Musical Portraits: The Composition of Identity in Contemporary and Experimental Music [Illustrated] 0190653507, 9780190653507

Joshua S. Walden's Musical Portraits: The Composition of Identity in Contemporary and Experimental Music explores t

238 94 16MB

English Pages 200 [201] Year 2018

Report DMCA / Copyright

DOWNLOAD PDF FILE

Table of contents :
Cover
Musical Portraits
Copyright
Dedication
Contents
List of Figures
List of Musical Examples
Acknowledgments
Introduction: Portraiture as a Musical Genre
1. Musical and Literary Portraiture
2. Musical Portraits of Visual Artists
3. Listening in on Composers’ Self-​Portraits
4. Celebrity, Music, and the Multimedia Portrait
Epilogue: Musical Portraiture, the Posthumous, and the Posthuman
Bibliography
Index
Recommend Papers

Musical Portraits: The Composition of Identity in Contemporary and Experimental Music [Illustrated]
 0190653507, 9780190653507

  • 0 0 0
  • Like this paper and download? You can publish your own PDF file online for free in a few minutes! Sign Up
File loading please wait...
Citation preview

  i

Musical Portraits

ii

  iii

Musical Portraits The Composition of Identity in Contemporary and Experimental Music Joshua S. Walden

1

iv

1 Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and certain other countries. Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America. © Oxford University Press 2018 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above. You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer. Library of Congress Cataloging-​in-​Publication Data Names: Walden, Joshua S., 1979– author. Title: Musical portraits : the composition of identity in contemporary and   experimental music / Joshua S. Walden. Description: New York, NY : Oxford University Press, [2018] |   Includes bibliographical references and index. Identifiers: LCCN 2017020694 | ISBN 9780190653507 (hardcover : alk. paper) |   ISBN 9780190653521 (epub) Subjects: LCSH: Characters and characteristics in music. | Music—20th   century—History and criticism. Classification: LCC ML197 .W36 2018 | DDC 781.5/9—dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2017020694 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Printed by Sheridan Books, Inc., United States of America

  v

To Judy Schelly, Mike Walden, and Danny Walden

vi

I drew men’s faces on my copy-​books, Scrawled them within the antiphonary’s marge, Joined legs and arms to the long music-​notes, Found eyes and nose and chin for A’s and B’s. —Robert Browning, “Fra Lippo Lippi,” in Charlotte Porter and Helen A. Clarke (eds.), Poems of Robert Browning (New York: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1896), 127–​8.

  vii

CO N T E N T S

List of Figures   ix List of Musical Examples   xi Acknowledgments  xiii Introduction: Portraiture as a Musical Genre   1 1. Musical and Literary Portraiture   22 2. Musical Portraits of Visual Artists   55 3. Listening in on Composers’ Self-​Portraits   81 4. Celebrity, Music, and the Multimedia Portrait   109 Epilogue: Musical Portraiture, the Posthumous, and the Posthuman   143 Bibliography  161 Index  177

viii

  ix

L IST O F F I G UR E S

I.1  Charles Demuth, “The Figure 5 in Gold,” 1928, oil on cardboard, 35-​1/​2 x 30 inches. The Metropolitan Museum of Art, Alfred Stieglitz Collection, 1949 (49.59.1). Image © The Metropolitan Museum of Art.   7 I.2  Katherine Dreier, “Abstract Portrait of Marcel Duchamp,” 1918, oil on canvas, 18 x 32 inches. Museum of Modern Art. Digital Image © The Museum of Modern Art/​Licensed by SCALA/ Art Resource, NY.   8 1.1  Pablo Picasso, “Gertrude Stein,” 1905–​1906, oil on canvas, 39-​3/​8 x 32 inches. © 2016 Estate of Pablo Picasso/​Artists Rights Society (ARS), New York. Image copyright © The Metropolitan Museum of Art. Image source: Art Resource, NY.   27 1.2  Buffie Johnson, “Portrait of Virgil Thomson,” 1963, oil on Masonite, 23-​3/​4 x 19-​1/​2 inches. Used by permission of the University of Missouri-​Kansas City Libraries, Dr. Kenneth J. LaBudde Department of Special Collections. Additional permission granted by Jenny J. Sykes.   33 2.1  Willem de Kooning, “Woman, I,” 1950–​1952, oil on canvas, 6 feet 3-​7/​8 x 58 inches. © 2016 The Willem de Kooning Foundation/​ Artists Rights Society (ARS), New York. Digital Image © The Museum of Modern Art/​Licensed by SCALA/​Art Resource, NY.   67 2.2  Chuck Close, “Phil,” 1969, acrylic on canvas, 108 x 84 inches. © Chuck Close, courtesy Pace Gallery.   70 2.3  Chuck Close, “Phil,” 2011–​2012, oil on canvas, 108-​5/​8 x 84 inches. © Chuck Close, courtesy Pace Gallery.   73 3.1  Brother Rufillus, Initial R, from a Passionale from Weissenau Abbey, c. 1170–​1200, Cod. Bodmer 127, f. 244r. Fondation Martin Bodmer, Cologny (Geneva).   82

x

( x )   List of Figures

3.2  Eugène Atget, “Coiffeur, Palais Royal,” 1927, albumen silver print (gold-​toned), 7 x 9-​1/​2 inches. Museum of Modern Art. Digital Image © The Museum of Modern Art/​Licensed by SCALA/​Art Resource, NY.   83 3.3  Richard Hamilton, “A Portrait of the Artist by Francis Bacon,” 1970–​1971, collotype and screenprint, 32-​3/​8 x 27-​3/​8 inches. © R. Hamilton. All Rights Reserved, DACS and ARS 2016. Image copyright © The Metropolitan Museum of Art. Image source: Art Resource, NY.   89 3.4  Kazimir Malevich, “Suprematism: Self-​Portrait in Two Dimensions,” 1915, oil on canvas, 31-​1/​2 x 24-​3/​8 inches. Stedelijk Museum. Art Resource, NY.   92 3.5  John Baldessari, “Beethoven’s Trumpet (With Ear) Opus # 133,” 2007, foam, resin, aluminum, cold bronze, and electronics, 84 x 120 x 84 inches. Courtesy of the artist and Marian Goodman Gallery.  96 4.1  Robert Wilson and Tom Waits, “Robert Downey Jr.,” 2004, video. Courtesy RW Work Ltd.   117 4.2  Robert Wilson and Michael Galasso, “Winona Ryder,” 2004, video. Courtesy RW Work Ltd.   118 4.3  Robert Wilson and Philip Glass, “Knee Play 1” from Einstein on the Beach, 2012–​2014 revival production. Courtesy of BAM Hamm Archives and the Robert Wilson Archives and the Byrd Hoffman Water Mill Foundation. © Lucie Jansch.   132 4.4  Robert Wilson and Philip Glass, “Knee Play 5” from Einstein on the Beach, 2012–​2014 revival production. Courtesy of BAM Hamm Archives and the Robert Wilson Archives and the Byrd Hoffman Water Mill Foundation. © Lucie Jansch.   133 E.1  Kim Novak in Vertigo, directed by Alfred Hitchcock, Paramount Pictures, 1958.   145 E.2  Robert Wilson and Bernard Herrmann, “Princess Caroline,” 2006, video. Courtesy RW Work Ltd.   149

  xi

L IST O F M U SIC A L E X A M P L E S

1.1  Virgil Thomson, “Miss Gertrude Stein as a Young Girl,” 1928, mm. 1–​11.   31 1.2  Virgil Thomson, “Buffie Johnson: Drawing Virgil Thomson in Charcoal,” 1981, mm. 1–​6.   34 1.3  Virgil Thomson, “Buffie Johnson: Drawing Virgil Thomson in Charcoal,” 1981, mm. 20–​4.   34 2.1  Morton Feldman, “de Kooning,” first page. Copyright © 1963 by C. F. Peters Corporation. All Rights Reserved. Used by permission.  64 4.1  Philip Glass, “Knee Play 1,” from Einstein on the Beach, premiered 1976, organ 1 part, first measure.   132 4.2  Philip Glass, “Knee Play 2,” from Einstein on the Beach, premiered 1976, solo violin part, rehearsal 3.   132 E.1  Bernard Herrmann, Carlotta’s leitmotif, from Vertigo, 1958, dir. Alfred Hitchcock. David Cooper, Bernard Herrmann’s Vertigo: A Film Score Handbook (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 2001), 20.   146

xii

  xii

AC KNOWL E DG M E N T S

I am thankful to Alessandra Aquilanti, Andrea Bohlman, Christopher Doll, Walter Frisch, Sharon Levy, Michael Maul, Laura Protano-​Biggs, Hollis Robbins, David Smooke, and Andrew Talle for the friendship and support they offered at various stages of my work on this project. This book received support from the Manfred Bukofzer Endowment of the American Musicological Society, funded in part by the National Endowment for the Humanities and the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation. I want to acknowledge the insightful editorship of Suzanne Ryan and to thank Andrew Maillet, Victoria Kouznetsov, and the rest of the Oxford University Press staff who helped with the production of this book. Peering back further, I am grateful to the instructor who taught me the most about art and assured it would always be a source of fascination for me, Michele Metz. Whenever I visit a museum I still remember her lessons vividly as I come across the artworks she discussed in her class, and I am sure those lectures played no small part in the generation of this project. Most importantly, as always, the deepest thanks are owed to my family. The education I have received from my parents and brother in music, art, and literature has profoundly shaped the way I think about the world, and no one can be more helpful than they are, as interlocutors, sounding-​boards, editors, and collaborators. It has been great fun to share this project with them.

xiv

  1

Introduction Portraiture as a Musical Genre The artist’s work is to show us ourselves as we really are. Our minds are nothing but this knowledge of ourselves; and he who adds a jot to such knowledge creates new mind as surely as any woman creates new men. —​George Bernard Shaw1

“A

h guarda, sorella,” sings the love-​struck Fiordiligi to her sister  Dorabella in the first act of Mozart and Da Ponte’s opera Così fan tutte (1790). In a lilting, circling melody, she repeats, “Guarda, guarda”—​“Look, look.” Both sisters wear portrait miniatures of their beaux about their necks. Fiordiligi gazes admiringly at the portrait of her beloved Guglielmo, but convincing her sister to look will mean distracting the impulsive Dorabella from the miniature portrait of Ferrando over which she is swooning. Fiordiligi doubts one can find a finer mouth or nobler countenance than those depicted in the portrait she beholds: she sees “the face of a soldier and a lover.” This characterization comes across in the orchestral accompaniment as well, his strength in the dotted rhythms rising in a major arpeggio, his amorousness in the suddenly languorous and melismatic singing style that follows. For her part, Dorabella is preoccupied by the depiction of her lover’s eyes, which seem to shoot flames and darts at her. She sees in her portrait “a face attractive but forbidding,” characteristics conveyed musically by the sudden change to minor and the ensuing anxious motivic repetition, an aroused turn to the Sturm und Drang style. Portraiture depicts aspects of our selves that are available to the senses, but it also proposes elements of our reality that we might not otherwise recognize so readily. It can reveal features of the human self that are hidden

2

( 2 )   Musical Portraits

beyond plain view, but it can additionally convince us of attributes of identity that are pure fabrication. If the opera had opened with this duet, we might be persuaded that the portraits tell the truth about the subjects they depict, or at least that these young women’s interpretations of what they see in their miniatures can be believed. But we met the young men they describe during the previous scene, in which, drunk and impetuous, they argued over which of them inspired the more intense devotion in his lover, and devised a plan to test Fiordiligi and Dorabella’s constancy by dressing as Albanians and trying to seduce one another’s sweethearts. Can these be the strong and reputable youths whose respective noble face and fiery eyes are depicted in their portraits? The young women’s duet derives its ironic depiction of loving idolization from the friction between perception and truth, symbolized simply but potently by the unreliability of portraits and the pitfalls of believing in the accuracy of their representations. The sisters’ vocal lines also reveal music’s ability to conjure aspects of character, bearing, and social status in a way that reflects the representational power of visual art: Mozart’s text setting and instrumental writing during this number mirror the portraits’ images as described by the two young women, evoking the series of affects about which they sing through the juxtaposition of musical gestures, textures, and topics. One can almost picture in the imagination the miniatures the women gaze at through the descriptions presented in the poetry and music. This operatic scene demonstrates how music, in combination with language, can be devised to fashion an impression of human identity. Like the miniatures that hang from the necks of Fiordiligi and Dorabella, Mozart’s musical portrayal of their lovers employs well-​known sonic tropes that serve as metaphors to depict qualities of respectability, moral strength, and maturity that both the young men and the young women would like to believe reflect the truth about their characters. But members of the audience—​along with the philosopher Don Alfonso and the maid Despina, the characters who join together to put the couples’ affection through a series of trials over the course of the narrative—​know these musical and poetic interpretations of the miniature portraits to be exaggerated and false. To recognize the music as ironic, we have to see the conflict between the way the men are represented in the first scene and the musical construction of their identities here. In this manner Mozart’s opera shows that the representations of individuals that emerge from the mixture of sound and words must always be viewed as subjective constructions rather than objective mirrors of reality. This book is about musical portraiture, a genre of compositions that operate as musical evocations of aspects of individual identities in the manner of portraits in the visual arts and literature. Musical portraits have been

  3

I n t ro d u c t i o n    ( 3 )

written in a variety of forms, from the eighteenth-​century keyboard miniature to the twentieth-​century portrait opera and beyond. With no other definitive distinguishing features, such works require the aid of a title or other manner of description by the composer in order to be identified as portraits. The genre emerged in the early 1700s with works by François Couperin (1668–​1733) and Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach (1714–​1788) and has remained of interest to composers through the present day, as a means of creating sonic depictions of patrons, family members, friends, and historical figures.2 Portraiture in music has proven a more complex and even elusive enterprise than portraiture in painting or sculpture, for obvious reasons: in the absence of a means of depicting physical appearance, an element of portraiture in the visual arts that is commonly considered essential, composers have grappled with the question of how music can convey attributes of identity other than appearance in such a way that listeners will construe the composition to represent an individual. The musical portrait invites interpretation, as the listener, inspired by the composition, constructs in the imagination an impression of the work’s human subject. Musical portraiture therefore evinces a particularly self-​conscious, interactive form of representation, in which a piece’s sounds and structures, in conjunction with a title identifying it as a portrait, are assembled by the composer and performer and heard by the listener to evoke abstract attributes of identity such as character, personality, social status, and profession. The second half of the twentieth century and the start of the twenty-​first have brought compelling developments to the genre of visual portraiture, as Western conceptions of identity have altered in parallel with increasing challenges to the predominance of mimesis in artistic representation. This book investigates the ways such recent debates over the nature of the self inform our understanding of music’s capacity to represent human identity by considering works of musical portraiture composed since 1950. Indeed, while composers have created musical portraits with some regularity since the early development of the genre, the contemporary focus in the arts on challenging traditional modes of representation has provoked increasing numbers of composers to experiment with the representation of personal identity in music and in multimedia combinations of sound, text, and image. The subjects of the musical portraits examined in this book are principally artists in the fields of literature, painting, composition, and performance. By looking in particular at musical portraits of authors and artists as well as composers’ self-​portraits, the case studies in each chapter explore the complex relationships among musical, visual, and linguistic modes of depicting human identity. This introduction offers a brief history

4

( 4 )   Musical Portraits

of visual and musical portraiture and a discussion of modes of representation in music. It then examines how the musical portrait operates as a narrative construction of an identity or self. Finally, it closes with an overview of the structure of this book’s exploration of contemporary musical portraiture. LIKENESS, IDENTIT Y, AND METAPHOR IN PORTRAITURE

Portraiture in the visual arts typically assumes the representation of physical likeness, the fixing for posterity of a person’s appearance in a single moment of life. Highlighting this function of the genre, the early modern art theorist Leon Battista Alberti wrote in his 1435 treatise On Painting: “Painting contains a divine force which not only makes absent men present . . . but moreover makes the dead seem almost alive. . . . Thus the face of a man who is already dead certainly lives a long life through painting.”3 The notion of the portrait as fixing a life in spite of human mortality is the focus of the 1850 short story “The Oval Portrait” by Edgar Allan Poe, which describes the creation of a portrait of a lively young woman that hangs on the wall of an abandoned chateau. The woman had fallen in love with the painter, whose devotion to his craft so distracts him that over the course of sitting for the portrait she becomes increasingly jealous of his attentions. After completing his last brush stroke and standing back to look at the finished portrait, the artist “grew tremulous and very pallid, and aghast, and crying with a loud voice,” he exclaimed, “This is indeed Life itself!” He then turns to discover, to his horror, that as he painted her portrait, his beloved has died.4 The artist who preserves a life for posterity, in Poe’s imagination, and in a reversal of the dynamic Alberti describes, renders that life absent in the present.5 Artists and critics have long remarked that the representation that captures an individual life in portraiture for eternity requires more than simply the reproduction of physical likeness: the portrait must convey a sense of a sitter’s character, understood to include such aspects as personality, social position, and profession.6 Thus even in the ancient world, the Greek historian Plutarch praised Lysippos—​the artist of the fourth century bce known as the “father of Hellenistic sculpture” for his bronze representations of Alexander the Great that combined physical idealization with the depiction of their subject’s individuality—​for bronzes that “preserve [Alexander’s] manly and leonine quality” and in so doing “brought out his real character . . . and gave form to his essential excellence.”7

  5

I n t ro d u c t i o n    ( 5 )

Identity is thus viewed as related to but not defined by the body; as the analytic philosopher Bernard Williams puts it, “Identity of body is at least not a sufficient condition of personal identity.”8 The successful portrait exceeds the mere representation of the body: it allows the viewer to infer a broader and multidimensional conception of the invisible aspects of the sitter’s subjectivity. As Paul Klee wrote of his portraiture in his diary in 1901, “I am not here to reflect the surface . . . but must penetrate inside. My mirror probes down to the heart. . . . My human faces are truer than the real ones.”9 The use of portraiture to represent interior identity rather than simply to mimic external appearance can be understood as a form of aesthetic realism, even as it involves the development of techniques for depicting something invisible to the eye. Indeed, a portrait that fails to define the sitter’s character is likely to be criticized as untruthful or incomplete, no matter how precise its likeness. In her first novel, Adam Bede (1859, rev. 1861), George Eliot (Mary Ann Evans) sets forth her conception of the importance of creating portraits of characters in all their complexity: she imagines a hypothetical reader asking why she has represented her characters as flawed individuals, and responds by explaining that her task is not to idealize “life and character entirely after my own liking,” but “to give a faithful account of men and things as they have mirrored themselves in my mind.”10 To describe this literary technique she raises the analogy of paintings of the Dutch Golden Age, with their focus on the realistic depiction of the appearance, character, and daily activities of the working classes. Though she does not call for the wholesale rejection of “the divine beauty of form,” she writes, But let us love that other beauty too, which lies in no secret of proportion, but in the secret of deep human sympathy. Paint us an angel, if you can, with a floating violet robe, and a face paled by the celestial light . . . but do not impose on us any aesthetic rules which shall banish from the region of Art those old women scraping carrots with their work-​worn hands, those heavy clowns taking holiday in a dingy pot-​house, those rounded backs and stupid weather-​beaten faces that have bent over the spade and done the rough work of the rough curs, and their clusters of onions. . . . It is so needful we should remember their existence, else we may happen to leave them quite out of our religion and philosophy, and frame lofty theories which only fit a world of extremes. Therefore let Art always remind us of them.11

In this passage, Eliot proposes that the artist has an ethical responsibility to represent the faces of ordinary people, and to do so in a way that favors the truthful depiction of interior life over the idealization of external appearance.

6

( 6 )   Musical Portraits

Eliot makes this distinction with regard to literature and painting, but it informs our study of portraiture in music as well, and in many of the portraits examined in the following three chapters of this book, composers explore ways to represent in music, without idealization, the interior lives of their subjects.12 The fourth chapter, on the other hand, views the influence of visual idealization, as found in images of military and political leaders and in celebrity and fashion photography, on contemporary portraiture in musical multimedia. Taking to its extreme this notion of portraiture as the art of depicting a person’s internal character, a number of artists in the early twentieth century began to experiment with the elimination of literal likeness in portraiture, developing innovative methods of representing individuals without relying on realistic visual mimesis, and thus expanding and challenging the traditional boundaries implied by standard definitions of the genre.13 For example, Pablo Picasso engaged the techniques of cubism to deconstruct his sitters’ bodies, and Francis Bacon painted images of sitters with their faces and bodies contorted, often beyond recognition. Charles Demuth’s portrait of William Carlos Williams titled “The Figure 5 in Gold” (1928) depicts words and images from Williams’s poetry rather than a likeness of his face to represent his identity (Figure I.1), while Katherine Dreier’s “Abstract Portrait of Marcel Duchamp” (1918) abandons pictorialism altogether to offer an abstract, fragmented representation of her subject (Figure I.2).14 In these works portraiture becomes a sort of game, in which the viewer is invited to interpret the relationship between various symbolic or abstract elements of the image and the named subject it is said to represent.15 Such developments in portraiture in the visual arts provide a model for describing how composers have experimented with depicting human subjects through music. In a manner reflective of cubism and other abstract modes of painting, composers of musical portraits have represented their sitters through musical elements such as form, rhythm, harmony, and style. Where portrait painters rely on visual art’s stasis to fix a moment for posterity, however, composers of musical portraits often take advantage of the temporal aspect of their medium as well. This allows them to create portraits that render their subjects’ character and life experiences from various perspectives and unfolding through time—​for example by using narrative techniques to portray events in their subjects’ biographies, or evoking a succession of affects to convey the development of character. The musical portraits of artists known for their work in various media that are discussed in this book also depict the subjects identified in their titles by suggesting affinities with qualities of their own works of portraiture in the visual arts, literature, and

  7

I n t ro d u c t i o n    ( 7 )

Figure I.1:  Charles Demuth, “The Figure 5 in Gold,” 1928, oil on cardboard, 35-​1/​2 x 30 inches. The Metropolitan Museum of Art, Alfred Stieglitz Collection, 1949 (49.59.1). Image © The Metropolitan Museum of Art.

music. These portraits call attention to analogies between musical and other aesthetic means of representation, especially through metaphors that associate what we hear with what we see. In all artistic media, portraiture is a genre that relies inherently on met­ aphor. Until the more recent era of abstraction in visual portraiture, works in the genre, including those that idealize their sitters’ likenesses, have traditionally depended on the standard metaphor that the body is a container for whatever one believes it is that makes an individual unique—​the soul, the self, character, personality, identity, or some other entity. As Richard

8

( 8 )   Musical Portraits

Figure I.2: Katherine Dreier, “Abstract Portrait of Marcel Duchamp,” 1918, oil on canvas, 18 x 32 inches. Museum of Modern Art. Digital Image © The Museum of Modern Art/​Licensed by SCALA/​Art Resource, NY.

Leppert writes, “Challenged to make identity visible .  .  . portraits must ‘employ’ the physical body as the proving ground of the soul, since the body is the only available terrain onto which the nonphysical can be visualized.”16 Wittgenstein suggests a similar point in his aphorism, “The human body is the best picture of the human soul.”17 According to this understanding, portraits represent “outer” attributes of physical appearance such as facial expression, posture, gesture, and physical bearing as signs of invisible “inner” aspects of identity. The notion that the appearance of the body offers a representation of what lies “on the inside” has been long-​standing in the discourse about portraiture. In a passage from The Memorabilia (fourth century bce), Xenophon recounts Socrates’s lesson to a sculptor: “Must not the threatening look in the eyes of fighters be accurately represented, and the triumphant expression on the face of conquerors be imitated? . . . It follows, then, that the sculptor must represent in his figures the activities of the soul.”18 In the late seventeenth century, the influential artist and art theorist Charles le Brun, who held the title of Premier Peintre du Roi at the court of Louis XIV, explains his view that facial expression (in the words of a 1701 translation) “is that which describes the true Characters of Things. . . . The external Characters, are certain Signs of the Affections of the Soul; so that by the Form of every Creature may be known its Humours and Temper.”19 In his 1753 treatise The Analysis of Beauty, William Hogarth, acknowledging his debt to le Brun, similarly writes, “It is by the natural and unaffected movements of the muscles, caused by the passions of the mind, that every man’s character would in some measure be written in his face.”20 The visible quality

  9

I n t ro d u c t i o n    ( 9 )

of facial expression, according to le Brun and Hogarth, makes apparent the combination of passions that combine to form a person’s internal self.21 Even as notions of what constitutes the self—​the passions, the humors, character, inherent qualities, or constructed elements of identity—​have changed over the centuries, this basic premise has remained largely intact. The metaphorical power of portraiture to dissect the body, to investigate its external aspects to find the self that lies underneath the surface, can be a source of self-​consciousness and anxiety for the sitter. Susan Sontag writes that in posing for photographs she experiences the distance between body and soul, the space between her physical appearance and her interior self, especially acutely: “Immobilized for the camera’s scrutiny, I feel the weight of my facial mask, the jut and fleshiness of my lips, the spread of my nostrils, the unruliness of my hair. I experience myself as behind my face, looking through the windows of my eyes, like the prisoner in the iron mask in Dumas’s novel.”22 But it is also precisely because identity is thought to reside beneath the surface, mapped onto but also hidden by the outward, visible aspect of the individual, that portraiture can operate without conveying physical likeness at all. Although musical portraits, as well as abstract visual portraits of the twentieth century such as Demuth’s painting of Williams and Dreier’s of Duchamp, do not depict physical likeness, they still rely on the metaphoric conception of an individual’s identity as interior, available to the senses through artistic representation and interpretation. Metaphors factor heavily in the ways music, like identity, is described in Western cultures, and these metaphors are typically brought into play in musical portraiture’s representations. Music is often conceptualized metaphorically through reference to qualities associated with physical movement, language, the visual, and other domains of human experience.23 More than simply descriptive tropes or figures of speech, such metaphors are defining concepts in cultural modes of understanding music, and contribute to how sound is perceived in relation to other aspects of aesthetic contemplation, physical and social experience, and cultural notions of one’s place in the world.24 In the musical portrait, the metaphorical concepts that govern the understanding of both the human individual and the musical work interact and combine. For example, the twin metaphors of the piece of music as a container for the composer’s ideas and the body as a container for the self overlap in the case of the musical portrait, so that the expressive and emotional content of the composition are understood to depict the corresponding attributes of the person being represented. In this way, for instance, the structure of the piece may be used to outline ordered aspects of the subject’s

10

( 10 )   Musical Portraits

biography, in a manner that depends in part on the metaphors of both music and life as types of narrative. The metaphors that help form the understanding of music by relating it to visual art also play an important role in the depiction of the musical portrait’s subject. Though arguably those musical elements typically characterized as “lines,” “shapes,” “colors,” and “textures” are rarely combined in the imagination into anything resembling physical likeness, they can map onto the way we employ visual metaphors in understanding human character as embodying varying degrees of color, vibrancy, darkness, hard and soft edges, and so forth. For example, a piece described as colorful—​ perhaps because it incorporates a variety of contrasting timbral or “tone color” effects—​might be understood to convey a portrait subject’s “colorful” personality. Paying critical attention to the connections we make between sound and sight helps to reveal what Simon Shaw-​Miller calls the “close and porous mutual surfaces” between musical and visual art forms that are too often treated as entirely distinct.25 Adapting philosopher Jerrold Levinson’s approach, in the essay “Hybrid Art Forms” (1984), to works of art that correlate different media types through processes of juxtaposition, synthesis, and transformation, Shaw-​Miller proposes the study of the hybrid arts as a way to reveal the rich interactions between music and the visual.26 Indeed, the appreciation of music often entails a visual dimension, one that involves the image of the human body, particularly that of the performer. Leppert explains, “Whatever else music is ‘about,’ it is inevitably about the body; music’s aural and visual presence constitutes both a relation to and a representation of the body.”27 Because many listeners are conditioned to associate the sounds of music with the appearance—​present or imagined—​of the body of the performer, and with human form and movement more generally, music operates particularly effectively as a medium in the construction of individual identities in portraiture, even if it is incapable of reproducing detailed physical likeness.28 Of course viewing art, like listening to music, also brings us in touch with the human body; while the sonic and visual arts are distinct in many fundamental ways, physical and psychological aspects of perception in both fields also overlap. In particular, although it may seem intuitive to describe music as temporal and gestural and visual art as static in time and space, the appreciation of visual art, like the experience of music, in fact also involves physical movement and gesture, as we reposition ourselves before an artwork to see it from different angles, move our eyes across its surface, and experience it in time, shifting our perspective from one area to another to observe different aspects of the image’s construction and narrative.29 Furthermore, we might infer from brush strokes and other elements of the canvas the

  1

I n t ro d u c t i o n    ( 11 )

motions that were made by the artist during the creation of the painting, much as we interpret the physical gestures of musicians when attending a performance or imagine them when listening to a recording, and such perception of the artist’s movements in any medium can influence the interpretation of the content and subject of the work.30 CONSTRUCTING THE CONTEMPORARY SELF IN MUSIC

The philosopher Jerrold Seigel writes that the Western conception of the self consists of three principal components: the bodily, or physical existence; the relational, deriving from social interaction and cultural contexts; and the reflective, the capacity to examine and question oneself.31 Of course, conceptions of what constitutes these three aspects of human identity have varied considerably over time, and conventions in both visual and musical portraiture have developed in parallel. According to the modern view, whose origins are found in the Renaissance, the self entails a coherent entity associated with notions of autonomy and free will; it is this isolated self that characterizes people as separate individuals with unique identities.32 With the postwar perspectives introduced by deconstructionist critique and the new understandings of identity developed by proponents of postcolonialism, gender, sexuality, ethnicity, race, and other modern schools of thought, the self came generally to be recognized as fragmented and mutable, and as formed discursively through social interaction, rather than unified and fixed at a single point of emergence.33 Madan Sarup writes, “Identity in postmodern thought is not a thing; the self is necessarily incomplete, unfinished—​it is ‘the subject in process.’ ”34 If the self is constructed, it is also performed and interpreted: individuals adopt certain actions in public that will express corresponding aspects of character, and onlookers interpret these behaviors to combine in the impression of an identity.35 In portraiture, the artist constructs an identity on the canvas, generally by representing physical appearance, but the subject posing for the image may also play a role in this construction through an act of performance that aims to depict the self. Roland Barthes describes his behavior when he is photographed as involving a self-​conscious sort of performance: I decide to “let drift” over my lips and in my eyes a faint smile which I mean to be “indefinable,” in which I  might suggest, along with the qualities of my nature, my amused consciousness of the whole photographic ritual: I lend myself to the social game, I pose,

12

( 12 )   Musical Portraits

I know I am posing, I want you to know that I am posing, but (to square the circle) this additional message must in no way alter the precious essence of my individuality: what I am, apart from my effigy. What I want, in short, is that my (mobile) image, buffeted among a thousand shifting photographs, altering with situation and age, should always coincide with my (profound) “self ”; but it is the contrary that must be said: “myself ” never coincides with my image.36

For Barthes, this performance, however superficial it might seem in its predication on the “social game” of image-​making, depends on positioning his external qualities to provide a view of the identity that resides deep within himself, under the surface. That the image that results is never sufficiently neutral to be entirely true to his identity is a necessary shortcoming of representation. Kenneth Gergen argues that the postmodern view of identity is not “the result of our ‘personal essence’ ” but the product of “how we are constructed in various social groups. . . . As a category of ‘real self ’ continues to recede from view, however, one acquires a pastiche-​like personality.”37 This definition of identity, which overlaps with fundamental aspects of the standard understanding of postmodernism itself, is characterized by polyvocality:  rather than being guided by a unique, personal voice, our identities, according to this view, are tuned to parallel streams of the voices of those around us and the constant drone of contemporary media, and this leads to a fragmentation and decentering of identity.38 Identity is also viewed as malleable and transient, constantly being reconstructed and presented in new ways through social interaction, and therefore lacking in coherence.39 Our understanding of our selves and the world in which we live is rooted in our relationships with others.40 The self is therefore founded in creative acts occurring within the contexts provided by one’s social, cultural, and political surroundings.41 Invoking Shakespeare’s line “all the world’s a stage,” Olav Bryant Smith writes, “What is equally true, and more fundamental, is that we are coauthors of the very plays in which we act.”42 The contemporary understanding of identity as multivalent, mediated, perpetually under construction, and open to varied interpretation has posed certain challenges to traditional modes of representing subjectivity in portraiture. Such complexity is conveyed in Calvin O. Schrag’s description of the philosophical project he undertakes in his book The Self after Postmodernity, which he describes in the introduction through the metaphor of “sketching a portrait of the human self ”: There is first the obvious truth that we are dealing not with a single, unitary, sharply defined portrait, but rather with a portrait that is itself curiously diversified. What thus appears to be at issue is a multiplicity of profiles and perspectives through which the

  13

I n t ro d u c t i o n    ( 13 )

human self moves and is able to come into view. . . . There is, however, another set of obstacles facing the projected undertaking. This has to do with the very grammar of portraits or profiles or perspectives. It is a grammar that invites a philosophical optics bent upon the field of vision as somehow privileged for the disclosure of self and world. But knowledge of self is as much the rendering of an account, the telling of a story, as it is the discernment of perceptual profiles—​and indeed it is the telling of a story in which the self is announced as at once actor and receiver of action. . . . I thus propose a metaphorical extension of the grammar of portraits, profiles, or perspectives to include the telling and hearing of stories and the performance and reception of action.43

The contemporary understanding of identity and the self has permitted artists to use more abstract means to represent individual subjects in a host of media. It has also made a space in the field of portraiture for the representational techniques of music, whose temporal aspect permits a narrative quality and whose reliance on performance requires an active and discursive process of creating meaning, reflecting Schrag’s call for “the telling and hearing of stories and the performance and reception of action” in the postmodern “grammar of portraits.” Composers of musical portraits typically construct representations of identities by selecting and depicting individual aspects of the sitter’s life, such as biographical experiences, artistic style, and emotional traits, in ways that reflect how we tell stories in the construction of our own characters. It is common to define identity through the selection and retelling of stories, creating what has been called a “narrative self.”44 Marya Schechtman argues, in her theory of what she calls the “narrative self-​construction view”: At the core of this view is the assertion that individuals constitute themselves as persons by coming to think of themselves as persisting subjects who have had experience in the past and will continue to have experience in the future, taking certain experiences as theirs. Some, but not all, individuals weave stories of their lives, and it is their doing so which makes them persons. On this view a person’s identity . . . is constituted by the content of her self-​narrative, and the traits, actions, and experiences included in it are, by virtue of that inclusion, hers.45

Though Schechtman is writing primarily about the way individuals construct their own identities through narrative, these principles apply to much portraiture as well, particularly in music, with its temporal dimension that permits the weaving of a narrative over a period of time.46 John Berger, who similarly invokes the value of looking forward and backward in the description of a life and identity, also links this sort of storytelling to portraiture: “Drawing a face is one way of noting down a biography. Good portraits are both prophetic and retrospective.”47

14

( 14 )   Musical Portraits

It has become a common observation among sociologists of music and media that music is used every day as a tool of identity construction, a process viewed as both social and narrative.48 One reason music operates effectively through composition and performance as a tool in the construction of identities in portraiture is that we are conditioned in our daily lives to consider music an important element in the social construction of our own sense of self as well as in the interpretation of other people’s identities. In the compositions under examination in this book, music is used to represent the self through a creative act of aesthetic construction; and the final product, the musical portrait, is a work of music that permits further reconstructions through the hermeneutic processes of performance and listening. THE CONTENTS OF THIS STUDY

Musical Portraits views works in the genre of musical portraiture composed after 1950 as representations of human identities that privilege a view of the self as socially and narratively constructed and changing through time. The mode of representation in the musical portrait relies principally on metaphors that draw connections between music and language, the visual, and aspects of human character. The musical portrait is a category of program music that relies on text—​at least in its title—​to identify it as a constituent of the genre and to aid in its interpretation; in this way it reflects the common view of the self as constructed by means of language.49 The form of programmatic representation in musical portraiture is typically highly abstract and therefore demands a particularly engaged and often playful form of interpretation. The book is structured around case studies that offer detailed readings of individual musical portraits, showing how one might construct impressions of the subjects of these works through interpretations of the music’s metaphorical meanings, guided by knowledge of the composers’ and sitters’ biographies. In particular, chapters examine portraits of artists whose work in the fields of literature, painting, and drama engage in multiple forms of portraiture, as well as musical self-​portraits in which composers explore various aspects of their own identities, especially by interpreting their own musical styles and influences. Following these studies of portraits that view how music can offer metaphors of linguistic, visual, and even musical modes of representation, the book turns to a set of works that combine all of these art forms together in multimedia portraiture, both in small-​scale creations and in the monumental genre of portrait opera,

  15

I n t ro d u c t i o n    ( 15 )

in which music takes center stage in the representation of an individual identity. Chapter 1 focuses on the critical role language plays in the composition, performance, and interpretation of the musical portrait. It examines musical portraits based on literary models, specifically “Buffie Johnson: Drawing Virgil Thomson in Charcoal” (1981) by Virgil Thomson (1896–​1989) and Pli selon pli: portrait de Mallarmé (1957–​1962, later revised through 1989) by Pierre Boulez (1925–​2016). Virgil Thomson was inspired by the modernist literary portraits of Gertrude Stein (1874–​1946) to develop his unique method of writing over 140 musical portraits, in which he sat before his subjects while composing in the manner of a portrait painter. Boulez’s portrait was inspired by his deep familiarity with the poetic works of the French symbolist Stéphane Mallarmé (1842–​1898), and his interest in Mallarmé’s description, in his essays, of an idiosyncratic theory according to which poetry should aspire to a representational purity and abstraction exemplified in music. Through the discussion of these two musical portraits, the chapter explores the crucial role of language in the musical representation of identity. Chapter 2 considers the connections between musical and visual modes of representing identity by examining musical portraits of visual artists. This chapter examines works that reflect the influence of modern trends in visual portraiture, focusing on musical portraits of contemporary painters: “de Kooning” (1963) by Morton Feldman (1926–​1987) and “A Musical Portrait of Chuck Close” (2005) by Philip Glass (b. 1937).50 Considering these musical portraits of the painters Willem de Kooning (1904–​1997) and Chuck Close (b. 1940) in relation to canvases by these artists reveals how the works portray their subjects by organizing musical structures to serve as metaphors of visual strategies of representation, evoking aspects of biography while mimicking painterly techniques in musical structures. In ­chapter 3 the book turns its attention to self-​portraiture, to explore the methods by which composers have depicted themselves and their compositional techniques and styles. It views musical self-​portraits in relation to self-​portraiture in visual art to identify techniques shared by the two art forms. The chapter focuses in particular on two self-​portraits, one that explores the question of artistic influence, and a second that represents its composer’s unique and personal perception of sound. The first case study is of György Ligeti’s two-​piano “Selbstportrait mit Reich und Riley (und Chopin ist auch dabei)” (Self-​Portrait with Reich and Riley (with Chopin in the Background)), from Drei Stücke (Three Pieces, 1976), in which Ligeti (1923–​2006) portrays himself with two musical contemporaries, Steve Reich (b. 1936) and Terry Riley (b. 1935), and their forerunner Frédéric Chopin (1810–​1849), by demonstrating overlapping elements

16

( 16 )   Musical Portraits

of their compositional techniques. In the second case study, “Quadraturen IV: ‘Selbstportrait mit Berlin’ ” (Self-​Portrait with Berlin, 1998), by Peter Ablinger (b. 1959), a compact disc recording of ambient sounds collected by the composer accompanies an instrumental ensemble playing a score produced by a computer analysis of this recording. In their self-​portraits, Ligeti and Ablinger reflect on their professional and artistic identities in the contexts provided by the music and sounds that they hear around them. Having explored musical interactions and intersections with literature, painting, and other music, the book turns in its final chapter to hybrid works of multimedia portraiture and the genre of the portrait opera, to consider how music operates in conjunction with these other artistic forms in the depiction of identity. Focusing in particular on strategies for the representation of contemporary cultural and intellectual icons, the chapter first introduces the Voom Portraits of the American avant-​garde director Robert Wilson (b. 1941), an ongoing series of multimedia video portraits of celebrities begun in 2004, made using high-​definition audiovisual technology. These works rely on the combination of image, music, and text, and feature eclectic sound effects and scores by composers whose work occupies a range of contrasting styles, such as Bernard Herrmann (1911–​1975), Michael Galasso (1949–​2009), and Tom Waits (b. 1949). The chapter then examines the portrait opera, with particular attention to Philip Glass’s Einstein on the Beach, created in collaboration with Wilson and choreographer Lucinda Childs (b. 1940), and premiered in 1976. The discussion considers how this trio of artists produced what they call a “portrait” of Einstein, an abstract representation that combines allusions to disparate objects, events, and concepts from his biography such as his physical appearance, his clothing, and the theory of relativity, as well as his artistry as an amateur violinist. The Voom Portraits and Einstein on the Beach evoke their subjects’ artistry to engage a particularly contemporary notion of identity, while they also foreground the complex ways music has been made to interact with imagery and theater in the production of meaning in multimedia arts of the second half of the twentieth century and the start of the twenty-​first. The book’s epilogue explores the place of musical portraiture in the context of posthumous depictions of the deceased, and in relation to the so-​ called posthuman condition, a way of describing contemporary changes in the relationship of the individual with such aspects of life as technology and the body. It first examines the treatment of music in Alfred Hitchcock’s Vertigo as a medium that can represent the overlapping identities of the living and the dead through the soundtrack scoring. It then considers the work of experimental musician Neil Harbisson (b. 1982), who has aimed, through the use of new digital capabilities, to convey something akin to

  17

I n t ro d u c t i o n    ( 17 )

visual likeness in his series of Sound Portraits. Harbisson has produced multiple brief portraits using his implanted audiovisual “eyeborg” device, a technology that he was inspired to develop as a result of his colorblindness, to enhance his sensory experience by creating a sonic analog to color, transforming light-​waves into pitches. The epilogue shows how an examination of musical portraiture in the context of the posthumous and the posthuman helps to illuminate the ways music represents identity throughout the genre of musical portraiture. One of the central claims of this book is that musical portraiture does not typically rely on techniques of mimesis to reproduce a convincing likeness, but draws instead on more abstract modes of representation that, through established metaphors that associate music with language, emotion, the self, and the visual, contribute to the rich opportunity for interpretation that is characteristic of the genre. Portraits in all art forms trade on the common belief that the genre makes human identity available to the senses. But they also rely on the fact that our understanding of identity and of how it is represented in art remains a subject of debate.51 Portraits—​in visual art, literature, music, and other media—​in this way permit a particularly imaginative form of interpretation on the part of the audience, and make possible the construction of a sense of identity through independent contemplation or discourse among multiple onlookers. For this reason portraits often provoke debate over whether or not their representations are “successful”: audiences may be likely to judge them not only on their artistic merits, but also on whether or not they convey the sitter’s identity in a way that accords with their prior conception of it. The analysis of what a musical portrait reveals to its viewers about its sitter’s identity is thus always a subjective and highly personal process, but the impossibility of offering any one definitive interpretation of a portrait is also what makes portraiture so rich and provocative a genre.

NOTES 1. George Bernard Shaw, Man and Superman:  A  Comedy and a Philosophy (Auckland:  The Floating Press, 2012), 63. 2. Music making and musical instruments are also prominent tropes in painted portraiture. See Richard Leppert, Music and Image: Domesticity, Ideology and Socio-​Cultural Formation in Eighteenth-​Century England (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988); Richard Leppert, The Sight of Sound: Music, Representation, and the History of the Body (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993), 4–​12; Michael A. Brown, “Portraits, Music and Enlightenment in the Atlantic World,” in Patrick Coleman (ed.), The Art of Music (San Diego: San Diego Museum of Art; New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2015), 167–​83.

18

( 18 )   Musical Portraits

3. Lorenzo Battista Alberti, On Painting, trans. John R. Spencer (New Haven, CT:  Yale University Press, 1956, rev. ed. 1966), 63. For further discussion of the extension of a subject’s “life” through portraiture, see also Richard Leppert, Art and the Committed Eye: The Cultural Functions of Imagery (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1996), 98–​9, 153. 4. Edgar Allan Poe, The Short Fiction of Edgar Allan Poe:  An Annotated Edition, ed. Stuart Levine and Susan Levine (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1976), 68. 5. Michal Peled Ginsburg, Portrait Stories (New  York:  Fordham University Press, 2015), 23–​4. 6. See Shearer West, Portraiture (Oxford:  Oxford University Press, 2004), 37; Richard Brilliant, Portraiture (London: Reaktion Books, 1991), 15; Ludmilla Jordanova, Defining Features:  Scientific and Medical Portraits 1660–​2000 (London:  Reaktion Books and National Portrait Gallery, 2000), 22–​5. 7. “Bodies:  Real and Ideal,” www.nga.gov/​content/​ngaweb/​features/​introduction-​to-​greek-​ bronzes/​bodies-​real-​and-​ideal.html, accessed June 21, 2016; Luke Syson and Dora Thornton, Objects of Virtue: Art in Renaissance Italy (Los Angeles: J. Paul Getty Museum, 2001), 115. 8. Bernard Williams, Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers 1956–​ 1972 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), 1. 9. Paul Klee, Paul Klee (New York: Parkstone, 2012), 16. 10. George Eliot, Adam Bede, ed. Carol A. Martin (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008; orig. 1859, rev. 1861), 159. 11. Eliot, Adam Bede, 162. 12. For a description of how realism operates in music, see Joshua S. Walden, Sounding Authentic: The Rural Miniature and Musical Modernism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 7–​9. 13. West, Portraiture, 187; Andrew Graham-​Dixon, foreword to Andrew Graham-​Dixon, Sandy Nairne, Sarah Howgate, and Jo Higgins (eds.), 21st-​Century Portraits (London: National Portrait Gallery, 2013), 7–​9; Lee Siegel, “On the Face of It,” in Donna Gustafson and Susan Sidlauskas (eds.), Striking Resemblance: The Changing Art of Portraiture (New Brunswick, NJ: Zimmerli Art Museum at Rutgers University; London: Prestel, 2014), 50. 14. West, Portraiture, 194–​201. 15. See Edward A. Aiken, “‘I Saw the Figure 5 in Gold’: Charles Demuth’s Emblematic Portrait of William Carlos Williams,” Art Journal 46.3 (Autumn 1987): 179. 16. Leppert, Art and the Committed Eye, 153. 17. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1958), II: iv, 178. 18. Jennifer Montagu, The Expression of the Passions:  The Origin and Influence of Charles Le Brun’s Conférence sur l’expression générale et particulière (New Haven, CT:  Yale University Press, 1994), 1. 19. Charles le Brun, The Conference of Monsieur Le Brun, cheif [sic] painter of the French King, . . . upon Expression, General and Particular, trans. J. Smith (London, 1701), 1–​2, 39–​40. 20. William Hogarth, The Analysis of Beauty. Written with a View of Fixing the Fluctuating Ideas of Taste (London: J. Reeves, 1753), 126. 21. For detailed historical and philosophical discussion of the relationship between expression and personality, see Sandra Kemp, Future Face:  Image, Identity, Innovation (London: Profile, 2004), 56–​66. 22. Susan Sontag, “Certain Mapplethorpes,” in Susan Sontag (ed.), Where the Stress Falls: Essays (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2001), 234. 23. Lawrence M.  Zbikowski refers to this form of metaphor as “cross-​domain mapping,” in Conceptualizing Music:  Cognitive Structure, Theory, and Analysis (Oxford:  Oxford University Press, 2002), 64. On visual metaphors in discourses around music, see also Gurminder Kaur Bhogal, “Visual Metaphors in Music Analysis and Criticism,” in Tim Shephard and Anne Leonard (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Music and Visual Culture (New York: Routledge, 2014), 191–​9. 24. On metaphor and the perception of music, see Steven Feld, “‘Flow Like a Waterfall’: The Metaphors of Kaluli Musical Theory,” Yearbook for Traditional Music 13 (1981): 22–​47;

  19

I n t ro d u c t i o n    ( 19 )

Laurence Dreyfus, “Christopher Peacocke’s ‘The Perception of Music,’” British Journal of Aesthetics 49.3 ( July 2009): 294. In their foundational book on the subject, Metaphors We Live By, George Lakoff and Mark Johnson write that metaphor plays a fundamental role in constructing the ways people perceive the world and interact culturally and socially with others. George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Metaphors We Live By (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980), 3–​5. On metaphors that characterize the visual arts in relation to music, see Simon Shaw-​Miller, “The Art of Music: A Complex Art,” and Patrick Coleman, “Music, Said and Scene: Encounters in Metaphor, Theory and Performance,” in Coleman, Art of Music, 33–​59, 105–​27. 25. Simon Shaw-​Miller, Eye hEar: The Visual in Music (Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 2013), 185. An extensive history of artists and art theorists whose work explores the borders between music and the visual arts can be found in Peter Vergo, That Divine Order: Music and the Visual Arts from Antiquity to the Eighteenth Century (London:  Phaidon, 2005); Peter Vergo, The Music of Painting: Music, Modernism, and the Visual Arts from the Romantics to John Cage (London: Phaidon, 2010). 26. Simon Shaw-​Miller, Visible Deeds of Music: Art and Music from Wagner to Cage (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2002), 11. Shaw-​Miller partially attributes the tendency to view the arts as fully distinct to academic disciplinarity: “Attempts at purification and homogeneity are reinforced by, and carried out within, the professionalization of academic disciplines as they form themselves into discrete subjects” (35). 27. Leppert, Sight of Sound, xx. The relationships between music, the visual aspects of performance, and the physical gestures of the body—​even those inferred rather than witnessed when music is appreciated by listening to sound recording—​have also been studied extensively in the field of psychology. See, from the perspective of perceptual psychology, W. Luke Windsor, “Gestures in Music-​Making: Action, Information and Perception,” in Anthony Gritten and Elaine King (eds.), New Perspectives on Music and Gesture (Farnham, UK:  Ashgate, 2011), 45–​66; and from the field of embodied cognition, Marc Leman and Pieter-​Jan Maes, “The Role of Embodiment in the Perception of Music,” Empirical Musicology Review 9.3–​4 (2014):  236–​46; Rolf Inge Godøy, “Gestural Affordances of Musical Sound,” in Rolf Inge Godøy and Marc Leman (eds.), Musical Gestures:  Sound, Movement, and Meaning (New York: Routledge, 2010), 103–​25. 28. The musical gestures in a composition labeled as a portrait might also imply certain aspects of the subject’s physical presence and bearing. On the correspondences between the ways meaning is communicated by musical gestures and the physical gestures made during speech, see Lawrence M. Zbikowski, “Musical Gesture and Musical Grammar:  A  Cognitive Approach,” in Gritten and King, New Perspectives on Music and Gesture, 83–​98. On music’s influences on the embodied perception of time, see Barbara G. Goodrich, “Tempos of Eternity: Music, Volition, and Playing with Time,” in Joseph P. Huston, Marcos Nadal, Francisco Mora, Luigi F. Agnati, and Camilo Jose Cela Conde (eds.), Art, Aesthetics, and the Brain (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015), 500–​18. 29. On the functions of body and eye movement in the contemplation of art, see Michael Madary, “Visual Experience,” in Lawrence Shapiro (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition (London:  Routledge, 2014), 263; Paul J. Locher, “Empirical Investigation of an Aesthetic Experience with Art,” in Arthur P. Shimamura and Stephen E. Palmer (eds.), Aesthetic Science: Connecting Minds, Brains, and Experience (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012), 163–​88 (esp. 175–​9); Raphael Rosenberg and Christoph Klein, “The Moving Eye of the Beholder:  Eye Tracking and the Perception of Paintings,” in Huston, Nadal, Mora, Agnati, and Conde, Art, Aesthetics, and the Brain, 79–​108. 30. In the twentieth century a number of visual artists began to explore methods for depicting the passing of time, the temporal “movement” of music, and the physical, rhythmic motions of dance through visual means. See Karin v. Maur, The Sound of Painting (London: Prestel, 1999), 43–​59, 94–​101. 31. Jerrold Seigel, The Idea of the Self: Thought and Experience in Western Europe since the Seventeenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 5–​6.

20

( 20 )   Musical Portraits

32. Paul C. Vitz, “Introduction: From the Modern and Postmodern Selves to the Transmodern Self,” in Paul C. Vitz and Susan M. Felch (eds.), The Self:  Beyond the Postmodern Crisis (Wilmington, DE: ISI Books, 2006), xi–​xii. 33. John Barresi and Raymond Martin, “History as Prologue: Western Theories of the Self,” in Shaun Gallagher (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Self (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011), 33–​56; Madam Sarup, Identity, Culture and the Postmodern World (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1996), 14; Kenneth Allan, “The Postmodern Self: A Theoretical Consideration,” Quarterly Journal of Ideology 20.1–​2 (1997): 3–​24. On the ways social and political movements in the 1960s in North America and Western Europe contributed to the rise of the social constructionist view of identity, see Kenneth J. Gergen, “The Social Construction of Self,” in Gallagher, Oxford Handbook of the Self, 634. The notion of a fragmented identity is implied by some portraiture from the earlier half of the twentieth century as well. For example, the surrealist artist Max Ernst, in preparing his 1935 self-​portrait, broke the glass-​plate negative of a photograph taken of his face by Man Ray, and adhered it back together, writing the details of the exhibition onto the surface of the tape. The image of the result of this fractured, reassembled likeness was then printed on the cover of the invitation to the exhibition of his works in Paris, Exposition Max Ernst—​dernières oeuvres. Ernst repaired the broken glass, but permitted the cracks in his reflection to remain. See Elza Adamowicz, “The Surrealist (Self-​)Portrait: Convulsive Identities,” in Silvano Levy (ed.), Surrealism: Surrealist Visuality (Edinburgh: Keele University Press, 1996), 32. 34. Sarup, Identity, Culture and the Postmodern World, 45. 35. An important early study of the performance of the self is found in Erving Goffman, The Presentation of the Self in Everyday Life (Garden City, NY: Doubleday Anchor, 1959). 36. Roland Barthes, Camera Lucida: Reflections on Photography (New York: Hill and Wang, 1982), 11–​12. 37. Kenneth Gergen, The Saturated Self:  Dilemmas of Identity in Contemporary Life (New York: Basic Books, 1991), 170. See also Vitz, “Introduction,” xiii–​xiv. 38. Vitz, “Introduction,” xiii. Helene Tallon Russell and Marjorie Hewitt Suchocki interpret the writings on selfhood of Søren Kierkegaard and Alfred North Whitehead, in order to argue that the self is multiple and relational, but they oppose the common understanding that the unity of the self ultimately triumphs over its multiplicity in the way the self is constructed and experienced. They conclude that “the self is composite, not singular; it is constituted in and through multiple relationships. This multiplicity is essential to the self, and is also, through dialectic, the basis for the common experience of the self as a unity.” Helene Tallon Russell and Marjorie Hewitt Suchocki, “The Multiple Self,” in J. Wentzel van Huyssteen and Erik P. Wiebe (eds.), In Search of Self: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Personhood (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2011), 196. 39. Vitz, “Introduction,” xiii–​xiv. Shari Stone-​Mediatore counsels against viewing identity as defined entirely in one of two contrasting ways, according to the modern or postmodern conceptions, recommending instead a consideration of identity as merging notions of the self as at once both true and constructed. Shari Stone-​Mediatore, “Postmodernism, Realism, and the Problem of Identity,” Diaspora 11.1 (2002): 131. 40. Gergen, “Social Construction,” 635. 41. Anthony Elliott, Concepts of the Self, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: Polity, 2008), 9. For Elliott, “all forms of identity are astonishingly imaginative fabrications of the private and public, personal and political, individual and historical” (10–​11). 42. Olav Bryant Smith, Myths of the Self:  Narrative Identity and Postmodern Metaphysics (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2004), 176. 43. Calvin O. Schrag, The Self after Postmodernity (New Haven, CT:  Yale University Press, 1997), 1. 44. Valerie Gray Hardcastle, Constructing the Self (Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2008), 35. 45. Marya Schechtman, The Constitution of Selves (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996), 94. See also Marya Schechtman, “The Narrative Self,” in Gallagher, Oxford Handbook of the Self, 394–​416.

  21

I n t ro d u c t i o n    ( 21 )

46. On the narrative element in contemporary visual portraiture, see Sarah Howgate and Sandy Nairne, introduction to 21st-​Century Portraits, 16. 47. John Berger, Portraits: John Berger on Artists, ed. Tom Overton (London: Verso, 2015), 442. 48. For example, Simon Frith writes, “Music constructs our sense of identity through the experiences it offers of the body, time, and sociability, experiences which enable us to place ourselves in imaginative cultural narratives.” Simon Frith, Performing Rites: On the Value of Popular Music (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), 275. For Tia DeNora, music is a “building material of self-​identity,” a “resource to which people turn in order to regulate themselves as aesthetic agents, as feeling, thinking and acting beings in their day-​to-​day lives.” Tia DeNora, Music in Everyday Life (Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press, 2000), 62. 49. Sarup, Identity, Culture and the Postmodern World, 47. 50. On Glass’s portrait of Close, as well as György Ligeti’s musical self-​portrait explored in ­chapter  3, see also Joshua S. Walden, “Representation and Musical Portraiture in the Twentieth Century,” in Joshua S. Walden (ed.), Representation in Western Music (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 127–​43. 51. Ludmilla Jordanova, “Visualizing Identity,” in Giselle Walker and Elisabeth Leedham-​ Green (eds.), Identity (Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press, 2010), 132. E.  H. Gombrich writes, “Expression is hard to analyze and harder to describe unequivocally. It is a curious fact, moreover, that our immediate reaction results in firm convictions, but convictions which are rarely shared by all—​witness the pages of interpretation that have been devoted to Mona Lisa’s smile.” E. H. Gombrich, Art and Illusion: A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation (London: Phaidon, 1969), 268.

22

CH A P T E R 1

Musical and Literary Portraiture Portrait painting is the biography of the pencil, and he who gives most of the peculiarities and details, with most of the general character . . . is the best biographer, and the best portrait-​painter. —​William Hazlitt1

T

he first half of George Eliot’s 1876 novel Daniel Deronda focuses primarily on the story of the beautiful, complicated young anti-​heroine Gwendolyn Harleth and her vain attempts to dig herself and her family out of financial ruin by attracting a wealthy suitor. In her narration of Gwendolyn’s story, Eliot describes her authorial task by analogy to portraiture: “Sir Joshua would have been glad to take her portrait; and he would have had an easier task than the historian at least in this, that he would not have had to represent the truth of change—​only to give stability to one beautiful moment.”2 In this statement, Eliot assumes overlaps between the goals and techniques of portraiture in painting and in literature—​principally, that the genre functions in both media to represent an individual subject’s appearance and character—​but, more significantly, she also points to an underlying difference that relates to the temporal dimension of writing. The painted portrait represents the subject in a single moment, even if that momentary glimpse features some elements that aim to evoke everlasting characteristics such as heroism, beauty, or social position, and if the experience of viewing the portraiture necessarily involves an element of time. The literary portrait, by contrast, must account for how the self varies over some chronological period. Whether it is a work of fiction or history, its author demonstrates the effects of the passage of time on the development of character, showing how all those moments that could be captured in individual painted portraits unite into a coherent but also changeable self. The novelist and literary critic A. S. Byatt, elaborating on the difference between literary and visual portraits, states that the two genres “are

  23

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 23 )

opposites, rather than metaphors for each other,” because the painting depicts surface appearance outside of the progress of time, while the story records the invisible aspects of a person.3 Literary portraiture may even rely on this invisibility: “The description in visual language of a face or body may depend on being unseen for its force.”4 The functions of time, the unfolding of description, and the triggering of the spectator’s imagination are central to this distinction between the verbal and the visual in this genre, and the musical portrait, particularly in works that emulate or show the influence of literary portraiture, also relies on these attributes to represent its subject’s self. Byatt concludes, “What a novelist can do, which is difficult for a painter, is convey what is not, and cannot, be known about a human being.”5 The composer of a musical portrait has a power similar to that Byatt attributes to the novelist, but in a medium that minimizes language for an entirely auditory form of narrative or description, or that in some cases employs text in combination with sound to make possible diverse, hybrid meanings. Like the musical portrait, the literary portrait—​a form whose early roots are typically traced to the Characters of the classical philosopher Theophrastus, Aristotle’s pupil and successor at the Lyceum—​does not conform to a single standard form, length, or approach to its subject matter.6 It can be short or long; it can stand on its own as an isolated work or appear as a passage embedded within a larger text; and it can represent a person’s outward appearance, inner character, or psychology, or even describe a painted portrait.7 And though many scholars accept only representations of living or historical individuals as portraits, others find it helpful to consider descriptions of fictional subjects or even character types as forms of literary portraiture.8 Meanwhile, portraiture is also frequently invoked as a metaphor to characterize the more widely recognized and easily defined genre of biography.9 Literary portraiture, in forms representing general character types as well as living or historic individuals, offered a source inspiration for composers of musical portraits at several points in the history of the genre. For example, the stimulus for François Couperin’s development of the pièce de caractère (character piece) was the fad in 1650s France for short literary portraits, prose documents of around 1,000 words written by and about members of high society.10 During this decade, Couperin’s uncle Louis composed short keyboard works, which, in a manner prefiguring the pièces de caractère that his nephew would eventually write, served the aristocratic audiences for these literary portraits by incorporating playfulness and “preciosity,” and emphasizing sophistication and delicacy.11 In the nineteenth century, Robert Schumann’s imaginary duo Florestan and Eusebius, whom the composer described repeatedly in his portrait essays as studies in contrasting characters—​depicted respectively as passionately fiery and dreamily

24

( 24 )   Musical Portraits

tranquil—​found their musical representation in individual movements of his Carnaval, Op. 9. And in the early twentieth century, Virgil Thomson decided to write musical portraits after becoming acquainted with the literary portraits that were an important component of the oeuvre and stylistic development of his friend, the modernist author Gertrude Stein.12 Even as some other composers of portraits were influenced more directly by painted rather than literary portraits, the important role of written language in musical portraiture brings the genre into perpetual contact with its linguistic counterpart. Because music cannot directly depict physical likeness in the manner of images or describe appearance or character the way language can, musical portraits require the aid of a title simply to be recognized as such. The title will often include the word “portrait,” but it will at least posit the name of the individual the work represents. The titles of musical portraits often also offer additional information that will further guide the listener’s interpretation of the piece. John Adams’s self-​portrait My Father Knew Charles Ives, for example, indicates that the composer represents himself in relation to his father, the iconic American composer who came before him, and the New England region in which he grew up and his father and Ives both built their homes and careers. Many musical portraits also use language in their scores’ paratexts to further identify their subjects and direct the listener’s interpretation; for instance, some of Thomson’s scores containing multiple brief portraits open with descriptions of each individual depicted in these works. Written historical documentation can additionally become a part of the contextual framework surrounding musical portraits, inspiring how people conceive of them as representations of individuals. For instance, the subjects of most of Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach’s musical portraits of the 1750s, long unknown to scholars and performers, have recently been identified, and this has inspired further research on and interpretations of these works (not least because this contextual writing was necessary to disprove the persistent assumption that his portraits, titled with the French feminine definite article La followed by the subject’s last name, were not depictions of women: La implied the noun pièce, not the sitter’s gender).13 This chapter examines two sets of musical portraits that illuminate the genre’s association with literary portraiture and its complex and essential relationship with language. The first is Thomson’s large corpus of musical portraits, composed across nearly sixty years of his career. These works provide an example of musical portraiture modeled directly on corresponding works of literature, rather than painting. In his portraits, Thomson explores music’s capacity for representation in spite of its perceived abstraction by developing a method for depicting human subjects that he hoped would produce something analogous to Stein’s modernist literary experiments.

  25

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 25 )

The second is Pierre Boulez’s set of pieces that are combined in his five-​ part Pli selon pli: Portrait de Mallarmé (Fold according to Fold: Portrait of Mallarmé), composed over more than thirty years, between 1957 and 1989. In Pli selon pli Boulez incorporates, into a large-​scale and varied musical context, fragments from the poems of the French symbolist poet and author Stéphane Mallarmé, whose “L’après-​midi d’un faune” (The Afternoon of a Faun, 1876) famously became the model for Claude Debussy’s path-​ breaking orchestral work Prélude à l’après-​midi d’un faune (1894), about which Boulez stated, “The flute of the faun brought new breath to the art of music.”14 Through Boulez’s rendering, Mallarmé’s poems become the core material of his own portrait, in which Boulez transforms Mallarmé’s complex linguistic inventions into a representation of his identity and his ideas about the relationship between music and literature.15 THE MUSICAL PORTRAITS OF VIRGIL THOMSON AND THE COMPOSITION OF PRESENCE

Virgil Thomson dedicated himself to experimenting with musical portraiture for many decades, composing over 140 works in the genre, for a variety of ensembles, between 1928 and 1985. He was inspired to create portraits by his friend and collaborator Gertrude Stein, who from 1908 onward wrote approximately 132 literary portraits in which she attempted to depict her subjects using language abstracted from traditional forms of narrative and grammar. Thomson had first encountered Stein’s work in 1919, and the two met several years later and soon developed a close personal relationship; he wrote in his autobiography that between their first encounter in 1926 and her death twenty years later, “we were forever loving being together, whether talking and walking, writing to each other, or at work.”16 In the words of Stein’s partner Alice B. Toklas, Stein and Thomson “got on like Harvard men.”17 Among other projects that brought them together, Thomson worked with Stein on the operas Four Saints in Three Acts and The Mother of Us All, wrote a musical arrangement of her play Capital Capitals for four male voices, and composed art songs based on her literary portraits “Susie Asado” and “Preciocilla.” In addition, Thomson wrote frequently about Stein, including in a chapter of his autobiography titled “A Portrait of Gertrude Stein” and an essay that served as the introduction to a 1953 collection of her poems. Thomson recognized a similarity between the modes of representation in Stein’s use of language and in his own music. In setting her writing in art songs, he explains, her literary style, “with meanings jumbled and syntax violated, but with the words themselves all the more shockingly present,”

26

( 26 )   Musical Portraits

inspired him to “put those texts to music with a minimum of temptation toward the emotional conventions, spend[ing] my whole effort on the rhythm of the language, . . . adding shape, where that seemed to be needed, and it usually was, from music’s own devices.”18 He elaborates on the effects of working with Stein’s texts in his autobiography: My hope in putting Gertrude Stein to music had been to break, crack open, and solve for all time anything still waiting to be solved, which was almost everything, about English musical declamation. . . . I had no sooner put to music after this recipe one short Stein text than I knew I had opened a door. I had never had any doubts about Stein’s poetry; from then on I had none about my ability to handle it in music.19

Setting Stein’s poetry to music proved to be an early turning point for Thomson in the development of his style. In his musical experimentations with the depiction of personal identities in music, Thomson sought to mimic Stein’s linguistic representations of individuals. As he would write to Stein, “the idea of it comes obviously out of you.”20 He particularly admired what he viewed as the spontaneity of Stein’s literary portraits, which he described as “an exercise not only in objectivity but also in avoiding the premeditated.”21 It has been widely argued that Stein took technical and aesthetic inspiration in her portraits from her experience of sitting for Pablo Picasso’s iconic portrait of her, painted in 1905 and 1906 (Figure 1.1). Stein posed for Picasso in his Paris studio repeatedly during that winter; the details of this process have proven difficult to confirm, but it seems possible the sittings took place over a period of three months.22 She and her brother Leo, who together collected modern paintings and interacted with a large number of the cutting-​edge artists in France during this period, had met Picasso in 1905, and they became his most important sponsors and collectors for the following nine years.23 The idea to create this portrait belonged to Picasso, and he gave the completed canvas to Stein as a gift. But Picasso took an uncharacteristically long time to finish the portrait of Stein. In early 1906, at the end of the winter in which she sat repeatedly for him, he grew frustrated, and, having “painted out the whole head” (in Stein’s words), left the canvas abandoned. It was not until he returned from Spain at the conclusion of the summer that he felt able to complete the face, and to do so without calling Stein in for an additional sitting.24 In its final rendering her head took on attributes of the mask-​like faces he had begun to paint that summer, partly on the basis of the inspiration he found in the so-​called Gósol Madonna, a twelfth-​century sculpture housed in a church near his vacation spot. In this way Stein’s likeness presaged the masks that stood in for the heads of the bathers in Picasso’s monumental and path-​breaking painting “Les demoiselles d’Avignon,” completed the following year.25 The work

  27

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 27 )

Figure  1.1: Pablo Picasso, “Gertrude Stein,” 1905–​1906, oil on canvas, 39-​3/​8 x 32 inches. © 2016 Estate of Pablo Picasso/​Artists Rights Society (ARS), New York. Image copyright © The Metropolitan Museum of Art. Image source: Art Resource, NY.

this proved a critical breakthrough for Picasso in his stylistic development and the transition to his Cubist phase.26 Picasso acknowledged the portrait’s importance in his career, and Stein adored the work; she later wrote to Picasso, in 1938, “I was and I still am satisfied with my portrait, for me, it is I, and it is the only reproduction of me which is always I, for me.”27 The painting in fact made Stein famous as an icon of the avant-​garde before she had made an international name for herself as a modernist writer.28 And it appears to have influenced the development of Stein’s modernist technique of writing portraits, in which she used words in a manner that resembles how the individual colors and shapes a modern artist assembles on an abstract canvas may derive meaning from their spatial relations to one another rather than from any specific signification.29 In her literary portraits, Stein aimed to portray her sitters as they existed in a single moment, the way they would be represented in painted portraiture, rather than in the context of any sort of story that involves action and change and plays out over time. In this way her portraits come closer

28

( 28 )   Musical Portraits

to resembling how George Eliot, in the passage from Daniel Deronda discussed earlier, describes visual, rather than literary, works in the genre. Stein explains her rejection of narrative and emotion in her portraits in the 1935 essay “Portraits and Repetition,” saying that these are to be avoided because of their association with memory. These forms of description, for Stein, portray only a person’s resemblance, not who he is; they render him into a type rather than an individual self, by inciting the reader to recall other encounters with similar descriptions of character and thus, through memory, to draw connections between different people.30 Instead, she wished to use portraiture to represent what she sometimes dubbed the subject’s “existence,” and elsewhere characterized as the person’s unique inner “movement.”31 She aimed to create depictions of her subjects’ interior selves as she apprehended them, using the most direct, momentary, and unmediated literary means she could devise.32 Stein’s notion of the self was based in large part on the ideas of psychologist William James, whose theoretical writings she had read as a student at Radcliffe College.33 According to James’s The Principles of Psychology, there are two ways to contemplate other people: through “acquaintance,” which constitutes a sort of immediate awareness, and through “knowledge about,” which involves the ability to recognize the continuity that links a succession of moments of awareness into a single entity. For James, the notion of identity requires “knowledge about,” because it demands the understanding, through processes of memory and comparison, that one is the same person from any one moment to the next.34 Stein concurred with James’s position in her early essays, but as she developed her philosophy and prose style, she grew to feel that portraiture required not the kind of description that will contribute to knowledge about a person, but instead an attempt at representing her unmediated perception of a subject.35 This way she could approach her goal of making the reader’s immediate acquaintance with her subject’s existence, as though in a moment that stands outside the forward progress of time and therefore does not permit comparison and memory. In some of the portraits that Stein wrote in what has been called the second phase of her work in the genre, including “Susie Asado” and “Preciosilla,” she felt that she accomplished an effect in language that was akin to music, producing “an extraordinary melody of words” that was able to represent the corresponding “internal melody of existence.”36 Though she subsequently grew to feel that the effect of this style came too perilously close to beauty, an effect she wished to avoid, and decided to find a more sober approach to writing, she allowed that this accomplishment served as an important stage in the development of her portraiture, and indeed these were two portraits that Thomson would later set to melody.

  29

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 29 )

In “Portraits and Repetition,” Stein explains why portraiture was so inspirational and formative a genre for her and elaborates on her personal notion of what constitutes the individual self, discussing why she chose to write her portraits in such abstract language: I had to find out what it was inside any one, and by any one I mean every one I had to find out inside every one what was in them that was intrinsically exciting and I had to find out not by what they said not by what they did not by how much or how little they resembled any other one but I had to find it out by the intensity of movement that there was inside in any of them.37

Stein described both the quality of existence that she aimed to portray in her works and the portraitist’s method of reproducing it by analogy to the experience of simultaneously “listening and talking”:38 “by listening and talking I conceived at every moment the existence of some one, and I put down each moment that I had the existence of that one inside in me until I had completely emptied myself of this that I had had as a portrait of that one.”39 It was thus a thorough contemplation of a subject that took place through a process akin to a deep layering of dialogue within oneself that brought Stein in touch with the individual, interior existence of her acquaintances that she wished to represent in her portraits.40 A principal characteristic of many of Stein’s portraits is the restatement of words and phrases through a technique that she called “insistence,” and was careful to distinguish from repetition.41 Through insistence, locutions can take on different emphases each time they recur, despite their similarity, and in this way come to resemble a person’s life, throughout which attributes of experience frequently reappear but their meanings shift.42 Explaining the process, she writes: “Each sentence is just the difference in emphasis that inevitably exists in the successive moment of my containing within me the existence of that other one achieved by talking and listening inside in me and inside in that one.”43 She likened this technique to the content of a reel of film, in which the sequence of multiple frames, each of which is much like the one that preceded it but has its own unique differences in form and emphasis, merge together when projected, to create a single image that contains an overarching sense of movement, or existence.44 During Thomson’s early efforts at writing musical portraits, he developed a method of composition that was inspired by Stein’s process of creating her literary portraits, as well as by the tradition in visual portraiture of creating representations in their sitters’ presence: he sat before his subjects and composed spontaneously, writing notes on the page as he felt inspired to by their proximity.45 Thomson explained, “It was in search of . . . immediacy that I began making musical portraits as a painter works, in the model’s

30

( 30 )   Musical Portraits

presence. This led me toward seeking ways to keep my work spontaneous, the music flowing out of me unhindered by thoughts, at least by verbalizings.”46 In doing so, he believed, he was best able to represent the abstract essence at the core of the sitter’s identity, bypassing physical appearance. As he wrote, “I do not try evoking visual art; in all my portraits only the sitter’s presence is portrayed, not his appearance or his profession.”47 Thomson also drew inspiration from the study of prior composers who took liberties with traditional musical forms; as he put it in his autobiography, his discovery of their rule-​breaking gave him a sense of freedom that “meant that I could write almost automatically, cultivate the discipline of spontaneity, let it flow.”48 In describing the genre of musical portraiture, Thomson suggested that all composition is inherently representational, but that musical portraits are unusual in that they aim to render a singular, identifiable image: “Very little has ever been written down that the author did not think was about something. Some thing or some body. So every musical portrait is tied to an individual, and the composer of it tends to believe it a true likeness.”49 Thomson understood representation in the composition of music to involve creating metaphoric connections between music and sights, sounds, perfumes, language, and emotion.50 The musical portrait, therefore, related to its subject, the sitter named in the title, through a variety of affective and sensory metaphors linking the music’s compositional structures and those abstract aspects of a sitter’s presence—​Thomson’s analogue to Stein’s existence—​ that he believed could be perceived most effectively through a momentary, spontaneous meeting. The simplicity and brevity of Thomson’s portraits is an outcome of the aesthetic goal of rendering the subject present before the listener as he once sat before the composer, making him available to the senses in a way that allows for an immediate encounter that does not require the interpretation of meaning (though it does not preclude such a reading, either, as the following analyses show).51 In this way Thomson attempts in his portraits to capture the sense of epiphany he feels in a person’s presence, and to reproduce this intense but ephemeral event for his portraits’ players and listeners. In other words, he hopes, in these works, to stage for the listener a similar confrontation with the sitter in the moment of the performance.52 In the late 1920s, Stein and Thomson exchanged portraits of one another through the mail. Thomson produced his first, in 1928; after its premiere performance in Paris (the reviewer for the New Yorker called it a “ ‘bust’ of Gertrude Stein”), he reported back to her, “Your portrait pleases. Is said to resemble.”53 Thomson received Stein’s rendering of him the following year. Stein explained that it exhibited a “profundity” that conveyed her belief in him, and Thomson wrote back that it was “very beautiful and serious and

  31

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 31 )

like me too. Yes very serious and with a quite gratuitous beauty.”54 In their respective media these two portraits resemble one another in the way they exhibit the technique of insistence, the restatement of musical or linguistic motifs with gradual and unpredictable variations that result in a shifting of emphasis and therefore of meaning. In Thomson’s portrait of Stein, titled “Miss Gertrude Stein as a Young Girl” and later published in the collection Eight Portraits for Violin Alone (1981), the composer restates and varies motivic fragments in a manner that resembles Stein’s linguistic insistence. Thomson explores several methods of slightly altering brief musical materials in just the first ten measures of the portrait (Example 1.1). He begins with the technique of sequencing, restating the opening two-​measure phrase in measures three and four, but at a whole step below. He then introduces a new five-​note motif in measure 5, which is in 5$time. This recurs three additional times in succession, always with a different set of emphases produced by changes in bowing, note length, or meter. In the first version of this motif, the notes are slurred in two groupings, the first comprised of three notes and the second of two. In the following measure, Thomson restates the motif with a different slurring, in groups of two and then three, altering the emphasis produced by the violinist’s bow changes from notes 1 and 4 to notes 1 and 3. In the second restatement of the motif, notes 1 and 4 are expanded in length to half notes, so the emphasis is now on these two pitches, both of which fall on downbeats. And in the final restatement, which begins on the third beat of the measure, the emphasis is on notes 2 and 5, which fall on downbeats in the new meter of 3$time. Something analogous to Thomson’s motivic restatements with altered emphases can be found in the insistence of individual words and phrases in the first portion of Stein’s portrait “Virgil Thomson,” which begins: Yes ally. As ally. Yes ally yes as ally. A very easy failure takes place. Yes ally. As ally. As ally yes a very easy failure takes place. Very good. Very easy failure takes place. Yes very easy failure takes place.55

Example 1.1:  Virgil Thomson, “Miss Gertrude Stein as a Young Girl,” 1928, mm. 1–​11.

32

( 32 )   Musical Portraits

In this passage Stein constructs several fragmented motifs and then restates them, each time modifying, conjoining, and reshuffling them. The text has no clear meaning, and the dizzying recurrence of several one-​syllable words—​“yes,” “as,” and “ally”—​has the result of separating these words from their usual signification and turning them into abstract sounds, whose shared letters (the y’s that open “yes” and close “ally” but produce different phonemes in these words) and assonance on the short “a” contribute to a rhythmic staccato that is broken up with the occasional insertion of the rarer multiple-​syllable words. Additionally, the division of word groupings with the punctuating period imposes emphases on the words that fall at the start and end of each individual “sentence,” in the manner of the bar-​ lines within the shifting time signatures of Thomson’s portrait. In the end, the danger of a “very easy failure” may loom ominously, but the affirmative repetition of “yes” (an echo of an ecstatic Molly Bloom at the close of Joyce’s Ulysses?) and the implication of collaboration in the word “ally” hint at a “very easy” friendship between these two portraitists, as do the lilting rhythmic variations of Thomson’s whimsical portrait of Stein. Musical restatement is also an important feature of one of Thomson’s much later portraits, “Buffie Johnson: Drawing Virgil Thomson in Charcoal,” where it is manifested in the simple, antiquated technique of imitation between the two musical voices, played by the left and right hand of the piano. This portrait was published in his collection Nineteen Portraits for Piano (1981), which included musical portraits of three artists of his acquaintance—​Buffie Johnson, Franco Assetto, and John Wright—​that he created in their presence while they simultaneously sketched portraits of him. In the introduction to the score of this collection, Thomson identifies his sitters, describing Johnson as an artist “celebrated for her giant flowers and for her portraits.” Johnson’s artistic mode was generally realist: though her portraits could be stylized in ways that gestured toward early twentieth-​ century expressionism, they did not engage with abstraction. In an earlier portrait of Thomson from 1963, for example, Thomson’s face, a recognizable likeness shown in three-​quarter view, emerges from—​and merges with—​a sketchy, shadowy background (Figure 1.2). His downturned lips convey an austere, taciturn character, and his heavy eyelids and distant gaze out of the right side of the canvas appear to indicate that he has become lost in thought. While both Morton Feldman and Philip Glass depict the subjects of their musical portraits of the painters Willem de Kooning and Chuck Close in part through the evocation of their characteristic artistic styles and techniques, as ­chapter 2 will demonstrate, Thomson once stated that his musical portraits of artists do not mimic the subjects’ own works of art.56 It might be the case that Thomson does not imitate the style or appearance

  3

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 33 )

Figure 1.2:  Buffie Johnson, “Portrait of Virgil Thomson,” 1963, oil on Masonite, 23-​3/​4 x 19-​1/​2 inches. Used by permission of the University of Missouri-​Kansas City Libraries, Dr. Kenneth J. LaBudde Department of Special Collections. Additional permission granted by Jenny J. Sykes.

of Johnson’s artworks, as he protests, but in this portrait, her act of creating art—​in particular, a representation in the genre of portrait drawing—​ becomes the central subject of Thomson’s musical construction of her identity. This is accomplished in this short neoclassical composition by way of its imitative structure, in which the left hand plays the same through-​ composed melody as the right, always two bars behind and a minor tenth below. With its canonic form, in which the melody is constantly at once presented and re-​presented in a large-​scale manifestation of Stein’s technique of insistence, “Buffie Johnson” appears to depict a mirroring effect, as the two artists serve as both model and portraitist for one another, each depicting the other in the process of creating a representation. The melodies in each line of Thomson’s portrait convey a neoclassical quality that gestures back to the Baroque era. For example, opening dotted rhythms evoke the French overture style (measures 1–​4, Example 1.2), and brief melodic fragments reappear throughout at differing pitch levels, in clear instances of sequencing (as in measure 20, Example 1.3). The imitative quality of the entire composition heightens this retrospective, learned-​style

34

( 34 )   Musical Portraits Example  1.2: Virgil Thomson, “Buffie Johnson:  Drawing Virgil Thomson in Charcoal,” 1981, mm. 1–​6.

Example  1.3: Virgil Thomson, “Buffie Johnson:  Drawing Virgil Thomson in Charcoal,” 1981, mm. 20–​4.

effect. In composing the portrait in this way, Thomson depicts Johnson as possessing a refined, classic, perhaps old-​fashioned affect and bearing. “Buffie Johnson” is a whimsical representation of the act of producing a portrait, in which the portrait’s subject is not only the sitter, but also the process of artistic representation. Just as portraiture has long been recognized as a medium that renders indelible an ephemeral moment in an impermanent life, Thomson’s work offers a permanent musical representation of the fleeting act of creating a portrait. And as a depiction of both Johnson and her process of drawing Thomson, this musical work operates not only as a portrait of another artist, but also as an unusual kind of self-​portrait. Thomson represents two artists, filtered through one another’s perception: he depicts Buffie Johnson as he experiences her “presence” when he sits before her, and he also describes himself as she perceives him, on the evidence of the way she portrays him at the same time in her charcoal drawing. In its reliance on repetition (or, for Stein’s sake, insistence) in a musical exploration of portraiture, likeness, and the representation of presence,

  35

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 35 )

Thomson’s imitative portrait of Buffie Johnson recalls a line in Stein’s second portrait of Picasso, titled “If I  Told Him:  A  Completed Portrait of Picasso,” from 1923. In this literary depiction of the artist who had created the iconic portrait of her that she would find so inspiring throughout her life, and whom she had first represented in one of her earliest word portraits, Stein writes: Exact resemblance to exact resemblance the exact resemblance as exact as a resemblance, exactly a resembling, exactly resembling, exactly in resemblance exactly a resemblance, exactly and resemblance.57

In Stein’s portrait, the aesthetic quality of exact resemblance appears to be attributed not to naturalism or realism, typical styles of portraiture in the artistic tradition, but to motivic restatement and developing variation as elements of literary depiction. It additionally seems to refer to some form of mutual contemplation and representation, of the sort Picasso and Stein engaged in, and Thomson also participated in with Stein and again with Johnson. Stein’s second portrait of Picasso is one of her more opaque texts, to be sure, but with its recurring verbal motifs operating as a kind of literary analogue to musical canon form, it may be seen as a work that explores how two portraitists can represent one another, the theme that Thomson would address many decades later in “Buffie Johnson.” Indeed, in “If I Told Him,” Stein continues, “Now actively repeat at all, now actively repeat at all, now actively repeat at all,” and this is a directive that Thomson appears to take to heart in both of the musical portraits discussed here.58 In representing his experience of Johnson’s presence and her impression of his—​her act of drawing him as he “composes” her—​ Thomson creates a portrait whose subject matter is the very process of producing a work of portraiture, of encountering, perceiving, interpreting, and depicting an individual’s identity through artistic creation. In other words, this composition is, ultimately, a study of musical representation itself, as well as of music’s capacity to represent the self. PIERRE BOULEZ’S PLI SELON PLI: PORTRAIT DE MALLARMÉ AND “MUSIQUE, PAR EXCELLENCE”

Where Thomson took both the literary portraits of Stein and her philosophical and critical essays on the subjects of identity and linguistic representation as sources of influence for the creation of his own musical portraits, Pierre Boulez found inspiration in Stéphane Mallarmé’s poetry and essays on aesthetics in devising his portrait of the French poet. In the

36

( 36 )   Musical Portraits

case of Boulez’s portrait, however, the composer also incorporated the texts of a number of Mallarmé’s poems into the musical texture. The resulting work, Pli selon pli: Portrait de Mallarmé, was composed across a number of years and repeatedly revised over the course of several decades, through the 1980s.59 Comprised of five movements for soprano and a changing ensemble that were written out of the sequence in which Boulez eventually ordered them, Pli selon pli opens with “Don” (Gift, composed 1961–​1962), based on Mallarmé’s “Don du poëme”; continues with three “Improvisations” (the first two composed in 1957 and the third in 1960) on Mallarmé’s sonnets “Le vierge, le vivace et le bel aujourd’hui” (The Lively, Lovely and Virginal Today), “Une dentelle s’abolit” (Abolished the Curtains Half-​Spread), and “A la nue accablante tu” (Still by the Crushing Cloud); and concludes with “Tombeau” (Tomb, 1959–​ 1961), based on Mallarmé’s poetic remembrance of the symbolist poet Paul Verlaine, “Tombeau de Verlaine” (the titles are given here as they appear in translations by William Matheson).60 The piece came together gradually: having drafted “Improvisation I” and “Improvisation II,” Boulez started composing “Tombeau” and, realizing he had begun to conceive of it as a commentary on the two Mallarmé “Improvisations,” he stopped briefly in order to round out the earlier set, writing “Improvisation III.” He then completed “Tombeau,” and finally composed “Don” in order to provide a symmetrical structure to the overall portrait, framing the three “Improvisations” by balancing the conclusion with an introduction.61 Boulez’s interest in literature was extensive, and he developed his literary theories across his career through numerous critical essays, in which he frequently raised the subject of Mallarmé’s poetic style and innovations. He wrote repeatedly about other poets and authors as well and composed incidental music for a production of the Oresteia, and around a decade after completing the first version of Pli selon pli he composed a piece evoking the poet e. e. cummings and incorporating his texts, cummings ist der Dichter (cummings Is the Poet, 1970, rev. 1986). Boulez’s collected prose also includes a number of literary portraits, brief character studies of composers including Bartók, Berg, Debussy, Schoenberg, and Webern.62 In his 1960 essay “Sonate, Que me Veux-​tu?” (Sonata, What Do You Want from Me?), Boulez, writing of the literary works that inspired the innovative formal techniques he developed in his Third Piano Sonata, lists Mallarmé and James Joyce as especially influential, explaining: Musical considerations have counted less than the literary contacts I have happened to have. Finally, my current form of thought arose more from reflections about literature than about music. . . . It seems to me . . . that certain writers have gone, as of now, much further than musicians in the realm of organization, of the mental structure of a work.63

  37

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 37 )

It is a particular sort of formal self-​awareness that Boulez finds in the modern novel and poem, and that informs his compositional innovation and his portrait of Mallarmé more specifically.64 Boulez was especially inspired by Mallarmé’s complex ideas about the relationships between poetry and music, and about choice and openness as factors in artistic performance and reception.65 Mallarmé’s poetry is notoriously challenging, and the obscurity of his imagery and use of language open his writings to a vast range of potential interpretations. The difficulty of Mallarmé’s poetry was widely acknowledged during his lifetime: even in France, in the period of his career in which he experienced the greatest popularity, his work was widely considered inscrutable, prompting French audiences to ask facetiously for the chance to read it in French translation.66 Reflecting a similar frustration, Marcel Proust wrote of Mallarmé in the last decade of the nineteenth century, “How unfortunate that so gifted a man should become insane every time he takes up the pen.”67 Mallarmé himself characterized his own works as deliberately available to multiple interpretations; he explained that he hoped his poems would reveal different meanings to the same reader on different days, and famously, describing his poetry by analogy to visual art, wrote that his desire was, “To paint not the thing but the effect that it produces.”68 The task of constructing an open text that offers the audience the chance to complete the art piece through an interactive form of readership was a preoccupation for Mallarmé, particularly in his effort to create his unfinished Le Livre, which Boulez encountered through its posthumous publication in a 1957 edition with an introduction by Jacques Schérer. Boulez’s musical portrait of Mallarmé incorporates something analogous to the way the poet’s works invite and even require participatory acts of readership. Its open formal attributes invite the performer to be an active collaborator in the structuring of the text, for example by leaving to the players’ discretion the ordering of various gestures, passages, and text fragments in “Don.” This structure also allows the listener to form a unique and personal interpretation of this complex and monumental composition.69 Boulez believed that in taking a critical approach to one’s aesthetic forebears, an artist is able to initiate a dialogue with the past in his own works. He writes: “If you question the masters of an earlier period with perseverance and conviction you become the medium of their replies: they speak of you and through you.”70 Given his view that the artist can channel the responses of the predecessors he “questions,” it may seem unsurprising that Boulez stated in an interview in 1996 that Pli selon pli is a “double portrait: It is a portrait of Mallarmé and myself. Of course Mallarmé is a poet who has been terribly important to me. The kind of relationship we had, our working together—​in spite of the difference in centuries!—​brings up somebody else: That is the portrait of a kind of mixture of Mallarmé and me, finally.”71

38

( 38 )   Musical Portraits

Pli selon pli was thus, for Boulez, the product of a process resembling collaboration with the deceased poet, a portrait in which Mallarmé spoke back through him as though the two were producing portraits of one another within the same work of art, in a manner that reflects, on a grander scale, Virgil Thomson’s portrait of Buffie Johnson drawing a portrait of him.72 In this way Pli selon pli comes across as a hybrid work, an instance of both musical and literary portraiture that depicts its subject through a rich intertextual interpretation of the relationship between the two artistic media. Boulez wrote of the interaction between these forms: “I have a profound belief in reciprocal influences between literature and music, not only through direct and effective collaboration, but at least as much through the transmutation of modes of thought which hitherto seemed confined to one or other of these two means of expression.”73 The basis of Boulez’s portrait is the selected works by Mallarmé that he incorporates, in some cases in their entirety and in others in fragments. In using Mallarmé’s texts to evoke the poet’s identity, Boulez engages in a representational mode that resembles a device that formed one of the oldest roots of literary portraiture, the classical rhetorical technique of prosopopeia. An orator engages this device when representing an individual by speaking as though in the person’s words and voice. Quintilian writes that in prosopopeia, “we display the thoughts of our opponents, as they themselves would do in a soliloquy. . . . In this kind of figure, it is allowable even to bring down the gods from heaven, evoke the dead, and give voices to cities and states.”74 Through prosopopeia, in other words, the living channel the dead within a single speech act, in a manner that resembles Boulez’s claim that by sufficiently questioning Mallarmé’s works he is able to make the poet “speak of . . . and through” him in Pli selon pli. The term prosopopeia derives from the phrase “to make a face,” and it is through the metaphoric conjuring of an individual’s likeness that the rhetorical device becomes an early root of portraiture. Paul de Man writes that in prosopopeia, “Voice assumes mouth, eye and finally face. . . . Prosopopeia is the trope of autobiography, by which one’s name . . . is made as intelligible and memorable as a face.”75 And so, through a triple layering of metaphors that reach across artistic media, Boulez retools Mallarmé’s language in Pli selon pli through an act of prosopopeia as a means of summoning his voice, transmuting it into music to conjure the impression of his face. This makes of Pli selon pli a portrait that shares aspects of the genre as it is manifested in the literary, musical, and visual arts. Nevertheless, Boulez’s conclusion in “Sonate, Que me Veux-​ tu?” might seem to preclude the use of prosopopeia to conjure the presence of the author. He suggests that in their writings, figures such as Mallarmé and Joyce have succeeded in effacing themselves and creating a kind of

  39

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 39 )

“absolute” literature: “The text becomes ‘anonymous’ in them, one might say, ‘speaking for itself and without an author’s voice.’ If it were necessary to find a profound motive for the work I have tried to describe, it would be the search for such ‘anonymity.’ ”76 To characterize this phenomenon, Boulez adopts a phrase Mallarmé wrote in a letter to Verlaine, “y parlant de lui-​même et sans voix d’auteur.”77 Boulez later elaborated that, in his view, artworks should go beyond the [artist’s] personality. . . . That is when I use the term “anonymity”: When the writer or the composer is no longer necessary as a presence; when the work goes beyond the person and is much stronger than the person himself. . . . With “anonymous” I mean beyond the author. A work that remains in itself—​and this is very important.78

Boulez’s theory of anonymity and the loss of the author’s voice in symbolist and modernist literature resonates strongly with the argument of the influential essay “The Death of the Author” by the French structuralist critic Roland Barthes, written in 1968, only a few years after “Sonate, Que me Veux-​tu?” In this essay Barthes proposes that in the novel, “As soon as a fact is narrated . . . the voice loses its origin, the author enters into his own death, writing begins.”79 Barthes writes this thesis in part to oppose the persistence of critical approaches to literature in which “The author still reigns” and “the explanation of a work is always sought in the man or woman who produced it, as if it were always in the end . . . the voice of a single person, the author ‘confiding in us.’ ”80 But in spite of Boulez’s claims about the absolutism of the poetry of the author whose works form the textual basis of Pli selon pli, this composition in fact accomplishes the opposite of the kind of anonymity that Boulez describes. Instead of marking the death of this author, divorcing his voice from its origin, or reaching beyond his personality, the composition uses Mallarmé’s words to summon his presence, or “make his face,” through the process of prosopopeia in which the author’s words gesture directly toward his identity. Pli selon pli conjures Mallarmé in two principal respects, one essentially narrative and the other more conceptual, but each produced by way of Boulez’s experiments with sound and with musical form, from movement to movement and across the work as a whole. And through these representational modes, the composition, as innovative as it is both structurally and as a work of musical representation, evokes the likeness of the deceased author rather than announcing his death. In this manner, Pli selon pli comes in some respects to resemble the rather traditional critical form that Barthes sought to move beyond, the “His Life and Works” genre of biography or literary portrait.

40

( 40 )   Musical Portraits

In the narrative sense, the five movements of Pli selon pli form an arc that begins with a birth and ends with a death and crosses through a life in between. The first movement, “Don,” is based on a poem Mallarmé published early in his career, in 1865, at the early age of twenty-​three. The theme of this text is the creation of a poem (Boulez suggests that in his musical arrangement, Mallarmé’s “don du poëme” is transformed into a “don de l’oeuvre,” a “gift of the [musical] work”),81 described according to the metaphor of a new mother’s harrowing labor and birth. Boulez uses only the first line, “Je t’apporte l’enfant d’une nuit d’Idumée!” (I bring you the child of an Idumaean night!); Mallarmé’s original continues, “O la berceuse, avec ta fille et l’innocence /​De vos pieds froids, acceuille une horrible naissance” (O nursing mother, with your child and the innocence /​Of your cold feet, receive this horrible birth).82 As Boulez put it, “if you read the entire poem, that is a kind of excruciating experience of giving birth to the poem.”83 Boulez’s first movement follows the poem’s opening line with individual words and phrases borrowed from the three sonnets that are adapted in the ensuing “Improvisations.” “Don” introduces these fragments in a perfunctory manner as though giving the gift of life to the work’s subsequent poems and their musical settings, which will fully take form and find their legs in the movements to follow.84 The sonnets that form the basis of the three “Improvisations” that come next were published in 1885, 1887, and 1895, respectively, when Mallarmé was in his forties and fifties. The final movement, whose title is abstracted from Mallarmé’s “Tombeau de Verlaine” to the shorter and less specific “Tombeau,” dates to 1897, and though it was written to commemorate Verlaine shortly after his passing, it becomes, in Boulez’s hands, a reminder of the death of Mallarmé the year after he wrote the poem. In this movement, Boulez incorporates only the final line of the sonnet, “Un peu profond ruisseau calomnié la mort” (A shallow stream calumniated death).85 In this musical setting the text enters late in the movement, arranged in a highly melismatic fashion that renders it essentially unintelligible, until the final two syllables, “la mort,” meaning “death.” These words can be heard more clearly, at the very conclusion, embedded within an extended elegiac drone in the orchestra and “Parlé sans timbre, uniquement sur le souffle” (Spoken without timbre, only breathed), as the score instructs. By combining these five poems in this manner, Pli selon pli: Portrait de Mallarmé offers something analogous in form to a chronological literary portrait or biographical study of Mallarmé, the type of text that might bear the subtitle “His Life and Works,” in which key poems spanning the middle and late periods of the poet’s career are framed by musical settings of the first line of an early poem that implies the subject of his birth and the closing words of a late sonnet that commemorates his death.86

  41

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 41 )

In addition to serving up a select poetic chronology and honoring Mallarmé’s life, Pli selon pli also operates as a portrait of its subject at a deeper level, by offering an attempt at realizing Mallarmé’s aesthetic goals, which he described in his essays using a complex musical metaphor for the way he wished to develop poetic language. Pli selon pli attempts to achieve, through an innovative approach to musical form, what Boulez called “a musical equivalent, both poetic and formal, to Mallarmé’s poetry.”87 As a model for his own experimentation with form, Boulez adopts Mallarmé’s use of traditional poetic structures such as the sonnet as a framework within which to experiment with syntax. Boulez stated that “the poems that are in verse are extremely disciplined,”88 but also that “Mallarmé tried to rethink the foundations of French grammar,” and “never has the French language been taken so far in the matter of syntax,” before or after the poet’s life.89 He compared this combination of formal traditionalism and syntactical complexity with the serialist composer Anton Webern’s pervasive but frequently indiscernible use of the imitative technique of musical canon.90 In the view of the poet and essayist Paul Valéry, Mallarmé’s vexed relationship with music could be characterized as “une sublime jalousie” (a sublime jealousy).91 Mallarmé regularly attended musical performances, with notebook and pencil in hand, listening with voracious attention for what he could assimilate into the language of his poetry.92 What he wished to achieve was a literature that would rise to the challenge posed by the ineffable and evocative expressivity of music, and in replicating this power would ultimately replace it; the resulting poetry would be “Musique, par excellence.”93 Mary Breatnach writes that for Mallarmé, the term “music” stood for—​in addition to its standard meaning—​“a system of relationships, an essentially silent structuring force which the poet believed underlay not only musical sounds, but the whole of existence, a force which was nothing less than the key to an understanding of the nature of the universe.”94 Mallarmé sought to create poetry that could express itself in a language equivalent to music, that could, in his words, “find . . . a way of accomplishing the transposition of the symphony to the Book” and thus reveal “the totality of the relationships existing between everything.”95 Music is a recurrent theme in the poems Boulez assembles in his portrait, whether it is vocal, instrumental, animal, silent, muffled, or carried by a distant echo. “Don du poëme” entreats the nursing mother: Et ta voix rappelant viole et clavecin, Avec le doigt fané presseras-​tu le sein Par qui coule en blancheur sibylline la femme

42

( 42 )   Musical Portraits

Pour les lèvres que l’air du vierge azur affame? (And with your voice recalling viol and clavecin, /​With your faded finger, will you press the breast /​Whence flows in the sibylline whiteness woman /​For lips made hungry by the blue virgin air?)96 The voice of this mother of poetry resembles the muted timbres of Baroque instruments when their strings are bowed, plucked, or struck. And in “Le vierge, le vivace et le bel aujourd’hui,” Mallarmé evokes (absent) music in the recollection of the silent singing voice of the swan trapped on an icy lake: Un cygnet d’autrefois se souvient que c’est lui Magnifique mais qui sans espoir se délivre Pour n’avoir pas chanté la région où vivre Quand du stérile hiver a resplendi l’ennui. (A swan of past times remembers he’s the one /​magnificent but surviving without hope /​for not having sung a land where he could stop /​ when the ennui of sterile winter has shone.)97 “Une dentelle s’abolit” follows up on the references to the antiquated instruments of the viol and clavecin in “Don du poëme” with an even more arcane gesture toward an obsolete strummed instrument: Mais, chez qui du rêve se dore Tristement dort une mandore Au creux néant musicien. (But with him of the gilded dream /​a mandola sleeps in sorrow /​in a hollow of musical zero.)98 The mandola is a round-​backed stringed instrument that is strummed and can accompany singing. Here it rests “asleep” and unplayed; perhaps the “hollow of musical zero” is silent like the swan’s unsung melody, but one can imagine that the breeze entering through the lace curtains might cause the strings to vibrate like those of an Aeolian harp. This gesture toward the sound of the plucked strings is emphasized by the rhythmic repetition of the syllable “dor,” with its percussive “d,” in the French “. . . se dore /​Tristement dort une mandore.” Perhaps the last tercet of the poem implies that the instrument might give birth to music, providing a counterpart to the birth of the poem in “Don du poëme”: Telle que verse quelque fenêtre Selon nul ventre que le sien,

  43

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 43 )

Filial on aurait pu naître. (Such that toward some pane /​involving no womb but its own /​one might be born as son.)99 In the following sonnet in Pli selon pli, “A la nue accablante tu,” the hint of a gust of air producing musical sounds from an instrument is compounded by a reference to the trumpet, which in this instance is heard as a muffled, distant sound rather than as music emerging directly from the original source: A la nue accablante tu Basse de basalte et de laves A même les échos esclaves Par une trompe sans vertu (Stilled by the crushing cloud /​low of basalt and lava /​by even the enslaved /​echoes of a trumpet not loud [without quality].)100 It seems implicit in this highly abstract poem that the trumpet is sounding the distress signal of a capsized ship; beneath the sea foam, the trumpet’s timbre is stifled and indistinct, rendered ineffective in its task. This notion is mirrored at the conclusion of the poem by an alternative interpretation of the foam as the white hair of a sunken siren. From underwater, the voice of this mythical creature, whose seductive song tempted Odysseus on his voyage home in Homer’s tale, is silenced, only a whispered or remembered echo of a sound. In the final poem of the set, “Tombeau de Verlaine,” Mallarmé returns to the theme of birdsong first taken up with reference to the swan trapped in the ice: Ici presque toujours si le ramier roucoule Cet immatériel deuil opprime de maints Nubiles plis l’astre mûri des lendemains Dont un scintillement argentera la foule. (Usually if the ringdove coos here /​this immaterial grief with many a cloud / enfolding crushes tomorrow’s ripened star / whose scintillations will besilver the crowd.)101 The sonic ambiguity of the previous poems, with their unsinging voices, instruments at rest, and sounds carried by echoes or muffled by water, is here augmented by the use of the conditional tense; we are told that something usually happens if the ringdove coos, but do not know whether, in fact, it does coo. The sounds conjured in Mallarmé’s works seem finally to resonate in the real world through Boulez’s music, whose timbral variety and innovation evokes the silent birdsong, echoes, wind-​strummed strings, and glittering

44

( 44 )   Musical Portraits

atmospheres of the poet’s texts. In “Don,” for example, the juxtaposed decaying sustained notes and abrupt staccatos of the vocal line “recall viol and clavecin” like the voice described in “Don du poëme,” an association supported by the held notes in winds, brass, and strings that surround the brief tones produced by the plucked harp, hammered tubular bells, vibraphone, and gong, and the sparkling combination of the celeste, mandolin, and guitar. The high-​pitched embellished gestures the soprano sings at the start of Improvisation I call to mind the voice of the swan trapped in the ice in “Le vierge, le vivace et le bel aujourd’hui.” The shimmering, almost iridescent timbres of plucked and struck instruments, including harp, vibraphone, chimes, bells, and crotales in Improvisation II resemble how one might imagine the sounds of Mallarmé’s sleeping mandola “in a hollow of musical zero” in “Une dentelle s’abolit.” The muted trombone that blows the first note of Improvisation III is a more direct representation of the “echoes of a trumpet not loud” that sound the alarm in the corresponding poem. And the recurrence of the quiet attacks in piano, percussion, harps, and tubular bells in Tombeau construct an envelope of sound that seems to come as close as a set of instruments can to evoking the atmosphere Mallarmé describes in the redolent phrase, “many a cloud /​enfolding crushes tomorrow’s ripened star /​whose scintillations will besilver the crowd.” Boulez appears to attempt to fulfill Mallarmé’s ideas about the relationship between poetry and music in Pli selon pli through a process the composer described as “osmosis,” “transformation,”102 and “transmutation.”103 He brings Mallarmé’s poetry together with musical sounds and structures in a way that aims to turn the language into something resembling the poet’s “Musique, par excellence,” absorbing the language into the music and making the connection between these art forms a main subject of the portrait. As he explains, “The relationship between poem and music is not only on the plane of emotional significance: I have tried to push the alliance still further, to the very roots of the musical invention and structure.”104 Elsewhere he writes not specifically about Pli selon pli, but in a reflection on the relationship between the arts, “In music, word and thought are one.”105 This theme of the association between expressive media is implied in the title “Pli selon pli,” which, Boulez writes, “indicates the meaning and direction of the work.”106 The phrase, which comes from Mallarmé’s poem “Remémoration d’amis belges” (Recollection of Belgian Friends), is not idiomatic in French and poses a challenge to translators. As Breatnach has shown, though the approximation “fold upon fold” might sound most familiar in English, the French words come closer to meaning “fold according to fold,” an expression that implies a deep examination of the structural associations between music and poetry and an interest in

  45

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 45 )

experimenting with how they can be made to fold in on, in the manner of, and as determined by one another.107 Though Boulez does not adopt any additional text from “Remémoration d’amis belges” in Pli selon pli, the poem is essential to the development of the five-​movement portrait. This sonnet describes in abstract terms the rising of the mist in the Belgian city of Bruges to reveal the old stones that construct its buildings. Boulez describes the poem as follows:  “Under something absolutely vague, which you cannot grasp, suddenly the reality is there, in front of you. . . . For me . . . you have to wait patiently before the real face of the world is revealed to you.”108 In the liner notes to the first recording of Pli selon pli, Boulez explains that much as the mist lifts to uncover the architecture of Bruges, “In a similar manner the development of the five pieces reveals, ‘fold upon fold,’ a portrait of Mallarmé himself.”109 At first blush, the series of increasingly complex musical treatments from one “Improvisation” to the next in Pli selon pli arguably appears to do the opposite, to enshroud further and further, with every musical fold, the already abstract poetic symbolism. Mallarmé’s language, with an abstraction that famously often borders on the unintelligible for even the most diligent reader, becomes progressively more difficult to make out in each successive vocal setting, the last of which uses only three lines of the poem, and the labyrinthine musical forms simultaneously grow less obvious in their connection to the French sonnet forms Mallarmé uses. But on closer examination, it becomes clear that Boulez is performing, through music, an archaeological analysis of Mallarmé’s writings—​both the poems Boulez selects and the essays in which Mallarmé describes his ideas about music and poetry—​that gradually aims to lift the fog that blankets Mallarmé’s abstract use of language by setting the poems to musical interpretations that delve ever more deeply into the sonnets’ formal structures.110 In a published interview, Boulez explains of the middle movements of Pli selon pli: These Improvisations become an analysis of the sonnet structure, in a more and more detailed and more and more profound way. The first takes a sonnet and uncovers only its strophic character, which is not very intense work; the second is elaborated at the level of the line and verse itself—​in other words, it is already an analysis of the stanza; the third proceeds in the sense that the line itself has a particular structure in terms of its position within the sonnet.111

Boulez also characterized his settings of the text as progressively ornamented, from the first, in which the poem is declaimed quite simply, to the third, in which it is devoured by ornamentation.112 The three poems Boulez selects for his “Improvisations” conform to the Petrarchan sonnet

46

( 46 )   Musical Portraits

form: each is constructed of fourteen lines, split between an octet and sestet, which are further divided into pairs of quatrains and tercets. They also follow the same rhyme scheme, ABBA CCD EDE. “Le vierge, le vivace et le bel aujourd’hui” is built of alexandrines, the traditional twelve-​syllable line found in French poetry going back at least to the twelfth century; “Une dentelle s’abolit” and “A la nue accablante tu” consist of octosyllabic lines. James McCalla has shown through an analysis of Pli selon pli how the musical treatment of the sonnet form, at first closely aligned in an obvious manner, becomes progressively more complex in each “Improvisation.”113 “Improvisation I” is divided into two major sections, separating the two quatrains from the tercets that follow.114 Between these sections, a brief transition (measures 32–​45), itself split into two parts, sits awkwardly as a sort of interpolated miniature improvisation, in which, writes McCalla, Boulez “initiates his progressive disintegration of Mallarmé’s forms.”115 “Improvisation II” is also written in a binary division that maps onto the two-​part structure of the Petrarchan sonnet, but the separation between these sections is considerably more vague, and melismatic text-​setting and formal variability in the work (certain decisions are left to the discretion of the conductor and performers) replace the clear articulation and punctuation of the poem and relatively straightforward musical structure of “Improvisation I.”116 “Improvisation III,” which is based on what is arguably the most challenging of the Mallarmé poems assembled in Pli selon pli, finally brings the gradual breakdown of the musical transmutation of sonnet form to its furthest extreme. As noted earlier, only the first three lines of the poem are incorporated into the movement, and they are set to music in such a way that they become incomprehensible, converted into long, heavily ornamented melismas that transform the poem’s vowel sounds into meaningless vocables and all but bury the consonants and any sense of punctuation. By contrast with “Improvisation I,” in which the musical structures are dictated by the language, here the poetry is fully absorbed into the surrounding orchestration, which has also dispensed with the binary form, replacing it with something fractured and more opaque.117 Mallarmé’s poem disintegrates fully late in the movement when the vocal line is no longer set to words, and the singer is instead instructed to utter sounds sometimes with the mouth closed and at other times with it open (the third line of the poem returns at the conclusion of the movement). Across the three “Improvisations,” Boulez’s musical setting has progressively plumbed the depths of Mallarmé’s poetic forms and syntactical innovations, in a way that mirrors how Mallarmé’s texts reached perpetually away from clarity of meaning and syntax, and toward a state of “Musique, par excellence.”118 Boulez wrote Pli selon pli principally as a portrait of Mallarmé, but he also viewed it as a form of self-​portrait. The work is a double portrait in

  47

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 47 )

which Boulez worked out a method of “transmuting” poetry into music that would bring together Mallarmé’s theory of an ideal poetry as “Musique, par excellence” with his own notion of a literary music inspired by the symbolist and modernist syntax of Mallarmé and Joyce. Additionally, while the portrait follows a narrative structure to depict Mallarmé across his life, from his birth, through a chronological tour of his mature poetic writings, and to his death, it accounts for a considerable portion of Boulez’s career as well, as about thirty-​two years span the period from his first work on the movements that would make up Pli selon pli to the completion of his final revisions. And the piece also incorporates and adapts fragments of other works by Boulez: the vocal line in “Improvisation I,” for example, is based on the pitch sequence in the unpublished “Strophes” for solo flute (1957),119 and this movement also reuses and orchestrates material from the solo piano Notations, numbers 5 and 9 (1945).120 But Boulez saw the work not only as a portrait of the author and, perhaps more abstractly, a portrait of the composer, but also as the material from which a listener can fashion a self-​portrait. Though the notion that a work of art permits spectators to explore their own identities is far from novel, Boulez offers a unique metaphor to link the experience of contemplating a portrait with the mirror’s reflection and with the layering of representations and art forms that inspired the title of this work: The listener can make his own portrait after that. He can look at himself in the work. Sometimes in museums some paintings are protected by glass. Francis Bacon likes his paintings to be presented like that, so that people are confusing the painting and their own face reflected in this glass panel. That is exactly the comparison I would like to make for the person listening to this piece of mine.121

Pli selon pli presents a complex sonic adaptation of some of the most abstract poetry of Mallarmé, but on close listening, it might offer to lift the fog that veils our own sense of who we are, what constitutes our selves at a given moment, and where we stand in relation to the art we contemplate and interpret. As listeners, we are invited to seek out our faint reflections in the music, as they are superimposed, fold according to transparent fold over the likenesses of Mallarmé and Boulez. CONCLUSION

In “Buffie Johnson” and Pli selon pli, Thomson and Boulez, like most painters and authors of portraits in the visual arts and literature, aim to represent something of their subjects’ unique identities or selves. Thomson created

48

( 48 )   Musical Portraits

his portrait in front of his sitter, in order to depict what he called “presence,” a kind of energy or attitude that he felt people naturally and spontaneously reveal during a personal encounter. Boulez engaged in a creative process that recalls the oratorical device of prosopopeia, recycling and transmuting Mallarmé’s language in order to conjure the impression of his presence. And in their very different portraits, both Thomson and Boulez portray their subjects’ artistic processes: Thomson composes a depiction of Johnson’s act of sketching in charcoal, while Boulez delves deeply into the experimental literary techniques that Mallarmé developed within the framework of centuries-​old poetic forms. In an essay about painted portraiture, the French philosopher Jean-​Luc Nancy writes that the portrait does not merely depict a subject’s identity, but in fact contains it: “The person ‘in itself ’ is ‘in’ the painting. Devoid of any inside, the painting is the inside or the intimacy of the person. It is, in short, the subject of its subject.”122 The portrait, for Nancy, is not so much a representation as a presentation; it does not portray the self, but rather originates it. According to this notion, we can understand the portrait as revealing the self to us directly and without mediation, rather than as a form of secondary source material that might help us in coming to understand a person’s identity, or as a translucent layer, like the surface of Mallarmé’s icy lake or his lace curtain waving in the window, that renders the subject at once visible but also separate from us.123 To the extent that we can consider Thomson’s and Boulez’s portraits as also being self-​ portraits—​something that both authors suggested, Thomson in his title and Boulez in his later statements—​this directness arises out of the sense that Johnson and Mallarmé are simultaneously represented by their portraits and engaged in creating portraits of their composers, from within the music. Nancy writes, “The portrait is less the recollection of a (memorable) identity than it is the recollection of an (immemorial) intimacy.”124 It is ultimately the intimacy of relationships—​between Thomson and Stein, Thomson and Johnson, Boulez and the writings of Mallarmé, and the listener and the sounds of these compositions—​that is most compellingly depicted in the overlapping folds of music, language, and visual art in these musical portraits.

NOTES 1. William Hazlitt, “On the Imitation of Nature (1814),” in A. R. Waller and Arnold Glover (eds.), The Collected Works of William Hazlitt, 12 vols. (London: J. M. Dent, 1904), xi: 221. 2.  George Eliot, Daniel Deronda, 2 vols. (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1876), i: 119. 3.  A. S. Byatt, Portraits in Fiction (London: Chatto and Windus, 2001), 1. 4. Byatt, Portraits in Fiction, 1.

  49

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 49 )

5. Byatt, Portraits in Fiction, 91–​2. 6. Theophrastan character types were revived and became widely influential in the Renaissance. Wendy Steiner, Exact Resemblance to Exact Resemblance:  The Literary Portraiture of Gertrude Stein (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1978), 9. 7. In the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, the literary portrait became an important vehicle for authors experimenting with new techniques of writing. Walter Pater, Maxim Gorky, Lytton Strachey, and Virginia Woolf each wrote multiple texts in the genre, and the titles of Henry James’s The Portrait of a Lady and James Joyce’s A Portrait of the Artist as a Young Man indicate that these turn-​of-​the-​century novels, published around three decades apart, operate by analogy to novel-​length portraits as well. 8. For a variety of approaches to the genre, see Edmund Heier, “‘The Literary Portrait’ as a Device of Characterization,” Neophilologus 60.3 ( July 1976):  321–​2; Ulla Haselstein, “Gertrude Stein’s Portraits of Matisse and Picasso,” New Literary History 34.4 (Autumn 2003): 724; Steiner, Exact Resemblance, 3. Studies of literary descriptions of painted portraits are found in Françoise Meltzer, Salome and the Dance of Writing: Portraits of Mimesis in Literature (Chicago:  University of Chicago Press, 1987); Michal Peled Ginsburg, Portrait Stories (New York: Fordham University Press, 2015). A. S. Byatt describes her own incorporation of painted portraits in fictional narratives in Portraits in Fiction. The broadest conception of literary portraiture is proposed by Jeffrey Wallen, who recommends against the imposition of any restrictive definition of the genre in terms of form, technique, or content. Jeffrey Wallen, “Between Text and Image: The Literary Portrait,” a/​ b: Auto/​Biography Studies 10.1 (1995): 56–​8. 9. Hermione Lee, Biography: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 2–​3. 10. David Fuller, “Of Portraits, ‘Sapho,’ and Couperin:  Titles and Characters in French Instrumental Music of the High Baroque,” Music and Letters 78.2 (1997): 155–​6. The production of these literary portraits came to be instrumental to the configuration of salon society during the short period of their intense popularity. 11. Fuller, “Of Portraits, ‘Sapho,’ ” 161. 12. Aspects of literary portraiture have influenced the genre’s visual counterpart as well. In Janice Krasnow’s 1999 oil painting “Portrait of Serena,” for example, the subject is depicted as a likeness conveyed in text rather than shapes and colors: Krasnow has painted, in black lettering over a pale background, the words, “vivid streaks of blonde and brown hair and uniquely broad visible cheekbones.” Donna Gustafson and Susan Sidlauskas, “One. 2. Many: Portraits by Numbers,” in Donna Gustafson and Susan Sidlauskas (eds.), Striking Resemblance: The Changing Art of Portraiture (New Brunswick, NJ: Zimmerli Art Museum at Rutgers University; London: Prestel, 2014), 27. 13. Joshua S. Walden, “Composing Character in Musical Portraits: Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach and L’Aly Rupalich,” Musical Quarterly 91.2 (Fall–​Winter 2008): 379–​411. For identifications of the subjects of C. P. E. Bach’s portraits, see Peter Wollny (ed.), Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach: Miscellaneous Keyboard Works II (Los Altos, CA: Packard Humanities Institute, 2005), xvii; Darrell M. Berg, “C. P. E. Bach’s Character Pieces and His Friendship Circle,” in Stephen Clark (ed.), C. P. E. Bach Studies (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), 6. 14. Paul Roberts, Claude Debussy (London: Phaidon, 2008), 105. 15. Composer Peter Gena also uses language, either quoted or implied, as an element of musical portraiture in his series Socio-​Political Portraits, which includes McKinley (1983), Mother Jones (1985), John Henry (1986), and Joe Hill Fantasy (1992–​1993). In these works, which represent figures from American political history and the labor movement, Gena incorporates elements of popular songs by and about his subjects, in some cases using their texts and in others melodic fragments that will remind listeners of the associated lyrics. See Peter Gena, “Socio-​Political Portraits,” http://​petergena.com/​political. html, accessed June 21, 2016. Tyshawn Sorey’s “Josephine Baker: A Portrait” (2016), a ninety-​minute work for vocalist and ensemble, similarly merges the words from a number of the songs she made famous with new poetry by Claudia Rankine, to form a multimedia representation of the American-​born singer, dancer, and actor who made her career in Paris in the early twentieth century.

50

( 50 )   Musical Portraits

16. Virgil Thomson, Virgil Thomson (New  York:  Knopf, 1966), 97. On the relationship between Thomson and Stein, see Thomas Dilworth and Susan Holbrook (eds.), The Letters of Gertrude Stein and Virgil Thomson: Composition as Conversation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 3–​22. A  collection of several of Thomson’s writings on Stein can be found in Richard Kostelanetz (ed.), Virgil Thomson:  A  Reader:  Selected Writings 1924–​1984 (New York: Routledge, 2002), 201–​13. 17. Linda Simon (ed.), Gertrude Stein:  A  Composite Portrait (New  York:  Discus Books, 1974), 121. 18. Kostelanetz, Virgil Thomson: A Reader, 212. 19. Thomson, Virgil Thomson, 90. 20. Anthony Carl Tommasini, “The Musical Portraits by Virgil Thomson,” Musical Quarterly 70.2 (Spring 1984): 239; Thomson, Virgil Thomson, 123. 21. Thomson, Virgil Thomson, 124. 22. Vincent Giroud, Picasso and Gertrude Stein (New  York:  Metropolitan Museum of Art; New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2006), 20. 23. Giroud, Picasso and Gertrude Stein, 16–​17. For more on the close relationship between Stein and Picasso, see Lucy Daniel, Gertrude Stein (London: Reaktion, 2009), 57–​9. 24. Giroud, Picasso and Gertrude Stein, 26–​7. 25. Giroud, Picasso and Gertrude Stein, 29. 26. Daniel, Gertrude Stein, 64. 27. Giroud, Picasso and Gertrude Stein, 30. 28. Giroud, Picasso and Gertrude Stein, 34. 29. Stein’s literary portraits in turn influenced other modernist visual artists in their work in the genre. For example, Charles Demuth found inspiration in her works for his “poster portraits,” a series that included his image of William Carlos Williams addressed in the introduction of this book, as well as his portrait of Stein, titled “Love Love Love.” See Daniel, Gertrude Stein, 91. On her influence on visual portraiture, see also Wendy Steiner, “Postmodern Portraits,” Art Journal 46.3 (Autumn 1987): 173–​7. 30. Gertrude Stein, “Portraits and Repetition,” in Lectures in America (London: Virago, 1985, orig. 1935), 178. For some years in the early stage of her career, Stein attempted to develop a theory of human typology. She worked out her ideas in a number of texts, including The Making of Americans, written over seven years between 1905 and 1912, in the middle of which period she produced her first portraits. On Stein’s categorizations of character types, see Steiner, Exact Resemblance, 32–​41. 31. Stein, “Portraits and Repetition,” 181, 171; Steiner, “Postmodern Portraits,” 173. 32. Steiner, “Postmodern Portraits,” 174. 33. Steiner, Exact Resemblance, 29. On the influence of James’s psychology on Stein’s thought, see also Allison Blizzard, Portraits of the 20th Century Self:  An Interartistic Study of Gertrude Stein’s Literary Portraits and Early Modernist Portraits by Paul Cézanne, Henri Matisse and Pablo Picasso (Frankfurt am Main and Berlin: Peter Lang, 2004), 36–​40. 34. Steiner, Exact Resemblance, 30. 35. Steiner, Exact Resemblance, 31. 36. Stein, “Portraits and Repetition,” 197–​8. Steiner divides Stein’s portrait-writing into three periods, the first from 1908 to 1913, the second from 1913 to 1925, and the third lasting from 1926 until her death twenty years later. Steiner, Exact Resemblance, 65. 37. Stein, “Portraits and Repetition,” 183. 38. Steiner, Exact Resemblance, 44. 39. Stein, “Portraits and Repetition,” 198. See also her description of this process on 178. 40. As Stein writes in “Portraits and Repetition,” 188–​92, around 1912 she expanded her process of listening and talking to include looking as well. 41. On Stein’s writings about insistence as a technique she developed throughout her literary oeuvre, see Steiner, Exact Resemblance, 49–​50. 42. Stein, “Portraits and Repetition,” 167–​8. 43. Stein, “Portraits and Repetition,” 198. 44. Stein, “Portraits and Repetition,” 198.

  51

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 51 )

45. Virgil Thomson, “Of Portraits and Operas,” Antaeus 21/​22 (Spring/​Summer 1976): 208–​10. 46. Virgil Thomson, Preface to Anthony Tommasini, Virgil Thomson’s Musical Portraits (Hillsdale, NY: Pendragon Press, 1986), ix–​x (x). 47. Tommasini, “Musical Portraits by Virgil Thomson,” 243. 48. Thomson, Virgil Thomson, 124. 49. Thomson, Preface, x. 50. Thomson, Preface, ix. 51. The directness with which these representations aim to recreate the effect of the unmediated impression one has in a fleeting encounter with another person reflects what philosopher and literary critic Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht has called the “production of presence.” Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht, Production of Presence: What Meaning Cannot Convey (Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press, 2004). A similar effect of an unmediated, momentary impression is produced by this book’s cover, which depicts a close-​up black-​and-​white photograph of Gumbrecht staring out at the viewer, unsmiling and with tired eyes and unkempt hair, as though in a spontaneous and unprepared encounter with the reader. 52. Gumbrecht outlines his conception of epiphany as a mode of experiencing presence through art in Production of Presence, 94–​5, 111–​14. Carolyn Abbate distinguishes the “drastic” experience of music in performance from the “gnostic” act of interpreting a musical work, in terms that overlap with Gumbrecht’s theories of the production of presence and the interpretation of meaning. Carolyn Abbate, “Music—​Drastic or Gnostic?,” Critical Inquiry 30.3 (Spring 2004): 505–​36 (536). 53. Dilworth and Holbrook, Letters of Gertrude Stein and Virgil Thomson, 91–​2. 54. Dilworth and Holbrook, Letters of Gertrude Stein and Virgil Thomson, 102–​3. In a subsequent letter he mentions the portrait again to reiterate and elaborate on his praise (105). 55. Reprinted in Dilworth and Holbrook, Letters of Gertrude Stein and Virgil Thomson, 307. 56. Tommasini, Virgil Thomson’s Musical Portraits, 17. 57. Gertrude Stein, “If I Told Him: A Completed Portrait of Picasso,” in Joan Retallack (ed.), Gertrude Stein (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008), 190. 58. Stein, “If I Told Him,” 191. 59. On Boulez’s revisions, see Philippe Albèra, “Entretien avec Pierre Boulez,” in Philippe Albèra (ed.), Pli selon pli de Pierre Boulez:  Entretien et études (Geneva:  Éditions Contrechamps, 2003), 16. 60. The Mallarmé poems assembled in Pli selon pli are translated in William Matheson, “Fold Upon Fold: Stéphane Mallarmé and Pierre Boulez,” Yearbook of Comparative and General Literature 36 (1987): 75–​9 (77–​9). 61. Susan Bradshaw, “The Instrumental and Vocal Music,” in William Glock (ed.), Pierre Boulez: A Symposium (London: Eulenberg, 1986), 180–​1. 62. These are included in Pierre Boulez, Notes of an Apprenticeship, trans. Herbert Weinstock (New York: Knopf, 1968), 305–​91; and Pierre Boulez, Orientations:  Collected Writings, ed. Jean-​Jacques Nattiez, trans. Martin Cooper (Cambridge, MA:  Harvard University Press, 1985). Jonathan Goldman argues that, taken together, these miniature literary portraits merge into a larger literary self-​portrait of Boulez. Jonathan Goldman, The Musical Language of Pierre Boulez: Writings and Compositions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 41. 63. Pierre Boulez, “Sonate, Que me Veux-​ tu?,” trans. David Noakes and Paul Jacobs, Perspectives of New Music 1.2 (Spring 1963):  32. Boulez writes in particular about the unique typographical structure of Mallarmé’s Coup de Dés and the formal considerations he learned from Le Livre. 64. Boulez, “Sonate, Que me Veux-​tu?,” 32–​3. 65. Goldman, Musical Language of Pierre Boulez, 14. For an analysis of openness in artworks, see Umberto Eco, The Open Work, trans. Anna Cancogni (Cambridge, MA:  Harvard University Press, 1989). 66. Alex Ross, “Encrypted,” New Yorker, April 11, 2016. 67. Charles Rosen, Freedom and the Arts:  Essays on Music and Literature (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2012), 354.

52

( 52 )   Musical Portraits

68. “Peindre, non la chose, mais l’effet qu’elle produit.” Stéphane Mallarmé, Correspondance, ed. Lloyd James Austin and Henri Mondor, 11 vols. (Paris: Gallimard, 1959), i: 137. The literary scholar Malcolm Bowie writes that for readers of Mallarmé’s deliberately difficult poetry, “our most important collaboration with the poet begins when we ourselves agree to be uncertain.” Malcolm Bowie, Mallarmé and the Art of Being Difficult (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), x. 69. On Le Livre as an open work of art, see Eco, Open Work, 12–​13. On Boulez’s early encounters with Mallarmé and Le Livre, see Albèra, “Entretien avec Pierre Boulez,” 7. 70. Pierre Boulez, Boulez on Music Today, trans. Susan Bradshaw and Richard Rodney Bennett (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 19. 71. Erling E. Guldbrandsen, “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (IV) Some Broader Topics,” Tempo 65.258 (October 2011): 37. 72. Several years before Boulez made this statement in the interview cited in the previous note, James McCalla argued similarly in an analysis of Pli selon pli that the work is a portrait of Boulez that reflects the composer’s own “mindset and mental processes.” James McCalla, “Sea-​Changes: Boulez’s Improvisations sur Mallarmé,” Journal of Musicology 6.1 (Winter 1988): 83–​106 (83). 73. Translated in Mary M. Breatnach, “Pli selon pli. A  Conflation of Theoretical Stances,” in Walter Bernhart, Steven Paul Scher, and Werner Wolf (eds.), Word and Music Studies:  Defining the Field:  Proceedings of the First International Conference on Word and Music Studies at Graz, 1997 (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1999), 273. 74. Quintilian, Institutes of Oratory, Book 9, Chapter  2, http://​rhetoric.eserver.org/​quintilian/​9/​chapter2.html, accessed June 21, 2016. On the relationship of modern literary portraiture to prosopopeia, see Wallen, “Between Text and Image,” 55; Steiner, Exact Resemblance, 12. 75. Paul de Man, “Autobiography as De-​facement,” MLN 94.5 (Dec. 1979): 919–​30 (926). 76. Boulez, “Sonate, Que me Veux-​tu?,” 44. 77. Erling E. Guldbrandsen, “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (III) Mallarmé, Musical Form and Articulation,” Tempo 65.257 ( July 2011): 11. 78. Guldbrandsen, “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (III),” 11. 79. Roland Barthes, “The Death of the Author,” in Image—​Music—​Text, trans. Stephen Heath (New York: Hill and Wang, 1977), 142. Boulez was acquainted with Barthes; he once stated, “I met DeLeuze [sic], Foucault, Roland Barthes, Derrida. I met and read all those people.” Rocco Di Pietro, Dialogues with Boulez (Lanham, MD: Scarecrow Press, 2001), 56. 80. Barthes, “Death of the Author,” 143. 81. Boulez, Orientations, 174. Originally published in the liner note to the recording Pierre Boulez, BBC Symphony Orchestra, Boulez Conducts Boulez—​Pli Selon Pli, Columbia Masterworks, CBS 75.770, 1970. 82. Matheson, “Fold Upon Fold,” 77. 83. Guldbrandsen, “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (III),” 13. 84. See William Matheson, “Pli selon pli: Mallarmé (and Boulez),” Yearbook of Comparative and General Literature, 36 (1987): 84–​7 (85). 85. Matheson, “Fold Upon Fold,” 79. 86. Mary Breatnach shows that in Mallarmé’s reference to death in this final poem of the set, there lies the implication of a kind of permanence to life as well. Mary Breatnach, Boulez and Mallarmé: A Study in Poetic Influence (Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 1996), 108–​9. 87. Célestin Deliège, Pierre Boulez: Conversations with Célestin Deliège (London: Eulenberg, 1976), 94. 88. Guldbrandsen, “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (III),” 11. 89. Deliège, Pierre Boulez, 93. 90. Guldbrandsen, “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (III),” 12. Webern used imitation in compositions such as the third movement of Five Pieces for String Quartet (1909), which features imitative gestures between voices in which instruments follow so closely upon one another that they can be found in an analysis but are essentially inaudible to the listener. On Boulez’s interest in Webern’s experimentation with canons, see Goldman, Musical Language of Pierre Boulez, 51–​2.

  53

M u s i c a l a n d L i t e r a ry P o rt r a i t u r e   

( 53 )

91. Breatnach, “Pli selon pli,” 266. 92. Breatnach, “Pli selon pli,” 267. On Mallarmé’s ideas about music, see also Pascal Durand, “‘Pli selon pli’: Les Modèles musicaux de Mallarmé,” in Philippe Albèra (ed.), Pli selon pli de Pierre Boulez:  Entretiens et études (Geneva:  Éditions Contrechamps, 2003), 83–​100. 93. Breatnach, “Pli selon pli,” 266. On Mallarmé’s ideas about music, and how his poetry evokes and inspires musical interpretation, see Michel Butor, “Mallarmé selon Boulez,” in Michel Butor, Répertoire, 5 vols. (Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit, 1964), ii: 243–​51. 94. Breatnach, “Pli selon pli,” 266. 95. These words come from Mallarmé’s essay “Crise de vers.” The translation is included in Breatnach, “Pli selon pli,” 267. See also Breatnach, Boulez and Mallarmé, 29–​30. 96. Matheson, “Fold Upon Fold,” 77. 97. Matheson, “Fold Upon Fold,” 78. 98. Matheson, “Fold Upon Fold,” 78. 99. Matheson, “Fold Upon Fold,” 78. 100. Matheson, “Fold Upon Fold,” 79. 101. Matheson, “Fold Upon Fold,” 79. 102. Guldbrandsen, “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (III),” 14. 103. Boulez, Orientations, 175. 104. Boulez, Orientations, 175. 105. Breatnach, Boulez and Mallarmé, 70. 106. Boulez, Orientations, 176; see also Breatnach, “Pli selon pli,” 269. 107. Breatnach, “Pli selon pli,” 270–​2. 108. Guldbrandsen, “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (III),” 14. Eric Wayne argues that Boulez uses the phrase “pli selon pli” as a metaphor for his musical experiments with time. According to this interpretation, the layers implied by the French expression are units of time that rest upon one another in an evocation of temporal depth, and the folds are the junctures at which they meet. Eric Wayne, “Mallarmé’s Folds: Mallarmé, Boulez, Pli selon pli,” Nineteenth-​Century French Studies 9.3/​4 (Spring–​Summer 1981): 220–​32 (223–​4). 109. Boulez, Orientations, 176. 110. Detailed analyses of the movements in Pli selon pli can be found in Bradshaw, “Instrumental and Vocal Music,” 180–​98; Breatnach, Boulez and Mallarmé, 103–​37; Iwanka Stoïanowa, “Pli selon Pli. Portrait de Mallarmé,” Musique en jeu 11 ( June 1973): 75–​98. 111. Deliège, Pierre Boulez, 94–​5. “Don” also appears to suggest a detailed analysis of the poetic form:  Roland Jordan views the movement as divided into fourteen sectional units, matching the number of lines in the original poem, and each featuring musical gestures that evoke the linguistic content of its corresponding line. Roland Jordan, “Fold Upon Fold: Boulez (and Mallarmé),” Yearbook of Comparative and General Literature 36 (1987): 88–​97. 112. Albèra, “Entretiens avec Pierre Boulez,” 8. 113. McCalla, “Sea-​Changes,” 93–​106. 114. McCalla, “Sea-​Changes,” 93–​5. 115. McCalla, “Sea-​Changes,” 95. 116. McCalla, “Sea-​Changes,” 97–​8. 117. McCalla, “Sea-​Changes,” 104. 118. Breatnach, Boulez and Mallarmé, 136–​7. 119. Erling E. Guldbrandsen, “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (II) Serialism Revisited,” Tempo 65.256 (2011): 18–​24 (18–​19). 120. Goldman, Musical Language of Pierre Boulez, 33. 121. Guldbrandsen, “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (IV),” 37. It is also a common trope in literature for characters to contemplate painted portraits, in Byatt’s words, “as temporary mirrors to see themselves with a difference.” Byatt, Portraits in Fiction, 5. The notion of portraiture as a medium of self-​reflection is brought to its extreme in the artist Gavin Turk’s Your Authorised Reflection (2009), in which a framed wall-​mounted mirror, signed by Turk in the lower right-​hand corner, transforms the image of one’s reflection into the

54

( 54 )   Musical Portraits

artist’s creation; the artwork becomes both portrait and self-​portrait of each individual spectator. Andrew Graham-​Dixon, Sandy Nairne, Sarah Howgate, and Jo Higgins, 21st-​ Century Portraits (London: National Portrait Gallery, 2013), 52. 122. Jean-​Luc Nancy, “The Look of the Portrait,” in Simon Sparks (ed.), Multiple Arts: The Muses II (Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press, 2006), 225. 123. Nancy, “Look of the Portrait,” 226. 124. Nancy, “Look of the Portrait,” 239.

  5

CH A P T E R 2

Musical Portraits of Visual Artists The soul is like music playing behind the veil of flesh; one cannot paint it, but one can make it heard or at least try to show what you have thought of it. —​Henri Fantin-​Latour1

O

ne goal of visual portraiture throughout the history of the genre has been the depiction of the interior aspects of a person’s identity, something that until recently has typically been accomplished through the depiction of traces of personality that can be read from outward appearance. Music has long been understood to be the art form with the most direct access to subjectivity, the one most able to invoke affects, emotions, and the ineffable and intangible aspects of personality. Although music is often assumed to have a more immediate access to interiority, however, musical evocations of character are still described using metaphors that refer to the creation of visual arts and architecture. In the early days of the genre of musical portraiture, Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach’s works were characterized by analogy to painting: in the 1770s, Johann Georg Sulzer wrote in an article titled “Mahlerey” (Painting) that Bach’s portraiture “entails more than painting inanimate elements of nature in music—​impressing the ear with the sounds found in nature itself. . . . It entails painting those emotions that stir our soul through specific sentiments.”2 Bach conveys character, according to Sulzer, by painting human feelings with musical brushstrokes. The notion that sound provides direct access to that which is beyond vision, that it can represent a human depth that is unavailable to the eye and can only be inferred from visual portraiture rather than depicted directly in it, has remained a trope in many theorists’ and artists’ approaches, up through the present day. For example, a related idea appears in the theories of the film artist Oskar Fischinger, who used film to create avant-​garde

56

( 56 )   Musical Portraits

pairings of sonic and visual effects: “Eye and ear supplement each other in orthogonal function. The eye seizes the exterior, surface, form, and color. The ear seizes through sound, which is particular to each body, the internal structure which the eye spies outwardly.”3 As identity is believed to reside beyond physical likeness, music adopts an important role in creating an impression of the hidden reaches of the self. In further exploring the relationship between music and the visual in the realm of portraiture, this chapter considers musical portraits whose composers, in seeking new ways to depict the personal identities of their acquaintances, reflect the influence of contemporary trends in the graphic arts. The chapter focuses in particular on twentieth-​and twenty-​first-​century musical portraits of contemporary artists, Morton Feldman’s “de Kooning” (1963) and Philip Glass’s “A Musical Portrait of Chuck Close” (2005). By considering these musical portraits in relation to works by the artists they represent, the chapter reveals how Feldman and Glass develop musical structures that operate as metaphors for visual strategies of representation. Through novel experiments with the device of musical ekphrasis, involving the use of music to depict a visual representation, or in these cases to describe styles of painting, these composers aim to portray not only the personalities of their subjects, but also their distinctive artistic techniques.4 For example, in Feldman’s portrait of Willem de Kooning and Glass’s portrait of Chuck Close, the metaphorically “colorful” use of legato lines and vivid timbral effects or the “angular” qualities of sudden juxtapositions between notes of different durations, pitch range, and volume operate as sonic analogues to the varied colors or sharply intersecting lines on these painters’ canvases. In such instances, the aesthetic character of the artist’s works is understood to be an important aspect of his identity. Although ekphrasis often involves the musical portrayal of an existing work of art, in the case of these compositions the subject of the ekphrasis is not any particular paintings by de Kooning or Close; rather, the musical portraits conjure for the imagination, more generally, the technical and stylistic attributes associated with these artists’ oeuvres. As the subject of each of these musical portraits is the identity of the artist named in the title, the paintings they evoke for the mind’s eye may be imaginary self-​portraits by these artists. Importantly, Feldman and Glass have chosen to depict artists whose characteristic styles seem especially well suited to their own musical techniques. Feldman’s works generally explore aspects of musical movement and stasis and expansion of the sense of time, in ways that overlap with de Kooning’s intricately planned but apparently violent and impromptu canvases. Similarly, Glass’s distinctive use of musical patterns that slowly transform through incremental variation resembles the repeated lozenges of layered colors that appear from a distance to merge

  57

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 57 )

together to make up the images in Close’s paintings. By exploring analogies between their techniques, and, more fundamentally, between hearing and vision, these composers ultimately turn the focus of their portraits back onto the nature of music itself. The subject of their works becomes not only the artists named in the titles, but also the ways their own compositional techniques correspond with the visual styles developed by their subjects, and, more generally, the ways music can operate as a medium of representation. MORTON FELDMAN’S MUSICAL PORTRAIT “DE KOONING”

Feldman wrote and spoke extensively about the connections between music and the visual, and what he perceived as the spatial aspects of sound and listening. In 1963, the same year he completed his one-​movement portrait “de Kooning,” for chamber ensemble, Feldman proposed a “vertical” mode of contemplating music, according to which time could be experienced as static while music could be understood to operate in the manner of a painting that conveys its entire “message” at once, in a single given moment. Instead of organizing a piece as “a horizontal series of events” differentiated by the forward progress of time, he wished for each element to be understood as “suggesting its own proportions,” in a manner analogous to the way a painter might find “that a colour insists on being a certain size, regardless of his wishes.”5 The composer should not attempt to control sound, he argued; thinking “vertically” rather than “horizontally,” one should “simply allow it to ‘be.’ ”6 Furthermore, Feldman believed that “horizontal thought” about composition prevented music from possessing a sound of its own that could be accessed directly. Instead, “What we hear is rather a replica of sound, and when successfully done, startling as any of the figures in Mme. Tussaud’s celebrated museum.”7 For Feldman, the horizontal approach to music that unfurls over time thus ends in a form of representation resembling the hyperrealist wax sculpture portraits of celebrated figures that trick the eyes with their detailed imitations of external appearance, but remain inert. By contrast, a piece conceived through vertical thought, in which the music is heard, metaphorically speaking, as a system of sounds distributed across a “surface aural plane,”8 contributes more than a mere lifeless representation. Rather, it allows direct access to the ideal sound in itself, which Feldman imbues with an internal subjectivity, by permitting it to “be” and submitting to its “wishes.” To approach his goal of creating “vertical” music, Feldman sought a methodology that would eliminate, to the degree that this was possible, the “horizontal” dimension, time, from the experience of the composition.

58

( 58 )   Musical Portraits

In their increasing abstraction, Feldman’s ideas about musical horizontality and verticality at times strain the bounds of describing the actual experience of musical perception for most listeners. Feldman takes these spatial metaphors far from their typical metaphorical meanings in relation to music, creating out of them something idiosyncratic and sometimes confounding. It is useful in the context of the discussion of Feldman’s musical portraiture, nevertheless, to extend Feldman’s analogy between wax sculpture portraits and musical subjectivity slightly further. If horizontal thought offers a detailed but lifeless representation of external appearance, vertical thought bypasses the trivial aspect of mimetic likeness to portray instead the invisible qualities of inner life and identity. Feldman composed the portrait “de Kooning,” his first experiment in “vertical thought,” for a short documentary film by Hans Namuth and Paul Falkenberg about the painter, and the score was premiered as a concert work independent of the film in September of the same year. Feldman’s emphasis on the “vertical” or “static” in music must be seen in the context of his long engagement with a group of New York artists that included de Kooning. Feldman and de Kooning had been acquaintances since 1951, and met regularly with other members of the art world at the Artists’ Club on Eighth Street in Manhattan. The two were supportive of each other’s work: de Kooning at one time reported having attended performances of Feldman’s music with some regularity over the period of a decade,9 and Feldman would later recall, “De Kooning was nuts about us. He gave us the green light.”10 Feldman also attributed “the beginning of my life”—​that is, the start of his career as a composer—​to de Kooning’s inspirational words, “I work—​other people call it art.”11 For Feldman, de Kooning’s “vulnerability . . . took me out of my romantic dream of what it was to be an artist, into the reality of it.”12 De Kooning was perhaps a natural choice of subject for a musical portrait, as he was known for his abstract portraits of archetypal figures, as in his Woman series, which he also associated with self-​portraiture, stating, “Those women are perhaps the feminine side of me,” and “Many of my paintings of women have been self-​portraits.”13 Throughout his career Feldman composed multiple works whose titles referred to living artists, poets, and composers, including “For Franz Kline” (1962), “Christian Wolff in Cambridge” (1963), “Rothko Chapel” (1971), “For Frank O’Hara” (1973), “For John Cage” (1982), “For Philip Guston” (1984), “For Stefan Wolpe” (1986), and “For Samuel Beckett” (1987). The preposition “for” in most of these titles indicates that they are dedications, as Feldman confirmed in an interview in 1976.14 He also distinguished “de Kooning” as more abstract in its relationship to its subject than “Rothko Chapel,” which he viewed as unusually referential among his works, with its allusions to Rothko’s biography and his art, as well as to the Houston

  59

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 59 )

chapel where it was to be premiered. The absence of the preposition in the title of “de Kooning,” however, implies a more direct correspondence between the music and the painter that it names than does a standard dedication, and in this way the title invites the listener to interpret the music as a portrait.15 Feldman acknowledged this representational aspect, stating that in “De Kooning there is a little bit of a tragic flavour which Bill still has. Remember, he is the most European.”16 Indeed Feldman appears to have been experimenting with ideas associated with musical portraiture during this period of his stylistic development, as two additional works from the time are named for historical figures, “Rabbi Akiba” (1963) and “The King of Denmark” (1964).17 Most of the artists named in Feldman’s dedicatory titles—​including Kline, Rothko, Guston, and de Kooning—​were among the friends and collaborators Feldman met in New York in 1951, the year after his inspirational first encounter with John Cage. They were members of the loosely associated group of artists that was known since 1946, to their general reluctance, as the “abstract expressionists,” and that was later dubbed the “New York School” by participant Robert Motherwell.18 Feldman forged strong bonds with these artists, whom he frequently credited as considerable influences on his career, and many of whose works he discussed in essays and lectures, and curated in the 1967 exhibition Six Painters at St. Thomas University.19 Though at times he downplayed the influence of contemporary composers on his music, including his teacher Stefan Wolpe and even his supportive and galvanizing older colleague Cage, Feldman never hesitated to credit the artists in his circle; in a 1985 lecture he stated, “I learned more from painters than I learned from composers.”20 The degree to which painting inspired Feldman’s work is also evident in the titles he gave his compositions and the terminology he employed in writing and speaking about music. He uses visual and spatial metaphors in some of his titles that indicate an ekphrastic representational quality, accomplishing a form of visual representation through musical sound, in works including “Illusions” (1950), his series Projections (1950–​1951) and Vertical Thoughts (1963–​1964), “Patterns in a Chromatic Field” (1981), “Crippled Symmetry” (1983), and “Coptic Light” (1986). In essays, interviews, and lectures, he discusses artists from Piero della Francesca to Cézanne and Picasso, in addition to his contemporaries in the abstract expressionist movement.21 He attributes his notion of temporal stasis in music to the influence of the abstract canvases of Rothko and Guston.22 His essays also frequently employ spatial and visual metaphors, such as in his 1962 characterization of Durations I, in which he describes musical notes as located “behind” and “ahead” of one another and addresses the process of “thinning and thickening my sounds [to keep] the image intact.”23 He even uses a visual metaphor in his homage to Wolpe,

60

( 60 )   Musical Portraits

thanking him late in life “for teaching me the plastic possibilities of musical shape.”24 For Feldman, notation was a crucial aspect of the composer’s art, and he developed novel notational practices multiple times during his career. These included his grid-​like graphic scores for Projections, constructed of squares and rectangles indicating tessitura and duration and containing numbers designating the quantity of pitches to be played; his free-​ duration scores, in works such as “Two Pianos” (1957), featuring staves without bar lines and note heads without stems; and the solid and dotted lines linking stemless note heads in different staves to signify simultaneity and sequence in “de Kooning” and other compositions from the early 1960s.25 Feldman approached the creation of the score as though he were painting. He frequently invoked metaphors that likened notating the score to daubing colors or hues (sounds) on a surface (time, conceived of as a static “aural plane”). He elaborated, “My obsession with surface is the subject of my music. In that sense, my compositions are really not ‘compositions’ at all. One might call them time canvases in which I more or less prime the canvas with an overall hue of the music.”26 This rather obscure description of his method appears to indicate a distinction between foreground and background in his music, the notion that principal musical figures are heard before a background “colored” by musical atmosphere, like the backdrop a portraitist chooses to depict behind his subject. Feldman’s music was thus caught, in his view, “Between Time and Space. Between painting and music. Between the music’s construction, and its surface,” a liminal position described by the title of the 1969 essay in which he wrote these words, and of a corresponding composition from the same year, “Between Categories.”27 This phrase can best be understood as reflecting Feldman’s desire for a vertical music from which time would be eliminated as a dimension of experience, but also as recognizing that pure “verticality” could not be achieved: music, which cannot be completely static, can nevertheless represent, through its notation, a desire to be static like painting. Of course painting does not permit complete stasis either: there is an inescapable temporal dimension to the contemplation of a painting as well as to its creation. Indeed, the time involved in making a painting was frequently acknowledged and celebrated among the abstract expressionists, particularly in the case of Jackson Pollock, whose unique process became the subject of an important part of the discourse around his works. De Kooning’s paintings, too, in their seemingly energetic and spontaneous brushstrokes, drew attention to the temporal dimension of their creation. In developing his ideas of notation for compositions that would occupy a space between painting and music, Feldman was inspired by the techniques

  61

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 61 )

of contemporary painters. According to his acquaintance Brian O’Doherty, “Phillip Guston, his closest friend, helped him to the idea of sound as a medium to use and abuse like paint.”28 Feldman devised his grid notation, found in the Projections series, under the influence of watching Pollock’s method of splattering paint in the early 1950s: “I put sheets of graph paper on the wall. . . . What resembled Pollock was my ‘allover’ approach to the time-​canvas.”29 In Feldman’s view, notation was far from a transparent set of instructions for the performer: as he explained, “The degree to which a music’s notation is responsible for much of the composition itself, is one of history’s best kept secrets.”30 Notation possessed “an aspect of ‘role playing,’ . . . a very strong voice, if not onstage, then off.”31 It was also performative in that it played an important part in the creation of musical style: “I find that if you use a certain type of notation, it cannot help but develop into a certain style. . . . All I’m really saying . . . is that notation, at least for me, determines the style of the piece.”32 As uncommon as Feldman’s preoccupation with the appearance of notation may appear, the analogy he frequently proposed between the composer’s work on the score and the artist’s process of applying paint to a canvas was not entirely novel; indeed it is implied in the centuries-​old metaphorical concepts that guide the perception of the horizontal relationships between notes printed on the staff as indicative of rhythmic relationships, and of the vertical positions of notes as equivalent to differences in musical pitch. But Feldman was interested not only in what the standard visual metaphors of musical notation can reveal about the relationships between distinct sounds, but also in what they fail to reflect. His notational innovations played with both the precision and the pitfalls inherent in the translation of visual-​aural metaphors. For example, his graph notation indicated precise durations but not pitch, while his “free duration” notation instructed musicians which pitches to play, but not how long to hold them. Patterns in the musical score, for Feldman, translated into “rhythmic shapes” in performance, but they were also, he writes, “in part notational images that do not make a direct impact on the ear as we listen. A tumbling of sorts happens in midair between their translation from the page and their execution.”33 In works such as “de Kooning,” the ways visual metaphors fall short in describing precise musical sounds can be as important as the ways they succeed. It is in this ambivalent space “between categories” that Feldman felt he could allow his music to “be,” to evoke a subjectivity and identity of its own, something that becomes especially important in his musical portraits of the early 1960s. The notion of a space between the artwork and the self, whose breadth is determined in part by the distinction between what the painted or notated surface can communicate directly to the spectator and what it cannot, was

62

( 62 )   Musical Portraits

instrumental to the stylistic development of the abstract expressionist painters, as it was to Feldman. For the composer, it was in this liminal space that the music contained a sense of identity and selfhood, an “omnipotent ‘I.’ ”34 Attempting to elaborate on Feldman’s intention in using this phrase, O’Doherty writes: He means an identity that is a sort of grown-​up surrealist “I”—​one that extends experience, balancing inside and outside, subject and object, discipline and freedom in a way that makes his music a sort of living sound object, a motif in time, the silence of the white canvas painted with sound. Like the action painters, he makes one aware of his medium as if it were a substance. . . . Attention switches from silence to sound and back again in a way reminiscent of figure-​ground relationships in the painting he admires.35

O’Doherty’s reference to “figure-​ground” relationships recalls Feldman’s metaphor of “priming” a musical “canvas.” In Feldman’s musical portraits, it is the figure of the subject named in the title that emerges before the musical background he supplies. As this passage implies, the abstract expressionists likewise focused their attention on the representation of the self, experimenting with visual means to depict individual subjectivities in painted abstractions, as indicated in the title of a 1949 exhibition featuring works by members of the group including de Kooning, “The Intrasubjectives.”36 In describing the New  York School, Motherwell stated, “the idea of the ‘self ’ now became foregrounded as the cornerstone and mainstay of artistic expression.”37 In a process that recalls musical portraiture as well as traditional painted portraits, the notion of abstract painting’s capacity to depict the self—​ either the artist’s own subjectivity or that of another individual—​depended on the interpretation of colors, shapes, the application of paint, and other attributes of the canvas visible to the eye as signifying aspects of identity.38 Through these metaphoric associations, the abstract painting represents, in the words of Meyer Schapiro, who sees an aspect of self-​representation in abstraction, “an individual who realizes freedom and deep engagement of the self within his work. . . . The art is deeply rooted, I believe, in the self and its relation to the surrounding world.”39 In seeking a musical language to depict the “omnipotent ‘I,’ ” Feldman similarly aimed to develop techniques for manipulating musical “materials” to relate through metaphor to aspects of the artist’s self. In his liner notes to a 1959 album of Feldman’s music, the poet Frank O’Hara describes the composer’s ability to conjure subjectivity in music as dependent on the visual aspect of his scores: “Whether notated or graphic, his music sets in motion a spiritual life.”40 In a portrait such as “de Kooning,” the subjectivity depicted is identified as belonging not to the composer himself but to the individual named in the title.

  63

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 63 )

“De Kooning” is thus a musical portrait that continues this abstract artistic engagement with selfhood, in the representation of the identity of the artist named in the title. As is typical in musical portraits of artists, the work depicts aspects of both its subject’s character and his artistic style. In this case, in addition to conveying de Kooning’s general affect, which Feldman understood as defined by a European “tragic flavor,” it evokes the artist’s method of painting and the appearance of his artworks, through not only the sound of the music but the visual aspect of the notated score as well. Although many listeners are unlikely to have access to the score, for those with the opportunity to view it, the notation of this work, in keeping with Feldman’s emphasis on the appearance of his scores as works of art in their own right, has an important representational function, apart from its role as a set of performance instructions. Considered separately from the musical sound, the score is ekphrastic in that given the title “de Kooning,” it has the potential on its own to conjure, in the viewer’s interpretation, an imagined artwork by de Kooning—​perhaps, given the genre of the composition, a self-​portrait.41 For those contemplating the score while listening to the music, this portrait is enriched by the way Feldman challenges established visual signifiers of musical sound in his notation, focusing attention on perceptual incongruities between the senses. By highlighting both the intricately close relationship and the inevitable gap between sight and sound in music, Feldman creates a work that emphasizes the space in art that lies between viewing—​o r listening—​ and understanding. This is the metaphoric space in which, according to the composer, he could allow the music to “be,” to take on aspects of a living subject, rather than signifying reality through a more imitative but lifeless form of representation like a wax sculpture at Madame Tussaud’s. In this manner, the portrait of de Kooning represents its subject by keeping him inaccessible rather than conjuring him clearly to the eye or ear: the painter’s identity is obscured in the enigmatic, slow musical phrases, and in the space “between” the sound and the score that prescribes its performance. Feldman composed “de Kooning” for a quintet featuring French horn; violin and cello playing arco, pizzicato, and artificial harmonics; a keyboardist alternating between piano and celeste; and a percussionist playing a range of instruments of contrasting timbres, the vibraphone, tenor and bass drums (usually rolled but occasionally struck), chimes, and antique cymbals (Example 2.1). The piece makes broad use of timbral effects through the juxtaposition of these different instruments and by calling for multiple ways of approaching their performance. This mix of tone qualities plays

64

( 64 )   Musical Portraits Example 2.1: Morton Feldman, “de Kooning,” first page. Copyright © 1963 by C. F. Peters Corporation. All Rights Reserved. Used by permission.

upon the metaphor of timbre as musical color, an association between sight and sound that was an important feature in much music of the first half of the twentieth century, particularly in works by Anton Webern, whose development of Klangfarbenmelodie (the notion that something akin to melody could be constructed of a string of contrasting timbres rather than pitches) inspired Feldman’s assessment that “In Webern, one also hears the

  65

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 65 )

beauty of simultaneity of movement and color.”42 The instruments in “de Kooning” sometimes play simultaneously, indicated by solid vertical lines between their staves, with an arrowhead to designate which performer is to cue the others. But for the most part the work is constructed of a series of solo attacks, with straight dashed lines marking the sequence in which the musicians enter one by one. Perhaps in the association with figure-​ground painting mentioned by O’Doherty, these unevenly distributed attacks represent the primary structural figures that emerge in focus before the background of the continuation and decay of each note. The piece’s musical phrases are marked numerically—​following an unnumbered introduction there are thirty-​two phrases—​and are separated by the absence of dashed lines between the concluding pitch of one phrase and the first pitch of the next. As in Feldman’s other free-​duration compositions, the note heads are not given stems, other than the occasional grace-​note stem to indicate that a pitch is to be cut off or to enter earlier than usual (though Feldman indicates such notes are also “to be played slowly”). The musicians have unusual freedom of interpretation and must respond in an improvisatory manner to their collaborators and surroundings in performing this work. They are supposed to begin any note as the previous one decays—​that is, as the sounds of the keyboard, percussion, and plucked strings fade out, or as the string players reach the end of a bow or the horn player comes to the end of a breath. This makes for an indeterminate tempo and pitches whose durations will depend on the acoustics of the performance space, the size of the audience, and technical aspects of the musicians’ rendition of the piece. The work also lacks meter and bar lines, except for a few interruptions of metered measures of rest with tempo indications, as well as the chord that concludes the piece, marked as a single measure containing a whole note played by strings, horn, and chimes. The music’s durational variability and the uneven length of individual phrases (which range from one attack to sixteen) interfere with the listener’s ability to anticipate the exact placement of each note. Compounding the effect of atmospheric mystery produced by the absence of meter and of rhythmic patterns, the score dictates, “Each sound with a minimum of attack,” and “Dynamics very low throughout.” Feldman’s novel musical notation in this work, joining elements of standard practice with the innovative graphic component of the solid and dotted lines, provides clear instructions for the performing ensemble. At the same time, however, its general appearance implies a set of musical “shapes” and sonic relationships that contrast markedly with what the listener hears in the performance of the portrait. If viewed as a work of art in its own right in the tradition of Augenmusik (“eye music,” the Renaissance and Baroque trend in pictorial music scores) or graphic notation that offers

66

( 66 )   Musical Portraits

a descriptive visual impression of the musical sound, the score, with its long, straight lines joining voices between staves and the sharp angles at which these splayed vertical and diagonal lines meet, implies harsh sound patterns that diverge in the viewer’s imagination from the atmospheric music the ensemble produces when reading the score prescriptively as a set of performance instructions. This conflict between the visual aspect of the score and the sound of its performance recalls contrasts and surprises inherent in de Kooning’s artworks. For Feldman, as for de Kooning, these conflicts arise from the disruption of the audience’s expectations regarding the connection between artworks and the objects they represent. The irresolvable challenges Feldman poses to the standard metaphoric links between the senses of sight and hearing serve in the depiction of what he understood to be the essentially tragic quality of de Kooning’s art, especially in conjunction with the more traditional association of the music’s ponderously slow tempo and desultory indeterminacy with the sense of a melancholy sensibility. The principal perceptual conflict between corresponding visual and aural components of the work’s notation and performance arises in listening to the piece while viewing the contours created by the lines joining simultaneous and sequential pitches, which, if the score is considered as a descriptive representation of the sound, appears to indicate that the music could be characterized as dynamic, energetic, angular, sharp, and fragmented. In fact these markings in the score instruct the musicians in the performance of a work that is leisurely and hushed, more rounded than pointed, and smooth rather than jagged, focusing not on articulation and sustained sounds but on decay and silence. This contrast between the appearance of speed and harshness in the notation and the almost static slowness and muffled timbres of the performance in Feldman’s work resembles the gap between the appearance of de Kooning’s canvases and the method by which he created them. Watching de Kooning paint, Feldman was surprised to find that the artist produced his seemingly spontaneous and hastily applied strokes of paint, for example in his “Woman, I” (1950–​1952, Figure 2.1), in an unexpectedly slow, methodical, and extended process. Feldman recounted: What was fascinating about watching de Kooning paint was that when you look at his pictures they look very, very fast but if you see him paint, he paints very slowly. Because of the way he would use a big brush, he would go like this and you would see that something is thinning out here, it seems gestural—​but it’s not. It’s in slow motion. It’s fascinating. . . . I just didn’t believe it. Very slow and everything looked like speed.43

Furthermore, as Jonathan W. Bernard has noted, by the time of Feldman’s composition of “de Kooning,” the painter was six years into a new phase

  67

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 67 )

Figure 2.1:  Willem de Kooning, “Woman, I,” 1950–​1952, oil on canvas, 6 feet 3-​7/​8 x 58 inches. © 2016 The Willem de Kooning Foundation/​Artists Rights Society (ARS), New York. Digital Image © The Museum of Modern Art/​Licensed by SCALA/​Art Resource, NY.

of his stylistic development in which he was creating relatively sparse constructions, whose brush strokes, still seemingly rough and energetic, formed broader shapes and fewer gradations of color than are found in his earlier, more chaotic canvases.44 This is a body of works that appears to conform to Feldman’s notion of allowing each color to “suggest its own proportions,” as he aimed to do with sound.45 In this way Feldman draws a further connection between his own art and that of de Kooning, as he develops his compositional technique of allowing his artistic materials “to be,” imbuing them with subjectivity and submitting to their “will.” The listener who attends to Feldman’s portrait while reading along with the score must learn not to associate the shapes produced by the lines

68

( 68 )   Musical Portraits

with the sounds they indicate, as the viewer contemplating de Kooning’s portraits must mentally reassemble the fragmented elements to perceive an intact human body. As O’Doherty puts it, de Kooning’s subjects’ limbs “look as if they want to be elsewhere. An elbow wants to be a foot, an eye wants to be a breast, a flank wants to be a thigh.”46 Techniques of representation are thus reoriented in de Kooning’s paintings of women, which exhibit the sorts of distortion and fragmentation of gesture that characterized much of the output of the abstract expressionists whose canvases explore matters of subjectivity and the self. De Kooning experiments with difference, rather than likeness, in his depictions of the human body, challenging deeply ingrained metaphors about people’s “interior” and “exterior,” and demanding that spectators derive their own impressions of the sitter’s inner subjectivity through a more dynamic act of interpretation. In “de Kooning,” Feldman similarly points to difference and to what the senses do not reveal about the world, in his case by challenging standard ways of reading visual signifiers of sonic effects, creating a score for his musical portrait that fails to map predictably onto the sounds produced in the work’s performance. In de Kooning’s “Woman, I” and Feldman’s “de Kooning,” the parts of the whole are all present and accounted for, but the representations in these artworks distort the reality they depict, and require us to relearn and reinterpret standard visual modes of signification. In fragmenting the viewer’s notion of space and form in his artworks, de Kooning aimed to replace the locus of meaning from the canvas to the painter, to transform the artist, in his words, into “the idea, the center, and the vanishing point himself—​and all at the same time.”47 The use of a vanishing point is a central technique in the representation of perspective in painting, and Feldman too invoked concepts relating to Renaissance theories of perspective when he described his changing views of notation during the year he composed “de Kooning,” in the essay “Vertical Thoughts”: “Precision did not work for me either. . .  . It was like painting a picture where at some place there is always a horizon.”48 He sought, in his new works, to distort the “aural surface,” metaphorically shifting the horizon and vanishing point as de Kooning described. With this in mind, one might be struck by the resemblance between the lines and angles of Feldman’s score and the converging solid and dotted lines that adorn standard textbook analyses of perspective in works of Renaissance painting.49 In the case of “de Kooning,” however, rather than meeting at a single vanishing point, the lines lead, phrase by phrase, in multiple directions, leaving it up to the music’s performers and listeners to give them a focus, as they actively interpret the work in a process analogous to the experience of contemplating a painting by de Kooning.

  69

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 69 )

PHILIP GLASS’S “A MUSICAL PORTRAIT OF CHUCK CLOSE”

Philip Glass’s 2005 musical portrait of Chuck Close, for solo piano, is another work that, like Feldman’s “de Kooning,” was created as a representation of an artist who was a close friend of the composer and who influenced his stylistic development. The portrait was commissioned by pianist Bruce Levingston, who was inspired to suggest the idea for the piece when he viewed Close’s large-​scale portrait of Glass hanging outside Caspary Hall at Rockefeller University. Glass’s work is constructed of two movements, though Glass originally conceived of it in another form, and its genesis is the result of serendipity.50 Glass had prepared two alternate works before choosing one that he favored as the final portrait, but his assistant mistakenly delivered Levingston the abandoned version. Later, when the error was discovered and Levingston received the composition Glass had intended to fulfill the commission, the pianist was enamored of both, and convinced Glass to combine them into a two-​movement work, also persuading him of the order in which they should be played. After hearing Levingston’s performance, Glass approved of the final two-​movement form of the musical portrait, stating, “I now think the current order is the right order. This is the fortunes of happenstance and synergy.”51 The formal and harmonic attributes of Glass’s composition in its final form allude to a narrative that depicts the trajectory of Close’s artistic career from his days as a young artist to the present as well as the chronology of major periods of emotional change during his life associated with periods of fluctuating health. At the same time, the short modular rhythmic and melodic gestures in “A Musical Portrait of Chuck Close” operate through ekphrasis to evoke the small repeating and gradually changing cells of overlapping colors typical of the technical construction of Close’s works of portraiture. In this way the work’s title provokes the listener to apprehend correspondences between Glass’s and Close’s signature artistic techniques.52 Glass and Close met in Paris in 1964 through mutual friends, the artists Richard Serra and Nancy Graves. They soon reunited in Manhattan, where they became integrated into the art world, forming relationships with prominent painters and sculptors, and occasionally collaborating; for example, Graves and Sol LeWitt both created posters to advertise Glass’s concerts.53 For a time Glass and Close worked as assistants in Serra’s studio, and Glass, who raised money during periods of his early career working as a plumber, laid the pipes in Close’s loft.54 Glass was the subject of the 1969 painting “Phil,” one of Close’s first series of portraits, his oversized, highly realistic black-​and-​white Big Heads begun that

70

( 70 )   Musical Portraits

year on the basis of photographs he had taken of the faces of a number of friends (Figure 2.2). Close has returned to many of these photographs throughout his career to paint them again, reusing none more frequently than the image of Glass, who has joked that he is the artist’s haystack, in reference to the recurring subject in the paintings of Claude Monet.55 Close has stated that his fascination with this photograph derived from the opportunities it offered him to experiment with modes of representation, taking inspiration from Glass’s “Medusa-​like hair” and his “heavy, hooded, druggy eyes and . . . sensuous mouth.”56 The portraits of Glass, numbering over a hundred, appear in a variety of media including painting, spit-​bite aquatint, dot drawing, finger painting, silk tapestry, watercolor, inkpad print, and paper pulp.57 In 2001 Glass sat for Close again, to be the subject of a daguerreotype, made using the nineteenth-​century photographic technique in which Close has produced a series of portraits; and in 2005, the year of Glass’s composition, Close created a representation of Glass in the form of a tapestry, “Phil, State I.” The friendship between Glass and Close was cemented early on by their shared interest in process as a basis for the creation of new works of music

Figure 2.2:  Chuck Close, “Phil,” 1969, acrylic on canvas, 108 x 84 inches. © Chuck Close, courtesy Pace Gallery.

  71

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 71 )

and art.58 Glass relied on process for much of his oeuvre prior to Einstein on the Beach (1976), allowing formal principles such as additive rhythms and cyclical structures to govern his work on compositions including “Two Pages” (1969), “Music in Similar Motion” (1969), and “Music in Twelve Parts” (1968–​1974).59 Like Glass in this process-​oriented period, Close has worked within strict, self-​imposed creative limitations to produce the final image. In an early series of large painted portraits, for example, he created images in the full spectrum of colors by building layers of diluted primary colors—​magenta, cyan, and yellow—​directly on the canvas rather than mixing colors on a palette.60 Though his paintings rely on representation and likeness, Close has professed affinity for the creations of minimalist artists including Donald Judd and LeWitt, figures who were also supportive of and influential to Glass.61 Throughout his career, Close has worked almost exclusively in the genre of portraiture, but his focus has been primarily on the development of the complex processes through which he creates his works. He has only rarely accepted commissions, and has argued that his aim is not to portray the sitter’s character, but to find new methods of depicting facial structures in an objective manner. He explains, “I just want to present [faces] very neutrally and very thoughtfully. I don’t try to orchestrate a particular experience or crank it up for high-​impact emotional effect.”62 His processes typically involve the division of the artistic surface into a grid that corresponds to his maquette, an expanded version of the original photograph overlaid with a grid.63 Though early on the grid was typically a tool to help him create oversized photorealist representations of his photographic originals, it began increasingly to remain visible in his finished artworks, as a repeating set of borders within which he painted contrasting colors or marked dots or thumbprints of varying hues. Because of his goal of depicting a generalized image, an aesthetic character at odds with the specificity typical of the genre of portraiture throughout much of its history, Close tended early in his career to call his works “heads,” rather than “portraits,” in order to avoid the expectations of the depiction of identity associated with the genre. In a 1970 interview, he explained, “I tried to purge my work of as much of the baggage of traditional portrait painting as I could.”64 In spite of his protestations of aesthetic neutrality, however, Close’s portraits of family and friends lend themselves to interpretations of his sitters’ characters and emotional states. In this way, they reveal that even when an artist focuses only on the structures of the face and makes a concerted effort to avoid manufacturing affect, viewers will be prone to “read” a portrait for signs of what a person’s exterior appearance can reveal about his or her interior self and identity, as they do when regarding portraits from other periods of the genre’s history as well as when meeting people face

72

( 72 )   Musical Portraits

to face. Close’s quasi-​objective distance forces the viewer to be especially creative in interpreting his portraits, complicating the task of imagining the sitter’s character and identity where they are not explicitly signified. The process of interpreting Close’s works thus resembles the way listeners are invited to engage with and interpret musical portraiture, in which physical likeness is excluded and musical elements must be contemplated as signs of character and allusions to biography. In 1988 Close suddenly experienced a devastating health trauma that made it impossible to continue painting:  he suffered a collapsed spinal artery that left him paralyzed from the neck down.65 After a long, frustrating period of rehabilitation, Close slowly began to regain some movement in his arms, though he never fully recovered the use of his hands and remains in a wheelchair. His desire to return to making art inspired a determination and stamina to recuperate, and through extensive physical therapy he slowly learned to paint again. Close calls this pivotal experience “the Event,” saying that art “saved my life.”66 The canvases he has created since his injury are typically more painterly in texture than his previous works, though they are still built on his maquette grids, over which he layers squares, circles, and lozenges in intense colors that contrast strikingly. In such paintings, the face is visible from a distance, but as the viewer approaches the image, it disintegrates into repetitive patterns of abstract cells that differ only slightly from those around them. It is these later works, with their undulating patterns of gradually changing repetition on the surface that combine to create a full portrait when contemplated from a greater distance, that Glass appears to evoke most directly in his portrait of the artist (Figure 2.3). Because the cells of color appear to cohere only from a distance into a detailed representation of a face, Close’s portraits seem to involve a sort of optical illusion, an out-​scaled analogue to the way an image is conjured in the eye out of miniscule pixels of color or particles of light. In his works the sense of a likeness and an identity seems to reside somewhere between the painted canvas and the perception of the viewer. As Wil S.  Hylton describes this effect, “You are no longer looking at the actual surface of the painting, but some apparition hovering above it.” 67 Hylton argues that in relying on the viewer’s ability to perceive something that is not actually there, Close “exploit[s]‌ the way we process human identity: the gaps of knowledge and the unknown spaces we fill with our own presumptions, the expectations and delusions we layer upon everyone we meet.”68 Glass’s portrait, in its repetition of melodic building blocks that coalesce to give the impression of a gradually developing musical shape, operates in an analogous manner, highlighting the way listeners form a sense of the larger work through the

  73

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 73 )

Figure 2.3:  Chuck Close, “Phil,” 2011–​2012, oil on canvas, 108-​5/​8 x 84 inches. © Chuck Close, courtesy Pace Gallery.

aural experience of its successive parts, linking moments together into the perception of a broader framework. In this way both Glass and Close, in their portraits, highlight, in Hylton’s words, “the fragile boundary between identity and perception.”69 Glass once described the experience of hearing music as being like looking over a field enshrouded in mist, and watching as images gradually come into view as the fog lifts. This simile recalls the impression of the mist lifting in Bruges from Mallarmé’s poem “Remémoration d’amis belges,” the text from which Boulez chose the title of his portrait Pli selon pli, and it could describe the way both Close’s and Glass’s portraits emerge in the perception of their painted and musical patterns.70 These artists, in their portraits of one another, provide just enough detail to permit the spectator to form a unique sense of the identities evoked in music or paint, and in this way the artists foreground the role of perception in the experience of art and in the contemplation of the subjectivities of the people we encounter in life and in aesthetic representation. Glass’s “A Musical Portrait of Chuck Close” thus evokes Close’s portraits in the way it invites the listener to imagine the subject’s character and

74

( 74 )   Musical Portraits

identity by interpreting works constructed of repetitive patterns, here using musical rather than visual clues.71 Glass employs formal techniques at both low and high structural levels to convey in the temporal medium of music Close’s varying affective states and life experiences over the period of their acquaintance, referring through the combination of musical elements to aspects of Close’s character. In particular, common metaphors that characterize major harmonies and faster tempos with happier emotional states and minor harmonies and slower speeds with sadness are engaged in the construction of a narrative description of Close’s career. The music appears to convey his vibrancy during the early period of his life as a painter, the grief caused by his health trauma, and the increasing sense of invigoration he felt during his period of gradual recovery. The shorter first movement of Glass’s musical portrait has an air of caprice. Glass creates a sense of playful energy out of rhythmic and harmonic friction, through juxtaposition of duple and triple divisions of the bar, rapid alternation between major and minor as a result of repeated raising and lowering of the third scale degree, and brilliant fanfare-​like rhythmic patterns in high tessitura. Glass represents Close’s tendency toward experimentation and both personal and creative unpredictability through the incorporation of rising and falling scalar patterns, unprepared dissonances, and recurring upward-​reaching unfinished melodic phrases. The movement concludes in F major, and is followed by the start of the second movement in the relative key of D minor, opening with a simple Alberti-​like bass pattern played at a significantly slower tempo. Above this ostinato, repeated arpeggios enter in groups of three pitches, in a plaintive gesture reminiscent of the Adagio sostenuto of Beethoven’s “Moonlight” Sonata in C♯ minor (Op. 27, no. 2). Approximately halfway through the movement, the right hand stops playing again, and after a louder reestablishment of the Alberti pattern, the treble returns with rapid, undulating arpeggios in six-​note groupings. These slower and faster passages alternate, and elements of both at times combine in a single phrase. The movement finally slows once more, to conclude in an ambivalent mood in the minor tonic. The structure of Glass’s work, with its movement from major to minor, from a fast and playful first movement to a second movement that begins with a bare texture and mournful, slow tempo before regaining speed and energy, creates a programmatic arc, a narrative progression that maps the major periods of his life through the music’s formal and harmonic structures, representing his creative and innovative work as a young artist, followed by the tragic sense of loss that followed his collapse, and the gradual return to work and the excitement of finding new ways to create his portraits. Interpreting the portrait’s structure to represent Close in this way,

  75

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 75 )

Levingston has said, “Every time I play the piece, I think about that phrase Chuck used about regaining his ability to paint: ‘loss and celebration.’ ”72 If Glass’s composition constructs a narrative identity for Close in its overarching harmonic and formal characteristics, it mimics his art in its structural detail. As a work of ekphrasis, this musical portrait creates a quasi-​visual representation by calling to mind the metaphors that are often used to describe music by analogy to visual media—​metaphors of shape, color, space, and line—​in creating a “surface” texture that evokes Close’s process-​oriented techniques of creating visual portraits. In an analogous manner to Close’s portraits built of dots, thumbprints, grids, and other small units that repeat across his gridded maquette, Glass’s musical portrait is constructed of brief modular “bricks” including scales, arpeggios, and rhythmic gestures that recur and gradually change in structure, pitch content, and other traits. As they appear in the score, these compositional units reflect the look of Close’s patterns (or the “insistence” of Gertrude Stein’s reiterated linguistic motifs) in the way they repeat with slight variation; as they reach the ear in performance, they work as sonic metaphors of the shapes and colors Close uses as the building blocks for his late grid-​ based portraits.73 Perhaps the pianist’s hand, too, as it plays the undulating recurring patterns in Glass’s work, mimics Close’s hand as he makes thumbprints across the page or holds the paintbrush against the canvas and paints circle after circle. Close has interpreted Glass’s portrait of him as representing the technical qualities of his works and the ways his artistic methods have developed across his career: “The first movement is more like my earliest work, much more minimal and reductive, almost black and white. And the second is the musical equivalent of a riot of color. It’s celebratory in much the same way I try to build these big color images out of lots of little pieces.”74 Glass has indicated that he also views a correlation between the brief gestures out of which his piece and Close’s portraits are created: To me the second piece has an expansiveness to it, it just seems to keep going on and on. And it’s like trying to find the edge of the canvas in one of Chuck’s paintings. There’s an edge there because there has to be an edge somewhere. But in another way you could say, well, why doesn’t it keep going forever?75

Glass hints that the double bar at the close of the movement stands as an arbitrary ending, that the work provides an unfinished, fragmented representation of his friend. This resembles, through ekphrasis, the grid-​like patterns in Close’s own works that could continue beyond the edge of the canvas, and it also indicates that Close’s identity, as well, is not a fixed entity, but will continue to develop and change beyond the completion of Glass’s

76

( 76 )   Musical Portraits

portrait. The end of the piece does not represent the end of a life or the boundary of an identity; the work concludes, rather, simply because it must stop at some point, but in ending abruptly, it acknowledges that it could continue indefinitely. CONCLUSION

In portraying the identities of Willem de Kooning and Chuck Close through references to their canvases, styles of painting, and processes of artistic creation, Feldman’s “de Kooning” and Glass’s “A Musical Portrait of Chuck Close” imply that an artist’s technical innovations open a window onto his personal identity. These compositions also function as studies of the elusive but vital relationship between music and the visual arts, by finding points of overlap between the ways they operate as modes of representation, and at the same time challenging standard metaphors that associate them with one another. In a portrait one finds constructions of the identity not only of its sitter but also of its creator and of the social and institutional contexts of each.76 In the final scene of Hamlet, Shakespeare’s Danish prince says of his dueling partner Laertes, “by the image of my cause I see /​The portrait of his.”77 One can almost imagine such a revelation, both figurative and literal, striking Feldman and Glass in the process of creating their portraits of their artist friends de Kooning and Close. In constructing these painters’ identities in musical portraits, the composers reveal significant similarities between their own musical innovations and styles and those of their subjects. And in this way they produce portraits that can be heard to merge the likenesses of composer and artist in a single work. Paul Cézanne remarked that the portrait is, in a sense, a form of self-​ portraiture: “We are always successful with our portraits, because in them we are one, you see, with the model.”78 As is evident in the case studies examined here, the genre of musical portraiture, too, has offered composers an opportunity to explore ways of representing the identities of their acquaintances, but also of examining themselves, their own artistic styles, and the nature of the relationship between music and painting. In creating musical frameworks with which to represent artists and considering the ways their own creative techniques overlap with those of their sitters, Feldman and Glass construct works whose true subject, in the end, is music’s capacity for representation. As their portraits demonstrate, this capacity is related to the kind of representation achieved in visual art, in which elements such as shapes, colors, and style are interpreted as suggestive of human qualities. But in a modern age marked by aesthetic innovation, abstraction, and

  7

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 77 )

the atomization of style, it is also apparent that it is an artistically willful act that has not only produced the portrait, but also designed the method by which it depicts its subject. It is ultimately the composer who stands at the vanishing point of the musical portrait, determining the rules of artistic representation. NOTES 1. Henri Fantin-​Latour, quoted in Therese Dolan, Manet, Wagner, and the Musical Culture of Their Time (Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 2013), 161. 2. Johann Georg Sulzer, “General Theory of the Fine Arts,” in Nancy Kovaleff Baker and Thomas Christensen (eds.), Aesthetics and the Art of Musical Composition in the German Enlightenment: Selected Writings of Johann Georg Sulzer and Heinrich Christoph Koch, trans. Nancy Kovaleff Baker (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 89–​90. 3. Oskar Fischinger, “‘Der absolut Tonfilm’ von Ingenieur Oskar Fischinger,” Dortmunder Zeitung, January 1, 1933, reprinted in translation as “The Composer of the Future and the Absolute Sound Film,” trans. James Tobias, in Cindy Keefer and Jaap Guldemond (eds.), Oskar Fischinger 1900–​1967:  Experiments in Cinematic Abstraction (Amsterdam:  EYE Filmmuseum; Los Angeles: Center for Visual Music, 2012), 96. 4. On ekphrasis and music, see, for example, Siglind Bruhn (ed.), Sonic Transformations of Literary Texts:  From Program Music to Musical Ekphrasis (Hillsdale, NY:  Pendragon Press, 2008), 7–​10; Siglind Bruhn, “A Concert of Paintings: ‘Musical Ekphrasis’ in the Twentieth Century,” Poetics Today 22.3 (Fall 2001):  551–​605; Siglind Bruhn, Musical Ekphrasis:  Composers Responding to Poetry and Painting (Hillsdale, NY: Pendragon Press, 2000). 5. Morton Feldman, “Vertical Thoughts,” Kulchur 3.9 (Spring 1963):  88–​9, reprinted in Seán Kissane (ed.), Vertical Thoughts: Morton Feldman and the Visual Arts (Dublin: Irish Museum of Modern Art, 2010), 3. 6. Feldman, “Vertical Thoughts,” 3. 7. Feldman, “Vertical Thoughts,” 3. 8. This phrase dates at least to a lecture Feldman gave in February 1951, and first appears in print in his essay “Between Categories,” The Composer 1.2 (Sept. 1969): 73–​7, reprinted in B. H. Friedman (ed.), Give My Regards to Eighth Street:  Collected Writings of Morton Feldman (Cambridge, MA: Exact Change, 2000), 84. On the content of the 1951 lecture, see Brett Boutwell, “Morton Feldman’s Graphic Notation: Projections and Trajectories,” Journal of the Society for American Music 6.4 (November 2012): 475. 9. Amy C. Beal, “‘Time Canvasses’: Morton Feldman and the Painters of the New York School,” in James Leggio (ed.), Music and Modern Art (New  York:  Routledge, 2002), 229. 10. R. Wood Massi, “Captain Cook’s First Voyage: An Interview with Morton Feldman (on 3.3. 1987),” Cum Notis Variorum 131 (April 1989): 7–​12, reprinted in Chris Villars (ed.), Morton Feldman Says: Selected Interviews and Lectures 1964–​1987 (London: Hyphen, 2006), 218. 11. Brian O’Doherty, “Feldman Throws a Switch Between Sight and Sound,” New York Times, February 2, 1964. 12. Morton Feldman, “Give My Regards to Eighth Street,” Art in America 59.2 (March/​April 1971): 96–​9, reprinted in Friedman, Give My Regards, 98. 13. De Kooning offered these interpretations in 1967 and 1975. Quoted in Richard Schiff, Between Sense and de Kooning (London: Reaktion Books, 2011), 57. Harold Rosenberg similarly interpreted de Kooning’s Woman paintings from 1950–​1952 as depicting the artist’s own individuality. See Debra Bricker Balken, Abstract Expressionism, Movements in Modern Art Series (London: Tate, 2005), 43. 14. Morton Feldman, “Morton Feldman: Interview by Fred Orton and Gavin Bryars,” Studio International 192.984 (November–​December 1976): 244.

78

( 78 )   Musical Portraits

15. On parallels between Feldman’s music and Rothko’s paintings, and the ways both artists discussed their work, see Steven Johnson, “Rothko Chapel and Rothko’s Chapel,” Perspectives of New Music 32.2 (Summer 1994):  6–​53; Brett Boutwell, “‘The Breathing of Sound Itself ’: Notation and Temporality in Feldman’s Music to 1970,” Contemporary Music Review 32.6 (2013): 539; Morton Feldman, “Rothko Chapel,” liner notes to Morton Feldman: Rothko Chapel/​For Frank O’Hara, Columbia Records/​Odyssey Y34138, 1976, LP, reprinted in Friedman, Give My Regards, 125–​6. Feldman also acknowledged that he adopted a partially autobiographical approach to the form of Rothko Chapel ( Johnson, “Rothko Chapel,” 16). 16. Feldman, “Morton Feldman: Interview,” 244. 17. The title “Rabbi Akiba” refers to the influential first-​to second-​century Jewish religious leader Akiba ben Joseph, a chief contributor to the Mishnah, the codification of Jewish law. “The King of Denmark” refers to the Danish King Christian X who, according to legend, wore a yellow Star of David during World War II as a sign of solidarity with his Jewish subjects. Brian O’Doherty, “Morton Feldman: The Burgacue Years,” in Kissane, Vertical Thoughts, 71. 18. The term “abstract expressionism” originated in a review by the New  Yorker art critic Robert Coates. Motherwell coined the moniker “New  York School” in 1949. Balken, Abstract Expressionism, 7, 26. 19. Juan Manuel Bonet, “I Learned More from Painters than I  Learned from Composers,” trans. Jonathan Brennan, in Kissane, Vertical Thoughts, 8. On Feldman’s relationship with the abstract expressionists, see Jonathan W. Bernard, “Feldman’s Painters,” in Steven Johnson (ed.), The New  York Schools of Music and Visual Arts (New  York:  Routledge, 2002), 173–​215. 20. Quoted in Bonet, “I Learned More from Painters,” 7. 21. Feldman discusses Piero della Francesca and Cézanne in “Between Categories,” 83–​6, and elsewhere. 22. Feldman describes this influence in Morton Feldman, “Crippled Symmetry,” RES: Anthropology and Aesthetics 2 (Autumn 1981): 91–​103, reprinted in Friedman, Give My Regards, 134–​49. See also Boutwell, “ ‘Breathing of Sound Itself,’ ” 540. 23. Morton Feldman, “Liner Notes,” Kulchur 2.6 (Summer 1962):  57–​60, reprinted in Friedman, Give My Regards, 7. 24. Bonet, “I Learned More from Painters,” 9. 25. On Feldman’s innovative scores of the early 1950s, see Boutwell, “Morton Feldman’s Graphic Notation.” For a study of his graph scores, see David Cline, The Graph Music of Morton Feldman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016). 26. Feldman, “Between Categories,” 88. 27. Feldman, “Between Categories,” 88. 28. O’Doherty, “Feldman Throws a Switch.” 29. Feldman, “Crippled Symmetry,” 147. 30. Feldman, “Crippled Symmetry,” 144. 31. Feldman, “Crippled Symmetry,” 145. 32. Tracy Caras and Cole Gagne, “Morton Feldman,” Soundpieces: Interviews with American Composers (Lanham, MD: Scarecrow Press, 1982), 163–​77, reprinted in Villars, Morton Feldman Says, 90–​1. 33. Feldman, “Crippled Symmetry,” 143. 34. O’Doherty, “Feldman Throws a Switch.” 35. O’Doherty, “Feldman Throws a Switch.” 36. Balken, Abstract Expressionism, 21. 37. Balken, Abstract Expressionism, 26. 38. On abstraction, meaning, and metaphor in abstract expressionist art, see Ann Gibson, “The Rhetoric of Abstract Expressionism,” in Michael Auping (ed.), Abstract Expressionism: The Critical Developments (New York: Harry N. Abrams, 1987), 72. 39. Meyer Schapiro, Modern Art: 19th and 20th Centuries (New York: George Braziller, 1979), 218, 222. 40. Frank O’Hara, “New Directions in Music,” in Kissane, Vertical Thoughts, 89.

  79

M u s i c a l P o rt r a i t s o f V i s ua l A rt i s t s   

( 79 )

41. On “notational ekphrasis,” see Lydia Goehr, “How to Do More with Words: Two Views of (Musical) Ekphrasis,” British Journal of Aesthetics 50.4 (October 2010): 408. 42. Morton Feldman, “A Life without Bach and Beethoven,” Listen 1 (May/​June 1964): 14, reprinted in Friedman, Give My Regards, 16. 43. Raoul Mörchen (ed.), Morton Feldman in Middelburg:  Words on Music:  Lectures and Conversations, 2 vols. (Cologne: Edition MusikTexte, 2008), ii: 618. 44. Bernard, “Feldman’s Painters,” 199. 45. Boutwell, “ ‘Breathing of Sound Itself,’ ” 549. 46. Brian O’Doherty, American Masters:  The Voice and the Myth (London:  Thames and Hudson, 1988), 122. 47. O’Doherty, Voice and the Myth, 120. 48. Friedman, Give My Regards, 6. 49. See, for instance, the perspective diagram of Leonardo da Vinci’s “Last Supper,” c.  1495–​1498, in Ross King, Leonardo and the Last Supper (London:  Bloomsbury, 2012), 143. 50. Charles McGrath, “A Portraitist Whose Canvas is a Piano,” New  York Times, April 22, 2005, www.nytimes.com/​2005/​04/​22/​arts/​music/​22glas.html?pagewanted=1&_​r=1, accessed June 21, 2016. 51. McGrath, “A Portraitist.” 52. For a similar observation, see also Tristian Evans, Shared Meanings in the Film Music of Philip Glass: Music, Multimedia and Postminimalism (New York: Routledge, 2016), 27. 53. Keith Potter, Four Musical Minimalists:  La Monte Young, Terry Riley, Steve Reich, Philip Glass (Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press, 2000), 266. For an autobiographical account of Glass’s collaborations with other artists and his musical influences during the 1960s and 1970s in the Soho area of New York, see Philip Glass, Music by Philip Glass, ed. Robert T. Jones (New York: Da Capo, 1987), 11–​24. Published in England as Philip Glass, Opera on the Beach, ed. Robert T. Jones (London: Faber and Faber, 1988). 54. Christopher Finch, Chuck Close: Life (London: Prestel, 2010), 9, 117–​19. 55. Martin Friedman, Close Reading:  Chuck Close and the Art of the Self-​ Portrait (New York: Harry N. Abrams, 2005), 182. 56. Dodie Kazanjian, “Metropolitan Opera: Close Encounter,” Playbill Arts, March 14, 2008, www.playbillarts.com/​features/​article/​7587.html, accessed June 21, 2016. 57. Christopher Finch, Chuck Close: Work (London: Prestel, 2007), 103. 58. Finch, Chuck Close: Life, 157. 59. See Potter, Four Musical Minimalists, ch. 4. On the role of process in the composition of “Two Pages,” see Wes York, “Form and Process (1981),” in Richard Kostelanetz (ed.), Writings on Glass: Essays, Interviews, Criticism (New York: Schirmer, 1997), 60–​79. On the construction and premiere of “Music in Twelve Parts,” see Tim Page, “Music in 12 Parts (1993),” in Kostelanetz, Writings on Glass, 98–​101. 60. Finch, Chuck Close: Work, 76. 61. Friedman, Close Reading, 39; Potter, Four Musical Minimalists, 266. 62. Friedman, Close Reading, 54. 63. Finch, Chuck Close: Work, 44. 64. Quoted in Robert Storr, “Chuck Close: Angles of Refraction,” in Robert Storr (ed.), Chuck Close (New York: Museum of Modern Art, 1998), 44. 65. Friedman, Close Reading, 178. 66. Friedman, Close Reading, 13. 67. Wil S. Hylton, “The Mysterious Metamorphosis of Chuck Close,” New  York Times Magazine, July 13, 2016. 68. Hylton, “Mysterious Metamorphosis of Chuck Close.” 69. Hylton, “Mysterious Metamorphosis of Chuck Close.” 70. Scott Hicks (dir.), Glass: A Portrait of Philip in Twelve Parts (Port Washington, NY: Koch Lorber Films, 2009, orig. 2007), DVD; Philip Glass, “It’s a State of Attention,” in Margery Arent Safir (ed.), Robert Wilson from Within (Paris: Arts Arena, 2011), 99. 71. Glass’s composition is not publicly available in published form, but can be heard on Bruce Levingston, Portraits, Orange Mountain Music 0025, 2006, compact disc.

80

( 80 )   Musical Portraits

72. McGrath, “A Portraitist.” See also Bruce Levingston, “Portraits,” www.premierecommission.org/​recordings/​portraits.html, accessed June 21, 2012. 73. See also Sandra Benito and Anita Feldman, Introduction to Patrick Coleman (ed.), The Art of Music (San Diego: San Diego Museum of Art; New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2015), 19. 74. Kazanjian, “Close Encounter.” 75. McGrath, “A Portraitist.” 76. Ludmilla Jordanova, Defining Features:  Scientific and Medical Portraits 1660–​ 2000 (London: Reaktion Books and National Portrait Gallery, 2000), 18–​20. 77. William Shakespeare, Hamlet, in Stephen Greenblatt (ed.), The Norton Shakespeare (New  York and London:  W. W.  Norton, 1997), 1748. On the subject of portraiture in Hamlet, see Marguerite A. Tassi, The Scandal of Images:  Iconoclasm, Eroticism, and Painting in Early Modern English Drama (Selinsgrove, PA: Susquehanna University Press, 2005), 193. 78. Malcolm Warner, “Portraits about Portraiture,” in Paloma Alarcó and Malcolm Warner (eds.), The Mirror & the Mask:  Portraiture in the Age of Picasso (New Haven, CT:  Yale University Press; Fort Worth: Kimbell Art Museum; Madrid: Museo Thyssen-​Bornemisza and Fundación Caja Madrid, 2007), 20.

  81

CH A P T E R 3

Listening in on Composers’ Self-​Portraits Every portrait that is painted with feeling is a portrait of the artist, not of the sitter. The sitter is merely the accident, the occasion. It is not he who is revealed by the painter; it is rather the painter who, on the coloured canvas, reveals himself. The reason I will not exhibit this picture is that I am afraid that I have shown in it the secret of my own soul. —​Basil Hallward, in The Picture of Dorian Gray1

A

t the turn of the thirteenth century, the artist known as Brother Rufillus of Weissenau illuminated a Passionale (Lives of the Saints), in which he offered attentive readers a self-​conscious view of his creative process in the form of a miniature self-​image. Under an initial letter R, the artist depicted himself holding a mahl stick and brush, using red paint (in reference to his name; rufus is Latin for red) to put the finishing touches on this calligraphic representation of the first letter of both the word that continues in the adjacent text and also his name (Figure 3.1). To the left of the artist stands a table holding cups of paint, and he sits on a bench among other tools of his trade: he occupies his artist’s studio, housed within the bottom of the capital letter. In this playful image, the artist shows himself at work creating the illumination the reader holds in his hands. The initial R serves a dual purpose, as part of the book’s linguistic content and as a gesture outside of the text, toward the creator of the very letters that combine to produce the document’s meanings, and of the illustrations that depict and ornament them. In this way the artist embeds himself within his creation.2 The self-​reflexive effect of the subtle image in Brother Rufillus’s illuminated R can be found in large-​scale painting as well, for example in Jan van Eyck’s Ghent Altarpiece (1432), in which the artist is thought to have depicted his own likeness as one of the judges on horseback on the left of

82

( 82 )   Musical Portraits

Figure  3.1:  Brother Rufillus, Initial R, from a Passionale from Weissenau Abbey, c.  1170–​1200, Cod. Bodmer 127, f. 244r. Fondation Martin Bodmer, Cologny (Geneva).

the massive work, and in Raphael’s Vatican fresco “The School of Athens” (1509–​1511), in which the painter peeks out from behind a group of figures to the far right, making eye contact with the viewer.3 The miniature embedded self-​image functions in part as a signature, attributing the painting to its

  83

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 83 )

Figure  3.2: Eugène Atget, “Coiffeur, Palais Royal,” 1927, albumen silver print (gold-​toned), 7 x 9-​1/​2 inches. Museum of Modern Art. Digital Image © The Museum of Modern Art/​Licensed by SCALA/​Art Resource, NY.

creator. But beyond a simple attribution, it suggests that the larger work of which it is a part does not only show the artist’s handiwork, but also reveals, more profoundly, a view into the artist’s thoughts, access to the creative inspiration that provides the underlying source of the painting’s substance.4 Centuries later a similar effect was created in the medium of photography, in particular in the subtle reflections of the artist and his camera that can be found in mirrors and windows in images by Eugène Atget such as “Coiffure, Palais Royale” (1927) (Figure 3.2). This photograph is primarily a depiction of a ubiquitous aspect of modern life rather than a self-​portrait, but the subtle reflection of Atget and his camera in the glass reminds the viewer of the photographer’s method, and of the careful artifice involved in the creation of the image of a banal aspect of the everyday. Despite music’s inability to convey detailed physical likeness, an analogous playful form of self-​reference is found in a number of works dating from the Baroque era to the present day, by composers who have used monograms formed of their initials or letters from their names to determine patterns of pitches that conjure the impression of their presence in the music. An early and well-​known example is J. S. Bach’s incorporation of his name, spelled with the pitches B-​A-​C-​H (with B in German meaning B♭ and H referring to B♮), in The Art of Fugue (early 1740s). Monograms

84

( 84 )   Musical Portraits

can be found with particular frequency in music of the twentieth century. For example, Alban Berg incorporated his initials A-​B—​alongside H-​F, the initials of his mistress Hanna Fuchs-​Robettin, and C-​C, equivalent to the solfège syllables Do-​Do, a homonym of the nickname of her daughter Dorothea—​in his Lyric Suite (1925–​1926). Dmitri Shostakovich built his monogram, D-​S-​C-​H (with S, or Es, denoting E♭ in German), into numerous compositions, notably the String Quartet No. 8 (1960). Shostakovich’s student Alfred Schnittke continued and expanded this practice: in addition to his own musical monogram, A-​S-​C-​H-​E, which appears in multiple works, B-​A-​C-​H recurs throughout much of his repertoire, in pieces such as the Concerto Grosso No. 3 (1985), as do letters from the name of the violinist Gidon Kremer, his frequent collaborator, which can be heard in the Violin Concerto No. 4 (1984).5 Schnittke often combines multiple monograms to reflect his compositional predecessors in his works, such as in the opening of his String Quartet No. 3 (1983), which incorporates Shostakovich’s D-​S-​C-​H alongside A-​D-​D-​A-​S-​S-​A—​letters from the name of Orlando di Lasso merged with Schnittke’s own initials, A-​S—​and Ludwig van Beethoven’s D-​G-​A-​B-​E-​H. In these examples, the pitches indicated by a monogram, in the manner of Brother Rufillus’s illuminated R, serve two simultaneous functions. Like the R that remains a functional part of the word it initializes, these monograms operate as components of the music’s melodic, rhythmic, and harmonic material. At the same time, the composers’ monograms serve, like the tongue-​in-​cheek image of Brother Rufillus completing his initial, as subtle attributions to the authors of the music, buried within its structures. They also reflect on the artistic process by which those artists created their works. But like Brother Rufillus’s self-​reflexive drawing, which is subordinate to the text of which it is a part, a musical monogram does not function as an autonomous self-​portrait: the Passionale is not principally about Brother Rufillus, and works carrying monograms are in general not about their composers’ identities. Composers’ musical monograms nevertheless self-​ consciously emphasize the fact that the sounds the listener hears have been assembled by the composer whose presence is echoed in the melodic surface, like Atget’s reflection in the pane of glass through which his camera peers. With its self-​conscious reference to the composer who wrote the piece and the creative process by which he did so, the work in which a monogram is embedded becomes, at least in part, a contemplation of the processes of composition. While some composers have used monograms to gesture toward the evocation of the self in this peripheral way, others have engaged more thoroughly with the depiction of their own identities in a subset of musical

  85

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 85 )

portraits that turn their focus back onto their creators. These autonomous musical self-​portraits invite the listener, usually by way of a title, to interpret the piece as a representation of the composer’s impression of his own character and artistic process.6 This chapter explores musical self-​portraiture, considering how the genre relates to self-​portraiture in the visual arts, before turning to two works whose composers depict themselves principally by exploring the sense of hearing. The first of these pieces is György Ligeti’s duet for two pianos “Selbstportrait mit Reich und Riley (und Chopin ist auch dabei)” (Self-​Portrait with Reich and Riley (with Chopin in the Background), 1976), in which Ligeti represents himself in the company of the composers Steve Reich and Terry Riley, and in the ghostly presence of their predecessor Frédéric Chopin. The chapter then turns to Peter Ablinger’s “Quadraturen IV: ‘Selbstportrait mit Berlin’ ” (Self-​Portrait with Berlin, 1998), a piece that depicts its composer by representing and analyzing his experience of the everyday urban thrum that surrounds him. In Ablinger’s work, a compact disc of ambient sounds recorded by the composer in Germany’s capital city is played back and accompanied by an instrumental ensemble that mimics the noises captured on the disc by performing a score produced using a computer analysis of this recording. In their self-​portraits, Ligeti and Ablinger reflect on their professional and artistic identities as they listen to the sounds around them. In Ligeti’s case this aural material constitutes his own music and that of his colleagues, and in Ablinger’s it comprises the noises of the city in which he lives. In this way these works reveal how their composers view the roles of their art, their experiences of sound, and the sense of hearing more generally in the construction of their own identities. MUSICAL AND VISUAL SELF-​P ORTRAITS

Since at least the nineteenth century there has been a recurrent critical approach in writings on music that holds a composer’s works to be autobiographical and to offer insights into his character, calling to mind the Renaissance dictum “Every painter paints himself.”7 One classic example of this way of understanding composers’ relationships with their works can be found in the multiple published nineteenth-​century interpretations of Beethoven’s Symphony No. 9 (1824) that held the work to be autobiographical, in criticism by Friedrich Kanne, Franz Joseph Fröhlich, and Richard Wagner, among others.8 In different ways, these authors considered the emotional progression implied in the symphony—​its assemblage of musical gestures indicating yearning, sadness, heroism, and, finally, happiness—​to mirror the mixture of affects that occupied Beethoven’s

86

( 86 )   Musical Portraits

troubled soul, and heard the move from darkness to exultation between the work’s first and last movements as a narrative construction of Beethoven’s identity, depicting his search for joy during his tumultuous struggle with deafness. Although this sort of approach to understanding composition as a form of self-​portraiture has persevered to the present day in the interpretations of some listeners, musical works explicitly identified as conscious representations of their composers in the form of self-​portraiture occupy a relatively rare but compelling and persistent genre. Among the earliest examples of self-​portraiture in music are François Couperin’s staid and somber “La Couperin” (1730) and Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach’s lively, playful, and ironic “L’Aly Rupalich” (first titled “La Bach” and thought to be a self-​portrait, 1755), both for solo keyboard.9 By using titles to indicate that these compositions are representations of their creators, these and other composers of such works invite their performers and audiences to interpret the music in a manner that corresponds with how they would contemplate a painted self-​portrait. Self-​portraiture in the visual arts is typically understood to have emerged as a coherent genre in the late fifteenth century, as a result of the confluence of both the developing notion of the painter’s intellectual and social role as a creator rather than simply an artisan, and the growing availability of the recent Venetian invention of the flat mirror, which allowed people to contemplate their own appearance in an unprecedented way.10 Self-​portraiture served in this period as an opportunity for artists to affirm their rising status in society, while at the same time reflecting upon and depicting their society through the way they portrayed themselves.11 In the early twentieth century, self-​portraiture flourished as a genre in which artists challenged the longstanding association between outward appearance and inner self, exploring ways of depicting identity in images that distorted physical likeness or even avoided it altogether. Art historian James Hall describes this development in painting by analogy to the way affect is depicted in composition: he calls the end of the first decade of the twentieth century the “high-​water mark of the self-​portrait as pure soul music.”12 Artists have often sought in their self-​portraits to foreground their craft and creativity as essential elements of their identities, interwoven with signs of character and social position.13 One principal way they have done this is through the depiction of the tools they use in the creation of art. In classic and modern works of self-​portraiture including Diego Velázquez’s “Las Meninas” (1656), Rembrandt’s “Portrait of the Artist at His Easel” (1660), Jacques-​Louis David’s “Self-​Portrait” (1794), Pablo Picasso’s “Self-​ Portrait with a Palette” (1906), Norman Rockwell’s “Triple Self-​Portrait” (1960), Richard Avedon’s “Self-​Portrait” (c. 1963), and Lucian Freud’s

  87

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 87 )

“Painter Working, Reflection” (1993), artists have shown themselves with easels, brushes, palettes, cameras, and other instruments of their trade, and sometimes in the process of creating new works of art. In this manner, they emphasize their roles as artists, and their methods, movements, and ways of seeing and representing the world, as crucial aspects of their personal identities. Musical self-​portraiture is often similarly self-​conscious about the musical materials the composer uses in the creation of music. In Benjamin Britten’s “E. B. B.,” the second of his Two Portraits (1930), for example, the composer chose to depict himself in musical form in a work for string orchestra ​that accompanies a solo part for viola, the instrument Britten himself played. The string orchestra and viola serve at one and the same time as the medium of Britten’s representation and the objects portrayed within it as the tools of his artistry, in the manner of the canvases and paintbrushes that are used in the construction of, and also appear depicted within, so many painters’ self-​portraits. The discussions of Ligeti’s and Ablinger’s self-​portraits in the sections that follow demonstrate how these composers are similarly self-​reflexive in their works, offering musical representations whose subject is, in part, the very instruments, technologies, and notes that form the components of the music the listener hears. In addition to representing the tools of their trade in self-​portraits, artists and composers have also treated the genre as providing an opportunity to explore their own aesthetic styles and creative influences. Corresponding examples in the musical and visual arts can also be found in works by the composer John Adams and the artist Richard Hamilton. In Adams’s orchestral work My Father Knew Charles Ives (2003), a piece he describes as a “musical autobiography, my own Proustian madeleine,” the composer combines techniques that he has developed throughout his career with others that he has borrowed from his predecessor Ives, creating a work that offers a fusion of self-​reference and pastiche.14 In the title of the work, Adams creates a fictional but plausible narrative backdrop to his self-​portrait: though his father never did meet Ives, Adams has pointed out that they resided near one another for a time in New England, where they both were businessmen and musicians, and were immersed in the writings of the transcendentalist philosophers who had lived and worked in the region during the previous century.15 Adams states that Ives’s mixture of “the sublime with the vulgar and sentimental,” which Adams views as a particularly American compositional technique, has served as a potent model for him in his career.16 This influence can be heard in Adams’s self-​ portrait, which is structured in three orchestral movements, each named for a place or element of the landscape in the northeastern United States,

88

( 88 )   Musical Portraits

mimicking the equivalent structure of Ives’s Three Places in New England (1911–​1914, rev. 1929). In the first movement, “Concord,” Adams opens by juxtaposing extended chorale-​like chords in the strings with a solo trumpet that plays a line comprising multiple triplet patterns; this instrumentation creates a texture that closely resembles Ives’s “The Unanswered Question” (1908, rev. 1930–​1935). As the movement progresses, wind instruments and ensembles begin to play distorted, overlapping melodic fragments resembling Sousa marches and American patriotic tunes, a technique that can be found in Three Places in New England. In Adams’s hand, however, these references are interwoven with passages of repeated staccato notes that recall earlier pieces by Adams himself such as “Short Ride in a Fast Machine” (1986). In this work, Adams constructs a musical representation of his personal identity by using compositional techniques a knowledgeable listener will readily identify as typical of and unique to Adams, but filtered through an equally recognizable pastiche of the music of his predecessor Ives. In his 1970–​1971 self-​portrait “A Portrait of the Artist by Francis Bacon,” in oil on collotype, Richard Hamilton similarly refers back to his own characteristic techniques while imitating the work of another artist, in this case the painter Francis Bacon, to represent himself, through pastiche, in a manner that conveys Bacon’s influence on his artistic development (Figure 3.3). Working from a Polaroid photograph of his face that was taken by Bacon, Hamilton manipulates the image, deforming his features and blurring its lines to create a figure that resembles Bacon’s haunting paintings such as his 1969 “Self-​Portrait.”17 The medium, manipulated photography and printmaking, is more typical of Hamilton’s oeuvre than Bacon’s, but the overall appearance and the use of oil paints is highly redolent of Bacon’s painted distortions of the human face, and the result is a hybrid self-​portrait, in which Hamilton shows his own visage as if a portrait of him had been painted by Bacon and then captured on photograph and retouched by Hamilton himself. Hamilton explained that he received feedback from Bacon while working on the image, and the final version—​which was, of the several studies for the work, the one that Bacon approved—​felt complete at “the point where I produced something that I found like Francis Bacon, and reasonably satisfying as something of mine. And I learned a great deal—​the interest for me was that I learned so much about Francis Bacon’s work in doing this.”18 In this way Hamilton depicts his artistic self by altering his own likeness in Bacon’s painterly style, an experimental process that offered him an opportunity to study and explore both his own identity and the artistic technique of a contemporary. This method is analogous to Adams’s representation of his identity by merging well-​known technical elements of the music of his American musical forebear with signature attributes of his own style, all

  89

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 89 )

Figure 3.3:  Richard Hamilton, “A Portrait of the Artist by Francis Bacon,” 1970–​1971, collotype and screenprint, 32-​3/​8 x 27-​3/​8 inches. © R. Hamilton. All Rights Reserved, DACS and ARS 2016. Image copyright © The Metropolitan Museum of Art. Image source: Art Resource, NY.

within a larger work whose structure is distinctly Ivesian and whose title is a personal homage to both Adams’s father and his artistic father figure. Self-​portraiture is a particularly intimate genre, one in which artists explore their own subjectivities in order to construct the image of their sense of self, typically through the representation of its visual manifestation in their physical appearance. T. J. Clark explains that self-​portraiture depicts not only the artist’s own likeness, but “the activity of self-​scrutiny[,]‌. . . the physical ‘look’ of looking at one’s face.”19 In the self-​portrait, he writes, “the self to be is shown representing itself.”20 And in this way, in self-​portraiture, the image works as “a metaphor of representing.”21 This genre of painting, then, involves the representation of the sense of sight, the process of visual contemplation. The intense intimacy of the self-​portrait, which requires of the artist an act of sustained personal reflection on himself and his craft, can give the genre an air of inaccessibility, as though the viewer is spying on a particularly private and penetrating gaze into a looking glass. Thus John Berger describes viewing self-​portraits as “watching the drama of a double-​ bind which excludes us.”22 Indeed, the onlooker’s position in relation to the

90

( 90 )   Musical Portraits

artist and his painting may feel ambiguous and even awkward: if the canvas conveys the artist’s identity in the manner of the mirror into which he peers to study his likeness, where can we stand so as to avoid obstructing this private moment of self-​reflection?23 The musical self-​portrait shares a similar sense of intimacy, offering the audience a chance to listen in on a private act of aural contemplation. Ligeti’s self-​portrait, for example, depicts the fruits of sonic self-​scrutiny, portraying what the composer hears when he meditates on the sounds of his own music. Ablinger’s work in the genre may give access to an aspect of hearing even more introspective and personal, as it offers an external realization of his cognitive experience of his urban soundscape, and thereby appears to depict not only how he understands his own music as he listens to it, but most fundamentally how he interacts, through the sense of hearing, with the world around him. GYÖRGY LIGETI’S GROUP SELF-​P ORTRAIT “SELBSTPORTRAIT MIT REICH UND RILEY (UND CHOPIN IST AUCH DABEI)”

In 1976, György Ligeti composed his musical representation of himself in the company of his contemporaries Reich and Riley and their predecessor Chopin, in the second movement of Drei Stücke für zwei Klaviere (Three Pieces for Two Pianos), bookended by “Monument” and “In zart fließender Bewegung” (In a Gentle Flowing Movement). Writing the piece at the request of the pianists Alfons and Aloys Kontarsky, Ligeti initially wished to call it “Still Life with Reich and Riley,” but, partly in order to avoid the morbid resonances of the still life genre, known in French as nature morte, he changed the title to Portrait, and then Self-​ Portrait.24 Ligeti had only first encountered the music of American minimalists in recent years, and was particularly inspired by Riley’s “In C” (1964) and Reich’s “It’s Gonna Rain” (1965) and “Violin Phase” (1967), which he heard on recordings at Stanford University in 1972, during his first visit to the United States.25 Ligeti employs pastiche in his “Selbstportrait” to emphasize compelling similarities between techniques developed independently but simultaneously in his works and those of his contemporaries, whose music he had not yet heard while he was writing “Continuum” (1968), his String Quartet No. 2 (1968), “Coulée” (1969), and other experimental compositions of the 1960s. In this self-​portrait he also highlights striking and unexpected resonances between compositions by these musicians and the romantic pianism of Chopin.

  91

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 91 )

The title of Ligeti’s movement evokes an imaginary snapshot of him alongside his American contemporaries, with Chopin’s visage in the background—​a ghostly apparition, as implied by the parentheses. Ligeti uses the title to indicate that the piece situates his own compositional technique in relation to piano music’s present and past. Ligeti’s group self-​portrait depicts the four musicians’ compositional innovations, in a manner that recalls the tendency of painters of self-​portraiture to emphasize their creative endeavors by depicting themselves with their artistic implements. He follows in this tradition by depicting his subjects in a manner that emphasizes their profession as composers. Painted self-​ portraits typically rely on mimesis to depict artists with their tools: the self-​conscious evocation of the artist’s profession in these works depends on the representation of palettes, brushes, and cameras. Without visual mimesis, Ligeti must find other means to portray himself, Reich, Riley, and Chopin as composers, and to indicate that the notes on the page do not only prescribe the structures for a performance, but also stand self-​ consciously for themselves as the tools these musicians employ in their art. Ligeti borrows musical techniques developed by his subjects to depict them through a stylistic pastiche that combines their compositional processes with his own.26 In painted self-​portraiture since the turn of the twentieth century as well, artists have repeatedly represented themselves not only through direct likeness, but also by emphasizing the artistic techniques they developed earlier in their careers.27 For some artists who challenged the supremacy of mimesis in their works, style and technique took clear precedence over likeness in self-​portraiture. In Picasso’s 1972 “Self-​Portrait,” the viewer sees the artist in the image less because it presents a recognizable likeness than because it offers an exemplar of the cubist style in which Picasso had worked throughout much of his career. Kazimir Malevich similarly turned to technique rather than likeness in self-​portraiture, representing himself in “Suprematism: Self-​Portrait in Two Dimensions” (1915) as an abstract pattern of quadrilaterals and a circle in primary colors and black on a white background (Figure 3.4). Even Malevich’s title indicates that he and his Suprematist style are equivalent.28 More unusual is Ligeti’s depiction of his own style in combination with pastiche evocations of the techniques of other composers. A visual analogy can be found in David Hockney’s etching and aquatint “Artist and Model” (1973–​1974), created shortly after the death of Picasso, with Picasso’s frequent collaborator, the printmaker Aldo Crommelynck. The study of Picasso’s works was pivotal for Hockney’s development, as he sought to break free of naturalism and explore new representational techniques.29 Hockney stages an imaginary meeting with the artist, in which they sit

92

( 92 )   Musical Portraits

Figure  3.4: Kazimir Malevich, “Suprematism:  Self-​Portrait in Two Dimensions,” 1915, oil on canvas, 31-​1/​2 x 24-​3/​8 inches. Stedelijk Museum. Art Resource, NY.

across from one another at a table, each depicted using a different method of printmaking, Hockney in hard-​ground etching and Picasso in a technique using a brush.30 Hockney represents himself naked; he is the artist’s model, and the artist his role model. The image refers in its detail and positioning of the two figures to both Robert Doisneau’s iconic 1952 photograph “Les Pains de Picasso” and Picasso’s depictions of artists and their models in his Vollard Suite (1930–​1937), a series of etchings partly inspired by Honoré de Balzac’s story Le Chef-​d’oeuvre inconnu (The Unknown Masterpiece, 1831), about an old master obsessed by the task of capturing life on canvas in a portrait of a beautiful young woman.31 Like Ligeti, Hockney portrays artistic influence as deriving from a complex relationship between himself and his predecessor, as they face one another, mutually playing the roles of both artist and model. In his program notes for “Selbstportrait,” Ligeti describes the work as a playful, ironic image of the four composers that represents them through the use of compositional techniques associated with their music. He writes that he created supersaturated canons and superimposed grids as tropes to depict himself; phase shifting to evoke the music of Reich; pattern

  93

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 93 )

transformation to stand for Riley; and, toward the end of the movement, a parody of the melodic and rhythmic patterns of the Presto from Chopin’s B​♭ minor Sonata, Op. 35 (1839).32 His notes explain that while the final movement of the Drei Stücke für zwei Klaviere includes allusions to the romanticism of Brahms and Schumann, the piece as a whole related to older musical traditions by paying tribute to the idiomatic piano writing of composers Scarlatti, Schumann, and Chopin.33 “Selbstportrait” is constructed of a perpetual motion of arpeggiated patterns, following the precedent set by Chopin for continuously moving, fast-​paced virtuosic finger work on the piano. The analysis of the piece reveals how Ligeti’s composition operates as a group portrait by combining references to all four composers in a complex musical texture. In section one, Ligeti employs a number of techniques that he had developed since the 1960s, while he also experiments with new compositional methods. Many visual artists have viewed self-​portraiture as offering a rich opportunity for technical experimentation, and in his foray in the genre Ligeti likewise initiates a new compositional procedure, the blocked-​key technique, whereby the left hand in each piano part silently depresses a set of keys while the right hand plays constant patterns of eighth notes in descending scalar units and rising and falling groupings in the contour of a sine wave.34 Because some of the same keys are blocked by the left hand, only a few of the notes make a sound. In the score, audible pitches are depicted with larger note heads and silent pitches with smaller ones; Ligeti asks the pianists to play continuously and evenly, allowing the placement of the left hand to determine the melodic and rhythmic content of each piano part, producing a sonic illusion that the pianists are playing complex arpeggiated rhythmic figurations, rather than constantly fluctuating upward and downward runs. Ligeti attributes the concept behind this technique to the music theorist Henning Siedentopf and the organist Karl-​Erik Welin, with whom he worked on the organ solo “Volumina” (1961–​1962).35 The continuous undulating cells in the right-hand parts in both pianos are composed in what Jane Piper Clendinning has called Ligeti’s “pattern-​ meccanico” style.36 Ligeti builds melodic lines of perpetually repeating fragments that change minimally and gradually as the piece progresses, in a manner evocative of broken machinery. He first experimented with the ideas behind his pattern-​meccanico music in the “Poème symphonique” for one hundred metronomes (1962), but developed the technique in earnest in “Continuum,” the String Quartet No. 2, and elsewhere. He associated his pattern-​meccanico writing with a childhood memory of reading a story by Hungarian author Gyula Krúdy about a widow who lives alone in a house full of ticking clocks. This haunting image, and a later experience of watching Charlie Chaplin’s Modern Times, in which Chaplin’s character works in

94

( 94 )   Musical Portraits

a factory and is at one point swallowed into the gears of a machine, inspired a lifelong fixation on the noises of functioning and broken machinery.37 In light of its deeply personal resonances, the pattern-​meccanico technique serves as a potent signifier of Ligeti’s artistic identity in his self-​portrait. In the first section, Ligeti layers two lines of pattern-​meccanico writing into a texture that he has referred to as micropolyphony in discussions of other similarly constructed works.38 In such compositions the structural techniques guiding the polyphony are inaudible, as unexpected rhythmic groupings, pulsations, and harmonic structures emerge as though through lattice-​works in performance.39 In a manner he had developed since the late 1960s, Ligeti delineates the thick washes of sound with moments of greater stability and clarity in which the texture reduces to narrow intervals that he called “signals.”40 He compared this juxtaposition of clear and dense textures with the traditional evocations of tension and resolution in harmonic and melodic structures of earlier Western music.41 “Selbstportrait” opens with the repetition of a narrow signal, a half step between E𝄫 (initially spelled as D♮) and D♭ in the first piano, with the unison E𝄫 in second piano. The texture gradually fills out into a dense mist by way of accretion, a process that Ligeti commonly employs for broadening his texture between signals, involving the addition of new pitches outside of the space of the initial boundary interval.42 First, Ligeti adds a C to the second piano part (measure N), producing the interval of a whole step with the E𝄫, and a layered pair of half steps across both voices. Next, B♮ enters in the same voice (measure Q), followed by A♯ in the first piano (measure R), and so on, until four discrete pitches are sounding in each voice.43 The texture subsequently thins again (from measure “b”) with the removal of pitches in each voice, until both pianos are playing only a major second of E and D, an interval Ligeti has called a “typical Ligeti signal.”44 The section closes with a sustained trill on these pitches in both pianos (at “m”). Ligeti had been unaware that Reich and Riley also employed continuously repeated patterns that incorporate gradual changes during the same period, and was surprised to learn of such shared compositional techniques between his works and those of his contemporaries when he first heard their music. In addition to using this shared technical innovation in “Selbstportrait,” Ligeti also experiments with new compositional principals that he learned from Reich and Riley, phase shifting and the relinquishing of authorial control by offering the performer an element of choice. Reich developed phase shifting in “It’s Gonna Rain,” “Violin Phase,” and “Piano Phase” (1967), in which multiple musicians or prerecorded tracks play the same melodic material in unison and one gradually accelerates or decelerates while the other remains at tempo. Riley incorporated performer choice into compositions including “In C,” constructed of fifty-​three brief modules

  95

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 95 )

that the musicians are permitted play any number of times before moving on to the next. In “Selbstportrait” a form of phase shifting occurs not because the pianists play at gradually different tempos, as in Reich’s works, but because they perform continuous groupings of different quantities of eighth notes, returning at the start of each set to E𝄫 (until “X,” at which point the groupings begin on F♭ or E, first in piano two, followed by piano one at “Z”). As a result they oscillate between playing unison pitches together and apart. After each new pattern of pitches, Ligeti writes a repeat symbol and indicates the number of times the pianist is to reiterate the same grouping. In the instructions at the start of the score, he explains that when the number of repetitions exceeds eight the pianist need not be entirely precise in counting; when it is between twelve and eighteen, “a deviation of 1–​2 in either direction is tolerated”; and when it is above eighteen the quantity is only approximate. Ligeti’s leniency offers the pianists considerable choice, and their communication in the performance is therefore critical: they each have to estimate the number of repetitions played by the other and signal to one another before continuing on to subsequent pattern groupings. In this way, Ligeti creates his group self-​portrait by combining his own pattern-​ meccanico and latticework processes with Reich’s phase shifting, while following Riley in relinquishing some control over the work’s structure to the performer, merging their stylistic developments in a piece whose idiomatic pianism he has attributed to the influence of Chopin. Ligeti frequently stated that he conceived of strong correlations between musical and visual forms of representation. Since childhood, he had experienced synaesthetic associations between sound and color.45 His compositions were influenced by the works of painters he admired, including Pieter Bruegel the Elder, Hieronymous Bosch, and René Magritte, and he viewed similarities between his pattern-​meccanico processes and the gradually transforming tessellations of M. C. Escher.46 Furthermore, Ligeti described his own works by analogy to visual techniques: he characterized the “acoustical illusions” in “Continuum” as resembling optical illusions, and considered some of his works to collapse the perception of time, unfolding as though over an area of space in a frozen instant, positing a notion of a temporal plane that resembles Morton Feldman’s similar concept of “time canvases,” described in c­ hapter  2.47 Given this deep-​seated correspondence between the aural and the visual in Ligeti’s perception, it is perhaps unsurprising that he would make a foray into portraiture, an artistic genre typically associated with visual media, as a mode in which to merge his compositional innovations with those of his American contemporaries. A typical self-​portrait represents not merely the artist’s likeness, but also what he comes to understand about himself when he considers his

96

( 96 )   Musical Portraits

appearance. By representing his conception of his musical and creative self in “Selbstportrait,” Ligeti offers his audience the opportunity to listen in on what he hears when he contemplates to his own music and compares it with the work of contemporary and past composers. This act of self-​hearing to which the audience gains access constitutes Ligeti’s exploration of his own identity as a composer. In “Selbstportrait,” the musical notes and technical guidelines in the score operate as more than simply instructions for a performer and signs of the sounds of this individual piece; they also stand more broadly for the body of works of Ligeti, Reich, Riley, and Chopin, and in doing so serve as a representation of the four composers’ musical identities. PETER ABLINGER’S SELF-​P ORTRAIT IN THE CIT Y, “QUADRATUREN IV: ‘SELBSTPORTRAIT MIT BERLIN’ ”

In John Baldessari’s 2007 sculptural portrait “Beethoven’s Trumpet (With Ear) Opus # 133,” a large bronze ear trumpet, modeled after one held in the Beethoven House museum in Bonn, emerges from an oversize white ear on a gallery wall (Figure 3.5).48 Rather than conforming to the long history of painted, printed, and sculptural likenesses of Beethoven,

Figure  3.5:  John Baldessari, “Beethoven’s Trumpet (With Ear) Opus # 133,” 2007, foam, resin, aluminum, cold bronze, and electronics, 84 x 120 x 84  inches. Courtesy of the artist and Marian Goodman Gallery.

  97

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 97 )

Baldessari’s portrait represents its subject by evoking not the composer’s appearance—​the wild hair and intense gaze that became so widely recognized in portraits—​but the way that he managed to perceive the world around him through sound in spite of his famously thwarted sense of hearing. When the viewer of this sculptural portrait of the composer speaks or sings into Beethoven’s ear through the trumpet, a portion of Beethoven’s late String Quartet Op. 133, the “Große Fuge” (Great Fugue), composed at a time when Beethoven suffered from advanced deafness, plays back outward in reply.49 The portrait explores a question that has fascinated generations of listeners: how was Beethoven, who was almost entirely unable to hear sounds and music late in his life, still capable of communicating through compositions that would contribute such a rich musical legacy? Baldessari seems to suggest that Beethoven interacted with the world through an individual sense of hearing that translated his experiences into an internal music. In this work the composer is represented principally through an evocation of his unique perception of his surroundings, in an attempt to reach past the external likeness that is the material of traditional portraiture, to access something about the subject that is otherwise fundamentally personal to him and unavailable to others. While Ligeti’s musical self-​portrait also explores a composer’s interactions with sound by evoking his perception of his own music, the self-​portrait of Peter Ablinger, like Baldessari’s multimedia portrait of Beethoven, represents his unique relationship to and experience of the sense of hearing more generally. Ablinger depicts himself through a juxtaposition of the mundane ambient sounds that characterize his environment, in the form of a compact disc that plays back field recordings of Berlin’s city streets, with a musical translation of those sounds for an instrumental ensemble that plays simultaneously with the CD. This pairing offers the listener an idea of how Ablinger himself interprets the sounds of his city as he moves through it: like Beethoven’s trumpet, which plays back a musical response as though to echo how Beethoven “hears” the spectator’s voice, Ablinger’s work offers his audience the representation of his own perception of the noises that surround him. What emerges is a particularly intimate work of self-​portraiture in which the composer proposes an understanding of the self as an object of its own perception.50 Throughout his compositions, Ablinger has frequently considered the relationship between vision and hearing, manipulating sounds as well as images to bring to light the ways these perceptual processes overlap. Ablinger was initially trained in the graphic arts, but he was also active as a jazz pianist, and he decided to enter the field of music instead of visual art when it occurred to him that “I was constantly translating everything I learned about visual sensitization into its equivalent in sound.”51 He has

98

( 98 )   Musical Portraits

explained, nevertheless, that he has found greater aesthetic inspiration in the work of late nineteenth-​and twentieth-​century visual artists than among his compositional predecessors and peers, naming Claude Monet, Andy Warhol, Gerhard Richter, Barnett Newman, and Ad Reinhardt as particularly influential to his music.52 Indeed Ablinger considers himself a painter in music: in his essay “Metaphern” about metaphorical associations between hearing and seeing, which reads as a sort of artistic manifesto, he declares, “Ich BIN ein Maler!”53 Ablinger’s development of a vocabulary of visual metaphors to illustrate his conception of music can be traced throughout many of his writings and interviews. Characterizing his creative process, he has explained, “When I first think about a composition, I try to compose something pictorial on a piece of paper—​it’s a drawing, not a score that is composed from left to right.”54 Ablinger’s descriptions of his music have often relied on analogies to elements of vision, and the titles of his works frequently refer to color, painting techniques, and other aspects of the visual arts, for example his series Weiss/​Weisslich (White/​W hitish) and his composition “Grisailles.” He has also presented his compositions in art galleries, notably in his 2008 solo exhibition Hören hören (translated as “Hearing Listening”) at the Haus am Wandsee in Berlin. The relationship between seeing and listening, which Ablinger conceives as closely knit processes through which we take in and interpret the world around us, is an important factor in the development of his compositions, and his multimedia works frequently involve a strong visual component. In his electroacoustic series IEAOV (1995–​2001), for example, Ablinger explores how the temporal aspect of music can be understood through spatial metaphors. He does so by manipulating and layering recordings of sound in a process he explains as the “verticalization or condensation of successive events within the simultaneousness of a spectrum.”55 He also considers the texture of sound in this work in relation to representational paintings that, like portraits, feature a principal element positioned in the foreground before a more intricate backdrop; for Ablinger, in IEAOV white noise serves as the “background” to the composition’s main “image,” its more salient individual sounds.56 Ablinger pushes the boundaries of the metaphorical connections between music and the visual even further in his series Seeing and Hearing (1994–​2004), a set of photographs taken while the camera is in motion or on an extended exposure setting. The viewer of these photographs is asked to consider them as works of music, to allow the images to conjure in the “mind’s ear” an individual, imaginary melody or sound.57 Ablinger has proposed that the self emerges from the sense of hearing: he writes, “Listening is something that brings myself into being.”58 It

  9

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 99 )

is in particular the din produced by the sounds that surround us on a daily basis, which Ablinger refers to with the German word Rauschen and the English terms “white noise” and “static noise,” that, he argues, offer us the opportunity to look inwardly and explore who we are.59 The sounds of a waterfall or of a city street corner, to him, “are as far as possible devoid of meaningful information yet they act like a mirror, they throw something back upon ourselves insofar as we read something into them, turn them into something which is anchored only in ourselves. Hence in such situations we experience ourselves.”60 Ablinger locates the origins of his interest in white noise in an experience he had that served as a sort of paradigm shift in his thinking about both art and his personal sense of self: when taking a walk through a field of grains in the Austrian countryside in 1986, he suddenly experienced a kind of epiphany, a “jerking open of perception” that allowed him to hear the noises created by the nature around him in a heightened way.61 With this moment of elevated sensory sensitivity, “Before and after were categorically separated, had nothing more to do with each other.”62 Most of the compositions Ablinger has written since this date have dealt in one way or another with the act of listening and how it relates to and defines the conception of the self.63 For Ablinger, listening is never passive; it is an active form of perception that “continuously reconstructs” ourselves and our surroundings rather than “simply record[ing] what is happening ‘out there.’ ”64 In much of his music, Ablinger explores this mode of perception by inviting audiences to interact with the sorts of “white noise” they are typically prone to filter out, to listen deeply to the droning sounds of daily life, and in doing so to reflect on how identity is formed through hearing. In this way, Ablinger views his compositions as “a research project; research into perception. And about how perception creates us!”65 Ablinger’s notions of the self as defined by perception through listening, and of listening as closely intersecting with seeing, are manifested in the composer’s ongoing series of compositions Voices and Piano (begun in 1998). In each of these works, Ablinger pairs a CD recording of the voice of a celebrated figure in art and politics, including Jorge Luis Borges, Bertolt Brecht, Marcel Duchamp, Mao Tse-​tung, Morton Feldman, and Gertrude Stein, with a part for live solo pianist playing what Ablinger calls a musical “analysis” of the voice. The piano part is designed on the foundation of a temporal and spectral scan of the recording, producing what Ablinger describes as “something like a coarse gridded photograph.”66 Notes are then assigned to the piano on the basis of this computerized output, to create a kind of musical translation of the voice. Ablinger has characterized these works as portraits of their subjects, and on the page of his website dedicated to the series he includes a photographic

100

( 100 )   Musical Portraits

portrait of each person whose voice he has used to create this set of compositions.67 More frequently, however, Ablinger has said that rather than functioning as individual portraits, the works in his Voices series come together to form a single large-​scale self-​portrait. Adopting a contemporary conception of the self as polyvocal, mutable, and perpetually under construction, he explains that the works together represent “a large encounter of voices ‘in me.’ ”68 If the individual’s identity is always created discursively through interactions with the voices of others, the series Voices and Piano will continually expand and change as Ablinger encounters new voices that help him to reconceive his identity and incorporates these one by one into new arrangements that join the others in a growing self-​portrait. The genre and aims of self-​portraiture have influenced Ablinger’s creative method more generally as he has attempted to develop compositional techniques that reflect his understanding of the self as the product of perception, and particularly of the sense of hearing. Expressing the common view that audiences have the opportunity to learn about and develop their own identities in contemplating a work of music, Ablinger has written that, in taking in a piece of music, the listener encounters his self-​image through the act of perceiving the sounds, which serve as a kind of mirror. Ablinger describes this process in idiosyncratic terms, adapting the language of Renaissance theories of perspective, as Willem de Kooning and Morton Feldman do in their discussions of art spectatorship described in ­chapter 2. He writes that this process requires “inverse perspective,” in which, rather than the spectator occupying the vantage point and looking toward the vanishing point represented in the work of art, the listener instead becomes both vantage and vanishing point as he looks back at himself as he is reflected in the artistic representation he contemplates.69 Like the viewer of Atget’s “Coiffeur, Palais Royale,” who might see his own portrait in the glossy surface of the photograph that features its own reflected image, or the listener Boulez describes in his discussion of Pli selon pli who perceives himself reflected in the music (see c­ hapter 2), the audience member, according to Ablinger, will notice his own faint likeness peering—​or listening—​back in a reflection on the surface of the art object he contemplates. Ablinger invokes portraiture as a metaphor for all art, characterizing it as a genre that reverses the direction spectatorship: “Sound, music, becomes a portrait of its individual perceivers. . . . Sound is what hears us, what scrutinizes us. Then and only then when sound itself is still and absolutely ‘attentive’ can it seize us, we the inattentive, we in motion, only then can it ‘portray’ us.”70 Though Ablinger’s explanations of what happens when we perceive a work of art can seem rather speculative and even eccentric at their most abstract, his basic point is that through active listening we are able to learn more about ourselves, and in this way music and sound act as a looking glass in

  10

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 101 )

which we can contemplate the image of ourselves as we would in preparing to create a self-​portrait. In “Selbstportrait mit Berlin,” Ablinger’s first work to be explicitly identified as a self-​portrait, the composer experiments with the technique of pairing recordings with their instrumental imitation as a mode of exploring how his identity might be defined by the sounds that surround him. This piece is the fourth installment of his Quadraturen, an ongoing series begun in 1997 that to date includes five works. In the Quadraturen, Ablinger experiments with what he calls “phonorealism,” the realist representation of sounds he has captured in recordings that he calls “phonographs,” sonic photographs. This method is a musical analogue to photorealism in painting, a movement that originated in the late 1960s in the works of artists including Robert Bechtle and Chuck Close (who has nevertheless resisted the use of this term to describe his early paintings) and involved the use of the traditional means of painting to create detailed canvases that resemble the precision of photographic representation.71 Ablinger describes his creative process in the Quadraturen series as involving three principal steps: (1) The first step is always an acoustic photograph (“phonograph”). This can be a recording of anything: speech, street noise, music. (2) Time and frequency of the chosen “phonograph” are dissolved into a grid of small “squares” whose format may, for example, be 1 second (time) to 1 second (interval). (3) The resulting grid is the score, which is then to be reproduced in different media: on traditional instruments, computer controlled piano, or in white noise.72 The resulting juxtaposition of actual sounds with their musical depictions offers Ablinger the opportunity to explore how musical representation might be construed as a form of perception. In these works, for Ablinger, “the music operates here as an observer: music observes reality. And it is precisely the limits of this approximation which afford us some insights into the instrument of observation. Music, the cultural creation, becomes a metaphor for perception.”73 His association of perception with the formation of identity and with the genre of portraiture is woven throughout the works in the Quadraturen series; in addition to his self-​portrait, the first piece in the series is called “Stadtportrait Graz” (City Portrait Graz), and the third incorporates musical portraits of his parents. Ablinger has explained that with “Selbstportrait mit Berlin,” he continues to link perception to the construction of the self, and to consider music as a mirror that reverses the typical perspective of artworks, so they reflect back

102

( 102 )   Musical Portraits

on the identity of the audience. He writes that in this work, “it’s not how people see me, but what I see (and hear) that forms the subject of the piece. In other words the portrait reveals the view of the observer rather than the observer himself.”74 He creates this effect in the pairing of “real” sounds, which consist of recordings of ambient noises captured on six microphones set up in Berlin and played through loudspeakers onstage, with a musical composition devised on the basis of the computer analysis of these recordings created using Ablinger’s temporal and spectral scanning software. The ensemble arrangement of the white noise of Berlin’s city streets, composed for flute, two clarinets, two violins, viola, two cellos, and three keyboards (pianos or a combination of pianos and electronic keyboards), suggests a representation of how Ablinger, with his particular aesthetic subjectivity, perceives the sounds recorded objectively by the microphones. As Ablinger puts it, “the music becomes an observer of reality”; the composition, with its inversion of perspective, doubles for Ablinger himself as the subject hearing the world around him.75 In other words, “if I bring together street noises and classical instruments, the first one functions as the uncomprehensive, surrounding everything, and the second as our given cultural reaction to it.”76 This cultural reaction is the perceptual process through which identity is constructed. “Selbstportrait mit Berlin” consists of six brief movements of nearly equal length, between two and three minutes. The first movement opens with the ensemble playing together, and the recording follows soon after. The ensemble plays staccato block chords at a regular pulse; the music leaves little room for expression, though slides in the clarinet add a touch of whimsical coloration. In the score, timings are marked to the fraction of a second to keep the performers on cue with the recording, and the meter changes regularly. This sense of repetition and the regularity of the chordal ostinato pattern suggest the effects of the grid-​like representation of the ambient sound recordings that Ablinger creates using the computer’s spectral analytical software. The CD recording, which enters soon after the players begin to perform, contributes a constant drone of white noise within which it is generally impossible to differentiate one sound or source from the other, though the attentive listener can make out the occasional noise, such as the fragment of a voice or of a squeak from the wheels of a vehicle. As the movement progresses, the ensemble’s part changes gradually:  the tempo slows and the musical texture thins as several instruments drop out, only expanding in forces again in a crescendo in the last moments of the section. The remaining movements of the work are constituted similarly of the ensemble playing regular pulsing chords alongside recordings of the city noises that merge into a sound resembling radio static. Occasional changes

  103

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 103 )

in texture and structure stand out in the work; for example, the end of the fourth movement involves greater rhythmic variation, with the instruments playing together in a sequence of irregular durations. And at times the sounds in the recordings change and become easier to identify. In movements 5 and 6 the CD seems to capture the din of an interior space, perhaps a restaurant or cafeteria, in which the white noise involves numerous human voices and the sporadic clinking of glasses or dinnerware. In these movements the rhythmic language also becomes increasingly rapid and complicated; toward the end of the final movement, the music has grown more and more chaotic, far from the homophony that characterized it at the start. In “Selbstportrait mit Berlin,” by playing back the “phonographic” sounds of the city and writing music for ensemble that represents a musical translation of these sounds, Ablinger posits a conception of identity as constantly in flux and based on the experience of the surrounding world, a view that accords with the social constructionist approach to the self that considers human identity to be changeable, fragmented, and polyvocal. But because the principal subject of his work is the process of perception, implying that how we hear (as evoked by the ensemble) supersedes in importance what we hear (as captured on the CD in the drone of white noise), he appears at the same time to suggest an understanding of identity as encapsulated in the inborn, elemental ability to take in, discern, and make sense of sound through hearing. This is a view that seems to accord with a more traditional notion of identity as embedded within us rather than constructed in an external social and discursive space, as embodied in and tied up with our inborn physiologies. In this self-​portrait, in other words, Ablinger refuses to cast his lot entirely with either the postmodern social constructionist or the more traditional essentialist view of the self; rather, he finds a way to bring these theories together, using perception and the physical senses as the bond between our surroundings and our bodies that helps us determine who we are. But Ablinger’s self-​portrait, constructed using microphones and analytic computer software and performed by a combination of live musicians and a stereo system, also leaves the listener with the potentially unsettling question of the extent to which identities are formed by contemporary technologies. The work is ostensibly about Ablinger’s simplest and most natural interaction with his surroundings through hearing—​a sense that cannot be avoided or shut off as easily as can sight, touch, taste, and smell, and that offers a source of constant input throughout the day—​ and through his personal and individual aesthetic sensibility, depicted in his hermeneutic transformation of unedited recordings of ambient sounds into musical notes. But as this depiction of human perception is

104

( 104 )   Musical Portraits

in fact largely devised by inanimate computers and performed by sound recording playback systems, it seems that Ablinger’s self-​portrait may imply, after all, that the senses through which we take in our surroundings involve perceptual processes that are inherently mechanical and automatic. Or perhaps he indicates that our contemporary selves are so tightly interwoven with today’s technologies that the construction of identity is no longer mediated so much by society as it is by machine. CONCLUSION

In Philip Roth’s 1974 novel My Life as a Man, the narrator, a novelist named Peter Tarnopol, pictures a conversation with a psychologist who has seen him in therapy and then written an article called “Creativity: The Narcissism of the Artist,” in which he disguises Tarnopol’s identity to describe their sessions. Among his imagined retorts to the therapist’s characterization of him, the chagrined Tarnopol exclaims: And if I may, sir—​his self is to many a novelist what his own physiognomy is to a painter of portraits: the closest subject at hand demanding scrutiny, a problem for his art to solve—​ given the enormous obstacles to truthfulness, the artistic problem. He is not simply looking into the mirror because he is transfixed by what he sees. Rather, the artist’s success depends as much as anything on his powers of detachment, on denarcissizing himself. That’s where the excitement comes in. That hard conscious work that makes it art!77

Like the novelist as Tarnopol describes him, Ligeti and Ablinger take the opportunity in their self-​portraits to propose answers to the questions of what constitutes the self, and of what role the composer’s creative techniques and his means of perceiving and contemplating his surroundings play in the development of his identity. These composers offer their audiences an opportunity to learn what they hear when they listen to their own music, and, moreover, when they consider how the sense of hearing constructs their personal identities. In “Selbstportrait mit Reich und Riley (und Chopin ist auch dabei)” and “Quadraturen IV: ‘Selbstportrait mit Berlin,’ ” these composers listen deeply, with the focus of an artist or author looking closely in the mirror to prepare to paint a self-​portrait or to write an autobiographical novel, and then they treat what they hear with sufficient detachment to analyze it thoroughly. It is these analyses—​of the technical characteristics of and influences on Ligeti’s music, of the sounds of Ablinger’s environment and the way he perceives them—​that ultimately form the material for the composers’ representations of their individual selves.

  105

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 105 )

NOTES 1. Oscar Wilde, The Picture of Dorian Gray (Leipzig: Bernhard Tauchnitz, 1908), 12. 2. See James Hall, The Self-​Portrait: A Cultural History (London: Thames and Hudson, 2014), 25. 3. For a history of this technique in the Italian Renaissance, see Joanna Woods-​Marsden, Renaissance Self-​Portraiture: The Visual Construction of Identity and the Social Status of the Artist (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998), 43–​62. 4. Omar Calabrese, Artists’ Self-​Portraits, trans. Marguerite Shore (London: Abbeville Press Publishers, 2006), 33. 5. See Christopher Segall, “Klingende Buchstaben: Principles of Alfred Schnittke’s Monogram Technique,” Journal of Musicology 30.2 (Spring 2013): 252–​86. 6. Some compositions may also be interpreted as self-​portraits though they lack titles that explicitly identify them as such. For example, Michael J. Puri sees Maurice Ravel’s ballet “Daphnis et Chloé” as involving an element of self-​portraiture. See Michael J. Puri, “Dandy, Interrupted: Sublimation, Repression, and Self-​Portraiture in Maurice Ravel’s Daphnis et Chloé (1909–​1912),” Journal of the American Musicological Society 60.2 (Summer 2007): 317–​72. 7. On this concept in art history, see Joanna Woodall, “‘Every Painter Paints Himself ’: Self-​ Portraiture and Creativity,” in Anthony Bond and Joanna Woodall (eds.), Self-​ Portrait: Renaissance to Contemporary (London: National Portrait Gallery, 2005), 17. 8. Nicholas Cook, Beethoven:  Symphony No. 9 (Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press, 1993), 27, 70–​3. 9. On self-​portraiture in Bach’s “L’Aly Rupalich,” see Joshua S. Walden, “Composing Character in Musical Portraits: Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach and L’Aly Rupalich,” Musical Quarterly 91.2 (Fall-​Winter 2008): 379–​411; Joshua S. Walden, “What’s in a Name?: C. P. E. Bach and the Genres of the Character Piece and Musical Portrait,” in Anthony DelDonna (ed.), Genre in Eighteenth-​Century Music (Ann Arbor, MI:  Steglein, 2008), 111–​38; Annette Richards, “Picturing the Moment in Sound: C. P. E. Bach and the Musical Portrait,” in Thomas Donahue (ed.), Essays in Honor of Christopher Hogwood: The Maestro’s Direction (Lanham, MD: Scarecrow Press, 2011), 57–​89. 10. Anthony Bond, “Performing the Self?” in Bond and Woodall, Self-​Portrait, 31. On the genre’s origins, see also James Hall’s suggestion that the roots of the genre can be found in the middle ages, earlier than the typical attribution of the late fifteenth century. See Hall, Self-​Portrait, 8–​9. 11. Hall, Self-​Portrait, 49–​51. 12. Hall, Self-​Portrait, 234. See also Wendy Wick Reaves, “Reflections/​Refractions:  Self-​ Portraiture in the Twentieth Century,” in Wendy Wick Reaves (ed.), Reflections/​ Refractions:  Self-​Portraiture in the Twentieth Century (Washington, DC:  Smithsonian Institution Scholarly Press; Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2009), 4. 13. Calabrese, Artists’ Self-​Portraits, 161, 183. 14. John Adams, Hallelujah Junction: Composing an American Life (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2008), 229. 15. John Adams, liner notes to The Dharma at Big Sur; My Father Knew Charles Ives, BBC Symphony Orchestra, Nonesuch 79857-​2, 2006, compact disc. 16. Adams, liner notes to The Dharma at Big Sur; My Father Knew Charles Ives. 17. Hal Foster, “The Hamilton Test,” in Mark Godfrey, Paul Schimmel, and Vicente Todolí (eds.), Richard Hamilton (London: Tate, 2014), 178, fn. 33. 18. Richard Hamilton, “Talk at the Palais des Beaux-​Arts, Brussels, 1971,” in Godfrey, Schimmel, and Todolí, Richard Hamilton, 201–​7 (204). 19. T. J. Clark, “Gross David with the Swoln Cheek: An Essay on Self-​Portraiture,” in Michael S. Roth (ed.), Rediscovering History:  Culture, Politics, and the Psyche (Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994), 280. 20. Clark, “Gross David,” 296. 21. Clark, “Gross David,” 297. 22. John Berger, Portraits: John Berger on Artists, ed. Tom Overton (London: Verso, 2015), 151. See also Richard Leppert, Art and the Committed Eye: The Cultural Functions of Imagery (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1996), 163. Leppert writes that in the case of self-​portraiture,

106

( 106 )   Musical Portraits

the viewer is made “almost, but never quite, irrelevant,” as the genre involves primarily a gaze between the painter and his self-​image. 23. Reaves, “Reflections/​Refractions,” 3. 24. Richard Steinitz, György Ligeti:  Music of the Imagination (London:  Faber and Faber, 2003), 207–​8. 25. Steinitz, György Ligeti, 206. 26. Constantin Floros interprets the work as a series of four consecutive musical portraits, representing Ligeti, Reich, Riley, and Chopin, respectively. This description is insightful and supported by a rich analysis, but it overlooks the complex ways Ligeti merges the techniques of all four composers throughout the piece. Constantin Floros, György Ligeti: Jenseits von Avantgarde und Postmoderne (Vienna: Lafite, 1996), 131. 27. Joseph Leo Koerner, “Self-​Portraiture Direct and Oblique,” in Bond and Woodall, Self-​Portrait, 68. 28. Calabrese, Artists’ Self-​Portraits, 358, 370. 29. Kay Heymer, “Mirror Images,” in Marco Livingstone and Kay Heymer (eds.), Hockney’s Portraits and People (London: Thames and Hudson, 2003), 28; Barbara Stern Shapiro, “Hockney Works on Paper,” in Sarah Howgate and Barbara Stern Shapiro (eds.), David Hockney Portraits (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press; London: National Portrait Gallery, 2006), 65. 30. Marco Livingstone, David Hockney (London: Thames and Hudson, 1981), 166. 31. Reaves, Reflections/​Refractions, 125. The depiction in self-​portraiture of the younger artist in the presence of a teacher or role model can be found in early works in the genre as well. In one compelling example, Sofonisba Anguissola’s “Self-​Portrait with Bernardino Campi” (1550), Anguissola depicts herself as the creation of her painting master Campi: her likeness appears as an image on a canvas resting on a easel, before which Campi stands with paintbrush and mahl stick, as though in the act of creating her portrait. Bond, “Performing the Self?” 36. 32. The program notes are reproduced in Stephen Ferguson, György Ligetis Drei Stücke für zwei Klaviere: Eine Gesamtanalyse (Tutzing: Hans Schneider, 1994), 265–​6. 33. Ferguson, György Ligetis Drei Stücke, 265–​6. See Ligeti’s discussion of his predecessors’ idiomatic writing for piano as a model for his work, in György Ligeti, Péter Várnai, Josef Häusler, and Claude Samuel, György Ligeti in Conversation (London:  Eulenberg, 1983), 23. 34. Ligeti returned to the blocked-​key technique in the third piece of his Études, Book 1 (1985). Jeffrey Perry proposes that Ligeti might have derived the idea for this procedure from Cage’s works for prepared piano. See Jeffrey Perry, “Cage’s Sonatas and Interludes for Prepared Piano: Performance, Hearing and Analysis,” Music Theory Spectrum 27.1 (Spring 2005): 55, fn. 19. 35. György Ligeti, “Performance Instructions,” in Monument-​Selbstportrait-​Bewegung (Mainz: B. Schott’s Söhne, 1976). 36. Jane Piper Clendinning, “The Pattern-​ Meccanico Compositions of György Ligeti,” Perspectives of New Music 31.1 (Winter 1993): 192–​243. 37. Ligeti, Várnai, Häusler, and Samuel, György Ligeti in Conversation, 17. 38. Ligeti, Várnai, Häusler, and Samuel, György Ligeti in Conversation, 14–​15. For a discussion of Ligeti’s micropolyphony, see Jonathan W. Bernard, “Voice Leading as a Spatial Function in the Music of Ligeti,” Music Analysis 13.2/​3 ( July–​October 1994): 227–​53. 39. Bernard, “Voice Leading as a Spatial Function,” 15. 40. Bernard, “Voice Leading as a Spatial Function,” 28–​9, 31. See also Jonathan W. Bernard, “Ligeti’s Restoration of Interval and Its Significance for His Later Works,” Music Theory Spectrum 21.1 (Spring 1999): 2. 41. Ligeti, Várnai, Häusler, and Samuel, György Ligeti in Conversation, 60. 42. Michael Hicks, “Interval and Form in Ligeti’s Continuum and Coulée,” Perspectives of New Music 31.1 (Winter 1993): 174. 43. For a discussion of this technique, see Michael Hicks, “Interval and Form,” 174. 44. Ligeti, György Ligeti in Conversation, 29. 45. Ligeti, György Ligeti in Conversation, 58. 46. Steinitz, György Ligeti, 206.

  107

L i s t e n i n g i n o n Co mp o s e r s ’ S e lf - P o rt r a i t s   

( 107 )

47. On “acoustical illusions,” see Herman Sabbe, “György Ligeti—​Illusions et Allusions,” Interface 8.1 (1979): 30. On Ligeti’s conception of time and space, see Jonathan W. Bernard, “Inaudible Structures, Audible Music: Ligeti’s Problem, and His Solution,” Music Analysis 6.3 (October 1987): 210. For a discussion of the challenges involved in the translation of the German-​language metaphors Ligeti employs in discussing music in relation to the senses of sight and touch, see Mark Shuttleworth, “Difficulty in Translation: Grappling with Ligeti’s Musical Metaphors,” in Helen Julia Minors (ed.), Music, Text and Translation (London: Bloomsbury, 2013), 175–​86. 48. Stefan Gronert and Christina Végh (eds.), John Baldessari:  Music (Cologne:  Verlag der Buchhandlung Walther König, 2007), 127. 49. There are six versions of this work, each named for the opus number of one of Beethoven’s late string quartets and featuring the sound of that piece. 50. Ablinger has composed one additional self-​ portrait, the 2009 multimedia work “Selbstportrait mit Mittersill” (Mittersill is the name of an Austrian city). In this “sketch in three sections,” the first part is scored for four children, one teenager, and red, blue, and yellow helium balloons; in the second a sound recording is played from the stage; and the third is for a solo performer who rubs twelve objects across the surface of a table to create a succession of noises. 51. Peter Ablinger and Chiyoko Szlavnics, “Two Composers’ Talk,” 2007, http://​ablinger. mur.at/​txt_​2_​talk.html. 52. G. Douglas Barrett, “Between Noise and Language: The Sound Installations and Music of Peter Ablinger,” Mosaic 42.4 (December 2009): 148; Peter Ablinger, “Metaphern (Wenn die Klänge die Klänge wären),” in Sabine Sanio and Christian Scheib (eds.), Übertragung—​ Transfer—​Metapher:  Kulturtechniken, ihre Visionen und Obsessionen (Bielefeld:  Kerber, 2004), http://​ablinger.mur.at/​docu14.html. 53. Ablinger, “Metaphern.” 54. Ablinger and Szlavincs, “Two Composers’ Talk.” 55. Sergio Bové, “Beyond the Boundaries of Music: Some Connections in Peter Ablinger’s Work,” 2013, http://​ablinger.mur.at/​docs/​bove_​beyond.pdf. 56. Bové, “Beyond the Boundaries.” 57. Bové, “Beyond the Boundaries.” 58. Katja Blomberg, Forward to Katja Blomberg, Chico Mello, Christian Scheib, and Trond Reinholdtsen (eds.), Peter Ablinger: HÖREN hören/​hearing LISTENING (Berlin: Kehrer, 2008), 18. 59. On Ablinger’s conception of noise, see also Jennie Gottschalk, Experimental Music since 1970 (London: Bloomsbury, 2016), 155–​7. 60. Peter Ablinger and Trond Olav Reinholdtsen, “The Sounds Do Not Interest Me,” 2005, http://​ablinger.mur.at/​engl.html. 61. Peter Ablinger, “Peter Ablinger—​English Texts,” trans. Bill Dietz, accessed February 15, 2016, http://​ablinger.mur.at/​engl.html. 62. Ablinger, “Peter Ablinger—​English Texts.” 63. Ablinger, “Peter Ablinger—​English Texts.” 64. Ablinger and Reinholdtsen, “Sounds Do Not Interest Me.” 65. Carlos Bermejo, “Seven Projections in the Music of Peter Ablinger,” accessed June 21, 2016, http://​ablinger.mur.at/​docs/​CarlosBermejo_​7Projections.pdf. Originally published as Carlos Bermejo Martín, “Siete proyecciones en la música de Peter Ablinger,” Revista Europea de Investigación en Arquitectura 1 (2013): 15–​24. 66. Peter Ablinger and Anny Ballardini, “About Voices and Piano,” ed. Rita Duckworth, accessed June 21, 2016, http://​ablinger.mur.at/​voices_​and_​piano.html. The statement on this web page is taken from a 2004 interview with Anny Ballardini. The computer analysis of the vocal recordings is conducted using software Ablinger created in collaboration with Thomas Musil at the Institute of Electronic Music in Graz. Peter Ablinger and Stéphane Ginsburgh, “Peter Ablinger: Voices and Piano,” 2011, http://​ablinger.mur.at/​ docs/​v+p_​ginsburgh.pdf. 67. Ablinger and Szlavincs, “Two Composers’ Talk”; Ablinger and Ballardini, “About Voices and Piano.”

108

( 108 )   Musical Portraits

68. Ablinger and Ginsburgh, “Peter Ablinger: Voices and Piano.” 69. Peter Ablinger, “Inverse Perspective,” trans. Bill Dietz, 1995, http://​ablinger.mur.at/​ engl.html. The idea that the viewer of a work of art sees himself in a kind of inverse perspective also underlies Philippe Halsman’s whimsical artwork Mona Dalì: What Dalì Sees When He Looks at Mona Lisa (1954), in which the Mona Lisa is reproduced, but with the eyes, mustache, and hands of Salvador Dalì. This painting is discussed in Wendy Steiner, “Postmodern Portraits,” Art Journal 46.3 (Autumn 1987): 174. 70. Ablinger, “Inverse Perspective.” 71. Ablinger, “Metaphern.” 72. Peter Ablinger, “Quadraturen,” trans. Bill Dietz, accessed June 21, 2016, http://​ablinger. mur.at/​docu11.html. In describing this process, which he developed at the Institute of Electronic Music in Graz, he elaborates: “First, a semitone filter was constructed, one that allowed intervallic sizes to be varied at will. Then, the concept of temporal screening—​in the sense of a series of more or less rapid static analyses—​was developed for the entire sound spectrum. At the beginning of 1997 the first two-​dimensional screenings in real time became possible.” 73. Ablinger and Reinholdtsen, “Sounds Do Not Interest Me.” 74. Ablinger, “Quadraturen.” 75. Ablinger, “Quadraturen.” 76. Ablinger, “Quadraturen.” 77. Philip Roth, My Life as a Man, in Philip Roth, Novels 1973–​1977 (New York: Library of America, 2006, orig. 1974), 597.

  109

CH A P T E R 4

Celebrity, Music, and the Multimedia Portrait The pictures that I am known for are not really my image, they’re always the photographer’s vision of me. I can look a hundred different ways, but what people see of me in pictures is not really my image. —​Kate Moss1

A

s the prior chapters of this book have explored, composers and artists often turn to the genre of portraiture to reveal the invisible attributes of identity that they perceive in the individuals they choose to represent, and in some cases also to portray their understandings of themselves. A portrait is accordingly considered successful when it conveys something truthful about its subject’s identity beyond simply mirroring physical appearance. But in the epigraph to this chapter the British supermodel Kate Moss, the subject of thousands of portraits since she began her career in the late 1980s, describes her ubiquitous likeness as inadequate to the depiction of her true self. Moss suggests that the images of her that have appeared in news, magazines, and tabloids, on billboards, and in advertising media accomplish the opposite of the goal that commentators have associated with portraiture for many centuries: in idealizing her likeness and employing it toward commercial ends, they hide her personal identity. Contemporary celebrity portraiture generally involves the idealization of physical appearance, often, arguably, at the expense of conveying true character, and Moss’s statement offers a reminder that the portrait always constructs a circumscribed interpretation or impression of its subject’s identity, one carefully devised by the artist. This remark might provoke us to reflect on how we can account for the aspects of a person’s character that may be omitted from a portrait, as well as how we should determine whether we

110

( 110 )   Musical Portraits

can trust the artist’s representation to show a truthful and comprehensive representation of its subject. Portraits of military and national leaders, like those of celebrity actors and models, have also historically tended toward idealization and exaggeration. Such depictions, in the forms of paintings, coins, and statuary, typically idealize attributes of strength, resolve, and virtue, while underplaying or entirely eclipsing any aspects of the subject that can be perceived as deficiencies of physical appearance or character.2 The capacity of a portrait’s representation to be opaque, to frame a person’s likeness in a manner that highlights or even invents particular aspects of character while blocking others from view, has been the subject of commentary on the genre at least since Aristotle, who advised poets, in describing noble characters, to follow the example of portrait painters who represent their subjects faithfully but at the same time improve upon them in their paintings, creating perfected imitations of what is found in life and revealing only certain attributes of character while occluding others.3 The potentially deceptive quality of the portrait that idealizes or otherwise constructs a limited interpretation of its subject is dramatized in the dreamlike third act of John Adams’s opera Nixon in China (1987). In this closing section of the opera, the iconic portrait of Mao that hung above Tiananmen gate in Beijing until the late 1960s (it was subsequently replaced by another portrait) and that was reproduced numerous times on colorful silkscreens by Andy Warhol, looms over the other characters from the back of the stage. This painting is a visual encomium to Mao, who exhibits the attributes of a leader: he appears resolute and strong, as well as inaccessible and larger than life. But Adams and his collaborators, the librettist Alice Goodman and director Peter Sellars, suggest that this austere, glorifying representation might have obscured from public view an identity that was more melancholy and introspective, a character reflected in the line Mao sings as he appears from behind a panel at the mouth of the portrait, “I am alone.” Madame Mao turns to him and sings, “Come down, give me your hand, old man.” And down he comes, emerging from his portrait to join his wife and sing an intimate duet in which they reminisce about the time they met and danced together years before. Mao is now agile and articulate, in contrast with the physical weakness and verbal opacity that marked his appearances before his American visitors in earlier scenes,4 and his behavior reveals a nostalgic private nature that is not depicted by the idealizing strength of his most famous representation. This contrast is reflected by a shift in his music, which, choppy and aggressive in prior scenes, now mimics the smooth, syncopated timbres of American swing. This sequence demonstrates the opera creators’ notion that the famous portrait, by which the world had come to perceive Mao, obscures more

  1

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 111 )

than it reveals, constructing a highly limited sense of his identity and hiding complexities of character behind the idealized likeness. On the other hand, as the sympathetic musical portrait of Mao in this scene sheds no light on the aspects of his character that contributed to the hardships of his governing policies, the cruelties of the Cultural Revolution, and the death and suffering of so many of his subjects, it could be said that Adams’s portrait of Mao, too, is far more opaque than it is revelatory. As an artistic construction of identity—​in painting, literature, music, or any other medium or combination of media—​portraiture can be as illusory as it is revelatory.5 But as Adams’s animation of the painting of Mao may be understood to indicate, the portrait’s deceptions are not necessarily entirely persuasive to the viewer who exercises the hermeneutic capacity to look beyond the image, constructing a more complex conception of its subject’s identity than the image seems to convey on its own. The American stage director and visual artist Robert Wilson’s extensive and varied body of work in the genre offers an especially compelling opportunity to explore this conflict of representation between the ways the portrait can heighten certain aspects of identity, obscure others, or even entirely mislead viewers with fabrications of character, and the expansive possibility it can still provide for rich interpretation. Wilson’s portraits highlight this aspect of the genre in large part because they tend to focus on the representation of widely recognized contemporary celebrities, including actors, singers, and political icons, figures who have already been the subjects of numerous portraits in genres such as fashion photography and magazine profiles that tend to idealize identity and appearance—​or, at times, to aim for the opposite effect. In addition to depicting such sitters, Wilson’s portraits often recycle, reframe, or distort the very representational techniques characteristic of such forms of popular portraiture. In an interview Wilson conducted for Greek television, broadcast to advertise an Athens exhibition of his set of multimedia portraits of the pop singer Lady Gaga created in 2013, he offers a bodily metaphor to convey the relationship between outer appearance and inner character: “You have the skin of the material and you have the meat of the material and you have the bone. The skin is what is attractive, but it’s what’s beneath the skin that makes the surface interesting.”6 Elsewhere Wilson has used an overlapping metaphor to express his ideal style of theater as combining aesthetic features that are easily accessible with others that are more dense and profound: “The surface remains simple but beneath that it can be very complex. The surface must be about one thing, but underneath it can be about many things.”7 Following this guiding concept, Wilson’s set of twenty-​two high-​definition video portraits of Lady Gaga that combine music, text, and image in stylized multimedia creations may offer little in

112

( 112 )   Musical Portraits

the way of a definitive revelation of her identity, but they entice viewers to appreciate the “surface,” and then invite them to interpret on their own “what’s beneath the skin,” the complex dimensions of the singer’s interior self, an entity she too explored, in preparation for posing for these portraits, by peering at her reflection in a mirror.8 This chapter turns to the portrait in multimedia and operatic forms, with focus on the works in the genre that Wilson has created in collaboration with composers, choreographers, actors, and other well-​known cultural figures, to examine the ways that portraiture can obscure, rather than clarify, its sitters’ interior identities. Through an exploration of Wilson’s portraits, this discussion suggests that, perhaps unintuitively, such rendering invisible permits the viewer to engage in an especially active mode of interpretation that can ultimately offer the potential for the development of a uniquely multidimensional and intimate conception of the subject’s identity. Wilson’s portraits operate in a manner that accords with Umberto Eco’s notion of the “open work”: they are pieces of art whose apparent gaps and discontinuities require a particularly creative form of contemplation on the part of the spectator, who performs the role of cocreator by assigning new personal meanings to the artist’s finished work.9 In an interview he conducted of Wilson, Eco observed that in the portrait opera Einstein on the Beach and other works by the director, “It seems that you foresee an audience able to complete your work. I have written a book, The Open Work, in which the same ideas were used for literature.”10 Indeed, Wilson himself has averred, “The fact is, I don’t really understand my own stuff,” and it is likely in part his works’ openness to the interpretation of the spectator, who collaborates by determining potential meanings, that provoked the surrealist artist Louis Aragon to describe Wilson’s early theatrical work Deafman Glance in 1971 as “an extraordinary freedom machine.”11 For Wilson, “My responsibility as an artist is to create, not to interpret. . .  . I think interpretation is for the public, not for the performer or the director or the author. We create a work for the public and we must allow them the freedom to make their own interpretations and draw their own conclusions.”12 In highlighting the limits of portraiture, its capacity for deception, and the creative, participatory role a portrait’s spectator must play in interpreting works in the genre, Wilson posits a notion of identity as socially derived, according to which the portrait is incomplete as a form of representation in and of itself, but its vast potential lies in the way it makes possible any number of individual constructions of the subject’s self. Wilson’s depictions of individuals, in his portraits of the pop singer Lady Gaga, his Voom Portraits series, and his cocreation with Philip Glass Einstein on the Beach, therefore reveal both the ways postmodern imagery of celebrities often eschews a deep engagement with personal identity, and

  13

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 113 )

how the emphasis on surface detail can in fact open up the potential for the spectator to develop a particularly personal but no less rich understanding of the contemporary self. ROBERT WILSON’S VOOM PORTRAITS AND THE REPRESENTATION OF CONTEMPORARY CELEBRIT Y

Wilson conveys an understanding of contemporary portraiture’s potential for clarity and opacity, its ability at once to reveal and obscure the self, in his Voom Portraits, a series of multimedia likenesses that he initiated in 2004 on a commission as part of his installation as artist-​in-​residence for the company Voom HD Networks, which produced high-​definition television stations between 2004 and 2009.13 The portraits have been displayed in gallery exhibitions around the world, and were also broadcast on massive screens over New  York’s Times Square each night for one month in 2012.14 For his videos in this series, which vary in length but are edited to be shown repeatedly on seamless loops, Wilson directs his subjects to pose before the camera and to move only minimally in choreographed gestures, or not at all. The austerity that characterizes the faces of most of his sitters in these portraits reflects his instruction that they “think of nothing” as they pose for the camera.15 These works can be witty, as in the portrait of Sumo wrestler Byambajav Ulambayar with a bright smile in front of a cotton-​candy-​pink curtain; dripping in old-​Hollywood glamor, like the video of actress Isabelle Huppert with her hands at the sides of her face, mimicking the famous photograph of Greta Garbo by Edward Steichen; or eerie and sardonic, as exemplified in the portrait of actor Steve Buscemi in pale makeup, black lipstick, and a stained butcher’s apron, chewing gum as he stands before a bloody carcass. In his description of celebrity portraiture in the essay “The Face of Garbo,” Roland Barthes writes that the famous photographs of Garbo (such as the one Wilson mimics in his Voom Portrait of Huppert) “represented a kind of absolute state of the flesh, which could be neither reached nor renounced,” and offered the “Platonic Idea of the human creature.”16 Her face appears as a mask-​like image, but rather than fixed and plastic, her likeness marks a transition in celebrity portraiture from a notion of beauty as defined in the “archetype of the human face” toward the understanding that beauty is related to something unique and individual: photographs of the actress indicate a moment “when the archetype leans towards the fascination of mortal faces.”17 This description of the celebrity portrait as teetering between the archetype and the individual may help illuminate how

114

( 114 )   Musical Portraits

Wilson’s multimedia representations of famous contemporary and historical figures work. Occupying a space between the austerely impersonal and the intimate and human, Wilson’s portraits of twentieth-​and twenty-​first-​ century icons require the spectator to complete that transition between the mask and the self that Barthes sees as having begun with images of Garbo’s face. In this way, his works in the genre imply that contemporary identity is a mystery that can be unlocked through interpretive and discursive interactions with and about art. Each of Wilson’s Voom Portraits is set to a musical soundtrack; sometimes this is written specifically for the portrait—​a number were provided by Wilson’s long-​time collaborator Michael Galasso—​and in other instances Wilson uses pre-​existing music by composers as diverse as J. S. Bach, Richard Wagner, Jerry Leiber and Mike Stoller, Nino Rota, and the band Mogwai. In these works, music plays an important role not only in the representation of the sitter but also in destabilizing the spectator’s experience of time. The painted and musical portrait differ in that the former typically represents an isolated moment snatched out of time and captured for posterity, while the latter often relies on the organization of time to produce a narrative construction of identity. Wilson’s portraits, in combining nearly still likenesses with music, confront the viewer with both an immutable image and an emerging narrative. The fixed pose or, at most, minimal movement of his sitters evokes an isolated moment whose duration has been stretched out beyond how time is naturally experienced, as though to expose an instant under a microscope; but the soundtracks of these portraits divide their durations into regular units of time through tempo, phrasing, and other structural means that, in general, do not come across as particularly slow or extended. The result of this juxtaposition of conflicting visual and aural representations of the passage of time is that the drawn-​out moment of the subject’s life that they appear to depict is experienced not as slow motion—​as it might be in a film—​but instead as a heightened, almost hallucinatory experience of the split second. Wilson has stated that “the time of my theatre is the time of interior reflection,” and indeed this audiovisual manipulation of time becomes the means by which he permits the viewer to reflect on and interpret his sitters’ interior subjectivities.18 Wilson has called his Voom Portraits “personal, poetic statements of different personalities,” and said, “the still life is a real life.”19 When one of his sitters, Farah Pahlavi, the Empress of Iran, viewed Wilson’s portrait of her from 2006, a black-​and-​white video in profile in which she slowly moves her hand down from and back up to her face, set to ambient music by the German electronic band Popol Vuh, she began to cry and insisted, “All my life is right there.”20 Nevertheless, in their exaggerations of posture and glamor, their mixture of earnest sincerity and tongue-​in-​cheek humor, their often

  15

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 115 )

bracing juxtapositions of sound and image, and their transformation of the sitter’s pose into a theatrical performance captured on film, as well as in the crisp, clinical precision of the HD video technology, these portraits can also be remote and cryptic, demanding a richly interpretive form of spectatorship before they give anything away. And in many of the portraits Wilson takes advantage of the representational capacities of his innovative merging of the newest multimedia technologies with centuries-​old techniques of painted and musical portraiture to explore the role of images and sound in the making of contemporary celebrity, and in creating or bridging the often cavernous space between the public and private construction of self. Wilson has stated that his earliest work in portraiture, which dates to the mid-​1970s when he created a set of portraits under the title Video 50, was inspired by the influential series Screen Tests produced by Andy Warhol and his assistant Gerard Malanga between 1964 and 1966.21 Inspired by both criminal mugshots and Hollywood glamor photography, and of course the film industry audition screen tests that lent the series its name, these artists would usher visitors at Warhol’s storied art and living space in New York, known as the Factory, to a corner where they were asked to sit as still as possible and without blinking before a sixteen-​millimeter Bolex camera, for about three minutes, until 100 feet of film had spooled through the reel.22 Warhol reportedly stated that the discomfort and insecurity this brought out in his sitters—​captured in Malanga’s description of the Screen Tests as “studies in subtle sadism”23—​made it possible to “catch people being themselves. It’s better to act naturally than to set up a scene and act like someone else. You get a better picture of people being themselves instead of trying to act like they’re themselves.”24 In spite of this observation, much of the power of the Screen Tests resides in the fact that they can seem as inert as the portrait genres that inspired them, the mugshot, which aims at producing a detached and objective likeness, and the Hollywood glamor shot, whose goals often involve idealizing physical appearance and advertising films and other commodities. With his Screen Tests, Warhol reveals the opacity of the contemporary popular portraiture of cinematic stills and celebrity photography, characterized by their careful calibration of a likeness that avoids the suggestion of anything definitive about the subject’s internal identity, or that projects an impression of the celebrity’s self that may not correspond to the way he truly sees himself. The modern celebrity image is a highly regulated form of portraiture, whose creation involves the hands of publicists, advertisers, trainers, film studio representatives, and fashion, hair, and makeup stylists, and as a result, a chasm often emerges between the internal self and its public representation, one implied by Cary Grant’s winking comment, “Everybody wants to be Cary Grant. Even I want to be Cary Grant.”25

116

( 116 )   Musical Portraits

The Screen Tests and the Voom Portraits demonstrate that while celebrity photography has vastly expanded the scope of and audience for portraiture, so that the genre has become a feature of everyday life, it has also emphasized interpretive challenges in the contested relationship between the representation of a person’s visible façade and his identity or self.26 To the extent that the modern media likeness can be said to betray the self beyond the surface, this requires a particularly creative interpretive act on the part of the viewer, who must construct an impression of the private self that is concealed in the celebrity portrait.27 And indeed Factory regulars viewed these Screen Tests, which Ronald Tavel called “breathing, living portraits,” as offering an opportunity to construct an understanding of the visitors’ true selves.28 For example, Warhol collaborator Mary Woronov explained, “Like medieval inquisitors, we proclaimed them tests of the soul and we rated everybody. . . . What appealed most of all to us, the Factory devotees . . . was the game, the cruelty of trapping the ego in a little fifteen minute cage for scrutiny.”29 The critic Lee Siegel uses a macabre metaphor to describe the way Warhol’s Screen Tests challenge contemporary modes of portraiture in popular media: he writes that Warhol “took the close-​up off the screen and put it on the dissecting table. It was like going into the kitchen of a fancy restaurant and seeing the bloody mess out of which an exquisite meal is made.”30 This notion of a bloody deconstruction of celebrity photography is made visible in Wilson’s Voom Portrait of the actor Robert Downey Jr., who is shown lying on his back, nude and partly covered by a sheet, on a dissecting table, the skin of his forearm sliced open to reveal the musculature underneath, which is being prodded by a scientist in black whose head cannot be seen above the upper edge of the image (Figure 4.1).31 Green lighting creates an antiseptic but sickly atmosphere, and the disembodied hand holds tweezers and wears an antiquated ruffled sleeve that confirms the basis of the image on Rembrandt’s group portrait “The Anatomy Lesson of Dr. Nicolaes Tulp” (1632), in which a crowd of men surround a scientist as he performs a pedagogical dissection of the arm and hand of a cadaver. In this visual reference, Wilson draws an analogy between the surgical theaters of the seventeenth century in which bodies—​often those of notorious criminals following execution—​were cut open before crowds of studious pupils and gawking visitors, and the public arena in which the contemporary media scrutinizes and dissects the lives of its celebrities.32 Where Rembrandt’s specimen is a pale corpse, however, Downey is revealed over the course of the video portrait to be alive: he repeatedly and almost imperceptibly turns his head from diagonally upward with eyes closed to looking toward the camera with eyes open and locked in an exchange with the viewer’s gaze.

  17

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 117 )

Figure  4.1: Robert Wilson and Tom Waits, “Robert Downey Jr.,” 2004, video. Courtesy RW Work Ltd.

Downey started acting in film as a child and has consistently remained in the public eye since his youth, famous for both his steady sequence of prominent roles in blockbusters and television series and his well-​publicized struggles with substance abuse, which brought him at various points to stints in rehabilitation clinics, hospitals, and state prison. This is a celebrity whose likeness is as widely recognized from magazine fashion shoots and film posters as it is from mugshots and courtroom photographs. In Wilson’s portrait, the imagery of the dissecting table appears to symbolize the way Downey has been laid bare before the glare of the cameras and scrutinized by the media. In staring with an enigmatic glance out toward the camera, Downey stages a confrontation, challenging the notion that the thousands of portraits by which he is known could ever reveal what lies behind the eyes that repeatedly make and break contact with the viewer’s. The portrait is set to a looped recording of a song from Tom Waits’s 1992 album Bone Machine, “The Ocean Doesn’t Want Me.” Waits recites, “The ocean doesn’t want me today /​But I’ll be back tomorrow to play.” Then he will go “down deep in [the] brine,” submerged by the dark waters, where “the rip tide is raging,” for “I’d love to go drowning /​And to stay and to stay.” In writing this song, Waits was inspired by a pair of photographs he had seen of a woman before and after she committed suicide by drowning in the ocean, and the song seems to be about the haunted thoughts that provoked her to end her life.33 In the context of the video portrait, these lyrics serve as a metaphor for celebrity image-​making, suggesting the challenge of the celebrity’s relationship with the portraitists—​photographers, filmmakers, columnists—​who repeatedly create his likeness. A period of obscurity

118

( 118 )   Musical Portraits

in which the fickle audience turns its attention away promises unsatisfying safety, and the opportunity to plunge back into fame brings a danger of drowning again. The lyrics’ musical setting creates a sonic representation of the murky expanses of the ocean. There is no sense of progression in the music, no harmonic direction, build-​up of the ensemble, or consistent metric pulse. Waits recites the text in heightened speech rather than singing, and his voice is processed to sound muffled, as though it is heard through water. The words are accompanied by percussion instruments and the quiet, intermittent droning of sustained tones from an electronic synthesizer, indistinct sounds that float through the musical arrangement like flotsam in the ocean. The lack of teleology in the music provides a sense of perpetual sameness, as though to convey either the slow, interminable descent into the oblivion of the ocean’s depths described in the text, or, in the context of celebrity portraiture, the tedium of constant surveillance and representation. This depiction of Downey brings musical, verbal, and visual media together with a reference to an iconic group portrait from the past to depict the way the camera’s clinical gaze dissects the modern celebrity, whose participation brings a vulnerability to drowning in the public scrutiny but fails ever to reveal the depths of the self. A similar focus on the austerity of representation in celebrity likenesses is found in Wilson’s 2004 portrait of the actress Winona Ryder, with music by Michael Galasso (Figure 4.2).34 In this video Ryder is visible only from the neck up, the rest of her body submerged in a grassy mound. She wears a colorful crown of flowers on her head, and looks outward, her eyes

Figure  4.2:  Robert Wilson and Michael Galasso, “Winona Ryder,” 2004, video. Courtesy RW Work Ltd.

  19

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 119 )

seemingly locked with the viewer’s, and her face still, betraying no particular emotion.35 At first the sky behind Ryder is dark blue, the color of early dawn, and the hill is in silhouette, with spotlights showing three objects that surround her on the hillside, a revolver, a toothbrush, and a handbag. Over the course of the video, which is about ten minutes long, the light gradually changes to create the effect of the rising and setting of the sun; at the conclusion, Ryder turns her head to the right and closes her eyes, as though for sleep. Wilson’s image of Ryder is modeled after the central character of Samuel Beckett’s play Happy Days (1961), a woman named Winnie (the fact that this could be a nickname for Winona can be no accident on Wilson’s part) who is buried up to her waist, in Act I, and then her neck, in Act II, in a hill exposed to the hot sunlight.36 Winnie’s day is marked by a bell that awakens her in the morning and restrains her from nodding off until night. She keeps herself active throughout the repetitive cycle of her days (“Never any change,” she says)37 by talking to herself and her husband Willie, who basks in the sun behind her and only occasionally barks replies to her questions, and by inspecting the objects in her handbag, especially her toothbrush, revolver, and parasol. Rather than allow herself to whither under the penetrating light, Winnie makes herself presentable each morning through a series of rituals including brushing her teeth, applying makeup, and protecting herself from the sun with her parasol. In Wilson’s portrait, Winnie’s story becomes an allegory of Ryder’s experience of celebrity. An actress since her teenage years, Ryder’s image became known not only through film stills and magazine shots, but also in the much-​publicized surveillance pictures that showed her arrest for shoplifting in the Beverly Hills Saks Fifth Avenue in 2001, followed by courtroom photographs taken as she received her verdict of guilt. Like Winnie, Winona was unable to escape the “blazing light” (in the words of Beckett’s stage direction) that fixed her image in place.38 In Happy Days Winnie expresses herself frequently through half-​remembered quotes from classical theater and poetry by Shakespeare, Dante, Milton, Keats, Yeats, and others.39 In this way she is an apt model for a portrait of a popular actress who is known largely through her recitation of the words of film and television screenwriters and her impersonation of fictional characters. Through this pairing of Winona and Winnie, Wilson’s portrait highlights the conception of identity as a polyvocal construction of texts, descriptions, and images. The multiple voices of Winnie and Ryder represent the self as perpetually constructed of texts that overlap and interrupt one another, a notion conveyed in Beckett’s description of Winnie to the actress Billie Whitelaw, who played the character in 1979: “She’s constantly being interrupted or interrupting herself. She’s an interrupted being.”40 The association with Winnie represents Ryder (who,

120

( 120 )   Musical Portraits

in a compelling coincidence, played a starring role in the 1999 film “Girl, Interrupted,” about a young woman in a mental hospital after a possible suicide attempt) as an interrupted self, her identity buffeted by celebrity and constructed in part by the steady stream of other people’s words. But despite the stasis of Winnie’s condition, which keeps her in the bright light each day, like the cameras that perpetually capture Ryder through the good and the bad, Beckett suggests that this is an ever-​changing identity. Winnie states, “I used to say, Winnie, you are changeless, there is never any difference between one fraction of a second and the next.”41 She realizes that she was incorrect in believing this; the cyclical nature of her life does not fix her identity, and she continues to grow, and to learn and forget things, even as her daily experiences repeat. In this way Beckett and Wilson offer portraits of identity as socially constructed, intertextual, and interchanging. The daily pattern of alarm bells, rituals, and the shifting of the earth to which Winnie is subjected conveys Beckett’s interest in the theory of eternal recurrence, and the play’s sense of cyclical repetition is invoked in the portrait of Ryder by the changing light as well as by Galasso’s music.42 The score, for violins playing predominantly harmonics with some whispered passages at full tone and other motifs for plucked strings, evokes birdsong and the occasional fragment of an imagined fiddle tune, in an unmetered, pastoral composition that creates a sense of timelessness and the possibility of eternity through its repetition and variation of brief musical gestures. The music seems to imply that this in an ordinary day within a perpetual cycle of celebrity image-​making, in which a figure such as Ryder is never far from the cameras’ glare and the staring eyes of the public. The effect of birdsong also reflects a prominent theme in Beckett’s play, in which Winnie discusses singing as an authentic form of self-​expression: “One cannot sing just to please someone, . . . song must come from the heart, that is what I always say, pour out from the inmost, like a thrush, . . . with no thought of benefit, to oneself or anyone else.”43 For Winnie, singing is essential and spontaneous, a truthful display of emotion through performance, and that sense of authenticity and purity makes its way into the portrait in the sparkling birdsong in Galasso’s violins, paired with Ryder’s unpretentious gaze. In contemplating Ryder as Winnie, it is not difficult to hear echoes of Winnie’s approach to remaining positive despite her plight—​she opens her morning with the words “Another heavenly day” and repeatedly declares, “Oh this is going to be another happy day!”44—​in Ryder’s later descriptions of her embarrassing public arrest as “a blessing” and “the best thing that could have happened to me.”45 Winnie must work so hard to keep positive because her partial burial results in her subjection to cruel treatment by others: Willie neglects her, and the occasional passers-​by gape and stare. Although Winnie spends much of the play attempting to attract Willie’s

  12

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 121 )

attention, she also describes the pain of being looked at. She recalls a couple that once encountered her on a stroll and embarrassed her with their conversation: Can’t have been a bad bosom, he says, in its day. (Pause.) Seen worse shoulders, he says, in my time. (Pause.) Does she feel her legs? he says. (Pause.) Is there any life in her legs? he says. (Pause.) Has she anything on underneath? he says. (Pause.) Ask her, he says, I’m shy. (Pause.) Ask her what? she says. (Pause.) Is there any life in her legs. (Pause.) Has she anything on underneath. (Pause.) Ask her yourself, she says. (Pause. With sudden violence.) Let go of me for Christ sake and drop! (Pause. Do.) Drop dead! (Smile.) But no. (Smile broader.) No no. (Smile off.) I watch them recede.46

In the context of Wilson’s portrait, this memory amounts to a condemnation of the gawking onlookers who have consumed and coolly assessed the thousands of images of Ryder. The related theme of the proliferation of celebrity portraiture as a form of suicide that makes its way into the portrait of Downey through Waits’s music also arises in this portrait of Ryder, both in the presence of the rifle and, more obliquely, for those who remember the play, in the recollection of moments in Winnie’s monologue when she hints at waiting for death. For example, she remarks on “the happy day to come when flesh melts,” an echo of Hamlet’s “Oh that this too, too solid flesh would melt”; and she calls Willie’s gift of sound sleep a “marvelous gift . . . wish I had it,” recalling the metaphor “To die: to sleep,” from Hamlet’s famous monologue.47 Yet Winnie does not shy away from attention; to the contrary, she thrives on it, like the singer in Waits’s lyrics who comes back to try again after rejection, and even the thought of being watched and listened to helps sustain her. She says to Willie that she is relieved that “I may say at all times, even when you do not answer and perhaps hear nothing, Something of this is being heard, I am not merely talking to myself, that is . . . a thing I could never bear to do. . .  . That is what enables me to go on, go on talking that is.”48 In a line that presages the feeling conveyed by Wilson’s portrait, with its oscillation of light and dark and its looped display, Winnie describes an existence in which she feels alone, unable to see others, but has a “Strange feeling that someone is looking at me. I am clear, then dim, then gone, then dim again, then clear again, and so on, back and forth, in and out of someone’s eye.”49 For the interpreter of Wilson’s portrait, Willie comes across as an analogue to the audience for Ryder’s numerous photographic portraits, and it is his relationship with Winnie at the end of the play that allows Wilson to characterize the connection between Ryder and her public as ultimately positive and affectionate, an association less confrontational than

122

( 122 )   Musical Portraits

that implied by Downey’s bloody dissection. In the last moments of Act II of Happy Days, Willie emerges from behind the mound wearing a dinner jacket with top hat and white gloves. He faces Winnie and attempts to climb up to her. He continues to falter and never reaches her, but looks up from below, on hands and knees. At the sight of this, Winnie declares gleefully, “That’s right, Willie, look at me. (Pause.) Feast your old eyes, Willie.”50 She then sings to him “I Love You So,” from the operetta by Franz Lehár The Merry Widow, a song whose final lines celebrate the joyous feeling of being loved: “Every touch of fingers /​Tells me what I know, /​Says for you, /​It’s true, it’s true, /​You love me so!”51 Before the light goes out, Willie and Winnie look at one another, locking eye contact like Ryder with the viewer of her portrait; and indeed the spectator familiar with Happy Days may feel that his intimate glance with Ryder, from below, places him together with the actress in the position of Willie with Winnie in the brief moment between the conclusion of her song and the fading light that marks the end of the play. It adds poignant context to recall the likely coincidence that one of Ryder’s most iconic roles, as Lydia in the comedy Beetlejuice (1988), concludes in much the same musical way as Winnie’s story. Where Winnie has been half-​buried atop a mound by unknown forces, Lydia, possessed by friendly ghosts, levitates toward the ceiling of her haunted home and, positioned in the middle of the frame like Beckett’s character midstage and Ryder in Wilson’s portrait, dances in place and moves her lips to the voice and words of Harry Belafonte’s 1961 recording of the love song “Jump in the Line” (“Senora dances Calypso /​ Left to right is the tempo /​And when she gets the sensation/​She go up in the air, come down in slow motion”).52 Lydia began the film as an alienated girl trapped in an inattentive family; she considers suicide to join the ghosts she has befriended, but by the end she is happy, and the audience, in the position of Willie, watches her from below as she smiles and sings spontaneously and authentically about the joy of being admired, like Winnie, and like a bird. By conveying celebrity images as superficially focused on likeness, and celebrity itself as a condition that commits the individual to public dissection or a life fixed in place under bright light, Wilson’s multimedia portraits “Robert Downey Jr.” and “Winona Ryder” suggest that the contemporary portraitist finds himself in a predicament conveyed in a famous line from Beckett’s Three Dialogues (1949): “The expression that there is nothing to express, nothing with which to express, nothing from which to express, no power to express, no desire to express, together with the obligation to express.”53 Wilson appears to create his portraits through a sense of obligation toward artistic representation, but unlike other portraitists who have traditionally sought to evoke a particular conception of the sitter’s

  123

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 123 )

character, he conveys in these works the belief that it is not in the capacity of the artist to construct identity. He can only design a work of portraiture and then leave it to spectators to establish their own personal interpretations of the sitter’s character.54 When Winnie recollects the cruel words of the passing couple, she attributes a particularly wounding question to the man, who wonders why she is buried in the ground: “What does it mean? he says—​W hat’s it meant to mean?”55 This question, considered in relation to Wilson’s portrait, aptly expresses a critical view of celebrity portraits as superficial and lacking in deeper meaning, focusing as so many do on likeness and beauty over the revelation of the interior self. In order to take something away from Wilson’s portraits, the viewer cannot simply respond like the man who asked “What’s it meant to mean?” because Wilson did not intend them to mean anything in particular. In his portraits, in all their austerity, the private selves of his subjects become available to the imagination and interpretation of the viewer who is willing to engage actively with these open works. And this will prove a particularly important principle in relation to Wilson and Glass’s depiction of Albert Einstein in their opera Einstein on the Beach. RELATIVIT Y AND THE PORTRAIT OPERA EINSTEIN ON THE BEACH

Einstein on the Beach was the first of Glass’s trilogy of what he has called portrait operas, joined in the following decade by Satyagraha (about Gandhi, 1980) and Akhnaten (1983).56 Glass has written that he conceived this set of operas as a study of “the transformation of society through the power of ideas and not through the force of arms.”57 He persisted in working in the genre after completing these three operas, later producing Galileo Galilei (2002) and Kepler (2009). Wilson had also experimented with theatrical portraiture prior to Einstein on the Beach, in works including The King of Spain (1969), The Life and Times of Sigmund Freud (1969), The Life and Times of Joseph Stalin (1973), and A Letter for Queen Victoria (1974). Later, he would continue to work in this form, creating Edison (1979) and The Life and Death of Marina Abramović (2011). The portrait opera typically represents its sitter by weaving a narrative about a period in the life of the central character, but in devising Einstein on the Beach, Wilson, Glass, and their collaborators were not interested in recreating a biographical narrative about Einstein, because, as Wilson explained, “We know stories about him and we come to the theater sharing something together. And in a sense there was no need to tell a story because we already had a story: How this man who was a pacifist also contributed to

124

( 124 )   Musical Portraits

the splitting of the atom.”58 By choosing to represent a subject whose story was well known, the creators could therefore rely on the audience to enter with their own understandings of this “god of our time,”59 and to use their preconceptions as the basis for interpreting the operatic portrait. Glass similarly stated that an ability to rely on the audience’s prior knowledge allowed the artists to create a portrait that could offer a deep but abstract and therefore aesthetically open representation of Einstein in the form of a “poetic vision,”60 in which “the person replaces the idea of plot, of story. In other words the character of the person becomes what the piece is about. The more you know about the person the better.”61 As Glass stated elsewhere, “Fundamental to our approach was the assumption that the audience itself completed the work.”62 Composer Wim Mertens has therefore argued that Einstein on the Beach has two protagonists, one onstage and one off:  the ensemble’s violinist, who is dressed as Einstein and plays extended solos in multiple scenes—​a reminder that Einstein was an avid amateur violinist—​ and the individual spectator.63 A forerunner to the Voom Portraits, Einstein on the Beach, the musical and theatrical portrait that would prove a landmark accomplishment in the flourishing of Glass’s and Wilson’s careers, suggests that contemporary portraiture is at once an opaque art form that reveals little on its own of a sitter’s character, and a uniquely effective medium through which to explore the subject of identity. The portrait may not independently give anything away, but because it is open-​ended and abstract, it invites the viewer to engage in an interpretive act of spectatorship that permits an individual understanding of Einstein, and of the self more generally. Robert Stearns describes Wilson’s approach to depicting identity in multimedia music theater through abstract representational means as akin to “peering, staring into a being as if to discover and reveal its essence. . . . We will never learn more about” Einstein and other subjects of Wilson’s works “if we expect Wilson to tell us about them. But we might come to see and feel their impenetrable presence.”64 In this way Einstein on the Beach reflects the goal of Gertrude Stein’s and Virgil Thomson’s works of literary and musical portraiture, with their use of abstract representational means to capture their sitters’ ineffable presence or essence. Einstein on the Beach engages with and reinterprets the principle with which Einstein is most readily identified, the theory of relativity, and in particular Einstein’s famous equation E = mc2. Roland Barthes described this apparently simple but historic equation as “the pure idea of a key, bare, linear, made of one metal, opening with a wholly magical ease a door which had resisted the desperate efforts of centuries,”65 and in the case of Einstein on the Beach, the equation becomes a potent metaphor that operates as a sort of key to understanding how art forms coalesce in opera, how people

  125

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 125 )

relate to one another and construct their own and each other’s identities, and how individual selves seem continually to collide with and split from one another.66 As in Boulez’s portrait of Mallarmé in Pli selon pli, in this work multiple expressive media merge, fold according to fold, to offer a profound study of contemporary identity. Spectators of the opera, in coming to understand what Einstein means to them, can also take the opportunity to explore how the portrait might reflect their own identities as well, by interpreting what it reveals of the relationships and interactions among people and artistic forms. FORM, MEDIA, AND MEANING IN EINSTEIN ON THE BEACH

Wilson and Glass practiced their art within the same artistic community of downtown New York in the early 1970s, and it was in 1973 that they would meet for the first time, after the final performance of Wilson’s twelve-​hour work The Life and Times of Josef Stalin at the Brooklyn Academy of Music. Glass admired the production, and recognized that he and Wilson shared an interest in experimenting with time in theater and music by extending form and development; Glass was working at the time on his six-​hour Music in Twelve Parts (completed in 1974).67 At the cast party at Wilson’s Spring Street loft, Wilson and Glass agreed to discuss a possible collaboration, and they met regularly over the course of the next year, slowly developing the structure, content, and thematic material that would eventually form Einstein on the Beach.68 The pair knew they wanted to create a portrait of a famous figure, discussing Charlie Chaplin, Hitler, and Gandhi before settling on Einstein.69 The premiere of Einstein on the Beach, which they created together with the choreographer Lucinda Childs, took place at the Avignon Festival in 1976. Performances continued that year across Europe and finally over two consecutive Sundays to full houses at the Metropolitan Opera in New York. The opera was revived in 1984 at the Brooklyn Academy of Music; in a 1992 touring production; and again on an international tour that ran between 2012 and 2014.70 In recalling the choice to create an opera about Albert Einstein, Glass later wrote of the scientist: [When I was] a child, Einstein had been one of my heroes. Growing up just after World War II, as I had, it was impossible not to know who he was. The emphatic, if catastrophic, beginning of the nuclear age had made atomic energy the most widely discussed issue of the day, and the gentle, almost saintlike originator of the theory of relativity had

126

( 126 )   Musical Portraits

achieved the 1940s version of superstar status. . . . For a time I, like many others of my generation, had been swept up in the Einstein craze. Perhaps Bob, growing up in Waco, Texas, had been too.71

In fact these artists took different approaches to research. Wilson once stated to Glass, “I don’t want to know any more than what everyone knows about Einstein. I  just want to know what the man in the street knows because that’s what they’ll be bringing to the work.”72 But for Glass, study was important: he explained, “In order for me to do a portrait of a person . . . I have to totally immerse myself in their work and life and at a certain moment I form a subjective image of the person which has a musical context. Then I can write the piece.”73 As the two continued to work on the opera, Wilson created drawings, which later came together in a full storyboard, or “visual book,” his preferred method for designing his stage works, and he showed these drawings regularly to Glass.74 They chose the title quickly, first settling on Einstein on the Beach on Wall Street before shortening that by removing the last three words, but they never discussed this change, nor indeed did they establish the meaning of the title, and this obscurity contributes to the work’s abstraction and the burden it places on the audience to interpret how it operates as a representation of Einstein.75 Glass has said, What Einstein on the Beach might mean to people is very much connected to the associations they bring to it. . . . I am sure that the absence of direct connotative “meaning” made it all the easier for the spectator to personalize the experience by supplying his own special “meaning” out of his own experience, while the work itself remained resolutely abstract.76

In spite of the abstraction that permeated every stage of the creation of the opera, it was always important to Glass that he was creating a work of portraiture, a concept that served both as the genre of the work and as a metaphor to describe the relation between his music and Wilson’s art. When he began composing partway through the collaboration, he explained, he put Wilson’s sketches “on the piano and composed each section like a portrait of the drawing before me.”77 Glass’s use of this metaphor is cryptic: it is not immediately evident how his repeated sound patterns create a musical portrait likeness of Wilson’s sketches. But comprehending portraiture in the manner in which it is developed in a work like Einstein on the Beach itself, one might take Glass to mean that his music provides a highly personal—​and ekphrastic—​interpretation of the character or identity of Wilson’s visual creations. According to this reading, the music is a “portrait” of the visual element, and both together form a portrait of Einstein.

  127

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 127 )

The form of the opera involves a deep integration of theatrical, musical, and choreographic techniques. Wilson explained that his goal was to work with the musical genre of theme and variations, and he chose three themes to begin with: the Train (theme A), the Trial (theme B), and the Spaceship (theme C).78 He then paired these themes in every possible combination, allowing each to repeat three times across the four acts. Act 1 featured themes A and B; Act 2 featured C and A; Act 3 featured B and C; and Act 4, at three scenes long, reassembled themes A, B, and C. Glass explained, “What we’re doing [in the first three acts] is taking two three-​part structures and spreading them over three two-​part structures.”79 In other words, the sequence of themes A, B, and C are distributed across three acts of two scenes each like a musical hemiola of three-​note patterns in duple meter, and this is followed by a final act that offers a recapitulation of each theme. These themes are also considerably varied in their reiterations. For example, the Train, in its third instance, takes the form of a large building. And in its first two appearances the Spaceship theme is introduced as a “Field,” a brightly lit stage across which a large group of dancers performs Childs’s choreography (in the original production, the choreography was by Andy de Groat). These extended dances serve as what Glass called “pillars” that evenly divide the opera into thirds.80 In between the acts are transitional scenes that Glass and Wilson referred to as Knee Plays, because they serve as joints between the material that precedes and follows them. As Glass explained, the opera’s form is “a musical idea that works as a dramatic idea.”81 Further augmenting this coherence between artistic forms, all three of the principal collaborators performed in Einstein on the Beach: Glass led his ensemble from the pit while Childs played several dramatic and dancing roles and Wilson also performed a solo dance, in the final Spaceship scene. Glass composed the score for his Philip Glass ensemble, featuring two electronic keyboards, three wind players on saxophones, flute, piccolo, and bass clarinet, and the solo violin part played by a musician dressed in a full Einstein costume, including makeup, wig, and mustache, and seated in a number of scenes on a chair at the front of the stage, between the pit ensemble and the actors and dancers.82 The score also includes some additional parts for solo voices. In his music for the opera, Glass explored ways of generating musical form through extended rhythmic structures, a project he had been working on since at least 1965, when he composed the score for Beckett’s Play. He was inspired in this effort by his studies of Indian musical form with sitarist Ravi Shankar and tabla player Alla Rakha.83 This experimentation found its way into his compositions Music in Twelve Parts (1971–​1974) and Another Look at Harmony, Parts 1 and 2 (1975), and Glass adapted the latter pieces into Einstein on the Beach, incorporating Part 1 into Act 1, scene 1, and Part 2 into the first “Field” dance.84 As

128

( 128 )   Musical Portraits

part of his study of rhythmic-​derived form, Glass developed two devices that he used at length in the opera: additive process, in which a pattern is repeated and gradually lengthened or shortened by small increments, and superimposed musical cycles, in which patterns of different lengths are layered and repeated, creating perpetually changing rhythmic interactions.85 Wilson and Glass’s layering of three dramatic themes across two-​scene acts can be understood as a structural instance of this technique of superimposed cycles. Einstein on the Beach replaces the customary components of opera—​a narrative scenario conveyed by a coherent libretto and populated by well-​ drawn characters—​with an abstract assortment of images, texts, choreography, and lighting effects, some of which relate directly to aspects of Einstein’s life and career, but most of which seem to be highly imaginative extrapolations from his biography, or even wholly unrelated to the subject of their portrait. Among the visual motifs that recur in the opera and refer to Einstein’s reputation are the costumes: all of the actors and chorus members are dressed as Einstein, in baggy pants, white shirt, and suspenders. Wilson designed this costume on the basis of a photographic portrait he looked at frequently in conceiving the production; he felt the clothes made Einstein “easy to identify,” and moreover, “He seemed a sort of Everyman. . . . He always said, ‘I’m not extraordinary. I’m just an ordinary man!’ ”86 The two principal actors, the choreographer Childs and long-​time Wilson collaborator Sheryl Sutton, who were featured in each Knee Play and elsewhere throughout the opera, also dressed as Einstein. (Additionally, multiple projected images represent photographs of Einstein at different ages.) And many of the objects onstage are implicitly connected with Einstein’s biography, including watches, clocks, and compasses. Certain physical movements similarly offer points of reference, such as a recurring gesture mimicking the writing of equations on a chalkboard and a visual gag that closes Knee Play 4: all of the members of the chorus mimic the act of brushing their teeth rapidly as they sing; they then look toward the audience with broad smiles and stick out their tongues, in a reference to the famous photograph of Einstein doing the same. Wilson also constructs some of the furnishings out of pipes, in reference to Einstein’s suggestion that if he had the choice to begin a new career once more as a young man, he would be a plumber rather than a scientist.87 Trains arise frequently in pedagogical explanations and illustrations of Einstein’s theory of relativity; the spaceship of course refers to Einstein’s work in this field as well; and the bright lights toward the end of the opera imply the explosion of an atomic bomb, a reference to Einstein’s discoveries leading to the splitting of the atom.88 Other images, on the other hand, seem entirely unrelated to Einstein. The scientist was never on trial, making the courtroom scenes entirely

  129

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 129 )

fanciful. And the bed in these sequences is not more than tangentially connected with Einstein’s biography: Wilson has called Einstein a “dreamer,” but it seems to serve equally as a pun on the French term for courtroom, “lit-​de-​justice” (literally, bed of justice).89 Also unrelated is the Witness’s rapid costume changes that dramatize the story of the kidnapped heiress Patty Hearst, a series of events that, rather than overlapping with Einstein’s life, was in the news during the time Wilson and Glass were constructing the opera.90 During rehearsals, Glass had his sixteen-​member chorus practice using a text comprised only of numbers—​counting out rhythmic measurements—​and the solfège syllables associated with the pitches they sang, to help them learn the challenging patterns he had composed for them. This was meant to be temporary, but when Wilson heard a rehearsal, he decided to retain this simple “libretto,” and nothing more was written for the vocal ensemble.91 The other texts in the opera, which are spoken, rather than sung, by members of the cast, came about through collaboration as well. Several were written by Christopher Knowles, a disabled young man Wilson befriended and with whom he had worked on several previous productions. One of the most prominent of Knowles’s texts in Einstein on the Beach offers a stream-​of-​consciousness litany of potential answers to the question Wilson posed to Knowles in asking him to write the monologue, “Who is Einstein?”:92 “It could be Franky it could be Franky it could be very fresh and clean. /​It could be a balloon. /​Oh these are the days my friends and these are the days my friends. /​It could get some wind for the sailboat. /​And it could get for it is. /​It could get the railroad for these workers.”93 The actor Samuel M. Johnson, who played the role of the judge in the trial scenes, wrote a pair of humorous texts for his character in the original and 1984 productions in which he starred, the first about the city of Paris and the second about the women’s liberation movement.94 And Childs wrote a speech to recite in her role as the Witness in the trial, a short text that she repeats multiple times about a visit to the swimming accessories aisle of a super market: “There were all these bathing caps that you could buy /​ which had these kind of Fourth of July plumes on them /​they were red and yellow and blue /​I wasn’t tempted to buy one /​but I was reminded of the fact that I had been avoiding the beach.”95 This reference to avoiding—​ not visiting—​the beach is the opera’s only allusion to the beach outside of its title, and serves to emphasize the obscurity and abstraction the opera aims at as a work of portraiture. To the extent that these texts offer insight into Einstein, it is only indirectly. Indeed, the associations between Einstein’s identity and the individual textual, visual, musical, and choreographic elements of the work are either extremely obvious (for example in the modeling of the costumes after his

130

( 130 )   Musical Portraits

typical dress) or highly attenuated. But despite the disparate nature of the opera’s constituent parts, it is always also stylistically coherent. This character, marked by a sort of unity in variety, permits the work to coalesce into an open representation of an individual self, albeit in postmodern terms. Knowles’s monologue suggests a spontaneous poetic rumination on Einstein’s identity in the manner of Gertrude Stein’s abstract literary portraits. Johnson’s and Childs’s may trigger the listener’s imagination in the manner that juxtaposed images in a visual collage inspire the viewer to draw connections between disparate people, places, and things. Robert Rauschenberg’s oil and silkscreen portrait of John F. Kennedy Retroactive II (1964), for example, represents its subject by grouping disparate photographs of Kennedy, an astronaut, a depiction of a woman peering in a mirror taken from an Old Master painting, and the wheels of a truck. Most of the texts in Einstein on the Beach also share a structure that involves gradually changing, repeated phrases, resembling Glass’s use of additive processes and incrementally modified rhythmic and harmonic patterns. Together the texts and score recall Stein’s technique of poetic “insistence,” the altered repetition that she argued help to represent a subject’s essence in poetry. The libretto of the opera, brought together by Glass’s stylistically consistent musical score and the formalist choral text of rhythmic counting and solfège pitch names, merge to present a view of the self as cohesive but polyvocal and open to infinitely varied interpretations and constructions, a multiplicity further depicted onstage by the principal actors and choir members all dressed as Einstein.96 In writing a portrait opera in so obscure and abstract a style, the creators of Einstein on the Beach developed a work that explores how identity emerges out of the mixture of engaged social discourse and inward self-​ examination. Wilson has stated, “The reason we make theatre is to ask ‘What is it?’ That’s why we invite an audience. To have a forum. We want to leave it open-​ended. As soon as you say what it is, it’s closed, it’s finished.”97 The opera’s performers, too, have described Wilson’s staging and Glass’s music as providing a time and space onstage for exploring the self. Characterizing her experience of working with Wilson, Sutton explained, “We felt we were working as much on the self as on the work. . . . We started with movement to learn to listen with the body. . . . We were doing research on perception and communication.”98 The actress Isabelle Huppert, who has performed in Wilson’s theatrical works in addition to posing for a Voom Portrait, has written, similarly: “With him, the theater becomes an exploration of one’s self, a gamble of one’s entire being, an affirmation of one’s joys, pains, fears, dreams, unattainable and yet so close.”99 Wilson once described Einstein on the Beach by drawing an analogy between his staging and human anatomy. According to his metaphor, the

  13

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 131 )

scenes that take place primarily at the back of the stage evoke a person’s bones, those at mid-​stage are the flesh, and the action in the foreground is the skin.100 Considered in this way, Einstein on the Beach, taken as a whole, offers a portrait of Einstein in three-​dimensions, in the manner of a Renaissance book of anatomical engravings such as Johann Remmelin’s 1619 Catoptrum microcosmicum, with flaps that can be opened to show the layered parts of the body, or the twentieth-​century anatomical model Visible Man, first produced by Renwal Products in 1958, with a clear plastic casing that forms a skin that can be opened to provide access to the flesh, organs, and bones underneath. Like both Remmelin’s book and the Visible Man, Einstein on the Beach requires audience participation to reveal the full scope of its representation, to disassemble and reassemble its rich portrayal of Einstein. Wilson, Glass, and their collaborators explore the contemporary notion of the self in Einstein on the Beach, and by working in a style that presents no easily discernible meanings, they provoke audiences to enter into this open work, to join in the process of interpreting the nature of identity. THE KNEE PLAYS, BY WAY OF CONCLUSION

In addition to the analogy he draws to human anatomy, Wilson has described his staging in Einstein on the Beach in relation to three principal genres of painting:  the Field and Spaceship scenes, which are predominantly at the rear of the stage, are landscapes; the Trial scenes, with their action in the middle of the stage, are still lifes; and the Knee Plays, which take place at the front of the stage, are portraits.101 Understood in this way, each Knee Play functions as a mise en abyme, a miniature portrait within the larger portrait opera.102 The first four of the five Knee Plays are performed in front of a lowered backdrop, with the chorus visible in the pit and the two principals on a small lit area at the far right (Figure 4.3). This space is in the shape of a square and projects partly beyond the front of the stage. The Knee Plays are musically coherent, with particularly close associations in the scoring of the outer two and the inner three sections. Glass incorporates two main themes in the Knee Plays, a low cadential chaconne progression on the pitches A–​G–​C descending in the organ in numbers 1 and 5 (Example 4.1), and, in numbers 2, 3, and 4, a cadential melodic theme in which a pivot chord in the middle of the phrase alters the progression from what is expected, resulting in a resolution that seems one half-​step too low (Example 4.2). Both of these simple patterns are repeated and modified rhythmically by way of additive processes throughout the Knee Plays in which they are heard.103

132

( 132 )   Musical Portraits

Figure 4.3:  Robert Wilson and Philip Glass, “Knee Play 1” from Einstein on the Beach, 2012–​2014 revival production. Courtesy of BAM Hamm Archives and the Robert Wilson Archives and the Byrd Hoffman Water Mill Foundation. © Lucie Jansch. Example 4.1:  Philip Glass, “Knee Play 1,” from Einstein on the Beach, premiered 1976, organ 1 part, first measure.

Example 4.2:  Philip Glass, “Knee Play 2,” from Einstein on the Beach, premiered 1976, solo violin part, rehearsal 3.

The first Knee Play begins before the audience is permitted into the theater, to produce the impression that the portrait, like the identity it represents, is already in progress. At first no one is onstage; the square space is lit to show a pair of desks, another light shines on a chair elsewhere at the front of the stage that will be the seat for the violinist dressed as Einstein, and the organ can be heard playing the cadential chaconne line. Several minutes later the two principals enter and sit at the desks; they gradually begin to raise their arms, moving their hands as though operating machinery, and they recite

  13

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 133 )

numbers and fragments of the texts by Knowles that will later be heard in full. One by one the chorus members also enter, filling the pit in front of the smaller stage, and when they are all assembled, they begin to sing rhythmic numbers and then solfège pitch names above the three-​note organ bass pattern. The following three Knee Plays are similar to the first, with slight variation. In the second, for example, the violinist plays a solo part in the chair off to the left, and at the conclusion, a projection appears on the backdrop showing a photograph of Einstein and the words “Bern. 1905,” a reference to the place and year in which the scientist, at the age of twenty-​six, produced a series of path-​breaking articles introducing the theory of special relativity and his famous equation E = mc2.104 In the third Knee Play, in which the violinist performs again, the principal actors stand with their backs to the audience and gesture as though making calculations on a chalkboard. And in the fourth, they lie on plexiglass tables and move as though floating, an obscure visual reference to an early scientific experiment measuring the speed of light using liquid mercury.105 The fifth Knee Play of Einstein on the Beach, the final section of the opera, occupies the entire stage, linking foreground, middleground, and background as though to conclude the work with a single image that puts a portrait of Einstein in a larger context of still life and landscape, or to produce a final three-​dimensional sculpture of Einstein depicting skin, flesh, and bones (Figure 4.4). The two principal actors sit on a park bench, the lighting indicating nighttime, repeating numbers and lines from the

Figure 4.4:  Robert Wilson and Philip Glass, “Knee Play 5” from Einstein on the Beach, 2012–​2014 revival production. Courtesy of BAM Hamm Archives and the Robert Wilson Archives and the Byrd Hoffman Water Mill Foundation. © Lucie Jansch.

134

( 134 )   Musical Portraits

texts by Knowles recited earlier in the opera. The audience hears excerpts including “Oh these are the days my friend” and “Do you remember Hans the bus driver?” as a stage flat in the form of a bus slowly enters from the right. The music in this scene looks back to the earlier Knee Plays, incorporating the cadential bass line and choral singing from Knee Play 1 and a violin theme from Knee Play 4. The bus driver (is it Hans?), also played by Samuel M. Johnson in the premiere and first revival, recites a text Johnson wrote for the opera; it is “the old, old story of love,” and recounts an evening conversation between a man and a woman.106 This final Knee Play, which relates to what came before while also featuring a new text and a rare emphasis on coherent narrative, offers concluding thoughts on Einstein, identity, and the relativity that binds art forms and individuals together.107 The bus driver begins his story by setting the scene: “Two lovers sat on a park bench, with their bodies touching each other, holding hands in the moonlight.”108 The woman asks her beau how much he loves her, and he responds with a series of metaphors: “Count the stars in the sky. Measure the waters of the oceans with a teaspoon.”109 Toward the conclusion of this conversation, in which the woman’s anxieties and the man’s profession of unbounded love recall the emotional extremes of a couple’s relationship in “Transfigured Night” (Verklärte Nacht), the 1896 poem by Richard Dehmel that inspired Arnold Schoenberg’s expressionist string sextet of 1899, the man tells his beloved, “Everything must have an ending except my love for you.”110 This suggestion of eternity and cyclicality finds its match in the opera’s form, the repetitive physical movements of its choreography, the recurrence of its principal imagery, and the reiterated musical themes. It also echoes the sentiment of Knowles’s line “Oh these are the days my friends and these are the days my friends,” with its duplicative wording and reference to the refrain of the Mary Hopkin song “Those Were the Days” (1969), “Those were the days my friend /​We thought they’d never end /​We’d sing and dance forever and a day.” But the reference to eternity also implies the apparently arbitrary quality of the end of this portrait of Einstein; in a manner that resembles the abrupt endings of Glass’s later portrait of Chuck Close and Thomson’s of Buffie Johnson and recalls the decision to start the opera before the audience has assembled in the theater, this line might imply that as long as people persist in thinking and talking about Einstein, his identity will remain in construction and continue to develop. The bus driver concludes his story with the words, “Once more her voice was heard. ‘Kiss me, John,’ she implored. And leaning over, he pressed his lips warmly to hers in fervent osculation.”111 In the most immediate sense, the word “osculation” here denotes the act of kissing, the display of the affection that relates these two lovers. But osculation also has a meaning in

  135

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 135 )

the field of geometry, in which it describes the contact between two curved lines or surfaces at a shared tangent. Taken this way, “osculation” might imply the point of intersection of two sets of train tracks or the orbits of two spaceships like those represented in the opera’s earlier scenes. It might also connote the bending of rays of light in a gravitational field and the curve of spacetime in Einstein’s theory of relativity. The final word of this portrait opera could furthermore be taken to indicate, more abstractly, an aesthetic and social theory of relativity, a meeting at a shared tangent point between both the multiple art forms that combine in this opera, and the identities of the audience members with those of the people with whom they have spent the foregoing four or five hours, Einstein, Wilson, Glass, and Childs. This view of relativity as the intersecting of the orbits of individuals’ lives permits the two women onstage, one white and one black, to represent at the same time Einstein himself, the pair of young lovers the bus driver describes, and the Everyman figure Wilson mentioned in characterizing his costume design. The director and playwright Richard Foreman has described Wilson’s theater as offering its audiences the opportunity to contemplate their own reflections: Wilson is one of a small number of artists who seem to have applied a very different aesthetic to theatre—​one current among advanced painters, musicians, dancers, and filmmakers—​a non-​manipulative aesthetic which would see art create a “field” situation within which the spectator can examine himself (as perceptor) in relation to the “discoveries” the artist has made within his medium.112

In similar but vaguer terms, the literary and cultural critic Julia Kristeva has also described how Wilson’s art allows the spectator to explore his own sense of self and how it relates to the content of the work and to Wilson’s identity, particularly in the way Wilson borrows from and merges multiple media in his creations. As a member of the committee that awarded him a prize for sculpture at 1993 Venice Biennale, Kristeva wrote: Clearly the traditional categories—​painting, sculpture, stagecraft, etc.—​no longer correspond to reality. Personally, I think this is due to the crisis in our psychic space and the borders that separate the object and the subject. In the same way that there is a breaking down of the boundaries between objects, there is an intrication of the roles of the artist and the spectator, erasing the borders between the self and the other. This lack of differentiation can have a dramatic effect on some people: loss of self, hallucinations, etc. But it can also give rise to jubilation, because it creates a sense of osmosis with Being, the Absolute.113

136

( 136 )   Musical Portraits

Wilson enacts this “breaking down of boundaries” among art forms, between artist and viewer, and between self and other in works that bring ordinary spectators of art face-​to-​face with arresting images of cultural and intellectual icons of the past century, as though to propose a theory of relativity that associates disparate people and different aesthetic media. The portraits’ lack of representational specificity—​their nature as open works of art—​invites audiences to discover the points at which their own selves intersect with and orbit past those of people whose ubiquitous and austere likenesses they see every day but whom they are not liable to encounter in person. When pressed to explain what his work means, Wilson has said, “You can look at a portrait by Rembrandt and be overwhelmed by its meaningfulness and not be able to tell what it means. The conviction of meaningfulness is all that was necessary for me. . . . It’s not a question of what Einstein means, it’s that it’s meaningful.”114 The full implications of the representation of a celebrity in a work of portraiture may remain obscure, much as the precise meanings of the terms on either side of the equal sign in E = mc2 are likely to be unknown to the average viewer. But in Einstein’s famous equation it is nevertheless evident that an important equivalency has been expressed, an identity forged, and the same is true of the portrait, no matter how abstract its terms.

NOTES 1. Quoted in Sandra Kemp, Future Face:  Image, Identity, Innovation (London:  Profile, 2004), 124. 2. Stephen K. Scher, in a deft layering of puns, calls Renaissance portrait medals “the currency of fame” in the title of his book on the subject, and argues that for those who coveted fame during the era, the portrait medal seemed an ideal form of representation, as it was thought to portray “a wealth of information” about its subject in a reproducible and durable form that rendered lasting fame and recognition. Stephen K. Scher (ed.), The Currency of Fame: Portrait Medals of the Renaissance (New York: Harry N. Abrams, 1994), 13. 3. Aristotle, The Poetics of Aristotle, trans. Preston H. Epps (Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press, 1970), Book XV, 30–​1. 4. Up to this point, the character Mao Tse-​tung has come across as physically and mentally hobbled by age, requiring the assistance of a trio of aides to help him move in and out of rooms and to clarify his abstruse statements. Meanwhile Mao’s wife Jiang Qing, known as Madame Mao, has assumed her husband’s mantle in his frailty: “I am the wife of Mao Tse-​ Tung. . . . When I appear the people hang upon my words.” 5. The conflicting capacities of portraiture to both reveal and obscure character is the central subject of Oscar Wilde’s novel The Picture of Dorian Gray (1890). In Wilde’s narrative, the painted likeness of the attractive young Gray appears to age—​and, more significantly, to take on the signs of his poverty of character—​while he himself remains fresh-​faced as the years pass, as though the portrait contains the real life while the man has become nothing more than his own idealized representation, a likeness that depicts no sign of the cruelty,

  137

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 137 )

selfishness, and evil that develop within his soul. At one stage Gray looks at his face in a hand-​mirror and, distraught at the torment he has brought to his acquaintances, reacts with violence against the looking glass that shows only his physical perfection and obscures his cruel character: “Then he loathed his own beauty, and flinging the mirror on the floor crushed it into silver splinters beneath his heel” Oscar Wilde, The Picture of Dorian Gray [(Leipzig: Bernhard Tauchnitz)], 282. Gray’s act of cracking the mirror offered the only way to make its representation of his unchanging appearance reveal the fractures within his soul. At the end of the novel, however, Gray takes a reverse tack, and attempts to stab the painting and destroy what it reveals about his interior self; but he is subsequently found deceased, his body old and decrepit, beside his portrait, which now depicts him in his dashing youth, putting right the inversion of the subject and its representation but also unveiling an idealized depiction that shows only its subject’s exaggerated beauty and betrays nothing of his immorality. See the discussion of the function of portraiture in this novel in Michal Peled Ginsburg, Portrait Stories (New York: Fordham University Press, 2015), 97–​108; A. S. Byatt, Portraits in Fiction (London: Chatto and Windus, 2001), 56–​64. 6. Robert Wilson, “Interview about Lady Gaga and Her Portraits,” YouTube, April 4, 2015, video, https://​www.youtube.com/​watch?v=an3OAM_​fAHA. 7. Robert Wilson and Umberto Eco, “Robert Wilson and Umberto Eco: A Conversation,” Performing Arts Journal, 15.1 ( January 1993): 91. Wilson has also described the distinction between appearance and identity as relating to a person’s “exterior screen,” the aspect of a person that one sees, and “interior screen,” the realm in which an individual processes external reality through perception, dreams, and intuition. Arthur Holmberg, The Theatre of Robert Wilson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 156; Laurence Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators (New York: Theatre Communications Group, 1989), 76. 8. Wilson, “Interview about Lady Gaga.” Most of the multimedia portraits in this set are based on iconic painted portraits, Andrea Solari’s “The Head of St. John Baptist” (1507), Jacques-​Louis David’s “The Death of Marat” (1793), and Jean-​Auguste-Dominique Ingres’s “Mademoiselle Caroline Rivière” (1870). An additional portrait, not based on an earlier model, depicts Lady Gaga naked, bound, and hanging upside down. Peter Weibel relates Wilson’s video portraits based on famous paintings to the tradition of tableaux vivants, the eighteenth-​century traditional of creating “living images” in which people reenacted the poses of paintings and sculptures. Peter Weibel, “Robert Wilson’s Video Portraits,” in Peter Weibel, Harald Falckenberg, and Matthew Shattuck (eds.), Robert Wilson: Video Portraits (Cologne: Walther König, 2011), 118–​23. 9. Umberto Eco, The Open Work, trans. Anna Cancogni (Cambridge, MA:  Harvard University Press, 1989), 4, 21. 10. Wilson and Eco, “Robert Wilson and Umberto Eco,” 87. 11. Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, xix, xviii. 12. Wilson and Eco, “Robert Wilson and Umberto Eco,” 89–​90. 13. Jonathan Kalb, “Robert Wilson, Beckett and a Celebrity from the Neck Up,” New York Times, January 30, 2007. Wilson created a number of his portraits of celebrities according to the arrangement that he would provide one copy to the subject in exchange for permission to sell another two. He has made others on commission, for a fee of $150,000. Bob Colacello, “The Subject as Star,” Vanity Fair, November 6, 2006. For discussion of Wilson’s collaboration with Voom HD Networks, see Ali Hossaini, “New-​ Definition Television:  Robert Wilson’s Video Portraits,” in Weibel, Falckenberg, and Shattuck, Robert Wilson:  Video Portraits, 174–​85; Matthew Shattuck, “Interview with Noah Khoshbin,” in Weibel, Falckenberg, and Shattuck, Robert Wilson: Video Portraits, 188–​93. 14. Tom Chen and Kyle Chayka, “Robert Wilson on Bringing Robert Downey Jr. and Boris the Porcupine to Times Square’s Jumbotrons,” Blouin ARTINFO, May 21, 2012, video, www.blouinartinfo.com/​news/​story/​805671/​v ideo-​robert-​w ilson-​on-​bringing-​robert-​ downey-​jr-​and-​boris-​the-​porcupine-​to-​times-​squares-​jumbotrons.

138

( 138 )   Musical Portraits

15. Colacello, “Subject as Star.” 16. Roland Barthes, “The Face of Garbo,” in Mythologies, trans. Annette Lavers (New York: Hill and Wang, 1972, orig. 1957), 56, 57. Huppert has said, “the portrait is a tribute to a time when actresses fabricated their faces with a high degree of self-​consciousness.” Isabelle Huppert, “The Time between Fixity and Motion,” trans. Alexandra Schwartz, in Margery Arent Safir (ed.), Robert Wilson from Within (Paris: Arts Arena, 2011), 85. 17. Barthes, “The Face of Garbo,” 57. 18. Christopher Innes and Maria Shevtsova, The Cambridge Introduction to Theatre Directing (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 161. 19. Robert Wilson, “A Still Life is a Real Life,” in Weibel, Falckenberg, and Shattuck, Robert Wilson: Video Portraits, 9. 20. Colacello, “Subject as Star.” 21. Colacello, “Subject as Star.” 22. Debra Miller, “Screen Tests: A History,” in Patrick Remy and Marc Parent (eds.), Gerard Malanga: Screen Tests, Portraits, Nudes 1964–​1996 (Göttingen: Steidl, 2000), 25; J. J. Murphy, The Black Hole of the Camera: The Films of Andy Warhol (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2012), 2. Around five hundred films were made for the Screen Tests series; among the more famed subjects were Susan Sontag, Dennis Hopper, Allen Ginsberg, Bob Dylan, and Salvador Dalí. A comprehensive catalogue of these works has been assembled in Callie Angell, Andy Warhol Screen Tests: The Films of Andy Warhol Catalogue Raisonné, vol. I (New York: Harry N. Abrams and Whitney Museum of Art, 2006). Malanga also wrote poems to accompany a number of the Screen Tests. These operate in the manner of abstract literary portraits. Fifty-​four of the poems are published beside stills from their corresponding films, in Gerard Malanga and Andy Warhol, Screen Tests/​A Diary (New York: Kulchur Press, 1967). A broader survey of portraiture and self-​portraiture in art cinema, including discussion of Warhol’s Screen Tests, can be found in Paul Young, Art Cinema, ed. Paul Duncan (Cologne: Taschen, 2009), 149–​64. 23. Miller, “Screen Tests,” 25. 24. Warhol’s words were recalled by Gene Youngblood. Joseph D. Ketner, II, “Image Machine: Andy Warhol & Photography,” in Joseph D. Ketner, II (ed.), Image Machine: Andy Warhol & Photography (Cincinnati:  Contemporary Arts Center; Nürnberg:  Verlag für Moderne Kunst; New York: Andy Warhol Foundation, 2012), 49. 25. Fred Inglis, A Short History of Celebrity (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2010), 187. On the contrast between public constructions of celebrity identities and the private sense of self, see also Chris Rojek, Celebrity (London: Reaktion, 2001), 10–​11; Richard Dyer, Heavenly Bodies: Film Stars and Society, 2nd ed. (New York: Routledge, 2004, orig. 1986), 4; Graeme Turner, Understanding Celebrity, 2nd ed. (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2014, orig. 2004), 10, 44–​5. On the central role of photography in celebrity portraiture since the age of the Daguerreotype, see Rojek, Celebrity, 125–​8. 26. For a study of the way Warhol and other pop artists handle this perceived distinction in portraiture, see Paul Moorhouse, Pop Art Portraits (London: National Portrait Gallery, 2007), 97–​9, 106. 27. Lee Siegel, “On the Face of It,” in Donna Gustafson and Susan Sidlauskas (eds.), Striking Resemblance: The Changing Art of Portraiture (New Brunswick, NJ: Zimmerli Art Museum at Rutgers University; London: Prestel, 2014), 65. 28. Ketner, II, “Image Machine,” 49. 29. Murphy, Black Hole of the Camera, 2–​3. 30. Siegel, “On the Face of It,” 64. 31. Robert Wilson and Tom Waits, “Robert Downey Jr.,” Dissident Industries Inc., 2004, video www.dissidentusa.com/​robert-​wilson/​subjects/​robert-​downey-​jr/​. 32. On Rembrandt’s painting and the practice of anatomical dissections, see Anthony Bailey, Rembrandt’s House: Exploring the World of the Great Master (London: Tauris Parke, 2014; orig. Boston: Houghton Mifflin; London: J. M. Dent, 1978), 88–​103. Nicola Suthor observes that Downey’s pose and loincloth also recreate those in Hans Holbein’s “The Body of the Dead Christ in the Tomb” (1521), a resemblance that makes Downey into a

  139

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 139 )

kind of Christ figure, sacrificed for the sins of the participants in modern-​day celebrity culture. Nicola Suthor, “Role Models,” in Weibel, Falckenberg, and Shattuck, Robert Wilson: Video Portraits, 164–​5. 33. Jay S. Jacobs, Wild Years: The Music and Myth of Tom Waits (Toronto:  ECW Press, 2000), 198–​9. 34. Robert Wilson and Michael Galasso, “Winona Ryder,” Dissident Industries Inc., 2004, video, www.dissidentusa.com/​robert-​wilson/​subjects/​winona-​r yder/​. When exhibited at the Paul Cooper Gallery in New York, the portrait of Winona Ryder was displayed in monumental form, at fifteen by twenty-​seven feet. Kalb, “Robert Wilson.” 35. Weibel interprets the inexpressive stares of Wilson’s subjects in the context of Denis Diderot’s 1773 treatise The Paradox of the Actor, in Weibel, “Robert Wilson’s Video Portraits,” 128–​31. 36. Wilson has always admired Beckett’s theater, and at an early stage in his career seriously considered putting on a production of Happy Days, though he did not follow through at the time. Holmberg, Theatre of Robert Wilson, 68. He did later stage the play—​his first time directing Beckett—​in 2008, in a French-​language production at the Grand Théâtre de Luxembourg starring Adriana Asti. He also directed Beckett’s one-​man play Krapp’s Last Tape in 2009. 37. Samuel Beckett, Happy Days: A Play in Two Acts (New York: Grove Press, 1961), 45. 38. Beckett, Happy Days, 7. 39. On Winnie’s literary references, see S. E. Gontarski, Beckett’s Happy Days: A Manuscript Study (Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Libraries, 1977), 62–​73. 40. Katharine Worth, Waiting for Godot and Happy Days: Text and Performance (Houndmills, UK, and London: Macmillan, 1990), 44. 41. Beckett, Happy Days, 60. 42. For a discussion of Beckett’s notion of eternal recurrence as it influenced Happy Days, see Worth, Waiting for Godot and Happy Days, 50–​1. 43. Beckett, Happy Days, 40. 44. Beckett, Happy Days, 8, 15. 45. See, for example, Stephen M. Silverman, “Winona Ryder Finally Speaks Out About Her Arrest,” People, July 17, 2007; Chelsea White, “Why My Shoplifting Arrest Was the Best Thing that Could Have Happened to Me,” Daily Mail, May 17, 2013. 46. Beckett, Happy Days, 58. 47. Beckett, Happy Days, 18, 10; Gontarski, Beckett’s Happy Days, 63. 48. Beckett, Happy Days, 21. 49. Beckett, Happy Days, 40. 50. Beckett, Happy Days, 62. 51. Beckett, Happy Days, 64. In light of the connection between Winnie and Ryder and more broadly between Happy Days and the contemporary condition of celebrity, these lyrics bring to mind actress Sally Field’s elation as she collected the Academy Award in 1984, declaring, “You like me! You really like me!” 52. For a discussion of authenticity of expression and the use of lip-​sync to familiar voices in film and television, see Joshua S. Walden, “Lip-​Sync in Lipstick: 1950s Popular Songs in a Television Series by Dennis Potter,” Journal of Musicological Research 27.2 (April 2008): 169–​95. 53. Samuel Beckett, Proust and Three Dialogues, ed. Georges Duthuit (London: John Calder, 1965), 103. Originally published as Samuel Beckett and Georges Duthuit, “Three Dialogues: Tal Coat—​Masson—​Van Velde,” Transition 49.5 (December 1949): 97–​103. 54. Wilson has stated, “For me, interpretation is not the responsibility of the author or the director: it is the public’s responsibility.” Katharina Otto-​Bernstein, Absolute Wilson: The Biography (London: Prestel, 2006), 159. 55. Beckett, Happy Days, 43. 56. Other twentieth-​and twenty-​first-​century works in the genre of the portrait opera include Hans Pfitzner’s Palestrina (premiered 1917), Paul Hindemith’s Mathis der Mahler (1933–​1934), Peter Maxwell Davies’s Taverner (1962–​1968, rev. 1970), Olivier Messiaen’s Saint François d’Assise (1975–​1983), Kaija Saariaho’s Émilie (about Émilie du Châtelet, 2008), and Osvaldo Golijov’s Ainadamar (about the Spanish poet and playwright Federico García Lorca, 2003).

140

( 140 )   Musical Portraits

57. Philip Glass, Words without Music (London: Liveright, 2015), 372. 58. Katharina Otto-​ Bernstein (dir.), Absolute Wilson, HBO Documentary Films (New York: New Yorker Video, 2007), DVD. 59. Otto-​Bernstein (dir.), Absolute Wilson. On the notion of Einstein as a “mythic god who is known generally by the man on the street,” see also Mark Obenhaus (dir.), Einstein on the Beach: The Changing Image of Opera, Brooklyn Academy of Music (Los Angeles: Direct Cinema, 1987), video. 60. Philip Glass, Music by Philip Glass, ed. Robert T. Jones (New York: Da Capo, 1987), 32. 61. Obenhaus (dir.), Einstein on the Beach. 62. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 35. Glass’s interest in creating open works of theater was inspired by his experience with the texts of Samuel Beckett, which he encountered when he was invited to write music for a production of Beckett’s Play by the Mabou Mines theater in Paris. See Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 35–​7. 63. Wim Mertens, American Minimal Music: La Monte Young, Terry Riley, Steve Reich, Philip Glass, trans. J. Hautekiet (London: Kahn and Averill; White Plains, NY: Pro/​Am Music Resources, 1983), 81. 64. Robert Stearns, “Robert Wilson: From a Theater of Images,” in Contemporary Arts Center (Cincinnati, Ohio) and Byrd Hoffman Foundation, Robert Wilson: The Theater of Images (New York: Harper, 1984), 43. 65. Roland Barthes, “The Brain of Einstein,” in Mythologies, 69. 66. Arthur Holmberg also associates Einstein on the Beach with a metaphorical conception of Einstein’s theory of relativity, in Holmberg, Theatre of Robert Wilson, 11. Katharina Otto-​ Bernstein relates the new ways of understanding time provoked by Einstein’s theory of relativity to Wilson’s innovative manipulation of the experience of time in his stage shows. Otto-​Bernstein, Absolute Wilson, 146. 67. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 27–​8. On the creation of the work, see also Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, 213–​27; Glass, Words without Music, 283–​8. 68. Glass, Music By Philip Glass, 28–​9. 69. Glass, Music By Philip Glass, 29. 70. For a detailed discussion of this performance history, see Maria Shevtsova, Robert Wilson (New York: Routledge, 2007), 83–​8; Glass, Words without Music, 292–​301; Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 40–​56. 71. Glass, Music By Philip Glass, 29. 72. Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, 215. 73. Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, 215. Glass has described his portrait operas as based in part on his undergraduate studies in the Great Books curriculum at the University of Chicago. See Glass, Words without Music, 33–​4. 74. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 29. On Wilson’s visual books, see Shevtsova, Robert Wilson, 42. 75. The title is likely a reference to the futuristic 1957 novel On the Beach, by Nevil Shute, set in Australia following a nuclear apocalypse caused by World War III. Glass, Words without Music, 286. 76. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 30, 33. 77. Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, 219. 78. Otto-​Bernstein, Absolute Wilson, 146. 79. Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, 220. 80. Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, 222. 81. Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, 220. 82. On the music for the opera, see Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 57–​62; Keith Potter, Four Musical Minimalists: La Monte Young, Terry Riley, Steve Reich, Philip Glass (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 326–​38. For a detailed discussion of the electronic organs used in the premiere of Einstein on the Beach and its recordings and revivals, see Rob Haskins, “Philip Glass and Michael Riesman: Two Interviews,” Musical Quarterly 86.3 (Autumn 2002): 520–​4. 83. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 28; Potter, Four Musical Minimalists, 258–​60. On Glass’s studies with Shankar and Rakha, see William Duckworth, Talking Music: Conversations with

  14

C e l e b r i t y, M u s i c , a n d t h e M u lt im e d i a P o rt r a i t   

( 141 )

John Cage, Philip Glass, Laurie Anderson, and Five Generations of American Experimental Composers (New York: Schirmer, 1995), 330–​1. 84. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 38. 85. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 58–​9. For further discussion by Glass, see Glass, Words without Music, 288–​9. 86. Stefan Brecht, The Theatre of Visions: Robert Wilson (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1978), 370–​1. Wilson also modeled the position of the fingers of many of his actors after the way Einstein holds his hands in this photograph. The image is reproduced, with a descriptive blurb by Wilson, in Robert Wilson, “From Within,” in Safir, Robert Wilson from Within, 313. 87. Holmberg, Theatre of Robert Wilson, 11. 88. David Cunningham, “Einstein on the Beach (1977),” in Richard Kostelanetz (ed.), Writings on Glass: Essays, Interviews, Criticism (New York: Schirmer, 1997), 152–​3, 158. Cunningham interprets the Field as a reference not to a field of grass or grains but to the metaphorical use of the word field to describe an area of science. 89. Cunningham, “Einstein on the Beach (1977),” 163. 90. Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, 227. Other elements of the drama appear to refer to aspects of Wilson’s own life. His sister Suzanne Wilson suggests that the judge’s glance at his watch is a memory of their father, a lawyer who was always punctual, and that the multiple scenes in which women sit in chairs recall their mother, who frequently sat in silence in their home. She also interprets the shaking head of one of the actors as a reference to their mother’s palsy. Otto-​Bernstein, Absolute Wilson, 146. 91. Wilson and Glass associated this formalist use of numbers and pitch names as choral text with the work of contemporary artists like Jasper Johns, for whom, in Glass’s words, “the painting is not the depiction of the thing, the painting is the thing.” Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, 227. 92. Wilson recalls this interaction in Obenhaus (dir.), Einstein on the Beach. 93. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 64. 94. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 68–​70. 95. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 74–​5. 96. Frederik J. Ruf writes that the overlapping abstract texts that make up the opera’s libretto “present a consistent model for the self.” Frederik J. Ruf, Entangled Voices: Genre and the Religious Construction of the Self (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997), 67. 97. Ruf, Entangled Voices, 72–​3. For a similar statement, see Wilson, “From Within,” 317. 98. Holmberg, Theatre of Robert Wilson, 4. 99. Huppert, “Time between Fixity and Motion,” 75. 100. Cunningham, “Einstein on the Beach (1977),” 153. 101. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 33; Cunningham, “Einstein on the Beach (1977),” 153. 102. The term mise en abyme refers to the technique by which works of art turn their focus back on themselves, reproducing within their structures a miniature version of their subject matter or form. Examples include the convex mirror in Jan van Eyck’s “The Arnolfini Portrait” (1434) that offers a different perspective on the room depicted in the painting; the tragic drama “The Murder of Gonzago” performed by the players in Shakespeare’s Hamlet, Act 3, scene 2 (c. 1599–​1601) that reflects elements of Hamlet’s plot; and the operatic scenes staged in the revised version of Paul Hindemith’s opera Cardillac (1952, orig. 1926). Meaning “placed into abyss,” the French phrase originates in heraldry, in which context it referred to the duplication within a shield of a small representation of a second shield with the same image. André Gide introduced the concept into art criticism in 1893. On mise en abyme, see Lucien Dällenbach, The Mirror in the Text, trans. Jeremy Whiteley and Emma Hughes (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), 7–​19. On the use of the technique in Cardillac, see Hermann Danuser, “Self-​Representation in Music: The Case of Hindemith’s Meta-​Opera Cardillac,” trans. J. Bradford Robinson, in Joshua S. Walden (ed.), Representation in Western Music (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 224–​46. In the case of Einstein on the Beach, the use of the term in this context refers to the Knee Plays as a series of miniature portraits of Einstein within the larger portrait of Einstein produced by the opera as a whole.

142

( 142 )   Musical Portraits

103. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 60–​1. Glass published a more detailed analysis in the Winter 1978 issue of Performing Arts Journal. This is reprinted in part in Brecht, Theatre of Visions, 317–​18. 104. In the revivals, the projection read, “Bern, Switzerland. 1905.” The image of Einstein playing violin alongside references to the scientific calculations that would contribute to the splitting of the atom also recalls Bob Dylan’s lyrics about Einstein: “Now you would not think to look at him/​But he was famous long ago/​For playing the electric violin/​On Desolation Row.” To take the analogy a step further, the score of simple counting and solfège syllables sung by a chorus dressed as Einstein resonates with Dylan’s image of an “immaculately frightful” Einstein “reciting the alphabet.” Bob Dylan, “Desolation Row,” in Highway 61 Revisited, Warner Bros. Inc., 1965; renewed Special Rider Music, 1993. 105. Brecht, Theatre of Visions, 353. Wilson’s description of this experiment in an interview about Einstein on the Beach is vague; he might be referring to the work in the late nineteenth century of Edward Morley and Albert Michelson, whose findings, some have argued, were influential to Einstein in developing his theory of special relativity. 106. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 78. 107. For the full text of Knee Play 5, see Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 78–​9. 108. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 78. 109. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 78. 110. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 79. 111. Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 79. 112. Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, xviii. 113. Shevtsova, Robert Wilson, 3. 114. Shyer, Robert Wilson and His Collaborators, 218.

  143

Epilogue Musical Portraiture, the Posthumous, and the Posthuman I wonder whether one oftener learns to love real objects through their representations, or the representations through the real objects. —​George Eliot, Daniel Deronda1

T

his book has addressed works of musical portraiture written since the middle of the twentieth century, viewing how composers have experimented in the genre as a means of exploring the capacity of music to operate as a representational medium, and the ways music can be used to portray the abstract elements of human identity that are understood to form a person’s individual self. In the portraits considered in the foregoing chapters, composers depict their friends and colleagues, they pay homage to important figures who came before them and to contemporary celebrities, and they also represent themselves. As portraits of painters, composers, writers, actors, and celebrities, these works depend on metaphors that forge intersections between modes of representation in music and in other aesthetic media including literature and painting, and also demonstrate how art forms merge together to operate in multimedia representations. In depicting the identities of the individuals named or suggested in their titles, musical portraits and self-​portraits may help guide us closer to an understanding of the seemingly ineffable but forceful bond between music and the human self. This epilogue brings this study to its conclusion by examining how musical portraiture has been used to represent people after death, in depictions of posthumous identities, and how it has operated in a realm beyond the human, in ways that involve what have

144

( 144 )   Musical Portraits

been called posthuman subjectivities, including those that entail a living body that has undergone significant technological modification. In the case of the former, the musical portrait is used to depict and even reanimate the deceased in a way that might recall Leon Battista Alberti’s statement on portraiture and immortality, quoted in the introduction to this book: “Painting contains a divine force which not only makes absent men present . . . but moreover makes the dead seem almost alive.”2 In the case of the latter, the self that the posthuman portraitist represents is an entity that has lost the independence that characterized it in humanist thought. According to critical theorist N. Katherine Hayles, “The posthuman subject is an amalgam, a collection of heterogeneous components . . . whose boundaries undergo continuous construction and reconstruction.”3 Andy Clark views this contemporary self as “a rough-​and-​tumble, control-​sharing coalition of processes—​some neural, some bodily, some technological—​ and an ongoing drive to tell a story, to paint a picture in which ‘I’ am the central player.”4 The posthuman musical portrait represents an identity as embedded in a network of tightly knit but perpetually changing relationships with humans, other species, machines, and the nonliving, and the stark division previously understood to separate the self and the other has lost its fixity and become permeable.5 To investigate how the musical portrait has been used to represent posthumous and posthuman selves, the epilogue explores two case studies in contrasting media. It first examines the music of Alfred Hitchcock’s 1958 movie Vertigo, to consider how Bernard Herrmann’s soundtrack operates as a musical portrait of a person seemingly possessed by the spirit of a deceased woman.6 It then turns to a more recent instance of musical portraiture, grounded in the relationship of the living not with the dead but with machines, by addressing the sound portraits created by the artist Neil Harbisson, a man who identifies himself as a cyborg and produces sonic constructions of people he encounters with the aid of a sensory antenna that extends from the back of his skull.7 Listening to musical portraits that bring together human, posthumous, and posthuman identities, and considering what these portraits might reveal about how we employ music to portray the identities of the dead, as well as how we let machines depict us through music, offers a final opportunity to enrich our understanding of the ways music operates as a medium of portraiture. In both of these unusual instances of musical portraiture, the visual sense is suggested to be a faulty mode of determining identity because of its capacity to mislead the viewer, or even to fail altogether to produce a complete and reliable image. It is finally sound and hearing that are proposed as replacements for visual representation and sight in the construction of the contemporary self.

  145

Epilo g u e    ( 145 )

“CAN’T YOU SEE?”

Hitchcock’s Vertigo is a multimedia study of portraiture and the social and aesthetic construction of the identities of the living and the dead in text, image, and music. The first half of the film follows the story of a retired police detective, Scottie ( James Stewart), as he accepts a commission from his old friend Gavin Elster (Tom Helmore) to follow Madeleine (Kim Novak), a mysterious blonde Scottie believes to be Elster’s wife. Something is wrong with Madeleine’s sense of self: her identity has evidently become possessed by the spirit of her deceased great-​grandmother Carlotta Valdes. (It is later revealed that this is, of course, a trick, and the gullible Scottie is being set up to witness Elster’s murder of another woman who is actually his wife, but to think that he has instead seen Madeleine’s suicide.) Scottie follows Madeleine through the streets and alleys of San Francisco; she leads him on a detour to the dead woman’s grave in the cemetery gardens of Mission Dolores, and finally to the Palace of the Legion of Honor, an art museum located in a neoclassical temple perched on a hillside overlooking the bay. There she settles onto a bench in front of a grand portrait of a woman in a lilac dress, her hair in a chignon, who holds a bouquet of roses and wears a large gold and ruby necklace. The portrait depicts Carlotta Valdes (Figure E.1). Scottie notes that Madeleine’s hair has been arranged in the same way as Carlotta’s, and that she has brought with her a similar bouquet. In this scene, the score introduces new material into the soundtrack that will return at key moments throughout the film as a leitmotif indicating the specter of Carlotta Valdes (Example E.1). This musical passage, played by

Figure E.1:  Kim Novak in Vertigo, directed by Alfred Hitchcock, Paramount Pictures, 1958.

146

( 146 )   Musical Portraits Example  E.1:  Bernard Herrmann, Carlotta’s leitmotif, from Vertigo, 1958, dir. Alfred Hitchcock. David Cooper, Bernard Herrmann’s Vertigo:  A Film Score Handbook (Westport, CT:  Greenwood Press, 2001), 20.

a small ensemble, features the harp performing a distinctive rhythm, the pattern associated with the habanera, the dance form named for Havana, Cuba, and made popular in Spain. The rhythm is familiar to many listeners from Georges Bizet’s incorporation of it into his aria “L’amour est un oiseau rebelle” (Love is a Rebellious Bird) for an earlier, operatic femme fatale, Carmen. This pattern maintains the single pitch D, serving as a pedal tone that restrains the motif from harmonic development and instead keeps it eerily static. Alongside the strumming, flutes play a repeating pattern of oozing half steps, ascending and descending in oscillation to create a ghostly impression that is compounded by the quiet resonance of the vibraphone that plays like distant cemetery bells and the muffled violins performed with the bow over the fingerboard, a technique that creates an effect that recalls a whistling draft of wind.8 A G♯ in the melodic flute patterns, the raised fourth scale degree above the pedal D, gestures toward flamenco scales and combines with the habanera pattern to paint a picture of Carlotta’s Hispanic origins and exotic, seductive eroticism. But the motif ’s spare melodic material also bears a striking resemblance to the swooningly romantic leitmotif introduced earlier in the film to refer to Madeleine, and the harp’s pulsing mimics a simpler repeated rhythmic pattern used previously to create suspense as Scottie followed Madeleine in his car. In this way the leitmotif for Carlotta links the two women together, as a sort of composite musical portrait that depicts both characters as sharing one identity.9 In the second half of the movie, Scottie believes Madeleine has suffered a sudden and violent death. He had fallen in love with her in the intervening scenes, and he now laments her loss to the point of distraction, until

  147

Epilo g u e    ( 147 )

he encounters a young brunette named Judy Barton (also Kim Novak). Taking Judy to a department store and beauty parlor, he dresses her in a suit like Madeleine’s and has her hair dyed blonde and put up in a chignon, transforming her so that she will adopt the appearance of the woman he loved, and thereby, he hopes, somehow embody that woman’s identity.10 Scottie’s behavior recalls Alberti’s dictum on portraiture: he wants to bring the dead back to life by making Judy into a kind of living portrait of Madeleine, much as Madeleine had once seemingly given new life to Carlotta’s identity by treating herself as a canvas upon which to recreate the woman’s likeness. Standing before a vanity mirror to prepare to go out to dine on the evening of her makeover as Madeleine, Judy asks for Scottie’s help with the clasp of her necklace. He obliges, fumbling; but when he looks up and witnesses her likeness in the mirror’s reflection, he recognizes the necklace as a reproduction of the one Carlotta wears in her portrait. Suddenly, the audience hears a return of the Carlotta leitmotif, characterized by its strummed habanera rhythm, and sees a montage of the two visual representations that Scottie has put together in his mind’s eye, the portrait of Carlotta that he recalls from the first day he saw Madeleine, and the mirror image of Judy he stands in front of.11 The last words Scottie heard Judy say before his discovery were: “Can’t you see?” Judy was asking if he could see how to work the clasp, but she was also articulating what many in the audience might by this point have been attempting to shout at Scottie through the screen for several minutes: can’t you see that Judy and Madeleine are the same woman? And one might just as effectively have asked “Can’t you hear?” because the leitmotif acts as a musical portrait that makes order out of the chaos of visual likenesses piling upon one another in the narrative and in Scottie’s consciousness. The habanera rhythm demonstrates that what has seemed to be three women was in fact a trio of visual representations obscuring a single individual self: Madeleine, who was sometimes Carlotta, was in fact always Judy. And here Judy, by foolishly selecting Carlotta’s necklace to wear to dinner, has given up the game.12 In George Eliot’s Daniel Deronda, the eponymous protagonist asks, in a line quoted in the epigraph to this chapter, “I wonder whether one oftener learns to love real objects through their representations, or the representations through the real objects.” As the return of the strummed habanera in the soundtrack finally shows, Scottie has learned to love both a real object through its representation and the representation through its real object. He thought he loved Madeleine as she portrayed Carlotta, and then as she was portrayed by Judy. But then it was revealed to him that Madeleine was always only a representation, a dramatic portrait, embodied and enacted

148

( 148 )   Musical Portraits

by Judy, of a woman possessed by a painted portrait of someone from the past. It is only through comparing the three likenesses that he finally alights on the identity of the figure he has fallen in love with, the one invoked by Herrmann’s slippery leitmotif: the object of his desire is in fact Carlotta Valdes, the woman depicted in the old painting that predates all of these characters, and whom Scottie only ever knew in the form of a representation, the portrait that inspired the convoluted plot laid by Elster to kill his wife. This conclusion, that the music shows us that the figure Scottie loves is neither Madeleine nor Judy but in fact the representation of the deceased Carlotta, is confirmed by his earlier irritated dismissal of yet another portrait, one painted by his friend Midge (Barbara Bel Geddes). In an attempt to coax Scottie’s amorous attention away from Madeleine and onto herself, Midge paints a self-​portrait as Carlotta Valdes, a pastiche of the original painting onto which she has added her own smiling face. Scottie responds by expressing disgust and disappointment that she has made light of Madeleine’s apparent plight and of the force of Carlotta’s posthumous identity. The soundtrack confirms Midge’s inability to embody Carlotta’s spirit, by remaining silent: no ghostly sonorities or habanera rhythms play in the background in the form of the Carlotta leitmotif; all that can be heard are the faint sounds of the street traffic out the window. In Vertigo, Hitchcock and Herrmann have created a complex multimedia depiction of the persuasive power of portraiture, in which visual and dramatic portraits construct identities that mislead the film’s central character, while musical portraiture, in the form of a motivic soundtrack, offers the audience the only clear perspective on this muddle of identities, and thus provides the key to understanding the protagonist’s true feelings. Robert Wilson later borrowed Carlotta’s musical portrait from its place in Herrmann’s soundtrack to Vertigo, reusing it in his 2006 video portrait of Princess Caroline of Monaco (Figure E.2).13 The leitmotif, repeated in a continuous loop, is heard for the duration of the video, as Princess Caroline stands starkly still, her back to the viewer and her face visible only in a partial profile. Princess Caroline’s pose is in part a reference to John Singer Sargent’s full-​length portrait “Madame X (Madame Pierre Gautreau)” (1883–​1884), as though spied from behind, a reminder of the theme of peeping at people who are unaware of being watched in another Hitchcock classic, Rear Window (1954), which again starred James Stewart, this time along with the Princess’s mother, Grace Kelly.14 But as the music helps to emphasize, Princess Caroline’s hair is up in a chignon like Carlotta’s, and the position of her head also recalls Madeleine’s, the way it appeared to Scottie from behind, as she sat staring at the portrait in the museum.

  149

Epilo g u e    ( 149 )

Figure E.2:  Robert Wilson and Bernard Herrmann, “Princess Caroline,” 2006, video. Courtesy RW Work Ltd.

Wilson has captured Princess Caroline’s image in black and white, and the only aspect that changes over the course of the seven and a half minutes of the portrait’s duration is the lighting, which gradually brightens, moves, and dims, so that the subject, at the start and end seen entirely in a black silhouette, is at times lit from certain angles that brighten the space between her shoulder blades, her hands—​held behind her back in a reference to a scene from Rear Window15—​and the edge of her face, which appears like the sliver of sunlight on a crescent moon. In this portrait, Princess Caroline, half-​invisible in the shadows, is a spectral apparition, and the musical soundtrack associates her with posthumous and nonhuman presences: the persistent spirit of the dead Carlotta and the obscure identity of Madeleine, a woman who first appeared to be possessed by a ghost, and was eventually

150

( 150 )   Musical Portraits

revealed never to have existed at all. With this portrait, Wilson effectively answers Judy’s question at the climactic moment in Vertigo, “Can’t you see?” We expect portraiture to make a subject’s appearance and identity available to the visual sense, but in its combination of the Carlotta motif and the darkness that enshrouds Princess Caroline, the portrait suggests that what we hear might in fact reveal just how little about a person we are able to see. MUSICAL PORTRAITS AND THE DIGITAL SENSES

The sound artist Neil Harbisson might also have to answer Judy’s question “Can’t you see?” in the negative. He is entirely colorblind, suffering from a condition called achromatopsia, a visual impairment that prevents him from registering the appearance of the people he encounters in as full and rich a way as he would like through sight alone.16 He has sought to remedy this effect of his condition by experimenting with the ways sound can be used to supplement or stand in for visual representation, and hearing can take the place of sight, to construct likenesses of the individuals he meets. Harbisson has turned to the genre of musical portraiture, creating a series of extremely brief works that depict his subjects in tones and harmonies that derive from the colors of the light that reflects from their faces. For Harbisson, music brings clarity in portraiture, because it can fill in the gaps with sound where vision fails. The resulting balance between sight and sound recalls the moment in Vertigo in which it is the musical portrait embedded in Herrmann’s leitmotif that finally clarifies the single identity behind the confusing handful of visual likenesses Scottie has encountered and fallen in love with. Harbisson has had a device created that converts the colors of the objects in front of him into corresponding sounds; this machine, which Harbisson calls an “eyeborg,” has been implanted in the back of his skull and curves over and above his cranium like a metal antenna that operates for Harbisson as a third eye and ear.17 This dual organ produces a new sensory connection to the world around him. It detects visible colors, as well as infrared and ultraviolet light waves, and transmits these from the camera at the tip of the antenna to a chip at the back of Harbisson’s skull. This chip translates the hues that are detected into associated pitch frequencies that Harbisson experiences through bone conduction. Donna Haraway’s “Cyborg Manifesto” argues that contemporary technologies “have made thoroughly ambiguous the difference between natural and artificial . . . and many other distinctions that used to apply to organisms and machines,”18 and indeed Harbisson explains that this machine is more than a prosthesis, it is a part of his body: “I don’t feel like I’m using technology, or wearing

  15

Epilo g u e    ( 151 )

technology. I  feel like I  am technology. I  don’t think of my antenna as a device—​it’s a body part.”‘19 The tones that Harbisson experiences by way of his antenna signify the colors of light according to a system of sonic and visual analogues through which Harbisson comprehends the appearance of people and things. For Harbisson, then, vision and hearing have merged into a single hybrid sense. Harbisson therefore states that he listens to paintings: “I like listening to Warhol and Rothko because their paintings produce clear notes,” he explains. “I can’t listen to Da Vinci or Velázquez because they use closely related tones—​they sound like the soundtrack for a horror film.”20 And when he dresses in the morning, he sometimes chooses to reproduce a sonority to suit his mood; on a happy day, he might wear C major—​a combination of items in pink, yellow, and blue.21 Harbisson has also described the impact of his new sensory organ on his perception of beauty: “When I look at someone, I hear their face, so someone might look very beautiful but sound terrible.”22 Harbisson has used his eyeborg to create a series of Sound Portraits of celebrities, musicians, actors, artists, and political figures, including Daniel Radcliffe, Gael García Bernal, Prince Charles, Woody Allen, Leonardo Da Caprio, Nicole Kidman, and Tracey Emin. He also sometimes approaches strangers on the street and offers to produce their portraits, sending them MP3s of their likenesses when he is finished.23 The individual portraits are short, at only about three seconds each, and many of them can be listened to in a series that Harbisson has made available online in a video in which the sound of each portrait is accompanied by a name in white type over a black background indicating its subject. Each portrait takes the form of a chord produced by the layering of multiple static tones. The pitches in these portraits represent the colors of the eyes, lips, skin, and hair of Harbisson’s subjects. The timbre of each portrait is the same, an electronic sound quality that is not made to resemble any instrument or voice but might instead call to mind the sounds of electronic machinery. Harbisson’s Sound Portraits announce their posthuman derivation in a number of obvious ways. They are produced not by a creative act of composition but by the use of a programmed machine that implements a set of preordained correspondences between light and color. Their timbres, additionally, are clearly technologically generated, and this renders largely uniform the sequence of people of varied backgrounds and professions that the portraits represent, like a series of smartphones of the same model but different colors lined up on a shop display table. Furthermore, the portraits, in the manner of a checkpoint retina scan, capture only the details of phys­ ical appearance, but not the “internal” characteristics of identity. And the portraits do not allow for human performance, apart from pressing “play”

152

( 152 )   Musical Portraits

on an interactive website like YouTube.24 This means that they will always sound more or less the same, and they leave no room for a performer’s interpretation or for the sort of meanings produced for an audience member by watching a human performer. Instead, they reach the listener directly and with minimal mediation, much as the sounds of Harbisson’s implanted chip transmits tones straight into his head without human interpretive intervention. The posthuman artist arguably requires new modes of representation to interpret and portray the posthuman self. According to theories of cyborg subjectivity, this new form of representation could also demand an altered conception of the relationship between the artist and the tools he employs in the creation of a portrait. Andy Clark and David Chalmers write that the “coupled process” of cognition, in which “the human organism is linked with an external entity in a two-​way interaction . . . counts equally well as a cognitive process, whether or not it is wholly in the head.”25 In this analysis, the painter’s paintbrush and the composer’s pen or notation software, no less than the implanted eyeborg, can be considered integral parts of the artist’s cognitive process, despite their existence beyond the physical boundaries of the body. And Clark and Chalmers conclude on the basis of this argument that the notion of extension also applies to personhood: “The extended mind impl[ies] an extended self.”26 Clark later develops this reasoning about extended cognition and the self, in Natural-​Born Cyborgs, to argue that we are all cyborgs, in the sense that we are “human-​ technology symbionts: thinking and reasoning systems whose minds and selves are spread across biological brain and nonbiological circuitry,” a notion with “roots in some of the most basic and characteristic facts about human nature.”27 In Harbisson’s portraits, both artist and sitter are cyborgs. Harbisson is a cyborg because he observes and represents others’ selves through a process of extended cognition using his technological implant. His subjects are cyborgs, too, because they are portrayed as automated sonic translations of visible and invisible colors of light, that sound distinctly electronic and must be listened to and contemplated through the use of new media devices, cybernetic cognitive extensions in the form of Internet-​enabled computers.28 Hayles argues that with the contemporary technologies that turn our attention away from print and toward “the flickering signifiers of digital media, visual forms, like the body, seem to lose their weighty materiality.”29 Elsewhere she writes that in cybernetic constructions of the posthuman subject, “embodiment is not essential to human being.”30 For Harbisson, whose own body has been technologically enhanced to transform him into a cyborg assemblage of flesh and metal who interacts with the world by way of organic and computerized senses, the bodies of those he encounters do

  153

Epilo g u e    ( 153 )

indeed seem to have lost some of their physical presence and individuality when perceived—​that is, scanned—​as intersecting, weightless flickers of light. The representations in his Sound Portraits are built of digital sound vibrations, as immaterial and intangible as the avatars that populate online virtual worlds such as Pokémon Go or Second Life, and that interact with other avatars as extensions of the invisible bodies and minds of the people who construct them as alternate self-​portraits.31 For this reason, this set of musical representations brings to mind the famous line in Bernard Wolfe’s science fiction novel Limbo, “The human skin is an artificial boundary: the world wanders into it and the self wanders out of it, traffic is two-​way and constant.”32 MUSICAL PORTRAITURE: HUMAN, POSTHUMOUS, POSTHUMAN

The Introduction to this book addressed the relationship between sound and appearance, to begin considering the question of why music’s incapacity to reproduce or evoke visual likeness does not curtail its use as a medium of portraiture. Until the twentieth century, mimetic likeness was generally considered an essential aspect of portraiture. The shift toward abstraction in visual art and literature in the twentieth century has been accompanied by an increase in the creation of musical portraits that perform their representations through techniques with analogues in modern art. But musical portraits have relied on elements of abstract representation from their inception in François Couperin’s and C. P. E. Bach’s musical portraits and character pieces. The notion proposed in the Introduction and explored throughout the subsequent chapters of this book is that music, which is incapable of reproducing visible likeness (beyond gesturing obliquely toward such attributes as a person’s size or weight or the lightness or heft of one’s footsteps), has long been understood to be able to convey mood, character, personality, profession, social caste, and any other of a number of invisible factors that are typically considered integral to a rich interpretation of an individual’s subjectivity or self, and that the representation of such attributes in a musical work named for an individual is sufficient for it to function as a work of portraiture. Indeed, by a mechanism analogous to how musical portraits are interpreted, visual and literary portraits, even before the twentieth century, have traditionally been considered incomplete if they convey likeness alone; they have been deemed successful only when their creators provide audiences with depictions of invisible aspects of character. In this way, and through a process that involves multiple levels of metaphoric allusion, music is an apt vehicle for portraiture, and in

154

( 154 )   Musical Portraits

contemporary multimedia, in representations of the dead, and even in posthuman exercises it has been combined with visual art and language to deliver intriguing representations of identity. Some scholars suggest that the posthuman condition, characterized in part by common contemporary preoccupations with the subject’s relationship to the body, mortality, and technology, compels us to reconsider the nature of the self and methods of its representation. In her writings about posthumanism, the philosopher Rosi Braidotti argues, “we need to devise new social, ethical, and discursive schemes of subject formation to match the profound transformations we are undergoing.” The posthuman condition, she continues, offers “an opportunity to empower the pursuit of alternative schemes of thought, knowledge and self-​representation.”33 The two instances of musical portraiture examined in this epilogue represent a pair of such efforts to rethink the representation of the self through music, with contrasting implications. In Vertigo, Herrmann’s Carlotta leitmotif fully bypasses physical appearance to serve as a representation of other aspects of Carlotta’s identity. The habanera rhythmic pattern gives an impression of the cultural origin that is implied by her name but rarely discussed in the film, and it also implies her seductive nature, while the eeriness of the subtly shifting sustained tones and whispering timbres implies her ghostly manifestation—​a virtual presence made poignant by her actual absence. The way the motif is used, moreover, suggests that sound holds a position of priority over image, because its clarifying role indicates that the narrative’s instances of visual portraiture have been misleading, that the various likenesses Scottie has encountered have thoroughly confused him and can ultimately lead only to the undoing of the film’s two leading characters. Harbisson’s Sound Portraits, on the other hand, immediately seem to take a different approach to representing the self than do Herrmann’s soundtrack and the multiple musical portraits considered throughout this book. As brief sonic objects constructed of layered pitches in the form of a single chord, Harbisson’s works are essentially musical likenesses. Hayles describes “the deconstruction of the liberal humanist subject in cybernetics,”34 and writes of the contemporary self, “We are the medium, and the medium is us.”35 By automatically translating the light rays that reflect off their subjects’ faces into corresponding tones, these portraits produce a direct sonic analogue to physical appearance. They thereby engage a form of musical mimesis that offers a direct translation of the way one appears into sound—​albeit in a rarified musical language that only Harbisson possesses the expertise to interpret effectively—​and in this manner they purport to tighten the bond between language (in the portraits’ titles), hearing, and sight to allow sound to reproduce appearance.

  15

Epilo g u e    ( 155 )

Of course, in their omission of any attributes of profession, artistic style, character, mood, or personality, these Sound Portraits, despite their ingenuity, open themselves to the criticism that they ultimately reveal too little about their subjects beyond appearance, recalling the age-​old argument that likeness alone is insufficient to represent an individual self in portraiture. What Harbisson’s attempt to devise a new method for creating physical likeness in sound might therefore unwittingly accomplish, for some listeners, is to emphasize the differences, rather than the overlaps, between modes of representation in music and those in other artistic media. Despite the basis of this genre on the precedent of portraiture in the visual arts and literature, musical portraiture seems ultimately to be most effective not when it relies solely on outward appearance, or the reflection of light off the face, but rather when it evokes, through modes of metaphoric allusion, and with the title mediating the listener’s interpretive process, the more abstract and intangible attributes that make up our identities. In spite of their unique focus only on mimetic likeness, and their resulting arguable deficiency as portraits because they fail to depict character, however, Harbisson’s series reveals striking intersections with the much more complex musical portraits examined to this point. For example, Harbisson has found a novel way of fulfilling the goal set out by Gertrude Stein and Virgil Thomson of developing a technique of portraiture that directly and immediately portrays something akin to the subject’s “existence” (to use Stein’s term) or “presence” (to use Thomson’s). Like Thomson, Harbisson creates his compositions in front of his sitters, in a spontaneous act of perception and representation that produces an abstract musical portrait of a person’s presence in a given instance. And in the manner of Boulez’s Pli selon pli, Harbisson’s “Sound Portraits” depend on a rich conception of the overlapping relationships between art forms and the senses. Boulez bases his musical structures on an increasingly deep reading of Mallarmé’s sonnet form, to find an artistic space in which music and poetry overlay one another, “fold according to fold.” Harbisson is also preoccupied with inter-​ sensory associations, and has said of sight and sound, “There is no difference for me between composing music or painting, it’s all the same.”36 In his portraits he finds a direct musical analogue to appearance; he also uses musical form to explore aesthetic experience, in this case employing brevity and homophony to reproduce the structure of a momentary glance at an individual’s face. Harbisson’s approach to using sound as a representational medium to relate directly to the role of color in visual representation and his statements about the equivalency between composing and painting also recall the ekphrastic character of the musical portraits that Morton Feldman and Philip Glass composed of Willem de Kooning and Chuck Close. Where

156

( 156 )   Musical Portraits

their musical formulations directly correlate to their subjects’ painterly techniques, Harbisson’s Sound Portraits reenact in tones the reflections of light off the structure of the face that are processed visually to form the mental representation of physical appearance. Harbisson’s discussions of hearing faces and listening to paintings also reflects the way Feldman characterized composition according to metaphors of painting, including his concepts of the “surface aural plane”37 and the “plastic possibilities of musical shape.”38 Harbisson’s portraits furthermore call to mind aspects of Ligeti’s and Ablinger’s musical self-​portraits. Ligeti and Harbisson engaged techniques that, in conveying the individuality of multiple subjects at once, also draw attention to their similarities:  Ligeti highlights correlations between the distinct compositional techniques of the four composers depicted in his group portrait, while Harbisson’s portraits, generally listened to in sequence, all share the same simple form, brief duration, and electronic timbre, but point to their sitters’ differences in appearance through contrasting harmonic structures. In addition, both Ablinger and Harbisson are concerned with the relationship between perception and selfhood, and the notion that it is through the senses of hearing and sight that people construct their own and others’ identities. Thus Ablinger writes that composition, for him, is “a research project; research into perception. And about how perception creates us!”;39 Harbisson expresses an overlapping view of art, identity, and perception, in stating, “Art . . . lies in the creation of our own senses.”40 Furthermore, Harbisson brings to its extreme the mechanization already incipient in Ablinger’s work, which is both created and “performed” largely by inert technologies rather than human creativity. Ablinger used his recording device to collect the Berlin city sounds, and developed computer software to analyze it, and the music is played back through speakers, to the accompaniment of the ensemble of live musicians. In this way, in Harbisson’s and Ablinger’s portraits, both composition and performance involve automation in a way that challenges assumptions about the role of thought, decision-​making, and interpretation in the development of the self and the creation of art, and raises the question of how both artist and sitter might be considered hybrid, cyborg subjects. Finally, Harbisson’s portraits call to mind certain key aspects of the Voom Portraits of Robert Wilson, as well as of Einstein on the Beach. Like the Voom Portraits, Harbisson’s sound structures involve a return to the centuries-​ old genre of portraiture, to remind us how the portrait can be used to mislead the viewer or to obscure rather than reveal the self in depictions of the identities of contemporary celebrities: Harbisson’s works focus on external form and obstruct other aspects of character from view, in a reminder of the way Wilson’s video portrait of Winona Ryder shows more about how

  157

Epilo g u e    ( 157 )

she constructs and maintains a façade mediated by celebrity culture than it does about her identity. But this absence of revelation necessarily leaves more up to the interpretation of the individual spectator or listener, and the listener to Harbisson’s Sound Portraits, like the audience for Einstein on the Beach, must take in the works’ isolated clues about their subjects, offered as a set of signifiers never fully explained by their creators, and engage in a highly individual and creative hermeneutic reading in order to construct an impression of the identities represented in sounds, language, and images. This epilogue’s musical portraits, which imply doubts about whether the human self controls or is controlled by its deceased antecedents and by its nonhuman tools and environments, remind us that the genre has always been preoccupied with the human self as a mutable and constructed entity associated with processes of perception and somehow existing apart from the visual signs of its embodiment. The musical portraits considered in this book raise the question observed in the line from George Eliot’s Daniel Deronda in the epigraph to this chapter, about the ambiguity of the hierarchy of our perceptions of real and represented subjects. In some cases, a listener may find a musical representation convincing because it confirms what he knows to be true about its subject; in others, a listener may appreciate that a musical representation proposes something new that was not previously evident, and that may or may not “in fact” be true. Music conveys information about the objects of its representations through the metaphors that guide its interpretation. But metaphors in music can also persuade us to change our conception of reality. Perhaps this is why musical portraits can be so powerful: they bypass portraiture’s typical dependency on visual likeness and its fraught relationship with the depiction of the invisible attributes that make up our sense of the self, and in doing so they offer us the chance to close our eyes and listen closely for those seemingly inaccessible abstractions of identity that lie beyond the surface.

NOTES 1.  George Eliot, Daniel Deronda, 2 vols. (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1876), ii: 27. 2. Lorenzo Battista Alberti, On Painting, trans. John R. Spencer (New Haven, CT:  Yale University Press, 1956, rev. ed. 1966), 63. 3. N. Katherine Hayles, How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature, and Informatics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 3. 4. Andy Clark, Natural-​Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 138. 5. Jennifer Thweatt-​Bates, “Posthuman Selves: Bodies, Cognitive Processes, and Technologies,” in J. Wentzel van Huyssteen and Erik P. Wiebe (eds.), In Search of Self:  Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Personhood (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2011), 247.

158

( 158 )   Musical Portraits

6. On music and the relationship between the living and dead, particularly in the context of popular music production, see Jason Stanyek and Benjamin Piekut, “Deadness:  Technologies of the Intermundane,” TDR/​The Drama Review 54.1 (Spring 2010): 14–​38. 7. For definitions of multiple strands of posthumanism, see David Roden, Posthuman Life: Philosophy at the Edge of the Human (New York: Routledge, 2015), 20–​32. On the “posthuman” merging of human and technology in music production and consumption, see Joseph Auner, “‘Sing It for Me’: Posthuman Ventriloquism in Recent Popular Music,” Journal of the Royal Musical Association 128.1 (2003): 98–​122. On the cyborg and its historical link to the fields of cybernetics and artificial intelligence, see Stefano Franchi and Güven Güzeldere, “Machinations of the Mind:  Cybernetics and Artificial Intelligence from Automata to Cyborgs,” in Stefano Franchi and Güven Güzeldere (eds.), Mechanical Bodies, Computational Minds: Artificial Intelligence from Automata to Cyborgs (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2005), 114–​23. 8. See Jack Sullivan, Hitchcock’s Music (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2008), 229. 9. David Cooper, Bernard Herrmann’s Vertigo:  A Film Score Handbook (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 2001), 20, 98–​100. 10. As the band Harvey Danger puts it in their 1997 song about the mysterious woman in the painting, “Carlotta Valdes: I will make you her.” 11. Hitchcock had dealt with similar themes previously, in Rebecca (1940), a film based on a novel by Daphne du Maurier in which a young newlywed ( Joan Fontaine) is taken to reside in the mansion where her husband (Laurence Olivier) had lived previously with his now-​deceased first wife Rebecca. This young woman feels haunted by Rebecca’s presence, and at one point the housekeeper Mrs. Danvers ( Judith Anderson), still loyal to Rebecca’s memory, misleads her into wearing a dress for a costume party based on a portrait that hangs in the hall. This turns out to be a depiction of Rebecca from the year before, and the emulation and reanimation of the portrait provokes a confrontation in which Olivier’s character is enraged and Fontaine’s is humiliated. In his soundtrack, Franz Waxman created a leitmotif to depict “the overshadowing spirit of the dead Rebecca” that features heavy chromaticism like Herrmann’s later Carlotta leitmotif. This was performed by what Waxman dubbed a “ghost orchestra” of electric organ and a pair of novachords, a new innovation of the era that created an eerie timbre using radio tubes and that he said “has a peculiar sound of unreality—​of something that you cannot define.” David Neumeyer and Nathan Platte, Franz Waxman’s Rebecca: A Film Score Guide (Lanham, MD: Scarecrow, 2012), 115–​16. 12. On the uses of portraiture in Vertigo, see Nickolas Pappas, “Magic and Art in Vertigo,” in Katalin Makkai (ed.), Vertigo (New York: Routledge, 2013), 18–​44. 13. Robert Wilson and Bernard Herrmann, “Princess Caroline,” Dissident Industries Inc., 2006, video, www.dissidentusa.com/​robert-​wilson/​subjects/​princess-​caroline/​. 14. Bob Colacello, “The Subject as Star,” Vanity Fair, November 6, 2006. The reference to Rear Window also suggests a pun on the traditional notion of the work of art as a window onto an alternate reality (see Rudolf Arnheim, Art and Visual Perception: A Psychology of the Creative Eye (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1974), 239). Further along these lines, Wilson has said that when his Voom Portraits are hung in people’s homes, “they can be like a window—​a window that shows us another world.” “Voom Portraits by Robert Wilson Opens Next Week in Valladolid,” http://​artdaily.com/​news/​29769/​Voom-​ Portraits-​by-​Robert-​Wilson-​Opens-​Next-​Week-​in-​Valladolid#.VzTuUWNWLiM, March 29, 2009. 15. Noah Khoshbin and Matthew Shattuck, “Overview,” Dissident Industries Inc., accessed June 21, 2016, www.dissidentusa.com/​robert-​wilson/​overview/​. 16. Stuart Jeffries, “Neil Harbisson:  The World’s First Cyborg Artist,” The Guardian, May 6, 2014, www.theguardian.com/​artanddesign/​2014/​may/​06/​neil-harbisson-worldsfirst-​cyborg-​artist. 17. See a detailed description of this machine at Harbisson’s professional website. Neil Harbisson, accessed June 21, 2016, www.harbisson.com. 18. Donna J. Haraway, “A Cyborg Manifesto: Science, Technology, and Socialist-​Feminism in the Late Twentieth Century,” in Donna J. Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The

  159

Epilo g u e    ( 159 )

Reinvention of Nature (New York: Routledge, 1991), 152. On the posthuman merging of human bodies and technology, see also Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, 3. 19. Jeffries, “Neil Harbisson: The World’s First Cyborg Artist.” 20. Jeffries, “Neil Harbisson: The World’s First Cyborg Artist.” 21. Paul Ivan Harris, “Neil Harbisson: The Man Who Hears Colour,” BBC News, November 11, 2014, video, www.bbc.com/​news/​technology-​29992577. 22. Neil Harbisson, “What’s It Like to Hear Color?” TED Radio Hour, March 7, 2014, video, www.npr.org/​2014/​03/​07/​283441986/​what-​s-​it-​like-​to-​hear-​color. 23. Harris, “Neil Harbisson: The Man Who Hears Colour.” 24. Neil Harbisson, “Sound Portraits,” YouTube, May 7, 2010, video, https://​www.youtube. com/​watch?v=JDqL-​PUZ148. 25. Andy Clark and David Chalmers, “The Extended Mind,” Analysis 58.1 ( January 1998): 8–​9. 26. Clark and Chalmers, “Extended Mind,” 18. 27. Clark, Natural-​Born Cyborgs, 3. 28. A discussion of the impact of new digital technologies on visual portraiture and the ways this has influenced the conception of the individual during the contemporary era appears in Michael Desmond, Present Tense: An Imagined Grammar of Portraiture in the Digital Age (Canberra: National Portrait Gallery, 2010), 2–​11. 29. N. Katherine Hayles, “Visualizing the Posthuman,” Art Journal 59.3 (Fall 2000):  51. Hayles remains supportive, nevertheless, of an embodied view of subjectivity, and opposes approaches to the posthuman subject that seek to separate the self from the physical body. 30. Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, 4. 31. See Lee Siegel, “On the Face of It,” in Donna Gustafson and Susan Sidlauskas (eds.), Striking Resemblance:  The Changing Art of Portraiture (New Brunswick, NJ:  Zimmerli Art Museum at Rutgers University; London:  Prestel, 2014), 78; Sandra Kemp, Future Face: Image, Identity, Innovation (London: Profile, 2004), 135–​6. 32. Bernard Wolfe, Limbo (London: Gollancz, 2016, orig. 1952), 131. Quoted as an epigraph in Clark, Natural-​Born Cyborgs. Kim Toffoletti shows that depictions of posthuman bodies in popular visual culture, especially those created with the aid of new technologies of representation, often indicate ambivalence about the individuality of identity, about the boundaries that separate self from other and reality from virtuality, and in this way they offer the potential to alter our understanding of the nature of the self. Kim Toffoletti, Cyborgs and Barbie Dolls: Feminism, Popular Culture and the Posthuman Body (London: I. B. Tauris, 2007), 5–​6. 33. Rosi Braidotti, The Posthuman (Cambridge: Polity, 2013), 12. 34. Hayles, How We Became Posthuman, 4. 35. Hayles, “Visualizing the Posthuman,” 54. 36. Harris, “Neil Harbisson: The Man Who Hears Colour.” 37. Morton Feldman, “Between Categories,” The Composer 1.2 (Sept 1969): 73–​7, reprinted in B. H. Friedman (ed.), Give My Regards to Eighth Street:  Collected Writings of Morton Feldman (Cambridge, MA: Exact Change, 2000), 84. 38. Juan Manuel Bonet, “I Learned More from Painters than I  Learned from Composers,” trans. Jonathan Brennan, in Seán Kissane (ed.), Vertical Thoughts: Morton Feldman and the Visual Arts (Dublin: Irish Museum of Modern Art, 2010), 9. 39. Carlos Bermejo, “Seven Projections in the Music of Peter Ablinger,” accessed June 21, 2016, http://​ablinger.mur.at/​docs/​CarlosBermejo_​7Projections.pdf. 40. Harbisson, accessed June 21, 2016, www.harbisson.com.

160

  16

BIB L I O G R A P H Y

Abbate, Carolyn. “Music—​Drastic or Gnostic?” Critical Inquiry 30.3 (Spring 2004): 505–​36. Ablinger, Peter. “Inverse Perspective.” Translated by Bill Dietz. 1995. http://​ablinger.mur.at/​ engl.html. Ablinger, Peter. “Metaphern (Wenn die Klänge die Klänge wären).” In Übertragung—​Transfer—​ Metapher:  Kulturtechniken, ihre Visionen und Obsessionen, edited by Sabine Sanio and Christian Scheib. Bielefeld: Kerber, 2004. http://​ablinger.mur.at/​docu14.html. Ablinger, Peter. “Peter Ablinger—​English Texts.” Translated by Bill Dietz. Accessed June 21, 2016. http://​ablinger.mur.at/​engl.html. Ablinger, Peter. “Quadraturen.” Translated by Bill Dietz. Accessed June 21, 2016. http://​ ablinger.mur.at/​docu11.html. Ablinger, Peter, and Anny Ballardini. “About Voices and Piano.” Edited by Rita Duckworth. 2004. http://​ablinger.mur.at/​voices_​and_​piano.html. Ablinger, Peter, and Stéphane Ginsburgh. “Peter Ablinger:  Voices and Piano.” 2011. http://​ ablinger.mur.at/​docs/​v+p_​ginsburgh.pdf. Ablinger, Peter, and Trond Olav Reinholdtsen. “The Sounds Do Not Interest Me.” 2005. http://​ ablinger.mur.at/​engl.html. Ablinger, Peter, and Chiyoko Szlavincs. “Two Composers’ Talk.” 2007. http://​ablinger.mur.at/​ txt_​2_​talk.html. Adamowicz, Elza. “The Surrealist (Self-​)Portrait: Convulsive Identities.” In Surrealism: Surrealist Visuality, edited by Silvano Levy, 31–​44. Edinburgh: Keele University Press, 1996. Adams, John. The Dharma at Big Sur; My Father Knew Charles Ives. BBC Symphony Orchestra. Nonesuch 79857-​2, 2006. Compact disc liner notes. Adams, John. Hallelujah Junction: Composing an American Life. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2008. Aiken, Edward A. “‘I Saw the Figure  5 in Gold’:  Charles Demuth’s Emblematic Portrait of William Carlos Williams.” Art Journal 46.3 (Autumn 1987): 178–​84. Alarcó, Paloma, and Malcolm Warner, eds. The Mirror & the Mask:  Portraiture in the Age of Picasso. New Haven, CT:  Yale University Press; Fort Worth:  Kimbell Art Museum; Madrid: Museo Thyssen-​Bornemisza and Fundación Caja Madrid, 2007. Albèra, Philippe. “Entretien avec Pierre Boulez.” In Pli selon pli de Pierre Boulez: Entretien et études, edited by Philippe Albèra, 7–​24. Geneva: Éditions Contrechamps, 2003. Albèra, Philippe. Pli selon pli de Pierre Boulez:  Entretien et études. Geneva:  Éditions Contrechamps, 2003. Alberti, Lorenzo Battista. On Painting. Translated by John R. Spencer. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1956, revised edition 1966. Allan, Kenneth. “The Postmodern Self:  A  Theoretical Consideration.” Quarterly Journal of Ideology 20.1–​2 (1997): 3–​24.

162

( 162 )  Bibliography

Angell, Callie. Andy Warhol Screen Tests: The Films of Andy Warhol Catalogue Raisonné. Volume I. New York: Harry N. Abrams and Whitney Museum of Art, 2006. Aristotle. The Poetics of Aristotle. Translated by Preston H. Epps. Chapel Hill:  University of North Carolina Press, 1970. Arnheim, Rudolf. Art and Visual Perception: A Psychology of the Creative Eye. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1974. Auner, Joseph. “‘Sing It for Me’: Posthuman Ventriloquism in Recent Popular Music.” Journal of the Royal Musical Association 128.1 (2003): 98–​122. Auping, Michael, ed. Abstract Expressionism:  The Critical Developments. New  York:  Harry N. Abrams, 1987. Bailey, Anthony. Rembrandt’s House: Exploring the World of the Great Master. London: Tauris Parke, 2014; orig. Boston: Houghton Mifflin; London: J. M. Dent, 1978. Balken, Debra Bricker. Abstract Expressionism. Movements in Modern Art Series. London: Tate, 2005. Barresi, John, and Raymond Martin. “History as Prologue: Western Theories of the Self.” In The Oxford Handbook of the Self, edited by Shaun Gallagher, 33–​56. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. Barrett, G. Douglas. “Between Noise and Language: The Sound Installations and Music of Peter Ablinger.” Mosaic 42.4 (December 2009): 147–​64. Barthes, Roland. “The Brain of Einstein.” In Roland Barthes, Mythologies, translated by Annette Lavers, 68–​70. New York: Hill and Wang, 1972, orig. 1957. Barthes, Roland. Camera Lucida: Reflections on Photography. New York: Hill and Wang, 1982. Barthes, Roland. “The Death of the Author.” In Image—​Music—​Text, translated by Stephen Heath, 142–​8. New York: Hill and Wang, 1977. Barthes, Roland. “The Face of Garbo.” In Roland Barthes, Mythologies, translated by Annette Lavers, 56–​7. New York: Hill and Wang, 1972, orig. 1957. Baxandall, Michael. Painting and Experience in Fifteenth-​Century Italy:  A  Primer in the Social History of Pictorial Style. 2nd edition. Oxford:  Oxford University Press, 1988. 1st edition 1972. Beal, Amy C. “‘Time Canvasses’: Morton Feldman and the Painters of the New York School.” In Music and Modern Art, edited by James Leggio, 227–​45. New York: Routledge, 2002. Beckett, Samuel. Happy Days: A Play in Two Acts. New York: Grove Press, 1961. Beckett, Samuel. Proust and Three Dialogues. Edited by Georges Duthuit. London:  John Calder, 1965. Originally published as Samuel Beckett and Georges Duthuit. “Three Dialogues: Tal Coat—​Masson—​Van Velde.” Transition 49.5 (December 1949): 97–​103. Benito Sandra, and Anita Feldman. Introduction to The Art of Music, edited by Patrick Coleman, 17–​31. San Diego:  San Diego Museum of Art; New Haven, CT:  Yale University Press, 2015. Berg, Darrell M. “C. P. E. Bach’s Character Pieces and His Friendship Circle.” In C. P. E. Bach Studies, edited by Stephen Clark, 1–​32. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988. Berger, John. Portraits: John Berger on Artists. Edited by Tom Overton. London: Verso, 2015. Bermejo, Carlos. “Seven Projections in the Music of Peter Ablinger.” Accessed June 21, 2016. http://​ablinger.mur.at/​docs/​CarlosBermejo_​7Projections.pdf. Originally published as Carlos Bermejo Martín. “Siete proyecciones en la música de Peter Ablinger.” Revista Europea de Investigación en Arquitectura 1 (2013): 15–​24. Bernard, Jonathan W. “Feldman’s Painters.” In The New York Schools of Music and Visual Arts, edited by Steven Johnson, 173–​215. New York: Routledge, 2002. Bernard, Jonathan W. “Inaudible Structures, Audible Music: Ligeti’s Problem, and His Solution.” Music Analysis 6.3 (October 1987): 207–​36. Bernard, Jonathan W. “Ligeti’s Restoration of Interval and Its Significance for His Later Works.” Music Theory Spectrum 21.1 (Spring 1999): 1–​31.

  163

Bibliography  ( 163 )

Bernard, Jonathan W. “Voice Leading as a Spatial Function in the Music of Ligeti.” Music Analysis 13.2/​3 ( July–​October 1994): 227–​53. Bernhart, Walter, Steven Paul Scher, and Werner Wolf, eds. Word and Music Studies: Defining the Field: Proceedings of the First International Conference on Word and Music Studies at Graz, 1997. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1999. Bhogal, Gurminder Kaur. “Visual Metaphors in Music Analysis and Criticism.” In The Routledge Companion to Music and Visual Culture, edited by Tim Shephard and Anne Leonard, 191–​9. New York: Routledge, 2014. Blizzard, Allison. Portraits of the 20th Century Self:  An Interartistic Study of Gertrude Stein’s Literary Portraits and Early Modernist Portraits by Paul Cézanne, Henri Matisse and Pablo Picasso. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 2004. Blomberg, Katja. Forward to HÖREN hören/​ hearing LISTENING, edited by Katja Blomberg, Chico Mello, Christian Scheib, and Trond Reinholdtsen, 18–​ 19. Heidelberg: Kehrer, 2008. Blomberg, Katja, Chico Mello, Christian Scheib, and Trond Reinholdtsen. Peter Ablinger: HÖREN hören/​hearing LISTENING. Heidelberg: Kehrer, 2008. Bond, Anthony. “Performing the Self?” In Self-​Portrait: Renaissance to Contemporary, edited by Anthony Bond and Joanna Woodall, 30–​41. London: National Portrait Gallery, 2005. Bond, Anthony, and Joanna Woodall, eds. Self-​ Portrait:  Renaissance to Contemporary. London: National Portrait Gallery, 2005. Bonet, Juan Manuel. “I Learned More from Painters than I  Learned from Composers.” Translated by Jonathan Brennan. In Vertical Thoughts:  Morton Feldman and the Visual Arts, edited by Seán Kissane, 7–​22. Dublin: Irish Museum of Modern Art, 2010. Boulez, Pierre. Boulez Conducts Boulez—​Pli Selon Pli. BBC Symphony Orchestra. Columbia Masterworks. CBS 75.770, 1970. LP. Boulez, Pierre. Boulez on Music Today. Translated by Susan Bradshaw and Richard Rodney Bennett. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971. Boulez, Pierre. Notes of an Apprenticeship. Translated by Herbert Weinstock. New York: Knopf, 1968. Boulez, Pierre. Orientations:  Collected Writings. Edited by Jean-​Jacques Nattiez, translated by Martin Cooper. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986. Boulez, Pierre. “Sonate, Que me Veux-​tu?” Translated by David Noakes and Paul Jacobs. Perspectives of New Music 1.2 (Spring 1963): 32–​44. Boutwell, Brett. “‘The Breathing of Sound Itself ’: Notation and Temporality in Feldman’s Music to 1970.” Contemporary Music Review 32.6 (2013): 531–​70. Boutwell, Brett. “Morton Feldman’s Graphic Notation: Projections and Trajectories.” Journal of the Society for American Music 6.4 (November 2012): 457–​82. Bové, Sergio. “Beyond the Boundaries of Music: Some Connections in Peter Ablinger’s Work.” 2013. http://​ablinger.mur.at/​docs/​bove_​beyond.pdf. Bowie, Malcolm. Mallarmé and the Art of Being Difficult. Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press, 1978. Bradshaw, Susan. “The Instrumental and Vocal Music.” In Pierre Boulez: A Symposium, edited by William Glock, 127–​229. London: Eulenberg, 1986. Braidotti, Rosi. The Posthuman. Cambridge: Polity, 2013. Breatnach, Mary M. Boulez and Mallarmé:  A  Study in Poetic Influence. Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 1996. Breatnach, Mary M. “Pli selon pli. A  Conflation of Theoretical Stances.” In Word and Music Studies: Defining the Field: Proceedings of the First International Conference on Word and Music Studies at Graz, 1997, edited by Walter Bernhart, Steven Paul Scher, and Werner Wolf, 265–​75. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1999. Brecht, Stefan. The Theatre of Visions: Robert Wilson. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1978.

164

( 164 )  Bibliography

Brilliant, Richard. Portraiture. London: Reaktion Books, 1991. Brown, Michael A. “Portraits, Music and Enlightenment in the Atlantic World.” In The Art of Music, edited by Patrick Coleman, 167–​83. San Diego: San Diego Museum of Art; New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2015. Browning, Robert. “Fra Lippo Lippi.” In Poems of Robert Browning, edited by Charlotte Porter and Helen A. Clarke, 124–​32. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell: 1896. Bruhn, Siglind. “A Concert of Paintings: ‘Musical Ekphrasis’ in the Twentieth Century.” Poetics Today 22.3 (Fall 2001): 551–​605. Bruhn, Siglind. Musical Ekphrasis:  Composers Responding to Poetry and Painting. Hillsdale, NY: Pendragon Press, 2000. Bruhn, Siglind, ed. Sonic Transformations of Literary Texts:  From Program Music to Musical Ekphrasis. Hillsdale, NY: Pendragon Press, 2008. Butor, Michel. “Mallarmé selon Boulez.” In Répertoire, Michel Butor, 5 volumes, ii:  243–​51. Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit, 1964. Byatt, A. S. Portraits in Fiction. London: Chatto and Windus, 2001. Calabrese, Omar. Artists’ Self-​Portraits. Translated by Marguerite Shore. London:  Abbeville Press Publishers, 2006. Caras, Tracy, and Cole Gagne. “Morton Feldman.” In Soundpieces:  Interviews with American Composers, 163–​77. Metuchen, NJ:  Scarecrow Press, 1982. Reprinted in Morton Feldman Says:  Selected Interviews and Lectures 1964–​1987, edited by Chris Villars, 87–​94. London: Hyphen, 2006. Chen, Tom, and Kyle Chayka. “Robert Wilson on Bringing Robert Downey Jr. and Boris the Porcupine to Times Square’s Jumbotrons.” Blouin ARTINFO. May 24, 2012. Video. www.blouinartinfo.com/​ n ews/​ story/​ 8 05671/​ v ideo-​ robert-​ w ilson-​ o n-​ b ringing-​ robert-​downey-​jr-​and-​boris-​the-​porcupine-​to-​times-​squares-​jumbotrons. Clark, Andy. Natural-​Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence. New York: Oxford University Press, 2003. Clark, Andy, and David Chalmers. “The Extended Mind.” Analysis 58.1 ( January 1998): 7–​19. Clark, T. J. “Gross David with the Swoln Cheek: An Essay on Self-​Portraiture.” In Rediscovering History: Culture, Politics, and the Psyche, edited by Michael S. Roth, 243–​307. Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994. Clendinning, Jane Piper. “The Pattern-​Meccanico Compositions of György Ligeti.” Perspectives of New Music 31.1 (Winter 1993): 192–​243. Cline, David. The Graph Music of Morton Feldman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2016. Colacello, Bob. “The Subject as Star.” Vanity Fair. November 6, 2006. Coleman, Patrick, ed. The Art of Music. San Diego: San Diego Museum of Art; New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2015. Coleman, Patrick. “Music, Said and Scene: Encounters in Metaphor, Theory and Performance.” In The Art of Music, edited by Patrick Coleman, 105–​27. San Diego: San Diego Museum of Art; New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2015. Cook, Nicholas. Beethoven: Symphony No. 9. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. Cooper, David. Bernard Herrmann’s Vertigo: A Film Score Handbook. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 2001. Cunningham, David. “Einstein on the Beach (1977).” In Writings on Glass:  Essays, Interviews, Criticism, edited by Richard Kostelanetz, 152–​66. New York: Schirmer, 1997. Dällenbach, Lucien. The Mirror in the Text. Translated by Jeremy Whiteley and Emma Hughes. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989. Daniel, Lucy. Gertrude Stein. London: Reaktion, 2009. Danuser, Hermann. “Self-​Representation in Music:  The Case of Hindemith’s Meta-​Opera Cardillac.” Translated by J. Bradford Robinson. In Representation in Western Music, edited by Joshua S. Walden, 224–​46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013.

  165

Bibliography  ( 165 )

DelDonna, Anthony, ed. Genre in Eighteenth-​Century Music. Ann Arbor, MI: Steglein, 2008. Deliège, Célestin. Pierre Boulez: Conversations with Célestin Deliège. London: Eulenberg, 1976. De Man, Paul. “Autobiography as De-​facement.” MLN 94.5 (December 1979): 919–​30. DeNora, Tia. Music in Everyday Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. Desmond, Michael. Present Tense:  An Imagined Grammar of Portraiture in the Digital Age. Canberra: National Portrait Gallery, 2010. Dilworth, Thomas, and Susan Holbrook, eds. The Letters of Gertrude Stein and Virgil Thomson: Composition as Conversation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010. Di Pietro, Rocco. Dialogues with Boulez. Lanham, MD: Scarecrow Press, 2001. Dolan, Therese. Manet, Wagner, and the Musical Culture of Their Time. Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 2013. Donahue, Thomas, ed. Essays in Honor of Christopher Hogwood: The Maestro’s Direction. Lanham, MD: Scarecrow, 2011. Dreyfus, Laurence. “Christopher Peacocke’s ‘The Perception of Music.’” British Journal of Aesthetics 49.3 ( July 2009): 293–​7. Duckworth, William. Talking Music: Conversations with John Cage, Philip Glass, Laurie Anderson, and Five Generations of American Experimental Composers. New York: Schirmer, 1995. Durand, Pascal. “‘Pli selon pli’: Les Modèles musicaux de Mallarmé.” In Pli selon pli de Pierre Boulez:  Entretiens et études, edited by Philippe Albèra, 83–​100. Geneva:  Éditions Contrechamps, 2003. Dyer, Richard. Heavenly Bodies: Film Stars and Society. 2nd edition. New York: Routledge, 2004, orig. 1986. Dylan, Bob. Highway 61 Revisited. Warner Bros. Inc, 1965. Renewed Special Rider Music, 1993. Eco, Umberto. The Open Work. Translated by Anna Cancogni. Cambridge, MA:  Harvard University Press, 1989. Eliot, George. Adam Bede. Edited by Carol A. Martin. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008; original 1859, revised 1861. Eliot, George. Daniel Deronda. 2 volumes. New York: Harper and Brothers, 1876. Eliot, George. Middlemarch: A Study of Provincial Life. New York: Harper and Brothers, 1873. Elliott, Anthony. Concepts of the Self. 2nd edition. Cambridge: Polity, 2008. Evans, Tristian. Shared Meanings in the Film Music of Philip Glass:  Music, Multimedia and Postminimalism. New York: Routledge, 2016. Feld, Steven. “‘Flow Like a Waterfall’: The Metaphors of Kaluli Musical Theory.” Yearbook for Traditional Music 13 (1981): 22–​47. Feldman, Morton. “Between Categories.” The Composer 1.2 (September 1969): 73–​7. Reprinted in Give My Regards to Eighth Street: Collected Writings of Morton Feldman, edited by B. H. Friedman, 83–​9. Cambridge, MA: Exact Change, 2000. Feldman, Morton. “Crippled Symmetry.” RES:  Anthropology and Aesthetics 2 (Autumn 1981): 91–​103. Feldman, Morton. “Give My Regards to Eighth Street.” Art in America 59.2 (March/​A pril 1971):  96–​9. Reprinted in Give My Regards to Eighth Street:  Collected Writings of Morton Feldman, edited by B. H. Friedman, 93–​101. Cambridge, MA:  Exact Change, 2000. Feldman, Morton. “A Life without Bach and Beethoven.” Listen 1 (May/​June 1964):  14. Reprinted in Give My Regards to Eighth Street:  Collected Writings of Morton Feldman, edited by B. H. Friedman, 15–​18. Cambridge, MA: Exact Change, 2000. Feldman, Morton. “Liner Notes.” Kulchur 2.6 (Summer 1962): 57–​60. Reprinted in Give My Regards to Eighth Street: Collected Writings of Morton Feldman, edited by B. H. Friedman, 3–​7. Cambridge, MA: Exact Change, 2000. Feldman, Morton. “Morton Feldman:  Interview by Fred Orton and Gavin Bryars.” Studio International 192.984 (November–​December 1976): 244–​8.

166

( 166 )  Bibliography

Feldman, Morton. “Rothko Chapel.” Liner notes to Morton Feldman: Rothko Chapel/​For Frank O’Hara. Columbia Records/​Odyssey Y34138. 1976. LP. Reprinted in Give My Regards to Eighth Street: Collected Writings of Morton Feldman, edited by B. H. Friedman, 125–​6. Cambridge, MA: Exact Change, 2000. Feldman, Morton. “Vertical Thoughts.” Kulchur 3.9 (Spring 1963): 88–​9. Reprinted in Vertical Thoughts: Morton Feldman and the Visual Arts, edited by Seán Kissane, 2–​3. Dublin: Irish Museum of Modern Art, 2010. Ferguson, Stephen. György Ligetis Drei Stücke für zwei Klaviere:  Eine Gesamtanalyse. Tutzing: Hans Schneider, 1994. Finch, Christopher. Chuck Close: Life. London: Prestel, 2010. Finch, Christopher. Chuck Close: Work. London: Prestel, 2007. Fischinger, Oskar. “The Composer of the Future and the Absolute Sound Film.” Translated by James Tobias. In Oskar Fischinger 1900–​1967: Experiments in Cinematic Abstraction, edited by Cindy Keefer and Jaap Guldemond, 96–​7. Amsterdam: EYE Filmmuseum; Los Angeles: Center for Visual Music, 2012. Fischinger, Oskar. “‘Der absolut Tonfilm’ von Ingenieur Oskar Fischinger.” Dortmunder Zeitung, January 1, 1933. Floros, Constantin. György Ligeti:  Jenseits von Avantgarde und Postmoderne. Vienna:  Verlag Lafite, 1996. Foster, Hal. “The Hamilton Test.” In Richard Hamilton, edited by Mark Godfrey, Paul Schimmel, and Vicente Todolí, 169–​78. London: Tate, 2014. Franchi, Stefano, and Güven Güzeldere. “Machinations of the Mind:  Cybernetics and Artificial Intelligence from Automata to Cyborgs.” In Mechanical Bodies, Computational Minds:  Artificial Intelligence from Automata to Cyborgs, edited by Stefano Franchi and Güven Güzeldere, 15–​149. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2005. Franchi, Stefano, and Güven Güzeldere, eds. Mechanical Bodies, Computational Minds: Artificial Intelligence from Automata to Cyborgs. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2005. Friedman, B. H., ed. Give My Regards to Eighth Street:  Collected Writings of Morton Feldman. Cambridge, MA: Exact Change, 2000. Friedman, Martin. Close Reading: Chuck Close and the Art of the Self-​Portrait. New York: Harry N. Abrams, 2005. Frith, Simon. Performing Rites:  On the Value of Popular Music. Cambridge, MA:  Harvard University Press, 1996. Fuller, David. “Of Portraits, ‘Sapho,’ and Couperin: Titles and Characters in French Instrumental Music of the High Baroque.” Music and Letters 78.2 (1997): 149–​74. Gallagher, Shaun, ed. The Oxford Handbook of the Self. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. Gena, Peter. “Socio-​ Political Portraits.” Accessed June 21, 2016. http://​petergena.com/ political.html. Gergen, Kenneth J. The Saturated Self: Dilemmas of Identity in Contemporary Life. New York: Basic Books, 1991. Gergen, Kenneth J. “The Social Construction of Self.” In The Oxford Handbook of the Self, edited by Shaun Gallagher, 633–​53. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. Gibson, Ann. “The Rhetoric of Abstract Expressionism.” In Abstract Expressionism: The Critical Developments, edited by Michael Auping, 64–​93. New York: Harry N. Abrams, 1987. Ginsburg, Michal Peled. Portrait Stories. New York: Fordham University Press, 2015. Giroud, Vincent. Picasso and Gertrude Stein. New  York:  Metropolitan Museum of Art; New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2006. Glass, Philip. “It’s a State of Attention.” In Robert Wilson from Within, edited by Margery Arent Safir, 99–​113. Paris: Arts Arena, 2011. Glass, Philip. Music by Philip Glass. Edited by Robert T. Jones. New York: Da Capo, 1987. Glass, Philip. Opera on the Beach. Edited by Robert T. Jones. London: Faber and Faber, 1988.

  167

Bibliography  ( 167 )

Glass, Philip. Words without Music. London: Liveright, 2015. Glock, William, ed. Pierre Boulez: A Symposium. London: Eulenberg, 1986. Godfrey, Mark, Paul Schimmel, and Vicente Todolí, eds. Richard Hamilton. London: Tate, 2014. Godøy, Rolf Inge. “Gestural Affordances of Musical Sound.” In Musical Gestures:  Sound, Movement, and Meaning, edited by Rolf Inge Godøy and Marc Leman, 103–​25. New York: Routledge, 2010. Godøy, Rolf Inge, and Marc Leman, eds. Musical Gestures:  Sound, Movement, and Meaning. New York: Routledge, 2010. Goehr, Lydia. “How to Do More with Words:  Two Views of (Musical) Ekphrasis.” British Journal of Aesthetics 50.4 (October 2010): 389–​410. Goffman, Erving. The Presentation of the Self in Everyday Life. Garden City, NY:  Doubleday Anchor, 1959. Goldman, Jonathan. The Musical Language of Pierre Boulez:  Writings and Compositions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011. Gombrich, E. H. Art and Illusion:  A  Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation. London: Phaidon, 1969. Gontarski, S. E. Beckett’s Happy Days: A Manuscript Study. Columbus: Ohio State University Libraries, 1977. Goodrich, Barbara G. “Tempos of Eternity:  Music, Volition, and Playing with Time.” In Art, Aesthetics, and the Brain, edited by Joseph P. Huston, Marcos Nadal, Francisco Mora, Luigi F. Agnati, and Camilo José Cela Conde, 500–​18. New York: Oxford University Press, 2015. Gottschalk, Jennie. Experimental Music since 1970. London: Bloomsbury, 2016. Graham-​Dixon, Andrew, Foreword to 21st-​Century Portraits, edited by Andrew Graham-​ Dixon, Sandy Nairne, Sarah Howgate, and Jo Higgins, 7–​9. London: National Portrait Gallery, 2013. Graham-​Dixon, Andrew, Sandy Nairne, Sarah Howgate, and Jo Higgins, eds. 21st-​Century Portraits. London: National Portrait Gallery, 2013. Gritten, Anthony, and Elaine King, eds. New Perspectives on Music and Gesture. Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 2011. Gronert, Stefan, and Christina Végh, eds. John Baldessari: Music. Cologne: Walther König, 2007. Guldbrandsen, Erling E. “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (II) Serialism Revisited.” Tempo 65.256 (April 2011): 18–​24. Guldbrandsen, Erling E. “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (III) Mallarmé, Musical Form and Articulation.” Tempo 65.257 ( July 2011): 11–​21. Guldbrandsen, Erling E. “Pierre Boulez in Interview, 1996 (IV) Some Broader Topics.” Tempo 65.258 (October 2011): 37–​43. Gumbrecht, Hans Ulrich. Production of Presence: What Meaning Cannot Convey. Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press, 2004. Gustafson, Donna, and Susan Sidlauskas. “One. 2. Many: Portraits by Numbers.” In Striking Resemblance:  The Changing Art of Portraiture, edited by Donna Gustafson and Susan Sidlauskas, 13–​41. New Brunswick, NJ: Zimmerli Art Museum at Rutgers University; London: Prestel, 2014. Gustafson, Donna, and Susan Sidlauskas, eds. Striking Resemblance:  The Changing Art of Portraiture. New Brunswick, NJ:  Zimmerli Art Museum at Rutgers University; London: Prestel, 2014. Hall, James. The Self-​Portrait: A Cultural History. London: Thames and Hudson, 2014. Hamilton, Richard. “Talk at the Palais des Beaux-​Arts, Brussels, 1971.” In Richard Hamilton, edited by Mark Godfrey, Paul Schimmel, and Vicente Todolí, 201–​7. London: Tate, 2014. Haraway, Donna J. “A Cyborg Manifesto: Science, Technology, and Socialist-​Feminism in the Late Twentieth Century.” In Donna J. Harraway, Simians, Cyborgs, and Women:  The Reinvention of Nature, 149–​81. New York: Routledge, 1991.

168

( 168 )  Bibliography

Haraway, Donna J. Simians, Cyborgs, and Women:  The Reinvention of Nature. New York: Routledge, 1991. Harbisson, Neil. Accessed June 21, 2016. www.harbisson.com. Harbisson, Neil. “Sound Portraits.” YouTube. May 7, 2010. Video. https://​www.youtube.com/​ watch?v=JDqL-​PUZ148. Harbisson, Neil. “What’s It Like to Hear Color?” TED Radio Hour. March 7, 2014. Video. www. npr.org/​2014/​03/​07/​283441986/​what-​s-​it-​like-​to-​hear-​color. Hardcastle, Valerie Gray. Constructing the Self. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2008. Harris, Paul Ivan. “Neil Harbisson: The Man Who Hears Colour.” BBC News. November 11, 2014. Video. www.bbc.com/​news/​technology-​29992577. Haselstein, Ulla. “Gertrude Stein’s Portraits of Matisse and Picasso.” New Literary History 34.4 (Autumn 2003): 723–​43. Haskins, Rob. “Philip Glass and Michael Riesman:  Two Interviews.” Musical Quarterly 86.3 (Autumn 2002): 508–​29. Hayles, Katherine. How We Became Posthuman:  Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature, and Informatics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999. Hayles, Katherine. “Visualizing the Posthuman.” Art Journal 59.3 (Fall 2000): 50–​4. Hazlitt, William. “On the Imitation of Nature (1814).” In The Collected Works of William Hazlitt, edited by A. R. Waller and Arnold Glover, 12 volumes, xi: 216–​23. London: J. M. Dent, 1904. Heier, Edmund. “‘The Literary Portrait’ as a Device of Characterization.” Neophilologus 60.3 ( July 1976): 321–​33. Heymer, Kay. “Mirror Images.” In Hockney’s Portraits and People, edited by Marco Livingstone and Kay Heymer, 15–​41. London: Thames and Hudson, 2003. Hicks, Michael. “Interval and Form in Ligeti’s Continuum and Coulée.” Perspectives of New Music 31.1 (Winter 1993): 172–​90. Hicks, Scott, director. Glass: A Portrait of Philip in Twelve Parts. Port Washington, NY: Koch Lorber Films, 2009, orig. 2007. Hogarth, William. The Analysis of Beauty. Written With a View of Fixing the Fluctuating Ideas of Taste. London: J. Reeves, 1753. Holmberg, Arthur. The Theatre of Robert Wilson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. Hossaini, Ali. “New-​ Definition Television:  Robert Wilson’s Video Portraits.” In Robert Wilson:  Video Portraits, edited by Peter Weibel, Harald Falckenberg, and Matthew Shattuck, 174–​85. Cologne: Walther König, 2011. Howgate, Sarah, and Sandy Nairne. Introduction to 21st-​Century Portraits, Andrew Graham-​ Dixon, Sandy Nairne, Sarah Howgate, and Jo Higgins, 11–​19. London: National Portrait Gallery, 2013. Howgate, Sarah, and Barbara Stern Shapiro, eds. David Hockney Portraits. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press; London: National Portrait Gallery, 2006. Huppert, Isabelle. “The Time between Fixity and Motion.” Translated by Alexandra Schwartz. In Robert Wilson from Within, edited by Margery Arent Safir, 75–​87. Paris: Arts Arena, 2011. Huston, Joseph P., Marcos Nadal, Francisco Mora, Luigi F. Agnati, and Camilo José Cela Conde, eds. Art, Aesthetics, and the Brain. New York: Oxford University Press, 2015. Hylton, Wil S. “The Mysterious Metamorphosis of Chuck Close.” New York Times Magazine. July 13, 2016. Inglis, Fred. A Short History of Celebrity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2010. Innes, Christopher, and Maria Shevtsova. The Cambridge Introduction to Theatre Directing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013. Jacobs, Jay S. Wild Years: The Music and Myth of Tom Waits. Toronto: ECW Press, 2000. Jeffries, Stuart. “Neil Harbisson: The World’s First Cyborg Artist.” The Guardian. May 6, 2014. www. theguardian.com/​artanddesign/​2014/​may/​06/​neil-​harbisson-​worlds-​first-​cyborg-​artist.

  169

Bibliography  ( 169 )

Johnson, Steven, ed. The New York Schools of Music and Visual Arts. New York: Routledge, 2002. Johnson, Steven. “Rothko Chapel and Rothko’s Chapel.” Perspectives of New Music 32.2 (Summer 1994): 6–​53. Jordan, Roland. “Fold Upon Fold:  Boulez (and Mallarmé).” Yearbook of Comparative and General Literature 36 (1987): 88–​97. Jordanova, Ludmilla. Defining Features:  Scientific and Medical Portraits 1660–​ 2000. London: Reaktion Books and National Portrait Gallery, 2000. Jordanova, Ludmilla. “Visualizing Identity.” In Identity, edited by Giselle Walker and Elisabeth Leedham-​Green, 127–​56. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010. Kalb, Jonathan. “Robert Wilson, Beckett and a Celebrity from the Neck Up.” New York Times. January 30, 2007. Kazanjian, Dodie. “Metropolitan Opera: Close Encounter.” Playbill Arts. March 14, 2008. www. playbillarts.com/​features/​article/​7587.html. Keefer, Cindy, and Jaap Guldemond, eds. Oskar Fischinger 1900–​1967: Experiments in Cinematic Abstraction. Amsterdam: EYE Filmmuseum; Los Angeles: Center for Visual Music, 2012. Kemp, Sandra. Future Face: Image, Identity, Innovation. London: Profile, 2004. Ketner II, Joseph D. “Image Machine: Andy Warhol & Photography.” In Image Machine: Andy Warhol & Photography, edited by Joseph D. Ketner, II, 41–​63. Cincinnati:  Contemporary Arts Center; Nürnberg: Verlag für Moderne Kunst; New York: Andy Warhol Foundation, 2012. Ketner II, Joseph D. Image Machine: Andy Warhol & Photography. Cincinnati: Contemporary Arts Center; Nürnberg:  Verlag für Moderne Kunst; New  York:  Andy Warhol Foundation, 2012. Khoshbin, Noah, and Matthew Shattuck. “Overview.” Dissident Industries Inc. Accessed June 21, 2016. www.dissidentusa.com/​robert-​wilson/​overview/​. Kissane, Seán, ed. Vertical Thoughts: Morton Feldman and the Visual Arts. Dublin: Irish Museum of Modern Art, 2010. Klee, Paul. Paul Klee. New York: Parkstone, 2012. Koerner, Joseph Leo. “Self-​Portraiture Direct and Oblique.” In Self-​Portrait:  Renaissance to Contemporary, edited by Anthony Bond and Joanna Woodall, 67–​81. London: National Portrait Gallery, 2005. Kostelanetz, Richard, ed. Virgil Thomson: A Reader: Selected Writings 1924–​1984. New York: Routledge, 2002. Kostelanetz, Richard, ed. Writings on Glass:  Essays, Interviews, Criticism. New  York: Schirmer, 1997. Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago:  University of Chicago Press, 1980. Le Brun, Charles. The Conference of Monsieur Le Brun, cheif [sic] painter of the French King, . . . upon Expression, General and Particular. Translated by J. Smith. London, 1701. Lee, Hermione. Biography: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009. Leggio, James, ed. Music and Modern Art. New York: Routledge, 2002. Leman, Marc, and Pieter-​Jan Maes. “The Role of Embodiment in the Perception of Music.” Empirical Musicology Review 9.3–​4 (2014): 236–​46. Leppert, Richard. Art and the Committed Eye:  The Cultural Functions of Imagery. Boulder, CO: Westview, 1996. Leppert, Richard. Music and Image:  Domesticity, Ideology and Socio-​Cultural Formation in Eighteenth-​Century England. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988. Leppert, Richard. The Sight of Sound:  Music, Representation, and the History of the Body. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993. Levingston, Bruce. “Portraits.” Accessed June 21, 2016. www.premierecommission.org/ recordings/​portraits.html. Levingston, Bruce. Portraits. Orange Mountain Music, 0025, 2006. Compact disc.

170

( 170 )  Bibliography

Levy, Silvano, ed. Surrealism: Surrealist Visuality. Edinburgh: Keele University Press, 1996. Ligeti, György. “Performance Instructions.” In Monument-​Selbstportrait-​Bewegung. Mainz: B. Schott’s Söhne, 1976. Ligeti, György, Péter Várnai, Josef Häusler, and Claude Samuel. György Ligeti in Conversation. London: Eulenberg, 1983. Livingstone, Marco. David Hockney. London: Thames and Hudson, 1981. Livingstone, Marco, and Kay Heymer, eds. Hockney’s Portraits and People. London: Thames and Hudson, 2003. Locher, Paul J. “Empirical Investigation of an Aesthetic Experience with Art.” In Aesthetic Science: Connecting Minds, Brains, and Experience, edited by Arthur P. Shimamura and Stephen E. Palmer, 163–​88. New York: Oxford University Press, 2012. Madary, Michael. “Visual Experience.” In The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition, edited by Lawrence Shapiro, 263–​71. New York: Routledge, 2014. Makkai, Katalin, ed. Vertigo. New York: Routledge, 2013. Malanga, Gerard, and Andy Warhol. Screen Tests/​A Diary. New York: Kulchur Press, 1967. Mallarmé, Stéphane. Correspondance. Edited by Lloyd James Austin and Henri Mondor. Vol. 1. 11 volumes. Paris: Gallimard, 1959. Massi, R. Wood. “Captain Cook’s First Voyage: An Interview with Morton Feldman (on 3.3. 1987).” Cum Notis Variorum 131 (April 1989):  7–​12. Reprinted in Morton Feldman Says:  Selected Interviews and Lectures 1964–​1987, edited by Chris Villars, 217–​27. London: Hyphen Press, 2006. Matheson, William. “Fold Upon Fold:  Stéphane Mallarmé and Pierre Boulez.” Yearbook of Comparative and General Literature 36 (1987): 75–​9. Matheson, William. “Pli selon pli: Mallarmé (and Boulez).” Yearbook of Comparative and General Literature 36 (1987): 84–​7. Maur, Karin v. The Sound of Painting. London: Prestel, 1999. McCalla, James. “Sea-​Changes: Boulez’s Improvisations sur Mallarmé.” Journal of Musicology 6.1 (Winter 1988): 83–​106. McGrath, Charles. “A Portraitist Whose Canvas is a Piano.” New York Times. April 22, 2005. www.nytimes.com/​2005/​04/​22/​arts/​music/​22glas.html?pagewanted=1&_​r=1. Meltzer, Françoise. Salome and the Dance of Writing:  Portraits of Mimesis in Literature. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987. Mertens, Wim. American Minimal Music: La Monte Young, Terry Riley, Steve Reich, Philip Glass. Translated by J. Hautekiet. London:  Kahn and Averill; White Plains, NY:  Pro/​Am Music Resources, 1983. Miller, Debra. “Screen Tests:  A  History.” In Gerard Malanga:  Screen Tests, Portraits, Nudes 1964–​1996, edited by Patrick Remy and Marc Parent, 24–​37. Göttingen: Steidl, 2000. Minors, Helen Julia, ed. Music, Text and Translation. London: Bloomsbury, 2013. Montagu, Jennifer. The Expression of the Passions: The Origin and Influence of Charles Le Brun’s Conférence sur l’expression générale et particulière. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1994. Moorhouse, Paul. Pop Art Portraits. London: National Portrait Gallery, 2007. Mörchen, Raoul, ed. Morton Feldman in Middelburg: Words on Music: Lectures and Conversations. 2 volumes. Cologne: Edition MusikTexte, 2008. Murphy, J. J. The Black Hole of the Camera: The Films of Andy Warhol. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2012. Nancy, Jean-​Luc. “The Look of the Portrait.” In Multiple Arts: The Muses II, edited by Simon Sparks, 220–​48. Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press, 2006. National Gallery of Art. “Bodies: Real and Ideal.” Washington, DC. Accessed June 21, 2016. www.nga.gov/​content/​ngaweb/​features/​introduction-​to-​greek-​bronzes/​bodies-​real-​ and-​ideal.html.

  17

Bibliography  ( 171 )

Neumeyer, David, and Nathan Platte. Franz Waxman’s Rebecca: A Film Score Guide. Lanham, MD: Scarecrow, 2012. Obenhaus, Mark, director. Einstein on the Beach:  The Changing Image of Opera. Brooklyn Academy of Music. Video. Los Angeles: Direct Cinema, 1987. O’Doherty, Brian. American Masters:  The Voice and the Myth. London:  Thames and Hudson, 1988. O’Doherty, Brian. “Feldman Throws a Switch Between Sight and Sound.” New York Times. June 21, 1964. O’Doherty, Brian. “Morton Feldman:  The Burgacue Years.” In Vertical Thoughts:  Morton Feldman and the Visual Arts, edited by Seán Kissane, 62–​74. Dublin: Irish Museum of Modern Art, 2010. O’Hara, Frank. “New Directions in Music.” In Vertical Thoughts: Morton Feldman and the Visual Arts, edited by Seán Kissane, 86–​9. Dublin: Irish Museum of Modern Art, 2010. Otto-​ Bernstein, Katharina, director. Absolute Wilson. HBO Documentary Films. DVD. New York: New Yorker Video, 2007. Otto-​Bernstein, Katharina. Absolute Wilson: The Biography. London: Prestel, 2006. Page, Tim. “Music in 12 Parts (1993).” In Writings on Glass: Essays, Interviews, Criticism, edited by Richard Kostelanetz, 98–​101. New York: Schirmer, 1997. Pappas, Nickolas. “Magic and Art in Vertigo.” In Vertigo, edited by Katalin Makkai, 18–​44. New York: Routledge, 2013. Perry, Jeffrey. “Cage’s Sonatas and Interludes for Prepared Piano:  Performance, Hearing and Analysis.” Music Theory Spectrum 27.1 (Spring 2005): 35–​66. Poe, Edgar Allan. The Short Fiction of Edgar Allan Poe: An Annotated Edition. Edited by Stuart Levine and Susan Levine. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1976. Potter, Keith. Four Musical Minimalists: La Monte Young, Terry Riley, Steve Reich, Philip Glass. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. Puri, Michael J. “Dandy, Interrupted: Sublimation, Repression, and Self-​Portraiture in Maurice Ravel’s Daphnis et Chloé (1909–​1912).” Journal of the American Musicological Society 60.2 (Summer 2007): 317–​72. Quintilian, Institutes of Oratory, Book 9, Chapter 2. Accessed June 21, 2016. http://​rhetoric. eserver.org/​quintilian/​9/​chapter2.html. Reaves, Wendy Wick. “Reflections/​Refractions: Self-​Portraiture in the Twentieth Century.” In Reflections/​Refractions: Self-​Portraiture in the Twentieth Century, edited by Wendy Wick Reaves, 1–​11. Washington, DC:  Smithsonian Institution Scholarly Press; Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2009. Reaves, Wendy Wick. Reflections/​ Refractions:  Self-​ Portraiture in the Twentieth Century. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Scholarly Press; Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2009. Remy, Patrick, and Marc Parent. Gerard Malanga:  Screen Tests, Portraits, Nudes 1964–​1996. Göttingen: Steidl, 2000. Retallack, Joan, ed. Gertrude Stein. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008. Richards, Annette. “Picturing the Moment in Sound: C. P. E. Bach and the Musical Portrait.” In Essays in Honor of Christopher Hogwood: The Maestro’s Direction, edited by Thomas Donahue, 57–​89. Lanham, MD: Scarecrow, 2011. Roberts, Paul. Claude Debussy. London: Phaidon, 2008. Roden, David. Posthuman Life: Philosophy at the Edge of the Human. New York: Routledge, 2015. Rojek, Chris. Celebrity. London: Reaktion, 2001. Rosen, Charles. Freedom and the Arts: Essays on Music and Literature. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2012. Rosenberg, Raphael, and Christoph Klein. “The Moving Eye of the Beholder: Eye Tracking and the Perception of Paintings.” In Art, Aesthetics, and the Brain, edited by Joseph P. Huston,

172

( 172 )  Bibliography

Marcos Nadal, Francisco Mora, Luigi F. Agnati, and Camilo José Cela Conde, 79–​108. New York: Oxford University Press, 2015. Ross, Alex. “Encrypted.” New Yorker, April 11, 2016. Roth, Michael S., ed. Rediscovering History:  Culture, Politics, and the Psyche. Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press, 1994. Roth, Philip. My Life as a Man. In Philip Roth, Novels 1973–​1977, 379–​678. New York: Library of America, 2006, orig. 1974. Ruf, Frederik J. Entangled Voices: Genre and the Religious Construction of the Self. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997. Russell, Helene Tallon, and Marjorie Hewitt Suchocki. “The Multiple Self.” In In Search of Self: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Personhood, edited by J. Wentzel van Huyssteen and Erik P. Wiebe, 182–​97. Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2011. Sabbe, Herman. “György Ligeti—​Illusions et Allusions.” Interface 8.1 (1979): 11–​34. Safir, Margery Arent, ed. Robert Wilson from Within. Paris: Arts Arena, 2011. Sanio, Sabine, and Christian Scheib, eds. Übertragung—​Transfer—​Metapher: Kulturtechniken, ihre Visionen und Obsessionen. Bielefeld: Kerber, 2004. Sarup, Madam. Identity, Culture and the Postmodern World. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1996. Schapiro, Meyer. Modern Art: 19th and 20th Centuries. New York: George Braziller, 1979. Schechtman, Marya. The Constitution of Selves. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996. Schechtman, Marya. “The Narrative Self.” In The Oxford Handbook of the Self, edited by Shaun Gallagher, 394–​416. New York: Oxford University Press, 2011. Scher, Stephen K., ed. The Currency of Fame: Portrait Medals of the Renaissance. New York: Harry N. Abrams, 1994. Schiff, Richard. Between Sense and de Kooning. London: Reaktion Books, 2011. Schrag, Calvin O. The Self after Postmodernity. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1997. Segall, Christopher. “Klingende Buchstaben:  Principles of Alfred Schnittke’s Monogram Technique.” Journal of Musicology 30.2 (Spring 2013): 252–​86. Seigel, Jerrold. The Idea of the Self: Thought and Experience in Western Europe Since the Seventeenth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005. Shakespeare, William. Hamlet. In The Norton Shakespeare, edited by Stephen Greenblatt, 1659–​1759. New York: Norton, 1997. Shapiro, Barbara Stern. “Hockney Works on Paper.” In David Hockney Portraits, edited by Sarah Howgate and Barbara Stern Shapiro, 62–​73. New Haven, CT:  Yale University Press; London: National Portrait Gallery, 2006. Shapiro, Lawrence, ed. The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition. New  York: Routledge, 2014. Shattuck, Matthew. “Interview with Noah Khoshbin.” In Robert Wilson:  Video Portraits, edited by Peter Weibel, Harald Falckenberg, and Matthew Shattuck, 186–​ 201. Cologne: Walther König, 2011. Shaw, George Bernard. Man and Superman: A Comedy and a Philosophy. Auckland: The Floating Press, 2012. Shaw-​Miller, Simon. “The Art of Music:  A  Complex Art.” In The Art of Music, edited by Patrick Coleman, 33–​59. San Diego: San Diego Museum of Art; New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2015. Shaw-​Miller, Simon. Eye hEar: The Visual in Music. Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 2013. Shaw-​Miller, Simon. Visible Deeds of Music: Art and Music from Wagner to Cage. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2002. Shephard, Tim, and Anne Leonard, eds. The Routledge Companion to Music and Visual Culture. New York: Routledge, 2014. Shevtsova, Maria. Robert Wilson. New York: Routledge, 2007.

  173

Bibliography  ( 173 )

Shimamura, Arthur P., and Stephen E. Palmer, eds. Aesthetic Science: Connecting Minds, Brains, and Experience. New York: Oxford University Press, 2012. Shuttleworth, Mark. “Difficulty in Translation: Grappling with Ligeti’s Musical Metaphors.” In Music, Text and Translation, Helen Julia Minors, 175–​86. London: Bloomsbury, 2013. Shyer, Laurence. Robert Wilson and His Collaborators. New  York:  Theatre Communications Group, 1989. Siegel, Lee. “On the Face of It.” In Striking Resemblance: The Changing Art of Portraiture, edited by Donna Gustafson and Susan Sidlauskas, 43–​83. New Brunswick, NJ: Zimmerli Art Museum at Rutgers University; London: Prestel, 2014. Silverman, Stephen M. “Winona Ryder Finally Speaks Out About Her Arrest.” People. July 17, 2007. Simon, Linda, ed. Gertrude Stein: A Composite Portrait. New York: Discus Books, 1974. Smith, Olav Bryant. Myths of the Self: Narrative Identity and Postmodern Metaphysics. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2004. Sontag, Susan. “Certain Mapplethorpes.” In Where the Stress Falls: Essays, Susan Sontag, 233–​7. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2001. Stanyek, Jason, and Benjamin Piekut. “Deadness: Technologies of the Intermundane.” TDR/​ The Drama Review 54.1 (Spring 2010): 14–​38. Stearns, Robert. “Robert Wilson: From a Theater of Images.” In Robert Wilson: The Theater of Images, edited by Contemporary Arts Center (Cincinnati, Ohio) and Byrd Hoffman Foundation, 32–​53. New York: Harper, 1984. Stein, Gertrude. “If I Told Him: A Completed Portrait of Picasso.” In Gertrude Stein, edited by Joan Retallack, 190–​3. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2008. Stein, Gertrude. “Portraits and Repetition.” In Gertrude Stein, Lectures in America, 165–​206. London: Virago, 1985, orig. 1935. Steiner, Wendy. Exact Resemblance to Exact Resemblance: The Literary Portraiture of Gertrude Stein. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1978. Steiner, Wendy. “Postmodern Portraits.” Art Journal 46.3 (Autumn 1987): 173–​7. Steinitz, Richard. György Ligeti: Music of the Imagination. London: Faber and Faber, 2003. Stoïanowa, Iwanka. “Pli selon Pli. Portrait de Mallarmé.” Musique en jeu 11 ( June 1973): 75–​98. Stone-​Mediatore, Shari. “Postmodernism, Realism, and the Problem of Identity.” Diaspora 11.1 (2002): 125–​38. Storr, Robert, ed. Chuck Close. New York: Museum of Modern Art, 1998. Storr, Robert. “Chuck Close:  Angles of Refraction.” In Chuck Close, edited by Robert Storr, 21–​59. New York: Museum of Modern Art, 1998. Sullivan, Jack. Hitchcock’s Music. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2008. Sulzer, Johann Georg. “General Theory of the Fine Arts.” In Aesthetics and the Art of Musical Composition in the German Enlightenment: Selected Writings of Johann Georg Sulzer and Heinrich Christoph Koch, edited by Nancy Kovaleff Baker and Thomas Christensen, translated by Nancy Kovaleff Baker, 3–​108. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995. Suthor, Nicola. “Role Models.” In Robert Wilson: Video Portraits, edited by Peter Weibel, Harald Falckenberg, and Matthew Shattuck, 160–​73. Cologne: Walther König, 2011. Syson, Luke, and Dora Thornton. Objects of Virtue: Art in Renaissance Italy. Los Angeles: J. Paul Getty Museum, 2001. Tassi, Marguerite A. The Scandal of Images: Iconoclasm, Eroticism, and Painting in Early Modern English Drama. Selinsgrove, PA: Susquehanna University Press, 2005. Thomson, Virgil. Preface to Anthony Tommasini, Virgil Thomson’s Musical Portraits, ix–​x. Hillsdale, NY: Pendragon Press, 1986. Thomson, Virgil. “Of Portraits and Operas.” Antaeus 21/​22 (Spring/​Summer 1976): 208–​10. Thomson, Virgil. Virgil Thomson. New York: Knopf, 1966.

174

( 174 )  Bibliography

Thweatt-​Bates, Jennifer. “Posthuman Selves: Bodies, Cognitive Processes, and Technologies.” In In Search of Self: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Personhood, edited by J. Wentzel van Huyssteen and Erik P. Wiebe, 243–​55. Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2011. Toffoletti, Kim. Cyborgs and Barbie Dolls: Feminism, Popular Culture and the Posthuman Body. London: I. B. Tauris, 2007. Tommasini, Anthony. “The Musical Portraits by Virgil Thomson.” Musical Quarterly 70.2 (Spring 1984): 234–​47. Tommasini, Anthony. Virgil Thomson’s Musical Portraits. Hillsdale, NY: Pendragon Press, 1986. Turner, Graeme. Understanding Celebrity. 2nd edition. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 2014. van Huyssteen, J. Wentzel, and Erik P. Wiebe, eds. In Search of Self: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Personhood. Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2011. Vergo, Peter. That Divine Order:  Music and the Visual Arts from Antiquity to the Eighteenth Century. London: Phaidon, 2005. Vergo, Peter. The Music of Painting: Music, Modernism, and the Visual Arts from the Romantics to John Cage. London: Phaidon, 2010. Villars, Chris, ed. Morton Feldman Says:  Selected Interviews and Lectures 1964–​ 1987. London: Hyphen Press, 2006. Vitz, Paul C. “Introduction:  From the Modern and Postmodern Selves to the Transmodern Self.” In The Self: Beyond the Postmodern Crisis, edited by Paul C. Vitz and Susan M. Felch, xi–​xii. Wilmington, DE: ISI Books, 2006. “Voom Portraits by Robert Wilson Opens Next Week in Valladolid.” March 29, 2009. http://​ artdaily.com/​news/​29769/​Voom-​Portraits-​by-​Robert-​Wilson-​Opens-​Next-​Week-​in-​ Valladolid#.VzTuUWNWLiM. Walden, Joshua S. “Composing Character in Musical Portraits: Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach and L’Aly Rupalich.” Musical Quarterly 91.2 (Fall–​Winter 2008): 379–​411. Walden, Joshua S. “Lip-​Sync in Lipstick: 1950s Popular Songs in a Television Series by Dennis Potter.” Journal of Musicological Research 27.2 (April 2008): 169–​95. Walden, Joshua S. “Representation and Musical Portraiture in the Twentieth Century.” In Representation in Western Music, edited by Joshua S. Walden, 127–​ 43. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013. Walden, Joshua S. Representation in Western Music. Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press, 2013. Walden, Joshua S. Sounding Authentic:  The Rural Miniature and Musical Modernism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014. Walden, Joshua S. “What’s in a Name?: C. P. E. Bach and the Genres of the Character Piece and Musical Portrait.” In Genre in Eighteenth-​Century Music, edited by Anthony DelDonna, 111–​38. Ann Arbor, MI: Steglein, 2008. Walker, Giselle, and Elisabeth Leedham-​Green, eds. Identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010. Wallen, Jeffrey. “Between Text and Image: The Literary Portrait.” a/​b: Auto/​Biography Studies 10.1 (1995): 50–​65. Warner, Malcolm. “Portraits about Portraiture.” In The Mirror & the Mask:  Portraiture in the Age of Picasso, edited by Paloma Alarcó and Malcolm Warner, 11–​23. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press; Fort Worth: Kimbell Art Museum; Madrid: Museo Thyssen-​ Bornemisza and Fundación Caja Madrid, 2007. Wayne, Eric. “Mallarmé’s Folds:  Mallarmé, Boulez, Pli selon pli.” Nineteenth-​Century French Studies 9.3/​4 (Spring–​Summer 1981): 220–​32. Weibel, Peter. “Robert Wilson’s Video Portraits.” In Robert Wilson: Video Portraits, edited by Peter Weibel, Harald Falckenberg, and Matthew Shattuck, 118–​58. Cologne: Walther König, 2011.

  175

Bibliography  ( 175 )

Weibel, Peter, Harald Falckenberg, and Matthew Shattuck, eds. Robert Wilson: Video Portraits. Cologne: Walther König, 2011. West, Shearer. Portraiture. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. White, Chelsea. “Why My Shoplifting Arrest Was the Best Thing that Could Have Happened to Me.” Daily Mail, May 17, 2013. Wilde, Oscar. The Picture of Dorian Gray. Leipzig: Bernhard Tauchnitz, 1908. Williams, Bernard. Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers 1956–​1972. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973. Wilson, Robert. “From Within.” In Robert Wilson from Within, edited by Margery Arent Safir, 304–​20. Paris: Arts Arena, 2011. Wilson, Robert. “Interview about Lady Gaga and Her Portraits.” YouTube. Video. www.youtube. com/​watch?v=an3OAM_​fAHA. April 4, 2015. Wilson, Robert. “A Still Life is a Real Life.” In Robert Wilson:  Video Portraits, edited by Peter Weibel, Harald Falckenberg, and Matthew Shattuck, 8–​9. Cologne:  Walther König, 2011. Wilson, Robert, and Umberto Eco. “Robert Wilson and Umberto Eco:  A  Conversation.” Performing Arts Journal 15.1 ( January 1993): 87–​96. Wilson, Robert, and Michael Galasso. “Winona Ryder.” Dissident Industries Inc. 2004. Video. www.dissidentusa.com/​robert-​wilson/​subjects/​winona-​r yder/​. Wilson, Robert, and Bernard Herrmann. “Princess Caroline.” Dissident Industries Inc. 2006. Video. www.dissidentusa.com/​robert-​wilson/​subjects/​princess-​caroline/​. Wilson, Robert, and Tom Waits. “Robert Downey Jr.” Dissident Industries Inc. 2004. Video. www.dissidentusa.com/​robert-​wilson/​subjects/​robert-​downey-​jr/​. Windsor, W. Luke. “Gestures in Music-​Making: Action, Information and Perception.” In New Perspectives on Music and Gesture, edited by Anthony Gritten and Elaine King, 45–​66. Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 2011. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G. E.  M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1958. Wolfe, Bernard. Limbo. London: Gollancz, 2016, orig. 1952. Wollny, Peter, ed. Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach:  Miscellaneous Keyboard Works II. Los Altos, CA: Packard Humanities Institute, 2005. Woodall, Joanna. “‘Every Painter Paints Himself ’:  Self-​Portraiture and Creativity.” In Self-​ Portrait:  Renaissance to Contemporary, edited by Anthony Bond and Joanna Woodall, 17–​29. London: National Portrait Gallery, 2005. Woods-​Marsden, Joanna. Renaissance Self-​Portraiture: The Visual Construction of Identity and the Social Status of the Artist. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998. Worth, Katharine. Waiting for Godot and Happy Days:  Text and Performance. Houndmills: Macmillan, 1990. York, Wes. “Form and Process (1981).” In Writings on Glass: Essays, Interviews, Criticism, edited by Richard Kostelanetz, 60–​79. New York: Schirmer, 1997. Young, Paul. Art Cinema. Edited by Paul Duncan. Cologne: Taschen, 2009. Zbikowski, Lawrence M. Conceptualizing Music:  Cognitive Structure, Theory, and Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002. Zbikowski, Lawrence M. “Musical Gesture and Musical Grammar: A Cognitive Approach.” In New Perspectives on Music and Gesture, edited by Anthony Gritten and Elaine King, 83–​ 98. Farnham, UK: Ashgate, 2011.

176

  17

I N DE X

Ablinger, Peter, 16, 85, 87, 90, 96–​104, 156 “Grisailles,” 98 Hören hören, 98 IEAOV, 98 “Metaphern,” 98 Quadraturen, 101 “Quadraturen IV: ‘Selbstportrait mit Berlin,’ ” 16, 85, 87, 96–​104, 156 Seeing and Hearing, 98 “Selbstportrait mit Mittersill,” 107n50 “Stadtportrait Graz,” 101 Voices and Piano, 99, 100 Weiss/​Weisslich, 98 abstract expressionism, 59–​60, 62, 68, 78n18 abstraction, 6–​9, 13–​17, 24, 27, 29–​30, 32, 43, 45, 47, 58–​60, 62–​3, 68, 72, 76, 78n38, 91, 100, 124, 126, 128–​30, 135–​6, 138n22, 141n96, 153, 155, 157 Adams, John, 24, 87–​9, 110–​11 My Father Knew Charles Ives, 24, 87–​9 Nixon in China, 110–​11 “Short Ride in a Fast Machine,” 88 additive process, 128, 130 Aeolian harp, 42 Akiba ben Joseph, 78n17 Alberti bass, 74 Alberti, Leon Battista, 4, 144, 147 On Painting, 4 Alexander the Great, 4 Allen, Woody, 151 Anderson, Judith, 158n11 Anguissola, Sofonisba, 106 “Self-​Portrait with Bernardino Campi,” 106 Aragon, Louis, 112 architecture, 45, 55 Aristotle, 23, 110 Assetto, Franco, 32

Atget, Eugène, 83–​4, 100 “Coiffure, Palais Royale,” 83, 100 Augenmusik, 65–​6 autobiography, 25–​6, 30, 38, 87 Avedon, Richard, 86 “Self-​Portrait,” 86 Bach, Carl Philipp Emanuel, 3, 24, 55, 86, 153 “L’Aly Rupalich” (“La Bach”), 86 Bach, Johann Sebastian, 83, 114 The Art of Fugue, 83 Bacon, Francis, 6, 47, 88 “Self-​Portrait,” 88 Baker, Josephine, 49n15 Baldessari, John, 96–​7 “Beethoven’s Trumpet (With Ear) Opus # 133,” 96–​7 Balzac, Honoré de, 92 Le Chef-​d’oeuvre inconnu, 92 Barthes, Roland, 11–​12, 39, 113–​14, 124 “The Death of the Author,” 39 “The Face of Garbo,” 113–​14 Bartók, Béla, 36 Bechtle, Robert, 101 Beckett, Samuel, 58, 119–​23, 127, 139n36, 139n51, 140n62 Happy Days, 119–​23, 139n36, 139n51 Play, 127, 140n62 Three Dialogues, 122 Beethoven, Ludwig van, 74, 84–​6, 97 deafness, 96–​7 “Moonlight” Sonata, 74 String Quartet Op. 133, 96–​7 Symphony No. 9, 85–​6 Beetlejuice, 122 Belafonte, Harry, 122 “Jump in the Line,” 122

178

( 178 )   Index

Berg, Alban, 84 Lyric Suite, 84 Berger, John, 13, 89 Bernal, Gael García, 151 Bernard, Jonathan W., 66–​7 biography, 6, 10, 13–​16, 22–​3, 25–​6, 30, 38–​40, 58, 72–​4, 78n15, 85, 87, 123, 128–​9 body, 5, 7–​10, 16, 19n27, 19n29, 21n48, 23, 56, 68, 130–​1, 144, 151–​2, 154, 159n29 Borges, Jorge Luis, 98 Bosch, Hieronymous, 95 Boulez, Pierre, 15, 24, 35–​48, 73, 100, 124, 157 cummings ist der Dichter, 36 Notations, No. 5, 47 Notations, No. 9, 47 Piano Sonata No. 3, 36 Pli selon pli: portrait de Mallarmé, 15, 24, 35–​48, 73, 100, 124, 157 “Sonate, Que me Veux-​tu?,” 36, 38–​9 “Strophes,” 47 Brahms, Johannes, 93 Braidotti, Rosi, 154 Breatnach, Mary, 41, 45 Brecht, Bertolt, 98 Britten, Benjamin, 87 “E. B. B.,” 87 Two Portraits, 87 Brooklyn Academy of Music, 125 Brother Rufillus of Weissenau, 81, 84 Bruegel the Elder, Pieter, 95 Buscemi, Steve, 113 Byatt, A. S., 22–​3 Cage, John, 58–​9 canon, 33, 41 Caroline, Princess of Monaco, 148–​50 Catoptrum microcosmicum, 131 celebrity, 6, 109–​23, 137n13 Cézanne, Paul, 59, 76 Chalmers, David, 152 Chaplin, Charlie, 93–​4, 125 Modern Times, 93–​4 character, 2–​11, 13–​14, 17, 22–​4, 28, 32, 36, 49n6, 50n30, 55–​6, 63, 71–​4, 85–​6, 109–​11, 123–​4, 126, 137n5, 151, 153–​6 character pieces, 23, 153 character types, 23, 28, 49n6, 50n30 Charles, Prince of Wales, 151

Childs, Lucinda, 16, 125, 127, 129–​30, 135 Chopin, Frédéric, 15, 85, 90–​1, 93, 95–​6 Piano Sonata Op. 35, 93 choreography, 16, 127–​9, 134 Christian X, King of Denmark, 78n17 Clark, Andy, 144, 152 Natural-​Born Cyborgs, 152 Clark, T. J., 89 Clendinning, Jane Piper, 93 Close, Chuck, 15, 32, 56–​7, 69–​77, 101, 134, 155 Big Heads, 69–​70 “Phil” (1969), 69–​70 “Phil” (2011–​2012), 72–​3 “Phil, State I,” 70 Couperin, François, 3, 23, 86, 153 “La Couperin,” 86 Couperin, Louis, 23 Crommelynck, Aldo, 91 Cubism, 6, 27 Cultural Revolution, 111 cyborgs, 144, 150, 152, 156 daguerreotype, 70 Dalí, Salvador, 108n69, 138n22 Dante Alighieri, 119 Da Ponte, Lorenzo, 1 David, Jacques-​Louis, 137n8 “The Death of Marat,” 137n8 Davies, Peter Maxwell, 139n56 Taverner, 139n56 Debussy, Claude, 25, 36 Prélude à l’après-​midi d’un faune, 25 de Groat, Andy, 127 Dehmel, Richard, 134 “Verklärte Nacht,” 134 de Kooning, Willem, 15, 32, 56, 58–​9, 63–​8, 76, 100, 155 “Woman, I,” 66–​8 Woman series, 58 della Francesca, Piero, 59 de Man, Paul, 38 Demuth, Charles, 6–​7, 9, 50n29 “The Figure 5 in Gold, ” 6–​7, 50n29 “Love Love Love,” 50n29 Doisneau, Robert, 92 “Les Pains de Picasso,” 92 Downey Jr., Robert, 116–​18, 121–​2, 138n32 Dreier, Katherine, 6, 8, 9 “Abstract Portrait of Marcel Duchamp,” 6, 8, 9

  179

Index   ( 179 )

Duchamp, Marcel, 6–​7, 9, 99 du Maurier, Daphne, 158n11 Dutch Golden Age, 5 Dylan, Bob, 138n22, 142n104 “Desolation Row,” 142n104 Eco, Umberto, 112 Einstein, Albert, 16, 123–​36 ekphrasis, 56, 59, 63, 69, 75, 126 Eliot, George, 5–​6, 22, 28, 143, 147, 157 Adam Bede, 5–​6 Daniel Deronda, 22, 28, 143, 147, 157 Emin, Tracy, 151 emotion, 9, 13, 17, 26, 28, 30, 44, 55, 69, 71, 74, 85, 119–​20, 134 Ernst, Max, 20n33 Escher, M. C., 95 expressionism, 32, 134. See also abstract expressionism Falkenberg, Paul, 58 Fantin-​Latour, Henri, 55 Feldman, Morton, 15, 32, 56–​68, 76, 78n15, 95, 99, 100, 155–​6 “Between Categories,” 60 “Christian Wolff in Cambridge,” 58 “Coptic Light,” 59 “Crippled Symmetry,” 59 “de Kooning,” 15, 32, 56–​68, 76, 155 Durations, 59 “For Frank O’Hara,” 58 “For Franz Klein,” 58 “For John Cage,” 58 “For Philip Guston,” 58 “For Samuel Beckett,” 58 “For Stefan Wolpe,” 58 “Illusions,” 59 “The King of Denmark,” 59, 78n17 notation of, 60–​8 Patterns in a Chromatic Field, 59 Projections, 59–​60 “Rabbi Akiba,” 59, 78n17 “Rothko Chapel,” 58–​9, 78n15 “Two Pianos,” 60 “vertical thought,” 57–​8 Vertical Thoughts, 59 Field, Sally, 139n51 film, 29, 55–​6, 58, 93–​4, 145–​50 Fischinger, Oskar, 55–​6 Fontaine, Joan, 158n11 Foreman, Richard, 135

Freud, Lucian, 86–​7 “Painter Working, Reflection,” 86–​7 Fröhlich, Franz Joseph, 85 Galasso, Michael, 16, 114, 117, 120 Gandhi, Mahatma, 123, 125 Garbo, Greta, 113 Geddes, Barbara Bel, 148 Gena, Peter, 49n15 Gergen, Kenneth, 12 Ginsberg, Allen, 138n22 “Girl, Interrupted,” 120 Glass, Philip, 15–​16, 32, 56, 69–​77, 112, 155 Akhnaten, 123 Another Look at Harmony, 127 Einstein on the Beach, 16, 71, 112, 123–​36, 156–​7 Galileo Galilei, 123 Kepler, 123 “A Musical Portrait of Chuck Close,” 15, 32, 56, 69–77, 134, 155 “Music in Similar Motion,” 71 Music in Twelve Parts, 71, 125, 127 Play, incidental music for, 127, 140n62 Satyagraha, 123 “Two Pages,” 71 Golijov, Osvaldo, 139n56 Gombrich, E. H., 21n51 Goodman, Alice, 110 Gorky, Maxim, 49n7 Gósol Madonna, 26 Grant, Cary, 115 Graves, Nancy, 69 Gumbrecht, Hans Ulrich, 51n51 Guston, Philip, 58–​60 habanera, 146–​8, 154 Hall, James, 86 Halsman, Philippe, 108n69 Hamilton, Richard, 87–​9 “A Portrait of the Artist by Francis Bacon,” 88–​9 Haraway, Donna, 150 “A Cyborg Manifesto,” 150 Harbisson, Neil, 16–​17, 144, 150–​7 Sound Portraits, 17, 144, 150–​7 Harvey Danger, 158 Hayles, N. Katherine, 144, 154 Helmore, Tom, 145 Herrmann, Bernard, 16, 144, 148, 154, 158n11

180

( 180 )   Index

Hindemith, Paul, 139n56, 141n102 Cardillac, 141n102 Mathis der Mahler, 139n56 Hitchcock, Alfred, 16, 144–​6, 148, 158n11. See also Rear Window; Rebecca; Vertigo Hockney, David, 91–​2 “Artist and Model,” 91–​2 Hogarth, William, 8–​9 The Analysis of Beauty, 8–​9 Holbein, Hans, 138n32 “The Body of the Dead Christ in the Tomb,” 138n32 Homer, 43 Hopkin, Mary, 134 “Those Were the Days,” 134 Hopper, Dennis, 138n22 humors, 8–​9 Huppert, Isabelle, 113, 130, 138n16 Hylton, Wil S., 72 idealization, 4–​7, 109–​11, 115, 136n2, 136n5 identity, 2–​17, 20n33, 20n39, 21n48, 25, 28, 30, 33, 35, 38–​9, 49, 55–​6, 58, 61–​3, 71–​6, 86, 88, 90, 94, 96, 99–​104, 109–​16, 119–​20, 123–​6, 129–​36, 137n7, 143–​51, 154, 156–​7 illumination, 81–​2, 84 Ingres, Jean-​Auguste-Dominique, 137n8 “Mademoiselle Caroline Rivière,” 137n8 interpretation, 2–​3, 6, 9, 11–​12, 14–​15, 17, 21n51, 24, 30, 35, 37–​8, 43, 45, 47, 51n52, 59, 62–​3, 68, 71–​2, 74–​6, 85–6, 97–​8, 109–​12, 114–​16, 121, 123–​6, 130–​1, 152–​7 Ives, Charles, 24, 87–​9 Three Places in New England, 88 “The Unanswered Question,” 88 James, Henry, 49n7 The Portrait of a Lady, 49n7 James, William, 28 The Principles of Psychology, 28 Jiang Qing (Madame Mao), 110, 136n4 Johnson, Buffie, 15, 24, 32–​5, 37, 48, 134 “Portrait of Virgil Thomson,” 32–​3 Johnson, Mark, 19 Johnson, Samuel M., 129–​30, 134 Joyce, James, 32, 36, 47, 49n7 A Portrait of the Artist as a Young Man, 49n7 Ulysses, 32 Judd, Donald, 71

Kanne, Friedrich, 85 Keats, John, 119 Kelly, Grace, 148 Kennedy, John F., 130 keyboard miniatures, 3 Kidman, Nicole, 151 Kierkegaard, Søren, 20n38 Klangfarbenmelodie, 64 Klee, Paul, 5 Kline, Franz, 58–​9 Knowles, Christopher, 129–​30, 134 Kontarsky, Alfons, 90 Kontarsky, Aloys, 90 Krasnow, Janice, 49n12 Kremer, Gidon, 84 Kristeva, Julia, 135 Krúdy, Gyula, 93 Lady Gaga, 111, 137n8 Lakoff, George, 19 Lasso, Orlando di, 84 le Brun, Charles, 8–​9 Lehár, Franz, 122 The Merry Widow, 122 Leiber, Jerry, 114 leitmotif, 145–​8, 150, 154, 158n11 Leonardo da Vinci, 151 Leppert, Richard, 7–​8 Levingston, Bruce, 69, 75 LeWitt, Sol, 69, 71 Ligeti, György, 15–​16, 85, 87, 90–​6, 104, 156 “Continuum,” 90, 93, 95 “Coulée,” 90 Drei Stücke für zwei Klaviere, 15, 90, 93 Études, 106n34 “In zart fließender Bewegung,” 90 “Monument,” 90 pattern-​meccanico technique, 93–​5 “Poème symphonique,” 93 “Selbstportrait mit Reich und Riley (und Chopin ist auch dabei),” 15–​16, 85, 87, 90–​6, 104, 156 String Quartet No. 2, 90, 93 “Volumina,” 93 likeness, 4–​7, 9–​10, 17, 20n33, 24, 26, 30, 32, 34, 38–​9, 47, 49n12, 56, 58, 68, 71–​2, 76, 81, 83, 86, 88–​91, 95–​7, 100, 106n31, 109–​18, 122–​3, 126, 136n5, 147–​8, 150–​3, 155, 157

  18

Index   ( 181 )

literary portraiture, 15, 22–​48, 49n7, 49n8, 49n10, 49n12, 49n29, 51n62, 124, 130, 138n22, 153 literature, 2–​3, 6–​7, 14, 16–​17, 22–​48, 53n121, 111–​12, 143, 153, 155 Lysippos, 4

Mozart, Wolfgang Amadeus, 1–​2 Così fan tutte, 1–​2 mugshots, 115, 117 multimedia, 3, 6, 14, 16, 49n15, 97–​8, 107n50, 109, 111–​15, 122, 124, 137n8, 143, 145, 148, 154

Mabou Mines, 140n62 Madame Tussaud’s, 57, 63 Magritte, René, 95 Malanga, Gerard, 115, 138n22 Malevich, Kazimir, 91 “Suprematism: Self-​Portrait in Two Dimensions,” 91 Mallarmé, Stéphane, 15, 25, 35–​48, 73, 124, 155 “A la nue accablante tu,” 36, 43 “Don du poëme,” 36, 40–​4 “L’après-​midi d’un faune,” 25 Le livre, 37 “Le vierge, le vivace et le bel aujourd’hui,” 36, 42, 44 “Remémoration d’amis belges,” 44–​5, 73 “Tombeau de Verlaine,” 36, 40, 43 “Une dentelle s’abolit,” 36, 42, 44 mandola, 42 Mao Tse-​tung, 99, 110–​11, 136n4 McCalla, James, 46 Mertens, Wim, 124 Messiaen, Olivier, 139n56 Saint François d’Assise, 139n56 metaphor, 2, 4, 7–​10, 12–​15, 17, 18n23, 19n24, 23, 30, 38, 40–​1, 47, 53n108, 55–​66, 68, 74–​6, 89, 98, 100–​1, 107n47, 111, 116–​17, 121, 124, 126, 130, 134, 140n66, 141n88, 143, 153, 155–​7 Metropolitan Opera, 125 Michelson, Albert, 142n105 Milton, John, 119 mimesis, 3, 6, 17, 91, 154 minimalism, 71 mise en abyme, 131, 141 modernism, 15, 24, 27, 39, 47, 50n29 Mogwai, 114 Monet, Claude, 70, 98 monograms, 83–​4 Morley, Edward, 142n105 Moss, Kate, 109 Motherwell, Robert, 59, 61, 78n18

Namuth, Hans, 58 Nancy, Jean-​Luc, 48 narrative, 2, 4, 6, 10, 13–​14, 21n48, 23, 25, 28, 39–​40, 47, 69, 74–​5, 86–​7, 114, 123, 128, 134 narrative self, 13 neoclassicism, 33 Newman, Barnett, 98 “New York School.” See abstract expressionism notation, 60–​8 Novak, Kim, 145, 147 objectivity, 2, 26, 71–​2, 102, 115 O’Doherty, 61–​2, 65, 68 Odysseus, 43 O’Hara, Frank, 58, 62 Olivier, Laurence, 158n11 open form, 37 open work, 112, 136 opera, 1–​3, 14, 16, 25, 110, 112, 123–​36, 139n56, 140n73, 141n102 Pahlavi, Farah, 114 painting, 3, 6, 9–​11, 14, 16, 22–​4, 26–​7, 47–​8, 49n11, 55–​77, 77n13, 78n15, 81–​3, 86, 88–​90, 95, 98, 101, 106n31, 110–​11, 130–​1, 135, 137n5, 137n8, 138n32, 141n91, 141n102, 143–​4, 148, 151–​2, 155–​6 paratexts, 24 passions, 8–​9 pastiche, 12, 87–​8, 90–​1, 148 perception, 2, 10–​11, 15, 28, 34–​5, 58, 61, 72–​3, 95, 97, 99–​101, 103, 130, 137n7, 151, 155–​7 performance, 3, 11–​15, 19n27, 30, 37, 51n52, 61, 63, 65–​6, 68–​9, 75, 91, 94–​5, 115, 120, 151–​2, 156 personality, 3–​4, 7 perspective, 100–​2, 108n69 Pfitzner, Hans, 139n56 Palestrina, 139n56 phase shifting, 92, 95

182

( 182 )   Index

photography, 6, 83, 88, 98–​100, 111, 115–​16 photorealism, 71, 101 Picasso, Pablo, 6, 26–​7, 35, 59, 91 “Gertrude Stein,” 26–​7 “Les demoiselles d’Avignon,” 26 “Self-​Portrait,” 91 Vollard Suite, 92 pièces de caractère. See character pieces Plutarch, 4 Poe, Edgar Allen, 4 “The Oval Portrait,” 4 poetry, 2, 6, 24–​48, 110, 134, 138n22 Pokémon Go, 153 Pollock, Jackson, 60–​1 Popol Vuh, 114 portrait medals, 136n2 portrait miniatures, 1–​2 portrait opera, 3, 14–​16, 112, 123–​36, 139n56, 140n73 posthumanism, 16–​17, 143–​4, 150–​7 posthumous representation, 16, 143–​50 postmodernism, 11–​13, 20n39, 103, 112, 130 presence, 19n28, 30, 32, 34, 48, 155 process, 70–​1, 75, 128, 130 program, 14, 74 prosopopeia, 38–​9, 48 Proust, Marcel, 37, 87 Quintilian, 38 Radcliffe, Daniel, 151 Rakha, Alla, 127 Rankine, Claudia, 49n15 Raphael, 82 “The School of Athens,” 82 Rauschenberg, Robert, 130 “Retroactive II,” 130 Ravel, Maurice, 105n6 “Daphnis et Chloé,” 105n6 Ray, Man, 20n33 realism, 5 Rear Window, 148–​9 Rebecca, 158n11 Reich, Steve, 15, 85, 90–​2, 94–​6 “It’s Gonna Rain,” 90, 94 “Piano Phase,” 94 “Violin Phase,” 90, 94 Reinhardt, Ad, 98 relativity, 123–​5, 128, 133, 135–​6

Rembrandt van Rijn, 86, 116, 136 “The Anatomy Lesson of Dr. Nicolaes Tulp,” 116 “Portrait of the Artist at His Easel,” 86 Remmelin, Johann, 131 Reynolds, Joshua, 22 Richter, Gerhard, 98 Riley, Terry, 15, 85, 90–​1, 93–​6 “In C,” 90, 94–​5 Rockwell, Norman, 86 “Triple Self-​Portrait,” 86 Rota, Nino, 114 Roth, Philip, 104 My Life as a Man, 104 Rothko, Mark, 58–​9, 151 Ryder, Winona, 117–​23, 157 Saariaho, Kaija, 139n56 Émilie, 139n56 Sargent, John Singer, 148 “Madame X (Madame Pierre Gautreau),” 148 Sarup, Madan, 11 Scarlatti, Domenico, 93 Schapiro, Meyer, 62 Schechtman, Marya, 13 Schérer, Jacques, 37 Schnittke, Alfred, 84 Concerto Grosso No. 3, 84 String Quartet No. 3, 84 Violin Concerto No. 4, 84 Schoenberg, Arnold, 36, 134 “Verklärte Nacht,” 134 Schrag, Calvin O., 12–​13 Schumann, Robert, 23–​4, 93 Carnaval, 24 sculpture, 3, 4, 8, 26, 57–​8, 63, 96–​7, 133, 135, 137n8 Second Life, 153 Seigel, Jerrold, 11 self, 1, 3–​4, 7, 9, 11–​14, 17, 20n38, 20n39, 22, 28, 35, 48, 56, 61–​2, 68, 84, 89, 97–​101, 103–​4, 113–​14, 116, 118–​19, 124, 129–​31, 135, 144, 152–​4, 156–​7, 159n29, 159n32 self-​portraiture, 3, 14–​16, 20n33, 24, 34, 37, 46–​8, 51n62, 54n121, 56, 58, 63, 76, 81–​104, 105n6, 105n22, 106n31, 107n50, 143, 148, 153, 156 Sellars, Peter, 110 Serra, Richard, 69

  183

Index   ( 183 )

Shakespeare, William, 12, 76, 119, 141n102 Hamlet, 76, 121, 141n102 Shankar, Ravi, 127 Shostakovich, Dmitri, 84 String Quartet No. 8, 84 Siedentopf, Henning, 93 Siegel, Lee, 116 Smith, Olav Bryant, 12 Socrates, 8 Solari, Andrea, 137n8 “The Head of St. John the Baptist,” 137n8 sonnet, 36, 40–​1, 43, 45–​6, 155 Sontag, Susan, 9, 138n22 Sorey, Tyshawn, 49n15 soul, 7–​9, 55, 81, 86, 116, 137n5 Steichen, Edward, 113 Stein, Gertrude, 15, 24–​35, 50n29, 50n30, 50n40, 75, 99, 124, 130, 155 Capital Capitals, 25 Four Saints in Three Acts, 25 “If I Told Him,” 35 The Making of Americans, 50n30 The Mother of Us All, 25 “Portraits and Repetition,” 28–​9 “Preciocilla,” 25, 28 “Susie Asado,” 25, 28 “Virgil Thomson,” 30–​2 Stein, Leo, 26 Stewart, James, 145, 148 still life, 90, 114, 131, 133 Stoller, Mike, 114 Strachey, Lytton, 49n7 Sturm und Drang, 1 subjectivity, 5, 12, 55, 57–​8, 61–​2, 67–​8, 102, 152–​3, 159n29 Sulzer, Johann Georg, 55 Suprematism, 91 surgical theaters, 116 Sutton, Sheryl, 128, 130

“Buffie Johnson: Drawing Virgil Thomson in Charcoal,” 15, 24, 32–​5, 47–​8, 134 “Capital Capitals”, 25 Eight Portraits for Violin Alone, 31 essays, 25 Four Saints in Three Acts, 25 “Miss Gertrude Stein as a Young Girl,” 30–​1 The Mother of Us All, 25 Nineteen Portraits for Piano, 32 “Preciocilla,” 25, 28 “Susie Asado,” 25, 28 titles, 3, 7, 14, 24–​5, 30–​1, 35–​6, 40, 44, 48, 56–​60, 62–​3, 69, 73, 78n17, 85–7, 89–​91, 98, 105n6, 126, 129, 140n75, 143, 154–​5 Toklas, Alice B., 25 transcendentalist philosophers, 87 tropes, 1–​2, 9, 33–​4, 92 Turk, Gavin, 53n121

tapestry, 70 Tavel, Ronald, 116 theater, 16, 111–​12, 114, 116, 119, 123–​36, 139n36, 140n62 Theophrastus, 23, 49n6 Characters, 23 theory of relativity. See relativity Thomson, Virgil, 15, 24–​35, 38, 47–​8, 124, 134, 155

Wagner, Richard, 85, 114 Waits, Tom, 16, 117, 121 Bone Machine, 117 “The Ocean Doesn’t Want Me,” 117–​18, 121 Warhol, Andy, 98, 110, 115–​16, 138n22, 151 Screen Tests, 115–​16, 138n22 Waxman, Franz, 158n11 wax sculpture, 57–​8, 63

Ulambayar, Byambajav, 113 Valéry, Paul, 41 van Eyck, Jan, 81–​2, 141n102 “The Arnolfini Portrait,” 141n102 Ghent Altarpiece, 81–​2 Velázquez, Diego, 86, 151 “Las Meninas,” 86 Venice Biennale, 135 Verlaine, Paul, 39 Vertigo, 16, 144–​50, 154 Visible Man, 131 visual art, 2–​4, 6–​7, 10, 15, 17, 19n24, 19n25, 19n30, 22–​4, 26–​8, 30, 32–​3, 37–​8, 47–​8, 50n29, 55–​77, 85–​7, 93, 95, 97–​8, 153–​5 visual portraiture, 3–​7, 9, 13, 22–​4, 28, 32–​3, 55–​77, 86, 104, 109–​36, 145, 147–​51, 154 Voom HD Networks, 113

184

( 184 )   Index

Webern, Anton, 36, 41, 52n90, 64–​5 “Five Pieces for String Quartet,” 52n90 Welin, Karl-​Erik, 93 Whitehead, Alfred North, 20n38 Whitelaw, Billie, 119 Wilde, Oscar, 81, 136n5 The Picture of Dorian Gray, 81, 136n5 Williams, Bernard, 5 Williams, William Carlos, 6, 50n29 Wilson, Robert, 16, 111–​36, 138n32, 139n36, 148, 157, 158n11 Deafman Glance, 112 Edison, 123 Einstein on the Beach (see Glass, Philip) “Isabelle Huppert,” 113, 130 The King of Spain, 123 Lady Gaga portraits, 111, 137n8 A Letter for Queen Victoria, 123 The Life and Death of Marina Abramović, 123 The Life and Times of Joseph Stalin, 123, 125

The Life and Times of Sigmund Freud, 123 “Princess Caroline,” 148–​50 “Robert Downey Jr.,” 116–​18, 121–​2, 138n32 Video 50, 115 Voom Portraits, 16, 112–​24, 130, 137n13, 148, 157, 158n11 “Winona Ryder,” 117–​23 Wolfe, Bernard, 153 Limbo, 153 Wolpe, Stefan, 59–​60 Woolf, Virginia, 49n7 Woronov, Mary, 116 Wright, John, 32 Xenophon, 8 The Memorabilia, 8 Yeats, William Butler, 119 YouTube, 152

  185

186