244 72 102MB
English Pages [657] Year 1993
PLATO'S CRETAN CITY A HISTORICAL INTERPRETATION
OF THE LAWS
:
g^ot^8 ^
PLATO'S CRETAN CITY ^A Historical Interpretation of the
BY
GLENN
laws
R.
MORROW
PRINCETON, NEW JERSEY
PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS
Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street,
New
Princeton, In the United
Copyright the
Jersey 08540
Kingdom: Princeton University Chichester, West Sussex
©
Press,
i960 by Princeton University Press;
new foreword
for the 1993 edition
is
copyright
©
1993
by Princeton University Press All Rights Reserved
Library of Congress Cataloging -in -Publication Data
Morrow, Glenn Plato's
Cretan
city: a historical
Raymond), 1 895-1973. interpretation of the Laws / by Glenn R. (Glenn
p.
R.
Morrow.
cm.
Originally published: i960.
With new
introd.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 1.
0-691-02484-7 (pbk.: acid-free paper)
Plato.
Laws.
The.
2. State,
JC71.P6M6
—dc20
Title.
1993
321 '.07
First Princeton
I.
93-2271
Paperback printing, 1993
Princeton University Press books are printed on acid-free paper
and meet the guidelines
for
permanence and durability of the
Committee on Production Guidelines
for
Book Longevity of the
Council on Library Resources
3579
10
864
PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA
TO GEORGE HOLLAND SABINE 'qyeyiocrvva
CONTENTS Analytical Table of Contents
Foreword
(1993), by Charles
ix
H. Kahn
xvii
xxix
Preface Bibliographical Abbreviations
xxxiii
Introduction
3
PART ONE: THREE HISTORICAL STATES I.
Crete
17
Excursus A. II.
The Minos
35
Sparta
40
Excursus B. Plato's Version of Peloponnesian History 63 III.
Athens
74
PART TWO: PLATO'S CITY IV.
Property and the Family
The Allotment
V.
of the
95
Land
103
Citizenship and the Family
112
Property Classes
131
Industry and Trade
138
Slaves
148
Government
^
153
The Assembly and the Council The Magistrates The Guardians of the Laws The Scrutiny and the Audit
215
"Aristocracy with the Approval of the People"
229
157 178 195
Excursus C. Atpecrt?, /cX^paxri?, and TrpoKpucns Excursus D.
The Double Version vii
in
Book
vi
233 238
CONTENTS VI.
VII.
The Administration
242
The Courts
251
Procedure
274
Education
297
Music and the Dance The Training of the Young
318
Festivals
352
Meals
302
389
Religion
Apollo and the Sacred
Law
399 402
Religious Officials
411
The Gods and their Worship The Law Against Impiety
434
The
Excursus E. IX.
241
Justice Before the Magistrates
Common VIII.
of Justice
Election of the Exegetes
470 496
The Nocturnal Council
500
Excursus F. Philippus of Opus
515
PART THREE: PLATO'S PRINCIPLES X.
The Mixed
Constitution
Law
XI.
The Rule
of
XII.
The Rule
of Philosophy
521
544 573
Retrospect
591
General Index
597
Index of Passages
609
Index of Modern Authors Cited
620
vm
ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction
3
The theme
of the
Laws\
its
appropriateness to the fourth century
and to the interests of the Academy, 3. Plato's knowledge of Plato's influence, through Greek law and political institutions, 5 the Academy, upon fourth-century states and statesmen, 7. The legislator a craftsman who knows both the ideal and the materials in which it is to be realized, 10. Knowledge of Plato's historical materials necessary for an accurate understanding of his political ;
theory,
12.
part one: three historical states Chapter
I.
Crete
17
Apparent unimportance but great prestige of Crete in the fourth Plato's part in the revival of interest in Crete, 20.
century, 17.
Evidences of his familiarity with Cretan
tween Cretan and Spartan laws,
common Dorian Excursus A.
Chapter
life,
25.
Similarity be-
Importance for Plato of their
32.
basis, 34.
The Minos
35
Sparta
II.
40
Plato's interest in Sparta often attributed to his aristocratic con-
nections, 41
but certainly also due to the admiration for Spartan
which he shared with
evvofxia 43.
;
practically all his contemporaries,
Plato's admiration, like that of his contemporaries, not un-
critical,
Sparta, 46.
The grounds
of the
as Plato sees
admiration of Sparta as
The
causes of Spartan euno-
them; (a) the Spartan
aycoyrj, 52; (b) the self-
limiting character of the executive in the 54;
(c) the
Dorian
the Dorians to
basis of
Greek
idealization of
common
reflected in the ancient writers, 48.
mia
Laws an
neither the Republic nor the
45;
Spartan
life,
government of Sparta,
58.
The
contribution of
culture, 62.
Excursus B. Plato's Version of Peloponnesian History
Chapter
III.
Athens
74
The Athenian Stranger the teacher of his two companions, 75. The fame of the ancient Athenian laws, 76. The "ancestral constitution" of
63
Solon and Cleisthenes, ix
78. Plato's
admiration of Solon
ANALYTICAL CONTENTS and the ancient Solon in his
Athens 86;
as
own still
His admiration Greeks,
His judgment of fourth-century the moderation that characterized her past,
legislation, 83.
having
but as
Evidences of his imitation of
constitution, 80.
lost
retaining traces of her ancient constitution, 87. for his native city as a leader #
and teacher of the
89.
part two: plato's city Chapter IV. Property and the Family
95
Physical features and advantages of the proposed sources
from which the
of regulating property
The Allotment
colonists will
come,
101.
of the Land. Private ownership a departure
the Republic, 103.
Conditions of land tenure in Plato's
of land
in.
restricted to citizens,
membership
from
city, 105;
Ownership
historical precedents for Plato's system, 107.
Citizenship
The importance
100.
from the beginning,
The
site, 95.
and the Family. One
qualification
in a land-owning family, 113;
for citizenship
hence descent from
118.
Importance of the family in Platonic law, Other subdivisions of the citizen body: tribes, 121; demes,
124;
phratries, 126.
citizen parents, 115.
of Plato's
The meaning
Another qualification
state, 128.
The
of citizenship, 128.
size
for citizenship educa-
tion by the state, 130.
Property Classes. Four in number, 131. Their purpose to bring
about proportionate equality, 132.
termining access to in Plato's law, 134.
office,
133.
Their unimportance in de-
Their relevance
Their relation
to the four
at other points
Solonian
classes,
135-
Industry and Trade. Trade and handicraft prohibited to citizens, 138.
Greek
attitude
toward trade and handicraft,
140.
Plato's
and concern for the prior obligations of citizenship, 143. The moral hazards of trade and Plato's attempt to diminish them for his metics, 144. The protection of the artisan, 145. The metic status in Greek and in Plato's law, 146; Plato's modifications of current law and their attitude a mixture of aristocratic disdain
probable
effects, 147.
Slaves. Public
and privately owned
slaves, 148.
The
status of the
agricultural slave, 149. The historical parallel to Plato's the Attica of an earlier time, 151.
economy
ANALYTICAL CONTENTS Chapter V. Government
The
153
three principles: (a) the rule of philosophy, 153; (b) the rule
of law, 154;
The Assembly and
constitution, 155.
Its
its
,
assembly an assembly of
functions as described chiefly electoral,
Electoral procedures, 160; the unimportance of the
Other functions of the assembly, the
The
the Council.
citizen soldiers, 157. 159.
mixed
the
(c)
The
164.
council:
its
lot, 161.
prototype
Athenian "popular council" of Solon and Cleisthenes, 165; constitution and mode of election, 166. Plato's reasons for
proposing
organized by property
a council
The
classes, 170.
divi-
Rela-
sion of the council into prytanies, 172; their functions, 173.
The
tion of the council to the assembly left undetermined, 174.
range of competence assigned to the assembly and council, 176.
The
The
Magistrates. Generals and other military officers, 178.
and dyopavofiot, 181; their functions analogous to those of such officers at Athens and elsewhere, 182. The aypo-
ao-Tvvofxoi
their organization, their duties, their
vo/jlol:
their relation to the Spartan KpvTrreia 189.
to the
The
The Guardians officers,
The manner
cial functions, 203.
206.
i^rjfiia,
and sources
state
to supervise the
(a)
(c) to act as administrators in special areas, 202;
version,
The
election procedure
in fourth-century Greece, 209.
(d) their judi-
of their election given in
Qualifications for this
office,
Plato's
215;
and
law, 219.
208.
institution
Nojito^vXaKe?
an imitation
number,
The hoKLfjLao-ia in Athenian law, The evSvva in common Greek 217.
Plato's introduction of a special
duties,
it,
220.
The
and honors, 223;
officers,
body of peculiar
election of the evOvvou, 222;
for abuse of their powers, 226.
other high
211.
the Audit.
in Plato's law,
nity to conduct
two
described in the earlier
and adaptation of the Athenian Council on the Areopagus,
The Scrutiny and
186;
(b) to act as a legislative commission, 200;
196;
versions, 204.
life,
omission of archons, 194.
Laws. Their duties:
of the
of
Athenian
Probable needs of the treasury in Plato's
of public revenue, 191.
other
and
mode
Relation of the euthynoi to the
227.
ness of Plato's constitutional law, 229;
nian experience, 231.
their
their liability to prosecution
"Aristocracy with the Approval of the People." tions are clear, 230.
dig-
The
incomplete-
yet Plato's basic inten-
Plato's innovations based largely
upon Athe-
Possible explanation for the incompleteness
of his constitutional law, 232. xi
ANALYTICAL CONTENTS Excursus C. Atpecris,
and
tfX^pcocris,
TrpoKpicriq
233
*
Excursus D.
The Double Version
in
Book
vi
238
Chapter VI. The Administration of Justice and court proceedings,
Distinction between magisterial
Justice Before the Magistrates. Judicial
Collegial action
cers, 242.
tures in other respects
241 241.
powers of the minor
offi-
assumed with, however, some depar-
from Attic law,
244.
Plato's
remedy
magisterial injustice a civil suit against the magistrate, 246; a novel provision, but
The
247.
for this
with analogies and prototypes in Greek law,
powers of the euthynoi, 248; and of the All magistrates responsible without exception,
judicial
guardians, 249. 250.
The
Courts.
justice, 251.
The supremacy
of the popular courts in Athenian
Plato's criticism, 253; yet acceptance of
pressing one of the prerogatives of citizenship, 254. a
mixture of popular and
instance: neighbors
and
The
The
arbitrators, 256.
His system
The courts of first The courts of second
Athenian popular
courts,
court of third instance: the court of select judges, 261.
court of the demos, 264;
clesia,
as ex-
select courts, 255.
instance: tribal courts, analogous to the 257.
them
265.
The
analogy with the Athenian ec-
court for capital offenses, 267;
relation to the court of the courts, 270.
its
demos, 269.
its
uncertain
Military and family
General estimate of Plato's system of courts, 271.
Procedure. Private prosecutors the chief agency for bringing offenders to account, 274;
but the distinction between private and
The
public suits clearly marked, 276.
filing of suits, 279.
The
preliminary examination by the magistrate, 279. Trial procedure: (a)
the presiding magistrate to have greater control over pro-
ceedings, 280; (b) an inquisitorial examination of charges
dence to be
made
at
some
stage of every case, 281;
oath, the challenge to the oath,
prohibited, 283. 286.
289.
Open
A
and the challenge
Witnesses, 285;
voting, 288.
and
evi-
(c) the party
to the torture
the suit for false testimony,
Discretion of judges in fixing penalties,
judge's decision to be rendered under oath, 290.
sponsibility of the state in the execution of
judgments, 291.
vices for discouraging excessive litigation, 292.
of Plato's procedural law, 295. xii
The
re-
De-
General estimate
ANALYTICAL CONTENTS Chapter VII. Education
The
education of
its
297 citizens the responsibility of the city, 297.
and modification of the Spartan
Plato's adoption
(£70)777, 298.
Music and the Dance. Importance of choral singing and dancing in Greek life, 302; especially at Sparta, 303. Value of music and the dance as means of molding the character, 304. Their mimetic function to be consciously directed towards the presentation
The procedure
of the good, 307.
chorus of elders, and
its
educated
musical
taste in the
this chorus, 315.
Its
of "enchantment," 309.
The
function as guardian of philosophically
Dionysus the patron of
arts, 313.
difference
from
its
alleged Spartan proto-
type, 317.
The Training
Young. Education in music, gymnastics, and letters common at Athens and elsewhere, 318. In Plato's state such education to be compulsory for all, and directed by the state, 322.
The
of the
educator, 324;
office of
Training of the infant, 327. 329.
336;
other educational
Equal education
officers, 326.
for boys
and
girls,
The program (c)
of studies: (a) gymnastics, 332; (b) dancing, (d) playing the lyre, 340; (e) mathe337;
letters,
Com-
astronomy, 347. Higher studies, 348. parison with the content of the Spartan agoge, 350. matics, 343;
Festivals.
(f)
Importance of
festivals
as
educational influences, in
Greek cities generally and in Plato's state, 352. Canons of songs and dances necessary, 354. Tradition and change in music, 355.
A
variety of dances to be permitted, 358:
(a) the pyrrhic
especially favored, 359; (b) certain kinds of Bacchic dances
dance
viewed
with disfavor but not actually excluded, 362; (c) €/u,/*e\€«u, (d) comic dances, 370. Comedy to be witnessed by citizens 365; but performed only by foreigners, 373. Tragedy to be permitted, if its teaching does not contradict the law, 374. The organization of musical contests, 377. in running, 381;
for
The
women
officers of athletics, 380.
as well as
men,
382.
Contests
Omission of
and substitution of hoplomachy and peltastic contests, 386. Races on horseback, 386. Comparison of Plato's program with the Olympic program and wrestling, boxing,
and the pancratium, 383;
with Spartan customs, 388.
Common life,
389;
Meals. relics
moral and
A
of
characteristic feature of Spartan
them found elsewhere
and Cretan
in Greece, 391.
Their
importance as seen by ancient writers, 392. Their existence taken for granted in Plato's city, but no explicit social
xiii
ANALYTICAL CONTENTS bringing them into
difficulty of
legislation in Plato's text, 393;
accord with the other institutions of Plato's
city, 396.
Chapter VIII. Religion
399
and reinterpretation of the religion
Plato's adoption
of his coun-
trymen, 400.
Apollo and the Sacred Law.
The
necessity of preserving ancient
Importance of the oracles as interpreters of the
traditions, 402.
The supremacy of Delphi, 405. Distinction from secular law, 407. The recognition of the author-
will of the gods, 403.
of religious ity
of Delphi not an abdication of the legislator's function, but
an aid in accomplishing
it,
409.
Religious Officials. Temples and their treasurers, 411.
and
priestesses,
413;
and
of secular officers, 416.
caretakers,
The
exegetes in Plato's
city,
toward their professed abuses of
it,
Expert interpretation of religious law
445;
Pythioi at Sparta, 423. Soothsayers, 427;
423.
art,
429;
and
his
Duties of the Plato's attitude
measures for preventing
Worship. The Olympians, 434: Athena, 438; Apollo, 438; Hera, 439;
Dionysus, 441.
Did
Exegetes in fourth-cen-
430.
The Gods and Zeus, 436;
Religious functions
415.
to be provided by official exegetes, 418.
tury Athens, 420.
Priests
their
Plato's
censorship
of
Hestia, 435; others, 440;
current mythology,
443.
The astral gods, The Chthonioi, 449.
Plato regard the Olympians as gods? 444. their relation to the
Olympians, 447.
Plato's admission but segregation of chthonic rites, 450.
Pluto
admitted to "the twelve," 451. Demeter and Persephone, 452. The afterlife not to be dreaded, 454; except by the wicked, 455. The worship of daemons, 457; and heroes, 459. The cult of ancestors, 461.
the living, 465.
Funeral
462.
rites,
Influence of the dead
Reverence to be paid
ligion to penetrate all areas of
life,
state the religion of his people, into
to living parents, 467.
468.
The
471;
Re-
religion of Plato's
which he has infused a deeper
conception of the meaning of worship, 469; of the divine nature, 470.
The Law Against
upon
and a
loftier idea
Impiety. \A.cre/3€ia a serious offense
at
Athens,
covering a wide variety of offenses in words and actions,
472. Offenses against religious
The law
law punishable
against impious opinions designed to
in Attic law, 475.
The
in Plato's state, 474. fill
prelude to this law, 477. xiv
a noticeable
The
gap
fallacious
ANALYTICAL CONTENTS doctrine of the soul in nature,
"modern wise men," and of rational 481;
478.
The primacy
of the
soul in the heavens, 482.
Refutation of the denial of the gods' providence, 484; and of the belief that the gods can be bribed, 486. The ignoratio elenchi
argument, 487.
in Plato's
Statement of the law against impiety,
488; impiety a delict of opinion, 488.
with those of Attic law, 490. Plato's
The
compared
Plato's penalties
prohibition of private
law follows the law of Athens, 494;
and
is
rites, 492.
an attempt to
stay degeneration in the religious life of his time, 495.
Excursus E.
The
Election of the Exegetes
496
Chapter IX. The Nocturnal Council Its
500
intimate relation to the rest of Plato's plan, 500.
Its constitu-
and educational purpose, 505. Its archetype Academy, 509. Its powers primarily moral, not legal, 510; tion, 503;
its
existence not inconsistent with the rule of law, 511;
it is
an important agency
Plato's
hence instead
in supporting the rule of law, 513.
Excursus F. Philippus of Opus
515
part three: plato's principles The Mixed
Chapter X.
The
political
of
as a
Constitution
521
mean, 521; a mixture of two extremes, 523; viz. monarchy and democracy, 525. The monarchical element in Plato's constitution, 526. Inadequacy of Aristotle's interpretation it
omy
a
mixture of oligarchy and democracy, 528.
mean between wealth and
poverty, 530.
Plato's econ-
The middle
and in religion, 532. The mixture of Dorian and Ionian, 533. Other evidences of mixture, 535. The doctrine of mixture in the Philebus as the secret of excellence and stability, 535; in politics the proper mixture a balance between authority and liberty, 537. The special doctrine: the mixed constitution a balance of powers within the executive, 538. Confusion of the
way
in education
—
special
Chapter
with the general doctrine in
XL The
Rule of
Basic conditions
from Attic law:
544 it
state,
544;
but
difficult to
make
presupposes taken over by Plato
(a) written law, 546;
ity of magistrates,
higher
thought, 540.
Law
This principle the salvation of the effective, 545.
later
548.
officers responsible
(b) courts, 547; (c) liabilPlato's special devices for making the
through mutual checks, 549.
xv
— Institu-
ANALYTICAL CONTENTS tions for
producing eunomia in the
citizens, 552.
Persuasive pre-
which often include nonrational means Morality and law two species of a comof persuasion, 557. mon genus, 560. The end of law to produce virtue in the citiDistinction between "right zen and order in the state, 561. law" and positive law, 563; right law to be discerned by nous, ambles
to the laws, 553;
—
—
564.
— The
formulation of the laws
art of legislation involves the
and systematic form, 565; and insight into the end of law, 567; and is dependent upon the lessons of history and experience, 567. The sovereignty of right law, and of all law that imitates it, 569. The process of amendment to be under the in rational
—
guidance of nous, 570.
—
The
scope and profundity of Plato's
doctrine, 571.
Chapter XII. The Rule of Philosophy Philosophy present in the Plato's city, 573.
573
Laws and intended
to
be important in
Philosophy and law interdependent, exercising
a joint sovereignty in philosophically formulated law, 576.
Com-
parison of this conception with the teaching of the Republic, law
not excluded from Plato's earlier work, as
is
sometimes
said, 577.
The
philosopher-guardians to be "guardians of the laws," 582; hence their rule implies the rule of law, 582. But the Republic
and an orderly process for amending the law, 583. The antithesis between science and law in the Politicus, 584. But law is necessary in any form of rule, however scientific, 586. The distinction between positive law and right law implied, 587; science antithetical to lacks legal devices for holding rulers responsible,
—
much
positive law, but not to right law, 588.
losophy implies the presence of law, not
its
— The rule of phi-
abolition, 589.
Retrospect
591
an irrelevant creation of philosophical imagination, but rooted in the soil of Greek history, 591; and of Athenian history in particular, 592. The Laws a. message Plato's political ideal not
prepared for Plato's intended
own
people, but delivered too late to have
efTect, 592.
xvi
its
FOREWORD Charles
(1993)
H. Kahn
The publication in i960 of Morrow's work on the Laws was a landmark in Platonic scholarship. For the first time it was possible for the modern reader to appreciate the nature of Plato's achievement in his last and longest dialogue. The Laws is so different from the had been largely neglected; the interest in Plato's political philosophy was focused almost exclusively on the Laws' more brilliant sibling. If the situation has changed in the last thirty years, that is in good measure due to Morrow's work, seconded ten years later by Trevor Saunders's excellent Penguin translation. What Morrow succeeded in doing was to clarify the sense of Plato's proposals in the Laws by comparing them at every
Republic in every respect that
it
1
point with the historical institutions of Greece. This has
what
made
it
from what is traditional in this mass of detailed legislation. Morrow's work was done so well that it will in all probability never need to be done again. Every informed interpretation of Plato's Laws in the last thirty years has built on the foundation that he provided. What I propose to do here, by way of introduction, is first to summarize the insights which Morrow's study gives us into Plato's design of political institutions in the Laws, and then apply these insights to the controversial question of the relation between the scheme of the Laws and that of the Republic. Finally, I will indicate what I take to be the limitations of Morrow's account of Plato's possible for us to distinguish
is
specifically Platonic
political philosophy.
Morrow
interprets the
rather than as a
upon
work of
Laws
primarily as a system of legislation
theoretical philosophy.
He
the concrete nature of the proposed constitution
rightly insists
and upon the
thought as a whole. Unlike the Republic, the Laws does not describe a Utopia but a Cretan city with a definite location in time and space, not an ideal state but as good an imitapractical bent of Plato's
Plato: The Laws, translated with an introduction by T. J. Saunders (Harmondsworth, England: Penguin, 1970). See also Saunders's Notes on the Laws of Plato (London: Institute of Classical Studies, 1972). Saunders's translation in turn inspired R. F. Stalley to produce a very lucid philosophical Introduction to Plato's Laws (Oxford: Black. well, 1983). Morrow's work also serves as the basis for G. Klosko's discussion of the Laws in chapters 12 and 13 of The Development of Plato's Political Theory (New York and London: Methuen, 1986). For further literature, see the Bibliographical Note. 1
xvii
FOREWORD By making material Plato was working with, see how Plato transformed this ma-
tion as Plato thought possible in fourth-century Greece. clear exactly
what
historical
Morrow's study permits us terial to his
own
to
purpose.
was an Athenian first and last, that Athens is the city he has constantly in mind, and that the Spartan influence on his political scheme was secondary and subordinate. The Athenian quality of the Laws is borne out in detail by Morrow's comparison of nearly every institution in this Cre-
The
central thesis of the
book
is
that Plato
tan city with the historical legislation of Athens.
Morrow
does not
deny, of course, that Sparta (and, to a lesser extent, Crete) provided the model for the state control of education and marriage, the conservative system of music
lotments, and the
Sparta by
its
and gymnastics, the
common
meals.
Above
all,
long freedom from tyranny and
an unparalleled example of constitutional law, which Plato sought to reproduce in
minimum
land
al-
he emphasizes that civil
stability
war presented and respect for
own
But the devices by which Plato does so, and the legal forms in which his proposals are expressed, are nearly always drawn from an Athenian precedent, even where the Platonic institution itself is an original creation.
Thus
aliens), the
his
state.
the property classes, the presence of metics (resident
system of private slavery, the education in
mathematics, the law against impiety, the
letters
civic tribes, the
and
popular
and minor officials, the courts appointed by lot all these and a hundred more features of Plato's city are based upon an Athenian model, not on Sparta. Morrow points out that even the inalienability of the family lot, which is at first sight a Spartan feature, probably had its counterpart in archaic Athens, that the Athenian family system so dominates Plato's council, the elected generals
—
imagination that the institution of
common
meals
is
never fully
and that the more barbaric aspects of the Spartan educational program the youth packs, the organized thievery and floggings are entirely absent from Plato's state. In some cases, of course, the lack of parallels outside of Athens may be due to the scarcity of information concerning other Greek cities. But the cumulative weight of Morrow's documentation seems overwhelming: "It is not a Hellenic city in general that Plato draws for us, but an idealized Athens" (p. 592). Morrow makes clear that this is an idealization based more often on archaic than on contemporary Athens. In this respect the Laws integrated within his social scheme,
—
xviii
—
FOREWORD and constructive way the flattering portrait of early Athens which the Timaeus and Critias had sketched. The attitude of Plato in these last dialogues reflects the fact that Athens is not only the home of extreme democracy, but also the city of Solon and Socrates, and of Plato's own Academy. It is, of all carries out in a detailed
Greece, the land best suited for the production of philosopherkings.
And
Plato's last
comment on
his native city
is
the figure of
an "Athenian stranger" legislating to two Dorians. Complications begin when we ask what Morrow means by an idealized Athens. By insisting that Plato's ideal itself is rooted in the soil
in
of Greek history, and that his political craftsmanship consists
"divining within the historical materials the
which they imperfectly serve"
(p.
591),
immanent purpose
Morrow
runs the risk of
underestimating the great originality and boldness of Plato's political
thought. In a sense, of course, Plato's ideal
conditioned. But
its
also historically
shows up precisely at the legislation and the Greek material
essential novelty
point of contrast between his
out of which
is
composed. The relationship between Plato's city and Athens is perhaps clearest and most decisive in the field of government. The political organs and offices of the Laws fall into two distinct categories. On the one hand are the institutions that parallel those of Athens: the popular assembly, the popular council, the municipal officials (astynomoi and agoranomoi), and the rural officials (agronomoi). On the other hand are the institutions that are not Athenian at all, but entirely Platonic: the law-guardians, the superintendent of education (chosen
it is
from the guardians), the examiners
(euthynoi),
and the
Nocturnal Council. Plato's innovations can be seen in the treatment of the first group of offices, but above all in the addition of the new elective magistracies, characterized
age: the guardians
by long tenure and advanced
and examiners are both
to be over 50,
and
to
and 75 years of age respectively. Plato's transformation of the Athenian offices consists primarily in clipping the power of assembly and council (by transferring much of their competence to the guardians) and in adding an oligarchical element in the form of property qualifications. The use of four classes based on wealth is clearly oligarchic, or plutocratic, and Morrow's partial denial (pp. i7of.) does not carry conviction. But it is certainly not true to say (as Barker does) that Plato turns serve until 70
xix
FOREWORD the rule of
wisdom
2 into the rule of the rich.
The
council and the
market-wardens do not rule Plato's city. On the other hand, property qualifications play no part whatsoever in election to the higher offices, or in appointment to the rural police, which may be considered as the preparation for high erty classes, Plato's class hostility
is
limited use of prop-
what he
to be
says
it is:
to avoid
by balancing the factor of wealth against that of mere
number (V.744C Plato
motive seems
office. In his
free to
offices precisely
VI.757E 4, 759B 6-7). reconcile democracy with oligarchy
3; cf.
in his
lower
because they will not be the object of any real
struggle for power.
The
essentially aristocratic character of the
guaranteed by the concentration of supreme authority in the hands of the law-guardians and examiners. The guardians exercise the principal executive power; the examiners stand above state
is
them,
power
at the
summit of the
civic structure,
with overriding negative
check and punish all other magistrates for misconduct. Morrow has perhaps not made sufficiently clear this hierarchical superiority of the examiners. It is marked not only by some unspeto
cified legal
power over
the guardians, 3 by the unique honors asso-
ciated with their election all
and
their
memory
after death, but
by their automatic inclusion in the Nocturnal Council, a privi-
lege granted to only ten out of the thirty-seven guardians. periority of the examiners
is
due
to the rule
of law.
The
su-
all
human
rulers
negative character of their supreme powers
a guarantee that these will not be abused.
less a special
The
precisely to the fact that they are
the final device for assuring the subordination of
is
above
And
there
is
neverthe-
provision for the "examination" or answerability even
of an examiner: any private citizen
may
bring a suit against
him
for abuse of his office (XII.947E-948A).
Such
"mixed constitution" can be described only in terms of paradox. Morrow suggests Plato's own formula from the Menexa
enus: "aristocracy with the approval of the people."
More
precisely,
an elective oligarchy. The long tenure of the guardians and examiners will make them unresponsive to the popular will and is
it
give
them
the fixed status of a governing class.
Ernest Barker, Greeks Political Theory. Plato and His Predecessors (Methuen/Barnes and Noble, 1950), p. 397. Klosko {Development, p. 217) complains that the law-guardians "are virtually immune from examination." But he himself recognizes that the examiners "are given the power to pass sentence on offending magistrates" (p. 216). See XII.945C-D; 946C 6: "They will examine ... all offices of the state" {pasas tas archas elenchonton). 2
?
.
XX
.
.
FOREWORD As
element of democracy in Plato's mixture, it is real though limited. The election of even the highest magistrates and the existence of popular, lot-appointed courts show that Plato has gone as far as he could to make a place for the Athenian tradition for the
"freedom" with wisdom (represented by the higher magistrates) and friendship (i.e., class harmony) in the three-fold goal of his legislation. But farther he cannot go. The popular courts must be reviewed by the select judges, just as the popular assembly and council must be supervised by the venerable guardians and examiners. For otherwise the second-best city would not even be an imitation of the first. We see, therefore, in what sense the government of the Laws represents an idealized Athens: it represents a compromise between Athens and the Republic. The rule of philosopher-kings has been integrated within the traditional framework of the polis. But Plato has not abandoned the central tenet of his earlier doctrine, as the institution of the Nocturnal Council makes perfectly clear. in his city,
It
and
to unite
has often been
felt
that the reappearance of these philosophic
councillors in the twelfth
book of the Laws forms an inorganic ap-
pendix, an afterthought ultimately incompatible with the eleven
preceding books. 4
have resolved
to
It is
one of the greatest merits of Morrow's work
this contradiction.
He
has
shown
that, far
from
undermining the other institutions of the city, the Nocturnal Council completes them by giving them their specifically Platonic sense. It is not the task of the Nocturnal Council as such to govern or control the city. Its members do in fact exercise such control, for the inner they include the examiners and the senior guardians circle of the ruling class. As a council, however, their function is not so much government as education and research. The Council constitutes the device by which an elective aristocracy is transformed into something that resembles the rule of philosopherkings. 5 The true model for this council, as Morrow says, is Plato's
—
G. H. Sabine, A History of Political Thought, 3d ed. (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1961), p. 85: in the last few pages of the Laws Plato "adds to the state another institution which contradicts the purpose of planning a state in which the law is supreme." Similarly, Barker, pp. 406-8: "Plato, when he wrote the last book of the Laws, was not of the same mind as when he wrote the earlier books" (p. 408, n. 1). Cf. T. A. Sinclair, A History ofGreel( Political Thought (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1951), 4
.
.
.
.
.
.
pp. 205f.
This is what Plato implies by his concluding remark that "the city should be entrusted Council" (XII.969B 3). Their practical decisions (including the completion and possible revision of the law code) will be informed by their philosophical studies in the 5
to the
XXX
FOREWORD own Academy:
advanced study of philosophy 6 as the source of rational law. What distinguishes it from all other schools or learned societies is that its membership is drawn from the supreme magistrates of the city, and that it has some (not fully specified) responsibility for the completion and possible revision of it is
a school for the
the law code.
no question of the Nocturnal Council being set above the laws. Legally, its powers are largely defined by the individual duties of the officials who compose it. The only two legal
There
is
really
prerogatives explicitly granted to the council itself are:
(i)
the ad-
monishment of atheists, and (2) the hearing and judging of citizen travellers returning from abroad. Not everyone will agree with Morrow that these responsibilities "are obviously of minor imporand most tance" (p. 510). They constitute in fact the most delicate alarming
—
stitute rule
—
feature of Plato's entire legislation. But they
of the
city.
On
do not con-
the contrary, they confirm the philo-
sophic rather than governmental competence of the Council.
It is
precisely because these questions involve matters of theology
and
comparative legislation that the guardians and examiners are called
upon
to deal
with them as members of the Council, rather than in
their usual capacity as magistrates.
Thus Morrow
has succeeded, against nearly
all
previous writers,
showing that there is no fissure in the system of the Laws, no sudden reversion from the second-best to the first constitution. We in
same way
as the philosopher-kings' political insight
is
keener
when
they return to the
cave.
Cf. Klosko, Development, p. 218: "The nocturnal council is envisioned as a kind of ongoing seminar. Its main purpose is to achieve a theoretical understanding of the laws of the state." In his 1988 paper, however (see Bibliographic Note below), Klosko has emphasized the loose threads and inconsistencies in Plato's reference to the Nocturnal Council and in his suggestions for revision of the lawcode. I think it is an exaggeration to speak of "a fundamental break in the argument of the Laws" as Klosko does in his later paper (p. 85). The inconsistencies do point to an unresolved tension in Plato's thought, but it is not a tension between the rule of law and the unfettered rule of philosophy (i.e., between the scheme of the Laws and the scheme of the Republic). That tension, characteristic of the Statesman, has been resolved in the Laws by the decision against any form of uncontrolled power. (Even the examiners can be called to account.) What Plato has not tully worked out is a balance between (a) the need for a fixed and stable body of legislation, and (b) the possibility of rational improvements in the light of new knowledge and deeper understanding. This is a genuine dilemma and an enduring problem, as we can see from contemporary debates about the "strict interpretation" of the United States Constitution. Now a modern constitution will specify a formal procedure for amendment. But the problem is more complicated for Plato, since he can in principle approve of a process of amendment only if it is guided bv philosophic wisdom. (Compare Statesman 300D-E.) 6
xxii
FOREWORD are
second
in the
still
city,
but the philosophic training of the rulers
simply not a principle that Plato
is
fact that this training
prepared to
is
sacrifice.
The
not clearly specified until the very end of
is
might be omitted, at least temporarily, if conditions were unsuitable. There is no mention of it, for instance, in the constitution which Plato proposes for Syracuse in the Eighth Epistle, and which otherwise bears such a close resemblance to the scheme of the Laws. This is presumably what the exposition suggests, of course, that
Plato
means by
it
the statement that he
is
ready to propose not
only a second-best but even a third-best constitution
if
necessary
(V 739B, E). 7 But only a philosophic council, authorized to improve the lawcode in the light of further knowledge, can provide the link that will
draw
Morrow
is
these copies as close as possible to their original.
obviously right in emphasizing the connections be-
—
tween the Laws and the Republic in looking, for example, to Republic VII rather than to the un-Platonic Epinomis for a fuller statement of the higher education of the rulers. In fact, all of the most controversial features of the Republic (with the exception of the
form proposed again, though
system of three classes) reappear in the Laws, at of aspirations.
The
equality of
women
is
never fully worked out (VIII.804D-805D).
community of
women, and
property,
On
least in the
the other hand, the
children
is
given up as un-
and Plato accepts the family with its land allotment as of his social order (V.745C and passim). Yet the vision of where everything is common where not even sensations
realizable,
the basis a society
—
or actions or thoughts are private
model, which Plato
now
—
still
stands before
admits to be beyond
human
him
as a
nature in
its
present form, but conceives of as a city of "gods or children of gods"
(V.739D-740A). The perfect unity of such a heavenly city is mirrored in his Cretan polis only by the symmetrical proportions of the number of land allotments. Morrow's utilitarian explanation of the
number
5,040 (pp. 129^)
is
correct as far as
it
goes, but fails to
take account of Plato's symbolic use of this unchanging
with
its
symmetrical subdivisions as an imitation of unity, "as close
immortality as possible" (739E
to
number
4).
In the case of property and the family, Plato's retreat from the position of the Republic gret. If the city 7
For
parallels
is
obviously
of the Laws
is
between the second-best
made with
a second-best, state
it
reluctance and reis
because Plato
is
of the Laws and Plato's proposals for Syr-
acuse in Epistles VII and VIII, see Klosko, Development,
xxiii
p. 239.
FOREWORD now
prepared to widen the gap between the model and its realization: the model itself has not changed (V.739E 1). That is equally true in the case of the other chief contrast with the Republic, the
from the discretion of the philosopher-king to the supremacy of written law. On this point, Morrow's dissent from the usual interpretation seems to blur an essential distinction. He points to the passages in the Republic which imply the sovereignty of law, and suggests that the only difference in the Laws is that what had been a moral desideratum has now been made into an enforceable rule shift
by the provision of legal safeguards against the irresponsible use of power (pp. 582^). But this statement of the case does not reflect the
profound change in spirit between the two dialogues. The Republic is built around the figure of the philosophic ruler, freely molding the state in the image of his own vision of the Good. The Laws, on the other hand, consists of one prolonged endeavor to restrict the future discretion of the guardians by the whole body of written law. Plato himself is aware of this contrast: he suggests that the final decision in favor of the rule of law is due to the "keener vision to an insight not unlike Lord Acton's of old age" (IV.715E 1)
—
principle of the corrupting influence of
power upon
The
to the rule
transition
pared
at
from the
rule of
Reason
its
of
possessor. 8
Law
length by the discussion in the Statesman, which
gues for Reason, but hints at the
new
is
pre-
still
ar-
solution in the cosmic myth:
unchecked rule of Reason belongs to an earlier world period, when the rulers of men were of more divine nature than at present. Characteristically, however, Plato's statement of the new principle is combined with a reaffirmation of the old ideal: if the right man could be found, he would have no need of laws above him; neither law nor any other arrangement deserves to rule over true knowledge and reason (IX.875C-D). Plato has reconciled himself to the weakness of human nature, not to the rejection of his original idethe
als.
Morrow's book, it is a full statement of these ideals in all their naked and shocking originality. It is, I think, misleading to suggest that most of us would accept the If there
is
something lacking
in
have been conscious of the debt. He writes that in "the history of and the largest place would belong to Plato and Aristotle. The Laws of the one, the Politics of the other, are, if I may trust my own experience, the hooks from which we may learn the most about the principles of politics." See "The History of Freedom in Antiquity," in J.E.E.D. Acton, Essays on Freedom and Power, ed. Himmelfarb (New York: Meridian, 1955), p. 74. 8
Acton seems
to
political science, the highest
(
.
xxiv
FOREWORD validity of the principles that Plato wishes his citizens to live by,
do not
most of
moral doctrine is completely obvious (p. 559). It is true that there is a large measure of overlap between Plato's moral principles and those of any civilized society. And in certain important respects Plato's proposals for reform are more democratic (in our sense) and more liberal than the corresponding institutions of Athenian democracy. (Thus Plato's law courts come much closer to what we count as "due process," and his preference for election over the choice of magistrates by lot is more in line with modern notions of democratic rule.) 9 But what is specifically and uniquely Platonic is the foundation of all morality and all politics upon a metaphysical vision of what is really true and good a vision which, in concrete terms, is expressed by a community whose members all think and feel and act and speak 10 Because of its concreteness, the Laws shows even more alike. clearly than the Republic the dangers inherent in using such a ce-
and
1
see that
his
—
model
lestial
as a blueprint for political action. If the state
ceived of as a realization of supreme goodness and truth
other words, often
comes
it is
—
con-
is
if,
in
treated as an instrument for saving souls or (what
same thing)
to the
for saving society
vention into every corner of the individual's
matter of course.
The
life
—then
its
inter-
will follow as a
and depends
existence of privacy, of free thought
speech, of autonomous creativity in literature
and the
arts,
upon a conception of the state which need not be merely negative, but must at least be limited. The liberal conception of government requires that there be a place beside the common good for other goods personal, private, and social with an independent status.
—
—
In the political sphere, Plato's unitary conception of the
means
monism
but his teleological
political theory that are
view.
swallow up all the metaphysical dualism
in practice that the public interest will
Paradoxically enough,
rest.
Good
As Rawls and
it
is
not Plato's
that accounts for the elements in his
most unacceptable from
a
modern
point of
others have emphasized, the liberal conception
of the state ultimately depends upon respect for normative diversity,
that
is
to say,
upon pluralism with regard
to
judgments con-
cerning the good. It
would be
difficult to
exaggerate the importance of this unitary
conception of the good in Plato's thought, since the very rule of 9 10
For Plato
as a "democratic elitist," see Stalley, Introduction, pp. 120-22. Republic V.462A-E; Laws V.739C-D.
XXV
FOREWORD based upon
modified and reinforced by another principle, the nostalgia for an archaic, stratified, unchanging social order, exemplified by Plato's admiration for the fixed canons philosophy
is
it.
It is
These two principles, archaism and the unitary Good, account for most of the repugnant features of Plato's legislation. The law of slavery may serve as a case in point. There can scarcely be any doubt of Plato's natural humaneness: this is evident, of Egyptian
for
art.
example, in
form of
play,
his
conception of the early stages of education as a
and even Yet
slaves (VI.777D).
in his general
his
humane
remarks on the treatment of
sentiments are so utterly over-
ruled by his sense for order and hierarchy that he proposes a slave
and more retrograde than that of his own time. In this connection, one wishes that Morrow had drawn more freely on his own admirable study of Plato's Law of Slavery. There is almost no mention in the present work of those passages in the slave law which, as Morrow put it, "do not make pleasant readlegislation harsher
ing.
11
Nor
is
there
much
said here about the preliminary population
purges, nor the implications for
home
life
of Plato's system of
"marriage inspectors." On the other hand, in regard to education, literature, and freedom of expression, Morrow does not hesitate to underline the features of Plato's constitution which are most in-
compatible with our
more concerned ality:
own
conceptions of a liberal society. But he
to reveal another side of Plato's political person-
the student of comparative jurisprudence
rational reform.
is
and the advocate of
Never before has Plato appeared
so clearly as the
spiritual heir of Solon, in the application of philosophic
wisdom
to
reform of the institutions of his ancestral city. When Morrow wrote, the controversy surrounding Karl Popper's attack on Plato as father of totalitarian ideology was still in its polemical stage, and Morrow preferred to avoid the quarrel. 13 From our perspective today it is easier to separate what was insightful in Popper's critique from what was exaggerated or distorted by Popper's fixation on the very real totalitarian threats in 12
a radical
G. R. Morrow, Plato's Law of Slavery in Its Relation to Greeks Law, Illinois Studies in Language and Literature 25 (Urbana, 111.: University of Illinois Press, 1939), p. 126. 12 In this connection Saunders cites "the complex arrangements for a 'mixed' constitu"
reforms of legal procedure, the enlightened theory of punishment, the persuasive and the provision for a continuing review of the legal code by a specially trained body" as constituting "an impressive program for the reform of society by the rule of law, informed by the insights of research and philosophy" {Plato: The Laws, p. 37). ,J Karl Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. 1: The Spell of Plato. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1950. tion, the
legal preambles,
xxvi
— FOREWORD own
No
one today would regard Plato as an apostle of liberalism, but we might be more inclined to emphasize his unparalleled insistence on the equality of women in education and politics. And we might well prefer Plato's class system in the Rehis
lifetime.' 4
public to Aristotle's modifications of class
of producers
to's city
rights,
—
—
the largest
and
in Politics VII,
it
where the
richest class of citizens in Pla-
are disenfranchised by Aristotle, deprived of property
and transformed
into slaves or serfs.
How
progressive or
upon
reactionary Plato's politics appear will largely depend gle selected for comparison. as his nostalgia for the
His
more
gift for
innovation
stratified society
is
the an-
just as radical
of pre-imperial Ath-
ens.
Morrow's book has the great merit of reminding us of the centrality of politics in Plato's conception of philosophy. It is no accident that Plato's three longest dialogues
—
Gorgias, the Republic,
and the Laws are devoted to the impact of moral philosophy upon the life of the polis. The Seventh Epistle tells us that Plato, until the age of forty, had aspired to a public career of political reform.
He
ultimately chose the
of politics by other means.
The
of philosophy as a continuation
life
vision in the Republic of a
nious society enlightened and governed by
wisdom
is
harmo-
the climax of
The Laws, coming at the end, stands as his legacy mankind. With the death of Dion and Plato's own approaching
Plato's lifework. to
death, the prospects for a philosopher-king were
Under
these circumstances Plato's
the cause for
which he had
construction of a second-best
lived
no longer
realistic.
most effective contribution to became the detailed, mundane
city. 15
BIBLIOGRAPHIC NOTE
We arc indebted to Trevor
comprehensive Bibliography on Plato's May igy^ (New York: Arno Press, 1976). The second edition (1979) covers 1920-1976, and has additional citations through March 1979.
Laws
Saunders for
a
i()20-jo, with additional citations through
R. F. Stalley's Introduction to Plato's
Laws (Oxford: Blackwell,
1983), pp. 190-
See the balanced survey in Stalley, chap. 16: "The Closed Society of the Laws." See Development, pp. 134-36, 1491^, 166-68. 15 Major portions of this commentary on Morrow's work were originally published in my review of Plato's Cretan City in the Journal of the History of Ideas 22 (1961): 418-24. Reprinted by permission of the Johns Hopkins University Press. 14
also Klosko,
xxv a
FOREWORD 97, has a
more
selective
list
The Development of Plato's
of suggested readings on specific topics. G. Klosko, Political
1986), has a useful bibliography (pp.
known
to
me
is
in
T.
J.
(New York and London: Methuen, 245-55). The most up-to-date bibliography
Theoiy
Saunders, Plato's Penal Code: Tradition, Controversy and
Gree\ Penology (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991). Plato bibliographies are also published regularly by L. Brisson in Lustrum (1977, 1983, 1988, 1989). Other relevant recent publications (kindly brought to my attention by Trevor
Reform
in
Saunders) include:
D. Cohen, "The Legal Status and Political Role of
Revue Internationale G. Klosko,
Women
in Plato's
Laws"
des Droits de I'Antiquite 34 (1987): 27-40.
"The Nocturnal Council
in Plato's
Laws"
Political Studies
36 (1988):
74-88.
K. Schopsdau, "Der Staatsentwurf der Nomoi zwischen Ideal und Wirklichkeit:
Zu
Plato leg. 739
A
i-E 7 und 745E 7-746D
2," Rheinische
Museum
134 (1991):
136-52. T.
J.
Saunders, "Penal
1990: Papers on Gree\
Law and and
Family
Law
Magnesia," in Symposion
in Plato's
Hellenistic Legal History, ed.
M. Gagarin (Bohlau Ver-
lag, 1991), 115-32.
For general discussions of
Plato's
tion to Saunders's introduction to
Laws
Morrow's book appeared, in addithe Penguin translation and the works of Stalsince
and Klosko mentioned above, we have substantial chapters in P. Fnedlander, and W.K.C. Guthrie, A History of Gree\ Philosophy 5 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978). For three quite different approaches see A. B. Hentschke, Politi^ und Philosophic bei Plato und Aristoteles (Frankfurt am Main: V. Klostermann, 1971), M. Pierart, Platon et la Cite grecque (Brussels: Academie royale de Belgique, 1973), and L. Strauss, The Argument and Action of Plato's Laws (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1975). There is also a somewhat eccentric translation and interpretation by T. Pangle, The Laws of Plato (New York: Basic Books, 1980). ley
Plato III (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1969),
XXVlll
PREFACE No work
more intimately connected with its time and with the world in which it was written than the Laws. The other dialogues deal with themes magnificently independent of time and place, and Plato's treatment of them has been recognized as important wherever
of Plato's
human
is
beings have thought about the problems of knowl-
edge, or conduct, or
human
destiny.
But the Laws
Greek
the portrayal of a fourth-century
city
—a
city that existed,
it is
only in Plato's imagination, but one whose establishment he
true,
The
could well imagine as taking place in his day. it is
concerned with
is
composed are the
political
and
materials of
which
social institutions characteristic
more than two thousand years ago in the eastern Mediterranean; and it is pervaded throughout by the concepts and incentives that guided their actions and gave meaning to their lives. With the passing away of this people for whom it of a small but talented people living
was intended, and the substitution of other horizons for those within which they lived, the Laws has tended to become a closed book, formidable in effort
its
contents,
and
involved in mastering them.
But the interpreter of Plato cannot afford of account. that
reward for the
at first sight offering little
may
There are many aspects of
well be understood without
it
;
to leave the
Laws
out
Plato's thought, to be sure,
but
we
cannot really under-
stand Plato the philosopher without recognizing the central position
he assigned to the guidance of in
which
life is
life
and the molding of the
lived; political philosophy
him not an apthought. Nor can we
was
pendage, but the crown and goal of philosophic
institutions
for
be content to rely upon the Republic alone for understanding his political philosophy.
The
very bulk of the
importance Plato himself attached to cal aims.
Whether
it is
Laws
this later
is
evidence of the
statement of his
politi-
a repudiation of his earlier principles, or a
development and exemplification of them, can be determined only after a careful analysis of the later work. Compared with the Republic, the
Laws
has the special value of presenting
its
in the abstract, but in their concrete reality, as Plato
principles not
imagined they
might be embodied in an actual Greek city. But these details of constitution making and legislation cannot themselves be rightly understood apart from their setting, the life of fourth-century Greece from which they are drawn or adapted. The significance of some casual phrase, some detail of election procedure, xxix
PREFACE some prescription regarding sacrifices and dances, can escape us if we do not know as Plato's readers did the practices to which he is referring or which he is modifying. Still less can we grasp the larger features of his construction without knowing the common institutions of the Greek city-state and the motives that actuated the citizen a knowledge that Plato takes for granted. Unfortunately even the best-informed reader of today is unable to do more than approach the understanding that Plato could assume without question in his readers. This means that the Laws will always remain in some respects obscure to us, just as many passages in Thucydides or Herodotus defy understanding; but no Platonist should rest content until he has diminished the obscurity as much as he can. And anyone who attempts to do so will be rewarded by discovering that much in the Laws which has hitherto been condemned as confused, or contradictory to something Plato has said elsewhere, turns out upon examination in its historical context to be lucid and in order. This book, then, attempts to set forth in some detail the main institutions of the state described in Plato's Laws, and to interpret them by comparing or contrasting them with the historical laws and social institutions of Plato's Greece, and in the light of the concepts and traditions current in his day. Part One examines the nature and extent of the major historical influences upon Plato's design, following for example, or
—
—
—
the clue provided by the dramatic structure of the dialogue; in Part
Three
I
venture an interpretation of his political principles in terms
of the concrete legislation that embodies
vides the confirmation of
my
my interpretation of was my former teacher
basis for
them; and Part
Two
interpretation of the influences
pro-
and the
the principles.
and lifelong friend, George Holland Sabine, who first suggested to me, more than thirty years ago, the value of such a comparison of Plato's Laws and the historical institutions with which Plato and his readers were familiar; and the inIt
quiry proved to be so fascinating that
it
has been the center of
my
and publications during almost all the intervening years. This book is therefore fittingly, and affectionately, dedicated to him; though it must be added that he would probably, nay certainly, dissent strongly from some of my interpretations. He cannot, therefore, be held responsible for anything here expounded; but only for the ideal of sober and dispassionate inquiry which has guided me, and to which I hope I have been faithful. scholarly interests
xxx
I
PREFACE In a study that ranges as widely as this over almost
Greek
life I
cannot hope to have avoided
of fact or emphasis that will be
—corrected.
I
My
aspects of
But the mistakes have unwittingly made can be and I hope
It will
be gratifying
if
errors.
—
this effort at synthesis acts
as a challenge to others to set the picture right
gone
all
where
my
hand has
astray.
indebtedness
me who
ars before
is
great, as
my footnotes
show, to the
have dealt with portions of
this task,
many
schol-
and without
whose individual labors this undertaking would have been impossible. I acknowledge also the help of the many friends who have read parts of this work in manuscript and have given me the benefit of their advice
Lloyd
W.
—my
colleagues at the University of Pennsylvania,
Daly, Paul Schrecker, and Francis P. Clarke; A. E.
Raubitschek of Princeton University; L. A. Post of Haverford College; and Sir David Ross, Richard Robinson,
and A. Andrewes
Oxford University. None of these men can be held responsible for the work as it stands, or for any part of it; but it is certainly less imperfect than it would have been without their counsel, and for their interest, their corrections, and their suggestions I record my sincere gratitude. I am grateful also to my former secretary, Mrs. Richard Parker, for valuable aid during the early stages of this work. But above all I am indebted to my wife, who has been my constant ally and aid from the beginning, in editing, in criticizing, in typing and retyping my numerous drafts, and in keeping a watchful eye on all of
the other
humdrum
details involved in a
work
of this sort.
Guggenheim Foundation I express my sincere thanks for the interest shown in this project from its beginning, and for the financial assistance without which it could not have been undertaken
To
the
nor carried through and also to the Fulbright Commission, on both ;
sides of the Atlantic,
who made
it
possible for
me
to
spend
a year at
Oxford among colleagues especially sympathetic toward my study. Finally, I acknowledge with deep appreciation the hospitality and facilities afforded me by the American School of Classical Studies at Athens, where this book was begun, and by Oriel College, of Oxford University, where it was brought to completion.
GLENN Philadelphia, Pennsylvania July 7959
XXX
R.
MORROW
ADDITIONAL ACKNOWLEDGMENTS acknowledge the permission of the University of Illinois Press to reprint in Chapter iv several pages of my earlier monograph on Plato's Law of Slavery. I am indebted also to James L. Celarier, who rendered valuable help in checking references and in the preparation of the indices; to the anonymous readers of the Princeton University Press for important suggestions and corrections contained in their reports; to the officers and staff of the Press for their work in designing and producing this book; and to Miss Miriam Brokaw, in particular, for her warm interest, her sage advice, and her competent superintendence of the progress of the work through the press. I
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL ABBREVIATIONS following abbreviations have been used in the footnotes, and oc-
The
and works frequently
casionally in the text, for authors
American Journal
AJP.
of Philology.
Otto Apelt, Platons Gesetze. 2
Apelt.
cited.
vols. Leipzig, 191 6.
Ernest Barker, Gree\ Political Theory: Plato and his Prede-
Barker.
cessors.
London,
Bonner and Smith.
191 8.
Robert
tration of Justice
J.
Bonner and Gertrude Smith, The Adminis-
Homer
from
to Aristotle. 2 vols. University of Chi-
cago Press, 1930, 1938. Burnet. John Burnet, Platonis Opera. Oxford, 1901-1906. R. G. Bury, Plato: Laws. Loeb Classical Library. 2 vols.
Bury.
and Cambridge (Mass.), 1942. Busolt-Swoboda. Georg Busolt, Griechische Staatsfande, Pt. 1920; Pt. 11 edited by Heinrich Swoboda, Munich, 1926. Cassara. Antonino Cassara, Platone: Le Legge. Padua, 1947.
CQ. Classical Quarterly. Des Places. Edouard des Places, Platon: Les Bude edition of Plato, Paris, 1951. Diels-Kranz.
Hermann
Diels,
Lois, Bks.
i-vi.
1,
London Munich,
Vol. xi of the
Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. 6th
edn. by Walther Kranz. 3 vols. Berlin, 1951-1952.
Auguste Dies, Platon: Les Lois, Bks.
Dies.
vii-xii.
Vol.
xn
of the
Bude
edition of Plato. Paris, 1956.
DS.
Daremberg and E.
Charles
grecques
England.
et
Saglio,
Dictionnaire
des antiquites
romaines. 10 vols. Paris, 1877-1919.
E. B. England,
The Laws
of Plato. 2 vols. Manchester Univer-
sity Press, 1921.
FGH.
Felix Jacoby,
Die Fragmente der Griechischen Histori\er> Berlin
and Leiden, 1923-1958. FHG. Karl and Theodor
Miiller,
Fragmenta Historicorum Graecorum.
4 vols. Paris, 1841-1851.
Gernet.
Louis Gernet, "Les Lois
Vol. xi of the Gilbert.
Vol. Hignett.
Bude
et le droit positif," in the Introduction to
edition of Plato. Paris, 1951.
Gustav Gilbert, Handbuch der Griechischen Staatsalterthiimer. 1,
2nd
edn., Leipzig, 1893; Vol.
C. Hignett,
A
11,
Leipzig, 1885.
History of the Athenian Constitution to the
End
of the Fifth Century B. C. Oxford, 1952.
IG.
Inscriptiones Graecae.
JHS.
Journal of Hellenic Studies. Jowett. Benjamin Jowett, The Dialogues of Plato. 3rd edn. 5 vols. Oxford, 1892.
xxxiii
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL ABBREVIATIONS Lipsius.
Hermann
Justus
Lipsius,
Das
Attische Recht
fahren. Leipzig, 191 5.
Liddell and Scott, Gree\-English Lexicon.
LSJ.
New
und
edn. by
Rechtsver-
H.
S. Jones,
Oxford, 1925-1940. Marrou. Henri-Irenee Marrou, Histoire de Veducation dans Vantiquite, 2nd. edn. Paris, 1950.
Martin P. Nilsson, Geschichte der Griechischen Religion. 2
Nilsson.
Munich, .1941,
vols.
1950.
PR.
Philosophical Review.
RE.
Pauly-Wissowa-Kroll, Realencyclopddie der Classischen Altertumswissenschaft.
REG. Revue
des Etudes Grecques.
O. Reverdin, La Religion de
Reverdin.
la cite platonicienne. Paris, 1945.
Constantin Ritter, Platons Gesetze: Darstellung des Inhalts
Ritter.
Kommentar. 2 vols. Leipzig, 1896. Robin. Leon Robin, Platon: Oeuvres Completes. Stallbaum.
Gottfried
und
2 vols. Paris, 1950.
Stallbaum, Platonis Leges et Epinomis. 3 vols.
Gotha, 1859-1860. Stengel.
Paul
Munich,
W.
Syll.
Die Griechischen Kultusaltertumer. 8th edn.
Stengel,
1920.
Dittenberger, Sylloge Inscriptionum Graecarum. 3rd edn. 4 vols.
Leipzig, 1915-1923.
TAPA.
Transactions of the American Philological Association.
A. E. Taylor, The Laws of Plato, London, 1934. Tod. Marcus Tod, A Selection of Gree\ Historical Inscriptions. Vol. 2nd edn. Oxford, 1946; Vol. 11, 1948.
Taylor.
Wilamowitz.
1,
Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorfr".
Abbreviations of the names of ancient authors will in most cases be clear,
but the following should perhaps be mentioned to avoid confusion.
Aeschines or Aeschylus, the former
Aesch.
numeral, the
latter
when followed by
Diod.
Diodorus Siculus.
Diog.
Diogenes Laertius.
Aristotle
is
cited
by the pages and
when
the
followed by a
title
Roman
of a play.
lines of Bekker's (the Berlin) edition,
except for the Constitution of Athens and the Fragments, and Plato by the pages of Stephanus'
and the
line
numbers of Burnet's
xxxiv
edition.
PLATO'S CRETAN CITY A HISTORICAL INTERPRETATION OF THE LAWS
INTRODUCTION The scene is Crete, and the characters in the dialogue are three old men — Cleinias, a Cretan; Megillus, a Spartan; and an unnamed Athenian—who have started out from Gnossos on a pilgrimage and sanctuary of Zeus. The distance is considerable, and the Athenian suggests that it would be a pleasant pastime during their tedious walk to discourse about government and laws (7repl 7ro\u-€ia5 re koll v6fjLG)v) and the others readily agree. The conversation begins with an inquiry by the Athenian regarding the purpose of the common meals and the gymnastic and military exercises prescribed by the Spartan and Cretan legislators; and from to the cave
,
there
it
proceeds to more general considerations concerning the pur-
pose of law, the importance of education, and the secret of stability in a constitution.
The
conclusions they reach turn out to be peculiarly
timely; for at this point (the end of the third book) Cleinias reveals that he
a
is
a
member
new Cretan
of a commission charged with
city that
Cnossos and other
is
cities
which they
for
to be established
under the sponsorship of
He
therefore urges that they
in the island.
pursue their inquiry by imagining themselves city of
making laws
are the founders; in this
as legislating for
way
a
their theoretical
and he will perhaps be able to use their results in the colony with which he is concerned. The remainder of the Laws is an exposition, in sometimes elaborate detail, of the institutions and laws that it would be appropriate to establish in this interest will
be
satisfied,
new city. The establishment
of colonies
was
a habit of long standing
the Greeks, less evident in Plato's century than days, but
still
lation (707c)
regarded 1
as the best
way
to deal
it
had been
among
in earlier
with a surplus of popu-
or with a discordant faction in a city (7o8bc).
The
which the Greeks had spread themselves and their culture all over the Mediterranean area, from the northern shore of the Black Sea to the western coast of Spain, was a thing of the past; but the tradition was kept alive by the Athenian cleruchies and other more pretentious establishments in the fifth and fourth centuries, and another era of colonization was to begin soon 2 after Plato's time with the conquests of Alexander. Such new cities
great age of colonization during
name
1
References unaccompanied by the
2
H. Bengtson, Griechische Geschichte, Munich,
s
of a dialogue are to the Laws. 1940, 338.
plato's Cretan city always started their political for them,
and
competent
a
vise the founder, or the
The
life
great Protagoras
with a
legislator
sponsoring
was asked
to
set
of laws especially designed
was often
city, in
called
upon
to ad-
the task of legislation.
draw up
the laws for Pericles'
ambitious colony of Thurii in southern Italy; and Plato himself,
according to one tradition, was invited to legislate for the
Megalopolis in Arcadia
We
set
up
that the
see, therefore,
new
city of
after the defeat of Sparta at Leuctra.
Athenian Stranger
is
3
in a historically
on with his companions is but an idealized version of the discussions that must have taken place on countless occasions among persons responsible for and the conversation he
familiar situation,
new
establishing a
carries
colony.
might confront Plato or a member of the Academy at any time. Plato's deep and lifelong interest in politics, in the broadest sense of the term, is evident from the large place that the problems of political and social philosophy occupy in his writings. His theories of education, of law, and of social justice are inquiries carried on not merely for their speculative inFurthermore,
terest,
was
it
a situation that
but for the purpose of finding solutions to the problems of the
statesman and the educator. Plato's
work
as a
than with theory. Epistle he
tells
It
may
well be affirmed,
when we view
whole, that he was more concerned with practice 4
In the autobiographical passage of the Seventh
us that in his youth
it
was
his intention to enter public
young man of his high connections and great abilities (324b). But he was disillusioned by the excesses of the Thirty, a revolutionary movement for which he had at first had considerable hope, and later by the unjust action of the restored democracy in condemning Socrates on a charge of impiety, "which he of all men least deserved." The disillusionment with contemporary politics increased as he came to know better the men active in public life and saw more clearly the instability of the laws and customs of his own and other cities; and although he did
life,
a career that seemed the obvious one to a
3
For Protagoras and Thurii see Diog. ix, 50. For Megalopolis see below, Note 11. "Platon est en effet, contrairement a ce qu'on croit souvent, beaucoup plus preoccupe de pratique que de theorie." Robin, Platon, Paris, 1935, 254. Similarly Dies, in the Introduction to the Bude edn. of the Republic, v: "Platon n'est venu en fait a la philosophic que par la politique ... La philosophic ne fut originellement, chez Platon, que de Taction entravee." But we must not suppose that for Plato theory was a substitute for action. Indeed the scientific statesman, he says in Polit. 26oab, cannot be content with theoretical principles alone, but must supplement them with 4
directions for Phil. 623b.
action
— the
iiriTaKTtKov
}iepot8trta by the Spartans but dvSpeta in Crete, and that the Cretan tables are supported by the public treasury, not by private contributions, as at Sparta. Both allege a similarity in function between the Cretan kosmoi and the Spartan ephors, and both point out that the former are ten in number, whereas the latter are five. Both point out that there are "elders" in both constitutions, elected in one case from previous kosmoi, in the other from former ephors, and note that this body is called the council (fiovkr)) among the Cretans. Both also believe the Cretan customs to be the older and in many cases the archetype of the Spartan. But Aristotle refers to the perioikoi of Crete and explains why they are not a source of danger as are the Helots at Sparta, a point passed over without mention by Ephorus. Furthermore, Aristotle's account of the powers of the Cretan kosmoi, council, and assembly (not even mentioned by Ephorus) is much fuller and more critical, and culminates in a severe judgment on the irresponsible power of the kosmoi. On the other hand, Ephorus pays much more attention to the education of the young, a subject completely omitted by Aristode, and describes at length the peculiar Cretan 26
customs of love, again a topic that Aristotle passes over. Van EfTenterre {op.cit. 77-78) seems to me to overstate the similarity between Ephorus' and Aristode's account, but he comes to much the same conclusion as I do. "It looks as if the major outlines of Cretan studies had already been laid down in previous literature, or as if the principal themes for discussion had already become fixed, constituting so many conventional topics to which one would be expected to make at least some reference, more or less forced, in passing. Aristode and Ephorus are independent of one another only in the sense that it is impossible to trace all the information one of them gives to what is found in the other. But there is no doubt that both made use of previous works."
22
CRETE able in the
Academy
and
there are features of both Ephorus'
make
On
Academy, but
be definitely established. Strabo
specifically tells
ference of opinion between Ephorus
character of Minos.
The
stories of
on
Plato's teaching,
was
us that there
can
a sharp dif-
and "the ancients" regarding the
him
ancient writers pictured
as a tyrannical
tribute,
Theseus and Daedalus.
28
None
of these fifth-century tragedies deal-
ing with Minos has been preserved, but their able, to
27
and they constructed tragedies based the Minotaur and the labyrinth and the adventures
and violent collector of of
a bare possibility.
one point the dependence of Aristotle and Ephorus,
not merely on the
on the
indeed
Aristotle's accounts that
upon them more than
Plato's influence at least
And
to others interested in the subject.
judge from the
titles
Attic historians, Pherecydes
that have
number was
come down
and Hellanicus,
also
to us.
29
consider-
The
emphasized,
early it
ap-
30
Minos as an enemy of ancient Athens. But the reputation of Minos underwent a complete change in the fourth century henceforth he is the great and wise legislator instructed by Zeus, and this is the opinion that Ephorus held, according to Strabo. 31 This is also the view that Plato, and presumably many others,
pears, the role of
;
espoused in the fourth century as a result of the tan customs
and the
belief in their great antiquity.
ing in Ephorus' position
with one
we
new
is
that he uses a curious
But what
argument
find in the Platonic writings. Strabo
quoted Homer's
interest in Cre-
tells
is
strik-
identical
us that he
lines
ev0a re Mlvcjs ivvicopos fiacrikeve A165 ^leydkov SapLcrTrjs. 27
Plato attaches great importance to the
common
meals, the
first
point about
which the Athenian Stranger enquires (625c). These are mentioned early in both Aristotle's and Ephorus' accounts and are treated as a fundamental institution. Aristotle is interested in the division of powers among t^e organs of government, the very point of constitutional theory to which Plato gives special attention in the third book of the Laws, and Aristotle's criticism of the Cretan constitution because the "elders" (yepovre?) are irresponsible seems an echo of Plato's repeated warning that no officials should be awrrevSwoL. Ephorus, on the other hand, treats other matters that engaged Plato's attention: the gymnastic and military exercises of the youth, the use of the pyrrhic dance and Cretic rhythms, and the customs of boy love. 28
Strabo x, iv, 8. Sophocles wrote a Theseus, a Daedalus and a Camicii, which must have dealt with the death of Minos at Camicus in his vain attempt to recapture Daedalus after 29
his flight from Crete (Herod, vn, 170). These works may have constituted a trilogy. Euripides wrote a Cretans, and one of the dramas of the politician-poet, Plato's cousin Critias, was entitled Rhadamanthys. For these and other titles of lost works, see Poland in 30 31
re s.v. Minos, 1891. For Pherecydes see fgh Pt. 1, 3, F148-F150; for Hellanicus Isocrates, for example (xn, 205).
23
Pt.
1, 4,
F164.
THREE HISTORICAL STATES This appeal
to
Homer
Platonic Mi?20s. oapLo-rrjs
The
is
exactly the defense
lines
an unfamiliar word
uncertain whether
The
or with oapLcrrrj^.
find in the pseudo-
quoted are highly obscure. Not only was
but the meaning of evviupos it is
we
it is
to the
Greeks of the fourth century,
ambiguous j and whatever it means, be taken with fiacrikeve, with Mi^cos,
is
to
Socrates in the
Minos explains
that oaptcrn]?
meaning "associate in discourse" (crvvovo-Lao-Trjs iv Xoyois), i.e. a pupil; and that ivvicopos means "every ninth year." The meaning of the passage, therefore, is that Minos went every is
to be taken as
ninth year to be tutored of Zeus, the great master of
This
is
wisdom
(3i9b-e).
obviously not the only possible interpretation of this passage,
nor even the most plausible. Socratic exegesis.
32
It
is
a
For our purpose
whether or not the Minos of the interpretation
is
is
good specimen of ingenious it
is
not necessary to decide
a genuine Platonic dialogue, for the gist
contained in the Athenian's question on the
opening page of the Laws: "And do you, Cleinias,
say, as
Homer
Minos used to go every ninth year and converse with his father Zeus and that he was guided by his oracles in making laws for your cities ?" The agreement of Ephorus with Plato in this strained Homeric exegesis is too much to be a coincidence. If Ephorus' history began to appear, as is now generally believed, about 350 or a little 33 later, the fourth book, in which he dealt with Crete, could hardly does, that
have appeared before Plato's death; so that Plato could not have been influenced by
it,
even
if
we assume
that he
was willing
to
make
such
an undisguised borrowing from another author. Ephorus' interpretation of Homer points definitely, therefore, to his acquaintance with this picturesque bit of Platonic
of the
The
teaching and possibly also to a reading
Laws and
the Minos.
evidence
therefore considerable that the
is
s*
Academy, and Plato
in particular, played an important part in the revival of interest in
Crete that took place in the fourth century. Plato's discussion of the island in the
Laws
is
the earliest of the fourth-century accounts about
32
Odyss. xix, 178-179. For the four interpretations of this passage in later antiquity The effrontery of Socrates is evident elsewhere in this defense of Minos. He cites Hesiod's characterization of Minos as the "kingliest of kings," and Odyss. xi, 569, where Minos, not Rhadamanthys, is said to wield the see Poland, loc.cit. 1902-1903.
But he refrains from mentioning the Mi'vcoo? 6\o6povo?
IttI
rrpoa-
rjKovra irpayixara). These acquaintances included Critias, and possibly also
Theramenes, the leader of the moderate party, whose
mem-
ory continued to be held in great respect by Aristotle and others in later days,
and who was
the extremists with
later to
whom
come
to his death at the
hands of
2
he had collaborated. Plato confesses that
Diels-Kranz, n, 378-380, 391-394; Wilamowitz, Platon 1, u6f., 122. They may also have included Socrates. Diod. xiv, 5, 1-3 reports that he was present at the meeting (presumably a meeting of the council; cf. Xen. Hell. 11, iii, 1
2
when Theramenes was condemned
to death, and endeavored to save him. The he was ordered to carry out under the Thirty (Plato, Apol. 32c; Ep. VII. 324c) may have been a commission assigned to him as a councillor; we know that he had been a member of the council under the democracy a year or
50)
illegal arrest that
THREE HISTORICAL STATES in his youthful enthusiasm for reform he at
first
entertained high
change of government, though he seems not to have taken any part in it; but that in a short time he was shocked and disillusioned by its excesses. Evidently he could not stomach, any hopes for
this
more than could Socrates and the majority of his fellow high handed and violent actions of his cousin.
citizens, the
Besides Critias there were other Laconizing influences on Plato's
youth.
He
probably served in the cavalry; only rich young
men
could
equipment for this branch of the armed forces. There is evidence that these young cavaliers affected Spartan manners and a de3 cided preference for the Spartan "aristocratic" constitution. Such associations have their effect undoubtedly: but how much they affected Plato, and in what way, we do not know. There are humorous remarks in the dialogues about the affectations of these Laconizers, an afford the
indication that Plato did not take
member
them very
seriously.
of the older generation in this group
was, at some periods at
least,
4
One
notorious
was Alcibiades, who
pro-Spartan; but this sentiment probably
sat as tightly to his self-interest as
did his occasional loyalty to Athens,
and Plato, though fascinated by him, shows no great respect for his memory. 5 Was Socrates also a Laconizer? We can hardly assume that he belonged to the group of shallow admirers whom Plato satirizes, but the evidence of both Xenophon and Plato shows that he had a high admiration of the Spartans' obedience to their magis6 trates and the laws. But such praise of Sparta had become commonplace by this time.
The only
tophanes, and his testimony
other witness is
we
can
summon
is
Aris-
ambiguous.
There was a Spartan mania, and people went Stalking about the streets, with Spartan staves, two before (Apol. 32b).
probably true that Critias in power "hated" him, as 3 iff-)) Dut if Theramenes had studied philosophy with him, as Diodorus says, he might well have been selected by Theramenes during the early period of the regime. The alternative reading "Isocrates" in Diodorus' text does not seem plausible; for
Xenophon
Isocrates
reports
was
a
It is
(Mem.
ii,
1,
young man
of thirty at this time,
whereas Theramenes was in
his
fifties. 3
See Albert Martin, Les Cavaliers Atheniens, Paris, 1886, 519^. Prot. 342DC; Gorg. 515c 5 The purpose of Alcibiades I (whoever is its author) cannot have been to honor Alcibiades; he appears in a very unpleasing garb of egoism and pretence. In the 4
Symposium
the picture of the
drunken Alcibiades
is
tering. 6
Xen.
Mem.
in, v, 15; iv, iv, 15; Plato Crito
52c
brilliant,
but certainly not
flat-
SPARTA With
their
many
Like so Is this
more than
long hair, unwashed and slovenly,
a
Socrates's.
7
comparison of Socrates' well-known appearance
with the affected austerity of the Laconizers
Clouds Aristophanes attacks Socrates as a
?
We
cannot
say.
In the
scientific disturber of the
and an unscrupulous teacher of rhetoric, but there is no hint of pro-Spartan leanings. Such a charge would hardly jibe with Aristophanes' main indictment; for of all the Greeks the Spartans were the most devoted to the existing order and least likely to take 8 up with the new science and rhetoric. old order
It is
evident that these inquiries into the personal influences that
may have molded any sure
thought do not carry us very
Plato's
result. Plato's interest in
far,
nor to
Sparta can easily be explained on
Eunomia had been the term had become
other grounds.
so often asserted of the Lacedae-
monians that a popular synonym for the Spar9 tan way. Both Herodotus and Thucydides record that at one time the Lacedaemonians had been almost the most lawless of all the Greeks, but at some ancient date (Thucydides puts it in the ninth century) had undergone a drastic reorganization of their lives which 10
had brought about ivvofiia. Almost a century later Aristotle echoes this judgment: as the aim of the physician is to cure, and of the orator to persuade, so the genuine statesman tries to bring about evvofiia, 11 and of this the Lacedaemonian "legislator" is an example. He puts the Lacedaemonian constitution at the head of his list of historical states that
experiences and intellectual qualities
and
Aristotle's, shares their
12
Xenophon, whose personal were so different from Plato's
he thinks worth examination.
admiration of Sparta;
13
so did Plato's
and the orator Lysias, not a man of Athenian birth 14 a loyal Athenian metic. Aristotle's pupil Dicaearchus
rival Isocrates,
but certainly 7
Birds 1281-1283, Frere's trans. Socrates' association, if it be a fact, with Theramenes and the Thirty might indicate only that he advocated a return to the "ancestral constitution," the professed purpose of this group. Cf. Arist. Const. Ath. xxxiv, 3; Xen. Mem. in, v, 14. 8
9
The
on eunomia
Andrewes, in cq xxxii, 1938, 89-102; Victor Ehrenberg, "Eunomia," in Aspects of the Ancient World, Oxford, 1946, 70-95; Wade-Gery, cq xxxviii, 1944, 1-9, 1 15-126; A. W. Gomme, Historical Commentary on Thucydides, Oxford, 1945, 1, 128-131. Herod. 1, 65: ix€re/3aXov cts evvoixirjv', Thuc. 1, 18, 1: rfvvofx-qdrj. literature
is
extensive. See especially
11
Mr.
12
Pol. 1269a 29fT.; cf. 1272b 24-29, 1273b 24-26.
13
Eth. 1102a
Const. Lac.
1
9,
1112b
14.
and passim.
14 Isoc. vii, 61; viii, 95; xii, 41, 109, 2ioff.; Lysias
43
xxxin,
7.
THREE HISTORICAL STATES wrote a
on Spartan laws which
treatise
so pleased the Spartans them-
provided for annual public readings of
selves that they
it.
15
Ephorus
regarded the Spartan constitution as one of the sources from which Zaleucus drew his famed legislation for the Locrians.
16
Of
men of the fourth century, Demosthenes seems one who had nothing good to say of Sparta. But the
all
the
eminent
to
only
chorus of
praise
the
is
continued in
first to
man
state,
Romans
later times.
be the
Polybius praised Lycurgus for being
draw up a mixed constitution, thus anticipating the Rowhich was to him the acme of political wisdom; 17 the
themselves, according to Strabo, held the Spartan constitu-
tion in high honor.
And
18
dramatized the virtues of
Plutarch, that echo of ancient thought,
its
men and
the excellence of
its
laws for
generations of later readers.
This
is
an impressive chorus.
as Oilier thinks,
it is
an
19
If this
picture of Sparta
which
illusion to
is
a "mirage,"
a great variety of ancient
and nonphilosophers alike, were subject. But to make the record complete we should add that this universal acclaim was by no means uncritical, at least not in the early period. The writers of the fifth and fourth centuries, in a better position than observers, philosophers
the later ones to see the reverse of the medallion, are unsparing in their
their
condemnation of certain traits of the Spartans. Herodotus notes 20 susceptibility to bribes. Thucydides points out their secrecy and
dissimulation, their lack of initiative, their harshness to foreigners, their brutality in
combat, and their lack of culture.
with
fairly bristle
critical
women,
of the Spartan
21
Aristotle's pages
comments on the unwholesome
the great inequality of property
influence
among
the
Lacedaemonians, the corruptibility of the ephors, the irresponsibility of the gerontes, and the warlike tendency of their educational sys22
Even Xenophon sorrowfully mentions the respects in which the Spartan harmosts failed to live up to the traditions he had so
tem.
grandly presented. 15
Suidas,
23
It is
Dicaearchus
s.v.
=
only in later times that the "idealization" Fr.
I,
Fritz Wehrli, Die Schule des Aristoteles
Basel, 1944.
De
i,
16
Strabo,
vi,
18
Strabo
ix,
19
For further details see F. Oilier, he Mirage Spartiate, Paris, 1933. Herod, in, 148; Cf. Aristoph. Peace 623-624, and the Delphic oracle reported in
20
i,
8.
ii,
17
Polyb.
vi, 3; cf. Cic.
Rep.
11,
41-42.
39.
Arist. Fr. 544, Rose. 21
Secrecy and dissimulation:
viii, 96, 5;
1, 90, 1-2; v, 68, 2; 74, 3; lack of initiative: 1, 118, 2; injustice to foreigners: in, 93; brutality in combat: n, 67, 4; in, 32, 68;
lack of culture: 22
1,
10, 2; 84, 3.
Pol. 1269b i2-i27ib 19.
23
Xen. Const. Lac. xiv,
u
1-5.
SPARTA which modern
of Sparta occurs
derstand.
The admiration
critics rightly
find
of Plato's contemporaries
it
un-
difficult to
was neither blind
nor uncritical.
was equally
Plato's attitude
The
dialogues contain
a
many
mixture of admiration and criticism.
echoes of the conventional praise of
Sparta for the excellence of her laws and the character of her
citi-
These commonplaces of popular thought are used to good effect the Hippias Major. Spartan concern for the right education of
zens. in
their
young men
since
he admits that the Spartans refused to put their sons under his
is
used to discredit Hippias' claims as a teacher,
(283^). Again Hippias' claim to be able to improve Spartan education is shown to imply that the Spartans are "lawless" {irapaan obvious reductio ad absurdutn otherwise, since vofioc, 285b) education produces evvofxia, they would have wanted to become tutelage
—
—
evvofjLMrepoL
through
his teaching. Similarly in the First Alcibiades
the Spartans are described as possessing the full
(122c)
;
but these virtues are paraded
Alcibiades can as yet
as excellences
make no claim
suggests that Plato (if Plato
is
popular opinion for dramatic
panoply of virtues
to possess,
the author)
is
which the young and the situation
here merely using a
effect.
But there seems to be a serious tribute in the Symposium
"Who would
not prefer," asks Diotima, "to leave behind him, rather
than any children of his
flesh,
Sparta, to be the saviors of
Greece?" There in
is
the offspring that Lycurgus
Lacedaemon and, we can even
left
in
say, of all
also a subtle tribute in the Protagoras, in a passage
which the underlying
satire.
(209/!).
seriousness
veiled, as so often in Plato,
is
Socrates contends that of all the Greeks, the Spartans
by
and the
Cretans have cultivated philosophy the most seriously and for the longest time (342a-343c).
The
irony
is
obvious; the Spartans were
generally regarded as uncultivated (they were even proud of this)
and
as interested
this
pretense
is
only in gymnastics and in military exercises. But
part of their cleverness, says Socrates.
Laconizers into thinking that of gymnastics,
conquer the
rest of the
that
shows
misleads the
they practise boxing and other forms
and wear short cloaks
the Spartans' superiority
dom
if
It
in the Spartan fashion, they can
Greeks, like the Spartans. But the truth is
due to
their
(crocfria)
—not
a wis-
and eloquent discourse, but such some pithy saying, like the "Nothing
itself in fluent
comes out unexpectedly in
wisdom
45
is,
as
in
THREE HISTORICAL STATES Lacedaemonian member
excess" attributed to Chilon, the
Seven Sages.
24
The wisdom meant
cal or intellectual cro(f)La
ment
of education;
superficial
is
of course not the dialecti-
which Plato regards
as the
maxims
that illustrate this
in Excess"; "Excellence
an attempt
crowning achieve-
rather a sturdy moral sense, unpolished by
is
undertone beneath Socrates' irony. as
is
accomplishments, and unaffected by
choice of the
"Nothing
it
here
of the
reflective doubts.
wisdom ("Know Thyself";
Hard") shows
One can
to correct the current
The
clearly the serious
even take
this
passage
misconception about the Spar-
tans which, in exalting their military prowess
and the
efficiency of
their military training, overlooks a deeper source of Spartan strength.
But tory.
Plato's references to the Spartans are
The
by no means
all
25
lauda-
passage in the Protagoras shows that he was not blind to
their lack of intellectual interests.
26
A
more
telling criticism occurs
book of the Republic, the very book in which he gives Sparta the place of honor in his survey of historical states. Here his criticism bears on precisely those qualities of the Lacedaemonians that were most admired, viz. their moral integrity and respect for law. This best of the imperfect states, which is said on two occasions to be exemplified by the Laconian constitution (544c, 545a), is called timocracy, and is characterized by the supremacy of the dvfios, the ambitious, combative, and passionate elements in human nature. Having thrown off the control of reason and intelligence, such a state is in an unstable position between aristocracy and oligarchy. It has some of the institutions of the former, e.g. respect for law and in the eighth
for public officials,
common
meals, military and gymnastic exercises.
and are inclined to war rather than peace (547de). They are covetous of money, and since they But
its
citizens distrust intelligence
cannot indulge their desire openly, they acquire their treasures
and hide them away from the law, as children evade their fathers (548ab). Even if Plato had not explicitly mentioned Sparta, it would be clear enough what state he had in mind; the avarice of the Spartans and the great wealth of gold and silver accumulated by some of them, in spite of the prohibition in the law, made one of secretly
24
makes a point of attributing this saying to Chilon. Diels-Kranz 11, 380. an anticipation of the Laws (630c!), where the Athenian Stranger endeavors to show his Cretan and Lacedaemonian friends that they do not truly understand the intent of their legislators if they regard their laws as designed solely for success 25
Critias It is
in war. 26
Cf. Hipp. Mj. 285cd.
46
SPARTA the juiciest scandals of Plato's time. Plato's readers likely to see a reference to
would
also be
Sparta in the description of oligarchy that
immediately follows. Socrates describes the inequality of wealth in an oligarchy, the restriction of the rights of citizenship to those having a property qualification, and the consequent division of the city
—
two classes, the rich and the poor traits that duplicate those which Aristotle explicitly mentions as grave defects in the Lacedae27 monian constitution. This critical attitude is especially marked in the Laws, particularly in the early books, where the principles are being laid down for the detailed legislation to follow. The Athenian Stranger is obviously into
bent on improving the opportunity presented by his casual encounter
with the two Dorians to examine their laws and probe his com-
Although the conversation remains
panions' opinions about them.
always
at the level of Attic urbanity, the
searching and
ment
and he does not hesitate to pronounce judgcompanions and indirectly upon the laws that they
critical,
against his
are defending.
Athenian's questions are
no young man present," he remarks, "hence the laws freely and no one of us should take offense
"There
we can criticize if we find fault"
is
;
At
(634c, 635a).
Cretan and Spartan laws
Cleinias' interpretation of the
primarily for success in
war
the very outset of the discussion
is
deftly refuted.
You must have misun-
derstood your legislators, says the Athenian, their
war
aim (63od). Peace is
And
which a
state
courage,
which he
is
may
was
a state;
result (628c).
the weakness that results
Your poet Tyrtaeus, who sang the virtues of overlooked the more serious malady against
should protect
part at that (630c)
extolled, ;
if
itself is
(629a-630c). In fact the virtue of
only a part of virtue, and the lowest
he concentrated his attention upon
this virtue,
he neglected the greater part of his task (631a).
interpretation of
name your
this
faction.
the warrior citizen,
say,
you think
good and healthy condition of
the
a worse evil than defeat in battle
you
if
sometimes necessary, but only that peace
from internal
as
is
designed
as
him may be
correct; for although
institutions that develop
courage
—the
And
you can
common
your easily
meals,
gymnastic exercises, the practice of hunting, the secret service, the contests in in 27
endurance of pain
—you have
naming any customs designed Pol. 1270a 15ft., 29ff.; 1307a 35-38.
47
to
difficulty,
and no wonder,
promote temperance (633a-
THREE HISTORICAL STATES 634b).
28
The
forward
when
which
the only thing you put
is
your contribution here, does not really promote temper-
as
ance, but
prohibition of wine,
is
likely to lead to the opposite
restraints are
orderly behavior of
extreme of drunkenness
removed (6373b). You Athenian citizens at the
are shocked
by the
rural Dionysia, but one
of us could equally well criticize the looseness of the Spartan
(637c).
Your common meals and gymnastic
dis-
exercises
women
have brought
great benefit to your state, but they also have disadvantages; they are a source of faction
and they lead
to unnatural love (636bc).
that your institutions are better because battle
is
win
stupid;
it
is
To
say
you can rout your enemies in
the bigger states, not always the better ones,
and subdue their enemies (638ab). In fact your state has the constitution of an armed camp; you have never learned the highest music (666de). This is not blind admiration. Obviously Crete and Sparta figure that
victories
in this dialogue not because Plato thought their constitutions to be
above criticism, but because he considered that they were worth
criti-
For Plato seems never to have abandoned the common judgment of his countrymen that Sparta was "well-governed" (ewo29 Then what was it in the fjiovfjiepr]) as compared with other states. Lacedaemonian laws and in the conduct of the Spartans that Plato and his countrymen held in such high esteem ? Thucydides gives us cizing.
most important part. "Sparta has never had a tyrant (alel aTvpdvvevTos tjv)" he says; "for it is a little more than four centuries, counting to the end of the present war, that the Lacedaemonians have had the same constitution."' This long record of stability would be especially impressive to the conservatives among Plato's countrymen, conscious as they were of the changes that their own constitution had undergone during the same period, and all would be impressed by the record of freedom from faction and tyranny, the twin evils to which the small city-state was by its nature exposed. Factional strife could often be terminated only by the advent of a tyrant to reduce the warring parties, and tyranny
a part of the answer, perhaps the
in turn bred
new enemies and new
divisions in the citizenry. If
Sparta was one of the few Greek states that had been exempt this recurrent cycle of disorder 28 29
during the previous centuries, she
For a similar criticism of Spartan education see Rep. 546c!, 548b. Cf. 635c, 696a, and the tradition, which Plato accepts, that Spartan laws
from Apollo. 30 Thuc. 1,
18,
1.
from
came
SPARTA could not but seem to the other Greeks an outstanding example of a well-ordered
commonwealth,
the
all
and fourth centuries because she
still
more remarkable
in the fifth
retained her hereditary kings,
when kingship had disappeared everywhere else, and kings who were commonly believed to be direct descendants of the two kings
who had
held power at the time of the Dorian conquest.
the sovereignty of law been upheld in Sparta
when
it
had been
intervals, in
on
tated
almost
all
some time or
to
discoveries,
The complement
had
these years,
other, for longer or shorter
but he ventured no opinion in his history.
much thought
most striking
all
How
other cities? Thucydides had probably medi-
this question,
Plato also gave of his
lost at
through
31
and
it,
his reflections led
which we
shall
come
him
to
one
to later.
to this constitutional stability at Sparta
was
a
peculiarly stubborn devotion of the Spartans to their laws. Herodotus,
writing of Xerxes' expedition against Greece in 480, describes the
Spartan Demaratus, then in exile from his native land, as speaking
King about
frankly to the Great
he was about to meet "but not free in
and
Thermopylae. "They are
things.
For the master
they fear (vTrepSeifxalvovo-i) far
this
fear you."
law
their
all
at
the quality of his opponents
32
is
lae.
The
over
men," he
them
is
more than your
subjects
the sentiment immortalized by Simonides in the
famous
who
died at
Thermopy-
Spartans did not always die at their posts; one of the things
Greeks during the Peloponnesian
War was
surrender of the beleaguered Spartan garrison at Pylos.
and shock
tans represented
that this caused
and
to their reputation for living
whose songs had
34
the
But the
testimony to the ideal the Spar-
is
had been memorably expressed for taeus,
the law,
felt for
that shocked the
surprise
says,
This profound fear and respect that the Spartans
epigram composed for these same Spartans 33
set
free
whom
all
up
to
it.
This ideal
Spartans by their poet Tyr-
stiffened their determination
during the long
war with the Messenians and were ever afterward cherished and sung as the best
expression of their conception of civic virtue.
taeus' elegies actually
bore the
to these songs (629a,e) 31
32 33
title
"Eunomia," and
shows that he
is
aware of
One
of Tyr-
Plato's reference
their
importance in
The Gree\ Tyrants, 66ff.; Busolt-Swoboda, 672. Herod, vn, 104. Herod, vn, 228: "Go, stranger, tell the Lacedaemonians that we lie here obedient See Andrewes,
to their 34
commands."
Thuc.
iv, 40.
49
THREE HISTORICAL STATES 35
molding the Spartan character. The ideal Tyrtaeus describes is not that of the Homeric hero, set above the undistinguished mass of his followers and engaged in single combat with an enemy king or chieftain;
who
Tyrtaeus sang the praises of the citizen soldier
stands in the
forefront of the battle, in serried disciplined ranks, his feet firmly
planted apart, determined to conquer or to die for his dren, and his fatherland.
36
sires, his chil-
This ideal of the warrior citizen emerged
Greek world with the rise of hoplite warfare in the seventh century we find it in a fragment of Callinus of Ephesus but it was the Spartans who took it most seriously and adapted
in various parts of the
—
—
their other institutions to
cation
no longer had
tion of
an entire
as its
Henceforth, as Jaeger
aim the
city of heroes.
The impression fellow Greeks
it.
Spartan edu-
selecting of heroes, but the forma-
37
that such well-disciplined heroes reflected in another passage in
is
says,
made upon
their
Thucydides. After
describing the disposition of the opposing forces before the battle of
Mantinea, he mentions briefly the exhortations
made by
the
Man-
and Athenian generals to their respective troops, reminding them of the issues at stake and the prizes to be won by victory. But the Lacedaemonians, he says, reminded themselves individually of the rules of war which they had mastered, secure in the knowledge that long practice in doing things is more conducive to safety than an eloquent speech just before the battle. And in the engagement which follows he describes the Lacedaemonian troops advancing tinean, Argive,
slowly to the sound of flutes "not for reasons of religion, but in order
might march more evenly, and not break their ranks, as so 58 often happens when large armies are advancing." In short, the Spartans were not amateurs in battle; by long and strenuous discipline the individual hoplite had become a conscious and intelligent part of the fighting unit at the disposal of his commander. This military discipline which Thucydides here describes with such manifest admiration, and which made the Spartan hoplites invincible on the battlefield, is but an illustration of the lifelong discipline required of the Spartan citizen. He was a member of a small dominant
that they
35
For an analysis of Plato's use of Tyrtaeus see des Places, "Platon et Tyrtee," in REG LV, 1942, I4-24. 36
Frs.
37
Jaeger, Paideia
11
and
12,
Edmonds.
i25ff. (Eng. trans. 84^.). Thuc. v, 69-70. Plutarch {Lye. 22) gives a similar description (doubtless taken from one of his ancient sources) of the Spartans marching into battle in close formation to the music of the flute. 1,
38
50
SPARTA group in the midst of a subject and hostile population many times larger. Surrounded by enemies who might rise and attack them at any time, the Spartans together
and by
knew
by standing
that they could survive Only
and
ruthlessly subordinating individual interests
ambitions to the good of
all.
Spartans confronted them.
own making. Few
These were the hard
It is
facts of life as the
was
true that the predicament
of their
conquerors in history have been as ruthless as they
were toward the peoples whose lands they took over in Laconia and Messenia.
We
39
can even argue, from the perspective of today, that
would have been had not met their it
But the fact
is,
history they
orous
sort,
far better for the
Greeks
difficult situation
they did meet
it
whole
At some period
in their
successfully.
discipline of the
involving a virtual militarization of
Greeks enjoyed.
It
the Spartans success.
imposed upon themselves a
that other
if
with such undeserved
the cradle to the grave. This discipline
much
as a
was
most
all their life
their "laws." It cost
rig-
from them
required the cultivation of physi-
meant living more frugally than was customary even in Greek states whose soil was much less fertile; it demanded the renunciation of wealth and the acceptance of a certain equality of poverty and hardship. They turned their backs upon the enjoyment of the poetry, science, and art that were flowering throughout the rest of the Greek world at this time. They even stopped taking part in the contests at Olympia; athletic prowess was incompatible with the training of the soldier, and perhaps also a cal
endurance to an incredible degree;
it
dangerous incentive to individual ambition.
gan" laws cost them; and sense
and
their tenacity of
no
40
All this their "Lycur-
hard
social
purpose that they maintained their
disci-
it is
little
tribute to their
pline over themselves for at least four centuries, so
Thucydides be-
lieved.
The supremacy citizens
dently
—these
had
in
are
of law, the courage and political concord of the
what the thoughtful Greeks
mind when
of the Spartans in battle 39
of Plato's time evi-
they praised Spartan eunomia.
was one of its
The
success
striking results ; but admiration
We
is, according to the common account. must admit, however, that evidence regarding what actually happened at the conquest, about the origin of helotage, and even about the status of the Helot in historical times is woefully
That
reliable
scanty. 40
Guy
Dickins, in jhs xxxii, 1912, 18-19; E. N. Gardiner, Gree\ Athletic Sports London, 19 10, 56-59; Andrewes, op.cit. 69-70. For the archaeological evidence, see R. M. Dawkins, ed. The Sanctuary of Artemis Orthia at Sparta, jhs Suppl. Papers 5, 1929.
and
Festivals,
51
— THREE HISTORICAL STATES of the Spartans
was not dependent on
their military success, for this
admiration survived the defeat at Leuctra in 371, and most of the contributors to the chorus of praise cited earlier come after that date. A constitution that could maintain the supremacy of law for so long
and could mold its citizens so efficiently into conformity with the law's demands, certainly had some secrets of wisdom to reveal to the earnest inquirer into politics, as Plato was. What were the causes of this eunomia so manifest among the Lacedaemonians, so frequently lacking elsewhere? To understand Plato we must try to find his answer to this question. a period,
One
educational system at Sparta. His attention to this
first
was the strict directed from the very
of these causes, so Plato undoubtedly thought, is
fundamental feature of Spartan
education in the
first
life;
two books of the Laws takes
the Athenian's inquiry regarding the
common
the discussion of its
departure from
meals, the gymnastic
and the other familiar elements of the Spartan system. Lacedaemon was one of the few Greek states (perhaps the only one, with the exception of Crete), that dealt seriously and systematically with the task of educating its youth. Education was made a primary concern of the state and placed under the supervision and control of the ephors. This was strikingly different from the custom of other cities of Plato's time, where the father alone was responsible for the kind 41 and amount of education that his sons received. Furthermore, the exercises,
Spartan system appeared to be peculiarly
efficient in
producing the
type of character that the Spartans thought the constitution required.
However
might be the Spartan conception of excellence and the discussion in the opening book of the Laws reveals that in Plato's opinion it was decidedly limited it showed what finished results can be obtained when the state has a definite idea of what it wants its citizens to be and pursues this end with vigor and consistlimited
—
ency.
The Spartan system
— the ayooyr),
as
it
came
to be called
—was in-
deed single-minded in its aim and unremitting in its demands, if we 42 can believe the accounts of it given by the ancient authorities. At the age of eight the Spartan boy was taken from his 41
Xen. Const. Lac. n,
42
The most
Educ. of Cyrus,
home and
placed
1337a 3 if. familiar ancient accounts are those in Xenophon's Constitution of 1-2;
1,
ii,
2; Arist. Pol.
the Lacedaemonians and Plutarch's lives of Lycurgus and Agesilaus. For a critical account based on these and other ancient testimonia see Busolt-Swoboda, 694-702.
52
SPARTA with others of his
members
own
age in a band or "herd" (ayeXrj)*
exercised, played, ate,
and
slept together,
3
whose
under the constant
supervision of an older youth, himself under the supervision of his elders.
They went
of food
was kept
was
barefoot, their clothing
to a
minimum,
they
scanty, their allowance
made long marches,
they slept
on beds of rushes, they studied some "letters," but not much, they had athletic and military contests, they danced and sang together. Breaches of discipline were heavily punished; there is no disciplinarian more rigorous than an older boy who has gone through the
and endurance were not the sole purpose of this training. They were taught to be grave in their demeanor, sparing of words, respectful to their elders. They were encouraged to supplement their meager rations by stealing food from the barns and homesteads in the country. This was presumably to cultivate ingenuity and dexterity, for one who was caught in the act, drill
himself. But bodily strength
Above all the boys learned to live not as individuals, but as members of a herd. Year after year this training continued, until at the age of twenty the youth was eligible for military service and received the rights of citizenship. At
Plutarch
tells us,
was
severely punished.
age also the law prescribed that he should marry, but for ten
this
young men of his own age, seeing his wife only by stealth at night when no duties were demanded of him. He was not allowed to go abroad, nor was any foreign teacher of the youth allowed at Sparta. Only at the age of thirty was he free to live in his own house, and even then he conyears longer he continued to live with the
member
tinued to be a
of a "mess" (