 Finally, and most importantly, according to Moore’s own understanding of skepticism, the latter arises when the issue of showing how one can know what one claims to know, and thus prove that one does indeed know it, is raised. To ask such a question does not produce a change of context according to Moore. Nor does it show the context-sensitivity of knowledge. On the contrary, it depends on making use of an invariant concept and yet asking a different question—not whether

472

SKEPTICISM

it is known that p, but, rather, how one can prove that p is known (if indeed it is). Moore, moreover, agrees that he is not able to answer such a question. Yet, as we have repeatedly seen, he refuses to agree with the skeptic that, because one cannot answer it, it follows that one does not know that p. This, however, is not simply a dogmatic and unphilosophical position, as Clarke claims.8 Rather, it depends on a specific conception of the relationship between the conditions of knowledge and their obtainment and the possibility of proving that they are in fact satisfied.

4  MOORE AND HUMEAN SKEPTICISM: WRIGHT’S INTERPRETATION OF THE PROOF Crispin Wright (1985) puts forward another reading of Moore’s proof. According to him, it is important to make explicit the grounds on which Moore claims to know the premises of his proof in the circumstances in which the proof was offered. As is apparent and as Moore himself made clear, in those circumstances, the assertion “Here is a hand” was based on his sensory evidence.9 According to Wright, if Moore’s grounds are made explicit, it becomes immediately evident why the proof fails. He reconstructs it as follows: (i) A given proposition describes the salient aspects of my experience at the time in question; (ii) I have a hand; (iii) Therefore, there is an external world. In fact (I) amounts to saying that there is a proposition that correctly describes the relevant aspects of Moore’s experience in the circumstances in which his proof was given, for example, “I am perceiving (what I take to be) my hand.” According to Wright, (II) is then inferred from (I), and (III) follows from (II) since a hand is a physical object. Moreover, given that the premises are known, according to Moore, so would be the conclusion. However, on Wright’s view, it is clear that (I) can ground (II) only if one can already take it for granted that one’s experience is being produced by causal interaction with physical objects. Hence, any sensory experience can warrant a belief about empirical objects only if it is already assumed that there is an external world. However, in order justifiably to go from (I) to (II), one needs already to have a warrant for (III). Hence, the proof is epistemically circular (or question-begging); antecedent and independent warrant for (III) is needed in order to have warrant for (II) in the first place,10 given one’s current sensory experience, as described in (I). Ironically enough, then, Moore’s proof—on Wright’s understanding of it—rather than being a response to skepticism, instantiates the template of a powerful form of skepticism, that Wright calls “Humean,” as opposed to “Cartesian.” The difference between these two forms of skepticism resides in the fact that while the latter makes play with uncongenial scenarios, such as the hypothesis that one may be the victim of a sustained and lucid dream, whereby one would be systematically unable to tell whether one is dreaming or not, the former does not. From such a starting point,

MOORE AND MOOREANISM

473

the Cartesian skeptic then claims that for any specific empirical proposition we take ourselves to know on the basis of our sensory experience, it is metaphysically possible that it be produced in a non-standard way. From the impossibility of excluding that this is the case, he takes it to follow that we do not know any such empirical proposition and, as a consequence, that we do not know (III)—that there is an external world (cf. Wright 1985, 2004; Coliva 2008, 2010b). Humean skepticism, in contrast, merely draws on an epistemic gap between having a certain kind of evidence and warrantedly forming a belief about a domain that goes beyond what one’s experience immediately testifies to—a gap that is bridged by inferences such as the (I)–(II)–(III) argument just offered, or indeed by inductive inferences—whence the title of “Humean” for this form of skepticism. For, in order warrantedly to go from the first premise, which is about one’s sensory experience, to the second, which is about an object whose existence is independent of one’s experience, warrant for the conclusion of the argument—that there is an external world—must be independently available. Since, however, by skeptical lights, there is no way of getting such an independent warrant, the argument fails to provide warrant for its conclusion. Wright calls this phenomenon “failure of transmission of warrant.” For the need of an antecedent warrant for the conclusion in order warrantedly to go from (I) to (II) prevents the warrant one may after all have for (I)—if somehow the skeptic was wrong in claiming that independent warrant for (III) could not be attained—from being transmitted to (II) and thus to (III). That is to say, Moore’s proof cannot give one either a first warrant to believe (III), or further epistemic support for the warrant one might already have to believe it.11 If Wright’s reading of Moore’s proof were correct, it would be devastating. For, Moore could insist that despite being unable to prove that he knew his premises he knew them, and—given the principle of closure—he would indeed know the conclusion. Yet, he would not be in a position to acquire knowledge of the conclusion, or indeed somehow enhance it, by running his proof. Interpreted thus, Moore’s proof would simply be no proof whatever of (III)—namely, that there is an external world. For, characteristically, proofs are means that allow us to extend our knowledge from their premises to their conclusions and thus provide us with reasons for first believing them, or else with reasons that enhance our epistemic support for believing them. On Wright’s reading of it, in contrast, Moore’s proof would dramatically fail to do so. Now, two things are worth pointing out. First, things might be different if Wright’s attack were meant to impugn merely Moore’s ability to redeem his knowledge of (III), as Wright’s more recent discussions of Moore’s proof seem sometimes to suggest (2004: 167, 210–211; 2007), and if this de-coupling could be matched by endorsing an externalist notion of knowledge (and/or warrant). In such a case Moore’s proof could establish that its conclusion is known—since its premises would be—and yet, just as Moore held, fail at proving, against skepticism, that either the premises or the conclusion be known. We will come back to this issue in Section 6. Second, Jim Pryor has recently challenged the correctness of Wright’s views upon the structure of empirical warrants. If Pryor were right, it would certainly come as a relief for the proof’s prospects of success. Let us now turn to a discussion of this rejoinder.

474

SKEPTICISM

5  MOORE’S COMEBACK: PRYOR’S DOGMATIST INTERPRETATION Jim Pryor (2004) claims that the proof is fine, from an epistemological point of view. In particular, it does not exhibit failure of warrant transmission. For, on Pryor’s understanding of the structure of perceptual warrants, it suffices, in order to possess such a warrant, merely to have a certain course of experience while lacking any reason to doubt that the experience is veridical, at least when perceptually basic beliefs are at stake.12 Hence, there is no need, on his view, to possess an independent warrant for the conclusion of that argument, namely, that there is an external world. Pryor, however, thinks that although Moore’s proof is perfectly in order from an epistemic point of view, it is not successful against a skeptic. In particular, it is dialectically ineffective for, according to him, a skeptic will think it is (likely) false13 that there is an external world. For such a reason he will not consider Moore’s experience as of a hand in front of him sufficient for warrant of the corresponding empirical belief. Starting with an unwarranted premise, the proof is not able to confer warrant upon its conclusion and hence to convince a skeptic that there is an external world. Yet, according to Pryor, skeptical doubts are not legitimate. He holds that skepticism is a “disease” we should not catch, or else cure ourselves of (Pryor 2004: 368). Is this interpretation correct? In fact, Moore never explicitly argued for the view about perceptual warrants that Pryor sees as the key to the proof’s epistemic success. No doubt he made explicit the grounds of his proof—that is, the fact that he believed its premises on the basis of his perceptual evidence. However, he never said that that would be sufficient, by itself, to give one a warrant—or indeed knowledge—of certain propositions about physical objects such as “Here is a hand.” On the contrary, one of the main tenets of Moore’s philosophy of perception is his appeal to sense data. Now, it merits emphasis that any such account would entail a conception of perceptual warrant (and therefore knowledge) as dependent on some extra element beside the occurrence of the sense-datum itself—at least unless the latter were taken to be identical with some part or other of a physical object (a view considered and rejected in Moore 1959a: §iv). Such an extra element would presumably be the (warranted) assumption that the experience one is having be produced by causal interaction with physical objects. Indeed, in “Four Forms of Scepticism” (FFS), Moore explicitly said that he agreed with Russell that propositions about specific material objects in one’s surroundings are not known immediately, but always on the basis of some “analogical or inductive argument” (1959b: 226). Thus, it is almost certain that he did not endorse in PEW14 the conception of the structure of empirical warrants (or of knowledge) that Pryor proposes. Moreover, it should be kept in mind that Moore raised the issue of having to prove that he was not dreaming because he realized that that was what stood in the way of his opponent’s recognition that the premises of his proof were known. If so, however, Pryor’s and Moore’s understanding of what would be needed to confront a skeptic would dramatically diverge. For, according to Pryor’s account,

MOORE AND MOOREANISM

475

it would suffice simply to remind him that, in order to possess a perceptual warrant for “Here is a hand,” it is enough to have a certain course of experience when there is in fact no reason to doubt that there is an external world and the conditions are such that no doubt of that kind is reasonable. In Moore’s view, in contrast, it should be proved that, in those circumstances, such a doubt would be unreasonable. Indeed Moore thought he could make some gesture in that direction, and accordingly said that the grounds for thinking that he might have been dreaming of his hand were weaker than the ones available to him to claim knowledge of his premises, or even totally non-existent. True, this move is unsuccessful, once coupled with other things Moore says. For assume it is legitimate to distinguish between, on the one hand, knowledge and the conditions of its obtainment and, on the other, the ability to prove that they are satisfied, as Moore claims. Assume, further, as he argues, that the skeptical challenge concerns such a proof. Then, merely to insist that one does know that there are hands and that, given one’s evidence, the hypothesis that one may be dreaming is less supported, or even unsupported by it, can’t exclude the metaphysical possibility that it be the case. Hence, Moore did not succeed in proving that he was not dreaming. Accordingly, he also failed to prove that he knew the premises of his proof, contrary to what he thought he should have done in order to counter a skeptic. Still, it is clear that he characterized the skeptical position not as a “disease” but as a genuine challenge that arises out of asking a kind of question that cannot be answered by simply exposing the structure of empirical warrants. It is to such a question and to its legitimacy that we shall now turn.

6  HAVING KNOWLEDGE AND BEING ABLE TO PROVE THAT ONE DOES In order to assess Moore’s proof from a historical point of view, we need to consider the issue of the relationship between, on the one hand, having knowledge and the conditions of its obtainment and, on the other, the possibility of proving that those conditions do in fact obtain and thus that one really has that knowledge one takes oneself to have, in such a way as to be able rationally to claim or redeem it. The “How do you know?” kind of question that the skeptic typically asks is meant to raise that issue. Hence, that question, when voiced by a skeptic, is not a simple request of exhibiting the grounds of one’s knowledge. Rather, it is meant as a request of giving a proof of what one claims to know. To exemplify once more with the premises of Moore’s proof, Moore can say that his ground for holding that there is a hand in front of him is his current visual experience. A skeptic, however, is precisely questioning Moore’s ability to prove that his experience is indeed veridical in those circumstances. Hence, according to Moore, the skeptic holds the following view of the relationship between having knowledge and being able rationally to redeem it: (1) If you cannot show how you know that p—that is, prove that you do know it—and cannot, therefore, rationally redeem your claim to knowledge, you do not know that p.

476

SKEPTICISM

Moore, however, thinks that (1) does not hold because he was in fact endorsing a somewhat externalist conception of knowledge.15 The caveat is apposite because he never proposed anything that would suggest his leaning toward one of the views that, later on, would have been qualified as externalist—for example, reliabilism, relevant alternative theories, counterfactual analyses, etc. Still, he introduced a kind of move, which would then become the typical externalist maneuver, that is, the contention that one can know that p even if one is unable to prove that one does. The evidence in Moore’s writings that he would deny (1) is plenty.16 For instance, in PEW, he quite explicitly said that neither he nor anyone else may have been able to prove the truth of his premises: [If what is required is a general proof for the existence of physical objects], (t)his, of course, I haven’t given; and I do not believe it can be given: if that is what is meant by proof of the existence of external things, I do not believe that any proof of the existence of external things is possible. (1959a: 149) Yet, he was adamant that such an impossibility would not have impaired the fact that he did know them. To repeat the relevant quotation: I can know things which I cannot prove; and among the things which I certainly did know, even if (as I think) I could not prove them, were the premises of my . . . [proof]. (1959a: 150) In the recent literature on skepticism, it is often remarked that if one makes this kind of move, one will then face some “crisis of intellectual conscience” or “angst.”17 That is to say, it is conceded that one may know that p, even if one is unable to prove it. Yet, one would not be able to reassure oneself that one does. Skepticism, on this reading, would not directly challenge one’s knowledge but, rather, one’s ability rationally to redeem it. Hence, skepticism would not be characterized by (1), but by: (2) If you cannot show how you know that p—that is prove that you know it— and cannot therefore, rationally redeem your claim to knowledge, you may know that p, but you cannot reassure yourself of it. Thus, skepticism brings about an “intellectual crisis,” at least prima facie, because, even supposing that through a gift of nature, as it were, we knew that p, we would also feel the intellectual need to be able to prove that we really do. The problem then becomes that of explaining the sources and legitimacy of this intellectual need. The issue is subtle, yet of the utmost epistemological and metaepistemological significance. In particular, a supporter of this view will have to claim that we have just an externalist notion of knowledge—which makes us hold that we know that p even if we cannot say how—and then a sort of selfreflective spontaneous attitude which forces us to look for an explanation of how that knowledge may have come about. Skepticism would thus be due to such a deeply rooted human attitude. Yet, it would have no bearing on whether we possess knowledge. One may then try to explain why, adaptively, it would be useful for us to have such an attitude; by saying, for instance, that it forces us to make inquiries, which sometimes show that we do not really know what we thought we knew.

MOORE AND MOOREANISM

477

Hence, that attitude prevents us from indulging in mistakes. Moreover, such inquiries into the sources of our knowledge may actually increase it, by providing an explanation of how it comes about. A case in point, which exemplifies both aspects, is that of chicken sexers. For, by inquiring into their ability, it was discovered that it is based on the operations of the sense of smell and, thereby, the incorrect belief that it depended on sight and touch was removed. One may then say that the price to pay, its advantages notwithstanding, is that at times such a self-reflective attitude gets in the way of our recognition of our real epistemic status and makes us worry when there is no need to. The circumstances in which Moore claimed to know that there was a hand where he seemed to see it would just be an example of this downside of our self-reflective attitude. For clearly he knew that there was a hand in what appeared to be cognitively optimal conditions. Yet, if our self-reflective attitude kicks in and demands that we provide a proof of the fact that those are indeed optimal conditions, how could we accomplish such a task? We could only set into operation the same cognitive faculties in the same kind of optimal conditions for which the problems of how we could prove them to be reliable and optimal, respectively, were raised. Hence, we would be caught up in a circle that would prevent us from being able to prove that we know what we take ourselves to know.18 Faced with this charge, an externalist could either say that, provided one does know that here is one’s hand, one would also be able to prove, via (successive steps of something like) Moore’s proof, that one does know that one’s sense organs are working reliably, that one is not dreaming, and so forth. Surely, we will not be able to settle the issue against an opponent who doubts that our sense organs are working reliably, that we are not victims of lucid and sustained dreams, etc., because such an opponent would not concede that we know that there is a hand in the first place. Yet, this is simply a dialectical failure that does not impugn our knowledge. Furthermore, an externalist should notice that the skeptic would raise a doubt that, on closer inspection, is illegitimate because it would be grounded in a mistaken conception of knowledge. Alternatively, an externalist could concede that we do have knowledge but cannot actually prove that we know that our sense organs are working reliably and that we are not victims of lucid and sustained dreams. Moreover, he could recommend that we had better tame our self-reflective attitude whenever its setting into motion would get in our way by raising challenges that cannot, in principle, be met. Nevertheless, both kinds of explanation would also have a metaepistemological consequence: that of casting doubt—albeit for different reasons—on the legitimacy of the skeptical challenge. In my view, Moore somehow anticipated, in many respects, the kind of approach that epistemic externalists have developed after him. He did not offer a diagnosis of why the skeptical challenge would be illegitimate by the lights of an externalist epistemologist, though. This may explain both why he was criticized by his contemporaries, who were rooted in an internalist conception of knowledge, and why, also nowadays, quite independently of one’s epistemological preferences, which may even go in that very same direction, one may find Moore’s strategy somewhat unconvincing. Yet, it is obvious that he had the great merit of initiating the kind of epistemology that is nowadays dominant.

478

SKEPTICISM

NOTES 1. It is impossible to do justice to all of G. E. Moore’s epistemological writings in the space allotted. For a fuller analysis, see Coliva (2010a: ch. 1). 2. Alternatively, if by “physical objects” one meant something compatible with idealist theses, such as objects that afford the possibility of occurrent perceptions, (4) would follow, but not (5), if by “external world” one meant a world populated by objects that exist independently of being perceived by us. Obviously, since Moore has painstakingly defined “physical object” and “external world,” the alternative reading just presented is not the intended reading of Moore’s proof, as he himself made clear in Moore (1942: 669–70). 3. A notable exception is Sosa (2007: 52). 4. Unless one denied the principle of closure for knowledge—according to which, if you know that p and you know that p entails q, you know that q. Dretske (1970) and Nozick (1981) denied closure, but Moore never proposed such a thing. 5. Stroud’s claims are dubious. For, if “knowledge” is context-sensitive in the way proposed, there would be no real contradiction between skepticism and common sense because, in order to have a contradiction, p should be both known and not known in the same context. 6. For a similar objection to Stroud’s interpretation of Moore, see McGinn (1989: ch. 3). 7. Travis (1989: 165–166), who is sympathetic to Moore’s claim that he knows the premises of his proof, and who supports contextualism about knowledge ascriptions, recognizes this point and deems it the source of the failure of Moore’s anti-skeptical strategy. 8. McGinn (1989: 49–53) rightly notes that Moore is directly engaging with skepticism and is not confining his claims to knowledge merely to ordinary contexts. Yet, she herself shares the view that he is dogmatic and somewhat unphilosophical because he fails to diagnose what is wrong with skepticism. 9. That Moore was basing his claim on his available evidence may appear obvious, but it is not within the historiography on the proof. For it has been denied that Moore made explicit the criterion on the basis of which he could assert his premises. See Malcolm (1949), Stroll (1994: 50–52), and Sosa (2007). 10. Since warrant is a necessary condition for having knowledge, on the tripartite conception of knowledge, and nowhere does Moore impugn the tripartite account, lack of such a warrant would impugn one’s alleged knowledge by Moore’s lights. Thus, the fact that Wright is talking about warrant while Moore talks of knowledge, though certainly inaccurate from a historical point of view, makes no substantial difference from a conceptual one. 11. These qualifications are important in order to clarify the difference between “transmission failure” and the failure of the principle of closure for epistemic operators. 12. “Here is a hand” would be such a perceptually basic belief. If one found this claim odd, Pryor would allow substituting it with “Here is a pinkish expanse.” I am not sure whether Moore himself would be happy with that substitution. Nevertheless, the important point (for both) is that the premises of the proof be about physical objects.

MOORE AND MOOREANISM

479

13. This is indeed a contentious rendition of the skeptical position, for a skeptic is no idealist! Rather, on the basis of philosophical arguments he holds an agnostic position and, in particular, that it cannot be warrantedly believed either that there is an external world, or that that there is not. See Coliva (2008; 2010b). 14. But it should be kept in mind that Moore wrote FFS in between 1940 and 1944, thus after PEW. 15. As Baron Reed has insightfully remarked, traditional foundationalists would reject (1), too, but that would not make them externalists. Basic beliefs grounded in the given or in self-presenting states cannot be proven, though they still count as knowledge. In reply, it should be pointed out that we are concerned with beliefs about physical objects here and that the basic beliefs foundationalists would normally appeal to would not be of this kind. Skeptics would then challenge the passage from having knowledge of these basic elements to having knowledge of physical objects, based on the former piece of knowledge. 16. Sosa (2007: 50) concurs with this appraisal. 17. The former phrase is Wright’s (2004: 167, 210–211); the latter is Pritchard’s (2005); similar remarks have been made by Stroud (1994). 18. For a discussion and different appraisals of these forms of “bootstrapping” arguments, see Sosa (1994), Cohen (2002; 2005), and Vogel (2000; 2008).

REFERENCES Clarke, Thompson. 1972. “The Legacy of Skepticism,” The Journal of Philosophy 69: 754–769. Reprinted in M. Williams (ed.), Scepticism, 287–302. Aldershot: Dartmouth, 1993. Cohen, Stewart. 2002. “Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 309–329. Cohen, Stewart. 2005. “Why Basic Knowledge is Easy Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70: 417–430. Coliva, Annalisa. 2008. “The Paradox of Moore’s Proof,” The Philosophical Quarterly 58: 234–243. Coliva, Annalisa. 2010a. Moore and Wittgenstein: Scepticism, Certainty and Common Sense. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Coliva, Annalisa. 2010b. “Moore’s Proof and Martin Davies’ Epistemic Projects,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88: 101–116. Dretske, Fred. 1970. “Epistemic Operators,” The Journal of Philosophy 67: 1007–1023. Grice, Paul. 1957. “Meaning,” The Philosophical Review 66: 377–388. Kant, Immanuel. 1929. Critique of Pure Reason, translated by N. K. Smith, London: Macmillan. McGinn, Marie. 1989. Sense and Certainty. A Dissolution of Scepticism. Oxford: Blackwell. Moore, George E. 1942. “A Reply to My Critics.” In P. A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of G. E. Moore. Evanston and Chicago: Northwestern University. Moore, George E. 1949. “Letter to Malcolm.” In his Selected Writings. London and New York: Routledge, 1993: 213–216.

480

SKEPTICISM

Moore, George E. 1959a. “Proof of an External World,” Proceedings of the British Academy 25, 1939: 273–300. Reprinted in Philosophical Papers. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1959: 127–150. Moore, George E. 1959b. “Four Forms of Scepticism.” In his Philosophical Papers. London: George Allen & Unwin: 196–226. Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Nuccetelli, Susana and Gary Seay. 2007 (eds.), Themes from G. E. Moore. New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pritchard, Duncan. 2005. “Scepticism, Epistemic Luck and Epistemic Angst,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83: 185–205. Pryor, James. 2004. “What’s Wrong with Moore’s Argument,” Philosophical Issues 14: 349–378. Sosa, Ernest. 1994. “Philosophical Skepticism and Epistemic Circularity,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 68: 263–290. Sosa, Ernest. 2007 “Moore’s Proof.” In S. Nuccetelli and G. Seay (eds.), Themes from G. E. Moore. New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics, 49–61. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stroll, Avrum. 1994. Moore and Wittgenstein on Certainty. New York: Oxford University Press. Stroud, Barry. 1984. The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Stroud, Barry. 1994. “Scepticism, ‘Externalism,’ and the Goal of Epistemology,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 68: 291–307. Travis, Charles. 1989. The Uses of Sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Vogel, Jonathan. 2000. “Reliabilism Leveled,” The Journal of Philosophy 97: 602–623. Vogel, Jonathan. 2008. “Epistemic Bootstrapping,” The Journal of Philosophy 105: 518–539. Wright, Crispin. 1985. “Facts and Certainty,” Proceedings of the British Academy 71: 429–472. Wright, Crispin. 2004. “Warrant for Nothing (and Foundations for Free)?” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 78: 167–212.

CHAPTER THIRTY-FIVE

Wittgenstein and Skepticism: Illusory Doubts MICHAEL WILLIAMS

1  WITTGENSTEIN: LIFE AND PHILOSOPHY Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951) is widely regarded as one of the pre-eminent philosophers of the twentieth century. He was born in Vienna, the youngest of eight children. His father’s family was of Jewish descent but had converted to Protestant Christianity. His mother had a Jewish father but followed her mother’s Catholic faith, and the Wittgenstein children were brought up as Catholics. Although Wittgenstein lost his faith as a schoolboy, questions of religion and personal morality preoccupied him throughout his life. Wittgenstein’s father was an immensely wealthy self-made industrialist, and the family was highly cultivated, with music at the center of its cultural life: Wittgenstein himself was deeply musical. However, for all its advantages the family was troubled. Two of Wittgenstein’s brothers committed suicide, a likely factor being the clash of their musical or literary proclivities with their father’s determination to see them follow a business career, and Ludwig Wittgenstein had a lifelong struggle with depression.1 But although often difficult to get along with, he was capable of forming deep friendships and was a compelling, if unorthodox, teacher. As a child, Wittgenstein showed a practical bent and was sent to technical high schools rather than a classical gymnasium. But his sister, Grete, introduced him to the philosophy of Schopenhauer as well as to contemporary currents in Viennese intellectual life, and he was uncertain of his suitability for a career in engineering. Nevertheless, in 1908, he enrolled at Manchester University to pursue research in aeronautical engineering. However, his interest in mathematics led him to questions concerning the nature of mathematical truth, the peculiar certainty of mathematical propositions, and the relation of pure mathematics to logic. Abandoning engineering for philosophy, in 1911 he moved to Cambridge, where he studied with Bertrand

482

SKEPTICISM

Russell. He also discussed philosophical questions with G. E. Moore and attended some of Moore’s lectures. Wittgenstein spent only five terms at Cambridge. At the outbreak of the First World War in 1914, he left the university without a degree and enlisted in the Austrian army. Despite hazardous frontline duty, he continued his work in logic and, by the war’s end, had a close-to-final version of his Tractatus LogicoPhilosophicus (henceforth, TLP). After some difficulties with publishers, the book appeared in 1922.2 Apart from a short paper, it is the only work he published in his lifetime. Following the lead of Frege, Russell had been engaged in an attempt to reduce mathematics to logic, defining basic mathematical terms in the vocabulary of pure logic and developing a system of formal proof. But what is logic? What is a proposition? When does a proposition express a logical truth? Wittgenstein’s Tractatus offers answers. At the base of language, there are elementary propositions, saying how things stand with some particular “objects.” Complex propositions are formed from elementary propositions with the aid of “logical constants” (“not,” “and,” “or”) and devices of quantification (“all” and “some”). All complex statements are “truth-functional,” in the sense that the truth-value of any complex statement is strictly determined by the truth-values of the elementary propositions of which it is composed.3 The only necessary (or logical) truths are truth-functional tautologies, such as “Either Baltimore is in Maryland or it is not the case that Baltimore is in Maryland.” The only necessary falsehoods are truth-functional contradictions, such as “MW was born in England and it is not the case that MW was born in England.” Since they are true no matter what or false no matter what, tautologies and contradictions take no stand on how things are and so fail to express propositions. But while senseless (sinnlos), they are not nonsensical (unsinnig): they say nothing but they show—graphically illustrate—the truth-functional characteristics of the logical constants. This is bad news for philosophy. Metaphysics seeks truths that are both substantive and necessary. For example, the Ontological Argument purports to show that the proposition that God exists is necessarily true. There are no such truths: the “statements” of metaphysics are nonsensical. The same goes for the sentences of the Tractatus itself, which are neither tautologies nor statements about how things stand in the world. Wittgenstein “resolves” the paradox by invoking a metaphor that Sextus Empiricus uses to characterize skepticism: his “propositions” are a ladder we climb but throw away once we “see the world aright”; and this is something we show by avoiding philosophical talk. So too for ethics, religion, and aesthetics. Ethical, religious, and aesthetic talk is idle chatter: a person’s ethical, religious, or aesthetic sensibility is shown in her actions and choices. “Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent” (TLP 7). Having put an end to philosophy, Wittgenstein left academic life, spending some years in the Austrian countryside as an elementary school teacher. However, he kept some philosophical contacts and began to question central doctrines of the Tractatus. In 1929, he returned to Cambridge, first as a fellow of Trinity College and later as professor.4 There he began the inquiries that culminated in his Philosophical

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

483

Investigations (henceforth, PI), published in 1953, two years after his death.5 The book is a devastating critique of the Tractatus and the approach to philosophy it exemplifies.6 In the Tractatus, language has a single, fundamental purpose: saying how things are. Reference—the relation between a name and the object for which it stands— is the root of all meaning. There is no vagueness. Wittgenstein abandons all this, offering a new conception of meaning but not a general theory. We must avoid presuming that language must work a certain way: “don’t think but look” (PI 66). We then find that language is used in many ways: to issue commands, express hopes and fears, tell stories, speculate about what might be, and so on. Instead of basing meaning on one fundamental semantic relation—naming or reference—we should look at the different ways words are used. Vagueness is inevitable. Language is, or can be made, precise enough for our undertakings, practical or theoretical, but what we ought to say in any possible circumstances is not fixed in advance. Wittgenstein analogizes using words to playing a game. He also invents simple “language-games” to make vivid his new approach to meaning. Like games, language is subject to rules: some “moves” are permitted and others not. In the builder’s game (PI 2), a builder calls for building-materials, and an assistant brings them. If the builder calls “Slab” and gets a pillar, the assistant has made a wrong move. However, if the rule were not generally followed, there would be no “game” at all. This does not mean that the rules of a language-game can be formulated so as to dictate what to do in every imaginable situation. Perhaps (not Wittgenstein’s example) the builders come across an item that is rather like a pillar but that could also be used as a beam: in that case, they would have to decide what to call it. We should not think that the meaning of a word can always, or even ever, be captured by a definition. Take “game” itself. Many things are called games: “board games, card games, ball games, athletic games, and so on” (PI 66). Some games are competitive, some not. Some you play with other people, some by yourself. Games are united by “family resemblance,” “a complicated network of similarities overlapping and criss-crossing” (PI 66).7 Nor can we think of ourselves as everywhere guided by rules, since an explicit rule would be open to interpretation. Using words correctly is a kind of know-how: understanding is shown by how a person uses words in practice. Even in making statements, words are used in different ways. Suppose the builders have words for numbers. If we are under the spell of the idea that meaning is always based on naming, we might think that just as ‘slab’ refers to slabs, numberwords refer to numbers. Since numbers don’t exist in the way that slabs do, we may be tempted to suppose that they exist in some more ethereal way. But this metaphysical temptation withers when we see that numerical symbols do not get their meaning from naming things, as ‘Michael Williams’ names me, but from how they are used in counting and calculation. We can say that ‘slab’ refers to slabs and “1” to the number one, but we should not let this blind us to the different ways in which these expressions function. The Tractatus and the Investigations have this much in common: in both works, questions about meaning and the “logic” of language lead to the view that philosophy presents confusions to be dispelled, not

484

SKEPTICISM

problems requiring theoretical solution. This is a kind of skepticism: skepticism about philosophy as a theoretical discipline.

2  THE ORIGINS OF ON CERTAINTY: WITTGENSTEIN AND MOORE Toward the end of Wittgenstein’s life, his former student Norman Malcolm, whom he was visiting at Cornell, suggested that they meet to discuss issues raised in two papers by G.E. Moore: “A Defence of Common Sense”8 and “Proof of an External World.”9 These discussions led Wittgenstein to fill the four notebooks that are the basis of On Certainty (henceforth, OC).10 While Moore’s two papers are generally seen as directed against skepticism, a view Wittgenstein shares to some extent, Moore’s immediate concern is to combat Idealism: Hegelian Idealism in Defence and subjective Idealism in Proof. In Defence, Moore gives a list of propositions that belong to common sense. Examples are that he has a body, that he has never been very far from the Earth, and that the Earth has existed for many years past. Not only are these propositions (or where personal pronouns are involved, their counterparts) accepted by everyone, they are wholly true. In making the latter claim, Moore means to contest a central claim of neo-Hegelian Idealists like his contemporary, the Oxford philosopher F. H. Bradley: that our present beliefs are only partially true.11 This doctrine of degrees of truth reflects the Idealist’s explaining both justification and truth in terms of coherence. A belief is justified if it belongs to a coherent belief system, and truth is idealized justification: coherence in the limit. Since our belief system is incomplete and can be extended in various ways, current beliefs, though justified, are compatible with propositions that are incompatible with each other and thus not wholly true. As our belief system becomes more comprehensive and integrated, our beliefs become more true, though only beliefs at the limit of coherence are wholly true. Moore will have no truck with this. Ever the Realist, he insists that his commonsense beliefs, here and now, are wholly true.12 In Proof, Moore responds to Kant’s claim that “It still remains a scandal to philosophy . . . that the existence of things outside of us . . . must be accepted merely on faith, and that, if anyone thinks good to doubt their existence, we are unable to counter his doubts by any satisfactory proof”13; and he means to end the scandal by producing the missing proof. However, Kant says that ‘external object’ is ambiguous, referring either to what exists as a thing in itself, with no logical relation to human cognition, or to something that “belongs to external appearance.” Taking the latter phrase to mean “things that are presented in space,” Moore argues that Kant has already gone wrong. External things, as ordinarily conceived, are not just presented in space: they are to be met with in space. Such things are essentially public, and they exist whether or not anyone meets or (given the circumstances) could meet them. Their existence is not tied to their ever being presented to anyone. By contrast, after-images are presented in space, in that they seem to float before our eyes. But they can’t be approached, viewed by different people or from different

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

485

angles, or re-encountered at some other time; and as “private,” they exist only through being presented to someone. Being presented in space is neither necessary nor sufficient for being a thing to be met with in space. Since Kant fails to make this vital distinction, his proof fails utterly. Having clarified what needs to be proved, Moore holds up his hands and, while making a certain gesture, announces “Here is one hand, and here is another.” Presumably, Moore’s gesture is intended to make manifest his hand’s character as a thing to be met with in space, rather than something merely presented in space. For example, it can be brought closer and viewed (by both Moore and his audience) from different angles. He concludes that at least two external objects have been proved to exist. The existence of indefinitely many such things could be proved in the same way. Moore argues that his performance really is a proof: his conclusion is different from his premises, his premises logically imply his conclusion, and he knows his premises to be true. However, he admits that he has not proved that he knows. For example, he has not proved, and does not know how to prove, that, while seeming to hold up his hand, he is not in fact dreaming. So while he has refuted subjective idealism, succeeding where Kant failed, he has not given a complete answer to skepticism.14 Rightly, Wittgenstein sees Moore’s Proof and Defence as raising different issues. In so far as Moore’s Proof engages skepticism, it is the Cartesian problem of our knowledge of the external world: can we know that external things even exist? The question raised by his Defence, which extends the bounds of certainty far beyond the everyday knowledge of things around us that the Cartesian skeptic claims to doubt, is what justifies the extension. On both topics, Wittgenstein thinks that Moore goes badly wrong. Cartesian skepticism is not to be met with a proof but exposed as an illusion. Moore’s blithe assurances that his commonsense certainties belong to everyone are unfounded. Deep—sometimes intractable—differences of opinion are a fact of life. We see, then, that Wittgenstein has two principal aims. The first is to dissolve Cartesian skepticism. The second is to investigate what to say about certainties beyond those that a dissolution of the Cartesian problem would secure. We also see that although Defence was written before Proof, for Wittgenstein the Cartesian skeptical problem has philosophical priority. Accordingly, he begins his investigation with the later paper. We shall follow him.

3  SKEPTICISM AND IDEALISM: MOORE’S PROOF 15 In the Tractatus, Wittgenstein dismisses skepticism as obviously nonsensical. In a way, he retains this view. He also retains the conviction that considerations pertaining to linguistic meaning hold the key to coming to terms with skepticism, though he now draws on the resources of the Investigations. The major change is that he no longer takes skepticism’s illusory character to be obvious. It has to be shown. Understanding how Moore’s proof misfires will offer essential clues.

486

SKEPTICISM

Wittgenstein is less interested in the “proof” itself than in Moore’s argument in favor of its being a proof, in particular his claim that he knows that his premises are true. 1. If you do know that here is one hand, we’ll grant you all the rest. When one says that such and such a proposition can’t be proved, of course that does not mean that it can’t be derived from other propositions: any proposition can be derived from other ones. But they may be no more certain than it is itself. 2. From its seeming to me—or to everyone—to be so, it doesn’t follow that it is so. What we can ask is whether it can make sense to doubt it. (OC) This opening remark is mildly misleading. Moore’s “proof” turns out to fail even if he does know that here is one hand. Nor is it simply wrong to say that this is something Moore knows. The problem is that Moore appeals to everyday knowledge in the context of responding to the skeptic. The skeptic questions whether anyone knows anything whatsoever about the external world.16 Such a doubt cannot be assuaged by Moore’s assuring us that he knows that here is one hand. We must take a less direct approach and ask when doubts make sense. The hyper-generality of skeptical doubts makes their meaning problematic: “If e.g. someone says ‘I don’t know if there’s a hand here’ he might be told ‘Look closer.’—This possibility of satisfying oneself is part of the language-game. Is one of its essential features” (OC 3). In the absence of any idea of how I might be going wrong, an expression of doubt would mean nothing. Further, in many everyday situations, no answer I could give to the question “How do you know?” would be more certain than the proposition supposedly in doubt. How do I know that here is one hand? Well, I can see my hand. Is that really an answer? Or is it just a dismissal of the question? This line of thought suggests that genuine doubts have grounds: a reasonable suspicion that I may have made a particular kind of mistake. However, if doubts need grounds, a general doubt is impossible. The skeptic will demur. I invite his questions by representing myself as not merely having an opinion but as knowing. If I can’t give an answer that is any more certain than the proposition whose epistemic credentials I have been asked to produce, this is grist to his mill. On the other hand, in everyday life, this is not how the language-game of knowing and doubting is played. 4. What about such a proposition as “I know I have a brain”? Can I doubt it? Grounds for doubt are lacking! Everything speaks in its favour, nothing against it. Nevertheless it is imaginable that my skull should turn out empty when it was operated on. 5. Whether a proposition can turn out false after all depends on what I make count as determinants for that proposition. (OC) There are two points here. First, skeptics assume that “How do you know?” is a permissible question anywhere and everywhere. But if doubts need grounds to make

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

487

sense, there is no right to ask epistemic questions no matter what has been claimed, by whom, or in what circumstances. Second, grounds for doubt are harder to come by than the skeptic thinks. We can imagine (vorstellen) all sorts of extraordinary happenings: we can picture them. (Wittgenstein would surely put Demon-deception and brain-in-a-vat tales in this category.) But ordinarily, far-fetched imaginings are not treated as grounds for doubt. Nor, for all we have seen, is there any reason why they should be. In our everyday epistemic practices, we (as everyday practitioners) set the rules for what counts as a reasonable or even an intelligible doubt. The question arises, has the skeptic found a paradox in our ordinary ways of talking about knowledge and certainty? Or is he subtly changing the rules of the languagegame, and if so why? If the skeptic’s doubts make sense, there must be some possibility of my being mistaken, even with respect to the most banal and obvious assertions about objects and events in the world around me. Is this possible? 17. Suppose now I say “I’m incapable of being wrong about this: that is a book” while I point to an object. What would a mistake here be like? And have I any clear idea of it? 18. “I know” often means: I have the proper grounds for my statement. So if the other person is acquainted with the language-game, he would admit that I know. The other, if he is acquainted with the language-game, must be able to imagine how one may know something of the kind. 19. The statement “I know that here is a hand” may then be continued: “for it’s my hand that I’m looking at.” Then a reasonable man will not doubt that I know. . . . (OC) If I have a clear idea of how I might be mistaken, I also understand what it would take to know. Notice that the topic here is Cartesian skepticism, so we are talking about mistakes as they arise with respect to simple empirical judgments. We are not talking about just any beliefs that we might judge to be false. For example, we are not talking about religious beliefs. We might indeed judge such beliefs to be false and explain how our other person came to hold them, without supposing that there is any way they could (reasonably) be shown to be true. However in cases like this, we would not think of the other person as simply making a mistake, in the sense at issue here. These are matters for later. Now according to the skeptic, I can be mistaken in thinking “Here is one hand,” even if I have no idea about how I could come to correct my error. If Wittgenstein is right to connect reasonable doubt, as ordinarily understood, with specific ways of going wrong, it would seem to follow that the skeptic’s doubts fail to be reasonable and perhaps less than fully intelligible. But Wittgenstein is in no hurry to draw this conclusion. Granted, the reasonable man will not doubt that I know. However, 19 Nor will the idealist; rather he will say that he was not dealing with the practical doubt which is being dismissed, but there is a further doubt behind that one.—That this is an illusion has to be shewn in a different way.

488

SKEPTICISM

Just because the skeptic’s doubts are out of the ordinary, we can’t conclude that they are senseless or even wholly unreasonable. But neither can we take their intelligibility for granted. 24. The idealist’s question would be something like: “What right have I got not to doubt the existence of my hands? (And to that the answer can’t be: I know that they exist.) But someone who asks such a question is overlooking the fact that a doubt about existence only works in a language-game. Hence, that we should first have to ask: what would such a doubt be like?, and don’t understand this straight off. (OC) This pivotal thought makes it clear why Wittgenstein has been emphasizing the difference between everyday and skeptical doubt. Supposedly, skepticism is an “intuitive” paradox, arising from reflection on ordinary ways of thinking about knowledge and justification. However, the extraordinary character of skeptical doubting suggests that it is a language-game of its own, with its own enabling presuppositions. They must be brought into the open. Perhaps skeptical doubting will turn out to be a natural extension of ordinary doubting. But then again, perhaps not. Wittgenstein works toward an initial diagnosis by addressing the question of my right not to doubt the existence of my hands: 25. One may be wrong even about “there being a hand here.” Only in particular circumstances is it impossible.—“Even in a calculation one can be wrong—only in certain circumstances one can’t.” 26. But can it be seen from a rule what circumstances logically exclude a mistake in the employment of rules of calculation? What use is a rule to us here? Mightn’t we (in turn) go wrong in applying it? (OC) These remarks introduce three important themes. The first theme is that, in certain circumstances, a particular claim cannot be doubted at all because expressions of doubt fail to make sense. In many ordinary situations, certainty is the default condition. This should be no surprise: unless most moves were uncontroversially correct, there would be no language-game in which to make a wrong move. This “transcendental” point stands in sharp contrast to the skeptic’s claim that while radically skeptical doubts are ignored for everyday practical purposes, they are always lurking in the shadows, ready to emerge when we retire to the study. As Wittgenstein sees things, even in my study I cannot really doubt the existence of my hands. Admitting that skeptical doubts come up only when we set aside practical concerns does not suffice to make them intelligible. The second theme is that contextually sensitive immunity to doubt is not tied to particular types of propositional content. Claims about “external” objects are not as such especially vulnerable to skeptical questioning. In arguing for this point, Wittgenstein challenges the traditional association of certainty with claims that are

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

489

“a priori,” “necessary,” or self-evident. If he is right, traditional epistemological distinctions may be less aids to solving skeptical problems than their source. There is an important methodological lesson here. We must not let philosophical preconceptions distort our view of how our language-games actually work: “Don’t think but look.” The third theme is that there is no strict rule determining when and where doubt is impossible, hence where knowledge resides.17 To master a language-game is to acquire a kind of know-how, a vital component of which is the ability to recognize when and where doubts and questions can properly be raised. Even when we can give a rule of thumb, it will involve a phrase like “in normal circumstances,” and we “recognize normal circumstances but cannot precisely describe them” (OC 27). This is a further hint that Wittgenstein’s response to epistemological skepticism will involve a healthy measure of skepticism about “epistemology,” understood as a general theory of knowledge. Wittgenstein is now ready to ask: does external-world skepticism make sense? Reflecting his Moorean inspiration, he confronts Cartesian doubt in its most radical form. The issue is not just our knowing things about external things but our knowing that such things, understood as physical objects, even exist. As noted, fairy-tale imaginings are not normally regarded as grounds for doubt. Now Wittgenstein goes a step further: can I even imagine there being no physical world at all? 35. But can’t it be imagined that there should be no physical objects? I don’t know. And yet “There are physical objects” is nonsense. Is it supposed to be an empirical proposition?— And is this an empirical proposition: “There seem to be physical objects”? (OC) It doesn’t matter what feats of imagination I can pull off. The proposition that there are physical objects, as asserted by some metaphysicians and denied by others, involves conceptual confusion. 36. “A is a physical object” is a piece of instruction which we give only to someone who doesn’t yet understand either what “A” means or what “physical object” means. Thus it is instruction about the use of words, and “physical object” is a logical concept. (Like colour, quantity . . .) And that is why no such proposition as: “There are physical objects” can be formulated. Yet we encounter such unsuccessful shots at every turn. (OC) The conclusion of Moore’s “proof” is one such. Moore’s contrast between “things to be met with in space” and “things presented in space” has to do with questions of individuation and re-identification and is therefore “logical” in Wittgenstein’s sense. Accordingly, the proof amounts to no more than “instruction in the use of words.” Using his hands as exemplars, Moore is teaching his audience the use of the technical term ‘external thing’. To think of this exercise as an existence proof is sheer confusion.

490

SKEPTICISM

4  CERTAINTY, MEANING, AND TRUTH While exposing Moore’s confusion deepens our understanding of the failure of his proof, it does not provide a full diagnosis of the illusions besetting the skeptic (or idealist) and his realist opponent: 37. But is it an adequate answer to the scepticism of the idealist, or the assurances of the realist, to say that “There are physical objects” is nonsense? For them after all it is not nonsense. It would, however, be an answer to say: this assertion, or its opposite is a misfiring attempt to express what can’t be expressed like that. And that it does misfire can be shewn; but that isn’t the end of the matter. We need to realize that what presents itself to us as the first expression of a difficulty, or of its solution, may as yet not be correctly expressed at all. Just as one who has a just censure of a picture to make will often at first offer the censure where it does not belong, and an investigation is needed in order to find the right point of attack for the critic. (OC) The persistence of the philosophical dispute shows that the participants can make some sense of it. We must look more deeply into the language-game of skeptical doubting. Wittgenstein returns to the themes he introduced at OC 25–26: that in certain circumstances, mistakes are impossible; that this circumstantial certainty is contentindifferent; and that it is not governed by strict rules. But this time around he begins with knowledge in mathematics. Philosophers have often traced mathematical knowledge to a special “inner” process, such as the exercise of rational insight. But the “inner process” or “state” is unimportant: “What is interesting is how we use mathematical propositions” (OC 38). An essential aspect of the use of mathematical propositions is that, in certain circumstances, “a calculation is treated as absolutely reliable, as certainly correct” (OC 39). With respect to “12 x 12 = 144,” there is no question of my saying “I see what you mean, but I’m not sure I agree.” If I think you might be mistaken, I haven’t learned my multiplication tables. That is why an expression of doubt fails to make sense. Without certainty, it is not just knowledge that goes missing but meaning and understanding. Wittgenstein reinforces the point that there is no need for a special faculty, giving us insight into “necessary” truths, by taking mystery out of modality: 43. What sort of proposition is this: “We cannot have miscalculated in 12 x 12 = 144”? It must surely be a proposition of logic.—But now, is it not the same, or doesn’t it come to the same, as the statement 12 x 12 = 144? 44. If you demand a rule from which it follows that there can’t have been a miscalculation here, the answer is that we did not learn this through a rule, but by learning to calculate. (OC) Exempting some propositions from doubt is built into how we play the game. As calculations become more complicated, the possibility of making a mistake creeps in, and the need for checking may arise. When does it arise? It depends. No rule covers all cases, and we don’t need one. “Nothing is lacking. We do calculate according to a rule, and that is enough” (OC 46).

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

491

With respect to propositions about things in the world, the logico-linguistic situation is essentially the same. In some situations, the notion of making a mistake gets no grip, in which case neither does doubt. 52. This situation is thus not the same for a proposition like “At this distance from the sun there is a planet” and “Here is a hand” (viz., my own hand). The second can’t be called a hypothesis. But there isn’t a sharp boundary line between them. 53. So one might grant that Moore was right, if he is interpreted like this: a proposition saying that here is a physical object may have the same logical status as one saying that here is a red patch. 54. For it is not true that a mistake merely gets more and more improbable as we pass from the planet to my own hand. No: at some point it has ceased to be conceivable. (OC) This is the point of attack we have been looking for. The external world skeptic assumes that certainty is tied to propositional content in a way that is independent of circumstances.18 He is wrong on two counts. First, he thinks that elementary mathematical propositions are self-evident: their truth is grasped by rational insight. Of course, people make mistakes in calculation, but potentially, and in some cases actually, mathematical propositions are absolutely certain. By contrast, for propositions about things around us certainty is never more than a point that we may approach asymptotically but can never reach. Being always haunted by a shadow of a doubt, all such propositions are hypotheses. This is not how our language of epistemic assessment works: “Are we to say that certainty is merely a constructed point to which some things approximate more, some less closely? No. Doubt gradually loses its sense. This language-game just is like that” (OC 56). “Here is my hand” is every bit as certain as “2 + 3 = 5” and certain in the same way.19 The skeptic will reply that Wittgenstein has overlooked the principal reason for regarding propositions about things around us as hypotheses. No such proposition is immediately evident because all such propositions are epistemically dependent on perceptual experience. This is why skeptical hypotheses are central to the externalworld problem. If I were the victim of a Cartesian Demon, or a brain in a vat, my perceptual experience would be just what it would have been had I been living a “normal” life. This is why such possibilities, however remote, cannot be ruled out and why every external world proposition is haunted by a shadow of a doubt. This reply also ties certainty to content, but in a different way. This time, the contrast is not between mathematical and empirical propositions but between two kinds of empirical proposition. Propositions concerning perceptual appearances, or what used to be called “sense-data,” are intrinsically certain in a way that propositions about things in the external world never can be. This is because propositions about how things appear to me express knowledge that I would have even if I were a victim of Demon deception or a brain in a vat.20 However, if we recognize that certainty is tied not only to content but to circumstances, then we see that “Here is a hand” can be every bit as certain as “Here is a red patch” (or “It seems to me as if

492

SKEPTICISM

there were a hand here”) and, again, certain in the same way. Wittgenstein returns to his point in the third notebook: 250. My having two hands is, in normal circumstances, as certain as anything that I could produce in evidence for it. That is why I am not in a position to take the sight of my hand as evidence for it. (OC) The real thrust of the skeptic’s claim that philosophical reflection on knowledge requires setting aside practical interests is to detach certainty altogether from circumstances, making it a property of abstract “propositions” rather than claims made and beliefs held by particular people in particular historical situations.21 This is his fundamental mistake. In the continuation of OC 54, Wittgenstein brings his points together in a general claim about the relation between meaning and truth. That doubt about propositions concerning things around us must, at some point, cease to be conceivable “is already suggested by the following: if it were not so, it would be conceivable that we should be wrong in every statement about physical objects; that any we ever make are mistaken.” Having expressed agnosticism with respect to the claim that the total nonexistence of physical objects is imaginable, Wittgenstein now turns to whether it is possible (möglich): “So is the hypothesis possible that all the things around us don’t exist? Would that not be like the hypothesis of our having miscalculated in all our calculations?” (OC 55). In the second notebook, a suggestion becomes a conclusion: 80. The truth of my statements is the test of my understanding of these statements. 81. That is to say: if I make certain false statements, it becomes uncertain whether I understand them. The connection between truth and understanding is pervasive and essential. If we didn’t get elementary calculations mostly right, there would be no practice of calculation. By parity of reasoning, if all our thoughts and sayings about things around us were false, they wouldn’t be about things around us. They wouldn’t be about anything, since meaning would have evaporated. Grounding meaning in use reveals the circumstantial nature of certainty, which in turn exposes the skeptic’s context-independent doubt for what it is: an illusion.

5  CERTAINTY INTERNALIZED: MOORE’S MISTAKE For many philosophers, the claim that the certainty of a proposition about things around us differs only superficially from that of a simple mathematical proposition is a hard pill to swallow. Don’t the cases just feel different? Wittgenstein has another card to play. He introduces the central idea early in the first notebook of OC: 6. Now, can one enumerate what one knows (like Moore)? Straight off like that, I believe not.—For otherwise the expression “I know” gets misused. And through this misuse a queer and extremely important mental state seems to be revealed.

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

493

12. —For “I know” seems to describe a state of affairs which guarantees what is known, guarantees it as a fact. One always forgets the expression “I thought I knew.” Wittgenstein does not object to the idea that knowledge is “infallible” in the sense that knowing excludes the possibility of my being mistaken. An important—perhaps the main—use of “I know” is to imply that I can’t be wrong, either because I have compelling grounds (OC 243) or because I have said something to which, in the circumstances, the notion of doubt doesn’t apply. However, there is a route to this “infallibilist” conception of knowledge that must be blocked. 21. Moore’s view really comes down to this: the concept “know” is analogous to the concepts “believe,” “surmise,” “doubt,” “be convinced” in that the statement “I know . . .” can’t be a mistake. And if that is so, then there can be an inference from such an utterance to the truth of an assertion. And here the form “I thought I knew” is being overlooked.—But if this latter is inadmissible, then a mistake in the assertion must be logically impossible too. And anyone who is acquainted with the language-game must realize this—an assurance from a reliable man that he knows cannot contribute anything. With respect to reporting my mental state, I have first-person authority. At least in normal circumstances, my sincere assertion that I believe, surmise, or am convinced that such and such is sufficient to establish that this is how things are with me. I can’t take myself to believe that p when I merely surmise that p, or to be convinced when I am dubious. In assuring his audience that he knows that here is one hand, Moore shows that he thinks that the “mental state” of knowing is like this.22 It isn’t. If I say “I thought I knew,” I will be readily understood: I was making some kind of mistake, or new evidence has led me to change my mind. By contrast, “I thought I believed” would take some explaining, and “I thought I surmised” has no use at all. As implying the impossibility of error, knowledge has nothing to do with feeling sure. 42. One can say “He believes it, but it isn’t so,” but not “He knows it, but it isn’t so.” Does this stem from the difference between the mental states of belief and of knowledge? No.—One may for example call “mental state” what is expressed by tone of voice in speaking, by gestures, etc. It would thus be possible to speak of a mental state of conviction, and that may be the same whether it is knowledge or false belief. (OC) The principle that if I know, I know that I know must not be misunderstood. “‘If I know something, then I also know that I know it, etc.’ amounts to: ‘I know that’ means ‘I am incapable of being wrong about that.’ But whether I am so needs to be established objectively” (OC 16). My knowing depends on the objective certainty of what I assert or believe: that is, on the impossibility, in the circumstances, of my going wrong in saying that. The thought that the difference between knowing and merely believing is one of “mental state” is a disaster. If we combine the triviality that knowledge is factive

494

SKEPTICISM

with the thought that knowing is a mental state subject to first-person authority, we are led to conclude that my awareness that my mental state is one of knowing, which is immediate and transparent to introspection, guarantees the truth of what I know. Knowledge of the world around us becomes instantly problematic. How can I guarantee the truth of propositions about things around me merely by reflecting on my mental states? I can’t. It follows that what I know “immediately” must itself be subjective: how it is with my sense-data, or how things appear to me. In the second notebook, Wittgenstein suggests that the temptation to internalize certainty can also arise from the “primitive meaning” of “I know.” 90. “I know” has a primitive meaning similar to and related to “I see” (“wissen,” “videre”). And “I knew he was in the room, but he wasn’t in the room” is like “I saw him in the room, but he wasn’t there.” “I know” is supposed to express a relation, not between me and the sense of a proposition (like “I believe”) but between me and a fact. So that the fact is taken into my consciousness. (Here is the reason why one wants to say that nothing that goes on in the outer world is really known, but only what happens in the domain of what are called sense-data.) This would give us a picture of knowing as the perception of an outer event through visual rays which project it as it is into the eye and the consciousness. Only then the question at once arises whether one can be certain of this projection. And this picture does indeed show how our imagination presents knowledge, but not what lies at the bottom of this presentation. This is a complex passage, but the central idea is clear enough. Assimilating knowing facts to seeing objects leads to a picture of perceptual knowledge in which experiential content is “given”—present to the mind—in a way that facts involving “external” events and objects never can be. Experience thus constitutes or underwrites a kind of knowledge that we could have even if all our beliefs about the world around us were false. As with Moore’s mistake, a temptation arises to think that knowledge properly so called is a mental state that cannot be confused with merely believing. But internalizing certainty makes knowledge of the world become incurably problematic. Diagnosing the sources of this fatal temptation is essential if the illusion of Cartesian doubt is to be dispelled.

6  THE LIMITS OF ARGUMENT Certain knowledge of the world around us goes with the very possibility of rational thought. However, this certainty does not extend automatically to the commonsense propositions enumerated in Moore’s Defence. These propositions may be certain for us, but they do not all belong to the human form of life. Take the proposition that the Earth has existed for many years past. It is not something we question, if we think of it at all. It is implied by anything and everything we believe about history, paleontology, or astrophysics. But must everyone share such commitments? 85. What goes into someone’s knowing . . . history, say? He must know what it means to say: the earth has already existed for such and such a length of time. For

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

495

not any intelligent adult must know that. We see men building and demolishing houses, and are led to ask: “How long has this house been here?” But how does one come on the idea of asking this about a mountain, for example? And have all men the notion of the earth as a body, which may come into being and pass away? (OC) Knowing history involves certainties that are not vouchsafed simply by our being competent judgers of things in the world around us. Even if Moorean propositions are widely shared, this may be because they are abstractions from more specific commitments: the contemporary scientist and the person who thinks that the Earth has always existed both believe that the Earth has existed for many years past, but their agreement is superficial. However, even this superficial agreement is not guaranteed. Wittgenstein imagines a king brought up to believe that the world began with him. Moore might be able to persuade the king otherwise, but could he prove him wrong? There is one way that we can’t prove that the Earth has been around for a while: “‘It is certain that after the battle of Austerlitz Napoleon. . . . Well, in that case it’s surely also certain that the earth existed then’” (OC 183). The “proof” is hopeless because everything that is known about history depends on documents and other things that have survived from the past. That the Earth has existed for many years past is taken for granted in any kind of historical thinking. The proof tacitly assumes what it sets out to prove. The apparent impossibility of proving that the Earth has existed for many years past is no reason to doubt its longevity. Wittgenstein: “What we call historical evidence points to the existence of the Earth a long time before my birth;—the opposite hypothesis has nothing on its side” (OC 190). As we have seen doubts need grounds, and there are none, at least none that we would ordinarily consider. But what about Russell’s “possibility” that the Earth came into existence five minutes ago, replete with what we take to be evidence of great antiquity?23 With respect to skepticism concerning knowledge of the past, Russell’s hypothesis plays the role played by Demon-deception and brains in vats in arguments for external world skepticism, and it invites the same response: it’s a fairy tale, not a ground for doubt. Fairy tale or not, does Russell’s “hypothesis” at least show that the Moorean proposition might be false? Moore has no such worries. He insists that his commonsense propositions, though contingent, are indisputably true. This cuts no ice with Wittgenstein. 191. Well, if everything speaks for an hypothesis and nothing against it—is it then certainly true? One may designate it as such.—But does it certainly agree with reality, with the facts?—With this question you are already going round in a circle. (OC) Wittgenstein does not deny our right to call Moorean propositions certain. His point is that our entitlement to treat such propositions as certain is not to be explained by an appeal to their truth. Saying that p is true, or corresponds to the facts, is just another way of insisting that p.24 Wittgenstein has excluded two ways of supporting Moorean certainties. How, then, should we think of them, given that they look like empirical propositions? This

496

SKEPTICISM

question leads us to what many readers see as Wittgenstein’s master thought. This thought is hinted at early in the second notebook: “It may be . . . that all enquiry on our part is set so as to exempt certain propositions from doubt, if they are ever formulated” (OC 88). The phrase “on our part” is important. Epistemic practices— inquiring, justifying, doubting—take place in the context of an interlocking and culturally transmitted network of deeply sedimented convictions. As Wittgenstein remarks, “I did not get my picture of the world by satisfying myself of its correctness; nor do I have it because I am satisfied of its correctness. No: it is the inherited background against which I distinguish between true and false” (OC 94). That said, the commitments that constitute this world picture do not derive their certainty from tradition but from their distinctive logical role. Wittgenstein explains what he has in mind with the aid of a metaphor: 95. The propositions describing this world-picture might be part of a kind of mythology. And their role is like that of rules of a game; and the game can be learned purely practically, without learning any explicit rules. 96. It might be imagined that some propositions, of the form of empirical propositions, were hardened and functioned as channels for such empirical propositions as were not hardened but fluid; and that this relation altered with time, in that fluid propositions hardened, and hard ones became fluid. (OC) In later passages, he introduces another striking figure: that of “hinge” propositions. 341. The questions that we raise and our doubts depend on the fact that some propositions are exempt from doubt, are as it were like hinges on which those turn. 342. That is to say, it belongs to the logic of our scientific investigations that certain things are in deed not doubted. 343. But it isn’t that the situation is like this: We just can’t investigate everything, and for that reason we are forced to rest content with assumption. If I want the door to turn, the hinges must stay put. (OC) Philosophers have often read these remarks as the basis of Wittgenstein’s response to skepticism. They may be, but not in the way that is generally thought. It is widely assumed that “hinge” propositions, because they structure our epistemic practices, are not even candidates for being known to be true. If this is what Wittgenstein intends, he faces what Duncan Pritchard identifies as a “core problem”: that “from a skeptical view it is hard to see just what is so anti-skeptical about the claim that the structure of rational evaluation has at its core arational commitments. Isn’t that just what the radical skeptic claims?”25 However, it is far from clear that this is Wittgenstein’s view. The “hinge” remark (OC 341) begins “That is to say . . .” and glosses Wittgenstein’s previous observation (OC 340): “We know, with the same certainty with which we believe any mathematical proposition, how the letters A and B are pronounced, what the colour of human blood is called, that human beings have blood and call it ‘blood.’” Apparently, Wittgenstein doesn’t hesitate to treat hinge propositions as known.

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

497

That said, Wittgenstein often seems to take the opposite view. Is he of two minds? However, when Wittgenstein declines to say that everyday certainties are things he knows, it is almost invariably to distance himself from Moore’s use of “I know” to combat skepticism. “I know,” Wittgenstein observes, may be taken to express “comfortable certainty, not the certainty that is still struggling” (OC 357). This use of “I know” is unexceptionable in everyday contexts. But in a discussion of skepticism it is pointless, if not actively dangerous: remember Moore’s mistake. Still, what gives us the right to this comfortable certainty when it comes to culturally specific, thus potentially controversial, commitments, which are not things that just anyone must know? Since the certainties in question extend far beyond anything secured by his response to Cartesian skepticism, Wittgenstein must introduce some new considerations or perhaps make explicit some further implications of ideas already on the table. He does both; and as before his response to the skeptical problem is rooted in his views about meaning and mind. The first point to note is that Wittgenstein’s conception of meaning-as-use involves a form of semantic holism: “When we first begin to believe anything, what we believe is not a single proposition, it is a whole system of propositions. (Light dawns gradually over the whole.)” (OC 141). Having a world picture is a precondition of having any beliefs whatsoever. However rudimentary, this world picture will have characteristic certainties that shape our practices of inquiry and epistemic assessment. These will not be Moorean abstractions but specific articulations of them: not just the certainty that the Earth has existed for many years but (if it had a beginning) for how long and how it came into being. An immediate consequence of Wittgenstein’s conception of extended certainty is that there is no universal, trans-historical standard of rationality: or better, of what is reasonable in the way of belief or doubt. Being reasonable is not a matter of conforming to abstract “epistemic principles” but of constraint by bedrock certainties: “I want to say: We use judgments as principles of judgment” (OC 124). This is one of Wittgenstein’s deepest insights. It lies at the heart of his profound skepticism concerning epistemology as a general theory of knowledge. Epistemology represents a hankering after an all-purpose recipe for “rationally” resolving disputes. Given that we use judgments as principles of judgment, there can be no such recipe: what is reasonable cannot be detached from substantive commitments, which may reach down to bedrock. This will strike many philosophers as a case of out of the frying pan, into the fire. In accordance with the role of judgments as principles of judgment, Wittgenstein notes that “If Moore were to pronounce the opposite of those propositions he declares certain, we should not just not share his opinion: we should regard him as demented” (OC 155). But would we regard anyone who challenged elements of Moorean common sense as out of his mind? Not necessarily. One of Moore’s commonsense certainties is that he has never been far from the surface of the Earth. Wittgenstein (OC 106) imagines someone telling a child that he had been to the Moon. Wittgenstein tells the child that it was only a joke, that it is impossible to get there; and ordinarily the child will be convinced. (Of course, Wittgenstein is writing long before the Apollo missions.) But suppose there were a tribe whose

498

SKEPTICISM

members believe that people sometimes go to the Moon: perhaps this is how they interpret their dreams. What could we say to show them the error of their ways, if justification and doubt are “hinge-relative”? Does Wittgenstein’s conception of certainty lead to cultural relativism and, if so, what becomes of objective truth? Wittgenstein anticipates this question: 108. “Is there then no objective truth? Isn’t it true, or false, that someone has been on the moon?” If we are thinking within our system, then it is certain that no one has ever been on the moon. Not merely is nothing of the sort ever seriously reported to us by reasonable people, but our whole system of physics forbids us to believe it. For this demands answers to the questions “How did he overcome the force of gravity?” “How could he live without an atmosphere?” and a thousand others which could not be answered. But suppose that instead of all these answers we met the reply: “We don’t know how one gets to the moon, but those who get there know at once that they are there; and even you can’t explain everything.” We should feel ourselves intellectually very distant from someone who said this. We should not be surprised at the last sentence, which seems to ignore the question about truth. As we have already seen, Wittgenstein’s view of the concept is deflationary. To ask whether it is true or false that someone has been on the Moon is just to ask whether someone has been on the Moon. The answer (at the time) is “No.” Period. Nor should we be overly perturbed by the reference to “our system.” It is a given that they do not think as we do. The question is whether we are epistemically entitled to take our views to be superior. Wittgenstein’s answer is unequivocal: we are. 286. What we believe depends on what we learn. We all believe that it isn’t possible to get to the moon; but there might be people who believe that that is possible and that it sometimes happens. We say: these people do not know a lot that we know. And, let them be never so sure of their belief—they are wrong and we know it. If we compare our system of knowledge with theirs then theirs is evidently the poorer by far. The Moon-visitors’ “system of knowledge”—that is, what they think they know but which we know isn’t true—is so much poorer than ours because they don’t even understand our questions, much less have answers for them. (While there is no reason to suspect influence on Wittgenstein, this is a worthwhile element in Bradley’s doctrine of partial truth and one that Moore simply failed to appreciate.) What can we say to the Moon-visitors themselves? We don’t share enough common ground for a straightforward argument. To get them to understand our questions, we would have to teach them physics, and teaching isn’t a matter of arguing. So suppose we managed to teach them physics: then what? There are two possibilities. If they learned physics in a sense that implies taking physics to heart, we would already have already got them to “look at the world in a different way” (OC 92), so there would be no need for an argument.

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

499

Changing the shape of their intellectual riverbed would reconstruct their sense of what is possible. With respect to lunar voyaging, Wittgenstein’s view is not that, as it happens, no one has been on the Moon. He is certain of that because, at the time of writing, flying to the Moon was impossible; and if the Moon-visitors learned physics, they would agree.26 Alternatively, even if they learn physics but remain attached to their lunar escapades, they might try to exempt Moon-visiting from physical constraints, as in the thought that they go to the Moon in their dreams. A response like this muddies the waters, in that it is no longer clear that they think of themselves as traveling to the Moon in a sense that implies physical transportation. A response along these lines is analogous to reconciling science with the Bible by abandoning Biblical literalism. Wittgenstein might well be sympathetic to this. Wittgenstein respected science but had no time for scientism: that is, he did not think that everything worth taking seriously was subject to scientific explanation. But in the example of the Moon-visitors, he envisages a less interesting response: that they don’t know how they get to the Moon, but they know when they are there, “and even you can’t explain everything.” Unlike the attempt to remove the conflict between physics and Moon-visiting by treating the latter as in some way non-physical, this generic epistemological remark is just an evasion: a simple refusal to engage. No one can explain everything, but some people can explain a lot more than others. Has Wittgenstein escaped skepticism, or relativism, only at the cost of embracing dogmatism? No. Nothing in Wittgenstein’s account of certainty implies that, when we meet people who think very differently from us, we will automatically favor own views. Belief-revision can go both ways. There is nothing to learn from the Moonvisitors, as Wittgenstein imagines them. However, more sophisticated interlocutors could lead us to rethink some of our own erstwhile certainties. Our world picture— though stable—is liable to change as we encounter new facts and new ideas. This aspect of Wittgenstein’s thought, not prominent in the much-quoted “hinge” passages, is insufficiently emphasized. To be sure, some things don’t change. Elementary mathematical propositions are fossilized; and without certainties concerning banal facts about things in our everyday environment we could have no beliefs at all. But from the outset, Wittgenstein’s picture of knowledge and certainty beyond this anti-Cartesian core is essentially dynamic: 97. The river-bed of thoughts may shift. But I distinguish between the movement of the waters on the river-bed and the shift of the bed itself, though there is not a sharp division of the one from the other. In flowing through their channels, the streams may change the shape of the river. Although this can happen slowly, through a kind of epistemic-semantic erosion, or more dramatically, as in the Scientific Revolution, in neither case will such change result from routine forms of argument: “Not all corrections of our views are on the same level” (OC 300). But corrections get made: our descendants may think of us (or we may come to think of our earlier selves) as Wittgenstein invites us to think of the Moon-visitors. While there must be bedrock certainties if our inquiries are to have their characteristic—indeed any—direction, such commitments are not an intellectual straightjacket.

500

SKEPTICISM

The skeptic will argue that allowing for change to the “scaffolding” (OC 211) of our inquiries compromises their claim to be objectively certain. In an important late passage, Wittgenstein considers the skeptic’s argument: 599. One could describe the certainty of the proposition that water boils at circa 100o C. . . . The proposition is a very elementary one in our text-books, which are to be trusted in matters like this because . . .—Now one can offer counterexamples to all this, which show that human beings have held this or that to be certain which later, according to our opinion, proved false. But the argument is worthless. [Here Wittgenstein adds a marginal note: May it not also happen that we believe we recognize a mistake of earlier times and later come to the conclusion that the first opinion was the right one? etc.] To say: in the end, we can only adduce such grounds as we hold to be grounds, is to say nothing at all. I believe that at the bottom of this is a misunderstanding of the nature of our language-games.27 Wittgenstein makes three points. One—not profound but not to be overlooked either—is that correction is not a one-way ratchet: rejection does not preclude all possibility of revival. A second point cuts deeper. Of course, we can only adduce such grounds as we hold to be grounds. But that is not the end of the matter: grounds are what we hold to be such, in the way that the rules of football are what we recognize as the rules. To be sure, when we recognize new grounds, we may take a critical view of our former practice, treating the new grounds as factors we overlooked: that is, that we should have considered. (That said, even with games like football, we may think of modifications to the rules as changes we should have made before now.) The point here is one that Wittgenstein introduced at the very beginning in his discussion of grounds for doubt: the rules of language-games are immanent in our practices, so that we are not merely responsible to them but also responsible for them. The inferential structure of our practices of inquiry and epistemic assessment cannot be “read off” from nature.28 This takes us to a third and decisive point: that without fixed points to determine what are and are not proper inferential moves, reasonable doubts, or relevant evidence, there is no inferential structure and thus no language-games at all, primitive or sophisticated. There is no thought. In consequence, there is no external perspective, outside of all language-games, from which we can judge that our present certainties fall short of some epistemic ideal. If they need correction, this will emerge through working with them: a retail business, though one that may have far-reaching implications. Where does all this leave us? Wittgenstein wants us to take seriously our epistemic limitations. At the same, he wants to insist that recognizing our limitations is not even the first step on the road to any form of radical skepticism or relativism: the thought that all views are equal or that no view is really “justified,” much less objectively certain. In the first place, there are limits to argument, if argument is supposed to be anything like Moorean proof. When disagreements engage bedrock certainties,

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

501

routine argument based on agreed evidence is impossible. This is true as much in our disagreements with our ancestors or former selves as with contemporaries. Faced with such deep disagreement, we can try teaching, as in the case of the Moon-visitors. Of course, teaching depends on a willingness to listen and learn, which might or might not be there. Or we could try looser, more coherentist kinds of argument: persuasion, Wittgenstein would say. Again, we might succeed or we might not: there is no recipe for getting someone to change aspects of his or her world-picture. Everything depends on what we are talking about, with whom, and the persuasive resources at our disposal. Deadlock is an ineliminable possibility. So why isn’t this a radically skeptical conclusion? Two reasons. First, deadlock does not imply epistemic equality. Our inability to get anywhere with the Moon-visitors gives us no reason to treat them as epistemic peers, so no reason to draw a skeptical or relativist conclusion. This isn’t a recoil to dogmatism, since more sophisticated interlocutors might give us reason to re-examine commitments of our own. Second, suppose that we reach deadlock: while this happens, it points to no general skeptical conclusion. Dialectical deadlock amounts only to undecidability with respect to some particular dispute, in our present epistemic situation. With further evidence or new ideas, seemingly intractable disagreements may be resolved, sometimes in favor of one party but sometimes because we come to see the dispute as misconceived. Our contingent limitations do not imply the impossibility of knowledge, any more than fallibilism means that nothing is ever certain and properly regarded as such. This point applies even at the level of hinge commitments. Pritchard’s “core problem” with respect to the apparently “arational” character of hinge commitments depends on treating Wittgenstein’s picture of knowledge, certainty, and justification as primarily a view about “the structure of rational evaluation,” giving insufficient weight to its fundamentally dynamic character.29 If we take a time-slice of our belief system, hinge commitments may seem to float in the air. But over time, they either continue to pay their way or become subject to revision. They are grounded in practices of inquiry: in our life. As Philosophical Investigations did with respect to meaning, On Certainty brings knowledge and certainty down to Earth. Wittgenstein shows us knowledge as it is for human beings, not disembodied intellects or thinkers wholly detached from any concrete, historical situation. For philosophers who find the certainty Wittgenstein describes as somehow less than we might wish for, he offers this advice: “Forget this transcendent certainty, which is connected with your concept of spirit” (OC 47). We should take it.

NOTES 1. A third brother, the only one to go into commerce, shot himself at the end of the First World War when the men under his command refused to obey his orders. 2. Wittgenstein (1961). Wittgenstein called his manuscript Logische-Philosophische Abhandlung. The Latin title, by which the book is generally known, was suggested by Moore.

502

SKEPTICISM

3. Wittgenstein exploits the fact that the truth-functional logical constants can be defined in terms of a single logical operation of joint negation, which he generalizes to apply to any number of propositions. He attempts to extend his truth-functional conception of logic to quantified propositions by treating “all”- and “some”statements as, respectively, conjunctions and disjunctions, possibly infinite. So “All men are mortal” is analyzed as “Socrates is mortal, Plato is mortal, Michael Williams is mortal . . . and so on.” “Some philosophers are Greek” comes out as “Socrates is a philosopher and Socrates is Greek, or Plato is a philosopher and Plato is Greek, or Descartes is a philosopher and Descartes is Greek, . . . and so on.” The adequacy of this analysis of quantification has been disputed, and Wittgenstein himself had second thoughts about it. 4. To make up for his lack of a degree, he was allowed to submit the Tractatus as a Ph.D. thesis. 5. Wittgenstein (2009). Wittgenstein had hoped to publish his two books in a single volume, so readers would have a clear understanding of the later work’s targets. 6. Though containing only first draft material, the notebooks are not just books of notes: each has considerable thematic unity, and the order in which they were written is significant. 7. It has been argued that Wittgenstein is wrong about “game.” See Suits (2014). 8. Moore (1970: 32–59). 9. Moore (1970: 127–150). 10. Wittgenstein (1969). Malcolm recounts his relationship with Wittgenstein, including the discussion that led to On Certainty, in Malcolm (1984). 11. Bradley (1914). 12. Moore also takes issue with philosophers who hold that while his commonsense propositions as ordinarily understood are false, there are related propositions that are philosophically more respectable and wholly true. Moore (1970: 115) surely has in mind Russell, who takes the ordinary notion of a thing, as an entity logically distinct from its perceptual appearances, to be an invention of “prehistoric metaphysicians” and advocates replacing such “inferred entities” with “logical constructions” out of sense-data. This position is also Idealist in spirit, though the Idealism is Berkeley’s rather than Hegel’s. 13. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, B xl, note, quoted in Moore (1970: 127). Moore follows the translation of Kemp Smith (1929). 14. Moore thought that critics had misunderstood his intentions. “I have sometime distinguished between two different propositions, each of which has been made by some philosophers, namely (1) the proposition ‘There are no material things’ and (2) the proposition ‘Nobody knows for certain that there are any material things.’ And in my latest published writing, my British Academy lecture called ‘Proof of an External World,’ . . . I implied with regard to the first of these propositions that it could be proved to be false in such a way as this; namely, by holding up one of your hands and saying ‘This hand is a material thing; therefore there is at least one material thing.’ But with regard to the second of those two propositions, which has, I think, been far more commonly asserted than the first, I do not think that I have ever implied that it could be proved to be false in any such simple way.” See Moore (1968: 668).

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

503

15. I offer a more extended treatment of Wittgenstein’s reaction to Moore’s Proof in Williams (2004a). However, the current discussion corrects some details concerning Wittgenstein’s “infallibilist” account of knowledge and “Moore’s mistake.” 16. For more detailed discussion of the peculiar generality of skeptical doubts, see Williams (1996: ch. 1). 17. Sextus would call such a rule a criterion and would argue that no criterion can be defended in a non-circular way. For Wittgenstein, the skeptical problem just shows what’s wrong with the idea of a criterion. 18. In Williams (1996) I call this doctrine a version of “epistemological realism.” My diagnosis of skepticism is much indebted to Wittgenstein. 19. In an important exploration of Wittgenstein’s response to skepticism, Marie McGinn (1989: ch. 7–8) stresses the point that Wittgenstein treats the certainty of “Moorean” propositions such as “Here is one hand” as essentially similar to that of elementary mathematical propositions. 20. Judgments about appearances, though contingent, have often been thought to be like mathematical propositions in that, if formulated with a clear understanding of their content, they cannot be false. For a classic deconstruction of this idea, see Sellars (1963: 164–167, para. 32–34). 21. Cf. Austin (1962: 118). “[T]he idea that statements about ‘material things’ as such need to be verified is just as wrong as, and wrong in just the same way as, the idea that statements about ‘material things’ as such must be based on evidence.” For Austin (1961: 89), statements are the primary bearers of truth, and “A statement is made and its making is an historic event, the utterance by a certain speaker or writer of certain words (a sentence) to an audience with reference to an historic situation, event or what not.” 22. Although Wittgenstein may be hard on Moore here, the view he attributes to Moore was certainly held by some of Moore’s contemporaries. Thus Cook Wilson writes that knowledge cannot be one of “two states of mind . . . the correct and the erroneous one . . . quite indistinguishable to the man himself,” the reason being that “as the man does not know in the erroneous state, neither can he know in the other state” [Quoted by Charles Travis (2008: 293)]. Travis’s paper is an important defense of a context-sensitive account of knowledge, though his inspiration is Austin rather than Wittgenstein. 23. Russell (1921: Lecture XI). 24. In PI Wittgenstein favors a redundancy conception of truth. See PI 136. However, although in my view Wittgenstein’s view of truth remains fundamentally deflationary, there are passages in OC (e.g., 200) suggesting sympathy for an epistemic account of truth as verifiability. I discuss this apparent tension in Williams (2004b). 25. Pritchard (2015: 71). The concern that Pritchard identifies lies at the heart of disputes over how to read On Certainty. Strawson thinks of framework certainties as analogous to Hume’s natural beliefs (1985: ch. 1). McGinn holds that we stand to these certainties in a “non-epistemic” relation (1989: ch. 7). Crispin Wright holds that because they enable inquiry, such certainties are the objects of a distinctive rational but non-evidentially based epistemic attitude that he calls “entitlement”

504

SKEPTICISM

(2004). Danièle Moyal-Sharrock defends her “enactivist” view that such certainties are not arational beliefs because they are not even propositional (2016). Pritchard thinks that, while Moyal-Sharrock’s interpretation has the most textual support, it makes better sense of Wittgenstein to read him as suggesting that hinge commitments are not beliefs, insofar as beliefs are supposed to be “knowledge-apt” (2016: 90). In my view, all these views fail because they start from the false presupposition that Wittgenstein has an all-purpose response to skepticism, based pretty much entirely on the idea of “hinge” propositions. All these commentators ignore the special diagnostic treatment accorded Cartesian skepticism in the first notebook. In Williams (2004a), I call this approach “the Framework Reading.” I hope in the future to offer a detailed account of its manifold inadequacies, both exegetical and philosophical. 26. The possibility at issue here is real possibility: the sense of “possibility” in which there is no possibility of my abandoning academic life to play center forward for Liverpool. Fans of skeptical fairy tales—the Earth’s having sprung into existence five minutes ago or my being a brain in a vat—legitimate such “hypotheses” by distinguishing senses of “possible”: while not physically or technologically possible, these eventualities are imaginable and so possible “logically” or “metaphysically.” From Wittgenstein’s standpoint, such distinctions serve only to defend a methodology that has no independent rationale. 27. A version of this argument can be found in Sextus Empiricus (PH I 34): “Before the founder of the school to which you adhere was born, the argument of the school, which is no doubt sound, was not yet apparent, although it was really there in nature. In the same way, it is possible that the argument opposing the one you have just propounded is really there in nature but is not yet apparent to us; so we should not yet assent to what is now thought to be a powerful argument.” 28. See Williams (1996: ch. 3). 29. Pritchard (2016: 94) recognizes that what he calls “personal hinges” are subject to change. However, he fails to realize the extent to which Wittgenstein’s dynamic vision of knowledge and certainty works against the supposed “core problem,” thus removing the rationale for Pritchard’s own “nonbelief” account of hinge propositions.

REFERENCES Austin, J. L. 1961. “Truth.” In his Philosophical Papers, 85–101. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Austin, J. L. 1962. Sense and Sensibilia. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bradley, F. H. 1914. “Coherence and Contradiction.” In his Essays on Truth and Reality, 219–244. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kemp Smith, Norman. 1929. Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. London: Macmillan. Malcolm, Norman. 1984. Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir, 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press. McGinn, Marie. 1989. Sense and Certainty. Oxford: Blackwell. Moore, G. E. 1970. Philosophical Papers, 3rd edn. London: Allen and Unwin. Moyal-Sharrock, Danièle. 2016. “The Animal in Epistemology: Wittgenstein’s Enactivist Solution to the Problem of Regress,” International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 6: 97–119.

WITTGENSTEIN AND SKEPTICISM: ILLUSORY DOUBTS

505

Pritchard, Duncan. 2016. Epistemic Angst. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Russell, Bertrand. 1970. “The Relation of Sense-Data to Physics.” In his Mysticism and Logic, 108–131. London: Unwin Books. Russell, Bertrand. 1921. The Analysis of Mind. London: Allen and Unwin. Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.). 1968. The Philosophy of G.E. Moore, Vol. 2, 3rd edn. Lasalle, IL: Open Court. Sellars, Wilfrid. 1963. “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind.” In his Science, Perception and Reality, 127–96. London: Routledge. Sextus Empiricus. 2000. Outlines of Scepticism, edited by J. Annas and J. Barnes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Strawson, Peter. 1985. Skepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties. New York: Columbia University Press. Suits, Bernard. 2014. The Grasshopper: Games, Life and Utopia, 3rd edn. Calgary: Broadview Press. Travis, Charles. 2008. “A Sense of Occasion.” In his Occasion-Sensitivity, 290–315. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Williams, Michael. 1996. Unnatural Doubts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Williams, Michael. 2004a. “Wittgenstein’s Refutation of Idealism.” In D. McManus (ed.), Wittgenstein and Scepticism, 76–96. Abingdon: Routledge. Williams, Michael. 2004b. “Wittgenstein, Truth and Certainty.” In M. Kölbel and B. Weiss (eds.), Wittgenstein’s Lasting Significance, 247–281. London: Routledge. Williams, Michael. 2007. “Why Wittgensteinian Contextualism Isn’t Relativism,” Episteme 4: 93–114. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1961. Tractatus Logico-Philosphicus, translated by D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuiness. London: Routledge. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1969. On Certainty, edited by G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright. New York: Harper. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2009. Philosophical Investigations, revised 4th edn., edited by P. M. S. Hacker and J. Schulte Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. Wright, Crispin. 2004. “Warrant for Nothing (and Foundations for Free)?,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society supp. vol. 78: 167–212.

CHAPTER THIRTY-SIX

Richard Popkin on the History of Skepticism JOSÉ R. MAIA NETO

1 POPKIN’S RÉPUBLIQUE DES LETTRES 1 Richard H. Popkin was born in New York in 1923 and died in Los Angeles in 2005. He taught at the universities of Connecticut, Iowa, UC San Diego (whose Philosophy Department he founded), Washington University in Saint Louis, and UCLA. He worked in the archives of the major research libraries in the United States and Europe (among many others, the Bibliothèque Nationale in Paris, the British Museum in London, the Laurenziana in Florence, and the Clark Library in Los Angeles). He played a major role in the development of the history of philosophy in the United States (he was a co-founder of the Journal of the History of Philosophy), in particular in the field of the early modern history of ideas and philosophy, in which he is a major world reference. He founded, with Paul Dibon, the Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Idées/International Archives of the History of Ideas, a series that has thus far published more than 200 volumes. Popkin was also important as a teacher and/or supervisor of major North American early modern historians of philosophy such as Harry Bracken, Richard Watson, Philip Cummins, David Norton, Donald Livingston, and James Force. He was probably the first North American early modern scholar to establish intellectual connections with European scholars.2 Popkin established an international network, collaborating with scholars from the United States, Canada, England, France, Italy, Germany, The Netherlands, Poland, Argentina, Mexico, Brazil, and Israel. He organized international conferences in Europe and the United States and published the proceedings.3 Popkin published more than 200 articles. Some of those concerning early modern philosophers were collected by Richard Watson and James Force in Popkin (1980). Others, mainly on early modern millenarianism, were collected by Popkin (1992) himself. With Paul Edwards, he edited the Readings in the History of Philosophy Series.4 He also edited The Columbia History of Western Philosophy (1999) and contributed to the diffusion of seventeenth-century skeptical views, translating and publishing selections of Pascal (1989) and Bayle (1991).

RICHARD POPKIN ON THE HISTORY OF SKEPTICISM

507

2  THE HISTORY OF SCEPTICISM Popkin’s most important and influential work is his book The History of Scepticism, the first edition covering from Erasmus to Descartes (Popkin 1960), the second from Erasmus to Spinoza (Popkin 1979), and the third from Savonarola to Bayle (Popkin 2003). The second edition was translated into Spanish, Italian, French, and Portuguese, and has stimulated original research on early modern skepticism in all of these languages—often critical of Popkin’s own views. As an undergraduate student at Columbia in 1941–1942, Popkin became acquainted with Sextus Empiricus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism in a survey course on the history of philosophy.5 In 1945–1946, in a graduate seminar on Hume given by Charles Hendel at Yale,6 Popkin perceived a great similarity between Sextus and Hume and wondered how the skepticism of the former may have influenced the latter.7 This question, which he discussed with his former teacher at Columbia and thereafter lifelong collaborator, the great Renaissance scholar Paul Oskar Kristeller, was the origin of the project that led to the History of Scepticism. In its first plan, Hume would be the subject of the concluding chapter. In a research project he wrote at the time, Popkin claimed that his aim was “to discover the historical antecedents of the sceptical philosophy of David Hume. . . . My hope is to publish my results in the form of a book on the history and influence of Pyrrhonism from Montaigne to Hume.”8 But as the research developed, Popkin realized that the material to be covered was too vast for just one volume. When he published the first edition of his History of Scepticism, up to Descartes, he envisaged three others. A second volume would deal with post-Cartesian seventeenth-century skepticism: Simon Foucher, Pierre-Daniel Huet, and Pierre Bayle on the skeptical side, and Baruch Spinoza, Nicolas Malebranche, Gottfried Leibniz, and John Locke on the side of those whose anti-skeptical reaction led to new forms of skepticism. A third volume would deal with the religious skepticism characteristic of the Enlightenment: Hume and the French philosophes. Finally, “if time permits, I hope to follow the sceptical trail from Hume to Kant, and to the reconversion of scepticism into fideism in Hamann, Kierkegaard and Lamennais” (Popkin 1960: xiii). Popkin then set to work on Bayle and Huet, for both were central figures in connecting Hume to the earlier modern skeptical tradition.9 But this was not the material incorporated in the second edition of the History of Scepticism, whose additional chapters on Isaac La Peyrère and Spinoza (Popkin 1979: 214–228 and 229–248, respectively) rather reflect Popkin’s new major interest at the time: Jewish intellectual history. His research on post-Cartesian skepticism (Pascal, Huet, Foucher, Malebranche, Leibniz, Glanvill, Boyle, Locke, and Bayle) was finally incorporated in the last edition of The History of Scepticism: From Savonarola to Bayle.10 Popkin’s History of Scepticism has provided a research program for historians of early modern philosophy and ideas all over the world. The following four sections (3–6) deal briefly with four theses that have been much debated since the first edition of the book.

508

SKEPTICISM

3  THE SIXTEENTH-CENTURY RELIGIOUS CONTROVERSY AND THE PROBLEM OF THE CRITERION The first thesis in question was called by Popkin “the Popkin-Schmitt thesis,” since it was also held by Charles Schmitt (1972: 163–170). In his autobiography, Popkin (1988: 115) tells us that the thesis was formulated after he became aware of the vast presence of skeptical views among sixteenth- and seventeenth-century philosophers. The thesis is that the great impact of ancient skepticism on modern thought resulted from the historical coincidence of the rediscovery of the works of Sextus Empiricus and the religious controversy brought about by the Reformation in the sixteenth century. Although there was a Latin fourteenth-century translation and three copies of Sextus’s Outlines (Floridi 2002: 23–24), we have no knowledge of any philosopher noticing it in Western Europe before the mid-fifteenth century when Italian humanists became interested in his works, mainly for philological and historical reasons. Manuscript copies of Sextus’s works increased rapidly through the sixteenth century (Floridi 2002: 95). The diffusion was naturally much larger when Henri Estienne translated into Latin and published Sextus’s Outlines in 1562 and Gentien Hervet translated what is known as Sextus’s Adversus Mathematicos and published the two works in 1569.11 Popkin noticed that by denying the authority of the Pope and the councils to decide religious controversies and by arguing that the direct examination of Scripture and each individual’s persuasion is the rule of faith, the Reformers unintentionally brought about the Pyrrhonian challenge of how to justify a criterion of truth without reasoning in a circle or falling into an infinite regress.12 Because Christians no longer shared a common criterion for the solution of religious controversies, what counted as evidence for one party was not accepted by the other, making a solution extremely difficult to find and therefore opening a “high road to Pyrrhonism,” as Bayle describes the problem in the Dictionary (article Nicole, remark C). Against the Reformers’ criterion, the Roman Catholics argued that there were many obscure passages in Scripture that required an external, traditional institution (the Roman Catholic Church) to interpret them. The Reformers replied that the Catholic Church could not claim to be the infallible rule for interpreting the Bible since its supposed authority derived from the Bible. Catholics fought back, claiming that since different persons interpret the Bible quite differently, the Reformers’ rule of faith allows a multiplicity of religious views, rendering a common orthodoxy impossible.13 If the rule is personal persuasion and there are many different persuasions, how can the true one be discerned? Luther cannot say it is his own since he is a party to the disagreement. Reformers turned the same problem against the Catholics. If tradition is the rule, which is the true one? The Roman Catholic or the Greek Orthodox? The Roman Catholic cannot claim to be the legitimate judge of the true tradition since it is one of the conflicting parties. Catholics claimed that the Reformers’ rule of faith is subjective, compromising the objectivity of religious knowledge. The Reformers replied that, since Catholics claim that human beings are fallible, needing the help of

RICHARD POPKIN ON THE HISTORY OF SKEPTICISM

509

the church to decide religious matters, how can Christians recognize the true church and the true Pope? Only the Pope himself, supposedly infallible on such matters, could know that he is the Pope (Popkin 2003: 13–15). The tremendous repercussion of the religious controversy at the time explains, according to Popkin, the great importance of skepticism in the period and why Pyrrhonism, which poses the criterion problem, and not Academic skepticism, played the major role in the skeptical crisis that led, still according to him, to the major developments in early modern philosophy. This is why he called such a crisis “crise pyrrhonienne.” If the criterion problem were not the crucial issue in the religious controversy that was excruciating to hearts, minds, and bodies, Sextus’s works would not have had the impact they had in different areas of culture (philosophy, theology, literature, politics).14 The Popkin-Schmitt thesis has been much challenged. Sylvia Giocanti claims that Popkin’s focus on the epistemological problems involved in the controversies of the time is very limited and “leads to the destruction of the skeptical position” (Giocanti 2001: 37). Ayers (2004) denies that there was a skeptical crisis in the period. According to him, Montaigne’s “skepticism” in the “Apology for Raymond Sebond” (Essays II 12)—considered by Popkin the major manifestation of the crisis—is a side effect of his overall Platonism. Maia Neto (2012) argues that Pyrrhonism in the “Apology” is just a strategic weapon to resist Calvinist proselytism (a view partially derived from Popkin’s) and therefore cannot be attributed to Montaigne himself. Notwithstanding the importance of Sextus’s works for Montaigne and others,15 new studies have shown that the role of Academic skepticism did not diminish after the availability of Sextus’s Pyrrhonian works,16 including in Montaigne’s own case.17 Pierre Charron develops an Academic skeptical view of wisdom that was extremely influential in the seventeenth century (see Maia Neto 2014). Academic skepticism becomes even stronger in post-Cartesian skepticism at the end of the seventeenth and first half of the eighteenth century. With Cartesian doubt, skepticism stops being a moral philosophy (as it was among the ancient and Renaissance skeptics) and becomes a philosophical method. In the last edition of his History of Scepticism, Popkin takes into account the part of this research that was available to him to recognize that philosophers such as Foucher and Huet (Bayle and Hume could also be added to the list) “still admired the methodological contribution of Descartes, although they strove to destroy the ontological dogmatism he had presented. They thought the skeptical method, which Descartes started with, was an important part of philosophical study” (Popkin 2003: 374–375 n. 23). Foucher and Hume identified this philosophical method as Academic.

4  SKEPTICISM AND ANTI-SKEPTICISM FROM RELIGION TO PHILOSOPHY The second thesis, an implication of the first, is that the three main reactions to the skeptical challenge in the sixteenth century were anticipated in the religious controversies. The first is a skeptical defense of Catholicism in Erasmus’s On

510

SKEPTICISM

Free Will (1524). Erasmus holds that the theological problems concerning the compatibility of grace and free will are too obscure to limited and fallible human reason so that Christians should accept (even if not understanding as true) the views of the Catholic Church. This position leads, according to Popkin, to the skeptical fideism of Montaigne, Charron, La Mothe Le Vayer, and others, for whom the human faculties are incapable of knowing even ordinary and natural things. The second position was taken by Luther in his reply to Erasmus, On the Bondage of the Will (1525). Luther claims that a skeptical attitude is unacceptable in religion where what is at stake is of such importance (eternal salvation or damnation) that any psychological state different from the firmest conviction is unnatural. This position anticipates, in the religious field, the philosophical attempts to provide a complete refutation of skepticism, of which the best known and most influential is Descartes’s. The third position was held by the liberal reformer Sebastian Castellio in his Concerning Heretics and De Arte Dubitandi. For Castellio, the rule of faith is neither tradition nor subjective certainty but reason and the senses, which, because limited, do not lead to certain knowledge. Given that certainty is unavailable in religious knowledge, Christians must look for what is probable and reasonable. Castellio’s position is thus a via media between the Catholic skeptical position and Luther’s dogmatic position that led, in the philosophical field, to what Popkin calls the “constructive or mitigated skepticism” (Popkin 2003: 112–127) of Marin Mersenne and Pierre Gassendi.18 We have no knowledge of the essence of things but can give probabilistic, experimental, and hypothetical explanations of the phenomena. Although Popkin’s view of the kinds of, and reactions to, skepticism in the different early modern philosophies he examined have been much debated (see below), and his interpretation of Erasmus’s and Castellio’s relation to skepticism has been challenged by Backus (2009), most scholars today recognize that any accurate historical treatment of sixteenth- and seventeenth-century philosophy cannot ignore its religious and/or theological background. In the 2003 edition, Popkin enlarged and diversified his presentation of the religious background of the skepticism of the time, recognizing the role of fourteenth-century scholastic skepticism derived from God’s omnipotence and the contingency of the world,19 pointing out different religious motivations in the use of skepticism by Blaise Pascal, Henry More, and the Quietists (Popkin 2003: 174–188), and expanding his analysis of Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola in the context of Savonarola’s influence in the Florence of the time (Popkin 2003: 19–28). The remaining two theses expounded below concern, respectively, the skeptical and Descartes’s reactions to the skeptical challenge.

5  SKEPTICISM AND FIDEISM Montaigne, Charron, La Mothe Le Vayer, and most Christian skeptics of the time claim that skepticism can be compatible with Christian faith and that it is even useful in Christian apologetics. Popkin disputes the standard view that these claims, La

RICHARD POPKIN ON THE HISTORY OF SKEPTICISM

511

Mothe’s in particular, are mere lip service to religious and political authorities.20 Popkin argues that skepticism understood as an epistemological position is compatible both with the suspension of judgment about religious claims and with the acceptance of such claims on a non-rational basis, a religious position usually called “fideism.” Popkin raises the following challenge to the standard irreligious interpretation: how is it possible to distinguish, without appealing to emotional pitch or relationships (as Pintard does), between (i) a use of skepticism by Charron, La Mothe Le Vayer, and Bayle to undermine Christianity and (ii) a use of skepticism by Pascal, Kierkegaard, and Hamann to support Christianity, given that they all attack natural theology and apparently defend a blind leap of faith? I have argued elsewhere (Maia Neto 1995) that the positions are quite different. So-called skeptical fideists such as La Mothe Le Vayer argue for a skeptical position on only natural or rational terms and then claim that this position is the most compatible with Christianity since it recognizes the incapacity of human reason to attain truth, indirectly supporting the necessity of an alternative way to it. This alternative way can be, depending on the particular Christian skeptic in question, supernatural grace, or the “blind” acceptance of the truths contained in the Bible as the Revealed word of God, or the recognition that we cannot give up what has been established by tradition given our incapacity to know on our own, or a combination of some or all of these views. Pascal and Kierkegaard—and also Bayle apud Bracken (1993), diverging from Popkin—never accept skepticism as a mental state previous to faith but interpret it as a consequence of Scripture and/or just as a philosophical tool to clarify specific features of Christian faith. The major problem that renders skeptical fideism suspect according to the view of most scholars is that skepticism— in particular Pyrrhonian skepticism, the branch of skepticism Popkin considered the most important in the period—would be intrinsically incompatible with any dogmatic affirmation whatsoever, even if not based on rational arguments.21

6  DESCARTES’S PHILOSOPHICAL PROJECT AS A REFUTATION OF SKEPTICISM Because Descartes is the central seventeenth-century philosopher, Popkin’s thesis about him is probably the most influential. Lennon (2004: 123) says the following about the relevance of Popkin’s reading of Descartes in Cartesian scholarship: A variation on Whitehead’s old saw about the history of philosophy as a series of footnotes to Plato—one that is more accurate than Whitehead’s original version—is that all histories of early modern philosophy since 1960 are footnotes to Popkin, certainly as far as Descartes is concerned. Popkin’s view of Descartes as endeavoring to “conquer skepticism” but ending as “a skeptic malgré lui” (the titles of, respectively, chapters 9 and 10 of the 2003 edition of The History of Scepticism) became standard, at least among English-speaking Descartes scholars.22 Before Popkin, Cartesian doubt was little studied and almost never—certainly not in English commentaries—in connection to the reappraisal

512

SKEPTICISM

of skepticism in the sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries. Popkin argued that Descartes’s quest for certain knowledge was a reaction to a widespread skepticism diffused mainly in France through Montaigne, Charron, Gassendi, La Mothe Le Vayer, and others. He also showed that Descartes’s anti-skepticism differed from most others in the period, which failed to meet the criterion problem and vainly attempted to defeat the skeptical threat either by reaffirming or reformulating Aristotle’s type of response23 or by dogmatically assuming human access to the truth.24 Still more influential—for it goes much beyond early modern philosophical scholarship—is Popkin’s view that Descartes’s attempt to defeat skepticism, though the best available in the seventeenth century, failed and that his strategy to radicalize doubt (by putting in doubt the existence of an external, material world) in order to overcome it with the certainty of the cogito, resulted in a skepticism still more formidable than the previous one. More recently, the view that Descartes’s metaphysics was to a significant extent a reaction to the skepticism of his time has been challenged. Scholars argue that Descartes’s real target was the Aristotelians, not the skeptics.25 Lennon (2008: 62–77) provides a very detailed analysis of the passages in which the skeptics are mentioned by Descartes and concludes that Descartes despised them—at least the Pyrrhonians—referring to their views almost always only defensively, that is, when accused of bringing about skepticism. Popkin’s view on Descartes’s relation to skepticism certainly needs revision. It is not plausible that refuting skepticism was a major goal of Descartes’s, even though he did argue that this was one of the benefits of his philosophy (see CSM I 127, 181–182; II 12, 374–375, 408). Paganini (2008; 2008b; 2009), though denying that refuting skepticism was a major goal of Descartes’s, presents a very compelling case for Popkin’s interpretation by showing, in more detail and depth than Popkin did, that not only was Descartes’s position partially anticipated by Charron,26 Francisco Sanches, Tommaso Campanella, and La Mothe Le Vayer, but also that he was genuinely concerned with confronting atheistic skepticism of the type, according to Paganini, upheld by La Mothe Le Vayer. Popkin’s most insightful view about Descartes’s connection to the skeptics of his time is his view that Charron anticipated Descartes in using doubt as a method to eliminate all acquired beliefs, establishing a provisional morality compatible with this elimination, and highlighting the need of an active role of the will in this process. The main common ground is the will to eliminate all acquired beliefs, in Charron’s case according to Popkin, in order to clean the mind so as to better dispose it to receive supernaturally revealed truth (through grace and revelation) and, in Descartes’s case, in order to preserve in the mind only the innate truths of the cogito, God, and extension, which are the foundations of the new science. In his comparison between Descartes, on the one hand, and the “noveaux Pyrrhoniens” (Charron in particular) on the other, Popkin points out two major differences, namely, the intensity of Cartesian doubt and the fact that it does not result in a tabula rasa: The process of doubting compels one to recognize the awareness of oneself, compels one to see that one is doubting or thinking, and that one is here, is

RICHARD POPKIN ON THE HISTORY OF SKEPTICISM

513

in existence. The discovery of true knowledge is not miraculous, not a special act of Divine Grace. Instead the method of doubt is the cause rather than the occasion of the acquisition of knowledge. Its truth . . . is the result of Divine intervention—not of sudden, new intervention, but rather a continuous and permanent act of grace that sustains our mind with its innate ideas, and with its natural light that compels us to accept as true that which we are unable to doubt. Thus, the method of doubt leads naturally to the cogito, and not supernaturally to truth as the nouveaux pyrrhoniens claimed. (Popkin, 2003: 151–152) Popkin’s analysis of the cogito places it in its philosophical context. I argue in Maia Neto (2014: 98) that Popkin is right in claiming that the Cartesian doubt is much more radical than the doubt of his contemporary skeptics, whose skepticism did not include the existence of the external world, remaining, like the ancient one,27 a skepticism about properties. However, as has also been remarked by other scholars (e.g., Giocanti 2001), the épochē of the French skeptics is not a blank tablet waiting for a miraculous reception of the truth. Far from it, they hold a critical rationalism (or rationalism without dogmas), that is characteristic of the Academic skeptical tradition and that is, in the specific case of Charron, the starting point of Descartes’s metaphysics. Descartes’s first principle, supposedly immune to skeptical doubt, is mainly based on the moral Academic self-assurance of Charron’s wise man. This reverses Popkin’s view of “Descartes conqueror of skepticism,” since the relevant kind of skepticism for Descartes is not the object of his refutation but a major inspiration for his own philosophy. However, Charron’s skeptical Academic wisdom is only the point of departure, since through hyperbolic doubt Descartes transforms the self-assurance of the Academic wise man into the metaphysical certainty of the cogito. Although Descartes does not see himself as going against—but only beyond— Charron,28 he completely reverses the latter’s Academic skepticism, inaugurating, as Popkin rightly claims, a new form of dogmatism, in a certain way immune to skepticism, since the moral skeptical position itself becomes—through hyperbolic doubt—the first principle of the new philosophy.29

7  POPKIN’S SKEPTICISM Unlike most philosophers examined in this book, Popkin did not advance skeptical arguments of any kind. But also unlike most of them, Popkin did consider himself a skeptic. His skepticism appeared in his view of the history of philosophy as a perennial and fruitless effort made by dogmatic philosophers to refute skepticism. At least this is how he sees the history of early modern philosophy, whose major events are the skeptical attack on Aristotelianism and Descartes’s attack on skepticism and establishment of a new dogmatism, only to give rise to the stronger skepticism of Bayle and Hume.30 Besides a skeptic, Popkin (1988: 117) considered himself a believing Jew. How so? I conclude this chapter with two brief considerations on this matter. The first is that this double identity is consistent with Popkin’s belief in the coherence of the position of the Christian skeptics he studied. The second is the following passage on the skeptics he quoted from Kant’s preface to the first

514

SKEPTICISM

edition of the Critique of Pure Reason: “the sceptics, a species of nomads, despising all settled modes of life, broke up from time to time all civil society. Happily they were few in number. . .” He comments: The sceptics as nomads, having no home, are like the Jews were, wandering across the world, and like the unaffiliated, non-Zionist Jews are still. The intellectual nomads (though few in number) like myself, find no home except in the broad humanistic values of Socrates, Montaigne, Spinoza, Tolstoy, Orwell, and Victor Serge, among others. This may make one a permanent outsider, one who sees the faults and failings and dangers of the insiders. (Popkin 1988: 147)

NOTES 1. One of Popkin’s heroes, the skeptic Pierre Bayle, edited and wrote from 1684 to 1687 one of the first journals of reviews, the Nouvelles de la République des Lettres. The title expresses Bayle’s ideal of a “republic” of philosophers and savants in which nationality and religion would not compromise the free interchange and criticism of ideas. 2. Popkin collaborated closely with Paul Henry, Alexander Koyré, Robert Lenoble, Bernard Rochot, Henri Gouhier, and Elisabeth Labrousse, among many others. He hired Herbert Marcuse when he was chair of the Philosophy Department of the University of California at San Diego. 3. One of these publications (Popkin 1996) was, to my knowledge, the first volume covering, like the present one, the complete history of skepticism, from the ancient Academic skeptics to Wittgenstein. Because the book was the publication of a conference to which Popkin invited scholars to present their ongoing research, it does not have the completeness of the present volume. 4. The series, published in 1966 by Macmillan, comprised eight volumes with major philosophical texts in English from Thales to the twentieth-century analytic tradition. 5. “I took the Loeb Library edition out of the library, and on some subway ride from Columbia to our house in the Bronx, or vice-versa, I encountered a philosophical author that I could make sense of, who spoke to me” (Popkin 1988: 106). 6. Popkin got a PhD in Philosophy from Columbia University in 1950. His thesis was on the philosophy of mathematics and logic. 7. The relevance of Popkin’s insight to contemporary Hume scholarship is attested by Don Baxter’s chapter on Hume in the present book. 8. Undated fellowship application cited by Jeremy Popkin (2009: 23). Popkin’s first published article on skepticism was on Hume (Popkin 1950). 9. Bayle is acknowledged today as a major source of Hume’s skepticism. Huet is cited by Hume in Part I of the Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (Hume 1980: 10). 10. With respect to the history of skepticism from Bayle to Hume to Kant, Popkin’s initial view that skepticism did not play a major role in the Enlightenment was probably one of the reasons he did not carry through the initial project. However, when he became acquainted with the work of the Italian scholar Giorgio Tonelli,

RICHARD POPKIN ON THE HISTORY OF SKEPTICISM

515

he changed his view and worked on Jean-Pierre Brissot and Condorcet. See his two articles on the role of skepticism in the Enlightenment—the first dismissing and the second recognizing its importance—in Popkin et al. (1997). Skepticism is today a well-established topic of research in the history of the Enlightenment—see Paganini et al. (2002), Bernier et al. (2005), and Charles et al. (2013). One of the conferences Popkin organized was on the wide role played by skepticism around 1800, in particular in Germany just before and after Kant with Gottlob Ernest Schulze and Friedrich Stäudlin. The proceedings were published in Van der Zande et al. (1998). 11. The edition also included Diogenes Laertius’s Life of Pyrrho and Erasmus’s translation of Galen’s De Optimo Docendi Genere. 12. For the problem of the criterion, see the chapter on Sextus in the present book. 13. The division into sects in the Protestant camp was already a tendency by the time Sextus’s works were published. 14. For the relevance of the skepticism of the period in political thought, see Battista (1966), Bianchi (1988), Laursen (1992), and Lessa (2009). For its importance in English literature, see Hamlin (2005). 15. For the centrality of Sextus’s Pyrrhonism to Montaigne’s skepticism in the Essays, see Paganini’s chapter in this book. 16. For the presence of Academic skepticism in general during the early modern period, see Maia Neto (1997; 2014); in Pedro de Valencia, see Levy (2001) and Laursen (2009); in Grotius, Tuck (1983); in Descartes, Lennon (2008: 242–244; 2011) and Giocanti (2013). 17. See Limbrick (1977), Panichi (2009), and Eva (2013). In probably the first critical reading of the manuscript of the first draft of the History of Scepticism, Kristeller remarks on Popkin’s dismissal of Academic skepticism (see Jeremy Popkin 2009: 26). 18. In the 2003 edition, Popkin attributes this position also to the “Philosophers of the Royal Society: Wilkins, Boyle, and Glanvill” (2003: 208–218). 19. Popkin was influenced mostly by Funkenstein (1987). However, Popkin (2003: 50) believed that this scholastic and theology-based skepticism was less influential in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries than the skepticism derived from ancient sources (mainly Sextus). For fourteenth-century skepticism, see Lagerlund’s and Grellard’s chapters in this book. 20. Popkin (2003: 34–35, 55, 85–88) criticizes two major French scholars who support the view that the French sixteenth- and seventeenth-century skeptics were irreligious, namely, Busson (1922; 1933) and Pintard (1943). This traditional view, although no longer hegemonic in the cases of Montaigne and Charron, is still accepted in the case of La Mothe Le Vayer (e.g., Cavaillé 2002: 141–191) and has been supported against Popkin’s view by, among others, Moreau (2007: 85–105) and Gros (2009: 540–542, 551–552). 21. Many early modern scholars have argued for this view: see Penelhum (1983), Gregory (1992), and Smith (2009). See also Giocanti’s chapter on La Mothe Le Vayer in this book. Naya (2000; 2009) and McKenna (2003) argue that Academic skepticism—but not Pyrrhonism—can be used in Christian apologetics. 22. See, for instance, Curley (1978). See also Lennon’s (2008: 55–62) review of the influence of Popkin’s “standard interpretation” of Descartes in the literature.

516

SKEPTICISM

23. See Popkin (2003: 105–111). Popkin finds this kind of “Aristotelian” reply to skepticism “in some comments of Sir Francis Bacon” (2003: 110). For criticism of Popkin’s view of Bacon as an anti-skeptic, see Oliveira (2002: 74–84) and Manzo (2009). 24. According to Popkin (2003: 128–142), this was the position held by Herbert of Cherbury and Jean de Silhon. 25. See, for instance, Gaukroger (1995: 181–186) and Secada (2000: 38–41). 26. See also Paganini’s chapter on Charron in this book. 27. But maybe unlike fourteenth-century skepticism—see the chapters by Christophe Grellard and Henrik Lagerlund in the present book. 28. The text that shows the crucial role of Charron’s De la Sagesse in Descartes’s philosophical project is the opening paragraph of Descartes’s unfinished dialogue, The Search for Truth (CSM II 400). CSM’s translation of the passage, however, conceals its Charronian source. See my analysis of the passage and criticism of CSM’s translation in Maia Neto (2014: 117–120). 29. For a different view of Descartes’s relation to Academic skepticism, see Lennon (2011). 30. See Laursen’s chapter on Bayle and Baxter’s chapter on Hume in this book.

REFERENCES Ayers, Michael. 2004. “Popkin’s Revised Scepticism,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12: 319–332. Backus, Irena. 2009. “The Issue of Reformation Scepticism Revisited: What Erasmus and Sebastian Castellio did or did not know.” In J. Maia Neto, G. Paganini, and J. Laursen (eds.), Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the work of Richard Popkin, 61–89. Leiden: Brill. Battista, Ana M. 1966. Alle Origini del pensiero politico libertino: Montaigne e Charron. Milano: A. Giuffrè. Bayle, Pierre. 1991. Historical and Critical Dictionary: Selections. Translated, with an introduction and notes, by R. Popkin. Indianapolis: Hackett. Bernier, Marc and Sébastien Charles (eds.). 2005. Scepticisme & Modernité. Saint-Étienne: Publications de l’Université de Saint-Étienne. Bianchi, Lorenzo. 1988. Tradizione liberina e critica storica. Milano: Franco Angeli. Bracken, Harry. 1993. “Bayle’s Attack on Natural Theology: The Case of Christian Pyrrhonism.” In R. Popkin and A. Vanderjagt (eds.), Scepticism and Irreligion in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries, 254–266. Leiden: Brill. Busson, Henri. 1922. Les sources et le développement du rationalisme dans la littérature française de la Renaissance (1533–1601). Paris: Letouzey et Ané. Busson, Henri. 1933. La pensée religieuse française de Charron à Pascal. Paris: Vrin. Cavaillé, Jean-Pierre. 2002. Dis/simulations: Jules-César Vanini, François La Mothe Le Vayer, Gabriel Naudé, Louis Machon et Torquato Accetto: religion, morale et politique au XVIIe siècle. Paris: Honoré Champion. Charles, Sébastien and Plínio Smith (eds.). 2013. Scepticism in the Eighteenth Century: Enlightenment, Lumières, Aufklärung. Dordrecht: Springer.

RICHARD POPKIN ON THE HISTORY OF SKEPTICISM

517

Curley, Edwin. 1978. Descartes against the Skeptics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Descartes, René. 1984. The Philosophical Writings. 2 vols, translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Eva, Luiz. 2013. “Montaigne et les Academica de Cicéron,” Astérion. Philosophie, histoire des idées, pensée politique 11 (online). Floridi, Luciano. 2002. Sextus Empiricus: The Transmission and Recovery of Pyrrhonism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Funkenstein, Amos. 1987. “Scholasticism, Scepticism and Secular Theology.” In R. Popkin and C. Schmitt (eds.), Scepticism from the Renaissance to the Enlightenment, 45–54. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz. Gaukroger, Stephen. 1995. Descartes: An Intellectual Biography. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Giocanti, Sylvia. 2001. Penser l’irrésolution. Montaigne, Pascal, La Mothe Le Vayer: Trois itinéraires sceptiques. Paris: Honoré Champion. Giocanti, Sylvia. 2013. “Comment traiter ce qui n’est pas ‘entièrement certain et indubitable.’ Descartes héritier des Académiques de Cicéron,” Astérion. Philosophie, histoire des idées, pensée politique 11 (online). Gregory, Tulio. 1992. “Pierre Charron’s ‘Scandalous Book.’” In M. Hunter and D. Wootton (eds.), Atheism from the Reformation to the Enlightenment, 87–109. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gros, Jean-Michel. 2009. Les dissidences de la philosophie à l’âge classique. Paris: Honoré Champion. Hamlin, William. 2005. Tragedy and Scepticism in Shakespeare’s England. Hampshire: Plagrave/St. Martin’s Press. Hume, David. 1980. Dialogues concerning Natural Religion and the Posthumous Essays. Edited, with an introduction, by R. Popkin. Indianapolis: Hackett. Laursen, John Christian. 1992. The Politics of Skepticism in the Ancients, Montaigne, Hume and Kant. Leiden: Brill. Laursen, John Christian. 2009. “Pedro de Valencia’s Academica and Scepticism in Late Renaissance Spain.” In J. Maia Neto, G. Paganini, and J. Laursen (eds.), Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the Work of Richard Popkin, 111–123. Leiden: Brill. Lennon, Thomas M. 2002. “What Kind of Skeptic was Bayle?” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 26: 258–279. Lennon, Thomas M. 2004. “Huet, Descartes, and the Objection of Objections.” In J. Maia Neto and R. Popkin (eds.), Skepticism in Renaissance and Post-Renaissance Thought: New Interpretations, 123–142. New York: Humanity Books. Lennon, Thomas M. 2008. The Plain Truth: Descartes, Huet and Skepticism. Leiden: Brill. Lennon, Thomas M. 2011. “Descartes, Arcesilau e a estrutura da epokhé,” Filosofia e educação 25: 37–62. Lessa, Renato. 2009. “Montaigne’s and Bayle’s Variations: The Philosophical Form of Skepticism in Politics.” In J. Maia Neto, G. Paganini, and J. Laursen (eds.), Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the Work of Richard Popkin, 211–228. Leiden: Brill. Lévy, Carlos. 2001. “Pierre de Valence, historien de l’Académie ou académicien?” In P-F. Moreau (ed.), Le scepticisme au XVIe et au XVIIe sècle, 174–187. Paris: Albin Michel. Limbrick, Elaine. 1977. “Was Montaigne Really a Pyrrhonian?” Bibliothèque d’Humanisme et Renaissance 28: 67–80.

518

SKEPTICISM

Maia Neto, José R. 1995. The Christianization of Pyrrhonism: Scepticism and Faith in Pascal, Kierkegaard, and Shestov. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Maia Neto, José R. 1997. “Academic Skepticism in Early Modern Philosophy,” Journal of the History of Ideas 58: 199–220. Maia Neto, José R. 1999. “Bayle’s Academic Scepticism.” In J. Force and D. Katz (eds.), Everything Connects, 264–276. Leiden: Brill. Maia Neto, José R. 2012. “O Contexto Religioso-Político da Contraposição entre Pirronismo e Academia na ‘Apologia de Raymond Sebond,’” Kriterion 126: 351–374. Maia Neto, José R. 2014. The Charronian Legacy: Academic Skepticism in SeventeenthCentury French Philosophy (1601–1662). Dordrecht: Springer. Maia Neto, José and Elene Pereira Maia. 2002. “Boyle’s Carneades,” Ambix 49: 97–111. Maia Neto, José, Gianni Paganini, and John Laursen (eds.). 2009. Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the work of Richard Popkin. Leiden: Brill. Manzo, Silvia. 2009. “Probability, Certainty, and Facts in Francis Bacon’s Natural Histories: A Double Attitude Towards Skepticism.” In J. Maia Neto, G. Paganini, and J. Laursen (eds.), Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the work of Richard Popkin, 123–137. Leiden: Brill. McKenna, Antony. 2003. “Scepticism at Port-Royal: The Perversion of Pyrrhonian Doubt.” In G. Paganini (ed.), The Return of Scepticism: From Hobbes and Descartes to Bayle, 249–265. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Moreau, Isabelle. 2007. « Guérir du sot »: Les stratégies d’écriture des libertins à l’âge classique. Paris: Honoré Champion. Naya, Emmanuel. 2000. Le Phénomène pyrrhonien: lire le scepticisme au XVIe siècle, Ph.D. dissertation, Université de Grenoble III. Naya, Emmanuel. 2009. “Renaissance Pyrrhonism: A Relative Phenomenon.” In J. Maia Neto, G. Paganini, and J. Laursen (eds.), Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the work of Richard Popkin, 13–32. Leiden: Brill. Oliveira, Bernardo. 2002. Francis Bacon e a Fundamentação da Ciência como Tecnologia. Belo Horizonte: Editora da UFMG. Paganini, Gianni. 2008. Skepsis. Le débat des modernes sur le scepticisme: Montaigne—Le Vayer—Campanella—Hobbes—Descartes—Bayle. Paris: J. Vrin. Paganini, Gianni. 2008b. “Charron et le scepticisme des modernes,” Corpus: revue de philosophie 55: 231–249. Paganini, Gianni. 2009. “Descartes and Renaissance Skepticism: The Sanches Case.” In J. Maia Neto, G. Paganini, and J. Laursen (eds.), Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the work of Richard Popkin, 249–267. Leiden: Brill. Paganini, Gianni, Miguel Benítez, and James Dybikowski (eds.). 2002. Scepticisme, Clandestinité et Libre Pensée. Paris: Honoré Champion. Paganini, Gianni and José Maia Neto (eds.). 2009. Renaissance Scepticisms. Dordrecht: Springer. Panichi, Nicola. 2009. “Montaigne and Plutarch: A Scepticism that Conquers the Mind.” In J. Maia Neto, G. Paganini, and J. Laursen (eds.), Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the Work of Richard Popkin, 183–211. Leiden: Brill. Pascal, Blaise. 1989. Selections, edited by R. Popkin. New York: Macmillan. Penelhum, Terence. 1983. God and Skepticism. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

RICHARD POPKIN ON THE HISTORY OF SKEPTICISM

519

Pintard, René. 1943. Le Libertinage érudit dans la première moitié du XVIIème siècle. Paris: Boivin. Popkin, Jeremy. 2009. “Richard Popkin and his History of Scepticism.” In J. Maia Neto, G. Paganini, and J. Laursen (eds.), Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the work of Richard Popkin, 15–34. Leiden: Brill Popkin, Richard. 1950. “David Hume: His Pyrrhonism and His Critique of Pyrrhonism,” Philosophical Quarterly 1: 385–407. Popkin, Richard. 1960. The History of Scepticism: From Erasmus to Descartes. Assen: Van Gorcum. Popkin, Richard. 1979. The History of Scepticism: From Erasmus to Spinoza. Berkeley: University of California Press. Popkin, Richard. 1980. The High Road to Pyrrhonism. Papers collected by R. Watson and J. Force. San Diego: Austin Hill. Popkin, Richard. 1988. “Intellectual Autobiography: Warts and All.” In R. Watson and J. Force (eds.), The Sceptical Mode in Modern Philosophy: Essays in Honor of Richard H. Popkin, 103–149. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff. Popkin, Richard. 1992. The Third Force in Seventeenth Century Philosophy. Leiden: Brill. Popkin, Richard (ed.). 1996. Scepticism in the History of Philosophy: A Pan-American Dialogue. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Popkin, Richard. 2003. The History of Scepticism: From Erasmus to Savonarola. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Popkin, Richard, Ezequiel de Olaso, and Giorgio Tonelli (eds.). 1997. Scepticism in the Enlightenment. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Schmitt, Charles. 1972. Cicero Scepticus: A Study of the Influence of the Academica in the Renaissance. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Secada, Jorge. 2000. Cartesian Metaphysics: The Late Scholastic Origins of Modern Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Smith, Plínio. 2009. “Skepticism, Belief, and Justification.” In J. Maia Neto, G. Paganini, and J. Laursen (eds.), Skepticism in the Modern Age: Building on the work of Richard Popkin, 171–190. Leiden: Brill. Tuck, Richard. 1983. “Grotius, Carneades and Hobbes,” Grotiana (NS) 4: 43–62. Van der Zande, Johan and Richard Popkin (eds.). 1998. The Skeptical Tradition Around 1800: Skepticism in Philosophy, Science and Society. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Watson, Richard. 1966. The Downfall of Cartesianism, 1673–1712: A Study of Epistemological Issues in Late 17th Century Cartesianism. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Wright, John. 1986. “Hume’s Academic Scepticism: A Reappraisal of His Philosophy of Human Understanding,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16: 407–436.

520

PART FOUR

Contemporary Skepticism

522

Introduction Contemporary Skepticism BARON REED Skepticism has been a powerful spur to innovation in epistemology throughout the history of philosophy. This is especially true in the present era, as many of the most significant developments in recent epistemology have been motivated, at least in part, as responses to global and perceptual skeptical challenges. The main argument for global skepticism has its origin in the Modes of Agrippa, presented by Sextus Empiricus in the Outlines of Pyrrhonism (PH I 164–177). Take any one of your beliefs. The skeptic will ask, why do you think it is true? A natural response might be to offer another of your beliefs in support of the first one. But this second belief can also be called into question, and it will need to be defended in turn. A third belief might then be offered in support of the second, but it, too, can be challenged and is in need of defense. As further beliefs are offered and challenged in turn, it becomes clear that there are three possible patterns your reasoning might take. (i) At every step, you could offer a previously unmentioned belief in response to the skeptic’s relentless challenges. But the skeptic will object that this amounts to a vicious infinite regress—it’s vicious because at no point do you ever succeed in offering a complete defense of any of the beliefs up for discussion. (ii) Alternatively, at some point you could offer again a belief that has already been used and challenged in the dispute. But the skeptic will object that this is circular reasoning and fails because it, too, does not permit a complete defense of any of the beliefs you have mentioned. (iii) Finally, you could offer a belief and refuse to defend it further. But the skeptic will say this is an arbitrary place to stop, subject to challenge itself, and incapable of putting to rest the questions that have been raised to your other beliefs. Because every response to the skeptic’s questioning must fit one of these patterns, and because the skeptic can raise this sort of challenge to any belief, it looks as though there is no way to successfully defend any of your beliefs.1 The Pyrrhonists thought that the natural outcome of this sort of questioning would be universal suspension of judgment. Other skeptics have thought that we are incapable of living without beliefs, and so the skeptical challenge does not lead us to abandon them altogether. Global skepticism, understood in this way, amounts to the claim that our beliefs lack a desirable normative status: they fail to count as knowledge, or they are irrational. The considerations underwriting perceptual skepticism stem largely from early modern philosophy. One major strand is the dream argument from Descartes’s First Meditation (CSM II 12–13; AT VII 18–19).2 The meditator says that there is no sure sign by means of which one can tell whether one is awake or dreaming. So,

524

SKEPTICISM

when you seem to see, for example, the pages of a book, you can’t be sure that you are actually reading it or are only dreaming that you are reading. Because the experience you are having is consistent with both possibilities, it is insufficient to justify your belief that you are actually reading.3 Another strand has to do with the indirect realist account of perception that became popular in the early modern period. Although it may seem obvious that perception makes us directly aware of everyday objects like trees and flowers, Hume says that this opinion “is soon destroyed by the slightest philosophy” (EHU XII 118). Our experiences vary with changes in our perceptual system—for example, the same water can feel cold to one person and hot to another, depending on whether they are hot or cold themselves—and a little reflection makes clear that sentient beings with different perceptual systems will perceive objects very differently than we do. Moreover, some of our experiences, like dreams, hallucinations, doublevision, etc., seem to present to us objects that aren’t really there. In those cases, we simply cannot be directly aware of mind-independent objects. What we are directly aware of, then, are experiences that are misrepresentations of reality. But ordinary cases of perception are just like these delusions, inasmuch as we often can’t tell, just from the experience itself, whether it is veridical or not. If so, this means that every case of perceptual experience involves a mental representation of which we are directly aware and which makes us indirectly aware of what it represents when the perception is veridical.4 The early modern philosophers sometimes combined this sort of indirect realism with the distinction between primary and secondary qualities.5 According to this distinction, our ideas of the secondary qualities— colors, sounds, smells, etc.—do not resemble the qualities in the object that cause them. Descartes, Locke, and others tried to maintain that our ideas of the primary qualities—spatial properties, number, and motion—do resemble the qualities that cause them, but later philosophers were not always persuaded.6 On the resulting account of perception, then, we are aware of everyday objects only indirectly, by means of a direct awareness of some representation that may be quite unlike the object it purports to represent. Many philosophers began to worry that, on such a view, perception seems to be incapable of providing us knowledge of the world outside our own minds. We are, instead, trapped behind a “veil of perceptions.”7 In response to these two central forms of skepticism, contemporary epistemologists have offered a rich variety of competing theories. One of the first to become prominent was foundationalism. According to this view, we can solve the regress problem posed by the Modes of Agrippa if we can identify a class of basic beliefs, which are capable of justifying other beliefs without needing to be justified themselves.8 That class was usually thought to comprise beliefs about the “given” element in experience (Lewis 1946: 203)—that aspect of perception that arises independently of, and prior to, our forming beliefs through the use of perceptual concepts. Because we are directly aware of the given, it was thought that beliefs arising immediately from our cognitive access to it would provide the secure foundation from which all of our knowledge could arise. Some philosophers have rejected the possibility that there could be a class of basic beliefs at all (BonJour 1985: 30–33). Others have argued that the different

INTRODUCTION

525

roles assigned to the given—as something independent of our conceptualization and as capable of justifying other beliefs—cannot be satisfied by the same thing (Sellars 1963). And many philosophers have worried that, even if we can find a level of basic beliefs that are directly justified through contact with the given, they will be too impoverished, cognitively speaking, to justify the vast majority of our other beliefs. Suppose it is granted that each of us can know with certainty, on some occasions, that we are having an experience of something red or something hot; even so, it is a long way from there to deriving an understanding of, say, the Great Red Spot on Jupiter. Motivated by these anti-foundationalist arguments, some epistemologists have tried to find other ways of getting past the Modes of Agrippa. Coherentists have articulated a theory of justification and knowledge that aims to rehabilitate what might otherwise look like circular reasoning.9 Infinitists have tried to defend the possibility that an infinite regress can be virtuous rather than vicious, underwriting justification for a challenged belief.10 Other philosophers have argued that there is no non-skeptical solution to the Modes of Agrippa available to us.11 A troubling consequence, if that is so, is that we may often lack a standard by which disagreements can be brought to a shared resolution.12 Many of the other responses to skepticism in contemporary epistemology can be understood as ways of relaxing, or abandoning, one (or more) of the elements of foundationalism. Some philosophers have thought that skepticism arises because we have set our aim too high. Instead of looking for absolutely secure foundations, capable of grounding certainty in our beliefs, we should be content with a lesser sort of knowledge. According to fallibilism, it is possible for a belief to count as knowledge even when it is grounded in a justification that is less than perfect.13 So, for example, the fact that I sometimes dream about rain falling doesn’t mean that I am unable to know it is raining now, when I see ripples in the puddles and feel drops on my face. That evidence is good enough for me to know it is raining, even though it doesn’t guarantee that I am not mistaken. Although fallibilism ought to make it easier to have knowledge, some philosophers have suggested that it brings with it a new vulnerability to skepticism.14 Fallibilism makes it possible for truth and justification to be combined in the same belief by accident; in that case, the belief fails to count as knowledge (Gettier 1963). On that point, epistemologists largely agree; the problem, however, is that it may not be possible to explain how truth and justification are combined in a non-accidental way in beliefs that do count as knowledge. Fallibilism may be understood as a family of theories, which differ from one another in the way they explain how imperfect justification and knowledge are possible. The fallibilist view that is closest to classic foundationalism is dogmatism. According to this view, much of our knowledge rests on perception, but the beliefs at the foundations need not be about the perceptual experiences themselves; rather, the dogmatist takes perception to put us directly in cognitive contact with everyday objects.15 The justification perception provides us is prima facie or defeasible, in that it can be refuted or undermined by counterevidence.16 Dogmatists then argue that this prima facie justification is usually good enough to

526

SKEPTICISM

allow us to have perceptual knowledge of the objects around us and to overcome the dream argument.17 A skeptic might note, however, that the existence of dreams, delusions, and deceivers provides an undercutting defeater for this prima facie justification. If so, the dogmatist will need to provide a rational response to that defeating consideration. Disjunctivism provides a second way of broadening the class of foundational beliefs. Like dogmatism, disjunctivism allows for beliefs about everyday objects to count as basic, but it offers a different account of the nature of perceptual experience. Where the dogmatist grounds justification in the way things seem to the perceiver, the disjunctivist says that perceptual justification arises from the fact that the perception includes the object as a constituent. For this reason, the dream argument for skepticism fails: someone who is having a waking experience of a pine tree is in a different sort of perceptual state than someone who is dreaming of a pine tree. The view is disjunctive in virtue of rejecting the argument from illusion mentioned above; disjunctivists reject the notion that all perceptual experience must be understood as involving a mental representation of external reality. At most, that holds only for delusory experiences. Veridical experience, by contrast, provides us with a direct cognitive access to the world around us.18 A skeptic will object, though, that it is impossible for the person having the experience in question to tell whether it is veridical or not. The debate between the skeptic and the disjunctivist, then, will turn on whether this is so and, if it is, whether it matters from an epistemological point of view.19 Fallibilism has also been developed in a variety of ways that break the connection between justification and knowledge, on the one hand, and what we are immediately aware of in experience, on the other. These theories, which fall under the rubric of externalism, take justification or knowledge to be grounded in a causal or subjunctive relationship holding between the belief and the fact that it is about.20 That relationship can hold without the believer being aware that it does. All that matters is that, in having the belief, the believer has the right sort of cognitive fit with her environment.21 If that is the case, then there is presumably a simple solution to both skeptical challenges mentioned above.22 First, there is no need for either a regress or a circle of beliefs to be offered in response to a skeptic’s questioning; as long as the target belief has the requisite externalist property, it is justified (and typically, when true, counts as knowledge as well). Second, the believer doesn’t have to antecedently know that she is not dreaming in order for her belief to count as justified; it simply has to be the case that she is not dreaming (and is otherwise appropriately related to her environment). Some externalists have then argued that the believer can make use of this knowledge to infer that she is not dreaming or a brain in a vat or the victim of an evil demon.23 Other philosophers object that this makes it too easy to reply to skepticism.24 A further problem for externalists has to do with the role that rationality plays in their theories. Like the dogmatists, most externalists have allowed that justification can be defeated by counterevidence that one has or should have.25 If the considerations that underlie skepticism can be used as a defeater for our purportedly justified beliefs—so that, even if our beliefs do properly fit with our surrounding environment, we nevertheless have reason

INTRODUCTION

527

to doubt that they do—then externalists will have to find a rational response to skepticism, just as internalists do.26 Given this sort of difficulty, some philosophers have sought to insulate our everyday knowledge from the threat of skepticism.27 One strategy for doing so is to argue, as Wittgenstein did, that the doubts raised by the skeptic are in some sense illegitimate. The challenges we raise to one another’s beliefs occur in frameworks that are shaped by our practical and theoretical needs. You may be told by both your uncle and a doctor that you have pneumonia, but the doctor will need to provide more evidence to support her diagnosis, due to the fact that we have higher expectations of accuracy for physicians. Even so, we do not expect the doctor to be able to trace her diagnosis back to first principles or to show that she is not dreaming.28 Some philosophers have replied either that skepticism embodies epistemological principles that govern all sorts of inquiry or that it creates its own, legitimate sort of inquiry.29 At the heart of this dispute is a deep disagreement over the nature of philosophy and the role it might play in everyday life. Another insulation strategy aims to protect from skepticism our everyday attributions of knowledge. According to contextualism about “knows” and cognate terms, they are context-sensitive: sentences that include them may express different propositions in different conversational contexts because those terms determine epistemic standards that can shift, depending on our conversational needs.30 Just as “he is tall” may assert very different propositions when I affirm it of a toddler and of a professional basketball player, so, too, “she knows it will rain” may assert different propositions when I affirm it of a farmer and of a meteorologist. Contextualists argue that shifts in epistemic standards are especially apparent when the practical stakes relevant to a knowledge attribution change in a conversation. But they also occur when a skeptical challenge is posed to an attribution of knowledge. When that happens, the epistemic standards governing the conversation go up to such an extent that very few beliefs will meet them. This is why skepticism often seems impossible to refute, once we are considering it. But, the contextualist will point out, most of our conversations are governed by much less stringent epistemic standards, and so our everyday knowledge attributions do not face this difficulty. When we are not engaged in conversation with the skeptic, there is apparently no bar to our continuing to attribute knowledge to ourselves and to others. Although contextualism has proven to be a fruitful way of theorizing about how we talk about knowledge attributions, some epistemologists have remained doubtful that it provides much illumination about knowledge itself.31 It may also be possible to regiment the skeptical challenge, so that it can be brought to bear on everyday beliefs without distortion from shifting epistemic standards.32 If so, contextualism may need to be supplemented with one of the other responses to skepticism considered above. In addition to the general and perceptual arguments for skepticism, there are also skeptical challenges to other modes and fields of inquiry. Skepticism about inductive inference, spurred in large part by Hume, continues to be a difficult problem in epistemology and philosophy of science.33 Skeptical challenges have been raised both to the possibility of a priori knowledge and to there being a

528

SKEPTICISM

coherent conception of the a priori at all.34 Our ability to know about the mental lives of others continues to be problematic.35 Moral skepticism remains a compelling possibility in ethical theory.36 And, although religious matters are no longer at the forefront of contemporary research on skepticism as they were in the early modern period, religious skepticism continues to be an illuminating perspective on questions of faith and doubt.37 The skeptical challenges of today have their origin in the great skeptical arguments of the past. As it has throughout the history of philosophy, skepticism continues to provoke new insights and to adapt itself to the changing problems and perspectives that compel our attention. For that reason, understanding skepticism in its full variety, both past and present, remains an essential part of a philosophical way of life.

NOTES 1. This form of argument has also been called the problem of the criterion, the regress argument, and the problem of epistemic circularity. See the chapters by Richard Fumerton, Andrew Cling, and Markus Lammenranta in this book. According to Richard Popkin (2003: ch. 1, 4), both Protestants and Catholics in the early modern period used the problem of the criterion to call into question each other’s preferred way of forming beliefs about theological matters; this was a major impetus in the revival of skepticism. This sort of problem can also be seen in the “Cartesian Circle” objection raised by Antoine Arnauld in the Fourth Set of Objections to Descartes’s Meditations (CSM II 150; AT VII 214). See Alston (1986; 1993) for more on epistemic circularity. See Chisholm (1966: ch. 4), Amico (1993), and Andrew Cling’s chapter in this book for a related, metaepistemological version of the problem of the criterion. Another argument for global skepticism can be found in the First Meditation, where the meditator considers the implications of not knowing whether he was created by a benevolent God, by natural causes, or by chance. This is often called the “evil demon” argument, though that is a misleading way to think of it. The force of the argument does not stem from the presentation of a skeptical scenario the meditator cannot rule out; that would simply be a failure of evidence. Rather, the point of the argument is that the very intellectual capacities with which the meditator might try to make use of evidence are themselves in need of vindication. See Reed (2015: 72–73). 2. An updated version of this argument substitutes for the evil demon’s victim a brain in a vat, hooked up to a computer that is stimulating it to have misleading experiences; see Putnam (1981: ch. 1). 3. See Brueckner (1994), Vogel (2004), and Ram Neta’s chapter in this book for the importance of the underdetermination of evidence in skeptical arguments. See Stroud (1984) for a recent, influential presentation of skepticism that turns on the underdetermination of our beliefs by the available evidence. 4. See Fumerton (1985: 78–87) on the argument from the possibility of hallucination (or, as it is sometimes called, the argument from illusion). 5. Locke (II.8.9–26). Although the name for the distinction is Locke’s, the distinction itself can also be seen in the work of many other early modern thinkers, including Galileo, Descartes, and Boyle.

INTRODUCTION

529

6. See Bayle (Dictionary, “Pyrrho,” rem. B; 1965: 197): “Heat, smells, colors, and the like, are not in the objects of our senses. They are modifications of my soul. I know that bodies are not at all as they appear to me. They [i.e., the Cartesians] would have wished to exempt extension and motion, but they could not. For if the objects of our senses appear colored, hot, cold, odoriferous, and yet they are not so, why can they not appear extended and shaped, in rest and in motion, though they are not so?” 7. See Bennett (1971: 68–70) for a characterization of Locke’s theory of perception using the “veil” metaphor. 8. See Lewis (1946), Chisholm (1966, 1989), and Fumerton (1985, 1995), as well as the chapters by Fumerton and Cling in this book. By “justification,” I mean to pick out a positive epistemic property of belief. There are many different ways of understanding justification; for my purposes, it is easiest to characterize it by way of example. Guessing it will rain tomorrow is not justified, even if it is true; forecasting it will rain tomorrow on the basis of a well-constructed model and careful gathering of evidence is justified, even if it is false. Someone with normal eyesight will be increasingly justified in believing that there is a goldfinch in the tree as she gets closer and closer to it. Belief that is both justified and true usually counts as knowledge, though not in cases where the truth and the justification are combined merely by accident; see Gettier (1963). There is still, of course, widespread disagreement over what it means for a justified belief to be accidentally true. 9. See, e.g., BonJour (1985). 10. See Klein (1999) and Turri and Klein (2014). 11. See Fogelin (1994). For more on Fogelin’s “Neo-Pyrrhonism,” see SinnottArmstrong (2004) and the chapter by Lammenranta in this book. See Fumerton (1995: ch. 7) on the prospects of avoiding skepticism from the framework of classic foundationalism. For more on responses to the regress problem, see the chapters by Fumerton and Cling in this book, DePaul (2001), and Turri and Klein (2014). 12. For the relation between disagreement and skepticism, see Bryan Frances’s chapter in this book, Frances (2005), Machuca (2012), and Christensen and Lackey (2013). 13. See Hetherington (1999), Reed (2002), and Brown (forthcoming). See Hetherington (2011), Sosa (2011), and Reed (2013) for an exploration of the idea that there may be different grades or kinds of knowledge, where some of them fall short of certainty. 14. See Hetherington (1996), Reed (2007, 2009), and Hetherington’s chapter in this book. See Neta’s chapter in this book for a consideration of the prospects of using fallibilism in a reply to skepticism about the external world. 15. See, e.g., Pryor (2000, 2004) and Huemer (2001). 16. Pollock (1986) distinguishes between rebutting defeaters, which indicate that the target belief is false, and undercutting defeaters, which indicate that the target belief was unreliably formed. Suppose, for example, I am justified in believing, on the basis of visual perception, that a dog in the distance is a husky. That justification can be rebutted by expert testimony that the animal is, in fact,

530

SKEPTICISM

a coyote; it can be undercut by expert testimony that huskies and coyotes are indistinguishable from this distance. For more on different types of defeaters, see Lackey (2008: 44–46). 17. See Pryor (2000, 2004). Davies (2004) and Wright (2004) agree that perception provides a kind of prima facie justification for knowledge of everyday objects, but they argue that this justification does not “transmit” to the conclusion that we know we are not dreaming. 18. See McDowell (1982), Snowden (1990), Butchvarov (1998), Pritchard (2012), and the chapter by Duncan Pritchard and Chris Ranalli in this book. 19. Williamson (2000) offers a view that is similar in some ways to disjunctivism, as he takes there to be a significant difference between being in the “good case” of veridical perception and being in the “bad case” of deception or dreaming. See Schiffer (2009) for a critical appraisal of Williamson’s response to skepticism and Williamson (2009) for his reply to Schiffer. 20. See Dretske (1970), Armstrong (1973), Goldman (1979), Nozick (1981), Williamson (2000), Sosa (2007, 2011), and Matthias Steup’s chapter in this book. 21. There is considerable disagreement among externalists over how to best understand what it means to have a proper fit with one’s environment. Armstrong (1973) offers a fairly simple causal theory, while Sosa thinks that the belief needs to be produced by an intellectual virtue (2007) or manifest a competence (2011) and, at least in the case of reflective knowledge, must be the target of the believer’s epistemic perspective (2009). 22. See Zalabardo (2012). See Steup’s chapter in this book for an argument that the externalist is in fact in no better position to respond to the skeptic than is an internalist. 23. Sosa (2009: ix) calls this “virtuous circularity”; the circularity arises because the person is using the very intellectual capacities she is vindicating with the inference. See also Van Cleve (1979). 24. Fumerton (1995: 177) argues that “the very ease with which externalists can deal with the skeptical challenge . . . betrays the ultimate implausibility of externalism as an attempt to explicate concepts that are of philosophical interest.” See also Cohen (2002) on the “problem of easy knowledge” and Steup’s chapter in this book. 25. See, for example, Goldman (1979), Nozick (1981), Bergmann (2004), and Lackey (2008). Externalists embraced defeaters as a way of responding to the objections pressed by BonJour (1985: ch. 3). 26. See Reed (2006). 27. See Burnyeat (1984) on insulating responses to skepticism in ancient and early modern philosophy. See also the chapter in Part I of this book on Sextus Empiricus by Tad Brennan and Cliff Roberts. 28. See Michael Williams’s chapter on Wittgenstein in Part III of this book, as well as Williams (1996). See also Bergmann (2004) and Ruth Weintraub’s chapter in this book on skepticism about induction and the “functionalist” framework for answering it. 29. See Stroud (1984) and Fumerton (1995: ch. 6), respectively.

INTRODUCTION

531

30. See Cohen (1988), DeRose (1995, 2009), Lewis (1996), and Michael BlomeTillmann’s chapter in this book, as well as Blome-Tillmann (2014). 31. See, e.g., Sosa (2000) and Kornblith (2000). 32. See Reed (2010: 225–27). 33. See Weintraub’s chapter in this book; see also Swinburne (1974). 34. See Otávio Bueno’s chapter in this book; see also Beebe (2011). 35. See Anil Gomes’s chapter in this book; see also Avramides (2001). 36. See Richard Joyce’s chapter in this book, Joyce (2012, 2014), and SinnottArmstrong (2006). 37. See J. L. Schellenberg’s chapter in this book, as well as Schellenberg (2007, 2013).

REFERENCES Alston, William. 1986. “Epistemic Circularity,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47: 1–30. Alston, William. 1993. The Reliability of Sense Perception. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Amico, Robert. 1993. The Problem of the Criterion. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Armstrong, David. 1973. Belief, Truth and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Avramides, Anita. 2001. Other Minds. London: Routledge. Bayle, Pierre. 1965. Historical and Critical Dictionary. translated by R. Popkin. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill. Beebe, James. 2011. “A Priori Skepticism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83: 583–602. Bennett, Jonathan. 1971. Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central Themes. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Bergmann, Michael. 2004. “Epistemic Circularity: Malignant and Benign,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69: 709–27. Blome-Tillmann, Michael. 2014. Knowledge & Presuppositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. BonJour, Laurence. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Brown, Jessica. Forthcoming. Knowledge, Evidence and Fallibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brueckner, Anthony. 1994. “The Structure of the Skeptical Argument,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54: 827–835. Burnyeat, Myles. 1984. “The Sceptic in his Place and Time.” In R. Rorty, J. Schneewind, and Q. Skinner (eds.), Philosophy in History, 225–254. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Butchvarov, Panayot. 1998. Skepticism about the External World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

532

SKEPTICISM

Chisholm, Roderick. 1966. Theory of Knowledge, 1st ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: PrenticeHall. Chisholm, Roderick. 1989. Theory of Knowledge, 3rd ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Christensen, David and Jennifer Lackey (eds.). 2013. The Epistemology of Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cohen, Stewart. 1988. “How to Be a Fallibilist,” Philosophical Perspectives 2: 91–123. Cohen, Stewart. 2002. “Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 309–329. Davies, Martin. 2004. “Epistemic Entitlement, Warrant Transmission, and Easy Knowledge,” Aristotelian Society Supplement 78: 213–245. DePaul, Michael (ed.). 2001. Resurrecting Old-Fashioned Foundationalism. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. DeRose, Keith. 1995. “Solving the Skeptical Problem,” Philosophical Review 104: 1–52. DeRose, Keith. 2009. The Case for Contextualism. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Descartes, René. 1984. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. II, translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dretske, Fred. 1970. “Epistemic Operators,” Journal of Philosophy 67: 1003–1013. Fogelin, Robert. 1994. Pyrrhonian Reflections on Knowledge and Justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Frances, Bryan. 2005. Scepticism Comes Alive. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Fumerton, Richard. 1985. Metaphysical and Epistemological Problems of Perception. Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press. Fumerton, Richard. 1995. Metaepistemology and Skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Gettier, Edmund. 1963. “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” Analysis 23: 121–3. Goldman, Alvin. 1979. “What Is Justified Belief?” In G. Pappas (ed.), Justification and Knowledge, 1–23. Dordrecht: Reidel. Hetherington, Stephen. 1996. “Gettieristic Scepticism,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 83–97. Hetherington, Stephen. 1999. “Knowing Failably,” Journal of Philosophy 96: 565–587. Hetherington, Stephen. 2011. How to Know: A Practicalist Conception of Knowledge. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. Huemer, Michael. 2001. Skepticism and the Veil of Perception. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Hume, David. 1975. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Joyce, Richard. 2012. “Metaethical Pluralism: How Both Moral Naturalism and Moral Skepticism May Be Permissible Positions.” In S. Nuccetelli and G. Seay (eds.), Ethical Naturalism: Current Debates, 89–109. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Joyce, Richard. 2014. “Taking Moral Skepticism Seriously,” Philosophical Studies 168: 843–851. Klein, Peter. 1999. “Human Knowledge and the Infinite Regress of Reasons,” Philosophical Perspectives 13: 297–325.

INTRODUCTION

533

Kornblith, Hilary. 2000. “The Contextualist Evasion of Epistemology,” Philosophical Issues 10: 24–32. Lackey, Jennifer. 2008. Learning from Words: Testimony as a Source of Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lewis, C.I. 1946. An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation. La Salle, IL: Open Court. Lewis, David. 1996. “Elusive Knowledge,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 549–567. Locke, John. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, edited by P. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Machuca, Diego (ed.). 2012. Disagreement and Skepticism. New York: Routledge. McDowell, John. 1982. “Criteria, Defeasibility and Knowledge,” Proceedings of the British Academy 68: 455–79. Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Pollock, John. 1986. Contemporary Theories of Knowledge. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield. Popkin, Richard. 2003. The History of Scepticism: From Savonarola to Bayle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pritchard, Duncan. 2012. Epistemological Disjunctivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pryor, James. 2000. “The Skeptic and the Dogmatist,” Noûs 44: 517–549. Pryor, James. 2004. “What’s Wrong with Moore’s Argument?” Philosophical Issues 14: 349–378. Putnam, Hilary. 1981. Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reed, Baron. 2002. “How to Think about Fallibilism,” Philosophical Studies 107: 143–157. Reed, Baron. 2006. “Epistemic Circularity Squared? Skepticism about Common Sense,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73: 186–197. Reed, Baron. 2007. “The Long Road to Skepticism,” Journal of Philosophy 104: 236–262. Reed, Baron. 2009. “A New Argument for Skepticism,” Philosophical Studies 142: 91–104. Reed, Baron. 2010. “A Defense of Stable Invariantism,” Noûs 44: 224–244. Reed, Baron. 2013. “Fallibilism, Epistemic Possibility, and Epistemic Agency,” Philosophical Issues 23: 40–69. Reed, Baron. 2015. “Skepticism and Perception.” In M. Matthen (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception, 66–80. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schellenberg, J. L. 2007. The Wisdom to Doubt: A Justification of Religious Skepticism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Schellenberg, J. L. 2013. Evolutionary Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schiffer, Stephen. 2009. “Evidence = Knowledge: Williamson’s Solution to Skepticism.” In P. Greenough and D. Pritchard (ed.), Williamson on Knowledge, 183–202. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sellars, Wilfrid. 1963. “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind.” In his Science, Perception, and Reality, 127–196. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview. Sextus Empiricus. 2000. Outlines of Scepticism, edited by J. Annas and J. Barnes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (ed.). 2004. Pyrrhonian Skepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

534

SKEPTICISM

Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (ed.). 2006. Moral Skepticisms. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Snowden, Paul. 1990. “The Objects of Perceptual Experience,” Aristotelian Society Supplement 64: 121–150. Sosa, Ernest. 2000. “Skepticism and Contextualism,” Philosophical Issues 10: 1–18. Sosa, Ernest. 2007. A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, volume I. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Sosa, Ernest. 2009. Reflective Knowledge: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, volume II. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Sosa, Ernest. 2011 Knowing Full Well. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Stroud, Barry. 1984. The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Swinburne, Richard (ed.). 1974. The Justification of Induction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Turri, John, and Peter Klein (eds.). 2014. Ad Infinitum: New Essays on Epistemological Infinitism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Van Cleve, James. 1979. “Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles, and the Cartesian Circle,” Philosophical Review 88: 55–91. Vogel, Jonathan. 2004. “Skeptical Arguments,” Philosophical Issues 14: 426–455. Williams, Michael. 1996. Unnatural Doubts: Epistemological Realism and the Basis of Scepticism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Williamson, Timothy. 2009. “Replies to Critics.” In P. Greenough and D. Pritchard (eds.), Williamson on Knowledge, 279–384. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wright, Crispin. 2004. “Warrant for Nothing (and Foundations for Free)?” Aristotelian Society Supplement 78: 167–212. Zalabardo, José 2012. Scepticism and Reliable Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

CHAPTER THIRTY-SEVEN

Regress Arguments and Skepticism RICHARD FUMERTON

1 INTRODUCTION The history of epistemology has been shaped to a very large extent by attempts to meet the challenge of skepticism. One of the most powerful weapons in the skeptic’s arsenal has always been the threat of problematic regress. Almost no contemporary epistemologists accept skepticism, at least in its most extreme forms, so epistemologists often conceive of their task as to block alleged problematic regresses, or to allow them but to argue that they are harmless. In what follows, I’ll examine a number of different potentially problematic regresses and evaluate the ways in which various schools of epistemology respond to the challenge they pose.

2 DISTINCTIONS Let’s begin by making some familiar distinctions. Skepticism itself comes in many forms. It is useful to distinguish skepticism concerning knowledge from skepticism concerning justified belief. It is further useful to distinguish, with respect to both kinds of skepticism, global and local versions. As I’ll define the view, the global skeptic concerning knowledge claims that no one knows anything (presumably, not even that no one knows anything). The view might even be held with a strong modal operator—it is impossible for anyone to know anything. The global skeptic certainly makes a startling claim. The claim, if true, would render false countless statements we make in ordinary discourse. But one can soften the claim a bit by talking about what we know with absolute certainty, where one makes clear that one is employing very high standards for achieving this sort of knowledge. There have been relatively few global knowledge skeptics. Most are content to embrace skepticism with respect to certain kinds of knowledge. So one might be a skeptic with respect to knowledge of the external world, other minds, the past, the theoretical world of physics, the future, God, global warming, and the existence of unicorns. The more consensus there is that one doesn’t know something (like that there are unicorns), the more

536

SKEPTICISM

odd it sounds to characterize the view that we lack such knowledge as a form of skepticism, but we won’t worry about that subtlety here. We can also make a distinction between global and local skepticism with respect to justified belief. And again we can hold the view with or without a modal operator. The most extreme form of skepticism is the view that it is impossible for anyone to have any justification at all for believing anything. Again, it trivially follows that, if the view is true, one has no justification at all for believing it. Asserting the view probably violates all sorts of “norms of assertion” (though odd assertions, and assertions that violate norms of conversation, can still be true).1 As with knowledgeskepticism, it is much more common to find epistemologists concerned only with arguments designed to cast doubt on the possibility of justifying belief in certain kinds of propositions. Many of the regress arguments that drive epistemological views actually threaten the possibility of global skepticism with respect to justified belief. Let us consider the most familiar regress argument for foundationalism.

3  THE EPISTEMIC REGRESS ARGUMENT FOR FOUNDATIONALISM The foundationalist believes that we must distinguish two sorts of justification— inferential and noninferential. Further, the foundationalist argues, we need to recognize that all inferentially justified beliefs must be legitimately inferred ultimately from propositions that we are noninferentially justified in believing. That some beliefs are only inferentially justified, if justified at all, seems plausible enough. I take myself to have good reason to believe that my wife is home after noticing that her car is in the garage. The car’s being in the garage obviously doesn’t entail that my wife is home, but that fact together with all sorts of background information (that my wife doesn’t lend her car to others, that cars don’t find their own way home, etc.) allows me to infer with relatively high probability that my wife is home. While it might be easy to give examples of beliefs that are only inferentially justified, if justified at all, it is much harder to give an uncontroversial general characterization of what kinds of beliefs involve inference. So the radical British empiricists all thought that to justifiably believe any proposition describing the physical world one would need to justifiably infer that proposition from some other proposition describing the character of one’s subjective experience. It also used to be taken for granted by most epistemologists that inductively formed beliefs, beliefs about other minds, beliefs about the (at least distant) past, and beliefs based on testimony, all involve explicit or implicit inference. The notion of implicit inference, however, becomes critical. I do believe that the next raven I see will be black and I have that belief, at least in part, because of my experience with past ravens. But I might be hard pressed to describe with any sort of accuracy the specific occasions on which I have observed a black raven. I believe that the Battle of Hastings took place in 1066, but I doubt I could describe the occasion on which I was taught that or read that. In the end we probably can’t get clear about

REGRESS ARGUMENTS AND SKEPTICISM

537

what inferential justification is until we contrast it with another sort of justification recognized by the foundationalist—noninferential justification. We might begin by characterizing noninferential justification negatively: a belief is noninferentially justified if it is justified but its justification is not constituted, even in part, by the having of other different justified beliefs. The epistemic regress argument for the existence of noninferential justification proceeds as follows: (1) One is justified in believing P by inferring it from some other proposition E1 only if one is justified in believing E1 (Garbage in—garbage out). (2) If the only way to justify a belief is through inference, then to be justified in believing E1 one would need to have inferred it from some other proposition E2 which one also justifiably believed, and, again, if the only way to justify a belief is through inference, we could have a justified belief in E2 only if we inferred it from something else E3 which one justifiably believed, and so on ad infinitum. (3) Finite minds cannot complete an infinitely long chain of reasoning. Arguably, even infinite minds couldn’t complete such a chain. So, (4) If the only way to justify a belief is through inference, we have no justification for believing anything (the most extreme of all skeptical positions). Notice that we haven’t got an argument yet for the existence of noninferentially justified beliefs. But if we add as an additional premise that global skepticism about justification is false, we get the foundationalist’s conclusion that there are noninferentially justified beliefs. We haven’t given yet a positive analysis of what noninferential justification is (it has been understood only negatively—as justification that is not inferential), or made a claim about what one is noninferentially justified in believing. But with an anti-skeptical commitment, we have reached the conclusion that there are noninferentially justified beliefs. Traditional epistemologists have often assumed, I think, that we need to block not just one regress threatening the possibility of justified belief. Some (a decided minority now) think that we are justified in believing P on the basis of E1 only if in addition to being justified in believing E1, we are also justified in believing that E1 makes probable P (where E1’s entailing P can be thought of as the upper limit of making probable). Again if the only way to justify a belief is through inference, inferential justification for believing P on the basis of E1 would require us to legitimately infer that E1 makes probable P from some other proposition F1, a proposition we would need to justifiably infer from some other proposition F2, and so on (another regress begins). But we would also need to justifiably believe that F1 does make likely that E1 makes likely P, a proposition we would need to infer from some other proposition G1, which in turn would need to be inferred from G2, and so on ad infinitum. And we would, of course, need to be justified in believing that G1 makes likely that F1 makes likely that E1 makes likely that P, a proposition we would need to infer. . . . On this view, if all justification were inferential, we

538

SKEPTICISM

would face not just one, but infinitely many regresses mushrooming out in infinitely many directions. The above arguments designed to force a choice between skepticism and foundationalism are most naturally thought of as epistemic regress arguments. The vicious nature of the regress is supposed to have something to do with the fact that finite minds cannot come up with infinitely many arguments of the sort required by the presupposition that all justification is inferential. There are at least two responses to the argument. The coherentist famously rejects the idea that justification is “linear.” As the label for the view implies, the coherentist claims that the justification for believing a given proposition is a function of the way that proposition coheres with other propositions believed (where we get different versions of the view depending on whose beliefs coherence among which are supposed to constitute epistemic justification). For reasons of space I won’t talk much about the coherence theory here. Coherence seems to me neither necessary nor sufficient for the having of justified beliefs. A single necessarily false proposition in my belief system renders the whole system inconsistent, but does nothing to defeat the justification I have for believing that I exist. And Foley (1979) has argued (successfully I think) that we can even be aware that we have inconsistent beliefs each of which is still nevertheless perfectly justified. Think about lotteries and the fact that we can justifiably believe of each ticket that it will lose even as we justifiably believe that there will be a winner. Or think about the proofreader who justifiably believes of each page that it contains no errors even as she concludes quite reasonably that there is bound to be a missed typo somewhere in the manuscript. So coherence doesn’t seem to be necessary for justification. And all kinds of examples seem to suggest that coherence without access to that coherence doesn’t generate epistemic justification. But a coherentist can’t give a coherentist account of the relevant access without again facing regress. The coherentist’s account of access to coherence would require a coherentist account of access to what one believes. But all the coherentist can point to in justifying a belief about what he believes is coherence with the metabelief about beliefs and the rest of his beliefs. But that doesn’t do any good unless one has access to that coherence, and off we go. The infinitist (a term coined by Klein 1999) challenges the assumption that, if all justification were inferential, finite minds couldn’t satisfy plausible conditions on inferential justification, at least if the requirement for inferential justification insists only on the capacity to come up with the relevant justifications. And we should be cautious before we denigrate the wondrous capacities of the human mind. In some sense, it seems that we can have not only infinitely many beliefs, but infinitely many justified beliefs. I justifiably believe that 2 is greater than 1, that 3 is greater than 1, and so on ad infinitum. I justifiably believe that I exist, that either there are unicorns or I exist, that either there are warlocks or I exist, and so on, for (arguably) infinitely many propositions I have the capacity to disjoin with the proposition that I exist. It is not clear to me, however, that the availability of infinitely many justified beliefs will help us to avoid another sort of regress that will still force us to choose between foundationalism and either skepticism or the view that the very idea of justification is incoherent.

REGRESS ARGUMENTS AND SKEPTICISM

539

4  CONCEPTUAL REGRESS Let us return to the idea of inferential justification, and let us focus again on the principle that one is inferentially justified in believing P on the basis of E only if one is justified in believing E. The principle seems true, indeed necessarily true. But why is it necessarily true? Perhaps the most straightforward answer is that the principle unpacks the very idea of inferential justification. It is, plausibly, analytic that one is justified in believing P on the basis of E only if one is justified in believing E. While one might be able to define inferential justification this way, however, one obviously can’t without circularity define justification in general as inferential justification. Our characterization of inferential justification is parasitic upon understanding what a justified belief is. The obvious solution is to recognize that one needs a recursive analysis of epistemic justification. The recursive analysis requires a base clause. The base clause will state a sufficient condition for noninferential justification, a condition that does not itself invoke the concept of justification. Inferential justification will be defined as justification that can be traced ultimately to noninferential justification. Being a descendent of stands to being a son or daughter of, and being instrumentally good stands to being intrinsically good, as being inferentially justified stands to being noninferentially justified. In the end, the infinitist won’t be able to offer an analysis of epistemic justification. We can talk all we want to about the capacity to offer arguments for premises, but we need to add that the relevant arguments will require premises that are justified. Those premises might be justified by further argument, but only if those premises are justified. And the infinitist will never be able to tell us what epistemic justification is without eventually relying on some notion of noninferential justification (see Fumerton 2013).

5  FOUNDATIONS OR SKEPTICISM The epistemic regress argument leaves one a choice between foundationalism and skepticism. The conceptual regress argument leaves one a choice between allowing that we have a concept of noninferential justification and rejecting the very intelligibility of epistemic justification. It is easy enough to conclude that foundationalism must be true (given what most take to be the implausibility of extreme skepticism), but it is much more difficult to give a plausible account of foundational justification. My own view relies heavily on unanalyzable concepts of acquaintance and correspondence (fit) between thought and fact. Its defense in large part involves arguments against alternative conceptions of noninferential justification—in particular externalist foundationalisms. We are not about to canvas competing accounts of noninferential justification here. If one is convinced that neither infinitism nor the coherence theory of justification is plausible, however, one might conclude that all of our energy as epistemologists should be devoted to figuring out what the correct account of noninferential justification is. But, before we reach that conclusion, we should probably look more carefully at reasons philosophers have for worrying about just how one could even in principle end a regress of justification in an intellectually satisfying way. Let’s look at two such

540

SKEPTICISM

reasons—BonJour’s influential argument against foundationalism (offered when he was a coherentist about empirical justification) and the problem of easy justification.

6  BONJOUR AND REGRESS BonJour (1985) offered a deceptively straightforward global argument against any form of foundationalism, an argument that influenced a great many philosophers (but which BonJour himself has since abandoned). Any version of foundationalism will identify some property of a belief or a believer (call it J) as the property exemplification of which renders a belief noninferentially justified. But surely, the argument goes, the mere exemplification of J wouldn’t justify for the believer S the relevant belief unless (1) the believer were aware that J is exemplified. Furthermore, even if S were aware of J, without some reason to think that (2) J beliefs are likely to be true, S would still lack any intellectually satisfying justification. A great deal probably hinges on the notion of what is supposed to make a justification intellectually satisfying. But the basic idea can be illustrated with examples. So consider condition (1). Some foundationalists have argued that a belief that P is noninferentially justified if it is caused by the fact that P (where the causal chain leading from the relevant fact to the belief involves no beliefs as causal intermediaries). The belief’s being caused by its truthmaker would certainly render it true, but if I am trying to figure out whether or not I have any justification for believing P, the belief’s causal ancestry will hardly help me answer the question when I have no idea what that causal ancestry is. But condition (2) is no less plausible. Suppose I notice that some of my beliefs are particularly vivid. I have no idea, however, whether vivid beliefs are more likely to be true than those that are not. If I am looking for assurance that what I believe vividly is true, how could I get such assurance without establishing (or at least getting some justification) for believing that vivid beliefs are likely to be true? It takes but a little reflection to worry that BonJour’s two conditions spell doom for foundationalism. On one interpretation, BonJour’s argument suggests that condition J constitutes noninferential justification for believing P only if it doesn’t really! It is only J conjoined with awareness of it and its connection to truth that could constitute justification (call that J and A). But J and A couldn’t constitute justification either—it’s only J and A conjoined with awareness of J and A and their connection to truth, and so on ad infinitum. Alternatively, one could insist that noninferential justification is exhausted by J, but J is such that necessarily one can’t be in state J without being aware (or having the capacity to be aware) of J and its connection to truth. This latter view is at least coherent, but still seems to require infinitely many capacities to entertain more and more complex propositions, something that might worry those of us who can’t keep thing straight past four or five metalevels. I can probably form the thought that I have the three acts of acquaintance that yield firstlevel noninferential justification. And I can probably get myself acquainted with that second-level thought and its correspondence to the complex fact that yields firstlevel justification. But as the levels move up, the thoughts and the facts that make

REGRESS ARGUMENTS AND SKEPTICISM

541

them true get ever more complex—so complex that it is hard to see how a mere mortal might be able to keep them straight. In the abstract, it is clear how the foundationalist must respond to BonJour’s argument. If a foundationalist puts forth some property J that is supposed to be genuinely sufficient for noninferential justification, then that foundationalist had better remember what the view is. That foundationalist should not concede that something other than the exemplification of J is required for noninferential justification. Indeed, reflection on BonJour’s argument should make one realize that, if successful, it is a “nuclear” objection that defeats any proposed account of justification (foundational or not). To illustrate, BonJour himself defended a coherentist account of empirical justification. Crudely, S’s belief that P is justified when P coheres in the “right” way with the rest of what S believes. Call the relevant property of cohering C. But the argument against foundationalism presumably applies equally to C. Coherence by itself wouldn’t do S any good when it comes to S’s seeking philosophical assurance for believing P. It would only be coherence coupled with S’s awareness of that coherence and S’s awareness of how coherence renders likely the truth of beliefs that cohere that would give S intellectually satisfying justification. But however the coherentist tries to understand that awareness (presumably it would be in terms of yet more coherence), it wouldn’t do the job unless we had awareness of that, and we are off on another apparently vicious regress. So if we are going to try to build a recursive analysis of justification on our understanding of noninferential justification, we will succeed only if we find some set of conditions that constitute noninferential justification without adding to those conditions the requirement that we be aware of them. The externalists are quite content to jettison the awareness requirements, but their externalist analyses seem vulnerable to what Bergmann (2006) calls (reminding us of BonJour’s argument) the subject’s perspective objection—the idea that having noninferential justification seems strangely divorced from anything that gives one, from the firstperson perspective, assurance of truth. The internalist, by contrast, needs to find an account of noninferential justification that connects having that justification to assurance, but without requiring infinitely many levels of awareness. I think the acquaintance theory I have developed elsewhere walks that fine line, but, if it doesn’t succeed, skepticism looms once again on the horizon. BonJour’s argument against foundationalism is heuristically valuable. It reminds us that our search for a plausible account of epistemic justification cannot be divorced from our search for intellectual assurance.

7  THE PROBLEM OF EASY JUSTIFICATION Most epistemologists have converged on the idea that we must avoid regress in both securing and understanding justification. But the impulse to always move in the direction of inferential justification when seeking justification is undeniably seductive. We can feel that impulse in yet another context when we consider the problem of easy justification.

542

SKEPTICISM

The locution “the problem of easy knowledge” was coined by Stewart Cohen (2002), but versions of the problem were also discussed in Fumerton (1995) and Vogel (2000). Let’s briefly look at examples that illustrate the dilemma. Suppose, as some do, that we have basic knowledge, or, for our purposes, noninferential justification for believing that something is red when the belief is based on the fact that the thing looks red. Consider a close variation of Cohen’s example. In his hypothetical situation his son starts worrying that a given object that looks red isn’t really red (but is, rather, some other color under distorting light). Cohen imagines trying to respond this way to his son’s concern: (1) That looks red (known through introspection) (2) That is red (noninferentially justified) (3) Since it is a red thing that looks red, it isn’t an object with some other color distorted by light to look red. We can relax. But the kid will surely realize that Dad pulled a fast one. If the kid wanted some sort of assurance that the object is red, he didn’t get it. Vogel considers a crude reliabilism that takes the reliability of a belief-forming process (i.e., suitably belief-independent) to be a sufficient condition for the resulting belief’s being justified. He then imagines a situation in which a person is absurdly trying to check on the reliability of his car’s gas gauge through an inductive argument whose premises rely on trusting the gauge. The reasoning proceeds this way: the gauge reads half full so the car is half full; the gauge reads a quarter full, so the car is a quarter full; the gauge reads an eighth full, and so on. Conclusion: this seems to be a pretty reliable gas gauge! But surely this is no way to get yourself justification for believing that the gas gauge is reliable.2 Finally, imagine someone trying to justify reliance on testimony, and suppose, as some do, that testimony is a basic source of justification: (1) S1 testified that P, so (I conclude based on the testimony) P. (2) S2 testified that Q, so (I conclude based on the testimony) Q. (3) S3 testified that R, so (I conclude based on the testimony) R. Repeat until you get tired and conclude (on inductive grounds) (4) Testimony is generally reliable. Again, self-respecting skeptics and those who take the problem of skepticism seriously will conclude that this attempt to vindicate reliance on testimony is a bad joke. What does all of this have to do with regress? Well, there is an obvious solution to each of the pathetic attempts described above that were designed to justify belief in the reliability of various sources of belief. In the case of basic (noninferential) justification, the solution is to conclude that the alleged basic justification supporting the premises wasn’t basic at all. In concluding that the object is red, the father needed as a separate empirical premise the claim that usually when an object like this looks red it is red, and that premise needs to be justified for the father

REGRESS ARGUMENTS AND SKEPTICISM

543

before the father can reach conclusions about the color of the object. In the cases of problematic attempts to “easily” use an inferential source to generate justified beliefs in the source’s reliability, we can offer a similar diagnosis. When justifying the premise asserting that the gas tank is half full by noticing that the gauge indicates that the tank is half full, we need to rely on the unstated premise that the gauge is reliable. But that premise is the very conclusion we are trying to establish with our inductive argument. Because our conclusion appears as a premise justifying the premise, we are blatantly begging the question. And to get ourselves justification for believing the premises of our inductive argument for the reliability of testimony, we need to have antecedent and independent justification that testimony is generally reliable.3 When that critical premise needed to get justified belief in the premises of our inductive argument is made explicit, we again realize that the conclusion of our inductive argument appears as critical support for its premises—the argument is viciously circular. In fact, I think that this diagnosis of why the “easy” justification isn’t available in our specific examples is quite correct. But can we generalize? Shall we always conclude that before we form a justified belief based on some input (whether a belief or some other stimulus), we need a justified belief in a connecting principle? That doesn’t seem like a good idea. We clearly face regress.

8  THE CARROLL PUZZLE Consider Lewis Carroll’s (1895) famous dialogue between the Tortoise and Achilles. The two end up discussing the following proof from Euclid: (A) Things that are equal to the same are equal to each other. (B) The two sides of this Triangle are things that are equal to the same. (Z) The two sides of this Triangle are equal to each other. The Tortoise convinces Achilles that he wouldn’t be forced by reason to the conclusion Z unless he accepted not only the premises (A) and (B) but the conditional: (C) If (A and B) then Z. But given that this acceptance of (C) is critical, the Tortoise insists that it be included as an additional premise yielding a different argument: (A) Things that are equal to the same are equal to each other. (B) The two sides of this Triangle are things that are equal to the same. (C) If A and B are true, Z must be true. (Z) The two sides of this Triangle are equal to each other. But Achilles is quickly convinced that we can’t stop here. Reason won’t force us to accept (Z) on the basis of the conjunction of (A), (B), and (C) unless we see the connection between that conjunction and (Z), so we should add yet another conditional (D), and off we go on a never-ending regress. The regress with which the Tortoise tortures Achilles is illustrated with what looks like a case of inferential justification. But as we have seen one could also

544

SKEPTICISM

imagine the Tortoise attempting to generate a similar regress with conditions (J) that are supposed to generate noninferential justification for believing some proposition P. When the Tortoise does, we have BonJour’s argument that we considered earlier against foundationalism. Both the Tortoise and BonJour want us to concede that J’s obtaining by itself won’t force us by reason to the conclusion that P. We’ll also need to be committed (in some sense) to the position that the belief is a fitting response to the obtaining of J.4 But if make such a commitment and formulate it as a premise necessary to reach the conclusion that P, we’ve just lost our noninferential justification.

9  THE PRINCIPLE OF INFERENTIAL JUSTIFICATION AND THE THREAT OF REGRESS We know we need to resist the Tortoise’s suggestion that whenever we reach conclusions based on some state we are in or some justified beliefs we have, we should add as a separate premise a proposition asserting that there is the appropriate evidential connection between the basis of our belief and the propositions believed. But at the same time, it seems hard to avoid the conclusion that we are sometimes irresistibly moved to add the additional “connecting” principle as a premise. In the case of the gas gauge discussed above, I argued that before you could rationally trust the gas gauge to reach a conclusion about the level of fuel, you would need an additional premise asserting the reliability of the gauge. In the case of testimony, I argued for the much more controversial conclusion that you could not justify your premises relying on testimony without a premise stating that the relevant testimony (at least of this sort, under these conditions) is reliable. But the reason one can’t reach a conclusion about the level of the gas based on observing the gauge, or a conclusion about the truth of what somebody asserts based on their merely asserting it is, I think, that the gas gauge display and the testimony are simply not evidence at all supporting the respective beliefs about the level of the gas and the truth of the testimony. To be sure, this sounds really odd. Normally, if I’m asked what my evidence is for thinking that my tank is half full, it would surely be appropriate to respond by appealing to what the gas gauge indicates. It would be more than a bit pedantic to start talking not only about the gas gauge but about whatever general evidence I have for thinking that gas gauges are normally reliable. But that only shows that in ordinary conversation we rely heavily on enthymematic descriptions of our reasoning. The total body of evidence from which we infer even commonplace truths about our environment is, I would argue, extraordinarily complex and involves all sorts of presuppositions. If we fail to realize this, we might be seduced by examples of enthymematic descriptions of reasoning to generalize to the conclusion that one always needs to add to whatever premises one appeals to in inferring a conclusion yet another premise asserting the relevant connection between one’s premises and one’s conclusion. One can’t infer from litmus paper’s turning red in a solution that the solution is acidic without the additional premise that the color of the litmus paper is a reliable guide to the acidity of the solution, but that’s only because there

REGRESS ARGUMENTS AND SKEPTICISM

545

is no evidential probabilistic connection at all between the proposition that the litmus paper turned red and the proposition that the solution is acidic. It is no longer that popular a view, but I would argue that it is also impossible for me to infer that your name is “Baron” from the fact that you told me it was, and that fact alone, because there is also no evidential connection between the former and the latter. So the critical question we need to address in dealing with the puzzle posed by the Tortoise is whether or not we need a premise describing the relevant connection between premises and conclusion (or in the case of noninferential justification, the basis of our belief and the proposition believed), when we have legitimate reasoning where the premises (or the noninferential basis for our belief) do make probable or entail the truth of what we believe. It is tempting to suggest at this point that one should simply decline the Tortoise’s invitation to do that. In the case of inferential justification, however, it still seems right to me that one needs to be able to see the connection between one’s premises and one’s conclusion if one is to have intellectually satisfying justification for believing the conclusion based on the premises. Even when the premises of an argument entail the conclusion of the argument, we surely want to distinguish the person who is aware of the entailment from the person who is not. Both may be caused to believe the conclusion by belief in the premises, but only the former is fully justified in believing the conclusion based on the premises. It is precisely this thought that leads me to endorse the following (highly controversial) principle of inferential justification: PIJ One is justified in believing P on the basis of E only if one is (1) justified in believing P and (2) justified in believing that E makes probable P (where entailment can be thought of as the upper limit of making probable). Won’t insistence on such a principle lead to vicious regress? It is crucial that in responding to this concern one makes clear that the suggestion is not that one adds the proposition that E makes probable P as an additional premise from which one infers P. That is to fall into the very trap that the Tortoise set for Achilles. But to insist on justified belief in that connection (call it C) as a necessary condition for being inferentially justified in believing P on the basis of E is not the same thing as to insist that the inference in question is really an inference from the conjunction E and E makes probable P to P. My former student, Sam Taylor (2013), insists that this response is too clever by half. If a justified belief in a connection between one’s premises and one’s conclusion is part of the story of what justifies one in believing one’s conclusion, why isn’t the proposition describing that connection functioning just as a premise does? And, if that’s right, then why aren’t we vulnerable to the Tortoise’s puzzle? Taylor’s suggestion is that we distinguish justified belief in the critical connection from nonpropositional awareness of the connection, and insist that only the latter is necessary for intellectually satisfying justification. Indeed, he suggests this would make an account of inferential justification analogous to what an acquaintance theorist should say about noninferential justification. On my own view, for example, one is

546

SKEPTICISM

noninferentially justified in believing P when one is directly acquainted with the fact that P and a “fit” between the thought that P and the fact that P. I specifically insist that one does not need to know the distinct proposition that the thought fits the fact in order to have the noninferential justification—I’d better insist on that lest the noninferential justification disappear! Insisting that we need only awareness of fit in the case of noninferential justification, and awareness of probabilistic connection in the case of inferential justification, not only avoids Carroll-style regress, but also allows for those who lack such sophisticated concepts as fit and probability to have justified beliefs. But suppose that one insists that for inferential justification one needs to be justified in believing a proposition describing the relevant probabilistic connection between premises and conclusion. One also insists that the relevant “connecting” proposition not be considered a premise among other premises. Still, how do we avoid regress, at least in the case of probabilistic connection? If E makes probable P (where E is one’s total evidence), won’t it be an empirical truth that E makes probable P and won’t one need to infer such a truth from some other proposition E2, beginning yet another inference pattern that involves regress? I think regress does, in fact, loom if one accepts the principle of inferential justification and holds the view that propositions describing evidential connections are empirical propositions justifiable only a posteriori. If there is a solution, then, it is to argue that when E makes probable P one can in principle know that a priori. Or if one accepts Taylor’s view, one would need to be able to argue that we can be directly aware of such facts as that E makes probable P. But isn’t it obvious that we can’t know a priori such truths, nor can we be directly acquainted with their truth makers? Didn’t we just suggest that whether or not one truth makes probable another is surely an empirical matter? That probably is the conclusion that most epistemologists reach—certainly most externalists—but it is not the only view that has been held in the history of philosophy. Keynes (1921) argued that making probable is an internal relation holding between propositions (where an internal relation is one that holds necessarily when its relata exist). The view isn’t as strange as it initially seems. I suspect the main reason we think that evidential connections hold only contingently is that we confuse genuine evidential connections with the premises and conclusions of arguments described enthymematically. It is almost obvious that the litmus paper’s turning red is only a contingent indicator of the solution’s acidity, but if we were right earlier, litmus paper’s turning red is not something from which we can legitimately infer that the solution is acidic. There are no legitimate arguments with that form.5 By contrast, consider the question whether it is true and, indeed, necessarily true, that my seeming to remember having experience E makes prima facie probable for me that I had experience E. Or consider the question whether it is true, indeed, necessarily true, that the conclusion of an enumerative inductive argument is made prima facie probable by that argument’s premises. Don’t confuse these questions with the question whether it is possible for apparent memories to mislead, or possible for the conclusion of an inductive argument to be false even when the premises are true. That clearly is possible. Nor should we confuse the question with the question whether

REGRESS ARGUMENTS AND SKEPTICISM

547

one can imagine a world in which apparent memory usually leads one astray, or inductive arguments usually have false conclusions. Even that seems possible. But it is far less obvious that one can even conceive of a world in which apparent memory wouldn’t make prima facie likely for one who has the apparent memory that which one seems to remember, or a world in which the conclusion of an enumerative inductive argument wouldn’t be (epistemically) probable relative to its premises (and those premises alone). If one does conclude (as Keynes did) that we can make sense of these “quasi-logical” probability relations holding between propositions, we will need to make sense of a probability relation that cannot be reduced to statistical generalizations—the probability to which this epistemologist appeals can’t be the concept of probability defined in terms of contingent relative frequencies.

10  MODEST FOUNDATIONALISM AND YET ANOTHER THREAT OF REGRESS I said earlier that the key to avoiding the kind of regress that leads us to skepticism is to find a plausible account of foundational justification—the kind of justification that give us assurance of a truth P without our needing to have additional justification for believing some proposition other than P. The goal of this chapter is to discuss regress without evaluating all of the different proposals for how to understand noninferential justification. These days there are important and interesting externalist versions of foundationalism that compete with more traditional views seeking to locate the source of noninferential justification in the mind’s awareness of its own mental states (coupled perhaps with a similar sort of awareness of abstract objects like properties or propositions and their relations). But a full critical evaluation of these views is the topic for another paper. I want to close, however, by adding one note of warning for foundationalists (of all stripes) who are fully committed to cauterizing both epistemic and conceptual regress. It is much more popular these days for foundationalists to adopt what is sometimes called modest foundationalism. The classic foundationalist (inspired often by Descartes) was convinced that one locates genuine foundational justification only when one finds justification so strong that it eliminates the possibility of error. Worried that foundations meeting this test will be too impoverished to support the huge edifice of knowledge and justified belief we seek, some foundationalists wanted to relax this criterion for foundational justification and allow that a belief could be noninferentially justified and defeasible. Let’s say that my justification J for believing P is defeasible when there might be something other than J which, if added to J, would defeat my justification for believing P. Let us illustrate the point with an example Goldman worried about in his early piece introducing a reliabilist version of foundationalism. Like classic foundationalists, Goldman wanted to understand epistemic justification recursively. To do so, he needed to find a base clause—a non-epistemic condition upon which justification supervenes (a sufficient condition for justified belief that was not itself an epistemic condition). His idea was that a belief is noninferentially justified when

548

SKEPTICISM

it is produced by a belief-independent process that is unconditionally reliable. A process is belief-independent just when the input to the belief-forming process is something other than a belief. With the exception of introspection of belief states, belief-forming processes that take as their input other beliefs will output justified beliefs only if the input beliefs are themselves justified. To yield justified beliefs, the belief-dependent processes need only be conditionally reliable, need only yield mostly true beliefs when the input beliefs are true. But Goldman worried about the following hypothetical situation. Let’s suppose that reliance on apparent memory is a good example of a belief-independent, unconditionally reliable process. But also imagine someone who seems to remember that he did X, but where he has been given plausible evidence that his memory is completely unreliable. If such a person goes on to believe that he did X, we would surely want to conclude that the belief he formed is unjustified. How do we fix our account of noninferential justification? Goldman suggests that we complicate it a bit. Let’s say that a belief P is noninferentially justified when the belief is produced by a belief-independent process that is unconditionally reliable and where there are no other reliable processes available which, had they been used as well, would have resulted in a different belief. It sounds OK initially. But if we think about the view, we realize that the other processes to which the account refers are both belief-independent and belief-dependent processes. But the only relevant belief-dependent processes are those that are available and that take as input justified belief. If we say all that, we have failed to give an account of noninferential justification that does not invoke a concept of justification. Conceptual regress looms again. The point is quite general. If foundationalism needs to avoid conceptual regress, it needs to find a recursive analysis that invokes a concept of noninferential justification that doesn’t itself appeal to our understanding of epistemic justification. Any “moderate” foundationalist will need to protect the account of noninferential justification by talking about the absence of defeaters. But the absence of relevant defeaters can only be specified ultimately by talking about the absence of other relevant justification. Our attempt to produce a non-circular account of justified belief (our attempt to avoid conceptual regress) is now in danger of failing.

NOTES 1. So some would argue that there is some sort of implicit rule that one shouldn’t assert what one doesn’t know to be true. A weaker suggestion is that one shouldn’t assert what one has no epistemic reason to believe. Weaker still is the idea that one shouldn’t assert what one doesn’t believe. It is not clear to me that philosophers follow any of these norms in their philosophical writings. 2. The situation actually isn’t quite this bad, at least if one allows oneself certain background assumptions as one initially trusts the gauge. So imagine that one looks at the gauge as it reads full. A few seconds later one looks at the gauge and it indicates that the tank is almost empty. A moment later, though, the gauge tells you once again that the tank is full. At this point one can use one’s background evidence (that the levels of fuel in the tank don’t vary in this way) to reach the conclusion that something is

REGRESS ARGUMENTS AND SKEPTICISM

549

wrong with the gauge. The fact that this didn’t happen doesn’t support the conclusion that the gauge is accurate, but it is not completely worthless—something that could have gone wrong, didn’t. 3. I’m not suggesting that it will be easy to get the critical justified belief without relying on testimony. The threat of skepticism is no doubt part of what drives people to the conclusion that testimony is in some sense a basic source of justification. 4. Sosa (2009) talks of such a commitment being present even in the case of what he calls “animal-level” knowledge. 5. Think about the form of that argument: P; therefore, Q. If there are legitimate nondeductive arguments, they will have a form just as surely as do deductively valid arguments. So one sort of inductive argument has something like the following form: (all) most observed F’s have been G; therefore, (all) most F’s are G. Reasoning from apparent memory arguably has the form: S seems to remember X; therefore, X. The form of reasoning to the best explanation is a matter of much dispute, but it is surely what we need from explanationists if we are to take seriously their suggestions as to how to understand commonplace inference.

REFERENCES Bergmann, Michael. 2006. Justification without Awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press. BonJour, Laurence. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Carroll, Lewis. 1895. “What the Tortoise Said to Achilles,” Mind 4: 278–280. Cohen, Stewart. 2002. “Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 309–329. Foley, Richard. 1979. “Justified Inconsistent Beliefs,” American Philosophical Quarterly 16: 247–258. Fumerton, Richard. 1995. Metaepistemology and Skepticism. Boston: Rowman and Littlefield. Fumerton, Richard. 2004. “Epistemic Probability,” Philosophical Issues 14: 149–164. Fumerton, Richard. 2006. “Epistemic Internalism, Philosophical Assurance, and the Skeptical Predicament.” In T. Crisp, M. Davidson, and D. Vander Laan (eds.), Knowledge and Reality: Essays in Honor of Alvin Plantinga, 179–192. Dordrecht: Springer. Fumerton, Richard. 2013. “Infinitism.” In P. Klein and J. Turri (eds.), Ad Infinitum: New Essays on Epistemological Infinitism, 74–86. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Goldman, Alvin. 1979. “What Is Justified Belief?” In G. Pappas (ed.), Justification and Knowledge, 1–23. Dordrecht: Reidel. Klein, Peter. 1999. “Human Knowledge and the Infinite Regress of Reasons,” Philosophical Perspectives 13: 297–325. Sosa, Ernest. 2009. Reflective Knowledge, volume II. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Taylor, Samuel. 2013. The Problem of Easy Justification: An Investigation of Evidence, Justification and Reliability. Dissertation, University of Iowa. Vogel, Jonathan. 2000. “Reliabilism Leveled,” Journal of Philosophy 97: 602–623.

CHAPTER THIRTY-EIGHT

The Problem of the Criterion ANDREW D. CLING

1 INTRODUCTION The problem of the criterion is the ancient skeptical paradox posed, roughly, by this argument: To know a proposition, we must first know a criterion of truth. To know a criterion of truth, we must first know a proposition. Therefore we cannot know any proposition or any criterion of truth. The problem is nascent in Meno’s paradox and appears in the skeptical “modes” of Sextus Empiricus, the problem of the Cartesian circle, the problem of induction, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, and elsewhere.1 It plays an organizing role in Chisholm’s influential epistemology and vigorous current debates are about issues it raises. The problem, properly understood, is not just about knowledge, justification, or any other specific epistemic value. It is a problem for any epistemic value that beliefs can have only if they are supported by the right kinds of reasons. I explain the problem, discuss some anti-skeptical responses, and show how some important contemporary debates are relevant to it. I conclude with a discussion of epistemic pluralism, human flourishing, and skepticism.

2 CHISHOLM Roderick Chisholm’s account has strongly influenced contemporary discussions of the problem.2 Chisholm intends to pose the problem as an argument from plausible premises to skeptical conclusions, a paradox. In fact, however, Chisholm presents two arguments. The first argument, paraphrased from Montaigne, concerns knowledge: [1] To know whether things really are as they seem to be, we must have a procedure for distinguishing appearances that are true from appearances that are

THE PROBLEM OF THE CRITERION

551

false. [2] But to know whether our procedure is a good procedure, we have to know whether it really succeeds in distinguishing appearances that are true from appearances that are false. And we cannot know whether it does really succeed unless we already know which appearances are true and which ones are false. And so [C] we are caught in a circle. [So [3a] we cannot know which appearances are true and [3b] we cannot know whether any procedure for distinguishing true from false appearances is good.] (Chisholm 1973: 3; here and below, material in brackets has been supplied by me.)3 The second argument poses the problem in terms of two questions about knowledge: [1] You cannot answer question A [“what do we know?”] until you have answered question B [“how do we know?”]. And [2] you cannot answer question B until you have answered question A. Therefore [3] you cannot answer either question. [3a] You cannot know what, if anything, you know, and [3b] there is no possible way for you to decide in any particular case. (1973: 14)4 Chisholm (1973: 12–15) takes these arguments to be the same and claims that there are three responses: reject [1] (particularism), reject [2] (methodism), or accept [3a] and [3b] (skepticism). He endorses particularism but claims that any response begs the question against the others (1973: 37). These arguments are different. The conclusion of the first—henceforth Chisholm’s first argument—is that we cannot know any proposition and we cannot know that any procedure for distinguishing true from false propositions is good. The second argument is metaepistemological. Its conclusion is that we cannot know any proposition about knowledge or any principle for distinguishing true from false propositions about knowledge. Because propositions about knowledge constitute a proper subset of propositions, and epistemic principles—principles expressing necessary and/or sufficient conditions of knowledge—can be criteria for distinguishing true from false propositions about knowledge, the problem posed by the second argument is a special case of the problem posed by Chisholm’s first argument (Cling 1994: 262–266).5 Chisholm’s first argument provides a good starting place for understanding the skeptical argument but it obscures some important features of the problem. First, Chisholm’s first argument does not make it explicit that the problem requires critical assumptions about the reason-providing relationships between propositions and criteria. What makes [1] and [2] plausible are their implicit claims that knowing a proposition P requires knowing a criterion of truth that is a reason for P and vice versa. A statement of the problem needs to make explicit reference to these reasonproviding relationships. Second, Chisholm’s temporal language—“already know,” “until”—needs to be explained. The problem concerns the epistemic, not temporal, priority that good criteria and good propositions seem to require. Chisholm’s first argument indirectly refers to this independence requirement by stating that [1] and [2] require a circle [C], but it does not display the principle that is required to rule out circles of reasons. In fact, however, [1] and [2] do not require circles of reasons, they jointly require endless regresses of reasons: sequences in which each component

552

SKEPTICISM

has a successor that is a good reason for it. Endless sequences can be circular, have infinitely many components, or both. So we need to state the necessary injunctions against all types of endless sequences of reasons. Finally, although Chisholm’s first argument is about the possibility of knowledge, the problem arises for any epistemic value propositions can have only if they are supported by the right kinds of reasons.

3  EPISTEMIC REASONS There are epistemic and non-epistemic reasons for belief. An epistemic reason is a factor that is taken to count in favor of believing a target proposition P because it is taken to count in favor of P’s truth. A non-epistemic reason is a factor that is taken to count in favor of believing a target proposition P because it is taken to count in favor of that belief’s having other benefits. Knowing that most people with the disease I have will die from it can be a good epistemic reason to believe that I will die from the disease. I might, however, have a good pragmatic reason to believe that I will not die from the disease if believing this would improve my chance of survival. Reasons for belief must be mental states with content that we can take to count in favor of the beliefs for which they are reasons.6 Epistemic reasons, therefore, must be beliefs or belief-like mental states with propositional contents that can be taken to count in favor of the truth of their targets.7 A good reason must (a) have content that stands in an appropriate relation to its target and (b) have the normative standing that epistemic reasons must have. That I have $1 million entails that I have at least $500 thousand and therefore stands in a reason-relevant relation to the latter. It is not a good epistemic reason for me to believe anything, however, because it lacks standing: the normative epistemic authority reasons must have if they are to be good reasons for any targets. That I have $1 million lacks the standing to be a good evidence-providing reason since, alas, it seems to have no epistemic value: I have no good reason to believe it and plenty of good reasons to reject it. Two kinds of epistemic reasons are evidential reasons and procedural reasons (Cling 2014b: 164). An evidential reason is a mental state with content P that is taken to count in favor of a target Q by a person S because S takes P to (deductively or inductively) imply that Q is true. P is a good evidential reason for a proposition Q only if (a) S believes that P, (b) P does (deductively or inductively) imply Q, and (c) S’s belief that P has the epistemic value required for standing. Hopes, for example, are mental states with propositional content, but hopes are not, by their nature, the sorts of things that can stand in the support relation required of good evidential reasons. Beliefs are the right sorts of things to stand in the relevant support relations, but beliefs lacking the epistemic value required for standing are not good reasons. Beliefs that it is epistemically impermissible or irresponsible to hold are not good evidential reasons for any proposition, for example. A critical question raised by the problem of the criterion, therefore, is whether propositions or criteria of truth can have epistemic value without being supported by good epistemic reasons.8 Procedural reasons involve criteria of truth. The word “criterion” derives from the Indo-European word for sifter (Watkins 2000: 113). Criteria are principles by

THE PROBLEM OF THE CRITERION

553

means of which we may sift or sort things in order to identify what we seek: wheat, sheep, Shinola™, truths, etc. A criterion of truth is a principle according to which a detectable property D is positively relevant to the truth of propositions. An ideal criterion of truth would be a true principle with this form: for any proposition P, P has D if, and only if, P is true. We should, however, be liberal and count other principles—principles that express only sufficient, necessary, or probabilistic conditions of truth; fallible principles; principles restricted to a limited domain; etc.—as criteria of truth. A procedural reason is a belief that C where C is a criterion of truth. C is not usually evidence for a proposition P that C identifies to be true, but a belief that C can be a reason to believe that P is true by expressing and underwriting the process, procedure, norm, rule, or method (henceforth “method”) by which a person identifies P to be true.9 That (S) propositions about macroscopic objects identified to be true in light of sensory experiences are usually true is not evidence that (E) there is a written sentence in front of me now but a person S’s belief that (S) can count in favor of the truth of (E) if (S) expresses and underwrites the method by which S identifies P to be true. That (I) inductive generalizations with true premises usually have true conclusions is not evidence that (R) the sun will rise tomorrow but can count in favor of (R) if S’s belief that (I) expresses and underwrites the rule of inference governing the method by which S identifies (R) to be true on the basis of S’s other beliefs. A belief that C is a good procedural reason for a target P for a person S only if (a) C is a criterion of truth that is implicit or explicit in the method by which S identifies P to be true, (b) C picks out P, and (c) S’s belief that C has the required epistemic standing.10 A good procedural reason would put us in a better epistemic position with respect to the propositions that a method M identifies to be true by making our commitment to M explicit and by being a good reason to trust M. A good reason to trust a method must be, at least, a belief that it is reliable or is in some other way epistemically trustworthy. Criteria of truth are themselves propositions, but I assume that we can distinguish them from propositions that are not criteria. Exactly how criteria of truth figure in the methods we use to identify truths is a question I also leave to the side. Unless criteria are believed, however, they cannot be epistemic reasons since such reasons must be beliefs.11

4  THE PROBLEM SCHEMA We are now in a position to state the problem of the criterion more carefully and completely. I shall state the problem as a schema for skeptical arguments about an otherwise unspecified epistemic value Ф. Let P be a variable for propositions that do not express criteria of truth, and let C be a variable for principles that do.12 This schema generalizes and completes Chisholm’s first argument: (1) A proposition P can have epistemic value Ф only if some C has Ф and C is an epistemic reason for P. (2) A criterion C can have epistemic value Ф only if some P has Ф and P is an epistemic reason for C.

554

SKEPTICISM

(NC) No P or C can have Ф if that requires a finite, circular sequence of epistemic reasons that have Ф. (NIR) No P or C can have Ф if that requires an infinite sequence of epistemic reasons that have Ф. (3a) ∴ No proposition can have Ф. (3b) ∴ No criterion can have Ф.

The premises of the argument are plausible for many epistemic values Ф. (1) says that a proposition P can have epistemic value only for persons who believe a principle underwriting the method by which they have identified P to be true and for whom that belief has that epistemic value. For example, it is plausible that P is justified only for persons who are justified in believing that the method by which they have identified P to be true is reliable. (2) says that a criterion can have epistemic value only for persons who have a good epistemic reason to believe that criterion. For example, it is plausible that a principle for distinguishing true from false propositions can be known by a person S only if S knows evidence that supports that principle. (NC)—for “No Circles”—states, plausibly, that no proposition can have epistemic value if that requires a finite circle of epistemic reasons that have that value. Likewise, (NIR)—for “No Infinite Regresses”—states, plausibly, that no proposition can have epistemic value if that requires an infinite regress of good epistemic reasons. (NC) and (NIR) are weak since they do not entail that circles or infinite regresses of reasons cannot be relevant to Ф. In particular, they are compatible with the idea that circles or infinite regresses of reasons might play a significant role in enhancing the epistemic value of some propositions or criteria.13 (1) and (2) jointly entail that epistemic value Ф requires either a circle or an infinite regress of good epistemic reasons. This, together with (NC) and (NIR), entails (3a) and (3b). So either at least one of these plausible assumptions is false or skepticism is true. The schema shows that there is a version of the problem of the criterion for any epistemic value Ф for which (1), (2), (NC), and (NIR) are plausible.

5  THE RANGE OF RESPONSES Following Chisholm, we can understand the types of responses to the problem of the criterion in terms of (1), (2), (NC), (NIR), (3a), and (3b). To describe these types of responses, I use Chisholm’s terminology as far as possible. Particularism holds that (1) is false: a good proposition need not be supported by a good criterion of truth. Perhaps, for example, one need not know that the procedure by which one has identified a proposition to be true is reliable in order to know that proposition. Methodism holds that (2) is false: a good criterion need not be supported by any good evidential reason. Perhaps, for example, a person can be justified in believing a criterion of truth without having any justified evidential reason for that criterion. Skepticism about an epistemic value is true if the argument is sound. This list leaves out responses that reject (NC) or (NIR). Coherentism, as we may call it, is a family of epistemological theories that reject (NC) on the grounds that propositions and criteria can have epistemic value Ф on the basis of finite but

THE PROBLEM OF THE CRITERION

555

circular sequences of reasons. Likewise infinitism, as we may call it, is a family of epistemologies that reject (NIR) on the related grounds that propositions and criteria can have value Ф on the basis of infinite regresses of good reasons. This list still undercounts the types of responses. For one thing, there are antiskeptical epistemologies that reject more than one of the premises of the argument. One variety of contextualism, for example, holds that propositions and criteria can have epistemic value without being supported by good epistemic reasons provided they are immunized against the need for reasons by the conventions governing the relevant context of inquiry, so both (1) and (2) are false. Similarly, intuitionism can hold that because we are able to apprehend the truth of some criterion and some proposition without having epistemic reasons for them, both (1) and (2) are false. So although there will be as many types of anti-skeptical response to the problem of the criterion as there are premises in the skeptical argument—four—there is no limit to the arguments that might be given against any premise on the basis of different epistemological theories. The epistemological theories that underwrite these arguments need share little else beyond the premises they reject. I shall not discuss specific epistemologies in detail. Rather, I consider each premise of the skeptical argument schema and call attention to problems for any epistemology that rejects it.

6  DISSOLVING THE PROBLEM Some claim that the problem is not genuine. Robert Amico, for example, argues that skepticism is self-refuting if “the skeptic” proposes to support skepticism with reasons and inert if “the skeptic” has no beliefs. So the problem dissolves (Amico 1993: 119–139).14 A problem for this response is that the problem does not require skeptics. The problem exists because propositions about what epistemic value requires that are individually plausible to anti-skeptics entail skepticism. Noting that it is constituted by such propositions is to recognize, not to dissolve, the problem. An anti-skeptical response must give an account that explains why one of the premises of the argument is false.

7  PARTICULARISM: REJECTING (1) Particularist epistemologies imply that (1) is false because they imply that propositions can have epistemic value without being supported by any criterion having that value. Assuming that propositions with epistemic value can be good (though possibly fallible) epistemic reasons for the propositions they deductively or inductively imply, a challenge for particularist epistemologies is to explain how propositions that are not supported by good criteria can be good epistemic reasons. In particular, particularist epistemologies must account for the conditions under which such propositions can be good reasons to believe criteria of truth. Some examples of particularist epistemologies are traditional foundationalism, reliabilism, intuitionism, some versions of contextualism, and many externalist

556

SKEPTICISM

theories, such as reliabilism. Traditional foundationalism holds that propositions can acquire epistemic value by being apprehended in a way that makes us directly aware of their truth or by standing in a relevant evidential relationship to non-doxastic mental states such as sensory experiences.15 So (1) is false. Reliabilism implies that beliefs have epistemic value if they are produced by methods that produce sufficiently more true than false beliefs. If so, then (1) is false since it is possible that some belief is produced by a reliable process that does not include any epistemic reasons. There are two major challenges for particularist epistemologies: arbitrariness and easy knowledge. The claim that some beliefs can have epistemic value without being supported by any criterion of truth implies that it can be good to trust a method for identifying true propositions—the method by which one has formed those very beliefs—without having any beliefs about that method. It seems, however, that there are some methods that it would not be good to trust without having evidence for their reliability. If you seek truth about the road to Larissa, it is not good to rely on the testimony of a stranger you have no reason to trust even if the stranger happens to be reliable. It seems arbitrary, however, to suppose that things are any different for the more general methods we happen to trust: sense perception, rational insight, memory, norms for deductive and inductive reasoning, etc. Second, if we claim that beliefs that are not supported by criteria of truth can be good reasons to believe in the reliability of the methods that produce them, we sanction a kind of epistemic circularity and face the problem of easy knowledge.16 The problem of easy knowledge is about whether beliefs that are produced by a method M can be good reasons to believe that M is reliable. If (1) is false, then beliefs that are not supported by any criterion can have epistemic value. Hence, in the absence of some principle preventing it, such beliefs can be good evidential reasons for the criteria that underwrite the very methods that produce them (bootstrapping). This seems too easy. If beliefs can be good evidential reasons for the reliability of the very methods that produce them, then a kind of epistemic circularity is not vicious.17 A plausible constraint on good evidential reasons, however, is that beliefs that result from a method cannot be good evidential reasons for the reliability of that method. This constraint would explain why it is not good to believe, for example, that a gas gauge is reliable on the basis of a belief about its track record—it has been correct every time I have checked—that is itself based on beliefs acquired by reading that gauge. Two responses to this problem that would allow us to maintain that (1) is false have received significant attention in contemporary epistemology: denying closure and biting the bullet. Rejecting (1) implies that bootstrapping is legitimate only if the epistemic value required to be a good evidential reason is closed under deductive and inductive implication. To say that epistemic value Ф is closed under implication is to say that if P has Ф, then P transmits Ф to any proposition Q for person S if P implies Q, perhaps provided that S recognizes the implication, bases the belief that Q on the belief that P, there are no relevant defeaters, and so on. If closure fails, therefore, we can reject the view that readings of a gas gauge are good evidential reasons for its reliability while still maintaining that some beliefs are good without being supported by good procedural reasons. To do so, however, we must reject one or more of the

THE PROBLEM OF THE CRITERION

557

following sorts of claims: (R) the gas gauge reads ½ full is a good evidential reason for (H) the gas tank is ½ full; (R) & (H) is a good evidential reason for (T) the gauge is correct this time; (T) is a good evidential reason for (C) the gauge has been correct every time I have checked; or (C) is a good evidential reason for the gauge is reliable. It is hard to see how any of these claims is mistaken (Barnett 2014: 181–187). This complex issue is vigorously debated in contemporary epistemology.18 Another response to the problem of easy knowledge is to bite the bullet, endorse bootstrapping, and accept that knowledge can be easy. On this view, beliefs produced by method M and for which one has no procedural reason can be good and can support M is reliable: this kind of epistemic circularity is not vicious. James Van Cleve argues that this strategy provides the key to solving both the problem of the Cartesian circle and the problem of induction, and is the only alternative to skepticism.19 This approach, however, faces the significant challenge of making a principled distinction between when it is and when it is not good to trust a method without having evidence for its reliability.

8  METHODISM: REJECTING (2) Methodist epistemologies imply that (2) is false because they hold that it is possible that a criterion can have epistemic value without being supported by a good evidential reason. A challenge for any methodist epistemology is to explain how this is not unacceptably risky and arbitrary (Chisholm 1973: 17). Two examples of methodist epistemologies are criteriological intuitionism and criteriological contextualism. Criteriological intuitionism holds that we can apprehend the correctness of some criterion without having a good epistemic reason for it. So criteriological intuitionism implies that (2) is false since a belief in an intuited criterion can have epistemic value without being supported by any epistemic reason.20 Likewise, a contextualist can hold that the rules governing what is appropriate in a context of inquiry immunize some criteria against any requirement that we have epistemic reasons for them.21 So (2) is false because unsupported criteria can have epistemic value in contexts where support is not required. Methodist epistemologies face a problem similar to one of the problems for particularist theories: it appears to be arbitrary to believe a criterion without a good epistemic reason. Just as particularists claim that it can be reasonable to trust an unsupported method—whether or not we explicitly believe it to be reliable— methodist epistemologies imply that it can be reasonable to believe that a method is reliable without having any good epistemic reason for that belief. Methodist epistemologies must, therefore, explain why it is reasonable to believe some criteria without having reasons for them, but not reasonable to believe others without having good reasons. An intutionist might claim that some criteria are special because we can simply apprehend their correctness without good epistemic reasons. This does not solve the problem, however, unless there is an explanation for why we should trust the products of intuition without evidence for the reliability of intuition itself. Responsible inquiry seems to require that we have good evidential reasons for some of the criteria that express and underwrite our belief-forming methods. Methodists

558

SKEPTICISM

must explain why this does not license arbitrariness and, specifically, why it is true in some cases but not others.

9  COHERENTISM AND INFINITISM: REJECTING (NC) OR (NIR) Coherentist epistemologies reject (NC) on the grounds that even though epistemic value always requires a circle of good epistemic reasons, beliefs can have epistemic value because not all circularity is vicious.22 Infinitist epistemologies reject (NIR) on the grounds that even though epistemic value always requires an infinite regress of epistemic reasons, beliefs can have epistemic value because we can have infinite regresses of good reasons. An attractive feature of both coherentist and infinitist epistemologies is that they imply that epistemic value requires good epistemic reasons. Therefore they have the resources to address the arbitrariness problems for particularism and methodism. Coherentism faces the challenge of explaining why circles of reasons can be good. If all complete sequences of good reasons are finite circles, then every good belief must appear both sooner and later in a sequence of reasons in which every component has a successor that supports it. This appears to imply that it can be good to assume the very proposition for which we need a reason. Coherentist epistemologies must also explain why circularity is good in some cases but not in others. Like particularism, coherentism also faces the problem of easy knowledge. For if the beliefs in a circular system can be good, it seems that such beliefs could be good reasons to believe in the reliability of the very methods that produce them. Though they occupy a position in the space of possible responses to the problem of the criterion, infinitist epistemologies have not usually been taken seriously. Due to work by Peter Klein and others, however, infinitist epistemologies have been defended by some contemporary philosophers, though they have not usually been advanced as solutions to the problem of the criterion.23 As a response to that problem, infinitism has a number of attractive features. Because they imply that good beliefs must be supported by good reasons, infinitist epistemologies are not subject to the arbitrariness problems for particularism and methodism. Unlike coherentist epistemologies, they need not accept circles of reasons. Nor need they face the problem of easy knowledge, provided that beliefs further “upstream” in an infinite sequence of good epistemic reasons are not produced by the same methods that produce the “downstream” beliefs. A major challenge for infinitist responses to the problem of the criterion is to explain how it is possible to have infinitely many procedural reasons, hence infinitely many methods of belief formation.24

10  CONCLUSION: VALUES, PLURALISM, AND SKEPTICISM Perhaps there are different kinds of epistemic goodness and good epistemic reasons. If so, then different epistemologies might identify different kinds of good beliefs and reasons. A common practice in epistemology is to debate the conditions on

THE PROBLEM OF THE CRITERION

559

epistemic goodness by appealing to intuitions about whether or not persons would have knowledge or justification in test cases involving the number of coins in one’s pocket, painted mules, and so on.25 A plausible explanation for the logjam of intuitions about whether there is knowledge or justified belief in such cases is that different epistemologies have identified different kinds of knowledge and justified belief. For example, if our goal is simply to have true beliefs, reliably produced beliefs might be good whether or not we have any reasons for them. If, however, our goal is to be responsible inquirers or to be rationally autonomous agents, then such beliefs might not be good. Pluralism about epistemic values and kinds of epistemic reasons supports the idea that we broaden epistemological inquiry by investigating the conceptions of human flourishing that inform our intuitions about whether or not persons have good beliefs in the cases that constitute epistemological examples and counterexamples. In particular, it supports the idea that we consider the kinds of reasons we need in order to satisfy the ideals expressed by different conceptions of a meaningful life. If the kinds of good beliefs and reasons we need according to a given conception of flourishing need not satisfy all of the premises that pose the problem of the criterion, we have the basis for an anti-skeptical response to the problem for that kind of epistemic value. I fear, however, that there are attractive conceptions of flourishing that do require the kinds of good beliefs and reasons that satisfy (1), (2), (NC), and (NIR): being intellectually responsible and being rationally autonomous agents, for example.26 If so, skepticism about such reasons and the epistemic goods that require them is true. Should we abandon the ideals that require such reasons? Might we, instead, be better persons by accepting ideals that we recognize to be impossible? I hope so, but making this plausible and figuring out what it implies for how we ought to conduct our intellectual lives requires a lot of explaining. I end on this skeptical note hoping that these questions and the problem of the criterion will be the focus of continued research in epistemology and ethics.27

NOTES 1. Sextus (1996: 104 = PH I, 114–117; 105 = PH I, 121–123; 128–129 = PH II, 19–20). The problem of the Cartesian circle is posed in Arnauld’s objections to Descartes’s Meditations in Descartes (1984: 150 = AT 214). Descartes’s reply, about which there remains deep disagreement concerning both its nature and success, is in his replies to Arnauld’s objection (Descartes 1984: 171 = AT 245–246). Van Cleve (1979) presents an exceptionally clear explanation of the Cartesian circle, a criticism of many proposed solutions, and an original proposed solution. Tlumak (1978) proposes a solution to the problem that is deeply informed, philosophically astute, and underappreciated (see also Tlumak 2007: 52–59). The problem of induction is raised in Hume (1977: section 4, 15–25). Weintraub (1995) shows that the problem of induction is a version of the problem of the criterion. The problem of the criterion is also raised by Hegel (1977: 52), who uses it to support his dialectical method. 2. Chisholm says, “I am tempted to say that one has not begun to philosophise [sic] until one has faced this problem and has recognized how unappealing, in the end, each of the possible solutions is” (1973: 1).

560

SKEPTICISM

3. Chisholm also poses the problem, among other places, in Chisholm (1957: 30–39; 1977: 119–134). 4. For critical discussion, see Cling (1994; 1997). 5. It seems that most contemporary epistemologists have identified the problem of the criterion with the narrower metaepistemological problem. See, for example, Steup (1992; 1995). Weisberg (2010: 598) addresses the problem in connection with bootstrapping, discussed below, but calls it “the regress problem.” For whatever reason, many discussions of issues concerning the most general version of the problem of the criterion have not been identified to be relevant to it. 6. For arguments for this, see Turri (2009), Gibbons (2010), and Cling (2014: 59–60). 7. I leave to the side the difficult question of whether non-doxastic states—with or without propositional content—can be epistemic reasons. In Cling (2008: 408– 411), I argue that reasons must be beliefs or belief-like mental states. 8. Strictly speaking, epistemic reasons must be de dicto beliefs. Since such beliefs have propositional content, I shall sometimes call propositions instead of beliefs “reasons,” either as shorthand or in contexts where it is the propositional content of the belief that plays the essential role. 9. As the literature on reliabilism—the family of views according to which positive epistemic values are to be understood in terms of the reliability of belief-forming methods—shows, it is non-trivial to individuate methods. See, e.g., Feldman (1985). 10. Giving only necessary conditions on good epistemic reasons as I have leaves it open that additional conditions must be satisfied. 11. In Cling (2014: 60–61), I make use of an attractive concept of norms due to Haugeland (1982: 16–17) that identifies norms with complex dispositions, not propositions. I conjecture that it is norms, in Haugeland’s sense, that play the fundamental role in most of the methods by which we identify propositions to be true and that a crucial role for procedural reasons is to make explicit the principles that are implicit in such norms and to give us reasons to trust those norms. 12. Epistemic propositions also need to be indexed to persons and times. Nothing in my discussion turns on this, so I abbreviate. When the epistemological chips are down, however, we can spell out principles in full. Premise (1) of the argument, for example, is short for a proposition P can have epistemic value Ф for a person S at a time t only if some C has Ф for S at t and C is an epistemic reason for P for S at t. 13. For an argument that a proposition can enhance the justification we have for it by being in its own reason ancestry, see Cling (2002). 14. Amico seems to be addressing only the metaepistemological version of the problem, but my criticism still applies. Amico has more to say on dissolution and pseudoproblems in Amico (1993: 13). 15. Moser (1985) offers a detailed survey and critique of a wide range of theories of justification, in addition to defending a powerful version of internalist foundationalism according to which non-doxastic sensory appearances provide evidence for basic beliefs. 16. On the problem of easy knowledge and bootstrapping see, e.g., Fumerton (1995: 173–181), Vogel (2000; 2008), Cohen (2002)—who explicitly notes the relevance

THE PROBLEM OF THE CRITERION

561

of the problem of easy knowledge to the problem of the criterion—and Barnett (2014). Weisberg (2012) gives a useful overview of the issues. 17. Excellent discussions of epistemic circularity are given in Alston (1986; 1993). I have attempted to characterize and apply the notion in Cling (2002: 254–256; 2003: 281–287). It will be clear from my discussion that problems about bootstrapping and epistemic circularity are intimately related. 18. For a good introduction to some of the issues about closure, see the debate between Dretske (2005a,b) and Hawthorne (2005). Barnett (2014) is especially helpful on the connections between bootstrapping, epistemic circularity, and closure, and his paper has greatly influenced my account of these issues. 19. Van Cleve has developed this view in connection with these problems in Van Cleve (1979; 1984; 2003). For a criticism of Van Cleve’s proposed solution to the problem of the Cartesian circle, see Cling (1997). 20. Van Cleve (2003: 50–51) cites Reid (1969: 617, 622, 625, 630) as holding this position. 21. Williams (2001: 169–170) outlines this type of contextualist response to the problem of the criterion. 22. DePaul (1988) defends coherentism as a response to the problem of the criterion in ethics. Elgin (1996) defends a coherentist epistemology for all beliefs, though it contains a particularist element by allowing that beliefs have a default positive epistemic status—initial tenability (Elgin 1996: 101–02)—until we have epistemic reasons to revise them. Initial tenability, however, may depend upon having nonepistemic reasons: “That the sentences we accept do not in general frustrate our efforts is some reason to accept them” (Elgin 1996: 102). If so, then Elgin’s system resembles Lynch’s, which also claims that we can have good non-epistemic reasons for our methods (Lynch 2012: 78; 88–108). 23. Defenses of infinitism are in Klein (1999) and Aikin (2010). Infinitism is discussed from a wide range of perspectives in Klein and Turri (2014). I criticize infinitism in Cling (2004; 2014a). I discuss the relationship between the epistemic regress problem and the problem of the criterion in Cling (2014b), though the statement of the problem in this chapter is, I think, superior to the one I gave in that one. 24. Klein (1999) responds to the related finite minds problem about evidential reasons by weakening the conditions on having a reason: reasons are merely second-order dispositions to be disposed to form the relevant beliefs in the required contexts. Can a similar sort of response give us access to infinitely many belief-forming methods? For an argument that the kinds of reasons that Klein provides to solve the finite minds objection are not the kinds of reasons we ought to want if we are to attain certain kinds of human flourishing, see Cling (2014a: 62–71). 25. An important boon to this approach was provided by Gettier (1963). For a detailed account of a range of attempts to solve Gettier’s problem, see Shope (1983). 26. I argue that there are such reasons in Cling (2009: 339–340; 2014a: 62–71; 2014b: 165–170). 27. I am very grateful to my colleague Nicholaos Jones and to Diego Machuca and Baron Reed for very useful comments on an earlier draft of this chapter. The errors that remain are mine alone.

562

SKEPTICISM

REFERENCES Aikin, Scott. 2010. Epistemology and the Regress Problem. New York: Routledge. Alston, William P. 1986. “Epistemic Circularity,” Philosophical Studies 47: 1–28. Alston, William P. 1993. The Reliability of Sense Perception. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Amico, Robert. 1993. The Problem of the Criterion. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Barnett, David. 2014. “What’s the Matter with Epistemic Circularity?” Philosophical Studies 171: 177–205. Chisholm, Roderick. 1957. Perceiving. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Chisholm, Roderick. 1973. The Problem of the Criterion. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. Chisholm, Roderick. 1977. Theory of Knowledge, 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: PrenticeHall. Cling, Andrew. 1994. “Posing the Problem of the Criterion,” Philosophical Studies 75: 261–292. Cling, Andrew. 1997. “Epistemic Levels and the Problem of the Criterion,” Philosophical Studies 88: 109–140. Cling, Andrew. 2002. “Justification-affording Circular Arguments,” Philosophical Studies 111: 251–275. Cling, Andrew. 2003. “Self-supporting Arguments,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66: 279–303. Cling, Andrew. 2004. “The Trouble with Infinitism.” Synthese 138: 101–123. Cling, Andrew. 2008. “The Epistemic Regress Problem,” Philosophical Studies 140: 401– 421. Cling, Andrew. 2009. “Reasons, Regresses, and Tragedy,” American Philosophical Quarterly 46: 333–346. Cling, Andrew. 2014a. “Reasons Require Reasons.” In P. Klein and J. Turri (eds.), Ad Infinitum: New Essays on Epistemological Infinitism, 55–74. New York: Oxford University Press. Cling, Andrew. 2014b. “The Epistemic Regress Problem, the Problem of the Criterion, and the Value of Reasons,” Metaphilosophy 45: 161–171. Cohen, Stewart. 2002. “Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 309–329. DePaul, Michael. 1988. “The Problem of the Criterion and Coherence Methods in Ethics,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18: 67–86. Descartes, René. 1984. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. 2, translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch. New York: Cambridge University Press. Dretske, Fred. 2005a. “The Case against Closure.” In M. Steup, and E. Sosa (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 13–25. Malden, MA: Blackwell. Dretske, Fred. 2005b. “Reply to Hawthorne.” In M. Steup, and E. Sosa (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 43–46. Malden, MA: Blackwell. Elgin, Catherine. 1996. Considered Judgment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Feldman, Richard. 1985. “Reliability and Justification,” The Monist 68: 159–174.

THE PROBLEM OF THE CRITERION

563

Fumerton, Richard. 1995. Metaepistemology and Skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Gettier, Edmund. 1963. “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” Analysis 23: 121–123. Gibbons, John. 2010. “Things that Make Things Reasonable,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81: 335–361. Haugeland, John. 1982. “Heidegger on Being a Person,” Noûs 16: 15–26. Hawthorne, John. 2005. “The Case for Closure.” In M. Steup and E. Sosa (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 26–42. Malden, MA: Blackwell. Hegel, G.W.F. (1977). Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A. Miller. New York: Oxford University Press. Hume, David. 1977. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, edited by E. Steinberg. Indianapolis: Hackett. Klein, Peter. 1999. “Human Knowledge and the Infinite Regress of Reasons,” Philosophical Perspectives 13: 297–325. Klein, Peter and John Turri (eds.). 2014. Ad Infinitum: New Essays on Epistemological Infinitism. New York: Oxford University Press. Lynch, Michael. 2012. Praise of Reason. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Moser, Paul K. 1985. Empirical Justification. Boston: D. Reidel. Reid, Thomas. 1969. Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, edited by B. Brody. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Sextus Empiricus. 1996. The Skeptic Way: Sextus Empiricus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism, translated by B. Mates. New York: Oxford University Press. Shope, Robert. 1983. The Analysis of Knowing: A Decade of Research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Steup, Matthias. 1992. “Problem of the Criterion.” In J. Dancy and E. Sosa (eds.), A Companion to Epistemology, 378–381. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell. Steup, Matthias. 1995. “Problem of the Criterion.” In R. Audi (ed.), The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 653. New York: Cambridge University Press. Steup, Matthias and Ernest Sosa (eds.). 2005. Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Malden, MA: Blackwell. Tlumak, Jeffrey. 1978. “Squaring the Cartesian Circle,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 16: 247–257. Tlumak, Jeffrey. 2007. Classical Modern Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction. New York: Routledge. Turri, John. 2009. “The Ontology of Epistemic Reasons,” Noûs 43: 490–512. Van Cleve, James. 1979. “Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles, and the Cartesian Circle,” The Philosophical Review 88: 55–91. Van Cleve, James. 1984. “Reliability, Justification, and the Problem of Induction,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9: 555–567. Van Cleve, James. 2003. “Is Knowledge Easy—or Impossible? Externalism as the only Alternative to Skepticism.” In S. Luper (ed.), The Skeptics: Contemporary Essays, 45–59. Aldershot: Ashgate. Vogel, Jonathan. 2000. “Reliabilism Leveled,” The Journal of Philosophy 97: 602–623. Vogel, Jonathan. 2008. “Epistemic Bootstrapping,” The Journal of Philosophy 105: 518–539.

564

SKEPTICISM

Watkins, Calvert (ed.). 2000. The American Heritage Dictionary of Indo-European Roots. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Weintraub, Ruth. 1995. “What was Hume’s Contribution to the Problem of Induction?” Philosophical Quarterly 45: 460–470. Weisberg, Jonathan. 2010. “Bootstrapping in General,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81: 525–548. Weisberg, Jonathan. 2012. “The Bootstrapping Problem,” Philosophy Compass 9: 597–610. Williams, Michael. 2001. Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.

CHAPTER THIRTY-NINE

Neo-Pyrrhonism MARKUS LAMMENRANTA

1 INTRODUCTION Classical Pyrrhonian skepticism had a practical side: the skeptics tried to attain tranquility by suspending beliefs. David Hume (1975: 160) famously attacks this form of skepticism thus: (1) life without beliefs is psychologically impossible, and (2) even if it were possible, life would be very short because intentional action is not possible without beliefs. Assuming Hume is right, it is no surprise that there have not been many Pyrrhonian skeptics. It is also a common interpretation that classical Pyrrhonism is based on the equal plausibility of conflicting or contrary propositions. When we find such sets of propositions, it is psychologically impossible for us to believe one of them rather than the other, and we are forced to suspend belief. However, if Hume is right, there cannot be many such conflicts, and therefore classical Pyrrhonism does not offer a serious skeptical challenge to our beliefs. This seems to be a widespread diagnosis of classical Pyrrhonism among contemporary epistemologists. It explains why they have been more interested in Cartesian skepticism, which appears to raise more interesting skeptical problems. However, there are a few philosophers who think that we should take Pyrrhonism more seriously, and that it should even be accepted. When it is properly understood, we can see that there have even been actual and, indeed, very influential Pyrrhonian skeptics such as Michel de Montaigne, Hume himself, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and, among contemporary philosophers, Robert Fogelin and Walter Sinnott-Armstrong. We cannot say the same of Cartesian skepticism (Sinnott-Armstrong 2004a: 4). How, then, should we understand Pyrrhonism? What constitutes updated Pyrrhonism or neo-Pyrrhonism? Fogelin (1994: 5–10), who is the main contemporary advocate, restricts the scope of skepticism to philosophical and perhaps other theoretical matters. Here he follows Michael Frede’s interpretation of classical Pyrrhonism: it is directed at the dogmatic beliefs of professors rather than the common beliefs of ordinary people. In the taxonomy proposed by Jonathan Barnes (1997: 60–62), Fogelin’s neo-Pyrrhonism is a form of urbane Pyrrhonism that suspends beliefs about philosophy, rather than a form of rustic Pyrrhonism that

566

SKEPTICISM

suspends all beliefs. This sort of Pyrrhonism avoids Hume’s worries: we can surely live without philosophical beliefs. Another important feature of Fogelin’s neo-Pyrrhonism is that it arises from philosophy: it is skepticism about philosophy, based on philosophical arguments. Philosophical reflection on ordinary epistemic practices leads us to deny the possibility of knowledge and justified belief. However, a neo-Pyrrhonian skeptic does not conclude that we cannot have knowledge or justified beliefs, which would be negative dogmatism. Neither does she reject ordinary epistemic practices: she rejects the philosophical reflection that leads to the impasse (Fogelin 1994: 3–4). So Fogelin’s neo-Pyrrhonism is based on a reductio ad absurdum of epistemology: because the epistemological enterprise leads to dogmatic skepticism, it should be rejected. This sort of neo-Pyrrhonism avoids the problems raised by Hume. Indeed, in Fogelin’s view, Hume himself was such a Pyrrhonist. In this chapter, I concentrate on Fogelin’s neo-Pyrrhonism and evaluate its plausibility. Does epistemology, when seriously pursued, destroy knowledge, as Fogelin (2004: 164) argues? This depends very much on the philosophical argument that is supposed to show that knowledge is impossible and that he takes to be a reductio of its philosophical premises. Unfortunately, it is not so clear what the argument is. Fogelin never formulates it explicitly. He suggests that it derives from the so-called Five Modes of Agrippa, but it is not easy to interpret these modes. I will formulate two different versions of the Agrippan argument and consider whether either of them supports the neoPyrrhonian moral. But let us first take a look at the moral itself.

2  FOGELIN’S NEO-PYRRHONISM Fogelin argues in the second part of his book Pyrrhonian Reflection on Knowledge and Justification that Agrippa’s problem arises from philosophical reflection on our ordinary epistemic practices and that the theories of justification he considers cannot solve it. The result is a kind of urbane Pyrrhonism that combines “philosophical skepticism with skepticism about philosophy, that is, to have doubts about philosophy on the basis of philosophical arguments” (1994: 3). In order to explain how Agrippa’s problem arises from our ordinary epistemic practices, Fogelin gives the following account of knowledge attributions: “S knows that p” means that “S justifiably believes that p on the grounds that establish the truth of p.” (Fogelin 1994: 94; 1997: 417) Although this is what we say when we make knowledge attributions, as Fogelin (1994: 91–93) points out, we often make serious knowledge attributions in the face of error-possibilities that the grounds do not exclude. We simply ignore these possibilities, or “rely on the grace of nature not to defeat us.” However, if we dwell on them, the level of scrutiny will rise and we will no longer be ready to attribute knowledge—indeed we will be inclined to deny it.1 Thus, our ordinary practice of knowledge attribution involves procedures for invoking higher levels of scrutiny that lead us to deny knowledge. When we allow the level of scrutiny to rise without restriction, we are inclined to say that nothing is

NEO-PYRRHONISM

567

known. According to Fogelin’s interpretation of Pyrrhonism, a Pyrrhonian skeptic will go along with these different levels and attribute knowledge when the level is low and deny knowledge when it is high. She will just report how things strike her without privileging any particular level. However, in Fogelin’s view, epistemologists have not been happy with this sort of Pyrrhonism. They have sought to propose theories of justification to remedy the fragility of our ordinary epistemic practices: I hold that the theory of knowledge, in its traditional form, has been an attempt to find ways of establishing knowledge claims from a perspective where the level of scrutiny has been heightened by reflection alone. (Fogelin 1994: 99) Unfortunately, this attempt fails because it falls into the Modes of Agrippa. Indeed, “the epistemological enterprise, when relentlessly pursued, not only fails in its efforts, but also Samson-like, brings down the entire edifice of knowledge around it” (Fogelin 2004: 164). Thus, traditional epistemology destroys knowledge: it leads inevitably to the conclusion that nothing is known or that no beliefs are justified. We can take this to be a reductio ad absurdum of the epistemological enterprise, which should therefore be discarded. We should become Pyrrhonists—or neoPyrrhonists—who go on making knowledge claims about ordinary matters but suspend belief about epistemology. Before deciding whether Fogelin succeeds in showing that the epistemological enterprise fails because it leads to dogmatic skepticism, let us consider the question of whether Fogelin’s neo-Pyrrhonism itself is coherent by examining Walter SinnottArmstrong’s neo-Pyrrhonism.

3  SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG’S NEO-PYRRHONISM Sinnott-Armstrong (2004b: 188–189) expresses puzzlement about Fogelin’s attitude to ordinary knowledge attributions. On the one hand, Fogelin (1994: 10, 88) supposes that Pyrrhonism leaves ordinary beliefs untouched, including epistemic beliefs about whether somebody knows something, but on the other hand he states that, “in making knowledge claims, we always (or almost always) assert more than we have a right to assert” (1994: 94). When the cost of being wrong is low, we make knowledge attributions in the face of uneliminated error-possibilities, but when the cost becomes excessive or we dwell on those error-possibilities, we deny knowledge and even assert that nobody knows anything. Fogelin’s Pyrrhonist seems to be self-contradicting, saying both that somebody knows something and that nobody knows anything. Both assertions cannot be true. Sinnott-Armstrong tries to reconcile these claims by appealing to contrastivism. According to Sinnott-Armstrong, justification is not a binary relation between a subject and a proposition but a ternary relation between a subject, a proposition, and a contrast class: Someone, S, is justified in believing a proposition, P, out of a contrast class, C, when and only when S has grounds that rule out any other member of C but do not rule out P. (2004b: 190)

568

SKEPTICISM

A contrast class is composed of propositions that are contrary to each other. We are justified in believing one of these propositions just in case it is the only member of the set that is left uneliminated by our grounds. Suppose, for example, that a father takes his daughter to the zoo and looks at a zebra in a cage. His sensory experience rules out the possibility that the animal is an antelope but does not rule out the possibility that it is a cleverly painted mule. The father is therefore justified in believing that he sees a zebra rather than an antelope, but he is not justified in believing that he sees a zebra rather than a painted mule. In order to reconcile Fogelin’s apparently conflicting claims, Sinnott-Armstrong (2004b: 190) distinguishes three contrast classes that correspond to Fogelin’s three levels of doubt: The unlimited contrast class for P = all propositions contrary to P, including skeptical scenarios that are systematically ineliminable. The extreme contrast class for P = all propositions contrary to P that could be eliminated in some way, even if doing so is not needed in order to meet normal standards. The everyday contrast class for P = all propositions contrary to P that could be eliminated and need to be eliminated in order to meet normal standards. We can now make sense of Fogelin’s apparently conflicting attributions and denials of knowledge. They can all be true if we understand him as saying that, although we are typically justified in believing things out of everyday contrast classes, we are not justified in believing anything out of extreme and unlimited contrast classes. However, according to Sinnott-Armstrong (2004b: 193), it is problematic to understand our unqualified knowledge attributions in this way. The linguistic meaning (or Kaplan’s character) of the sentences of the form “S is justified in believing that p” should be represented as: S is justified out of the relevant contrast class in believing that p. This is also what makes our attributions of justification normative: to call a contrast class relevant is to say that the believer needs to rule out all other members of the class in order to be justified in believing one of them. According to Sinnott-Armstrong (2004b: 193–202), such normative epistemic judgments are suspect because nobody has found plausible rules for relevance. Indeed, he suggests that a Pyrrhonian skeptic suspends judgment about all normative matters and instead makes judgments of the forms: S is justified out of the everyday contrast class in believing that p. Nobody is justified out of the extreme contrast class in believing that p. These judgments are quite compatible and purely descriptive.2 According to SinnottArmstrong’s version of neo-Pyrrhonism, a Pyrrhonist is allowed to make such judgments and suspends judgment only about normative and philosophical matters. Although Sinnott-Armstrong’s view reconciles the apparently contradictory knowledge attributions and denials of Fogelin’s neo-Pyrrhonist, it is in conflict with the spirit of Fogelin’s neo-Pyrrhonism, which leaves our ordinary epistemic

NEO-PYRRHONISM

569

practices untouched and allows the Pyrrhonist ordinary epistemic judgments. According to Sinnott-Armstrong, our ordinary epistemic judgments presuppose something that is false or at least suspect, namely, that there are relevant contrast classes. This is why purely descriptive claims should replace them. Fogelin’s version of neo-Pyrrhonism is preferable. It is much harder for Sinnott-Armstrong’s skeptic to avoid all philosophical commitments because she needs some reasons to revise our ordinary epistemic practices, and it is hard to see how such reasons could be anything other than philosophical. It seems that contextualism offers a better way of reconciling the neo-Pyrrhonist’s apparently conflicting knowledge attributions. It saves our ordinary epistemic judgments, as Sinnott-Armstrong understands them, by making the relevance of the contrast class dependent on the attributor’s context. When the stakes are low for us and we ignore all uneliminated error-possibilities, our knowledge attributions are true, but when the stakes grow higher and we dwell on some uneliminated errorpossibilities, our knowledge denials are also true. There is no contradiction, because our knowledge attributions and denials express relations to different contrast classes. Although Fogelin denies contextualism in the book, he acknowledges in a more recent paper, “The Skeptics are Coming! The Skeptics are Coming!” (2004) that it would be one version of neo-Pyrrhonism.

4  THE STRUCTURAL REGRESS PROBLEM OR AGRIPPA’S TRILEMMA How, then, does epistemology destroy knowledge? Fogelin argues that the theories of justification that are put forth to remedy the fragility of our ordinary epistemic procedures disappoint us because they fail to solve Agrippa’s problem, and this failure will “bring down the whole edifice of knowledge” (2004: 164). What, exactly, is Agrippa’s problem? Fogelin (1994: 114) considers the common reference to Agrippa’s problem as the infinite regress problem misleading, because a philosophical theory of justification must avoid involvement not only with infinite regress but also with vicious circularity and an appeal to arbitrary assumption (or hypothesis). The problem is rather a trilemma: how can one avoid all three bad options? According to Fogelin (1994: 114–115, 120–121), Agrippa’s trilemma constitutes a serious philosophical challenge only if we make two assumptions. The first of these is the normative principle of epistemic justification, which W. K. Clifford expresses thus: “It is wrong always, everywhere, and for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence.” As Fogelin interprets it, the principle says roughly that epistemic justification is a matter of responsibility, and that responsibility requires that we base our beliefs on good reasons (or grounds). The second assumption is that we have or could have knowledge and justified beliefs. Together these assumptions entail that we have knowledge that conforms to Cliffordian standards. The task of a theory of justification is to explain how this is possible. Thus, it seems clear that Fogelin sees the problem as a paradox. In

570

SKEPTICISM

assuming the Cliffordian principle, we must face Agrippa’s trilemma with its three bad options, none of which can make beliefs justified. Yet, we believe that we do have justified beliefs. To be more precise, the paradox arises through the formulation of a valid skeptical argument leading to the conclusion that there are no justified beliefs, and then denying the conclusion. The argument seems to be this (cf. Comesaña 2005): (S1) If a belief is justified, it is either a basic belief (justified independently of reasoning) or an inferentially justified belief. (S2) There are no basic beliefs. (S3) If a belief is justified, it is made justified either by (a) an infinite chain of reasons, (b) a circular chain of reasons, or (c) a chain of reasons terminating in an unjustified belief. (S4) No belief is made justified by an infinite chain of reasons. (S5) No belief is made justified by a circular chain of reasons. (S6) No belief is made justified by a chain of reasons terminating in an unjustified belief. (S7) Thus there are no justified beliefs. This is a valid argument: the subsidiary conclusion S3 follows from premises S1 and S2, and then the final conclusion S7 follows from premises S3, S4, S5, and S6. Whereas premises S2 and S6 derive from the Agrippan mode of hypothesis, premises S4 and S5 derive from the modes of infinity and circularity. Theories of justification offer different responses to this argument: foundationalism (including holistic coherentism3) rejects premise S2, infinitism rejects premise S4, circular (or linear) coherentism rejects premise S5, and Wittgensteinian contextualism rejects premise S6. Fogelin (1994: 117) lists the same options for the dogmatic epistemologist, except infinitism, which he takes to be hopeless. Why, then, should all these attempts at responding to the argument fail? One would expect it to follow from Cliffordism that all premises of the argument are true, which is why Cliffordism leads to dogmatic skepticism. This would happen if the principle stated that only justified beliefs could serve as reasons or evidence. In that case every justified belief must be based on other justified beliefs, which in turn must be based on other justified beliefs, and so on. This would rule out foundationalism, which the majority of epistemologists take to be the most plausible solution to the paradox, and thus leaves us with the three bad options. The problem with this interpretation of Cliffordism, as Michael Williams (1999: 147) points out, is that the argument merely shows that the Cliffordian principle is too strong and should therefore be rejected. It does not show that the whole epistemological enterprise fails. Indeed, Fogelin (1994: 116–117) does not think that Cliffordism rules out foundationalism. He sees Paul Moser as a Cliffordist and foundationalist, and conducts an extensive discussion about Roderick Chisholm’s foundationalism. Thus, Cliffordism as he understands it seems to allow other than justified beliefs as reasons or evidence, such as non-doxastic experiences or seemings.

NEO-PYRRHONISM

571

However, if we accept this more liberal interpretation of the Cliffordian principle, it becomes unclear why we should reject foundationalism, according to which the regress ends in basic beliefs that are justified even though they do not derive their justification from other justified beliefs. Nevertheless, Fogelin (1994: 123–162) argues that the best existing theories of this sort, such as Chisholm’s foundationalism and BonJour’s holistic coherentism, fail because they do not even come close to satisfying the success conditions for a theory of justification. Fogelin (117–119, 138–139) provides three success conditions for such a theory: (1) it should help to determine which particular beliefs are justified; (2) it should explain why these particular beliefs are justified; and finally (3) it should be defended by arguments that do not beg the question against skepticism, in other words: the arguments should not depend on the undefended assumption that we do have some justified beliefs. The first two conditions seem quite reasonable, but although Fogelin sees much to be hoped for in Chisholm’s and BonJour’s theories regarding them, it does not seem unreasonable to assume that many theories can satisfy them. It is the third condition that is hard to satisfy. Indeed, it seems to be impossible.4 However, it is strange that Fogelin should hang on to it. He claims elsewhere that we need to assume that we do have justified beliefs in order to have Agrippa’s problem at all, but here he states that we are not allowed to make this assumption if we want to solve the problem. Indeed, it was this assumption that points to Fogelin’s understanding of the problem as a paradox, and it seems that all we need to do in order to solve a paradox is to determine which of the propositions comprising it is false and explain why. This is exactly what we can do if we have a theory that satisfies Fogelin’s first two conditions for success. Perhaps the problem is that we have competing possible solutions and should not just assume that we have the right one, thereby begging the question against the alternatives. One of those possible solutions is the skeptical one supporting the conclusion that we have no justified beliefs. Thus, we should not just assume that we have justified beliefs and beg the question against the skeptical option. This is exactly what epistemologists do, Fogelin (1994: 119) claims, when they first assume that we have justified beliefs and then argue by means of disjunctive elimination that only their own theory can explain this. For example, foundationalists argue that because infinitely regressive reasoning, circular reasoning, and reasoning starting from arbitrary premises cannot make beliefs justified, there must be basic beliefs that are justified independently of reasoning. This argument merely assumes that we have justified beliefs and thus begs the question against the skeptical resolution of the paradox. However, if we understand Agrippa’s problem in this way, we should ask where the motivation for the third condition of success comes from. Why are we not allowed to beg the question?5 This requirement does not come from the Cliffordian principle or the considered theories of justification, which are non-dialectical. They allow justified beliefs that we cannot defend without begging the question. It therefore seems that Fogelin’s dialectical requirement comes from the modes of Agrippa. If this is the case, they may not constitute an epistemically neutral skeptical

572

SKEPTICISM

strategy that can be directed against any theory of justification, as Fogelin (1997: 397) assumes. They presuppose in themselves some requirements for justification.

5  THE DIALECTICAL REGRESS Although the contemporary discussion of Agrippa’s problem typically focuses on three modes, the original problem, as Sextus Empiricus describes it in the Outlines of Scepticism (PH I 164–177), comprises five modes. It is the remaining two modes that bring on the dialectical requirements. Fogelin refers to them as the challenging modes: Two of Agrippa’s modes, discrepancy and relativity, trigger a demand for justification by revealing that there are competing claims concerning the nature of the world we perceive. Given this competition, it would be epistemically irresponsible for the Cliffordian to choose without argument one of these competing claims over others. Thus the modes of discrepancy and relativity force anyone who makes claims beyond the modest expression of opinion to give reasons in support of these claims. (Fogelin 1994: 116) He refers to the rest of them as the dialectical modes: The task of the remaining modes—those based on regress ad infinitum, circularity, and (arbitrary) hypothesis—is to show that it is impossible to complete this reasongiving process in a satisfactory way. If the Pyrrhonists are right, no argument, once started, can avoid falling into one of the traps of circularity, infinite regress, or arbitrary assumption. (1994: 116) Fogelin thus understands the modes as showing that it is impossible to adequately justify or defend our beliefs once they are properly challenged. He thus appears to be suggesting that Agrippa’s problem does not—as we assumed—concern the structure of justification: it rather concerns the process of justification, our ability to defend our beliefs by giving reasons for them (see also Williams 2001: 61–63). This way of understanding the modes makes it easier to understand why Fogelin believes that existing theories of justification fail: because there is disagreement about the conditions of justification, one should not accept any theory of justification without defending it against competing theories, but no such theory can be defended without begging the question. However, the way Fogelin describes the modes makes them more widely applicable. They do not merely challenge epistemologists to defend their theories of justification: “The modes of discrepancy and relativity force anyone who makes claims beyond the modest expression of opinion to give reasons in support of these claims” (Fogelin 1994: 116). Hence, the Agrippan modes apply to any knowledge claim whatever the subject matter. It is somewhat surprising that Fogelin very quickly starts considering whether certain existing theories of justification meet the conditions of success and ignores the question of whether these theories can explain how to stop the process of reason-giving in the first place. Perhaps this is because the phrases Fogelin (2004: 162) uses—“validating knowledge claims” and “presenting reasons establishing

NEO-PYRRHONISM

573

their legitimacy”—are ambiguous between showing that a claim or belief is true (justifying it) and showing that it is justified (justifying the claim that it is justified). In the book he concentrates on the latter rendering, although it is the former that is more fundamental—the latter is just a special case of it. In any case, Fogelin is committed to the failure of existing theories of justification to address the first-order problem: if some such theory, such as foundationalism, can solve the first-order problem, there seems to be no reason to doubt its ability to solve the second-order problem as well. For example, if a foundationalist can stop the first-order regress by appealing to basic beliefs, why could he not do the same with the second-order regress? He could simply deny the arbitrariness of the secondorder belief that a particular belief is justified. It is not arbitrary because it is itself a basic belief, which can then be used as evidence for the theory of justification.6 Therefore, in order to block this move Fogelin needs to show that foundationalism fails to explain how to stop the reason-giving regress.

6  CAN FOUNDATIONALISM STOP THE DIALECTICAL REGRESS? We can thus assume that Agrippa’s problem concerns the reason-giving or dialectical regress. Because Fogelin’s neo-Pyrrhonism is based on the failure of existing theories of justification to solve it, we are owed an explanation as to why they fail and, indeed, why the failure leads to dogmatic skepticism. Unfortunately, Fogelin does not discuss this explicitly. We have to turn to another philosopher, Peter Klein (2005: 131–135), who understands Agrippa’s problem in a similar way and argues in greater detail that foundationalism cannot solve the problem. Because, as Klein points out, holistic coherentism is just a special case of foundationalism, foundationalism covers very well the theories Fogelin discusses in his book. In explaining why foundationalism cannot solve Agrippa’s problem, Klein (2005: 133) imagines a dialogue between Fred, the Foundationalist, and Doris, the Doubter. Fred asserts proposition p. Doris asks Fred for his reasons for believing that p, perhaps saying, “Why do you believe that p?” or “How do you know that p?” Fred then gives his reason, r1, for p. Doris asks why r1 is true, and Fred gives another reason, r2. This goes on until Fred arrives at reason b, which he takes to be a basic proposition. Doris naturally asks Fred for his reasons for b, but Fred, being a selfconscious foundationalist, tells Doris that b is a basic proposition that does not need reasons in order to be justified. Thus Doris’s request for reasons is inappropriate. In Klein’s view, Doris can concede for the sake of argument that foundationalism is true and that b is basic in virtue of possessing some property F, such that any proposition having F is noninferentially justified. Even so, she can say to Fred: “Do you think that propositions having F are likely to be true?” Once Fred considers the proposition that such propositions are likely to be true, he faces three options: to (1) affirm it, (2) deny it, or (3) withhold it. If he affirms it, Doris will ask him for his reasons, and the regress does not stop. If he either denies or withholds it, he should concede that that p is not, after all, justified for him, presumably because in both cases he would have a defeater for his justification for believing that p.7 Klein

574

SKEPTICISM

concludes that foundationalism does not solve Agrippa’s problem. It cannot explain how the reason-giving regress can be stopped. Indeed, though Klein does not put it in this way, a foundationalist should concede that if foundationalism is true, there are no justified beliefs. This is exactly the result Fogelin wants. However, there is a response that a foundationalist can give: to affirm that propositions having F are likely to be true, and even to give reasons for this generalization, but to insist that the justification of b does not depend on this generalization, which just explains why b is basic. A foundationalist can and should have an explanation for what makes basic propositions basic. Such an explanation does not mean that the propositions are not basic, however. On the contrary, it is assumed to explain why subjects without the epistemological sophistication to defend their beliefs can have justified beliefs (Bergmann 2004: 164–165). Doris may point out that this response changes the subject, which is justification rather than explanation. The aim of the modes—within the present interpretation— is to show that no proposition can be justified by giving reasons for them. The challenging modes are supposed to raise doubts about the truth of a proposition, and pointing out that the proposition is basic does not answer the challenge because even the truth of basic propositions can be challenged (cf. Klein 2004: 169–170). Foundationalism thus appears unable to explain how the reason-giving regress can be stopped. Yet it does not follow that there are no justified beliefs if foundationalism is true. Justification must also depend on the ability to respond to challenges by giving reasons. This is what the modes must assume if they are to support skepticism. However, it is what contemporary foundationalists can and typically do deny, insisting that justification does not require an ability to give reasons. Before evaluating this response, let us see what Agrippa’s problem looks like once this implicit assumption about the nature of justification is made explicit.

7  THE DIALECTICAL PROBLEM As shown above, two of Agrippa’s modes challenge us to give reasons for our beliefs, and the rest of them aim to show that the reason-giving process cannot succeed. If they are to constitute a skeptical argument for concluding that there are no justified beliefs, some epistemic principle connecting justification to reason-giving must be presupposed. Let us suppose that the principle is this: (D1) If S is justified in believing that p, S can defend p against appropriate challenges. Assuming this principle, Agrippa’s modes become relevant to justification. The challenging modes show that there are appropriate challenges to the truth of p, and the dialectical modes show that the challenges cannot be answered. Hence the second premise: (D2) S cannot defend p against appropriate challenges. The conclusion follows from these premises via modus tollens: (D3) S is not justified in believing that p.

NEO-PYRRHONISM

575

In fact, the challenging modes and the dialectical modes work in tandem. When S tries to defend p by giving reasons for p, the challenging modes show that these reasons can be challenged, and when S gives further reasons for these reasons, the challenging modes are applied to these reasons, and so on. The dialectical modes show that this reason-giving regress can end only in three bad ways, none of which can provide an adequate response to the challenges. D2 is thus true, and D3 follows from D1 and D2. Now, it is clear why the appeal to basic beliefs appears to fail. Because the truth of even these beliefs can be challenged, they are not able to stop the regress. However, this argument may not serve the neo-Pyrrhonist’s dialectical purposes as Fogelin understands them: the neo-Pyrrhonist is supposed to use premises that her dogmatic opponent, the foundationalist, accepts and then to show that there are no justified beliefs. The problem is that the foundationalist need not accept premises D1 and D2. He can deny either one or the other.

8  ARE WE ALL NEO-PYRRHONISTS NOW? Fogelin seems to be aware of this problem. In Fogelin (2004: 164), he notes that many contemporary epistemologists—he calls them New Epistemologists—“have foresworn this large-scale attempt at validation through reason-giving.” They have either severed the connection between knowledge and reason-giving altogether, or dispersed reason-giving into a plurality of contexts. According to externalists/reliabilists, beliefs are made justified by their reliable connection to reality. Thus, we can know without being able to defend our beliefs by giving reasons for their truth or for their being based on reliable sources. What matters is that they are, in fact, based on reliable sources. Hence, the modes of Agrippa are no threat to our knowledge. Contextualists, inspired by Wittgenstein’s last manuscript On Certainty, concede that knowledge and justification depend on the ability to respond to challenges, but they insist that the question of which challenges are appropriate and need to be responded to is context-dependent. In philosophical or skeptical contexts in which ineliminable skeptical error-possibilities are under discussion, I know nothing about the external world because I cannot show that I am not a brain in a vat. However, in ordinary contexts, in which the challenge that I may be a brain in a vat is not appropriate, I do have knowledge about the external world because I can defend myself against the challenges that are appropriate in these contexts. Both options deny one of the premises of the reconstructed Agrippan argument. Externalist/reliabilists deny D1. They deny that justification is a matter of being able to respond to challenges. This is a very popular position nowadays, accepted not only by externalists but also by many internalists who typically think that nondoxastic experiences can make beliefs justified. There are far fewer Wittgensteinian contextualists who accept D1 but deny D2. However, both options avoid the skeptical conclusion arising from Agrippa’s modes. What should a neo-Pyrrhonist say to such New Epistemologists? According to Fogelin (2004: 166–170), she should point out that their doctrines will leave you

576

SKEPTICISM

dissatisfied if you are looking for good reasons for believing that you are not a brain in a vat. Saying that you may still know, because your beliefs are reliably connected to the external world, does not give you what you are looking for: good reasons for believing that your beliefs are so connected, and that you are not a brain in a vat. Thus the alleged consolation that the externalist/reliabilist can give simply changes the subject. The contextualist’s consolation is also beside the point. When you are looking for reasons to deny the skeptical hypothesis, you are actually in a philosophical context in which, the contextualist concedes, you know nothing about the external world. It does not console you to be told that knowledge attributions made in ordinary contexts may still be true. You are now in a philosophical context in which you know nothing. Fogelin admits that he has interpreted the New Epistemologists as if they are continuing the traditional epistemological project of trying to show that we have knowledge without falling into the modes of circularity, infinite regress, and arbitrary hypothesis. However, there is no reason to assume that this is what they try to do. They do, or at least should, realize that this is a project that cannot succeed for simple logical reasons, as Ernest Sosa (2009: 159) points out: It is impossible to attain a legitimating account of absolutely all one’s own knowledge; such an account admits only justifications provided by inference or argument and, since it rules out circular or endlessly regressive inferences, such an account must stop with premises that it supposes or “presupposes” that one is justified in accepting, without explaining how one is justified in accepting them in turn. It should be clear by now that it is impossible to show that we have knowledge (or justified beliefs) without circularity, infinite regress, or assuming some knowledge (or justified beliefs). No epistemologist should seriously pursue the end of legitimating all our knowledge at once. As his final point, Fogelin (2004: 170–171) concedes that New Epistemologists who have given up the legitimating project are no longer the targets of a Pyrrhonian attack, but only because they have themselves become neo-Pyrrhonists. This is a very disappointing result. It means that virtually all epistemologists nowadays are neo-Pyrrhonists. Why should we even bother to argue for the position? What is worse, it cannot be right. Neo-Pyrrhonists are skeptics about philosophy, but most epistemologists who reject the legitimating project are not such skeptics. Once the legitimating project and either premise of the Agrippan argument are rejected, we lack a philosophical argument for skepticism about philosophy or other matters.

9  HOW TO BE A NEO-PYRRHONIST Fogelin argues that neo-Pyrrhonism results naturally from reflection on our ordinary epistemic procedures. Because these procedures do not eliminate all possibilities of error, it is always possible to raise the level of scrutiny by paying attention to new error-possibilities. When we allow the level of scrutiny to rise without restriction,

NEO-PYRRHONISM

577

we will conclude that nothing is known. Fogelin understands theories of justification as attempting to repair this fragility in our ordinary procedures. Unfortunately, these theories fail because they cannot solve Agrippa’s problem. Therefore, we have no choice but to settle for the fragility of ordinary knowledge attributions and become neo-Pyrrhonists. I have argued that Fogelin fails to show that contemporary theories of justification cannot solve Agrippa’s problem. The quandary is that, as a neo-Pyrrhonist, Fogelin may use only premises that advocates of those theories accept in order to show that they have skeptical consequences. I have given two versions of the argument on which Agrippa’s problem seems to be based: the structural and the dialectical. In neither version are most contemporary epistemologists committed to the truth of the premises of the argument. Indeed, it follows from their theories that one or another of them is false. Hence, neo-Pyrrhonism appears to lose its motivation. However, there is a more direct way of defending neo-Pyrrhonism. The neoPyrrhonist may argue that the premises of Agrippan argument are intuitively plausible, and that neo-Pyrrhonism provides the best resolution of the resulting paradox. Only neo-Pyrrhonism both explains the intuitive plausibility of the premises and avoids dogmatic skepticism. It seems that the paradox does arise from the ordinary practice of knowledge attribution. It is plausible to assume that the purpose of this practice is to share information (Craig 1990). When I attribute knowledge to someone else, I pick her out as an informant. If she says that p, I believe that p. However, I cannot believe her and attribute knowledge to her unless I believe what she says is true. If I believe it is true, there may be no need to ask for reasons, but if I am not convinced of the truth of what she says, it is quite appropriate to ask her: “How do you know?” or “What reasons do you have for believing so?” If she can answer my question by giving reasons that I take to be true and to support her belief, I take her to be justified in her belief and to know what she is saying. If she cannot do this, I will not take her as an informant and will deny her knowledge. Thus, it seems that the practice of knowledge attribution supports the view that knowledge and justification depend on an ability to give reasons when properly challenged. Premise D1 appears to be true. When I attribute knowledge to myself I typically volunteer myself as an informant for other people. Because I want to convince them—to share my information with them—I am prepared to give reasons when properly challenged. If I cannot do this, I understand that I am not a good informant and am ready to take back my knowledge self-attribution—indeed, I am ready to deny my knowledge. As my audience grows larger and larger, it becomes less and less likely that I can convince all of its members. Indeed, it is the point of the mode of discrepancy or disagreement to bring it to mind that there are always some people that I cannot convince with my reasons and must therefore give up my knowledge claim. Hence premise D2 also appears to be true. However, in ordinary contexts we are ready to attribute knowledge even though we are aware that there are people whom the subject cannot convince. Thus, in one context we are inclined to attribute knowledge that we deny in another context. The semantic theory that aims to explain these apparently inconsistent attributions

578

SKEPTICISM

and denials is contextualism. According to the version of it that is relevant here, the content and truth of knowledge attribution depend on the attributor’s intentions and interests—especially on the intended audience. If this is true, we can easily explain our intuitions about the Agrippan argument. If the intended audience is a skeptic, we cannot defend our beliefs against all the challenges she raises. Consequently, the premises and the conclusion of the argument are indeed true in a context in which we are trying to convince a persistent skeptic. However, knowledge attributions are often true in ordinary contexts, because either the intended audience has no challenges8 or the subject can answer them. This contextualist resolution of Agrippa’s paradox closely resembles Fogelin’s neo-Pyrrhonism: such a neo-Pyrrhonist is a skeptic about philosophy. There are so many persistent disagreements in philosophy that knowledge attribution will almost always be false in philosophical contexts. Furthermore, one of the main criticisms of contextualism has been that it has no epistemological consequences. It does not follow from the fact that people often speak the truth when they use sentences of the form “S knows that p” in ordinary contexts that anybody knows anything (Sosa 2000). This is no problem for the neo-Pyrrhonists. It is rather the central feature of their position that they go on making knowledge attributions about everyday matters while suspending judgment about the traditional epistemological question concerning the scope of knowledge. An alternative way of explaining the plausibility of the Agrippan argument is to assume that it is based on confusion between knowledge and assertion (Rescorla 2009; Gerken 2012; cf. Turri 2012). One might concede that a warranted assertion requires defense against challenges, but it can be denied that knowledge requires this: you may very well know something that you cannot defend and thus properly assert. Agrippa’s problem concerns only what you may assert and is therefore epistemically harmless. However, this view still provides a version of neo-Pyrrhonism: its target is assertion rather than knowledge. Indeed, Duncan Pritchard (2005: 213–220) argues that this is the right way of understanding ancient Pyrrhonism. A Pyrrhonist may very well have beliefs and thus knowledge, but she makes no dogmatic assertions. Of course, contextualized neo-Pyrrhonism may even allow assertions in contexts where there are no appropriate challenges. There are thus two initially quite plausible versions of neo-Pyrrhonism that both seem to accord with practices of knowledge attribution. The choice between them depends on whether we should prefer semantic or pragmatic resolutions of Agrippa’s problem and other skeptical paradoxes, which is a big question in contemporary epistemology and philosophy of language.9

NOTES 1. Fogelin seems to accept some sort of relevant alternative account here. Cf. Lewis (1996: 551): “S knows that P iff S’s evidence eliminated every possibility in which not-P—Psst!—except for those possibilities that we are properly ignoring.” 2. As Juan Comesaña (2005) points out, these judgments are still normative, being attributions of justification.

NEO-PYRRHONISM

579

3. According to holistic coherentism, justification does not transfer from one belief to another. It emerges from the whole system of beliefs when there are enough crisscrossing inferential relations among them. It has been noted that this view makes every justified belief a basic belief. So holistic coherentism is a form of foundationalism, which Sosa (1991c: 180) calls formal foundationalism. 4. See Chisholm (1982: 61–75) on the problem of the criterion. Chisholm insists, plausibly, that we cannot solve the problem of the criterion without begging the question against skepticism. 5. Chisholm (1982: 75) acknowledges that “we can deal with the problem only by begging the question” and insists that this is exactly what we should do. See also Sosa (2009: 176). 6. Chisholm (1982: 68–69) calls this strategy particularism. It seems that a particularist should think that there are basic epistemic beliefs about particular cases of justified beliefs. See, for example, Sosa (1991b: 158) and Lemos (2007: 160). 7. At least foundationalists such as Bergmann (2005: 426) and Feldman (2006: 232–233) accept that not only the denial of reliability but also the conscious suspension of judgment about it would defeat one’s justification. 8. There are, of course, other conditions that must be satisfied if knowledge attributions are to be true, such as truth, reliability, and perhaps safety. 9. I wish to thank Raul Hakli, Jaakko Hirvelä, Antti Kylänpää, Arto Laitinen, Luca Moretti, and Tommaso Piazza as well as the editors of this book, Diego Machuca and Baron Reed, for comments and discussion.

REFERENCES Alston, William P. 1989. Epistemic Justification: Essays in the Theory of Knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Barnes, Jonathan. 1997. “The Beliefs of a Pyrrhonist.” In M. Burnyeat and M. Frede (eds.), The Original Sceptics: A Controversy, 58–91. Indianapolis: Hackett. Bergmann, Michael. 2004. “What’s not Wrong with Foundationalism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68: 161–165. Bergmann, Michael. 2005. “Defeaters and Higher-Level Requirements,” The Philosophical Quarterly 55: 419–436. Chisholm, Roderick. 1982. “The Problem of the Criterion.” In his The Foundations of Knowing, 61–75. Brighton: The Harvester Press. Comesaña, Juan. 2005. “Review of Pyrrhonian Skepticism,” Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2005.06.8. Craig, Edward. 1990. Knowledge and the State of Nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Feldman, Richard. 2006. “Epistemological Puzzles About Disagreement.” In S. Hetherington (ed.), Epistemology Futures, 216–236. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Fogelin, Robert. 1994. Pyrrhonian Reflections on Knowledge and Justification. New York: Oxford University Press. Fogelin, Robert. 1997. “Précis of Pyrrhonian Reflections on Knowledge and Justification.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57: 395–400.

580

SKEPTICISM

Fogelin, Robert. 2004. “The Skeptics are Coming! The Skeptics are Coming.” In W. SinnottArmstrong (ed.), Pyrrhonian Skepticism, 161–173. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gerken, Mikkel. 2012. “Discursive Justification and Skepticism,” Synthese 189: 373–394. Hume, David. 1975. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, (ed.), L. A. Selby-Bigge, rev. P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Klein, Peter. 2004. “What Is Wrong with Foundationalism Is that It Cannot Solve the Epistemic Regress Problem,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68: 166–171. Klein, Peter. 2005. “Infinitism is the Solution to the Regress Problem.” In M. Steup and E. Sosa (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 131–140. Oxford: Blackwell. Lemos, Noah. 2007. An Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lewis, David. 1996. “Elusive Knowledge,” The Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 549–567. Pritchard, Duncan. 2005. Epistemic Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rescorla, Michael. 2009. “Epistemic and Dialectical Regress,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87: 47–60. Sextus Empiricus. 2000. Outlines of Scepticism, translated by J. Annas and J. Barnes. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. 2004a. “Introduction to Pyrrhonian Skepticism.” In W. SinnottArmstrong (ed.), Pyrrhonian Skepticism, 3–9. New York: Oxford University Press. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. 2004b. “Classy Pyrrhonism.” In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Pyrrhonian Skepticism, 188–207. New York: Oxford University Press. Sosa, Ernest. 1991a. Knowledge in Perspective: Selected Essays in Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sosa, Ernest. 1991b. “The Foundations of Foundationalism.” In his Knowledge in Perspective: Selected Essays in Epistemology, 149–162. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sosa, Ernest. 1991c. “The Raft and the Pyramid: Coherence Versus Foundations In The Theory of Knowledge.” In his Knowledge in Perspective: Selected Essays in Epistemology, 165–191. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sosa, Ernest. 2000. “Skepticism and Contextualism,” Philosophical Issues 10: 1–18. Sosa, Ernest. 2009. Reflective Knowledge: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, Volume II. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Turri, John. 2012. “Pyrrhonian Skepticism Meets Speech-Act Theory,” International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 2: 83–98. Williams, Michael. 1999. “Fogelin’s Neo-Pyrrhonism,” International Journal of Philosophical Studies 7: 141–158. Williams, Michael. 2001. Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

CHAPTER FORTY

Disagreement and Skepticism BRYAN FRANCES

1 INTRODUCTION Odds are, you have some beliefs that you know full well to be fairly controversial. Perhaps you think God exists, we have free will, socialism is better than communism, affirmative action is unjust, and global warming is going to be catastrophic. Or think of beliefs that aren’t out there in the public eye but are controversial none the less: your belief that father had an affair when you and your sister were ten years old (you believe it, your sister denies it), or your opinion that your son lied about stealing from the corner store (your spouse thinks he’s innocent, you disagree). In each case, you are well aware that there are people who disagree with you—people who aren’t foolish or evidentially challenged or any more biased than you are. And yet you think you’re right and they’re wrong; and you’re holding fast to your view even though you know that the people who disagree with you have heard your side of the story, have understood it, and still think you’re wrong. You’re aware that your reasons, the ones that convinced you of the belief in question, have not impressed them enough to agree with you. In such a scenario, your belief may well be the true one; good for you. But will it amount to knowledge? Will it be wise for you to keep your belief in those circumstances? The disagreement skeptic thinks that awareness of disagreement provides one with a reason to think one’s belief is false—a reason often strong enough to make one’s epistemic position impoverished in the event that one retains one’s belief in the face of recognized disagreement. In what follows I address these questions, starting with a comparison of traditional skepticism with disagreement skepticism, moving on to some inadequate skeptical arguments that turn on disagreement, and then closing with a presentation and analysis of a superior disagreement argument for skepticism.

582

SKEPTICISM

2  TRADITIONAL SKEPTICISM VERSUS DISAGREEMENT SKEPTICISM Disagreement skepticism is importantly different from traditional skepticism, not only with regard to the supporting argument, which will be made obvious below, but with regard to what the conclusion comes to. To see this, ask yourself how much we should worry about whether traditional philosophical skepticism is true. Consider the following standard argument for one traditional kind of philosophical skepticism: 1. If a person knows that she has hands, then she can know that she wasn’t kidnapped by Santa and unwittingly made into a handless brain in a vat (BIV). 2. If she can know that she wasn’t kidnapped by Santa and unwittingly made into a handless BIV, then she must have evidence, broadly construed, that rules out that BIV scenario. 3. But she doesn’t have any such evidence. 4. Thus, she doesn’t know that she has hands. There are just five possibilities with respect to this argument. Premise (1) is false. She knows she has hands but can’t know that she isn’t a handless BIV via Santa’s lunacy. That’s pretty odd: if she knows she has hands, then why can’t she then deduce that she isn’t a handless BIV? Premise (2) is false. Our subject can know she isn’t a Santa-induced handless BIV but she doesn’t have evidence that rules out that BIV possibility. That’s odd, too: how can someone know that X doesn’t obtain unless she has some evidence that rules out X’s obtaining? Premise (3) is false. She has some evidence that rules out the BIV scenario. That’s pretty odd, too. For instance, it seems clear that there’s nothing she can do to rule it out, like checking her hands carefully, pinching herself, or researching Santa Claus. Anything she can point to as evidence could easily be part of Santa’s deception. A fourth possibility is that the claims in the argument are ambiguous, different disambiguations have different truth-values, and different disambiguations will be “chosen” depending on subtle contextual factors (of the subject, the person asserting (1)–(4), or the person evaluating those assertions). The fifth possibility is that the argument (1)–(4) is sound; this is a type of traditional philosophical skepticism. What is interesting, and what makes much of this book worthwhile, is the fact that, no matter which of the five theories is right about (1)–(4), the correct one says something interesting about knowledge, evidence, and perhaps related epistemic notions. But once you understand the reasoning behind the traditional skeptical thesis, that thesis gets robbed of a good portion of its oddness. All the skeptic is saying with her (1)–(4) is that the notion knowledge is a lot more peculiar than we thought

DISAGREEMENT AND SKEPTICISM

583

it was: she is not saying that our ordinary beliefs are false or even that our overall evidence goes strongly against our ordinary beliefs. With some more detail: (a) The traditional skeptic is not saying that your belief B (e.g., “I have hands”) is false. (b) She is not saying that your overall evidence is strongly against B (so much so that you should disbelieve B). (c) She admits that everything non-skeptics might point to as evidence for B really does exist and is at least prudentially relevant to your holding B. (d) She admits that you haven’t overlooked some new and powerful evidence against your belief. (e) She just says that technically speaking, all that stuff non-skeptics might call evidence for your belief B doesn’t actually support B enough to make it knowledge or justified: that “evidence” (e.g., your sensory experiences) provides much weaker support than non-skeptics think it does. That is, according to her, non-skeptics have not so much missed out on some powerful evidence against B (that’s (d)) as grossly inflated the strength of the so-called evidence for B that you possess (that’s (e)). (f) According to her, it is simply impossible to discover whether B is true; so you might as well go on acting the way you did before, when you believed B. (g) Her skepticism is limited: it doesn’t apply to your beliefs about your own mind or about mathematics. (h) Contextualism, pragmatic encroachment, relevant alternatives theory, reliabilism, and Gricean theory each supply prima facie serious objections to her skeptical argument (see Goldman 2011 and Rysiew 2011 for explanations of these ideas). This just doesn’t strike me as a terribly worrisome kind of skepticism. Even if I become convinced that this traditional kind of skepticism is true, I won’t be worried that your belief in your hands is false in any way that really matters. Suppose I believe that global warming is going to raise sea levels on the east coast of the United States by over eight feet by 2100. The disagreement skeptic argues that I know no such thing, as there is a real chance that the scientists who say the increase will be only three feet are right. The radical skeptic says I know no such thing because there is a chance that there is no earth. It’s even tempting—we see undergraduates do this all the time—to think that, even if the skeptic is right, your belief in your hands is true “in your reality,” in the reality you are epistemically confined to. Sure, your belief might not be true “in the grand scheme of things,” from “the God’s eye point of view of real truth,” but that fact only matters to philosophers. Of course, the bald claim, “You know virtually nothing,” sounds awful and shocking, but as soon as one understands the view behind the claim—claims (a)– (f) in particular—one is inclined to think that all that has really been said is that “knowledge” fails to latch on to what matters in our doxastic lives. When someone says, “You think you know P, but you don’t,” it sounds as though she’s saying

584

SKEPTICISM

that P is false, or what you claim as evidence doesn’t exist. But the radical skeptic isn’t saying P is false or that your so-called evidence doesn’t exist. For comparison, imagine watching some children play a baseball game. Then someone says “No, there is no baseball game there.” At first, you would find this shocking, but once you learn what she is really saying—the game being played isn’t really baseball because they are allowing four strikes for an out, whereas in baseball one gets just three strikes—you no longer find it at all shocking, merely peculiar even if true. Part of what makes disagreement skepticism so interesting is that (d)–(h) are false for it. The phenomenon of disagreement supplies a kind of skepticism worth worrying about because it generates an argument for the conclusion that many of your most precious beliefs are false in a way that can make a difference. The traditional skeptic says that, even if your belief is false, no one will ever know that it’s false and there isn’t a damn thing anyone can do about this lack of knowledge. The disagreement skeptic says none of that. This is a much more worrisome kind of skepticism. In what follows, I examine the cases of disagreement that generate what I take to be the best arguments for skeptical conclusions that have some bite in the sense that they generate skepticism for a large portion of our actual beliefs—especially ones we really care about.

3  WHEN DISAGREEMENT DOES NOT GENERATE SKEPTICISM Clearly, the mere fact that you know of a bunch of people who disagree with you does not preclude your knowing that they are wrong and you are right. A group of children might think that so-and-so is the most famous person alive, but you could easily know that they are wrong. Disagreement generates a worthwhile skeptical argument only when the disagreement meets demanding conditions. However, it isn’t easy to come up with an impressive skeptical argument based on disagreement.1 We begin with some stipulations. Suppose you’re faced with the question, “Is belief B true?” You have your view on the matter: you think B is true. If you are convinced that a certain person is clearly lacking compared to you on many epistemic factors when it comes to answering the question “Is B true?”—factors such as general intelligence, relevant evidence, time spent thinking the evidence through, amount of distractions encountered while thinking about the evidence, and background knowledge—then you’ll probably say that you are more likely than she is to answer the question correctly (provided there are no other factors that give her an advantage over you). If you are convinced that a certain person definitely surpasses you on many of those factors when it comes to answering “Is B true?,” then you’ll probably say that you are less likely than she is to answer the question correctly (provided you think there are no factors that give you an advantage over her). In general, you can make judgments about how likely someone is compared to you when it comes to answering “Is B true?” correctly. If you think she is more likely (e.g., the odds that she will answer it correctly are 90%, whereas your odds

DISAGREEMENT AND SKEPTICISM

585

are just 80%), then you think she is your epistemic superior on that question; if you think she is less likely, then you think she is your epistemic inferior on that question; if you think she is about equally likely, then you think she is your epistemic peer on that question. With those notions in mind, here is a simple rule to start us off looking at skeptical arguments from disagreement: Rule 1 If before the discovery of disagreement you think that a certain person is your epistemic peer/superior on the question whether belief B is true, then if upon realizing that the two of you disagree you retain your belief B, your belief B won’t be reasonable. The reasoning behind Rule 1 in the case of peers is the following. Prior to the discovery of disagreement, you think that the two of you are equally likely to judge B correctly. You probably think there is about a 90 percent, say, chance that you’ll be right and, thus, a 90 percent chance your peer will be right. When you find out she believes not-B while you believe B, you can’t conclude that there is a 90 percent chance not-B is true and a 90 percent chance B is true. Such a conclusion is incoherent. Instead, you have to conclude that there’s just a 50 percent she’s right and a 50 percent chance you’re right. So you’re saying to yourself that there’s just a 50 percent chance B is true. So you should suspend judgment on B. The reasoning in the case of superiors is similar. In both cases, peers and superiors, if you don’t give up your belief B, then it won’t be reasonable. And if it’s not reasonable, then it won’t amount to knowledge. By that reasoning, if you discovered you had disagreeing peers or superiors on a great many of your beliefs, then a great many of your beliefs would fail to amount to knowledge, even if they were true—or so says Rule 1. That would be a limited but significant kind of skepticism. But many cases show that Rule 1 is dubious. Suppose Viktoriya is very confident that B is true, where B is “Smoking causes cancer.” Viktoriya is highly confident B is true because she is well aware that virtually all of the many experts on the topic have long thought that it’s true. She has excellent testimonial evidence backing up her belief in B. She knows, of course, that there are many people who verbally deny the smoking-cancer connection, but she thinks those people are either ignorant, foolish, lying, or caught in self-deception. Viktoriya is also convinced that Willard is her peer on knowing whether B is true. The basis for this belief in peerhood isn’t anything fancy or involved: she just supposes that Willard is about as intelligent and scientifically literate as she is, since he is a software engineer like she is and he seems generally knowledgeable about many scientific things in the news (e.g., he knew about the latest mission to Mars). Then she finds out that Willard genuinely thinks smoking doesn’t cause cancer. By my lights, when Viktoriya learns of Willard’s opinion, she will have acquired little or no reason to give up her belief that smoking causes cancer. When she learned of Willard’s opinion she probably thought to herself, “Oh Jeez. He is one of those people, ones who have been brainwashed by the tobacco companies and their shills.”

586

SKEPTICISM

She already knew about “those people”; actually running into one won’t matter to her overall evidence regarding smoking and cancer. And even if she didn’t already know of those people, she did know that for almost any topic there’s almost never 100 percent agreement among intelligent and informed people. So Rule 1 looks dubious. If we are going to find a powerful skeptical argument from disagreement, we will need a better rule to use. Things don’t change if the person you disagree with is a recognized superior on B. Even if Viktoriya thought that Willard was her superior on the issue (e.g., he is a doctor or a medical researcher), she would be reasonable in keeping B. She would just recall or perhaps conclude that even the experts are rarely 100 percent in agreement. She might think to herself “He probably thinks he knows something all the many thousands of other experts missed. But the odds are really against that.” She might conclude that Willard must be biased or somehow emotionally invested in denying the smoking-cancer connection—or maybe she will just think to herself, “Well, something is definitely going on with that guy on this topic” (so she is open to the possibility that he isn’t saying what he appears to be saying). She will implicitly think that even though he’s smarter than her, knows all about her good testimonial evidence for the smoking-cancer connection, has thought about the issue a lot more than she has, etc., there must be some explanation of why he went wrong. One thing we can do in order to find a better skeptical rule is focus on groups instead of individual people: Rule 2 If you think that the group you’re disagreeing with is in an equal/better position than your group (the group of people who, like you, believe B) to judge belief B correctly, then retaining B will be unreasonable and B won’t amount to knowledge. This rule is better than Rule 1 because it better captures the worrisome disagreements we find ourselves in: often the most intriguing disagreements hold among very large groups of people, some of whom are experts. Focusing on one-on-one disagreements, as Rule 1 does, is useful mainly for theorizing about disagreement, not for applying to real-life disagreements. The smoking-cancer case isn’t a counterexample to Rule 2 because Viktoriya did not think that, when it came to judging B, the group of deniers of B was in an equal or better position than the group of affirmers of B. Indeed, it was precisely because her group contains almost all the relevant experts that she was reasonable in sticking with B. However, Rule 2 is doubtful as well. Suppose in a college class the students break into two groups of ten students in order to independently investigate some complicated matter. Student Stu thinks the groups are evenly matched, based on his modest knowledge of their abilities (pretend this is a small college and Stu knows a great many of his fellow students). After a week of work, representatives of the two groups give oral progress reports to the whole class. The representative from the other group says that her group has figured out several things regarding the topic of investigation (college resources), including the idea that there are about 113 student

DISAGREEMENT AND SKEPTICISM

587

computers in the college’s main library. But this strikes Stu as way too low: he was 100 percent confident in his belief B “The number of computers in the main library is at least 140.” He briefly wonders whether the student in question is accurately presenting the verdict of her group, but when he sees the members of her group nodding their heads he knows that his group definitely disagrees with their group. Stu is extremely confident the number is quite a bit more than 113, as he and his group members have scoured the library to count the computers. He keeps his belief B and starts to doubt whether he was right to think the other group had done about as much work on the project as his group did. We can use the college student case to cast doubt on the “superior” part of Rule 2 as well. Suppose Stu started out, before hearing the other group’s view on B, with mildly good evidence that the other group was mildly better positioned to answer “How many student computers are in the main library?” Suppose further that he learns that, although the other group believes not-B, they do not do so with extreme conviction: they believe it, but not vehemently. For what it’s worth, in my judgment he is reasonable if he retains his belief B and just concludes that, despite their mild superiority, the other group just got things wrong this time around. Stu knows they were more likely than his group to judge B correctly, but that doesn’t mean that they were guaranteed to judge B correctly. The main thing that secures his reasonability is his extremely powerful overall evidence for B coupled with his comparatively mild evidence for the other group’s mild superiority and mild belief in not-B. Considerations like the ones above show that it’s no small matter to construct a skeptical argument that centers on disagreement. So what are the troublesome cases, the ones that do generate a worrisome kind of skepticism?

4  CONTROVERSY AND KNOWLEDGE When one knows that one’s belief is highly controversial, then one has available a good if potentially defeasible reason for serious doubt. However, once again it’s tricky to formulate the skeptical argument, as there may be flaws lying in wait.2 For the sake of argument, I will assume that controversial beliefs very often start out epistemically rational and even overall justified (in any of several senses of those terms). Roughly put, the disagreement skeptic thinks that even if a controversial belief starts out as knowledge, once one appreciates the controversy, one’s belief will no longer amount to knowledge. However, just because someone learns that his belief is highly controversial doesn’t guarantee that his belief will no longer amount to knowledge. For instance, he might be the only living soul who knows that Oswald assassinated Kennedy, as he is Oswald. So we will have to work harder to develop a controversy-based skeptical argument. In ordinary life, the cases of disagreement that generate powerful arguments for types of skepticism that have real bite typically satisfy the following conditions: You know that the belief B in question has been investigated and debated (i) for a very long time by (ii) a great many (iii) very smart people who (iv) are your epistemic superiors on the matter and (v) have worked very hard (vi) under

588

SKEPTICISM

optimal circumstances to figure out if B is true. But you also know that (vii) these experts have not come to any significant agreement on B and (viii) those who agree with you are not, as a group, in a better position to judge B than those who disagree with you. We typically come to know (i)–(viii) through testimony; the truths known are just brute facts about society that we are well aware of. For instance, I might have some opinion regarding free will or capital punishment or affirmative action or spiritual experience or the causes of the Second World War. I know full well that these matters have been debated by an enormous number of really smart people for a very long time—in some cases, for centuries. I also know that I’m no expert on any of these topics. I also know that there are genuine experts on those topics—at least, they have thought about those topics much longer than I have, with a great deal more awareness of relevant considerations, etc. It’s no contest: I know I’m just an amateur compared to them. Part of being reflective is coming to know about your comparative epistemic status on controversial subjects. The person who knows (i)–(viii) is robbed of the reasonableness of several comforting responses to the discovery of disagreement. If she is reasonable, then she realizes that she can’t make, at least with high confidence, anything like the following remarks: (a) Well, the people who agree with me are smarter than the people who disagree with me. (b) We have crucial evidence they don’t have. (c) We have studied the key issue a great deal more than they have. (d) They are a lot more biased than we are. This phenomenon is particularly prevalent with regard to religion, politics, morality, and philosophy. To see why, recall college student Stu. When he learned that the other group disagreed with him, he could reasonably say to himself, “Well, I guess they didn’t do as much work on the issue as I thought” or “Maybe they aren’t as smart as I thought” or “Perhaps they just screwed up the count of the computers or made some other slip, even though they’re just as generally smart and thorough as we are.” But when it comes to debates about free will, capital punishment, affirmative action, and many other standard controversial topics, a great many of us—not all of us, but many—either know that such responses are false or, if we do embrace them, we do so irrationally. If when it comes to the question of whether we have free will you say to yourself regarding the experts who disagree with you, “Those people just don’t understand the issues,” “They aren’t very smart,” “They haven’t thought about it much,” etc., then you are doing so irrationally in the sense that you should know better than to say that, at least if you’re honest with yourself. Now for the disagreement skeptical argument that centers on controversial belief: (1) Suppose you believe B. (2) Then you become aware of the controversial nature of B: you know (i)–(viii) from before.

DISAGREEMENT AND SKEPTICISM

589

(3) If (2) is true of you, then your retained belief in B is epistemically second-rate in a significant manner—and this is true even if B is true, you previously (before the discovery of disagreement) had a propositionally and doxastically justified belief in B, and your belief was not Gettiered. (4) Thus, for any belief that makes (2) true, that belief will be epistemically second-rate in a significant manner. This argument concludes that even if your belief B is optimal in key epistemic respects (true, previously propositionally and doxastically justified, not Gettiered), it still faces a hurdle in order to attain high levels of epistemic goodness—a hurdle it does not clear. The argument leaves open what the conclusion amounts to. By “epistemically second-rate,” it might be meant that the controversial belief fails to amount to knowledge. Then again, maybe it fails to be doxastically and/or propositionally justified. Perhaps both. Then again, it might mean that although the retained belief is justified and amounts to knowledge, it still suffers from a serious epistemic defect. Perhaps we can be unwise in keeping a belief even when it amounts to knowledge; this might be true if the standard for knowledge is significantly lower than most epistemologists have thought.

5  TWO OBJECTIONS TO THE DISAGREEMENT SKEPTICAL ARGUMENT First, the skeptical argument appears to have a severely limited scope, as there are quite a few conditions in (i)–(viii)! For instance, (viii) will be denied in many religious disputes, thereby falsifying (2): people tend to think that they have evidence that the other side doesn’t have, or that the other side suffers from some serious epistemic mistake that their side has avoided. Theists tend to think that non-theists are just missing out on experiences of God; non-theists tend to think that theists either don’t understand science sufficiently well or have been unable to get over their childhood indoctrination. If a disputant has come to this comparative opinion in a justified way, then the argument from disagreement doesn’t touch him, even if this comparative opinion of his happens to be false. And if he has come to his comparative opinion without justification, then although he has made an epistemic error (by hypothesis), it’s arguable that it’s epistemically rational for him to retain his religious view, pro or con, in the face of disagreement given the beliefs he has, since he thinks the people who disagree with his group are definitely epistemic inferiors on the topics in question. Setting aside premise (2), the argument is vulnerable to objections to (3). Pretend that Pat thinks little boys are naturally more violent than little girls. He thinks this because he has run a day care for little kids for twenty-five years, and he has talked about the issue with many other experienced daycare workers over many years. He is not, however, a child psychologist or anything related; neither has he read any studies on the issue. Suppose further that he’s exactly right: little boys are naturally more violent than little girls, no matter how you construe “natural,” “little,” “violent,” “boy,” or “girl.” Assume that the experts on child behavior—at least,

590

SKEPTICISM

the ones doing the research with PhDs—have for a very long time been stubbornly divided on the question whether little boys are naturally more violent than little girls. They are well aware of the observational evidence that has suggested that boys are naturally more violent—they know all about the kinds of evidence Pat has—but for a couple decades now they have had studies that collectively strongly suggest the exact opposite. In this story, the question of natural violence and gender has long been one of the outstanding questions in child psychology. Might Pat’s belief amount to knowledge provided: he obtained and holds the belief on the basis of his experiences, experiences that gave him plenty of justification for his true belief; the evidence the experts have that suggests otherwise is unknown to him; and although he is vaguely aware that there have been some studies that go against his view, he just shrugged his shoulders and never really dwelt on this fact? Would the epistemic sin involved in that shrug—if it is such—be so bad as to ruin his chance at knowledge? I don’t know. Perhaps it matters what knowledge comes to. Over the centuries many philosophers have thought that knowledge is something pretty special, something that has to be fought for with real cognitive power. Others have thought that any two-year-old child has loads of knowledge: if she is minimally functioning, then she will know an enormous number of mundane facts. It’s not entirely clear that anyone is wrong in that debate. We use the words “know” and “knowledge” quite a bit in life, but that doesn’t mean that our use has fastened on to an epistemic joint in nature, as “water,” “gold,” and “shark” have marked objectively existing joints in nature. Perhaps “knowledge” is polysemous, which would go some way toward explaining why we can never agree on the analysis of “the” notion knowledge (because there is no such singular notion). In any case, the story involving Pat suggests that even when one is aware that (i) one’s belief is controversial among the experts, (ii) one is an amateur in many respects compared to them, and (iii) one has no evidence that they have missed, it isn’t clear that this will mean that one’s belief fails to amount to knowledge. So (3) is contentious. The disagreement skeptic may well protest that Pat was in an unusual situation: he knew P due to extensive experience, the experts had generated large amounts of misleading evidence, Pat had none of that misleading evidence, and, although Pat knew the issue was controversial, he didn’t think about it much and it more or less slipped from his consciousness. The skeptic’s point here is that even if Pat is in a position to have knowledge, for the vast number of controversial beliefs this position is rare.

NOTES 1. For introductions to the epistemology of disagreement, see Christensen (2009) and Frances (2010b; 2014). 2. Goldberg (2009), Frances (2010a; 2013), Fumerton (2010), Kornblith (2010), Machuca (2013), and Christensen (2014) each address the epistemology of controversial belief. Feldman (2007), Oppy (2010), Thune (2011), Kraft (2012), and Frances (2015) each address the specific case of religious controversy. General issues regarding the epistemology of disagreement are addressed in Feldman and Warfield (2010) and Christensen and Lackey (2013).

DISAGREEMENT AND SKEPTICISM

591

REFERENCES Christensen, David. 2009. “Disagreement as Evidence: The Epistemology of Controversy,” Philosophy Compass 4: 756–767. Christensen, David. 2014. “Disagreement and Public Controversy.” In J. Lackey (ed.), Essays in Collective Epistemology, 142–163. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Christensen, David and Jennifer Lackey (eds.). 2013. Disagreement: New Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Feldman, Richard. 2007. “Reasonable Religious Disagreements.” In L. Antony (ed.), Philosophers Without Gods: Meditations on Atheism and the Secular Life, 194–214. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Feldman, Richard and Ted Warfield (eds.). 2010. Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Frances, Bryan. 2010a. “The Reflective Epistemic Renegade,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81: 419–463. Frances, Bryan. 2010b. “Disagreement.” In S. Bernecker and D. Pritchard (eds.), Routledge Companion to Epistemology, 68–74. New York and Abingdon: Routledge. Frances, Bryan. 2013. “Philosophical Renegades.” In D. Christensen and J. Lackey (eds.), Disagreement: New Essays, 121–166. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Frances, Bryan. 2014. Disagreement. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Frances, Bryan. 2015. “Religious Disagreement.” In G. Oppy (ed.), Routledge Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, 180–191. London: Routledge. Fumerton, Richard. 2010. “You Can’t Trust a Philosopher.” In R. Feldman, and T. Warfield (eds.), Disagreement, 91–110. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Goldberg, Sandy. 2009. “Reliabilism in Philosophy,” Philosophical Studies 124: 105–117. Goldman, Alvin. 2011. “Reliabilism.” In E. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy  (Spring 2011 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/ reliabilism/. Kornblith, Hilary. 2010. “Belief in the Face of Controversy.” In R. Feldman and T. Warfield (eds.), Disagreement, 29–52. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kraft, James. 2012. The Epistemology of Religious Disagreement: A Better Understanding. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. Machuca, Diego (ed.). 2013. Disagreement and Skepticism. New York: Routledge. Oppy, Graham. 2010. “Disagreement,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 68: 183–199. Rysiew, Patrick. 2011. “Epistemic Contextualism.” In E. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ win2011/entries/contextualism-epistemology/. Thune, Michael. 2011. “Religious Belief and the Epistemology of Disagreement,” Philosophy Compass 6: 712–724.

CHAPTER FORTY-ONE

Skepticism and the InternalismExternalism Debate MATTHIAS STEUP

1 INTRODUCTION Since the early 1980s, it has been common to classify theories of justification as internalist or externalist.1 Advocates of internalism take justification, in some way or another, to be internal; externalists deny that justification is internal in the way internalists assert it is. What is at issue here is not only whether a belief’s being justified but also whether a belief’s not being justified is internal. The term j-status will serve to refer to either one of these statuses. Justification, or the lack of it, is conferred upon a belief by j-determiners: the factors that fix a belief’s j-status. Whatever internality is, it would seem that the internality of j-determiners is both necessary and sufficient for the internality of j-status.

2  THREE THEORIES OF JUSTIFICATION To discuss what the internality of justification is supposed to be, it will be helpful to have at our disposal sample theories of justification that qualify as either internalist or externalist. We will consider classical foundationalism and evidentialism as examples of internalism, and reliabilism as an example of externalism. According to classical foundationalism, a subject’s beliefs are divided into two sets.2 The first comprises inferred beliefs about the external world, and the second is made up of foundational beliefs about the subject’s perceptual experiences. All beliefs in the first set are ultimately justified by suitable beliefs in the second set. For example, an external world belief such as “This object is red” is inferentially justified by the foundational belief “This object looks red.” The latter belief is noninferentially justified through a special cognitive relation such as acquaintance or direct apprehension, which provides a kind of justification that does not itself require any further justifying beliefs.

SKEPTICISM AND THE INTERNALISM-EXTERNALISM DEBATE

593

Evidentialism is the view that whether a subject’s belief is justified is determined by the total body of the subject’s evidence.3 A subject’s evidence includes not only beliefs about one’s perceptual experiences, but also perceptual experiences themselves. As a consequence, what justifies the belief “This object is red” need not be a belief such as “This object looks red to me” but can be the kind of experience a subject describes when she says, “It looks to me as though the object is red.” Reliabilism, in its most basic form, is the view that a belief is justified if and only if it is reliably produced.4 In other words, a belief’s origin in a reliable source is both necessary and sufficient for its status of being justified. Consider again the example of believing that the object before you is red. Reliabilism says that your belief is justified because color perception is a reliable process. So, according to reliabilism, your belief’s justificational status is determined by the following two facts: (i) your belief originates in color perception and (ii) color perception is reliable. Why do classical foundationalism and evidentialism qualify as internalist, whereas reliabilism is externalist? To answer this question, we need to examine the notion of internality that is in play when epistemologists debate whether justification is internal or external.

3 INTERNALITY According to Roderick Chisholm, a main advocate of internalism in the second half of the twentieth century to be internal is to be recognizable on reflection (Chisholm 1977: 17; 1989: 62). But what is the difference between being able, and not being able, to know some proposition p through reflection? The key thought appears to be that you can know p solely through reflection if you can come to know p on the basis of what you already have to go on, that is, without having to engage in any further observations. Suppose you wonder what your car’s license plate says. If you remember it, reflecting on the question will provide you with an answer. If you forgot, you will have to go and look at your license plate. Or suppose you ask yourself, after you have had a headache all morning long, whether you still have it now. Presumably you need not consult a neurologist to find out. Reflecting on the question will provide you with an answer to it. But if you wonder whether your colleague Carl, who complained earlier in the morning about a headache, is now feeling better, reflection will not answer your question. You will have to ask him. Finally, consider the question whether “~(p & q)” is equivalent to “~p & ~q.” If you arrive at the correct answer (which would be “no”) by thinking about the truth conditions of negation and conjunction, you have answered the question by reflecting on it. If you answer it by asking a logician or looking it up in a textbook, you have not. According to an alternative criterion of internality, what is internal is what is located within one’s own cognitive perspective.5 What is located outside of one’s perspective is external. The problem with this proposal is that of illuminating the concept of one’s own cognitive perspective. If it turns out that what is within and what is outside of one’s perspective is precisely what is, and what is not, recognizable on reflection, then the cognitive perspective criterion is not a genuine alternative to the recognizability-on-reflection criterion. According to yet another approach,

594

SKEPTICISM

referred to as mentalism, internalism is the view that j-status is determined by mental states only (see Conee and Feldman 2001). As before, it is not clear that this proposal qualifies as a genuine alternative. Clearly, not any brain state qualifies as a mental state. Is it possible to explain how mental and non-mental brain states differ without relying on a cognitive accessibility criterion like introspection? It is doubtful that that is possible. We may reasonably suspect that what is definitive of the mental is introspective access. If that suspicion is correct, then mentalism is not a genuine competitor for the recognizability-on-reflection criterion.6 In what follows we will proceed to work with the latter. Having at our disposal a criterion of internality, the difference between internalist and externalist theories can be defined as follows: Internalism: T is an internalist theory of justification iff, if T is true, then justification is always recognizable on reflection. Externalism: T is an externalist theory of justification iff, if T is true, then justification is not always recognizable on reflection. In these definitions, the word “always” is essential.7 Without it, we would get the uncontroversial claim that justification is sometimes recognizable on reflection. This rather modest claim should not generate disagreement. Reliabilists need not, and should not, advocate the rather implausible claim that justification can never be recognized on reflection. Rather, as we shall see below, what is distinctive of reliabilism is that justification is not always recognizable on reflection.

4  RELIABILISM AS A VERSION OF EXTERNALISM If reliabilism is true, then, for two reasons, justification is not always recognizable on reflection. First, there are possible cases in which the presence of reliabilist justification—justification resulting from a belief’s originating in a reliable source— is not recognizable on reflection. Second, there are scenarios in which the absence of reliabilist justification is entirely hidden and thus not recognizable on reflection (nor in any other way). An example of the former situation is Laurence BonJour’s case of Norman the reliable clairvoyant (BonJour 1985: ch. 3). Suppose Norman acquired the faculty of clairvoyance for no noticeable reason, say, because of imperceptible cosmic radiation. Suppose further that Norman’s faculty of clairvoyance, which we assume is as reliable as Norman’s other perceptual faculties, produces, for the very first time after Norman acquired it, a belief, namely the belief that the president is currently in New York. Since Norman’s clairvoyance is reliable, Norman’s belief is justified. But through reflection, this is not recognizable to Norman. If he were to reflect on his belief’s epistemic credentials, Norman would have to conclude that his belief is not justified, for he has no reason to think, right then and there, (a) that his belief was produced by a newly acquired faculty, namely, by clairvoyance, and (b) that, contrary to what he would reasonably expect, clairvoyance is, at least in his particular case, reliable. Next, let us turn to the kind of case where the absence of reliabilist justification is not recognizable on reflection.8 Consider your belief that you have hands. Classical

SKEPTICISM AND THE INTERNALISM-EXTERNALISM DEBATE

595

foundationalists, evidentialists, and reliabilists all agree that your belief is justified. Moreover, they would (or at least should) agree that you can recognize on reflection that your belief is justified. Now suppose you are a brain in a vat (a BIV).9 As a BIV, your belief that you have hands is of course false. Moreover, the belief’s source is unreliable since nearly all beliefs originating from this source are false. Reliabilists would therefore have to say that, if you are a BIV, your belief that you have hands is unjustified. But if, as a BIV, you were to consider your belief’s j-status, you would arrive—and reasonably so—at the conclusion that you are entirely justified in believing that you have hands. You would arrive at this conclusion because your being a BIV is, ex hypothesi, undetectable. You do not, therefore, have any reason to suspect that your belief originates in an unreliable faculty. Hence there is no way you could, as a BIV, recognize, on reflection or otherwise, that you are not justified in believing that you have hands. To sum up, if reliabilism is true, neither the presence nor the absence of justification is always recognizable on reflection. That is why reliabilism is an externalist theory.

5  CLASSICAL FOUNDATIONALISM AND EVIDENTIALISM AS VERSIONS OF INTERNALISM According to internalist theories such as classical foundationalism and evidentialism, j-status is determined through factors that can be recognized through introspection and a priori intuition, factors such as how the external world appears to one in one’s experiences and what support relations obtain between the content of one’s experiences and one’s beliefs about the external world. It is plausible think that such j-determiners are frequently, perhaps even typically, recognizable on reflection. Why think they always are? It is helpful to approach this question by considering the two cases in which, if reliabilism is true, justification is not recognizable on reflection. First, consider Boris, who unfortunately has been envatted. According to reliabilism, Boris’s external world beliefs are not justified because, since Boris is a BIV, his perceptual processes are unreliable. But their unreliability is undetectable to a BIV. That’s why, if reliabilism is true, it is undetectable to Boris that his external world beliefs are unjustified. If evidentialism is true, we get a different outcome. Boris’s external world beliefs are then (typically) justified, and Boris can tell on reflection that they are justified. This is so for the following reasons. First, according to evidentialism, the unreliability of a belief’s origin is not a necessary condition of the belief’s being justified. Second, Boris has plenty of evidence for his external world beliefs, namely, the kind of perceptual experiences BIVs and normal people share. Third, Boris can tell on reflection that he has such experiences and that they support his external world beliefs. A similar line of reasoning will support the conclusion that, according to classical foundationalism, Boris can recognize on reflection the justificational status of his external world beliefs.10 Next, consider Norman the reliable clairvoyant. According to reliabilism, Norman’s belief about the president’s location is justified because it is reliably

596

SKEPTICISM

produced. But since Norman has no reason to think that his belief has its origin in reliable clairvoyance, he cannot tell on reflection that his belief is justified. In contrast, according to classical foundationalism and experiential evidentialism, Norman’s belief about the president’s location is not justified. And since introspection and a priori reasoning will reveal to Norman that he has no support for his belief, he can tell on reflection, according to these theories, that his belief is not justified. Such goes, in any case, the traditional story of how internalist justification works. J-status is always recognizable on reflection because the j-determiners of our external worlds beliefs are transparent to the mind’s eye. Through introspection we can tell what our perceptual experiences are, and through a priori intuition we can recognize what beliefs these experiences support. We might wonder whether such optimism about the luminosity of both the mind and epistemic support relations is well advised. Timothy Williamson has argued, famously, that the mind is not luminous (Williamson 2000: ch. 4). If his anti-luminosity argument is sound, then introspection cannot always reveal to us what our perceptual experiences are. It is then possible to be in a situation in which, for example, one simply cannot tell whether an object looks red to one or not. Williamson’s argument puts considerable pressure on traditional, internalist epistemology. However, the soundness of his anti-luminosity argument has been challenged.11 And even granting its soundness, it is unclear how much damage it inflicts on the traditional internalist position.12

6  MOTIVATING INTERNALISM Internalists have rejected reliabilism on the ground that origination in a reliable cognitive process is neither necessary nor sufficient for making beliefs justified. Beliefs that are false due to undetectable deception are unreliably produced, but, internalists have argued, they can nevertheless be justified; beliefs that are in fact reliably produced, but undetectably so, need not be justified. These are serious arguments that put considerable pressure on reliabilism. But do they show that a theory’s being internalist is something recommending it? They do not. If these arguments are successful, they show that reliabilism is false, without showing that reliabilism is false because it is an externalist theory. Let us distinguish, then, between merely attempting to show that a particular version of externalism is false and arguing for or against internalism as such. Why should we think that a theory’s being internalist is something recommending it? The perhaps dominant way of motivating internalism is to argue that justification is conceptually linked to deontological status.13 The argument’s first premise is a claim about the meaning of the word “justification.” To be justified in believing p is to believe p in a way that does not violate the duties one has qua being an intellectual being who aims at truth and the avoidance of falsehood. Alternatively, the point can be expressed by saying that to be justified in believing p is to believe p in a way that manifests epistemic responsibility, or in a way that is not epistemically blameworthy. Let us express the first premise in terms of the latter point: justified belief is epistemically responsible belief. The argument’s second premise asserts that

SKEPTICISM AND THE INTERNALISM-EXTERNALISM DEBATE

597

whatever determines whether a belief is responsibly held must be recognizable on reflection. It then follows that j-determiners must be recognizable on reflection. Why think that the second premise is true? The basic idea is that facts not recognizable on reflection cannot determine the deontological status of either one’s actions or one’s beliefs. Let’s consider actions first. If you cannot know that the capsules in the Tylenol bottle you recently purchased are laced with cyanide, you will not act irresponsibly if you offer a couple to your colleague.14 The passengers on Pan Am Flight 103 (which crashed over Lockerbie) did not act irresponsibly when they boarded the plane.15 Sometimes what people do has unfortunate outcomes. If these outcomes are not recognizable or foreseeable at the time, they do not render such actions irresponsible or unreasonable. An analogous point can be made about beliefs. Sometimes, our beliefs are false. If nothing that’s recognizable to us at the time indicates that they are false, such beliefs are not held irresponsibly. When the passengers on Flight 103 believed the plane would in due time safely land in New York City, their belief was not irresponsible, for nothing they could have figured out at the time would have given them a reason to suspect there was a bomb on board. Likewise, nothing a BIV can tell on reflection indicates that its external world beliefs are unreliably produced (and indeed mostly false). Therefore, a BIV’s beliefs about the external world are not epistemically irresponsible. Examples like these suggest that what determines deontological status must be recognizable on reflection.16 In response to the epistemic responsibility argument for internalism, externalists can reject the deontological conception of justification.17 They could easily agree that evaluating beliefs as responsible or irresponsible is an interesting and legitimate mode of epistemic evaluation but, at the same time, insist that a belief’s deontological status is not related to truth in the way justification is supposed to be. William Alston captures this point by saying that deontological justification is not truth-conducive and thus is not the same as epistemic justification. He argues that deontological status is sensitive to personal and situational limitations to which epistemic justification is not. Alston describes two cases that illustrate this point (Alston 1985: 67f). First, consider a philosophy major of limited talent. His interpretation of John Locke might be responsibly arrived at because he did his best to read the text carefully; but, given the limits of his understanding, it is not justified. Second, consider an isolated tribe of indigenous people in a remote region in Brazil. Some of their beliefs are such that, given what the tribe members have to go on, they are not irresponsibly held. But, given the way these beliefs are actually arrived at, ways that are not at all likely to produce true beliefs, they do not qualify as epistemically justified. According to Alston, such examples show that responsibly held belief is one thing, justified belief is another. They are not to be equated with each other. If that is correct, then the deontological attempt to motivate internalism fails. Next, we will turn to the question of how the internalism-externalism debate is related to the issue of skepticism. Specifically, we will consider the following two questions: First, does internalism have skeptical consequences that cannot be attributed to externalism? Second, are externalists better positioned than internalists when it comes to responding to arguments for skepticism about knowledge of the external world?

598

SKEPTICISM

7  INTERNALISM, CLASSICAL FOUNDATIONALISM, AND SKEPTICISM Let the word “skepticism” designate the claim that we do not have knowledge of the external world.18 Advocates of externalism could argue that whereas internalism, when closely inspected, reveals itself as a form of skepticism, externalism is not vulnerable to this accusation.19 Using reliabilism as a representative of externalism and classical foundationalism as a representative of internalism, the argument proceeds in two stages. At the first stage, it is asserted that reliabilism does not have skepticism as a consequence: According to reliabilism, having justified beliefs about the external world does not require reasons in support of these beliefs. Nor does it require any beliefs about, or awareness of, the fact that beliefs about the external world are reliably produced. For such beliefs to be justified, their being reliably produced is sufficient. Therefore, if reliabilism is true, external world beliefs are typically justified and, if true, instances of knowledge. Reliabilism, therefore, qualifies as a paradigmatically non-skeptical theory. At the second stage of the argument, it is asserted that classical foundationalism cannot avoid the outcome of skepticism: According to classical foundationalism, our beliefs about the external world qualify as instances of knowledge only if they are supported by foundational beliefs about how the external world appears to us. But ordinarily, we do not form foundational beliefs about how the external world appears to us. Rather, we tend to acquire beliefs about the objects in the external world spontaneously, without inferring them from beliefs about how these objects appear to us. Therefore, if classical foundationalism is true, our external world beliefs are under ordinary circumstances unjustified and thus fail to be instances of knowledge. Hence, classical foundationalism, and therefore internalism, produces an unacceptably skeptical outcome. Although the claim that classical foundationalism generates the outcome of skepticism is quite plausible, this argument suffers from an obvious limitation. Classical foundationalism is just one form of internalism among others. Like classical foundationalism, evidentialism assigns an important role to foundational beliefs. However, according to evidentialism, foundational beliefs need not be about how the external world appears to us. They can be beliefs about objects in the external world. As such, they will make up a large part of a normal person’s belief system. Therefore, the criticism that we do not under ordinary circumstances form foundational beliefs does not apply to experiential evidentialism. To make the internalism-leads-to-skepticism objection stick, externalists need to show that any form of internalism suffers from the defect of making justification too difficult to attain. That is, they need to identify an essential feature of internalism, a feature that is necessarily a part of every version of internalism, and they need to show that, by virtue of this feature, internalism is bound to have a skeptical outcome.

SKEPTICISM AND THE INTERNALISM-EXTERNALISM DEBATE

599

8  INTERNALISM, EPISTEMIC RESPONSIBILITY, AND SKEPTICISM If externalists wish to reject internalism on the ground that, whatever version it takes, the view either renders knowledge of the external world impossible or at least unacceptably minimizes its extent, they must meet the challenge of identifying a skepticism-breeding feature that is essential to internalism. This feature, externalists might argue, is the deontological conception of epistemic justification. Without it, internalism remains unmotivated. Therefore, part and parcel of every version of internalism is the claim that justified belief is epistemically responsible belief. But, so the argument continues, the standards of epistemic responsibility are excessively high. Therefore, internalism is bound to be a version of skepticism. Why think that the standards of epistemic responsibility are excessively high? The worry is that the demand for responsibility generates a vicious infinite regress.20 Suppose you believe p on the basis of a reason R. Suppose also your belief is justified. R might be a perceptual experience with p as its content, or a further justified belief from which p can be inferred. Initially, it might look as though the two conditions— (i) having R and (ii) believing p on the basis of R—are sufficient for being responsible in believing p. The externalist, however, might argue that (i) and (ii) are not sufficient for being responsible in believing p. For your belief to be responsibly held, you must also believe (iii) that there is a suitable support relation between R and p; that is, you must believe that R makes it likely that p is true. Without such a metabelief, you would not be responsible in believing p.21 Now two problems arise. First, in ordinary circumstances, we do not form metabeliefs about the truth-conduciveness of our reasons. This is simply a fact about human psychology. Second, a vicious infinite regress ensues. Suppose you actually form the metabelief in question. If it is not justified in turn, it will hardly be of help in making you responsible in believing p. Now, for your metabelief to be justified, you need a reason R* that supports it, and you need a metabelief* to the effect that R* supports your first metabelief. But your metabelief* needs to be justified in turn, which calls for a reason R**, supporting your second metabelief, and so forth. This regress is vicious because its increasing complexity makes it impossible for human beings to move beyond the first few steps. So, if epistemic responsibility does require justifying metabeliefs, then it is impossible to satisfy the demands of such responsibility. Hence, if justified belief is indeed epistemically responsible belief, justified belief remains elusive. Internalism leads to skepticism. To this line of reasoning, internalists can respond by questioning the premise that epistemic responsibility requires justifying metabeliefs. According to an alternative proposal, for responsibly believing p, the following is sufficient: the belief’s being based on a reason R, and the existence of a true proposition to the effect that R makes the truth of p likely. The true-proposition requirement does not have the skeptical consequences of the requirement for a metabelief. It is consistent with the fact that, in ordinary circumstances, we do not form justifying metabeliefs, and it does not generate a vicious infinite regress.

600

SKEPTICISM

Alas, is the mere existence of a true proposition of the form R makes it likely that p is true enough to render it responsible for a subject to believe p on the basis of R? Arguably, it is not. In the very least, the subject must, it might be argued, somehow appreciate that R makes it likely that p is true. And how can such appreciation be instantiated short of believing the meta-proposition about the support relation between R and p? According to the objection to internalism presently under consideration, the demands of epistemic responsibility can only be discharged by believing such meta-propositions. Internalists could insist, however, that epistemic responsibility is not as demanding as the externalist critic would have it. They could argue that, if a belief p is based on a reason R, understanding and appreciating the epistemic support relation between R and p is sufficient for the belief to be epistemically responsible. Moreover, understanding and appreciating the support relation does not require the subject to form a metabelief to the effect that R supports p. According to this approach, part of what it is to understand a proposition p is to understand what counts as a reason in support of p. For example, an ordinary, competent speaker of English understands that an object’s looking red is a reason to think it is red, and that an object’s looking like a tomato is a reason for taking it to be a tomato. Such a subject manifests an understanding and appreciation of these support relations through the patterns of her epistemic conduct: typically, when she believes an object to be red, that objects looks red to her; when the object does not look red to her, she does not form the belief that it is red. Such an understanding, internalists could argue, need not manifest itself through any epistemic metabeliefs. By itself, it is enough to make it epistemically responsible for a competent speaker to take an object to be red when the object looks red to her.

9  CLOSURE DENIAL AS AN EXTERNALIST RESPONSE TO SKEPTICISM We have considered two arguments for the conclusion that internalism leads to skepticism. According to the first, internalism is identified with classical foundationalism, which arguably makes skepticism unavoidable. According to the second, internalism inevitably produces skepticism because the deontological conception of justification as epistemic responsibility is too demanding. It turned out that neither of these arguments is an unqualified success. Alternatively, externalists could argue that, when it comes to rebutting skeptical arguments, they are in a strong position whereas internalists are in a weak position.22 To examine the plausibility of this claim, let us consider the following argument: The BIV Argument (1) If I know that I have hands, then I know that I am not a BIV. (2) I do not know that I am not a BIV. Therefore: (3) I do not know that I have hands.

SKEPTICISM AND THE INTERNALISM-EXTERNALISM DEBATE

601

The first premise is plausible because it’s difficult to deny that knowledge requires the ability to discriminate. If I cannot discriminate between a goldfinch and a canary, I cannot know that the bird before me is a goldfinch simply by looking at it. If I cannot tell Mark from Matt, who are identical twins, then I cannot know that the person before me is Mark just by looking at him. Likewise, if I cannot discriminate between being a normal person with hands and being a handless BIV, I’m not in a position to know that I’m not a BIV. The second premise is also plausible. The BIV hypothesis involves the stipulation that, if you were a BIV, your evidence—the total set of your memories, beliefs, and introspective and perceptual experiences—would be exactly the same as it is in the normal situation. This stipulation, it seems, makes it impossible for me to have any reason to think I am not a BIV. The argument we will discuss in this section aims to establish the conclusion that rebutting the BIV argument is easier for externalists than it is for internalists. To discuss this claim, we must first get clear on what a successful rebuttal of the BIV argument is supposed to accomplish. A benchmark that’s neither too easy nor too ambitious is the following: a rebuttal of the BIV argument is successful if, and only if, it makes a strong, prima facie plausible case that at least one of the argument’s two premises is false. On this understanding of rebutting a skeptical argument, the claim under consideration is that externalists are in a better position than internalists to show that at least one of the two premises of the BIV argument is false. We will first examine the plausibility of this claim using Fred Dretske’s conclusive reasons theory as an example of externalism, and then move on to discuss how the claim holds up when we consider reliabilism. The first premise of the BIV argument expresses commitment to the closure principle, which says the following: Closure If one knows that p and knows that p entails q, then one is in a position to know that q.23 Many epistemologists think that the closure principle is extremely plausible. Let’s apply the principle to the goldfinch example. If p = the bird is a goldfinch and q = the bird is not a canary, then, given I know that p entails q, it is hard to see how I could know p without also knowing (or at least being in a position to know) q. Likewise, if p=I have hands and q=I’m not a BIV, then, given I know that p entails q, it is hard to see how I could know the former proposition without also knowing (or at least being in a position to know) the latter. Nevertheless, Dretske’s theory of knowledge recommends that we should reject the first premise of the BIV argument. According to Dretske, having a conclusive reason is sufficient for knowledge.24 R is a conclusive reason for a subject S to believe p if, and only if, the following condition is met: in all close possible worlds in which p is false, R is false or, alternatively, S does not have R.25 Now, my reason for thinking I have hands is that I have hand-like experiences: I can see and feel my hands. In close worlds in which I do not have hands, I do not have hand-like experiences. Instead, I would have stump-like, or prostheses-like, experiences. Of course, in a world in which I am a handless BIV, I nevertheless have hand-like experiences; but such a

602

SKEPTICISM

world is not close. My hand-like experiences, therefore, are a conclusive reason for me to think I have hands. That’s why, on Dretske’s theory, I know that I have hands. Alas, my belief that I am not a BIV is not supported by a conclusive reason. Whatever my reasons are for believing I am not a BIV, I have these reasons in the closest possible worlds in which I am a BIV. That’s simply how the BIV hypothesis is set up. Thus, on Dretske’s theory, I do not know that I am not a BIV. Hence, if Dretske’s conclusive reasons theory of knowledge is right, we get the following picture: (i) I know I have hands and (ii) I do not know I’m not a BIV, even though (iii) I know that having hands entails not being a BIV. If (i) and (ii) are conjoined with (iii), then the closure principle is false. So according to Dretske, the proper response to the BIV argument is to reject the first premise. If the first premise is false, then my being unable to know I’m not a BIV is not an obstacle to my knowing that I have hands. Why does Dretske’s closure-denial strategy qualify as an externalist response to skepticism? It does because Dretske’s conclusive reasons theory, like reliabilism, is externalist. Whether a reason is conclusive is not always recognizable on reflection. If you are a BIV, then, for you, the actual world is such that, in it, you have hand-like experiences even though you do not have hands. So, if you are a BIV, your hand-like experiences are not conclusive but rather misleading reasons. Alas, you have no way of recognizing this. The non-conclusiveness of your hand-like experiences is entirely hidden from you. The strategy of avoiding skepticism by denying closure runs into two serious problems. The first is that of abominable conjunctions (see DeRose 1995: 27–29). Consider: Conjunction A: (a) I know that this bird is a goldfinch, but (b) I do not know that it is not a canary. This sounds pretty awful. If somebody were to admit (b), we would be very reluctant to agree to part (a) of the assertion. Now consider: Conjunction B: (a) I know that I have hands, but (b) I do not know that I am not a handless BIV. This, too, sounds quite awful. It is difficult to see why we should agree to Conjunction B if we reject Conjunction A. The second problem is no less serious. Dretske’s conclusiveness requirement is actually quite demanding. A lot of what we take ourselves to know is not based on conclusive reasons but on what we might call inductive evidence: on beliefs about how the world by and large works. Consider the proposition that there isn’t a nuclear bomb in your basement. Call this proposition “No Bomb.” You have strong inductive evidence to think that No Bomb is true. Nuclear devices are exclusively kept at military installations that are extremely well guarded. They are never in the basements of houses in which ordinary citizens live. Alas, such inductive evidence is not conclusive. In close possible worlds in which No Bomb is false (i.e., in close worlds in which there really is a nuclear bomb in your basement), you still have strong inductive evidence to think that No Bomb is true.26 To acquire a conclusive reason for No Bomb, you would have to go into your basement and look. So, if Dretske’s conclusive reasons

SKEPTICISM AND THE INTERNALISM-EXTERNALISM DEBATE

603

theory were right, you couldn’t know that there isn’t a nuclear bomb in your basement without having to go and check. That seems odd. An analogous outcome follows for similar propositions such as: there isn’t a million dollars hidden inside your mattress, or the current secretary of defense does not secretly plan to steal the gold in Fort Knox. It’s easy to make a long list of such propositions. It would seem, then, that Dretske’s externalist closure-denial response to skepticism significantly reduces the scope of what we know. It avoids the outcome that we have no knowledge of the external world at all by giving up a good chunk of such knowledge.

10  RELIABILISM AND SHOWING THAT ONE ISN’T A BRAIN IN A VAT Nothing about externalism requires its advocates to respond to the BIV argument by denying the closure principle. An externalist might as well rebut the argument by asserting “I know I’m not a BIV,” that is, by denying the BIV argument’s second premise. What we will examine in this section is the claim that, when it comes to the challenge of proving that premise wrong, externalists are in a better position than internalists. To do so, we will focus on reliabilism and evidentialism.27 According to reliabilism, the belief “I’m not a BIV,” if true and reliably produced, is an instance of knowledge. What the belief’s origin is is not obvious. Non-philosophers do not even consider the question of whether they are BIVs. Philosophers disagree on how to justify the rejection of the second premise of the BIV argument. Some reject it because they take themselves to know they have hands.28 Others reject it because they take themselves to know that BIVs do not exist.29 For our purposes here, we can easily accommodate a variety of reasons why people believe they are not BIVs. What matters is that, whatever the source of the belief “I’m not a BIV” is, if the belief is true, then, according to reliabilism, it amounts to knowledge if that source is sufficiently reliable. The reliabilist response to the BIV argument, then, can be stated as follows: (R) I know that I am not a BIV because my belief that I’m not a BIV has its origin in a reliable source. In contrast, the evidentialist rejection of the BIV argument’s second premise goes thus: (E) I know that I am not a BIV because I have knowledge-grade evidence for the belief that I am not a BIV. In each case, we are looking at a mere recipe for articulating a fully developed response. Obviously, for (R) to carry weight, the reliabilist would have to present evidence in support of the claim that her belief not to be a BIV stems from a reliable source. Likewise, for (E) to carry weight, the evidentialist would have explain what knowledge-grade evidence justifies her belief that she is not a BIV. Why should we think that presenting evidence in support of (R) is easier than presenting evidence in support of (E)? The thought might be that defending (R)

604

SKEPTICISM

is easier than defending (E) because reliabilism makes the acquisition of reliability knowledge easier than evidentialism does. This thought, however, runs into a serious problem, for it is in fact very difficult to demonstrate—as opposed to merely knowing—that a particular belief has its origin in a reliable source. In general terms, the challenge is to establish the reliability of one’s faculties. Alston, himself a reliabilist, has argued that, while knowing that one’s faculties are reliable is easy, it is not only difficult but in fact impossible to demonstrate that one’s faculties are reliable (Alston 1993: ch. 2).30 Knowing it is easy because, according to reliabilism, if a faculty F is indeed reliable and the belief “F is reliable” is itself reliably produced, then that belief is an instance of knowledge. However, demonstrating that one’s faculties are reliable is not easy because one cannot argue for the reliability of one’s faculties without using one’s faculties. To show that perception is reliable requires the use of perception; to show that memory is reliable requires the use of memory. Alston refers to the circularity exhibited here as epistemic circularity. An argument is epistemically circular if at least one of its premises is such that a legitimate appeal to it requires antecedent knowledge of the conclusion. Suppose I appeal to a proposition p as a premise in an argument for the reliability of perception. If showing that p is true requires antecedent knowledge of the reliability of perception, appealing to p will hardly serve as a good reason to think that perception is reliable. It would be a mistake, then, to think that defending (R) is easier than defending (E). In fact, it might be thought that, if Alston is right, the opposite is true: defending (R) is more difficult than defending (E). But that, too, would be a mistake. For the evidentialist, the task of showing that she has knowledge-grade evidence for believing she is not a BIV involves the subtask of showing that the adduced evidence stems from a reliable source. For in response to any claim of the form “I know I’m not a BIV because of fact F,” the skeptic can ask: “How do you know that the faculty through which you think you know F is reliable?” If the evidentialist does not answer this question, she can hardly claim to have a successful response to the BIV argument. If the evidentialist attempts to answer the question, she faces the very same challenge reliabilists do when they attempt to defend (R).31 So, part of demonstrating that one knows one is not a BIV is to show that the faculties through which such knowledge is acquired are reliable. Showing that without epistemic circularity is impossible. Therefore, a successful refutation of the BIV argument’s second premise requires a sound argument for the conclusion that epistemic circularity can be benign. This is a formidable challenge. Two conclusions follow from our findings. First, rejecting the BIV argument’s second premise is difficult. Second, in the attempt to meet this challenge, neither reliabilism nor evidentialism has an advantage over the other.

NOTES 1. All occurrences of “justification” or “justified” refer to epistemic justification, the kind that bears on a belief’s likelihood of being true and turns, under the right conditions, a true belief into knowledge. For early work on the internalism-externalism issue, see Alston (1986) and BonJour (1985: ch. 3).

SKEPTICISM AND THE INTERNALISM-EXTERNALISM DEBATE

605

2. For contemporary examples of classical foundationalism, see BonJour (2001) and Fumerton (2001). 3. See Conee and Feldman (1995; 2004). Related views are dogmatism (Pryor 2000) and phenomenal conservatism (Huemer 2000). 4. See Goldman (1979) for the initial, classical articulation of reliabilism. For the sake of succinct presentation, we are considering the simplified version according to which reliable belief formation is both necessary and sufficient for justification. Fully developed versions of reliabilism distinguish between inferential and noninferential justification and attempt to address the phenomenon of defeat. 5. Alston (1986) distinguished between a “cognitive access” and a “perspectival” version of internalism. 6. According to Michael Bergmann (2006; 2008), an opponent of internalism, the distinctive mark of internalism is some kind of awareness requirement; see (2008: 504). Awareness, however, is naturally interpreted as a special kind of knowledge. The requirement Bergmann has in mind, therefore, is very demanding. Because of its obvious regress implications, internalists should not define internality in this way. 7. The always-recognizable-on-reflection criterion of internality might seem excessively demanding. The worry might be that there is no theory of justification that makes justification something the presence or absence of which can always be recognized on reflection. However, “can be recognized” should not be identified with “will be recognized.” To say that justification is always recognizable on reflection is not to say that an attempt to determine through reflection whether a belief is justified will always be successful. Someone who is momentarily confused might at the present moment be unable to recognize what is in principle recognizable to him. 8. Cases of this kind have become known as the “new evil demon” problem. See Cohen (1984) and Ginet (1985). 9. A BIV’s mental states are induced through computer-controlled stimulation of nerve endings in the brain. The stimulation is so perfect that the experiences of a normal human being are duplicated. To a BIV, everything seems perfectly “normal,” which is why the deception that is actually going on is undetectable. 10. The main thought would be that, according to classical foundationalism, (i) the unreliability of a belief-producing process does not block justification, and (ii) to BIVs and normal subjects alike, the support relations between foundational and non-foundational beliefs are recognizable on reflection. 11. See Berker (2008), Steup (2009), and also Williamson (2009). 12. See Hawthorne (2005), Reed (2006), and Fumerton (2009). 13. For a lucid account of the relationship between epistemic deontologism and internalism, see Plantinga (1993: ch. 1). 14. See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Tylenol_murders. 15. See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Pan_Am_Flight_103. 16. The claim is fairly plausible but not immune to proposed counterexamples. Suppose a subject S is culpably in a situation in which he cannot recognize on reflection that p is the case. If S had conducted a proper investigation, his total evidence would have

606

SKEPTICISM

concluded E*, but since S failed to conduct a proper investigation, his total evidence is missing E*. Had it included E*, S would have noticed on reflection that p is true. Without E*, S’s total evidence indicates that p is false. Arguably, S is epistemically irresponsible in disbelieving p, even though this is not recognizable to him on reflection. Against this kind of objection, it could be argued that a case like this involves two different dimensions of evaluation. The agent was irresponsible in the way he conducted the investigation; however, he is not irresponsible in disbelieving p, for the very reason that his evidence indicates that p is false. 17. See Alston (1985; 1988). 18. There are of course other kinds of skepticism. Of these, the most prominent are claims to the effect that we lack knowledge of the past, the future, or other minds. For reasons of space, here we can focus only on skepticism about our knowledge of the external world. 19. For arguments to the effect that internalism breeds skepticism, see Goldman (1999). 20. For an argument roughly along these lines, see Michael Bergmann’s “dilemma for internalism” argument (Bergmann 2006: ch. 1). 21. An argument along these lines is embedded in BonJour’s primary objection to foundationalism in his The Structure of Empirical Knowledge (8BonJour 1985: 30–33). 22. For an excellent review of externalist responses to skepticism, see Bergmann (2008). 23. For a discussion of the issues involved in rejecting and defending the closure principle, see Hawthorne (2013). 24. See Dretske (1970; 1971; 2013). Another externalist closure-denial approach to skepticism is Robert Nozick’s (1981) tracking theory of knowledge. 25. Alternatively, the notion of a conclusive reason could be defined in terms of a counterfactual: R is a conclusive reason for S to believe p =df if p were false, R would be false or S would not have R. 26. The closest worlds in which there is a nuclear bomb in your basement are not worlds in which the reasons mentioned are false, but rather worlds in which terrorists got hold of a suitcase bomb and, due to highly coincidental and unlikely circumstances, ended up hiding it in your basement. In a situation like that, you still have excellent reason for thinking there is not a nuclear bomb in your basement. 27. Another externalist approach to rejecting the BIV argument’s second premise is Timothy Williamson’s controversial equation E=K: one’s evidence equals what one knows. What normal Boris and envatted Boris know is vastly different. Normal Boris has lots of knowledge of the external world. Envatted Boris does not. Now, the standard line for saying normal Boris cannot know he is not a BIV is that, if he were a BIV, his evidence would be the same: normal Boris’s evidence=envatted Boris’s evidence. This line of reasoning is blocked if Williamson’s E=K is correct, and one main challenge to claiming knowledge of not being a BIV has been removed. Williamson’s approach qualifies as externalist because, according to Williamson, only beliefs that are reliably based qualify as knowledge. Given E=K, it follows that only what is reliably based qualifies as

SKEPTICISM AND THE INTERNALISM-EXTERNALISM DEBATE

607

evidence. For reasons of space, Williamson’s response to the BIV argument cannot be discussed in this chapter. 28. See Huemer (2000: ch. 8). 29. See Steup (2011). 30. Ironically, it has also been argued that reliabilism makes arguments for reliability too easy to come by. See Fumerton (1995: 173–178) and Vogel (2000). Cohen (2002) has argued, however, that the problem—the problem of easy knowledge— arises for all theories, internalist or externalist, that allow for basic knowledge: knowledge acquired without knowledge that its source is reliable. 31. For an attempt to show how evidentialists can argue for the reliability of their faculties, epistemic circularity notwithstanding, see Steup (2013).

REFERENCES Alston, William. 1985. “Concepts of Epistemic Justification,” The Monist 68: 57–89. Alston, William. 1986. “Internalism and Externalism in Epistemology,” Philosophical Topics 14: 179–221. Alston, William. 1988. “The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification,” Philosophical Perspectives 2: 257–299. Alston, William. 1993. The Reliability of Sense Perception. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Bergmann, Michael. 2006. Justification without Awareness. New York: Oxford University Press. Bergmann, Michael. 2008. “Externalist Responses to Skepticism.” In J. Greco (ed.), The Oxford Handbook to Skepticism, 504–538. New York: Oxford University Press. Berker, Selim. 2008. “Luminosity Regained,” Philosophers’ Imprint 8: 1–22. BonJour, Laurence. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. BonJour, Laurence. 2001. “Toward a Defense of Empirical Foundationalism.” In M. De Paul, (ed.), Resurrecting Old-Fashioned Foundationalism, 21–38. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Chisholm, Roderick. 1989. Theory of Knowledge, 3rd edn. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall. Cohen, Stewart. 1984. “Justification and Truth,” Philosophical Studies 46: 279–295. Cohen, Stewart. 2002. “Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 309–329. Conee, Earl and Richard Feldman. 1985. “Evidentialism,” Philosophical Studies 48: 15–35. Conee, Earl and Richard Feldman. 2001. “Internalism Defended.” In H. Kornblith (ed.), Epistemology: Internalism and Externalism, 230–260. New York: Blackwell. Conee, Earl and Richard Feldman. 2004. Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press. De Paul, Michael (ed.). 2001. Resurrecting Old-Fashioned Foundationalism. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. DeRose, Keith. 1995. “Solving the Skeptical Problem,” Philosophical Review 104:1–52. Dretske, Fred. 1970. “Epistemic Operators,” The Journal of Philosophy 67: 1007–1023 Dretske, Fred. 1971. “Conclusive Reasons,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49: 1–22.

608

SKEPTICISM

Dretske, Fred. 2013. “The Case against Closure.” In M. Steup, J. Turri, and E. Sosa (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 27–40. New York: Wiley Blackwell. Fumerton, Richard. 1995. Metaepistemology and Skepticism. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield. Fumerton, Richard. 2001. “Classical Foundationalism.” In M. De Paul, (ed.), Resurrecting Old-Fashioned Foundationalism, 3–20. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Fumerton, Richard. 2009. “Luminous Enough for a Cognitive Home,” Philosophical Studies 142: 67–76. Ginet, Carl. 1985. “Contra Reliabilism,” The Monist 68: 175–187. Goldman, Alvin. 1979. “What is Justified Belief?” In G. S. Pappas (ed.), Justification and Knowledge, 1–23. Dordrecht: Reidel. Goldman, Alvin. 1999. “Internalism Exposed,” The Journal of Philosophy 96: 271–293. Hawthorne, John. 2005. “Knowledge and Evidence,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70: 452–458. Hawthorne, John. 2013. “The Case for Closure.” In Steup, M., J. Turri, and E. Sosa (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 40–56. New York: Wiley Blackwell. Huemer, Michael. 2000. Skepticism and the Veil of Perception. New York: Rowman and Littlefield. Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Plantinga, Alvin. 1993. Warrant: The Current Debate. New York: Oxford University Press. Pryor, James. 2000. “The Skeptic and the Dogmatist,” Noûs 34: 517–549. Reed, Baron. 2006. “Shelter for the Cognitively Homeless,” Synthese 148: 303–308. Steup, Matthias. 2009. “Are Mental States Luminous?” In Greenough, P. and D. Pritchard (eds.), Williamson on Knowledge, 217–236. New York: Oxford University Press. Steup, Matthias. 2011. “Evidentialist Anti-Skepticism.” In T. Dougherty (ed.), Evidentialism and Its Discontents, 105–122. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Steup, Matthias. 2013. “Is Epistemic Circularity Bad?” Res Philosophica 90: 1–20. Steup, Matthias, John Turri, and Ernest Sosa (eds.). 2013. Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 2nd edn. New York: Wiley Blackwell. Vogel, Jonathan. 2000. “Reliabilism Leveled,” The Journal of Philosophy 97: 602–623. Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Williamson, Timothy. 2009. “Reply to Steup.” In P. Greenough and D. Pritchard (eds.), Williamson on Knowledge, 370–374. New York: Oxford University Press.

CHAPTER FORTY-TWO

Skepticism and Fallibilism STEPHEN HETHERINGTON

1 KNOWLEDGE-SKEPTICISM Epistemology harbors many shades of, and guises for, skeptical thinking. This chapter will discuss perhaps the simplest of all—knowledge-skepticism: No belief is ever knowledge. That is, for no belief is there even a single moment when it is knowledge. Let us understand this as a thesis about any belief belonging to any actual or possible person.1 Is it a thesis we should accept as true? It is, if it is derivable from grounds we independently regard as true—a potential concession which brings us to our chapter’s main question. Can knowledge-skepticism be derived from a fallibilist conception of people’s cognitive powers and attainments? These days, many epistemologists claim to be fallibilists. Yet typically they regard this as saving them from being committed to knowledge-skepticism. (The usual explanation of this escape is said to be that accepting a lower standard for knowing makes it easier to attribute knowledge.) Are fallibilists correct in that optimistic assessment, though? Or does even fallibilism imply a skepticism about there being any knowledge?

2  FALLIBILISM AND FALLIBILITY That depends upon what is meant by “fallibilism.” Here is a generic initial attempt to understand it: Somehow, in some way, fallibility attends or infuses all beliefs (all instances of having a belief). But what is it for a belief to be fallible? The guiding idea in reflection upon fallibility’s nature has long been that of the possibility of being mistaken, even when believing carefully, say. You could be mistaken even in a belief resting on what seem to you to be good evidential grounds: A belief is fallible when it might be false in spite of its apparently good grounds.

610

SKEPTICISM

And because knowledge was generally thought of as a true belief supported by good grounds,2 one apparent implication of that guiding idea would have been this: A belief is fallible when, in spite of apparently being knowledge, it might not be knowledge (due to being false). This use of “apparently” conveys that in any such case it would seem to us—and not randomly or unjustifiedly—that we have knowledge. Yet the use here of “might not be” allows that perhaps we would not really have knowledge. This possibility of mistake—of falsity in our apparently well-grounded belief—would be a possibility of our actually not knowing even when apparently we do. This is an initial step toward knowledge-skepticism. It accords fallibility a structure akin to probably the most venerable philosophical idea that has ever spurred people to skeptical heights or depths. That venerable idea asks us to gaze or reflect upon what is apparently real, before conceiving of it as possibly only apparently real— possibly not really real. Once we imbue our experiences and thoughts with that conceptual pallor, no longer need we take ourselves to be gaining knowledge of what is real through those experiences and thoughts. If we might not know even when we seem to know, do we ever know—really? Should we lower our confidence that we are connected as knowers to what is real? Let us deepen that potential sense of disconnectedness. I offered a candidate formulation of what it is for a belief to be fallible, followed by an implication of that formulation. The initial formulation talked of a belief’s possible falsity even when supported by apparently good grounds. The implication noted that this would be a possible failure by the belief to be knowledge even in a setting of apparently being knowledge. That same implication could have been gained from this alternative possible initial formulation of fallibility’s nature: A belief is fallible when it might be false in spite of its actually good grounds. This is a stronger statement of fallibility’s nature because it talks of actually good grounds (not of apparently good ones). It tells us that, for any belief you have, even if your evidence supporting the belief is good, the belief need not be true. This is a fallibilist view of what even genuinely good justification or support gives a belief— namely, nothing that guarantees the belief’s being knowledge. Are we thereby closer still to having to accept knowledge-skepticism if we adopt this fallibilist view of justificatory support? Before conceding so, we should note another complexity involved in conceiving of fallibility. What does “it might be false” mean in our possible formulations of fallibility’s nature? This is a first suggestion: The belief in question is false in some possible situation. (If that situation is only possible, not actual, it is as much like this actual one as possible—for a start, by including the same grounds for the belief.) There is a problem with that suggestion. It never allows us to understand a belief as fallible when the belief’s content is necessarily true (e.g., when a mathematical or logical truth is believed). For no such belief is ever false in even a single possible

SKEPTICISM AND FALLIBILISM

611

situation.3 Yet we naturally say that a person could form or hold a fallible belief with such a content. (Fallibilism tells us to expect nothing more.) How can we understand her as doing this? Many epistemologists would respond to that challenge by proposing a shift of perspective in our conceiving of fallibility. In particular, should we talk of having the (necessarily true) belief fallibly, not of having the (necessarily true) fallible belief? This shift could encourage us to regard a belief’s fallibility as always included in the means—the method, the capacity, or more generally the circumstances—by which the belief has arisen and/or is being held. For short: The belief would arise and/or be held in a fallible way. We might allow that a belief-forming way could be fallible by allowing for the production of false beliefs, either actually or in alternative (non-actual) possible situations relevantly similar to the situation where the belief in question has been formed. We might regard a belief-holding way as fallible when it allows for the belief’s possible replacement by false beliefs, either actually or in alternative (nonactual) possible situations relevantly similar to the situation where the belief is being held. And even a way of thinking that has produced a necessarily true mathematical belief on a given occasion might—if fallible—have produced instead a different and mistaken mathematical belief.4 So, even when a necessarily true belief arises, there would be fallibility in how it has arisen.5 Are we thus able now to understand fallibilism’s saying that all our beliefs—including necessarily true ones—are attended by fallibility? This is what fallibilism needs to understand.

3  SKEPTICAL IMPLICATIONS? Yet once we understand the nature of the fallibility that is said by fallibilism to attend all of our beliefs, we must ask whether such rampant fallibility poses a skeptical challenge to our beliefs ever being knowledge. We have described fallibility as a respect in which knowledge might be absent when it appears to be present, even when good support for it is actually present. Does (1) imply (2)? (1) At any time, for any belief: knowledge might be absent due to fallibility’s being realized (i.e., due to the belief’s being false in spite of actually and/or apparently being well supported). (2) At any time, for any belief: knowledge is absent due to fallibility’s presence (regardless of whether fallibility is being realized). (1) is fallibilism, while (2) is knowledge-skepticism’s being said to be grounded in (1). The rest of this section presents a few arguments that could be thought to take us from fallibilism to knowledge-skepticism.

3a  Degrees or Grades of Fallibility Might fallibilism threaten knowledge by allowing degrees or grades of fallibility? We talk regularly of individual belief-forming capacities or methods as more fallible

612

SKEPTICISM

or less so. The more reliably a method produces true beliefs rather than false ones, the less fallible it is (all else being equal). For it would be more likely to generate a true belief on a particular occasion, even as it might have generated a false belief. But consider the possibility, on any given occasion, of a belief having been formed in a very fallible way rather than merely in a fallible way. This leads to skeptical reasoning, as follows. Even those who feel no anxiety at the idea of our beliefs being formed fallibly might be less sanguine at the thought of those beliefs arising very fallibly. Of course, in practice it would be rare to know how fallibly a given belief has arisen. But this admission, too, harbors skeptical potential. Once you admit to not knowing how fallibly you have formed a particular belief, you should concede the possibility of having formed it very fallibly—certainly of having formed it much more fallibly than you realized. But this amounts to allowing that the belief has arisen in a way that could very easily have given you a belief which is false while seeming true. And once you allow, not merely that your belief could have been formed so as to be false, but that this could very easily be what has happened, you should not continue regarding the belief as knowledge. This problem pertains to all of your beliefs, though. Consequently, you should view none of them as knowledge. That would be a knowledge-skeptical stance. Attempted replies to it will encounter responses of a form familiar from traditional skeptical arguments. If you assure yourself that on this occasion you have not formed a mistaken belief, you achieve nothing if you are relying on that same belief-forming method—with its unknown grade of fallibility. If you use a different belief-forming method to assess your use of the first one, you face the question of the new method’s grade of fallibility. If it might likewise be too fallible (for all that you know to the contrary), the same skeptical implication persists.

3b  Gettiered Beliefs One way for a true belief to arise fallibly, perhaps very fallibly, is for it to be Gettiered—the centerpiece of what epistemologists call a Gettier case.6 And most epistemologists deem any Gettiered belief not to be knowledge. Let us see how that view of Gettiered beliefs—this way for a belief to arise fallibly—might help us to argue for knowledge-skepticism. There is dispute as to what makes a situation a Gettier case.7 There are two general kinds of Gettier case:8 Helpful Gettier cases Someone forms a true belief on the basis of what would normally be good evidence of the belief’s being true. The belief is true. But it is made true by a further circumstance within the setting—a circumstance not noticed within the person’s evidence. (For instance, from outside some field it looks to you—and so you believe—that there is a sheep in the field. You are correct—not, though, because what you are seeing is a sheep. It is a disguised dog. A real sheep is hidden elsewhere in the field.)9

SKEPTICISM AND FALLIBILISM

613

Dangerous Gettier cases Someone forms a true belief on the basis of what would normally be good evidence of the belief’s being true. The belief is true. And (in contrast to what happens in Helpful Gettier cases) the belief is made true by a circumstance noticed within the person’s evidence. But there is a further circumstance within the setting, one which—if it had been noticed in that same way by the person’s evidence—would have made the same belief false while leaving intact the person’s sense of what evidence she is using. (For instance, from outside some field, it looks to you in a normal way that there is a barn in the field. You are correct. Your evidence, though, takes no account of the many only-apparently-real barns—fake barns— elsewhere along that road.)10 In neither sort of case (we are standardly told) is the belief knowledge. It is true. It is fallibly justified. But it is not knowledge. Why so? This question has spawned many epistemological theories of what a true belief also needs in order to be knowledge, if its being fallibly justified is not enough. Gettier acknowledged the fallibility present within his imagined cases (1963: 121). We may assume that the believer within each Gettier case could do likewise, if asked. Nonetheless, any Gettiered belief is produced far more fallibly within its Gettier case than the believer realizes. She is aware of her evidence. But standard interpretations of any given Gettier case also mention part of the case’s odd-yetunnoticed-by-the-believer circumstance. That combination of her evidence and this other part-circumstance amount to the actual pattern (even if not exactly what she would say is the pattern) by which she has gained her true belief. This will clearly— to us, reading the case—have been a very fallible way of gaining a belief with the content in question. Here is how the sheep-in-the-field case, for example, would standardly be interpreted along such lines: Your apparently good evidence of the sheep, plus your not really looking at a sheep, constitutes a very fallible way for you to have reached the belief that there is a sheep in the field.11 Is that why (according to the standard interpretation) such a belief is not knowledge? Epistemologists differ over this. But what is clear is the standard interpretation’s denying that any Gettiered belief is knowledge, while needing to insist that the belief is supported only fallibly. I have added that the belief’s support is perhaps very fallible. Each Gettier case is an odd situation. And no epistemologist would argue that you are in a Gettier situation for each true belief you have. Still, this skeptical challenge hovers nearby: How could you know that you are not in a Gettier case, for each of your beliefs? You never know this at the time. After all, even if a belief is true, it could be present as part of your being in a Gettier situation without realizing that you are; in which event, the belief would not be knowledge. You would not notice any difference between being in that setting and the belief’s arising in a normal way within a normal setting. The odd circumstance, in particular, would escape your notice.

614

SKEPTICISM

That argument embeds, within a familiar form of skeptical reasoning, the possibility of a belief’s being Gettiered. This form is one in which many epistemologists have embedded the dreaming possibility or the evil demon possibility, both memorably described by Descartes in his “Meditation I.”12 The form is simple: Here is a possibility, P, whose actualization would be incompatible with your belief B’s being knowledge: [P is then described—your belief’s being Gettiered, or your dreaming, etc.]. You do not know that P is not being actualized. (You lack this knowledge because any belief that P-is-not-being-actualized might itself be present as part of P’s being actualized.) But in that event B is not knowledge. (For instance, if you were dreaming seeing a barn, you would not know that you are seeing it; and any belief that you are not dreaming could itself be present as part of your dreaming.) Any odd circumstance within a Gettier case (the circumstance somehow precluding the Gettiered belief’s being knowledge) would be hidden similarly—like her dreaming or her being deceived by an evil demon—from the believer. So, if epistemologists are correct in saying that a (fallibly formed) belief’s being Gettiered precludes its being knowledge, the possibility of a (fallibly formed) belief’s being Gettiered can be used by skeptical reasoning much as the dreaming possibility and the evil demon possibility can be. No one need actually be in a Gettier situation, if that skeptical reasoning is to succeed; just as the dreaming argument does not require that anyone is dreaming at a given time. It is sufficient, for these skeptical purposes, if no one ever knows that she is not in a Gettier situation, or that she is not dreaming.13

3c Quantity-Fallibilism Section 3a alerted us to the idea of there being grades of fallibility. Section 3b’s Gettier cases are illustrative reminders that a belief can be very fallible. Those cases also instantiate a further fallibilist moral, we will now see, that might have knowledge-skeptical implications. The cases contain circumstances which are such that if the believer were to know of them, the situation would no longer be a Gettier case. No longer would the setting contain a justified true belief falling short of being knowledge: Re the sheep-in-the-field case If you were to know that what you are seeing is not really a sheep, then (other things being equal) you would cease believing that there is a sheep in the field or you would no longer be justified in having that belief. Re the fake-barns case If you were to know that there are fake barns nearby—visually indistinguishable for you from what you are seeing—then (all else being equal) you would either cease believing that you are seeing a barn or you would no longer be justified in having that belief. Section 3b asked whether one ever knows that one is not in a Gettier situation—such knowledge possibly being needed if one is to have other knowledge. We may now

SKEPTICISM AND FALLIBILISM

615

generalize that question. Does one ever know that one knows enough about one’s belief-context—enough for having some particular knowledge within that context? That is a question about the quantity of one’s attendant knowledge. That question can arise naturally if we accept fallibilism. Let us distinguish between qualityfallibilism and quantity-fallibilism. The former is what has been characterized so far in this chapter. It is the traditional sense of fallibilism. It concerns a modal quality or strength of any given belief. (e.g., it implies that even a belief which appears, by being based on good evidence, to be knowledge need not be true and therefore need not be knowledge.)14 But we may also describe a quantitative fallibility, possibly best understood as applying primarily to a person, only secondarily to her belief: A person is being fallible whenever, in spite of apparently having done enough to have a particular item of knowledge, she might not actually have done so (due to there being more she needs to know). Quantity-fallibilism says that people are always fallible in this way. Quantityfallibilism admits of degrees or grades: one could have done more or done less, even when one might not have done enough. And quantity-fallibilism may be used in the following way to derive knowledge-skepticism. This supposed link to lacking knowledge will be adduced: A person lacks a particular item of knowledge because she is being fallible, whenever, in spite of apparently having done enough to have that piece of knowledge, she might not actually have done so (due to there being more she needs to know). Then this challenge may be issued: How could a person ever know that she has done enough for her belief—which apparently is knowledge—actually to be knowledge? (She need not be troubled by this question. Still, she might be. And some will say that she should be.) For example, has she ascertained how her belief is being made true? (Hence, has she checked on whether she is in a Gettier case like the sheep-in-the-field one?) Does she know how much there is to know, and therefore how much more she might need to know, in knowing the particular truth? (Hence, has she checked on whether she is in a Gettier case like the fake-barns one?)15 So, imagine accepting, in a quantity-fallibilist spirit, that there is always more that could be known, even when seeking to know some particular truth. Here is an example I have used previously (Hetherington 2011a: ch. 5): In knowing the particular state of affairs that here is a hand, you know this aspect of the world in more or less detail.16 You could know more, or you could know less, of what is involved in the fine structural details of the state of affairs that here is a hand. Maybe you do not know all of what a hand surgeon would know in knowing that here is a hand. Maybe even the surgeon would not know all of the pertinent details within the world’s including this state of affairs that here is a hand. Perhaps in principle

616

SKEPTICISM

continued science could always reveal more such details. Yet perhaps even our best possible finished science would not report all such details. To accept that picture of perennial incompleteness in our knowledge of the world’s constitutive details opens the door to accepting that there could always be much of relevance that one does not know. Even in apparently knowing a seemingly simple state of affairs, one might not know much of what is involved in the world’s including that state of affairs. This could be so for any state of affairs. Maybe you never know even how much you do not know of what is involved in a state of affairs you claim to know. When should this potential limitation make you wonder whether you have the particular knowledge that would be supported by the further-but-maybe-unattainable knowledge? Do you really know that here is a hand, if you do not know much of what this hand even is? The skeptical conclusion possibly to be inferred is that you never have a particular piece of knowledge. You never know whether you have done enough to have the particular knowledge; so you lack that knowledge.

4  ONWARDS, EVER ONWARDS The term “fallibilism” comes from C.S. Peirce, a founder of American pragmatism (Peirce 1931–1958: vol. 1, para. 171). His fallibilist picture was this: No inquirer can ever claim with full assurance to have reached the truth, for new evidence or information may arise that will reverberate throughout one’s system of beliefs affecting even those most entrenched. (Hauser 1992: xxii) That picture combines quality-fallibilism—the lack of “full assurance”—with quantity-fallibilism—the ever-present possibility of “new evidence or information” arising with potentially dire effects upon the beliefs already present. Fallibilism pervades our cognitive efforts, thought Peirce17: fallibilism is the doctrine that our knowledge is never absolute but always swims . . . in a continuum of uncertainty and indeterminacy. (Hauser 1992: xxii) Was Peirce also a skeptic? No. He thought that we know, in fallible ways.18 Should all fallibilists be skeptics, though? As section 1 noted, the usual epistemological view of fallibilism is that, if we can formulate it coherently, we may evade knowledge-skepticism: we would understand knowledge’s not needing to attain a standard as impossibly demanding as an infallibilist one. The quest continues to find such a conception of fallible knowledge. In the meantime, this chapter has described a few ways in which fallibilism might be thought to lead us toward knowledge-skepticism, not away from it.19

NOTES 1. Or—if there is collective belief—any actual or possible group of people. For simplicity, this chapter will focus upon beliefs being possessed by an individual person. The chapter’s theses and arguments also apply, mutatis mutandis, to collective beliefs and believers.

SKEPTICISM AND FALLIBILISM

617

2. Since 1963, that thought has not been so epistemologically universal. Section 3b will say more about this. 3. This is equally so if we seek to understand “it might be false” in terms of probability, such as with “its truth is not probabilistically certain or guaranteed.” The probability of a necessarily true belief’s being true, given . . . well, whatever . . . is 1. The belief is certain, in that sense at any rate. It might be fallible, even so. 4. “What is the way of thinking used on a given occasion? Is this always manifest?” That question arises for all theories assessing a belief (its being justified or knowledge) even partly in terms of how it has been formed and/or is being held. If the question is not answerable accurately and informatively, those theories face the problem of generality. For its original formulation, see Feldman (1985). 5. McDowell (2011) advocates conceiving of fallibility only as a property of a beliefforming capacity: doing so rescues beliefs from skeptical doubts. A perceptual belief-forming capacity is fallible—he argues—if it can misfire, giving its user a false perceptual belief; whenever there is no misfiring, the resulting true belief is knowledge. Indeed, McDowell regards that true belief as conclusive knowledge. So, his strategy is beside our present aim of examining whether skeptical doubts afflict beliefs that are fallible. 6. For the original Gettier cases, see Gettier (1963). 7. For overviews of this issue, see Shope (1983) and Hetherington (2011c). 8. This categorization comes from Hetherington (1999). 9. This case’s initial version is from Chisholm (1966: 23 n. 22; 1977: 105; 1989: 93). 10. For this case, see Goldman (1976). 11. “Wait a moment. The situation’s odd circumstance also includes your belief’s being made true by the real sheep hidden in the field. Once we include this in our description of how your belief is formed, no longer can we describe as so fallible the means—the evidence plus the circumstance—by which your belief has arisen. For now the means is described as generating a true belief.” Yet epistemologists do not include this further part of the situation’s odd circumstance in their usual assessments (of knowledge as absent from the situation). Including within their assessment a description of this further part of the odd circumstance would undermine their usual claim that the belief is not knowledge. Accordingly, section 3b ignores this further aspect of the situation, presenting a skeptical argument derived from the standard interpretation of Gettier cases. For an argument against that standard interpretation, see Hetherington (2011a: ch. 3). 12. For contemporary formulations of the skeptical reasoning using the dreaming possibility, see Stroud (1984: ch. 1) and Hetherington (2011b). 13. See Hetherington (1996) for this skeptical argument. 14. This does not imply that any beliefs are false. It is potentially misleading to say, as Talisse and Aikin do, that “[f]allibilism is the view that any number of our beliefs are false, and that one should run one’s cognitive life in a way that one is able to find and revise those false beliefs” (2008: 48). This is misleading unless the number in question could be zero. 15. These questions need not be understood in terms of Gettier cases.

618

SKEPTICISM

16. I write here of knowing as knowing the world and a state of affairs, maybe not as knowing a true proposition. On that choice, see Sayre (1997). I assume that a state of affairs within the world can include within it further states of affairs—maybe only some of which one need know, in knowing the former state of affairs. 17. On how Peirce intended his fallibilism to encompass mathematical claims, see Cooke (2006: ch. 3). 18. One of Peirce’s marks of such fallibility is our need as individual inquirers to work with others’ views (1931–1958: vol. 5, para. 265): We individually cannot reasonably hope to attain the ultimate philosophy which we pursue; we can only seek it, therefore, for the community of philosophers. As Hookway (2012: 156) puts Peirce’s point: So long as we are careful in our reasoning, we can trust fallible methods of belief formation, probably in the hope that any errors will eventually surface and be corrected; but we can do this responsibly only as members of a community of inquirers. Yet unless we define truth so that it is bound to be what the community of scientific inquirers would eventually-and-then-lingeringly settle upon as true, this chapter’s skeptical thoughts are no less applicable here than to individual inquirers. And although Peirce characterized truth in that way, he apparently defined it in terms of correspondence (1931–1958: vol. 1, para. 578; vol. 2, para. 652; vol. 7, para. 659), albeit with a pragmatist twist (ibid.: vol. 5, paras. 553–4). On Peirce on fallibilism and truth, see Almeder (1980: ch. I) and Cooke (2006: ch. 6). 19. For more on the nature of fallibilism, see Hetherington (2005), Dougherty (2011), and Reed (2012).

REFERENCES Almeder, Robert. 1980. The Philosophy of Charles S. Peirce: A Critical Introduction. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Chisholm, Roderick M. 1966. Theory of Knowledge. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: PrenticeHall. Chisholm, Roderick M. 1977. Theory of Knowledge, 2nd edn. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Chisholm, Roderick M. 1989. Theory of Knowledge, 3rd edn. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Cooke, Elizabeth F. 2006. Peirce’s Pragmatic Theory of Inquiry: Fallibilism and Indeterminacy. London: Continuum. Dougherty, Trent. 2011. “Fallibilism.” In S. Bernecker and D. Pritchard (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, 131–143. New York: Routledge. Feldman, Richard. 1985. “Reliability and Justification,” The Monist 68: 159–174. Gettier, Edmund L. 1963. “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” Analysis 23: 121–123. Goldman, Alvin. I. 1976. “Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge,” The Journal of Philosophy 73: 771–791.

SKEPTICISM AND FALLIBILISM

619

Hauser, Nathan. 1992. “Introduction.” In N. Hauser and C. Kloesel (eds.), The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings, Vol. 1 (1867–1893), ix–xli. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. Hetherington, Stephen. 1996. “Gettieristic Scepticism,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 83–97. Hetherington, Stephen. 2005. “Fallibilism,” Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at http://www.iep.utm.edu/f/fallibil.htm. Hetherington, Stephen. 2011a. How to Know: A Practicalist Conception of Knowledge. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. Hetherington, Stephen. 2011b. “The Cartesian Dreaming Argument for External-World Skepticism.” In M. Bruce and S. Barbone (eds.), Just The Arguments: 100 of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy, 137–141. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. (Corrected version available at http://justthearguments.com/?page_id=49.) Hetherington, Stephen. 2011c. “The Gettier Problem.” In S. Bernecker and D. Pritchard (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, 119–130. New York: Routledge. Hookway, Christopher. 2012. “American Pragmatism: Fallibilism and Cognitive Progress.” In S. Hetherington (ed.), Epistemology: The Key Thinkers, 153–171. London: Continuum. McDowell, John. 2011. Perception as a Capacity for Knowledge. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1931–1958. Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vols. I–VI, (eds.) C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss, vols. VII–VIII, (ed.) A. W. Burks. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Reed, Baron. 2012. “Fallibilism,” Philosophy Compass 7/9: 585–596. Sayre, Kenneth M. 1997. Belief and Knowledge: Mapping the Cognitive Landscape. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. Shope, Robert K. 1983. The Analysis of Knowing: A Decade of Research. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Stroud, Barry. 1984. The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Talisse, Robert, and Scott Aikin. 2008. Pragmatism: A Guide for the Perplexed. London: Continuum.

CHAPTER FORTY-THREE

Skepticism and Contextualism1 MICHAEL BLOME-TILLMANN

1  WHAT IS EPISTEMIC CONTEXTUALISM? Let’s begin with an example.2 Imagine schoolteacher Jones in the zoo explaining to her class that the animals in the pen are zebras. Tom is unconvinced and challenges Jones: “Are you sure those aren’t antelopes?” After Jones has explained the difference between antelopes and zebras, Tom assures his classmates: (1) She knows that the animals in the pen are zebras. Has Tom spoken truly? Surely, Jones’s epistemic position seems good enough for satisfying the predicate ‘knows that the animals in the pen are zebras’ (henceforth ‘knows Z’): Jones has visual experiences of a black and white striped horse-like animal, she can discriminate reliably between zebras and antelopes, she has read the sign on the pen that reads “Zebra Pen,” etc. Thus, Tom’s utterance of (1) seems to be a paradigm case of a true ‘knowledge’ attribution. Next, imagine a couple, Bill and Kate, walking along. Bill, a would-be postmodernist artist, gives details of his latest ideas: he envisions himself painting mules with white stripes to look like zebras, putting them in the zebra pen of a zoo and thereby fooling visitors. Our couple randomly considers Jones, and Kate claims, at the same time as Tom is asserting (1): (2) She doesn’t know that the animals in the pen are zebras. In Kate’s mind, for Jones to “know Z,” she must have better evidence or reasons in support of Z than are momentarily available to her. In particular, Kate has it that Jones’s evidence must eliminate the possibility that the animals in the pen are painted mules. As long as her evidence, however, is neutral with respect to whether or not the animals are cleverly painted mules, Kate claims, Jones doesn’t qualify as ‘knowing Z’. What is going on in our little example? According to our intuitions, an utterance of (1) is true in the context of the school class, while an utterance of (2) is true in the context of the artistic couple. Moreover, (2) is the negation of (1): it doesn’t differ from (1) except for containing the verbal negation ‘doesn’t’. And since the personal

SKEPTICISM AND CONTEXTUALISM

621

pronoun ‘she’ refers in both contexts to Jones, it seems that the schoolteacher satisfies the predicate ‘knows Z’ in the context of the school class but not so in the context of the artists. How are we to account for these phenomena? First, note again that Tom and Kate are talking about one and the same person—Jones—at exactly the same time. Thus, we cannot resolve the situation by claiming, for instance, that Jones “knows Z” in one context but not the other because she believes Z in one context but not in the other. Similarly, we cannot plausibly respond that Jones has certain visual experiences in one context that she is lacking in the other, or that she has the ability to discriminate reliably between certain scenarios in one context but not the other, or, finally, that she has read the sign on the zebra pen in one context but not in the other. All factors pertaining to the subject are identical with respect to both contexts, as the speakers in both contexts—Tom and Kate—are talking about one and the same subject at one and the same time.3 Thus, what the above example suggests is that the mentioned factors—Jones’s visual experiences, her discriminatory abilities, etc.—are sufficient for her to satisfy ‘knows Z’ in one context, but not so in the other. And it is this view that epistemic contextualism (EC) takes at face value: how strong one’s epistemic position toward p must be for one to satisfy ‘know(s) p’ may vary with the context of utterance. In the artists’ conversational context, Jones needs to be in a stronger epistemic position— she needs more evidence in support of Z—than in the school class’s conversational context in order for her to satisfy ‘knows Z’. In fact, some contextualists describe the situation by claiming that contexts of utterance are governed by so-called epistemic standards.4 Given this terminology, the epistemic standards in our example are lower in the context of the school class than in the context of the artists’ conversation. In fact, in the former context, the standards are low enough for Jones to satisfy ‘knows Z’, while in the latter they are too high: Jones doesn’t, in the artists’ context, satisfy ‘knows Z’ but, rather, satisfies ‘doesn’t know Z’. Now, the notion of an epistemic standard can be explicated in a number of different ways. On the most popular way, which is inspired by relevant alternatives approaches to contextualism, epistemic standards are said to be higher in the school class’s context because, as David Lewis (1996) puts it, satisfying ‘knows Z’ in that context doesn’t require the elimination of the possibility that the animals are painted mules, while this is required in the context of the postmodernist artists: more alternatives must be eliminated in the context with the higher standards than in the context with the lower standards. Given the hypothesized context-sensitivity of the predicate ‘know(s) p’, it is in general possible that a subject satisfies the predicate in one conversational context but doesn’t do so in another, or, in other words, that somebody in a given context speaks truly when uttering a sentence of the form ‘x knows p’ while somebody in a different context speaks falsely when uttering the very same sentence—even though both speakers are speaking about the same subject x at the same time of utterance t. Epistemic contextualism is, as a consequence, a linguistic or a semantic view— namely, the view that ‘knowledge’-ascriptions—sentences of the form ‘x knows p’—may express different propositions in different contexts of utterance. According to EC, ‘knowledge’-ascriptions are, as Stanley (2005: 17) puts it, context-sensitive

622

SKEPTICISM

in a distinctively epistemological way: the content of a sentence S containing the predicate ‘know(s) p’ can change with context, independently of whether S contains further indexicals, is ambiguous, or is context-sensitive in any other way. In a first approximation, we can thus define ‘epistemic contextualism’ as follows: (ECʹ) Knowledge ascriptions may express different propositions relative to different contexts of utterance, where this difference is traceable to the occurrence of ‘know(s) p’ and concerns a distinctively epistemic factor. Given semantic compositionality—the view that the content or semantic value of complex expressions is a function of its ultimate constituents and the way in which they are combined—(ECʹ) entails (EC): (EC) The content of the predicate ‘know(s) p’ may vary with the context of utterance in a distinctly epistemic way. According to EC, the predicate ‘know(s) p’ adds context-sensitivity to a sentence it occurs in, and this context-sensitivity is distinctly epistemic—that is, it goes over and above the context-sensitivity that the verb contributes to the sentence by virtue of its tense.5 The exact details as to how to semantically model the context-sensitivity of ‘know(s) p’ shall not concern us in this chapter. However, it is worth noting that EC is not a lexical ambiguity theory—that is, it doesn’t claim that ‘know(s) p’ is assigned multiple conventional meanings in English, as are the lexically ambiguous expressions ‘bank’ or ‘orange’. On the contrary, contextualists have commonly compared ‘know(s) p’ to indexical expressions, such as ‘I’, ‘that’, and ‘today’ or to gradable adjectives such as ‘flat’ and ‘empty’: these expressions are widely taken to have only one conventional meaning—what Kaplan (1989) calls their “character”—but different contents or semantic values in suitably different contexts of utterance. While there are several distinct ways to semantically model the context-sensitivity of ‘know(s) p’, contextualists have often stressed an analogy between the semantics of ‘know(s) p’ and the semantics of gradable adjectives such as ‘flat’, ‘empty’, or ‘tall’: just as what counts as satisfying ‘flat’, ‘empty’, or ‘tall’ may vary with context, contextualists have argued, what counts as satisfying ‘know(s) p’ may vary with context, too.6 Given this analogy, EC can be construed as claiming that (1) and (2) in our above example stand in a relation similar to the relation between a basketball coach’s utterance of “MB-T isn’t tall” and a jockey coach’s utterance of “MB-T is tall”: while the surface syntax of these sentences suggests a contradiction, the propositions expressed are compatible, as the semantic value of ‘tall’ changes with the context of utterance. Ordinary usage of ‘tall’ and ‘know’ seem to be similar: both expressions seem to be context-sensitive.7

2  EVIDENCE FOR CONTEXTUALISM The main evidence for EC derives from our intuitions about the truth-values of ‘knowledge’-ascriptions in examples such as the above Zebra Case. However, there

SKEPTICISM AND CONTEXTUALISM

623

are further, more familiar examples that have been presented in support of EC in the literature. Consider, for instance, Stewart Cohen’s (1999: 58) Airport Case: Mary and John are at the L.A. airport contemplating taking a certain flight to New York. They want to know whether the flight has a layover in Chicago. They overhear someone ask a passenger, Smith, if he knows whether the flight stops in Chicago. Smith looks at the flight itinerary he got from the travel agent and responds, “Yes I know—it does stop in Chicago.” It turns out that Mary and John have a very important business contact they have to make at the Chicago airport. Mary says, “How reliable is that itinerary? It could contain a misprint. They could have changed the schedule at the last minute.” Mary and John agree that Smith doesn’t really know that the plane will stop in Chicago. They decide to check with the airline agent. As Cohen’s example suggests, the sentence “Smith knows that the flight stops over in Chicago” seems true as uttered in Smith’s context but false as uttered in Mary’s and John’s context. Moreover, it seems as though the practical interests and goals of the conversational participants or how high the stakes are with regard to the proposition that the flight will stop over in Chicago influence the respective contexts’ epistemic standards, and thus whether Smith satisfies ‘knows’: in Smith’s own context he satisfies ‘knows that the flight will stop over in Chicago’, but in Mary’s and John’s context, where the stakes are significantly higher, he doesn’t. Here is another example reinforcing this point—namely, Keith DeRose’s (1992) famous Bank Cases, as presented by Stanley (2005: 3–4): Low Stakes Hannah and her wife Sarah are driving home on a Friday afternoon. They plan to stop at the bank on the way home to deposit their paychecks. It is not important that they do so, as they have no impending bills. But as they drive past the bank, they notice that the lines inside are very long, as they often are on Friday afternoons. Realizing that it isn’t very important that their paychecks are deposited right away, Hannah says, “I know the bank will be open tomorrow, since I was there just two weeks ago on Saturday morning. So we can deposit our paychecks tomorrow morning.” High Stakes Hannah and her wife Sarah are driving home on a Friday afternoon. They plan to stop at the bank on the way home to deposit their paychecks. Since they have an impending bill coming due, and very little in their account, it is very important that they deposit their paychecks by Saturday. Hannah notes that she was at the bank two weeks before on a Saturday morning, and it was open. But, as Sarah points out, banks do change their hours. Hannah says, “I guess you’re right. I don’t know that the bank will be open tomorrow.” Similar to Cohen’s example, DeRose’s case suggests that it is more difficult to satisfy ‘knows’ in a context in which the stakes are higher: in Low Stakes Hannah satisfies ‘knows that the bank will be open tomorrow’, whereas in High Stakes she doesn’t, even though she is in exactly the same epistemic position in both cases. And, again,

624

SKEPTICISM

the defender of EC argues that the difference in our intuitions in the two bank cases is due to the fact that the relevant ‘knowledge’-ascriptions are made in different conversational contexts: in the context of High Stakes, the argument goes, it is considerably more difficult to satisfy ‘knows that the bank is open on Saturday’ than it is in the context of Low Stakes.8 The above examples and others like them have attracted a large amount of critical attention in recent years. Note, for instance, that the argument in support of EC emerging from the above data amounts to an inference to the best explanation: in evaluating the support EC receives from the examples, we must therefore compare EC’s account of the data with competing explanations of rival theories. Such comparisons of explanatory virtue in philosophy, however, are usually rather difficult and complicated. A further challenge to EC’s account of the above data pertains to the data’s evidential status: some practitioners of so-called experimental philosophy have, in recent studies, aimed to undermine the contextualists’ case by arguing that the professional philosopher’s intuitions about the above cases do not coincide with the intuitions of the more general public. Now, while the above issues present interesting and legitimate challenges to EC, we shall, in this chapter, leave them to one side and focus our attention on a topic that is commonly taken to provide an important philosophical motivation for EC: skeptical puzzles.9

3  CARTESIAN SKEPTICAL PUZZLES We have seen so far that EC receives some prima facie support from certain linguistic data—namely, the examples discussed in the previous sections. Traditionally, however, contextualists have also claimed that besides the above empirical evidence in favor of their views there is also an independent, philosophical motivation for EC. More specifically, contextualists have argued that the context-sensitivity of ‘know(s) p’ suggested by the above examples provides us with an attractive resolution of skeptical puzzles. Now, even though the issue of skepticism has somewhat moved into the background in recent discussions of EC, it is certainly worthwhile considering the traditional contextualist treatment of skepticism in some detail.10 To begin our discussion of the contextualist response to skepticism, consider the following argument: Skeptical Argument (i) If I know that I have hands, then I’m in a position to know that I’m not a handless brain in a vat. (ii) I’m not in a position to know that I’m not a handless brain in a vat. (iii) I don’t know that I have hands.11 The above argument is valid: if we accept its premises, we must accept its conclusion, too. Moreover, the above Skeptical Argument leaves us with a philosophical puzzle: its premises are highly plausible while its conclusion is highly implausible. One way to bring this out in more detail is to consider the negation of its conclusion: (iv) I know that I have hands.

SKEPTICISM AND CONTEXTUALISM

625

The propositions (i), (ii), and (iv) form an inconsistent set; and so at least one of them has to be rejected. However, merely rejecting one of the members of our set doesn’t amount to a satisfactory resolution of our puzzle. As Stewart Cohen (1988: 94) has pointed out, an intellectually satisfying resolution of the skeptical puzzle doesn’t merely block the argument by identifying the culprit. Rather, a satisfactory resolution of the skeptical puzzle must, in addition, offer us an explanation of why the false member of the set appeared so plausible at first glance (see also Cohen 1999: 63). Why is it that our intuitions about the truth-values of at least one of the propositions at issue are misguided? And what exactly is the mistake we have made when we find ourselves puzzled by the Skeptical Argument?

4  THE CONTEXTUALIST SOLUTION TO SKEPTICAL PUZZLES The traditional contextualist’s response to the skeptical puzzle is to claim that the Skeptical Argument is unsound in conversational contexts that are governed by our moderate everyday epistemic standards but sound in contexts with artificially high, skeptical epistemic standards.12 In everyday contexts, the argument goes, I satisfy ‘knows that he isn’t a handless brain in a vat’ and premise (ii) of the Skeptical Argument expresses a falsehood: if I satisfy, in ordinary contexts, ‘knows that he isn’t a handless brain in a vat’, then I also satisfy, in ordinary contexts, ‘is in a position to know that he’s not a handless brain in a vat’. Consequently, the Skeptical Argument is unsound in ordinary contexts, and its conclusion doesn’t follow: relative to ordinary contexts, I satisfy ‘knows that he has hands’ and the conclusion of the Skeptical Argument expresses a falsehood. However, as indicated already, things are different in so-called skeptical contexts in which we practice epistemology and consider and discuss skeptical scenarios such as the brain-in-a-vat scenario. In such contexts, the argument goes, the epistemic standards are considerably higher—in fact, outrageously high—to the effect that premise (ii) expresses a truth in such contexts. For instance, contextualists have argued that because skeptical possibilities are epistemically relevant in skeptical contexts, premise (ii) of the Skeptical Argument expresses a truth: skeptical possibilities are, after all, uneliminated by our evidence, and we therefore do not, in skeptical contexts in which they are relevant, satisfy the predicate ‘is in a position to know that s/he is not a handless brain in a vat’. Consequently, when the skeptic asserts, in her skeptical context, “MB-T doesn’t know that he has hands,” she asserts a truth. However, it is crucial to emphasize that the truth of the skeptic’s assertion does not affect the truthvalues of my positive ‘knowledge’-ascriptions in ordinary contexts. To illustrate this view further, it is worth noting that traditional contextualists aim to resolve the tensions between our anti-skeptical intuitions on the one hand and the intuition that skeptical arguments are sound (and their conclusions, therefore, true) on the other. We can represent these intuitions as follows: Anti-Skeptical Intuition (ASI) People often speak truly when they assert ‘I know p.’

626

SKEPTICISM

Skeptical Intuition (SI) People sometimes speak truly when they assert ‘Nobody knows p’ in contexts in which skeptical arguments are discussed. The traditional contextualist claims that both of these intuitions are correct and only seemingly contradictory: they are correct because the semantic value of ‘know(s) p’ varies with the context of utterance; so when we claim in everyday contexts that we ‘know p’, our utterances are not in contradiction to our utterance of ‘Nobody knows p’ in skeptical contexts. Thus, it is crucial to note that, according to the traditional contextualist, it is not (iv) which is shown to be true or (iii) which is shown to be false. Rather, the traditional contextualist emphasizes that our skeptical and anti-skeptical intuitions are exclusively intuitions about the truthvalues of utterance tokens, which are by their very nature situated in particular conversational contexts. Our intuitions are not about the truth-values of sentences as considered more or less in the abstract in a philosophical essay or discussion. Once we appreciate this point and take into account the context-sensitivity of ‘knowledge’-attributions, the skeptical puzzle is—the traditional contextualist argues—easily dissolved: the argument is sound in contexts with exceedingly high or skeptical epistemic standards, but unsound in contexts with ordinary or everyday epistemic standards.

5  ERROR THEORY AND CONTEXTUAL SHIFTS An important question arises at this point: if the semantic value of ‘know’ can in fact change in a way allowing for both (ASI) and (SI) to be true, why, then, are we initially puzzled by skeptical arguments? Shouldn’t we be somehow sensitive to or aware of the context-sensitivity of ‘know(s) p’ and avoid making the mistake the contextualist ascribes to us? If EC is true, why, in other words, are skeptical arguments puzzling in the first place? To account for the puzzling nature of skeptical arguments, the contextualist is committed to the view that we sometimes lose sight of the context-sensitivity of epistemic terms, and in particular that we do so when confronted with skeptical arguments.13 Therefore, according to the traditional contextualist, we do not recognize that the skeptical conclusion is true in the context of discussions of skeptical arguments while false in everyday contexts. Thus, the traditional contextualist argues that, when we are puzzled by skeptical arguments, we fail to realize that the propositions expressed by the arguments’ conclusions are perfectly compatible with the propositions expressed by our everyday ‘knowledge’-claims. Contextualists accordingly pair their semantics of ‘know(s) p’ with the view that we are sometimes unaware of or tend to overlook the context-sensitivity of ‘know(s) p’. Stephen Schiffer, in an important paper criticizing this view, aptly calls this element of standard contextualism its error theory (see Schiffer 1996). Ultimately, it is, of course, entirely due to this error theory that EC can claim to be able to account for both the plausibility of skeptical arguments and our intuition that our everyday ‘knowledge’-ascriptions express truths.

SKEPTICISM AND CONTEXTUALISM

627

We shall return to the plausibility of EC’s error theory later on in this chapter (in Section 7). In the meantime, however, note that the contextualist’s resolution of skeptical puzzles makes crucial use of the intuitive notion of a shift in or variation of epistemic standards between contexts. It is important to note at this point, however, that arguing for the context-sensitivity of ‘know(s) p’ on the basis of the claim that the Bank Case, the Airport Case, and our Zebra Case involve contextual variation of epistemic standards is one thing, while claiming that epistemic standards are “shifty” in precisely the way required for a resolution of skeptical puzzles is quite a different proposition. In fact, for the contextualist’s resolution of skeptical puzzles to be credible, we need to be told more about what exactly the mechanisms underlying contextual shifts and variations are. In other words, we need to be told more about what epistemic standards are and how they are determined by context: why is it that epistemic standards are high in so-called skeptical contexts, and why are they lower in everyday situations? Different contextualists have different stories to tell about what epistemic standards are and about how they shift and vary. But it is fair to say that the original approaches defended by early contextualists (such as DeRose (1995) and Lewis (1996)) are highly problematic and must be refined and amended substantially before we can grant the contextualist that her view offers a resolution of skeptical puzzles. However, a detailed discussion of the more recent literature on epistemic standards is beyond the scope of this chapter.14

6 CLOSURE Another important aspect of the contextualist resolution of skeptical puzzles to be mentioned here is that the contextualist resolves skeptical puzzles while fully respecting our intuition that one can extend one’s knowledge by competent deduction. To see what I have in mind here, consider the following principle, which is familiar under the label Single-Premise Closure: (CL) If x knows p and x knows that p entails q, then x is in a position to know q. Here is an instance of (CL) for illustration: if, first, I know that the animal outside my window is a fox and if, secondly, I know that its being a fox entails that it’s not a cat, then I am also in a position to know that the animal outside my window is not a cat. Of course, I am in a position to know that latter proposition because I can competently deduce it from (i) my knowledge that the animal is a fox and (ii) my knowledge that its being a fox entails that it is not a cat. Single-premise closure captures fairly precisely the intuition that one can extend one’s knowledge by means of deductive reasoning. Now, while some epistemologists have argued that giving a response to the skeptic requires us to give up (CL), the contextualist resolution gets by without any such move.15 How does the contextualist avoid rejecting closure? Note that, according to EC, every semantic value that the verb ‘knows’ can express in a given context is, loosely speaking, closed under “known” entailment. Here is a more

628

SKEPTICISM

precise and contextualized formulation of the single-premise principle to illustrate the idea: (CLC) If x satisfies ‘knows p’ in context C and satisfies ‘knows that p entails q’ in C, then x is in a position to satisfy ‘knows q’ in C. (CLC) is a meta-linguistic principle. Loosely speaking, (CLC) says that (CL), its non-contextualized cousin, expresses a truth as long as the conversational context is kept fixed.16 Thus, unlike Nozick (1981) and Dretske (1970), who reject (CL) in giving a response to the skeptic, the contextualist, by ascending semantically, merely modifies and clarifies (CL) in a way that respects our intuitions about the validity of the closure principle. Contextualists have traditionally taken this to be a great comparative advantage of their theories over epistemological theories that advocate closure failure.

7  CRITICISMS OF CONTEXTUALISM Epistemic contextualism has been criticized for a number of reasons. In this chapter, we shall focus on two criticisms of EC that have figured most prominently in the recent literature. First, Ernest Sosa has wondered what the epistemological relevance of contextualism is, given that EC is a linguistic view—that is, a view about the predicate ‘know(s) p’ and its content rather than about knowledge. Considering the contextualist’s resolution of skeptical puzzles sketched above, this worry may appear somewhat surprising. However, Sosa thinks that EC, even though true, has only little epistemological relevance, if any at all: The main thesis of [EC] has considerable plausibility as a thesis in linguistics or in philosophy of language. In applying it to epistemology, however, it is possible to overreach. (Sosa 2011: 98) What, then, is Sosa’s objection? To see what Sosa has in mind, let us introduce some technical language. Let ‘KE’ express the content of ‘know’ in everyday contexts and let ‘KS’ express the content of ‘know’ in skeptical contexts. Now consider (3), which we derive from (ASI) by disquotation: (3) People often speak truly when they assert that they know p. Depending on whether the epistemic standards of our present context are those of everyday contexts or those of skeptical contexts (3) expresses the content of either (4) or (5): (4) People often speak truly when they assert that they KE p. (5) People often speak truly when they assert that they KS p. Since Sosa assumes that contexts of epistemological enquiry are inevitably skeptical contexts, Sosa thinks that (3), in the context of this chapter, expresses the proposition expressed by (5). Now, the alleged problem for EC is that (5) is clearly false, for it suggests that people in quotidian contexts assert that they KS p. However, when people in quotidian contexts use the word ‘know’, its semantic value is always KE

SKEPTICISM AND CONTEXTUALISM

629

rather than KS. Thus, Sosa complains that contextualists convey a falsehood, when they assert (3) in a context of epistemological discussion. How serious an objection is this to EC? The obvious reply to Sosa’s objection is, of course, that the contextualist ought to distinguish more carefully between the mention and the use of ‘know’ and thus only assert (ASI) instead of the disquoted (3): Sosa’s objection rests on a conflation of the use/mention-distinction.17 Moreover, it is worthwhile noting that more recent contextualists have developed accounts according to which contexts of philosophical and epistemological enquiry are by no means automatically skeptical contexts.18 On these more moderate views (3), in the context of this chapter, expresses the content of (4) rather than that of (5), and I therefore speak truly when, in the context of this chapter and the epistemology classroom more generally, asserting (3). As a consequence, there are several ways the contextualist can respond to Sosa’s charge that EC is epistemologically irrelevant. Another recently influential type of objection to EC proceeds by highlighting disparities between certain linguistic properties of ‘know(s) p’ on the one hand and more recognized context-sensitive expressions on the other. Remember that, for instance, contextualists compare ‘know(s) p’ to gradable adjectives, such as ‘flat’, ‘empty’, and ‘tall’. However, as Jason Stanley (2005, ch. 2) has pointed out, “know(s) p” has very different syntactic properties from gradable adjectives: as Stanley shows in great detail, ‘know(s) p’ is not syntactically gradable and doesn’t accept a large number of constructions that gradable adjectives can be felicitously combined with. Similarly, it has been pointed out that our semantic blindness toward the contextsensitivity of ‘know(s) p’—discussed above under the label of EC’s error theory— is not observed in connection with recognized indexicals such as ‘I’, ‘here’, and ‘today’. This fact is illustrated by the following principle: (6) If an English speaker E sincerely utters a sentence S of the form ‘A knows that p’, and the sentence in the that-clause means that p and ‘A’ is a name or indexical that refers to a, then E believes of a that a knows that p, and expresses that belief by S. As John Hawthorne (2004: 101) points out, (6) seems entirely natural. But, of course, (6) is false if ‘know(s) p’ is context-sensitive: since E’s context might be governed by epistemic standards that are different from those operative in this chapter, the disquotation of ‘knows’ in (6) is illegitimate. Since the possibility of an asymmetry between E’s and our own epistemic standards is largely hidden from competent speakers, the contextualist must accept that the context-sensitivity of ‘knows’ is non-obvious: it is not as readily detected by competent speakers as the context-sensitivity of core indexicals. Interestingly, however, similar phenomena are not observed with respect to ‘I’. Consider (7), a disquotation principle for ‘I’: (7) If an English speaker E sincerely utters a sentence S of the form ‘I am hungry’, then E believes that I am hungry, and expresses that belief by S. Clearly, it is not the case that every English speaker who utters “I am hungry” believes that I, MB-T, am hungry.

630

SKEPTICISM

What is worth emphasizing in response to Hawthorne’s worry, however, is that the gradable adjectives ‘flat’ and ‘empty’ display somewhat similar behavior with respect to disquotation. Consider the following disquotation principles for ‘flat’ and ‘empty’: (8) If an English speaker E sincerely utters a sentence S of the form ‘A is flat’, and ‘A’ is a name or indexical that refers to a, then E believes of a that a is flat, and expresses that belief by S. (9) If an English speaker E sincerely utters a sentence S of the form ‘A is empty’, and ‘A’ is a name or indexical that refers to a, then E believes of a that a is empty, and expresses that belief by S. As the intuitive plausibility of (8) and (9) demonstrates, the context-sensitivity of ‘flat’ and ‘empty’ is just as non-obvious or hidden from competent speakers as the context-sensitivity of ‘knows’. Thus, on the assumption that gradable adjectives are in fact context-sensitive, the context-sensitivity of ‘know(s) p’ has been shown to be no more puzzling or mysterious than the comparatively humdrum contextsensitivity of ‘flat’ and ‘empty’. It is due to data such as these that there is a growing consensus in the literature that the semantic blindness objection is not all that damaging to contextualism. Finally, it is worth emphasizing that, even if ‘know(s) p’ varies in certain linguistic respects—whether semantic, syntactic, or pragmatic—from other recognized context-sensitive expressions, it is not clear whether the contextualist should be worried about such a discovery. For why shouldn’t we accept that ‘know(s) p’ is linguistically exceptional? Let’s not forget, after all, that ‘know(s) p’ combines a number of fairly interesting and unique properties: ‘know(s) p’ is a factive verb that accepts a sentential complement, and its satisfaction at a context is, arguably, the norm of assertion, practical reasoning, and belief at that context.19 Moreover, ‘know(s) p’ gives rise to skeptical puzzles, which surely makes the predicate rather unique. This combination of properties is no doubt unique, and we should therefore not expect ‘know(s) p’ to function in each and every linguistic respect exactly like other context-sensitive expressions. Thus, if EC should in fact commit us to the uniqueness of ‘know’, then this shouldn’t worry us too much, as long as a coherent, illuminating, and systematic account of this uniqueness can be given.

8 CONCLUSION In summary, epistemic contextualism not only offers an interesting approach to skeptical puzzles but also is motivated by a large set of empirical data. To be sure, the philosophical jury is still out on epistemic contextualism: the view is, after all, still rather contentious and hotly debated in the literature. However, it is undeniable that EC is nowadays rather popular, not only among epistemologists but also among philosophers more generally.20 And as we begin to achieve an increasingly better understanding of natural language semantics in general and linguistic contextsensitivity in particular, contextualists may hope that EC will someday become one

SKEPTICISM AND CONTEXTUALISM

631

of the progressively more standard views in philosophy. At least to the author’s mind, the prospects are rather bright that EC will one day be considered as making a lasting and important contribution to our understanding of skepticism and skeptical puzzles.

NOTES 1. This work was supported by Marie Curie Actions (PIIF-GA-2012-328969 “Epistemic Vocabulary”). 2. The following example is derived from the Zebra Case in Dretske (1970). 3. Similarly, it follows that we cannot plausibly explain the phenomena by pointing out that Jones is in a different practical situation with respect to the two contexts: she isn’t. This fact about the above example provides problems for so-called SubjectSensitive Invariantist accounts of knowledge. See, for instance, Fantl and McGrath (2002); Hawthorne (2004); Stanley (2005). 4. Cf. Cohen (1988); DeRose (1995); Lewis (1996). 5. Cf. Schaffer and Szabó (2014) for the above definition of EC. 6. For this analogy see Unger (1975); DeRose (1995); Lewis (1996); Cohen (1999, 2004). 7. Not all contextualists endorse the analogy to gradable adjectives (see, for instance, Schaffer et al. [forthcoming]), but it is at this point helpful in illustrating the general concept of context-sensitivity underlying the view. 8. Note that since the relevant ‘knowledge’-ascriptions in DeRose’s bank cases as presented above are made from the first-person perspective—they are so-called self-ascriptions—the data from DeRose’s example are not suited to support EC over certain rival accounts such as Subject-Sensitive Invariantism (SSI): according to SSI, whether one knows p depends in part on one’s own and thus the subject’s (as opposed to the ascriber’s) epistemic standards (see Hawthorne (2004); Stanley (2005); Fantl and McGrath (2009) for versions of this view). A straightforward subject-sensitive invariantist explanation, however, is not available for Cohen’s Airport Case and the Zebra Case in Section 1 of this chapter. 9. See DeRose (2011) for a critical discussion of some experimental philosophy papers in the area. 10. Ludlow (2005), for instance, defends EC purely on the basis of the linguistic data, leaving aside the issue of skepticism entirely. 11. Here is a formalized version of the argument, where ‘sh’ is shorthand for ‘skeptical hypothesis’ and where ‘op’ ranges over ordinary propositions about the external world:

(i) Kp → ◊K¬sh. -



(ii) ¬◊K¬sh. - A



(iii) ¬Kp.

i, ii

A MT

12. The following is a description of standard contextualist views on skeptical puzzles, as it can be found—more or less explicitly—in all major writings of contextualists. See, for instance, DeRose (1995) and Cohen (1999).

632

SKEPTICISM

13. Cf. Cohen (1988: 106); DeRose (1995: 40). 14. Lewis’s (1996) “Rule of Attention” and DeRose’s (1995) “Rule of Sensitivity” offer accounts of contextual shifts that, on the face of it, are useful for the resolution of skeptical puzzles, but that turn out to be problematic for independent reasons. For criticism of DeRose’s approach, see Blome-Tillmann (2009a), and, for a refinement of Lewis’s relevant alternatives approach to contextualism that avoids a number of problems, see Blome-Tillmann (2009b). 15. Note also that the skeptic uses (CL) when motivating premise (i) of her argument: she reasons from the assumption that I know that my having a hand entails that I am not a handless brain in a vat to the conclusion that if I know that I have a hand, then I am in a position to know that I am not a handless brain in a vat, i.e., to premise (i) of the Skeptical Argument. The precise reasoning is as follows: Closure Argument for (i)

(1) (Kp^K(p → ¬sh)) → ◊K¬sh. from CL

(2) K(p → ¬sh) → (Kp → ◊K¬sh). 1

Exp

(3) K(p → ¬sh).

- A

(i) Kp → ◊K¬sh.

2, 3



MP

Note that there are other ways to motivate (i), but I shall ignore them in this chapter (see, for instance, Brueckner (1994)).

16. See DeRose (1995); Lewis (1996); Cohen (1999). 17. See Blome-Tillmann (2007) for more details on this line of reasoning. 18. See Blome-Tillmann (2009b) and Ichikawa (2011a, b). 19. See Blome-Tillmann (2013) for a discussion of the knowledge norms in a contextualist account. 20. See Chalmers et al. (2014), whose data suggest that EC is the most widely accepted view in the semantics of ‘knowledge’-attributions.

REFERENCES Blome-Tillmann, Michael. 2007. “Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series 107 (1/3): 387–394. Blome-Tillmann, Michael. 2009a. “Contextualism, Safety, and Epistemic Relevance,” Philosophical Studies 143: 383–394. Blome-Tillmann, Michael. 2009b. “Knowledge and Presuppositions,” Mind 118 (470): 241–294. Blome-Tillmann, Michael. 2013. “Contextualism and the Knowledge Norms,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94: 89–100. Brueckner, Anthony. 1994. “The Structure of the Skeptical Argument,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54: 827–835. Chalmers, David J., and David Bourget. 2014. “What Do Philosophers Believe?” Philosophical Studies 70: 465–500. Cohen, Stewart. 1988. “How to Be a Fallibilist,” Philosophical Perspectives 2: 91–123.

SKEPTICISM AND CONTEXTUALISM

633

Cohen, Stewart. 1999. “Contextualism, Skepticism, and the Structure of Reasons,” Philosophical Perspectives 13: 57–89. Cohen, Stewart. 2004. “Contextualism and Unhappy-Face Solutions: Reply to Schiffer,” Philosophical Studies 119: 185–197. DeRose, Keith. 1992. “Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52: 913–929. DeRose, Keith. 1995. “Solving the Skeptical Problem,” Philosophical Review 104: 1–52. DeRose, Keith. 2011. “Contextualism, Contrastivism, and X-Phi Surveys,” Philosophical Studies 156: 81–110. Dretske, Fred. 1970. “Epistemic Operators,” Journal of Philosophy 67: 1007–1023. Fantl, Jeremy, and Matthew McGrath. 2002. “Evidence, Pragmatics and Justification,” Philosophical Review 111: 67–94. Fantl, Jeremy and Matthew McGrath. 2009. Knowledge in an Uncertain World. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hawthorne, John. 2004. Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ichikawa, Jonathan. 2011a. “Quantifiers and Epistemic Contextualism,” Philosophical Studies 155: 383–398. Ichikawa, Jonathan. 2011b. “Quantifiers, Knowledge, and Counterfactuals,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82: 287–313. Kaplan, David. 1989. “Demonstratives.” In J. Almog, J. Perry, and H. Wettstein (eds.), Themes from Kaplan, 481–563. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. Lewis, David. 1996. “Elusive Knowledge,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 549–567. Ludlow, Peter. 2005. “Contextualism and the New Linguistic Turn in Epistemology.” In G. Preyer and G. Peter (eds.), Contextualism in Philosophy: Knowledge, Meaning and Truth, 11–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schaffer, Jonathan and Zoltan G. Szabó. 2014. “Epistemic Comparativism: A Contextualist Semantics for Knowledge Ascriptions,” Philosophical Studies 168: 491–543. Schiffer, Stephen. 1996. “Contextualist Solutions to Scepticism,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96: 317–333. Sosa, Ernest. 2011. Kowing Full Well. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Stanley, Jason. 2005. Knowledge and Practical Interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Unger, Peter. 1975. Ignorance: A Case for Scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon.

CHAPTER FORTY-FOUR

External World Skepticism RAM NETA

1 INTRODUCTION Skepticism has a long history in philosophy. But skeptical concern with “the external world” is a more recent phenomenon. The phenomenon is sometimes thought to have originated in the early modern period, perhaps with Descartes (1993) or Locke (1975). But it is not clear that this is true: to know whether Descartes’s argument for the existence of what he called “extended substance,” or whether Locke’s claim to have sensitive knowledge of what he called “material substance,” constitute attempts to address skepticism about “the external world,” we would have to understand not only what Descartes and Locke meant by those phrases, but also what we mean by the phrase “the external world.” I begin with a discussion of that issue.

2  WHAT IS THE “EXTERNAL WORLD”? One way to approach the task of trying to understand what it is that early-twentyfirst-century philosophers who’ve been trained in the Anglophone tradition might have in mind when we speak of the “external world” is to look at the texts that have most directly influenced our thinking. We can look, for instance, at some of Bertrand Russell’s writings on what he called “matter.” Russell (1912) asks what, if anything, we can know about a particular table that we perceive. After noting the various ways in which our perception of the table varies independently of any variation in the table itself, he writes: Let us give the name of “sense-data” to the things that are immediately known in sensation: such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so on. . . . It is plain that if we are to know anything about the table, it must be by means of the sense-data—brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness, etc.— which we associate with the table; but, for the reasons which have been given, we cannot say that the table is the sense-data, or even that the sense-data are directly properties of the table. Thus a problem arises as to the relation of the sense-data to the real table, supposing there is such a thing.

EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

635

The real table, if it exists, we will call a “physical object.” Thus we have to consider the relation of sense-data to physical objects. The collection of all physical objects is called “matter.” (Russell 1912: 4–5) In this passage, Russell introduces the term “physical object” by means of a single example (the table), and his only hint as to what it is about that example that makes it an example of the category at issue is that our perceptions of it can vary independently of variation in it, and so cannot be identical to it. But it’s not clear that this fixes what category Russell has in mind: there are plenty of things that we typically perceive when we look at (say) a table, and many of those perceived things are not identical with our perceptions of them. For instance, when I look at a table, I typically perceive a situation of one kind or another (e.g., people sitting at a table having dinner) and I typically perceive a complex scene (e.g., a dining room in a state of disarray) and these things are not identical to my perception of them. Further constraints on the category of “physical object” are imposed elsewhere in Russell’s writings from the same period. For instance, Russell (1957) treats “physical objects” as logical constructions out of actual and possible sense-data. This has some utility: the logical construction itself imposes structural constraints on what can count as a physical object; for instance, it is a consequence of how Russell’s construction works that no physical object can be completely contained in two entirely distinct regions of physical space at the same time. But the “sense-data” that serve as the materials for the construction are themselves explained only as those things that are given in sense at one time and that might be singled out by attention. Unfortunately, this account of “sense-data” leaves open precisely how that category is understood: why not say, for instance, that a particular table is given in sense at one time, and might be singled out by attention? In other words, why exclude tables from the category of “sense-data”? Nothing that Russell says in his characterization of “sense-data” answers this question. An alternative conception of the “external world” is provided by G. E. Moore, in his celebrated “Proof of an External World” (1959b). Moore devotes most of that paper to characterizing the category of external things, or “things to be met with in space.” This phrase, Moore writes, is to be understood in such a way that many “things,” e.g., after-images, double images, bodily pains, which might be said to be “presented in space,” are nevertheless not to be reckoned as “things that are to be met with in space,” and . . . there is no contradiction in supposing that there have been and are “to be met with in space” things which never have been, are not now, and never will be perceived, nor in supposing that among those of them which have at some time been perceived many existed at times at which they were not being perceived. (1959b: 156) For Moore, the category of “external things” is the category of space-occupying things that may fail ever to be perceived. This is as close as Moore gets to characterizing external things, and it is also as close as anyone in the contemporary discussion of skepticism about the external world has got to characterizing them. Thankfully, his characterization, rough as it is, will prove useful to us in understanding what gives

636

SKEPTICISM

rise to skeptical doubts concerning our epistemic relation to the external world specifically.

3  THE VARIETIES OF SKEPTICISM Before canvassing the considerations that have raised skeptical doubts concerning our epistemic relation to the external world, I should first distinguish the various forms that such skepticism has taken. Skepticisms can differ in their attitude, their depth, and their scope. A skeptic’s attitude may be one of doubt, one of denial, one of suspension, or one of withholding. In other words, a skeptic may harbor doubts concerning whether we possess a positive epistemic relation to external things, or she may outright deny that we possess any such positive epistemic relation, or she may suspend belief concerning whether we possess any such relation, or she may altogether withhold any attitude concerning whether we possess any such relation: one dimension along which forms of skepticism differ, then, is in attitude. Another way in which different forms of skepticism differ from each other is in their depth, that is, the range of epistemic positions concerning which they are skeptical. Our common convictions are that we know that we live on the Earth, we justifiably believe that we live on the Earth, we have justification for believing that we live on the Earth, it is rational for us to believe that we live on the Earth, and we have evidence that we live on the Earth. A relatively superficial skepticism may call into question the first of these common convictions, without calling into question any of the others. A much deeper form of skepticism will call into question all five of these common convictions. Finally, skepticisms differ from each other in the range of facts our epistemic relation to which they call into question. Thus, there is skepticism about the external world, skepticism about the future, skepticism about the past, skepticism about other minds, skepticism about value, and so on. Of course, there are also forms of skepticism that are completely general with respect to range, that is, they call into question our epistemic relation to all facts of any kind. Such completely general forms of skepticism include the forms that have been defended by appeal to Agrippa’s Trilemma (see Sextus Empiricus (1996) or Williams (2001)), those that have been defended by appeal to the Problem of the Criterion (see Chisholm (1982)) and that which was defended by Unger (1975). In the next section, I survey the various arguments that have been offered for one or another version of skepticism concerning the external world.

4  THE CONSIDERATIONS THAT GENERATE THE PROBLEM OF THE EXTERNAL WORLD The skeptical problem of the external world has been developed in four ways, though it is a matter of some controversy what relation these four skeptical arguments bear to each other (Brueckner (1994) argues, for example, that the argument from

EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

637

underdetermination and the argument from closure are not distinct). What all four of them have in common is that they depend on the thought that perceptual experience can vary independently of the external world: there is, in short, a gap between appearance and reality. But this crude idea gets developed in different ways in each of the following four lines of thought.

4a  The Argument from Fallibility Our beliefs about the external world are formed in ways that are fallible: beliefs formed in those ways (i.e., through a series of events that involve the stimulation of one’s sensory surfaces, the resulting transmission of a chemical signal through one’s neural pathways, and consequent belief fixation) are liable to be false, since the parts of the external world that initiate that series of events can be utterly different from how they are represented as being by the beliefs that lie at the end of that series. But if a belief is formed in a way that is liable to be false, then it is a matter of good fortune if and when that belief is true. But, when a belief is knowledgeably held, then it is not a matter of good fortune that the belief is true. Thus, our beliefs about the external world are not knowledgeably held. The argument is articulated by Albritton (2011): The argument, here, is from natural possibility to epistemic possibility. Imagine a philanthropic lottery in which almost everyone wins, but to keep things exciting . . . there are a few losing tickets. I have a ticket, like all the others. I have no concrete reason to suppose that it, in particular, as distinguished from others, may lose. But this lottery is so set up that some tickets do lose. That’s a perfectly concrete fact about the lottery, and is a compelling reason . . . to suppose that this ticket I’ve bought may lose. I don’t know that it will, but I don’t know that it won’t, either. (Albritton 2011: 7–8) The “natural possibility” that Albritton here takes to establish a skeptical conclusion is the possibility that our ways of forming beliefs lead us into error. The plausibility of Albritton’s view here is indicated by the fact that, in developing his very influential account of knowledge, Armstrong (1973) claims that a belief can be knowledgeably held only if it was formed in a way that, by the laws of nature, guarantees the truth of the belief. If nature allows the possibility that a particular belief, formed in a particular way, is false, then that belief is not knowledgeably held. But when, Albritton’s skeptic pointedly asks, does nature not allow that possibility?

4b  The Argument from Underdetermination Descartes thought he could demonstrate the existence of extended substance in his Sixth Meditation by appeal to the non-deceptiveness of God and our natural inclination to believe that our sensory ideas are caused by extended things. Berkeley (1975) thought he could demonstrate that Descartes was wrong by calling into question the possibility that our sensory ideas represent material substances. But Russell (1959) thought both philosophers were wrong: the existence of matter, said Russell, is a hypothesis, and we cannot achieve certainty concerning the truth or

638

SKEPTICISM

falsity of that hypothesis. The hypothesis, Russell thought, is credible because it provides the simplest and most conservative explanation of our having the sensedata that we have. While there may be disagreement concerning Russell’s claim that this explanation is simplest (perhaps it is simpler to say that God is the direct cause of everything) or most conservative (perhaps it is more conservative, at least for children and other primitive thinkers, to say that spirits are the direct cause of everything), it seems more plausible to say that the hypothesis in question provides the best explanation of our having the sense-data that we have—whatever exactly is packed into its being the “best.” And so this is precisely the view that a number of contemporary philosophers have adopted. We can call this view “abductivism.” Abductivism comes in two main varieties: externalist and internalist. According to the externalist version of the view, defended by Lycan (1988) and Goldman (1988), what makes us justified in our belief that there are material objects, and in many of our more specific beliefs about the behavior of those objects and their causal role in shaping our sensory experiences, is the very fact—whether or not we are aware of it—that the contents of those beliefs do provide the best explanation for our having the sensory experiences that we have. According to this externalist version of the view, explanatory “bestness” is a relation that can obtain between our sensory experiences (the explananda) and the hypotheses that we believe about the external world (the explanans) whether we are aware that it obtains. The internalist version of abductivism, defended in various forms by Harman (1973), Vogel (1990), and BonJour (1985), claims that we are justified in believing in the existence of material objects, and also believing various hypotheses about their behavior, because we are justified in believing that these hypotheses provide the best explanation of our sensory experiences. Abductivism, in either of its forms, paves the way for the skeptical argument from “underdetermination.” Why, this skeptic will ask, should we grant that our hypotheses about material objects do in fact provide the uniquely best explanation of our sensory experiences? If, in fact, another hypothesis does just as well at explaining our sensory experiences, then, by the externalist abductivist’s own lights, this implies that we are not justified in our beliefs about the external world. Or, even if no other hypothesis does just as well at explaining our sensory experiences, still, so long as we have no reason to believe that our hypotheses about the external world provide the uniquely best explanation of our sensory experiences, then, by the internalist abductivist’s lights, this implies that we are not justified in believing those hypotheses about the external world.

4c  The Argument from Closure You take yourself to know that you have hands. But notice that, if you do have hands, then you are not merely a brain floating in a vat of nutrient fluid and being electrochemically stimulated to have the sensory experiences that you have now: such a brain does not have hands, but you do. So if you know that you do have hands, then you must also be in a position to know that you are not such a brain. But how could you know that you are not such a brain? If you were such a brain,

EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

639

everything would seem exactly as it does now; you would (by hypothesis) have all the same sensory experiences that you’re having right now. Since your empirical knowledge of the world around you must somehow be based upon your sensory experiences, how could these experiences—the very same experiences that you would have if you were a brain in a vat—furnish you with knowledge that you’re not such a brain? And if you don’t know that you’re not such a brain, then you cannot know that you have hands. Although the skeptical argument just stated applies specifically to your putative knowledge that you have hands, it needn’t have targeted that proposition in particular: your putative knowledge that you have feet, or that you have a head, or that you live on the planet Earth, or that Lincoln is the capital of Nebraska—all of these empirical propositions about the external world would have done just as well for the skeptic’s purposes. And so, if the skeptical argument just stated can call into question your knowledge that you have hands, it can call into question all of our empirical knowledge of the external world. This skeptical argument is an instance of modus tollens on the following principle: If S knows that p, and S knows that p implies q, then S is in a position to know that q. If we let p be any ordinary empirical proposition about the external world (e.g., “I have hands”), and q be the negation of some skeptical hypothesis that is logically inconsistent with p (e.g., “I am a handless brain in a vat”), then we get the following instance of the principle above: If S knows that she has hands, and knows that her having hands implies that she is not a handless brain in a vat, then S is in a position to know that she is not a handless brain in a vat. The argument from closure begins from the premise that the consequent of this conditional is false, but the second conjunction of the antecedent is true. It concludes, then, that the first conjunct of the antecedent must be false. More generally, it concludes, empirical knowledge of the external world is impossible. Some philosophers, following Moore’s (1959a,c) lead, have been tempted to do a modus ponens where the skeptic does a modus tollens, and argue that, because we do have empirical knowledge of the external world, it follows that we must be in a position to know that the skeptic’s hypotheses are false. But to this the skeptic can reply: “How can you know that my hypotheses are false? You cannot know it empirically, since your sensory evidence would be just the same if my hypotheses were true. And of course you cannot hope to achieve knowledge of contingencies about the external world non-empirically. So you cannot know that my hypotheses are false.” What this skeptic demands is an account of how it is possible to know that we are not in a skeptical scenario in which, by hypothesis, our sensory experiences are exactly the way that they are now, but in which our beliefs about the external world are generally wrong. It is not obvious how to satisfy this demand, and thus the argument from closure can generate skepticism about the external world.

640

SKEPTICISM

4d  The Argument from Dogmatism Suppose, for the sake of argument, that you are in possession of some particular bit of empirical knowledge about the external world—for instance, that you have hands. In what way is it better to have this knowledge than merely to hold a true opinion to the effect that you have hands? This is an issue that Socrates addresses by means of an analogy that he offers at the end of Plato (1976): This is an illustration of the nature of true opinions: while they abide with us they are beautiful and fruitful, but they run away out of the human soul, and do not remain long, and therefore they are not of much value until they are fastened by the tie of the cause . . . . But when they are bound, in the first place, they have the nature of knowledge; and, in the second place, they are abiding. And this is why knowledge is more honourable and excellent than true opinion, because fastened by a chain. (Plato 1976, 31) How should we understand Socrates’s claim that knowledge, unlike true opinions, is “fastened by a chain” or “fastened by the tie of the cause”? And how does such “fastening” prevent knowledge from running “away out of the human soul”? Although there is considerable scholarly controversy concerning these questions, here is one plausible sort of answer: to know that p, for Socrates, involves not merely having the true opinion that p but moreover involves understanding “the cause” of one’s taking it to be true that p. The cause that one understands is the reason for which one takes it to be true that p. And so knowledge differs from true opinion at least by virtue of one’s having a good reason—a reason that one understands—for taking it to be true. But how does this difference help to make it the case that knowledge does not “run away out of the human soul”? Is this merely an empirical claim to the effect that one is less likely to forget that p if one knows that p than if one merely has the true opinion that p? I think not: even if Socrates took such an empirical claim to be true, he gives no evidence for its truth here. Rather, I think we can more plausibly understand Socrates’s claim if we think about the way in which knowing that p entitles us to dismiss apparent counterevidence to p. So, given that you know that you have hands, if a stranger tells you that you do not have any hands, then you are entitled to dismiss the stranger’s testimony: her testimony should not affect your high degree of confidence that you have hands. We can abbreviate this point by saying that, when you know that p, your knowledge is “indefeasible”: no apparent counterevidence to p can make it rational for you to lower your confidence in p. This requirement on knowledge was defended in recent philosophy by McDowell 1982. But if this is what knowledge requires, then the case for skepticism about the external world may seem overwhelmingly plausible, since it seems that very few, if any, of our empirical beliefs about the external world satisfy this stiff requirement. Consider, for instance, your very confidently held belief that you have hands: is there any apparent counterevidence that can make it rational for you to lower your confidence that you have hands? It seems there is: imagine if, a moment from now, you have an extremely vivid and lifelike experience as of waking up from a dream,

EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

641

lying in a hospital bed, looking down at your arms and seeing that your hands have been amputated. In such a case, would it not be rational for you to be at least slightly less confident of your having hands than you now are? And if this “waking up in a hospital bed” experience were the beginning of a long stream of coherent conscious experience, throughout which it seemed clear to you that you had no hands, would this not make it irrational for you to maintain your present level of confidence that you have hands? It seems so. But, in that case, if knowledge makes it rationally permissible for you to dismiss all apparent counterevidence to what you know, then you do not know that you have hands. Since the proposition that you have hands was chosen as an arbitrary example of an empirically grounded belief about the external world, and the same considerations would apply to virtually any other empirically grounded belief about the external world, it follows that you have virtually no empirical knowledge of the external world. The indefeasibility requirement on knowledge—if indeed it is a requirement—seems to make the world safe for skepticism. The four sorts of arguments I’ve canvassed in this section—arguments from fallibility, from underdetermination, from closure, and from dogmatism—have been the main ways in which skepticism about the external world has been dialectically generated. In the next section, I will canvass the main ways in which epistemologists have attempted to rebut these four sorts of argument.

5  RESPONSES TO THE SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS 5a  Responses to the Argument from Fallibility By far the most common response to the argument from fallibility—the response issued (either explicitly or implicitly) by Goldman 1986, Nozick 1981, Lehrer 1974, Williamson 2000, Sosa 1999, and many, many others—is simply to deny that natural possibility (“possible for something to be F”) implies epistemic possibility (“possible that something is F”). According to these philosophers, the fact that it is possible for you to form the beliefs that you currently have in just the way that you formed them, and yet be wrong in those beliefs, does not imply that, as things actually are, those beliefs are not knowledgeably held. That they could have been wrong does not imply that they could be wrong. While this “fallibilist” view of knowledge is widely held, it is not obviously correct. If it’s possible for this very belief (say, that I am now typing on a keyboard), formed in the way it has been formed, to be wrong, then why isn’t it possible that this very belief is wrong? Albritton’s analogy with the philanthropic lottery can seem compelling here: since it’s possible for a particular ticket to be a loser, it seems possible that the ticket is a loser. The defenders of fallible knowledge would reply that, even if the analogy to the philanthropic lottery is compelling, what this shows is not that knowledge requires forming one’s belief in a way that could not have gone wrong, but rather it requires forming one’s belief in a way that would not have gone wrong. If one forms one’s belief in a way that is reliable (where this “reliability” condition can be cashed out in a variety of ways that fall short of infallibility), then one’s belief

642

SKEPTICISM

can be knowledgeably held even if fallibly formed. The reason that we cannot know, of the ticket in the philanthropic lottery, that it is a winner is that it is a fair lottery, and so one could just as easily (even if not just as probably) lose as win. It’s not the case (the fallibilist will say) that if one had bought a ticket one would have won: it’s only true that if one had bought a ticket one would probably have won. And the latter modal condition is weaker than the former. So—the fallibilist concludes—to explain why the ticket holder in the philanthropic lottery cannot know of his ticket that it is a winner, we need not impose any condition on knowledge that is stronger than the former condition. So the lottery example does not dispose of fallibilism. But there is another consideration that may seem to tell against fallibilism. Suppose, for reductio, that S has fallible knowledge that p. Suppose also that S’s belief that p is based upon some grounds g, and S knows that this is so, and knows that g are good (albeit fallible) grounds for believing that p. In that case, S is in a position to know (by the closure of knowledge under known consequence from two known premises) that her grounds g are not misleading with respect to the truth of p. In other words, S must be in a position to know that, though it is possible for g to be true while p is false, that possibility does not obtain. But how could S be in a position to know this whenever she knows that p while knowing that her grounds for believing that p are fallible? In the absence of a satisfying answer to this question, we may conclude that the original supposition—namely, that S has fallible knowledge that p—cannot be true, and so fallibilism about knowledge is false. Even if fallibilism is false, this does not show that the skeptical argument from fallibility succeeds. For there is another possible response to the argument from fallibility, and that is Albritton’s own response, namely, that many of our beliefs are formed in a way that is not fallible. It simply is not possible for those beliefs, formed as they were, to be false, even if other beliefs formed in apparently similar ways actually were, or are, false. (In order to avoid the generality problem, we should specify that, when we here speak of “the way” in which a belief was formed, we mean to be describing those features of its fixation that are relevant to the epistemic status of the belief.) Epistemological disjunctivists like McDowell adopt this antiskeptical strategy when they claim that knowledgeably held beliefs are only those that register the fact that they represent: a belief may seem to the believer to do this without actually doing it, but any belief that fails to do this is not knowledgeably held, however it seems to the subject. So, on this “infallibilist” view, a knowledgeably held belief is one that is formed in a distinctive way, and the way it is formed is such that no false belief can be formed in that way.

5b  Responses to the Argument from Underdetermination The most common response to the argument from underdetermination involves the claim that, even if our perceptual evidence is logically consistent with skeptical hypotheses, it nonetheless provides evidence against those hypotheses in favor of our commonsensical beliefs about the external world, and that is because, even if skeptical hypotheses can be constructed that do explain that perceptual evidence,

EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

643

our commonsensical beliefs about the external world provide a much better explanation of that same perceptual evidence. Why is this? Some philosophers have argued that our commonsensical beliefs about the external world provide a simpler or more ontologically or ideologically parsimonious explanation. But it seems that the skeptic can rebut these claims by designing her competing hypothesis to be as simple and as parsimonious as our commonsensical beliefs about the external world. Vogel (1990), however, points out an important difference between the former (which he calls the “computer skeptical hypothesis,” or CSH) and the latter (which he calls the “real world hypothesis,” or RWH). The RWH explains our perceptual evidence by appeal to the locations of objects, the CSH explains that same evidence by appeal to some property analogous to location—call it “pseudo-location.” Much of the RWH’s explanatory power depends on the necessary truth that no two material objects can occupy the same location at the same time. If the CSH is to enjoy all the explanatory success of the RWH, it will need to appeal to some analogous principle, that is, that no two causes of our perceptual evidence can occupy the same “pseudolocation” at the same time. But either the CSH explains this analogous principle or it doesn’t. If it does, then the CSH explanation of our perceptual evidence is more complicated. If it doesn’t, then the CSH explanation of our perceptual evidence is not as deep or powerful. Either way, the CSH explanation of our perceptual evidence is not as good as the RWH explanation (Vogel 1990: 664–665). While Vogel may have succeeded in showing that the skeptic cannot provide the best explanation of our perceptual evidence, this rebuts the argument from underdetermination only when that argument is understood as assuming that our ordinary beliefs about the external world do provide some explanation of our perceptual evidence, where the latter is accessible to us in terms that don’t presuppose the existence of an external world. But that assumption has been challenged by Neta (2004), who argues that the “explanatory gap” that has been raised, for example, by Levine (1983) and Chalmers (1996), as a problem for explanations of conscious phenomenology in terms of physical processes poses a challenge to any attempt to explain our perceptual evidence, understood in terms that don’t have any commitments to the existence of an external world, by appeal to any physical events or processes. A way to put this worry is that, even if the skeptic cannot provide a good explanation of our perceptual evidence, so conceived, neither can our ordinary beliefs about the external world. The latter can explain our perceptual evidence only insofar as such evidence is described in terms that do presuppose the existence of external things, for example, as perceptual relations to external things. In other words, the solution to this problem of underdetermination demands that we think of our perceptual evidence in terms that presuppose the existence of external things. But in that case this “response” to the skeptical problem of underdetermination is no response at all.

5c  Responses to the Argument from Closure Though many philosophers have attempted to rebut the argument from closure, nothing close to consensus has been achieved on the correct reply. One common line

644

SKEPTICISM

of reply, issued by Nozick (1981) and Dretske (1971), among others, is simply to deny that knowledge is closed under known implication. Nozick and Dretske each develop an account of knowledge that has as a consequence that knowledge is not closed under known implication. According to Dretske, S knows that p only if S’s belief that p is based on conclusive grounds for p, where grounds for p are conclusive just in case S would not have those grounds if p were not true. According to Nozick, S knows that p if and only if (a) S believes that p by means of some method M, and (b) S would not believe that p by means of M if p were not true, and (c) S would believe that p by means of M if p were true. Nozick and Dretske each argues for his account by showing that it issues correct verdicts about the various cases that emerged in the post-Gettier literature on knowledge. But one consequence of both of their accounts is that knowledge is not closed under known implication. And this consequence, as Kripke (2011) has pointed out, is not easy to accept. Consider, for instance, the following example: you see a carpet store’s truck pull up into your neighbor’s driveway, and the delivery people bring a new red carpet out of the truck and into your neighbor’s home. If your neighbors had not bought a new red carpet, they would have bought a blue carpet, and you would have seen it (just as you are now seeing the red one), and so would not have believed that they bought a red carpet. On both Dretske’s and Nozick’s account, you know that your neighbors just bought a new red carpet. But suppose that, if your neighbors had not bought a carpet, they would have paid delivery people to drive the carpet store’s truck into their driveway and unload a new red carpet into their home anyway, just for display purposes, and in order to fool you and their other neighbors into thinking that they bought a carpet. Then, on both Dretske’s and Nozick’s account, you do not know that your neighbors just bought a carpet. So, by Dretske’s and Nozick’s lights, this is a situation in which you know (by looking) that your neighbors have just bought a new red carpet, but you do not know that they have bought a carpet. The implausibility of this consequence damages any attempt to rebut the argument from closure by rejecting the closure principle. Another way to rebut the argument from closure, without rejecting the closure principle, is to reject the premise that we cannot know that the skeptic’s hypothesis is false. On this view, defended by Sosa (1999), Williamson (2000), Wright (2004), Lehrer (1974), Pritchard (2005), Byrne (2004), and others, for any hypothesis that the skeptic designs—any hypothesis the falsity of which is obviously implied by the claims about the external world that we ordinarily take ourselves to know, and according to which our perceptual experiences are just as they actually are—we know that the hypothesis is false. Of course, this position raises two questions. First, how is it that we manage to know that the skeptic’s hypothesis is false? (For instance, how do I manage to know that I am not a brain in a vat being electrochemically stimulated to have the very experiences that I’ve been having?) And second, why are so many philosophers tempted into making (what is, by the lights of this position) the mistake of thinking that we do not know the skeptic’s hypothesis to be false? The first question tends to be answered in one of two ways. Externalists like Sosa and Williamson take it that our knowledge of the falsity of the skeptic’s hypothesis

EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

645

does not require us to be able to justify our belief that the skeptic’s hypothesis is false: all that such knowledge requires is our bearing the relevant modal relation to the fact that we are not (say) mere brains in vats. In contrast, internalists like Wright and Pryor (2000) take it that our knowledge of the falsity of the skeptic’s hypothesis— or, at least, our internalist justification or warrant for believing that the hypothesis is false—is based on some considerations that are available to us upon reflection. (Wright and Pryor hold very different views about what those considerations are: Wright takes them to be non-empirical considerations concerning what sorts of things we must accept if we are to be rationally successful at all, and Pryor takes them to be empirical.) The second question has been answered in many different ways. Sosa, for example, thinks that the following true principle S knows that p only if it would not easily happen that S falsely believes that p is easily confused with the following false principle S knows that p only if S would not believe that p if p were false. While the false principle implies that we do not know the falsity of the skeptic’s hypothesis, the true principle has no such implication. Nonetheless, since we confuse the two principles, we also are confusedly led to the view that we do not know the falsity of the skeptic’s hypothesis. Roush (2010) has a different diagnosis: the skeptic’s hypotheses are typically ambiguous. On one reading, they are incompatible with the claims that we ordinarily take ourselves to know, but we can easily know that they are false. On the other reading, they are not incompatible with the claims that we ordinarily take ourselves to know. For instance, I ordinarily take myself to know that I have hands. But is the claim that I have hands inconsistent with my being a brain in a vat? Of course not: that hypothesis leaves it open that I am a brain in a vat with hands! But there is yet another diagnosis of why so many philosophers have been tempted into the view that we do not know the skeptic’s hypotheses to be false, and this other diagnosis forms the basis of a third way of rebutting the argument from closure. According to this diagnosis, our attributions of knowledge are held to different standards in different situations. And while our ordinary positive attributions of knowledge cannot be correct relative to the strictest standards of knowledge, they can be correct relative to the more relaxed standards that govern our everyday talk and thought. This view can be fleshed out in different ways, depending on whether the variation in standards is taken to be a variation in the truth conditions of our ordinary knowledge-attributing sentences (as DeRose (1995), Lewis (1996), Cohen (1988), Schaffer (2005), Neta (2002), and Blome-Tillmann (2014) would say) or whether it is instead a variation in the acceptability of asserting our ordinary knowledge-attributing sentences (as Fogelin (1994), Williamson (2000), Stanley (2005), and Turri (2010) would say). This way of rebutting the argument from closure accepts the closure principle outright, and then takes our ordinary claims to knowledge to be true and/or acceptable only relative to standards that are less than fully strict. Even if some version of this view is correct—and it is controversial that any version of it is (see Reed (2009), for opposition)—it’s not clear to what extent

646

SKEPTICISM

skepticism about the external world is committed to denying this view. Perhaps this sort of view should be thought of not so much as a rebuttal of the argument from closure, but rather as an attempt to show how the skeptical conclusion of that argument can be understood in a way that doesn’t impugn the positive knowledge attributions that we ordinarily issue.

5d  Responses to the Argument from Dogmatism By far the most common response to the argument from dogmatism was the one originally issued by Harman (1973): we can know that p even if we cannot rationally disregard apparent counterevidence to p, but that is because when we gain apparent counterevidence to p, we thereby lose our knowledge. According to this popular view, knowledge that p does rationally permit the knower to disregard apparent counterevidence to p, but if and when such counterevidence comes into view, then the subject ceases to know, and is no longer rationally permitted to ignore that counterevidence. For example, suppose that I know, on the basis of testimony, that the current American secretary of state is Rex Tillerson. Then, so long as I continue to know that fact, I am rationally permitted to ignore evidence to the contrary. For instance, so long as I continue to know that the current American secretary of state is Rex Tillerson, I am rationally permitted to ignore news reports to the effect that Tillerson has suddenly resigned. However, when I hear such news reports, I no longer continue to know that the current American secretary of state is Rex Tillerson, and so I am no longer rationally permitted to ignore those reports. This view allows that many of the things that we ordinarily take ourselves to know are things that we do know, even if we are not rationally permitted to ignore apparent counterevidence to them. The problem with this view has been pointed out recently by Maria LasonenAarnio (2014). Let’s grant, she says, that knowledge that p does rationally permit one to ignore counterevidence to p. Let’s also grant, as seems immensely plausible, that it’s possible to know that p is true when the balance of one’s evidence provides very compelling support for p, even if one has a very slight bit of counterevidence to p. Now, in such a case, what should the defender of Harman’s view say? Should she say that, since the subject continues to know that p despite having some slight counterevidence to p, she is rationally permitted to ignore her very slight counterevidence to p? That seems implausible: rationality requires us to distribute our credence in light of all our relevant evidence, and it should not matter whether that evidence comes in all at once, or the positive evidence all comes in first (to give us knowledge) and only later does the very slight negative evidence come in. So should the defender of Harman’s view instead say that knowledge is lost as soon as the knower acquires even the slightest bit of counterevidence to p? That also seems implausible: presumably, it’s possible to know things even without being absolutely certain of them, and it’s also possible to continue to know things of which we were absolutely certain even once we acquire evidence that rationally requires us to be only ever so slightly less than absolutely certain of them. So the defender of Harman’s view cannot explain why someone who knows that p is not rationally

EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

647

permitted to ignore even very slight counterevidence to p, counterevidence the possession of which is consistent with their knowing that p. But if the Harman response to the skeptical argument from dogmatism does not work, then how can we reply to that argument? Another line of reply is implicit in the view of McDowell (1982), who grants that knowledge is indefeasible: when you do know that p, you are rationally permitted to ignore counterevidence to p, and your knowledge is not defeated by your obtaining such counterevidence. Part of why this reply is so unorthodox is that it seems, on the face of it, implausible to claim that our ordinary knowledge can never be defeated by counterevidence. Can I not lose my knowledge that Rex Tillerson is the current American secretary of state if I come to hear seemingly credible news reports that he has resigned and been replaced? Suppose I do come to hear such news reports, and then learn, on the basis both of those reports and subsequent corroboration, that Tillerson has in fact resigned and been replaced: what would I say then about my earlier claim to know that Rex Tillerson is the current American secretary of state? I would say that I only thought I knew, but I did not really know. Now suppose that I come to hear these same news reports, and then have not yet corroborated them but am still investigating, and so am no longer sure what to believe: what would I say then about my earlier claim to know that John Kerry is the current American secretary of state? Once again, I would say that I thought I knew, but I did not really know. On McDowell’s view, this later claim is exactly right. What happens when I gain sufficient counterevidence to p is not that I cease to know that p, but rather I learn that I do not, and did not, know that p. If you know that p, then you will not gain evidence that would make it rational to doubt that p. If you do gain such evidence, then you did not know that p. (We are assuming here that p is a proposition the truth of which is constant over time.) Fortunately for our epistemic position, many of the things that we ordinarily take ourselves to know are never put in doubt by counterevidence.

6  CONCLUSION: HOW THE VERY IDEA OF THE EXTERNAL WORLD CAN GENERATE SKEPTICAL WORRIES What all four of the skeptical arguments above have in common is that they include premises the plausibility of which depends on the thought that external things are the way they are independent of how they perceptually appear to us: that’s why the beliefs that we form on the basis of those appearances can be false, why our beliefs about external things are underdetermined by our perceptual evidence, why we cannot know that we’re not receiving those appearances in the way described by some skeptical hypothesis, and why we cannot rationally disregard apparent counterevidence to our beliefs about external things. But notice that, while it follows from Moore’s characterization of external things that such things can be as they are without being perceived, it does not follow from that characterization that our perceptual states can be as they are without external things. It is easy to confuse these two thoughts, but they are not

648

SKEPTICISM

logically equivalent. We can accept the first thought, but reject the second. In this section, I canvass three famous attempts to do this, and thereby to undermine skepticism about the external world. According to the “content externalism” defended by Putnam (1981), the contents of our mental representations are metaphysically determined by the causal relations that we bear to features of our environment. It is only because we spend our lives in causal contact with water that so many of our thoughts are about water. Our doppelgangers on Twin Earth, who spend their lives in causal contact with a substance that is perceptually indistinguishable, but distinct, from water, have mental representations that are about that distinct substance, and not about water. Thus, on Putnam’s view, there is a metaphysical limit to how wrong our beliefs about the external world can be, and that limit is imposed by the fact that the contents of those beliefs depends on facts about the external world. More specifically, as Putnam put it: “If we can consider whether [the hypothesis that we are brains in vats being electrochemically stimulated to have the very experiences that we’ve had] is true or false, then it is not true. . . . Hence it is not true” (Putnam 1981: 8). Davidson (1984) argues for a form of psychological externalism by appeal to the premises that (i) what we think is just what the method of radical interpretation, when ideally executed in application to all of our observable behavior, would claim that we think, and (ii) the method of radical interpretation delivers the result that most of the interpreter’s beliefs are true by the lights of the interpreter, and (iii) an omniscient being could, in principle, execute the method of radical interpretation. From these three principles it follows that, for any particular thinker, what they think is just what the omniscient interpreter would claim (on the basis of radical interpretation) that they think, and most of those beliefs would be true by the lights of the omniscient interpreter. But what is true by the lights of an omniscient interpreter is true. Therefore, for any particular thinker, most of her beliefs are true. This could only be the case if the external world were at least very roughly the way we believe it to be. Therefore, the external world is at least very roughly the way we believe it to be. Both Putnam’s content externalism and Davidson’s psychological externalism impose a metaphysical limit to how wrong our beliefs about the external world can be, but this limit is consistent with various narrow skeptical hypotheses (e.g., five minutes ago I made the transition from being a normally embodied human to being a brain in a vat). In contrast, on McDowell’s disjunctivist view, it’s true not only that our representations depend globally on some features of the external world; it’s also true that particular representations depend on particular features of the external world. For instance, when I look at my hands in the clear light of day, I see my hands, and when I see my hands, I have a perceptual experience that is different in kind from any perceptual experience that I could have if I did not have hands. It’s true that I could have a convincing hallucination as of having hands: in such a case, I would falsely believe myself to be seeing my hands. It might also be true that when I dream about, or imagine, my hands, I falsely believe myself to be seeing my hands. Nonetheless, when I do in fact see my hands, I can know, simply by reflecting on my perceptual state itself, that I’m seeing my hands and

EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

649

not merely dreaming, imagining, or hallucinating them. On this disjunctivist view, while it can still be true that external things (like my hands) can exist without being perceived, it’s not true that I could occupy my current perceptual states (my current seeing of my hands) without the existence of the perceived external things. If this disjunctivist view is correct, then we can grant the skeptic that knowledge of the external world requires infallibility, no underdetermination, closure under known implication, and indefeasibility, but still deny that the skeptic can gain any mileage from these requirements.

REFERENCES Albritton, Rogers. 2011. “On a Sceptical Argument from Possibility.” In E. Sosa and E. Villanueva (eds.), Philosophical Issues (The Epistemology of Perception) 21: 1–24. Armstrong, David. 1973. Belief, Truth and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Austin, J. L. 1961. “Other Minds.” In his Philosophical Papers, 76–116. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Ayer, A. J. 1956. The Problem of Knowledge. London: Hammondsworth. Berkeley, George. 1975. Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, edited by P. H. Nidditch. London and Melbourne: Everyman’s Library. Blome-Tillman, Michael. 2014. Knowledge and Presuppositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. BonJour, Laurence. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Brueckner, Anthony. 1994. “The Structure of the Skeptical Argument,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54: 827–835. Byrne, Alex. 2004. “How Hard Are the Skeptical Paradoxes?” Noûs 38: 299–325. Chalmers, David. 1996. The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press. Chisholm, Roderick. 1982. “The Problem of the Criterion.” In his The Foundations of Knowing, 61–75. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Cohen, Stewart. 1988. “How to Be a Fallibilist.” In J. Tomberlin (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives 2 (Epistemology), 91–123. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview. Davidson, Donald. 1984. “Belief and Its Basis in Meaning.” In his Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, 141–154. Oxford: Clarendon Press. DeRose, Keith. 1995. “Solving the Skeptical Problem,” Philosophical Review 104: 1–51. Descartes, René. 1993. Meditations on First Philosophy, translated by D. Cress. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Dretske, Fred. 1971. “Conclusive Reasons,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49: 1–22. Dretske, Fred. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Fogelin, Robert. 1994. Pyrrhonian Reflections on Knowledge and Justification. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. Ginet, Carl. 1980. “Knowing Less by Knowing More.” In P. French, T. Uehling, and H. Wettstein (eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy V: Epistemology. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 151–161. Goldman, Alan. 1988. Empirical Knowledge. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

650

SKEPTICISM

Goldman, Alvin. 1986. Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Harman, Gilbert. 1973. Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Kripke, Saul. 2011. “Nozick on Knowledge.” In his Collected Papers, Volume 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lasonen-Aarnio, Maria. 2014. “The Dogmatism Puzzle,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92: 417–432. Lehrer, Keith. 1974. Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Levine, Joseph. 1983. “Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64: 354–361. Lewis, David. 1996. “Elusive Knowledge,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 549–567. Locke, John. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, edited by P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lycan, William. 1988. Judgment and Justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. McDowell, John. 1982. “Criteria, Defeasibility, and Knowledge,” Proceedings of the British Academy 68: 455–479. McDowell, John. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Moore, G. E. 1959a. “Certainty.” In his Philosophical Papers, 223–246. New York: Collier. Moore, G. E. 1959b. “Proof of an External World.” In his Philosophical Papers, 126–148. New York: Collier. Moore, G. E. 1959c. “Four Forms of Scepticism.” In his Philosophical Papers, 193–222. New York: Collier. Neta, Ram. 2002. “S Knows that P,” Noûs 36: 663–681. Neta, Ram. 2003. “Contextualism and the Problem of the External World,” Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 66: 1–31. Neta, Ram. 2004. “Skepticism, Abductivism, and the Explanatory Gap.” In E. Sosa and E. Villanueva (eds.), Philosophical Issues 14, 296–325. Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Plato. 1976. Meno, translated by G. Grube. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. Pritchard, Duncan. 2005. Epistemic Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pryor, James. 2000. “The Skeptic and the Dogmatist,” Noûs 34: 517–549. Putnam, Hilary. 1981. Reason, Truth, and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reed, Baron. 2009. “A New Argument for Skepticism,” Philosophical Studies 142: 91–104. Roush, Sherrilyn. 2010. “Closure on Skepticism.” Journal of Philosophy 107: 243–256. Russell, Bertrand. 1957. “The Relation of Sense-Data to Physics.” In his Mysticism and Logic, 140–173. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books. Russell, Bertrand. 1959. The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schaffer, Jonathan. 2005. “Contrastive Knowledge,” Oxford Studies in Epistemology 1: 235–271. Sextus Empiricus. 1996. Outlines of Pyrrhonism, translated by Benson Mates. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. Sosa, Ernest. 1999. “How to Defeat Opposition to Moore.” In J. Tomberlin, Philosophical Perspectives 13: Epistemology, 141–153. Cambridge, MA and Oxford: Blackwell.

EXTERNAL WORLD SKEPTICISM

651

Stanley, Jason. 2004. Knowledge and Practical Interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stroud, Barry. 1984. The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Turri, John. 2010. “Epistemic Invariantism and Speech Act Contextualism,” Philosophical Review 119: 77–95. Unger, Peter. 1975. Ignorance. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Vogel, Jonathan. 1990. “Cartesian Scepticism and Inference to the Best Explanation,” Journal of Philosophy 87: 658–666. Williams, Michael. 2001. Problems of Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wright, Crispin. 2004. “Warrant for Nothing (and Foundations for Free?),” Aristotelian Society Supplement 78: 167–212.

CHAPTER FORTY-FIVE

Disjunctivism and Skepticism DUNCAN PRITCHARD AND CHRIS RANALLI

1  THE NATURE OF PERCEPTUAL EXPERIENCE I see a particular book on the shelf. How should I characterize the nature of this visual perception? According to naïve realism, what explains what it is like for me to see this book is the book itself and its manifest properties—the properties that I can see, like its color, shape, size, texture, and so on. In particular, naïve realism maintains that the objects in the world around us—objects like trees, books, tablecloths, and so on—enter into our experiences of them as constituents. On this view, it is the external objects and their manifest properties which explain the “phenomenal character” of our perceptual experiences—what Thomas Nagel (1974) called those features of experience such that there is something that it is like to undergo them. Most philosophers reject naïve realism in favor of some form of intentionalism about the nature of experience.1 According to intentionalism, sense experience is an intentional state, like belief or thought. Consider a now famous expression of the view from Christopher Peacocke: A visual perceptual experience enjoyed by someone sitting at a desk may represent various writing implements and items of furniture as having particular spatial relations to one another and to the experiencer, and as themselves having various qualities. . . . The representational content of a perceptual experience has to be given by a proposition, or set of propositions, which specifies the way the experience represents the world to be. (Peacocke 1983: 5) Intentionalism thus holds that perceptual experiences have representational content—contents which are about something, or represent the world as being some way—which permits an assessment of them as successful or unsuccessful, veridical or unveridical, or true or false. When framed in the terms of the old debate between direct realism and indirect realism, both naïve realism and intentionalism are versions of direct realism because neither view maintains that there are surrogate objects or properties that we experience which mediate our perceptual experiences of mind-independent external

DISJUNCTIVISM AND SKEPTICISM

653

objects and their properties. For the naïve realist, objects and properties in the world around us can enter into our experiences as constituents. Our perceptions of those objects are “direct” in the sense that those objects in part constitute our perceptual experiences when perceived. However, while the intentionalist does not characterize perceptual experience as a relation to mind-independent objects and properties, she doesn’t thereby commit herself to characterizing it as a relation to other kinds of objects and properties. Instead, perceptual experience is a representational state, and just as we can believe that snow is white without the belief first being about something else distinct from snow and its whiteness, so too we can have a perceptual experience in which we represent that snow is white without the experience first being about something else distinct from snow and its whiteness. If we describe the nature of perceptual experience like this, it’s not clear what could make the mental state “indirect” in any philosophically significant sense. In this way, while the naïve realist and the sense-datum theorist agree that the nature of sense experience is relational—experience is a relation to objects and properties—they disagree on the nature of what it’s a relation to. And this distinction helps sharpen the difference between naïve realism and intentionalism. For the intentionalist, sense experience is not a relation to mind-independent external objects and properties, but not because it is a relation to mind-dependent objects and properties. Instead, sense experience is not a bona fide relation, in which both relata exist. So, while the naïve realist and the sense-datum theorist agree about the relational character of sensory experience, the naïve realist and the intentionalist, contra the sense-datum theorist, agree that sense experience is “direct,” in the sense that we can perceive external material objects without first perceiving something else ontologically distinct from them, like sense-data. The central reason for rejecting naïve realism is some form of the argument from hallucination. As a general template, the argument can be framed as a paradox. Naïve realism appears to best articulate how perceptual experience strikes us as being on reflection. That is, it just strikes us that during visual perception, say, those objects and properties around us that we see and attend to are themselves part of the very visual perception. As P. F. Strawson (1974) once put the point, it seems like if we try to attend to the objects and properties of our experiences, we thereby attend to the objects and properties in the world around us. But naïve realism is apparently shown by the argument from hallucination to be inconsistent with two other plausible theses: experiential naturalism (EN) and the common kind assumption (CKA).2 According to experiential naturalism, our sense experiences are subject to what Mike Martin (2004: 39) calls the natural “causal order”—that is, are subject to causal stimulation, just like other material objects, properties, or states of affairs. In particular, a suitable stimulation to the brain can cause an experience in the subject which—at least in principle—is indistinguishable from a perception. Moreover, the common kind assumption claims that the kind of mental event that occurs when I perceive an external material object is a kind of event I can undergo even in the absence of the objects or properties that I perceived. Naturally, one might think that this thesis gives credence to the idea that it’s possible to undergo

654

SKEPTICISM

hallucinations which are indistinguishable from veridical perceptions because such mental events are simply events of the same kind being instantiated in two different kinds of cases: one in a case where what causes the experience is a mind-independent object, the other a suitable brain-stimulation. The argument from hallucination against naïve realism then moves as follows. (CKA) implies that whatever the nature of the sense experience during perception, that kind of mental event can occur during hallucination. According to naïve realism, however, perceptual experience is a kind of mental event which is constitutively a relation, and in particular, a relation to mind-independent, external objects. From (CKA) and naïve realism alone, there is no inconsistency. But once we add the plausible (EN), (CKA) and naïve realism are rendered inconsistent. After all, naïve realism tells us that perceptual experience is constitutively relational. So by (CKA), that kind of mental event can occur in cases of hallucination. But then there must exist both relata of the sensory relation. However, (EN), together with (CKA), tells us that brain-stimulation alone is sufficient to cause a sensory experience of the kind that is instantiated during perception. But the conditions necessary to cause a hallucinatory experience are not sufficient to cause the existence of the relata, namely, the subject and the object of the subject’s awareness. And, ex hypothesi, hallucinations aren’t relations to anything. So, from (CKA) and (EN), naïve realism is false. Disjunctivism about the nature of sense experience can be seen as a tool for blocking the negative conclusion of this argument—viz., that naïve realism is false (Martin 2006: 354). According to disjunctivism, the nature of the experiences we have while veridically perceiving some object differs in kind from the nature of the experiences we have when undergoing indistinguishable hallucinations. Instead of thinking of the nature of sense experience as what is metaphysically in common between cases of veridical perception and cases which fall short of it, we can instead think of the metaphysical nature of sense experience as divergent across “good” cases like veridical perception and “bad” cases like hallucination. According to this line, there are no metaphysical commonalities between the disjoint cases of perception and hallucination from which a general theory of the nature of sensory experience can be given.3 With disjunctivism in hand, the proponent of naïve realism can respond to the argument from hallucination as follows. It is true that brain-stimulation alone can cause us to have experiences which are indistinguishable from veridical perceptions. But it does not follow from this that that kind of mental event, the indistinguishable hallucination, has the same nature as the kind we have when we veridically perceive external material objects and properties. Instead, we can characterize the visual experience as of a coffee cup, say, as either a state in which we perceive the coffee cup or as one in which it seems to us just as if we do, as when we suffer from an indistinguishable hallucination.4 In this fashion, disjunctivism allows one to maintain that the explanans of the relevant features of experiences in cases of veridical perception, such as its phenomenal character, can be external mind-independent objects and properties, even if it fails to be that in cases which fall short of veridical perception, such as hallucination and illusion.

DISJUNCTIVISM AND SKEPTICISM

655

However, disjunctivism need not be understood as a view committed to naïve realism. One can be an intentionalist and accept disjunctivism. For example, one might want to characterize perceptual experience as a distinctive kind of representational state that cannot be instantiated in cases which fall short of veridical perception, such as hallucination.5 Following a view like Bertrand Russell’s (1912; 1917) about the nature of our grasp of propositions, we might think that we grasp some types of propositions in virtue of being acquainted with some of the constituents of those propositions. If we add that external mind-independent objects and properties can be constituents of those kinds of propositions, and we also add that those kinds of propositions can be the content of a perceptual experience, this allows one to formulate a distinctive kind of disjunctivism about the nature of sense experience in virtue of appealing to the different kinds of representational content an experience can instantiate in cases of veridical perception, but not in cases of hallucination.6 This argument highlights how, even if naïve realism entails disjunctivism, the converse need not be true. Disjunctivism is compatible with intentionalism, at least if we take the central component of intentionalism to be the thesis that sensory experience has representational content, and it is its representational content which bears the burden of explaining the nature of sensory experience. Indeed, this helps us to further sharpen the distinction between naïve realism and intentionalism. What is central to naïve realism is the thesis that external material objects and properties, and our sensory relation to them, bear the burden of explaining the nature of sensory experience. But what is central to intentionalism is that it’s the representational content of experience which bears that burden, and ipso facto not that sensory experience is a relation to external material objects and properties, even if it were. Of course, one can be an intentionalist who believes that the representational content of veridical perception is a kind of content where we are acquainted with—and so related to—some of the components of the content, where some of the components of the content are external material objects and properties. But note that this kind of intentionalism obscures the distinction between naïve realism and intentionalism, and it’s not clear that it doesn’t simply collapse the distinction. So, whether a significant distinction between the two would remain at that point is still quite controversial and difficult to answer.7

2  SKEPTICISM AND DISJUNCTIVISM The epistemological problem of the external world is the problem of explaining how knowledge of the external world is possible given certain obstacles that make it look impossible. One obstacle to this kind of knowledge can be derived from a certain intuitive requirement on knowledge. For example, we might think that in order to know that p we have to know that all of those propositions which we know to be incompatible with p are false. For example, consider the proposition that I’m a bodiless brain in a vat, stimulated to have experiences which are indistinguishable from the corresponding veridical perceptions that I think I’ve had. Call this proposition (BIV). Now consider the following argument:

656

SKEPTICISM

(P1) If I know that I have hands, then I know that ~(BIV). (P2) I don’t know that ~(BIV). Therefore, (C) I don’t know that I have hands. The following principle can be proffered in favor of (P1): Competent Deduction Closure If S knows that p, and S competently deduces from p that q, thereby forming a belief that q on this basis while retaining her knowledge that p, then S knows that q.8 We might think that this principle—“closure” for short—just gives expression to our intuition that competent deduction from known propositions can be a means of extending our knowledge to the known consequences of those propositions. Since we know that having hands implies that we are not bodiless, and so not bodiless brains in vats, the closure principle implies that, if we do know that we have hands, then we can know that ~(BIV). But ~(BIV) seems to be just the sort of proposition we cannot know to be true. After all, how could I know that I’m not a bodiless brain in a vat if being the victim of that kind of scenario would produce in me just the sorts of experiences I would have were I an embodied human being, active in the familiar world around us? This makes it look like I don’t know that ~(BIV). But this together with (P1) entails that I don’t know that I have hands, which is counterintuitive. How disjunctivism fares against this problem depends on how we understand the skeptical challenge. For example, if we frame the problem of the external world as arising out of the supposed fact that sense experience underdetermines the choice between various propositions about the world around us and (known to be incompatible) competitor propositions, then disjunctivism about the nature of sense experience might be able to provide a response to this challenge. If we conceive of the nature of sense experience in general as disjunctive—as dividing into states in which either we perceive external material objects or states in which we seem to do so but fail (as with indistinguishable hallucinations)—then why couldn’t some sense experiences put us in a position to know propositions about the world around us, and so put us in a position to infer that ~(BIV) from our knowledge that those propositions are true, even if our capacity to do so is fallible? Call this the simple disjunctivist response. An immediate problem for the simple disjunctivist response is that it’s not at all clear that a core component of the problem of the external world depends on a view about the relation between sense experience and the external world.9 Moreover, even if it is a core component of the problem, it’s not clear that mounting a competing thesis is sufficient to remove the challenge. After all, certain arguments make it look plausible that sense experience underdetermines the choice between propositions about the world and their corresponding skeptical competitors. The disjunctivist would have to speak to these arguments.10 Another concern is that the disjunctivist about sense experience just misses the point that the problem of the external world is an epistemological problem, arising out of core epistemological intuitions. For example, (BIV) might express a scenario

DISJUNCTIVISM AND SKEPTICISM

657

where the subject is not perceiving the world around her for how it is (since she’s a bodiless brain in a vat, even though it doesn’t seem to her that she is). But what is at issue with (BIV) is not the fact that she cannot perceive the world around her for how it is, but that whether or not (BIV) is true, it’s not clear that we could come to know that ~(BIV). The reason need not be that the kinds of experiences we have in either case are experiences of the same nature. Instead, it can be that we cannot distinguish between cases in which we do get things right from cases in which we seem to get things right but nevertheless fail. For example, one might argue in support of the following principle, which we will call perceptual discrimination: Perceptual Discrimination (PD) If S knows that p on the basis of perceptual experience, then S can discriminate cases in which p from cases in which ~p. For example, if I know that a goldfinch is in the garden on the basis of visual experience, then I must be able to discriminate the case where it’s a goldfinch in the garden from other kinds of birds being in the garden. If not, what makes it the case that the visual experience supplies me with the knowledge that it’s a goldfinch rather than some other bird, or something less specific like that a bird is in the garden? With (PD), there is a quick move available to (P2) (i.e., ~K~(BIV)). After all, I cannot discriminate cases in which I see hands from cases in which I am a bodiless brain in a vat who seems to see hands.11 Moreover, we can leave (PD) to one side and just consider the closure principle. This latter principle seems to reflect a general epistemological intuition, and it implies that if we know propositions about the world around us, such as that we have hands, then we can know ~(BIV), at least provided we make the competent deduction. But we might just take it as primitive that we don’t know that ~(BIV). It might just reflect a basic epistemological intuition: an intuition as basic as that not all propositions can be known. If this is right, then the proponent of the simple disjunctivist response will need to explain why it isn’t primitive, even if initially it strikes us as being primitive. How might the proponent of the simple disjunctivist response overcome this challenge? One thought is that she should speak directly to epistemological concerns. For example, she could say that our perceptual relation to mind-independent external objects is sufficient for knowledge-level justification: justification which, if we have it, would put us in a position to know. After all, what else could be better reason for believing that I have hands than just my hands themselves being part of the very sensory episode that I enjoy? But why is disjunctivism any better off than, say, its intentionalist rival in arguing that perceptions provide us with knowledgelevel justification? More generally, there is a strong intuition in favor of the idea that there’s nothing about the “directness” of a sensory perception that makes it any better a candidate for knowledge-level justification than a matching hallucination. The thought here finds a clear expression in these remarks by Earl Conee:

658

SKEPTICISM

It remains strongly intuitive that perception does not provide any better reason for an external world belief than would be provided by a matching hallucination. There is no a priori limit on the potential verisimilitude of hallucination. Whether S1 is in perceptual state P1 or the matching hallucination H1, it appears to S1 exactly as though T1 is true. Intuitively, that is as good a basis for reasonable belief in T1 as is the veridical perception. Thus, since the strength of epistemic justification is equal to the strength of reasonableness, a perception does not justify more strongly than does a matching hallucination. (Conee 2007: 18) Like the previous criticism, this criticism challenges the epistemological benefits of the disjunctive conception of sensory experience. It says that even if the sensory experiences implicated in perception and hallucination are metaphysically different kinds of states, what remains epistemologically problematic is the fact that we cannot introspectively distinguish them. Notice that this challenge appeals to the following intuitive principle: Same Epistemic Status (SES) If a perceptual state E provides S with an epistemic standing for her belief that p, then any perceptual state R which is (for S) introspectively indistinguishable from E provides at least as much of an epistemic standing for S to believe that p. If we accept (SES), then the epistemological benefits of the disjunctive conception of sensory experience dissipate.

3  EPISTEMOLOGICAL DISJUNCTIVISM Let us now consider a distinctively epistemological form of disjunctivism, which we will refer to as epistemological disjunctivism. Like its metaphysical counterpart, epistemological disjunctivism is composed of a negative thesis about the fundamental difference in epistemic significance between successful and unsuccessful cases of sensory experience and a positive thesis about the nature of the epistemic significance of the sensory experience in the successful case. Epistemological disjunctivism’s negative thesis consists of its rejection of (SES), which we just encountered. In particular, epistemological disjunctivists will contend that in pairings of introspectively indistinguishable good and bad cases, the subject concerned has a much stronger epistemic standing for her belief in the good case than in the bad case. (SES) can look appealing because, given that good and bad cases are indistinguishable, it is hard to fathom how the epistemic standing of one’s belief in the good case could be better than the epistemic standing of one’s belief in the corresponding bad case.12 Nonetheless, epistemological disjunctivism rejects this thesis. In particular, it argues that we should not limit the epistemic support available for our beliefs to the low level of epistemic support which is available in the bad case. Instead, we should regard the epistemic standing of one’s belief in the corresponding good case as being far superior.13

DISJUNCTIVISM AND SKEPTICISM

659

In specifying that the epistemic support is different in the two cases, however, this still leaves open a number of options in terms of what constitutes this difference. For example, is the difference between the subject’s epistemic standing in the good case and the bad case one of kind or only of degree? Either way, what is crucial to epistemological disjunctivism is the idea that there is epistemic support available to one in the good case that’s unavailable in the bad case. Call this the core epistemological disjunctivist thesis. It is an interesting question how metaphysical and epistemological disjunctivism relate to one another. They are certainly dialectically affiliated in the sense that, if one endorses metaphysical disjunctivism, then one will be naturally inclined to also endorse epistemological disjunctivism, and vice versa. But whether they actually entail one another is a different matter. In particular, it seems at least possible to hold the one thesis while rejecting the other, even though such a combination of views may well be philosophically quite uncomfortable.14 It should be clear that epistemological disjunctivism’s prospects for dealing with the problem of radical skepticism are more promising than metaphysical disjunctivism. Recall that one core issue facing the latter proposal was that it was attempting to confront an epistemological problem and yet its own epistemological ramifications were moot. For epistemological disjunctivism, there is no such difficulty. In particular, by rejecting (SES) epistemological disjunctivism directly challenges a claim which seems to be presupposed in the radical skeptical problem. Radical skeptical scenarios, after all, are extreme examples of bad cases. And yet part of what is motivating the skeptical thought that we are unable to rule out such scenarios is that our epistemic standing in the good case is no better than it would be in a corresponding radical skeptical scenario (on account of the latter being indistinguishable from the former). Once we have rejected (SES), however, then what would prompt us to concede this point to the skeptic? Why not instead insist that so long as one is in the good case, then one’s epistemic support is substantially greater than it is in the skeptical bad case, and hence that one has an epistemic basis on which one can reject this error-possibility? Whether such a line of argument is tenable will to a large extent depend on the positive thesis that the epistemological disjunctivist offers about the nature of the epistemic support in the good case. In particular, the problem facing epistemological disjunctivism on this score is that if the positive account is cast along epistemic externalist lines then the view becomes pedestrian, while if it is cast along epistemic internalist lines the view will strike many as absurd. Consider first an epistemic externalist rendering of epistemological disjunctivism, whereby the different epistemic standing of the subject’s belief in the pairs of good and bad cases are not reflectively accessible to the subject.15 Such a view would be pedestrian because it is entirely normal for epistemic externalists to hold that a subject’s epistemic standing differs across good and bad cases in this way. After all, on epistemic externalist views the epistemic standing of one’s beliefs is dependent on non-reflectively accessible factors, such as the reliability of the belief-forming process through which one acquired one’s belief. Hence it is unsurprising that in

660

SKEPTICISM

the bad cases, where those externalist factors do not obtain, the subject’s epistemic standing will tend to be much worse than it is in the corresponding good case. A further upshot of the foregoing is that an epistemological disjunctivism which is wedded to epistemic externalism will offer a response to the problem of radical skepticism which is no more plausible than the standard epistemic externalist responses which many find unpersuasive.16 In particular, the normal epistemic externalist line on radical skepticism is to treat our knowing as being in a sense contingent on factors beyond our ken. That is, while the skeptic insists that knowledge is (for the most part anyway) impossible, the epistemic externalist anti-skeptic argues that knowledge is possible, just so long as we are in the right kind of conditions which would sustain it. Whether we are in such conditions, however, is not held to be something that we can determine by reflecting on the nature of our epistemic position, since these conditions concern facts about the world such as whether we are indeed reliably forming our beliefs (as opposed to being a brain in a vat who merely thinks that she is). The combination of epistemological disjunctivism and epistemic externalism is no different on this score. If we are indeed in the good case rather than the bad, then we are in the market for knowledge, contra the skeptic. But whether we are in the good case depends on factors outwith our reflective ken.17 Hence, if epistemological disjunctivism is to offer anything distinctive to the contemporary debate about radical skepticism, then it will need to be cast along epistemic internalist lines. Such a view would hold that the superior epistemic standing available to the subject’s belief in the good case is reflectively accessible to the subject. One can straight away see a difficulty looming for this approach, which is why it is thought unattractive (indeed, simply unavailable). For given that pairs of good and bad cases are by definition introspectively indistinguishable to the agent, then how can it be that in the good case one’s superior epistemic standing is reflectively accessible? We will examine this issue by looking at a particular version of epistemological disjunctivism which is cast along epistemic internalist lines. This is the approach offered by John McDowell (e.g., 1995) and, following him, Duncan Pritchard (e.g., 2012a).18 On this view, one’s perceptual knowledge can consist, in paradigmatic cases at least, in one’s possession of rational support that is both reflectively accessible and factive. More specifically, in such cases one perceptually knows that p in virtue of seeing that p, where that one sees that p is one’s reflectively accessible rational support for believing that p. On this form of epistemological disjunctivism we thus get a particularly strong rendering of the epistemic standing of the subject’s belief in the good case, in that it is an epistemic standing which actually entails the truth of the believed proposition. Clearly this is an epistemic standing which is unavailable to the subject in the bad case, since as bad cases are usually described the target belief is false.19 This form of epistemological disjunctivism is distinctive in another respect too, in that the very idea that there can be factive yet reflectively accessible reasons of this kind is thought highly controversial. The claim that knowledge consists of the possession of reflectively accessible rational support marks the view out as a kind of epistemic internalism.20 But, on standard forms of epistemic internalism, the facts

DISJUNCTIVISM AND SKEPTICISM

661

to which one has such special epistemic access are by their nature not such that they entail specific claims about the subject’s environment (but rather concern, for example, the subject’s mental states, narrowly understood). In contrast, whereas epistemic externalism does allow that knowledge can be in virtue of an epistemic standing which entails specific facts about the subject’s environment, these facts (such as facts about the reliability of the process through which the subject acquired her belief) are not held to be reflectively accessible to the subject. By allowing that one’s epistemic standing can be both reflectively accessible and also entail specific facts about one’s environment, this form of epistemological disjunctivism is thus a highly non-standard version of epistemic internalism. Is this view tenable? We noted above that there is at least a strong prima facie reason for thinking not. For how is one to square this form of epistemological disjunctivism with the claim that pairs of good and bad cases are introspectively indistinguishable to the subject? On this view, in the good case one’s rational support for believing that p can be that one sees that p, where it is reflectively accessible to one that one has this rational support. But if there are facts reflectively accessible to the subject which are only available in the good case (and the subject is in a position to know that this is so on purely a priori grounds), then surely the subject can, through an entirely reflective process, come to know that she is in the good case as opposed to the bad case. Isn’t that in direct conflict with the stipulation that pairs of good and bad cases are introspectively indistinguishable?21 There is a further, but related, problem in play here. For consider our subject’s perceptual knowledge that there is a table before her in virtue of her possession of the relevant factive reason. Given that this rational support is reflectively accessible, and given that the subject is also presumably in a position to know on a purely a priori basis that this rational support is factive, then what is to stop the subject acquiring a completely non-empirical route to the knowledge that there is a table before her? But that seems absurd. How can it be possible to come to know specific facts about one’s environment through purely reflective processes?22 Let us grant for the sake of argument that these problems can be satisfactorily resolved and consider the distinctive approach epistemological disjunctivism, so understood, offers us for the problem of radical skepticism.23 On this view it is not just that one’s belief has a better epistemic standing in the good case than it does in the (skeptical) bad case. Rather, one’s belief in the good case has an epistemic standing which is factive (i.e., which entails the truth of the proposition believed) and which is also reflectively accessible to the subject. It follows that the subject has excellent—indeed, decisive—rational grounds available to her to prefer her everyday beliefs to radical skeptical alternatives. Hence, this version of epistemological disjunctivism can take a broadly “Moorean” line with radical skepticism and insist that we can know the denials of radical skeptical hypotheses after all. Moreover, this view can diagnose the enduring attraction of radical skepticism as being due to our having implicit philosophical commitments to such theses as (SES), theses which the epistemological disjunctivist argues we should jettison.24 One concern with this way of dealing with the problem of radical skepticism is that it can strike one as too strong. On this view, for example, it seems

662

SKEPTICISM

somewhat mysterious that the problem of radical skepticism has had such a hold on the philosophical imagination for so long. Doesn’t the radical skeptic succeed in highlighting anything important about the human epistemic condition? Moreover, given the difficulties which plague epistemological disjunctivism on this construal—problems which we have set to one side for now—this response to radical skepticism has an essentially contingent status. This inevitably diminishes somewhat the intellectual comfort that might be offered by this way of responding to radical skepticism.25,26

NOTES 1. Although support for naïve realism has grown. See Snowdon (1990), Campbell (2002; 2011), Martin (2004; 2006), Brewer (2007; 2011), and Fish (2009b). 2. This is how Martin (2004; 2006) formulates the argument from hallucination. 3. Note that the disjunctivist is not claiming that no theory of the nature of sensory experience can be given. Instead, she is claiming that no theory of the nature of sensory experience can be given which appeals to what is metaphysically common between perception and hallucination. Instead, she might recommend that the nature of sensory experience in general should be explained epistemologically: as our inability to know introspectively a perception from a metaphysically different kind of state. See Martin (2004) for an expression of this kind of theory. 4. Put another way, we might say that cases of hallucination that are indistinguishable from veridical perception are states in which we are not only misled about how the world is, but about how we are experientially: introspectively, we are apt to judge that we enjoy a veridical perception of some object, when in fact we suffer a mere appearance of a veridical perception of some object. See McDowell (2008) for this way of characterizing the relationship between hallucination and introspective knowledge. 5. See Martin (2002: 395n). 6. Cf. Martin (1997). 7. For recent work on whether the distinction is as deep as some philosophers of perception seem to suggest, see Brewer (2011) and Robinson (2012); For some useful recent overviews of the literature on disjunctivism, see Haddock & Macpherson (2009), Byrne & Logue (2009), Fish (2009a), Soteriou (2009), Brogaard (2010), and Dorsch (2011). 8. This is essentially the formulation of the closure principle put forward by Williamson (2000a: 117) and Hawthorne (2005: 29). 9. See Wright (2008) in particular for this view. 10. One might feel that this objection turns on the debate between the disjunctivist response to the argument from hallucination and illusion, and its rivals. After all, the disjunctivist will say that what makes it look like sense experience in general underdetermines the truth-value of propositions about the external world is an argument from hallucination/illusion, blocking the support for the thesis that compelling arguments establish that sense experiences underdetermines the truthvalue of those kinds of propositions.

DISJUNCTIVISM AND SKEPTICISM

663

11. See Pritchard (2010; 2012: part two) for further discussion of discrimination-style principles like (PD) and their role in an account of perceptual knowledge. 12. We are in effect here motivating (SES) by appeal to the so-called “new evil genius” thesis—roughly, that one has the same extent of epistemic support for one’s beliefs that one’s envatted counterpart enjoys for her beliefs. This is meant to be a core epistemological intuition that all epistemological theories must either accommodate or explain away. Epistemological disjunctivists opt for the latter horn—see, for example, Neta & Pritchard (2007) and Pritchard (2012: passim). The locus classicus for discussions of the new evil genius thesis is Lehrer and Cohen (1983). For an excellent survey of recent work on this topic, see Littlejohn (2009). 13. As McDowell (e.g., 1995) famously tends to put the point: we should reject a “highest common factor” conception of epistemic standing such that the epistemic standing enjoyed by one’s beliefs in the good case is no better than that available for one’s beliefs in the corresponding bad case. See Pritchard (2012: part one) for an elaboration of McDowell’s argument. 14. Various commentators have argued that epistemological disjunctivism does not in itself entail metaphysical disjunctivism. See, for example, Snowdon (2005), Millar (2007; 2008), Byrne and Logue (2008), McDowell (2008: 382n), and Pritchard (2008). In particular, the claim in this regard is often that epistemological disjunctivism is compatible with a causal theory of perceptual experience, as defended, for example, by Grice (1961) and Strawson (1974). For further discussion of the logical connections between metaphysical and epistemological disjunctivism, see Haddock & Macpherson (2008), Byrne and Logue (2009), Fish (2009a), Soteriou (2009: esp. §2.4), and Pritchard (2012: part one). 15. Note that we are here casting the epistemic externalism/internalism distinction along broadly accessibilist lines. That is, roughly, we are understanding an internalist epistemic condition such that its obtaining should be reflectively accessible to the subject, and hence treating an externalist epistemic condition such that it is not reflectively accessible to the subject. Although this is a fairly standard way of understanding the epistemic externalism/internalism distinction, it is far from being uncontroversial. This way of construing the distinction should suffice for our purposes, however. For a useful recent overview of the epistemic externalism/ internalism distinction, see Vahid (2011). 16. See Stroud (1989; 1994) for a subtle articulation of this kind of concern regarding standard epistemic externalist responses to radical skepticism. 17. For a variety of epistemological disjunctivism of an epistemic externalist stripe which is not pedestrian, see Williamson (2000), though note that he does not himself describe his view as being a variety of epistemological disjunctivism. What distinguishes this view from standard epistemic externalist proposals in this regard is that it is wedded to some further distinctive philosophical claims, such as that knowledge is a mental state. See Pritchard (2011b) for more on this point. Interestingly, some commentators, such as Brueckner (2010), explicitly run together the McDowellian-style epistemological disjunctivism put forward by Pritchard (e.g., 2012) and the kind of position defended by Williamson. 18. See also McDowell (1982; 1986; 1994a,b; 1995; 2002a; 2008; 2011) and Pritchard (2007; 2008; 2009; 2011a,b).

664

SKEPTICISM

19. Note that we are glossing over some of the nuances regarding the good/bad case distinction which are relevant to at least Pritchard’s rendering of this form of epistemological disjunctivism. See Pritchard (2012: part one) for more details. We are also side-stepping the issue of what the subject’s epistemic standing is in the bad case on this view. What is salient for our purposes is just that it falls well short of the factive rational support available to the subject in the good case. 20. Of an accessibilist variety at least (see note 16). See Neta and Pritchard (2007) and Pritchard (2011a; 2012: part one) for further discussion of how this form of epistemological disjunctivism should be understood in relation to the epistemic externalism/internalism distinction. 21. For a more extensive discussion of this difficulty, which he refers to as the “distinguishability problem,” see Pritchard (2012: part one). 22. For a more extensive discussion of this difficulty, which he refers to as the “access problem,” see Pritchard (2012: part one). The problem in play here is structurally akin to the so-called McKinsey problem which is held to afflict the combination of (some forms of) content externalism and first-person authority. See McKinsey (1991). 23. Pritchard (2011a; 2012: passim) claims that these problems—along with a third problem, which he refers to as the “basis problem” can be resolved. Note that the basis problem turns on an issue which we haven’t explored here—viz., whether seeing that p is a way of knowing that p. See Ranalli (2014) for a discussion of the issues in this regard. 24. See Pritchard (2008; 2009; 2012: part three) for a development of this way of exploiting epistemological disjunctivism to deal with the problem of radical skepticism. For a critical appraisal of this proposal, see Schönbaumsfeld (2013). 25. In more recent work, Pritchard (2015) has argued that epistemological disjunctivism of this variety should only be thought of as applying to that variety of radical skepticism which trades on the claim that the rational support we have for our beliefs is underdetermined with respect to radical skeptical scenarios. 26. This chapter was written as part of the AHRC-funded “Extended Knowledge” project which is hosted by the University of Edinburgh’s Eidyn Philosophical Research Centre, and we are grateful to the AHRC for their support of this research. Thanks also to Baron Reed for detailed comments on an earlier version of this chapter.

REFERENCES Brewer, Bill. 2007. “Perception and its Objects,” Philosophical Studies 132: 87–97. Brewer, Bill. 2011. Perception and its Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Brogaard, Berit. 2010. “Disjunctivism,” Oxford Bibliographies: Philosophy, DOI:10.1093/ OBO/9780195396577-0033. Brueckner, Anthony. 2010. “¬K¬SK.” In his Essays on Skepticism, 367–381. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Byrne, Alex and Heather Logue. 2008. “Either/Or.” In A. Haddock and F. Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, 57–94. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

DISJUNCTIVISM AND SKEPTICISM

665

Byrne, Alex and Heather Logue. 2009. “Introduction.” In A. Byrne and H. Logue Disjunctivism: Contemporary Readings, vii–xxix. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Campbell, John. 2002. Reference and Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Campbell, John. 2011. “Relational versus Kantian Responses to Berkeley’s Puzzle.” In J. Roessler, H. Lerman, and N. Eilan (eds.), Perception, Causation, and Objectivity, 35–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Conee, Earl. 2007. “Disjunctivism and Anti-Skepticism,” Philosophical Issues 17: 16–36. Dorsch, Fabian. 2011. “The Diversity of Disjunctivism,” European Journal of Philosophy 19: 304–314. Fish, William. 2009a. “Disjunctivism.” In B. Dowden and J. Fieser (eds.), Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://www.iep.utm.edu/d/disjunct.htm. Fish, William. 2009b. Perception, Hallucination, and Illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Grice, H. P. 1961. “The Causal Theory of Perception,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (suppl. vol.) 35: 121–152. Haddock, Adrian and Fiona Macpherson. 2008. “Introduction: Varieties of Disjunctivism.” In A. Haddock and F. Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, 1–24. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hawthorne, John. 2005. “The Case for Closure.” In E. Sosa and M. Steup (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 26–43. Oxford: Blackwell. Lehrer, Keith, and Stewart Cohen. 1983. “Justification, Truth, and Coherence,” Synthese 55: 191–207. Littlejohn, Clayton. 2009. “The New Evil Demon Problem.” In B. Dowden and J. Fieser (eds.), Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, www.iep.utm.edu/evil-new/. Martin, M. G. F. 1997. “The Reality of Appearances.” In M. Sainsbury (ed.), Thought and Ontology, 77–96. Milan: Franco Angeli. Martin, M. G. F. 2002. “Transparency of Experience,” Mind & Language 17, 376–425. Martin, M. G. F. 2004. “The Limits of Self-Awareness,” Philosophical Studies 120: 37–89. Martin, M. G. F. 2006. “On Being Alienated.” In T. S. Gendler and J. Hawthorne (eds.), Perceptual Experience, 354–410. Oxford: Oxford University Press. McDowell, John. 1982. “Criteria, Defeasibility and Knowledge,” Proceedings of the British Academy 68: 455–479. McDowell, John. 1986. “Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space.” In P. Pettit and J. McDowell (eds.), Subject, Thought and Context, 137–168. Oxford: Clarendon Press. McDowell, John. 1994a. “Knowledge by Hearsay.” In B. K. Matilal and A. Chakrabarti (eds.), Knowing from Words: Western and Indian Philosophical Analysis of Understanding and Testimony, 195–224. Dordrecht: Kluwer. McDowell, John. 1994b. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. McDowell, John. 1995. “Knowledge and the Internal,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55: 877–893. McDowell, John. 2002a. “Knowledge and the Internal Revisited,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64: 97–105. McDowell, John. 2002b. “Responses.” In N. H. Smith (ed.), Reading McDowell: On Mind and World. London: Routledge.

666

SKEPTICISM

McDowell, John. 2008. “The Disjunctive Conception of Experience as Material for a Transcendental Argument.” In A. Haddock and F. Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, 376–389. Oxford: Oxford University Press. McDowell, John. 2011. Perception as a Capacity for Knowledge. Milwaukee WI: Marquette University Press. McKinsey, Michael. 1991. “Anti-Individualism and Privileged Access,” Analysis 51: 9–16. Millar, Alan. 2007. “What the Disjunctivist is Right About,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 176–198. Millar, Alan. 2008. “Perceptual-Recognitional Abilities and Perceptual Knowledge.” In A. Haddock and F. Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, 330–347. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nagel, Thomas. 1974. “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?,” Philosophical Review 83: 435–450. Neta, Ram, and Duncan Pritchard. 2007. “McDowell and the New Evil Genius,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 381–396. Peacocke, Christopher. 1983. Sense and Content: Experience, Thought and Their Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pritchard, Duncan. 2007. “How to be a Neo-Moorean.” In S. Goldberg (ed.), Internalism and Externalism in Semantics and Epistemology, 68–99. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pritchard, Duncan. 2008. “McDowellian Neo-Mooreanism.” In A. Haddock and F. Macpherson, Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, 283–310. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pritchard, Duncan. 2009. “Wright Contra McDowell on Perceptual Knowledge and Skepticism,” Synthese 171: 467–479. Pritchard, Duncan. 2010. “Relevant Alternatives, Perceptual Knowledge and Discrimination,” Noûs 44: 245–268. Pritchard, Duncan. 2011a. “Epistemological Disjunctivism and the Basis Problem,” Philosophical Issues 21: 434–455. Pritchard, Duncan. 2011b. “Evidentialism, Internalism, Disjunctivism.” In T. Dougherty (ed.), Evidentialism and its Discontents, 362–392. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pritchard, Duncan. 2012. Epistemological Disjunctivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pritchard, Duncan. 2015 Epistemic Angst: Radical Skepticism and the Groundlessness of Our Believing. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Ranalli, Chris. 2014. “Luck, Propositional Perception, and the Entailment Thesis,” Synthese 191: 1223–1247. Robinson, Howard. 2012. “Relationalism versus Representationalism: How Deep is the Divide?” Philosophical Quarterly 62, 614–619. Russell, Bertrand. 1910. “Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 11: 108–128. Russell, Bertrand. 1912. The Problems of Philosophy. London: Home University Library. Schönbaumsfeld, Genia. 2013. “McDowellian Neo-Mooreanism?,” International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 3: 202–217. Snowdon, Paul. 1990. “The Objects of Perceptual Experience,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (suppl. vol.) 64: 121–150.

DISJUNCTIVISM AND SKEPTICISM

667

Snowdon, Paul. 2005. “The Formulation of Disjunctivism: A Response to Fish,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105, 129–141. Soteriou, Mathieu. 2009. “The Disjunctive Theory of Perception.” In E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/perception-disjunctive/. Strawson, P. F. 1974. “Causation in Perception.” In his Freedom and Resentment, 73–93, London: Methuen. Stroud, Barry. 1989. “Understanding Human Knowledge in General.” In M. Clay and K. Lehrer (eds.), Knowledge and Skepticism, 31–50. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Stroud. Barry. 1994. “Scepticism, ‘Externalism,’ and the Goal of Epistemology,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (suppl. vol.) 68: 291–307. Vahid, Hamid. 2011. “Externalism/Internalism.” In S. Bernecker and D. H. Pritchard (eds.), Routledge Companion to Epistemology, 144–155. London: Routledge. Williamson, Timothy. 2000. “Scepticism and Evidence,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60: 613–628. Wright, Crispin. 2008. “Comments on McDowell’s ‘The Disjunctive Conception of Experience as Material for a Transcendental Argument.’” In A. Haddock and F. Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, 390–404. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

CHAPTER FORTY-SIX

Inductive Skepticism: A Functional Investigation RUTH WEINTRAUB

1 INTRODUCTION I wish to present a new way of responding to skepticism and consider its application to inductive skepticism. The chapter is structured as follows. I present Hume’s argument in support of inductive skepticism (Section 2) and draw some distinctions between types of responses to skepticism (Section 3). Having explained what I mean by a “functional” response, I illustrate its application to Hume’s inductive skepticism (Sections 4–5).

2  HUME’S SKEPTICAL ARGUMENT AGAINST INDUCTION Hume’s argument against induction is presented in the course of his (complex) discussion of causality in the Treatise (1739: 1.3.4), and more succinctly and perspicuously in the Enquiries (1777: 35–36): (1) The conclusion of an inductive argument isn’t logically entailed by its premises. “Concerning matter [sic] of fact and existence,” Hume claims, “there are no demonstrative arguments . . . since it implies no contradiction that the course of nature may change . . . and the trees will flourish in December. . . . If we be, therefore, engaged by arguments to put trust in past experience . . . these arguments must be probable only” (1777: 35). (2) Every inductive argument assumes that nature is uniform; “that the future will be conformable to the past.” (3) The principle of the uniformity of nature, which must be warranted if induction is to be justified, cannot be justified a priori. (4) The principle of the uniformity of nature cannot be justified a posteriori since such a justification would be circular. It would itself be inductive,

INDUCTIVE SKEPTICISM: A FUNCTIONAL INVESTIGATION

669

inferring nature’s uniformity tout court from its observed uniformity, thus presupposing—like any inductive argument—that nature is uniform.

3  SOME DISTINCTIONS BETWEEN TYPES OF RESPONSE TO SKEPTICISM The first distinction I wish to draw is between combative and acquiescent responses to a skeptical claim. A combative response attempts to rebut the skeptical arguments adduced in support of the skeptical claim and show that the claim is, in fact, false. (These are two distinct aims.) This can be done in (at least) three ways. Russell (1948: 9) claims that we are justified in taking “for granted that scientific knowledge, in its broad outlines, is to be accepted,” because the skeptical doctrine cannot lastingly and steadily be believed, and anyone who preaches it is being “frivolous and insincere.” This is, perhaps, the least promising of combative responses. If skepticism is “logically impeccable” (Russell 1948: 9), the insincerity of its proponents does not show that it is false or that the arguments adduced in its support aren’t cogent. The second way of rejecting the skeptical conclusion is to take its implausibility as a reason for thinking that it is false (Reid 1764; Moore 1953; Chisholm 1982; Greco 2000). The third is to offer a diagnosis of the flaw in the seemingly cogent skeptical argument. It can be illustrated by considering the argument (in the form of a dilemma) adduced by Sextus Empiricus, the ancient Greek skeptic, to “set aside the method of induction”: When they propose to establish the universal from the particulars by means of induction, they will effect this by a review either of all or of some of the particular instances. But if they review some, the induction will be insecure, since some of the particulars omitted in the induction may contravene the universal; while if they are to review all, they will be toiling at the impossible, since the particulars are infinite and indefinite. [PH II 204; I follow Bury’s (1933) translation] In a similar (skeptical) vein, Popper suggests that “any conclusion drawn in this [inductive] way may always turn out to be false: no matter how many instances of white swans we may have observed, this does not justify the conclusion that all swans are white” (1972: 27, original italics). The argument can be rebutted (thereby exemplifying the third version of the combative strategy) by pointing out that justification is fallible. We can concede that the conclusion of an inductive argument may be false even if its premises are true, and that in this induction differs from, indeed falls short of, deduction. But that doesn’t mean, as the skeptic is (implicitly) assuming, that inductive grounds do not provide good reasons. The term “reason,” we will point out (Edwards 1949), doesn’t mean “logically conclusive,” and inductive grounds, despite being logically inconclusive, may well provide perfectly good reasons, thereby rendering their conclusions rational. Taking a risk, we will remind the skeptic (and ourselves), may be eminently reasonable. It is rational, for instance, to take a medicine one thinks

670

SKEPTICISM

is very likely, although uncertain, to cure a horrible disease even if it sometimes has pretty unpleasant side-effects. In contrast to a combative response to skepticism, an acquiescent response accepts the skeptical claim (as true). This might engender distress, as it does in Hume. When ruminating about his skeptical findings, he says: The wretched condition, weakness, and disorder of the faculties, I must employ in my enquiries, encreases my apprehensions. And the impossibility of amending or correcting these faculties, reduces me almost to despair. (1739: 264) But this (woeful) reaction isn’t mandatory. Even if we accept the skeptical claim, we might try to take the sting out of it. Perhaps—initial appearances notwithstanding— the skeptical claim isn’t as threatening as it seems to be, because it doesn’t deny us something valuable. We can neutralize the skeptical claim in two ways. The first is illustrated by Sextus Empiricus. He is unperturbed by the skeptical conclusion because he is not interested in the cognitive endeavors that it impugns. He aims to attain peace of mind (ataraxia), an aim that acceptance of the skeptical conclusion may actually promote (PH I 25–30). Even if (contentiously) Sextus’s psychological claim is sound, it is irrelevant if our perspective is epistemological (rather than practical, for instance). But the skeptical claim about induction may have no sting even if our interest is cognitive. The fact that induction is unjustified doesn’t constitute a threat to our rationality if the practice the claim brands as irrational isn’t ours. This eliminativist response to inductive skepticism provides us with a distinct way of rejecting Broad’s (1952: 143) memorable claim that induction is “the glory of science and the scandal of philosophy.” Inductive skepticism may well be “a skeleton in the cupboard of Inductive Logic” (Broad 1952: 143), but the cupboard isn’t ours! In this (eliminativist) vein, Popper (1972) claims that science doesn’t invoke induction. It progresses by formulating bold hypotheses and subjecting them to rigorous tests. The only mode of reasoning it requires, Popper claims, is deduction. Predictions (“observation statements”) are deductively derived from hypotheses, and, when observationally refuted, a theory is deductively falsified: if T├ E, then ~E├ ~T. We may now cheerfully concede the skeptical conclusion—that induction is irrational. Since science does not invoke induction, its rational credentials are not thereby impugned. We could shrug aside, or at least belittle the significance of, the skeptical claim, even if it concerns our practice, a practice that we deem to be valuable. This might sound paradoxical, but I have in mind the possibility that the skeptical claim pertains to an epistemological concept (“justification,” “knowledge”) that is needlessly stringent. Our beliefs, which never count as “justified” (“known”) when assessed in the light of our concept of justification (knowledge), can, nonetheless, measure up to the requirements of some other concept that is well-worth falling under (cognitively speaking). To see whether the skeptical claim denies us something valuable, we need to know what the point is of imposing the requirements the concept embodies, what role it plays in our cognitive lives. Focusing on such considerations is the hallmark of the functional response to skepticism.

INDUCTIVE SKEPTICISM: A FUNCTIONAL INVESTIGATION

671

The functional approach to the study of a concept is attractive for three reasons. First, it will deliver a better understanding of the concept than that provided by (extensionally adequate) necessary and sufficient conditions for its application.1 Second, it enables us to bypass the (vexing) question as to the real meaning(s) of the term “justification” (“knowledge”), in the discussion of which so much energy has been invested.2 Surely it is far more important to decide which (epistemic) labels are worth fighting for, and whether these battles can be won. These questions may be answered while remaining neutral about the actual meaning(s) of the term “justified” (“knows”). Of course, we should—as a result of the investigation—adopt a useful concept of justification (knowledge), but for that we don’t need to know whether we are retaining or supplanting an existing one. The third (and final) advantage of a functional investigation is that it might (depending on its outcome) enable us to contend with an impeccable skeptical argument. The skeptical conclusion may be true with respect to a concept that the functional analysis reveals to be inappropriate, or at least, to have a non-skeptical alternative that is “good enough.” The functional perspective changes the rules of engagement with the skeptic. Correct usage of the relevant term (“justification,” “knowledge”) is no longer necessary for success, and this can work to the advantage of both sides. The skeptic is often accused of distorting our epistemic standards (Schmitt 1992: 7–10). He is likened to someone who claims that there are no physicians in New York and turns out to mean by the term “physician” someone who can cure any disease in ten seconds (Edwards 1949). Once this nonstandard usage is discerned, it is argued, it becomes clear that the skeptic is not disputing with us, that he is “changing the subject” (BonJour 1985: 37). But from the functional perspective, the skeptic cannot be silenced in this way. If the concept he is invoking is epistemologically important, our failure to measure up to it is damning, even if our concept is more permissive and significantly less vulnerable to skepticism. The converse is also true. Suppose the skeptic is using an epistemological concept (knowledge or justification) correctly and exposes its skeptical implications. Nonetheless, like any tool, a concept may turn out to be ill-suited for the use to which it is put. And our investigation could reveal that our concept is needlessly stringent, and that we are doing well according to a new concept that is suitably stringent. Since we aim to assess the usefulness of proposed concepts, rather than to analyze existing ones, we will be indifferent to linguistic intuitions—an important tool employed in the old-fashioned style of analysis. That we do not count as justified a lucky guess shows that truth is insufficient for justification (knowledge) as we use the term(s), but considerations of a different kind should be invoked to show that counting a lucky guess as “justified” (known) leaves out something epistemologically crucial. The suggestion that we should focus on the point of concepts is not new. The function and significance of knowledge attributions is explored by Craig (1987), Sartwell (1992), Papineau (1992), Brandom (1998), and Kaplan (2008), and that of justification by Alston (1988), Lycan (1988: ch. 7), Plantinga (1990), Bergmann

672

SKEPTICISM

(2000), and Weiner (2005), to name but a few. But my aim is significantly different. First, my interest is not restricted to extant concepts, so the outcome of the investigation may be a revision of our usage. Second, although I will be considering a particular (reliabilist) concept of justification, it is by way of illustrating the functional response and the way it transforms the debate. Other concepts could turn out to be more appropriate. If in our analysis we are not bound by our concepts, it might be wondered, how do we determine whether a proposed concept is adequate? We cannot, ex hypothesi, appeal to our intuitions about its application in particular cases, and general platitudes about epistemic justification—for instance, that it is an evaluative concept that has something to do with truth—do not suffice to pick out a sufficiently determinate concept. The answer is twofold. First, we can consider the point of concepts picked out by proposed analyses of our concept(s) of justification. Although we are not concerned with the extensional adequacy of an analysis, still, it picks out a concept that is of the right sort, and worth considering (functionally). Second, we can discern features of a concept of justification from skeptical arguments. We can then consider the point of having a concept with these features and the loss attending the adoption of a concept that lacks them. For instance, if the skeptic invokes a necessary condition for justification (that he aims to show cannot be satisfied), we will consider the point of imposing the condition. With these clarificatory points in mind, I will now consider Hume’s argument against induction from the functional perspective. From this perspective, we cannot assume that the argument is concerned with justification (and not, for instance, knowledge), because we are interested in (epistemological) concepts that may not even be ours. But Hume’s argument is best construed as targeting the justification (as determined by our concept) of inductive inferences.3 So to facilitate the exposition, I will call the concepts I will be considering concepts of justification. These may well not be our concept(s) of justification, since my interest is in those that violate conditions that the argument imposes, conditions the skeptic thinks—with at least some plausibility—are incorporated by our concept(s).

4  A FUNCTIONAL RESPONSE TO HUME’S SKEPTICAL ARGUMENT AGAINST INDUCTION I start by slightly modifying the argument, so as to make it more perspicuous and easier to consider functional responses to it. The reformulated argument will also enable us to see how the functional strategy can be applied to other skeptical claims (pertaining, for instance, to deduction, sense-perception, and inference to the best explanation). What does it mean to say that nature is uniform? It can’t mean that all generalizations (not even those that we can formulate in our language) are true. First, some generalizations, “All ravens are black” and “All ravens are white,” for instance, are mutually contradictory.4 Second, if it did mean that, there would be no need to rely on positive instances of a generalization to infer its truth. Accepting

INDUCTIVE SKEPTICISM: A FUNCTIONAL INVESTIGATION

673

nature’s uniformity would render induction otiose. Finally, if this is how nature’s uniformity is construed, then a single counterexample to a generalization would falsify the principle of uniformity. But we don’t take a black swan to refute the principle of uniformity (Ayer 1972: 22)! The suggestion that nature is uniform if most generalizations (formulable in our language) are true fails for a similar reason. If all ravens are black, then “All ravens are white,” “All ravens are green,” etc., are all false. So every true generalization brings in its wake several that are false. The suggestion that nature is uniform if as many generalizations as possible are true fails, too. It entails that if there is one black raven, all ravens are black. But we don’t take the observation of a black raven and a white raven (for instance) to show that nature is not uniform. If the principle of uniformity is invoked when we reason inductively, it must mean that sufficiently many generalizations (that we can formulate in our language) are true. The idea is that there aren’t too many generalizations with both positive instances and counterexamples. The principle is quite vague, but this is harmless. The argument purports to show that the invocation of the principle is illicit whatever the degree of uniformity the principle assumes (so long as it is positive, i.e., nature isn’t perfectly chaotic, and the principle is not a logical truth). Note, next, that the principle of uniformity is true if and only if induction is reliable. Putting these two insights together, we can reformulate the argument against induction: If a belief derived inductively is to be justified, the argument’s first (“internalist”) premise suggests, induction must be justifiably believed to be reliable.5 Without “a patent of trustworthiness—a soundness argument—for a putative rule,” Howson (2000: 28–29) argues, “you have no reason for confidence in any reasoning which employs it.” How are we to establish that induction is reliable (that nature is uniform, to use Hume’s terminology)? Since the claim is contingent6 and (very) general, it cannot be basic: it must, that is, be justified inferentially (Fumerton 1995; Van Cleve 2003). But this inference, Hume argues, is inductive, based on induction’s track record. So—by the first premise—it is subject to the same requirement: to be justified, induction must first be shown to be reliable. And we have a vicious circularity: induction’s reliability must be established prior to reasoning inductively, but it can only be established by inductive reasoning. Inductively derived beliefs, the argument concludes, are unjustified. For ease of exposition, I will label this “Hume’s argument against induction” (and sometimes “the argument against induction”), although Hume’s actual argument is slightly different.7 The interpretive inaccuracy is harmless in our context. My interest is in inductive skepticism, but the argument against induction can be modified so as to apply to other belief-acquisition methods, such as inference to the best explanation, perception, and deduction: (1) If a belief, p, derived by a method, M, is to be justified, M must be justifiably believed to be reliable. (Call this the “internalist” premise.)

674

SKEPTICISM

(2) The belief that M is reliable (call it q) is itself acquired via a method, M' (which may be identical with M.) (3) In order for q to be justified, its acquisition method, M', must be justifiably believed to be reliable. (4) The justification of p involves a chain of uses of methods, each giving rise to the belief that the previous use of a method is a use of a reliable method. (5) The chain of methods required for p to be justified is either circular or infinite or terminating (with a belief that isn’t justified by another). (6) None of the possibilities canvassed in (5) makes for genuine justification. (7) Conclusion: p is unjustified. Hume’s original argument cannot be generalized in this way (so that it applies to other acquisition methods in addition to induction). Such a generalization requires that some “super principle” be added to each inference. But it is not clear what the analogue to the principle of the uniformity of nature is in the case of inference to the best explanation or perception. What, for instance, does it mean to say that nature is intelligible (explicable)? That inference to the best explanation is a reliable beliefacquisition method, by way of contrast, makes perfect sense. I propose to consider a concept of justification that doesn’t satisfy the internalist requirement on the justification of inductive inference—reliabilism—and isn’t, therefore, vulnerable to the modified version of Hume’s argument. Reliabilists (Braithwaite 1953; Goldman 1979; Van Cleve 1984; Greco 2000) think that an inference rule has to be reliable if its invocation is to be justified, but it may be justifiably used by one who doesn’t believe that it is reliable. The reliabilist concept of justification, call it R-justification, is satisfied by beliefs that result from a reliable process—one whose products are typically true.8 Thus, a belief derived inductively is R-justified if and only if induction is (sufficiently) reliable, and the premises (of the inductive argument) are (sufficiently) reliably acquired. I am not interested in reliabilism as such. It merely serves to illustrate in a very simple fashion how the functional strategy is to be implemented and how the functional perspective transforms the debate with the skeptic. We could consider concepts that violate other premises of the argument, and non-reliabilist concepts that violate the internalist requirement. Indeed, this is what we should do if our aim is a comprehensive exploration of the functional response. From the functional perspective, the focus is on the point of imposing the internalist requirement. We wish to know why internalist justification matters and how severe is the (epistemic) loss incurred by the adoption of non-internalist concepts. From this perspective, familiar, and seemingly very forceful, objections are rendered irrelevant, and new questions come to the fore. Our prospects in the dispute with the skeptic are quite bright. His argument, which may have seemed invincible when couched in terms of the internalist concept of justification, collapses once our attention turns to R-justification. Our new concept is unabashedly externalist, and renders the first premise false!

INDUCTIVE SKEPTICISM: A FUNCTIONAL INVESTIGATION

675

What of an alternative skeptical argument to establish the impossibility of R-justification? The skeptic’s task now is to show that induction isn’t reliable. And, again, his prospects aren’t bright: induction’s track record is pretty good.9 Moreover, in pointing this out, we will be taking the offensive and showing the skeptical claim to be false. It will, of course, be objected that showing induction’s reliability by appealing to its track record is circular and, therefore, illicit. Isn’t this one of Hume’s truistic premises? The objection is natural but mistaken. Hume’s assumption that circular justification is illicit is eminently plausible given the internalist requirement. If induction’s reliability has to be presupposed—as a premise—when invoking induction, then inductively inferring induction’s reliability is viciously circular. The circular justification of propositions is non-discriminating: every proposition entails itself. But in adopting the concept of R-justification, we deny the first premise (of the modified argument). And the question now is whether the invocation of an inference rule to show that it is reliable is similarly illegitimate because trivial. The answer is No. Even if we are allowed to invoke an inference rule in its own justification, success is not guaranteed. The horoscope may predict the unreliability of its predictions and the superiority of an alternative method of prediction (Lewis 1971). The same is true of the circular justification of induction. Consider the inductive rule I1: Most observed A’s have been B’s ____________________________ I1 The next A will be B The rule I1 can be defended by invoking the following inductive argument, utilizing I1 itself: Most applications of I1 have been successful ____________________________ I1 The next use of I1 will be successful Note that the premise is contingent, and the self-supporting defense can (logically) fail. Indeed, it does fail in the case of the following inductive rule, I2: All observed A’s have been B’s __________________________ I2 The next A will be B The (circular) justification fails, since the requisite premise is false: All applications of I2 have been successful __________________________ I2 The next use of I2 will be successful10

676

SKEPTICISM

We can now answer Alston’s contention that track-record arguments “do not serve to discriminate between reliable and unreliable doxastic practices,” even if their conclusion—that a method is reliable—is (reliabilistically) justified (1993: 17, my italics). “We can just as well say of crystal ball gazing,” he explains, “that if it is reliable, we can use a track record argument to show that it is reliable” (1993: 17, original italics). But what is the “discrimination” that reliabilistically justified beliefs fail to achieve? It can’t be that the track-record argument makes justification too easy to achieve, that it can be invoked to vindicate doxastic methods that are “crazy”—crystal ball gazing, for instance. The success of the argument requires that the method be self-certifying and reliable. Crystal ball gazing fails (we think) at least the second condition. (It will pass the first only if the crystal ball certifies itself. And this may fail to obtain.) We are not yet home and dry. Competing rules can be invoked in their own defense (Salmon 1957: 46). Consider the anti-inductive rule, AI, which allows us to infer from “Most observed A’s have been B’s” that the next A will not be a B. We can construct an argument with true premises utilizing AI to show that AI will be successful: Most applications of AI have not been successful _________________________ AI The next use of AI will be successful The answer is that self-certification, “immodesty” (Lewis 1971), isn’t sufficient for the justification of an inference rule. In citing it, I simply want to show that invoking an inference rule to show its reliability isn’t trivial. And the fact that another (“crazy”) inference rule is also self-certifying doesn’t put it on a par with induction. To be sure, its proponents might also attempt to use it to infer its reliability. But whereas our belief in induction’s reliability is R-justified, their belief in the reliability of their rule isn’t! I am assuming that induction (unlike anti-induction, for instance) is reliable. If it isn’t, then our (circular) way of establishing its reliability won’t work: its conclusion won’t be R-justified. But the point still stands. A circular vindication isn’t trivial, and cannot be invoked equally successfully by rivals that are in serious opposition.11 Here are the two most telling objections that have been leveled against reliabilism. The first is the extensional inadequacy of the analysis. The demon’s victim shows, Cohen (1985) claims, that reliabilism is too stringent. And several examples have been adduced to show that reliabilism is too lenient. The most familiar one is BonJour’s clairvoyant agent, who thinks she has no clairvoyant powers and seems intuitively unjustified in her (reliably acquired) beliefs (1985: 43). But my favorite is Vogel’s Roxanne (2000: 313–314). Her car has a reliable gas gauge, and she uses it to form beliefs about how much gas there is in the tank of her car. She also forms beliefs about the gauge’s readings by looking at it. Both beliefs are reliably acquired: the gauge and her perception are (sufficiently) reliable. By conjoining these two types of belief, Roxanne forms several beliefs of the form: The gauge reads “F” (“E”) and F (E). She now reasons inductively from these conjunctions and concludes that the

INDUCTIVE SKEPTICISM: A FUNCTIONAL INVESTIGATION

677

gauge is reliable. Since induction is reliable, her belief is justified by reliabilist lights but is intuitively (resoundingly) unjustified.12 Perhaps reliabilists can explain away these putative counterexamples. But from our functional perspective, we can ignore them even if we find them convincing. We are not trying to capture our concept of justification, and are allowing for a revision of our concept(s).13 But there is a difficulty we cannot shrug aside, the revisionary nature of our proposal notwithstanding: the “generality problem,” described by Heller (1995: 501) as “the most formidable challenge to . . . [the] reliability theory.” Reliabilists define the (degree of) justification of a belief as the (degree of) reliability of the process via which it was acquired. Thus, a belief is justified to the extent that it is engendered by a doxastic process the relative frequency of truths among whose products is (sufficiently) high. The problem is that a particular belief is a token of indefinitely many process types, with different attendant frequencies of truth. My belief that the sun will rise tomorrow is inductively formed, formed by a woman, formed on Tuesday, etc. And the reliabilist needs a principled way of picking out a unique description if his notion of justification is to be well defined. The revisionary reliabilist can bypass the generality problem, at least when he is contending with Hume’s skeptical argument against induction. The argument pertains to the use of induction, which is an acquisition method, and not a belief that falls under (indefinitely) many descriptions. (The same is true for the reliabilist who is attempting to contend with skeptical arguments that purport to impugn other acquisition methods: perception, deduction, inference to the best explanation, and memory). But the generality problem will resurface when he tries to vindicate particular beliefs derived by induction—that the sun will rise tomorrow, for instance. For this, it is not enough to vindicate the inductive inference rule. The belief will have other descriptions, and the reliabilist will have to eliminate them if he is to invoke the R-justification of induction. He will also have to assign the belief in the premise (that the sun has hitherto always risen) an acquisition method (perception or testimony) so as to show that it is R-justified. Without this, the conclusion of the inductive inference will only be conditionally R-justified—that is, justified if the premise is justified.

5  TAKING STOCK We can now attempt to assess our epistemic situation from a reliabilist perspective, remembering that the purpose of the (possibly revisionary) exercise is to see how well we would fare relative to an alternative, non-internalist, justificatory standard. We are able to fend off Hume’s skeptical challenge. But this—by itself—is not enough to allay our worries: skepticism is true relative to another standard of justification, one that does include the internalist requirement. So should we be concerned? From the functional perspective, the question is what we lose by relinquishing the internalist requirement for justification and why R-justification matters (by way

678

SKEPTICISM

of compensation). The internalist requirement may have more than one rationale, but here is one suggestion. To decide whether a claim is true (and the belief in its truth is justified), one must test it by reference to a criterion of truth. I will now explain and defend the suggestion. The criterial conception of justification is as old as epistemology. According to Sextus Empiricus, “Those who claim for themselves to judge the truth are bound to possess a criterion of truth . . . For no matter of dispute is to be trusted without judging” (AM VII 340; I follow Bury’s (1935) translation). Descartes, too, searches for a criterion of truth: “Everything which I clearly and distinctly perceive is of necessity true. . . . I was ignorant of this rule for establishing the truth” (CSM II: 48–49, my italics). Descartes’s conception of a criterion differs from Sextus’s in two respects. His criterion is infallible: a belief that satisfies it is true. And it is universal, applicable to all propositions, whereas Sextus allows for two propositions being adjudicated by reference to two different criteria. It is fairly easy to see that the criterial conception of justification brings in its wake the internalist requirement. In applying a criterion, one must believe that it is reliable, sufficiently well correlated with that which it serves to identify. Thus, the physician who uses red spots as a criterion for measles believes that having red spots is correlated with measles. So if acquisition by induction is to function as a criterion of truth, the property inductively acquired must be believed to be (sufficiently well) correlated with truth; induction, that is, must be believed to be reliable. And since this belief is a premise in an argument supporting the belief (say) that the sun will rise tomorrow, it must be justified. We have now got the internalist requirement. (There is an additional requirement the criterial conception engenders, which is not pertinent to our concern. In properly applying a criterion to decide that X is, indeed, the case, one must believe that X satisfies the criterion.) For Descartes’s criterion, clarity and distinctness (however understood), we get an analogous requirement: to be justified in a belief, the agent must justifiably believe that clarity and distinctness are reliable indicators of truth. (He must also believe that the belief is clear and distinct.)14 Appropriate requirements go with other (putative) truth criteria. The criterial conception of justification renders it unattainable. Hume’s argument shows this for acquisition by induction as a criterion, and Sextus’s criterion argument shows it more generally: Those who claim for themselves to judge the truth are bound to possess a criterion of truth. This criterion, then, either is without a judge’s approval or has been approved. But if it is without approval, whence comes it that it is trustworthy? For no matter of dispute is to be trusted without judging. And if it has been approved, that which approves it, in turn, either has been approved or has not been approved, and so on ad infinitum. (AM VII 340)15 How serious is our predicament? Sosa (1994) thinks that the very fact that a desire turns out to be necessarily unattainable means that we should give it up. If an objective turns out “to be unfulfillable,” he asks rhetorically, “Is it reasonable . . . to insist that somehow the objective is still worthy?” Well, it may well be. Of course,

INDUCTIVE SKEPTICISM: A FUNCTIONAL INVESTIGATION

679

in such a case, one would be advised “to put [one’s] time to better use” (Sosa 1994: 287), stop treating it as an “objective” in the practical sense. It is, of course, silly, to look for a truth-criterion. But that is different from deeming it worthless. It seems to me that there is nothing incoherent (as opposed to strange) about wishing the circle could be squared, even if we know it is mathematically impossible. What is silly is to look for ways of doing it. The same is true for the unsatisfiable desire to have a truth-criterion. And it isn’t even strange. If we cannot dismiss the criterial conception of justification because it renders justification unattainable, we must (more messily) consider whether Sextus Empiricus is right in thinking that without a criterion we are like “people . . . searching for gold in a dark room containing many treasures. . . . None of them will be convinced that he has lighted on the gold, even though, in fact, he has lighted upon it” (AM VII 52). Of course, given the criterial conception of justification, the analogy is apt: we are never “justified.” But from the functional perspective, this needn’t constitute a serious predicament even if our concept of justification is criterial. And, conversely, it may be a predicament if our concept isn’t criterial but should be. To assess our epistemological situation, we should consider the point of non-criterial concepts of justification, reliabilism, for instance. Our question, more precisely, is whether we should value a belief’s being R-justified. A positive answer will complete the vindication of an acquiescent response to Hume’s argument, enabling us to accept its conclusion with equanimity. Remember, the skeptical challenge to the R-justification of induction fails on two counts: the argument adduced in its support isn’t sound and its conclusion is false. There are two (complementary) responses the reliabilist can give so as to meet this challenge. The first invokes the fact that R-justification is truth-conducive, so a belief that is R-justified is likely to be true. This is, of course, a good thing. Note, too, that not every truth-conducive property of beliefs enables us to meet the (corresponding) skeptical challenge. Consider the theological concept of justification, G-justified, which applies to a belief just in case God holds it. This concept is perfectly truthconducive (assuming—for the sake of the example—that God exists), because God is doxastically perfect: he believes all truths and no falsehoods. But our position visà-vis the G-justification skeptic is inauspicious. To be sure, the skeptic cannot show that God does not believe (say) that the sun will rise tomorrow. But neither can we show that He does (so that our belief that it will rise is G-justified). The skeptical argument against the R-justification of induction, by way of contrast, is unsound and its conclusion is false. We might be able to find yet another way in which R-justification is valuable by considering the Meno problem (raised in Plato’s dialogue), which challenges us to explain why knowledge is more valuable than (mere) true belief. The relevance of the Meno problem to ours is easy to discern, the differences between the two notwithstanding. The Meno problem pertains to the value of knowledge, and ours to that of R-justification. But this only means that we will not be interested in the full plethora of solutions to the Meno problem, only in those that pertain to knowledge construed as true belief reliably acquired. And we can also take in our stride the fact that an answer to the Meno problem might invoke a feature of knowledge that—unlike R-justification—presupposes truth (while going beyond

680

SKEPTICISM

it). We will only consider solutions to the Meno problem that locate the added value of knowledge in reliable acquisition. Zagzebski claims (2003) that reliable acquisition has only instrumental value. Forming beliefs in a reliable manner is valuable because they are more likely to be true. So a true belief isn’t more valuable than a true belief reliably acquired, just as a good cup of coffee made by a reliable coffee machine isn’t more valuable than an equally good cup of coffee that is produced by an unreliable coffee machine. Brogaard (2006) demurs. The coffee-machine analogy isn’t apt, she claims, because it is based on a flawed conception of the good, according to which two things that are identical in their intrinsic properties have the same intrinsic value. Although this is true in the case of coffee, she continues, it isn’t true in general, because the distinction between intrinsic and instrumental value isn’t exhaustive. As Rabinowicz and Roennow-Rassmussen (1999) point out, value may derive from an object’s being extrinsically related to something else that we value. For instance, we value Princess Diana’s dress more than an exact copy because it belonged to Diana. In a similar fashion, we value one true belief over another because it was produced by a reliable cognitive trait, which is independently valuable. I will not attempt to adjudicate the Meno question (with the reliabilist slant we have adopted on it). I use it so as to provide another illustration of the way the “functional turn” transforms the debate with the skeptic: the “value question” now becomes part and parcel of our engagement with the skeptic. It is sometimes claimed that an analysis of knowledge that cannot explain its distinctive value is thereby shown to be erroneous (Zagzebski 1999; Sosa 2000). This may be doubted, but even if it is true, there is—from a functional perspective—a much more important lesson to be learned from such a failure. It shows that we should be unperturbed by failing to satisfy the concept the analysis determines, and that skeptical arguments targeting it can be shrugged aside. An acquiescent strategy is here appropriate.

6 CONCLUSION I do not have a verdict to offer with respect to the success of the functional response to Hume’s skeptical argument. I considered only one rationale for a premise of the argument and only one concept that doesn’t satisfy it (and renders the argument unsound). But I have pointed out the way the discussion should be conducted so as to yield a verdict.

ACKNOWLEDGMENT I am grateful to the editors for their painstaking and perceptive comments. This research was supported by the ISRAEL Science Foundation (grant No. 366/14).

NOTES 1. Craig (1987) goes even further. He suggests that the concept of knowledge cannot be given a traditional analysis, because it doesn’t have (informative) conditions that are (individually) necessary and (jointly) sufficient for its application.

INDUCTIVE SKEPTICISM: A FUNCTIONAL INVESTIGATION

681

2. I use the plural, because it is claimed (Swinburne 2001; Alston 2005) that there are (in English) several concepts of justification. Similarly, there may well be more than one concept of knowledge. 3. We may be misconstruing Hume. Perhaps he isn’t claiming that induction isn’t justified, only arguing against a rationalist conception of justification (Garrett 1997). But the purpose of my exploration isn’t interpretive. My concern is with an argument that may be suggested by Hume’s text, even if it isn’t his. 4. I owe this point to Baron Reed. 5. I add yet another way of using the term “internalism.” It is hitherto used in (at least) five different ways. There is, first, the doctrine that requires for the justification of a belief (inference rule) a second-order justified belief about the factors that make first-order justification possible (Van Cleve 2003). This usage is closest to mine. The difference is that unlike mine, Van Cleve’s doesn’t require the second-order belief to be justified before (independently of) the first-order belief in order for it to be legitimately invoked in its justification. According to the second variety of internalism, epistemic status supervenes on facts about the subject’s mental states. According to the third, the subject must be able to tell by reflection that his belief (inference rule) is justified. According to the fourth, the subject constitutes the conditions of justification: a belief (inference rule) is justified just in case the subject thinks it is. The last two doctrines Schmitt (1992) aptly labels “accessibility internalism” and “perspectival internalism,” respectively. The fifth sense is found in Plantinga (1990) and Sosa (1994). They use the term to denote the doctrine that a belief can be justified and amount to knowledge only through the backing of reasons or arguments. On this usage, internalism stands in opposition to foundationalism. 6. Hume belabors this point, but to us the claim seems truistic. 7. The difference is that in Hume’s original argument, there is premise circularity: the principle of the uniformity of nature is assumed in the proof of itself. The modified argument, by way of contrast, purports to discern in our practice epistemic circularity: a faculty (belief-acquisition method) is used to prove itself reliable. I am grateful to Baron Reed for pressing me to clarify this. 8. We do not here have to decide whether the preponderance of truths is to be found in a method’s actual outputs, potential outputs in all possible worlds, or (Alston 2005) potential outputs in (sufficiently) similar worlds. 9. This is not true in general. Hume’s argument doesn’t conclude that induction isn’t reliable. But the “bad lot” argument against inference to the best explanation (van Fraassen 1989: 142–150) purports to show that it is an unreliable inference rule. It takes us to the best explanation among those we have considered. And even if the best explanation is likely to be true, we have no reason to suppose that the best explanation is to be found among the theories we have considered. Indeed, van Fraassen argues (1989: 146), it is very likely that among the explanations we haven’t considered there are many that are as good as (or even better than) the explanation that is the best among those we have considered. Stanford (2006) adduces historical evidence to support the claim that scientists choose from theories to which there are unconsidered rivals that explain equally well or even better. For instance, the evidence available to proponents of Aristotelian science was equally well (or even better) explained by Newtonian science (which they didn’t consider).

682

SKEPTICISM

10. Black (1958) points out that a circular justification of a rule involves no formal circularity. But this difference between the circular justification of an inference rule and that of a proposition doesn’t seem significant. 11. A rival rule to induction that diverges from it only very occasionally can be invoked to show its own reliability. But the two rules are roughly equally reliable, and the conclusions of the two (circular) arguments have the same truth-value. So this failure of self-certification to be unique isn’t damaging. To be sure (as Baron Reed pointed out), the two rules may diverge with respect to some important claim, and for every claim, there will be two very (but imperfectly) reliable rules that diverge over it. But this is beside the present point—that reliabilist self-certification is genuine: it works only for reliable methods. 12. Conjunctions of reliabilistically acquired beliefs are typically not as likely to be true as the conjuncts. Two methods may count as reliable by reference to some threshold, yet the reliability rate of the combined method might fall below it. But we may suppose that overall, conjunction is sufficiently reliable. 13. Is Quine (1973) a revisionary reliabilist? There are three reasons for resisting the suggestion. First, it is not clear that he repudiates the old (validatory) project (answering the old skeptic): “Our liberated epistemologist ends up as an empirical psychologist, scientifically investigating man’s acquisition of science. . . . Yet it is no gratuitous change of subject matter, but an enlightened persistence rather in the original epistemological problem. It is enlightened in recognizing that the skeptical challenge springs from science itself, and that in coping with it we are free to use scientific knowledge. The old epistemologist failed to recognize the strength of his position” (1973: 3). Since the skeptic is invoking science against us, we can answer him using science. Second, to the extent that Quine’s project (explaining knowledge) is revisionary, it recommends that epistemology jettison normative questions altogether, replacing them with empirical ones. Revisionary reliabilism, by way of contrast, is still normative: it replaces our concept of justification with another. Finally, Quine’s aim is to explain “how it is that man works up his command of that science from the limited impingements that are available to his sensory surfaces” (1973: 3), to explain the acquisition of knowledge. To say that a belief is reliably acquired isn’t terribly explanatory. 14. According to Van Cleve (1979), Descartes doesn’t think that the agent must believe a belief is clear and distinct if it is to be justified. It is, rather, the epistemologist who identifies clarity and distinctness as features that render a belief (externalistically) justified. 15. If Descartes doesn’t subscribe to the full-blooded criterial conception of justification (see n. 11), he isn’t vulnerable to Sextus’s argument.

REFERENCES Alston, William. 1993. The Reliability of Sense Perception. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Alston, William. 2005. Beyond “Justification”: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Ayer, A. J. 1972. Probability and Evidence. London: Macmillan.

INDUCTIVE SKEPTICISM: A FUNCTIONAL INVESTIGATION

683

Bergmann, Michael. 2000. “Externalism and Skepticism,” Philosophical Review 109: 159–194. Black, Max. 1958. “Self-Supporting Inductive Arguments.” In R. Swinburne (ed.), The Justification of Induction, 127–134. Oxford: Oxford University Press. BonJour, Laurence. 1985. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Braithwaite, R. B. 1953. Scientific Explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Brandom, Robert. 1998. “Insights and Blindspots of Reliabilism,” The Monist 81: 371–392. Broad, C.D. 1952. “The Philosophy of Francis Bacon.” In C.D. Broad, Ethics and the History of Philosophy, 117–143. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Brogaard, Berit. 2006. “Can Virtue Reliabilism Explain the Value of Knowledge?” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36: 335–354. Chisholm, Roderick. 1982. Foundations of Knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Cohen, Stewart. 1985. “Reliability and Justification,” The Monist 68: 149–158. Craig, Edward. 1987. “The Practical Explication of Knowledge,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87: 211–226. Descartes, René. 1628. Philosophical Works of Descartes, vol. 2, translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985. Edwards, Paul. 1949. “Russell’s Doubts about Induction,” Mind 68: 141–163. Fumerton, Richard. 1995. Metaepistemology and Skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. Garrett, Don. 1997. Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Goldman, Alvin. 1979. “What is Justified Belief?” In G. Pappas (ed.), Justification and Knowledge: New Studies in Epistemology, 1–23. Dordrecht: Reidel. Greco, John. 2000. Putting Skeptics in Their Place. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Heller, Mark. 1995. “The Simple Solution to the Problem of Generality,” Noûs 29: 501– 515. Howson, Colin. 2000. Hume’s Problem. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hume, David. 1739. A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd edn., edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975. Hume, David. 1777. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding, 3rd edn., edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978. Kaplan, Mark. 2008. “Austin’s Way with Skepticism.” In J. Greco (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism, 348–371. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lewis, David. 1971. “Immodest Inductive Methods,” Philosophy of Science 38: 54–63. Lycan, William. 1988. Judgement and Justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Moore, G.E. 1953. “Hume’s Theory Examined.” In G.E. Moore, Some Main Problems of Philosophy, 108–126. London: MacMillan. Papineau, David. 1992. “Reliabilism, Induction and Scepticism,” The Philosophical Quarterly 42: 1–20.

684

SKEPTICISM

Plantinga, Alvin. 1990. “Justification in the 20th Century,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, supplement vol. 1: 45–71. Popper, Karl. 1972. The Logic of Scientific Discovery, 4th edn. London: Hutchinson. Quine, W. V. O. 1973. The Roots of Reference. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court. Rabinowicz, Wlodek and Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen. 1999. “A Distinction in Value: Intrinsic and for its Own Sake,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100: 33–49. Reid, Thomas. 1764. An Inquiry into the Human Mind. In W. Hamilton (ed.), The Works of Thomas Reid, 5th ed., vol. I, 95–211. Edinburgh: McClachlan and Stewart, 1846. Russell, Bertrand. 1948. Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits. London: George Allen and Unwin. Salmon, Wesley. 1957. “Should We Attempt to Justify Induction?” Philosophical Studies 8: 33–48. Sartwell, Crispin. 1992. “Why Knowledge Is Merely True Belief,” Journal of Philosophy 89: 167–180. Schmitt, Frederick. 1992. Knowledge and Belief. London: Routledge. Sextus Empiricus. 1933. Outlines of Pyrrhonism, translated by R. G. Bury, The Loeb Classical Library, London: W. Heinemann. Sextus Empiricus. 1935. Against the Logicians, translated by R. G. Bury, The Loeb Classical Library, London: W. Heinemann. Sosa, Ernest. 1994. “Philosophical Skepticism,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. 68: 263–290. Sosa, Ernest. 2000. “Skepticism and Contextualism,” Philosophical Issues 10: 1–18. Stanford, P. Kyle. 2006. Exceeding our Grasp: Science, History and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Swinburne, Richard. 2001. Epistemic Justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Van Cleve, James. 1979. “Foundationalism, Epistemic Principles, and the Cartesian Circle,” The Philosophical Review 88: 55–91. Van Cleve, James. 1984. “Reliability, Justification and Induction,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9: 555–567. Van Cleve, James. 2003. “Is Knowledge Easy—or Impossible? Externalism as the Only Alternative to Skepticism.” In S. Luper (ed.), The Skeptics, 45–60. Hampshire: Ashgate. van Fraassen, Bas. 1989. Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Vogel, Jonathan. 2000. “Reliabilism Leveled,” Journal of Philosophy 97: 602–623. Weiner, Matthew. 2005. “Why Does Justification Matter?” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86: 422–444. Zagzebski, Linda. 1999. “What Is Knowledge?” In J. Greco and E. Sosa (eds.), Epistemology, 92–116. Oxford: Blackwell. Zagzebski, Linda. 2003. “The Search for the Source of the Epistemic Good,” Metaphilosophy 34: 12–28.

CHAPTER FORTY-SEVEN

Skepticism about A Priori Knowledge OTÁVIO BUENO

1 INTRODUCTION A priori knowledge is, roughly, knowledge that does not depend on experience (except perhaps for whatever experience that may be needed to acquire the relevant concepts). This is a rough formulation since, when analyzing the notion of a priori knowledge, some care is needed to characterize the independence-from-experience condition so that what is taken to be known independently of experience (such as mathematical and logical results) turns out to be known a priori (according to the proposed analysis of a priori knowledge), and what is taken to be known based on experience, and thus is dependent on experience (such as particular physical traits of the world), is not known a priori (according to the relevant account). The challenge is then to secure that the proposed analysis is extensionally adequate. Two questions then emerge: (a) Can we have a priori knowledge? (b) Can we know that—or, at least, determine whether—we have such knowledge? Corresponding to these two questions, there are two forms of skepticism regarding the a priori: (aʹ) One can provide arguments to the effect that, despite appearances to the contrary, one doesn’t have knowledge of the a priori, such as mathematical claims and claims about the validity of arguments. This is a priori skepticism (see Beebe 2011). Alternatively, (bʹ) one can provide arguments to the effect that conceptual analyses (characterizations, definitions) of a priori knowledge (see, for instance, Kitcher 1980, 2000; and, for an account of a priori justification, Casullo 2003) are ultimately problematic. This is skepticism about a priori knowledge. And if it is unclear what a priori knowledge ultimately is, it is similarly unclear how we can determine whether we have any such knowledge. In this chapter, I will consider both forms of skepticism regarding the a priori, focusing in particular on skepticism about a priori knowledge. After all, by challenging the very concept of a priori knowledge, it seems to me that this form of skepticism is more basic. Given the centrality of a priori knowledge to so many cognitive endeavors (from mathematics and logic to philosophy), the presence of

686

SKEPTICISM

these forms of skepticism highlights a central issue that needs to be addressed by those who claim to have the corresponding knowledge.

2  A PRIORI SKEPTICISM Most people think they know several mathematical claims, including simple arithmetical results, such as that 71 is the sum of 13 and 58. Most people think they also know whether a given conclusion follows logically from certain premises, such as that q follows logically from p and if p then q. Since such mathematical and logical results are arguably instances of what is known a priori, most people think they have a priori knowledge (although, unless they have some philosophical training, they are unlikely to describe that knowledge in these terms). A priori skepticism challenges such knowledge claims, and any others that are based on a priori considerations (Beebe 2011). The form of the argument for it is the same as the familiar brain-in-a-vat or evil-demon arguments, in which, first, a necessary condition for knowing something about the world is that one knows that one’s experiences are not being generated in a brain-in-a-vat scenario or by an evil demon. Support for this premise is provided by the closure principle, according to which (roughly) one knows what follows logically from things that are already known and that are established on the basis of that knowledge. Second, it turns out that one is unable to know that one is not in such skeptical scenarios. After all, one’s perceptual experiences are insensitive to such scenarios: one would believe that one is experiencing the world even if one weren’t (as the case would be if one were in such skeptical situations). The result is that one doesn’t know anything about the world. The argument for a priori skepticism is entirely analogous. In fact, it is an application of the familiar evil-demon argument to a priori knowledge claims, such as knowing the validity of modus ponens. As James Beebe notes: (P1) If I know that modus ponens is correct, then I know that my belief that modus ponens is correct is not based on faux intuitive experiences induced in me by a bumbling evil demon. (P2) I don’t know that my belief that modus ponens is correct is not based on faux intuitive experiences induced in me by a bumbling evil demon. (C) Therefore, I don’t know that modus ponens is correct (Beebe 2011: 590; the numbering of the premises and the conclusion of this argument has been changed; of course, nothing hangs on this). Interestingly, the argument above does not depend on establishing the invalidity of modus ponens. Those who take this form of inference to be valid would insist on the impossibility of demonstrating the inference’s invalidity: on their view, any such attempt would inevitably lead one into a contradiction. Rather, the argument is meant to challenge one’s knowledge that modus ponens is valid (or correct) on the grounds that one’s belief in the validity of this inference could be based on a bumbling evil demon. Whether modus ponens is ultimately valid or not, one cannot know that it is valid.

SKEPTICISM ABOUT A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE

687

There is also a different route to a priori skepticism (Beebe 2011: 593–594). It emerges from the consideration of alternative logical and mathematical practices, in which established mathematical and logical truths may not hold. This route surfaces from Ludwig Wittgenstein’s work (see Wittgenstein 1956, as understood by Stroud 1965; for a discussion, see Beebe 2011: 593–594). From the perspective of those who adopt the traditional view regarding logical and mathematical truths—according to which these truths are metaphysically necessary—one may not understand under what conditions mathematical and logical truths would be false. However, one’s inferential and calculation practices, which shape the relevant logical and mathematical results, could differ significantly from the traditional ones. This would generate genuine alternatives to these practices, so that despite the agreement that modus ponens is valid, one would not agree that from p and if p then q, it would follow that q; one could also follow the rule “adding 2” in such a way that after reaching 1,000, the rule continues as 1,004, 1,008, etc. It is ultimately a contingent fact that we developed the mathematical and logical concepts we currently have. Had the history of our species been different, we could have developed correspondingly different concepts. As Wittgenstein points out: I am not saying: if such-and-such facts of nature were different people would have different concepts (in the sense of a hypothesis). But: if anyone believes that certain concepts are absolutely the correct ones, and that having different ones would mean not realizing something that we realize—then let him imagine certain very general facts of nature to be different from what we are used to, and the formation of concepts different from the usual ones will become intelligible to him. (Wittgenstein 1956: I 141; quoted in Beebe 2011: 594) It is possible then, in light of the contingency of the way in which mathematical and logical concepts have been developed, that these concepts could have evolved differently, thus resulting in different logical and mathematical practices (see also Stroud 1965: 513, and Beebe 2011: 594). As a result, one doesn’t know the correctness of one’s current mathematical and logical practices. It seems to me that a priori skepticism provides a significant challenge to those who claim to know mathematical and logical results. But the challenge depends on the version of the challenge that is advanced. The second, contingency-based, formulation of this skeptical challenge seems to me more effective. The concern about the first, brain-in-a-vat or evil-genius-based formulation, is that it invites a particular sort of Moorean response. One could easily complain that we have more reason to believe in the truth of the relevant mathematical and logical results than we have to believe in the truth of the second premise, (P2), of the argument for a priori skepticism, according to which we don’t know that our relevant logical or mathematical beliefs are not based on experiences induced by an evil demon (or that emerge from a brain-in-a-vat scenario). Of course, as a principled response to skepticism, this move blatantly begs the question, since it assumes that we know precisely those items that the skeptical argument challenges. From this point of view, the response is clearly ineffective. But one can think of it as expressing a particular attitude: one that dismisses the entire skeptical argument as being so general, so

688

SKEPTICISM

detached from the particular mathematical and logical issues under consideration, that it verges on being irrelevant. The response reinforces the point that, due to its generality, there is very little in the first argument for a priori skepticism that engages with the content of logical or mathematical beliefs per se. The fact that the argument is a particular instance of the usual brain-in-a-vat or evil-demon argument clearly illustrates this point. In the end, the Moorean response is perhaps better thought of as an expression of the difficulty of taking such an argument very seriously. In contrast, the contingency-based formulation of a priori skepticism is more relevant. It engages with the content of the relevant mathematical and logical concepts. It is the fact that these concepts could have been developed differently that allows for the possibility that alternative logical and mathematical results could have been entertained. However, despite the advantage of this formulation of a priori skepticism, it can be made stronger. There is no need to leave the argument, as Wittgenstein, Stroud, and Beebe have left it, as a mere possibility, namely, that alternative mathematical and logical practices, shaped by different concepts, could have emerged. These possibilities are, in fact, actual. Challenges have been raised to the validity of modus ponens (McGee 1985) as well as to the correctness of classical mathematics, by intuitionists (Dummett 2000), predicativists (Weyl 1918/1994), and paraconsistentists (Mortensen 1995; for a discussion, see da Costa, Krause, and Bueno 2007). Even classical arithmetical results have been challenged within these circles (Priest 1997, 2000). The alternative logical and mathematical practices, posited as mere possibilities in the formulation of a priori skepticism above, are, in fact, not only possible, but actual. This means that one cannot claim to know, so easily, traditional mathematical and logical results, since they have all been challenged. Of course, the challenge is more focused and targeted at particular logical and mathematical results. In contrast to the first argument for a priori skepticism, this is a local rather than a global skeptical challenge. It is far more relevant, specific, and cannot be so easily dismissed. As an illustration, consider the challenge one can pose to modus ponens using the 2016 US presidential election as a context for the counterexample (this is adapted and updated from McGee 1985): (P1) If a Republican wins the election, then it if is not Donald Trump who wins, it will be Ted Cruz. (P2) A Republican will win the election. (C) If it is not Donald Trump who wins, it will be Ted Cruz. The premises of the argument are clearly true: Ted Cruz is the closest Republican contender to Donald Trump, and a Republican will win (and, in fact, did win) the election. However, the conclusion is clearly false: if it is not Donald Trump who wins the election, it will be Hillary Clinton, rather than Ted Cruz, who does it. (In fact, Clinton eventually won the popular vote by about 3 million votes!) This local, substantive form of a priori skepticism is clearly something to be reckoned with.

SKEPTICISM ABOUT A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE

689

3  EMPIRICISM AND A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE Before considering skepticism about a priori knowledge, it’s important to dispel a concern about a priori knowledge that has often been raised. Traditionally, from Sextus Empiricus through David Hume, skepticism and empiricism have often been closely connected. And a priori knowledge (and a priori justification) have often been a source of puzzlement particularly for those who are sympathetic to empiricism. How is it possible to have such knowledge (and justification) independently of empirical information? Those who are unmoved by these concerns insist that the content of the relevant statements, since their truth does not depend on empirical factors, is non-empirical, too, and therefore considerations to support the statements in question need not, and in fact should not, invoke empirical reasons, that is, reasons based on empirical information. Note that empiricists, just for being empiricists, need not be worried about a priori knowledge (or justification). Suppose empiricism is understood as involving the requirement that all information about the world is based on experience. There are at least two ways in which empiricism is not in tension with the a priori (a priori knowledge and justification): (a) when experience is understood in a suitably broad sense or (b) when the offending statements, which are known or justified a priori, are not about the world. With regard to (a), consider that among the experiences in question there are intellectual seemings (or intellectual intuitions; see Chudnoff 2013). In this case, one could have suitable experiences about objects of a non-empirical sort. Admittedly, it would require a correspondingly broader empiricism to accommodate such a broader notion of experience, and not every sort of empiricist will be willing to embrace this proposal. With regard to (b), one could argue that (pure) mathematical statements (those that are only about numbers, functions, sets, categories, and other mathematical objects and structures) are not about the world, since none of the objects invoked in such statements are empirical. If the truth of mathematical statements does not depend on what goes on in the empirical world, and if such statements are not about the empirical world either, there is nothing in these statements that can contravene empiricism—understood in the more restricted sense as a conception that is only concerned with information about the empirical world. This move clearly limits the scope of empiricism, which is then ultimately restricted to empirical objects alone. But that makes a priori knowledge (and justification) safe for empiricists. At this point, one can be concerned about (allegedly) synthetic a priori statements, that is, statements about the world whose knowledge and/or justification do not depend on empirical information about it (the world). Understandably, such statements raise concerns for empiricists. After all, if the statements in question are about the world, how can knowledge of their truth be independent of what goes on in it? Consider a statement such as “The standard meter is one meter in length.” This is clearly a statement about the world, but, the argument goes, it is known independently of experience, given that the standard meter specifies what one meter is. In response, it can be pointed out that knowledge of this statement ultimately

690

SKEPTICISM

depends on traits of the world, namely, the particular length of the standard meter (whatever it turns out to be). So, it is unclear that this statement is a priori in the end: it is known on the basis of knowledge of the length of the standard meter (an empirical fact about the world). Not surprisingly, empiricists have traditionally been skeptical about the existence of synthetic a priori statements in the first place. It is, of course, an issue whether mathematical statements are synthetic a priori. Kant famously argued that they are. But empiricists have very little reason to grant that, and may have concerns about the way Kant conceptualized the notions of analytic and synthetic. In fact, whether the subject is contained or not in the predicate crucially depends on how subjects and predicates are understood (for instance, are they formulated intensionally or extensionally?), and what the proper notion of containment is (e.g., should it be understood set-theoretically or in some other way?). However these notions are spelled out, arguably (pure) mathematical statements are not about the (empirical) world at all, given that they concern abstract mathematical objects, which are neither spatiotemporally located nor causally active. That every metric space is a topological space (but not vice versa) is a fact about the relevant spaces (which are abstract if they exist at all) and not about any particular (partial) spatial instantiation of such spaces. Any such concrete (partial) instantiation depends on a suitable physical interpretation of the abstract notions of metric and topological spaces. Depending on how such interpretations are worked out, different instantiations end up being provided. Just consider the different metrics (metric functions) that characterize different metric spaces. The way in which such metrics are physically interpreted yields different instantiations of the corresponding spaces. The same metric space is compatible with a variety of distinct physical instances. These considerations illustrate that (pure) mathematical statements do not depend on concrete objects for their truth or falsity, and thus neither knowledge nor justification of mathematical objects depend on knowledge or justification of empirical facts. The result is that, properly understood, a priori knowledge and a priori justification need not pose particular difficulties for empiricists—assuming, of course, that there are any. We can now address the second kind of skepticism regarding the a priori: it challenges the very characterization of a priori knowledge. We start by considering an influential attempt at providing an analysis of this concept.

4 ANALYZING A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE A priori knowledge, we noted, is taken to be knowledge independent of experience.1 Although the intuitive idea underlying the notion of a priori knowledge seems clear enough, it turns out to be extremely difficult to characterize properly what a priori knowledge is. In what follows, I illustrate this by arguing that a classic, and prima facie plausible, characterization of a priori knowledge—the one provided by Philip Kitcher (1980, 2000)—fails. Kitcher’s account has been criticized for being too strong (see, e.g., Harper 1986). As I argue here, however, the account turns out to be too weak, as it’s ultimately unable to distinguish empirical and a priori knowledge. In the end,

SKEPTICISM ABOUT A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE

691

the proposal seems unstable, since it seems to over-generate (turning clear cases of empirical knowledge into a priori knowledge) or under-generate (failing to classify clear cases of a priori knowledge as such). This raises a partial doubt, in light of the failure of this account, regarding the prospects of characterizing the notion of a priori knowledge more generally. Kitcher’s account of a priori knowledge was developed as part of an investigation— and, ultimately, a defense—of the claim that mathematics is not a priori; thus, making it safe for empiricists.2 So, one of the challenges the account needs to meet is not to have stacked the deck in the first place. Kitcher is, of course, aware of the problem, and he explicitly tries to avoid this difficulty. The proposed analysis is meant to capture the two crucial features of a priori knowledge: (i) the fact that this type of knowledge doesn’t depend on experience, while acknowledging that (ii) some of the concepts involved in a priori knowledge can only be obtained from experience. To accommodate (ii), one introduces the notion of experiences that are “sufficiently rich for an agent X to entertain the proposition p.” That is, X has experiences that yield all the relevant concepts invoked in p. To accommodate (i), the requirement of independence of experience, one introduces the idea that the same type of processes that produce, in the actual world, the belief that p in X will warrant that belief in all (epistemically) possible worlds. In this way, the justification for an a priori belief does not depend on experience, given that processes of the same type will warrant that belief in different possible worlds. The definition is formulated in two steps. First, a priori knowledge is characterized in terms of a priori warrant. Second, a priori warrant is then formulated in terms of a process. Here is the account (which revisits and improves on an earlier account provided in Kitcher 1980): X knows a priori that p iff X knows that p and X’s knowledge that p was produced by a process that is an a priori warrant for p. α is an a priori warrant for X’s belief that p just in case α is a process such that for any sequence of experiences sufficiently rich for X for p (a) some process of the same type could produce in X a belief that p; (b) if a process of the same type were to produce in X a belief that p, then it would warrant X in believing that p; (c) if a process of the same type were to produce in X a belief that p, then p. (Kitcher 2000: 67) As Kitcher notes, if only condition (a) is met, we obtain weak a priori knowledge. If conditions (b) and (c) are satisfied as well, we obtain strong a priori knowledge. Is this definition adequate? The responses have been unanimous in stressing that the definition is too strong (see, e.g., Parsons 1986; Harper 1986, Summerfield, Casullo, and Peacocke 1994). Talking about a particular a priori warrant, William Harper insists that it might “even approach the outrageously high standards set out by Philip Kitcher in his attempt to explicate a priori knowledge” (Harper 1986: 268 n. 8).3 As it turns out, however, I don’t think that Kitcher’s standards for apriority are too high. If anything, as will become clear below, they are not high enough.

692

SKEPTICISM

5  SKEPTICISM ABOUT A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE: SOME DIFFICULTIES The main problem with this account of a priori knowledge is that, ultimately, it cannot distinguish a priori and empirical knowledge, and so, it fails to deliver an extensionally adequate characterization of the a priori. To see why this is the case, let’s first highlight what might be taken to be, initially, a benefit of the view. Recall that, according to this account, the notion of a priori warrant is defined in terms of the notion of process. But the latter is left completely open in this proposal. No constraints are imposed on what counts as a process. (The term seems to be taken as a primitive.) It might be argued that the lack of constraints here is not without reason. It’s sensible to expect that any account of a priori knowledge should leave it open which processes yield this type of knowledge, whether they are proofs, conceptual analyses, or perhaps some sort of introspection.4 So, the openness of the notion of process might be taken as an advantage of the proposal. Moreover, the notion of process had better be left open indeed. After all, it’s not clear that a process adequate to define the notion of a priori warrant could be exactly characterized without somehow presupposing the notion of the a priori: either the processes in question are extensionally equivalent to a priori warrants or they are not. If they aren’t, these processes clearly fail to characterize, in an extensionally correct way, the notion of an a priori warrant. If, however, the processes under consideration are extensionally equivalent to a priori warrants, then in virtue of what does the extensional equivalence obtain? To circumscribe correctly the class of a priori warrants, one needs to have already some sort of grasp of what counts as an a priori warrant, but this means that, ultimately, the notion of a priori has to be presupposed. To avoid this sort of circularity, it’s not by chance that the notion of process is then left completely open. But this openness comes with its price, and it’s in virtue of this openness that the account is unable to distinguish a priori and empirical knowledge. Let’s start with weak a priori knowledge. Consider the process of knowledge acquisition about quarks provided by particle accelerators, and consider a community of physicists X who, by using particle accelerators, have now formed the belief p that quarks have been detected. Of course, the community of physicists, understanding what quarks are, has had a series of experiences sufficiently rich for p. The trouble is that particle accelerators yield a process of detection of quarks that immediately satisfies condition (a) in the definition above. After all, for any sequence of experiences sufficiently rich for the community of physicists X for the belief that p (i.e., that quarks have been detected), there is always a process of the same type—such as, a particle accelerator built in the other side of the planet—that could produce in X a belief that p.5 In other words, according the account, particle accelerators provide us with (weak) a priori knowledge of quarks! Kitcher may grant this point, given that he himself acknowledges that the notion of weak a priori knowledge is far from adequate. But more than a simple inadequacy, this suggests that the notion of weak a priori knowledge is importantly problematic: in the end, it does not seem to be a notion of a priori knowledge. If the latter cannot

SKEPTICISM ABOUT A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE

693

be distinguished from empirical knowledge, there’s something deeply unsettling with the proposed account. But perhaps this is only a feature of weak a priori knowledge, and strong a priori knowledge may fare better. Alas, the same problem also plagues the latter notion. To see why this is so, let’s examine the particle accelerator case a little further. Is condition (b) in the account above satisfied in this case? This seems to be so. Let’s consider all epistemically possible worlds—in particular, worlds in which the community of physicists X has experiences sufficiently rich for the belief in quarks p, and in which it is known that quarks exist. We should now consider processes of the same type as those that, in the actual world, produce in X the belief that p. But what would count as a process of the same type in this case? Certainly, at least other particle accelerators built in these epistemically accessible worlds. Clearly, any such particle accelerators also warrant the belief that quarks have been detected, given that it is a process of the same type as the one in the actual world. After all, if the processes are of the same type, presumably the same propositions will be true in each of them. (Compare: if two structures are isomorphic, the same propositions will be true in each structure.6) Note that this doesn’t require infallibility: a warranted belief can, of course, be false. But epistemic processes of the same type will validate the same beliefs; that is, in part, what makes them processes of the same type. In other words, epistemic processes are individuated, in part, by the beliefs they validate. Those beliefs that are true in one process will be true in other processes of the same type; those that are false in one process will be false in other processes of that type as well. As a result, in each of these worlds, the belief p, being generated by the same type of process, will be warranted. Condition (b) is met. In response, it might be argued that cases of empirical knowledge fail to satisfy condition (b). If it is merely nomologically (as opposed to metaphysically or logically) necessary that the world has a certain structure, then there will be worlds in which particle accelerators don’t give us a window into the structure of the world. Particle accelerators in those worlds will be like witch detectors in the actual world. There are no witches to be detected, and we are not justified in thinking that the output of a witch detector tells us anything about the natural world. Ditto for particle accelerators in worlds where the laws of nature are different from the laws of nature in the actual world. This response, however, faces two difficulties. First, if in some worlds particle accelerators fail to warrant X in believing that quarks exist, that means that, in these worlds, the accelerators in question end up not being processes of the same type as those that produce the corresponding beliefs in the actual world. After all, in the actual world, particle accelerators do warrant the physics community in believing in the existence of quarks. And if the processes are indeed of the same type, presumably they will warrant the same propositions. In other words, condition (b) is met—by contraposition. It may be argued that the condition to the effect that processes of the same type warrant the same propositions yields too easy a response to skepticism. If perception is a process that yields warranted beliefs in the actual world, but does not in an evil-demon world, then the process relied on in the latter is not of the same kind as

694

SKEPTICISM

the one invoked in the former. After all, true beliefs are generated in one case, and false ones in the other. Similarly, testimony arguably generates true beliefs, at least in the typical cases. In contrast, a testimony that conveys false information, and thus yields false beliefs, would be a different type of epistemic process, given the distinct outcomes in the two cases (true vs. false testimonies). But this would make skeptical challenges extremely easy to address, since the challenges can be set aside as engaging with a different kind of epistemic process rather than with veridical, truth-conducive procedures.7 In response, arguably one does not perceive in an evil-demon scenario, given that the beliefs that are yielded are not produced, as in the case of perception, by the objects they are about. Since this is a constitutive feature of perception, the experiences one undergoes in an evil-demon scenario are of a different kind, despite the many similarities they share with perception, particularly regarding their phenomenology. (The same point goes through in the case of hallucinations.) Similarly, a false testimony, as opposed to a true one, doesn’t typically yield true beliefs. Despite the similarities between the testimonies of a liar and of a truthteller, there is a significant epistemic difference between them: in one case, truth is preserved and transferred; in the other, it isn’t. It’s not unreasonable, thus, to consider them as distinct epistemic processes. Note, however, that this doesn’t provide a response to skepticism. After all, one typically doesn’t know when a testimony is true or when it is false, nor does one know whether the scenario one experiences is of an evil demon or not. And without these pieces of knowledge in place, the skeptical challenges still stand. Returning now to the case of worlds involving quarks, a second difficulty emerges. If in some worlds quarks don’t exist (just as witches don’t exist in the actual world), then, in these worlds, we had better not have knowledge of them. After all, how could we have knowledge of an object that doesn’t exist? So, in these worlds, we couldn’t have a priori knowledge of quarks, given that we simply don’t have knowledge of them. (Recall that, on this account, for one to know a priori that p, one needs first to know that p.) This seems to be good news for the account. The trouble, however, is that in the worlds in which quarks do exist, processes of the same type as those that produce the belief in quarks in the actual world will also warrant X in believing in the existence of quarks. After all, it was the nonexistence of quarks that undermined X’s warrant in p. In other words, in those worlds in which quarks exist, the warrant is no longer undermined. But, in this case, condition (b) will be, once again, satisfied. How about condition (c): is it met? Recall that we are considering all epistemically possible worlds in which the community of physicists X has experiences sufficiently rich for the belief in quarks p. We are also considering processes of the same type as those that produce in X the belief that p. Given these assumptions, for exactly the same reason discussed above, in each of these worlds the proposition p (that quarks have been detected) will also come out true. Hence, this satisfies condition (c). After all, is it possible that p is not true? Well, note that the first requirement of the account of a priori knowledge is that X knows that p. Typically, this entails that p is true. So, p’s truth follows from the assumption that X has knowledge that

SKEPTICISM ABOUT A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE

695

p. Moreover, given that the processes under consideration are of the same type (as those that yield the belief that p in X), the same propositions will come out true in each of these processes (and as noted above, this doesn’t assume infallibility). But p is one of these propositions, and p is true in the actual world. Hence, condition (c) is also met. The result is then a counterexample to the proposed account of strong a priori knowledge. After all, it is typically assumed that knowledge of quarks is empirical rather than a priori. However, for the reasons provided above, according to the proposal under consideration, we have strong a priori knowledge of quarks! In the end, it seems that even the strong version cannot distinguish empirical and a priori knowledge.

6  SKEPTICISM ABOUT A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE: EPISTEMIC COMMUNITIES, MODALITY, AND WARRANT 6a  Epistemic Communities on the Fringes Let me consider some ways in which one could try to resist the counterexample above. Adapting a point made in Kitcher (2000), one could suggest that, among the epistemically possible worlds, there is one in which the community of physicists X is actually on the fringes, and their methods of knowledge acquisition about quarks are taken by everyone else outside the community X to be mistaken. In this case, condition (b) of the account won’t be satisfied, given that X won’t be warranted in believing that p—or, at least, X won’t be taken to be warranted in believing that p. As a result, as one would expect, the account won’t entail that we have strong a priori knowledge of the detection of quarks. In response, note first that it’s not clear that the proposed situation shows that condition (b) is not met. After all, to establish that (b) is not satisfied, we need to provide a process of the same type as the one that produces in X the belief that p, but which fails to warrant X in believing that p. Moving the community of physicists X to the fringes doesn’t establish that their methods for believing that p no longer warrant this belief. The fact that the methods are not taken to be warranted by anyone else outside X doesn’t entail that the methods aren’t warranted. Condition (b) is a claim about the warrant of the methods (or processes), not a claim about whether these methods are taken to be warranted. Second, if considering the community X to be on the fringes counts as an epistemic possibility that undermines condition (b), exactly the same move can be made in the case of mathematics. After all, consider a possible world in which a community of mathematicians Xʹ uses methods that are taken by everyone else as being mistaken, and so these methods are not taken to warrant Xʹ in believing that pʹ (say, that inaccessible cardinals exist). This would then establish that Xʹ doesn’t have strong a priori knowledge of the existence of such mathematical entities.8 As a result, it follows from the account that in order for us not to have strong a priori knowledge of the existence of quarks (by allowing the possibility of communities of physicists on the fringes), we can’t have strong a priori knowledge of the existence of

696

SKEPTICISM

certain sets (given the possibility of communities of mathematicians on the fringes). In other words, for the account not to over-generate—that is, for it not to turn clear cases of empirical knowledge into a priori knowledge—it ends up under-generating— that is, it fails to classify clear cases of a priori knowledge as such. Thus, once again, a priori and empirical knowledge are not properly distinguished by the account.

6b  Truth: Contingent and Necessary Matters But perhaps there is an important aspect of the distinction between a priori and empirical knowledge that the account above is able to capture. According to the traditional view about mathematics, mathematical objects are necessary objects: they exist in all possible worlds. And so, in particular, they exist in all epistemically possible worlds. Hence, in the case of mathematics, as one would expect, condition (c) can be met easily, given that the consequent of (c)—being necessarily true— will make (c) true. But the same doesn’t happen in the case of contingent objects, such as quarks. After all, quarks only exist in some worlds, and presumably only in some epistemically accessible worlds. So, when we deal with contingent matters, condition (c) is not immediately met. In response, note first that it’s an advantage of the proposed account that it doesn’t identify a priori knowledge with knowledge of necessary truths (see Kitcher 2000: 69). Since Kripke (1980), it has become clear that apriority and necessity are different notions. After all, we may know a priori things that are contingent (such as our own existence), and we may fail to know—and hence fail to know a priori—necessary things (such as extraordinarily complex mathematical results). Hence, taking mathematical objects as necessary doesn’t lend any support per se to the proposed definition of a priori knowledge. Second, even in the case of mathematics, the fact that condition (c) might be easily met is irrelevant. After all, as noted, to have a priori knowledge we need first to have knowledge (see the formulation of Kitcher’s account above). And given that we may not be able to know a particular mathematical result, for example, due to its complexity, we will not have a priori knowledge of this result, either. Exactly the same point applies to empirical knowledge.

6c  Warrant: Contingent and Necessary Matters But let’s follow a little further the traditional account that insists that mathematical objects exist in all possible worlds. Presumably, in all epistemically accessible worlds, any process of the same type as those that produce in X a belief that p will also warrant X in believing that p. After all, no empirical constraints play any role in the warrant process, and presumably, nothing that could happen in any world would change the warrant in question. As a result, if we deal with necessary entities, condition (b) can be met without difficulty. But the same doesn’t happen in the case of contingent objects, such as quarks, which presumably exist only in some epistemically accessible worlds. So, perhaps this aspect of the distinction between a priori and empirical knowledge—the fact that the latter, but not the former, depends on what goes on in each world—can be secured via this account.

SKEPTICISM ABOUT A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE

697

But it’s not clear that the account captures even this much. After all, consider again the possibility of a world with a community of mathematicians on the fringes, so that the techniques developed to warrant mathematical beliefs fail to warrant them. This possibility would undermine the claim that even mathematical results are known a priori. Hence, mathematical knowledge, just as empirical knowledge, turns out to be world-dependent. To overcome this difficulty, one could reject the possibility of epistemic communities of mathematicians on the fringes, by insisting that they are epistemically impossible. But if this move is made, then epistemic communities of physicists in the fringes will also have to be ruled out. After all, it will simply beg the question to claim that, given that physics is not known a priori, the relevant epistemic possibilities can be entertained! But, as a result, and as we saw above, if the possibility of epistemic communities of physicists is not entertained, we will end up having a priori knowledge of physical objects! Once again, the proposed analysis is unstable: it either over-generates or under-generates.

7 CONCLUSION Can the criticism of this account of a priori knowledge be generalized to other attempts to characterize this type of knowledge? Or is this criticism restricted only to this particular characterization? It is possible that the point made here has a broader scope, although I will not try to argue for this claim here. Suffice to note that, in general, attempts to characterize an intuitive notion in an extensionally adequate way are typically plagued with difficulties, as challenges to proposed conceptual analyses of knowledge (Gettier 1963), modality (Shalkowski 1994), and logical consequence (Etchemendy 1990) clearly show. A priori knowledge is no exception in this respect. In conclusion, although the intuition that motivates one to develop an account of a priori knowledge is clear—a priori knowledge is knowledge independent of experience—it’s not so apparent that one can turn this intuition into a problemfree characterization of a priori knowledge. In particular, if we judge from the difficulties faced by Kitcher’s account, it’s much less obvious that one can articulate an extensionally adequate account of a priori knowledge that captures the above intuition. Given this difficulty, the problem of how to characterize a priori knowledge remains open, and thus, in the end, so does the answer to the question: just what is a priori knowledge? In light of the considerations discussed in this book, it seems that both a priori skepticism (particularly in its local form) and skepticism about a priori knowledge are alive and well.9

NOTES 1. As also noted, this is not meant to include the concepts required to understand the propositions that are known a priori. After all, we may know a priori propositions whose concepts can only be obtained from experience.

698

SKEPTICISM

2. See Kitcher (1983) for his defense of this view about mathematics. 3. Similar complaints can be found in, e.g., Parsons (1986) and Summerfield, Casullo, and Peacocke (1994). 4. In the end, maybe the issue regarding the “sources” of a priori knowledge shouldn’t be settled a priori! 5. Note that condition (a) only requires the existence of a particular process that could produce in X the relevant belief that p, not a process that has actually done so. 6. In other words, isomorphic structures are elementarily equivalent. 7. My thanks to Baron Reed for pressing this point. 8. Kitcher agrees, of course, with this conclusion. But if he made this move as part of the characterization of a priori knowledge, he would be clearly stacking the deck. 9. My thanks go to Diego Machuca and Baron Reed for all their help and feedback on earlier versions of this work.

REFERENCES Beebe, James. 2011. “A Priori Skepticism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83: 583–602. Boghossian, Paul and Christopher Peacocke (eds.). 2000: New Essays on the A Priori. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Butts, Robert (ed.). 1986. Kant’s Philosophy of Physical Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Casullo, Albert. 2003. A Priori Justification. New York: Oxford University Press. Chudnoff, Elijah. 2013. Intuition. Oxford: Oxford University Press. da Costa, Newton, Décio Krause, and Otávio Bueno. 2007. “Paraconsistent Logics and Paraconsistency.” In D. Jacquette (ed.), Philosophy of Logic, 791–911. Amsterdam: North-Holland. Dummett, Michael. 2000. Elements of Intuitionism. 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Etchemendy, John. 1990. The Concept of Logical Consequence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Gettier, Edmund. 1963. “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” Analysis 23: 121–123. Harper, William. 1986. “The A Priori and Materially Necessary.” In Kant’s Philosophy of Physical Science, 239–272. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Jacquette, Dale (ed.). 2007. Philosophy of Logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland. Kitcher, Philip. 1980. “A Priori Knowledge,” Philosophical Review 89: 3–23. Kitcher, Philip. 1983. The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press. Kitcher, Philip. 2000. “A Priori Knowledge Revisited.” In P. Boghossian, and C. Peacocke (eds.), New Essays on the A Priori, 65–91. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kripke, Saul. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. McGee, Vann. 1985. “A Counterexample to Modus Ponens,” Journal of Philosophy 82: 462–471. Mortensen, Chris. 1995. Inconsistent Mathematics. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

SKEPTICISM ABOUT A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE

699

Parrini, Paolo (ed.). 1994. Kant and Contemporary Epistemology. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Parsons, Charles. 1986. “Review of The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge,” Philosophical Review 95: 129–137. Priest, Graham. 1997. “Inconsistent Models for Arithmetic: I, Finite Models,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 26: 223–235. Priest, Graham. 2000. “Inconsistent Models for Arithmetic: II, The General Case,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 65: 1519–1529. Shalkowski, Scott. 1994. “The Ontological Ground of the Alethic Modality,” Philosophical Review 103: 669–688. Stroud, Barry. 1965. “Wittgenstein and Logical Necessity,” Philosophical Review 74: 104–118. Summerfield, Donna, Albert Casullo, and Christopher Peacocke. 1994. “The Origins of the A Priori.” In P. Parrini (ed.), Kant and Contemporary Epistemology, 47–72. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Weyl, Hermann. 1918/1994. The Continuum: A Critical Examination of the Foundations of Analysis. Translated from the 1918 German edition by Stephen Pollard and Thomas Bole. New York: Dover. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1956. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, edited by G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees, and G. E. Anscombe, and translated by Anscombe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

CHAPTER FORTY-EIGHT

Skepticism about Other Minds ANIL GOMES

1 INTRODUCTION Skepticism about others’ minds is the claim that we have no knowledge of other people’s mental lives. This can sometimes strike us as a manifest truth. We occasionally find ourselves in situations where we feel cut off from what other people think and feel, and when this happens it can seem like the bringing to the surface of a cognitive estrangement which is always there. Thus Lily Briscoe, in Virginia Woolf’s To the Lighthouse, expresses frustration at her inability to enter into “the chambers of [another’s] mind and heart. . . . How, then, she had asked herself, did one know one thing or another about people, sealed as they were?” (1998: 44). Such knowledge is unattainable, she concludes. Yet such skepticism should also strike us as strange and revisionary. For we do take ourselves to know many things about what other people think and feel. I know that Arun hopes for a Labor victory; I know that Priya is angry with her sister; I know that Ayesha suffers from back pain. This knowledge is part of our everyday dealings with other people. And it is a central part of many of those relationships that give our lives significance: part of what makes Ayesha such a good friend is that she knows when a particular conversation topic is upsetting those around her and moves to change the topic. Skepticism about others’ minds conflicts with our ordinary conception of our relation to other people. My aim in this chapter is to consider what reason we have to endorse skepticism about others’ minds. I’ll argue that we need to distinguish two distinct ways in which one might motivate such skepticism and provide some reason for focusing on the second of these motivations. I’ll set out some of the responses to the skeptical problems before providing my own sense of which avenues of further exploration will be most fruitful. An initial point of clarification: which knowledge claims does skepticism about others’ minds rule out? I take the knowledge in question to be any claim that ascribes a mental feature to another person. Since the category of a mental feature is so broad, this is itself an expansive category: the ascription of beliefs, feelings,

SKEPTICISM ABOUT OTHER MINDS

701

character traits, emotions, actions, and activity all fall under the heading of mental features, broadly construed. Those who write on this topic tend to concentrate on our knowledge of what other people believe and feel. I will follow that restriction in what follows. But we should not assume that the same considerations apply to our knowledge of each and every member of this diverse class.

2  THE PROBLEM OF ERROR One common way to raise a skeptical problem about others’ minds is by appeal to cases of pretense (e.g. McDowell 1998c, drawing on a tradition emanating from Wittgenstein 1992). Cases of pretense are ones in which someone presents themselves as having a mental feature which they in fact lack. A judgment based on how things seem in such cases will result in a false belief. But—the skeptic argues—your evidential basis for this judgment is the same as that in the case in which you judge someone to have a mental feature that they do have. Since your evidence does not suffice for knowledge in the bad case, it cannot suffice for knowledge in the good case. Note first that there is something odd about using pretense as an exemplar of this skeptical scenario. Another person can pretend to have a mental feature that she lacks only if she has other mental features such as a desire to simulate and the belief that this is the way to do so. For this reason, a case of pretense does not support the claim that we have no knowledge of others’ minds, for I can reason as follows: either she is pretending or she is not. If she is not pretending, then she really does instantiate the mental feature that she appears to instantiate. If she is, then she must have some other beliefs and desires. In either case, she has a mind. The case of pretense is ineffective in motivating complete skepticism about others’ minds for the same reason that Descartes judged the evil demon hypothesis ineffective in motivating skepticism about his own existence.1 This implication is avoided by choosing an alternative skeptical scenario, such as one in which those around us are robots or philosophical zombies. I will refer to such cases as ones of error, understood as ones in which it seems to you as if someone has a particular mental feature which they in fact lack. Unlike cases of pretense, certain cases of error are compatible with it not being possible for a subject to have knowledge of others’ minds. With this in mind, we can formulate the skeptic’s argument. Where ascriptions to another of a mental feature are of the form “o is F,” let “the bad case” designate a case in which it seems to you as if someone has a particular mental feature which they in fact lack and you judge mistakenly that o is F, and let “the good case” designate the case in which it seems to you as if someone has a particular mental feature which they do in fact have and you judge accurately that o is F. Let two cases be phenomenally indistinguishable when things are phenomenally the same for the subject in the two cases. Then we can reason as follows: 1. The good case and the bad case are phenomenally indistinguishable. 2. If the good case and the bad case are phenomenally indistinguishable, then the subject’s evidence is the same in the two cases.

702

SKEPTICISM

3. If the subject’s evidence is the same in the two cases, then the epistemic status of her belief is the same in the two cases. 4. In the bad case, you don’t know that o is F. 5. In the good case, you don’t know that o is F. (From 1, 2, 3, and 4) This argument generalizes to take in all mental phenomena that fall under cases of error. It can thus be used to show that we don’t have any knowledge of other people’s mental lives. How should an anti-skeptic reply to this argument? (4) follows from the assumption that knowledge entails truth. That leaves us with (1), (2), and (3). Some forms of epistemological externalism reject (3): they hold that factors external to a subject can affect the epistemic status of her beliefs without changing her evidence. Evidential externalist responses reject (2): they hold that the evidence available to a subject can differ even when things seem to her to be the same. Disjunctive responses reject (1): they hold that how things seem to the subject is not the same in the two cases for in the good case, “the appearance that is presented to one . . . is a matter of the fact itself being disclosed to the experiencer” (McDowell 1998c: 387). The rejection of (1) is compatible with the good and bad cases being subjectively indiscriminable—in the sense that in both cases one can’t know, through reflection, that one is not in the good case—but subjective indiscriminability does not entail phenomenal indistinguishability. I won’t evaluate these responses here. What should be clear, from the way in which I’ve set up the problem, is that this style of skeptical problem arises in many domains. In the case of perceptual knowledge, the bad case is one of illusion or hallucination. In the case of knowledge of the past, it is one in which the world came into existence five minutes ago with all my apparent memories included. Skeptics claim that the indistinguishability of such cases from genuine cases undermines our claims to knowledge. This form of argument generalizes. Furthermore, the forms of response mentioned above also apply in each of these domains. Evidential externalists about perceptual knowledge hold that the evidence in the good case is not the same as the evidence available in the bad case; disjunctive responses hold that how things seem to one is different in the two cases. This fact of wider application is made more salient by the fact that John McDowell’s influential response to the skeptical problem arises in the context of drawing a link between the problem of other minds and the problem of perceptual knowledge. Once one has noted this generalization, it is hard not to sympathize with Fodor’s comment that “it’s gotten harder to believe that there is a special problem about the knowledge of other minds (as opposed to other anything elses)” (1994: 292). What are the implications for skepticism about others’ minds? My provisional conclusion is that we have seen nothing, thus far, to motivate the thought that we have a distinctive philosophical problem of other minds—one that turns on aspects of our mentality and its expression to others. This conclusion is only provisional because it may be that the plausibility of any particular application of the responses mooted above will depend on facts specific to the domain in question: perhaps a disjunctive solution is plausible for perceptual knowledge but not knowledge of

SKEPTICISM ABOUT OTHER MINDS

703

others’ minds, say. But, as a general moral, we can say that what we have here is a problem about knowledge, one that can be raised in the case of our knowledge of others’ minds. And while this is a way of motivating skepticism, it doesn’t motivate a distinctive skepticism about others’ minds.

3  THE PROBLEM OF SOURCES In the rest of this chapter, I want to motivate an alternative way of raising a skeptical problem about others’ minds. It is a way of raising the problem that I think is both more faithful to the history of the problem as discussed in twentieth-century analytic philosophy and turns on issues distinctive to our mentality. Let me start with the history. When one looks at discussions of the problem of other minds at the start of the twentieth century, issues about pretense and deception are largely absent from the debate. Instead, the starting point is a supposed contrast between the way we know our own minds and the way in which we know the minds of other people. Here are two examples, spanning the first half of the twentieth century. First, G. F. Stout, introducing his discussion of knowledge of others’ minds by means of an implied contrast with the way in which we know our own mind: To introspect is to attend to the workings of one’s own mind. . . . No-one can directly observe what is passing in the mind of another. (Stout 1898: 14, 20) Second, A. J. Ayer, characterizing the problem of other minds: We may take as our starting-point the propositions that I can have direct knowledge of my own experiences and that I cannot have direct knowledge of anyone else’s. (Ayer 1953: 193) Each of these writers adverts, in different ways, to a certain contrast between the way in which we know our own mind and the way in which we know the minds of others. The exact nature of this contrast is largely unimportant except for dialectical purposes. What matters, for each of them, is that the contrast shows up a problem in accounting for the source of our knowledge of another’s mind. The thought is this: we have a way of knowing about our own mental lives. But this source of knowledge cannot be used to find out about the mental life of another person. If we do not have a source of such knowledge, then we do not have knowledge of others’ mental lives. We can best formulate this line of thought as an antinomy of three claims: (S1) If you know that p, then there is a means by which you know that p. (S2) There is no means by which one can know truths about another’s mind. (S3) We know truths about another’s mind. These three claims are jointly incompatible. From (S1) and (S3) it follows that there is a means by which we know about other people’s mental lives; this is in contradiction with (S2). Skepticism about others’ minds is a rejection of (S3): we have no knowledge about other people’s mental lives. Most participants in the debate reject (S2): it is

704

SKEPTICISM

certainly the most obviously contestable, and I will focus on it in what follows. But it will be useful to say something about (S1), a claim which is rarely articulated but which I take to be assumed in the debate. J. L. Austin (1961) notes that whenever someone makes a claim to knowledge, it is appropriate to ask “How do you know?” Timothy Williamson (2000: 252–253) agrees, and Quassim Cassam (2009: 112) calls this “something like a conceptual truth.” The natural way of taking this question is as requesting identification of the source or means of one’s knowledge. The linguistic fact about the appropriateness of a certain question reflects a metaphysical fact about knowledge: namely, that if someone knows that p, then there is a means by which she knows it. Challenges to (S1) arise in cases in which the “How do you know?” question is claimed to be inappropriate, thus identifying potential counterexamples to the thesis. Consider the assertion “I am in pain.” Certain readers of Wittgenstein have taken the question “How do you know?” to be inappropriate in response to this assertion. One response is to conclude that it is false to say that a subject knows she is pain. But an alternative, canvassed by Stuart Hampshire, is to hold that a subject can know that she is in pain without there being a means by which she knows it (1969: 282–283). Donald Davidson makes the same claim for other cases of selfknowledge (1991: 212). I will put these challenges to one side. They arise specifically in the context of certain cases of self-knowledge, and the considerations adduced do not motivate the failure of (S1) for other types of knowledge. Moreover, (S1) has a great deal of plausibility. If one thinks of states of knowledge as part of the natural world, then there must be a causal story one can tell about how subjects get into them. Those who are sympathetic to some form of naturalized epistemology will hold that telling such a story identifies the means by which a subject knows. Those who want to reject skepticism about others’ minds should deny (S2).

4  PERCEPTION AND INFERENCE Why would one think that there is no means by which we know truths about another’s mind? One reason would be if there were some general condition on knowledge which couldn’t be met by truths about another’s mind. Say, for example, that knowledge requires a causal interaction between a subject’s belief and that which is known. This condition has been thought to raise a problem in explaining our knowledge of domains from which we are causally isolated, for example, mathematical truths (Benacerraf 1973: 671–673) or moral values (Mackie 1977: 38–39). If others’ minds were causally isolated from the physical world, then there would be no means by which we could know about them, and (S2) would hold. This suggests that (S2) follows from certain conceptions of the mental, such as those on which the mental features are attributes of an immaterial substance causally isolated from the physical world. It may also follow from those conceptions of the mental that deny the existence of immaterial substance but hold that particular mental features such as the qualitative character of consciousness are causally

SKEPTICISM ABOUT OTHER MINDS

705

isolated from the physical world. I take it that these conceptions of the mental are neither popular nor attractive, so put this motivation of (S2) to one side. The discussion in Ayer and Stout offers us an alternative way of motivating (S2). Consider the standard way in which we know about our own mental lives. Call this method introspection. It is necessarily first-personal, that is to say, it cannot be used to find out about the mental features of another person. So the source of our knowledge about own mental life is not one that can provide us with knowledge of another’s mind. I take this to be the reason why some of those writing on this issue focus on the asymmetry between self-knowledge and our knowledge of others’ minds: it shows up the fact that one prevalent source of knowledge of mental features cannot be used to gain knowledge of another’s mental life. How, then, do we know about others’ minds? Other people and their mental features are aspects of the world around us. And when we think about how we gain knowledge about the external world, there seem to be two broad methods of which we make use: perception and inference. Perceptual knowledge is knowledge based on the basic deliverances of the senses, as when I come to know that the chairs are blue by looking at them. Inferential knowledge is knowledge that takes us beyond what is given in experience, as when I come to know that there was a party at my neighbor’s house on the grounds that it is the best explanation of the contents of her recycling bin. Perhaps there are interesting philosophical questions about how exactly we are to distinguish these sources of knowledge, but they look to be distinct. Is our knowledge of others’ minds perceptual or inferential? This is where the case for (S2) has been thought to get its bite. For one recurring theme in the literature is that neither of these sources of knowledge can enable us to gain knowledge about another person’s mental life. Against perception it is said that we cannot perceive the mind of another person: at best we can perceive her behavior. So we cannot be said to have perceptual knowledge of her mental life. But against inference it is claimed that this experience of behavior isn’t secure enough to ground an inference to the presence of others’ minds. If neither perception nor inference can serve as a source of knowledge of other people’s mental lives, then there is a problem in accounting for the source of such knowledge. What reasons are given for ruling out these sources of knowledge? Take perception first. In comparing the perceptual and inferential responses, Price comments that “it must strike every unprejudiced person that [the perceptual theory] is much the odder of the two. . . . It is extremely paradoxical” (Price 1931: 54). This sense of absurdity is often shared: what would it be to perceive another’s mental life? Colin McGinn offers further considerations in support: “While propositional perceptual reports sometimes seem natural in specifying my cognitive relation to the mental states of another, direct object perceptual reports (‘I saw the pain in his foot’) seem definitely wrong” (McGinn 1984: 123 n.2). If this linguistic phenomenon tells us something about the objects of perception, knowledge of others’ minds cannot be a form of perceptual knowledge. What about the claim that inference cannot serve as a source of such knowledge? Various arguments have been put forward in support of this claim. It has been claimed that we do not appear to engage in inferential reasoning; that infants and

706

SKEPTICISM

animals can know things about others’ minds without possessing the cognitive powers necessary to engage in inference; that we do not know enough about other people’s behavior to provide a sound base for inference (Price 1931: 55–56). More sophisticated objections hold that one cannot engage in inference in cases where it is logically impossible to verify the conclusion, or that the link between behavior and mind is known only from one’s own case and that this is not a secure enough basis to secure inferential justification (Ryle 1949: 15–16; Malcolm 1958: 969). If one finds these reasons persuasive, knowledge of others’ minds is not a form of inferential knowledge. It is the supposed inadequacies of perceptual and inferential models of knowledge that motivate skepticism about others’ minds. Standard responses to this problem opt to deny one or other of these claims: either they claim that perception can be a source of knowledge of others’ minds, or—as is more common—they claim that the experience of behavior can ground inferential knowledge about another’s mind. Either option amounts to a denial of (S2): there is a means by which we know truths about another’s mind. Let us consider each in turn. First, perception. Although it has been the less popular of the two options, the claim that our knowledge of others’ minds is a form of perceptual knowledge has been defended throughout the twentieth century (Duddington 1918; Dretske 1973; McDowell 1998c; Cassam 2007a: ch.5; McNeill 2011). It was a prominent part of the phenomenological tradition, and some recent defenders of a perceptual account have drawn on the work of Scheler, Husserl, and Merleau-Ponty in presenting their proposals (Gallagher and Zahavi 2008; Krueger and Overgaard 2012). Much of this work is primarily defensive. Consider the following objection to perceptual accounts: other people’s mental lives can’t be perceived; therefore, our source of knowledge of such lives can’t be perception. There are two responses to this claim in the literature. Dretske and Cassam accept the premise of the objection while rejecting its conclusion: they hold that one can see that another person is angry and thus come to know that another person is angry without seeing her anger. Others hold that our perception of others extends beyond their behavior to take in their mentality: other people’s mental lives are perceptible. In defending the first option, Dretske offers the following analogy: one can see that a piece of metal is hot without seeing its heat. Similarly, one can see that another person is angry without seeing her anger. These claims rely on the account of epistemic seeing—seeing that something is the case—set out in Dretske (1969). If one accepts Dretske’s account of epistemic seeing, it is possible to see that someone is angry and thereby come to know that she is angry without seeing her anger.2 The second form of response holds that certain mental features can be seen. This is sometimes supported, contra McGinn, by appeal to the facility of certain perceptual locutions in reporting the source of our knowledge of others’ minds: “I heard the anger in her voice”; “I saw the pain in her eyes” (Green 2007; Stout 2010). The claim has been developed in different ways: some hold that mental states are expressed in behavior and thus perceptible (Green 2007); others hold that behavior is partly constitutive of mentality, such that in seeing others’ behavior one sees their mental features (Krueger and Overgaard 2012). These claims turn

SKEPTICISM ABOUT OTHER MINDS

707

on wider issues in the philosophy of mind about the relation between mental states and behavior. The above comments are defensive: they aim to defend the perceptual model against a natural and prominent objection. Are there any positive reasons for adopting a perceptual account of our knowledge of others’ minds? One can find two lines of thought in the literature. The first is that it seems to us as if our access to other people’s mental lives is perceptual and that we should take this appearance seriously. This is particularly stressed by those who draw on the phenomenological tradition (e.g., Krueger and Overgaard 2012: 248), but it might also be thought to be part of John McDowell’s influential presentation of a perceptual account. As McDowell puts it, “We should not jib at, or interpret away, the commonsense thought that . . . one can literally perceive, in another person’s facial expression or his behavior, that he is in pain, and not just infer that he is in pain from what one perceives” (McDowell 1998b: 305). This explains why the bulk of this literature is primarily defensive: if our starting point is the commonsense thought that our access to others’ minds is perceptual, then all we need do is defend that starting point against objections. The second motivation relates to what is sometimes called “the conceptual problem of other minds.” This chapter is concerned with the epistemological problem of other minds, the problem of accounting for our ability to know about others’ mental lives. The conceptual problem of other minds concerns the problem of explaining our ability to think about others’ mental lives. This latter problem is often traced back to a set of remarks in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations (1953: §243–315). Details of this supposed problem needn’t concern us here, but some philosophers who address the conceptual problem take it that explaining our ability to think about others’ mental lives requires us to take other people’s mental lives to be perceptible.3 And this, they hold, supports the claim that our knowledge of others’ mental lives is perceptual.4 Let me turn now to inference. There have been two historically popular ways of cashing out the thought that our knowledge of others’ minds is based on inference. According to analogical accounts, my beliefs about another’s mental life are warranted in virtue of my recognizing that my thoughts and feelings cause certain patterns of behavior, perceiving other people exhibiting those same patterns of behavior, and concluding—by analogy—that when other people exhibit that behavior, they also instantiate those thoughts and feelings (Mill 1979; Russell 1948). According to best explanation accounts, my beliefs about another’s mental life are warranted in virtue of the hypothesis that the person instantiates those mental features being the best explanation of her observable behavior (Pargetter 1984). J.S. Mill is often claimed to have provided the paradigm statement of an analogical account. He writes: I conclude that other human beings have feelings like me, because, first, they have bodies like me, which I know, in my own case, to be the antecedent condition of feelings; and because, secondly, they exhibit the acts, and other outward signs, which in my own case I know by experience to be caused by feelings. (1979: 190)

708

SKEPTICISM

This argument is typically presented as a case of enumerative induction. I observe that, in my own case, behavior type B is caused by feeling type F; I conclude that for all humans, behavior B is caused by feeling F; I observe another person exhibiting behavior B and conclude that she instantiates feeling F. But so presented, it is vulnerable to the objection that observation of one positive instance is not sufficient to warrant belief in a universal statement. According to this objection, the argument from analogy no more justifies my believing that other people have thoughts and feelings than my having a mole under my left arm justifies my believing that everyone has a mole under their left arm (Malcolm 1958: 969; Putnam 1975: 342–343). There are two ways to respond to this objection. First, one might hold that enumerative induction from a single case is sometimes permissible. Hyslop and Jackson (1972: 175), for example, hold that enumerative induction from a single case is permissible when one already knows that the relation between the two features in question is causal. Second, one might deny that the argument from analogy really proceeds from consideration of a single case. Ayer (1956: 219–222), for instance, holds that the analogical inference rests on a multitude of correlations between instances of mental properties and instances of behavior, albeit instances all confined to a single person. Whatever the merits of these responses, the single-case objection is a poor objection to Mill, whose discussion is much more sophisticated and interesting than typically presented.5 Central to Mill’s discussion—which bears reading beyond the sample of text quoted above—is the thought that we are dealing with the class human beings. Human beings are members of a natural kind, and Mill himself is a member of that kind. Since the laws of nature that govern our mental features apply to all members of the natural kind uniformly, Mill takes himself to be licensed in moving from the identification of those features of himself which hold in virtue of him being a member of that kind to the reasonable assumption that other members of the kind will instantiate the same features. This is comparable, Mill thinks, to the chemist who makes pronouncements about the properties of a new chemical element after having conducted one proper experiment (Mill 1973, quoted in Thomas 2001: 519). Mill’s positive proposal is closer to the best explanation accounts according to which our belief in others’ mental states is justified in the same way as our belief in scientific unobservables: on the grounds that the postulation of such entities best explains the observed data. In the case of others’ minds, the observed data is the movement of their bodies, and the best explanation is the ascription to others of mental states. This is perhaps the dominant account of our knowledge of others’ minds in the psychological literature, but it raises a number of questions. First, does inference to the best explanation warrant the beliefs of those who do not have explicit beliefs about the explanatory role of mental states—a group which I take to include most of us before we took up philosophy or psychology? Second, can it warrant the beliefs of children, say, who lack the conceptual resources to hold beliefs about the explanatory connections between mental states and observable behavior? And finally, is the ascription of mental states genuinely the best explanation of other people’s behavior, or are there other neuroscientific explanations that crowd it out?

SKEPTICISM ABOUT OTHER MINDS

709

Two final comments on the perceptual and inferential approaches. First, it should be common ground that some of our knowledge of others’ minds is inferential. We sometimes puzzle over another’s strange behavior, before concluding that it is explained by some fact about her mental life. This knowledge is based on inference. Or consider the way in which historians come to know what those in the past believed. Perhaps cultural historians of the British Empire know whether Dadabhai Naoroji—the first British Asian MP—regretted leaving mathematics for politics. But if they do so, it is because they have inferred it from historical evidence. The debate, then, should not be phrased as whether our knowledge of others’ minds is either perceptual or inferential, but given that some of it is inferential, whether it is all so. Second, in presenting the opposition between these accounts, I have taken it for granted that there is a distinction between perceptual and inferential knowledge. How are we to characterize this distinction? Defenders of a perceptual model sometimes seem to assume that a piece of knowledge is inferential if it is the result of a process of inferential reasoning (Cassam 2007a: 160; cf. Price 1931: 55). But a piece of knowledge can be supported by inferential relations even if it is not the result of inferential reasoning (Brandom 2002: 95–98; Pryor 2004: 190). My belief that you’re at home, for example, may come to me unbidden upon seeing your car in the driveway; in this sense, it is not the result of a process of inferential reasoning. But its epistemic justification may still lie in my warranted belief in an inferential relation between the proposition that your car is in the driveway and the proposition that you are at home. We need a fuller characterization of the differences between perceptual and inferential knowledge if we are to confidently evaluate the reasons for thinking that one or other is the source of our knowledge of others’ minds.

5  NEXT STEPS I finish with some more general comments on skepticism about others’ minds. As I’ve presented the issue, the aim is to identify the source of our knowledge of others’ mental lives. The recent debate confines itself to discussion of perception and inference as possible sources of knowledge. This marks a change from the discussion conducted at the start of the previous century where other sources of knowledge, such as telepathy, were given serious consideration. Let me conclude by noting two ways in which broadening our horizons may help this debate. First, testimony. When one thinks about the way in which we come to know about others’ mental lives, it is not perception or inference that stand out. Rather, other people tell us things—and among the things they tell us are facts about their mental life. Could testimony be a source of knowledge of others’ mental lives? One might think not for a simple reason: knowledge gained through testimony presupposes that one knows that the other person has a mind, so it can’t be used to explain how one gains such knowledge (Stroud 2000b: 101; Cassam 2007a: 157). But this form of reasoning has a parallel in discussions about perceptual knowledge: knowledge gained through perception presupposes that one knows that one is perceiving (Stroud 2000c: 131–133). And the presupposition claim about perception has been the subject of much discussion: it looks to lead to skepticism about perceptual knowledge, and

710

SKEPTICISM

many have argued that it should be rejected (McDowell 1998d, 1998e). It is worth considering whether the lessons of this debate can be applied to the case of gaining knowledge of others’ minds through testimony and, if so, whether testimony could serve as a basic source of knowledge of others’ minds (Gomes 2015). Second, variety. I’ve assumed throughout that there is one way—or better, that there is some fundamental way—by which we come to know about others’ minds. But perhaps this is false: perhaps there is no general way by which we come to know about the minds of others. Let us draw a distinction between two different ways of grouping known facts: on the basis that such knowledge has been gained from the same source, or on the basis that it all concerns the same domain. Call these two ways of classifying knowledge source-knowledge and domain-knowledge. Some examples of source-knowledge include the facts I know on the basis of perception; the facts that you know on the basis of reading Wikipedia; the facts that Priya knows through divine revelation. Some examples of domain-knowledge include everything I know about cars; that which you know about Sri Lanka; the things you know about the Catholic Church. The difference between these two ways of classifying known facts is not always made clear, as when philosophers move interchangeably between discussing perceptual knowledge and knowledge of the external world. But we should be careful to mark the distinction, for it need not be the case that some knowledge picked out via a certain domain has all arisen from the same source. And, indeed, although there are cases where all the things we know about a particular domain were gained from the same source—“Everything I learned about love I learned from romance novels”—this is the exception rather than the norm. Given that knowledge of others’ thoughts and feelings is a type of knowledge picked out via its domain, we have no grounds for thinking that it is all gained via the same source. Does such variety have implications for the skeptical challenge? If the aim is to identify the means (perhaps plural) by which we know about others’ minds, then we need some way of individuating sources of knowledge. This is particularly important in a context in which psychological and neuroscientific investigation is providing us with a wealth of information on the mechanisms by which we ascribe mental states to one another (Nichols and Stich 2003). There have been discussions of how to individuate sources of knowing in the epistemology literature (Nozick 1981: 179–185; Audi 2002; Cassam 2007b), but presentation of the problem of other minds often proceeds as if we have an unproblematic understanding of the means of knowing which are antecedently available for consideration. Addressing skepticism about others’ minds may require renewing interest in this epistemological question.6

NOTES 1. I owe this point to Paul Snowdon. 2. For criticisms and discussion of Cassam and Dretske on this point, see Gomes (2010) and McNeill (2011). 3. See Avramides (2001) and Gomes (2011) for introductions to the conceptual problem.

SKEPTICISM ABOUT OTHER MINDS

711

4. See Malcolm (1958) for an influential presentation of this thought. 5. See Thomas (2001) for an excellent discussion of Mill’s text. 6. Many thanks to Nick Jones, Rory Madden, Matt Parrott, Ian Phillips, and Lee Walters for helpful comments.

REFERENCES Audi, Robert. 2002. “The Sources of Knowledge.” In P. Moser (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology, 71–92. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Austin, J. L. 1961 (1946). “Other Minds.” In his Philosophical Papers, 76–116. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Avramides, Anita. 2001. Other Minds. London: Routledge. Ayer, A. J. 1953. “One’s Knowledge of Other Minds.” In his Philosophical Essays, 191– 214. London: Macmillan. Ayer, A. J. 1956. The Problem of Knowledge. London: Macmillan Benacerraf, Paul. 1973. “Mathematical Truth,” Journal of Philosophy 70: 661–679. Brandom, Robert. 2002. “Non-inferential Knowledge, Perceptual Experience, and Secondary Qualities: Placing McDowell’s Empiricism.” In N. Smith (ed.), Reading McDowell: On Mind and World, 92–105. London: Routledge. Cassam, Quassim. 2007a. The Possibility of Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cassam, Quassim. 2007b. “Ways of Knowing,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 107: 339–358. Cassam, Quassim. 2009. “What is Knowledge?” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 84: 101–120. Davidson, Donald. 1991. “What is Present to the Mind?” Philosophical Issues 1: 197–213. Dretske, Fred. 1973. “Perception and Other Minds,” Noûs 7: 34–44. Dretske, Fred. 1969. Seeing And Knowing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Duddington, N. A. 1918. “Our Knowledge of Other Minds,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 19: 147–178. Fodor, Jerry. 1994. “Jerry A. Fodor.” In S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, 292–300. Oxford: Blackwell. Gallagher, Shaun and Dan Zahavi. 2008. The Phenomenological Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science. London: Routledge. Gomes, Anil. 2009. “Other Minds and Perceived Identity,” Dialectica 63: 219–230. Gomes, Anil. 2011. “Is There a Problem of Other Minds?” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111: 353–373. Gomes, Anil. 2015. “Testimony and Other Minds,” Erkenntnis. 80: 173–183. Green, Mitchell. 2010. “Perceiving Emotions,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 84: 45–61. Hampshire, Stuart. 1979 (1969). “Some Difficulties in Knowing.” In T. Honderich and M. Burnyeat (eds.), Philosophy as It Is. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Hyslop, Alec and Frank Jackson. 1972. “The Analogical Inference to Other Minds,” American Philosophical Quarterly 9: 168–176.

712

SKEPTICISM

Krueger, Joel and Søren Overgaard. 2012. “Seeing Subjectivity: Defending a Perceptual Account of other Minds,” ProtoSociology: Consciousness and Subjectivity 47: 239–262. Mackie, J.L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin. Malcolm, Norman. 1958. “Knowledge of Other Minds,” Journal of Philosophy 55: 969– 978. McDowell, John. 1998a. Meaning, Knowledge and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. McDowell, John. 1998b (1978). “On ‘The Reality of the Past.’ ” In his Meaning, Knowledge and Reality, 295–313. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. McDowell, John. 1998c (1982). “Criteria, Defeasibility and Knowledge.” In his Meaning, Knowledge and Reality, 369–394. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. McDowell, John. 1998d (1986). “Singular Thought and the Extent of ‘Inner Space’.” In his Meaning, Knowledge and Reality, 228–259. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. McDowell, John. 1998e (1995). “Knowledge and the Internal.” In his Meaning, Knowledge and Reality, 395–413. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. McGinn, Colin. 1984. “What is the Problem of Other Minds?” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 58: 119–137. McNeill, Will. 2012. “On Seeing That Someone is Angry,” European Journal of Philosophy 20: 575–597. Mill, J. S. 1973 (1843). A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive, Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volume VII, ed. J. M. Robson. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Mill, J.S. 1979 (1865). An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy, Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volume IX, ed. J. M. Robson and A. Ryan. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Nichols, Shaun, and Stephen Stich. 2003. Mindreading: An Integrated Account of Pretence, Self- Awareness and Understanding Other Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Pargetter, Robert. 1984. “The Scientific Inference to other Minds,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62: 158–163. Price, H.H. 1931. “Our Knowledge of Other Minds,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 32: 53–78 Pryor, James. 2004. “There Is Immediate Justification.” In M. Steup and E. Sosa (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, 181–202. Oxford: Blackwell. Putnam, Hilary. 1975. “Other Minds.” In his Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2, 342–361. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Russell, Bertrand. 1948. Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits. London: Routledge. Ryle, Gilbert. 1949. The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson. Stout, G. F. 1898. Manual of Psychology. London: University Correspondence College Press. Stout, Rowland. 2010. “Seeing the Anger in Someone’s Face,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 84: 29–43. Stroud, Barry. 2000a. Understanding Human Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stroud, Barry. 2000b (1989). “Understanding Human Knowledge in General.” In his Understanding Human Knowledge, 101–121. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

SKEPTICISM ABOUT OTHER MINDS

713

Stroud, Barry. 2000c (1996). “Epistemological Reflection on Knowledge of the External World.” In his Understanding Human Knowledge, 123–138. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Thomas, Janice. 2001. “Mill’s Argument for other Minds,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9: 507–523 Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1992. Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology. Vol. 2: The Inner and the Outer. Oxford: Blackwell. Woolf, Virginia. 1998 (1927). To The Lighthouse. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

CHAPTER FORTY-NINE

Moral Skepticism RICHARD JOYCE

1  WHAT IS MORAL SKEPTICISM? The moral skeptic denies (or at least refuses to affirm) that anyone has moral knowledge. Moral skepticism could, of course, fall out of a more ubiquitous skepticism according to which we lack knowledge in general, but as an interestingly distinct position it is the view that there is something problematic about moral knowledge in particular. If one assumes that for S to know that p is (at least) for S to (i) believe that p (ii) truly and (iii) with justification, then there are several different ways of being a moral skeptic: (1) Noncognitivism: the denial that moral judgments are beliefs. (2) Error theory: the acceptance that moral judgments are beliefs while denying that these beliefs are ever true. (3) Justification skepticism: the acceptance that moral judgments are beliefs while denying that we are ever justified in holding these beliefs. If one takes moral realism to be the thesis that we sometimes succeed in making objectively true moral judgments, then the first two forms of moral skepticism count as moral anti-realist views.1 However, moral skepticism and moral realism are neither contraries nor contradictories. First, consider the constructivist view that we sometimes succeed in making moral judgments that are true but lack any robust claim to objectivity. Such a view leaves room for moral knowledge and yet remains (by the above criteria) a form of antirealism. Second, consider the justification skepticism just described in 3. One might lack justification for holding moral beliefs that are in fact objectively true. Such a view satisfies the criteria both for moral realism and for moral skepticism. To clarify moral skepticism further, let us consider an ancient distinction. The Academic skeptic assents that we lack knowledge and therefore suspends judgment on many matters, whereas the Pyrrhonian skeptic withholds assent even to the claim that we lack knowledge.2 One might think that this distinction would “scale down” to the moral domain, perhaps matching some version of modern moral skepticism, but it does so only clumsily. Let us define “moral knowledge” as knowledge of first-order

MORAL SKEPTICISM

715

moral claims, such as “Shoplifting is wrong,” “One ought not break promises without good reason,” and so forth. The natural thought would be that the Academic moral skeptic assents that we lack moral knowledge (and therefore suspends judgment on moral matters), whereas the Pyrrhonian moral skeptic withholds assent even to the claim that we lack moral knowledge. What is noteworthy is that the proposition that we have/lack moral knowledge is not itself a first-order moral claim (but is rather an epistemic claim about moral claims), and therefore such a Pyrrhonian moral skeptic must doubt something more than just first-order moral claims. In other words, one cannot be Pyrrhonian about just first-order moral claims. The classical Pyrrhonian skeptic poked fun at his Academic opponent for withholding assent to many claims while making a seemingly unaccountable exception for the universal epistemic claim that there is no knowledge. But the Pyrrhonian moral skeptic is robbed of this stratagem, for the Academic’s suspension of judgment for moral claims is perfectly compatible with the wholehearted assertion of the higher-order claim that there exists no moral knowledge. While a modern skeptic may side with the Academic in affirming that we have no moral knowledge, she does not necessarily therefore suspend judgment on all first-order moral matters. The moral error theorist, for example, may base her confident denial of moral knowledge on her equally confident denial that any moral judgments are true. Faced with a moral proposition like “Shoplifting is morally wrong,” the error theorist does not suspend judgment, but affirms its falsity. (She also, of course, affirms the falsity of “Shoplifting is morally right” and “Shoplifting is morally permissible”—so her affirmation must not be taken to imply any kind of practical tolerance of shoplifting.)3 Nevertheless, something with the flavor of the Academic/Pyrrhonian distinction can exist at the level of moral skepticism, for one can either be confident that there is no moral knowledge or be quite undecided on the matter. One may, for example, be undecided whether moral judgments are beliefs or rather some kind of affective/conative mental state, in which case one will be undecided whether noncognitivism is true, and hence potentially undecided whether there is such a thing as moral knowledge. This is not, however, a terribly interesting kind of position to hold, since it may reflect a simple contingent and temporary ignorance on the subject. (I, for example, know nothing of advanced set theory, and therefore maintain a healthy but mundane skepticism on any controversial claim from that domain.) A more interesting kind of skepticism would hold that there is something undecidable about these matters.4 While this latter view is coherent (and possibly plausible), modern metaethicists who hold a position implying the nonexistence of moral knowledge have tended to be more assured in advocating their favored arguments, and therefore the three skeptical positions listed above are usually put forward with some confidence, meaning moral skepticism as it is discussed in the philosophical literature generally has a more Academic color. (In other words, Pyrrhonian skeptics would probably accuse modern moral skeptics of dogmatism.) In any case, let us discuss the three metaethical versions of modern moral skepticism in turn.

716

SKEPTICISM

2 NONCOGNITIVISM Noncognitivism has its roots in the nineteenth century, and arguably goes back to Hume,5 but it first crystallized in the 1930s in works by Rudolf Carnap (1935), Ayer (1936), and Stevenson (1937).6 The noncognitivist claims that moral utterances are not really assertions, despite appearances to the contrary. Noncognitivism can be put forward as a semantic thesis—that the meaning of moral sentences cannot be properly rendered in the indicative mood—or put forward as a thesis concerning the pragmatics of moral language—that moral sentences are not used with assertoric force. According to the former understanding, moral sentences, such as “Shoplifting is wrong,” need to be transcribed into some other non-indicative format, such as “Don’t shoplift!” or “Boo to shoplifting!” What is metaethically important about these renderings is that (i) they are no longer truth-evaluable, (ii) reference to moral properties (e.g., wrongness) has disappeared, and (iii) they are no longer items of belief. These same features are claimed of moral discourse according to a pragmatic understanding of noncognitivism. Imagine that one were to utter the sentence “Shoplifting is wrong” as a line in a play. The meaning of the sentence would remain the same as ever—it would be a mistake to transcribe the sentence into some other format—yet the sentence would not be put forward as a truth (i.e., it would not be asserted), the speaker would not be committed to the existence of wrongness (any more than “Once upon a time there lived a dragon” commits the storyteller to the existence of dragons), and it would not be believed, either by utterer or by audience. The pragmatic noncognitivist claims all this for ordinary moral utterances. For our current purposes, the key noncognitive claim is that moral judgments are not items of belief, implying that there can be no such thing as moral propositional knowledge. Noncognitivism faces many challenges. If moral sentences are not truth-evaluable, then it is difficult to make sense of their appearance in standard logically complex contexts, such as negations or conditionals (Geach 1965). We frequently form views about the world on the basis of our moral judgments, yet if moral judgments are essentially conative (as opposed to doxastic), then our doing so would appear to be nothing more than a form of wishful thinking (Dorr 2002). If there are no moral beliefs, then it appears that we should reject as false or incoherent claims like “John believes that Hitler was evil.” If moral judgments are nothing more than expressions of the speaker’s desires, then what practical authority could such judgments purport to have over others? Indeed, why would we engage in serious moral debate at all, if all we are doing is trying to express conflicting feelings?7 The noncognitivism of the mid-twentieth century tended to be unapologetic about these consequences, seemingly willing to bite the bullet that many aspects of everyday moral discourse are flawed and its speakers confused. Contemporary noncognitivism is more conciliatory, attempting to win the right for many of these seemingly cognitivist features for moral discourse. Simon Blackburn’s quasi-realist program, in particular, aims to provide legitimacy for talk of moral truth, moral belief, moral properties, moral assertions, and moral knowledge, all within a noncognitivist framework (Blackburn 1993, 1998). Regarding moral knowledge, for example, Blackburn claims that we know things when our confidence will

MORAL SKEPTICISM

717

not be overturned. One’s disapproval of shoplifting, say, may not be as assured as one’s disapproval of punching babies—after all, one may be willing to accept the possibility that shoplifting may, by some unforeseen but reliable causal chain, result in overall economic benefit, in which case one may be willing to countenance the possibility of ceasing to disapprove of shoplifting. One is considerably less likely to countenance this possibility for punching babies. Thus, Blackburn maintains, one can claim to know that punching babies is wrong in a way that one does not claim to know that shoplifting is wrong—though both associated moral judgments are mere expressions of attitude rather than belief. The potential instability of this quasi-realist program has been pointed out several times (Dreier 2004; Lewis 2005), inasmuch that if quasi-realism is successful it becomes difficult to differentiate the position from the cognitivist perspective from which it is supposedly distinct. Perhaps the problem here arises from shifting and imprecise characterizations of the term “noncognitivism.” If, for example, one defines “noncognitivism” as the view that moral judgments are not truth-evaluable, then obviously earning the right to the literal use of the full-blown truth predicate for moral judgments is precluded. It would seem Blackburn himself has a somewhat different understanding of the anti-realist stance for which he aims to earn the trappings of realist talk, and on at least one occasion he has expressed a lack of enthusiasm for “noncognitivism” as a label for his position; he tends to prefer the title “projectivism.”8 It is clear, though, that if his quasi-realist program earns for morality a claim to genuine knowledge, then the resulting position is no longer a skeptical one (a result Blackburn will welcome).

3  ERROR THEORY Error-theoretic moral skepticism is the thesis that while our moral discourse does function assertorically (contra the noncognitivist’s view), the world lacks the properties and relations that are necessary to render these assertions true. A good analogy is atheism: the atheist denies that when someone utters, say, “God loves us” the speaker is merely expressing his/her feelings; rather, religious speakers really are making assertions about the world. (Thus the atheist is a cognitivist about theistic discourse.) However (the atheist thinks), the world is not furnished with the items necessary to make “God loves us” true; religious discourse suffers from a massive and systematic error. Similarly, the moral error theorist thinks that, in order for our moral judgments to be true, the world would need to provide properties like goodness and badness, rightness and wrongness, evil and virtue—which it simply does not. The error theorist doesn’t merely think that the world lacks objective moral properties, but that it lacks subjective moral properties. (To press the analogy, the atheist doesn’t merely hold that the gods fail to exist objectively, but that they fail to exist subjectively, too.) The error theory was coined and clearly articulated by John Mackie in 1977, though one can find awareness of the viewpoint running back to the ancients. Even Brutus is reported to have died with the despairing words “Wretched virtue;

718

SKEPTICISM

although you were nothing but a name, I practiced you as something real!”9 Several centuries earlier, Anaxarchus espoused a moral view that has been interpreted as an error theory (Warren 2002: 81).10 Generally speaking, although this form of skepticism has had few staunch defenders, the fact that so much of moral philosophy can be interpreted as striving to refute the view suggests a perennial awareness of its possibility. In order to approach the question of what considerations might lead one to endorse a moral error theory, it is useful to reflect on what considerations might lead one to endorse atheism. While a person might be persuaded by a careful philosophical argument, such as the argument from evil, more likely would be a general conviction that appeal to divine entities is explanatorily redundant, along with some vague evocation of a principle of parsimony. This might be coupled with a set of images about why religious belief emerged for sociological reasons, a component of which might be the notion that humans are prone to gullibility when it comes to theistic ideas. The atheist need not claim to have any demonstrative falsification of theism (though, again, he might try to develop such an argument)— need not claim to know that there are no gods—but nevertheless thinks that, on balance, the evidence is in his favor sufficiently to support disbelief being accorded high credence. The moral error theorist takes a similar view of moral discourse. Perhaps he reflects on the thousands of years of trying to make sense of moral facts and judges the enterprise to have been a spectacular failure. Nothing in the world seems to require the existence of moral facts (he thinks), which, coupled with a more-orless stringent and more-or-less precise principle of parsimony, counsels in favor of disbelief. Perhaps this pessimistic conclusion is bolstered by a set of images about why moral thinking might have evolved (at evolutionary, sociological, and psychological levels), a component of which is the notion that humans are particularly prone to this kind of gullibility. The moral error theorist (like the atheist) faces challenges that may force more careful defense. It goes without saying that many will find it an appallingly counterintuitive and pernicious position. On the basis of its counterintuitiveness, opponents might employ an epistemological principle according to which any sufficiently implausible conclusion should be rejected in preference to overturning any less implausible premises. Thus, any argument to the conclusion “There is nothing morally wrong with punching babies” can be rejected out of hand, it will be claimed, perhaps even without one’s being able to pinpoint its fault, since we know that accepting the conclusion will require a greater violation of our intuitions than rejecting any philosophical premise that might appear to entail it (see Enoch 2011). The error theorist, though, is unlikely to accept this epistemological methodology, and in any case the principle arguably fails to count against a counterintuitive skeptical thesis if the advocate of the thesis also has at her disposal a plausible hypothesis about why the skeptical thesis would seem counterintuitive even though true (see Joyce 2014). Other opponents will endeavor to provide a characterization of moral properties about which the error theorist will find it difficult to locate grounds

MORAL SKEPTICISM

719

for complaint. For the religion analog this is implausible. To the atheist someone may say “But God is just love, and you believe in love, don’t you?”—to which it is reasonable to reply adamantly that God is not love (not, at least, in a literal sense involving the “is” of identity). That the concept God essentially involves characteristics that the concept love does not is something one can pronounce as assuredly as that the concept dog involves characteristics that the concept glove does not. The same sort of reply can be maintained by the moral error theorist but cannot be pressed with quite the analogous assurance. A hedonic utilitarian, for example, might say “But moral goodness just is happiness, and you believe in happiness, don’t you?”—to which the error theorist’s reply “No, moral goodness is not happiness” is a response that will require rather more deliberation and argument. In likelihood, what the error theorist will claim is that the concept moral goodness essentially involves reference to a certain kind of practical authority that the concept happiness does not (though it is open to the error theorist to highlight some other difference). Mackie, for example, refers to the work of rationalist Samuel Clarke, who in the early eighteenth century argued for (in Mackie’s words) “necessary relations of fitness between situations and actions, so that a situation would have a demand for such-and-such an action somehow built into it” (1977: 40). Mackie cashes out this “intrinsic action-guiding” quality by saying that it would provide “reasons . . . for doing or for not doing something [that] are independent of that agent’s desires or purposes” (Mackie 1982: 115). Such reasons, he thinks, can exist only in virtue of normative institutions, in the same way as one’s reason to move a chess piece in a certain manner exists only in virtue of some human-decreed system of rules. But moral rules, according to Mackie, have their reason-giving quality objectively; we do not treat them as norms of our invention, for to do so would rob them of their practical authority, which is, arguably, their whole point. The important elements of this argument are, first, that this “intrinsic-actionguiding” quality is (according to Mackie) something that moral goodness has essentially (such that any property lacking the quality simply wouldn’t upon reflection be recognizable as moral goodness), and, second, that it is a quality that happiness does not instantiate; therefore moral goodness cannot be happiness. Mackie goes further, of course, and claims that this quality is instantiated by no actual property; therefore the property of moral goodness is uninstantiated; therefore no claim of the form “X is morally good” is true.11 (Whether this is taken to hold contingently or necessarily is an interesting distinction that I won’t investigate here, except to say that either will suffice for an error theory.) The thorniest element of the argument is the conceptual claim that moral goodness has this intrinsic-action-guiding quality essentially. It is open to the error theorist’s opponent to acknowledge that many people have believed moral properties to have this kind of objective authority, while still maintaining that it is a dispensable component, conceptually speaking. Analogously, it was at one time almost universally believed that gorillas are violent brutes, but the discovery that the large primates living in Africa are in fact quite gentle and sociable creatures was not taken to be the discovery that gorillas do not exist. “Violent brutishness” was never

720

SKEPTICISM

an essential part of the concept gorilla. By contrast, the realization that nobody is or ever has been in cahoots with the devil was taken to imply that witches do not exist, since having supernatural powers is an indispensable trait of witches, conceptually speaking. So are moral concepts more like the concept gorilla or more like the concept witch? Not only has it proven hard to say, it has proven hard to decide upon a framework with which to address the question.

4  JUSTIFICATION SKEPTICISM Let us now turn to the third form of modern moral skepticism, the thesis that moral judgments are not justified. It is important first of all to establish that we mean epistemic justification. Suppose a person, S, holds the belief that p on the basis of good evidence, but would actually be better off, in terms of welfare (understood however you like), believing that not-p. Then we might say that S’s believing that p is instrumentally unjustified but, nevertheless, epistemically justified. Or suppose that S believes that p on the basis of some terribly flawed process of reasoning, but that having this belief is of great benefit to S. Then we might say that S’s believing that p is epistemically unjustified but, nevertheless, instrumentally justified. Of course, precisely what it takes for a belief to be epistemically justified is a matter of great controversy. (Even my references to S’s being sensitive to the evidence will not please everyone.) Speaking generally, one person may be justified in believing that p while another person is not justified in believing that p. Someone may lack justification for her belief but at a later date gain justification, or have justification but at a later date lose it. Nobody, I suppose, will object to the claim that some people sometimes lack justification for some of their moral beliefs (assuming that moral judgments are beliefs). Probably few will deny the somewhat bolder claim that everyone sometimes lacks justification for some of their moral beliefs. Maybe we’ll be willing to accept that there are some people who lack justification for all their moral beliefs. But the interesting skeptical thesis is stronger than any of these: that we all lack justification for all of our moral beliefs. And one can go stronger still, by maintaining that this epistemically disheartening situation is permanent, that there is nothing any of us can do to acquire justification for our moral beliefs. Call the penultimate thesis “justification skepticism” and the final thesis “strong justification skepticism.” Both views appear to prescribe a suspension of judgment upon learning that one’s moral beliefs lack justification. In what follows, I will confine attention to two arguments that might lead one to endorse justification skepticism, keeping an eye on whether the arguments also support strong justification skepticism. Let us begin by considering a person ordinarily lacking justification for one of her everyday moral convictions. What might lead us to endorse this description of her epistemic state? Perhaps we think that she hasn’t really considered this moral matter in any depth but is simply voicing an opinion that she was brought up with or that her peers all hold. Perhaps we think that she is biased or emotionally invested in the matter in a way that distorts her judgment. (Witness the eagerness manifested in people to punish someone when a deeply upsetting crime has been

MORAL SKEPTICISM

721

committed.) Perhaps we are aware that other parties, who are no worse off in terms of access to information or the capacity to deliberate, have come to a completely different moral conclusion. In everyday contexts, any combination of these findings might lead us to the conclusion that an individual’s moral conviction lacks justification. The proponent of justification skepticism about morality maintains that, upon reflection, one or more of these features that we ordinarily think of as removing justification actually applies across the board, to everyone’s moral beliefs at all times. Focus, to begin with, on the case when a person’s moral judgment is merely a matter of unreflectively voicing a view with which she was raised and by which she is surrounded. Some will claim that this is not sufficient for a lack of justification, since the moral view in question might nevertheless be an accurate one, picked up by the epistemic community via reliable truth-tracking mechanisms and transmitted to the person via reliable causal means; the fact that the individual herself cannot articulate evidence for her moral view is neither here nor there. Our attention, then, should move from the individual to her epistemic community: how likely is it that the community is (or in the past was) reliably tracking moral facts? At this point questions about the genealogy of moral thinking come to the fore— not just at the individual or sociological level but potentially from an evolutionary and biological perspective as well. In recent years, there has been much interest in hypotheses of moral nativism: the thesis that human moral thinking has evolved as a discrete psychological adaptation (see Krebs 2005; Joyce 2006; Mikhail 2011; Boehm 2012). What is noteworthy about these hypotheses is that they explain why moral thinking evolved in terms of its enhancing social cohesion among our ancestors—something that is no less plausible for an error theorist than a moral realist. In other words, moral nativism provides an explanation of why humans engage in moral judgment in a manner that does not imply or presuppose that the faculty in question was or is truth-tracking. (And, importantly, it is not a far-fetchedbut-unfalsifiable skeptical hypothesis, like Descartes’s demon, but a perfectly respectable and plausible empirical theory.) One might be tempted by an error-theoretic argument at this point: that because moral facts are not needed to explain anything, not even our making moral judgments, then one should, via a principle of parsimony, eliminate them from our ontology. But this is not the argument with which we are concerned here. Rather, the argument is that because our moral judgments can be explained without reference to moral facts—because they flow from a non-truth-tracking mechanism—we have reason to suspend judgment as to their truth. Whether the availability of moral nativist hypotheses undermines the epistemic status of moral judgments in this fashion is a matter of current debate (see Street 2006; White 2010; Brosnan 2011; Joyce 2013). A second argument for justification skepticism focuses on moral disagreement— an argumentative schema familiar to classical skeptics. Agrippa’s first Mode (diaphōnia) states that we must suspend judgment when there is undecided conflict over a proposition, while several of Aenesidemus’s Ten Modes highlight conflicting judgments among parties as the basis of Pyrrhonism. Modern epistemology

722

SKEPTICISM

continues to struggle with the question: what impact should disagreement have on the epistemic status of our beliefs? According to what is called “the Equal Weight View,” one’s confidence that p should fade upon encountering a dissenting epistemic peer if one’s prior conditional credence that p is low, where “prior” means prior to thinking things through and knowing what one’s peers think about whether p, and “conditional” means conditional on what one has learned about the circumstances of disagreement (see Elga 2007; also Feldman and Warfield 2010; Machuca 2013). In the case of moral matters, disagreement is ubiquitous. Norm variation among cultures on topics like infanticide, cannibalism, and incest are the most obvious and vivid examples to reach for; but one might instead simply advert to the small number of dedicated moral error theorists, who (when speaking carefully and sincerely) dissent to every moral claim to which anyone else wishes to assent. After all, the empirical prevalence of disagreement may not be an important factor; if it is merely possible that a rational agent with the same information as you, with the same facilities of discernment and deliberation as you, could come to believe that not-p, then this may be sufficient to undermine the epistemic status of your belief that p. If only actual peer disagreement were to count, then, as Lammenranta (2011: 211) notes, one could render one’s beliefs justified by killing all actual dissenters (see also Kelly 2005; for criticism, see Tersman 2013).12 I will end by briefly drawing attention to three features of these arguments for justification skepticism. First, they seem particular to the moral realm; they don’t fall out of a more general epistemic skepticism. Even if human moral thinking is the output of a mechanism that is non-truth-tracking, evolutionarily speaking, this need not be true of other evolved psychological mechanisms. Many of the various faculties involved in perception, for example, have surely evolved to track aspects of the world. (There would, for instance, be no adaptive gain in seeing distant things as close, or vice versa.) Also, moral disagreement seems to be different from many other forms of disagreement. We will (arguably) countenance the possibility of two rational agents with the same information and the same powers of deliberation disagreeing over a moral matter in a way that we will not accept the possibility of their disagreeing over an empirical matter. The second thing to note about justification skepticism is that in counseling suspension of judgment on moral matters it differs both from noncognitivist skepticism—which allows one to carry on confidently making moral judgments— and from error-theoretic skepticism—which seems to require one to deny moral propositions. In this respect justification skepticism seems more akin to classical versions of skepticism. The final observation is that neither of the arguments outlined—from genealogy and from disagreement—appears to contain the resources to establish strong justification skepticism. If they succeed at all, they succeed in removing any benefit of the doubt that we might otherwise have been inclined to accord our moral judgments, but there doesn’t appear to be anything in these arguments to exclude

MORAL SKEPTICISM

723

the possibility of justification being instated. Ancient skeptical arguments also suffered from this limitation. Perhaps the skeptical Modes succeeded in showing that our current beliefs lack justification, but the conclusion that this justification is unattainable was more a matter of the rhetoric of the skeptics’ language than an established thesis. Philo, for example, in On Drunkenness talks of disagreement being “chronic and hopeless” (in the words of Annas 1998: 196), which does suggest that the skeptical plight is envisaged to be a permanent human fixture.13 The crucial phrase in Sextus Empiricus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism I 165 (and elsewhere) is translated variously as “unresolvable impasse” (Mates 1996) and “undecidable dissension” (Annas and Barnes 2000). But the problem is that neither Philo, Sextus, nor any other ancient philosopher possessed a solid argument to show that disagreement must always have these qualities; they are just pessimistic. The ancients, of course, lacked an awareness of the impressive menu of epistemological theories now available—foundationalism, coherentism, reliabilism, and so forth— all of which hold out hope of demonstrating that many of our moral beliefs are justified. Perhaps what these arguments for justification skepticism achieve is the overthrow of the force of epistemic conservatism regarding moral beliefs: the idea that some degree of warrant for moral beliefs comes from the mere fact that we already hold them. The arguments for justification skepticism would shift the burden of proof onto the shoulders of the non-skeptic, challenging her to articulate a sound and defensible account of moral justification. The skeptic may then proceed to reject these accounts as they are offered, thus showing that the initial skeptical challenge remains unanswered. Sextus shows awareness of this strategy, since not only does he use the Modes to throw down the skeptical gauntlet, so to speak, but he also then backs this up with arguments aimed at exposing the failings of every available positive theory.14 (An updated version of Sextus’s Against the Ethicists might include “Against the Foundationalists,” “Against the Coherentists,” etc.) Such a strategy is by no means doomed to failure, but its advocate can never declare victory, since one never knows what vindicative epistemological theory the next generation might devise. The justification skeptic may have to rest content with the open-ended conclusion that until such a theory is enunciated and persuasively defended, a suspension of judgment on moral matters is called for.15

NOTES 1. If discourse about X consists of assertions that are sometimes true, then minimal realism is true of X. If, in addition, these assertions are true in virtue of the obtaining of objective facts, then robust realism is true of X. Some people doubt the distinction (Sayre-McCord 1986; Rosen 1994). Here I am privileging robust realism. 2. The distinction as presented here is widely accepted though possibly not entirely accurate. For more subtle discussion of the relation between Academic and Pyrrhonian skepticism, see Part I of this book.

724

SKEPTICISM

3. There are complications here concerning what counts as a “moral proposition.” If S claims to know that it is not the case that shoplifting is wrong, is this not a claim to moral knowledge, and therefore is it not incompatible with S’s claim that there is no such thing as moral knowledge? I do not think so. The error theorist can maintain that moral propositions are all and only those the assertion of which commits one to the existence of moral properties. “Shoplifting is morally wrong” is such a proposition, but “It is not the case that shoplifting is wrong” is not. (“Wilma is a witch” commits the speaker to the existence of witches; “It is not the case that Wilma is a witch” does not.) The error theorist can therefore confidently claim to know that it is not the case that shoplifting is wrong without contradicting the claim that there is no such thing as moral knowledge. See Pigden (2010) for useful discussion of the nuances of how the error theory should be described. 4. For views along these lines, see Sinnott-Armstrong (2006); Loeb (2008); Joyce (2012). 5. I myself doubt that Hume should count in any straightforward way as a noncognitivist. See Joyce (2010) for discussion. 6. See Satris (1987) for discussion of the nineteenth-century continental roots of noncognitivism. 7. See Smith (2001) for discussion of some less conspicuous problems for noncognitivism. 8. Blackburn (1996) writes: “I for many years strenuously opposed the label ‘noncognitivist,’ and . . . finding the label appropriate is a prime symptom of failing to stand by the advertised minimalism” (the minimalism referred to being a central plank of the quasi-realist program). For discussion of the relation between noncognitivism and projectivism, see Joyce (2009). 9. Reported by both Plutarch and Dio Cassius, though apparently Brutus (if he said it at all) was paraphrasing something poetically attributed to Heracles. See Nauck (1889: 910). 10. Though Julia Annas (1986) sensibly cautions against reading modern moral skeptical concerns into ancient skeptical thinking. 11. Here I have limited attention to moral goodness, but of course the dialectic is supposed to generalize to any moral property. One might complain that Mackie’s references to the “intrinsic-action-guiding” quality of moral properties is more suitable to a discussion of obligation than goodness. This, I think, is a fairly superficial complaint, and the example could easily be altered to accommodate. See Joyce (2001: 175–177) for some pertinent discussion. 12. We must again distinguish this epistemological argument from a superficially similar argument for a moral error theory. Mackie claims that the best explanation of the phenomenon of widespread intractable moral disagreement is that there are no moral facts (1977: 36–38). The argument currently under discussion, by contrast, does not rely on inference to the best explanation, and does not conclude that there are no moral facts, merely that our beliefs about them lack justification. 13. The Philo mentioned here is Philo of Alexandria, not the Academic skeptic Philo of Larissa. Still, in the passage cited Philo of Alexandria trenchantly builds a case against dogmatism, employing arguments that clearly draw on the Greek skeptical tradition.

MORAL SKEPTICISM

725

14. On Sextus’s skepticism, see the chapter on him in Part I of this book. Cicero’s de Finibus also contains arguments designed to refute each major moral theory in turn. 15. Many thanks to the editors of this book for a lot of sensible advice.

REFERENCES Annas, Julia. 1986. “Doing without Objective Values: Ancient and Modern Strategies.” In M. Schofield and G. Striker (eds.), The Norms of Nature: Studies in Hellenistic Ethics, 3–29. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Annas, Julia and Jonathan Barnes. 2000. Sextus Empiricus: Outlines of Scepticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ayer, Alfred J. 1936. Language, Truth and Logic. London: Victor Gollancz. Blackburn, Simon. 1993. Essays in Quasi-Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Blackburn, Simon. 1996. “Commentary on Ronald Dworkins’ ‘Objectivity and Truth: You’d Better Believe it,’ ” Brown Electronic Article Review Service in Moral and Political Philosophy. Accessed August 04, 2014. Blackburn, Simon. 1998. Ruling Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Boehm, Christopher. 2012. Moral Origins: The Evolution of Virtue, Altruism, and Shame. New York: Basic Books. Brosnan, Kevin. 2011. “Do the Evolutionary Origins of Our Moral Beliefs Undermine Moral Knowledge?” Biology and Philosophy 26: 51–64. Carnap, Rudolf. 1935. Philosophy and Logical Syntax. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co. Dorr, Cian. 2002. “Non-cognitivism and Wishful Thinking,” Noûs 36: 97–103. Dreier, Jamie. 2004. “Meta-ethics and the Problem of Creeping Minimalism,” Philosophical Perspectives 18: 23–44. Elga, Adam. 2007. “Reflection and Disagreement,” Noûs 41: 478–502. Enoch, David. 2011. Taking Morality Seriously. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Feldman, Richard and Ted Warfield (eds.). 2010. Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Geach, Peter. 1965. “Assertion,” Philosophical Review 74: 449–465. Joyce, Richard. 2001. The Myth of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Joyce, Richard. 2006. The Evolution of Morality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Joyce, Richard. 2009. “Is Moral Projectivism Empirically Tractable?” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12: 53–75. Joyce, Richard. 2010. “Expressivism, Motivation Internalism, and Hume.” In C. Pigden (ed.), Hume on Motivation and Virtue, 30–56. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan. Joyce, Richard. 2012. “Metaethical Pluralism: How Both Moral Naturalism and Moral Skepticism may be Permissible Positions.” In S. Nuccetelli and G. Seay (eds.), Ethical Naturalism: Current Debates, 89–109. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Joyce, Richard. 2013. “Irrealism and the Genealogy of Morals,” Ratio 26: 351–372. Joyce, Richard. 2014. “Taking Moral Skepticism Seriously,” Philosophical Studies 168: 843–851.

726

SKEPTICISM

Kelly, Thomas. 2005. “The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement,” Oxford Studies in Epistemology 1: 167–196. Krebs, Denis. 2005. “The Evolution of Morality.” In D. Buss (ed.), The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology, 747–771. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. Lammenranta, Markus. 2011. “Skepticism and Disagreement.” In D. Machuca (ed.), Pyrrhonism in Ancient, Modern, and Contemporary Philosophy, 203–216. Dordrecht: Springer. Lewis, David. 2005. “Quasi-Realism Is Fictionalism.” In M. Kalderon (ed.), Fictionalism in Metaphysics, 314–321. Oxford: Clarendon. Loeb, Don. 2008. “Moral Incoherentism: How to Pull a Metaphysical Rabbit out of a Semantic Hat.” In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Moral Psychology, Volume 2: The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity, 355–385. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Machuca, Diego (ed.). 2013. Disagreement and Skepticism. New York: Routledge. Mackie, John L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin. Mackie, John L. 1982. The Miracle of Theism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mates, Benson. 1996. The Skeptic Way: Sextus Empiricus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mikhail, John. 2011. Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls’ Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nauck, August. 1889. Tragicorum Graecorum Fragmenta. Leipzig: Teubner. Pigden, Charles. 2010. “Nihilism, Nietzsche, and the Doppelganger Problem.” In R. Joyce and S. Kirchin (eds.), A World Without Values: Essays on John Mackie’s Moral Error Theory, 17–34. Dordrecht: Springer. Rosen, Gideon. 1994. “Objectivity and Modern Idealism: What is the Question?” In M. Michael and J. O’Leary-Hawthorne (eds.), Philosophy in Mind, 277–319. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Satris, Stephen. 1987. Ethical Emotivism. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff. Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey. 1986. “The Many Moral Realisms,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, suppl. vol. 24: 1–22. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. 2006. Moral Skepticisms. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Smith, Michael. 2001. “Some not-much-Discussed Problems for Non-cognitivism in Ethics,” Ratio 14: 93–115. Stevenson, Charles L. 1937. “The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms,” Mind 46: 14–31. Street, Sharon. 2006. “A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value,” Philosophical Studies 127: 109–166. Tersman, Folke. 2013. “Moral Disagreement: Actual vs. Possible.” In D. Machuca (ed.), Disagreement and Skepticism, 90–108. New York: Routledge. Warren, James. 2002. Epicurus and Democritean Ethics: An Archaeology of Ataraxia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. White, Roger. 2010. “You Just Believe That Because. . .,” Philosophical Perspectives 24: 573–615.

CHAPTER FIFTY

Religious Skepticism J. L. SCHELLENBERG

1  WHAT IS RELIGIOUS SKEPTICISM? Religious skepticism is often understood fairly loosely today. Both in academic and nonacademic contexts, pretty much anyone who is at all negative about religion, or who questions it in any way, may be seen as having an attitude that fits under this label. In the present discussion I adopt a narrower and, I hope, more illuminating understanding of the term. On this understanding, the term “religious skepticism” allows us to pick out certain specific attitudes in relation to religion— obviously associated with skepticism in the history of philosophy and deserving of discriminating attention—that are associated with being in doubt. What it is to be in doubt is best understood in relation to belief: ordinary usage and philosophical discussion alike suggest that someone is in doubt about a proposition when, and only when, having considered the proposition, she believes neither it nor its denial.1 (Note that being in doubt about a proposition is not the same as doubting that a proposition is true, which would usually be taken to entail or bring one close to belief of its denial.) Thus Suneetra, who on reflection does not believe that the soul is reincarnated but does not disbelieve this either, is to be regarded as being in doubt about whether the soul is reincarnated. But is this the only sort of skepticism to be associated with doubt? I think not. For example, consider Sam, who finds himself with the belief that there is a God but thinks doubt would be more appropriate because of the force of certain arguments his desires strongly resist. Sam may take it upon himself to actively question theistic belief over a period of time, hoping thereby eventually to do justice to the arguments, psychologically speaking. And it would be odd to deny that Sam is being skeptical about the claim that God exists as he does so. We can deal with this fact by distinguishing between active skepticism and passive skepticism, saying that Sam exemplifies the former but seeks to reach the latter by, so to speak, helping the relevant arguments induce a state of doubt in him. (He is forced to do so because the state of being in doubt, like belief, is fundamentally involuntary rather than voluntary.)2 This distinction between passive and active skepticism also neatly permits us to accommodate the commonly used phrase “suspending judgment,” which is often linked to skepticism but sounds like it refers

728

SKEPTICISM

to something one does—something active. One may voluntarily suspend judgment about a proposition by refusing to assert that the proposition is true or that it is false, and resisting inner affirmations on either side too, and this precisely is what one does when one exemplifies active skepticism.3 So we have passive skepticism, which is involuntarily being in doubt, and active skepticism, which means voluntarily identifying with doubt in the way I have described. These ways of being skeptical might of course arise in relation to many different subjects of inquiry. So we have to ask: what makes either form of skepticism religious? There are various possibilities here, the most obvious of which are (as my examples suggest) tied to religious propositions. But this point only invites a further question: what makes a proposition religious? Unfortunately, there is no standard answer to this question about the nature of religion; the matter is controversial. But, pretty clearly, restricting religiousness to behavior tied up with views about God or gods would be overly narrow: though they may be in the minority, there evidently are in the world today nontheistic and nonpersonalistic forms of religion (they can be found, for example, in Hinduism, Buddhism, and Taoism). Having said that, it is understandable if philosophers find most interesting those forms of religion that have clear and distinctive nonnaturalistic metaphysical commitments of the sort that belief in a personal god exemplifies. (Metaphysical naturalism is the view that concrete reality is a single unified system of natural law.) To deal with this issue here I will assume for the purpose of our discussion, which is primarily philosophical, that religion is bound up with the notion that metaphysical naturalism is false. Religious realities, if such there should be, would in other words be transcendent realities—transcendent of the natural world. It seems clear that religious people also greatly value the transcendent toward which they think of themselves as oriented. These metaphysical and axiological points I think we may safely assume, in a philosophical context. But to ensure wide relevance for what I say, I will not assume any more than what they contain. With that as background, we may continue elucidating religious skepticism by reference to religious propositions, now taken as claiming or entailing that there is a religious reality, thus understood. One might say that being skeptical about even one religious proposition is enough to instantiate religious skepticism. And so on this option, Suneetra, even if the proposition I mentioned before is the only religious proposition about which she is in doubt, exhibits religious skepticism. But to make our discussion of religious skepticism philosophically interesting, we need to construe the latter as a general stance on religion, not a particular one of the sort exhibited by Suneetra. Even if Suneetra is in doubt about the reincarnationist proposition, she may believe many other religious propositions, such as the propositions propounded by the Catholic Church, to which she has just converted. And it seems implausible to say she exhibits religious skepticism of any philosophically interesting sort in that case, for she is then a theist and a Christian! Notice that we are helped here by the fact that someone who, in a philosophical context, exhibits religious skepticism we should be able to call a religious skeptic. It would certainly be odd to apply this label to Suneetra if she is well on her way toward being a full-fledged Catholic.

RELIGIOUS SKEPTICISM

729

So when would it not be odd? To see when, we need to make a shift from the particular to the general. Suneetra is skeptical about whether one specific religious proposition is true. The religious skeptic, properly so-called, is skeptical about whether any religious proposition is true. This is what is required to have an alternative both to the religious believer, who thinks she has found at least one religious proposition that merits a more positive response than skepticism (there are of course innumerable examples of this stance, including many in contemporary philosophy of religion), and to a certain general sort of religious disbeliever, who thinks that religion merits, across the board, a more negative response than skepticism affords, believing all religious propositions to be false (metaphysical naturalists, whose view is presently in the ascendancy in philosophy more generally, afford examples here). The religious believer holds that there is truth in religion, the religious disbeliever holds that there isn’t, and the religious skeptic is unsure. One must be careful about the details here. Being skeptical about whether any religious proposition is true is not the same as being skeptical about each religious proposition; rather many of them—take, for example, the propositions of ancient Greek religion—are clearly false, and contemporary religious skeptics usually see this. Nor is it the same as being skeptical about the conjunction of all religious propositions, which brings them together, linking each to another using the logical connective “and.” It’s not hard to see that that proposition, properly understood, will not inspire doubt but rather disbelief, since, given religious disagreement, it entails innumerable contradictions and must be false. Instead, what we have is something that, if made precise and clarified in the skeptic’s mind, would amount to skepticism about the disjunction of religious propositions (also an enormous proposition including all religious propositions, but this time one that links each to another with the logical connective “or”). The religious skeptic typically sees a huge number of religious possibilities, some false, others unknown and so unassessable, and still others assessable but allowing for no verdict one way or the other. She is unsure as to whether any of these possibilities is realized: perhaps (at least) one is, perhaps not. Various states of mind seem to represent a sufficient condition for being religiously skeptical in this sense. Consider the proposition “Some religious proposition is true.” It might not seem itself to be a religious proposition (we would not inappropriately call it meta-religious). But being skeptical about that proposition should surely count as a sufficient condition of being a religious skeptic in the desired general sense, since that proposition is logically equivalent to the disjunctive proposition mentioned above. For the same reason, so should being skeptical about “There is a religious reality” (where a religious reality is one whose being realized would be sufficient to make some religious proposition true). Another sufficient condition for being skeptical about religion in the desired general sense can be detected in skepticism about a particular religious proposition which the skeptic regards as being such as must be true if any religious proposition is true. For many in the West today, who suffer from shrunken imaginations about what’s possible, that would be theism, that is, “God exists” (where by “God” is meant a broadly person-like ultimate divinity). And here we also bump into the term “agnosticism.” Purely at the

730

SKEPTICISM

level of attitude-type, there is evidently a close relationship between “skepticism,” as we are using the word, and “agnosticism.” But the latter term also has for us, these days, a strong religious connotation, associated with theism. The agnostic most often addressed in Western discussions of religion is skeptical about whether there is a God. And so we may think it is Sam, rather than Suneetra, who exemplifies religious skepticism, properly construed. And Sam might be a religious skeptic if he thinks theism (or propositions entailing theism) to represent the only “live” option, religiously speaking. Many religious skeptics of recent years appear to be agnostics about theism who make the latter assumption. Let’s call the general sort of religious skepticism just delineated categorical religious skepticism. Quite a number of individuals in the history of philosophy give the appearance of being categorical religious skeptics. In ancient Greece, we find Sextus Empiricus arguing that “it is inapprehensible whether there are gods” (PH III 11, trans. in Annas et al. 2000). Moving forward in time we find similar sentiments in thinkers such as Michel de Montaigne and Pierre Bayle. Ironically, some of these individuals seem more in tune with relevant cultural facts and conceptual possibilities than many of us in the twenty-first century, noticing that a divine reality might have lineaments very different from those of any god or indeed any reality with which we are acquainted—this theme may be found, for example, in Montaigne’s “Apologie de Raimond Sebond,” the longest chapter of his famous Les Essais (Montaigne 1981). Even Bertrand Russell, in the twentieth century, was able to distinguish between the traditional theistic idea of an all-good and all-powerful personal deity and another sort of “God” not so defined or restricted, declaring himself a disbeliever about the former but only an agnostic or skeptic about the latter: “That sort of God is, I think, not one that can actually be disproved, as I think the omnipotent and benevolent creator can” (1996: 258). One of my aims in this chapter is to push us back toward this sensitive and sensible perspective, which enables the acknowledging of a wide range of religious possibilities. Something that will help us get there is the recognition that a further way of being a religious skeptic, related to but distinct from categorical religious skepticism, remains to be identified. It is perhaps a less obvious sort of religious skepticism, one that does not get its religious character from being straightforwardly tied to religious propositions. I call it religious capacity skepticism. This sort of skepticism involves a skeptical attitude in response to the proposition that we have (sometimes that we have now, sometimes that we ever will have) the capacities required to discern religious truth, if such there should be. Though certainly to be found among a few contemporary religious skeptics, particularly in the work of Schellenberg (2007), such skepticism is also present in classical writers—for example, in the work of David Hume, where it can be seen as one aspect or application of his famous “mitigated skepticism,” which urges us to limit our thinking to the matters that “are best adapted to the narrow limits of human understanding” (1975: 162). Hume, like Russell after him, realizes that arguments against specific religious claims (perhaps including traditional theism) may be successful in justifying disbelief of certain such claims even if we cannot rule out that some religious claim—perhaps one of whose content we cannot even form

RELIGIOUS SKEPTICISM

731

a clear conception—is true and so must, in general terms, remain religious skeptics. As can be seen here, capacity skepticism is closely related to categorical skepticism. The former sort of skepticism can provide one with justification for the latter. After all, if there may be religious propositions that we are incapable of formulating or incapable of assessing (perhaps because the relevant evidence is at least for now beyond our grasp), how are we in a position to rule out that one of them is true? Or that some such proposition is true and incompatible with religious propositions known to us, which we are inclined to believe? Religious capacity skepticism will therefore lead, for those in its grip who understand the state at all, to categorical religious skepticism. So we have categorical religious skepticism, which is active and/or passive skepticism about the proposition that there is truth in religion (or some logically equivalent proposition), and religious capacity skepticism, which means being actively and/or passively skeptical about the proposition that human beings possess the capacities required to discern truth in religion, if such there should be. And although the former can exist without the latter, they may also go together, with the former grounded in the latter. A final point we should make note of here is that where religious skepticism occurs or is discussed in philosophy, we may expect it to be associated not only with such attitudes but with an epistemological claim: the claim that religious skepticism is intellectually preferable to both religious belief and a general religious disbelief of the sort I described earlier in this section. This claim need not be interpreted in such a way as to imply or suggest that religious believers and disbelievers have something wrong with them personally, some defect of intellectual character, perhaps, or the failure to fulfill intellectual duties of a sort that philosophers often have in mind when they speak of someone being unreasonable or unjustified in her belief. Rather, what we should think of here is a proposal as to what is objectively the case—what reason actually best supports in the way of a response to religious propositions. The religious skeptic, naturally enough, proposes that the best response is going to be religiously skeptical. I shall now outline what I regard as the strongest case for this proposal—a case I regard as being successful.4

2  A SCIENTIFIC CASE FOR RELIGIOUS SKEPTICISM The case begins with points that have long been emphasized by religious skeptics, having to do with human limitations. But its true force emerges most clearly when we add to these certain further points, allowed and indeed encouraged by modern science, concerning human immaturity. We have seen already that Hume emphasizes the first sort of point. So we can take him as an example of someone who would push that part of my case. Human beings, on this view, have cognitive powers that are severely circumscribed, and are prone to cognitive errors. Though this is not where they are most fruitfully brought into play, here too scientific developments can help to buttress the case. Cognitive psychology has in recent years, in part through the rich ingenuity of its experiments, revealed many surprising biases in the workings of human minds (Kahneman 2011).

732

SKEPTICISM

More generally, what we have learned about the vicissitudes through which humans have emerged in evolutionary history, the particular environments to which they have contingently become adapted, has led some philosophers—notably Chomsky (1988), whose view is developed by McGinn (1993)—to surmise that the human brain is quite good at some cognitive tasks, such as those of science itself, and not so good or perhaps even really bad at others, such as the general and fundamental problems addressed by philosophy. Now the intellectual questions referenced by McGinn are of the same sort—general and fundamental—that religious belief and disbelief purport to answer. And it would not be surprising if religion were an area of human life that particularly invited cognitive bias. So humans could, by virtue of the contingent and limited cognitive structures they have to work with, be prevented from learning whether there are any realities beyond the natural world studied by science or what such realities—should there be any—would be like. It might of course be hard to be sure, in any rationally approvable manner, whether we have been thus prevented. But our limitations may nonetheless be noticeable enough to support being in doubt about whether this is not the case. What we have here is an argument for capacity skepticism that undergirds categorical religious skepticism. Now to such reasoning the religious believer may be inclined to reply in terms of revelation, perhaps a revelation from God. Precisely because of our human inability to find God on our own, so it may be said, God reveals Himself to us through scriptures or human authorities or special experiences or miracles. Or perhaps God is revealed in the very tendencies of our minds, as exposed by science: the cognitive science of religion (CSR) has recently documented how “natural” it is for humans to think of the divine in personal, agential terms, and to believe in God or gods (Guthrie 1993; Barrett 2004). The religious disbeliever, for her part, may scoff at doubt, arguing that no singular ability is needed to tell that there obviously is no God and gods, or insisting that science is so much more impressive, intellectually, than religion as to justify consigning the latter to the dustbin of history. But even in their common use of male personal pronouns—such as “Himself”— for a transcendent spiritual reality, the influence on believers of human limitations may be observed! And the religious skeptic will wonder whether what CSR has revealed may not be precisely the sort of limitation she is talking about: being constitutionally such as to be specially attracted to what may be a very small subset of religious possibilities. It is in any case question-begging to speak of revelation in response to an argument purveying doubt as to the accessibility to us of a divine reality: how can we have any confidence that we would understand the information that needs to be delivered to us? The disbeliever’s argument is no better. The various god ideas may only scratch the surface when it comes to transcendent possibilities. Just the likeness to us of God and gods should already make any serious religious adventurer ready to move on in the quest for what, if anything, lies beyond ourselves. (Here too the CSR results might be illuminating, and in an unexpected way, helping to explain why critics of religion such as Daniel Dennett (2006: 9) seem just as onesidedly focused on personalist religious ideas as believers are.) By the same token, the disbeliever subtly begs the question too. For if our limitations are as serious as the religious skeptic

RELIGIOUS SKEPTICISM

733

suggests, mightn’t there very well be a religious reality even if human religion hasn’t found it? The very unimpressiveness of human religion (supposing the disbeliever to be right about that) should lead the disbeliever to wonder whether its ideas are, as she assumes, representative of all there is in the domain of religious possibilities. What both religious believers and religious disbelievers typically overlook is, as I have suggested, what Montaigne and Hume and Russell saw: that there might be innumerable possibilities when it comes to alternative ways of construing reality beyond nature. Human limitations may lead us to miss one or another or various sets of such possibilities, or large swaths of evidence pertaining thereto. The relevant information might be such as we are capable of recognizing, but nonetheless overlooked, neglected, or inaccessible (by which I mean that the particular directions of our thinking conspire to obscure it from us). It might also be such as we are incapable of recognizing: undiscovered or undiscoverable. The importance of these five ways of missing relevant evidence is itself something we tend to overlook (Schellenberg 2007). So much for the Limitation Mode of religious skepticism. Now it’s time to see how adding the Immaturity Mode allows us to take the case for religious skepticism to a whole new level. The Limitation Mode is about how we are constituted as finite beings and the constraints this imposes on investigation into the ultimate and infinite or at any rate the transcendent. It is not about our stage of development as a species, and indeed it might inspire doubt at any stage of development (even if some of its concerns could to some degree be mitigated at higher levels of finite development). The Immaturity Mode, on the other hand, is all about development—or rather a (relative) lack thereof. The Limitation Mode argues that human beings, given their finite constitution, may lack the capacities required for religious or irreligious insight. The Immaturity Mode argues similarly but with a twist: even if finite beings could have the relevant capacities, we may not yet have them (Schellenberg 2007; 2013). “Immature” can be understood in two senses, both quite familiar to us. The first is illustrated by Theresa, who is called an immature chess player because she has a tendency to become angry and overturn the chess board. Todd too might be called immature at chess, but that’s because he just started playing chess six months ago. The first sort of immaturity might be called normative, the second descriptive. Now what’s interesting is that the human species, in respect of thinking about religious matters, is presently immature in both senses. In matters of religious investigation we have surely done less well than might have been hoped with the time already allotted to us, but it is also true that—at least when scientific timescales are brought to bear—we must be regarded as having just got started. To see the former point, we need only consider the fact that credulous belief, dogmatic preaching and teaching, and fighting and killing in the name of God or gods are rife in religion as we’ve known it so far. This normative immaturity is a familiar fact, so I will not tarry in its precincts. The more interesting and also far less familiar fact is the descriptive fact about our place in time—one that we will count as representing a very early stage of development both for human beings and for intelligent life on our planet when we have reached a proper understanding of scientific time and internalized it.

734

SKEPTICISM

Clearly we have not yet internalized it. Indeed, this is part of our immaturity. In our culture we are constantly bombarded with scientific results, but our awareness and internalization of deep scientific time is still incomplete. It is true that we have begun to adapt to the fact of a deep past. Daily we are reminded that we come at the end of a long evolutionary process. But there is little to stimulate the thought that we come at the very beginning of one too, and that we humans may have inscribed in the book of intelligent life only its first few lines. To be thus stimulated, we need to meditate on such uncontroversial scientific results as the following. Our planet has supported life for about 3.8 billion years. But only about 5 million years ago did the human lineage diverge from the ape lineage. You’d have to travel almost all the way through that period, stopping just 100,000 or 50,000 years short of the present, to finally meet beings a lot like us, who are clearly capable of practicing some form of religion.5 What’s more, you’d have to make it almost all the way through that 50,000-year span of time to arrive at the forms of religion, including Christianity, that preoccupy us today. Now contrast all this, the human religious story of about the last 50,000 years, still touched by the violence that is in our genes and conspicuously heavy at our end, with the fact that, according to science, although the sun will eventually scorch our planet, Earth may remain habitable for as long as another billion years more (Schroder and Smith 2008). What this means is that the human story, so far, appears in about the first twenty-thousandth of the portion of deep time that may feature intelligence on Earth! Long story short: religious experience and inquiry might only be getting started. When we refer to the twenty-first century, we should think of this as indicating how very brief and flickering has been the existence of religion so far, rather than (as is more usual) taking it as grounding claims of ancient venerability. So what can the religious skeptic do with such facts and with the new sensibility sponsored by an ability to convert from human to scientific time? Well, there are consequences for both religious belief and religious disbelief. To religious believers the skeptic says this: perhaps religious experiences of the future will, because of much greater future intellectual and spiritual capacities, reveal a transcendent reality with defining characteristics quite different from those of any such reality we have yet conceived. To the disbeliever she may of course say the same, but here she may also put her point directly in opposition to what religious disbelievers commonly hold concerning their argumentative prowess: for all we know, what we have ruled out so far in the way of religious ideas, however impressively we may have done so, is only what beings at a very early stage of thought about such things have been able to come up with. So let the human species develop some of the more advanced capacities that may in the future come with a larger brain, or with the overcoming of violent tendencies, and think then about what the evidence shows. Believing now is premature! Perhaps it will be thought that this reasoning is rather too permissive. Doesn’t it have the unacceptable consequence that advocates of many views we should confidently dismiss—say, views favoring alchemy—can now propose the possibility of improved future results and rightly ask us to retreat from disbelief to skepticism? But at least two conditions necessary for justified dismissal are realized in relation

RELIGIOUS SKEPTICISM

735

to such views: the available evidence is against them, and there has been a serious attempt to ensure that no relevant evidence has been overlooked or neglected. And even if these same conditions are satisfied for this or that specific religious claim—say, the theistic claim that there is a person-like God—arguably neither is satisfied for the very general claim that the religious skeptic is reluctant to dismiss as false: the claim that in one way or another there is a religious reality beyond nature. That this is so one might indeed regard as following from the arguments I have made. Therefore, even if there are other and nonreligious views that should rightly take comfort from those arguments, they do not include views we ought to confidently dismiss. Another objection to my argument says that fallibilism accommodates it well enough. Fallibilism is a position in epistemology according to which those who believe a proposition true or who believe it false should (at any rate for many propositions) admit that they could be wrong, and could be shown to be wrong in the future, but may believe meanwhile in response to what the available evidence supports. This view, it seems to me, is overly sanguine, at least in the present context. Fallibilism makes a “one size fits all” sort of concession to human limitations, refusing expressions of certainty (“I’m not certain I’m right” is what “I could be wrong” comes to here). But it lacks the sensitive discriminating quality required to do justice to the specific sorts of limitations and especially to the immaturities we have found to be at work in the religious case, which call us to take more seriously what the unavailable evidence might show. Especially in light of deep time, and recognizing our very early stage of development, we have to say that on the profound and general and relatively unexamined issues concerning which, on the basis of available evidence, religious believers and disbelievers claim insight, the evidence we don’t see might be vast. And there is no justification for the belief that it points to religion or for the belief that it points away. Of course, the state of being in doubt that I have called passive religious skepticism may not immediately be induced by reflection on such considerations as I have marshalled here. I think the religious skeptic will quite sensibly prescribe extended contemplation of our immaturity, both normative and descriptive, for all of us. For those who see that doubt is appropriate but are prevented by the involuntariness of belief, this will of course amount to a prescription of active skepticism. But the religious skeptic has another move up her sleeve—the most powerful one, which I have left for last. The key here is to see how, although either the Limitation Mode or the Immaturity Mode might, on its own, be seen as justifying religious skepticism, these two can also be combined in a certain way to produce an even more impressive result. This is how to produce it. Strategically back away from the claim that the Limitation Mode on its own justifies religious skepticism. Instead, use the points made there to support just the following unexceptionable claim: that the very least we can conclude from our limitations is that an extended process of high-quality religious inquiry instantiated in our midst would be required to justify religious belief or disbelief for human beings. (The principle here is the same as the one preventing us from expecting correct answers on a test from a child who has little aptitude for

736

SKEPTICISM

a subject and moreover hasn’t studied.) The clinching move will perhaps be obvious. For surely the very least we can conclude from our immaturity is that we have not yet engaged in such inquiry. The human species is both profoundly limited and profoundly immature. Thus, even more obviously than before, religious belief and religious disbelief are shown to be intellectually unjustified for beings such as we are.

3 CONCLUSION What we should conclude, then, is that against the backdrop of a more subtle and adequate understanding of just what religious skepticism is, and with vital help from science, the reasoning implicitly or incipiently found in Montaigne, Hume, Russell, and like-minded others can be brought into the light of day and the religious skeptic’s proposal wins powerful intellectual support. In our culture, science is often taken as supporting metaphysical naturalism. But deep time is a wake-up call. The thinking about human immaturity it inspires and reinforces shows that what science actually supports is doubt about whether naturalism is true and also about whether any religious proposition is true. What science supports is religious skepticism.6

NOTES 1. What this means is that skepticism here is not simply or specifically knowledgeskepticism, which could exist even in someone who happily believes a proposition p and thinks she is justified in doing so (someone in this condition might still wonder whether she knows that p). Of course, someone skeptical in my sense will not claim to know either of the propositions involved in her skepticism if she recognizes that knowledge entails belief. 2. It should be noted that the “passivity” involved here reflects not the absence of such actions as are involved in active skepticism (in which case passive and active skepticism would be mutually exclusive) but rather the involuntariness of doubt just mentioned. 3. Of course, as my descriptions already suggest, one could be both actively and passively skeptical (even after he reaches doubt, Sam may engage in active skepticism to keep himself in that subjective condition). These two attitudes are not mutually exclusive. But it is also important to note that they don’t have to go together, and in particular to recognize that active skepticism may occur without passive. 4. The case I here present in outline form is a somewhat revised version of the case detailed in Schellenberg (2007). 5. For an authoritative survey of recent scientific thinking about these early periods, see Wade (2006). The behavioral changes I’ve alluded to are visible in the archaeological record of about 50,000 years ago, and recent genetic evidence suggests that they may have been spurred by the advent of fully articulate language—something that could be required for anything more than incipient religiousness. 6. Many thanks to the editors of this book for their helpful comments on a draft of this chapter.

RELIGIOUS SKEPTICISM

737

REFERENCES Annas, Julia and Jonathan Barnes (ed. and trans.). 2000. Sextus Empiricus: Outlines of Scepticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Barrett, Justin. 2004. Why Would Anyone Believe in God? Lanham, MD: AltaMira Press. Chomsky, Noam. 1988. Language and Problems of Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Dennett, Daniel. 2006. Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. New York: Viking. Guthrie, Stewart. 1993. Faces in the Clouds: A New Theory of Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hume, David. 1975. Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, in Enquiries concerning Human Understanding and concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by L. A. SelbyBigge, 3rd ed. revised by P. H. Nidditch. Originally published in 1748. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Girioux. McGinn, Colin. 1993. Problems in Philosophy: The Limits of Inquiry. Oxford: Blackwell. Montaigne, Michel de. 1981. Les Essais. Originally published in 1580. New York: Georg Olms, Hildesheim. Russell, Bertrand. 1996. “The Existence and Nature of God.” In J. G. Slater (ed.), The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, Vol. 10, 253–270. New York: Routledge. Schellenberg, J. L. 2007. The Wisdom to Doubt: A Justification of Religious Skepticism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Schellenberg, J. L. 2013. Evolutionary Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schroder, K.-P. and Robert Connon Smith. 2008. “Distant Future of the Sun and Earth Revisited.” Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society 386: 155–163. Wade, Nicholas. 2006. Before the Dawn: Recovering the Lost History of Our Ancestors. New York: Penguin Books.

738

NAME INDEX

The indexes have been compiled by D. Machuca. Aenesidemus  3, 5–6, 8, 25–6, 67–78, 114, 116, 120, 126, 166 Agrippa  6, 71, 141, 431 Alexander the Great  24, 145 al-Ghāzalī, Abū Ḥāmid Muḥammad  xiv–xv, 169, 196–207 Alston, William  395, 401, 597, 604, 676 Anaxagoras  38 Antiochus of Ascalon  6, 67, 70, 82–3, 85–6, 89, 90 n.10, 91 n.22, 122 n.2, 324, 326, 331–2 Antipater  117–18 Arcesilaus of Pitane  3–4, 6, 8, 36–46, 51, 61 n.18, 67, 69, 81, 83, 85–7, 90 nn.8–9, 114–17, 119, 268 n.5, 320, 324–6, 330, 332–3, 355, 357, 444 Aristippus  16, 21 n.8 Aristo of Chios  37 Aristocles of Messene  16, 19, 24–8, 32–3, 34 n.6, 69, 72–3 Aristotle  18, 25, 31, 45, 86, 130–1, 186– 90, 192–3, 196, 198–9, 207, 219 n.11, 226, 237, 242, 263–4, 267, 296, 512 Armstrong, David  530 n.21, 637 Augustine of Hippo  81, 84, 87, 89, 166, 170, 175–83, 186, 210–11, 218 n.5, 235, 268 n.4, 275, 296, 336, 361 Aulus Gellius  8, 121 Austin, J. L.  503 n.21, 704 Avicenna  198–9, 203, 207 Ayer, A. J.  673, 703, 705, 708, 716 Bayle, Pierre  235, 260, 273, 275–6, 279 nn.12, 15, 284, 286, 292 n.3, 295, 355–66, 443, 507–9, 511, 513, 730 Berkeley, George  318 n.6, 339 n.8, 369–78, 402, 454, 637 Bernard of Arezzo  167, 210–11, 227

Blackburn, Simon  716–17 Boethius  188–9, 263 Bonjour, Laurence  524, 540–1, 544, 571, 594, 606 n.21, 638, 671, 676 Brueckner, Anthony  xv, 528 n.3, 636, 663 n.18 Brunschwig, Jacques  29, 118 Buridan, John  166–8, 209–10, 213, 215–18, 226–7, 229 Burnyeat, Myles  22 n.18, 61 n.17, 132–7, 249, 266, 381–3 Carnap, Rudolf  454, 716 Carneades of Cyrene  3–4, 6, 8, 40, 43, 46, 51–60, 81–4, 109, 115–18, 178, 190, 254, 284, 325–6, 330, 332–3 Carroll, Lewis  543–4 Celsus  7 Charmadas  83, 88, 90 n.10, 91 n.19 Charron, Pierre  xiv–xv, 170–1, 247–57, 287–8, 290, 296, 320–1, 509–13 Chisholm, Roderick  395, 550–4, 570– 1, 593 Chrysippus  38–9, 43, 47 n.13, 48 n.14, 49 n.33, 117–18, 130–1, 358 Cicero, Marcus Tullius  xiii–xv, 3, 6, 8, 36–7, 39–41, 53, 55–6, 58–9, 81–7, 89, 93–9, 115, 119, 121, 166–7, 169–70, 175–7, 186, 188, 190, 196, 235, 240, 255, 296, 320–1, 325 Clarke, Thompson  470–2 Clifford, W. K.  95–7, 569–72 Clitomachus  6, 8, 43–4, 46, 57, 62 n.24, 63 n.32, 81, 87, 93–5, 99 n.6, 100 n.13, 116–17, 284 Cohen, Stewart  542, 607 n.30, 623, 625, 676

740

Colotes  17–18, 22 n.17, 37, 45, 47 n.4, 119 Cudworth, Ralph  380, 385–6 Davidson, Donald  648, 704 Democritus  22 n.21, 38, 114, 267, 290, 297 Dennett, Daniel  732 DeRose, Keith  xiv, 602, 623, 627, 631 n.8, 632 n.14 Descartes, René  xiv–xv, 18, 154, 165–7, 169, 175–6, 181, 222–3, 228, 243, 253, 266, 273–4, 276–8, 295, 299–300, 302, 306–18, 321–4, 326–9, 331–8, 342–4, 346–7, 349–52, 358, 386, 398–9, 402, 419, 425, 445, 461, 507, 509–13, 523–4, 614, 634, 637, 678, 701, 721 Diogenes of Babylon  118 Diogenes Laertius  6, 8, 16, 24, 37–8, 46, 68, 72, 103, 145, 234, 263, 323, 331, 443, 445 Dretske, Fred  601–3, 628, 644, 706

NAME INDEX

Harman, Gilbert  638, 646–7 Hawthorne, John  629–30 Hegel, G. W. F.  260, 407, 430–9, 550, 559 n.1 Henry of Ghent  166–7, 209, 218, 219 n.9 Heraclitus  37–8, 70–1, 119, 297, 444 Hervet, Gentian  169, 235–6, 508 Hippocrates  110, 297 Huet, Pierre-Daniel  320–8, 338, 507, 509 Hume, David  xiv, 107, 133, 169, 253, 279 nn.12, 16, 17, 360, 380–91, 397–400, 402, 411, 420, 438, 443–5, 507, 509, 513, 565–6, 668–70, 672–80, 689, 716, 730–1, 733, 736 Israel, Jonathan  364–5 Jayarāśi  3, 145, 152–3, 155 John Duns Scotus  166, 224–5, 268 n.15 John of Salisbury  167, 170, 186–93, 219 n.9

Empedocles  38, 297 Epictetus  8 Epicurus  119, 445, 448 Estienne, Henri  169, 235–7, 240, 243 n.4, 290 Eusebius of Caesarea  16, 24, 28, 69, 120

Kant, Immanuel  136, 149, 357, 402, 404, 407–8, 410, 413, 419–27, 436, 439, 455, 467–8, 484–5, 513, 690 Kitcher, Philip  690–2, 695–7 Klein, Peter  538, 558, 561 n.24, 573–4 Kripke, Saul  644, 696

Favorinus of Arles  3, 7–8, 120–2 Fine, Gail  22 n.18, 22 n.24, 129, 130, 133, 141, 142 n.8, 143 n.17 Fodor, Jerry  702 Fogelin, Robert  565–78, 645 Foucher, Simon  320–1, 323–4, 328–38, 507, 509 Frede, Michael  128–33, 135–6, 141, 380–3, 565 Fumerton, Richard  530 n.24, 542, 607 n.30

La Mothe Le Vayer, François de  283–91, 321, 510–12 Lewis, David  578 n.1, 621, 627, 632 n.14 Lorenzi, Giovanni  166

Galen  7–8, 102, 104–12, 121, 262, 267 Gassendi, Pierre  136, 295–303, 321, 328, 510, 512 Gettier, Edmund  159 n.29, 561 n.25, 612–15 Goldman, Alvin  547–8, 605 n.4, 606 n.19, 638 Gregory of Rimini, 166, 228

Mackie, J. L.  704, 717, 719, 724 nn.11–12 Malebranche, Nicolas  322–3, 328–9, 333, 335, 338, 355, 358, 507 McDowell, John  617 n.5, 640, 642, 647–8, 660, 663 n.14, 702, 707 Menodotus of Nicomedia  3, 7, 102–12 Mill, John Stuart  707–8 Montaigne, Michel de  xiv, 136, 170–1, 232–43, 247–51, 253–6, 284–91, 296, 255, 442–4, 509–10, 512, 550, 565, 730, 733, 736 Moore, G. E.  xiv, 454, 467–7, 482, 484–6, 489–95, 497–8, 635, 639, 647 Morison, Benjamin  138–9, 141

NAME INDEX741

Muhammad  203–4, 206 Nāgārjuna  3, 145, 147–51 Nagel, Thomas  438, 652 Niccolò da Reggio  166 Nicholas of Autrecourt  166–7, 209– 18, 227 Nozick, Robert  606 n.24, 628, 641, 644 Numenius  84 Ockham, William  166, 225, 227–8, 263 Paganini, Gianni  286, 291, 358, 512 Parmenides  37, 119, 130 Pascal, Blaise  235, 283, 287, 290, 321, 444, 447, 510–11 Peirce, C. S.  616, 618 n.18 Peter of Ailly  166, 225–30 Philo of Alexandria  9 n.8, 72, 115–16, 724 n.13 Philo of Larissa  6, 8, 67, 70, 81–9, 115, 118, 332 Photius  68–70, 72, 75, 166 Pico della Mirandola, Gianfrancesco  235, 296, 510 Pico della Mirandola, Giovanni  235, 331 Plato  6–7, 36–8, 51, 62 n.28, 68, 70, 82, 85–8, 102, 118–19, 121, 131, 196, 315, 330–2, 386, 436, 444, 679 Plutarch  7, 16–18, 39, 46, 85, 89, 114–20, 135 Polemo  82, 85–6, 88, 120 Popkin, Richard  169–70, 261, 278 n.2, 279 n.16, 286–8, 320–1, 333, 338, 350, 364, 506–14 Popper, Karl  669–70 Porphyry  186 Protagoras  38, 48 n.27, 444 Pryor, James  473–4, 478 n.12, 645 Putnam, Hilary  648, 708 Pyrrho of Elis  3–6, 8, 21 n.13, 24–33, 36–7, 67–70, 73–4, 76–8, 110–11, 145, 286, 355–6, 384, 396, 444–5, 448

Sanchez, Francisco  170–1, 260–7, 512 Seneca  8, 255, 296 Sextus Empiricus  xv, 3–8, 14–20, 32–3, 36, 40–6, 53–5, 58, 68–78, 81, 83, 86–7, 103–4, 107, 111–12, 114, 125–41, 158 n.18, 166, 169–71, 196, 218, 234–8, 242, 254, 261, 266, 302, 320, 323, 325, 355–6, 359, 380–3, 385–6, 388, 390, 432, 442–3, 482, 507–9, 550, 572, 669–70, 678–9, 723, 730 Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter  565, 567–9 Socrates  6, 16, 36–8, 51, 85–6, 88, 102, 114, 119, 121, 241, 254, 297, 324–5, 331–3, 409–12, 444, 448, 640 Sosa, Ernest  530 nn.21, 23, 549 n.4, 576, 628–9, 644–5, 678–9 Spinoza, Baruch  342–52, 355, 358, 436, 507 Śrīharşa  145, 153–5 Stroud, Barry  222, 438, 470–1, 663 n.17, 688 Timon of Phlius  3–5, 24–33, 37, 67, 73, 78 n.13 Unger, Peter  636 Van Cleve, James  405 n.5, 557, 559 n.1, 561 n.19, 681 n.5, 682 n.14 Vogel, Jonathan  528 n.3, 542, 638, 643, 676 Williams, Bernard  266, 274, 318 n.2 Williams, Michael  391 n.11, 438–9, 561 n.21, 570 Williamson, Timothy  530 n.19, 596, 606 n.27, 644, 663 n.18, 704 Wittgenstein, Ludwig  391 n.7, 469, 481–501, 565, 687–8, 701 Wright, Crispin  472–3, 503 n.25, 645 Xenocrates  82, 86, 118, 332

Quine, W. V. O.  454, 682 n.13 Russell, Bertrand  454–63, 474, 482, 495, 634–5, 637–8, 655, 669, 730, 733, 736

Zeller, Eduard  27, 34 n.8, 443 Zeno of Citium  16, 36–7, 39–41, 43–5, 52, 59, 83, 86, 118

SUBJECT INDEX

a priori: intuition  595–6; knowledge 176, 546, 685–97; reasoning 596; skepticism about the 309–11; warrant 217–18 Academic skepticism: Bayle on  357; Favorinus on 120–2; Foucher on 328–38; history of ancient 6–7; Huet on 324–8, 338; John of Salisbury on 186–8; neo253–4; and morality 714–15; Plutarch on 118–19, 135; and Pyrrhonism 6, 8, 44, 261; Sanchez and 261–2; in Western medieval thought 166–7 Academy: New  58, 63 n.33, 81, 85–7, 93, 114–18, 175–6, 182, 324–5, 392 n.23; Old 6, 82, 85–8, 324–5 ad hominem argument  40, 45, 171, 209 agnosticism  409, 492, 729–30 Agrippa’s trilemma  9 n.9, 299–302, 431–2, 439, 569–72, 636. See also modes, the Five aim (τέλος)  5, 8, 14, 62 n.22, 130, 252–3, 291, 670 aporia  39, 42, 46, 70, 115, 169, 196, 239, 243, 264, 431–2, 443 appearances (φαινόμενα): assent to  127–8, 133–4, 297; conflicting 70–1, 74, 249; as criterion of action 73, 127; to follow 53, 73, 112, 240, 405 apprehension (κατάληψις)  16–17, 22 n.24, 39, 41–2, 52–3, 57, 59, 70, 86 assent: action without  45–6, 119; to a ­cognitive impression 41; Hume on 380–91; Sextus Empiricus on 128–37; skeptical vs. dogmatic 127–8; suspension of 57, 94, 127, 290; varieties of 57–9; withholding of 38, 41–2, 52, 68, 296–7, 397, 714–15 assertion  5–6, 31–3, 38, 40, 42, 46, 75, 132, 153, 169, 241, 359, 362, 493, 704, 715; bare 138; confusion between knowledge and 578; dogmatic 111,

196, 578; moral 716–17; norm of 536, 630; warranted 578 atheism  196, 257, 279 n.12, 285, 287, 357, 359–60, 717–18 Buddhism  145–52, 154, 728 Cartesian circle  278 n.3, 528 n.1, 550, 557, 559 n.1 certainty  xiv, 52, 54, 70, 86, 121, 168–70, 177, 181, 188, 190, 200, 203, 209, 274, 277, 295, 297–8, 310, 315, 323–4, 333, 342–9, 351, 399, 409, 411–12, 414, 433–4, 460, 470, 481, 487–8, 490–4, 496–501, 510, 512–13, 535, 637, 735 Christianity: apologia for  235; Augustine’s conversion to 175; Cartesianism as d ­ angerous to 323; Nietzsche on 445, 447; obedience to 286; paradoxes in 364; ­principles of 361; skepticism as compatible with 276, 287, 511; truth of 180; validity of 286 circularity  138, 151, 434, 530 n.23, 539, 556–8, 569–70, 572, 604, 673, 692 closure: argument from  632 n.15, 638–9, 643–6; principle of 473, 478 n.4, 556, 600–3, 627–8, 656–7, 686 cogito  181–2, 266, 332, 343, 398, 416, 445, 512–3 common sense  xiv, 39, 118, 285–7, 373–4, 395, 402, 461, 463, 469, 471, 484–5 contextualism  431, 470–1, 527, 555, 557, 569–70, 575–6, 578, 583, 620–31 contrastivism  567 disagreement: argument from  586, 589; deep 501, 527; intractable 501; mode from 138, 577; moral 721–2, 724 n.12;

SUBJECT INDEX743

peer 722; religious 273, 729; skeptical method of 242 doubt: Cartesian  489, 494, 509, 511–13; about the evidence of the senses 84, 201; general 187, 210–11; hyperbolic 266, 315–8, 513; levels of 568; method of 324–5, 513; methodological 181, 411, 445; ordinary 488; philosophy of 119, 238–41; reasonable 487, 500 Empiricism, medical  3, 7–8, 78 n.13, 102–12, 126, 171, 266–7 emptiness (śūnyatā)  148–9, 151 Epicureanism  117, 119–20, 131, 328 epilogismos  105, 107–11 epistemic peer  501, 585, 722 epistemic superior  585, 587 equipollence (ἰσοσθένεια)  38–9, 42, 46, 74–5, 77, 133–5, 139–41, 169, 196, 236, 249, 251, 283, 285–7, 291, 432 error theory: epistemic contextualism’s  626–7, 629; moral 714–15, 717–22 evidence: agreed-upon  72, 501; criterion of 328, 333, 335–6; inductive 602; objective 239; perceptual 212, 474, 642–3, 647; testimonial 585–6 evidentness (evidentia)  168, 172 n.12, 211–14, 216–17, 226, 298 evidentialism  592–3, 595–6, 598, 603–4 evil demon  165, 222, 266, 274, 278 externalism  215, 592–604, 648, 659–60, 663 n.16, 664 nn.21, 23, 702 experience: perceptual  158 n.21, 318, 419, 491, 524–6, 592–3, 595–6, 599, 601, 637, 644, 648, 652–5, 657, 686; subjective 17–8, 21 n.15, 337, 419–20, 422–3, 536; waking 308–9, 464 n.5, 526 faith: Christian  175, 283, 338, 510–11; as a condition for understanding 178; as a means to acquire knowledge 170, 447; and reason 179–80, 323–4, 357; Reformers’ rule of 509–10; skepticism as preparation for 287 fideism  119, 178–9, 276, 283, 286–8, 507, 510–11 foundationalism  150, 167, 209–12, 214–15, 227, 399, 460, 462, 524–5,

536–41, 547–8, 555–6, 570–1, 573–5, 592–3, 595–6, 598 God: as deceiver  165–6, 168, 209, 215–6, 222–30, 316–17, 343, 419; knowledge of 177–8, 199, 207, 345, 349, 351–2, 408; omnipotence of 210–11, 229, 315, 336–7, 510; veracity of 169, 344 hallucination  150, 177, 419, 524, 648, 694, 702; argument from 653–8. See also illusion happiness  26, 29–30; and pleasure 16; and wisdom 51, 53; as moral goodness 719; as the goal of life 43–4, 54; as tranquility 33, 78, 88, 244 n.14 Hinduism  146, 156 n.3, 728 hinge: commitments  501, 504 n.25; ­propositions 496, 504 n.25 ignorance: learned  196, 203–4, 207, 257; Socrates’s profession of 38, 51, 85, 241, 254, 324, 409–11 illusion  120, 154, 167–9, 214–15, 226, 318 n.2, 456; argument from 373, 526, 528 n.4. See also hallucination impression (φαντασία): cognitive  40–1, 52, 83–4, 86, 89, 97, 154; persuasive 51–60; probable 54, 61 nn.17, 19, 84 inaction/inactivity (ἀπραξία)  44, 46, 52–3, 62 n.27, 73, 94, 128 inapprehensibility (ἀκαταληψία)  7, 15, 19–20, 37, 40–1, 46, 47 n.10, 52–3, 75, 83, 103 (infinite) regress  150, 152, 155, 236, 239, 423, 554–5, 558, 599; argument from 165, 214–15, 401, 404, 535–48; Pyrrhonian mode from 138–9, 299, 301, 385, 508, 523, 569, 572–6 internalism  592–600, 660–1, 681 n.5 justification: a posteriori  45; a priori 689–91; circular 675; ­deontological 597; ­doxastic 589; epistemic 170, 216, 431, 433, 569, 597, 599, 604 n.1, 672, 709, 720; fallible 669; inferential vs. ­non-inferential 537–48, 605 n.4; ­internalist 596, 645, 674–7; moral 723; prima facie 525–6, 530 n.17;

744

­propositional 589; rational 44, 46, 250, 267, 365; ­reliabilist 674–7, 679–80 knowledge: certain  86, 166–7, 169, 176, 179, 193, 198–9, 203–5, 207, 227, 261–2, 274, 320–1, 334, 351, 494, 510, 512; empirical 105, 639–41, 691–3, 696–7; intellectual 215; perceptual 215, 369, 372, 376, 404, 494, 526, 660–1, 702, 705–6, 709–10; the problem of easy 542, 556–8, 607 n.30; sources of 147, 150, 152, 201, 705, 709–10; testimonial 153 language-game  277, 483, 486–91, 493, 500 libertinage  283, 285–9, 291 materialism  152, 176, 242 memory: and knowledge of the past  423; medical Empiricists on 104, 107, 109–11; reliability of 425, 604 metaphysics: Cartesian  321, 329, 333, 338, 512–13; of modality 223; nihilist 68; as nonsensical 482 Methodism, medical  7, 104 modes: against causal explanations  72, 137; the Five 5–6, 9 nn.9, 11, 137–9, 141, 327, 566–7, 571 (see also Agrippa’s trilemma); the Ten 5–6, 71–4, 77, 137–9, 237, 242, 276, 287, 296–9, 301, 303, 721; the Two 9 n.11, 137, 158 moral anti-realism  714, 717 moral noncognitivism  714–17, 724 n.8 natural light  326–8, 361–3, 365 nature of things: assertions about the  5; cannot be known 15, 26, 295, 297; nonevident 77; knowledge of 19, 83, 115, 202; suspension of judgment about 43, 158 n.18 nihilism: extreme  442, 449; Nāgārjuna’s rejection of  157 n.8; skeptical 149 no more (οὐ μᾶλλον)  25, 31–3, 74, 240, 382 nominalism  264, 266 non-assertion (ἀφασία)  35 n.13, 32, 44, 46, 120

SUBJECT INDEX

opinions: conflict of  5, 485; dogmatic 132, 290; mere 59, 68, 94; neither tell the truth nor lie 25; to hold no 25, 40, 53, 59, 381; weak 171, 252, 298 paradox: Agrippa’s problem as a  569–71, 577–8; in Christianity 358, 364; the liar 241; Meno’s 550; practice of 283, 285–7 pathοs (πάθος)  7, 10 n.21, 15–20, 21 n.12, 22 nn.18–19, 249 perception  17–18, 109–10, 150–2, 202, 207, 210–17, 237–8, 265, 306–10, 313–15, 371–4, 398–400, 403–4, 455–7, 462, 593, 604, 634–5, 652–5, 657–8, 693–4, 704–6, 709–10; clear and distinct 299–300, 327–8; of the intellect 310; internal 210, 420; ­relativity of 215, 400 (see also sensation) perplexity  169, 196, 203, 241, 291 pramāṇa (knowledge source)  146–7, 149–51 presentation. See impression probability 51, 54, 57, 61 n.17, 82, 219 n.11, 254, 295, 299, 547, 617 n.3 Pyrrhonism: and Academic skepticism 8; of Aenesidemus 67–78; and Arcesilaus’s stance 37, 40, 42–4, 46; Bayle on 356–8, 362, 364–5; and Carneades’s stance 53, 58; and Charron 171, 249–55; and ­classical Indian thought 3, 145, 158 n.18; and ­Cyrenaicism 14–16; Gassendi on 296, 299; and Favorinus’s interest in 120–2; Huet on 324–6, 328; history of ancient 4–6; influence on contemporary philosophy 4; and Hegel 431–2; and Hume 380–91; and La Mothe Le Vayer 283, 286, 290–1; and medical ­Empiricism 7–8, 103–4, 111–12; of ­Montaigne 170–1, 232, 234–42; neo565–78; and moral disagreement 721, 723; and morality 714–5; and Nietzsche 442–7, 449; Plutarch’s attitude towards 120; Popkin on the history of 507–9, 511–13; of Pyrrho and Timon 24–33; Renaissance rediscovery of 169–70; of Sanchez 171, 260–3, 265, 267; of Sextus Empiricus 125–41; varieties of 5; in Western medieval thought 165–6

SUBJECT INDEX745

rationalism: Bayle on  357–8, 360–5; in ­Cartesianism 285; critical 513; excessive 178, 180; medical 7, 102–6, 108–11 realism: direct  405 n.5, 463; metaphysical 151; minimal 723 n.1; moral 714, 721; naïve 371, 652–5; refutation of 155; robust 723 n.1 reason: and Academic skepticism  62 n.24; Augustine on 178–80; Bayle 356– 8, 361–5; Charron on 249–50, 252, 255–7; contrast between experience and 102; in the debate between medical Empiricists and rationalists 106–8; epistemic value of 170–1; Foucher on 332–3, 335, 337–8; Hamman on 408–9, 411–15; Huet on 323–5, 328; Hume on 387–8, 392 n.19; La Mothe Le Vayer 283–5, 289–91; medical Empiricists’ stance on 103, 105, 109–11; medical ­rationalists’ stance on 102; Reid on 397–9, 403–4; unreliability of 68 reasons: epistemic  552–9; practical/pragmatic 389, 552 reductio ad absurdum  41, 167, 210–11, 358, 566–7 Reformation, the  171, 255, 273, 275, 508 refutation: self-  73, 298, 304 n.11; of skepticism 168, 175, 177, 266, 277, 335, 510–13; Socrates’s practice of 38; of ­Stoicism 115, 117 relativism  243 n.6, 499–500; cultural 498; phenomenal 75 reliabilism  476, 542, 555–6, 560 n.9, 583, 592–6, 598, 601–4, 674, 676 religion: cognitive science of 732; ­Pyrrhonism as the best preparation for 235; ­relation between morality and 275, 359; ­relation ­between reason and 358, 413; ­relation between wisdom and religion 256; ­skepticism as not opposed to 323; true 239, 256, 275, 362 sage: Academic  42–3, 55–6, 59–60; ­Charron’s skeptical 249–52, 254, 256; Stoic 41–2, 45, 52–3, 55, 57, 130–1 scholasticism  198–207, 239, 276 science: constructive  390; demonstrative 187–8, 190–2; Hegel’s philosophical of

431–9; modern 186, 278, 731–2; natural 167–8, 189–90, 216, 230 scientia  191, 213, 263–4, 266, 298–9 self  175, 182, 238, 241–3, 249, 254, 415, 420 self-evident  211, 214, 339 n.4, 401–2, 425, 460, 489, 491 self-refutation  26, 73, 298, 412, 555 sensation  5, 25, 27–31, 115, 119–20, 127, 214, 249, 311–13, 334–5, 375–6, 386, 454, 456, 462 sense-data  277, 454–8, 460–2, 474, 491, 494, 634–5, 638, 653 sense-perception/sensory perception. See perception sign: commemorative  107; the idea of God as a 352; indicative 302–3; inferential 152 skepticism: about the external world  15, 19–20, 165, 168, 177, 211, 222, 226, 266–7, 334, 419–20, 428 n.1, 438, 467, 489, 491, 494, 597–8, 634–49; Academic (see Academic skepticism); Cartesian 266–7, 300, 473, 485, 487, 497, 565; experimental 446–9; mitigated 53, 63 n.32, 94, 98–9, 280 n.26, 295, 442, 510, 730; constructive 295; Pyrrhonian (see Pyrrhonism); radical 6, 53, 94, 167, 211, 390, 448, 454, 462, 496, 500, 583–4, 659–62 solipsism  20, 181–2, 211, 227, 411 sorites  49 n.33, 52 Stoicism  16, 71, 115, 117–18, 234, 242, 250 subjectivity  241–3, 248, 250, 433–4 suspension of judgment (ἐποχή): as the ­centerpiece of Pyrrhonism 15; and ­equipollence 38–9; on moral claims 715, 720, 722–3; and ‘no more’ 32; about the real nature of things 43; on religious claims 511; as the skeptic’s aim 8, 42; and tranquility 68, 76, 135, 240, 266, 290, 296; universal 6, 41–4, 94, 103, 114, 167, 523; violation of 5; as a voluntary decision 171, 249 Taoism  728 testimony  139–40, 147, 151–4, 179, 401, 457, 460–1, 536, 542–4, 556, 588, 640, 646, 677, 694, 709–10

746

theology  6, 126, 202, 223, 226, 255; Christian 361; fideistic 116; natural 511; negative 256–7; post-Scotist 215; Stoic 51, 62 n.29 tranquility (ἀταραξία)  5, 25, 33, 53, 68–9, 73, 78, 132–5, 171, 235–6, 240, 253, 266–7, 290–1, 296, 326, 565, 670 truth: apparent  58; criterion of 16, 40, 44–5, 51, 54, 83–5, 181, 296, 300, 302, 321, 324, 326–9, 332, 335–6, 431, 508, 550–6, 678–9; innate 512; inquiry into 77, 97, 299; logical 482, 610, 687; ­mathematical 337, 343–6, 481, 610, 687, 704; ­metaphysical 315, 361, 438; moral 350, 359, 716; necessary 336, 363, 427, 490, 643, 696; objective 498; religious 198, 201, 350, 730; revealed

SUBJECT INDEX

512; search for 39, 48 n.18, 51, 88, 97, 171, 252, 263, 290, 325, 329–30, 387 uncertainty  252, 283–4, 387, 447, 616 underdetermination: argument from 636–8; of evidence 528 n.3; responses to the ­argument from 642–3 undisturbedness. See tranquility Vedānta  145–6, 163–5 via media  295, 302–3, 510 wisdom  51, 53, 56, 59, 70, 96–7, 117, 242, 255–7, 325–6, 410–12; Academic sage’s 60; common 251; divine 255, 288; human 248–9, 255; and opinion 53, 62 n.31, 63 n.32; skeptical 248, 288, 320–1, 509, 513; Stoic view of 52

747

748

749

750

751

752